MATH 10 Logic and Reasoning
MATH 10 Logic and Reasoning
Introduction
Logic plays a very important role in mathematics – it is the foundation on which the
discipline is built. Remember all the proofs you had to write to establish some
theorems in algebra and geometry? You start with the given assumptions, use
definitions and perhaps some known results, and argue logically to establish the
conclusion. We consider mathematics as a language with its own symbols and
“grammar”. These symbols may represent various mathematical objects like
numbers, sets, or functions. The grammar will be the rules when combining these
symbols. We apply logic to deduce properties of these objects and rules based on
some axioms. One cannot overemphasize the importance of logic in mathematics,
but logic, or logical reasoning, is just as important in our everyday life. In this era of
fake news, post-truths, false advertising, we must be able to discern what is true or
false. We should be able to determine if a certain argument is valid or not.
Learning Outcomes
After studying this module, you should be able to:
1. Determine whether a statement has truth value;
2. Negate simple and compound statements;
3. Describe the various forms of the conditional;
4. Use truth tables to determine the truth value of a statement;
5. Determine whether an argument is valid or invalid using Euler diagrams or
truth tables; and
6. Illustrate deductive and inductive reasoning.
In this section, we shall study a very basic object in mathematical logic, statements,
and operations and relations on statements. These will be important when we
discuss valid and invalid arguments.
The first three sentences do not have a truth value and note that they are not
declarative statements. The expressions “5 + 1” and “x + 3 = 0” may seem to be
mathematical statement because they involve mathematical symbols, but they
have no truth value, and in fact, have no meaning. However, “For all numbers x, x
+ 3 = 0” is a mathematical statement which is false. Statements (6) and (7) are
declarative statements but are not considered as mathematical statements since
they have no definite truth value. In particular, mathematics may be interesting for
some people, so it could be true for these people, but false for those who find
mathematics boring. In the same manner, some people might consider 7 as their
lucky number and some may think of this as false. In fact, the sentence is vague
since “lucky” has to be defined. However, the statement “7 is an odd number” is a
true mathematical statement.
EXERCISES 1.1
Determine whether the following are mathematical statements or not.
We consider the following operations on statements and their notations. These will
give us ways to combine two statements p and q:
1. Conjunction “p and q”
p∧ q
2. Disjunction "p or q"
p∨ q
3. Conditional "If p then q"
p→q
Statement p is called the premise and q is called the conclusion.
Except for the negation, all the operations are binary, that is, they involve two
statements at a time.
Example 1.3 The statements in Example 1.1 can form the following compound
statements using connectives:
1. p ∧ q : 1 + 1 = 2 and 2 + 3 = 6.
2. r ∨ s : All roses are red or the Philippines has more than 7,000 islands.
3. p → s : If 1+1=2 then the Philippines has more than 7,000 islands.
4. q ↔ r : 2 + 3 = 6 if and only if all roses are red.
5. ~p : 1+1 ≠ 2
Are the resulting statements using the connectives still considered mathematical
statements? That is, do they have a truth value? For the operations on
mathematical statements to be "legitimate" or well-defined operations, the result
must also be a mathematical statement that is, it must have a truth value. We now
define when the above are true and when they are false:
1. The conjunction p ∧q is true if both p and q are true. Otherwise, it is false.
2. The disjunction p ∨ q is true if at least one statement (p, q, or both) is true.
It is false only if both statements are false.
3. The conditional p → q is false only when the premise p is true and the
conclusion q is false. Otherwise, it is true.
4. The biconditional p ↔ q is true if p and q have the same truth value, that is,
either p and q both true or both are false.
5. The negation ~ p is true if p is false. If p is true, ~p is false.
Example 1.4 In Example1.3, since p and s are true while q and r are false, we
have
1. p ∧ q is false
2. r ∨ s is true
3. p → s is true
4. q ↔ r is true
5. ~p is false.
p q
T T
T F
F T
F F
We present the truth tables for the conjunction, disjunction, conditional and
biconditional. Recall when the statements resulting from connectives are either
true or false.
p q p∧ q
T T T
T F F
F T F
F F F
p q p∨ q
T T T
T F T
F T T
F F F
3. Conditional p → q (false only when the premise is true and the conclusion is
false)
p q p→q
T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T
4. Biconditional p ↔ q (true only when p and q have the same truth value)
p q p↔q
T T T
T F F
F T F
F F T
5. Negation ~p
p ~p
T F
T T
If there are two statements, as seen above, there are 4 = 22 rows in the table
showing all possible cases. If there are three statements, there are 23 = 8 cases. In
general, if there are n statements, there are 2n cases.
Example 1.6 Construct a truth table for the following statements
1. p → ~q
2. (~p ∧ q) → ~r
Solutions:
1. For p → ~q, we have
p q ~q p → ~q
T T F T
T F T F
F T F T
F F T T
2. There are three (3) statements, p, q, r, so there are 23 = 8 possible cases for
all combinations of truth values of p, q, r.
p q r ~p (~p ∧ q) ~r (~p ∧ q) → ~r
T T T F F F T
T T F F F T T
T F T F F F T
T F F F F T T
F T T T T F F
F T F T T T T
F F T T F F T
F F F T F T T
Note that the first row of the given table (p, q, r are all true) corresponds to
Example 1.5 (3).
EXERCISES 1.3
Construct a truth table for the following statements.
1. p ↔ ~q
2. ~ q → ~ p
3. (~ p ∨ q) ↔ (p → q)
4. p ∨ (q ∧ r)
5. (~p ∧ q) ∨ ~ (r → ~q)
In the previous section, we defined the possible operations on statements that are
used to construct compound statements. The resulting compound statement has a
truth value although it may or may not make sense. For example, the statement “If
all roses are red, then all violets are blue.” This is a true statement (F → F) but it is
not materially true (the two statements are not related). We have conditionals p → q
and biconditionals p ↔ q that actually make sense or are materially true. We
consider two relations on statements, implication and equivalence.
1. Implication. We know for a fact that all cats are mammals. This means that if an
animal is a cat, then it is a mammal. We can state this as “If it is a cat, then it is
a mammal.” This is not just a compound statement with the connective “ → “,
rather a material implication. So, if something is a cat, it is also true that it is also
a mammal. We call this relation an implication, denoted by “ ⇒ ” . Hence, if
statement p (materially) implies statement q, we denote this by “p ⇒ q ” (read
as p implies q).
2. Equivalence. On the other hand, we may also have statements which are
equivalent. We usually see this in definitions and compound statements which
may be restated in another way. Consider the definition “A polygon is a triangle
if and only if it has three sides”. This actually means that the statements
p: A polygon is a triangle.
q: A polygon has three sides.
are equivalent. In this case, we may replace p with statement q. We denote the
equivalence of two statements p and q by p ⇔ q.
In the following sections, we shall discuss further negation of statements and the
conditional and in these discussions, we can find more examples of equivalent
compound statements. Note that we can determine the equivalence of two
compound statements by comparing their truth tables. If they have the same truth
value for each case, then they are equivalent.
T T F F T F F
T F F T F T T
F T T F F T T
F F T T F T T
Observe that for each case, the two statements have the same truth value so
∼ ( p ∧ q ) is equivalent to ∼ p ∨ ∼ q. This implies the negation of the conjunction
of p and q may be restated as the disjunction of the negation of p and the negation
of q. (See Section 2.2 for examples illustrating negation of compound statements.)
Page 9 of 36 July 2018
LOGIC AND REASONING
EXERCISES 1.4
1. Prove the following equivalences using truth tables:
a. ~ ( p ∨ q ) ⇔ ~p ∧ ~q
b. (p → q) ⇔ ( ~p ∨ q )
2 Negation of Statements
Suppose someone claims that Brand X is both cheap and good and you would like
to disagree and state the opposite. Or your teacher tells you that if you work hard
then you will get an excellent grade, and you know (from experience) that this is not
true. It is important to know how to determine the opposite of a statement, that is, to
negate a given statement.
To negate simple statements, we add the word “not”, as appropriate. Let us illustrate
this with the statements given in Example 1.1.
Statement Negation
p : 1+1 = 2 ~p : 1+1 ≠ 2
q:2+3=6 ~q : 2 + 3 ≠ 6
r : All roses are red. ~r : Not all roses are red.
s : The Philippines has more than ~s : The Philippines has at most
7,000 islands. 7,000 islands.
3. Note that the phrase “more than” is negated as “at most” (see statement t
above) and NOT as “less than”. In our example, we can express the
statement as an inequality “7,000 < x” (or x < 7,000), where x is the number
of islands in the Philippines. To negate “<”, recall that given two numbers y
and z, there are only three possibilities: y < z, y = z, or y > z. So, the
negation of “7,000 is less than x” (7,000 < x) is “7,000 is not less than x”
(7,000 ≮ 𝑥). This means that either 7,000 is equal to x (7000 = x) or 7,000 is
more than x (7,000 > x) or simply 7,000 ≥ 𝑥. This is equivalent to x is at
most 7,000.
EXERCISES 2.1
Negate the following statements:
1. 100 is a multiple of 10.
2. x+y≤z
3. All trees are tall.
4. There are 12 months in a year.
5. Juan is at least 18 years old.
Answers:
1. The chairs are NOT red or UP is less than 100 years old.
2. 1+1 ≥ 5 and not all roses are red.
3. Jose Rizal is not intelligent or he is not nationalistic.
We can also negate statements with the quantifiers all, some, none. Let us
consider the following statements with quantifiers and their negation.
2. Note that “Some roses are red” means there are roses which are red. The
negation is: there are no roses which are red, that is,
~ q: No roses are red.
This is NOT equivalent to “Some roses are not red.” If some roses are
red, this could also mean that some roses are not red. So the negation
should be none are red.
3. The negation of “No roses are red” is
~ p: Not all roses are red.
Page 12 of 36 July 2018
LOGIC AND REASONING
3 The Conditional
Everyday we have to make decisions, as simple as which route to take in going to
school. The decisions we make normally depend on some conditions or premises or
information given. For example, it it rains, then you will not walk going to school or
not go to class at all. We also encounter a lot of conditional statements or “if –
then’s” in advertisements, instructions, arguments, and ordinary conversations.
Hence, it is important to understand the conditional and the many forms it takes and
statements which are not equivalent to a given conditional.
q if p. q is necessary for p.
2. p only if q:
It is a bird only if it flies.
3. p is sufficient for q:
Being a bird is sufficient for it to fly.
4. q is necessary for p.
Flying is necessary for it to be a bird.
6. Either not p or q.
Either is not a bird or it flies.
EXERCISES 3.1
1. Give five (5) equivalent statements for the following:
a) If you care for the environment, then you should recycle.
b) All animals are friendly.
c) No insect is useless.
p q p→q q→p ~p → ~q ~q → ~p
T T T T T T
T F F T T F
F T T F F T
F F T T T T
Remark : From the above truth table, we have seen that the conditional is
equivalent to its contrapositive and not equivalent to its converse and inverse.
EXERCISES 3.2
1. Which of the following statements is/are equivalent to
“All Filipinos are law-abiding.”
A. If you are a Filipino, then you are law-abiding.
B. If you are not a Filipino, then you are not law-abiding.
C. If you are not law-abiding, then you are not a Filipino.
D. If you are law-abiding, then you are a Filipino.
E. You are law-abiding if you are a Filipino.
F. You are law-abiding only if you are a Filipino.
The objective in each puzzle is to draw a conclusion based on all the premises
given. Logical reasoning is important in puzzle and problem solving, as it provides a
systematic way to come up with a solution. We are also regularly inundated by
arguments or reasoning which may seem nonsensical or puzzling. We also
encounter phrases like : God is love. Love is blind. Therefore, God is blind. This
seems logical or valid, but is it? Hence, logical reasoning should be applied when
we discern the validity or soundness of arguments.
In this section, we discuss valid and invalid arguments, common forms or valid
arguments and some examples of fallacies we could encounter in everyday life.
An Euler diagram represents statements, the way Venn diagrams represent sets.
For example, consider the statement
p: Jose is a UP student.
The statement involves inclusion in a set, that is, Jose is an element of the set of UP
students. We can use a circle to represent the set of UP students and if we let x
represent Jose, the Euler diagram of statement p is given by :
UP students
We can also represent statements with the quantifiers all, some, and none.
mammals
cats
dogs. This is represented by two intersecting sets and the region where
they intersect contains the set of dogs which are hairy.
dogs hairy
things
hairy dogs
Hairy dogs
even odd
numbers numbers
In general, we have the following Euler diagrams for statements with quantifiers all,
some, or none involving members of two sets A and B:
All A are B. Some A are B.
A B
No A is B.
A B
An argument consists of premises, say p1, p2, ..., pn, and a conclusion q and
consider the conjunction p1∧p2∧... ∧pn = p . The argument p→q is valid if the
premises are assumed to be true, then the conclusion must also hold true. That is,
the statement p→q is an implication. We can use Euler diagrams to determine the
validity of an argument. We construct a diagram which represents the premises.
The argument is valid if the conclusion is satisfied by the Euler diagram
representing all premises. Note that the premises are assumed to be true
although the statements may not be true in the strict sense.
To determine if it is valid, we draw an Euler diagram for the premises. The first
premise is represented by two sets, the set of dogs is inside the set of hairy things:
hairy things
dogs
and the second premise, we have Cotton (represented by x) inside the set of dogs:
dogs
hairy things
dogs
x
Since x is in the set of the smaller set (dogs), it follows that s is also in the set of
hairy things. This means the conclusion "Cotton is a dog" follows naturally from the
premises so the argument is valid.
hairy things
dogs
Remark: One may also show that an argument is invalid by exhibiting two different
diagrams representing the premises. In the above example, we have the two
diagrams:
dogs
dogs x
x
which both satisfy the two premises given but give two possible conclusions. In the
diagram on the left, Cotton (x) is a dog and also hairy, but in the second diagram,
Cotton is hairy but is not a dog. If an argument is valid, there should only be one
possible conclusion.
5. All parrots are birds. Some parrots fly. Therefore, some birds fly.
6. All parrots are birds. All cats are mammals. No bird is a mammal.
Therefore, no parrot is a cat.
Solutions:
1. This argument is VALID. The two premises are represented by the
following diagram, with D representing Donut.
hairy things D
dogs
Since Donut is not in the set of hairy things, it follows that Donut is also
not in the set of dogs. Therefore, the conclusion is implied by the
premises.
Take note that the premise given “All dogs are hairy” is not really a true
statement since some dogs are not hairy, but we evaluate the validity of
the argument and NOT the truth value of the conclusion.
2. The argument is INVALID. Although Donut is not a cat, it does not
automatically follow that Donut is not a mammal. This can be illustrated
with a diagram:
mammals
cats D
animals
mammals
Page 22 of 36 July 2018
mammals
cats
LOGIC AND REASONING
A
A - animals
M
M - mammals
C
C - cats
The diagram shows that any element of the set of cats is automatically an
element of the set of animals. Hence, the argument is VALID.
B
B C
P
P C
which satisfies the two premises but not the conclusion. That is, it does
not follow that some parrots fly. Hence, the argument is invalid.
P F
Since (F) intersects (P), it automatically intersects (B). That is, the parrots
which fly are the birds which fly. Hence, the argument is valid.
All parrots (P) are birds (B). All cats (C) are mammals (M).
B M
P C
The diagrams, taken together, satisfy the third premise as well, that no
bird is a mammal. As can be seen, the conclusion that no parrot is a cat
follows from the three premises. Therefore, the argument is valid.
Remark: As mentioned in the first example, the argument may be valid even if the
premises are not universally true. That is, the argument is valid but not “sound”. In
fact, we can have premises that may be meaningless, but the conclusion (which is
also meaningless) can still follow logically if the premises are assumed to be true.
Let us consider the following argument:
Example 4.5. All booms (B) are zooms (Z). All feeps (F) are meeps (M). No zoom is
a meep. Therefore, no boom is a feep.
Z M
Note that since no zeep is a meep, this will ensure that no boom is a feep. This
argument is actually in the same form as the argument given in Example 6 above.
EXERCISES 4.2
1. Determine if the following arguments are valid or invalid. Justify your answers
by drawing a diagram.
a. All Filipinos enjoy singing. Juan is a Filipino. Therefore, Juan enjoys
singing.
b. Some physicists are poets. Einstein is a physicist. Therefore,
Einstein is a poet.
c. All lions are animals. Some lions have manes. Therefore, some
animals have manes.
d. All parrots are birds. Some birds are colorful. Therefore, some parrots
are colorful.
e. All booms (B) are zooms (Z). All feeps (F) are meeps (M). No boom is
a feep. Therefore, no zoom is a meep.
2. Consider the following premises : Every sane person can do logic. No cat
can do logic. Those who are not sane cannot serve in the government.
Which of the following is not a valid conclusion?
a) Cats cannot serve in the government.
b) No cat is sane.
c) Logical persons cannot serve in the government.
d) Those who serve in the government are not logical.
3. Consider the following premises: All physicists are scientists. Some scientists
are artists. All mathematicians are artists. Some physicists are
mathematicians. No scientist is illogical. Which is a valid conclusion?
a) No physicist is illogical.
b) Some mathematicians are illogical.
c) Some physicists are artists.
4. Find a valid conclusion for the following Lewis Carrol puzzles (HINT: Express
the given statements in conditional form):
a. Babies are illogical. Nobody is despised who can manage a crocodile.
Illogical persons are despised.
b. No ducks waltz.
No officers ever decline to waltz.
All my poultry are ducks.
c. No kitten that loves fish is unteachable.
Modus ponens
Cotton is a dog. p
Modus tollens
Syllogism
We can use truth tables to show the validity of these arguments. In particular, we
find the truth value of the conditional whose premise is the conjunction of the
premises and the conclusion is the given conclusion in the argument, that is,
1. (Modus ponens) [(p →q) ∧ p] → q
If the statement is true for each of the four cases in the truth table, then the
argument is valid. In this case, we call the statement a tautology and the
conditionals given are in fact, implications. We have the following truth tables:
1. Modus ponens
T T T T T
T F F F T
F T T F T
F F T F T
2. Modus Tollens
T T T T T
T F F F T
F T T F T
F F T F T
(p → q) ∧ [(p → q) ∧ (q→r)]
p q r p→q q→r p→r
(q→r) → (p→r)
T T T T T T T T
T T F T F F F T
T F T F T F T T
T F F F T F F T
F T T T T T T T
F T F T F F T T
F F T F T F T T
F F F F T F T T
Example 4.6. Verify that the following arguments are valid and determine if they
are of the given valid argument forms (modus ponens, modus tollens, or syllogism).
3. If you love cats, then you love animals. If you love animals, then you should
be kind to animals. Therefore, if you love cats, you should be kind to animals.
Answers: The given arguments are valid and this can be shown using Euler
Diagrams (left as an exercise). Arguments 1, 2, 3 are examples of a modus ponens,
modus tollens, and syllogism, respectively.
EXERCISES 4.3
1. Verify that the following arguments are valid and classify according to the
type of valid argument form.
a) If it rains, I will sleep. I did not sleep. Therefore, it did not rain.
2. Using Euler Diagrams, establish the validity of the modus pones, modus
tollens and syllogism.
4.4 Fallacies
These are examples of two invalid argument forms, the fallacy of the converse and
the fallacy of the inverse, respectively. In symbols, these are of the form:
p→q p→q
q ~p
Therefore p Therefore ~ q
Let us look at the truth tables for these two arguments. We consider the two
conditionals {[(p → q) ∧ q] → p} and { [(p → q) ∧ ~p] → ~q}.
T T T T T
T F F F T
F T T T F
F F T F T
T T T F T
T F F F T
F T T T F
F F T F T
Observe that unlike the valid argument forms, the arguments given above are not
tautologies since they are not true for each of the four cases. They are called
fallacies. The argument {[(p →q) ∧ q] → p} is false when p is true and q is false,
and {[(p → q) ∧ ~p] → ~q} is false when p is false and q is true.
Example 4.6. Verify that the following arguments are invalid and determine
whether the argument is an example of the fallacy of the converse or the fallacy of
the inverse.
1. If you can add, then you can subtract. You cannot add. Therefore, you cannot
subtract.
3. If I sing, then it rains. If it does not rain, then birds sing. Birds are not singing.
Therefore, I am singing.
Answers: The above statements can be shown to be invalid using Euler diagrams.
Arguments 1 and 3 are fallacies of the converse while argument 1 is an example of
a fallacy of the inverse. In argument 3, the premise “Birds are not singing” implies
that it is raining (by the contrapositive of the second premise). If it rains, no
conclusion may be drawn since the given premise is “If I sing, then it rains.”
Other fallacies
We also have fallacies other than the forms given above. In fact, we probably
encounter these fallacies more frequently:
1. Ad Hominem. The argument is based on the character of the opponent
instead of the argument itself. This may also involve insulting the opponent
to make opponent’s argument seem false.
Example: Maria wears leather shoes, so she cannot be a vegetarian.
Exercises 4.4
1. Verify that the following arguments are invalid and determine whether the
argument is an example of the fallacy of the converse or the fallacy of the
inverse:
a. All birds have feathers. I am not a bird. Therefore, I have no feathers.
b. If you are smart, then you are successful. You are successful.
Therefore you are smart.
3. Give at least three (3) other fallacies aside from the forms discussed in this
section and give an example for each. You may refer to these sources:
a. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=0RyVj2FPGyg
b. https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=VDGp04CfM4M
c. http://www.don-lindsay-archive.org/skeptic/arguments.html
d. https://www.huffingtonpost.com/mario-livio/logical-
fallacies_b_1932906.html
(Trivia: Prime numbers which can be expressed in the form 2p- 1 where p is a prime
number are called Mersenne primes, named after the French scholar Marin
Mersenne who took interest in prime numbers of this form. The search for Mersenne
primes continues and the largest known as of December 2017 is 277,232,917 – 1.)
Exercises 5.1
1. Determine whether the following arguments use inductive or deductive
reasoning.
c. In a mystery case, it is known that Jose did it or Maria did it. Maria did
not do it. Therefore, Jose did it.
2. Activity: Circles and Chords. Given a circle, if you mark n points on the
circle, what is the maximum number of chords (a chord is line joining two
points on a circle) that can be drawn? What is the maximum number of
regions formed? Investigate the case for n = 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6. Can you
generalize the results? Let us illustrate, for n = 2, 3 and do the case for 1, 4,
5, 6
n=2
x
1 2
x
n=3
x x
3 4
Example 5.1. Place the numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 in the circles in the figure below,
such that each side totals 12.
Solution: The problem involves writing the numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 such that if you
add the numbers on one side of the triangle formed by the singles, the sum should
be 12. This is a problem where guess and test may be employed. However, if you
just guess and write the numbers randomly, solving it might take some time until you
“guess” the correct solution. Since the sum is 12, you cannot place the smaller
numbers 1, 2, 3 on the same side. Moreover, to get a sum of 12, you will need
exactly two of the higher numbers 4, 5, 6, but not all three, on one side. Hence, 4,
5, 6 will be on the vertices of the triangle and 1, 2, 3 may now be placed in the
appropriate circles. The solution is
. 4
3 2
5 1 6
Exercises 5.2
Solve the following problems and explain how you arrived at your solution using
Polya’s process.
1. Find the next two (2) numbers, x and y, in the given sequences:
a. 1, 4, 9, 16, 25, x, y
b. 3, 9, 15, 21, 27, x, y
c. 3, 15, 75, x, y
d. 1, 6, 15, 28, 45, x, y
e. 2, 6, 22, 56, 114, x, y
2. Three school children Junie, Glory, and Mickey are sitting side by side. Junie
always tells the truth, Glory sometimes tells the truth and Mickey never tells
the truth. The child on the left says “Junie is in the middle”. The child in the
middle says “I’m Glory”, and the child on the right says “Mickey is in the
middle”. Determine the seating arrangement of the three.
3. In a certain jungle, there are three tribes: Tribe T, Tribe L, Tribe X. Members
of Tribe T always tell the truth, Tribe L members never tell the truth and Tribe
X members sometimes tell the truth and they sometimes lie. If you meet one
tribe member and he tells you, “I always lie,” which tribe does he come
from? If you meet another tribe member and he says, “I sometime lie,”
which tribe can he come from?
4. Jose must take a cat, a mouse, and a sack of rice across a river with his
boat. The boat to be used can only accommodate Juan and either the cat,
mouse or the sack of rice. However, if left together, the cat will eat the
mouse. Also, if the mouse is left alone with the rice, it will eat the rice. The
cat does not eat rice. The mouse and rice are safe when Jose is present.
What is the minimum number of times Jose needs to cross the river so he
could get everything across?
5. Four children, Amy, Susie, Tessie, and Eddie are lined up according to
height, each holding a balloon. The child in front (the shortest) is holding
Page 35 of 36 July 2018
LOGIC AND REASONING
neither a red nor blue balloon. Susie is holding a red balloon. Tessie sees
exactly two balloons in front of her. The child holding the blue balloon is right
in front of the child with the yellow balloon. Amy is in front of Tessie. One
child is holding a white balloon. Determine the arrangement of the four
children (from shortest to tallest) and the color of the balloon they are holding.
References:
1. Mathematical Ideas, C.D. Miller, V. Heeren, J. Hornsby, C. Heeren, Pearson,
2015.
a. https://owlcation.com/humanities/Logical-Fallacies-Logical-Fallacies-
and-How-They-Are-Used
b. http://www.math.hawaii.edu/~hile/math100/logice.htm
c. https://www.huffingtonpost.com/mario-livio/logical-
fallacies_b_1932906.html
d. http://www.fallacydetective.com/articles/categoriescategory/fallacies/