PHD The Role of Temporality in Freedom and Agency PDF
PHD The Role of Temporality in Freedom and Agency PDF
The official electronic file of this thesis or dissertation is maintained by the University
Libraries on behalf of The Graduate School at Stony Brook University.
©
©AAllll R
Riigghhttss R
Reesseerrvveedd bbyy A
Auutthhoorr..
An Unconditioned Will: The Role of Temporality in Freedom and Agency
A Dissertation Presented
by
Roman Altshuler
to
Requirements
Doctor of Philosophy
in
Philosophy
May 2010
Stony Brook University
Roman Altshuler
We, the dissertation committee for the above candidate for the
Doctor of Philosophy degree, hereby recommend
acceptance of this dissertation.
Lawrence Martin
Dean of the Graduate School
ii
Abstract of the Dissertation
by
Roman Altshuler
Doctor of Philosophy
in
Philosophy
2010
Eliminativists about free will and moral responsibility argue that no action can be
free and responsible because in order to be actions, our movements must be caused by
features of our character or will. However, either the will is constituted by states that are
themselves produced by events outside our control, or it is constituted by our own
choices, which must themselves stem from our will in order to be up to us. Thus, any
attempt to account for freedom and responsibility seems to either run into an infinite
regress or leave the ultimate causes of our actions up to something outside our agency.
Compatibilists attempt to respond to this challenge by arguing that we need not have
control over our will in order to be free, but only to have control of our actions on the
basis of our will. Libertarians, on the other hand, argue that we can be free so long as our
choices are caused indeterministically and chosen for reasons.
I argue that both approaches ultimately leave the constitution of the will up to
non-agential factors because the dominant accounts view all choices—including those
that constitute the will—as essentially events caused by other events, leaving no function
for agents to perform. In response, I argue that we can avoid eliminativism if we take the
will to be irreducible to events such as choices and also our own. Through an examination
of recent non-volitionist approaches that allow for responsibility for non-deliberative
action, I argue that such accounts presuppose a Heideggerian view of agency on which all
action and deliberation occur on the basis of an underlying projection of possibilities into
which we are thrown. Heidegger’s account of temporality in turn allows us to own
ourselves in the present by retrieving our past as always already chosen in light of our
self-projection into the future. Agents are thus self-constituting beings capable of owning
themselves and independent of causation by prior events. Freedom and responsibility are
therefore irreducible features of agency.
iii
Table of Contents
1. Introduction …………………………………………………………. 1
A. Motivations and Threats ………………………………………2
B. Shallow and Deep Temporality ………………………............. 5
C. Summary of the Dissertation …………………………............. 8
7. Conclusion …………………………………………………………...279
iv
1
Introduction
It is impossible for the will, which cannot of its very nature do otherwise than
obey itself (for there is none who doth not will what he willeth, or who willeth
what he doth not will), to be deprived of its freedom. The will can, indeed, be
changed, but only to another will,- in such a way that it never loseth its freedom.
Therefore it can no more be deprived of its freedom than it can be deprived of
itself.
— Bernard of Clairvaux
Our will would not be a will if it were not in our power. And since it is in our
power, we are free with respect to it.
— Augustine
have a will—just is to be free on their account. But this is not the view held by most
then ask whether free will is a property that agents, so defined, can have. At least part of
my argument will be to suggest that this is a mistake. If free will is separated from agency
in this way, it loses coherence. I will focus primarily on this conceptual problem: how
can we even make sense of the idea of a free will? Drawing on Nagel’s argument for the
incoherence of free will, I will argue that the problem is even more complex than usually
assumed. The difficulty of understanding free will is not simply one of figuring out
with our actions in just the right way. Rather, I will argue, the difficulty involves trying to
make sense of how the movements of some region of the world could be assigned
1
selfhood, agency, or freedom. In the rest of this introduction, I will briefly note the
motivation for developing a theory of free will and the threat to it, introduce the idea of
deep temporality that I will use throughout, and provide a brief summary of the following
chapters.
What are the motivations for defending free will? In explaining the motivations
for a libertarian view of free will, Robert Kane outlines a number of things we might
want that seem to require that we be the originators of our actions. Among these, he lists
creativity, autonomy, desert, moral responsibility, being an appropriate object for reactive
attitudes, dignity, individuality, life-hopes, and genuine love or friendship. (Kane 1996 80
ff.) I confess that for many of these, I lack the intuition that they depend on any kind of
free will. For others, the sort of free will they require does not seem to demand anything
as extreme as origination. For some, the “challenge” supposedly posed by the absence of
free will, or at least of origination, seems to be simply the problem posed by the
possibility of prediction. Someone might be outraged, for example, if they were told that
their wonderfully inventive piano solo could have been predicted in detail even before
their birth. But this is hardly a pressing problem: whether someone might dislike the idea
that their actions are predictable has no bearing on free will unless it is at least possible to
predict the future with absolute certainty given the current state of the universe. But there
are reasons to doubt whether this is even a conceptual possibility (at least for any entity
that exists in time rather than eternity), and it is difficult to imagine it as a real
2
technological possibility. In any case, concerns that prediction could frustrate some of our
hopes or desires seems only tangentially connected with the issue of free will.
On the other hand, even the emphasis on our hopes or desires strikes me as
explain the world so as to match our desires. That we desire free will for one purpose or
another is neither here nor there, especially since we need hardly worry that eliminating
free will is likely to end things like genuine friendship or love—even were hard
determinism and all its consequences fully accepted by the general population, friendship
and love would no doubt go on, with or without an implicit change in the implications
involving them. Something more than a desire seems needed to provide a motivation for
free will. In this regard I want to emphasize moral responsibility. It is true that,
historically and to this day, one motive for developing theories of free will is a
example, may have a desire to hold others responsible. In this sense, the search for free
will once again involves only a desire to justify existing institutions, ones without which
we could likely continue to live quite well, and perhaps even better.
But there is also a sense of moral responsibility that has a stronger appeal, one
that goes beyond simple desire. I doubt we can get something important out of
detail would derail the purposes of an introduction, I see a theory of free will as providing
and to understand ourselves as able to respond to them, we need a theory of free will as
3
an unconditioned will. Of course even without freedom of any sort we can strive to
follow moral laws. But without an unconditioned will, our success or failure will be only
a matter of luck; it will not be attributable to us. And in this sense, the search for free will
desire. If morality commands us not merely to act in certain ways, but to act in those
ways on the basis of an unconditional acceptance of the moral motives as our sole
motives, we will need a free will to be able to fulfill our obligation. Of course this view
of morality is not especially popular in Anglophone ethics. It is simply the motivation for
seeking a coherent account of free will that I find especially compelling: we need free
will not in order to satisfy a desire to be moral agents, but in order to do our moral duty.
What is the threat to this sort of free will? In the course of the past few centuries,
but going back in time at least to the Stoics, the major threat to free will has been taken to
be causal determinism. Causal determinism is the thesis that the state of the universe at
any time is necessitated by the state of the universe at any previous time, together with
the laws of nature. Consequently, much ink has been spent on defending a space for
indeterminism within nature. But other philosophers have been skeptical of the idea that
causal determinism as such is the real threat to free will. Thomas Scanlon, for example,
This is the thesis that the events which are human actions, thoughts, and decisions
are linked to antecedent events by causal laws as deterministic as those governing
other goings-on in the universe. According to this thesis, given antecedent
conditions and the laws of nature, the occurrence of an act of a specific kind
follows, either with certainty or with a certain degree of probability, the
indeterminacy being due to chance factors of the sort involved in other natural
processes. (1988 152)
4
This thesis differs from determinism because it recognizes that indeterminism alone does
not provide any obvious help to defenders of free will. If our actions are not causally
necessitated but merely caused, this cannot help give us free will if the indeterminacy
involved in free will is of the same kind as the indeterminacy involved in any other, non-
agential events. It is something very much like the Causal Thesis that Nagel takes up in
his attack on free will. Throughout, I will generally use the term “eliminativism” to
describe this threat after introducing it in Chapter 2A. At times, however, I will simply
use “determinism,” with the caveat that causal determinism is not my only, or even
primary concern. After all, if—as the Causal Thesis suggests—my actions are no
different in terms of their production than any other event in the physical world, the
problem seems to arise that my actions are not attributable to me in any genuine sense;
they are not products of my agency, unless agency is merely the name of a more ordinary
type of causal process. And if my actions do not spring from me, and whether or not they
happen depends ultimately on events prior to any exercise of agency on my part, then my
actions are, for all intents and purposes, determined by non-agential factors.
I will describe shallow and deep temporality in terms of the temporal relation
each account allows between two entities. I will illustrate with a few examples. Imagine
that I am a sniper lying in ambush behind a rock, waiting for a caravan to go past below
me so I can startle the horses and pacify the guards. If I shoot too soon, they will return
fire and avoid the disaster I intend for them; if I wait too long, they will be able to escape.
5
I wait for the perfect moment, or at least the moment that seems perfect to me, and
deliberately pull the trigger. Here I have already made either a somewhat complex
choice, or a complex of two different choices: I have decided to shoot, and I have decided
on the exact moment at which I will shoot. In any case, this one decision, or this complex
of decisions, is made at an identifiable moment in time. This need not mean, of course,
that we can always pinpoint the moment with certainty, or that the moment is literally
momentary. The point, rather, is that it is at least in principle a choice that we can plot out
my finger on the trigger and perhaps half a minute after the first riders of the caravan
enter my visual field. This choice (or complex of choices), is thus an event, identifiable in
Suppose, now, that I am sitting in a bar. I have called my partner to tell her not to
wait up, because I expected to be working late. I managed to finish work early, however,
and decided to wind-down over a drink. A brunette approaches the bar and begins
speaking to me in riddles with a tantalizingly deep voice. Within this increasingly clichéd
and fully fictional scenario, suppose that I have a choice to make: I can finish my drink
and go home to surprise my partner by returning in time for supper, or I can make off
with it ex-nihilo. It presents itself as a choice for me because there is some at least
potential internal conflict, something in the way of my deciding effortlessly one way or
the other. For example, I have decided to be faithful to my partner and consider myself
bound by that decision (otherwise, what kind of decision would it be?). On the other
hand, in order to have a conflict, there must be something tempting me in the other
6
direction—a certain weakness for mysterious women, for example. The conflict here is
between two opposing attitudes or constituents of my will. It is only on the basis of a will
that I can face—and make—choices at all. The constituents of my will, moreover, range
across a number of choices or possible choices. They are therefore not simple events, but
If I did indeed at some point decide to be faithful to my partner, then that attitude
itself results from a choice made at some point in time; that is, such a constituent of the
will is reducible to an event. On the other hand, it is possible that I have always been
susceptible to mysterious women, and that no origin point in time can be found for this
susceptibility; that attitude, then, is something that is present within the time-frame of all
my choices; in a sense, it precedes any choices I might make on its basis and cannot be
mapped out relative to them on a timeline. When we say, for example, that lying has
always come naturally to Jack, that Jill has never been able to commit herself, or that
Snip has never been partial to candy corn, we imply a temporality of this sort. A classic
example here is the notion of an instinct in Freud’s sense. Freud speculated that the two
competing instincts, Eros and the death instinct, are not simply psychic entities—they are
already built into any living entity, no matter how simple. (Freud 1960) The instincts are
choices. But since to be human, to be alive at all, is already to have these instincts, it is
not through occurring (as events in time), but through existing that they serve their
function as constituents of the will. They are the sort of attitudes that do not belong on a
timeline along with the events of our choices. In other words—and nothing is meant to
ride on this example—our wills make possible and structure the events of choosing, but
7
the constituents of our wills may or may not themselves be reducible to prior events,
I will call an account temporally shallow when all the elements among which it
postulates relations are either events or reducible to events. For example, if I choose to be
a clown and then, on the basis of this attitude, choose to make a joke at every possible
occasion, then the relation here is a temporally shallow one. Similarly, if my actions are
caused by my will, which itself is the causal result of other events stretching back into the
distant past, this account is temporally shallow. It is shallow because every element in the
account can be plotted on the same timeline as occurring earlier or later than another
element. On the other hand, a temporally deep account will include at least one
nor reducible to an event. To anticipate: I will argue that free will requires a temporally
deep account on which our will is not reducible to any events and is also our own.
I will split up free will and moral responsibility into two discussions, each
addressed in two chapters. Chapters 2 and 3 focus on free will. In chapter 2, I work out
strategies are likely to work against it. The aim here will not be to examine cutting edge
work on free will, and my argument is not meant to be a knock-down attack on all
attempts to resolve the free will problem. Both contemporary compatibilist and libertarian
accounts are frequently much more subtle and involved than my comments here will
8
suggest. My aim is only to make a plausible case for the view that eliminativism cannot
be overcome along the usual lines of development, and to suggest that ownership and
deep temporality are needed to resolve the problems. Chapter 3 will develop these themes
further. It is sometimes thought that determinism is an entirely external problem, one that
arises in a purely artificial elevation of abstract theory over concrete experience. I will
argue that this is a mistake; experience can give rise to determinist intuitions, and do so
from the first-person perspective. Determinism is then not only an abstract theoretical
problem, but one internal to the very experience of agency. From here I proceed to
develop a concept of deep temporality on the basis of Korsgaard’s early work, ultimately
concluding that it runs into the same aporia faced by other approaches to free will.
Here I change emphasis. Since attempting to develop a theory of free will runs
needed to offer a response to Galen Strawson’s argument for the impossibility of moral
played by Nagel in the chapters on free will. I work out and defend attributionism as a
response to Strawson in Chapter 4. Chapter 5 works out the control condition necessary
Problems inherent in this account of agency and responsibility turn us again to ownership
and temporality. In Chapter 6 I finally turn to the task of working out the Heideggerian
9
2
Free Will
A. Eliminativism
The starting point for Nagel’s conception of freedom lies in his distinction
between the subjective and the objective standpoint or point of view or, to take another
formulation, the internal and external perspective. Subjective and objective are, on this
account, not two distinct standpoints, but operate instead in a continuum going from more
subjective to ever more objective points of view. The movement from subjectivity to
Though Nagel does not cite the source from which this view seems to be adapted
(namely, Hegel’s Phenomenology of Spirit), the basic idea is a familiar one. It involves
recognizing our own relation to the world as itself a part of the world open to
that the “world” is approachable through largely empirical means, a certain tension
On one hand, the transcendental position seems already to be excluded from any claims
10
ultimately understandable within the world. On the other hand, however, the Kantian
specter within Hegel’s work materializes here: if we attain to greater objectivity by taking
up a new relation to the world, one which now sees our previous relation to the world as
part of that world, then objectivity has certain built-in limits.1 A relation is always
between two entities, but only one side of that relation (the world) is open to empirical
analysis; the other side, the self, will always remain concealed. This tension becomes
This formulation is slightly misleading: the “ourselves” that we place in the world when
we strive for a more objective view are not identical to the “ourselves” that examine this
new world. Though something of the self must—as one of the relata—enter into a
conception of the world that includes our prior relation to the world, something else must
serve as a relata in this new relation. Insofar as any relation to the world, no matter how
objective, is still a relation, something will be left out of it. And while some aspects of
our subjective view may come to seem like mere appearance, that which stands outside of
appearance.
Nagel does seem to recognize the tension when he admits that, since we always
see the world from a particular perspective, a fully objective view, a “view from
nowhere,” is not actually open to us. But the tension seems to have particularly
1
See Žižek (1993) for a somewhat Kantian reading of Hegel along these lines.
11
problematic consequences in Nagel’s account of freedom. As we will see, something very
un-Hegelian happens in that account: when we take an objective view of our freedom, the
self becomes integrated into the world and our understanding of the self changes; but our
understanding of the world, oddly, remains the same. Nagel’s point seems to be that it is
the—in principle unattainable—ideal of objectivity that the subject be placed fully into
the world, so that nothing remains on the subjective side of the relation. But this appeal to
an ideal condition does not explain why the subject must be assimilated to the object.
After all, a move toward greater objectivity might, for all Nagel has said, involve the
assimilation of the world to the subject, and consequently a view that does not speak to
every point of view from no point of view, but instead speaks from every point of view
by speaking from one point of view. Nagel’s account of objectivity is thus directed
toward a certain outcome, a certain ideal of objectivity, but his conception of this ideal is
Nagel’s account of freedom begins with a distinction between agency and action
on one hand, and freedom on the other. Nagel suggests that agency is automatically
threatened by a more objective view of the world: “my doing of an act—or the doing of
(1986 111) The solution, then, is to classify action as a basic and irreducible category.
This does not, however, mean that freedom can be treated in the same way: we might
have agency without having free agency. Clearly what Nagel wants here is to be able to
analyze the problem of freedom in isolation from various difficulties in the philosophy of
action, but he does not explain what he means in claiming both that action is irreducible
and that such a view of agency is possible without a view of free agency. There is no
12
explanation of why freedom—which Nagel thinks is threatened by the objective view in
the same way that agency seems to be—cannot likewise be seen as an irreducible
category. On the other hand, many authors (e.g., Hornsby (2003 283), Velleman (1992
467)) have taken Nagel’s account as raising the threat of disappearing agency, and not
As is already clear, Nagel believes that the objective standpoint undermines our
conception of ourselves as free, and his task in dealing with this is twofold. First, he must
show in what way the objective standpoint seems to undermine freedom. Second, and
more importantly, he must demonstrate that, when we attempt to discover what it is that
the objective standpoint seems to undermine, “we end up with something that is either
former question of why we cannot save freedom from the threat of the objective view by
declaring it, like agency, to be an irreducible category. The answer is that we cannot
make freedom irreducible because we cannot explain what it is, though again there will
assumptions about human freedom. I call one the problem of autonomy and the other the
problem of responsibility; the first presents itself initially as a problem about our own
freedom and the second as a problem about the freedom of others.” (1986 111)2 If both
2
I should perhaps note that Nagel’s use of the term “autonomy” here is problematic, since what he means
by it actually matches up much more closely to what is generally meant by free will than by any accounts
of autonomy. I will use Nagel’s terminology, but with the caveat that his conception of autonomy, by
insisting on the presence of having alternatives or being able to “do otherwise,” in itself already contradicts
the idea of autonomy. That may well strengthen Nagel’s point; but it nevertheless seems odd to define a
term in an idiosyncratic way simply in order to show that that term, on that definition, stands for something
incoherent. To see the contradiction, we can look at Nagel’s footnote on p. 116, in which, responding to
13
our own freedom and the freedom of others are threatened by the objective view, and if
neither is intelligible, then the idea of freedom does indeed seem to collapse.
Initially it seems to us that we are constantly faced with open possibilities and that
attempting to see ourselves from outside, we can consider not only the possibility as it
appears to us—that is, as open—but also the various background conditions of our
actions, both outside and inside ourselves. From an internal perspective, we see ourselves
as having choices when we act. But when we take an external perspective, we must look
not only at the choice directly behind an action, but also at the various antecedent
conditions that make up the person, and then it seems like nothing is really open to us.
“While we cannot fully occupy this perspective toward ourselves while acting, it seems
possible that many of the alternatives that appear to lie open when viewed from an
internal perspective would seem closed from this outer point of view.” (1986 113)
Much rests on whether there is something coherent in this: if we fully lay out the
various attitudes of the agent, “it is not clear how this would leave anything further for
rather than merely as the scene of the outcome—the person whose act it is. If they are left
open given everything about him, what does he have to do with the result?” (1986 113-
114) Is there anything coherent in the idea of a “person” or, more specifically, an “agent,”
being merely “the scene of the outcome”? Isn’t a “scene” in this sense itself not a person
or agent? Freedom and agency seem to come bundled together, so that in making one
Wolf (1980), he expresses strong doubt about the idea that determination of any sort could be compatible
with autonomy. But if autonomy involves the idea of self-rule, and self-rule is in turn understood as
involving—at the least—consistency in our choices, then an autonomy without any determination
whatsoever seems already to be ruled out. A fully indeterminate choice is arbitrary, and anarchy does not
sit well with rule of any sort.
14
incoherent, we undermine the other as well. Furthermore, Nagel notes that the threat to
actions. The question of whether or not we are “authors” of our actions seems to depend
on whether we ourselves or various impersonal conditions are the causes of these actions.
When we view ourselves externally, we see ourselves as part of the world, rather
than something standing apart from it. And once we see ourselves as part of the world,
our freedom is threatened regardless of whether or not that world is deterministic. If this
world is deterministic, then our actions are caused by antecedent circumstances, which
are themselves caused by prior events, in a chain stretching back to the beginning of the
universe. On this view, it does not make sense to say that we have anything to contribute.
If, on the other hand, the world is not deterministic, it is still simply a collection of
various entities and events, and these entities and events are still impersonal. While there
may be genuinely open possibilities in front of us, the events involved in selecting one or
authors. At this stage of the argument, Nagel is not trying to prove any point about
freedom: he is only attempting to bring out an intuition, a doubt about whether or not we
are free, or autonomous, that occurs to us the moment we start thinking about ourselves
as merely parts of the world. As soon as we do that, we are bound to recognize that there
are many things about our motivations that we do not know, and that these must cause
even the motivations that we are aware of, and if the influence of all such factors is
autonomy that can answer the question, and Nagel’s main argument is that no such
15
account can be made coherent. The idea of autonomy, “presents itself initially as the
belief that antecedent circumstances, including the condition of the agent, leave some of
the things we will do undetermined: they are determined only by our choices, which are
motivationally explicable but not themselves causally determined.” (1986 114) Since the
objective view explains the occurrence of every event in terms of causal mechanisms, the
That is, it must be able to explain actions solely in terms of the motives and reasons of
the agent. And this, Nagel thinks, is the real stumbling block, because any such account
wants both to provide an explanation of action and to reject the possibility of such an
explanation.
We can see this last point clearly as soon as we try to offer a non-causal but
complete explanation for why an agent chose to do one thing rather than another. The
answer, presumably, will be in terms of the agent’s reasons for choosing that action. But
if the agent had instead made a different choice, then we would again have to appeal to
the agent’s reasons to explain that choice. But since at the moment of any choice the
agent only has a fixed set of reasons, this implies that whatever he chooses, each choice
can be explained by means of the very same reasons. If the same set of reasons can
explain both why an agent did one thing and why—if he had so chosen—he could have
done another, then clearly this set of reasons does not provide a complete explanation of
the choice; something more must be involved. But to explain this something more we are
forced either to invoke further reasons, which leads to an infinite regress, or we must turn
be explained in causal terms. There is, on Nagel’s view, no way out of this predicament:
16
either invoking the agent’s reasons cannot explain why the choice was made to do one
thing rather than another, or the invocation explains the agent’s choice but only by
Nagel suggests that what gives the idea of autonomy its force in the first place is
precisely the objective view. Since this view opens up the possibility of knowing
ourselves from the outside, it also seems to suggest that, once we know our motivations,
we should be able to evaluate them and choose whether or not to be influenced by them
in our actions. But this aspiration is clearly made impossible by that same objective view.
To be able to evaluate and to either endorse or reject all of our motivational states, we
would have to somehow separate ourselves from those motivational states. But this idea
is incoherent. What, after all, is a self separated from all of its reasons and motivations?
On what grounds does it endorse or reject anything about itself? We can evoke such a self
only if we are willing to fully give up on any account of explaining its actions, but then
we have simply conceded that the entire defense of the idea of autonomy rests on an
inexplicable intuition. Either the self is part of the objective world, in which case it is
ultimately causally determined in its choices, or it is outside the world, in which case it is
no longer coherently described as a self, since it is a self without reasons and without
motivations. “We belong to a world we have not created and of which we are the
products” (1986 119), and therefore we have no way of standing apart from it. We want
to fully encompass ourselves and create ourselves from the ground up, and at the same
3
Nagel is invoking a classic problem that first raised its head in theology: we are dependent, finite beings
and yet somehow capable of acting with free will. As I will argue, Heidegger takes up this exact problem
and reformulates it as the basis of a solution to the problem of freedom rather than the conclusion of an
argument against it.
17
Nagel’s argument for the incoherence of responsibility is largely the same. “To
praise or blame is not to judge merely that what has happened is a good or a bad thing,
but to judge the person for having done it, in view of the circumstances under which it
was done. The difficulty is to explain how this is possible—how we can do more than
welcome or regret the event, or perhaps the psychology of the agent.” (1986 120) It
seems we cannot hold anyone responsible for actions because actions are just events of a
certain kind, and it does not make sense to pass moral judgment on events. Instead, we
must enter into the psychology of the agent, seeing the alternatives open to him from his
perspective, and understanding his reasons for taking the praiseworthy or blameworthy
alternative.
soon as we try to understand the alternatives from the agent’s motivational standpoint, we
are presented with two possibilities. Either the agent did what he did for no reason at all,
in which case it would be difficult to understand how he could be responsible for the
outcome, or the agent acted for reasons, but these reasons are only the products of
something beyond them over which the agent had no control. “Either something other
than the agent’s reasons explains why he acted for the reasons he did, or nothing does. In
either case the external standpoint sees the alternatives not as alternatives for the agent,
but as alternatives for the world, which involve the agent. And the world, of course, is not
an agent and cannot be held responsible.” (1986 123) The case of responsibility turns out
exactly like that of autonomy: we have no way of assigning the action to the self that
performed it as his responsibility. The action is either an event that occurred for no reason
18
In light of this point, I want to again question whether agency can be understood
on an objective view even if free agency cannot. If alternatives are really alternatives for
the world, rather than for the agent, the agent contributes nothing either to the explanation
or to the ontology of action—“agent” is only the name for a particular, bounded scene of
events. At least some minimal conception of freedom seems necessary if we are to have
This is, more or less, the whole of the story Nagel gives about freedom. Although
he recognizes that the internal view of our decisions cannot be done away with, he does
not think that anything close to a satisfactory treatment of freedom has yet been
proposed. Consequently, both autonomy and responsibility are, on the final analysis,
grounded in incoherent accounts. Nagel does, however, suggest that the objective view
can offer another kind of freedom, one that may not match the aspirations of acting from
outside the world, but at least operates as a substitute for the desires that lead us to
believe in freedom. This substitute lies in morality. The belief in freedom, Nagel
suggests, is really an expression of human beings’ desire “to be able to stand back from
the motives and reasons and values that influence their choices, and submit to them only
if they are acceptable.” (1986 127) The satisfaction of this desire does not require us to
step entirely outside of ourselves; it requires only that we be capable of discovering and
being influenced by motives, reasons, and values that are themselves objective. In other
words, the desire for freedom is really satisfied by objective norms. Morality is “a
practical analogue of the epistemological hope for harmony with the world.” (1986 127)
Morality opens up the possibility for a kind of freedom, and consequently we are
19
for actions and allowed ourselves to be guided by them. Morality can replace autonomy,
Nagel argues, because it gives us a way of satisfying a desire: the desire to have objective
criteria from which to evaluate our motives. I have a sneaking suspicion that this is a bit
of a theoretical trick: although most people do evaluate some of their motives to some
extent, it is hard to imagine that there is some universal human desire to act on objective
criteria, and that this is what the desire for freedom really comes to. To anticipate my
argument somewhat, this hope for harmony can be seen not as a conscious desire, but as
light of it without achieving it: that is, roughly put, we do not need to “achieve” the level
of objective norms in order to be free. Rather, we can be free by virtue of acting in light
of our relation to the future; our actions can themselves be guided—well or poorly—by
As noted, Nagel claims that the problems of autonomy and responsibility initially
present themselves to us, respectively, as problems about our own freedom and the
freedom of others. If we look at autonomy and responsibility in this way, then it does not
seem too difficult to admit that these are simply appearances—because we do not act
with full knowledge of every event involved in the production of our actions, it seems to
us as if our actions are fully under our control; because we resent and want to punish
others, we fool ourselves into thinking that they are fully responsible. But something
problem about our own responsibility. If I have acted wrongly and know that I have acted
wrongly, then it seems to me that I am responsible for having acted wrongly. Of course
20
theory to demonstrate that I was not in fact responsible will come off as a kind of
rationalization and self-deception. Of course it may turn out that this is right—that, in
fact, I am not responsible for anything I do. But this point has implications that differ
from the implication of the claim that others are not responsible for what they do. For
even if I am not responsible for what I do, in claiming that “I could not have done
otherwise,” I am offering an excuse. If I fail to follow norms that I accept as binding, the
excuse has a necessary ring of self-deception about it: I know what I had to do, but I
failed to do it because what I do is not up to me. There are cases in which this will be
accurate, but for it to be accurate at a global level, we would have to entirely give up on
ever taking responsibility for who we are and what we do. Our relation to ourselves
primary aim of developing a theory of free will. And avoiding this problem is crucial if
we take moral responsibility not as a problem about third-personal freedom, but as a first-
personal concern: unless I can be genuinely responsible, even having access to objective
morality will not by itself allow me to follow that morality. From an objective standpoint,
either the world—or at least the region of it embodied in me—will take up the moral
norms or it will not; but I do not have control over whether or not I allow myself to be
guided by the question of whether or not I have any choice about the morality of my
actions.
Let us return now to freedom and the question of what kind of freedom the
objective view might require us to reject. Every choice, as an event in the world, must be
caused by previous events. In the case of actions, the previous events are motives or
21
attitudes. For an action to be freely chosen, on the account Nagel lays out, its causes must
also be freely chosen, since otherwise the action will depend on something outside the
agent’s control. The motives or attitudes themselves, then, would also have to be, or be
the products of, choices. The same would go for any causal predecessors to the relevant
motives or attitudes. But the string of causal choices will have to go back to before the
agent’s birth, all the way to the origin of the world, and certainly no agent is responsible
for that. If any free actions were to exist, then, there would have to be at least one choice
of the agent, making up some attitude (motive, reason, or value) that breaks this causal
chain. But since this choice would be an event in time, it must have causal antecedents;
shallow account of agency. Freedom, seen as an agent’s ability to create in time an event
without causal conditions, cannot make sense within a world in which an event, by
definition, has a cause. A choice, as an occurrence in some present moment, must have
prior occurrences causing it. It is therefore not surprising that, in offering a substitute for
freedom, Nagel looks to “hope” for “harmony with the world.” This would be no more
coherent if this hope were for some future event that takes place outside the causal
framework, but Nagel presents it instead as a hope for a kind of state, one in which the
ask whether freedom is this kind of state, rather than property of an event. What Nagel
rejects is free action; he does not touch essentially on free will, except insofar as the
factors (motives, reasons, and values) that make up a will are themselves understood as
actions. The problem with any temporally shallow account, in fact, is that it reduces any
22
candidate for freedom to the status of an event. But this automatically seems to
undermine not simply freedom, but agency as such; if everything that occurs is seen
merely as an event in a causal chain in the objective world, then it is unclear what actions
have to do with an agent, except insofar as that agent is a scene of their occurrence.
What is happening here? In recognizing that the question of freedom is not likely
to go away even after we take up the objective view, Nagel remarks that “I cannot say
what would, if it were true, support our sense that our free actions originate within us.
Yet the sense of an internal explanation persists—an explanation insulated from the
external view which is complete in itself and renders illegitimate all further requests for
“within us” is contrasted with that action’s being an “event in the world.” This contrast
suggests that an action cannot originate both in us and in the world. The agent is already
taken outside the framework of the world. And this removal of the agent as something
internal from the world as something external creates a rift. Sealing that rift will require
Nagel’s argument attacks the coherence of the idea that an action can originate in
us. Origination involves cause, and the argument is that neither an action nor its
precursors can be caused both by us and by the world. But what we are trying to
understand is what it means for something to be not merely an event in the world, but
also my action, or my choice, or my attitude, and this semantically implies, first of all, not
just origination but ownership. And ownership, obviously, does not imply origination or
this idea of ownership. This, in turn, can help us to understand how an agent that is fully
23
in the world can, at the same time, stand in a different sense “outside” the world, at least
relations. For what distinguishes agents from other entities, what places them outside the
domain of mere causal explanation, and what accounts for “our sense that our free actions
originate within us” is that we are the only sorts of beings who are capable of owning our
actions, choices, and attitudes. Origination and authorship seem to be grounded in such
ownership, not the other way around. To anticipate: that my will is mine, in some sense,
B. Compatibilism
work of Donald Davidson and Harry Frankfurt, the two figures whose approaches
of action and free will. This is largely because these two introduced analyses that
describe action and freedom in terms of the relations between events or entities
actions (and intentions) and reasons; in Frankfurt’s case it is between first-order desires
and second-order volitions. These attempts open a path toward a temporally deep account
strength of these compatibilist theories is that the tools of their analysis can be—and have
24
that any theory of agency, regardless of its commitments to causal determinism, would
have to satisfy. But these theories also suffer from a corresponding weakness: their dual
applicability makes them inherently unstable, and when pushed from either direction they
tend to collapse into either eliminativism or libertarianism. This section, then, sets up the
account of agency that is taken up by libertarians but, at the same time, is meant to work
because they allowed for a middle path between the highly problematic compatibilism of
the times and the mysterious libertarianism that seemed like the only alternative. The
action, on that view, is nothing mysterious: it can be easily explained by reference to the
causal framework. On Ayer’s account, for example, the apparently problematic nature of
causal determinism arises entirely out of our loose understanding of this term. We tend to
imagine an effect (an action) being somehow compelled by its cause, while “the fact is
simply that when an event of one type occurs, an event of another type occurs also, in a
certain temporal or spatio-temporal relation to the first. The rest is only metaphor. And it
is because of the metaphor, and not because of the fact, that we come to think that there is
an antithesis between causality and freedom.” (Ayer 1982 22) But it is not so simple to
decisively distinguish between compulsion and causation; if all we are doing is tracing
out causal connections between events, there seems to be little reason to care about the
types of events involved. On another note, as Frankfurt argues, this account only explains
25
free action, in a sense in which we can attribute it to any being with purposes from
chimpanzee to spider. (Frankfurt 1982 82) If you hold down a spider’s legs, it cannot
move, but if you leave it be, then it seems to enjoy the same freedom of action as any
human being. To distinguish between ourselves and spiders, Frankfurt proposes that
another kind of freedom is needed: a freedom not merely of action, but of will.
different type of cause: unlike the causality involved in scientific explanation of events,
occurrent causality, free action had to be explained in terms of agent causality. Normally,
an event is caused by another event, which itself follows from prior events according to
natural laws. A free action, on the other hand, is caused by an agent, and this cause has no
necessitating precursors. The theory, as expounded by Chisholm (1982, 1966) and Taylor
(1966, 1983), states that in order for an agent to be responsible for an action, two
conditions must be met. First, the agent must be the sole cause of his action. Second, to
avoid the action being randomly produced, the agent must have a reason for his action,
stated in terms of purposes. Asking why an agent did something, “which is clearly a
request for a reason, is almost never a request for a recital of causes. It is rather a request
for a statement of purpose or aim.” (Taylor 1966 141) But immediate problems with this
theory arise. First, if an action is fully explained by means of reasons, it is unclear what
explanation is supposed to explain the action insofar as causes are thought necessary to
explain events in general. However, the idea of an uncaused cause within the natural
world, as an explanatory feature, has failed to achieve widespread support. If the appeal
26
occurrent causality. If, on the other hand, accounts in terms of reasons do not involve
I. Davidson
This brief survey of the difficulties should, hopefully, suffice to show the
importance of Davidson’s seemingly modest proposal that reasons simply are causes of
actions. It is the bringing together of these two conditions for action into a unified
explanation that accounts for the historical importance of Davidson’s major entry onto
the scene with his “Actions, Reasons, and Causes.” Davidson’s causal theory of action
intentions on one hand, and those in terms of causes on the other, fall into two distinct
language games that must not be confused. Davidson’s response was to separate
linguistic description from ontology: we can give two different descriptions of an action,
and on one it will be rational (and intentional), while on the other it will be merely
physical. But these explanations are compatible with each other because the action in
question is, ontologically, a single event, where events are understood as “unrepeatable,
dated individuals”. (Davidson 1980f 209) This move will underlie the description of
The argument itself is typically elegant. Davidson argues that intention is a basic
concept that allows us to distinguish actions from the broader class of physical events. He
distinguishes between three sorts of situations in which an event (his example is the
spilling of coffee) is attributed to an agent: “in the first, I do it intentionally; in the second
27
I do not do it intentionally but it is my action (I thought it was tea); in the third it is not
my action at all (you jiggle my hand)." (1980b 45) The second case is the problematic
one: I am holding a cup of coffee, but I believe it is tea. I want to spill tea and thus tip my
cup, but to my surprise it is coffee that I spill. In this case my action of spilling coffee is
not intentional; so how is it an action at all? Davidson’s solution is to note that an action
can admit of a number of descriptions. “My proposal might then be put: a person is the
agent of an event if and only if there is a description of what he did that makes true a
sentence that says he did it intentionally.” (1980b 46) The spilling of the coffee in the
second case is an action because under another description, like “trying to spill tea,” it is
intentional. An action, then, is an event that has at least one correct description on which
it is intentional.
the basis of, what Davidson calls a primary reason. “R is a primary reason why an agent
performed the action A under the description d only if R consists of a pro attitude of the
agent towards actions with a certain property, and a belief of the agent that A, under the
description d, has that property.” (1980a 5) A primary reason is thus analyzed into two
component parts. The first is a pro attitude, or an attitude in favor of certain types of
actions. Davidson presents these attitudes in a very broad way, so that they contain all
sorts of wants, desires, obligations, customs, values, and in general any sort of attitude
capable of motivating an agent. The second component is a belief that a particular action
that the agent has an opportunity to perform is an action of a type for which the agent has
28
longstanding (or sudden) need for a new thrill, coupled with a belief that jumping out of
The task now is to show that these reasons are causes of the actions they
rationalize. Davidson argues that unless we take reasons to be causes, we have no way of
might, make any rational sense is bound to appear as nothing but a reflex, a spasm, or a
seizure. Being explicable in terms of reasons is thus a condition of possibility for being
understood as an intentional action. But even if we grant that an action must allow for a
rationalizing explanation, this does not yet guarantee that the reason for the action is a
cause. Davidson’s response here is that we have no other way of explaining the relation
of the reason for the action to the action itself. Consider a case where an agent has two
reasons for doing something: he might raise his hand to ask a question, or he might do so
to stretch his shoulders. If he raises his hand and this is an action, then it must be done for
one of the reasons. But we cannot appeal to the mere presence of either reason to explain
the “because” in “he raised his arm because he wanted to stretch out his shoulder” in a
non-circular way. We can only say that this is the reason because it is the reason, which
fails to contribute any kind of explanation at all where two or more possible reasons are
in play. Davidson’s account allows us to explain what makes this reason into the reason
why the action was done: the agent’s desire to ask a question, together with his belief that
he could do so only if he first raised his arm, caused him to raise his arm, and thus we can
29
Action is thus explained entirely within a causal nexus; the agent seemingly plays
no role whatsoever, leading to “an agentless semantics of action” (Ricoeur 1992 87)4 in
which an action is nothing but an event produced by other events. This may seem
surprising: pro attitudes, after all are specifically described by Davidson as covering “not
only permanent character traits that show themselves in a lifetime of behaviour, like love
of children or a taste for loud company, but also the most passing fancy that prompts a
unique action, like a sudden desire to touch a woman’s elbow.” (1980a 4) Are all of these
events? Yes, it turns out. In the case of the latter sorts of attitudes, those which appear
suddenly, it is not the attitude itself, but its onset that is the event under consideration. In
the case of longstanding or permanent attitudes, on the other hand, the relevant event
might be not the onset of the attitude itself, but rather the sudden recognition or
realization that one has this attitude. My love of chocolate is not usually in the forefront
of my thoughts, but springs into existence, so to speak, the moment I am face to face with
a chocolate mousse. It is thus my love for eating chocolate, coupled with a belief that the
cake in front of me is made of the stuff, that causes me to dive into it headlong.
Explaining just how reasons can be causes opens the way for Davidson’s first
strategy of getting freedom into the equation, which involves his theory of anomalous
monism. The approach is designed to show, on the one hand, that we cannot construct
any strict laws by means of which to predict mental events, due to “the holistic character
of the cognitive field. Any effort at increasing the accuracy and power of a theory of
behaviour forces us to bring more and more of the whole system of the agent’s beliefs
and motives directly into account. But in inferring this system from the evidence, we
4
This is a polemical claim: the agent does play some role in Davidson’s account, though Davidson never
clarifies this role. Ricoeur’s description is therefore apt, if slightly misleading.
30
necessarily impose conditions of coherence, rationality and consistency.” (1980g 231)
But this structure does not have the form of a physical system, and we thus cannot hope
to find a direct correlation between the physical and the mental. This means that, even if
we are in possession of all strict laws for predicting physical events, mental events will
The theory is characterized by monism because Davidson does believe that all
events are physical events, but it is anomalous because mental events are not subject to
the laws that govern physical events. The reason is that a mental event is a physical event
under another description. Since laws apply only to the events under their physical
descriptions, the same laws do not apply to mental events. Furthermore, for Davidson,
knowing all the physical events that occur would not tell us all the mental events—the
correlation between mental and physical events is token-token, not type-type, which
prevents any crude reductionism. Thus, for Davidson, although we can speak of actions
as caused by reasons (because reasons, as mental events, are also describable as physical
Whatever freedom this opens, however, is far more vague than Davidson
suggests. For one thing, it is obvious that what is normally understood as freedom is
explicable in terms of such laws as an action. Anomalous monism suggests that physical
description cannot eliminate mental description, but this doesn’t guarantee freedom of
any sort; it guarantees only talk of freedom. Second, whatever is free here, it is not an
agent. It is some set of events, perhaps a rationally and coherently organized set, but what
31
this set has to do with an agent is never specified. A real account of freedom would have
to take the extra step of relating desires, intentions, reasons, and so on to the agent whose
mental states they are; this is a bit difficult, however, given that all the states have been
characterized as events.
discourse, and it is similarly compatibilist. What he wishes to show is not that freedom is
compatible with determinism (he believes that “Hobbes, Locke, Hume, Moore, Schlick,
Ayer, Stevenson, and a host of others have done what can be done, or ought ever to have
been needed, to remove the confusions that can make determinism seem to frustrate
freedom”5 (1980c 63)), but that freedom can be understood as a causal power. This
involves explaining how an action can be both free and caused. Typically, for Davidson,
he approaches the question not by showing that freedom is a causality, but by attacking
the leading objection to that view. The objection is that—as we have already seen—if an
action is caused by something else, then the question arises whether or not the cause itself
is free.
In order to be eligible as a cause, the event mentioned must be separate from the
action; but if it is separate from the action, there is, it seems, always the
possibility of asking about it, whether the agent is free to do it… The only hope
for the causal analysis is to find states or events which are causal conditions of
intentional actions, but which are not themselves actions or events about which
the question whether the agent can perform them can intelligibly be raised. (1980c
72)
The candidates for this position are the pro attitudes and beliefs of the agent. These
conditions cause intentional actions but, at the same time, they are not actions
themselves. “The antecedent condition does not mention something that is an action, so
the question whether the agent can [or is free to] do it does not arise.” (1980c 73)
5
Anomalous monism, on the other hand, does seem to be an attempt to answer the first question.
32
At one level, this is a neat solution to the problem: freedom is a causal power
because to perform a free action is simply for that action to be caused by an agent’s
reasons. The action itself is free because there is no further question about whether or not
the agent was free to take up those reasons—the reasons are not things the agent does. Of
freedom, and Davidson notes this by mentioning that he does “not want to suggest that
the nature of an agent’s beliefs and desires, and the question how he acquired them, are
irrelevant to questions of how free he, or his actions, are. But these questions are on a
different and more sophisticated level from that of our present discussion.” (1980c 73)
Davidson does not return to these questions, though given his list of compatibilist heroes,
one may assume that by the nature of an agent’s reasons and how he came to acquire
them, Davidson means something like whether the reasons are products of brainwashing,
compulsion, or ignorance. But even given this caveat, we may ask whether Davidson’s
question of whether it makes sense to say that someone’s actions are free in a situation
where he would have done the same thing even if he had not chosen to. It turns out that
the answer is yes, because “even in the overdetermined cases, something rests with the
agent. Not, as it happens, what he does (when described in a way that leaves open
whether it was intentional), but whether he does it intentionally. His action, in the sense
in which action depends on intentionality, occurs or not as he wills; what he does, in the
broader sense, may occur whether or not he wills it.” (1980c 75) Given that an agent is
not physically prevented from doing something, and his doing of it is caused by his
33
reasons, the action is free. Otherwise, it is not even an action. But what it means to say
that “something rests with the agent” remains mysterious. What makes the action free on
this account is that it is (1) rationalized by a combination of a pro attitude and belief (a
primary reason) and (2) caused by that reason. But surely this is where questions about
(a) the nature and kind of acquisition of the pro attitudes and beliefs, and (b) the agent’s
role in making the reasons into a cause, come into play. The role of the agent cannot be
irrelevant here: if there are no strict psychophysical laws under which the relation of
reason to action falls (as anomalous monism maintains), then the causality of these
reasons remains inexplicable. What Davidson’s analysis shows us is that, given that an
intentional action has been performed, we can then give a causal description of this
action. It does not show how freedom could be a causal power—Davidson has only
repeated that causal relations hold for all cases of acting. Davidson’s account is thus
internally incomplete. Something further is needed to explain what makes the reason
essays, Davidson had looked only at two usages of “intention”: the “intention with” and
with which Odysseus lied about his name,” “Mercader intentionally stabbed Trotsky with
the ice pick”); but what about “intending to” (“Heidegger intended to prepare the way for
the fleeing or arrival of the gods” or “Bush intended to finish the war in Iraq within
weeks”)? The difficulty is that with the first two usages, intention is analyzed as a
component of an action, but in the third case we have an intention directed toward the
future, and such an intention may never be fulfilled by an action at all. For example, I
34
intend to write a novel but never get around to it; my intention may well be sincere, but
other factors (laziness, lack of time, lack of talent) get in the way. What is this strange
entity, this “pure intending”? After an extended analysis, Davidson finds a way to bring
pure intendings in line with his overall theory without making them into private mental
entities. He does this by distinguishing between prima facie judgments (“judgements that
actions are desirable in so far as they have a certain attribute” (1980e 98)) and all-out
judgment is merely a judgment, for example, that getting rid of eavesdroppers behind
curtains is desirable. But such judgments are, despite providing reasons for acting, not
sufficient to cause an action because it is entirely possible for me to have the judgment in
question but also believe that the person eavesdropping behind the curtain is my greatest
love, and I do not want to harm her. An unconditional judgment, on the other hand, is the
judgment that a certain action is good all things considered; that is, in light of my other
beliefs, it is the right thing to do. So, if I believe that the person behind the curtain is the
king, then I might make the unconditional judgment to run the curtain through with my
sword.
Somewhat incredibly and all too neatly, then, it turns out that a pure intention is
really a kind of judgment that is identical to the judgment that accompanies any action.
This is, perhaps, not so odd: since action is by definition intentional, it might seem to
follow that there should be no important difference between the intention that
accompanies an action and one that precedes it. The only difference is, for Davidson, a
fairly minor one: a pure intention “is directed to the future.” (1980e 98) In other words, it
differs from the intention that accompanies an action only in that it involves a deferral of
35
the action (I do not say that the difference is only some stretch of time between the
intention and the action, since the action might never occur—it is the deferral that is
important). Ricoeur’s critique comes in at this point. He argues that “Davidson has
underestimated the unsettling effect that this addition of all-out judgment imposes on the
earlier analysis” (1992 82), because this introduces a temporal dimension into the
framework, and it is a dimension that necessarily involves the agent. Davidson has,
accompany actions; but the analysis should go the other way: “with the delay there
appears not only the character of anticipation—the intention’s empty sighting, as one
would say in a Husserlian perspective—but also the prospective character of the very
condition of agency, as one would say in a Heideggerian perspective.” (1992 82) In other
words, we should interpret all intention in terms of intention to, reversing Davidson’s
analysis, because action as such involves as its condition a reference to the future. This
reference, further, is inseparable from a reference to an agent, that is, the being for whom
We can go a step further here: the elimination of the agent from the analysis
obscures the relation between the intention and the action. If the action fulfills the
intention’s empty sighting, surely the agent is the one who brings this fulfillment into
being, but the question of how is left open. If I have a pure intention and then act on it,
what leads me from the pure intending to the action? Is it merely a further belief? Or a
account of the reason an agent acts at just that moment, which is not reducible to the
reason for the action itself, which is just the reason for the intention. This question is
36
related to the earlier one of what makes a reason into the cause of an action. And by way
of pure intending, it becomes tied also to the question of what connects any intention to
the event that it makes into an action, or any reason to the action it causes. An agent is
not merely a medium for these strange connections; not a “scene” in which the events of
the world play out. The agent—to be an agent—must be active in this process, and that
the process does not make sense without this activity lends credence to that idea.6
I want to wrap up the discussion of Davidson by tying it back to the line I have
been slowly working out. What Davidson’s account opens up is the possibility of a deep
temporality: freedom is now made into a relation between attitudes and beliefs on one
hand, and action on the other. The action may involve a choice about which it makes
sense to ask whether or not, and in what sense, the choice was free. But the underlying
states that cause the action are not themselves actions, they are not products of choice,
and about them it makes no sense to ask such questions. But this relation between
something that is a choice and something that isn’t, a pro attitude, is quickly undermined.
desires and beliefs that rationalize x) is prior to and separate from the action, and so is
suited to be a cause (in this case, it is a state rather than an event—but this could be
changed along these lines: ‘coming to have desires and beliefs that rationalize x’).”
(1980c 73; italics mine) The same approach that first allows for a fruitful distinction
between the action and the underlying attitudes—that is, the causal analysis—also
reduces those attitudes, for all intents and purposes, to events. Even if they are, overall,
6
I want to stress, however, that Davidson does not explicitly exclude the agent: quite the contrary. The
agent is needed for deliberation (2004 107) and it is the agent’s deliberative process that leads to various
problems of irrationality and so on. But Davidson never clarifies the role of the agent in this account, nor it
is clear how any strong notion of agency can be reconciled with the rest of the analysis.
37
states, they play their role in the causal nexus as events. They are, to be sure, not choices,
but they are still clearly marked out as mere events in the world. The account, then,
remains temporally shallow, though at the same time a possibility has been opened.
II. Frankfurt
This possibility is carried further by Harry Frankfurt, who attempts to fix the hole
in Davidson’s account by introducing the concept of the person into the analysis. An
account of intentional action is, for him, insufficient if we want to understand what
differentiates persons from other beings. After all, “human beings are not alone in having
desires and motives, or in making choices.” (Frankfurt 1982 82) What is lacking in an
analysis of the Davidsonian type is the notion of a will, which is not brought in simply
through an analysis of intentional action. That analysis can, at best, give us a notion of
what it means for someone to be free to act in light of his mental states, and “this notion
does capture at least part of what is implicit in the idea of an agent who acts freely. It
misses entirely, however, the peculiar content of the quite different idea of an agent
whose will is free.” (1982 90) Frankfurt approaches this issue through the introduction of
two central concepts: that of endorsement (which relies on having volitions of the second
order) and that of identification (by means of which an agent’s volitions are, in some
Frankfurt identifies the will with the agent’s “effective desire—one that moves (or
will or would move) a person all the way to action.” (1982 84) Though a person may
have any number of desires or wants, it is generally the case that most of them are not
38
ultimately expressed in action. The term “will,” then, is limited only to those desires that
are or would be if circumstances allow. These are what Frankfurt calls first-order desires.
The crucial aspect of his account, however, is the introduction of second-order volitions.
While first-order desires concern what an agent wants to do, second-order desires are
desires to the effect that a particular first-order desire be effective, that is, that the first-
contrast between a person and a wanton. A wanton has first-order desires, and may even
have second-order desires insofar as they are simply desires to have certain desires which
the wanton does not have. Furthermore, the wanton may be a perfectly rational being; he
can deliberate how best to carry out his strongest desire, and when to do so. But unlike a
person, the wanton “does not care about his will.” (1982 86) The wanton is simply not
concerned about which of his first-order desires should be the strongest. A person, on the
other hand, has second-order volitions that are concerned specifically with this. Frankfurt
clarifies the difference by comparing a drug addict who always happily pursues his
addiction whenever possible to one who does this unwillingly. An unwilling addict is a
person—he has a desire to continue taking drugs as well as a desire to stop, and while he
always acts on the former desire, he wants the latter to be effective. Although he cannot
choose which desire will determine what he does, he is nevertheless a person because it
makes a difference to him which desire will be effective. “When a person acts, the desire
7
Sometimes he emphasizes having second-order volitions, while at other times he suggests that the ability
to have them is constitutive of personhood, but the central point is clear in any case.
39
by which he is moved is either the will he wants or a will he wants to be without. When a
This capacity for forming second-order volitions is naturally tied to a concern for
the freedom of one’s will. If the will consists of effective first-order desires, whereas
second-order volitions are concerned with the issue of which first-order desires are to be
effective—that is, the issue of what the person’s will should be—the possibility of a free
will is opened in the relation between these two levels of desire. “Freedom of action is
(roughly, at least) the freedom to do what one wants to do. Analogously, then, the
statement that a person enjoys freedom of the will means (also roughly) that he is free to
want what he wants to want. More precisely, it means that he is free to will what he wants
to will, or to have the will he wants.” (1982 90) Freedom of action and will are sharply
separated on this account: one can have a free will without enjoying freedom of action,
and clearly one can have freedom of action without even having the capacity for a free
will. With this step, Frankfurt opens the way for later theories of agency and free will,
according to which either the ability to endorse or to control one’s effective desires is the
There are, on Frankfurt’s account, two major advantages to this way of viewing
free will. First, it explains why we attribute free will to human beings but not to other
animals. The target here is the tradition of accounts claiming that an action is free when
the agent is its sole originator. As Frankfurt points out, there is no particularly good
reason to think that human beings are capable of originating their actions while other
animals are not, and this account of freedom—freedom of action but not of will—is
40
therefore insufficient.8 Second, this theory explains why free will is desirable: “the
enjoyment of a free will means the satisfaction of certain desires—desires of the second
or of higher orders… The satisfactions at stake are those which accrue to a person of
whom is may be said that his will is his own.” (1982 92) We want free will because it
involves the satisfaction of desires we have; if we lack it, then our second-order volitions
are left unfulfilled. Perhaps even more importantly, Frankfurt here introduces the notion
of ownership, which I hinted at in my reading of Nagel. An agent whose will is the will
he wants to have owns that will; if his will is not the will he wants, then he experiences it
as something foreign. Free will, then, involves having a will that one feels to be truly
one’s own.
Frankfurt adds two important points to this account of freedom of will. The first
concerns identification, while the second concerns moral responsibility. Taking them in
turn, we may note that the issue of identification is crucial, because it is intended to be
Frankfurt’s reply to the problem of infinite regress, which is the obvious objection to his
theory. One might ask: why is free will a matter involving only first- and second-order
desires? Don’t we—in order to have genuine free will—also need to have the second-
order desires we want? That is, don’t we need our second-order desires to correspond to
our third-order desires? But why stop there? Frankfurt admits that the possible number of
orders is theoretically limitless, but attempts to dismiss the difficulty. The series of ever-
rising orders is terminated, “when a person identifies himself decisively with one of his
first-order desires”. (1982 91) If this occurs, there is no further important question of
whether the relevant second-order volition—the identification involved—is the desire the
8
Adding reasons to this account, as Richard Taylor does, would not help, since a wanton may both
originate his action and have reasons for them, and yet not be a person.
41
person wants to have from a higher vantage point: that answer is provided in the decisive
Second, Frankfurt is eager to use this new theory of free will to bolster the claims
he had made two years earlier concerning moral responsibility. There, the goal had been
to undermine the principle of alternate possibilities, which “states that a person is morally
responsible for what he has done only if he could have done otherwise.” (1969 829)
Essentially repeating the argument of the earlier piece, Frankfurt here distinguishes
between having a free will and acting of one’s free will. On his view, only the latter is
required for moral responsibility. The distinction is drawn in the following way: “a
person’s will is free only if he is free to have the will he wants” (1982 94), but acting of
one’s free will requires only that the person’s will is the will he wants to have. If the
latter condition holds, then regardless of whether the agent could have acted otherwise,
he would not have, because he acted the way he wanted, “and even supposing that he
could have had a different will, he would not have wanted his will to differ from what it
was.” (1982 94) This latter condition is important because, given the agent’s
identification with his first-order desire, his will is his own; he cannot complain that it
was outside of his control, because it is the will he wanted to act on. The further question
of whether or not his will was free—that is, whether or not he really could have chosen a
have had a different will, he would not have chosen to. Free will is thus not needed for
moral responsibility because it does not contribute anything; in these situations, it would
not change how the agent acted. Frankfurt illustrates the point with an example that,
regrettably, does not make his claim significantly easier to swallow: an unwilling addict
42
is not morally responsible for his actions, because he experiences his addiction as
something foreign to him, as something outside his control; he feels he is being pushed
around by external forces and is himself reduced to the role of an innocent bystander. But
a willing addict, an addict who identifies with his desire to follow through on his
addiction, takes his will as his own: he is therefore justly held responsible for it.
If something here does not seem quite right, it is because there are at least two
major problems in Frankfurt’s theory. The first concerns the notion of identification, and
whether this is sufficient to stop the infinite regress while still maintaining free will.9
satisfaction with that endorsement. Satisfaction, in turn, means that the agent is not
unfortunately, is insufficient, since there are many possible reasons why someone might
be satisfied in this way. In addition, although Frankfurt strives for a theory of free will
that would be satisfactory to all sides, clearly this notion of identification cannot be
enough for libertarians: if identification with some first-order desire is, ultimately, a
matter of chance or, as Frankfurt argues in his later work, even a matter of necessity, then
the entire structure of endorsement and satisfaction leads to nothing more than an illusion
of free will. An agent who is satisfied with his endorsement may well feel that his will is
free, but this feeling is only a self-deception, since ultimately he cannot help feeling that
way. If the implication, then, is just that free will is a matter of feeling—one either feels
9
The classic criticism is leveled by Gary Watson, who questions whether a desire of any sort is capable of
making a will into one’s own will: “We wanted to know what prevents wantonness with regard to one’s
higher-order volitions. What gives these volitions any special relation to ‘oneself’? It is unhelpful to answer
that one makes a ‘decisive commitment’, where this just means that an interminable ascent to higher orders
is not going to be permitted. This is arbitrary.” (1982 108)
43
one’s will to be free or one doesn’t, and that’s the end of it—clearly something is still
second problem: Frankfurt’s vacillation between two notions of free will, a vacillation he
exploits to great effect. We can catch a certain ambiguity already in the distinction
between having a free will and acting of one’s free will. As we have seen, Frankfurt
claims that, so long as the agent wants to have the will on which he acts, he is responsible
for his action because “he did it freely and of his own free will.” (1982 94) But this
implies that having a will that is one’s own does not actually require free will at all—it
requires only that the agent wants to have the will that he does. And this, in turn, puts into
question Frankfurt’s argument that his theory can explain why free will is desirable. He
argues that it is desirable because it involves the satisfaction of a higher-order desire. But
a morally responsible agent is an agent whose higher-order desires are satisfied and who
may yet lack free will! What Frankfurt shows, then, is that moral responsibility is
The ambiguity in question is that between being able to have the will that one
wants, and simply having a will that corresponds to the will one wants to have. Frankfurt
himself is well aware of the distinction, since it underlies his argument against the
principle of alternate possibilities. Furthermore, he points out that “it is in the discrepancy
between his will and his second-order volitions, or in his awareness that their coincidence
is not his own doing but only a happy chance, that a person who does not have this
freedom feels its lack.” (1982 90-91) In other words, someone whose first-order desires
happen to correspond to his second-order volitions, yet who does not feel that he himself
44
has any power over this correspondence, lacks free will. Free will requires a level of
agency such that, “with regard to any of his first-order desires, [a person] is free either to
make that desire his will or to make some other first-order desire his will instead.” (1982
94) Yet immediately after stating this criterion, Frankfurt points out that it is “a vexed
question” of how this sort of freedom is possible, and affirms that it is not needed for
moral responsibility. But that claim seems to be in direct conflict with the following
account of the morally responsible agent who may not have free will: “since the will that
moved him when he acted was his will because he wanted it to be, he cannot claim that
his will was forced upon him or that he was a passive bystander to its constitution.” (1982
agent’s will happened to be the will he wanted—this will not be enough, following
Frankfurt’s own admission quoted in the previous paragraph, for the agent to avoid
feeling that he was “a passive bystander”: that is precisely how he must feel, if he
recognizes that the correlation between his first- and second-order desires is not his own
doing; and thus the correlation alone is not sufficient for a person’s will to be his own.
himself must somehow cause his will to conform to his second-order volition. Only in
Frankfurt’s attempt to separate the possession of free will from the conditions of
moral responsibility therefore fails, and it fails according to the terms of his own account.
An agent without a free will does not own his will. And the problem is exacerbated once
45
we realize that, per the previous analysis, even if the agent feels satisfied with his
endorsement of his will, there is no clear reason to think that this alone provides a
eliminativist (there is an event of identifying with some first-order desire and an event of
according to which agency extends beyond identification. This latter follows from the
even more serious problem raised by the foregoing: what Frankfurt has left out of his
account of freedom of the will is, oddly enough, freedom of the will. He has, to be sure,
given at least a preliminary definition of what such freedom entails, yet there is no
account of how it might be possible, or of what exactly the crucial term—the term
and second-order desires without there being actual freedom involved, the implication is
that desires or volitions are not of themselves active: the simple fact that I want my will
to be X, and at the same time my will is X, does not in itself provide evidence that these
two events are connected in any non-contingent way. The causal, or agential power
any feature or aspect intrinsic to desires. It is something else, something that only agency
can bring to the fold. But surely that is the question of free will. Unless it is answered, a
further infinite regress threatens to open. If the will is the dominant first-order desire,
while free will involves the selection of a will that corresponds to a second-order volition,
it seems that some will must be involved in connecting these two desires. But if there is,
46
in this way, a will behind the will (so to speak), what prevents us from having to admit
that yet a further will might be needed to ensure the efficacy of this one?10
What I have been suggesting is that Frankfurt does set out to close a major gap in
Davidson’s theory: it is not enough for freedom that an action be caused in the right way
by the desires (and beliefs) that rationalize it. A further structural level is needed, and this
agent’s relation to that desire. The sort of freedom that matters, for Frankfurt, is not
contained in the relation between reason and action; it involves the further relation
between the reason and the person for whom it is a reason. What Frankfurt’s account
lacks, however, is precisely a way of making the leap that he wants to make: the leap to
the person. In presenting the relation as one between desires of different orders, he gives
us (with the addition of relevant beliefs) only a relation of reasons to the further reasons
for those reasons. On this level, then, his account does not differ in any major way from
Davidson’s compatibilism, which certainly also allows that mental events like reasons be
opens up the question of the person, or agent. He takes a deliberate step back from the
action itself and asks about the relation of the person who performs this action to the
primary reason that causes it. The notion of owning a desire or will, though ultimately
action is rationalized by reasons, which are simply kinds of events. But those reasons are
10
Watson’s solution, which emphasizes an agent’s values or evaluations rather than second-order volitions,
may seem to help with the earlier problem of infinite regress in desires—though I do not think it ultimately
does—but it is of no help here. For the question of what can cause values to be effective is just as
problematic, if not more so, as the question of what makes desires effective.
47
endorsed by persons, who are not events. Frankfurt therefore deepens—or points to a way
which are now relegated to the background. What takes center stage on a Frankfurtian
theory is not the choice at all, but the agent’s ownership of it. But to get us anywhere, the
account requires a further explication of identification and ownership. To get past the
Davidsonian theory of events causing each other, we need to establish that the
both lay out what they consider to be structural or relational features of agency, which
any theory would have to account for. But we can clearly see how both writers could
easily be pressed into an eliminativist mode. If (in Davidson’s theory) we are merely
dealing with events linked in a causal chain, and if (on Frankfurt’s approach) what allows
for freedom and responsibility is a certain identification, which may (for all we know) be
necessitated by natural causes, then the resulting structures might explain the feeling of
freedom, but they will not be sufficient to account for responsibility; freedom will be a
mere surface phenomenon, even if (accepting anomalous monism) some version of it can
never be fully eliminated from the account. But on the other hand, I have argued that
Davidson and Frankfurt both share a common problem: the problem of accounting for the
“because.” Frankfurt leaves it mysterious; Davidson insists that we can explain it only
through causality, but he does not account for the causality itself, or for the effectiveness
48
of the cause. A certain relation, apparently crucial to freedom, is contained in the
How, then, are we to make sense of the agency that seems necessary to account for this
“because” in terms that do not simply eliminate freedom? It is in dealing with this
C. Libertarianism
put forward by van Inwagen.11 The argument essentially formalizes the basic intuition
behind incompatibilism: if determinism is true, then what one does happens necessarily
given the state of the universe at any prior time together with the laws of nature. But no
one has or ever had any choice about the state of the universe prior to their birth, not to
mention prior to the existence of life on earth. Thus, if determinism is true, no one has or
ever had any choice about what actions they will take.
Some libertarians, like Goetz (1988) and Ginet (2007, 1990), simply reject the
notion that causation of any kind is consistent with free action. They argue that the belief
that free actions must be caused is simply misguided. But most recent libertarians have
avoided this train of thought due to the difficulty of making sense of uncaused events.
11
In, among other places, Peter van Inwagen, An Essay on Free Will. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1983) and
“The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism,” in Free Will.
49
First, such events seem to be out of place within a universe in which events are normally
parts of causal chains; second, as already noted, the post-Davidsonian presumption is that
explaining the relation between an action and the reason for which it was taken requires a
causal account. Noncausalists have responses to these concerns, of course; but the
responses have not been widely convincing. Most libertarians have therefore followed the
roughly Davidsonian line that reasons and causes cannot be kept entirely isolated from
each other. In their broad outlines, the theories attempt to respond to the question I raised
against Davidson: the question of what role the agent plays in making a reason effective.
In some sense, the agent’s role is taken the be causal; the libertarian strategy differs from
the compatibilist one primarily in the claim that the causation involved in action may be
nondeterministic. Frankfurt is also taken up, though usually with some tweaks. Freedom
Ekstrom picks up a largely Frankfurtian account, arguing that, for the most part,
compatibilism works: autonomous actions may well be determined, so long as they are
determined by the agent’s preferences. Agents themselves, on the other hand, are made
up by attitudes coherently structured along the lines of those preferences together with
acceptance states, along with a certain capacity” (2005 54), which itself consists of the
ability to form and reform one’s character through the choosing of preferences. So much
of the discussion of which attitudes or beliefs are internal to the agent or external can
50
proceed along Frankfurtian lines. The major difference is that responsibility itself
to one’s conception of the good.” (2000 106), and its formation is not causally
determined, it represents the agent. Thus, any action that takes place on the basis of such
here: since the agent is simply identified with her preferences, and these are the products
of nondeterministic deliberation about the good, any usual sense of agency seems to be
lost. Actions are free insofar as they are determined by preferences; the preferences result
from deliberation. The agent is, once again, only a site for that deliberation. Now I do not
think this is itself a problem; the difficulty is that the preferences are themselves chosen
the ground of preferences, what we have are preferences choosing other preferences, and
Randolph Clarke, a major recent exponent of the agent causal theory, argues that
we can reconcile freedom with event causation so long as we allow that such causation is
cause the action. The nature of this intervention, in turn, takes the following form: “what
an agent directly causes, when she acts with free will, is her acting on (or for) certain of
her reasons rather than on others, and her acting for reasons ordered in a particular way
by weight, importance, or significance as the reasons for which she performs her action.”
(1993 194) The Davidsonian notion of reasons as causes is preserved; the only point here
51
is the addition of an agent—something Davidson does not expressly exclude, but simply
fails to explain. And Clarke fixes the difficulties inherent in earlier agent-causal
theories—such as those of Chisholm (1966) and Taylor (1966, 1983)—by offering what
he calls an integrated account, one on which the agent causes his actions in conjunction
Agent causation, on this view, “is (or involves) exactly the same relation as event
causation. The only difference between the two kinds of causation concerns the types of
entities related, not the relation.” (1993 197) Clarke thus tries to demystify agent
causation by making it an ordinary kind of causal relation, though the “agent that is a
relatum of such a relation is not identical to any event, property, fact, or state of affairs,
nor to any collection of such things.” (1993 196-197) Much of Clarke’s positive account
aims at making sense of the notion of an agent as a substance and defending the
Let me take just one point: a standard objection has it that agent causation cannot
explain why particular actions are performed at specific times. If agents are enduring
substances, they are present as a whole at each moment in time; but why would a
substance present as a whole at each moment act at one moment rather than another?
Clarke responds that his integrated account allows for a solution: “whether a certain agent
who possesses an agent-causal power is disposed to act at a given time, and, if so, which
specific actions she is empowered to cause then, depend on factors such as which reasons
or motivations the agent has then… A fact of this sort, it may be held, may explain why
it did not happen yesterday but did happen today that she caused this particular action.”
52
(2005 202) So we can explain why an action was performed at one time rather than
another in the usual way: by appealing to other events—the presence of certain reasons or
Clarke recognizes that it is the reasons and motives that we are generally
interested in when trying to explain an action, but he notes that agent causation isn’t
supposed to solve the problem of control, very roughly, the problem I have been raising
of how the agent enters into his actions. Rather than reducing the agent to particular
mental functions, events, or simply a stage on which events play themselves out, Clarke
wants to insert the agent as such into the picture. But however this is supposed to work, it
is not clear that postulating an agent really solves the problem. Pointing to something
quite different from the other sorts of entities we encounter in the world and saying that it
can help explain what role the agent plays in causing actions strikes many as
Furthermore, let’s say that the agent is a substance that acts in concert with certain
events (desires, motives, etc.) to cause another event (an action). The agent is not
reducible to any of these events; but, as substance, the agent is also not constituted by any
of those events. If she were so constituted, this would simply be the kind of reduction
Clarke is arguing against. But if the agent’s motives, desires, choices, and action do not
make up who she is, then we seem to lose much of what we might normally want in a
theory of agency: what it is that makes us who we are. To say that we are just substances
adds a formal feature to agency, but it doesn’t help satisfy the major concern: how it is
that who I am, as this particular agent, can cause my actions? What is individual to me
53
seems to belong to the events that jointly cause my action. Thus, in attempting to stop the
regress involved in tracing the causes of actions back to further events, themselves the
products of previous events, agent causation seems to lose track of the agent’s role in the
significantly better. The account itself, however, is quite subtle, and once again I will not
do it justice here. It involves taking up a roughly Frankfurtian model, but building in the
condition that the agent must be the ultimate source of his actions: “free will – as opposed
to mere freedom of action – is about the forming and shaping of character and motives
actions. Free will (in contrast to mere free action) is about self-formation.” (2007 16)
Essentially, Kane breaks down what he calls the Ultimate Responsibility condition into
three aspects, which I here oversimplify: (1) the action must be produced by the agent’s
effort of will, (2) the action is rational,12 and (3) the conjunction of (1) and (2) provides
the complete and only explanation of why the action occurred. In other words, it is
important, “first, that the agent produces or causes the outcome, and second that the
agent’s doing so is rational.” (1989 232) Kane’s concern is with the standard anti-
libertarian argument, i.e., that indeterminacy alone is not sufficient for freedom. That
indeterminacy must be incorporated into the account in such a way as to explain the
action as dependent on the agent and as rational. Thus, the above is meant to satisfy two
conditions, the Ultimacy Condition (which places the agent at the origin of the action by
12
“The agent (r1) has reasons for doing so (whichever occurs), (r2) does it for those reasons, (r3) does not
choose (for those reasons compulsively), and (r4) believes at the time of choice that the reasons for which it
is made are in some sense the weightier reasons.” (Kane 1989 232)
54
answers the question of why the agent did what he did and not something else—the point
here being to prevent the arbitrariness that might seem to be associated with
indeterminacy).
There are two points in Kane’s analysis that I want to call attention to. First is the
reference to the effort of will. The agent causal account, avoids the problems raised by
placing some extra action—like an effort of will—in front of the action in question by
linking the agent causally to an action performed for certain reasons. Kane deals with the
problem by similarly insisting that we need not place another action of some sort before
the effort of will. The effort is the result of certain conditions, like the character and prior
motives of the agent, which raise the question of how the agent is to act in the first place.
But these conditions do not determine the outcome of the deliberation: the effort of will
with a set of conditions, it arrives at a conclusion of how to act given these conditions.
Second, there is the problem of rationality: as stipulated, the agent’s final decision
must be seen by him as rational. But the indeterminacy requires that the agent could have
decided otherwise, and that decision, too, would be seen as rational. Furthermore, either
decision would be seen as rational by the agent given exactly the same set of background
conditions. This problem threatens to turn any libertarian theory into either a theory of
is subtle, but not essentially dissimilar to Clarke’s: “in libertarian choice we must be
choosing the reasons that in turn explain our action.” (Kane 1989 246) The account is
largely Davidsonian: an action appears rational to an agent in light of the reasons he has
(or at least the ones he considers in the deliberation) and the weight he assigns to them.
55
The further step here is that the choice itself determines the relative weight of those
reasons for the agent. Whether the agent chooses to do one thing or another, then, he will
have reasons for that choice, and these reasons will seem like the better reasons for action
because the agent has chosen them, in the same deliberative process, as weightier
reasons. Though Kane admits that this solution is circular, he does not think it is empty—
it leaves something missing, but it explains everything that needs explaining. What is
missing, or what seems to be missing, is just an account that would make the final
decision necessary in light of the prior conditions; but that, of course, is precisely the
point of a libertarian theory. We may also note that what makes the final decision into the
agent’s own is not that he somehow chooses the underlying motives, but that he decides
what respective weight to give them in producing his action. This, despite some
placed on choosing among opposing motives, which explain both why the agent makes
an effort to choose and (since there is an opposing motive) why this is an effort. The
difference from Frankfurt is just that the deliberation that issues in choice is
Like Clarke, Kane argues that absolute freedom—in the sense of being the
ultimate origin of one’s action—is required for moral responsibility, and he insists that
The Epicurians held that if there was to be room in nature for human freedom, the
atoms must sometimes ‘swerve’ from their determined pathways. If the atoms do
not ‘swerve’—if the appropriate ‘causal gaps’ are not there in nature—then there
is no room for an incompatibilist free will in nature. One would need a Kantian
noumenal order, or some similar stratagem, to make sense of it, and this I think
should make incompatibilists uncomfortable. (1989 231)
56
Kane’s “comfortable” solution appeals to quantum indeterminacy, essentially the last
place in which one might still hope to find indeterminacy in nature, which on his view
may be produced by the effort involved in making a choice. This sounds highly
unlikely—and some have argued that, based on what we already know about the brain, it
is false. But interestingly Kane is not willing to give up on freedom however the
empirical science turns out—naturalism is only the (currently) most plausible way of
attaining it. We need freedom, because without it we cannot have moral responsibility.
Kane’s wording clearly implies that even if the gap in nature turns out not to be there, he
will still maintain that we are free—we’ll just have to find a different, more
Kane sticks to the quantum explanation because of his naturalist convictions, but
there is a further point to note here. The “further stratagem” that Kane finds so
“uncomfortable” would, on his view, involve not some change in our conception of the
agent, but rather a different conception of the agent’s role in the world of natural
causality; in other words, even if a naturalist account of freedom should fail, we must still
hold on, at any expense, to a fully naturalist conception of agency. Although the
understanding of agency, Kane is still content with understanding the agent in essentially
the same way as the compatibilists. True, he does add a notion of indeterminate willing,
but this does not change the agency—it changes only the nature of the agent’s willing
and, even there, it says nothing especially new about the willing itself, but only adds a
be not a feature of agency as such, but a property superimposed on agency, then the
57
libertarian and the compatibilist account will simply converge. This should worry
libertarians far more than the discomfort of having to develop a new account of agency.
What I have been arguing is that Kane’s account is ambiguous. On one hand, the concern
responsibility is somehow internal to our conception of agency itself. On the other hand,
then it is unclear why we cannot happily maintain our view of ourselves as agents
without invoking indeterminism. Compatibilists are happy to maintain that the freedom
allowed within determinist constraints is perfectly sufficient for all the responsibility we
need. If we accept their notion of agency, why not accept the rest of the account?
implicit in theories of this sort. Free will is defined exclusively in terms of indeterminacy
plus rationality. But this reduces free will to free action. Kane, as we saw, emphasizes
freedom of will, to the extent that he calls his account “free willist.” His view, then, is
that agents must be the ultimate sources of the purposes on which they act; that is, they
must be the sole choosers of what constitutes their will through what Kane calls self-
forming willings. But self-forming willings involve actions of, at some point, choosing
the motives that will heretofore determine how we act. Kane’s claim is that all self-
forming actions are self-forming willings (1996 125). But the reverse also holds: we form
Thus the question we saw raised by Frankfurt’s account—of how the will itself
can be free—falls by the wayside: the will is free only because it is formed by free
actions. But the question about free action is, arguably, not the right sort of question. Let
58
us admit, for the moment, the possibility that there is a genuine indeterminacy in our
decision making. What could possibly rest on that? The idea, for both Clarke and Kane,
causality on which the agent alone determines himself to action. But this gives rise to a
problem we have already seen: the agent is not responsible at all for the pre-conditions of
his action. His responsibility occurs only in the deliberation between those preconditions
and the action itself. But this makes it look like the action, though undetermined, is now
entirely random, and although we can perhaps assign responsibility for it in the sense of
supposedly provided by the heavy reliance on reasons: I select based on reasons. But this
doesn’t help.
There are two points here. First, my selection among reasons itself seems random,
and then we are back to the problem of randomness. Kane’s argument that the act of
choosing both establishes which reason is most weighty and provides a rational
justification for taking that reason as most weighty could only help us in explaining the
But this doesn’t seem to allow for responsibility any more than irrational randomness.
there before the deliberative process begins. The materials on which I deliberate, on the
libertarian account, are pre-given; the best I can do is select among them. I agree that this
possible, for example, that all the pre-conditions I am considering are bad ones. In that
case, even though I originate the decision reached on their basis, I still cannot be held
59
responsible for it because I am not responsible for the framework within which the choice
is made. That is, libertarian theories that focus on indeterminacy fail to answer Nagel’s
challenge: how I can be responsible for anything I do given that I am not responsible for
(at least some of) the preconditions of my action. Indeterminacy in my deliberation, even
There are attempts to address this problem, of course. Both Kane and van
Inwagen (1989) attempt to show, though with a slightly different goal, that the scope of
our responsibility is broader than the scope of our free action. Invoking the Aristotelian
account that our actions habituate us into patterns of action, they argue that our free
actions result in our acquiring certain character traits—if I freely choose to lie, for
example, then I become accustomed to lying so that it does not seem to me that lying is
especially wrong; but since this habit of lying is the consequence of my free choice, I am
responsible for it. There are, some obvious problems with this account, of course: for
example, we lack knowledge of the effect to which our actions will influence our
after all, even if we freely choose the action, we certainly do not freely choose all the
unknown effects of that action. But this also doesn’t expand the field of responsibility far
enough: my free actions do not occur starting with my birth; in fact, for Kane and van
Inwagen, because of the stringent conditions imposed on the definition of free action, it
turns out that very few of our actions really are free. But this implies also that the vast
majority of my character traits, motives, and values are completely outside the scope of
anything I did or could have done. But since those features, for which I cannot
conceivably be held responsible on this account, will likely play a role in even my free—
60
or undetermined—actions, it is still unclear how responsibility can be assigned to those
libertarians, is likely to fill the hole. What is missing, I believe, is a conception of agency
that contains responsibility as an internal feature: either we are the sorts of being who are
in some sense responsible by our very nature, or we are not responsible at all.
virtually every feature necessary for freedom—the existence of prior grounds of choice,
the indeterminate choosing among those grounds—as themselves undermining free will.
And this is highly counterintuitive. In my defense, I note only that these points are
problematic; that is exactly why there have been ongoing, increasingly complex efforts to
deal with them. If none of those efforts have taken permanent ground, of course, this does
not mean that the process of adding complexity is misguided. I want only to suggest that
perhaps a different strategy altogether may be needed. I will hint at it briefly in the next
61
3
One way of attempting to address the problem of free will is to appeal directly to
noted that all theory is against. One way to defend free will, then, is to stick to
experience. In this chapter I will argue that this is a mistake: experience is not for free
A. Searle
defended ontologically, he asks: “there is no doubt that the gap is psychologically real,
but is it otherwise empirically real?” (2001 269) He rejects the appeal to quantum
indeterminacy and admits that it is not clear how we could exercise conscious causation
within nature; but he concludes that this problem is really the problem of consciousness,
so anyone who rejects libertarian freedom will be unable to explain consciousness as well
and that difficulty seems to give the libertarian a certain leg up. Searle’s position, then, is
that if we establish that experience is on the side of freedom, we have won the major part
of the battle; reconciling experience with reality is a secondary task. The real argument is
62
in his theory of rationality, which Searle presents as an attack on what the calls the
Classical Model of rationality. What he means by this is largely Humean rationality, but
he takes Davidson—mistakenly, I think—as his main target. The main point of the
Classical Model that Searle seeks to refute (at least for my purposes) is the claim that our
The centerpiece of Searle’s account is the claim that freedom consists of a gap:
“‘The gap’ is the general name that I have introduced for the phenomenon that we do not
normally experience the stages of our deliberations and voluntary actions as having
causally sufficient conditions or as setting causally sufficient conditions for the next
stage.” (2001 50) Specifically, the gap is the experience of indeterminacy between our
reasons for a decision or action and that decision or action itself. Though Searle thinks
there is really one gap, he argues that we can locate it in three different places, in each of
which the self must play the crucial role of connecting conditions to consequences;
nothing else can play that role (“what fills the gap? Nothing. Nothing fills the gap” (2001
17)13). First, there is a gap between the reasons for acting and the decision made on the
basis of those reasons; the reasons by themselves cannot be causally sufficient for the
decision. Second, there is a gap between the decision and the action. Third, there is—in
any extended action—a gap between the initiation of the action and the carrying out of
that action to completion; for example, I might start writing a dissertation but then give
up (not bloody likely), and finishing the project requires conscious continuation of the
action on my part. In each case, the gap implies that, whatever the preceding initial
13
There is an implicit reference to Sartre here: what Searle means by the “nothing” is that there are no
causally sufficient conditions: the “nothing” is a way of saying that only the self operates in this gap.
63
conditions, the region between those and the final outcome is the domain of freedom. I
First, Searle insists that “when one has several reasons for performing an action,
or for choosing an action, one may act on only one of them; one may select which reason
one acts on.” (2001 65) Searle takes up as his example the case of voting for a particular
candidate, where I have a number of reasons to do so. “I may not vote for the candidate
for all of those reasons. I may vote for the candidate for one reason and not for any of the
others. In such a case, I may know without observation that I voted for the candidate for
one particular reason and not for any of the others.” (2001 65) My conscious awareness
of choosing a particular reason for action demonstrates that I am free with regard to my
reasons—they do not cause how I act. Rather, I choose how I act on the basis of them. “If
we think of the reasons I act on as the reasons that are effective, then it emerges that
where free rational action is concerned, all effective reasons are made effective by the
agent, insofar as he chooses which ones he will act on.” (2001 66) Searle makes it clear,
then, that he is replying to the concern I raised earlier in relation to Davidson, that is, the
question of what accounts for the causality, or efficacy, of a reason. Searle’s point is that
a reason cannot, by itself, cause an action—an agent has to act on that reason.
Searle’s goal with this argument is to show, contra Davidson, that reasons are not
causes. In that sense, the argument clearly falls far short of its mark. It is based on a
common misunderstanding of what Davidson means by his claim that reasons are
causes.14 The misunderstanding involves trying to show that reasons do not provide
14
Goetz, for example, makes a similar point in claiming that “a reason provides a basis for the agent acting
in one way as opposed to another (or not acting at all) without causally determining the agent to act (or not
to act) in the way in which she does.” (1988 312)
64
sufficient causes for action.15 But of course Davidson never claims that reasons are
sufficient causes for action. First, reasons appear as causes only retroactively. Before an
action is committed, it cannot, on his account, be predicted on the basis of the agent’s
element. Second, Davidson actually stresses that the reasons for which an agent acts are
not sufficient causes. He points repeatedly to the various problems of irrationality and
wayward causal chains that make it impossible to find the sufficient rational causes of an
action. And he is very clear on this point: no given reason can be a sufficient cause for
any action because the agent acts not in light of a single reason, but after consideration of
many reasons. Of course, this might still imply that even though no particular reason is a
sufficient cause of an action, the reasons making up an agent’s total motivational set
might serve as sufficient causes, and that would provide a challenge for freedom. But
even that suggestion is fully rejected by Davidson, on the grounds that it would make
intention with which someone acted does not allow us to reconstruct his actual
reasoning.” (Davidson 1980e 98) Or, in another place, “every judgment is made in the
light of all the reasons in this sense, that it is made in the presence of, and is conditioned
by, that totality.” (1980d 41) The point is that an agent’s act is based on a judgment, itself
caused by some reason. But the question of which reason ends up causing the judgment,
and for that matter which reasons out of the entire set of an agent’s reasons are even
15
See, e.g., Searle: “cases of actions for which the antecedent beliefs and desires really are causally
sufficient, far from being models of rationality, are in fact bizarre and typically irrational cases” (12); or
again: “I can tell you why I am doing what I am now doing, but in telling you why, I am not trying to give a
causally sufficient explanation of my behavior, because if I were, the explanation would be hopelessly
incomplete… because in specifying these causes, I do not give you what I take to be causally sufficient
conditions.” (Searle 2001 69)
65
considered, or taken to be important, by the agent is left completely open. The total set of
Not only does Davidson have a response to the arguments against him, but in fact
his position is stronger than Searle’s, because it has a way of explaining actions that does
not terminate simply with “the agent did it.” I mentioned earlier that, in discussing the
question of the agent’s role in making a reason effective, Searle is addressing a gap in
Davidson’s account. That much is true. But Davidson does not deny that the agent has a
role in determining which reason causes his action—he rather insists on that fact. It is
only that he does not explain how that happens. Searle attempts to fill the gap by, well,
inserting a gap. But our alleged ability to choose which reason we actually act on does
not really show that we are free in the strong sense Searle intends. For one thing, we
frequently do not know which of our reasons we acted on; though Searle is certainly not
the only one to think that we do, I cannot imagine the piece of phenomenology that
would confirm that intuition. We often believe we are acting on one reason rather than
another because we deceive ourselves, and frequently, when we think about it, we change
our mind about which reason we really acted on. In an interesting turn, this is a much
bigger challenge for Searle than for Davidson. The latter recognizes that we are
frequently wrong about our own reasons, but this does not touch on the claim that reasons
serve as causes: we are frequently wrong about the causes of all sorts of things (like
weather patterns), but this does not generally lead us to think that those things are
uncaused. (Davidson 1980a 18) But since Searle’s argument is entirely about the
consciousness of freedom, I do not see how it could deal with the challenge.
66
There are two upshots of this discussion: first, there is no reason to think that
reasons are not causes; the claim that an agent chooses which reasons to make effective
does not make the reasons any less causal, provided we understand that a reason is not a
sufficient cause. Second, this strategy for demonstrating that we are free by taking a first-
person perspective and peering into our own consciousness as opposed to some third-
person standpoint ultimately fails to show anything about our freedom: we may think we
are free and feel we are free (if there is such a feeling), but this can be illusive—the
conclusion that we really are free, even psychologically, is only as strong as the certainty
of our self-knowledge. I want to dwell on this second point in a slightly different context
Searle seems to think that our freedom is, really, an analytic truth given that we
are rational: if we are capable of exercising rationality, this implies that the use of
rationality must make some difference to how we act. But if rationality is to make a
genuine difference, then it must be possible for us to act otherwise than we actually do.
This is a roughly Kantian argument, and Searle works it out through a strategy frequently
ascribed to Kant.16 The important point, on Searle’s account, is that we can deliberate
only in light of the appearance of alternate possibilities: deliberation as such only makes
sense on the assumption that the deliberation has a role to play in determining which way
we end up deciding, and this presupposes that there must be more than one thing we
could decide. The point, though, is not simply that there are different ways that I could
decide (since a determinist can easily accept that but reject the further claim that what I
16
“Kant pointed this out a long time ago: There is no way to think away your own freedom in the process
of voluntary action because the process of deliberation itself can only proceed on the presupposition of
freedom, on the presupposition that there is a gap between the causes in the form of your beliefs, desires,
and other reasons, and the actual decision that you make.” (Searle 2001 14)
67
decide is ultimately up to me), but that my deliberation is instrumental to the final
outcome; that means that I must assume that I am free in order to be able to deliberate at
all. Does this conclusion really follow? Searle suggests the following: “If I really thought
that the beliefs and desires were sufficient to cause the action then I could just sit back
and watch the action unfold in the same way as I do when I sit back and watch the action
unfold on a movie screen. But I cannot do that when I am engaging in rational decision
making and acting.” (2001 71) Here is an even more graphic display of the point:
“Suppose you go into a restaurant, and the waiter brings you the menu. You have a
choice between, let’s say, veal chops and spaghetti; you cannot say: ‘Look, I am a
determinist, che sarà, sarà. I will just wait and see what I order! I will wait to see what my
beliefs and desires cause.’ This refusal to exercise your freedom is itself only intelligible
intuition pump. But clearly it has nothing to do with the point at issue. A determinist can
simply respond that we are determined to deliberate and the actual process of the
deliberation is determined, so that any step from our deliberating to our being free cannot
be a logical one. The convinced determinist need no more sit back and watch what he
ends up doing than the convinced libertarian needs to spend every conscious moment of
his life making decisions. Searle’s point seems, at least on the surface, to depend on the
not a new idea, but I confess that I have never been able to see its force. If “the
the claim is question begging. If, however, there is some separate and unambiguous
68
experience of freedom in this sense, I confess that I lack it. “What is it like to be
indeterministically free?” I don’t know, but it doesn’t seem to be much like the
But let me try to reconstruct the argument more charitably. If I am faced with a
choice, I do not know what I am going to choose until I choose it. Thus, I am at least
uncertain about the outcome of my deliberation. This means that I do not experience
myself as being driven toward a particular outcome. Furthermore, the arguments against
this experienced indetermination come from outside—from assumptions about how the
determination. Searle does in fact seem to take an approach along these lines: “The
question ‘Why did you do it?’ asks for a totally different sort of answer from the question
‘Why did it happen?’,” and this distinction leads to the advice to “always look at
phenomena such as rational behavior and its explanation from the first-person point of
view, because they have a first-person ontology. They only exist from the first-person
point of view.” (2001 85) This is an interesting point, and Searle raises it in reply to
Nagel: in deliberating, we cannot see our actions as mere events in the world, because we
perspective has an ontology that differs from the deterministic, third-person, perspective.
Unfortunately, Searle doesn’t quite develop the implications; in fact, he seems to cancel
them out in claiming that “the gap might be an illusion,” though he immediately adds that
“it is not a belief we can give up.” (2001 71) The problem is this: if the gap (or freedom)
69
has a different ontology from that of the sciences, if this is a first-person ontology, and if
belief in freedom cannot be avoided from the first-person perspective, then what can it
mean to say that it might be an illusion? I cannot see how Searle could avoid the problem
except by suggesting either that freedom might be doubted from the first-person
standpoint, or that there is a meta-ontology within which the first-person and third-person
have the upper hand). The second approach would, of course, dull the force of the word
“ontology” (and, in fact, make it completely useless), but the first would seem to
critique of Korsgaard, I will argue that the first approach is actually the better strategy
here.
B. Korsgaard
Although written several years before Searle’s account, and providing a clear
influence on his version, Korsgaard’s argument is far more subtle. Korsgaard defines
freedom in terms of the reflective capacities of our minds: to act, we must have a reason
for acting. But having a reason is not a matter of just picking some desire or other and
going with it. In fact, insofar as we are reflective, we cannot just do that. We have to
decide whether or not the desire (broadly construed) provides a sufficient reason for
action; that is, we must evaluate it and either endorse or reject it. “The reflective mind
cannot settle for perception and desire, not just as such. It needs a reason. Otherwise, at
least as long as it reflects, it cannot commit itself or go forward.” (1996b 93) Our
70
freedom, then, is the freedom from external determination of the will, and it is a freedom
because our reflective nature makes it possible for us to question any desire that presents
itself as a candidate for determining our action. Having questioned, we can reject the
desire, so that nothing determines the will to act except its own rules. Korsgaard’s
argument is not that this proves that determinism is false, but rather that the truth or
Korsgaard suggests that determinism might seem to pose a problem for freedom
by giving us the knowledge that, even if we thought we were free, in fact we could not
have done otherwise. But that still would not challenge freedom; at most, Korsgaard
freedom does not operate within the same sphere as theoretical knowledge. “The freedom
discovered in reflection is not a theoretical property which can also be seen by scientists
considering the agent’s deliberations third-personally and from outside. It is from within
the deliberative perspective that we see our desires as providing suggestions which we
may take or leave.” (1996b 96) In other words, there are two perspectives or, as
they represent a practical and a theoretical viewpoint” (1996a 185): on the one hand, we
can look at ourselves from a scientific, theoretical, third-person perspective. On this view,
we are fully determined, and the point of this perspective is to explain why our actions
occurred and to predict future actions. On the other hand, we can look at ourselves from
the practical, first-person perspective of deliberation, and there we are trying to decide
not why we act, but how to act. The concepts of freedom and determinism thus apply to
two different perspectives or standpoints and cannot conflict with each other.
71
To make the point clearer, Korsgaard invites us to imagine that scientists have
taken control of our brains as part of an experiment. In this situation, you know that the
scientists are controlling your actions as well as the thoughts leading up to those actions.
But while your knowledge that you are being controlled by scientists can influence your
decision (you might try to do something unpredictable, hoping to outsmart the machine,
or might try to stop making decisions altogether—in this earlier piece Korsgaard is still
using that version of the argument), but “in order to do anything, you must simply ignore
the fact that you are programmed, and decide what to do—just as if you were free. You
will believe that your decision is a sham, but it makes no difference.” (1996a 163) This is
a subtle move; unlike Searle, Korsgaard openly rejects the idea that we must believe
ourselves to be free. “The point is not that you must believe that you are free, but that you
must choose as if you were free. It is important to see that this is quite consistent with
believing yourself to be fully determined.” (1996a 162) But I am not sure that Korsgaard
quite succeeds in holding on to this move. Her point “is not about a theoretical
assumption necessary to decision, but about a fundamental feature of the standpoint from
which decisions are made. It follows from this feature that we must regard our decisions
as springing ultimately from principles that we have chosen, and justifiable by those
Korsgaard’s argument shows that determinism does not pose a threat to freedom
in the sense that it cannot—or should not—change how we act; at least, unless we react
to the idea of determinism in a highly irrational way. But this argument does not seem so
much to say anything about our freedom, but rather about our psychology, particularly
72
our psychological reactions to determinism.17 Moreover, the appeal to the first-person as
of Nagel’s challenge: Nagel argued that, even though we cannot let go of freedom, the
objective view of ourselves forces doubts on us. Taken far enough, it involves a radical
skepticism about freedom. But the objective view, for Nagel, is not the third-person view:
it is thoroughly first-personal. His point is not that we only doubt freedom when we look
at ourselves from the outside, but that we can—and in the course of reflection must—
come to see ourselves from the outside while remaining within the first-person
perspective.18 But, on a related note, Korsgaard seems to miss a deeper threat to freedom.
The threat is not that we will be unable to deliberate rationally; the threat is that the tools
of that deliberation, the values and reasons we already have, will serve as the grounds
based on which we deliberate; but those values and reasons cannot themselves be freely
chosen by us, at least not all the way down, because for that we would need to freely
create ourselves from outside the world. I might act as if I am free, and I might try to do
my best to have good reasons for my actions, but I can also recognize that it is impossible
for me to fully subject all my relevant reasons to scrutiny. I may regard myself as free in
the sense that knowing determinism to be true would not alter my behavior in any way,
but this is neither equivalent to nor sufficient for regarding all the principles on which I
act as chosen.
cannot spring from something I have chosen or created. Both Nagel and Korsgaard seem
to agree that, if we act on sufficiently objective reasons, we will have a kind of freedom.
17
Similar versions of these arguments are raised in Chapter 3 of Guevara (2000).
18
For a more developed argument along these lines, see Nelkin (2000).
73
But if our decisions are necessarily conditioned by features of our character, and these are
furthermore not features we could have freely chosen, this undermines our ability to act
on those principles that we might consider to be the best, or most objective, principles of
action. Our reflective nature, certainly, is not enough to counter this threat: if all our
actual reflection is conditioned by features we have not chosen, then whether or not we
will act on principles that we have chosen—even if there are such—will be merely a
matter of luck. This is a variant of the problem I earlier raised with regard to libertarian
theories: if our character is not chosen, both the freedom and the responsibility of our
Finally, what does it mean to say that I must deliberate “as if” I were free? If this
alternative. That is, can I deliberate “as if” I were not free? For both Searle and
Korsgaard, that alternative is incoherent. But, in fact, I think there is an alternative. Both
Searle and Korsgaard present the argument that we cannot simultaneously, or from the
same point of view, see ourselves as free and determined. And it is this version of the
argument that falls to Nagel’s analysis, because it seems that we can, from the first-
person perspective, see our actions as merely events in the world. In considering the
alternative to the “as if” scenario, we can achieve two things: first, we undercut the
pretensions of these arguments to open a realm of genuine freedom within the first-
modify the arguments in light of this objection to undercut Nagel’s eliminativism. Here is
how.
74
The argument for freedom depends on the idea that, from the first-person
perspective, we cannot see ourselves as determined: we must see ourselves as free. But I
don’t think this is true, because consciousness is not transparent. Take the following
scenario: I have applied to several graduate programs. Months go by with no reply, and I
become anxious and pessimistic. Finally, a representative from program A calls to inform
me that I have been accepted. As a result, I immediately develop a strong liking for this
program. A week or so later I receive an acceptance letter from program B. Now I have
to make a decision. I deliberate for weeks. I visit both campuses, compare various
requirements, placements, and so on. Based on these criteria, I finally decide in favor of
program A. Now what I have just undergone is a genuine deliberation: I did consider
various factors, and I chose which ones of them are effective in making up my mind. That
is, I chose the reasons I act on and acted based on those reasons. But did I? Isn’t it
possible that the warm feelings initially engendered by the phone call from program A
inclined me toward program A, coloring all my other considerations? In other words, the
decision I made may well be biased. The libertarian could respond that the decision is
still not determined. But how do I know that? In one way, I do feel that I genuinely
deliberated and reached a decision based on my deliberation. But at the same time, I feel
that perhaps I had already decided prior to the deliberation, prior to considering any of
the factors, and that the deliberation process was not so much a process of deciding as a
actual decision was not really determined but merely biased? I do not see how.
75
This may be a somewhat extreme case, but such cases do occur19: cases in which
we undergo deliberation, but at the same time entertain some doubt about whether the
deliberation is the determining factor in the decision. In other words, it is possible to (1)
go through a process of deliberation, and (2) doubt whether that deliberation is a decisive
factor. I am not suggesting that such cases necessarily involve a loss of freedom. What
they do involve, however, is a case where we do not act “as if” we are free, at least in the
total sense Searle and Korsgaard seem to suggest. Though Searle does not have this
must still deliberate “as if” we are free: we have no choice but to go on deciding how to
act, regardless of whether or not we think this deliberation will be effective. That, in fact,
is precisely what Korsgaard says. But we must distinguish between the following sorts of
deliberations: (1) searching for the best reasons on which to act, (2) searching for the best
reasons to support a pre-decided course of action, and (3) searching for the best
justification (perhaps in a moral vein) for a pre-decided course of action. And there seems
to be a difference between searching for causally effective reasons on the one hand, and
searching for rationalizations or justifications on the other. The difference is not merely
one of how we see the very same activity of deliberating, but must change the form and
course of that deliberation itself. The threat is that we might see ourselves as spectators
Both Korsgaard and Searle could respond that cases such as I have described are
rare, and that maybe we can isolate those situations in which we do suspect that our
19
I suspect, in fact, that this is what the vast majority of our decisions are like—which may be one reason
Kane and van Inwagen exclude most of our decisions from the domain of freedom—but I won’t press the
point. Merleau-Ponty seems to me to be suggesting something similar at the beginning of his chapter on
“Freedom” in The Phenomenology of Perception.
76
decisions are determined prior to deliberation and take only others as paradigms of
deliberation and therefore freedom. But this might be harder than it seems. What cases of
the sort I indicate suggest is that it is possible to see ourselves as both deliberating and
determined at the same time, and to see ourselves this way from the first-person
perspective. If this is possible, there is no reason I can see, other than dogmatic assertion,
to insist that the same sort of prior determination does not occur in the cases where we do
not experience ourselves, prior to deliberation, as inclining toward one of the alternatives.
Referring to this possibility as the second of three objections to his theory of the gap,
Searle offers: “maybe the unconscious psychology overrides the conscious experience of
freedom in every case. The psychological causes may be sufficient to determine all our
actions, even if we are not conscious of these causes.” And then he counters, in typical
Searle style: “I have nothing to say about [this objection], because I do not take it
seriously. There are indeed some cases where our actions are fixed by unconscious
psychological causes—hypnoses cases for example—but it seems incredible that all our
I think Searle is simply missing the force of the argument, and this for several
reasons. First, the case I have suggested is clearly not a case of hypnosis or even remotely
similar. Second, the causes involved need not be unconscious. Consciousness is not
completely transparent, and there may well be all sorts of thoughts, motives, and reasons
that influence our actions, and that are conscious, but that are not explicitly conscious
(rather pre-conscious, in Freud’s sense). This latter point can be bolstered in the
following way: sometimes we are quite sure that we are acting on a particular reason, but
in retrospect change our minds about what our reason was. Should this suggest that the
77
motive we now think was dominant is a new invention? That it was not present at the
time? Third, it is not necessary that all our actions be fixed by underlying motives and
reasons in this way. If some of our actions are, then this is enough to at least create doubt
about our other actions. My argument need not establish that we simply lack self-
knowledge. It need only put the certainty of that knowledge into question. If we can
sometimes be wrong about having genuinely open choices, then it is at least possible that
we are always wrong. That is: we find no refuge from the threat of determinism within
the first-person perspective. We need not, in order to deliberate, do so “as if” we were
free. In fact, even in cases where I do recognize a very strong prior inclination toward one
need to justify the final decision, even if only to myself—a need to weigh my options, to
deliberate, despite the strong suspicion that the outcome is determined. Of course I could,
just to spite the determinist, choose to act against my prior inclination; but that would
Nagel’s argument that free will is actively threatened from within the first-person
perspective thus finds support in this view. As I have been arguing, I do not think Searle
and Korsgaard succeed in demonstrating what they want to: that we must act as if we are
free, or with the belief in our freedom, so that at least at the level of psychology we are
free from determinism. Having pointed out the role of reflection in our conception of
“You will say that this means that our freedom is not ‘real’ only if you have defined the
‘real’ as what can be identified by scientists looking at things third-personally and from
outside.” (1996b 96) Especially in some circles, this view—that determinism cannot be a
78
threat to freedom except from an impersonal perspective—has a certain amount of
authority; I think it is mostly bunk. And it falls to the notion of the “blind spot” pointed
out by Nagel. As mentioned earlier, Nagel thinks that the objective view at first gives us
hope for autonomy: by widening the scope of our self-knowledge, it also widens the
scope of the motives we can subject to scrutiny. “But this objective self-surveillance will
inevitably be incomplete, since some knower must remain behind the lens if anything is
to be known.” (1986 127) Thus, though we may strive to attain complete self-knowledge,
it will always be beyond our grasp. Our view of ourselves is “essentially incomplete”:
“The incomplete view of ourselves in the world includes a large blind spot… that hides
something we cannot take into account in acting, because it is what acts.” (1986 127)
This blind spot drives another nail into the coffin of autonomy. Insofar as the idea of
autonomy involves the idea of being able to know all the motives that influence our
decisions and actions and subject those motives to reflective scrutiny, the blind spot
“our actions may be constrained by an influence we know nothing about. This might be
either something we could successfully resist if we did know about it, or something we
wouldn’t be able to resist even then, but which we also couldn’t accept as a legitimate
The final step in the argument against autonomy along this line is that “we can’t
decisively and irrevocably endorse our actions, any more than we can endorse our beliefs,
from the most objective standpoint we can take toward ourselves, since what we see from
that standpoint is the incomplete view.” (1986 128) This, in essence, is the argument I
have raised against Searle and Korsgaard—but also against the libertarian tradition as
79
such—as the real and overlooked threat posed by determinism. Moreover, my attempt
was to expand this threat from an epistemological necessity into a real psychological
possibility. But we can also reverse the argument against Nagel: what acts is what we
cannot take into account in deliberation. There is therefore the possibility—it is only a
possibility at this point—of responding that the objective view cannot decisively exclude
agency and freedom, because it cannot get at the blind spot. There is—as I noted at the
limitation comes from the fact that the objective view is always taken by someone; it is
not, as Nagel admits, a view from nowhere. As transcendental traditions insist, the limit
on any objective view is the result of the fact that it is a view, that is, that it is always
from some perspective. Whether the source of that perspective can be a source of
freedom is a point I will put off. While Searle and Korsgaard cannot use appeals either to
guaranteed by the first-person standpoint, the standpoint itself might provide such an
opening.
C. The Will
A final point of disagreement between Korsgaard and Searle concerns the nature
is something like the following: Korsgaard claims that to act on a reason is necessarily to
act on a self-given law. But, the objection goes, it is possible for human beings to act
capriciously. I can decide to act on a whim without committing myself to any law that
80
requires me to act on all of my whims, or even on this whim every time it occurs. This is
a common tendency for us, and to deny it seems a bit silly. Korsgaard’s reply to this line
of criticism is ingenious, but as with the argument about freedom, it seems to vacillate
points about human psychology, and it appears to move a bit too freely from the former
to the latter. Nevertheless, there is a core to her argument that I hope I can interpret
correctly in order to extract its truth. Here is where a number of the strands of this chapter
understand willing by analogy with the Humean notion of a cause. A cause involves a
distinguish two events following each other from two causally related events. The will
operates in the light of reflection. To will is not just to be a cause, or even to allow an
impulse in me to operate as a cause, but, so to speak, to consciously pick up the reins, and
make myself the cause of what I do.” (Korsgaard 1996b 227) But this means that I must
be able to distinguish between myself causing an action and one of my desires causing
my action through me. “I am not the mere location of a causally effective desire but
rather am the agent who acts on the desire. It is because of this that if I endorse acting a
certain way now, I must at the same time endorse acting the same way on every
relevantly similar occasion.” (1996b 228) This is clearly confusing; the two sentences do
not seem to belong together in the order and relation that Korsgaard gives them. The first
81
claim seems to be a definition, or a metaphysical description of a self: a self is not a site
of active desires, but is itself active with regard to those desires. But if a self is by
definition active with regard to its desires, it becomes difficult to see why this requires
me to endorse my actions now in any more general form. That is, a move from “is” to
“ought” is implied here with no clear explanation, and I think this problem persists
through Korsgaard’s early account. On the one hand, if I do not will generally, then I am
not an active self. On the other hand, my being an active self requires me to will
generally. Something here is in the wrong order, and I am not convinced that it can be
Searle, in fact, is convinced that it cannot be. He points out that Korsgaard is
Just as the special relation between cause and effect, the necessitation that makes
their relation different from mere temporal sequence, cannot be established in the
absence of law or regularity, so the special relation between agent and action, the
necessitation that makes that relation different from an event’s merely taking
place in the agent’s body, cannot be established in the absence of at least a claim
to law or universality. So I need to will universally in order to see my action as
something which I do. (1996b 228)
This is more than a little odd. As Searle points out, regularity is an epistemic condition of
our being able to recognize a relation of causality; but the lack of regularity does not
guarantee a lack of causality. The fact that we do not see a relation does not mean that the
relation is not there.20 Thus, Searle rejoins that “we can say that from the third-person
decisions as truly his considered decisions, as opposed to his capricious and whimsical
20
It is only a little ironic that Searle is here using precisely the sort of argument a Davidsonian would use
against him.
82
behavior, that they have some sort of order and regularity. But it does not follow that in
order to be his decisions, they have to proceed from a universal law that he makes for
himself.” (2001 155) Searle has a genuine complaint here, but he is clearly missing some
we could not identify the actions of others as their actions in the absence of regularity.
But this is not her argument. Her argument, rather, is that if we did not adopt generality—
or normative regularity—into our reasons, then we could not identify ourselves as agents.
Thus, Searle’s references to the third-person point of view are out of place: Korsgaard’s
point is explicitly about the first-person perspective. I suspect that Searle’s mistake is not
the will: he wants to argue, instead, that regardless of whether we act on principle or on
whim, “the experience of the gap can be the same in both cases.” (Searle 2001 156) As I
have already argued, the whole matter of the “experience of the gap” is a mysterious
cannot be used to support any argument. Furthermore, Searle has another stake in this
debate: he wants to argue against Korsgaard’s notion that the self somehow makes or
creates itself by willing universally. If the self does so, “this is a totally different notion of
the self from the one I am now expounding. [She] must mean we create our character and
personality. The point I am making now is not that action creates a self, but that action
presupposes a self.” (2001 87) Searle’s presupposed self is actually a completely shallow
formality; in fact, he says nothing about it other than that it somehow chooses which of
its reasons for action will become effective; it is, effectively, a Cartesian self that
83
exercises pure willing in a vacuum, with no consequences for its identity. If that notion of
so far as to simply attribute freedom to this self by definition, because a free self is
needed to account for the experience of the gap. But this is just piling suspicious
arguments on top of each other. We can, however, get the kernel of a legitimate
complaint from this argument: it is not clear how the self can create itself without already
Korsgaard’s argument, despite its obscurity, is far more interesting than Searle
allows. An agent, for her, is not an abstract entity that somehow works on reasons, but
rather an entity that, by definition, is self-creating. Searle dismisses the idea because,
clearly (for him, at least), creating our “character and personality” is a merely contingent
matter, which comes only after the real issues of free will have been settled. But that is a
mistake, and it is in this confrontation that we see Korsgaard bringing together the strands
bring out, at least in general form, how she accomplishes this, and I want finally to relate
this move to the notion of temporality at which I have been hinting throughout.
It is true, despite Searle’s various errors, that Korsgaard does seem to conflate
epistemic conditions for identifying agency with ontological conditions of being an agent.
She does not confuse these in the way that Searle thinks, however, although this too is
confusing, because Korsgaard moves quite quickly from an account of why regularity is
agency. But this is not where the odd part of her argument is to be found. Instead, what’s
odd is the ease with which Korsgaard moves from what is required for us to be able to see
84
ourselves as agents, to what is required of us as agents. Let me quote a few typical
remarks.
First, there are those places where Korsgaard seems to suggest that universal
Nagel misses the point when he says that regularity does nothing to establish the
causality of my will. What it does is establish my own ability to see myself as
having a will, as having the kind of self-conscious causality that is a rational will.
(1996b 229)
I cannot regard myself as an active self, as willing an end, unless what I will is to
pursue my end in spite of temptation. (1996b 231)
But then Korsgaard seems to also claim that generality is needed on an ontological level
If I change my mind and my will every time I have a new impulse, then I don’t
really have an active mind or a will at all. (1996b 232)
Perhaps what Korsgaard means is that one cannot be a self without being able to identify
oneself as a self; she seems, in fact, to suggest something of the sort: “we impose the
form of universal volitional principle on our decisions in our attempts to unify ourselves
into agents or characters who persist through time.” (1996b 229) But I do not think this
really works, because Korsgaard wants to make the act of imposing general principles on
oneself into a conscious, self-aware act of self-creation. This is the notion that Searle
rebels against, and rightly so. Phrased without the baggage of the “gap,” Searle’s
argument is essentially like this: my experience of my self is not altered by whether I act
tendency to act capriciously, perhaps I will see myself as lacking consistency and others
85
may see me as unreliable, but my sense of self will not be shattered. That seems right.
The difficulty is that Korsgaard postulates essentially two selves: an “ephemeral self” that
attempts, through making and following general principles, to create an “active self.”
Despite noting the character of paradox here, Korsgaard does not do nearly enough to
resolve it; in fact she exacerbates it, because the phrasing of her remarks about being able
an ephemeral self, a self faced with decisions, feels a psychological need to make general
principles—to create a will—in order to see itself as an agent, i.e., as in charge of its
desires rather than subservient to them. At the same time, Korsgaard seems to recognize
the oddness of this claim, and she seems to reject it, insisting that the real problem is
“whether the active self can coherently be conceived as ephemeral.” (1996b 230)
discussion of the difficulties. Dwelling on difficulties first is poor expository strategy, but
I do not believe that the account itself is coherent; there is thus no way of summarizing
what strikes me as right about it without first acknowledging that my version is not
faithful to the original and why. The difficulty is that if Korsgaard’s claim is taken as a
matter of empirical psychology then the account will not work. To work, it has to assume
into a feature of its decision-making. By having—or making for itself—a will, the self
separates itself from its desires and becomes active with regard to them. This is not quite
Korsgaard’s account because this description of the self is not in terms of its desire or
need to identify itself as an agent; it is about the need of a self to be an agent; but this is
86
self must, to be a self, make its decisions into its will. I am saying that this is a matter of
condition of possibility of the self’s becoming an agent. And it is on these grounds that I
cannot accept Korsgaard’s account as given. She seems to present the choosing of
universal principles as itself an act of agency, but that gives rise to the infinite regress
that the entire tradition, compatibilist and libertarian, has tried so hard to avoid: we must
agency at all. I am not here giving a solution to the problem; I will attempt to do that in
my last chapter. Here I merely note the need for an account of agency that is not itself
agency-dependent.
I want to point to the three most important implications, as I see it, suggested by
Korsgaard’s account.
explicit rejection of Davidson: she repeatedly claims that the point is to separate the self
as agent from the self as a location for effective desires, and she makes two negative
remarks about “anomalous” causes and desires. But the distance from Davidson is only
superficial. It comes in two forms. First, the insistence that our actions are not caused by
our desires. Second, the claim that the cause of our actions lies in the active self.
Korsgaard gets at the issue by embracing Frankfurt’s account, though with two
87
agent’s effective first-order desire but, instead, is associated with the agent’s evaluative
and universal second-order principles.21 Second, she adds the level of freedom
Frankfurt’s account was missing. The agent must still endorse her desires in order to be
free, but this endorsement need not itself be necessitated by external causes—it can
problematic because Korsgaard takes the threat of determinism too lightly). And thus we
come back to Davidson. Though Korsgaard argues that it is the self, not its reasons, that
has the causal power, the distinction becomes far less dire when we recognize that the
self—in its constitution as agent—is identified with its will. The causality, then, is not in
the first-order desire, but in second order principles, or the reasons that an agent makes
into reasons. This strikes me as a largely Davidsonian account, though one transformed
via Frankfurt.
need to be seen as tied to particular acts: they are tied, instead, to the universal principles
taken up in those acts. That is, what is free is the agent’s will; actions are free only in a
derivative sense, insofar as they are the actions of an agent who is in turn already a being
precisely from the fact that they take up a compatibilist concept of personhood and then
append freedom and responsibility to that concept. Korsgaard gets around the problem by
building freedom into the concept of an agent, but building it in as a freedom that goes all
the way down, so to speak, so that it is not a matter of luck. Problems remain, which is
21
This is a deviation from Frankfurt’s early work. The relation between Korsgaard’s (later) work and
Frankfurt’s later work will is discussed in Chapter 6.
88
why I will have more to say on the subject, but this is a major step. A resolution of the
that we are equally free regardless of whether or not we act on general principles or on
our whims. This is right. But Korsgaard’s argument is not that we cease to be free (or to
epistemological and ontological conditions seems to imply this. We are, of course, free (if
we are) regardless of how we act. But the point is that we could not act at all in any
principles; that is, unless we already had a will. Or, to generalize the conclusion: the point
is that the will is ontologically prior to the actions that issue from it. In a different
register, we might say that Korsgaard combines the truth of compatibilism (that freedom
and responsibility are internal aspects of agency) with the truth of libertarianism (that
empirical psychology, social norms, non-agential events, and so on). What allows for this
examined so far, the temporality for the first time is a deep temporality. I believe
Korsgaard gets the account backwards but, at the same time, she shows exactly why a
theory of free agency requires a deep temporality, a point I have largely avoided
universal principles that the self must adopt in order to be an agent. In explaining why a
self must unify itself into an agent by taking up universal principles, Korsgaard states that
89
“the view of itself as active now essentially involves a projection of itself into other
possible occasions.” (1996b 230) In endorsing a desire to act as a reason, that is, as a
universal ground for action, the self essentially creates for itself a temporally persisting
identity. By deciding now that a certain desire is a reason, I decide simultaneously that
future, and should have been as binding on me in the past, as it is now. An obvious
criticism at this point would go like this: perhaps our principles are binding on us in the
future, but what could it mean to say that they are binding in the past? Here is one
answer: It is possible for me to act in a way I think is right but, in retrospect, to feel guilty
about having acted that way. The reason is that in my past action I violated a principle to
which I now hold. Although back then I was, in a sense, a different self with different
principles, from my current vantage point I recognize that I was the same self and was
The argument that principles must be universal can be broken up into two parts.
First, as we have already seen, a unity across time is needed in order to establish the self
as an agent. Korsgaard draws out this idea by pointing to the role, first, of hypothetical
that, if we will a certain end, we must also will the means to it. Korsgaard’s argument is
that if we do not will the means—or, more specifically, if we give up the means every
time that they seem too difficult—then we never really will any end. If this were to occur,
we would not have agency, because we would be drawn each time only by the desire of
the moment, which tempts us from our goal. The argument is not entirely sound: it seems
perfectly conceivable that we might will ends without willing the means if they are too
90
difficult. This reflects that we do not will the ends very strongly, which is perfectly
compatible with agency, but it does not, I think, involve a loss of agency. Yet
Korsgaard’s account has a deeper level, and this is another case where her language
seems misleading. The point is that I cannot have a will at all unless I do, occasionally,
commit myself to some ends. A self that genuinely cannot pursue goals is, clearly, a self
that lacks agency. And so the better way of putting Korsgaard’s point, I think, is not that
following hypothetical imperatives is necessary for agency, but that the ability to follow
hypothetical imperatives is. Something similar is true of principles: if, every time we are
confronted with a difficulty, we deviate from our principles, then we have no principles at
all. But the deeper point is that it is the ability or capacity of sticking to our principles, of
resisting temptation, that is essential to agency. An agent, then, is a self that is capable of
Second, temporality is built into the very idea of being able to do otherwise. This
is why I can act capriciously—I can violate my principles—and still remain free, even
though it is the ability to have principles that constitutes my agency. “When we act self-
consciously, we act under the idea of freedom: we think that we could act otherwise on
this occasion. But that means that ‘this occasion’ itself must be conceived in general
that it could be otherwise.” (Korsgaard 1996b 231) When I act reflectively, when I take
my desire as a reason for action and so adopt a principle on which I act, I am not making
a principle for any particular moment. That would make no sense. I am making a
22
I am stressing this point because it is the substantive conclusion I want to draw from Korsgaard’s
account. As I am about to argue, however, I think it gets things exactly backwards: the will is not
dependent on its choices in the now, but the reverse. Thus, I offer this substantive conclusion as a contrast
to my argument in Chapter 6.
91
principle that applies to moments in the past and (more significantly) future that are in
relevant ways similar to the present moment. The reason I must do this, as the argument
just quoted shows, is that otherwise it would not make sense for me to say that I could
have acted otherwise. If the reason I act on is only valid in this single instant, then it does
not make sense to say that I can, or could, act otherwise, since I do not in fact act
otherwise than I do. To say that I could act otherwise already implies that I am making a
rule that applies not in a particular moment, but in a certain kind of situation; this
situation, in turn, is only contingently tied to a given moment in time. That I can deviate
from this rule at other times—in fact, that I could make a rule now for the moment at
hand and immediately violate it—is possible. In fact it is implied in the universality of the
rule. And this is Korsgaard’s point: it is only because I have a rule, or because I choose
my reason not for the instant but for the universal case, that it even makes sense for me to
How does this step introduce deep temporality into the account of freedom and
why does it show the importance of that temporality? Korsgaard’s argument, essentially,
an attitude, that applies not just to the moment at which the choice is made, or to the
moment at which the choice is carried out, but to any relevantly similar moment. The
choice is an event that occurs at a particular moment in time. But the attitude that is
chosen along with it is not a similar event. In fact, it is not an event at all. An event, as
Davidson tells us, is a dated occurrence. But the attitude is neither dated nor an
23
Of course I might act otherwise simply because I do not reflect. But since completely unreflective action
is not taken by Korsgaard or by most free will theorists to be a free one, we can leave the issue of such
actions aside.
92
similar occasions. On those occasions, if they arise, I may or may not act on the basis of
this attitude, and my conforming or failing to conform to the principle will, each time, be
an event. But the principle itself is clearly not an event; there are moments at which it is
instantiated or not instantiated, but there is no moment or set of moments, not even a set
of possible moments, to which the rule is confined. This is the notion of deep temporality
I have been using: the relation between the choice and its relevant underlying attitude or
motive or principle is precisely the relation between an event in time and a non-event, a
Now, the second question: why is deep temporality important? As I have tried to
show, Korsgaard’s account opens the way to a functional theory of freedom that can also
not succeed because they lack genuine freedom in their attitudes; or at least in whatever
attitudes ultimately underlie our choices. While the choices may be free relative to the
attitudes, the origin of the attitudes seems to negate that freedom. I have tried to make
this point in relation to both Davidson and Frankfurt. Libertarian theories, on the other
hand, focus on indeterminacy, but since they accept the compatibilist account of the
self—an account on which the motives and reasons among which the agent chooses are
simply given to the agent from outside—they also seem to deprive the agent of genuine
agency. Both the compatibilist and the libertarian, in other words, run into problems
because their accounts are ultimately reducible to a shallow temporality. They take both
terms in the choice/will distinction as events; even if the choice is free relative to the will,
and even if the choice is genuinely undetermined in some way, its underlying will is still
93
see both our choices and the relevant motivating factors behind them as mere events,
incoherent. The deep temporality of Korsgaard’s account opens the way out of the
predicament: if our choices are freely chosen events, and if the attitudes behind them are
not events at all and are also chosen, then Nagel’s reduction of freedom to incoherence
may be avoided.
But I have also argued that Korsgaard’s account is problematic, because she fails
to recognize the genuine threat posed by determinism and eliminativism. The threat, as I
mentioned, is that the “blind spot,” our lack of complete self-knowledge, might prevent
us from being able to endorse our actions in a purely unbiased way. We might think that
we are acting on the strongest reasons in light of self-chosen universal laws, but we might
be wrong.24 Furthermore, we might simply lack access to the best reasons for action. This
is tied to another issue: Korsgaard does not establish the will as a guidance mechanism
for actions, but the reverse. She is right to set up a deep temporality, but she
accomplishes it in the wrong way. For Korsgaard we create our will by making choices
that involve not simply the selection of a particular action, but a universal rule. But this,
in turn, is similar to the libertarian model we have seen in Kane, on which a free choice
involves both a choice of action and the assignment of relative weights to the reasons
its will, the self projects itself into other past and future circumstances, is significant, but
it does not alter the model in a fundamental enough way. The will is chosen together with
24
Since, as I have argued, freedom is needed to give us the ability to act on moral laws, I want to briefly
raise the real Kantian threat to Korsgaard’s account: the threat is that, although we might act legally, we
would not be able to act morally. In a more common idiom: we might end up acting on the right reasons,
but not for the right reasons. This threat is why freedom, for Kant, is not simply untouched by determinism,
but requires the rejection of determinism, at least outside the phenomenal world.
94
the choice; while it has a different temporality, it does not establish a genuinely
temporally unifying will unless the self decides to follow the general rules contained in
this will in future circumstances. Korsgaard does attempt to deal with that difficulty by
insisting that, if the self fails to maintain its will in other similar circumstances, then it
ceases to be a self. But, again, this move is clearly insufficient, for Korsgaard strongly
appears to be making a claim about empirical psychology and probably a false one at
that.25 She does at one point suggest that she is offering a transcendental argument, but I
Despite the deep temporality suggested in the idea that a self commits itself to a
will in its reflective choices, this alone is insufficient for either genuine freedom or
responsibility. Korsgaard’s step illustrates the role deep temporality can play in agency;
but something further is needed, namely, a will that is not simply chosen within its
actions, but one that underlies the actions. Unless we develop an account along those
lines, I do not think we have a convincing account of freedom, and not one sufficient for
either morality or responsibility. The will, or the attitudes constituting it, cannot be
chosen within a temporal choice, because that merely reduces the will of the agent back
to the particular choices made; in other words, the will vanishes into its choices instead of
grounding them. This account, on which we choose our long-term dispositions by making
decisions in the present, may seem satisfactory from the standpoint of surface
psychological phenomena, but it is insufficient for any transcendental account that could
ground responsibility. Its consequence is that the will fails to affect its choices in any
25
As I mentioned earlier, it has to be false because one must already have agency in order to be able to
actually commit oneself to universal rules. Korsgaard seems to reverse the order, but that reversal is
untenable. This is separate from the point that one must be able to commit oneself to universal rules in
order to be an agent at all.
95
way; it is rather the choices that determine the will. But if so, then the introduction of the
will in this context fails to radically transform the standard libertarian account of
freedom. What we need to resolve this problem is a way of having a free will without
position, freedom and responsibility require as a condition only that agents’ actions
follow from some underlying character or will. But if the will does not originate in some
sense form the agent, what we are left with is a collection of states or events—willings,
desiring, choosing, actings—connected to each other in some way. In order to insert the
agent into this picture, one must make the agent into a site for the occurrence of events.
There are various happenings, linked together through causal chains, so that some region
of these events, entirely continuous with events outside the region, can be circumscribed
and referred to as “agent.” Here the agent is not really active at all, but only a recipient
and medium for the happening of events. What acts is the world. The agent participates.
To give the agent an active role, one must in some sense sever the links between
This is the point at which libertarians come in. Typical libertarian accounts defend
freedom of action, or at least the freedom of the effective deliberative process, and
thereby seem to fall to the Humean objection: it makes no sense to hold someone
responsible for an action that is in no way continuous with his character. The action is
96
then random; it is not an action at all, but a mere event. One libertarian attempt to deal
with this problem is to state that the agent’s character or will (including reasons, motives,
and so on) is already in place prior to deliberation. The agent must decide on the basis of
this character, but the decision is not determined by the character. Thus, whichever way
the agent decides, his decision will be continuous with his character but, at the same time,
free. But this still doesn’t escape the eliminativist threat: if whatever choice the agent
makes is continuous with his character, but his character is outside the domain of his
freedom, then the freedom so attained does not seem to allow for the sort of radical
meet: on the one hand, agents must somehow choose on the basis of their will. On the
other hand, their will must be unconditioned, that is, it must not be composed of elements
that pre-exist the agent’s choice. We are born into social structures that provide us with
norms we adopt and we have various biological and psychological tendencies; if these
wholly constitute our wills, then any choice we make will not be up to us. Perhaps we can
choose among those tendencies of our wills, but we will be choosing on the basis of the
wills. And if the wills are—to start with—not up to us, then choosing on the basis of
them will not make them so. This combinations of requirements, however, seems to be
incoherent: if the agent does not choose his will on the basis of pre-existing reasons, then
And that is Nagel’s point: what we are looking for in free will is incoherent. Responding
to eliminativism, then, will require a further strategy. I have been suggesting that this
97
In the previous section I argued that we need an account of the will that (1) like
Korsgaard’s ranges over all times, or all choices that the agent might take up, and (2)
unlike Korsgaard’s is not reducible to individual events of choice but instead precedes
and affects those choices. The former requirement is needed because otherwise we will
not be able to get any genuine freedom out of the equation: we will be left with a
sequence of events, none of which can properly be attributed to an agent. We need the
latter requirement, on the other hand, because without it the temporal depth established
threatens to disappear: if the agent creates his will at the same time as he makes a choice,
then the will is threatened by dissolution from the outset. This is, in fact, already implicit
in Korsgaard’s account: the will must actually be effective with regard to the various
choices of the agent; if it is constituted together with the choice, then it is only
I have argued that the trick is to fit the agent into what is a mere sequence of
events. How does one do this? Postulating an indeterminate choice does not seem to help.
But we can take a page from Frankfurt here: by identifying with their wills, agents can
make those wills their own. And agents can originate actions only if they take those
actions on the basis of their own will. Frankfurt’s account of this will not do, however,
since he makes ownership entirely a matter of luck. And that seems like a consequence of
the view that ownership is a matter of a match between different states, each of which can
view of ownership, we have to develop a different view of temporality, which allows our
98
will allows it to affect choices in time without being reducible to them: it stops the
regress involved in events that pre-exist and condition the will. At the same time, the
agent’s ownership of his will stops the regress involved in discovering the will to be
do we get agents in a strong sense: entities capable of being the sole originators of their
actions. To develop this account, I am going to start over. The attempt to work out an
account of free will has hit an aporia. Instead of pursuing it further, I will now turn to the
strongest theory of moral responsibility that does not presuppose free will.
99
4
Responsibility
Let me begin with Galen Strawson’s “Basic Argument,” which like Nagel’s
whether or not determinism is true. The simplest version of the argument goes like this:
The way the argument is supposed to work is quite simple. Strawson focuses on actions
that are done for a reason (though presumably the same argument would be even stronger
in the case of actions that are not), and states as a premise that in acting for a reason,
“what one does is a function of how one is, mentally speaking.” (Strawson 1994 6) But if
this is true, it follows that, in order to be responsible for one’s action, one must also be
responsible for how one is, mentally speaking (Strawson later refers to “how one is” in
short” (Strawson 1994 9)). There are of course important ways in which we can shape
how we are: we can evaluate and attempt to change our attitudes on the basis of our
evaluations, and we can undertake to acquire habits that will change our CPM. The
problem, however, is that in order to make such choices in the first place, one must
100
already possess “some principles of choice, ‘P1’—preferences, values, pro-attitudes,
ideals—in the light of which one chooses how to be.” (Strawson 1994 6) In order to be
responsible for the CPM we choose on the basis of P1, however, we must also have
chosen the P2 on the basis of which we can choose P1. We have clearly arrived at an
infinite regress.
What gives rise to the regress is the claim that, in order to be responsible for any
action or state of character, we must also be responsible for whatever it is in our CPM on
the basis of which we can choose that action or state of character. We could avoid the
regress only if we could, at some point in the chain, be causa sui: if we could choose our
CPM, and the resultant Pn, on the basis of no underlying CPM and Pn-1. But human
beings cannot be causa sui in this way. Strawson brings the point home by rejecting two
replies to the Basic Argument. One suggestion is that one’s self—the self we hold
responsible—is somehow independent of one’s CPM. We can make choices on the basis
of our CPM, but the CPM does not determine which choice we make; that part is up to
our self. The response, however, is that this self, in order to be able to choose among
alternatives, must still have some preferences, some Pn, on the basis of which to choose.
Simply adding another level, a self, to the CPM model does not dissolve the problem; it
the answer: what one does, on this view, may well be a “function” of how one is, but the
choice between different alternatives, each of which finds some reason or motivation
among the agent’s existing CPM, is not determined by that CPM. Strawson’s response
here is to point out that indeterminism does not help. Either, once again, the choice is
101
made by the agent in some way (in which case it must depend on how the agent is), or the
choice is completely random, and “it is absurd to suppose that indeterministic or random
factors, for which one is ex hypothesi in no way responsible, can in themselves contribute
to having any [responsibility] for how one is” (Strawson 2000 151). Either how one
which case the result is a matter of luck, for which the agent cannot be responsible.
since he replies to opposing views in “their more simple expressions, in the belief that
truth in philosophy, especially in areas of philosophy like the present one, is almost never
very complicated” (1994 11). This has lead Strawson’s opponents to attempt to formulate
more complex accounts of how indeterminism might help with the problem, though it is
not clear that any of these accounts can defeat Strawson’s simple point. A further
in a rather extreme way: “true moral responsibility is responsibility of such a kind that, if
we have it, then it makes sense, at least, to suppose that it could be just to punish some of
us with (eternal) torment in hell and reward others with (eternal) bliss in heaven” (1994
6). Strawson points out, of course, that his argument is not meant to rest on this religious
One problem, raised by Clarke (2005), points to the fact that, if we tone down the
notion of responsibility to account for the fact that we are finite beings, and thus eternal
might end up with different conclusions. Another line of thought, raised by Ekstrom
(2000), among others, points out that the question of moral responsibility is a
102
metaphysical question that is conceptually distinct from questions about the desirability,
appropriate to hold someone responsible without punishing them at all; and questions
about responsibility do, after all, make sense even if we believe that punishment, as such,
is simply not the right response to violations of norms (a view defended, for example, by
Sayre-McCord (2001). Smith (2005) goes one step further, pointing out that “being
responsible” can and often does come apart from our reasons for “holding [someone]
responsible.” If so, not simply the issue of punishment, but the issue of whether or not we
should hold someone responsible for their actions will simply be entirely irrelevant to the
issue of whether or not one is, in fact, responsible. But it is not clear that these arguments
serve to undermine Strawson’s basic point. Making them stick would require a notion of
punishment and holding responsible, but that separates responsibility from the agent’s
control. And this is a far more difficult issue (I will address some attempts along these
argument directly, providing two lines of attack. Let me begin with the second. A slew of
(PAP) (Frankfurt 1969) has attempted to establish that agents can be responsible for their
actions regardless of whether or not they could have done otherwise. Frankfurt himself
defended this claim by arguing that what matters for moral responsibility is that the first-
order desire on which the agent acts be one with which the agent identifies through a
second-order volition. If this condition holds, the agent is responsible for his action A
103
even if—counterfactually—some intervener was on hand to ensure that, had the agent in
fact decided to perform some other action not-A, he would still have been forced to
perform A. The moral of the story, then, is that the presence of the counterfactual
intervener, and thus the agent’s inability to do not-A, is irrelevant to the issue of moral
responsibility given that the agent identified with his desire to A and did in fact A.
The literature on PAP is vast, and I do not have space to survey it here. But the
because of the way he is mentally, this does not by itself detract from his responsibility.
Thus, whether or not the agent is responsible for the way he is mentally is irrelevant to
the question of his responsibility for A-ing. Clarke’s point here is merely that Strawson’s
is, he can only be responsible for A if he is also responsible for the way he is—that a
number of philosophers reject. In order to convince them, Strawson would have to show
Chapter 2, questioned the basic intuition behind Frankfurt’s view of moral responsibility.
To rehash: Frankfurt argues that agents are responsible, and act of their own free will,
provided that their second-order volitions match up with their effective first-order desires.
But Frankfurt considers irrelevant whether or not the agent is responsible either for his
second-order volitions or for the correspondence between those volitions and their first-
luck. But this result seems counterintuitive: if I am not responsible for whether or not my
action in fact stems from a desire with which I identify, responsibility is reduced to a
104
lucky coincidence: some people are responsible for their actions while others are not, just
as some people are tall while others are short. But our responsibility does not, on this
view, depend on what we do; it depends only on whether or not what we do also happens
seems, we must attempt to establish some responsibility for our attitudes, as well.
aforementioned premise that “what one does is a function of how one is.” There are two
ways of taking this claim: either what one does is determined by what one is, or it is not.
Without offering any attempt at a knock-down argument, Clarke points out that
Strawson’s assumption that the latter is correct begs the question against a number of
libertarians. Citing Van Inwagen and Nozick, Clarke brings up an alternative largely
overlooked by Strawson’s account. The alternative runs, roughly, thus: An agent might
have reasons to do either A or B. That the agent has both of these reasons (or sets of
reasons) is a result of how he is mentally. Assuming that the agent is not responsible for
how he is mentally, it may still be possible for him to be responsible for whether he does
because of his reasons to B. Thus, even though the agent is responsible neither for the
reasons he has, nor for the fact that A is caused by one set of reasons and B by another,
he may still be responsible for which set of reasons was in fact effective. All that is
needed is that (1) how one is mentally does not deterministically cause the action and (2)
the agent somehow determines which set of reasons in fact led to the action. Should this
account succeed, agents could be responsible for their actions without having to also be
105
The simplest response to this line is to press the standard objection to
indeterministic accounts, as Strawson does in passing. Let us say that, given his CPM, an
indeterministically caused by his CPM. This means that in some possible worlds, the
agent will do A; in others, he will do B. In each possible world the agent has exactly the
same CPM, but performs different actions. But surely, the objection goes, the agent is not
responsible for which possible world he is in. But whether the agent performs A or B
seems to depend entirely on precisely that; nothing about the agent determines what he
does, since, by hypothesis, the agent is exactly the same in each of the relevant worlds
responsible for the world they happen to inhabit, it seems they also cannot be responsible
for which action they perform in the world they happen to be in. Clarke’s point, of
course, is not that the indeterministic model has a particularly devastating response to
such arguments; his claim is only that, given the vast array of philosophical literature
dealing with such problems, Strawson cannot simply assume the deterministic model.
It is worth pointing out that the Basic Argument, like van Inwagen’s Consequence
Argument, is not a new argument at all. It is, as Strawson readily admits, as ancient as the
problem of free will and moral responsibility itself. As with the Consequence Argument,
in fact, it is difficult to see how the free will problem could be a problem at all for anyone
who fails to take the argument seriously. These arguments merely express features of the
phenomena of free will and moral responsibility, features without which these
phenomena could not be what they are. One might thus wonder whether either argument
106
can be diffused through endless metaphysical quibbling over the nature of causation.
There is, in any case, a further reason to take the view that responsibility for one’s action
Perhaps, as the indeterminist claims, we might choose different actions given the same
CPM, but deliberate actions do not simply flow from one set of attitudes or another. They
are chosen on the basis of deliberation. And deliberation requires not simply having
certain beliefs and desires, but also performing some operation involving those beliefs
and desires, issuing in decisions, intentions, and actions. Nor are such deliberations
typically simple: we rarely find ourselves in a situation with exactly two possible courses
of action and exactly two, clearly defined, sets of attitudes supporting each one. What we
encounter in deliberation is far more complex; our attitudes often remain shapeless and
ill-defined before we reflect on them, and frequently do not gain much clarity despite
entering into deliberative operation. The idea that desires and other pro-attitudes are
clearly defined propositional attitudes is a useful simplification, but it can easily become
misleading: in real life deliberation we frequently discover what we want, if at all, only
when we first reflect on what we should do. Nor, incidentally, do we have well-defined
algorithms telling us just which of our attitudes we must call up in making our decisions.
explanation of weakness of will. (Davidson 1980d) The scope of beliefs and desires
involved in causing our actions may well be far narrower than the scope of beliefs and
desires that enters into forming our all things considered judgment concerning the best
course of action. Moreover, as Arpaly (2003) adds, there is no guarantee that the all
107
things considered judgment agents come to in deliberation will, in fact, consider all
relevant things: we are liable to miss all sorts of relevant desires and beliefs, precisely
because we lack the perfect algorithm for gathering an exhaustive list. (Unfortunately,
Arpaly equates the actual judgment an agent reaches with the agent’s “best judgment,”
though it is fairly clear that, on any common meaning of that term, the point is instead
that the agent’s considered judgment may well fail to be her best judgment.) Advising
agents to follow their considered judgment will not, then, guarantee that their action best
represents their character; nor, obviously, will advising them not to follow that judgment.
Arpaly herself uses the argument as a springboard for the further insistence that
depends on the extent or even the presence of deliberation in producing our actions. I will
return to that point. For now, however, I want to raise the following issue: What we
decide to do depends on (1) how clear we are about the relevant character states, (2) how
clear we are about which character states are relevant, and (3) which character states
finally cause our actions. But all of these features are, themselves, products of character.
Some people are better attuned to their wants and beliefs than others; some are better at
finding and considering the relevant ones; and some are better at having their actions
stem from the best considerations.26 But how good agents are at each of these tasks is a
matter of character, and insofar as one’s CPM is behind the clarity with which their
choices are made, and the efficiency with which the clearer choices determine one’s
26
I do not mean to refer here, exclusively, to continence in the classic sense as involving strength of will.
Having the sort of character that allows one to follow through on one’s judgments of what is best is one
thing; having the sort of character that facilitates having the rights sorts of mental connections—
connections that link decisions about what to act to decisions about what is best—is another. We often do
what we should not merely through inattention; whether one wishes to call such cases instances of “weak
will” is not important to my considerations here.
108
action, character clearly plays a crucial role in the production of action, and one that does
not—in any obvious way—allow the final choice of action itself to ground the agent’s
responsibility.
thought is not a kind of action. “The role of genuine action in thought is at best indirect. It
we may actively decide to think about a certain topic, keep ourselves from wandering
away from it, or try to reinforce the thought process in various ways, there is “no action
phenomena just mentioned” (2003 232). So whatever role action plays in getting us to
think and keeping us there, “the coming to mind itself—the actual occurrence of
thoughts, conscious or non-conscious—is not a matter of action.” (2003 234). And this
view, that thought is something that “just happens” to us, can be carried into the sorts of
thoughts that constitute our judgments about what to do and even our decisions, so that
“most deciding what to do is best seen as something that just happens, even if there is
also, and crucially, some sort of genuine action of positive commitment to the decision,
either at the time it is reached, or at the moment of the ‘passage à l’acte’.” (2003 244)
So while our actions are up to us, in the sense that we can decide what to do, the
decisions themselves do not seem to be up to us in that way any more than the content of
decisions—is up to us. It is, incidentally, for this very reason that virtue ethicists tend to
stress the moral importance of being a certain kind of person: if our chosen actions flow
from the thoughts that occur to us, then being the sort of person to whom particular
109
thoughts and not others occur enters into considerations of moral responsibility. Whether
or not immoral considerations occur to us in the course of deliberation may have only a
whether or not moral ones do will certainly make more of a difference. Moreover,
whether we decide to act on our moral or immoral considerations, provided that both
occur to us, may well be a matter of which way our deliberation happens to go and the
idea that we actively choose a course of action, or make a judgment about which course
One can, of course, take note of Strawson’s use of “most” in “most deciding what
to do.” And this might open the way for a restrictivist response: while most of our
decisions are the sorts of events that “just occur” to us, some are not, and perhaps we can
hold those to be the locus of responsibility. But there is a sense in which Strawson’s
“most” is just a way of being agreeable: ultimately, even if some of our decisions are
actions rather than just thoughts that occur to us, those decisions themselves will need
some preconditions in thought. In other words, even if some of our decisions involve
agency, they do not ultimately involve it: we are not causa sui with regard to anything we
decide.
Once again, then, we come back to character. The attitudes or character traits that
cause our actions do, of course, belong to character. But so do the other attitudes, the
character and of attitudes frequently focus only on the narrow, former group. But it is the
latter group that forms the decisive links between what we are mentally (in the narrow
sense) and what we do. Our character does not merely provide us with the raw materials
110
for taking actions; it serves also as the inescapable background of those actions. With this
acknowledgement I want merely to complicate any position that attempts to make our
responsibility for our actions independent of our responsibility for character, for how we
are mentally. Indeterminism or not, the decisions that lead to actions rise out of a
complex soup, much of which we are not aware of; as the term “background” suggests,
much of it we cannot be aware of insofar as we are engaged in making decisions. If, then,
we are to be responsible for our actions, it is difficult to avoid the conclusion that we
must also be responsible for the background of those actions, for how we are mentally.
With this consideration in mind, I now turn to recent discussions about the nature of such
responsibility.
While Frankfurt has changed his mind about what is required for identification
with a desire, a constant theme in his work has been that responsibility requires a match
between certain of the agent’s attitudes. Depending on how one explains identification,
then, it becomes possible to give an account of responsibility that is detached from the
agent’s voluntary control over her actions or attitudes; what matters for responsibility is
whether an agent’s action is representative of her Real Self.27 This theme has in recent
years been combined with a view of responsibility developed from Peter Strawson’s
influential “Freedom and Resentment” (1962), which appeared nine years prior to
Frankfurt’s seminal work. In that article, Strawson proposes that we accord priority to the
111
disconnect the practical questions of whether we can or should give up such attitudes
from the theoretical question of whether or not agents do in fact have metaphysical free
will. If we should and must treat someone as if they are responsible, the suggestion runs,
responsibility from metaphysics. But it adds two other crucial (and connected)
components as well. First, it centers on our actual practices of praise and blame, focusing
specifically on what about the agent evokes our reactive attitudes. Second, in answering
this question, it proposes that we feel gratitude or resentment, anger or sympathy, on the
basis of the quality of the agent’s will. Thus, for example, we will resent someone who
acts out of malice while we may not resent—or may resent less—someone who carries
out the same action out of a mistaken sense of love or loyalty to a worthy person or
cause. And we may not resent at all someone who acts out of a compulsion, especially
one that runs counter to her overall attitude. The combination of these two approaches—
the Real Self View and the quality of will theory—has led to a number of new theories of
volitionist view of responsibility, I will attempt to shed some light on the notion of
control required for responsibility; in the next chapter I will look at the notion of choice.28
28
I take the terms “attributionism” and “volitionism” from Neil Levy (2005). Levy borrows the term
“volitionism” from Smith (2005), who refers to her own approach as the “rational relations” view and
groups it under the general category of “non-volitional” accounts (2008). I will use Levy’s terminology
here.
112
Attributionism is the view that an agent is responsible for her action, omission, or
attitude29 if it can be attributed to her as an agent.30 Volitionism, on the other hand, takes
the more traditional line that we can be responsible only for something we have chosen
and have control over. Or so the standard definitions go. The central—and to
responsible for that which is traceable back to his choice, voluntary control, or conscious
deliberation. But this rough characterization obscures what is, on my view, the central
bone of contention between the two accounts: by presupposing that we already know the
meaning of terms such as “deliberation,” “choice,” “control,” and “voluntary,” the parties
to this debate seem to me to conceal the central requirement for responsibility. What
responsibility requires something like choice or control, but rather what kind of choice or
converge.
I will develop this thought as I go along. For now, however, I want to make one
which the agent is not aware, from deep-seated drives to processes occurring just below
the level of awareness. This terminological haziness forces consciousness into a thin skin,
29
Smith specifically defines her view as one that accounts for responsibility for attitudes and—she thinks—
omissions. Arpaly and Sher take in actions as well.
30
On Smith’s view, “according to these philosophers, what really matters in determining a person’s
responsibility for some thing is whether that thing can be seen as indicative or expressive of her judgments,
values, or normative commitments.” (Smith 2008 368) While this is a fine summary of her view, however,
it is too narrow to encompass all the views she has in mind. Sher, in particular, argues that this account is
still too narrow to account for the entire range of our ordinary judgments of responsibility.
113
with only enough room for thoughts to which we have immediate, effortless access. It
thus problematically drives the vast majority of our thoughts, decisions, and actions into
the realm of the unconscious, a realm for which—as the dominant paradigm would have
it—we lack responsibility. To avoid prejudging the issues in this way, I will treat the
(CTDs). These are decisions or choices that agents make not merely with awareness of
what they are doing, but with a thematized awareness—such a decision (and perhaps the
deliberation leading up to it) is, so to speak, the focal point of the agent’s awareness at
the time it is made. The debate may thus be rephrased in the following terms: volitionists
believe that responsibility requires CTDs; attributionists do not. But what, then, do
Here I will look at three approaches, developed by Angela Smith, Nomy Arpaly
(alone and together with Timothy Schroeder), and George Sher. These theorists share the
Frankfurtian view that responsibility for a thing requires some straightforward connection
between that thing and the self. At the same time, they reject Frankfurt’s insistence that
the “self” relevant to responsibility consists of higher order volitions, by means of which
agents either identify or fail to identify with their first order desires. Consider, for
example, the case of a man who knowingly treats others badly, although he does this
enough to excuse him from responsibility. This is even clearer if we take a brief look at
the version of the Real Self view developed by Gary Watson. Concerned that Frankfurt’s
account of identification allows for an infinite regress of higher order volitional states,
114
Watson suggested that we contrast desires and values; our Real Self, on this view, is to be
identified with our values (Watson 1982). But this hardly works any better: when a
person acts contrary to his values, this does not—intuitively—excuse him from
responsibility; rather, it compounds it: not only does he act wrongly, but he betrays his
values while doing so. Responding to such concerns, attributionists seek to link
responsibility to a notion of self far broader than identification, choice (in the volitionist
sense), or reflective endorsement. The goal—and this is the aspect of attributionism that
will particularly interest me—is to show that these intermediaries are not needed in an
account of responsibility. Instead, the idea goes, we can be responsible for actions and
attitudes because these can be immediately and directly attributed to our selves.
seriously the Strawsonian focus on our actual practices of praise and blame. In ordinary,
the agent’s choice. Or, at least, it is clear that if we were to do so, many of our ordinary
judgments would turn out to be false, and we often attribute responsibility for actions and
attitudes that were clearly not chosen by the agent, a point illustrated in detail through the
attempted to deal with the problem through tracing, i.e., the view that in cases where
agents seem to be responsible for an action or attitude, and yet clearly have not chosen it,
we might show them to be responsible by tracing the development of the attitude or the
creation of a situation in which the action became unavoidable to some earlier act of
choice on the agent’s part (theories of tracing often draw on updated versions of the
115
problem cases—seem implausible to anyone not in the grip of a particular theory, it has
recently come under sustained theoretical fire as well. Vargas (2005), for example,
presents a series of clear examples such as that of Jeff the Jerk. Jeff has the job of firing
people, and fulfills this job in the rudest possible way because he is, to put it simply, a
jerk. He is, intuitively, responsible for the insensitive way he treats those he fires. But, as
Vargas neatly shows, it is fairly easy to construct a back story on which Jeff does not, at
any point in his life, knowingly make choices that will lead him to become the sort of
person who will treat people badly as he fires them. In fact, it would be rather difficult, in
cases of this sort, to construct a different back story. No doubt we can sometimes choose
to cultivate particular sorts of habits and character traits, and we might even choose to do
so knowingly, but this sort of deliberate character formation accounts for only a tiny
minority of the character traits of normal human beings.31 If we are to account for what
seems like a vast majority of our ordinary judgments, then, a volitionist view once again
Smith develops a view clearly meant to handle these two difficulties. To be proper
objects for moral appraisal, a person’s actions, attitudes, or omissions need have no
particular history, nor must they stand in a relationship removed from the agent by some
volitional act of choice or identification. Rather, they need to directly “reflect her
31
Vargas’s point is even stronger. He argues not simply that Jeff did not know that some of the actions he
undertook as a teenager would lead him to become a jerk, but that Jeff certainly did not know that whatever
character-forming practices he engaged in as a teenager would lead him to one day be insensitive in firing
people. I would venture that there are two further epistemic criteria for “choice” in the volitionist sense that
character-forming acts will fail to meet, both resting on the impossibility of knowing the future. First, since
we lack anything like precise knowledge of how character-formation works, we cannot have full
knowledge of how even the most deliberate character-forming acts will shape our character. Second, since
when I choose acts that I believe will form a certain character, I cannot, in principle, know what it will be
like for me to have that character. I can know what it is like to act as if I were a jerk, but I cannot know
what it is like to think and act as a jerk since, presumably, I have not yet managed to form that character
trait. Even if I choose to become a jerk, then, I cannot do so in the full knowledge of the sort of character I
am, in fact, acquiring for myself. (For example, I may assume that I will still have certain options of
thinking and behaving open to me that will, in fact, never even occur to me once I become a real jerk.)
116
practical agency.” (Smith 2008 381) What counts as belonging to a person’s practical
agency, in turn, must be broad enough to include the sorts of things we commonly hold
people responsible for, yet narrow enough to exclude inexplicable urges, implanted
features (which, though they may play some role in agency, do not belong to agency as
such). What allows us to delineate the field of responsibility in this way is an appeal to
rationality: agents are responsible for those things that, roughly speaking, have a rational
content and are at least somewhat integrated into the agent’s overall normative
framework. Since physical features have no rational content, whereas inexplicable urges
and implanted thoughts will lack any normative connection to the agent’s other beliefs
and judgments, this criterion seems to contain just what is needed while excluding
anything external to agency; this view therefore “gives us a satisfying account of the
In working out her account in a plausible way, Smith discusses the sorts of things
we hold people responsible for, showing the ways in which they reflect evaluative
judgments on the part of the agent. In particular, Smith emphasizes that we often hold
people responsible for things frequently left out by standard volitionist accounts: patterns
of noticing or neglecting states of affairs around us, the sorts of thoughts that occur to us,
and even some involuntary reactions. Consider the first case: it is one thing for a driver to
notice a child riding a bicycle near his car, and whether or not a driver sees this may not
reflect his practical agency in the least. But it is quite another thing for a driver to take
care to keep track of the child’s position in order to minimize any risk of a collision. A
driver who fails to continue to keep tabs on the child, or perhaps does not notice that the
117
child is in poor control of his bicycle, is blameworthy for this oversight. Someone
concerned for the child’s safety, on Smith’s reasoning, would notice the child’s lack of
control, although these activities of noticing and monitoring need not be consciously
willed. It is simply the case that drivers who hold the safety of children to be important
notice certain things that other drivers do not, and the difference between these drivers is
a morally relevant one. The driver who fails to take further notice of the child is
blameworthy not because he has decided not to take further notice, or even because he at
some prior point decided not to care about children, but because he does not care now, or
does not care as much as, perhaps, he cares about getting to his destination on time.
involuntarily. Smith illustrates the idea with the example of a businessman who wonders
whether having a rival killed might solve his problems. The businessman has no
voluntary control over whether such a thought occurs to him and, furthermore, he may
immediately dismiss it. Yet the fact remains that there is a difference between people to
whom such thoughts occur and those to whom they do not. Of course the businessman
who actually puts out a hit on his rival is far more blameworthy than one who merely
considers it, and one who has the thought but dismisses it out of hand is less blameworthy
still—hardly at all. But Smith, like the other attributionists, works hard to distinguish
suspect about the person who insists on blaming someone for having a fleeting thought.
(Smith 2007) Yet having such a fleeting thought reveals a flaw in one’s character
nevertheless.
118
Finally, involuntary emotional responses are generally thought to be entirely free
from moral evaluation. Smith contends, however, that like the previous cases, they can
show something morally relevant about the agents who have them. Someone who gets
annoyed when asked to donate to a cause, for example, is someone who likely is not
committed to that cause; and someone who does not regret forgetting a dinner date with a
friend likely has no particularly warm feelings toward that friend. Our involuntary
underlying commitments. This does not, of course, mean that all voluntary responses, or
all failures to notice something, or all fleeting thoughts, really do reveal something about
our deeper underlying evaluations. As Smith admits, we can have islands of irrationality,
as an agoraphobic’s fear of heights might persist despite her judgment that the railing in
front of her is perfectly safe. Nevertheless, much of the spontaneity of our thoughts,
hold people responsible for despicable attitudes, various omissions, and even actions that
hold people responsible for clearly voluntary and deliberate actions despite the fact that
the considerations that enter into those deliberations are not, in the volitionist sense,
What makes us responsible for attitudes on this account, then, is that they reflect
underlying judgments on the agent’s part, either by directly embodying those judgments,
119
their inferiority, or by standing in a rational relation to them, as a fear of the Roma might
depend on an underlying judgment that they are likely to pick one’s pocket. These
underlying judgments need not, as Smith stresses, be ones that the agent has reached
through conscious and explicit deliberation, or CTD; they may well be “things we
discover about ourselves through our response to questions or to situations” (2005, 252).
They may, in other words, belong to the background operating behind the scenes of an
agent’s deliberations, perceptions, emotional responses, and so on. And what makes it
appropriate to hold someone responsible for such judgments or the various states that
reflect them is that they are, taken together, constitutive of a person’s practical agency.
“We are not merely producers of our attitudes, or even guardians over them; we are, first
and foremost, inhibiters of them. They are a direct reflection of what we judge to be of
weight, hair color, or inability to perform simple mathematical tasks (unless, of course,
that inability reflects a judgment that the tasks at hand are not worth bothering with).
Instead, we address a demand to the agent. We ask the agent to justify her attitude or the
underlying judgment, to “explain or justify her rational activity in some area, and to
acknowledge fault if such a justification cannot be provided.” (Smith 2008 381) This
need not mean that they must reply, of course; as Smith notes, “this is not to say… that I
about the nature of moral appraisal itself, and how it differs from mere negative
description.” (2008 381) A further point, one which seems to follow but which Smith
120
unfortunately does not address, is that agents need not be able to provide anything
resembling a justification. Rather, the point about the legitimacy of a demand for
justification is intended only to delimit a class of things for which someone may be held
responsible, in much the same way as the legitimacy of the question “why?” may delimit
2000 11)32
This last point, about the agent’s ability, strikes me as important. Moral
philosophers too often seem to think of adult human beings as universally endowed with
the ability to defend and justify their views, and it is a source of wonder that, despite the
constant challenges to this view presented by daily interaction with students (not to
mention the hordes of non-philosophers we tend to bump into in the real world),
recognition of this fact so rarely seeps into writing on rationality, agency, or ethics. But
their moral attitudes; if they feel pressed to offer a justification, the justification is
frequently ad hoc, and likely not reflective of their actual judgments. This recognition, I
think, should make Smith’s point a bit more radical than she wishes it to: the legitimacy
of a demand for justification is the mark of that for which one is responsible; but it is so
regardless of whether the agent can provide any such justification. We are, in other
words, responsible for our attitudes insofar as we can be asked to justify them, not insofar
32
This raises an interesting suggestion: that the difference between an intentional action and an action for
which an agent is responsible will revolve around the difference between the question “why?” and the
demand for justification. Whether we are responsible for all our intentional actions, then, will depend on
whether we take all motivating reasons to also be justifying reasons.
121
The point here is supposed to be one about the connection between responsibility
and agency. The demand for justification “by its very nature implies responsibility, for it
is directed at [the agent’s] judgmental activity, activity for which we must regard him as
responsible if we are to regard him as a moral agent in any sense.” (Smith 2008 388)
What makes responsibility judgments possible, then, is—as in the volitionist case—the
activity of the agent, but the activity need not be conscious, explicit, voluntary. This
account, then, is meant to leave control (in the volitionist sense) entirely out of judgments
of responsibility, and this has led some to attempt to soften the blow rather than reject the
theory outright. Michael McKenna, for example, suggests that control has to be involved
somehow, but that it has two components, one of which is Smith’s, and “involves the
possibility of rational activity (that, let us grant, falls shy of free mental acts). A second
evaluate one’s moral standpoint(s).” (2008 36) Even this much control, however, is too
much.
Consider Smith’s insistence that we can hold someone responsible “even if the
person’s failure was not a failure of choice, and even if she is not in a position to change
her attitude ‘at will.’” (Smith 2008 383) Of course this is not an explicit rejection of
McKenna’s second condition; after all, an agent may have the capacity to evaluate
without being in a position to change an attitude at will. But such a capacity fails to add
any control whatsoever. A weaker version of the second condition is, in fact, built into
Smith’s account, since for someone to be responsible for an attitude, “it must be the kind
of state that is open, in principle, to revision or modification through that creature’s own
process of rational reflection.” (Smith 2005 256) That a state is “open” to revision in this
122
way does not imply that the agent can simply decide to change it and thereby make it so;
it indicates only that the state belongs to the agent’s rational activity, and whether or not
it changes is, thus, attributable to the agent qua agent. In any case, an attributionist will
have reason to doubt whether McKenna’s second condition is even coherent in light of
his other concessions; whether or not an agent performs “a free mental act” must, after
all, itself depend on whether the agent judges such a performance to be worthwhile.
Should we then have to look for an extra capacity to evaluate (and change) that judgment
itself—as the idea that “control must come in somewhere” seems to demand—we are
stuck in an infinite regress. It seems as if either one accepts attributionism or rejects it,
failure of volitionist and Real Self theories to adequately delineate the boundaries of
moral agency: an agent who acts against her best judgment or on the basis of a desire
with which she does not identify is not, intuitively, exempt from responsibility on that
ground alone. Overcoming the limitation thus drives an expansion of the boundaries
Smith articulates the difference between implanted attitudes and ones that are the agent’s
own. Only the latter are based on judgments that reflect the agent’s practical self, and we
see this by comparing them with other judgments that the agent holds to find patterns;
implanted judgments and attitudes do not fit into those patterns. We thus figure out what
attitudes are the agent’s own by seeing how they fit into the overall framework of
33
I do not mean to suggest that no rapprochement between volitionism and attributionism is possible; on
the contrary, I will argue that it is necessary. My point is only that whatever control condition one wishes to
read into an attributionist account cannot be a expressed in volitionist terms.
123
attitudes and judgments on the basis of which we attribute responsibility. And this appeal
to holism is, Smith argues, a strength of her account, since a good account of
responsibility “should preserve our sense of the rational interrelations among our
attitudes, rather than treating these things as isolated entities, each of which must meet
some further criterion before it can be considered attributable to a person for purposes of
moral assessment.” (Smith 2005 262) A person’s rational agency is not a collection of
unrelated items; they are items rationally bound together into a web, that web being the
The goal, thus, is to develop a conception of the self that does not restrict its
“real” or essential characteristics to some volitional core. Arpaly and Schroeder take up
this challenge with “the Whole Self View.” Unlike the Real Self View, which looks at
whether the desire behind an action is linked to some higher order volitional state or
value, the Whole Self View aims to take into account the myriad volitions, attitudes, and
beliefs of an agent. A kleptomaniac who acts unwillingly and against all his desires may,
on this view, be excused from responsibility. But what of the kleptomaniac who, looking
back on his petty thefts, inwardly smiles to himself? Human beings have complex
relationships to their actions, and this complexity is not exhausted by pointing at some
simple feature such as identification with a volition.35 Accordingly, the Whole Self theory
34
I leave aside the issue of whether it still makes sense to speak of “states” in this regard. The idea of a
“state” implies a stability that may not sit well with the ongoing, constantly unfolding process of an agent’s
rationality at work, binding together her various judgments and attitudes into a more or less coherent
whole. But I mention this point to suggest that the reference to a “state” here is theoretical; in theory and in
explanation we reconstruct the agent as having “states” due to the difficulty of referring to transitional
processes as the causes of action.
35
Frankfurt hints at some recognition of this in later work, where he notes the phenomenon of ambiguity—
where we are torn between identifying with a desire and identifying with its opposite—and suggests that
such ambiguity may not be completely avoidable for human beings. If so, the Real Self View ultimately
collapses into the Whole Self View.
124
links responsibility for an action to the degree to which “the morally relevant
personality.” (Arpaly and Schroeder 1999 172) Those factors—beliefs and desires—are
taken to be “well-integrated within a person to the extent that (1) they are deep; and (2)
they do not oppose other deep beliefs or desires”; an action, in turn, is well-integrated “to
the extent that it results from such beliefs and desires.” (1999 173) Depth, in this case, is
understood as the force which the belief or desire in question has in the person’s
other considerations. And the less opposition there is between the mental states in
agent as a whole. The condition of responsibility, then, is not some mental state or act
that legitimates a trait as the agent’s own; this purpose is served by the entire nexus of the
agent’s character.
This view lies in the background of Arpaly’s Unprincipled Virtue, which aims to
overturn accepted theories of rationality and moral worth. Drawing on a host of literary
and real life examples, Arpaly argues that an agent’s deliberately reached conclusions
and consciously held principles may well be at odds with the agent’s character as a
whole, and this fact should lead us to reexamine the reliance of moral psychology on
accounts that inevitably privilege the side of the conscious and explicit. With regard to
moral worth, she draws on the example of Huckleberry Finn (among others) to
demonstrate that agents may act in praiseworthy (or blameworthy) ways despite failing to
act on their consciously held principles. Huck believes that it is wrong to help slaves
escape, and he helps Jim in spite of that belief. If—as Arpaly thinks our intuitions
125
demand—we are to take Huck’s action as praiseworthy, we should recognize that what
makes it so is not any reason Huck happens to hold explicitly, but just the opposite. Huck
helps Jim because he responds to Jim’s humanity, recognizes Jim as a fellow person—
though not, to be sure, in those terms—and what makes Huck’s action praiseworthy is
that these reasons are precisely the reasons that (objectively) make it right to help Jim.
Arpaly’s account, then, holds that agents are morally praiseworthy insofar as the reasons
on which they act, perhaps unbeknownst to them, are the reasons that make their action
right; they are blameworthy when the reasons on which they act are ones that make the
action wrong; the depth of the agent’s commitment to the right (or wrong)-making
deliberately chosen, or voluntary is, for the most part, irrelevant, and the same account
plays out in Arpaly’s view of rationality. An entire chapter is devoted to defending the
possibility of reverse akrasia, in which an agent acts rationally despite acting contrary to
her own best judgment.36 Reverse akrasia, Arpaly insists, is precisely what we find in
Huck’s case, since he acts contrary to his own explicit judgment and yet does what she—
and, she assumes, her readers—holds to be the rational conclusion. What it is rational for
an agent to do is to act on the reasons best supported by the agent’s mental framework as
a whole. Deliberation and reflection may help us to discover those reasons, since they
serve to “focus your concentration, allowing you to pull together mental resources from
many different corners of your psyche in order to solve whichever problem you have
decided to reflect on.” (Arpaly 2003 64) But they may also fail to help, since deliberation
36
The phrase “best judgment” is somewhat misleading. What Arpaly means by this is the conclusion that
an agent reaches after explicit deliberation; on a more common-sense use of the term, Arpaly’s view is
precisely that deliberation may result in the agent’s reaching a quite poor judgment.
126
itself may well be distorted by self-deception, wishful thinking, or some other irrational
condition. In Arpaly’s example, Sam, a student, believes that in order to get his studying
done, he must stop interacting with people and become a hermit. Although he reaches this
belief through deliberation, however, the belief is mistaken: Sam ignores a good deal of
evidence that suggests, for example, that he works much less efficiently when distanced
from other people. Thus, while becoming a hermit may be the course of action
act on Sam’s part, the truth remains that, given his goals, continuing to interact with
others is the rational course of action for Sam to take. The rational course of action is
determined by reference to the agent’s character, the whole of his desires, beliefs, and
attitudes; since agents lack access to the whole of their character in deliberation, they can
easily reach mistaken conclusions about what the rational course of action for them is.
To further illustrate the claim that rationality does not require deliberation, Arpaly
points to common cases of rationality that do not involve it, at least in the standard sense.
A fast-acting athlete, for example, reacts instantaneously to a change in the play; there is
no time for deliberation, and yet the reaction can be a rational or an irrational one. Of
course someone might deny that fast-acting athletes act for reasons at all (Dreyfus, as we
will see, makes precisely this claim), but Arpaly suggests that this runs counter to our
intuitions. “A major part of what it is to be a competent tennis player is to have the ability
to play tennis rationally—to act for good reasons rather than bad reasons in all of your
game-related actions.” (2003 53) If a jump to the right will allow a player to hit the ball
while a jump to the left will not, the player has a reason to jump to the right. One could
reply that even though the player has a reason to jump to the right, he is not acting on a
127
reason when he does so: he is merely acting on instinct. But this could be a hard sell: as
Arpaly’s remark about competence suggests, a player trains precisely to match his
instincts to the right reasons, so that in acting on instinct he is acting for a reason. If he
were not responding to reasons at all, it would be hard to make sense of the fact that the
In two further cases, Arpaly notes experiences of having a realization dawn one
one as, for example, a man might realize that he is in love with his childhood friend
without having come to this realization through deliberation. The thought suddenly
occurs to him, and occurs with an obvious sense of its truth; and it may well be a
realization that has been long in coming, and has involved a good deal of sub-conscious
responsiveness to reasons—to this evidence of his actions and reactions where his friend
is involved, say—over a long span of time. Finally, deliberation itself can be a rational
process without involving further deliberation to support each step in thought. That
would threaten an infinite regress and, in any case, Arpaly notes that emotional responses
play an important role in deliberation: one can quickly move from one step in the
deliberative process to another because a particular thought feels right (the earlier
discussion of Galen Strawson has already addressed these issues). What the theory of
rationality suggested here implies, then, is that agents can and frequently do act for
reasons without knowing what those reasons are and certainly without explicitly
recognizing that they are acting for reasons. A match between the reasons for which the
agent acts and the actual reasons to do something is all that is needed for an action to be a
rational one; the agent’s own attitudes or beliefs with regard to her reasons are largely
irrelevant. Whether or not my attitudes and beliefs on balance favor a certain course of
128
action determines whether the pursuit of that action is rational; whether or not some of
Against this backdrop, Arpaly presents her account of moral responsibility, the
features of which should already be clear: we are responsible for actions, i.e., open to the
possibility of praise or blame for them, if those actions are taken for reasons supported by
well-integrated attitudes. Once again, then, the argument is clearly an attributionist one:
the agent’s choice, deliberation, and volition do not come into play in attributions of
responsibility; Huck is responsible (and thus open to praise) for helping Jim because the
reasons for which he helps Jim are good ones, and because they are integrated with the
rest of his character. Arpaly concedes that Huck would be even more praiseworthy if he
did not have, as part of his character, the belief that helping slaves escape is wrong. But
the fact that Huck acts contrary to what he thinks are good reasons, and instead acts for
what he does not even recognize as reasons does not detract from his responsibility.
Similarly, Arpaly draws on Le Carré’s character of Oliver Single, who betrays his
criminal father to the police without ever choosing, or deciding to do so in order to make
the point that choice, or CTD, is neither the necessary nor a sufficient condition for
attribution of responsibility.
Sher’s account differs slightly from the others, but begins in a similar vein, by
enumerating case after case in which we are likely to hold an agent responsible despite
anything like deliberation, choice, or control (in the volitionist sense) being present.
Among his examples: Alessandra, who leaves her dog in the car on a hot day while
picking the kids up from school but forgets about the dog when she is approached by the
principal about her children’s performance; Joliet, home alone, hears movement
129
downstairs and, fearing it to be a burglar, gets her gun and sneaks down; seeing a figure,
she panics and shoots, but it turns out that she has shot her son. These—and many other
responsible; clearly, however, volitionist control is missing in these cases. The characters
act on poor judgment or get distracted, and do so in culpable ways, but they certainly do
exercised any explicit judgment at all, most of them would have avoided the
conscious awareness that one is acting wrongly, we frequently hold people responsible
for actions beyond their control and a theory of responsibility should account for this.
Sher’s reply takes an unusual form. Rather than insisting that control is
way. Rather than thinking “that an agent’s control extends no further than the searchlight
of his conscious awareness” (Sher 2006 296), Sher suggests that control may be a product
of the agent as a whole person. Agents have “innumerable beliefs, desires, motives,
convictions, and commitments of which [they are] not aware” and these may well be the
agent’s own just as much as his conscious attitudes. If the failure to recognize that the
action is wrong is itself caused by some combination of such attitudes, this may yield the
sense of control we are looking for. Thus, for example, Alessandra would not have
forgotten her dog had she cared less for her children and more for the dog; and she has
control in the sense that the attitudes she actually has, in the strength and combination in
which she has them, caused her to neglect her dog. With Joliet, the case is harder, but
“we can say that the tendency to panic that prevents Joliet from recognizing that she
130
should not pull the trigger is itself part of what makes her the person she is.” (Sher 2006
301)
Despite lacking an account of what it means to say that the attitudes in question
are the agent’s own, an account it seems we may have to fill out with some view of
holism or integration, Sher’s argument is quite close to the attributionist view. In fact, his
one disagreement with the attributionists is, I think, unwarranted. Sher notes that on the
attributionist view, the wrongful act must be caused by some combination of the agent’s
states but that, furthermore, there must be an “ineliminable semantic component” present,
since “this account makes essential reference to the match or fit between the relevant
feature of the act and the contents of the attitudes or judgments that determine the agent’s
practical identity.” (Sher 2008 225) His own view, Sher insists, has no such implication
and consequently can apply to a wider range of cases. Specifically: “If we accept the
judgment that [her dog’s] safety doesn’t matter much, or to a lack of good will toward the
dog, and we will have to attribute Joliet’s responsibility to a judgment that it is not
important to take precautions against inflicting serious harm.” (Sher 2008 226) But even
if such judgments are absent, we may still hold Alessandra responsible for neglecting her
dog’s safety, and “Joliet would surely remain responsible if her panic had simply
overwhelmed her judgment.” (2008 226) Our judgments of responsibility here, then, do
But this seems mistaken, at least when taken at face value. First, Smith, at whom
the remark seems to be directed, clearly does not believe that there must be a direct match
between the act and a judgment of the agent. Her discussions of responsibility for what
131
we notice or miss, what occurs to us, and so on, would make no sense if that were so (the
businessman who considers having his rival killed is blameworthy—on her account—not
because he judges that killing business rivals is good, but because he seems to lack
commitment to the judgment that such actions are impermissible). Nor would Smith’s
Sher’s description. Second, Sher’s own account of what gives Alessandra control draws
though he does not say so—that the connection between the agent’s attitudes and her
action that he has in mind must not merely be causal, but must also be appropriate
(otherwise his account would seem too bizarre). But giving sense to the notion of
appropriateness without any semantic component might prove difficult. Fourth, drawing
on the last point, we might ask whether a merely causal account could make any
did genuinely believe that Joliet was overtaken by panic and that was all there was to the
story, we could not hold her responsible. We do hold her responsible because there is
more to it: Joliet took a loaded gun, with the safety off, downstairs with her, aimed it at a
human form, and pulled the trigger. Panic is not a brute causal force in this story, but a
crucial explanatory factor that helps make sense of the rest; yet it is the rest—which
includes any number of semantic connections—that explains the relation between the
panic and the trigger-pulling. That is: Sher’s account is straightforwardly in line with
attributionism, or else it is meaningless. But I said that this is only if we take his
37
Sher notes that he does not mean to take any “position on the question of whether the… attitudes that
account for the agent’s failure to recognize that he is acting wrongly must themselves have been produced
in an appropriate way.” (Sher 2006 298)
132
argument at face value; another way to take it is as suggesting that control may not
require rational—and thus semantic—connections at all. And to this point I will return.
recent years has been laid out in a series of papers by Neil Levy. In laying out his
arguments, I am indirectly presenting the upshot of this chapter: volitionism is right on its
are to provide a theory of responsibility that is true to the phenomenon, we will have to
combine the two, and this will be my project for the rest of this chapter and the following
one. Levy himself has suggested that much of the disagreement may be verbal: given the
attributionist distinction between blaming (and/or punishing) and holding responsible, the
volitionist account may aim at the former but not the latter, which may perhaps be titled,
in Watson’s terminology, areatic criticism. (Levy and McKenna 2009 118) But I think
attempts to bring the two camps together must be more involved. First, I have attempted
to raise the stakes by arguing that the Basic Argument requires us to accept a roughly
attributionist view in order to make sense of responsibility not just for attitudes and
omissions, but for any action whatsoever, insofar as actions are themselves the products
of attitudes, values, and patterns of thought and inference that we do not have control
over (again, in the volitionist sense). Second, we will need to redefine notions such as
133
(1) Consciousness is necessary for responsibility.
(2) Attributionism fails to account for the conceptual distinction between bad and
blameworthy agents.
(3) Attributionism fails to consider epistemic conditions on responsibility.
(4) Attributionism presupposes volitionism.
First, Levy argues that, on a common and plausible view about the function of
Levy argues that attributability itself presupposes consciousness. “The relevant control
problem arises, recall, because we do not exercise control over anything of which we are
unaware” (Levy 2008 216); thus, in proposing that the agent’s failure to recognize his
wrongdoing can be explained by reference to his other (unconscious) attitudes, Sher does
not restore control; he merely shows that agents lack it. But why should we accept the
premise here? Why should we think that we do not exercise control over anything of
which we are unaware? Levy begins by pointing out that, “in the absence of
consciousness we are at the mercy of automatic responses we are not responsible for
acquiring, that we may consciously reject and which we may even have worked hard to
eradicate. It is therefore unfair to hold us responsible for actions which reflect such
responses when we cannot control them.” (2008 219) But this is a mix of (1) the clearly
true (that in the absence of consciousness, automatic processes rule), (2) the question
begging (the claim that we are not responsible for acquiring the processes; that we cannot
control them), and (3) the normative (that it is unfair to hold us responsible). Given the
attributionist willingness to hold responsible for automatic processes, this is not yet a
response.
134
workspace,” which “allows all the mechanisms constitutive of the agent, personal and
Hence conscious deliberation is properly reflective of the entire person, including her
consciously endorsed values.” (2008 220) Consciousness, in other words, brings together
the various attitudes and mechanisms of the person, allowing for a CTD to emerge. Levy
does not claim that consciousness itself makes decisions; rather, decisions are the
products of our subpersonal mechanisms; but since consciousness brings these together,
the resulting action “will be controlled by us, in the fullest sense; by our real selves, for
these mechanisms are us.” (2007 242) A CTD, then, is representative of the person’s
values and commitments in a way that automatic processes are not, precisely because
consciousness brings those processes together with values and commitments out in the
open so they can be explicitly compared and contrasted. The interesting conclusion here
is that a CTD is therefore reflective of the person, of the real self, which suggests that
only CTDs are properly attributable to agents. Attributionists, in other words, should
embrace consciousness.
This argument is hardly conclusive, however. For one thing, it is clear that
unconscious (in the sense Levy, Sher, et al use) processes can be rational; and they can be
fairly global, as well. Consider the “dawning” examples raised by Arpaly: if it dawns on
you that you are in love with a friend, that you live under a corrupt regime, that Jews are
not servants of the devil, the conclusion can be a fully rational one, and one that clearly
draws on many of your different processes and values. Anyone involved in problem
solving also knows that it is possible to solve problems in one’s sleep, sometimes even
when the problems are highly complex and require diverse mechanisms and values for
135
their solution: the solution simply dawns on you, in such cases, after a period of not
consciously thinking about the problem. So if the mark of being representative of the self
as a whole is that a decision involves bringing together different values, attitudes, and
accomplishing this task. Nor is consciousness infallible; as Levy writes, deliberation will
“greatly increase the likelihood that the resulting action reflects our real selves”;
here from an attributionist standpoint, however: consciousness improves the quality and
makes it more likely that the decision will reflect our real selves. Arpaly, we should note,
agrees fully: “Another central property of deliberation and reflection is that they focus
your concentration, allowing you to pull together mental resources from many different
corners of your psyche”, and this “makes it likely that more and more of your relevant
beliefs will become salient to you, increasing the chances of a satisfactory solution.” So
CTD is extremely useful; “the ability to deliberate and reflect helps make us, as humans,
Consciousness is very useful in helping us reach conclusions that are rational, and
that better reflect our values, and this should be common ground. But it does not follow
that only consciousness can do this; nor does it show that consciousness necessarily will.
The same tasks can be performed without CTD, and sometimes CTD yields inferior
consciousness does not guarantee that all relevant evidence will become salient). If so,
136
then consciousness is neither necessary nor sufficient for reaching conclusions that reflect
our deep, real, or whole selves, though it typically increases the chances of our doing so.
Levy contends that decisions reached through automatic actions and processes are not
attributable to an agent; “it might be reflective of the agent…but it is only by chance that
it is so. The bad agent did not have the opportunity to think twice, and therefore cannot
be blamed for their action.” (2007 242) But consciousness, or “thinking twice,” does not
representative of an agent is perfectly correct. But the claim that consciousness is a pre-
condition for attributability presupposes that CTD is privileged vis-à-vis the other
attitudes and processes of the psyche. And this is plainly question begging.
agent, attitudes or actions need a focus. That focus may not be CTD, but it does not
follow that we can treat the whole self as a giant lens, magically focusing a beam of light
Let me now take up the next two, interrelated, objections. Levy argues (1) that
there is a prima facie plausible distinction between bad and blameworthy agents: it is one
epistemic access to the moral norms he is violating (2). In response to the first argument,
Smith (2008) has argued that we should be loathe to treat agents as bad rather than
blameworthy, though she has not ruled out our doing so. We should avoid it, however,
137
because to treat agents as merely bad is to treat them as no longer subject to our reactive
attitudes; that is, it is to no longer regard them as persons. But in response to at least some
of the cases Levy cites, it seems like this is exactly what we should do. For example, in
discussing Scanlon’s attributionist view, Levy notes the problematic case of the
psychopath who cannot see that the fact that an action harms another person counts as a
reason against it. On Scanlon’s view, this fact alone demonstrates that the agent is
value is an evil one. And Levy is right, I think, to note that this is a deeply
counterintuitive claim. A similar issue crops up in the case of Phineas Gage, whose
objectionable behavior is the result of a spike through the brain. Arpaly’s response to
Gage is that, regardless of what made him this way, he is blameworthy now. I think we
can reject these ways of addressing the cases, however, without rejection attributionism
as such.
There is a difference between a killer who is not a psychopath and a killer who is.
One can understand that causing suffering to others is morally objectionable—he grasps
the reason—but fails to respond to it because, for example, he values the enjoyment he
gets from the suffering, and this valuation runs deep. We may even suppose that, because
the value of enjoying suffering runs so deep, he is completely oblivious to the reason not
to cause harm. Here we can explain the agent’s responsibility in attributionist terms by
running a counterfactual scenario: were the agent not so attached, or attached at all, to the
pleasure he derives from the suffering of others, he would respond to the reason not to
cause that suffering. But the case of the genuine psychopath may well be different:
perhaps he does not see the reason at all, and this failure to see the reason is not a result
138
of his other attitudes at all. If this is a reasonable way to distinguish between the psycho
killer and the run-of-the-mill sadist, then the correct response should be this: the
psychopath really ought to be excluded from the persons club, while the sadist is fully
one that excludes the psychopath because he fails to fulfill it. (I will address this point
later on.) In this case we can make a distinction between the bad and the blameworthy,
volitionist stance.
What about Gage? A spike through the head, we might assume, interferes with the
be hard to explain. But if Gage cannot reason properly, then it is difficult to claim that his
actions and attitudes stand in the requisite rational connection to his underlying
judgments and the rest of his character. In fact, the case is just the opposite: Gage’s
behavior is not attributable to him, because it is not an expression of his rational activity
as an agent; his rational activity has been shot to hell. If we could determine just which
rational connections have been disrupted, perhaps we could decide to what extent, and in
what contexts, to treat Gage as a person and in which ones not to. But treating him as a
full-fledged person would make no sense, since his agency is clearly not responsive to
reasons in anything like the normal way. The claims so far suggest a deviation from some
of the specific judgments attributionists have made, but I do not think a rejection of
historical condition. One reason attributionists have trouble distinguishing bad from
blameworthy agents, after all, is that they leave history entirely out of our assessments of
139
responsibility, leading to an impoverished, one-dimensional account. (Stroud 2007) Just
what sort of historical account we will need to add to attributionism is a point I will
return to.
Let us turn to Levy’s third objection: there are strict epistemic conditions on
for failing to consider it” (2005 9), and attributionists fail to account for them. To some
extent, we have already addressed this point in connection with (2): agents who,
counterfactually, would lack access to the relevant epistemic standards whatever their
other character traits will simply have to be treated as non-persons in an important sense.
But Levy has a few other examples, ones that pertain not only to psychopaths but to the
rest of us as well. He gives us two examples of how lack of access to epistemic standards
could serve to excuse one from responsibility (this is connected to (2), since someone
who violates norms to which he lacks epistemic access can be considered bad but not
blameworthy). First, suppose “that plants can be harmed, and that this harm is a moral
reason against killing or treading on them. In that case, many of us are causally
responsible for a great many moral harms. Are we morally responsible for them?” (2005
9) The answer Levy insists on, of course, is negative. Second, “many people have the
intuition that Aristotle was not blameworthy for keeping slaves or for his sexism; that his
actions and attitudes were wrong, but not blameworthy.” (Levy and McKenna 2009 117)
These are supposedly cases in which agents have “faulty” norms, and as a result cannot
But the cases are not clear. The plant example, in particular, is not one on which
our intuitions are likely to be good either way, since it is hard to see what it means to say
140
that causing harm to plants is immoral in a way we are not aware of. Does it mean, for
example, that plants suffer in ways we are not currently familiar with but that, if we only
knew them, we would be likely to recognize as binding on us? In this case—if it is even
coherent—we are clearly not blameworthy on the attributionist view, since ignorance is
an excusing factor. But perhaps—and this is the only way I can interpret this—at some
point in the future biocentrism will win out as the dominant account of moral
considerability, so that common sense will dictate that harming plants is morally wrong.
In that case, the attributionists will indeed have a harder time than the volitionists; they
may even have to admit that we are blameworthy for harming plants today. But it is not
obvious that they would be wrong, and it is even less obvious that they would be wrong
in the eyes of the people of this imaginary future. To see this, let us turn to Aristotle.
How seriously are we to take the intuition, held by “many people”, that Aristotle
was not blameworthy? After all, most of my students (and not just my students) have the
intuition that—in Aristotle’s time and culture—slavery is not wrong; in which case, of
course, Aristotle was not blameworthy.38 That intuition, as virtually all philosophers
would agree, is a bad one, because it fails to withstand scrutiny. How much better does
the intuition that Aristotle was not blameworthy hold up? To keep this question from
being rhetorical, we can look at Arpaly’s account of the conscientious Nazi and similar
figures. Are these people blameworthy? Her answer is: probably yes, but it depends.
Imagine, first, the German whose encounters with Jews have always been negative ones,
such that anyone in their position would conclude that Jews are greedy and a threat to
German society. Such a person genuinely lacks any reason to accept the opposite
38
A few weeks ago, many of my students insisted that there was nothing wrong with the Romans feeding
Christians to lions—after all, this is what entertained them!
141
conclusion, and to that extent he is not blameworthy. But this is not the case with most
Germans. A German who was aware that Jews were people like himself, but focused on
their negative features and reinforced these with what he heard from the propaganda
campaign is hardly free of blame: his willingness to believe the worst is not based on
depends. To the extent that he had ample opportunity to recognize that slaves are
conditioned by slavery into a certain mode of behavior, and that they are otherwise no
different than him, and to the extent that this failure was itself conditioned by some desire
to believe in natural inequality, there is good reason to wonder why anyone would—after
volitionism would help: if Aristotle genuinely had no way of discerning that slaves were
just as much human beings as citizens, volitionists and attributionists are in the same boat
in that neither has any reason to hold him blameworthy. But if—as seems more
plausible—he had access to the relevant reasons but ignored them as a result of his other
What about (4), the argument that attributionism covertly relies on volitionism?
First, Levy rejects the attributionist claim “that our judgment-sensitive attitudes are in
principle within our control.” (2005 10) On his view, it makes sense to say that “I am
responsible for my attitudes if I have genuinely been (relevant) active with regard to
them; if I have chosen them.” But this is not what attributionists claim: they insist, as we
have seen, that we are responsible for expressions of our rational activity even when we
cannot change them “at will”. While recognizing that actual control makes a difference,
Levy sees no reason “for thinking that in principle control matters at all.” (2005 10) The
142
attributionists have set up the problem in such a way, however, that it is difficult to make
a response that is not question-begging. Levy thus provides two analogies. First, “I don’t
have a kind of ersatz control over my car if the steering wheel falls off; the fact that cars
are in principle controllable does not alter my lack of control in that particular
things that are and things that are not judgment-sensitive (e.g., attitudes vs. height), Levy
imagines the scenario that we are one of very few intelligent species whose height is not
attributionists will claim that we are: Since height belongs to the class of things that are
judgment-sensitive, Homo sapiens’ actual inability to control their height does not alter
their responsibility for it.” (2005 10) The argument here is that it only makes sense to
hold us responsible for attitudes that we can change at will, that we have actual control
over. And this is a volitionist condition; an attributionist notion of “in principle” control
seems to rely on the intuitive idea that actual control is what really matters.
But are the analogies convincing? Again, it matters what these are supposed to be
analogies for. A car is, of course, in principle controllable, but a car without a steering
wheel is not controllable even in principle. So, once again, we need to distinguish
between the psychopath, who lacks control even in principle, and Aristotle, at least on my
reading, who has control in principle but fails to exercise it. As for the Martians: they are
wrong, and wrong in obvious ways. Perhaps Martian height is judgment sensitive, but
sensitive, they are mistaken about the facts, for in this case we lack even in principle
control. But we do not lack in principle control over our judgments and attitudes in the
143
same way unless we have been incapacitated by an injury or illness that blocks our
rationality. If any attributionists claim that all humans have in principle control over all
their attitudes, they are wrong. But this is a strike against the attributionists in question,
not against attributionism, and it is a strike against them precisely because they fail to
Finally, Levy takes issue with the attributionist view of justification. We can
indeed ask agents to justify their judgment-sensitive attitudes, but justification is forward-
looking. In discovering a flaw in you, I can bring the flaw to your attention by asking you
to justify it (and, perhaps, by pointing out the ways in which it is a flaw). Having done
this, I help you to satisfy the epistemic condition on responsibility since, now that your
flaw has been brought to your attention, you are in a position to do something about it.
But it follows from this only that you become responsible for your attitude after I have
demanded a justification for it; “you are responsible for your attitude because the
volitionist, and not the attributionist, conditions upon responsibility are satisfied, and,
second, it hardly follows from the fact that you are now responsible that you were
responsible all along.” (2005 11) This is a strong intuitive point, but of course the
attributionist does not claim that the appropriateness of a demand for justification is the
reason why we are responsible for our attitudes: rather, the appropriateness of the
demand is a sign that the thing in question is one for which we are responsible. And it can
serve as such a sign because the thing in question is an expression of our rational activity.
of justification, but because it drops the control requirement rather than revising it. Here
we can make a start toward remedying that, for the attributionist can ask: If I am not
144
responsible for my attitude, how, exactly, does my being asked to justify it make me
relevant facts—it seems nothing more is needed. The antisemite who has no evidence that
Jews are anything but vicious schemers can become responsible if we introduce him to
Jews who clearly aren’t; he does indeed become responsible, but only because he was
lacking evidence that was required for him to, counterfactually, have been responsible in
the first place. The antisemite who ignores some evidence and sticks to other evidence as
a result of his attitude toward Jews, on the other hand, will not be likely to change his
mind when asked for a justification. And if his attitude before the demand for
justification was not blameworthy, it is unclear why his attitude after will be any more so.
No doubt I might now hold him responsible, having demanded justification from him; but
change my mind (perhaps over a long period of time, as such things frequently go), if you
convince me that I have been overlooking something, say. If I ignore it, it is not clear that
anything new has been added; if you convince me and I change my mind, this shows only
that I was capable of changing my mind all along—that I was already in control.
Smith, as we have already seen in sketching the reply she might give to McKenna,
has something very much like a control condition built into rational activity as such. We
are responsible for a state, on her account, if it is in principle open to revision. This in
suggested in response to Levy’s criticism of this point, the state must be genuinely open
145
to revision: the rationality of the agent must be intact enough that it could,
counterfactually, change the attitude; and the agent must have access to the relevant facts
attitude in question need not be conscious, but that does not mean it is not control. Smith
notes that, “if one thinks that ‘choices’ can, like judgments, be inexplicit, unconscious,
and attributed to a person simply in virtue of her responses, then my disagreement with
the volitional view would turn out to be much less significant.” (Smith 2005 256) The
could provide accounts of “control” and “choice” that do not demand conscious
awareness.
similar point. Arpaly, he argues, overstates her case; if her point is largely that we can
and do deliberate, respond to reasons, and make decisions without explicitly sitting down
to think, being able to fully describe what we are doing, or even having a grasp on the
principles on which we may be acting, this point is not necessarily a challenge to standard
moral psychology. Oliver Single may not have made a fully aware decision to turn state’s
evidence against his father’s firm; but his action was not like an involuntary spasm,
coming to effect rather than merely undergo, and I see no reason why we should not call
that a matter of ongoing everyday deliberation over a long period of time.” (Pippin 2007
293-294) The suggestion is that a non-explicit process of which the agent is largely
unaware may well be called “deliberation” without much change in the ordinary meaning
of the term. Can we not do the same for “control” and “choice”?
146
This sort of redefining strategy is at the heart of Sher’s argument and his attempt
to lay out a new, non-volitionist notion of control. But we miss a crucial point here if we
focus on the question of whether Sher manages to meet the right epistemic conditions for
control, since control is not the only element in question. After pointing to the traditional
idea that “an agent’s control extends no further than the searchlight of his conscious
awareness,” Sher notes that “underlying this assumption was a certain familiar
conception of the controlling agent himself—one which takes him to be simply a center
of consciousness and will.” (2006 296) Though I do not find Sher’s account of control
sketched above—this is a crucial claim. The phrase “the agent’s control” has two terms:
an agent, and his control. But we cannot focus only on the control aspect, since our
notion of agency is obviously relevant here: if we compare the phrase “the agent’s
control” with the phrase “the sponge’s control,” we clearly mean different things by
“control” if both phrases are to be referring to something coherent, and very different
epistemic conditions will apply. That is: the conditions for control, and the definition of
the term itself, will depend heavily on how we understand the agent. The central
difficulty with relying on intuitions about the relation between control and consciousness
is that they import many underlying notions about the agent, the person, or the self,
including the Cartesian view that the self is co-extensive with consciousness. I am not
claiming that objections to attributionism rest on the Cartesian view as a premise; only
that they may smuggle the view in through the backdoor. Someone who rejects the
Cartesian picture may still find it active in his intuitions. And, we might wonder, if we
147
manage to remove the picture from our intuitions, would the need to establish a
I have been arguing that attributionism is, at least partly, the right account of
moral responsibility, and that it is necessary if we are to offer a response to the Basic
Argument. But my point here is not that volitionism is off the mark; its mistake is only to
assume that the “control” and “choice” of the kind needed for moral responsibility must
notions of these volitionist terms, without which the link between the agent and the things
stronger account of what it means for an attitude or action to be the agent’s own. Finally,
both of these projects will require adding a temporal dimension to the attributionist
account, or we run the risk of holding the wrong agent responsible—a problem of
blaming the bad agent. As Levy notes, it is perfectly possible, not to mention common, to
be a globally responsible agent while having islands of attitudes for which one is not
responsible. (Levy and McKenna 2009 118) Without ownership, control, choice, and
historical conditions, we will be unable to make sense of this division within the self.
148
5 Control and History
A. Control
In the last chapter I suggested that there are two ways to understand Sher’s
disagreement with attributionism. The first—what I called taking the criticism at face
value—is to see Sher as arguing that the connections between an agent’s beliefs or
attitudes and her action need not involve a semantic component in order to allow for
attempted to cast doubt on the idea that we can make any sense of the notion of
also that there might be another way to take Sher’s criticism: as arguing that control may
not require rational (or semantic) connections at all. We can take up this point by noting
something peculiar about many of the cases that anti-volitionists (Sher included) marshal
about something while involved in work or conversation, or tossing one’s niece in the air,
they are textbook examples of what Hubert Dreyfus has called “absorbed coping.” They
are cases, in other words, of situations where agents act without any explicit thinking,
usually because the activity they are performing is one they have mastered to such an
extent that thought is unnecessary and could, in fact, interfere with the performance of the
149
action.39 Anti-volitionists, in general, want to argue that such cases, despite the lack of
The disagreement I am here suggesting between Sher and the others is over
whether a lack of CTD in absorbed coping involves also a lack of rationality. The
attribute agential control, so that we need not separate responsibility from control. But the
position becomes more tenuous if we shift to Sher’s view and leave rationality out of
absorbed coping altogether. In a recent attack on John McDowell’s work, Dreyfus has
defended just such a position. My aim here will be to argue that Dreyfus (and Sher, on
this understanding of his argument) cannot be right; that cases of absorbed coping
involve rationality capable of grounding agential control, and that, furthermore, this
control is precisely what allows for responsibility attribution.40 Dreyfus’s position in this
debate is far more extreme than his previous work, and I do not claim to be accurately
conveying his views (or, for that matter, those of McDowell). The point is only to
suggest, on the basis of what is at stake in the debate, a rough model of agency that
in an oscillation. On the one hand, we face the Myth of the Given, the idea that passive
experience can have only a causal effect on our beliefs. The difficulty with this view, as
39
Not all the cases described by anti-volitionists are examples of absorbed coping. Nevertheless, these
cases, which leave out any possibility of explicitly made blameworthy judgments, pose the greatest
challenge to volitionist accounts.
40
Of course the presence of rationality within absorbed coping is not sufficient for responsibility. After all,
it is not even sufficient for agential control. The point here will be only that action—even absorbed
action—involves rationality, and is thus subject to being carried out by an agent.
150
amply demonstrated by Wilfrid Sellars, is that it makes it impossible to explain how
experience can provide any justification for beliefs. The other side of the oscillation
results from the temptation to recoil from the Myth by insisting that experience does not
justify our beliefs—only other beliefs can do that, as Davidson argued. Both approaches
are unsatisfactory, and McDowell argues that the way out of the dilemma is to recognize
“that even though experience is passive, it draws into operation capacities that genuinely
belong to spontaneity.” (McDowell 1996 13) In other words, the difficulty is that our
experience clearly plays some role in justifying our beliefs, and we cannot account for
this fact without taking experience to already have a rational structure. On this picture,
then, “our perceptual relation to the world is conceptual all the way out to the world’s
impacts on our receptive capacities.”(McDowell 2007b 338) To put it another way, “our
bundled with an account of rational agency. To perform a rational action, he points out,
one must be exercising one’s conceptual capacities in two ways. First, one must have a
conceptual experience of something in the world that solicits one to action and, second,
one’s action itself must be the actualization of a conceptual capacity. That an agent act
rationally in this sense, however, requires neither prior deliberation nor the explicit
grasping of something in the world as a reason for acting. Rather, for some action on an
inclination (e.g., an inclination to flee from danger) to be action for a reason, “we would
need to be considering a subject who can step back from an inclination to flee… and raise
the question whether she should be so inclined—whether the apparent danger is, here and
now, a sufficient reason for fleeing.”(McDowell 2009 128) But McDowell stresses that
151
acting for a reason does not involve stepping back and explicitly considering it; “acting
for a reason, which one is responding to as such, does not require that one reflects about
recommend. It is enough that one could.” (2009 129) This means that for some
inclination I to be a reason for action R, and for an agent to act on that reason, what is
needed is only that the agent be capable of taking I to be a reason R, i.e., capable of using
I in practical deliberation, though the deliberation need not and may never occur.
To illustrate the point, McDowell imagines the case of a hiker on a marked trail,
who at a crossing of paths goes to the right in response to a signpost pointing that
way. It would be absurd to say that for going to the right to be a rational response
to the signpost, it must issue from the subject’s making an explicit determination
that the way the signpost points gives her a reason for going to the right. What
matters is just that she acts as she does because (this is a reason-introducing
‘because’) the signpost points to the right. (This explanation competes with, for
instance, supposing she goes to the right at random, without noticing the signpost,
or noticing it but not understanding it.) What shows that she goes to the right in
rational response to the way the signpost points might be just that she can
afterwards answer the question why she went to the right—a request for her
reason for doing that—by saying ‘There was a signpost going to the right’. She
need not have adverted to that reason and decided on that basis to go to the right.
(McDowell 2009 129)
We should not, I think, take McDowell’s account to mean that the ability to
retrospectively reconstruct one’s reasons for action is a necessary condition for acting for
a reason. It would, after all, not even be a necessary condition if acting for a reason did
require explicit deliberation. Compare, for example, the case of two hikers, A and B. A
deliberates whether to follow the signpost and, after deliberation, turns right. B fails to
register the signpost in any way, and turns right entirely at random. Surely the difference
between A and B cannot turn on whether or not A remembers the deliberation: A might,
for example, have an awful memory, so that she is incapable of reconstructing even her
152
explicit deliberative processes. “Why did you turn right back there?” “I turned right back
there?” The difference between someone who acts for a reason deliberately and someone
who acts for a reason without deliberation, then, is not a matter of one acting rationally
and the other acting irrationally, but merely a matter of whether the reason is taken up
into practical deliberation. The difference between someone who acts for a reason and
someone who does not, on the other hand, will be much harder to specify.
conceptuality. First off, a concept—as we have seen—is just something that can be taken
up into explicit reasoning. But in response to Dreyfus’s insistence that our embodied
coping with the world does not and cannot make use of abstract, general principles,
McDowell notes that concepts can be situation-specific. They might, for example, take
the form of demonstratives, so that a shade of color for which agents have no word might
efficiently to first base.’” (McDowell 2007a 368) Thus, McDowell can accommodate
Dreyfus’s point—that embodied coping leaves no room for abstract thinking, and that in
fact abstract thinking about how to act interferes with the ability to act efficiently—
without giving up on the idea that rationality may well be present within the embodied
McDowell’s sense—for the agent to have a word for the concept or even to ever bring it
into her linguistic repertoire. Thus, McDowell distinguishes between experience that “is
experience,” and experience that can be isolated and articulated by “annexing bits of
153
language to” it, even though “some of the content of a typically rich world-disclosing
experience never makes its way into constituting part of the content of our repertoire of
conceptual capacities.” (McDowell 2007b 347) So while obviously not all of our
experience—not even most of it—is ever articulated, “all its content is present in a form
McDowell thus introduces a category of what I will call pre-conceptual experience; that
is, experience that has not yet been assimilated under a concept (and perhaps may never
be so assimilated), and yet which has, by virtue of its form, the potential to be fully
conceptually articulated.
Dreyfus, on the other hand, argues that McDowell has fallen into “the myth of the
mental,” namely, the myth that all our capacities are permeated with mentality,
“declaring that human experience is upper stories all the way down”. (Dreyfus 2005 47)
This myth, Dreyfus argues, effectively ignores the embodied coping going on at the
lower stories, and thus overlooks the background necessary for any rational thinking to
occur in the first place; the world draws us to action with its solicitations and without our
explicit deliberation, and “these solicitations have a systematic order that… works in the
background to make rationality possible, but the system of solicitations is not itself
rational.” (Dreyfus 2007c 358) Embodied coping, which involves action that is expert
and thus does not require deliberation, consists not of openness to a conceptually
allows us, Dreyfus thinks, to make sense of the idea that “animals, prelinguistic infants,
and everyday experts like us” all share the same space, which only we can step back
from, but “when a master has to deliberate in chess or in any skill domain, it’s because
154
there has been some sort of disturbance that has disrupted her intuitive response.”
(Dreyfus 2005 57) The intuitive idea, then, is that in interacting with the world we seem
to share certain capacities with the other animals, and that we—expert copers that we
are—only transcend those shared capacities when something has gone wrong with our
just how do we manage to move from the non-conceptual lower story to a conceptual
precisely to this problem: the question, once asked, cannot be answered. Unless we
recognize that our perception is conceptual all the way down, we will never be able to get
back up again. McDowell thus stresses that, although we do, in some sense, share
capacities with the other animals, the deliverances of our perception are always already of
a form suitable for rationality—to continue with the upper stories analogy, we might
present McDowell’s account thus: humans and animals might have the same perceptual
matter, but in humans that matter lives in the upper stories. Now if we were to accept
McDowell’s position, it would indeed help resolve the problem Dreyfus leaves unsolved.
The issue, however, is whether this model makes sense. Dreyfus seems to take it as an ad
early arguments against McDowell—which rely on the notion that any explicit rational
thought necessarily interferes with our ability to perform engaged bodily tasks, and that
our engaged coping responds directly to solicitations from the world rather than relying
on any general rules—are easily disposed of once McDowell’s view of concepts as both
155
situation-specific and not necessarily explicit is laid out. Dreyfus’s remaining objections,
(1) Rationality is not part of our phenomenology; nowhere in our absorbed coping
with the world do we encounter our conceptual capacities at work. The
“conclusion [that our coping is permeated with rationality] is supposed to follow
from the fact that if one has a capacity—in this case the capacity to use situation-
specific concepts—this capacity must be ‘operative’, as McDowell puts it, in all
situations whether or not I am aware of exercising it.” And this, we are told, is a
“category mistake”: “Capacities are exercised on occasion, but that does not allow
one to conclude that, even when they are not exercised, they are, nonetheless,
‘operative’ and thus pervade all our activities.” (Dreyfus 2007b 372) Although we
can step back from our engaged experience in the world and contemplate its
affordances (e.g., doors afford going through; telephones afford dialing), we
cannot respond to its solicitations as such if we are thinking about them;
McDowell’s view of our openness to the world, “while true to our experience of
affordances as facts, flies in the face of the phenomenon of solicitations… there is
no place in the phenomenology of highly skillful action for conceptual
mindedness.” (Dreyfus 2007c 361)
(2) Experts or masters do not follow rules in their expert activity; they act on
immediate perception, and it is difficult to see how reasons can play any role in
such action, especially when we notice that “when an expert is forced to give the
reasons that led to his action, his account will necessarily be a retroactive
rationalization that shows as best that the expert can retrieve from memory the
general principles and tactical rules he once followed as a competent performer.”
(Dreyfus 2005 54)
(3) Following on this point, we can note that if the deliverances of sensibility cannot
be fully articulated, or can be articulated only in extremely wide-range
demonstrative concepts, it becomes unclear what sense there is in saying that an
agent is acting for a reason when she follows a particular solicitation. Something
about the world draws her to act, but what it is sometimes cannot be fully
articulated. Using one of his favorite examples, the Grandmaster, Dreyfus notes
that “pointing to the specific pieces on the specific squares on the board as that
position doesn’t capture what it is about that position that draws the Grandmasters
to make that move.” (2007a 105) First off, it is not merely the position that draws
the Grandmaster to move: the tempo, the opponent’s style, and myriad other
factors contribute as well. Ultimately, it may be that the Grandmaster’s only
explanation for his move would be that this was the move that made sense, or that
he felt like making this move, “but such a response would be too situation-
specific to count as a reason.” (2007a 107) The challenge, then, is that there is
nothing in what motivates the Grandmaster that it would make sense to call a
reason; by extension, “something similar happens to each of us when any activity
156
from taking a walk, to being absorbed in a conversation, to giving a lecture is
going really well.” (2007b 373)
control can be present in agency in the absence of CTD. Before moving on to that
discussion, I want to motivate it a bit further by pointing out that Dreyfus’s account
cannot make coherent sense of our responsibility for the agency undertaken in absorbed
coping. After pointing out that absorbed coping goes on without any sense of a subject or
of reasons for acting, Dreyfus notes that “of course the coping going on is mine in the
sense that the coping can be interrupted at any moment by a transformation that results in
an experience of stepping back from the flow of current coping. I then retroactively
attach an ‘I think’ to the coping and take responsibility for my actions,” even though
within the experience itself, what is encountered are only solicitations drawing out
responses. (2007c 356)41 This account is already odd, given Dreyfus’s constant insistence
that our essential feature, or most pervasive kind of freedom, is not the ability to step
back, but rather to become absorbed in our activity, since—as it seems—an action is only
mine by virtue of that stepping back. But, more problematically, the references to
The idea seems to be that I can be responsible for my absorbed agency because
I—as a thinking subject and not simply a coper—can always jump into my activity and
stop it if something is not going well. Dreyfus gives the analogy of an airport radio
beacon, which only gives a warning signal if the plane goes off course; but when the pilot
is followings its beam, “the silence that accompanies being on course doesn’t mean the
beacon isn’t continuing to guide the plane. Likewise, in the case of perception, the
41
Dreyfus repeats the point in his next reply to McDowell: “My coping is mine in that I can break off doing
it, and for that reason I can take responsibility for it.” (2007b 375)
157
absence of tension doesn’t mean the body isn’t being constantly guided by the
solicitations. On the contrary, it means that, given past experience in this familiar
domain, everything is going exactly the way it should.” (2007c 358) But this idea is
puzzling, since Dreyfus’s point is that there is no monitoring going on within the
experience of absorbed coping. If so, the beacon analogy raises difficulties for both
Dreyfus’s account of responsibility and for the coherence of his overall attempt to excise
conceptuality from most of our agency. It is, first of all, unclear just how responsibility is
supposed to enter into the picture. Suppose that I am absorbed in coping, without the
operation of any conceptual capacities. Responsibility does not kick in unless something
goes wrong—or, perhaps, I simply step back to think about what I am doing—and I take
responsibility for how my body has been responding to solicitations. But why, exactly,
should I take responsibility for something my body has been doing? I don’t enter onto the
scene as long as the absorbed coping is going smoothly; unless my body has been
following my guidance all along, taking responsibility for it seems like an odd maneuver;
one else is available. But if there is no rational link between myself and what my body
has been doing there is no particularly good reason for me to take responsibility for its
activity. Far from explaining how responsibility for absorbed coping—that is, for the vast
majority of the work of our agency in the world—is possible, Dreyfus’s account seems to
In the case of the beacon, the pilot may be greeted with silence so long as the
plane stays on course, but the system can work only because the beacon itself is
monitoring the plane’s trajectory. But now imagine, as Dreyfus would have it, that
158
nothing is monitoring the absorbed coping. If something goes wrong—some tension
has happened here: a rational system has kicked in, but it has—presumably—kicked in
for no reason! After all, there was no rational monitoring of the body’s responding to
solicitations, nor was any rational faculty patiently looking for a tension to arise, since
this would make the tension itself—a sign that something was going wrong—into a
rational activity. Dreyfus admits that phenomenology has difficulty explaining how our
non-conceptual coping can be transformed into conceptual activity. But the problem here
goes deeper: since neither the coping nor the tension can be conceptual, on Dreyfus’s
view, any appearance on the scene of our rational capacities would necessarily be lacking
in rational motivation; not only would it be unclear why we should take responsibility for
our coping, but responsibility would also be absent from our rational interference—or
lack thereof—with such coping. If the relation between our absorbed coping and our
rationality is to make any sense, then, it seems our best option is to recognize that coping
as such is already permeated by rationality, which is precisely why its malfunctioning can
provide reasons for our reasons-responsive explicit thinking to step in when needed. And
We thus have a first stab at answering Dreyfus’s first objection: thinking of our
coping as already permeated with rationality makes sense of the idea that we are capable
of rationally interfering with it, or of “stepping back” just when we need to. Nor is the
idea that some monitoring experience must always be in the background of all our
coping—rather, the point is that since the coping is already conceptual and thus capable
159
of providing reasons to our reasons-responsive deliberative apparatus, the monitoring
goes on at the level of the form of our coping and not through some additional conscious
process. We may add another observation: Dreyfus argues that rationality cannot be
present in coping, since much of what goes on in our expert activity happens too quickly
to involve any thought. If this is right, we have a problem. Rational thought, it would
seem, can enter on the scene almost instantaneously; and it can halt whatever absorbed
coping is taking place. But how can it do that if the absorbed coping is not really coping
with anything conceptual at all? In other words, how can rational thought interfere with
non-rational activity unless that activity is already pre-rational, i.e., of the correct form to
interface with higher level cognitive abilities? Unless such an interface is in place,
rational thought will not be interfering with absorbed coping at all by grasping and
evaluating affordances and solicitations; at best, it will simply crowd out those
affordances and bodily responses to them and replace them with acting for a reason, a
mechanism of a completely different kind that will have no reference to what the agent
was doing before the shift to rational thought took place. On Dreyfus’s conception, what
whatever does present itself to explicit thought can have nothing in common whatsoever
with those affordances, since they lack the potential to be taken up into conceptual
thinking. This, incidentally, is another variant of the earlier problem of how I could take
responsibility for whatever I was doing in the mode of absorbed coping: whatever it is I
take responsibility for, it could not be the absorbed coping itself, since that is not
something I could attach an “I do” or “I think” to. That McDowell’s approach helps to
160
bridge this gap suggests phenomenological evidence for that approach rather than a
rejection of it.
In arguing that we have no grounds to posit any sort of conceptual activity that is
not experientially present, Dreyfus has apparently reverted to the flaccid, though
they are experienced at the time they occur.42 It is true that, when we are engaged in
absorbed coping, we are not explicitly aware of any conceptualization occurring. But we
should not take such experience out of context, since something happens after my
absorbed coping as well: I reflect on it (not to mention, as Dreyfus admits, that I can both
attach an “I think” to it and take responsibility for it). And something happens before: I
am aware, generally, of what I will be doing (though of course I need not have it planned
out) and, in the past, have performed similar tasks with explicit conceptual guidance in
play. Dreyfus admits this point, but he thinks that after one has gone through the learning
phase, where one is guided by concepts, one transcends that stage, becomes an expert,
and no longer needs concepts at all. But this is quite odd: if I needed concepts to play
chess in the past, is it not reasonable to think that, as I’ve gotten better, I have lost the
need to rely on keeping those concepts explicit? But how can this be evidence that they
are not present? Perhaps the Grandmaster is no longer following rules, explicit or
otherwise, but his perception of the game ought to be structured by the conceptual
repertoire he began with, now even more finely articulated. And it may be precisely
because of the finer articulation that the Grandmaster does not need to think explicitly
42
Again, “reverted” is the operative term here, since Dreyfus’s conception of phenomenology is much
deeper in his earlier work.
161
about what move to make: the conceptual relations in play already link up with each
coping, I often know what happened during that time. If asked why I made a certain
move, I can give a reason, although I may have to think about it in order to make it
explicit. No doubt I cannot explain every feature of my actions, but so what? The fact that
I cannot describe every feature of a blade of grass I saw does not mean that I did not see
something that fits under the concept “grass.” Why, then, should we focus on the
thematize the experience that goes on within it—it is of the nature of absorption that only
some object of it, but not the experience itself is thematized. By Dreyfus’s reasoning, we
would have to conclude, more or less, that absorbed experience has no structures or
features, since none of them are explicitly the object of awareness within the experience
itself. Phenomenology on this account loses all ability to provide anything other than
definition, was not explicitly thematized at the time it occurred; reconstructing this
our basic perceptual experience lacked suitability for conceptualization, it is unclear how
162
We can now address Dreyfus’s latter two objections. Absorbed copers often
cannot give the reasons—or even give wrong reasons—on which they acted. Dreyfus
cites the case of fighter pilots who, studies show, do not in fact make the movements they
however, they appeal to those rules. Here is a clear case of copers performing expertly
but, when called on to give their reasons, giving the wrongs ones. But this example does
not by itself cast doubt in the idea that there are in fact reasons for which the copers act.
Though McDowell, in his discussion of the hiker turning right at a sign, does seem to
suggest that retroactive reconstruction of reasons is evidence that the agent acted for a
reason, he cannot be taken to be claiming that the ability to give such a reconstruction,
defense of this thought, we can marshal three of the points I have raised above. First,
agents are likely to forget why they acted—they may even forget that they had acted—
especially in cases where no explicit thought went into their action. But second, precisely
because the conceptual repertoire of an expert is more varied and more finely
articulated—possibly to the point where the expert lacks pre-existing expressions for
may well be impossible. (Think of the common experience of trying to reconstruct the
surprising if the agent simply fell back on the simple explanations provided by pre-
learned rules, even though these were not in fact involved in her action. Finally, many of
the concepts involved may be demonstrative ones, for example ones referring to what are
basic actions for an agent. An attempt to reconstruct one’s reasoning explicitly, in trying
163
to make a demonstrative point to a listener on whom the situation-specific demonstrative
But none of this shows that agents engaged in absorbed coping cannot be acting
for reasons.43 Dreyfus’s insistence that—at least in many cases of absorbed coping—
whatever the agent acts on is too general to be a reason seems mistaken. Let’s return to
the example of basic action. Say I have mastered the skill of blocking a fencing strike. A
novice now asks: how did you do that? Whatever account I give the novice will, indeed,
seem too general and unhelpful. I blocked it because I saw the strike coming, and that’s
that. And the novice can learn my reasons, but only by being taught to see them, that is,
to perform the basic action himself. Dreyfus takes himself to be basing his account, via
Heidegger, on Aristotle’s notion of the phronimos, who simply perceives the right thing
to do. McDowell correctly points out that, in Aristotle’s account, the perception involved
in phronesis is clearly not outside the domain of logos. The phronimos acts rationally,
although only another phronimos can understand his reasons. In training for virtue, the
initiate learns to reason correctly by first applying general rules—e.g., steer away from
extremes and aim for the mean, act justly or generously—and eventually learning to
grasp the “ultimate particular fact,” i.e., the action required.44 But if the phronimos is
asked why he performed the action, he may be able to say nothing better than “this is
what justice required.” To the initiate, this may indeed seem too general to count as a
reason; but it may nevertheless serve as the phronimos’s reason for action. Dreyfus
43
We can compare the account to Arpaly’s examples, illustrating that one may well be acting rationally
without knowing it.
44
This is the rendering of Nic Ethics 1142a25 in the Oxford World’s Classics translation by David Ross
(revised by Lesley Brown).
164
suggests that the phronimos, or the Grandmaster, might simply say that the action or
move was just what “felt right to him,” or that he “felt like doing it.” But this explanation
in terms of feelings and motives is obviously not intended by Aristotle to crowd out an
account that makes it the deliverance of a properly trained practical reason.45 That an
agent “felt like doing it” is far more general than the explanation in terms of reasons—
after all, one might feel like doing in any number of situations where there is no reason
whatsoever to do it. “This looked like the right move to make” is a much better
explanation than the simple “he felt like making that move,” since the former at least
implicitly relates the making of the move to some goal—winning the game—while the
latter leaves the entire question of why the Grandmaster did what he did entirely open;
perhaps he was simply tired of playing and felt like surrendering his queen.
the pre-articulated field of experience is an incredibly difficult one, and I will not even
make a gesture at addressing it here. I will merely point to three options in attempts to
outline the interaction of these two spheres within the domain of responsible action. First,
we might simply state that we somehow learn certain concepts, while much of our
experience remains wholly non-conceptual. The conceptual then enters into our activity,
and it is this and only this sort of activity that counts as responsible action. For example,
a perception with some propositional content, together with the propositional contents of
a desire and a belief, entails the propositional content of an intention, which content is
then (paradigmatically) realized in or by the action. Second, Dreyfus’s approach has the
45
Just how motivation and reason may be combined in this way is, of course, a difficult question. For an
interesting stab at this, see Korsgaard’s “Acting for a Reason,” reprinted in her Constitution of Agency
(2008a). On her account, the agent simply sees the whole action—e.g., going to Chicago to visit a sick
relative—as something worth doing, takes that recognition as the reason to perform the action, and is
motivated by the recognition.
165
conceptual arise out of the non-conceptual. We can act, and act responsibly, by
withdrawal of the agent from the world. There is a difference in kind here between non-
conceptual and conceptual content, such that to represent the former as the latter is to
distort its true nature. Finally, McDowell’s account, by contrast, draws a distinction
between the conceptual and the pre-conceptual, rather than the non-conceptual. The field
articulated precisely because experience—at least that of rational agents—is of the kind
to allow articulation. When we act, we may well act smoothly on the basis of solicitations
presented by the world; but these very solicitations can and must, in order to enter into
Philosophers sometimes write as if human beings have their heads filled with
rather odd metaphysical entities: propositional states. Our beliefs, desires, attitudes, and
accessed as such in order to allow for genuine, and certainly for responsible, action. The
alternative to such a view, it sometimes seems, is the thought that instead we are simply
filled with blind natural processes and proddings, irrational pulls and pushes that—should
they issue in bodily movement—involve no more agency, and carry with them no more
compromise. Our beliefs, desires, attitudes, and so on are, largely, inchoate. They have
form, but the form is potential; it is actualized when this matter of our experience bonds
166
appearing as conceptually articulated and capable of entering into rational deliberation,
thus shows itself to have been conceptual all along. And it is just such a position that
allows us to say that, although much—probably most—of what we feel and do is not yet
conceptual, not yet articulated, and presses on us and through us without much by way of
attribution, this need not drive us into a volitionist corner where the only action that
counts as responsible is action that involves CTD. Such an account allows us to make
sense of the suggestion that our attitudes (Smith) and actions (Korsgaard) embody our
judgments (or, to put it another way, the judgments are partially constitutive of our
attitudes and actions) while allowing that the judgments may be entirely outside the
agent’s awareness. Our evaluative judgments are not free-floating entities grounding our
attitudes. They are, rather, embodied in those attitudes. This is why the claim that we can
discover our judgments through self-observation (Smith 2005 252) has significant force:
demonstration, that one’s response to an exam question was wrong. It involves changing
changing an evaluative attitude. And we can allow that our attitudes and patterns of
conceptually without thereby giving up on the notion that rationality is in play even in
those behaviors and attitudes that one has never consciously chosen.
167
On this reading, then, McDowell’s work comes far closer to Heidegger than
Dreyfus’s supposedly Heideggerian stance. We can see this from a footnote in which
Dreyfus in fact attempts to assimilate Heidegger’s position to his own without having to
In this attempt to separate perception from “our understanding of our identity” Dreyfus
diverges fundamentally from a theme crucial to Being and Time, which is precisely that
any such separation is a theoretical construct that obscures the phenomenon of being-in-
reference; I will lay out the discussion only in basic outline, as the standard features of
Key to Heidegger’s account is the notion that Da-sein, his term for the kind of
being of human beings, is always in a world. This world is always a referential totality, in
which entities disclose themselves to us first as tools, that we use for, with, and in
common with other entities like ourselves with whom we share practices of interacting
with the world and understanding ourselves. I will save a discussion of this latter aspect
for the next section; here I want to focus only on the way that tools—and our coping with
them—become meaningful in Heidegger’s account, as this is one key part of his account
168
In his famous tool analysis, Heidegger lays out the conditions for there being
entities for us to interact with. These entities are disclosed primarily as tools: as
equipment to be used for some task. But, as Heidegger stresses, tools do not disclose
themselves as individual objects; “strictly speaking, there ‘is’ no such thing as a useful
thing. There always belongs to the being of a useful thing as totality of useful things in
which this useful thing can be what it is.”46 This totality, furthermore, is always a
notebooks, and books, to the drawer in which I keep it, to my need for keeping notes, to
my writing. And in its own turn, the pencil has a certain materiality—it is sharp or dull,
fitting or unfitting for the task relative to which it is a pencil; what makes it so suitable is,
never need to appear in order for the pencil to be put to use.47 So long as the pencil
remains sharp, in its place, and otherwise suitable for underlining or writing, I need not
explicitly notice it as a pencil—I merely use it to write. When it correctly plays this role
say that it does not appear as a pencil at all but rather withdraws, in Heidegger’s
formulation. In using things—or taking care of them—in this way, we need not explicitly
be aware of them at all; the experience or seeing of things that conforms to this mode of
46
Heidegger 1996, 68. All page references to Being and Time will refer to the pagination of 1953 Max
Niemeyer Verlag German edition, given in the margins of both English translations. I will quote from
Stambaugh’s translation, though some terminology will occasionally need to be altered. From this point on,
when page numbers are given without further information, they always refer to the German pagination of
Sein und Zeit.
47
Heidegger commentators frequently focus entirely on the social dimension of tools—that is, the norms
that govern their use—as marking their user-independence. That the materiality of the tools constitutes
another level of user-independence—one that, moreover, both places constraints on and is taken up in
norms of use—is a point recently worked out in detail by Graham Harman in his (2010) and elsewhere.
169
Of course we do not spend our lives fully absorbed in rote activities in which our
tools function smoothly. Sometimes the tools break down, or go missing, or instead
present themselves as the wrong sort of thing (the form in front of me asks me to use a
pen, but I have only a pencil). In these cases I am snapped out of my absorption with the
task at hand and am forced to repair the tool, find it, or replace it. When my absorption is
Instead of interacting with the pencil circumspectly, I now see it as a what it is—a dull
object that needs to be sharpened—and, having sharpened it, I quickly return to work and
the pencil withdraws again. The breakdown may be more serious—something I normally
take for granted might vanish, for example, or suddenly stop functioning. And then I
become aware of the entire context, the referential whole within which I have taken the
thing for granted. Of course this does not mean that I can only think about entities
explicitly when they break—I can do so at any time, as Heidegger makes clear.48 The
point is only that things appear to me as things, with purposes, and of a certain material
context of absorption, in which our taking care of things is “subordinate to the in-order-to
constitutive for the actual useful thing in our association with it.” (69) Explicit thought
about something, in other words, requires us to leave the agential stance in which we
simply use the thing for its standard purpose. But obviously this does not mean that
contemplation breaks free of the normal contexts of interaction with innerworldly beings;
48
In History of the Concept of Time, he articulates three, rather than two ways of seeing entities, and he
makes it clear that each of these can be entered into at any point.
170
it means only that such contexts are implicit in every act of explicit contemplation. To
contemplate a pencil—to know that it is a pencil, I must already have access to the
referential context in which that pencil has relevance. And since every reference in this
context will point to something further outside of it, I can only grasp the pencil on the
basis of a familiarity with the totality of references, i.e., the world. Thus, “being-in-the-
world signifies the unthematic, circumspect absorption in the references constitutive for
the handiness of the totality of useful things. Taking care of things always already occurs
things, this means that we can never make the entire context constitutive of a thing
explicit. Dreyfus has made good use of this thought over the years, especially in his
argument that it is impossible to get computers to think, or to interact with entities in the
way we do, by teaching them a finite set of explicit rules. No set of explicit rules can
fully articulate the underlying referential context. But in the debate with McDowell,
Dreyfus takes the claim further: he argues that our taking care of things is not, at bottom,
fundamentally different sort of content. But both of these claims go far beyond the former
claim that the world cannot be made conceptually explicit. It is one thing, in other words,
to say that we cannot make the entire referential totality explicit all at once, and to say
that the totality contains elements that cannot be made conceptually explicit. And, we
might recall, McDowell’s claim is simply that our perceptual openness to the world
involves pre-conceptual elements, that is, elements that can be conceptualized even
though initially one may lack—and may in fact always lack—any concept for them. I
171
think McDowell’s account, then, comes far closer to Heidegger’s than Dreyfus would
First, I want to address two apparent puzzles that Heidegger’s account seems to
raise. On the one hand, one might wonder whether his tool analysis is really an account of
human agency, or of only a segment of it—that is, the segment that involves writing,
hammering, and other uses of tools. On the other hand, Heidegger seems to objectionably
assimilate all innerworldly entities to tools. What, one might ask, are we to make of trees
or of the sun? Do those entities only appear to us when we need lumber or a way to tell
the time, as Heidegger sometimes seems to imply? The answers to these puzzles naturally
belong together. All human action is action in the world.49 The point of Heidegger’s
analysis—or at least one of the points—is just that we often use tools without recognizing
them as such. Tools are not just things like hammers and pencils. They are also
sidewalks, that we use to get somewhere; or the sun, which we use for warmth, for light,
or to get a tan. We may make use of trees not only for lumber, but also for atmosphere, or
for entertainment; or we might treat them (like Hansel and Gretel) as something
frightening to escape from. But even here the trees are, in some sense, “useful things,” in
that they make themselves manifest within a referential whole. Thus, the world in which
we act is a world of tools, and human action almost necessarily involves making use of
tools (in this sense) in some way. This is not a complete account of agency—we still have
49
We can list “mental actions”—acts of thinking, deciding, realizing, and so on—in a special category,
since these do not necessarily make use of things in the usual sense. But even that is not clear. One thinks
or has realizations about something, something that is perhaps not an innerworldly being, but stands in
some relation to such a being. And acts of deciding do, after all, involve deciding to do something,
something that typically involves bodily movements that change something in the physical configuration of
the entities around me.
172
The foregoing account of our being-in-the-world as a background condition of
First, the in-order-to constitutive of tools, and to which our activity in the world is
subordinate, must have a source: our ways of using tools and of acting are appropriated
from “the they,” a topic I will address in the next section. Second, it is clear that the
not yet been explained. Heidegger addresses this topic—which he calls an analysis of
being-in as such, or the being of the there (133)—through three structural features
features are equiprimordial; none of them have priority over the others, and all are
that the moods involved in attunement should be understood as distinct from emotions
and perhaps even as “deep” moods that differ from surface moods, this does not seem to
passions, and the later philosophical work on “the affects and feelings,” which “fall
thematically under the psychic phenomena, functioning as a third class of these, mostly
along with representational thinking and willing. They sink to the level of accompanying
does not single out moods as a special category distinct from what philosophers have
addressed as affects and feelings; rather, he chides the tradition for losing sight of the
importance of this “third class” of “psychic phenomena.” That Heidegger uses a common
173
But moods are not, on his view, subjective states that color a pre-given objective
world. Rather, they are constitutive of our having a world at all—they disclose Da-sein in
its thrownness. In other words, moods disclose the world in such a way that it can matter
to Da-sein (or, better, in such a way that it already matters to Da-sein); it is thanks to
them that regions of the world can have salience or, in Dreyfus’s terminology, that
such a way that what it encounters in the world can matter to it in this way. This
for example, as something by which it can be threatened.” (137) On the other hand,
moods disclose how Da-sein is in this world—how we relate to the world in which we
find ourselves. Whether the mood is love or fear, it always simultaneously discloses two
poles: it discloses the world in such a way that a region of it is loved or fearful; and it
discloses Da-sein as that which relates to this region through love or fear. To have a
world is to have regions of it stand out in this way—as something that attracts or repulses
us, for example, that draws us in and makes us pay attention to it. My self-apprehension
Understanding, on the other hand, adds the key component that Dreyfus
revealing Da-sein and its world, and it reveals both by projecting possibilities. Just as
that are co-constitutive of both Da-sein and the entities with which it interacts. “In
50
Although all moods reveal both Da-sein and its world, this does not mean that all moods reveal certain
regions of the world as mattering. Angst, as we will see later, is a mood that reveals the world, but in such a
way that nothing in it matters.
174
of an explicitly or inexplicitly grasped potentiality-of-its-being for the sake of which it
is.” (86) In using entities, in other words, we must already encounter them as having
purposes—the in-order-to, or the task in terms of which such entities are useful. But such
purposes are only meaningful for the sake of something else. Less abstractly, the point is
that the tasks for which we use tools are, ultimately, defined by human purposes. In a
stock example, one encounters a hammer in hammering boards together, and one
hammers boards together in order to build a house, but one builds a house for the sake of
an entity that dwells in houses. Similarly, one encounters the earth beneath one’s feet as a
“tool” for walking on; and as such it is meaningful within a framework ultimately
then, gives the purposes in terms of which we grasp the referential whole within which
entities are disclosed. And this means that Da-sein itself is disclosed—usually only
Heidegger’s view, understands itself exclusively in terms of its occurrent features, such
as its height, age, nationality, and so forth. Rather, these features themselves are grasped
only relative to Da-sein’s potentiality-for-being, that is, it’s projection of a possible way
to be. And possibility, in this sense, is not just a logical or metaphysical possibility (in the
sense that it is possible that one might—or might not—lose one’s hair, or even sprout
wings and fly off into the sunset), but rather Da-sein’s competence in dealing with its
world. “We sometimes use the expression ‘to understand something’ to mean ‘being able
175
existential, the thing we are able to do is not a what, but being as existing… Da-sein is
not something objectively present which then has as an addition the ability to do
something, but is rather primarily being-possible.” (143) My having or lacking hair (or
wings), my skill in playing chess, or my prowess with a samurai sword are objective facts
about me, much the way that hardness is an objective fact about tables. But I understand
myself in terms of these things not because I take them as defining features of myself, but
because I take them up in the ways of being that I project for myself—that is, in my
possibilities. Of course I can define myself by my kendo skill, but this will be because I
already understand myself as a braggart about my sword abilities or, perhaps (in a
different time and place) because I am honored to be able to slay the enemies of my
shogun.
fulfill or press into, and it is in light of these possibilities, our for-the-sake-of-which, that
matter. To put it another way, “the project character of understanding constitutes being-
in-the-world with regard to the disclosedness of its there as the there of a potentiality of
51
Blattner (1996), in an excellent analysis, refers to this as “the Unattainability Thesis: Dasein’s ability-
characteristics [in terms of which it understands itself] are not attainable.” (107)
176
and then set out to master the art of kendo. But if I succeeded in mastering kendo, it
would no longer be a possibility. To say that Da-sein projects (and, therefore, is) its
understands itself are not things like mastering kendo, but being a kendo expert, and one
can certainly have expertise in kendo without understanding oneself as a kendo expert,
since one can simply—despite having mastered kendo—see oneself as a lawyer who
to its potentiality of being: Da-sein always exists as possibility, or as potential, and not as
actuality or fact.
The possibilities we project for ourselves are thus co-constitutive with the
possibilities in terms of which entities in the world are disclosed to us (my self-
kendo sword). “The essential possibility of Da-sein concerns the ways of taking care of
the ‘world’ which we characterized, or concern for others and, always already present in
all of this, the potentiality of being itself, for its own sake.” (143) Commentators who
focus on the connection between our interactions with objects and our identity sometimes
focus on overly particular identities (e.g., the way I handle a hammer might reflect my
carpenter).52 But the way Heidegger’s account seems to work is both simpler and more
complex than this. Consider the following set of considerations: As an embodied being, I
am sometimes tired. It is customary in our culture to sit when tired. It is also customary to
52
This is the way so-called pragmatists tend to read Heidegger. See, e.g., Okrent (2000a, 2000b).
177
sit in class, during job interviews, and so on. And my world includes various objects,
some of which are designed for sitting on. Others are merely convenient, and yet sitting
on them is not ruled out by the social conventions applicable within particular situations
(though it may be ruled out in others). And this set of considerations—along with many
others, which it may be impossible to fully articulate—is what allows me to interact with
(or take care of) certain regions of my world as chairs or, more generally, as seats.
Furthermore, the way I sit, my posture, the movements involved in lowering my body,
social conventions, my sense of comfort or discomfort, the shape and hardness of the
object I am sitting on, and so on. And, we might add, I can take care of the chair for other
purposes. Perhaps a light bulb has gone out. The lack of a ladder, the height of the chair,
my need to change the light bulb, the fact that I am taller than my household partner or
perhaps simply the sense that I should be doing more around the house—in light of these
considerations, I might see the chair as a surface to step on to get closer to the ceiling.
The point of this long-winded discussion of seats, chairs, and step-stools is just
this: I can interact with something as a chair only in light of a totality of considerations
through which the chair becomes significant. But unpacking these considerations is
difficult. Some of them refer to the materiality of the object. Others refer to social norms,
example, I am someone who needs to do more around the house, I am someone who
occasionally becomes tired (and is not embarrassed to let others see this), and so on. Part
178
entities unlike Da-sein, to our social dimension (the they), and to Da-sein itself—are
intertwined in such a way that picking them apart requires standing away from them and
seeing them as referring only in a specific direction. And part of the story is that what is
meant by Da-sein’s “identity” can be a far more everyday and banal matter than a
profession, which is the standard example used by commentators. In fact, it must be,
since my identity as, say, a philosopher could not possibly account for the myriad ways in
which entities in the surrounding world appear to me in my taking care of them. Identity
Heidegger’s view, “a role or identity organizes all of one’s activity. One does not have an
identity because one acknowledges tool using norms as Okrent claims, but one uses tools
reference is not a feature of each act; it is the way many of one’s actions are organized or
implicitly—every time it follows a norm in its taking care of things. Instead, Da-sein’s
innerworldly entities manifest themselves to be used (together with their norms) in the
first place. But we should avoid falling into the trap of thinking that Da-sein must
explicitly pick an identity before it can have a world. The opposite seems to be the case:
“As essentially attuned, Da-sein has always already got itself into definite possibilities…
But this means that Da-sein is a being-possible entrusted to itself, thrown possibility
179
surrendered to thrownness, Da-sein has always already gone astray and failed to
recognize itself. In its potentiality of being, it is thus delivered over to the possibility of
first finding itself again in its possibilities.” (144) It is true, in other words, that
the world. But precisely because the two go hand in hand, Da-sein gets lost in those
interactions. Rather than using tools “in order to manifest one’s identity,” Da-sein has to
discover its identity as something with which it is already saddled, and which it already
manifests; that is, Da-sein can find itself in its taking care of things because that taking
care is structured by its projected self-understanding, but it finds itself first (or, in
Heidegger’s terminology, proximally and for the most part) among the things it takes care
of.
the circumstances in which I find myself. Blattner illustrates this relation with the
example, find myself associating law with power, and it is because I already have this
association, and because I already care about power, that law appeals to me:
This is right, but since attunement and understanding are co-constitutive, the relation
works the other way as well: my projecting self-understanding modifies the meaning of
180
the situation in which I find myself. As mentioned earlier, occurrent features of Da-sein
are never simply givens; they are not factual, but factical, in that their mattering to me is
always taken up within my for-the-sake-of-which, and takes its meaning from the
possibilities I project. In the case of the entities I take care of, their materiality both
places limits on, and is disclosed within, their uses. Similarly, Da-sein’s thrownness both
saddles it with possibilities and itself becomes meaningful in light of those possibilities.
As is well known, Heidegger identifies Da-sein with care, with the care structure
incorporating both our thrownness and projection, our encounter with entities in light of
our projection of world and identity: “The being of Da-sein means being-ahead-of-
encountered).” (192)
Finally, this structure strongly suggests that one cannot separate our taking care of
entities from our identity in the way Dreyfus suggests. Our identity—the for-the-sake-of-
which—is co-extensive with the world within which we take care of things. Our taking
care, then, cannot operate as a background condition detached from our identity. Nor can
one say in response to McDowell—as Dreyfus does—that our coping activity is not
rational because “most of our activities don’t involve concepts at all. That is, they don’t
have a situation-specific ‘as structure’”. (Dreyfus 2007b 371) What Dreyfus says here is
interpretation, in this sense, is not yet linguistic. In interpretation, entities are made
what is at hand in the surrounding world which ‘sees’ this as a table, a door, a car, a
181
bridge does not necessarily already have to analyze what is circumspectly interpreted in a
particular statement.” (149) Instead, statements that present something as something are
founded on this more primordial interpretation, and they are deficient in their disclosive
referential whole; language, as such, necessarily detaches the entity that it discloses from
The distinction between two types of as structures indicates that there is a pre-
linguistic as. Thus, Heidegger points out that a hammer can be disclosed as too heavy
within interpretation but without stating that it is too heavy. Circumspective interpretation
“may take some such form as ‘the hammer is too heavy’ or, even better, ‘too heavy, the
other hammer!’ The primordial act of interpretation lies not in a theoretical sentence, but
in circumspectly and heedfully putting away or changing the inappropriate tool ‘without
wasting words.’” (157) Thus, the as structure of interpretation, instead of stating that
some property belongs to some entity, treats the entity as having that property precisely
by dealing with it in a certain way. Dreyfus, oddly, wants to detach interpretation from
our absorbed coping experience, insisting that interpretation only enters onto the scene
“when we are no longer able simply to cope.” For example, “when the doorknob sticks,
circumspection discovers what the doorknob is for, although it fully understands it only
in using it.” (Dreyfus 1991 196) But this seems to be the exact opposite of Heidegger’s
claim that “any perception of useful things at hand always understands and interprets
were involved only when we cannot continue to cope, it could hardly be present in all
182
circumspective dealings with entities, as Heidegger suggests. The point, instead, seems to
account—do not utilize concepts at all. But this fact is perfectly in accord with
McDowell’s positing of a pre-conceptual domain: that is, the idea, developed above, that
whatever we encounter in the world already is conceptual, not because we have already
conceptualized it or even have the words with which to do so, but because it is of the
right form to be taken up into concepts. And this is precisely the view Heidegger
interpretation. That is, our understanding of the world as a referential whole allows us to
interpret—i.e., to deal with entities in the world as such and such—and interpretation, in
turn, provides the structure taken up in explicit linguistic conceptualization. Our concepts
are founded in a pre-conceptual understanding of world; but this does not mean that the
conceptualized; but it provides the form that allows for conceptualization. Thus,
Heidegger’s view gives us something similar to the McDowellian picture, with the main
distinction being a matter of emphasis: McDowell stresses that conceptuality pervades all
our activity, whereas Heidegger instead stresses that our activity is the basis on which
conceptuality operates. There is, among critics of Heidegger and even among some
himself says about the traditional philosophical view of human beings as “zoon logon
echon”: “The later interpretation of this definition of human being in the sense of the
183
animal rationale, ‘rational living being,’ is not ‘false,’ but it covers over the phenomenal
basis from which this definition of Da-sein is taken. The human being shows himself as a
being who speaks. This does not mean that the possibility of vocal utterance belongs to
him, but that this being is in the mode of discovering world and Da-sein itself.” (165) In
other words, Da-sein is properly understood as rational, but its rationality must be seen as
equiprimordial with attunement and understanding. Discourse is, on his view, “the
in language is brought out through the rhythm or a way of speaking). Discourse allows us
to have a shared world, which we can express to each other and make ourselves
understood. And Heidegger provides evidence that discourse underlies language in the
circumspect taking care of the world. The entities we deal with must be entities we can
make someone else see, communicate something about. And again, that discourse is not
conceptual does not support Dreyfus’s view, but rather McDowell’s: what we can
184
conceptually, though it need not be, and though sometimes in practice one might find it
impossible to do so.
later rely on. I have been arguing that the background on which we act is such that it can
be taken up and articulated rationally, so that even if one does not explicitly deliberate
about what one is doing, and even if one is utterly absorbed in a task, one may still be
acting for a reason. Let me now call the background character. One’s character is what,
for the most part, one acts on; for example, when one responds to solicitations, they are
soliciting our character. Character as articulated through discourse, on the other hand—
that is, not as full-blown linguistic self-understanding, of the sort used in CTD—I want to
call will. So using this terminology we can say that agents have both a character and a
will. If I speak of someone driven to act by his love, I am referring to his character. If I
speak of him as acting because his action serves the interest of his beloved (for example),
I am referring to his will. Or, to take another example, to say that someone is honest
might mean that he cannot lie, is not suited to it, and then one is referring to his character.
Or it might mean that he appreciates truthfulness, and acts on that reason. And this is his
will. So we might think of Dreyfus as attempting to separate character from will, whereas
content, that is, the background involved in the agent’s agency. But they refer to it
terminology allows us to say that on the attributionist view, when the agent acts
185
according to his character, he is also expressing his will. It is this latter element that
makes his action of a type that can, in principle, be said to be in his control.
My aim in the above was to sketch out what is involved in an account of acting
rationally without CTD. Because attributionists take such cases of absorbed coping as
paradigmatic in their account of responsibility, it is important to see just how the idea that
evaluative judgments or values are embodied in our pre- or non-deliberative actions and
attitudes is supposed to work. And, as I argued in the last chapter, the important point is
not just that much of the activity for which we typically hold people responsible is non-
deliberative, but that any volitionist account of responsibility must still be grounded in
pre-deliberative processes (e.g., the processes on the basis of which we take up some
considerations rather than others in the deliberation itself, and the processes on the basis
Making sense of pre-deliberative agency is thus crucial to working out how anyone can
involved in the connection between features of the agent’s character and the agent’s
actions, I tried to work out, by means of the McDowell-Dreyfus debate, a way of making
sense of the thought that our actions may proceed from a pre-deliberative background and
yet still be rational, and thus subject to agential control. The sense of rationality involved
turned out to be not one where our agency is maxims all the way down (in Dreyfus’s
186
critical formulation)—so that every human action or attitude is the upshot of a prior
retrievable. Agents can act for reasons even in the absence of CTD because they can
articulate the reasons for their actions retrospectively and, even when they cannot, this
need not serve as evidence that their action was arational. The processes involved in
generating action may be rational, in other words, so long as the capacities operating in
suggest (indirectly) that we can thereby work out the most comprehensive account of
how this notion of control might work, and especially of the crucial idea that rational
considerations such as judgments or values are embodied in our actions and attitudes.
This idea is crucial because it allows agents to be responsible for their actions and
attitudes directly, without the mediation of prior thought, and this is just what we need to
that attitudes and actions reflect values or judgments of the agent because those attitudes
and actions stem from the agent’s care—that is, from her affectivity as it is modified by
attributionism, which is to claim that our rational judgments are (at least) partly
constitutive of our attitudes and actions. Instead, our picture now presents those
referential totality within which our attitudes and actions have their full significance. But
this preserves the basic picture: the rational judgments are no longer constitutive of our
187
attitudes and actions, but they still reflect our selves insofar as they are derived from
At the same time, however, the Heideggerian account should make it easier to see
that there is something deficient in the attributionist picture worked out so far. For one,
we can return to the difference, already noted by Levy, between expressing and
reflecting. On the Heideggerian picture, at this point, the agent’s attitudes only reflect her
self—they do not necessarily express it, since the agent might simply find herself thrown
into her possibilities and have to find herself within them. The same seems to go for the
attributionist account the connection between agency and the agent’s self or will is far
correct a difficulty with Frankfurt’s view, on which agents are responsible only for acting
on those desires with which they identify. The attributionist, recognizing that an agent’s
self is wider than the narrow scope of identification, attempts something like a coherence
theory of the self. But on the other hand, giving up the link with identification makes it
difficult to see just how the various judgments involved are genuinely the agent’s own,
rather than simply belonging to her. Attributionists may attempt to fix this, as we have
seen, by postulating criteria of integration and depth: an attitude is the agent’s own, on
this view, if the judgment it embodies is sufficiently well integrated with the agent’s
other judgments, and if it is especially difficult to change. But this may seem to bring us
to the unappealing Stoic view that we can change our attitudes simply by changing our
judgments; discover what is good or evil, and the attitudes will follow!
188
Consider two points here. First, an example: an individual may discover that he
has strong sexual urges. These sexual urges are reasonably well integrated with his other
attitudes (at least, considering how un-integrated most of our desires are): they are
especially difficult to shake (and thus deep) and they are not opposed by other beliefs and
values the agent holds. But it is possible that he simply cannot see a good reason to
satisfy those urges; “it feels good” is not a justification he accepts. He does not see
anything wrong (or at least seriously wrong) with those urges, so there is no significant
opposition with other beliefs. But it is hard to see how there is any valuing on his part
going on. Should we say that he does not, in fact, value sex, we are making his values
depend on his endorsement, which is what the attributionist account is meant to avoid. On
the other hand, if we insist that—since the relevant attributionist criteria are fulfilled—
the man genuinely values sex, the claim seems awkward. We may just as well claim that
his body values sex and makes evaluative judgments with which he disagrees (or towards
Second, the difficulty with the attributionist criteria is that the criteria are entirely
third-personal. This is not to say, of course, that it is especially easy to determine how
integrated an attitude is from the outside; the point is that the criteria are specifically
position with regard to knowing his desires and beliefs, but he is in a better position to
know whether or not he is responsible than an outside observer only by virtue of this
epistemic fact. The desires and beliefs relevant to judgments of responsibility seem here
to be only properties that an agent has; since he need neither identify with nor choose
them in any sense, they belong to him in the same way as any external property—like his
189
height, or his shoes.53 That this is the attributionist view is especially clear on Arpaly’s
account: she likens moral criticism to the sort of criticism involved in saying that
kind of third-personal description. Arpaly notes that, in the case of business, one can
make a judgment that someone is good or bad at it, and the person’s history—what made
her that way—is completely irrelevant to the judgment. Moral criticism, on her view, is
descriptive in the same way: whether or not your bad will is traceable back to a bad
childhood or something of the sort is simply irrelevant to the quality of your will now,
and praise and blame are judgments that respond to one’s quality of will.54 But this view
entirely. To say that what makes blame warranted or unwarranted is the quality of an
agent’s will is to presuppose that the agent is responsible for her will in the first place.
is, being an appropriate target for praise or blame). For the attributionist, then, if an agent
satisfies the criteria for deserving praise or blame (on their view: having a good or ill
will), he is thereby shown to be responsible. My point here is that the reverse holds: if an
agent can fail to be responsible and yet manifest a good or ill will, praise and blame will
53
This, of course, is cognate to Levy’s criticism.
54
This comparison of moral criticism with criticism of business ability only seems wrong, she thinks, if one
holds praise and blame to require or be akin to punishment and reward, as something that can be required
or forbidden, or as something appropriate or inappropriate. Instead, she argues, “it is first and foremost
warranted or unwarranted, the way that my fear of getting a flu shot is warranted only if flu shots are
dangerous to me.” (Arpaly 2003 172) I doubt, however, that this is the real problem, or that we can make
much sense of the idea implied here, that praise and blame are the upshots of epistemic judgments. In any
case, not all attributionists share this view—the important point, as we’ve seen in Angela Smith, is that the
attributionists hold that anti-volitionism should be easier to swallow once we uncouple praise and blame
from reward and (especially) punishment.
190
be inappropriate. Recall that the attributionist’s aim is to give criteria for responsibility
I have treated moral blame as justified when one person correctly judges that
another has guided his actions in a way that expresses contempt or disregard for
the first person’s moral standing. The justification of blame, then, has mainly to
do with our capacity to guide our actions in a way that reveals our attitudes
toward others, and this requires no investigation into how a wrongdoer came to
possess the dispositions that incline him to exercise his power of self-governance
as he does. (Talbert 2009 18)
So what is supposed to justify judgments of praise and blame is that the agent’s actions
reveal her attitudes—that is, whether her attitudes guide her actions (or, in Smith’s case,
whether her values guide her attitudes; there are clearly a few variations on this theme). If
they do—if the proper reasons-responsive mechanisms are in place—then we can simply
hold the actions (or attitudes) blameworthy because they reflect underlying blameworthy
The fact that we praise or blame someone implies that we hold the agent
responsible. But it does not follow that the agent is responsible. A crucial premise needs
to be inserted, tying the agent to the quality of her will. As the last paragraph
representative of the agent: her attitudes or her evaluative judgments? That attributionists
disagree with each other, of course, does not show they are all wrong. What it does
suggest in this case, however, is that they take praise and blame to be justified by factors
that are stand-ins for the agent: we blame agents because their attitudes or evaluative
judgments express who they are. And these features are supposed to express who the
a whole. The problem is that this does not follow. Agents are not automatically
191
identifiable with each of their rational operations, nor necessarily even with the coherent
bulk of their rational operations; they are identifiable only with those operation that are
Fischer and Ravizza’s Responsibility and Control. In earlier work, Fischer had already
developed what he calls semi-compatibilism, that is, the view that moral responsibility is
compatible with determinism (although free will—in at least one sense—is not). There,
responsibility does not require alternative possibilities and can therefore be made
that early work often argued that there was a problem with Fischer’s account of reasons-
55
In discussing whether we should hold agents who have been the subjects of manipulation responsible,
Talbert seems to address this concern: “One way to put the general point here is to say that the question we
should ask when confronted with a manipulation scenario is not really whether the values that an agent now
has are her values – in a sense, values cannot fail to be those of the agent who acts on them. Rather, …we
should ask whether her actions issue from the right sort of internal states such that they are capable of
expressing interpersonally significant values, attitudes and judgments about reasons.” (Talbert 2009 13)
But to say that “in a sense, values cannot fail to be those of the agent who acts on them” is simply question-
begging. As the phrasing implies, and as I will argue later, there are at least two different senses in which
values can belong to an agent; which sense we have in mind will be relevant to whether “her actions issue
from the right sort of internal states.”
56
Manipulation scenarios often involve science fiction evil scientists poking around in someone’s brain,
often disregarding mental holism and anti-reductionism at will. The point, for the most part, is both to
clarify the conceptual field of moral responsibility and to provide scenarios similar enough to determinism
192
responsiveness—a topic I will not address here—Responsibility and Control lays out a
new, historical condition meant to allay manipulation concerns: guidance control now
requires both that the mechanism that issues in an action be reasons-responsive, and that
In introducing their account of ownership, Fischer and Ravizza stress that they
have in mind a historical notion of responsibility: agents must take responsibility for their
responsible for any actions that issue from these mechanisms in the future. What makes
the account historical, then, is that responsibility for an action requires a past act (broadly
construed) of taking responsibility on the part of the agent. To set up the account, Fischer
and Ravizza contrast historical phenomena, which depend somehow on their history, with
properties. (Fischer and Ravizza 1998 171) For example, the property of being a correct
answer to a math problem does not depend on the history of how someone came to that
answer. And a book’s property of having exactly 173 pages does not depend on how
those pages came to be in the book; it depends only on the number of pages the book has
at a particular time. On the other hand, some phenomena are historical. A simple example
the authors give is that of being a genuine Picasso. No snapshot properties of a work—
that is, no properties present here and now—can determine whether a painting is a
genuine Picasso; that depends entirely on whether or not it was painted by Picasso. (Of
by art historians to ascertain whether a painting is indeed a genuine Picasso, but those
as to raise doubts (if one allows that the manipulation in question rules out moral responsibility) about
compatibilism. For a discussion of manipulation-based arguments against Fischer’s early account, see
Ekstrom (2000 169-173).
193
properties clearly do not make the painting such.) Another example is drawn from Robert
Nozick’s view of justice. Roughly, the idea is that we cannot determine whether a given
distribution of resources is a just one without knowing the history of that distribution. For
example, it is possible that most people living with a just distribution chose—according
to just transactions—to give their money to a particular individual in that society, creating
massive wealth inequality. The existence of inequality, however, does not show that the
current distribution is unjust, since there was no injustice involved in its coming about.
On the other hand, exactly the same distribution could be brought about through theft,
The argument that responsibility is a historical notion, then, claims that there are
certain conditions prior to an action that must be met in order for the agent to be
Fischer and Ravizza contrast their account with what they call “mesh” theories of moral
responsibility—theories that require a mesh between some features of the agent. (Fischer
and Ravizza 1998 183-186) They give three examples. For Frankfurt, as we have seen,
responsibility requires a mesh between the agent’s first-order desires and his second order
volitions—this constitutes identification with the first-order volition on which the agent
similarly, requires a mesh between an agent’s desires and her values. And, finally,
attributionist theories are clearly mesh theories of this sort as well: they require a mesh
between actions or attitudes, on the one hand, and the agent’s character, on the other.
But the problem with such theories is that they are indifferent to how the mesh
came about: what matters for responsibility is whether or not the mesh exists. But,
194
Fischer and Ravizza contend, there are ways of creating such a mesh that are intuitively
and brainwashing may also bring a mesh into being. Anecdotal evidence suggests, for
example, that it is possible to quit smoking through hypnosis—those who undergo it find
that they identify with their desire not to smoke rather than their first-order desire to have
a cigarette. And certainly prominent cases of brainwashing are easy to find. Thus, mesh
theories seem to falter because they do not require that the key elements in the agent be
his own—identifications acquired through hypnosis are, intuitively, not one’s own, and
this seems to undermine the agent’s responsibility.57 One possible conclusion to draw
from this, as I suggested earlier, is that mesh theories alone are insufficient—to be
responsible, an agent must have control over whether or not the mesh exists. But Fischer
and Ravizza take a different approach: they argue that the problem with mesh theories is
that they require a mesh between current time-slice properties of the agent, when what is
To see what is needed, Fischer and Ravizza describe the process by which one
becomes a moral agent, which involves three interrelated components: training, taking
responsibility, and being held responsible. That is, children are typically trained to take
responsibility for their reasons-responsive mechanisms, and are then held responsible
(and hold themselves responsible) once the training is concluded. The training is needed
in order to bring about the process of taking responsibility, and being held responsible is
important in seeing that the training has worked—that is, someone who genuinely cannot
understand the reactive attitudes others take toward him (regardless of whether or not he
57
Of course agents can be responsible for the results of hypnosis, brainwashing, or manipulation if they
undergo these voluntarily, as do the smokers who use hypnosis to help them quit.
195
agrees with them) has not yet become a moral agent. But the middle component—taking
responsibility—is clearly the most important one, as “the process by which an agent takes
responsibility for the springs of this action makes them his own in an important sense.”
(Fischer and Ravizza 1998 210) Taking responsibility, in turn, also consists of three
components.
First, individuals must learn to recognize themselves as agents; that is, the
individual “must see that his choices and actions are efficacious in the world. The agent
thus sees that his motivational states are the causal source—in certain characteristic
ways—of upshots in the world.” (Fischer and Ravizza 1998 210-211) Next, they must
learn to see themselves as apt targets of reactive attitudes on the basis of their exercise of
their agency: not only do their motivational states have effects in the world, but those
effects can be fairly subject to praise and blame. This need not, the authors stress, involve
any metaphysical deliberation about fairness. Rather, “the individual must see that in
certain contexts it is ‘fair,’ in the sense of being part of our given social practices, for
others to subject him to the reactive attitudes in certain circumstances. That is, he must
see that it is an appropriate move in the relevant ‘social game’ to apply to him the
reactive attitudes in some contexts.” (Fischer and Ravizza 1998 211) This step involves
recognizing and understanding the reactive attitudes others take towards one’s exercise of
agency. That is, agents must learn how the game is played, and see themselves as players
in that game.
player requires internalizing one’s role. That is, agents must come to hold reactive
attitudes towards themselves that correlate appropriately with the reactive attitudes others
196
take towards them. Fischer and Ravizza stress that the correlation need not be complete:
it is perfectly reasonable for moral agents not to feel guilty in cases where others blame
them, since one can clearly be a moral agent—in the sense of being an appropriate target
helps slaves escape may rightly refuse to feel guilty about the negative judgment his
neighbors pass on him; the point is only that he must see the appropriateness of applying
those attitudes to himself. So moral agreement with one’s community is not necessary,
but being a moral agent does require one to at least recognize the significance of the
reactive attitudes that go along with violating the relevant norms. The authors thus picture
taking responsibility as taking part in a conversation, where all sides can competently use
the language of praise and blame even if they do not always agree on the cases in which
The final ingredient in taking responsibility is that the individual must come to
see himself as an agent and an apt target for reactive attitudes in an appropriate way on
the basis of evidence. Normally, this means that agents—usually as children—figure out
how their desires and actions impact the world, and are taught by their parents and other
members of the community that some actions appropriately draw particular types of
beliefs on the basis of evidence, but once again, the agent need not have any deep
appreciation for the normative grounds—he need only learn that certain norms apply, that
they are deployed in particular ways, and that he is himself subject to them. The point of
this condition is that the agent must take responsibility in ways that do not involve any
197
To be responsible for an action, then, agents must first undergo the entire process
of taking responsibility outlined above. But to make the condition historical, Fischer and
Ravizza insist that what agents take responsibility for are not their actions themselves at
the moment they occur, but the reasons-responsive mechanisms that issue in those
actions. Or, more precisely, “having taken responsibility for behavior that issues from a
kind of mechanism, it is almost as if the agent has some sort of ‘standing policy’ with
respect to that kind of mechanism. Thus, when the agent subsequently acts from a
mechanism of that kind, that mechanism is his own insofar as he has already taken
responsibility for acting form that kind of mechanism.” (Fischer and Ravizza 1998 216)
In particular, they mention two types of such mechanisms: our mechanism of ordinary
practical reasoning, and our nonreflective mechanisms. Typically, children learn not only
that they are apt targets of reactive attitudes when they deliberate about their actions, but
that sometimes they can also be blamed (or praised) for actions that issue out of habit.
This, of course, is supposed to explain how we can hold people responsible for the sorts
of pre-deliberative (or non-deliberative) actions that have been the topic of my discussion
above: since they recognize that those actions spring from their own agency and that they
can fairly be blamed for them, they have taken responsibility for the mechanisms that
issue in those actions and are thereby responsible for the actions.
This account helps to explain why manipulation rules out responsibility: in taking
responsibility for their ordinary reflective and nonreflective mechanisms, agents do not
also take responsibility for mechanisms that might later be implanted through
manipulation, although it is possible after manipulation of some sort occurs for an agent
to take responsibility for the actions that issue from this new mechanism. (This is why we
198
might hold the subjects of brainwashing responsible in some cases—Patty Hearst is one
prominent example.) As this point clearly shows, Fischer and Ravizza’s account of
responsibility is, in their words, a “subjectivist” one. “In order to be morally responsible,
a person must see himself as an agent who is an appropriate candidate for the reactive
attitudes.” (1998 229) Thus, a person can be responsible for an action only if she has
taken responsibility for the mechanism that produced it; if she has not taken
responsibility, on the other hand, she cannot be held responsible. To say that the account
is subjectivist does not, of course, mean that it is merely subjective. That is, taking
This point, of course, raises an immediate objection: that people can opt out of
being held responsible simply by refusing to take responsibility. But, as Fischer and
Ravizza respond, while this is true, it is not clear that opting out in this way is possible
action, an agent would have to not simply refuse to see herself as a fair target of reactive
attitudes in the case of that action; she would have to fail to see herself that way with
regard to the entire mechanism that produced the action, and this mechanism can stretch
back into her childhood. So to avoid being responsible for any particular action that
issues from one’s ordinary mechanisms, the agent would somehow have to either go back
in time and fail to take responsibility for the relevant mechanism in childhood, or she
would have to have a complete breakdown sufficient for loss of responsibility prior to the
action (this may be the strategy Hamlet was aiming at), but in such a way that she were
199
not responsible for the breakdown itself. Moreover, as Fischer and Ravizza contend, it is
not obvious that agents can voluntarily refuse to take responsibility since, on their
account, doing so involves not making a conscious decision, but something more like
acquiring a cluster of beliefs, mostly in non-deliberative ways. And it is not easy to avoid
acquiring beliefs, such as the belief that one can cause events in the world or that one is a
player in a particular kind of game. And finally, even if one can voluntarily choose to
avoid taking responsibility, the consequences would be dire. Failing to recognize oneself
as the source of events in the world essentially robs one of any control over their actions;
and failing to see oneself as an apt target of reflective attitude excludes one from the vast
majority of interactions that make human life worthwhile—friendship and love, for
example, are difficult to participate in for someone incapable of recognizing that another
While this account of taking responsibility has garnered a great deal of largely
positive attention, it is not clear that it succeeds on either of the two fronts that I am
phenomenon and providing an adequate account of ownership. Let’s take up the first
point. While history is introduced primarily to deal with various manipulation cases,
critics immediately set out to work out numerous ever-more fantastic scenarios in which
the process of taking responsibility is itself manipulated, but in such a way that the
possible, then the historical condition does not succeed in providing an account that can
withstand manipulation cases and—unless appropriate ways of fixing the problem can be
200
found—the motivation for giving a historical account of responsibility is seriously
undermined.
as follows. An agent first recognizes himself as the apt target of reactive attitudes on the
basis of particular behaviors. He thereby adopts something like a standing policy with
regard to the mechanism underlying those behaviors, and this makes him responsible for
any future behavior issuing from the same mechanism. But this is puzzling. If an agent
adopts his standing policy on the basis of a finite set of behaviors, this is not intuitively
sufficient to make him responsible for just any future behaviors produced by the same
mechanism, especially since the agent need not (and cannot) know all the details of the
mechanism when he takes responsibility for it.58 But no one can predict every possible
upshot of a mechanism, especially if one does not know the details of the mechanism.
To develop this point, we might keep in mind that a good deal of “situationist”
psychology has strongly suggested that, often, environmental factors provide a far better
mechanisms) could. And even without the strong conclusions often derived from the
research, it is fairly clear that our actions are at least strongly influenced by the context in
which they take place—if they were not, after all, they could not be reasons-responsive at
all. But if so, one might ask how an agent who has taken responsibility for a mechanism
on the basis of actions in a limited range of contexts could take responsibility for what
that mechanism might produce in an entirely new context. Many college students—to
58
As Fischer and Ravizza concede, “in taking responsibility for acting from a kind of mechanism, one
takes responsibility for acting from the mechanism in its full reality. To employ a metaphor, when one
takes responsibility for acting from a kind of mechanism, it is as if one takes responsibility for the entire
iceberg in virtue of seeing the tip of the iceberg.” (1998 216-217)
201
take just one example—discover many new things about themselves as they start college;
religious orientation, and ethnicity might not know how they will behave when
surrounded by a more diverse crowd; or, for that matter, how they might behave in the
absence of parental authority. And the case obviously does not apply exclusively to
college students: anyone thrust into a new and unfamiliar context might act in ways that
Now we can widen the point further: encountering new situations is a standard
fact of life. Whether one moves to a new country, finds a new job, begins a new
to deal with the situation will require adjusting. And, if we were to go even further,
though this is not necessary to the argument, virtually any situation in which we find
ourselves is, in some way, new. Of course we do not need to acquire new (or modify old)
mechanisms to deal with every situation, just as we do not need to acquire new habits to
cope with every new solicitation—most situations are similar enough to previous ones
that we can seamlessly move forward with our lives. But if sufficiently new contexts can
require modifications to the existing mechanisms, given our ignorance of how our
mechanisms work (or might work in new contexts) it is unclear that a process of taking
responsibility in childhood—or at any time—can make one responsible for any and all
future actions. Rather, it seems like taking responsibility will have to be an ongoing
process, not one that occurs before any action for which we can be held responsible.
202
So much for history. What about ownership? We can note from the outset that
Fischer and Ravizza center their account on socialization. Kane already points out a key
problem: one can be socialized in ways that are akin to brainwashing—he uses Brave
New World as his fictional example—so that one fulfills all the conditions for taking
socialization. (Kane 2000) Although Fischer suggests that we can get around the
problem, because there are ways (though perhaps not clear-cut ones) to distinguish
background. Since the entire account depends on a kind of social training, “it is by no
means clear whether there is room in such a picture for a meaningful distinction between
account] does not entail that the child is learning to act reflectively. He is simply being
assisted to internalize admirable values.” (Zimmerman 2002 223) So it looks like the
norms, and this does not seem to give us enough for an account of ownership.
Fischer and Ravizza’s account seems to work, roughly, like this: if I have taken
might—because they disagree with a particular social norm—refuse to accept the praise
or blame as justified in a given case. But the point is that they lack grounds for complaint
since they see themselves as fair targets, and at least understand that it is generally fair to
hold them responsible for their actions. Thus the account seems to settle a problem: when
is it fair to take certain reactive attitudes toward individuals? And their solution is this: it
203
is fair when the individuals can recognize that it is fair. But this isn’t the problem of
moral responsibility at all. The problem is figuring out when I am responsible, not when I
can be held responsible without my putting up argument. And this seems to require that
ownership and socialization in the semi-compatibilist account. The two are not mutually
exclusive, of course. But internalization alone does not constitute ownership. To bring
out the point more clearly, we can return to Heidegger’s description of Da-sein’s
sein is always mine, and Heidegger accordingly designates Da-sein’s being as existence,
essentially first-personal—Da-sein differs from all other entities, which are only third-
personally accessible. And Da-sein’s mineness means that, unlike the actuality that can
lays out all these features—along with the themes that he will pursue throughout Division
I and much of Division II of Being and Time immediately after his introduction of
Jemeinigkeit:
204
yet gained itself because it is essentially possible as authentic, that is, it belongs to
itself. (42-43)
There is a good deal to unpack here. Let me merely index some of the key features to be
discussed later: First, Heidegger clearly connects the mineness of Da-sein with its
later), Da-sein can win (or find) or lose itself, which means that mineness alone—in
seemingly paradoxical fashion—does not guarantee actually grasping myself, but instead
creates the possibility for not grasping myself. Finally, this relation between mineness
and authenticity involves a choice: because Da-sein is always mine, its possibility is
characterized by a decision (“it has always already decided”) or choice concerning the
Here I want to address the key theme of Da-sein’s losing itself, which will help
illustrate the flaw in Fischer and Ravizza’s view of responsibility. We can begin by
asking a question immediately implied by the above: if Da-sein is always mine, and this
mineness distinguishes Da-sein from other kinds of entities, what of the being of other
people, other Da-seins? If there is an asymmetrical relation between my own being and
the being of other entities in the world, does that mean that—at least from the perspective
of my Da-sein—other Da-seins are essentially “mere things” for me, disclosed primarily
within a referential context of use? The answer has to be no: if Da-sein is characterized
by mineness, and this distinguishes it from all other entities,59 this will be true of every
Da-sein and not merely my own. But then what is needed is an explanation of how—
given that I do not “see” the Da-sein of others as mine—I could distinguish them from
59
I am leaving out here the difficult case of animals in Heidegger’s philosophy, which places them in a sort
of intermediate category between Da-sein and mere things, since animals on the one hand interact with
other entities and use them, but nevertheless lack a world.
205
mere things. This account is important, since without it, it would seem as if other Da-
seins exist, in contrast to mere things, and yet each Da-sein would systematically see
Heidegger’s account of our circumspect dealing with things. Every referential structure—
every in-order-to that governs the use of tools—has its ultimate reference or in-order-to
in Da-sein. But obviously this ultimate reference is not only one’s own Da-sein. When I
grade papers, I use paper, pen, and ink, a desk and a lamp, a chair and a reference book,
and I use all of these in order to provide a grade for my student. In reading the paper,
underlining strange word formations, adding comments and occasional question marks, I
am not explicitly thinking about the student—I am focused on the content of the paper—
but the student is the one for whom I do all of this, and that reference governs the care
with which I read and comment and the content on my comments. I can perform the same
activity for any of my students; I can even perform it for myself, when I revise a paper
for publication. Similarly, a carpenter may build a chair for a client, or he may build it for
himself. The activity will be the same, and so will the constitutive references governing
it, though of course the particular identity of the individual for whom the activity is
performed might change some details (I might, for example, make my comments to
myself more cryptic than those I write for my students). Thus, all tool-using activity—all
our agency, really—is ultimately performed for the sake of Da-sein. And it is performed
not simply for my Da-sein—though it can be—but for any Da-sein. The point, in other
of the activity, and which is interchangeable and indefinite. And of course it has to be so:
206
otherwise every activity I perform for the sake of one individual would be radically
different from an activity performed for another; but this is, again, not the case: my
commenting on my paper and my commenting on a student’s paper are the same kind of
Thus, not only does an indefinite Da-sein govern our activity as the recipient of its
product, but the activity itself operates on the basis of publicly accessible norms. Not
only do I use the pen and chair in order to return the paper to a Da-sein, but I use the pen
and paper in a way prescribed by Da-sein. These two ways in which Da-sein’s
possibilities are social possibilities are, clearly, connected. On the one hand, Da-sein
performs tasks for the sake of other Da-seins. Again, even if it performs the task for
itself, it takes itself as one Da-sein among others. Since the Da-seins for whom the tasks
are performed are interchangeable, the tasks themselves are publically accessible: I can
brush my teeth and you can brush your teeth, and we will be performing the same
activity; or, I can buy an ice cream for myself or for my friend, but I will be performing
the same task. And since the tasks are publicly accessible, this means that the tools used
in them must also be publicly accessible. Thus, other Da-seins are already disclosed
within our use of tools as those for whom these tools are used: by walking down the
street, I use the sidewalk as a tool. In using the sidewalk as a tool, what is disclosed to me
is the nature of the sidewalk as something for the use of Da-sein as such—not my own
Da-sein, but Da-sein in general. Heidegger refers to this as the representability of our
being in the world with others. “In the everydayness of taking care of things, constant use
of such representability is made in many ways. Any going to…, any fetching of…, is
representable in the scope of the ‘surrounding world’ initially taken care of.” (239) Since
207
both what we do and what we do it with are essentially public, anyone who does these
We can see the significance of this if we recall that Da-sein first finds itself within
its world. “This nearest and elemental way of Da-sein of being encountered in the world
goes so far that even one’s own Da-sein initially becomes ‘discoverable’ by looking away
from its ‘experiences’ and the ‘center of its actions’ or by not yet ‘seeing’ them all. Da-
sein initially finds ‘itself’ in what it does, needs, expects, has charge of, in the things at
hand which it initially takes care of in the surrounding world.” (119) As we have already
seen, Da-sein is always thrown into a world, and it must find itself—if it is to do so—
from out of that world. In Heidegger’s account of Da-sein’s sociality, or its essential
being-with, the world in which Da-sein finds itself is already constituted by other Da-
seins. Since the other Da-seins whose norms govern the world in which Da-sein initially
finds itself are representable (this is, again, what makes the norms public, or capable of
structuring the world of any Da-sein), Da-sein initially finds itself defined by a
does not guarantee that Da-sein has found itself in an authentic way. Instead, Heidegger
muses, “what if the fact that Da-sein is so constituted that it is in each case mine, were the
reason for the fact that Da-sein is, initially and for the most part, not itself?” (115-116)
The question is rhetorical, as Heidegger indicates on the same page. And, as we have
60
Of course the term Heidegger uses is “das Man,” which has no workable noun equivalent in English.
There are three options here: (1) One can simply write Man, which means the term cannot function as part
of an English sentence. (2) One can use “one,” as in “one can use…” (3) One can use “they,” as in “they
talk a lot, don’t they” (Pulp Fiction). I will stick to “they,” because I find it easiest to navigate
grammatically. Occasionally, however, I will also use “one,” and the context should make it clear that das
Man is intended.
208
already seen, Da-sein’s being always mine is precisely what allows it to win or lose itself.
To see how this works, we need only consider the features already introduced: in its
always-mineness, Da-sein’s being matters to it. That is to say, Da-sein always projects
and pushes ahead into its possibilities, and these possibilities are ones that essentially
Da-sein takes its projected possibilities as its own. But the possibilities with which it
initially finds itself saddled are ones understood in terms of its world and its taking care
of that world. “‘One is’ what one does.” (239) So the very feature of Da-sein that allows
it to win itself, initially always leads it astray into taking the public possibilities in which
Thus, Heidegger notes, “‘the others’ does not mean everybody else but me—those
from whom the I distinguishes itself. They are, rather, those from whom one mostly does
not distinguish oneself, those among whom one is, too.” (118) Da-sein’s self, in the
everydayness in which it is initially and for the most part, “is the they self which we
distinguish from the authentic self, the self which has explicitly grasped itself.” (129) So
in finding itself thrown into possibilities prescribed by the they, Da-sein does what one
does, understands itself as one understands oneself, and is as one is. On the one hand,
“the they itself, for the sake of which Da-sein is every day, articulates the referential
meaningful in the way they see it as meaningful so that “the everyday possibilities of
being of Da-sein are at the disposal of the whims of the others.” (126) Da-sein’s
possibilities—it’s for-the-sake-of-which—are given to it. But on the other hand, they are
not given by anyone in particular, because “the others, as distinguishable and explicit,
209
disappear more and more. In this inconspicuousness and unascertainability, the they
unfolds its true dictatorship.” (126) Da-sein does not, in its everyday mode of being,
notice that its possibilities are set out by others—the others withdraw in much the same
way that tools withdraw in absorbed coping, so that Da-sein takes the self handed over to
it by the they as its own. It does not see itself as something separate from others, and it
does not see the norms, values, and self-understanding it has been given as something
external or foreign to it; it accepts it at face value as its own, and this is the sense in
So what, exactly, is the result of this becoming a they self? The “dictatorship” of
the they “prescribes what can and may be ventured,” and thus gives rise to “the leveling
down of all possibilities of being.” (127) In other words—and this is the problem—it
instead of unfulfillable ways to be. Thus, it tends to lead Da-sein to see itself not as
existing, in the technical sense, but as present-at-hand, as defined not by its possibilities,
but by its actual properties. Of course Da-sein cannot literally become a present-at-hand
entity, and it cannot literally trade in its possibilities for objective properties. In seeing
continues to exist as Da-sein; the point is only that, as a they self, it misunderstands itself.
Heidegger brings out the extent of the misunderstanding in his discussion of Da-sein’s
falling prey.
Falling prey describes the way in which the they self distorts Da-sein’s disclosure
describes three aspects of this phenomenon: idle talk, curiosity, and ambiguity. Idle talk
210
is a modification of discourse, which emphasizes communication over disclosing. Instead
of bringing what is talked about to light in a genuine way, idle talk discusses it in
“average” terms, terms that are understandable to everyone, giving the impression that
entirely for the sake of novelty, so that Da-sein does not “dwell” within any one
possibility, but immediately abandons it to seek another. Just as in idle talk nothing is
really disclosed but only the illusion of disclosure is given, so in curiosity possibilities are
leveled down, so that instead of pressing forth into something genuinely new, Da-sein
pursues trends and guesses what the future will bring, so that anything that happens is
In all these phenomena, Heidegger notes, Da-sein becomes absorbed in the world
and “lost in the publicness of the they. As an authentic potentiality for being a self, Da-
sein has initially always already fallen away from itself and fallen prey to the ‘world’”.
(175) So Da-sein, as its finds itself initially in the they, is already lost. But it is important
to note that it hasn’t simply gotten lost; it has lost itself, which it can do because it has the
character of being always mine. That is, in attempting to grasp its mineness, Da-sein
locates itself in the world; but by looking at the world, Da-sein is locating itself in the
wrong place. To put it another way, falling prey is not simply something that happens to
Da-sein; it is something that Da-sein does, and it does this because fallenness appeals
directly to its concern with its own being. In seeking understanding, for example, Da-sein
grasps the shallowness of idle talk. In seeking its own possibilities, it finds the constant
211
novelty of possibilities presented to it by the they. The public world provides Da-sein
with a way—or rather innumerable ways—to satisfy its search for itself. Thus, Da-sein is
“tempted” by the world and “tranquilized” into constantly feeling that it is gaining
something important. But at the same time, it is “alienated” from itself and “entangles”
itself so that it cannot see any possibilities beyond those offered by the they.
The they already lays out what Da-sein cares about, so that “the public way in
which things have been interpreted has already decided upon even the possibilities of
being attuned, that is, about the basic way in which Da-sein lets itself be affected by the
world” (169-170), so that “we enjoy ourselves and have fun the way they enjoy
themselves. We read, see, and judge literature and art the way they see and judge. But we
also withdraw from the ‘great mass’ the way they withdraw, we find ‘shocking’ what they
find shocking.” (126-127) Some interpreters argue that Heidegger’s notion of authenticity
is simply identified with the first-person perspective as opposed to the second and third-
person perspective we take on others. (Carman 2006, 2005) But this cannot be right: if
the they modifies both our understanding and our attunement, it is clear that the they can
enter into and structure our first-person perspective on ourselves; that is the point of
referring to the fallen self as a they self. It is a self, with motivations, reasons for acting,
Consider a simple event: I am eating in a restaurant and, after the main course, it
occurs to me that I want desert. It may well be true that I want desert only because that is
what one eats at the end of a meal; but that does not change the fact that I want it. If I
reason, and this may well be the reason on which I act. And what is interesting on
212
Heidegger’s account is that the reason is mine. But, at the same time, it is not my own.
Consider another example: I am walking on the sidewalk and not in the middle of the
road. Why? To avoid the cars. That is a reason, a good one, and—in accordance with the
McDowellian analysis given above—it may well be the reason on which I act. But at the
same time I am walking on the sidewalk because that is what one does. This is not a
reason; it provides no rational justification (though, of course, “this is what one does” can
provide justifications and reasons for actions in some situations). But it is nevertheless an
explanation of what I do. That I have a reason—“to get away from the cars”—does not
make that reason my own; it is, after all, the reason one gives; it is an obvious
seems obvious; so obvious that certainly one does not need to even have it explained. The
explanation in its obviousness does not appear as something given to me. “The they is
everywhere, but in such a way that it has always already stolen away when Da-sein
presses for a decision. However, because the they presents every judgment and decision
as its own, it takes the responsibility of Da-sein away from it.” (127) And here we get to
the heart of the problem: Da-sein’s responsibility is “taken away” insofar as it exists as a
they self. If my actions, along with all the reasons and motives prescribed for them, are
already given to me by the they, by everyone and no one, then I am no more responsible
If this account of Da-sein’s falling prey to the world according to possibilities laid
out by the they is right, we can now crystallize a critique of all the approaches discussed
213
entirely in a process of socialization, of internalizing the values and attitudes of others,
explicitly lays out a notion of taking responsibility that involves a giving away of
responsibility. That individual agents may be held responsible by others, and that they
even hold themselves responsible, does not show that they are responsible; it could show
only that they are participants in a discourse that misunderstands responsibility. But
attributionism fares no better. The suggestion, cited above, that “in a sense, values cannot
fail to be those of the agent who acts on them,” simply refers us to the distinction
between mineness and ownership. Yes, the values on which I act as a they self are mine;
but they are not values I own. Simply laying out a framework on which our rationality—
our will—is embodied in our actions and attitudes allows us to lay out the possibility of
control, but control of the sort that can support agency, never mind responsibility, will
need ownership.
But volitionism does not help either; as I argued in the last chapter, deliberation will
not give us responsibility, because we would need to be responsible for the grounds of
our deliberation as well. If the they already makes our decisions by handing us our values
and motives, and if this is precisely how responsibility gets taken away, deliberation can
only contribute to this process. Steven Crowell brings out this claim in his reading of
Heidegger:
deliberation takes place (as did the action from which it arose) within the
constitutive rules of the ‘world’ in which I remain engaged. That is, I deliberate as
that which I understand myself to be, in terms of my ‘practical identity’… Thus,
while only an individual can deliberate, I do not deliberate as my ownmost self.
Rather, the reasons I adduce and the evidence that I find salient will normally be
those typical of the current cultural, historical composition of the One… This
does not mean that my reasoning is nothing but the rationalization of specific
cultural conditions, but it does mean that the practice of deliberation, like all
practices, is grounded ontologically in what is public, typical, and normative in a
given community. That deliberation is explicitly oriented toward ‘reasons for’
214
does not, ontologically, get us any further than the analysis of everyday coping.61
(2007a 53)
If my identity is taken over from the they, and if my deliberation necessarily takes place
than my unreflective agency. Of course deliberation can contribute a great deal to make
our actions more effective, or in getting them to better conform to social and moral
norms—but none of this explains why deliberation would give us either ownership of
responsibility.
But Fischer and Ravizza’s account does add something. As I’ve already argued,
ownership is precisely the condition we need for responsibility. I have only argued that
their own view of ownership is insufficient. But it suggests two important points. First,
helps to shift the discourse concerning responsibility from the third-person perspective to
taking responsibility, which involves coming to own the mechanisms on which I act.
responsibility will require distinguishing the temporality of action from the temporality of
morally responsible for his behavior, that a process of taking responsibility… has taken
place at some point prior to the behavior.” (1998 242-243) Where I think they go wrong
is in the notion of priority involved. On their view, taking responsibility must be prior to
action in a historical sense—a sense I earlier characterized as temporally shallow. That is,
there is an event of taking responsibility (to be sure, it is a drawn out and complex event)
61
The reference to the Dreyfusian term “coping” here strongly suggests that Crowell means to extend
Dreyfus’s view of absorbed coping not only to “mindless” activity, but also to deliberation itself.
215
that occurs at a particular time that is in turn earlier than the event of the action taking
place. And this account, I have suggested, does not succeed precisely because it is
moment as the action, since every action takes place in new circumstances and no one
can properly take responsibility for the way their mechanisms will act in new,
unanticipated circumstances.62
In fact Heidegger’s attempt to explain how Da-sein can be authentic given its
62
This is the extreme version of the criticism I gave above, where I conceded that not every action is new.
But, first of all, enough actions are new that an earlier act of taking responsibility cannot cover them all.
Second, especially in the case of unreflective actions where the agent simply responds to solicitations, it is
always open to the agent to deny responsibility on the grounds that the solicitation in the present case was
just different enough from past ones to throw off his nondeliberative mechanism. Consider here Sher’s
example of Father Poteet, who, though a competent driver, mistakenly believes he can weave seamlessly
into traffic and ends up causing a massive accident. Just what is supposed to block the thought that Father
Poteet saw a solicitation because the case was similar to previous ones, but that in fact the situation was
slightly different from past ones, so that his normally reliable driving mechanism—the one he has taken
responsibility for—failed to operate correctly? In fact, it seems like this is exactly what happened. But, had
Father Poteet been aware that his mechanism could misfire in situations with differences imperceptible to
him, he would perhaps not have taken responsibility for it as a nondeliberative mechanism, but would
instead have been a less impulsive, defensive driver.
216
6
A. Discovering Ownership
Strawson’s Basic Argument: that responsibility is impossible for a being that is not causa
sui. This problem is already implicit in the earliest view of responsibility, in Aristotle’s
suggestion that we can get out of it by postulating a joint responsibility: perhaps we are
not entirely self-created, but we can create ourselves just enough to make moral
responsibility possible. This requires that we have the ability to produce something that is
our own, and not simply given over to us by nature, by society, or whatever other external
short: our deliberation itself, for the most part, takes place against a background of
values, ways of thinking, and attitudes that are not our own. Our thrownness into the
world and our being-with the they prevents us initially from owning ourselves.
Deliberation, no matter how explicit, cannot break free of our thrownness, because we are
thrown as deliberating beings. Attributionism thus cuts out the deliberation and appeals
directly to the idea of a self as defined by the coherence of its values and judgments. If a
self is nothing more than such a coherence, and its actions follow from that coherence,
then the self can be held responsible for those actions. But this does not help: if a self is
only a coherence, then it is not clear why the actions it produces are any different from
217
the “actions” that result from the functioning of any other coherent entity, like a rock or a
light bulb. Constitutivism, which will be a topic of this chapter, seemingly bypasses the
need for absolute self-creation, but it must still give an account of the basis on which we
might say that an entity is responsible: integrity and cohesion are not sufficient for
ownership, because they are phenomena that occur in all sorts of entities that are not self-
owned.
terms. One is responsible for an action if one has already taken responsibility for it, or
come to own the character (or background) that produces the action, before the action has
taken place. But if we take this “before” in terms of shallow temporality, we are no better
off. The problem with volitionism and attributionism was that they could not separate
what is one’s own from what is not, and thus give an account of ownership as the ground
subject to the same charge. Fischer and Ravizza, of course, set out to argue that taking
responsibility is consistent with causal determinism. But whether or not their argument
succeeds, its reliance on socialization in taking responsibility means that the process is
just as trapped in the they as any other. We are thrown into the possibilities laid out by
the they. Taking responsibility, in Fischer and Ravizza’s sense, only involves
responsibility as appropriate. But that does not make them appropriate unless our taking
responsibility can itself be our own. So the way out is to stop assuming that ownership
must be understood as a historical process, that is, a process in which I start (as a child,
218
Consider one of the most famous arguments in defense of ownership: John
Locke’s argument in The Second Treatise of Civil Government. (1980 18-30) Locke lays
out the problem thus: originally, the earth and its products belong to all of humanity in
common. How, then, can any individual rightfully come to own anything? Locke argues
that there must be a solution, since each of us has a right to life, and thus a right to eat;
and if I have a right to make something my own for the purpose of eating it, there must be
a way of turning a common right of property into an individual right. Famously, the
solution involves labor: since I own my body and the labor I perform with it, in laboring
to turn the fruits of the earth into food, I mix something of my own with something that is
owned in common. And through the mixing of what is my own, I make what I mix it with
my own. Now clearly the argument has problems, and it is not my aim here to defend it.
Let me just consider one problem: why would mixing something that is mine with
something that is not mine make it mine? If I purchase a box of chocolates with a group
of friends, the chocolates belong to all of us. They do not become mine alone simply by
virtue of my performing the labor of fighting off the others and shoving the entire
contents into my mouth! But Locke makes no such claim: I have no right to property that
labor or my body my own? It is not my own in the sense of property, since it is not
still remains my own in the sense in which it was my own to start with—it is always
mine.
219
So let me work out the key points. First, Locke does not ask how I can come to
create ownership. He is asking how I can transfer ownership, from something owned in
common to something owned singly (and, remember, if we ask where ownership comes
from in the first place, the answers is pretty mysterious: God). I do so by mixing what is
now owned in common with something that is always mine, that is, my labor (which, of
course, is always mind in the sense that it is non-transferable, but also in the sense that it
is not something I came to own at any point: as long as I have existed, it has always
already been my own). And the resulting single ownership is legitimated by a teleological
condition: my right to survive (which is also, in a sense, my own), for the sake of which I
can take something owned in common and, mixing it with what is mine, make it my own.
Taking this as a guide, I suggest the following features as constitutive of what is involved
in genuine ownership: (1) current ownership, (2) always mineness, and (3) a teleological
Heidegger along these lines. I find myself now owned by the they.63 The self owned by
the they is already always mine. As a self characterized by mineness, my self “is
essentially possible as authentic.” (43) Key to this view is the recognition that I do not
create myself wholly from nothing in order to become my own; rather, I take myself up
63
Technically, the self is not initially “owned” in a genuine sense by the they. The they, as noted, is
absolutely anonymous. So ownership by the they is not ownership strictly speaking, since it is ownership
by no one in particular. Yet it is also not non-ownership. As Heidegger notes, “the they-self is an
existentiell modification of the authentic self” (317), which suggests that it is something like a non-owning
type of ownership; perhaps in the way that someone may forget that they own something, so that they
remain the rightful user of the item but cannot make use of it.
220
well be translated as “self-ownership.” The authentic self is distinguished from the
inauthentic self, the self that is entangled in the world and the they. But Heidegger is
always explicit that in taking ownership of ourselves we do not somehow step out of the
world and the they—both are constitutive of Da-sein as care. This theme is one
(1) “It is only on the basis of an antecedent “transposition” that we can, after all,
come back to ourselves from the direction of things.” (Heidegger 1982 161)
(2) “Understanding can turn primarily on the disclosedness of the world, that is,
Da-sein can understand itself initially and for the most part in terms of the world.
Or else understanding throws itself primarily into the for-the-sake-of-which,
which means Da-sein exists as itself. Understanding is either authentic,
originating from its own self as such, or else inauthentic. The “in” does not mean
that Da-sein cuts itself off from itself and understands “only” the world. World
belongs to its being a self as being-in-the-world.” (146)
Obviously this is all schematic. The key is to understand how Da-sein is disclosed to
responsibility is revealed. But then, “only in responsibility does the self first reveal
itself—the self not in a general sense as knowledge of an ego in general but as in each
case mine.” (Heidegger 1982 137) In revealing the self as a responsible self, Da-sein can
take over its ground: it takes its thrownness into itself in light of its ownmost potentiality
of being, which is its anticipatory self-projection into itself existing as a whole. In other
words, Da-sein compares itself to itself as a whole—a point I will try to make sense of—
221
and thereby discloses itself as an owned, free entity. In the last chapter, we left Da-sein
an image “of Da-sein as fragmentary.” (233) Finding itself, for Da-sein, requires finding
though an insufficient one—to avoid the difficulties that threaten both compatibilism and
capacity. In developing the account I outlined earlier, Korsgaard has adopted a position
that has come to be called constitutivism. Just as Korsgaard’s account suggests a way out
of the free will dilemma, I believe constitutivism can give us the strongest solution to the
will attempt to explain why—properly carried out—it stands a chance of answering the
Basic Argument. For contrast, I will then outline Frankfurt’s position, which is both the
starting point and the major target of constitutivism. I will then lay out the basics of
Korsgaard’s approach and suggests that it does not succeed because it implicitly relies on
a constitutive aim that serves as a condition of possibility for the aim she proposes. In the
following section, I will then argue that the needed constitutive aim is Heidegger’s notion
binding. It functions like this: There are norms or aims constitutive of agency. Thus, in
222
order to be agents, we must be subject to those norms. But we cannot help but be agents;
therefore, some norms—those that are constitutive of agency or that can be derived from
worked out, constitutivism stands to provide the strongest foundation for a theory of
moral responsibility. The Basic Argument holds that the task of providing such a
foundation cannot be met without the possibility of agents’ being self-causing. But that is
norm. If the norms against which agents can properly be held responsible are, in fact,
norms constitutive of agency, then agents, simply by being agents, necessarily create
in light of those norms. It remains true that agents cannot be responsible for the norms
themselves, but this no longer undermines their responsibility: they are, as agents,
responsible for the sorts of agents they are in light of the norms due to which they are
agents in the first place. Agents are thus self-created in light of the very norms that make
them agents. Another way of putting the point is this: acting on constitutive norms makes
one’s action autonomous; we often fail to act autonomously, of course, but we still act in
64
For reasons of space, I will address only Korsgaard’s account, but another major constitutivist approach
is laid out by David Velleman, for which see especially Velleman (2000, 1992) and Chapter 3 of Velleman
(2009). Very roughly, he argues that human beings naturally seek understanding, and note that there is a
part of the universe—their own bodies—that they can control in such a way as to match their
understanding. From a different starting point, he argues that in acting intentionally, we must know why we
are acting. Both accounts suggest that, in order to act intentionally, we must guide our actions by our self-
understanding, so self-understanding is constitutive of action (or, perhaps, only of full-bloodied action—
Velleman’s view on this point has changed over time).
65
Though she spends little time on this point, Korsgaard says as much: “I think it is true that we could not
rightly be held responsible unless we created ourselves, but false that that makes the idea of responsibility
incoherent.” (2009 130) Velleman does not draw this connection; when he comments on responsibility, it is
only to make the traditional—and problematic—claim that even if what I do is not an “action” in the full
sense, because it is not guided by self-understanding, I can be held responsible for not exercising greater
self-control. (1992 465)
223
light of the norms that constitute autonomous action. Thus, we can be responsible for
and free when we act on first-order desires with which we identify. Working out the
notion of identification has been one of the key tasks of Frankfurt’s work since “Freedom
of the Will and the Concept of a Person.” Here I will attempt a construction of one of his
views. To say that a person identifies with a desire, for Frankfurt, is to say that acting on
it furthers something he cares about. What we care about depends on what we love. And
love is a volitional necessity: it places limits on what choices a person can make.
other constraints on our choices. The unwilling addict, again, can serve as an example to
make the point clear. The addict’s desire for his drug places constraints on him: he cannot
help wanting the drug, and perhaps he cannot help acting on that desire. But this desire is
not one he identifies with, in the sense that pursuing the drug does not further (but,
perhaps, harms) anything he loves. Thus, the desire is external to who he is; such desires
“are generated and sustained from outside the will itself.” (Frankfurt 2006 44)
Volitional necessities, on the other hand, are internal to the will. What makes
them so is that the agent is not only constrained to act in accordance with them, but he
loving them. If I do not care whether or not I will still want to do philosophy in a year,
then I do not really care about doing philosophy now. “Caring about something implies a
diachronic coherence, which integrates the self across time.” (Frankfurt 2006 19) This
224
means that what we care about determines who we are as persons; if I stop caring about
something, or if I betray what I care about, there is a sense in which I am no longer the
self that I was. In Frankfurt’s famous example, Agamemnon is torn by a love for his army
and a love for his daughter; in betraying one—killing his daughter—he violates his
diachronic unity, destroying himself. (Frankfurt 1999a) So the self is constituted by its
commitments: I am who I am because I care about the things that I care about, though
most of these are contingent; a different person might not care about them at all.
signals the end of personhood, is a common one. Considering the case of a bully who has
undergone a moral conversion, he points out that in extreme enough cases we might
ordinarily say that he has become a new man. (Frankfurt 2002 124-125) My volitional
necessities, then, determine who I am; if they change, I become a different person.
As the case of Agamemnon shows, however, things are not always simple: the
things we care about might conflict. And this sort of conflict, which Frankfurt calls
“ambiguity,” is different from the case of the unwilling addict. The unwilling addict faces
a compulsion from outside his will, so there is a truth about who he is. The ambiguous
person faces a conflict from within, and thus there is no such truth. The only way out of
resolved with regard to one side or the other, his will has a definite shape: he is clear on
what he cares about. When he is ambiguous, there is no truth about who he really is, “his
10) Becoming wholehearted thus involves giving one’s will a reality by placing oneself
firmly on one side or the other. Of course things are not always simple: one might solve
225
an apparent conflict, for example, by prioritizing the things one cares about. But one
necessities conflict directly and so the person cannot abandon either of them without
ceasing to be who he is. Even more complicated, however, is the question of how one
wholeheartedness requires satisfaction with one’s self, that is, with one’s volitional states.
And this is not accomplished through anything the agent does or decides; satisfaction
requires “no adoption of any cognitive, attitudinal, affective, or intentional stance. It does
not require the performance of a particular act; and it also does not require any deliberate
abstention. Satisfaction is a state of the entire psychic system—a state constituted just by
the absence of any tendency or inclination to alter its condition.” (Frankfurt 1992 13) To
be wholehearted, then, an agent needs to have no tendency to change the state of his will;
why he has no such tendency (perhaps he is simply tired, or has given up) doesn’t matter.
Frankfurt does add an important condition, however: satisfaction must involve the “entire
psychic system.” That is, the agent must not remain conflicted at all; and he must be
satisfied not on the basis of repression or self-deception, but on the basis of a self-
understanding. But, again, after that self-understanding is achieved, the agent either
Wholeheartedness, after all, is a matter of “really” being a particular person, and reality—
even the reality of our will—is something independent of our will. We can, of course, try
to resolve ourselves to wholeheartedness, but this does not guarantee that we will
226
wholeheartedness, which will fail to hold up when we are faced with a conflict. To be
be satisfied with who we are. But we lack volitional control over whether or not we are
satisfied. Frankfurt appeals here to Spinoza’s notion that the highest good is
esteem”), he writes:
There is something to be said for a bluntly literal construction of his Latin. That
would have Spinoza mean that the highest good we can hope for consists in
acquiescence to oneself—that is, in acquiescence to being the person that one is,
perhaps not enthusiastically but nonetheless with a willing acceptance of the
motives and dispositions by which one is moved in what one does… When we are
acquiescing to ourselves, or willing freely, there is no conflict within the structure
of our motivations and desires… The unity of our self has been restored.
(Frankfurt 2006 17-18)
One attains freedom and becomes responsible for what one does, then, when one is
wholehearted and does not act contrary to the demands of one’s volitional necessities. Let
me reiterate a key point: for Frankfurt, we do not constitute ourselves. Our selves are
constituted by our volitional necessities, by the things we care about. But we do not
control what things we care about. Nor do we control whether we are coherent persons at
all: this results only from acquiescing to oneself. Acquiescing to oneself, however, means
something interesting. It means finding oneself. But finding oneself in such a way that,
she rejects the premise that the self is something we find. Rather, we constitute ourselves
in acting, and in fact we must do so, with the result being that self-constitution is the
constitutive aim of agency. We have already seen much of this account, so I will be brief.
227
norms, efficacy and autonomy.66 To decide on an action, we must decide to succeed (for
example, one cannot decide to turn on a light but refuse to flip the switch), and we must
decide to make ourselves the cause of the action; that is, the action must be self-
determined. Korsgaard argues that, as rational agents with reflective distance from our
desires, we are under the necessity of choosing whether or not to act on them. Agency is
inescapable for us: “It is our plight: the simple inexorable fact of the human condition.”
(Korsgaard 2009 2) But, as Korsgaard tells us again and again, acting necessarily
involves an agent: there is a difference between an event being merely caused by a desire,
and its being caused by an agent. The former is not an action at all. As the
will non-universally, since then there is no difference between an action’s being caused
commit ourselves to a universal principle, i.e., a principle that extends beyond the
situation at hand. And in committing ourselves to such a principle we identify with it, that
is, we choose it as constituting our will. Thus, Korsgaard can argue that Frankfurt’s
account has things backwards, at least insofar as it has autonomous actions being ones
that arise out of a self that the agent has discovered as his own. “The intimate connection
between person and action does not rest in the fact that action is caused by the most
essential part of the person, but rather in the fact that the most essential part of the person
66
She identifies these with Kant’s hypothetical imperative and categorical imperative, respectively.
(Korsgaard 2008b 82-83) I will not take up here the question of whether her interpretation of Kant has
much to do with Kant or, for that matter, whether there is in Kant anything like “the Hypothetical
Imperative.”
228
particular action, we must thereby commit ourselves to having a particular kind of will, or
only counts as an action if it succeeds in constituting the agent. But then it seems we lose
any notion of normativity. Normativity, per general agreement, involves the possibility of
getting things wrong: an unbreakable standard isn’t a norm at all. But if we fail in our
constitutive aim, then it seems we have not acted at all, so violating the norm appears
impossible. (Lavin 2004) Korsgaard’s reply relies on a bit of Aristotelianism: a good harp
player and a bad harp player are not performing different activities; they are performing
the same activity, but only the former is performing it excellently. Similarly, Korsgaard
relies on an analogy that recurs throughout her work: to build a house, one must follow
certain standards. “A good house is a house that has the features that enable it to serve as
a habitable shelter—the corners are properly sealed, the roof is waterproof and tight, the
rooms are tall enough to stand up in.” (Korsgaard 2008b 112) These are internal
standards constitutive of something’s being a house. Something that deviates too far from
the internal standards is not just a bad house; it isn’t a house at all. So “even the most
venal and shoddy builder must try to build a good house, for the simple reason that there
is no other way to try to build a house.” (2008b 112-113) An obvious objection is that of
course someone could try to build a bad house by saving money on everything, using the
worst materials and the cheapest paid labor, and so on, so that the result has a leaky roof,
walls that can barely survive in high wind, etc. But Korsgaard sensibly points out that
simulation of a house that is good enough to fool someone into buying it. Deviating too
229
far from the standards constitutive of house-building involves participating in a different
activity. Similarly, a bad action—one that fails to be autonomous—does not on that count
cease to be an action. “Obviously, it doesn’t follow that every action is a good action. It
does, however, follow that performing bad actions is not a different activity from
performing good ones. It is the same activity, badly done.” (2008b 113)
So just how is defective action possible? Korsgaard suggests that agents can, in
fact, simply follow their desires. What they cannot do is shrug off the norms constitutive
of agency. Through a reading of Plato’s Republic, Korsgaard argues that it is possible for
agents to act on principles that fail to effectively constitute them in the following sense:
principle of following whatever desire he happens to have. All of these serve to unify, or
constitute, the agent under a single principle. But the principle, if it succeeds in creating
stability in the agent, does so only contingently. The clearest example is that of choosing
to act on whatever desire one has at the moment. If my desires keep changing, it will be
impossible for me to get anything done, since each new desire will distract me from
whatever I was doing on the basis of the previous one. So if I do manage to get anything
done, it will be the result of a lucky accident, because I will be leaving it entirely up to
chance whether or not new desires distract me from what I am doing. And action on such
account to Kantian universalizability—Korsgaard notes that “it is only when you ask
whether your maxim can be a universal law that you exercise the self-conscious causality,
the autonomy, that yields an action that can be attributed to you as a whole person.”
230
(Korsgaard 2008b 124) So a defective action is one that fails to be autonomous, and thus
All actions, including defective ones, are attributable to us, however; otherwise
they would not be actions. “An action is yours when it is chosen in accordance with your
constitution. Your constitution is what gives you the kind of volitional unity you need to
be the author of your actions.” (2008b 125) What makes an action mine, what establishes
ownership, is my constitution. But this constitution arises in the action itself. This, of
course, is why Korsgaard can argue that if an action is too defective, deviates too far from
and so there is no one acting. But a defective action that is still an action does constitute
me as a unified self, though it does so poorly, and fails to fully unify me because it fails
to guarantee diachronic unity. But who is it that fails to be fully unified? In order for me
terms—over and above the self constituted in the defective willing. Otherwise, whether I
will autonomously or not would itself be an accident. And this would return us to
autonomy, which is itself entirely out of our control. Here we are back to the problem
of willing seems to already presuppose an underlying will on the basis of which self-
willing in order for both of these to be my willings, and in order for the latter to itself be
231
The problem is similar to another one: if the self is only constituted in its willings,
this seems to imply that it does not exist prior to willing, and we must then ask who is
undertaking the willings in the first place. Korsgaard argues that we become selves by
choosing in light of—and thus endorsing—principles that make up our specific practical
identities. In so doing, we make those identities our own. It might thus seem as if we must
already have an identity in order to endorse an identity, since we must have a standpoint
in light of which some reasons are salient. But Korsgaard argues that this objection rests
on a misunderstanding, since “it assumes that the endorsement of our identities, our self-
constitution, is a state rather than an activity.” (2009 43) Korsgaard compares this to the
following its principles, which are its instincts. No one asks how a giraffe can constitute
itself if it must already exist prior to following its instincts. And agential self-constitution
works the same way: it is an activity, or process, that is ongoing throughout the course of
an individual’s life. This may be right, but Korsgaard’s account doesn’t explain how it is
possible. To see this, we can look once again at the problem of pre-deliberative agency.
fact, and is willing to accept that non-deliberative activity can still count as action, and
not simply a reversion to animality. It can still involve principles, albeit not explicit ones.
“Acting on a rational principle need not involve any step-by-step process of reasoning,
for when a principle is deeply internalized we may simply recognize the case as one
falling under the principle.” (Korsgaard 2009 107) But this seems to make non-
232
the absence of tracing—is impossible. This means that acting on anything other than a
self-chosen principle is impossible, and that already seems highly suspect. And this
further raises the question of how principles dependent on self-consciousness can become
“internalized” in the first place: once a principle is internalized in this sense, self-
consciousness is absent from it. And thus I am not involved in applying the principle to
particular cases. (Crowell 2007b) What Korsgaard cannot account for is complete self-
creation, which is precisely what she is aiming to do. But we already find ourselves with
afford actions, and yet which we do not self-consciously choose; of which we are not, in
fact, conscious. This should be clear from the prior discussion of deliberation: what we
consider in deliberating is not up to us; it springs from who we already are. And even
when we do deliberate, “we need a way to distinguish deliberation directed by the agent
from reasoning processes in the agent that mimic such deliberation but are not directed or
endorsed by the agent.” (Bratman 2001 317) This, of course, is what the constitutive
account is trying to do, but since our deliberative mechanisms spring from our prior
would only account for ownership of the relevant deliberative processes if it could do so
retroactively. There is no hope of fully identifying the self that acts with the self that
then, we must already have a way of retrieving ourselves, or finding ourselves in the
possibilities we have been thrown into. We need a constitutive principle that allows for
67
Again, though I cannot go into it in detail, I think there is an argument to be made for a similar response
to Velleman. Unlike Korsgaard, he does not think we can constitute our selves. The self is only a reflexive
233
I concluding, I want to draw attention to several points. First, despite Arpaly’s
claim to a “whole self” view, attributionism has no monopoly on that notion. Frankfurt’s
wholeheartedness, and his account of volitional necessities are precisely meant to delimit
the boundaries of the self. Korsgaard is also clearly after a notion of wholeness; for her,
central to all accounts, which hold it as a key component in freedom or, at least,
constitutive aim that underlies and makes possible the agential aims of Korsgaard’s
account. Although Korsgaard lays claim to an account of the constitutive aim of agency, I
have been suggesting that her account falls short of giving us agency as a whole. It gives
us only norms for actions, or for choosing actions. What I will now look for is an aim that
constitutes agency as a whole, which will involve finding oneself, thus moving (in a
sense) closer to Frankfurt’s account. I will argue that this aim is anticipatory resoluteness.
As noted, we left Da-sein at the end of the last chapter in a fragmentary state,
scattered among innerworldly beings, entangled in the world, and fully in the thrall of the
they as a they self. Removing all of these obstacles requires finding a way to individuate
Da-sein, that is, to find a way to free it from the they and from innerworldly beings.
perspective. (Velleman 2002) But Velleman does think self-understanding must constitute agency.
However, since agency can also constitute self-understanding—since we do act in ways we do not (yet)
understand—his aim presupposes that agency and understanding have already been brought together. And
this is what Heideggerian authenticity provides.
234
Heidegger lays out this possibility in what he calls the fundamental mood of Angst.
Unlike fear, which is always fear of something in the world, Angst is not about anything
in particular. What it is about is not something in the world, but about “being-in-the-
world as such.” (186) Like every mood, Angst discloses, but what it discloses is the world
without significance. Since Angst discloses the world, it still discloses it as a referential
totality, but in such a way that “innerworldly beings in themselves are so completely
unimportant that, on the basis of this insignificance of what is innerworldly, the world is
all that obtrudes in its worldliness.” (187) The world obtrudes, or is experienced as a
burden, because in Angst Da-sein doesn’t know what to do with it: it is faced with a
familiar referential framework, but one that lacks any solicitations. It presents no reason
to do or want anything. In opposition to the tranquilizing falling prey, which draws Da-
sein in through the semblance of complete understanding and perpetual seeking after
possibilities, Angst discloses a world in which Da-sein is not at home, an uncanny world.
What makes Da-sein at home in the world is its existence, it’s understanding of itself as
its being-in-the-world. Uncanniness is thus the term for Da-sein’s recognition that it’s
“fit” with the world, it’s being at home in it, is dependent on its projection of
possibilities.
itself apart from its factical involvements with entities and their usual importance. By
thus separating Da-sein from the significances bestowed on the world by the they, it
projects itself essentially upon possibilities. Thus along with that for which it is anxious,
235
individuation of its own accord.” (187-188) In other words, since in Angst Da-sein does
not project itself onto concrete possibilities, and in fact cannot so project itself, what is
the they and without being entangled in them but, of course, also (and by virtue of)
without being able to press into those possibilities. To see how this works, we can take up
Blattner’s attempt to differentiate between thin and thick senses of existence. In the thin
sense, Da-sein is concerned about its own being; in the thick sense, it presses forward
into particular factical possibilities, thus filling out that being. (Blattner 1994, 2006) In
Angst, Da-sein is still concerned about its being, and so is still seeking to press forward
into possibilities, but it cannot do so because all possibilities have been stripped of
significance.
This means that in Angst, Da-sein discovers its “true self,” but in an empty sense:
its true self is just being-possible, or understandingly projecting itself upon possibilities.
as, which defines who we are. Our self-understanding—our being anything at all in
particular—is what is stripped away, leaving only the bare structure. Angst thus “reveals
in Da-sein its being toward its ownmost potentiality of being, that is, being free for the
freedom of choosing and grasping itself. Angst brings Da-sein before its being free for…
(propensio in), the authenticity of its being as possibility which it always already is.”
(188) Since Da-sein is disclosed as possibility, but not as any concrete possibility, it
recognizes itself as free to choose itself. Of course being free to choose, or grasp oneself
also opens the possibility of losing oneself, so Angst discloses the possibility of
authenticity and inauthenticity. But both possibilities are now disclosed as possible on the
236
ground of choice. Rather than having to take the world as it is given, Da-sein sees its
freedom to project its own possibilities. This does not give Da-sein any absolute
freedom—it is still always in a world. But it serves to individualize it, and to disclose
itself as possibility, though without any content. This means that Angst by itself discloses
Recognizing one’s freedom is, we might say, a preliminary to using that freedom.
Authenticity enters the picture when Angst is expressed in discourse, in the “voice
of conscience.” Conscience is a call from Da-sein in Angst, in its uncanniness, to its self
lost in the they. And what conscience reveals to Da-sein is its guilt. This guilt discloses a
double “nullity” within Da-sein. First, as thrown, Da-sein has not thrown itself, nor has it,
so to speak, prepared the pillows for its throw. After all, Da-sein is characterized by its
facticity, and it always discovers itself among particular possibilities laid out for it by the
they. To put it in standard English: we do not choose the world we are born into, nor do
we choose the ways of life that world presents to us as options. But as we have seen, Da-
sein exists “only by projecting itself upon the possibilities into which it is thrown.” (284)
Thus, Da-sein exists as something, and must always exist as something, but it does not
give itself the “as-what.” In a straightforward sense (though not an exclusive sense) Da-
sein cannot be causa sui. “The self, which as such has to lay the ground of itself, can
never gain power over that ground, and yet it has to take over being the ground in
existing. Being its own thrown ground is the potentiality-of-being about which care is
over and over, he does not—despite the consistently negative characterization of guilt as
237
missing—for example, if I am subject to a law and fail to follow it, this is a lack on my
part. But Heidegger rejects this idea as a determination of Da-sein’s existence, because
the notion of lack belongs to entities unlike Da-sein. (283) An apple, for example, can
lack something when we take a bite out of it; a train with a broken engine lacks
functionality.
Da-sein does not lack something in the way an apple or a broken train does: being
above quote, a point I will elaborate later: Da-sein is a not in the sense that it is
characterized by an inability to “gain power over” its ground. But this inability is a
positive feature of existence: Da-sein must exist as this ground. Thus, the inability
and can come to own its possibility. More importantly, it can do so only because it is
fundamentally guilty. Consider a being of infinite power, equipped (somehow) with the
power to be entirely causa sui. Such a being could never own any possibility: since it has
absolute power over all alternatives open to it, it can never really be its possibility, since
it could always simply flit from possibility to possibility. None of its possibilities could
define it, and thus none could be its own. It is at least partly in recognition of this that
much of theology tends to characterize God as eternal rather temporally self-created and
as having some inabilities, since (for example) God cannot act against what is best or
diminish His perfection.68 Unlike God, we are not perfect. But like God, we can be
68
For a clear argument to this effect, see Ch. 7 of the Proslogion in Anselm (1995). The comparison is, of
course, flawed, since God is supposedly actuality—though not in the mode of an innerworldly entity—and
not possibility. This is why God has to be eternal—he must always exist as actuality. So our guilt clearly
238
But Da-sein is guilty in a second way as well. As existing, Da-sein must live
not other possibilities and has relinquished them in its existentiell project.” (285) And
here, in an odd turn, lies Da-sein’s freedom. “Freedom is only in the choice of the one,
that is, in bearing the fact of not having chosen and not being able to choose the others.”
(285) Da-sein not only exists among possibilities that it has not itself made, but it must
necessarily choose from among these possibilities. Its freedom is precisely this necessity
of choosing. Da-sein is not free in the sense that is could have chosen some other
possibility. This absolute sense of freedom is absent here and is quite possibly
attributable to the they, since only the they allows Da-sein to pursue constantly new—
possibilities that have not been chosen. It is in and through this disclosure that Da-sein
can come to own its possibility: it comes to own it precisely as the possibility that it has
guilt, this second dimension allows for ownership: an entity that can be all possibilities at
once, that does not exclude any possibility or way of being by choosing another
Unlike innerworldly things, which have a fixed essence, Da-sein is always possibility, so
that its essence is never fixed. But it is that possibility, rather than all possibilities, and
sets us apart from God; the point, however, remains: an entity that created itself in time could not own
itself.
239
thus it can be concerned with its being. Furthermore, it should be clear that it is on the
basis of this guilt that Da-sein can first be responsible in the ordinary sense: to be
responsible in the ordinary sense is to be subject to a norm, which one may follow or
self. That is precisely what guilt, in this second sense, allows. Someone who can be all
possibilities at once cannot be genuinely subject to a norm, since one can deviate and
adhere. But someone who can deviate and adhere at the same time is not genuinely
both A and B, but choose to be A, doesn’t that make A more my own? But the contrast
here is not between being able to be both A and B, on the one hand, and being able only
to be A, on the other. Rather, it is between being able to be both A and B, or being able to
be either A or B. Only the latter is placed under the necessity of having the choose
himself; his being something is demanded of him. The former can indeed be A or B, but
is under no requirement to be so; his being something is not constitutive of his self, but
But in what sense has Da-sein “always already chosen” itself? Aren’t we all born
into a particular social group? And doesn’t that group map out for us at least our initial
possibilities, those in terms of which we define ourselves even before being able to
reflect on our options? This is slightly beside the point, in a sense: Heidegger grants—in
fact, insists—that falling prey belongs to the care structure. This is why Da-sein initially
and for the most part exists as a they self. Therein lies its guilt: in hearing the call of
conscience, Da-sein “must bring itself back to itself from its lostness in the they, and this
240
means that it is guilty.” (287) And indeed, in apparent contradiction to my reading,
Heidegger does claim that Da-sein becomes authentic “by making up for not choosing.”
(168) But it turns out that Da-sein does not choose only in the sense that “the they even
conceals the way it has silently disburdened Da-sein of the explicit choice of these
possibilities” (268) and it “has let itself be given such possibilities as are prescribed by its
public interpretedness.” (270) This suggests that Da-sein must make up for “not
choosing” only in the sense that its having chosen is hidden from it, so that it must
reclaim or retrieve that choice in authenticity. Once again, when Da-sein can find itself, it
finds itself as having always already chosen. And this is what is revealed to it in the call
of conscience. Protesting that, after all, it had no choice is simply a refusal to heed the
call.
But this still seems fishy. Did Da-sein really choose its possibility? This question
rests on the idea that Da-sein could have chosen a different possibility. But this could
have is not disclosed in guilt. The question of whether or not this choice could have been
guilt as, first, having before it a field of possibilities which it has not created itself and
from among which it must choose. And it is disclosed in the second place as already
having chosen, and chosen in such a way that it has not chosen other possibilities. Da-
sein owns its possibility because it has chosen it, not because it could have chosen
otherwise. There is here no further question to ask about whether or not Da-sein has
really chosen. This question adds nothing at all; it cannot be answered, because there is
having chosen a possibility and as not having chosen others, the question of whether it
241
ever really chooses is ontologically meaningless. In other words, Da-sein is disclosed to
sense is not to somehow fail to choose, but rather to “forget,” under the influence of the
Of course this point is controversial, and most Heidegger readers avoid it.
that in revealing its grounds as beyond its power, conscience thereby reveals to Da-sein
the ability to choose—and this first allows Da-sein to take up its grounds as reasons, that
is, to act in light of norms and not merely according to them. (Crowell 2007a, 2008) This
suggests that Da-sein’s choice is always only in its listening to conscience; it does not
discover that it has already chosen, but only that it can choose. This reading thus wipes
out the temporal account I am giving, and also brings Heidegger closer to common sense.
On my reading, conscience discloses Da-sein’s deep temporality (as I have been calling
it): we have not chosen our possibilities at some previous point in time, but rather we
encounter them in our thrownness as something that we have already chosen. And that is
puzzling, to say the least. The above objections, thus, make a good deal of sense, and I
will have to postpone a fuller defense until the discussion of temporality in the next
section.
Conscience “calls back by calling forth: forth to the possibility of taking over in
existence the thrown being that it is, back to thrownness in order to understand it as the
null ground that it has to take up into existence.” (287) So guilt places an inescapable
demand on Da-sein: to project itself onto the possibilities into which it has been thrown,
242
to exist as its ground. Furthermore, it is important that this demand—while it comes from
Da-sein in Angst—does not reach Da-sein in Angst; the Da-sein in Angst cannot project
itself onto its possibilities, but the Da-sein who hears the call can. At the same time, this
Da-sein is summoned “to one’s own self. Not to what Da-sein is, can do, and takes care of
in everyday being-with-one-another, not even to what has moved it, what it has pledged
itself to, what it has let itself be involved with. Understood in a worldly way for others
and for itself, Da-sein is passed over in this call.” (273) Thus the self reached by the
call—beyond its worldly commitments—is deeper than the self as constituted by its
volitional necessities, or the self constituted by its reasons. But what does this Heidegger-
speak mean? Again, a fuller discussion has to wait until the next section, but the
though of course it is always possible to ignore it and go one with one’s commitments,
volitional necessities, and endorsements. The alternative is to hear the call and be
Key to the structure of the call of conscience is that it is silent—unlike the “idle
chatter” of the they, conscience speaks without words. And so the proper understanding
response to it is, likewise, not verbal; it is reticent. But the point of the reticence is not
simply that Da-sein, in understanding the call, does not speak—it responds by being
resolute, resoluteness being “the reticent projecting oneself upon one’s ownmost being-
guilty which is ready for Angst.” (279) But resoluteness is not “passive,” since projecting
onto being guilty involves being summoned to take over the ground. So in reticence, Da-
sein responds by acting: “Understanding the call, Da-sein lets its ownmost self take
action in itself in terms of its chosen potentiality-of-being. Only in this way can it be
243
responsible.” (288) It is worth noting that “responsible” here translates “Verantwortlich,”
heeding the call, which reveals Da-sein’s guilt (Schuld), Da-sein takes action and
becomes answerable for itself: in other words, it takes responsibility for itself.
On the other hand, Da-sein does not, as in the constitutivist and volitional
theories, take responsibility for its action in the standard sense; despite frequently using
the term, Heidegger suddenly tells us that “resolute, Da-sein is already acting. We are
purposely avoiding the term ‘action.’ For in the first place, it would have to be so broadly
conceived that activity also encompasses the passivity of resistance. In the second place,
special mode of behavior of the practical faculty as opposed to the theoretical one.” (300)
The latter point signifies that resoluteness is both acting and understanding; it is
both discloses Da-sein to itself and does so through Da-sein’s agency in the world. But
resoluteness does not mean taking action in the usual sense; Heidegger clearly means
agency as such—not, that is, particular acts, but the projecting of possibilities that
structures those acts or omissions. Resolute Da-sein is a self that owns itself. Its agency,
thus, is not scattered among the they and the many things to be taken care of in the world.
This is not to say that resoluteness is removed from the world, of course, as Heidegger
stresses that this is impossible (world is, after all, constitutive of Da-sein). Rather,
resoluteness re-enters the world as self-owning, disclosing the “situation,” a term I will
take up later.
69
Macquerrie and Robinson’s translation notes the distinction; Stambaugh’s, unfortunately, does not.
244
Finally, conscience does not tell Da-sein how to act; it gives no concrete guidance
care of things; it “passes over what Da-sein understands itself as initially and for the most
part in its interpretation in terms of taking care of things.” (273) So the call is silent and
not action-guiding; otherwise, “with its unequivocally calculable maxims that one is led
to expect, conscience would deny to existence nothing less than the possibility of acting.”
(294) That is, if conscience were action guiding, it would block Da-sein’s ability to act.
This may seem odd, but the point is fairly clear: since Da-sein exists as possibility, the
imperative it receives from conscience is simply to project its ground upon its ownmost
possibility. But just what this consists of has to be determined by each Da-sein itself;
truly acting, for Da-sein, involves being-possible. Thus, in fully acting as itself, Da-sein
still exists as possibility. But to give it definite criteria for action would be to define an
actuality for which Da-sein, as possibility, must strive. Falling prey in the they, among its
guidelines and rules, prevents Da-sein from truly acting; it even reduces genuine willing
to mere wishing (194-195), since all possibilities for action are already pre-given, so that
Da-sein need not do anything but conform and wait for results rather than accomplishing
them. If conscience were to lay down rules, it would simply reduce Da-sein back to the
of following any pre-given rules. “But to what does Da-sein resolve itself in resoluteness?
On what is it to resolve? Only the resolution itself can answer this. It would be a complete
245
is precisely the disclosive projection and determination of the actual factical possibility.”
(298) That is, resoluteness involves genuine acting, which itself discloses the situation
that calls for action. It does so by projecting onto Da-sein’s being guilty, that is, by taking
up Da-sein’s ground and existing out of it. And since each Da-sein exists as being-
possible, there cannot be any possibility that, in advance, all Da-sein must take up. At
least, there cannot be any such public possibility; there is one possibility that is for every
Da-sein its ownmost possibility: death. And it is here that I now turn.
Remember that at the end of the last chapter, we had left Da-sein in a
“fragmentary” state. It is fragmentary in two senses. First, as absorbed in the they, Da-
sein is scattered among the entities that it takes care of, among the possibilities of the
they-self that constantly take it from project to project in the mode of curiosity. But there
is also an important second sense in which Da-sein—in the analysis so far—is scattered.
Heidegger defined Da-sein’s being as care, and care was formulated as being-ahead-of-
as defined by a set of its dispositions or judgments (of by its possibilities), however well
these cohere together, we necessarily leave something out, since Da-sein, as existent, is
not definable by the possibilities it is in at any given time; those possibilities are always
246
projected ahead. It seems, then, that to understand Da-sein, we will have to grasp its
entire life, and this means we have to take up the issue of its death.
we can understand Da-sein only if we grasp it all the way through its death, it seems to
follow that we cannot know what Da-sein is until it has died. And this would be
problematic if the aim were to give an account of responsibility such that we are
responsible for actions that express a whole self, since we couldn’t know what the whole
self is until after death: of course, we might say, an agent’s actions might express her
whole self; but we could not in principle know whether they do until after death.70 But
Heidegger argues that the problem is only a superficial one, based on a misunderstanding
of what death is. It arises from thinking of death as an event, that will occur at some
future point in an agent’s existence. And Heidegger responds that once we properly
understand death, we will see it as, in a sense, always constitutive of Da-sein. This will
As I’ve already noted, most accounts of responsibility try to take up some notion
of a whole self: the attributionists think of the whole self as made up by the coherence (or
of reasons for actions. And some of these accounts emphasize a diachronic aspect of
selfhood: the perseverance of my volitional necessities, the commitment to act for the
same reason in relevantly similar future circumstances, the laying out of long-term plans,
or the persistence of reasons-responsive mechanisms for which one has already taken
70
This problem is roughly analogous to Aristotle’s difficulty in Nicomachean Ethics, I.10, where he
wonders how—since happiness depends on one’s actions over a lifetime—we could call someone happy
while they are still alive.
247
responsibility, are all attempts to understand the self as a diachronically continuous
entity. Heidegger’s account, I propose, flips the entire approach on its head. On the one
hand, actions do indeed express a whole self. On the other hand, this self is not simply
not constituted by actions, moments of choosing, or any other discrete events. Rather, all
acquisitions, and so on take place against a backdrop of a temporally unified whole that is
dependant on the events that it gives rise to (such as discrete willings or choosing), it is
not constituted from within a timeline. Instead, all such acts of the self are constituted
from without, by the self’s pre-existing temporal unity. And this is what Heidegger’s
Older readings of Heidegger tend to explain this account of death through some
variation on the following theme: knowing that I am going to die, I structure my life
argued that death, properly understood, imparts a narrative structure on a life. (1984,
2000, 2002) But this cannot be what Heidegger means. First, he insists that death is
Second, the reading assumes what Heidegger calls “the vulgar concept of time”: at some
time later than now, I will no longer exist, and thus am under the imperative of arranging
the events of my life—what I did yesterday, what I do now, what I will do tomorrow—in
a coherent order that makes sense in light of the expected end. But this is not what
Heidegger has in mind. It is the mark of a narrative that it is going somewhere; its story
248
aims at a resolution. But death is not a resolution, or a self-fulfillment or actualization of
Da-sein; “for the most part, it ends in unfulfillment, or else disintegrated and used up.”
(244) And, as I have already hinted, Heidegger simply does not think our life is made up
of events that can be arranged to make up a whole. The point of the narrative
interpretation of Heidegger, of course, is that the parts of are constituted by, or make
sense in light of, the whole. And this is right. But the reference to “narrative” is then only
a misleading metaphor, especially given the role narrative has acquired in recent work as
constituting a diachronic self. It is, in other words, precisely the opposite of Heidegger’s
aim.
More recent interpreters usually spend a good deal of time attacking the older
about, once again talks tends to turn to the way I am to structure my life; perhaps what
death reveals is just the greater gravity of choosing among my possibilities. Now, it does
reveal that, in some sense, but this doesn’t explain what death could have to do with
owning oneself, which is clearly to the point, since Heidegger begins Division II, the part
of Being and Time aimed at making sense of authentic Da-sein, with a discussion of it.
our possibilities, is right. (Blattner 1994) But this interpretation needs to be spelled out in
its implications. Death is a boundary condition, but what is the implication of this? How
does it enable self-ownership? And what does it have to do with our everyday agency if
its purpose is not to organize it into a narrative? And, in any case, clearly death is not a
boundary condition on just any possibility, which is what Blattner suggests when he notes
that Da-sein can have an “existential death” at any time—if, for example, I fall out of
249
love, I can no longer press into my self-projected possibility as a lover. But surely death
is not supposed to mark the boundary of each possibility individually, but of all
Let me note two points about the structural role of death in Being and Time, both
of which I have already hinted at and will now go on to sketch in more detail. First, it is
introduced explicitly in answering the question of how we can grasp the being-a-whole of
Da-sein. And second, it makes its return in the text (despite minor mentions) only once
Heidegger has introduced resoluteness and notes that, to be fully authentic, it must also
resoluteness), been entirely formal, or a mere “ontological project.” (309) What is it that
especially given the fact that the section is in prelude to Heidegger’s introduction of
possible, it makes clear the phenomenon of temporality that underlies Da-sein’s care
structure. And it makes the phenomenon clear precisely through bringing death and
should not focus too much on death as such, but on what it discloses: the being-a-whole
of Da-sein, and the notion of future as anticipation, which is implied by and first makes
First, Heidegger takes up the everyday understanding of death as the end of Da-
sein, in the sense of concluding its life. This understanding turns out to be flawed in a
250
number of ways. First, it presents death as a common, or public phenomenon. Other
people die, and we ourselves will die as well. But this understanding of death is entirely
third-personal, and it misses the asymmetry between the death of others and one’s own
death. We can see others die, but we cannot experience ourselves die in the same way.
Thus, death is an individualizing notion: only I can die my death, and “no one can take
the other’s dying away from him.” (240) This is what allows death to separate Da-sein
from its they self. Among the possibilities laid out by the they, everyone is
another can also do it, and this is due to the public nature of the they’s possibilities. But
no one can represent my death, and thus no one can represent the being-a-whole that
death signifies; “in ‘ending’ and in the totality thus constituted of Da-sein, there is
death is essentially not shareable. And since death is supposed to have something to do
possibility that is not laid out by the they self.71 Heidegger thus calls death Da-sein’s
ownmost possibility. The point of this slightly misleading formulation is not that dying is
the only thing we can do apart from the they self, but that self-ownership—wresting
one’s authentic self away from the they self—is possible only in light of death.
order to accomplish something, and what it accomplishes is for the sake of beings like
itself. This referential framework constitutes the world. But death has no such relational
71
Of course the possibilities involved in dealing with death, or preparing for it—making funeral
arrangements, meeting with friends and family, writing out a will—are laid out by the they. But death itself
is not.
251
structure: it is not and cannot be for anything.72 One might, of course, organize one’s life
in a certain way in light of death; but this does not involve using death in-order-to
organize one’s life in that way; rather, it involves organizing one’s life for the sake of
the-sake-of that allows Da-sein to press on into those possibilities. But death is not the
sort of possibility that allows pressing on into it. It is both constituted nonrelationally, and
is also the possibility one cannot go beyond; it “reveals itself as the ownmost
possibility is especially strange, since possibilities are characterized by our pressing into
them; death, on the other hand, is “the possibility of the absolute impossibility of Da-
ourselves and the world in terms of the possibilities we project. Thus, understanding
death as a possibility requires understanding ourselves in light of it, that is, in light of our
Heidegger stresses what should already be clear: that death is, here, an existential
make this point: animals perish, humans demise, but only Da-sein—as the being of
an existential concept from any feature that could belong to things present-at-hand. This
72
This again shows why death is individualizing: since Da-sein normally understands itself in terms of the
things it takes care of, in understanding itself in terms of death it is stripped of those ways of self-
understanding.
252
something that is yet to happen. Heidegger contrasts death with ways in which present-at-
hand things can end: rivers might reach their completion in the sea or come to a man-
made block, weather patterns may end and so may debts, when one discharges them.
Once one reaches the end of the river, one has traversed the entirety of that river; and
once one pays off a debt by giving what is owed, it is no more. Death can also be seen
this way: we know that we will die, that our process of life will at some point end. But
this kind of empirical certainty, Heidegger suggests, is the way the they tries to cope with
death by covering it over: it portrays death as certain, but only in the sense that it
“happens,” it is an event that one undergoes, and that will at some point in the future
happen to us all.
entity, Heidegger suggests the analogy of a ripening fruit. An unripe fruit has not become
ripe, but not simply in such a way that the ripeness is an event in its future. The ripeness
is not something foreign to the fruit, but is its own completion, and so the unripe fruit
does not simply have a state different from that of the ripe fruit—we miss something, for
example, if we think of the green tomato and the red tomato as two unrelated event-states
of tomatoes. In its ripening, the fruit “is not only not indifferent to its unripeness as an
other to itself, but, ripening, it is the unripeness. The not-yet is already included in its
Correspondingly, Da-sein, too, is always already its not-yet as long as it is.” (244) The
unripened fruit, in other words, exists as unripe, so that its future finished state of
immediately distinguishes Da-sein from the fruit, since the fruit, unlike Da-sein, reaches
253
its fulfillment in its ripening. Da-sein’s death, as noted above, is not a fulfillment in any
sense. Nevertheless, this is perhaps the clearest analogy Heidegger gives to explain how
he sees Da-sein’s relation to its death: as existing, Da-sein is always constituted by its
being-toward-death.
Now we can work out the idea that death is a possibility, though a rather odd
possibility of the impossibility of being. When death is not being covered over as
empirically certain, Da-sein can be in the certainty—that is, instead of simply knowing
that it will die, it understands itself as finite. On the one hand, as we’ve just seen, this
means that death becomes constitutive of Da-sein’s being-possible; on the other hand, it
becomes clear that death—not as an outstanding end, but as thus constitutive—is not an
event, but itself a possibility in terms of which Da-sein understands itself and exists.
Death is a possibility not in the sense that when its heart stops beating, Da-sein will still
be projecting its understanding one last time, but in the sense that Da-sein’s possibilities
Da-sein’s understanding of its possibilities, and this is itself its ownmost possibility.
So how does this possibility work? Again, recall that Da-sein’s other possibilities
are subject to the danger of being interpreted by the they as mere possibilities, that is, as
processes on the way to actualization. The possibility of being a job-seeker, for example,
reaches its actualization in finding a job, and the possibility of being a dissertation writer
finds its actualization in a dissertation. “Being out for something possible and taking care
254
available” (261), Heidegger warns. And this makes it seem as if, in completing a task or
carrying out an action, we cease to project possibilities and return to what is actual, as if
actuality is the stable state and possibility an occasional distraction from it. This tendency
to make the possible real is, after all, a mark of Da-sein’s felling prey in curiosity. But
what makes such understanding inauthentic is that it overlooks the fact that all actions
and tasks are still meaningful only within a further possibility. “The actualization of
useful things at hand in taking care of them (producing them, getting them ready,
readjusting them, etc.), is, however, always merely relative, in that what has been
actualized still has the character of being relevant. Even when actualized, as something
One can actualize a possibility only against the backdrop of a further possibility,
and an authentic understanding thus sees possibility as higher than actuality—as both
prior to it and as a condition of its possibility, not merely in the sense that every actuality
is the outcome of pressing into some possibility, but in the further sense that every
light of which the actuality can be what it is. And this is precisely what death gives us to
nothing to ‘be actualized’ and nothing which it itself could be as something real.” (262)
other possibilities have some purpose, some end for which they are possible, death
provides no such purpose. Being-toward-death opens the way for self-ownership because
in it Da-sein cannot interpret itself in terms of world and the purposes of the they; it no
255
nonrelational possibility. In recognizing itself as possibility, Da-sein is freed of its
tendency toward entanglement and “from one’s lostness in chance possibilities urging
themselves upon us, so that the factical possibilities lying before the possibility not-to-be-
bypassed can first be authentically understood and chosen.” (264) In revealing Da-sein as
possibility, death frees Da-sein with regard to its factical possibilities: Da-sein sees these
everydayness, Da-sein primarily relates to its future through expectation: it treats the
death as such an event, something to merely expect or wait for, the they covers over the
recognizing oneself existing as possibility—as being ahead of itself, Da-sein does not
have a closed future that it must expect, but an open future that, in principle, cannot be
sein sees its future as fixed, consisting of an actualization as a corpse. In anticipation, Da-
sein recognizes its future not as an event, but as a mode of being in which its possibility
is not actualizable. Anticipating, Da-sein can avoid being entangled in the world and
73
“Anticipation” is Stambaugh’s translation of “Vorlaufen,” literally “fore-running,” which Macquarrie
and Robinson had translated awkwardly as “running ahead in thought.” In some ways, anticipation is an
unfortunate translation—it obliterates the active dimension of Vorlaufen, which is obviously crucial to
Heidegger’s account. On the other hand, Vorlaufen has connotations of “preparedness,” which suggests a
standard Heideggerian theme: the unify of activity and passivity, or perhaps the casting of the active as
passive; in any case, it is clear that he thinks the common way of drawing the distinction is misleading.
Anticipation does, however, serve as a nice contrast with “waiting” and “expecting.” I will continue using
Stambaugh’s translation while noting that the active dimension of anticipation needs to be kept in mind.
The translation is not a good one; but there are no good English translations of many of Heidegger’s key
terms. Bringing Heidegger into a serious dialogue with Anglophone philosophy will require a wholescale
retranslation and appropriation of his terminology, much as his own appropriation of Aristotle plays a
major role in his work. But that is obviously not a project I can undertake here.
256
understanding in the they; “Da-sein guards itself against falling back behind itself, or
behind the potentiality-for-being that it has understood.” (264) That is, Da-sein can no
longer understand itself in terms of its prior understanding, because its understanding, as
projection of possibility, does not have any particular actualization as its end; rather, Da-
sein must constantly exist as possibility, that is, understanding anew and transforming its
prior understanding.74
Finally, we can bring the results together. Since death is not something
outstanding that Da-sein must wait for, we can resolve the initial problem—that the
whole self cannot be grasped during life. Death is a possibility of understanding oneself,
and as anticipation it already modifies Da-sein’s pressing forward into possibilities. “The
movement toward a future ability to be constitutes our current ability to be.” (Nicholson
2005 55) Da-sein exists as a temporally unified whole not by virtue of diachronic
agency—which can, in any case, allow for only a partial and contingent unity—but as
anticipating, and therefore understanding itself as possibility. On the one hand, it does not
constitute itself as unified by making choices; rather, it makes choices on the basis of a
pre-existing unity. On the other hand, it does not always reside in the same volitional
when called to do so by the situation. And in so doing Da-sein remains the same self,
because its unity is not contingent on those necessities, but rather first allows them to be
possibilities that Da-sein presses into. Finally, Da-sein exists as a whole in anticipation
possibility not-to-be-bypassed also discloses all the possibilities lying before it, this
74
Velleman’s account—on which (full blooded) action is guided by a self-understanding—would on this
scheme ensure that no action is ever possible: understanding is never finished; in acting on my
understanding, I transform that understanding.
257
anticipation includes the possibility of taking the whole of Da-sein in advance in an
existentiell way, that is, the possibility of existing as a whole potentiality-of-being.” (264)
limited by death, and thus none have any essential privilege or salience in the face of the
ownmost possibility—it can bring them together under a single limiting condition that
and set free to choose among its factical possibilities, so that its ownmost possibility—
and not those factical possibilities—guides its actions. Its agency can thus become its
own.
We must now bring the threads together. Heidegger argues that resoluteness—as
requires anticipatory resoluteness, which he insists does not involve two phenomena
haphazardly brought together, but rather a “modalization” of the latter by the former. In
some ways it is already clear how the two belong together: in Angst, Da-sein discloses
itself in its being-toward-death, since Angst presents the world and its possibilities as
lacking in salience. And from Angst—that is, from anticipation—Da-sein calls to itself in
its they-self and into a projection of its being-guilty. But to make sense of how this
works, how anticipation makes sense of guilt (or, rather, its disclosure of Da-sein as
having always already chosen), and how the two together allow for genuine ownership, I
258
will first draw on Heidegger’s account of temporality.75 I will not work out the account in
its full details. Instead, I will focus on the salient points needed to establish my argument:
that freedom and responsibility require what I have been calling deep temporality.
secondary literature, in his discussion of death Heidegger does not do what one would
expect: he does not use death to emphasize the distinction between the finite and the
infinite. In part, this is because something like infinite understanding plays no role in
Heidegger: bringing it in could only serve to cover up the question of being, since the
major role in Heidegger in contrast to infinity, it is not in the account of death, but in that
of conscience, where guilt does serve the role of characterizing Da-sein as essentially
limited in its possibilities. But even there, as I’ve noted, he immediately stresses that guilt
75
Heidegger, of course, works out the unity of anticipatory resoluteness first, in order to disclose the basis
for authentic temporality, which allows him to repeat the account given up to that point and leading into his
conception of historicity. My purpose here is more modest, and I can thus reverse the order of presentation
so as to show how the account of authentic temporality allows for and makes sense of the idea that we have
always already chosen our possibilities.
76
I am therefore puzzled by analyses that claim that, in guilt, Da-sein always falls short of a standard of
achieving itself. See, for example, Dreyfus and Rubin’s early account of what Angst discloses in Dreyfus
(1991), and a very different and fascinating account by Tanzer (2001). In the context of defending the claim
that Heidegger’s account is not purely decisionist and thus inviolable, but rather postulates a norm that can
be violated, Tanzer emphasizes Da-sein’s inability to authentically achieve itself, arguing that Da-sein’s
guilt involves a constant violation of a norm. On my reading these accounts are contrary to Heidegger’s
intention: he explicitly states that he is taking over the notion of “guilt” from the common view of what
consciousness discloses, and immediately goes on to characterize it as a positive phenomenon, thus in
direct opposition to the common view. True, Da-sein cannot achieve itself in the sense of becoming actual;
it can only—in death—become not-possible, and this is no self-achievement. But on my reading, Heidegger
is not positing a norm that Da-sein always fails to fulfill; rather, he is insisting that the very idea of self-
achievement involves an inauthentic understanding of Da-sein, and he contrasts it with the positive
understanding of Da-sein as possibility which cannot be actualized. Its aim is not to actualize itself by
overcoming possibility, but to actualize itself—if the term still makes sense—by understanding itself as
being-possible.
259
almost exclusively—not to distinguish finitude from infinity, but rather to distinguish the
existential concept of death from its constant covering over in the they. When he does
emphasize finitude, Heidegger does so precisely to separate death from demise: Da-sein
“does not have an end where it just stops, but it exists finitely.” (329) His aim in
What is wrong with waiting for death? One can wait only for an event, but death
possibility. The notion of death as an event belongs to what Heidegger calls the vulgar
understanding consists, among other things, precisely in the fact that it is a pure
succession of nows, without beginning and without end, in which the ecstatic character of
primordial temporality is leveled down.” (329) This, of course, is what I have been
calling shallow temporality: a view according to which both our choices and our
at a particular point—a now—on a timeline. Heidegger does not insist that this view of
present-at-hand entity, and Heidegger’s entire analysis is aimed at showing that such an
understanding is inappropriate to the sort of being that Da-sein is. In what sense, then, is
the view of time as consisting of a series of events, or nows, not primordial? In his
occurs in accordance with the law of cause and effect, Heidegger notes that causality
260
already presupposes a deeper account of temporality, since “perceiving an event means
not just perceiving something as it occurs, but knowing in advance that this follows on
from something earlier.” (Heidegger 2002 124) Thus, perceiving events as essentially
that “causality (as causation) means: running ahead in time as determining letting follow
on such that what runs ahead is itself an event that refers back to something earlier that
determines it. As such a relation, causality necessarily involves the temporal character as
this going before.” (2002 131) Causality is thus not a primordial understanding of the
But this account does not apply only if we assume that all events are caused by
structure. As Heidegger has already argued, our intentionality is grounded in our taking
care of things. But taking care implies that we already “retain” a referential whole within
which the things can be used and “await” or “expect” a purpose to be attained by their
use. “If heedful association were simply a succession of ‘experiences’ occurring ‘in time’
and if these experiences were ‘associated’ with each other as intimately as possible,
(355) Awaiting and retaining are conditions of possibility for experiencing an event as an
event; they co-constitute our encounter with things as present or as occurring in a now.
So time cannot, primordially, be a series of nows strung together, since the occurrence of
each now itself requires a prior understanding of a pre-given referential whole and an
expected effect. That we are not normally aware of this underlying temporality is not
261
referential whole or the context in which we act. Absorption in everyday tasks in fact
presupposes a “forgetting” of the whole in order to focus on what we are doing. And, for
that matter, “simply looking,” or grasping things thematically, involves forgetting the
practical context that such looking presupposes. Thus Heidegger has both an argument
against the primordiality of shallow temporality, and an error theory for explaining why
“awaiting”—is all that the pragmatist reading of Heidegger typically gives us. But these
terms still belong to the vulgar understanding of time: they are appropriate only for
temporality in which Da-sein fully understands and owns itself rather than losing itself in
the world—requires finding the grounds of such retaining and awaiting.77 Awaiting
involves some actuality, some concrete, objective event: one awaits only something that
can, at least potentially, occur in a future present. Similarly, one retains (or forgets)
something that is already there, that itself is objectively present. And one acts, when one
acts irresolutely, on the basis of a fixed framework and for the sake of a purpose that this
framework allows or affords. Inauthentic temporality, then, is geared toward our dealings
with things. But it already demonstrates the impossibility of a present, a now, as a basic
constituent of our experience of entities and events. And it already displays a unified
structure: “the making present that awaits and retains constitutes the familiarity in
accordance with which Da-sein ‘knows its way around’ as being-with-one-another in the
77
That authentic temporality, the temporality in which Da-sein understands itself as itself, must ground the
inauthentic temporality in terms of which it understands its world and itself as worldly is not surprising.
Our relation to the world is permeated by possibility, which is fully grasped as possibility only in
authenticity. Since our understanding of things in everyday use depends on our projection of possibilities, it
follows that everyday temporality will involve a modification of an underlying authentic temporality.
262
public surrounding world.” (354) What remains is to bring out authentic temporality and
Anticipation does not involve expecting an event to happen, but “the being toward one’s
ownmost, eminent potentiality-of-being.” (325) That is, the authentic future—the future
possibility that does not aim at actualization. As being-possible, Da-sein is always ahead
of itself, but “the ‘ahead’ does not mean the ‘before’ in the sense of a ‘not-yet-now, but
later.’” (327) That something might occur at a later time is obviously not excluded by this
notion of the future; the point is only that the sense of “future” in which events happen—
and requires a sense of future as anticipation as its condition of possibility. The authentic
past, similarly, is not simply something one retains or forgets, and is not a “no-longer-
now, but earlier.” (327) Instead, it is a “having been,” which involves coming back to
there is also a “making present,” which is unified with the anticipation and retrieval of
future and past. Authentic making present, which goes along with anticipation and
retrieve, is the Moment (Augenblick). All these “ecstases,” as Heidegger calls them, are
unified in one structure; they are ecstatic, or “stand out from themselves,” insofar as each
implies the others: the authentic future has a past and a present. The same goes for the
other ecstases:
263
Understanding is grounded primarily in the future (anticipation or awaiting).
Attunement temporalizes itself primarily in having-been (retrieve or
forgottenness). Falling prey is temporally rooted primarily in the present (making
present or the Moment). Still understanding is always a present that ‘has-been.’
Still, attunement temporalizes itself as a future that ‘makes present.’ Still, the
present ‘arises’ from or is held by a future that has-been. (350)
The unity of temporality, in which past, present, and future always belong together, is for
Heidegger the meaning of—what makes it possible to project—the care structure. Being-
and the present of together-with-entities. And this temporal unity can be either
that resoluteness must project its being-guilty onto Da-sein as a whole; and Da-sein as a
whole is grasped in the mode of anticipation. But this is not particularly clear. Let me
take up two further hints about the relation between anticipation and resoluteness. On the
one hand, anticipatory resoluteness is “the understanding that follows the call of
conscience and that frees for death the possibility of gaining power over the existence of
power” over Da-sein in the sense of letting Da-sein own itself, or taking over its
ownership from the they-self. On the other hand, “being guilty, which is constantly with
us, does not show itself without being covered over in its character as prior until that
priority is placed in the possibility which is for Da-sein absolutely not to be bypassed.”
(307) In other words, being guilty—which I have characterized as disclosing that we have
264
always already chosen—can only make sense as such, without being misinterpreted, in
So now we come to the crux of the issue: how does anticipation “modalize”
the previous discussion of this idea, it seemed that this notion of choosing is only a
metaphor; that, after all, we have not chosen, but the they has chosen for us. And it
seemed like we cannot make sense of the idea that we have let the they “disburden” us of
our choice of possibilities; there seems to be no room for agency in this picture. This
objection assumes that the past is absolutely fixed, as something that was and is now no
longer. That is, it assumes inauthentic temporality. But Da-sein’s authentic temporality
includes the past in the future, and the future in the past. We project ourselves always out
of thrownness, but we also retrieve our thrownness in the project. “The authentic coming-
ownmost self thrown into its individuation. This ecstasy makes it possible for Da-sein to
be able to take over resolutely the being that it already is.” (339) So in coming forth to
itself as its ownmost possibility, Da-sein also comes back for itself in its thrownness.
Resoluteness projected Da-sein onto its guilt in thrownness, and placed Da-sein under an
imperative of taking over its ground and existing out of it. So how does Da-sein do that?
Anticipation discloses Da-sein as a whole. This means not only that Da-sein is
constituted by its future so that its future is not something still outstanding, but also that
its past is never something that has simply happened. “To take over thrownness means to
authentically be Da-sein in the way that it always already was.” (326) As being-a-whole,
Da-sein is not simply its present, with a past that has already happened and is, in a way,
265
already closed off as a possibility. As existing, Da-sein always exists as its possibility—
that is, it is what it understands itself as in acting. Da-sein’s facticity, then, is not
something simply given that it must accept, but something offered that it must take up as
also constitutive of its possibility in its projection of itself onto its ownmost possibility.
The imperative to take over one’s ground, to understand it within the context of one’s
ownmost possibility, comes from that ownmost possibility itself: existing as possible and
never actual, Da-sein is not merely opened up to its possibilities in the present, but must
take up its past as part and parcel of its pressing into its open possibility. Consequently,
been arises from the future.” (326) Anticipatory resoluteness sets Da-sein free from
determination by the they and by its past precisely because, in Da-sein’s being-a-whole,
its future is constitutive of its past. In disclosing itself as possibility, separated from the
distortions introduced by the they in which Da-sein tends to understand itself as a mere
thing, Da-sein can understand its past as its own, that is, as chosen on the basis of its open
future. Of course this does not change “the facts” of Da-sein’s past; but “facts” enter into
Da-sein’s constitution only as facticity, that is, as involved in but not determining of its
Heidegger puts it, “understanding the call, Da-sein listens to its ownmost possibility of
But isn’t Da-sein still bound by the they? There is a lively debate on this topic, as
there is on almost every aspect of Heidegger. Dreyfus (1991) used to insist that Da-sein is
always trapped in the they.78 Heidegger does, after all, tell us that “authentic being one’s
self is not based on an exceptional state of the subject, a state detached from the they, but
78
As I will mention below, Dreyfus’s view on the topic has changed.
266
is an existentiell modification of the they as an essential existential.” (130) And this
seems to suggest that Da-sein is always trapped in the they, so that authenticity does not
free it after all. To some extent, this view has been helpfully fixed by Guignon (1984)
and, in detail, by Boedeker (2001), who note that authenticity involves a grasp or
modification of the they, but it is opposed to the they-self. The idea, then, is that we can
free ourselves from the they-self in the individuation of Angst, but the they remains the
source of our possibilities. Boedeker thus argues that “Dasein in the self-owning mode of
Being-itself thus projects the same concrete possibilities of itself as it does in the mode of
the Man-self. What is distinctive about the mode of self-ownership is that Dasein for the
first time owns up to the existential consequence of doing so imposed by its ownmost
possibility of death.” (2001 89) But Heidegger also speaks of authentic possibilities, and
of Da-sein being led astray from those in the they (174, 178, 344, see also Bracken
(2005)). This seems contradictory: either Da-sein’s possibilities are entirely drawn from
The answer, I think, may be that both are right. Boedeker suggests that in
Heidegger means; but then it becomes unclear why he might speak of authentic
possibilities in the plural. Perhaps what Heidegger means is, rather, something like the
because that is what one does. But I can also walk on the sidewalk—doing what one
does—because I choose to. Perhaps, then, Da-sein is open to authentic possibilities in the
sense that it can take up the same old possibilities of the they, but understand them—and
267
so exist—in a new way, exercising a new possibility. This may be what Boedeker has in
mind. But this also doesn’t seem quite right, because it clashes with Heidegger’s account
of falling prey. Heidegger notes, for example, that curiosity—constantly flitting here and
there—never dwells anywhere; that idle talk presents everything as understood and thus
does not have time for authentic understanding. Fallen Da-sein does not seem to act in
escape the everyday way of being interpreted into which Da-sein has grown initially. All
appropriation come about in it and out of it and against it. It is not the case that a Da-sein,
untouched and unseduced by this way of interpreting, was every confronted by the free
land of a ‘world.’” (169) But the public way of interpreting does not allow for anything
genuinely new; thus, Heidegger is suggesting that something new is possible. But it is
immediately taken back up into the they, so its newness is quickly covered over by idle
talk; and it appears only against an existing shared backdrop of the they. But this is not
strange: Da-sein’s world is a public world. To entirely escape the they, Da-sein would
have to escape the world; and then it would no longer be Da-sein. But to say that every
interpretation and understanding is grounded in the they and returns to it is not to say that
nothing new is possible. Da-sein can authentically take up possibilities that draw on, but
are not entirely drawn from, the possibilities of the they. This is precisely the point: the
authentic possibilities. One’s facticity may always be characterized by the they; but
insofar as we can choose new possibilities on the ground of that facticity, we also choose
268
the facticity as the ground of those possibilities. There can be no existing into the future
without a past, which is at least part of what conscience discloses. Only in inauthenticity
can Da-sein flit from possibility to possibility detached from a past it forgets; but it is
only when it does so that it fails to retrieve its having-been and it thus lets itself be
to. Heidegger insists that resoluteness brings us to action, but it might seem that the
action in question is meaninglessly abstract. In response, Heidegger insists that “the call
of conscience does not dangle an empty ideal of existence before us when it summons us
to our potentiality-of-being, but calls forth to the situation,” which resoluteness both
discloses and places itself into. (300) What he says concerning the situation is not entirely
clear. We learn, for example, that in the situation Da-sein “becomes free of the
entertaining ‘incidentals’ that busy curiosity provides for itself, primarily in terms of the
events of the world.” (310) And the situation cannot be available to the they, which
“knows only the ‘general situation,’ loses itself in the nearest ‘opportunities,’ and settles
its Da-sein by calculating the ‘accidents’ which it fails to recognize, deems its own
achievement and passes off as such.” (300) What are these “accidents” that the they
deems (mistakenly) its own achievement? The suggestion, I gather, is that the they does
entirely on the basis of “calculating,” and doing what one does, rather than what is called
269
for. But there is a more interesting suggestion here, which I will return to shortly: that the
they takes its responses to the situation as its own achievements, as something it has
accomplished, when in fact no one has accomplished anything: the they, seeing only the
“general situation,” that is, seeing each situation as falling under a type in which one does
context of his account of Nicomachean Ethics, Bk. VI. He refers to Aristotle’s notion that
the phronimos acts in the right way, with regard to the right people, using the right things,
and so forth. “These circumstances characterize the situation in which Dasein at any time
finds itself…In this way, Dasein, as acting in each case now, is determined by its
situation in the largest sense. The situation is in every case different. The circumstances,
the givens, the times, and the people vary. The meaning of the action itself, i.e., precisely
what I want to do, varies as well.” (Heidegger 1997 100-101) The situation is, there,
disclosed by phronesis, which guides Da-sein to its resolution or decision and through
action. “In every step of the action, phronesis is co-constitutive.” (1997 101) In Being
and Time, however, resolution is seen as disclosing the situation, whereas Umsicht,
context. Especially since Kisiel’s The Genesis of Heidegger’s Being and Time, these
points have led to a common, and not entirely unwarranted speculation that resoluteness
is Heidegger’s taking up of Aristotelian phronesis.79 But to what extent and in what way?
79
For a dissenting voice, see Sadler (1996 150), who argues that Heidegger’s fundamental disagreement
with Aristotle about the relative standing of phronesis with regard to sophia, his alterations in translation of
key terms, and his general tendency to appropriate other thinkers in ways uniquely his own, makes the
thesis of Nic Ethics’s direct influence on the content of Heidegger’s philosophy (as opposed to its method)
highly suspect.
270
Dreyfus (2000a), for example, typically sees resoluteness as phronesis in the
sense of skill acquisition: the virtuoso is one who always does the right thing within the
situation because he has progressed beyond (even internalized) rule application. But
Dreyfus now grants that resoluteness allows Da-sein to recognize the contingency of its
thrownness and thus go beyond the they in solving problems; anticipatory resoluteness,
cultural heritage, thus allowing for something radically new. This takes us rather far
beyond skill acquisition, and certainly further than Carman’s view of resoluteness,
according to which “resolute agents… maintain a subtle feel for the situations they
confront and so are able to deal with them intelligently, skillfully, with finesse.” (Carman
2006 234) This is not wrong, but it seems grossly incomplete; and, as in Dreyfus’s
account, Carman seems to take the relation between anticipation and resoluteness as more
or less contingent, related only by the fact that “what the two notions have in common…
is precisely their emphasis on finitude and particularity,” allowing Da-sein to avoid being
like this.” (Carman 2005) These accounts fail to do justice to the intimate connection
between anticipation and resoluteness (especially since the former is intended to make
sense of the latter), the relation of anticipatory resoluteness to temporality (in Carman),
and especially its role as an account of self-ownership (in Dreyfus, though Carman’s
Recall that Heidegger describes the authentic future in terms of Da-sein coming
toward itself (325) and the authentic past as its coming back (326). But when Da-sein
271
comes back to itself on its way toward itself, where does it head? “Resolute being
together with what is at hand in the situation, that is, letting what presences in the
present.” (326) The pattern is a repetition of the earlier account of conscience: Da-sein
calls to itself in the they, and calls it to what? To the situation! This should look puzzling
to commentators, though often it apparently does not. But clearly something odd is afoot:
Heidegger repeatedly refers to Da-sein in the past and future, but brings up the situation
in the present. Is the situation, then, Da-sein’s authentic present? There are, no doubt,
some vestiges of Aristotle: in acting, the phronimos exercises his virtue, both expressing
and maintaining his character. And Heidegger, too, notes that the situation is not merely
the context in which Da-sein can act, but rather one in which it is “already acting.” (300)
And this should remind us of the Sophist claim, above, that Da-sein, in acting, “is
determined by the situation.” Since Da-sein, as care, is always involved with entities, is
always circumspectly dealing with them, its acting and its being are co-constitutive.
So what is the point of the situation? Why would Heidegger spend so much space
Recall that Da-sein necessarily understands itself and world together. It is inauthentic
when it understands itself in terms of world; authentic when it understands itself in terms
of itself. But this sounds like the exact opposite of being determined by the situation. So
incidental “new” possibilities; in the they, it acts in an unowned way by simply retaining
272
what it has been given on the basis of possibilities laid out for it. As authentic, or owned,
Da-sein can be determined by the situation, which is unified rather than broken down into
world. “When one is absorbed in the everyday multiplicity and rapid succession of what
is taken care of, the self of the self-forgetful ‘I take care of’ shows itself as what is
constantly and identically simple, but indefinite and empty.” The self is “unified” only in
a completely empty way; but “the constancy of the self means nothing other than
anticipatory resoluteness.” (322) Da-sein has a constant self—we might say it constitutes
Unlike a now, which can last forever—is “now” this minute? this day? this year?
it’s length is entirely indefinite, as Augustine had already noted—the Augenblick has no
duration; it allows the past and present to meet, so that Da-sein, in taking over the
situation that determines its action, can let itself be so determined on the basis of its
freely having chosen itself in light of its ownmost possibility. Since its future is entirely
open as possibility, and from it it comes back to itself to take up its having-been as its
choice, Da-sein is not determined either by the weight of what it retains nor by any
definite aim. In letting itself be determined by the situation, Da-sein paradoxically avoids
any kind of determinism, because the situation is its own: “It gives itself the actual
factical situation and brings itself into that situation… It is disclosed only in a free act of
resolve that has not been determined beforehand, but is open to the possibility of such
is disclosed entirely without the they—Da-sein frees itself; and relative to the situation it
can (and, authentically, must) always retrieve itself anew in light of its anticipation: it
273
holds itself in the certainty of what the situation demands, and this, “as a resolute holding
oneself free for taking back, is the authentic resoluteness to retrieve itself.” (308)
be required in the situation. Thus the steadiness of existence is not interrupted, but
constancy in which it remains faithful to itself and its self-understanding as possibility. Its
self-constitution does not bind it to any concrete commitment in terms of which it must
then go on to define itself, but rather allows it to be open to the demands of the situation,
so that it is always prepared to take back its attachments when needed. It is individualized
and whole, so that its actions express its will, the background through which—on the
unconditioned, because as thrown, Da-sein must take up its ground and exist from it, and
it can understand that ground as chosen on the basis of its ownmost possibility, thus
making it its own. As whole, Da-sein can make sense of and transform its past—not, of
course, in the sense of changing the facts of that past, but in letting its past as having-
been determine its future only in light of that future, as meaningful only relative to that
future. What openness to the future dictates in the present resolve is, of course,
the concrete situation in which Da-sein, in acting, can be what it is. As Heidegger
famously wrote in an approving defense of Kant, the question of what one must will in
adherence to the fact of reason is answerable thus: “Everyone who actually wills knows:
to actually will is to will nothing else but the ought of one’s existence.” (2002 196)
274
In willing, as opposed to merely wishing and awaiting in the mode of the they,
Da-sein owns itself. The possibility of owning itself is already present in its always-
mineness, which, as always concerned with its being and under the necessity of becoming
can first take responsibility by retrieving its having-been from its always already having
been chosen. And although it has let the they self choose itself, it can “make up for not
choosing” by reclaiming that choice by letting its past be constituted by the open
possibility of anticipation and the demand of the situation. At the same time, its ability to
To say that Da-sein has a constitutive aim, which it fulfills or fails to fulfill, is to
let it be self-created, in a sense, by being toward its future. But this doesn’t seem to be the
whole story: after all, Da-sein is, for the most part, not authentic. Heidegger frequently
notes that Da-sein is inauthentic, irresolute, and lost “initially and for the most part.”
While commentators differ on whether this means that authenticity can be maintained, or
whether authenticity might not rather play a merely methodological role in the account,
so that it is not even meant to be a possibility Da-sein can live in (Staehler 2008),
Heidegger does seem clear that Da-sein does not “achieve” itself in authenticity and
remain perpetually in the moment until its demise. And in any case, authenticity requires
someone who wants to have a conscience may become responsible, but what about the
rest of us?
275
Recall that Da-sein has let the they take over its choice, not in the sense that the
they forced it to choose its possibility, but rather in that Da-sein itself—as a they-self—
chose in the mode of the they. That Da-sein has always already chosen itself is disclosed
in authenticity and covered over in inauthenticity. And only authenticity allows Da-sein
to understand itself as being-possible and to take over its ground as having-been. But Da-
sein always takes over its ground, because it always exists as possibility, though it may
understand itself in terms of innerworldly entities and thus lose itself, forgetting that it is
never actuality, and letting the they direct it into frivolous and ever-changing
responsibility, a process that is temporal but not historical: after all, taking responsibility
in this sense is not a one-time affair that gives rise to responsibility for future actions.
Instead, it is the co-constitutive past dimension of all agency in the Moment, in light of
But taking responsibility in this sense is not a prerequisite for being responsible.
always under the necessity of defining oneself essentially. This disclosive component of
not always concerned with its being and under the necessity of taking up its thrown
ground into its possibility, and if it were not thus responsible for the possibility as which
the situation is not necessary for being responsible. Rather, being responsible is the
condition of possibility for taking responsibility and owning oneself. On the other hand,
276
self-ownership discloses Da-sein as responsible, which is why it cannot be bypassed in an
autonomous action, insofar as owning ourselves allows for a distinction between what is
properly ours and what is not and autonomy requires self-government. Inauthentic Da-
sein, failing to make the distinction, is always governed by norms that are not its own
because it exists as unowned. But responsibility need not hinge on the exercise of
On the one hand, then, Da-sein is always already pressing forth into its
possibilities and existing as these possibilities: it constitutes itself in acting in the world.
On the other hand, in understanding itself in terms of itself rather than world, Da-sein
takes ownership of itself and defines its being in terms appropriate to the sort of entity it
is. Because it is concerned about its being and must define itself through projective
Heidegger calls it, or a constitutive aim of its pressing forth into possibilities. This aim,
however, is the aim of Da-sein’s being as such, which is defined by its so pressing forth,
that is, in action. But the aim is not, as in the standard constitutivist accounts, an aim
aim of Da-sein’s existence as being-possible, on the basis of which choice, action, and
deliberation can occur. Of course there is a further question—in the constitutivist mode—
about whether any norms that are still remotely recognizable as ethical norms can be
derived from this aim. But I cannot see why deriving norms from “willing the ought of
80
Kant, of course, did not think responsibility is co-extensive with autonomous action. One acts
autonomously only when acting on the moral law (that is, according to duty and from duty), but
responsibility hinges only on our being able to conform to the law.
277
one’s existence” should be especially complicated compared with deriving norms from
can act in light of a self-constituted will that it has been in the past and takes up in light
of the future, and its present actions and choices are in turn constituted by this prior
choosing, which attempt to establish self-constancy from temporal nows rather than from
adherence to a temporal unity in the Moment. The account is thus closer to Frankfurt’s
defense of self-acquiescence: in action, Da-sein does acquiesce to the self it has already
chosen in anticipation. But this self is not fixed by volitional necessities, which cannot be
violated without ceasing to be the self that it is: being free to take back its commitments
in response to the demands of the situation is what allows for self-constancy: a self bound
to particular volitions or commitments even in the face of good reasons to abandon them
lacks constancy because its actions are always guided by necessities rather than by its
81
I note here that Velleman does not exactly think that we can derive ethical norms from self-
understanding. Rather, he believes that in aiming for self-understanding, we automatically place ourselves
under more or less contingent norms. Moral philosophy is a post-facto attempt to grasp those norms.
278
7
Conclusion
finally, in Chapter 5, I described the will more concretely—though still vaguely—as the
articulation (again, not necessarily verbal or explicit) of character, that is, the background
of responses to solicitations in the world. In that account, the will was constituted by the
affordances can solicit us—but these turned out to be entirely subservient to the they. The
question therefore arose of how we can take ownership of these possibilities and, thus, of
the will. I argued that coherence and conscious deliberation are both unsuitable for
providing a genuine account of self-ownership and that even Fischer and Ravizza’s
events, and attitudes making up the will in light of which those choices first appear as
choices and must be resolved. And I defined deep temporality as an account in which at
least one of the attitudes is not—or does not have as a starting point—an event on a
timeline. I then argued, or at least attempted to make plausible, that both compatibilism
and libertarianism run aground in part because they are temporally shallow accounts: they
279
present both the choices and their underlying attitudes as events occupying a single
timeline. And I suggested that deep temporality coupled with ownership could point the
eliminativism: that agency seems to be excluded either if the agent’s choices are not
conditioned by his will, or if his will is itself conditioned by prior events, whether or not
those events are choices. The schematic solution to this problem goes as follows.
Our choices are conditioned by our will, since they necessarily take place against
And our will is chosen, but it is not chosen by the sort of choice, in time, that issues from
that will. There is no time in which such a will-forming choice occurs. The point is not
that at some instant in time we choose ourselves, but that we have always already chosen
ourselves. We know that we have always already chosen ourselves because we are
always ahead of ourselves—we exist as open possibility and not as fixed entities with
And since anticipation discloses to Da-sein its being as a whole, it can retrieve its initial
choice as choice. What I have been, in other words, is constituted by what I aim to be. So
on the one hand, this account satisfies the condition that the agent’s choices must arise
from the will rather than the other way around, since what we do in the world depends on
the will we have. On the other hand, the will is not conditioned by any prior events. Nor
is it already pre-given, as something we find ourselves with and must act in light of: we
take up our past in light of the anticipation of the future, not the other way around.
Therefore, whatever I have already chosen, it does not necessitate what I do, since my
280
Along with attributionism, we can claim that we are directly responsible for what
we do and what attitudes we have regardless of whether or not we have made a conscious
representative or expressive of the self because they issue from the self’s projected
possibilities, and they are just as representative or expressive of those possibilities as our
conscious deliberation which, after all, takes place within the same background. In
inauthenticity, of course, we can say that both the subpersonal mechanisms and the
conscious deliberations are reflective rather than expressive of the agent. But this does
not eliminate responsibility: in both cases, world and self are co-constitutive. The
difference is in whether the self understands itself and its world in its own terms, or
whether it understands itself in terms of world. And while this may make a difference to
whether or not an agent takes or accepts responsibility, it does not make a difference to
whether the agent can take or accept responsibility, that is, to whether or not the agent is
of authenticity that allows us to own our wills and, moreover, provides a vantage point
from which we can see that we are directly (absent either conscious deliberation or
history) responsible for our actions and attitudes because we have chosen the will that
they stem from. The Medievals were right: we are free by virtue of having a will. But we
are not free because our will is always in its own power as such; we are free because the
that the self, seen as a part of the natural world, seems to simply dissolve into that world
281
agents out of the loop. How can we be free and responsible on this picture? I suggested in
Chapter 2 that this question, when asked, necessarily appears as self-deception, and
Augustine noted long ago that “the only reason that most people are tormented by this
question is that they do not ask it piously; they are more eager to excuse than to confess
their sins.” (1993 73) That in itself does not, of course, mean they are wrong: seeking an
excuse perhaps increases the chance that one will make an error in one’s own favor, but it
does not guarantee such an error. On the other hand, the strength of Heidegger’s account
casts itself as one of them. The idea that our agency might simply be reduced to the
agency of the world, taking away our freedom and responsibility, misconstrues our
essence. The authentic self, indeed, does let itself be determined by the world in a sense;
but it is precisely when it does so that it is most fully self-determined, because it retrieves
On a final note, we may ask: even if the Heideggerian account might offer a
determinism? A thoroughgoing naturalist is likely to say no. But the fact that
thoroughgoing naturalists are unlikely to accept that causality itself can only be disclosed
to an entity that has the temporal structure of anticipation and retention should not rule
out the possibility of offering a response to causal determinism; it rules out only the
possibility of convincing some determinists. But with some other determinists, there can
be a dialogue. One of the strongest defenders of hard determinism, Ted Honderich, has
282
recently suggested a model he thinks would allow, in some sense, for a reconciliation
between determinism and the sense of our lives as individual and our own. Though
Honderich rejects the Kantian noumenal self, he suggests that we may draw on a
similarly radical idea, one that involves, roughly, a theory of perception on which
perceived objects are, literally, constituted by the atoms making up the objects together
with our neuronal structure; this view of consciousness allows for a view of personal
consciousness as well, which will depend uniquely on our own neural framework rather
than the shared one that contributes to constituting the public world. And even if (or,
rather, even though) determinism is true, this view of perceptual consciousness “explains
your sense of your life as a sense of something for which you are accountable and also
something that is individual.” (Honderich 2002 151) This idea does not make sense; even
if the public world depends on each individual’s perceptual consciousness, and each
individual’s perceptual consciousness is unique, that can explain at best how our lives
and worlds depend on our unique neural architecture, but it leaves responsibility entirely
unexplained. The strength of the Heideggerian account is precisely that the world does
involve always pressing forth into them. We project our possibilities in agency. And it is
283
References
Aristotle. 2009. The Nicomachean Ethics. Translated by D. Ross. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Arpaly, Nomy. 2003. Unprincipled virtue : an inquiry into moral agency. Oxford ; New
York: Oxford University Press.
Arpaly, Nomy, and Timothy Schroeder. 1999. Praise, Blame and the Whole Self.
Philosophical Studies 93 (2):161-188.
Ayer, A. J. 1982. Freedom and Necessity. In Free Will, edited by G. Watson. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Bernard. 1920. The Treatise of St. Bernard Concerning Grace and Free Will. Translated
by W. W. Williams. New York: The Macmillan Company.
Blattner, William D. 1992. Existential Temporality in Being and Time (Why Heidegger is
not a Pragmatist). In Heidegger: A Critical Reader, edited by H. L. Dreyfus and
H. Hall. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
———. 1994. The Concept of Death in Being and Time. Man and World (27):49-70.
———. 1996. Existence and Self-Understanding in Being and Time. Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research (56):97-110.
———. 2006. Heidegger's Being and Time: A Reader's Guide. London: Continuum.
Boedeker, Edgar C. 2001. Individual and Community in Early Heidegger: Situating das
Man, the Man-self, and Self-ownership in Dasein's Ontological Structure. Inquiry
(44):63-100.
284
Bracken, William F. 2005. Is There a Puzzle About How Authentic Dasein Can Act?: A
Critique of Dreyfus and Rubin on Being and Time, Division II. Inquiry 48
(6):533-552.
Bratman, Michael. 2001. Two Problems About Human Agency. Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society 101 (3):309-326.
Chisholm, Roderick. 1966. Freedom and Action. In Freedom and Determinism, edited by
K. Lehrer. New York: Random House.
———. 1982. Human Freedom and the Self. In Free Will, edited by G. Watson. New
York: Oxford University Press.
Clarke, Randolph. 1993. Toward a Credible Agent-Causal Account of Free Will. Nous 27
(2):191-203.
Davidson, Donald. 1980a. Actions, Reasons, and Causes. In Essays on Actions and
Events. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 1980b. Agency. In Essays on Actions and Events. New York: Oxford University
Press.
———. 1980c. Freedom to Act. In Essays on Actions and Events. New York: Oxford
University Press.
———. 1980d. How is Weakness of the Will Possible? In Essays on Actions and Events.
New York: Oxford University Press.
285
———. 1980e. Intending. In Essays on Actions and Events. New York: Oxford
University Press.
———. 1980f. Mental Events. In Essays on Actions and Events. New York: Oxford
University Press.
———. 1980g. Psychology as Philosophy. In Essays on Actions and Events. New York:
Oxford University Press.
———. 2005. Overcoming the Myth of the Mental: How Philosophers Can Profit from
the Phenomenology of Everyday Expertise. Proceedings and Addresses of the
American Philosophical Association 79 (2):47-65.
———. 2007c. The Return of the Myth of the Mental. Inquiry 50 (4):352-365.
Ekstrom, Laura Waddell. 2000. Free will : a philosophical study. Boulder, Colo.:
Westview Press.
———. 2005. Alienation, Autonomy, and the Self. Midwest Studies in Philosophy
XXIX:45-67.
Fischer, John Martin, and Mark Ravizza. 1998. Responsibility and Control. New York:
Cambridge University Press.
Frankfurt, Harry. 1969. Alternate Possibilities and Moral Responsibility. The Journal of
Philosophy 66 (23):829-839.
286
———. 1982. Freedom of the Will and the Concept of A Person. In Free Will, edited by
G. Watson. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 1992. The Faintest Passion. Proceedings and Addresses of the American
Philosophical Association 66 (3):5-16.
———. 1999a. Autonomy, Necessity, and Love. In Necessity, Volition, and Love.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1999b. On the Necessity of Ideals. In Necessity, Volition, and Love. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
———. 2006. Taking Ourselves Seriously & Getting it Right. Stanford: Stanford
University Press.
Freud, Sigmund. 1960. The Ego and the Id. Translated by J. Strachey. New York: W. W.
Norton & Company.
———. 2007. An Action Can be Both Uncaused and Up to the Agent. In Intentionality,
Deliberation and Autonomy, edited by C. Lumer and S. Nannini. Burlington, VT:
Ashgate Publishing Company.
Guevara, Daniel. 2000. Kant's Theory of Moral Motivation. Boulder: Westview Press.
287
Harman, Graham. 2010. Technology, Objects and Things in Heidegger. Cambridge
Journal of Economics 34 (1):17-25.
———. 1996. Being and Time. Translated by J. Stambaugh. Albany: SUNY Press.
———. 2002. The Essence of Human Freedom. Translated by T. Sadler. New York:
Continuum.
Honderich, Ted. 2002. How Free Are You? New York: Oxford University Press.
Hornsby, Jennifer. 2003. Agency and Causal Explanation, edited by A. Mele. New York:
Oxford University Press.
———. 1996. The Significance of Free Will. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2000. Non-Constraining Control and the Threat of Social Conditioning. The
Journal of Ethics 4 (4):401-403.
———. 2008a. The Constitution of Agency. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2008b. Self-Constitution in the Ethics of Plato and Kant. In The Constitution of
Agency. New York: Oxford University Press.
———. 2009. Self-Constitution: Agency, Identity, and Integrity. New York: Oxford
University Press.
288
Lavin, Douglas. 2004. Practical Reason and the Possibility of Error. Ethics 114 (3):424-
457.
Levy, Neil. 2005. The Good, the Bad, and the Blameworthy. Journal of Ethics and Social
Philosophy 1 (2):1-16.
Levy, Neil, and Michael McKenna. 2009. Recent Work on Free Will and Moral
Responsibility. Philosophy Compass 4 (1):96-133.
McDowell, John. 1996. Mind and World. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
———. 2009. Conceptual Capacities in Perception. In Having the World in View, edited
by J. McDowell. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
McKenna, Michael. 2008. Putting the lie on the control condition for moral
responsibility. Philosophical Studies (139):29-37.
Nagel, Thomas. 1986. The View from Nowhere. New York: Oxford University Press.
Nelkin, Dana. 2000. Two Standpoints and the Belief in Freedom. Journal of Philosophy
97:564-576.
Nicholson, Graeme. 2005. The Constitution of Our Being. In Heidegger's Being and
Time: Critical Essays, edited by R. Polt. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield
Publishers.
Okrent, Mark. 2000a. Intending the Intender (Or, Why Heidegger Isn't Davidson). In
Heidegger, Authenticity, and Modernity, edited by M. Wrathall and J. Malpas.
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
289
Pippin, Robert. 2007. Can There Be 'Unprincipled Virtue'?: Comments on Nomy Arpaly.
Philosophical Explorations 10 (3):291-301.
Sadler, Ted. 1996. Heidegger and Aristotle: The Question of Being. London: Athlone
Press.
Scanlon, Thomas. 1988. The Significance of Choice. In The Tanner Lectures on Human
Values, edited by S. M. McMurrin. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.
———. 2008. Who's in Charge Here?: Reply to Neil Levy. Philosophia 36 (2):223-226.
Smith, Angela M. 2005. Responsibility for Attitudes: Activity and Passivity in Mental
Life. Ethics 115 (2):236-271.
———. 2008. Control, Responsibility, and Moral Assessment. Philosophical Studies 138
(3):367-392.
Strawson, Peter F. 1962. Freedom and Resentment. Proceedings of the British Academy
(48):1-25.
290
Stroud, Sarah. 2007. Moral Worth and Rationality as Acting on Good Reasons.
Philosophical Studies (134):449-456.
Talbert, Matthew. 2009. Implanted Desires, Self-Formation and Blame. Journal of Ethics
& Social Philosophy 3 (2).
Taylor, Richard. 1966. Action and Purpose. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall.
van Inwagen, Peter. 1989. When is the Will Free? Philosophical Perspectives 3:399-422.
Vargas, Manuel. 2005. The Trouble With Tracing. Midwest Studies in Philosophy
XXIX:269-291.
Velleman, J. David. 1992. What Happens When Someone Acts? Mind 101 (403):461-
481.
———. 2000. Introduction. In The Possibility of Practical Reason. New York: Oxford
University Press.
———. 2002. Identification and Identity. In Contours of Agency: Essays on Themes from
Harry Frankfurt, edited by S. Buss and L. Overton. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
———. 2009. How We Get Along. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Watson, Gary. 1982. Free Agency. In Free Will, edited by G. Watson. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Žižek, Slavoj. 1993. Tarrying With the Negative. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
291