Kantian Ethics Moral Philosophy Immanuel Kant 4045398
Kantian Ethics Moral Philosophy Immanuel Kant 4045398
Home
Table of Contents
By Emrys Westacott
Updated August 31, 2019
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) is generally considered to be one of the most profound and original
philosophers who ever lived. He is equally well known for his metaphysics–the subject of his
"Critique of Pure Reason"—and for the moral philosophy set out in his "Groundwork to the
Metaphysics of Morals" and "Critique of Practical Reason" (although "Groundwork" is the far
easier of the two to understand).
Moreover, everyone had an incentive to obey these codes. If you “walked in the ways of the
Lord,” you would be rewarded, either in this life or the next. If you violated the commandments,
you'd be punished. As a result, any sensible person brought up in such a faith would abide by
the moral rules their religion taught.
With the scientific revolution of the 16th and 17th centuries that led to the great cultural
movement known as the Enlightenment, these previously accepted religious doctrines were
increasingly challenged as faith in God, scripture, and organized religion began to decline
https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print 1/5
2/12/2020 https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print
among the intelligentsia—that is, the educated elite. Nietzsche famously described this shift
away from organized religion as “the death of God.”
This new way of thinking created a problem for moral philosophers: If religion wasn’t the
foundation that gave moral beliefs their validity, what other foundation could there be? If there is
no God—and therefore no guarantee of cosmic justice ensuring that the good guys will be
rewarded and the bad guys will be punished—why should anyone bother trying to be good?
Scottish moral philosopher Alisdair MacIntrye called this “the Enlightenment problem.” The
solution moral philosophers needed to come up with was a secular (non-religious) determination
of what morality was and why we should strive to be moral.
https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print 2/5
2/12/2020 https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print
If consequences are all that matter, then the millionaire’s action is technically the "better" one.
But that’s not how the majority of people would see the situation. Most of us judge actions more
for their motivation than by their consequences. The reason is obvious: the consequences of our
actions are often out of our control, just as the ball is out of the pitcher’s control once it's left his
hand. I could save a life at the risk of my own, and the person I save could turn out to be a serial
killer. Or I could accidentally kill someone in the course of robbing them, and in doing so might
unwittingly save the world from a terrible tyrant.
By contrast, goodwill, says Kant, is always good—in all circumstances. What, exactly, does Kant
mean by goodwill? The answer is fairly simple. A person acts out of goodwill when they do what
they do because they think it is their duty—when they act from a sense of moral obligation.
What is remarkable about human beings, though, is that we can, and sometimes do, perform an
action from purely moral motives—for example, when a soldier throws himself on a grenade,
sacrificing his own life to save the lives of others. Or less dramatically, I pay back a friendly loan
as promised even though payday isn't for another week and doing so will leave me temporarily
short of cash.
In Kant’s view, when a person freely chooses to do the right thing simply because it is the right
thing to do, their action adds value to the world and lights it up, so to speak, with a brief glow of
moral goodness.
https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print 3/5
2/12/2020 https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print
Saying that people should do their duty from a sense of duty is easy—but how are we supposed
to know what our duty is? Sometimes we may find ourselves facing moral dilemmas in which it's
not obvious which course of action is morally correct.
According to Kant, however, in most situations are duty is obvious. If we're uncertain, we can
work out the answer by reflecting on a general principle that Kant calls the “Categorical
Imperative.” This, he claims, is the fundamental principle of morality and all other rules and
precepts can be deduced from it.
Kant offers several different versions of this categorical imperative. One runs as follows: “Act
only on that maxim that you can will as a universal law.”
What this means, basically, is that we should only ask ourselves, How would it be if everyone
acted the way I’m acting? Could I sincerely and consistently wish for a world in which everyone
behaved this way? According to Kant, if our action is morally wrong, the answers to those
questions would be no. For instance, suppose I’m thinking of breaking a promise. Could I wish
for a world in which everyone broke their promises when keeping them was inconvenient? Kant
argues that I could not want this, not least because in such a world no one would make promises
since everyone would know that a promise meant nothing.
The key to Kant’s belief regarding what makes humans moral beings is the fact that we are free
and rational creatures. To treat someone as a means to your own ends or purposes is to not
respect this fact about them. For instance, if I get you to agree to do something by making a
false promise, I am manipulating you. Your decision to help me is based on false information
(the idea that I’m going to keep my promise). In this way, I have undermined your rationality. This
is even more obvious if I steal from you or kidnap you in order to claim a ransom.
Treating someone as an end, by contrast, involves always respecting the fact that they are
capable of free rational choices which may be different from the choices you wish them to make.
So if I want you to do something, the only moral course of action is to explain the situation,
explain what I want, and let you make your own decision.
ethics?
The answers go back to the problem of religion no longer providing a satisfactory foundation for
morality. What Kant calls humanity’s “immaturity” is the period when people did not truly think for
themselves, and instead, typically accepted moral rules handed down to them by religion,
tradition, or by authorities such as the church, overlord, or king. This loss of faith in previously
recognized authority was viewed by many as a spiritual crisis for Western civilization. If “God is
dead, how do we know what is true and what is right?"
Kant’s answer was that people simply had to work those things out for themselves. It wasn't
something to lament, but ultimately, something to celebrate. For Kant, morality was not a matter
of subjective whim set forth in the name of god or religion or law based on the principles
ordained by the earthly spokespeople of those gods. Kant believed that “the moral law”—the
categorical imperative and everything it implies—was something that could only be discovered
through reason. It was not something imposed on us from without. Instead, it's a law that we, as
rational beings, must impose on ourselves. This is why some of our deepest feelings are
reflected in our reverence for the moral law, and why, when we act as we do out of respect for it
—in other words, from a sense of duty—we fulfill ourselves as rational beings.
https://www.thoughtco.com/kantian-ethics-moral-philosophy-immanuel-kant-4045398?print 5/5