Mark Bevir, Jason Blakely - Interpretive Social Science - An Anti-Naturalist Approach-Oxford University Press (2019)
Mark Bevir, Jason Blakely - Interpretive Social Science - An Anti-Naturalist Approach-Oxford University Press (2019)
Title Pages
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
Page 1 of 2
Title Pages
Impression: 1
Page 2 of 2
Introduction
Introduction
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0001
This book is written for anyone who wishes to understand human behavior
better. Some readers might be students and scholars in the social sciences—
political scientists, sociologists, economists, anthropologists, and psychologists.
Others might be political theorists, philosophers, or free-spirited experts in the
humanities or natural sciences. Still others may be policy analysts, political
actors, and strategists coping with the world of action. But this book is not
merely written for experts and elites. It is also intended for ordinary citizens:
tenacious laypeople, inquisitive undergraduates, curious autodidacts, and
amateur seekers. No one can live for very long without needing to decode and
grasp the behavior of those around them.
Page 1 of 19
Introduction
One purpose of this book is to argue that anyone who really desires to
understand and explain human agency must adopt a “hermeneutic” or
interpretive philosophical perspective. But what is an interpretive approach to
the social sciences? Many people in the social sciences already think they know
the answer. So the most widely read introductions to political science often give
a familiar but misleading reply: namely, interpretivism is a “qualitative” method
favored by researchers who have a squishy, touchy-feely view of the world. This
means interpretivism is just one among various tools (one with a strength for
focusing on the analysis of meanings and beliefs) that social scientists can opt in
or out of depending on their disposition and research goals.1 On this view, an
interpretive approach is basically reducible to activities like conducting long-
form interviews, hunting in archives, beefing up on foreign languages, doing
ethnography, and traveling to foreign countries for case studies. Interpretivism
is instrumental because it is a means for achieving some further research goal or
aim. It is optional because those who do not share a particular research goal can
safely ignore it (much like a piano tuner does not need to bother with a wrecking
ball or a jackhammer).
to vindicate the work of the many brilliant interpretive philosophers and social
theorists of the last century while also critically clarifying for readers how an
anti-naturalist articulation of this philosophy has an impact on nearly every
aspect of social scientific research, from concept formation and methods to
empirical inquiry and public policy. Indeed, so profound is the effect of
interpretive philosophy on the social sciences that it even opens new areas for
empirical study and ethical engagement. Our particular anti-naturalist approach
also sheds light on some of the most important social science findings of the last
fifty years—placing major contributions to our understanding of social,
psychological, economic, and political reality within a coherent philosophical
framework. But we are running ahead of ourselves.
For now the first step is identifying the nature of hermeneutics and the
interpretive turn. This involves discerning what interpretive philosophy is
“turning” away from; what it is rejecting. Indeed, interpretive philosophy
originated as a critical response to the dominant philosophical paradigm in the
social sciences—a movement known to philosophers as “naturalism.” Anyone
who wishes to fully grasp the interpretive turn must first understand the critical
dialogue between hermeneutics and naturalism.
Naturalism’s deepest historical roots reach back to the seventeenth century and
the attempt by a group of European intellectuals to model knowledge of ethical
and political life on the newly emergent revolution in the natural sciences.4
Thomas Hobbes’s Leviathan is a classic, early example of this ambition. Hobbes
opens with a famous attempt to construct a purely materialist psychology of
human sense perception by discussing the way an organ like the eye apprehends
Page 3 of 19
Introduction
Hobbes is only one of the earliest and most influential attempts to found a
science of human behavior modeled on the natural sciences. But many ingenious
forms of naturalism were devised and advanced by intellectuals during the
seventeenth and eighteenth centuries. For our purposes, we do not need to take
a deep dive into naturalism’s past or familiarize ourselves with all its astonishing
varietals. Instead, we only need to focus on the birth of the contemporary social
sciences, and the particular versions of naturalism used to philosophically orient
many of today’s disciplines. The key shift toward the current reign of naturalism
occurred near the end of the nineteenth century, when many intellectuals turned
away from the historical narratives that had shaped the study of politics and
society for a century.6 Specifically, they renounced the nineteenth-century study
of human behavior via grand historical narratives of the development of politics
and society through organic phases.
Page 4 of 19
Introduction
Although they have never disappeared entirely, what is certain is that very few
professional social scientists today are interested in building such culminating,
quasi-organic narratives of the past. To the contrary, the kind of naturalism that
currently dominates the social sciences was born out of a rejection of
developmental historicism in favor of ahistorical and formal modes of
explanation and analysis. Indeed, the naturalists who set up the foundations of
disciplines like political science, economics, and sociology drew on
countertrends in the nineteenth century. One crucial source of the break away
from developmental historicism was utilitarianism. Although utilitarians like J. S.
Mill seemed to accept a developmental view of human liberty, creative
dispositions, and capacities, utilitarianism also provided resources for a more
synchronic study of society. For example, William Stanley Jevons took (p.5)
utilitarianism’s ahistorical notions of rational preference selection as well as its
emphasis on quantification in order to develop a neoclassical theory of
economics. Jevons’ view of economics stressed formalism, mathematization, and
static systems as opposed to grand historical developments and changes.13
Although neoclassical economists sometimes still linked their theories to
historical narratives, a decided shift away from history and toward ahistorical
formalism was taking place.14
Page 5 of 19
Introduction
histories exist in each of the other major disciplines of the social sciences,
meaning that the transformation of political science stands in for a wider
revolution in the human sciences. Interpretivists, as we shall see, are responding
critically to the transformation of the human sciences as a whole.
Finer was symptomatic of a larger trend afoot to modernize the study of politics
by making it more naturalistic. The notion of a nation-state that was expressive
of some basic ethical unity, a Hegelian Geist, a single Whiggish value, or
somehow the culmination of the arc of history was replaced by that of a
government as a collection of competing interests and beliefs. Rather than focus
on history, students of government looked to psychology. Behavior—conceived of
as simply the empirical analysis of human action free of ethical or historical
depth—became central to the study of politics. The concept of behavior as an
ahistorical field of human action would become crucial to all the modern social
sciences.
For example, in England Graham Wallas rejected idealist historicism and tried to
create a political science that relied solely on the quantitative study of (p.6)
behavior, dropping deeper historical meanings.18 Meanwhile in America, Charles
Merriam, one of the key figures in the founding of political science as a
discipline, shared Wallas’s goal of a form of inquiry that used surveys and
statistics to analytically categorize and relate isolated beliefs and actions.
Merriam insisted that the new political science use “instruments of social
observation in statistics” together with “the analytic technique and results of
psychology.”19 His approach helped shape what came to be known as the
Chicago school of political science, which trained many of the leading political
scientists of the next generation.20
The effort to make politics into a more thoroughgoing naturalistic science was
also helped along by the burgeoning interest in survey research. Researchers
like Walter Lippmann focused on aggregating public opinion analyzed in terms
of census data and statistics.21 Major survey institutes began opening at
universities across the country at midcentury.22 These survey institutes sought
to promote the study of public opinion and political behavior as an ahistorical,
Page 6 of 19
Introduction
During this time many universities opened what they dubbed “political science”
departments, which increasingly replaced the historical political studies of the
prior era.23 This is not to say that the new movement to modernize the study of
politics was all of apiece. To the contrary, the new political science was
characterized by certain deep divisions that persist today. The most important of
these was advanced by theorists who had been influenced by a positivist
conception of science. For instance, at the University of Chicago, David Easton
led a growing number of political scientists who believed that the new shift to an
ahistorical, formal political science involved too much collection of facts and not
enough general theoretical explanation. Easton helped advanced the so-called
behavioral revolution in political science in which deductive theories of general,
law-like rules were constructed and subsequently assessed in light of individual
facts.24
Page 7 of 19
Introduction
Page 8 of 19
Introduction
Making this claim does not negate the deeply important differences in methods,
training, and aims embodied by the various empiricist, positivist, and rational
choice branches of contemporary political science. Nor are we trying to suggest
that modern economics is reducible to rational choice. To the contrary, there are
undoubtedly extremely important differences dividing these and many other
research traditions and communities.32 But it does mean that philosophically the
mainstream in these disciplines embodies rival attempts to achieve the
naturalist goal of an ahistorical science of society, and not a full-blown
interpretive alternative. The three-cornered debate between forms of political
science concerned primarily with universal theory building through the use of
large-N statistics versus an idealization of human rationality versus those
concerned with the accumulation of regional case studies in order to induce
certain midlevel correlations and analytic classifications continues to the present
day. What they all share at the philosophical level is the break away from
historical narrative and holistic treatments of meaning, in favor of formalism,
atomism, and units of analysis that remain historically silent. In short, the major
research programs of contemporary political science are heirs to the project of
modernizing the discipline by cleansing it of the noise of interpretive
phenomena. The messy nature of interpreting meanings—its lack of
susceptibility to a fixed method or reduction to a science—remains largely
hidden from view. Rather than the study of politics being concerned with history
and narrative, it is presented as a science closer to the formal quantifications
and ahistoricism of the physical sciences.
This attempt to free (albeit to differing degrees) the study of human life of
strongly historical and thick meaning dimensions forms the main impetus of the
interpretive critique of naturalism across the social sciences. Rather than a
formal, synchronic knowledge, hermeneutics sees the social sciences as
primarily engaged with webs of meaning, beliefs, and significances. Rather than
(p.9) searching for ahistorical correlations, typologies, or causal laws,
hermeneuticists and interpretivists maintain that social science must construct
narratives of the contingency and holistic complexity of the meanings and
cultures comprising social reality. These are all points that will be developed at
length (in Chapters 2 and 3). But this much should be clear: interpretive
philosophy emerges as a repudiation and a turning away from naturalism’s
increasingly dominant conception of social science which was spreading with
astonishing speed throughout the universities of modern society.
naturalism) best clarifies the interpretive turn and helps political and social
scientists achieve a comprehensively distinct research agenda. The goal of this
book is thus to provide a basis for turning away from the highly ingrained and
pervasive naturalism that dominated the twentieth century and continues to
reign supreme in the intellectual culture of modern societies. The research
paradigm presented here is the basis for a transformed conception of the human
sciences—but one that can absorb, learn from, and accept much from the
methodological rigor, empirical research, and investigations currently conducted
by working social scientists. The interpretive turn does not call for wholesale
rejections of current research and findings in the social sciences, but rather for
gaining greater clarity about how to ground, understand, and explain the
growing trove of knowledge about human beings and their societies. What parts
of contemporary social science are accepted, rejected, and reformed by those
undergoing the interpretive turn will become clearer as our argument
progresses. The basic structure of our argument in favor of hermeneutic or
interpretive philosophy will be as follows.
First we offer readers a basic primer in the key philosophical concepts of the
hermeneutic tradition. How should social scientists think about an interpretive
approach to their chosen discipline of social science? What are the basic
features of the interpretive turn that color the other aspects of empirical
research and study? Chapter 2 is devoted to explaining the basic philosophical
concepts and features of the interpretive turn. Philosophical reflection is needed
in order to decide the concepts and forms of reasoning that are appropriate to a
given domain of study. Interpretive philosophy governs the (p.10) approach
social scientists take to research and what kinds of topics they favor. This will be
contrasted with some of the fundamental philosophical assumptions found in
naturalist approaches to social science.
interpretive turn. This is a claim that we hope gains continual nuance and
complexity as layers of argument are added to the thesis in each ensuing
chapter.
How is it the case that an interpretive and anti-naturalist approach informs all
aspects of social scientific research? Chapter 4 is crucial for furthering the claim
that interpretive philosophy is not simply a method that working social scientists
can treat neutrally like a tool that they pick up and put down at will. This is
because the basic ways in which researchers conceptualize social and political
reality can either take naturalist forms or more philosophically defensible anti-
naturalist forms. Concept formation is inescapably philosophical and social
scientists cannot study political reality without making some tacit assumptions
about the relevant concepts. The question then becomes: which concepts are
proper to the human sciences? To answer this question, Chapter 4 draws on
some of the most influential political science methodology literature as well as
top research programs of empirical political science (including critical
discussions of voter behavior, so-called “contentious politics,” democratic peace,
and selectorate theory, to name a few). As part of this argument, readers will
also see how naturalist versus anti-naturalist philosophy is not simply a method
but pervades all aspects of research.
What is the role of methods in interpretive research? After all, most students of
social science today will spend a significant portion of their education and
training learning to become experts in a particular set of methods—statistics and
regression analysis; foreign languages and ethnography; decision theory
frameworks; or various forms of polling, surveys, and interviews. Do
interpretivists need to wed a particular set of methods? We (p.11) have already
proclaimed that we are methodological pluralists. That is, we believe that
researchers can select whichever method or methods best serve their research
interests. This contrasts with naturalism and interpretivism, which are not
methods, but rather philosophical worldviews or approaches. Whereas methods
can be used by social scientists on a completely pragmatic basis depending on
their research goals and the constraints on their time and resources,
philosophical assumptions are omnipresent and inescapable. Chapter 5 draws on
the latest methodological literature in order to elaborate these crucial claims
and show how an anti-naturalist framework justifies multi-methods reigning
supreme. Here we also justify our claim that interpretive social scientists can
make use of what are sometimes dubbed “quantitative” and “qualitative”
methods like mass surveys, random sampling, regression analysis, statistics,
rational choice modeling, ethnography, archival research, and long-form
interviewing. Chapter 5 will also show readers how to avoid naturalist pitfalls
when employing methods in their research. Important to understanding our
discussion of methods is our belief that methodology (or the tools used for
empirical inquiry) is distinct from philosophical questions. Our hope is that our
anti-naturalist approach will help methodological debates take a more
Page 11 of 19
Introduction
Can students and scholars who wish to explain human behavior also engage in
ideological and ethical critique? When and how do values enter into social
scientific research? One of naturalism’s most serious limitations results from its
disavowal of ethical engagement, ideology, political theory, and the critical
analysis of values. Inspired by the natural sciences, naturalist philosophy
encourages social scientists to believe they have no intrinsic contribution to
make in debates over values and ideology. Instead, their research must remain
value-free, an instrumental repository of facts, and never engage in ethical,
ideological, or political criticism. By contrast, most interpretive philosophers
reject this strict dichotomy between facts and values. But once again, our anti-
naturalist framework can clarify the ways in which political and social scientists
are free to engage values if they are so inclined.
Page 12 of 19
Introduction
A few important provisos are necessary, however, before beginning our analysis.
First, as we have already mentioned, our conception of the interpretive turn
allows for philosophical pluralism. The chapters that follow explore the critique
of naturalism and the shift to more interpretive forms of social science. When it
Page 13 of 19
Introduction
comes to this paradigm shift, there is much shared ground among post-
structuralists, phenomenologists, American pragmatists, analytic philosophers,
social constructivists, and others. Different traditions generate a variety of
reasons and arguments for making this turn. Specifically, the interpretive turn
allows philosophical pluralism in the domains of ontology and epistemology.
Readers can accept our case for the interpretive turn and remain either realists
or anti-realists when it comes to ontology; empiricists or anti-empiricists when it
comes to epistemology.34 Indeed, some of the most prominent proponents of the
interpretive turn (especially those hailing from the phenomenological tradition
like Charles Taylor and Hans-Georg Gadamer) have argued that explanation in
political science is based on intrinsic, ontological features of the object of
inquiry. As we will touch on again in later chapters, Taylor famously claimed that
interpretive study in the social sciences is justified by the ontological claim that
humans are “self-interpreting animals.”35 In a different vein, social
constructivists like John Searle and others have made ontological claims about
the nature of institutions as distinct from the brute facts of the natural
sciences.36 But the interpretive turn has also been justified by those who are
more philosophically reluctant to make ontological claims. For example, Ludwig
Wittgenstein and Donald Davidson have emphasized the kinds of explanations
that are appropriate to human behavior as the grammar of a particular
language.37 These linguistic arguments are about the logic of conceptual
languages and not about the nature of being or ontology. Yet other advocates of
the interpretive turn have drawn on pragmatic arguments stemming from John
Dewey.38 This means that our arguments in subsequent chapters withstanding,
the interpretive turn can rest on a variety of philosophical claims: from
ontological claims about how human beings are in reality to linguistic claims
about the grammar or logic of certain language games.39 We leave these
questions for individual readers to decide for (p.14) themselves. What we do
argue, however, is that whatever the fundamental philosophical commitments
generating the interpretive turn, they ought to have a certain general shape and
form. This shape and form is what we call “anti-naturalism.”
The interpretive turn thus allows for a far wider range of philosophical
commitments than many of its own proponents realize. Our anti-naturalist
approach in this book affirms this broad-tent notion of interpretivism that can
embrace positions that otherwise disagree on other key questions in philosophy.
However, this philosophical pluralism has certain necessary limits. There is no
way for us to philosophically affirm naturalism as an acceptable pluralism. This
is because—as will be substantively established in each chapter—naturalism and
interpretivism are fundamentally philosophically incompatible. Both cannot be
affirmed without contradiction.
Getting a little ahead of ourselves, our claim that the study of human behavior
must properly reckon with meanings doesn’t entail that social scientists are
prohibited from the use of statistics, regression analyses, and mass polling if
Page 14 of 19
Introduction
these prove handy for their research. We agree, therefore, with Bent Flyvbjerg’s
argument that determining which methods are appropriate to a research project
depends on exercising judgment within context (Flyvbjerg follows Aristotle in
dubbing this “phronesis”).40 At the level of practical day-to-day research,
mastering particular methods is difficult and time-consuming. Social scientists
currently spend years mastering a method like regression analysis or
ethnographic immersion into a foreign culture. The sophistication of modern
methods means that future social science may need to engage in more
collaborative work across methodological lines for sheer practical purposes in
order to advance certain research goals. Ethnographers and statisticians may
yet learn to work in tandem, and produce insights out of dialogue and
collaboration with one another, as opposed to the closed silos of inquiry that too
often predominate in the modern university. However, all will receive fuller
treatment in the coming pages.
Notes:
(1.) See, for example, David E. McNabb, Research Methods for Political Science:
Quantitative and Qualitative Methods, 2nd ed. (New York: Routledge, 2015) xix,
287–8.
Page 15 of 19
Introduction
2004); Alfred Schutz, The Phenomenology of the Social World, trans. George
Walsh and Frederick Lehnert (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press,
1967); analytic philosophy: Peter Winch, The Idea of a Social Science (London:
Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1958); Hegelianism: R. G. Collingwood, The Idea of
History, ed. T. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon, 1946); American pragmatism: Richard
Bernstein, The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory (Philadelphia, PA:
University of Pennsylvania Press, 1978); New Left Marxism: E. P. Thompson,
“Socialist Humanism: An Epistle to the Philistines,” New Reasoner 1 (1957):
105–43; post-structuralism: Michel Foucault, “The Subject and Power,” in Michel
Foucault: Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2nd ed., eds. Hubert Dreyfus
and Paul Rabinow (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1983); neo-
Aristotelianism: Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, 3rd ed. (Notre Dame, IN:
University of Notre Dame Press, 2007); social constructivism: Colin Hay, Political
Analysis: A Critical Introduction (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2002); Colin
Hay, “Social Constructivism,” in Routledge Handbook of Interpretive Political
Science, eds. Mark Bevir and R. A. W. Rhodes (New York: Routledge 2016), 99–
112; Ian Hacking, The Social Construction of What? (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press, 1999); social material relations: Bruno Latour, Science in
Action (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1987); Andrew Pickering, The
Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency, and Science (Chicago, IL: Chicago University
Press, 1995).
(5.) Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, in Leviathan, with Selected Variants From the
Latin Edition of 1668, ed. Edwin Curley (Indianapolis, IN: Hackett, 1994).
(6.) What follows draws heavily on the work of the scholars in: Mark Bevir, ed.,
Modernism and the Social Sciences: Anglo-American Exchanges, c. 1918–1980
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017).
(7.) See: Mark Bevir, “Political Studies as Narrative and Science, 1880–2000,”
Political Studies 54 (2006): 584–8.
(9.) J. W. Burrow, A Liberal Descent: Victorian Historians and the English Past
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983).
Page 16 of 19
Introduction
(11.) Auguste Comte, The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte, vol. 1., ed. and
trans. Harriet Martineau (London: George Bell & Sons, 1896), 1–18.
(12.) Robert C. Tucker, ed., The Marx-Engels Reader, 2nd ed. (New York: W. W.
Norton & Company, 1978).
(13.) Margaret Schabas, A World Ruled by Number: William Stanley Jevons and
the Rise of Mathematical Economics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press,
1990).
(14.) See: Donald Winch, Wealth and Life: Essays on the Intellectual History of
Political Economy in Britain, 1848–1914 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2009).
(15.) William Everdell, First Moderns (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press,
1997); Theodore Porter, Trust in Numbers: The Pursuit of Objectivity in Science
and Public Life (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995); Dorothy Ross,
The Origins of American Social Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1991), chs. 8–10.
(16.) See the essays collected in: Bevir, Modernism and the Social Sciences.
(19.) Charles Merriam, “The Present State of the Study of Politics (1921),” in
New Aspects of Politics (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1970) 82–3.
(20.) Barry Karl, Charles Merriam and the Study of Politics (Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press, 1974) viii–ix, ch. 8.
(21.) Walter Lippmann, Public Opinion (New York: Harcourt, Brace and Co.,
1922).
(22.) Susan Herbst, “Polling in Politics and Industry,” in The Modern Social
Sciences. Vol. 7 of The Cambridge History of Science, eds. Theodore Porter and
Dorothy Ross (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 577–90.
(23.) James Farr, “Political Science,” in The Modern Social Sciences. Vol. 7 of The
Cambridge History of Science, eds. Theodore Porter and Dorothy Ross
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003), 315.
(24.) David Eason, The Political System (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago
Press, 1953), 24–5, 65–6.
Page 17 of 19
Introduction
(25.) For example: Theda Skocpol, “Bringing the State Back In: Strategies of
Analysis in Current Research,” in Bringing the State Back In, eds. Peter B.
Evans, Dietrich Rueschemeyer, and Theda Skocpol (New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1985), 3–43.
(29.) Margaret Levi, Of Rule and Revenue (Berkeley, CA: University of California
Press, 1988), 198.
(30.) Jon Elster, ed., Rational Choice (New York: New York University Press,
1986); Kristen Renwick Monroe, ed., The Economic Approach to Politics (New
York: Harper Collins, 1991).
(31.) For two seminal examples from economics—the first arguing that
something essential about human behavior is captured by rational choice
modeling, the second claiming that its value is chiefly predictive—see: Gary S.
Becker, The Economic Approach to Human Behavior (Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press, 1976); Milton Friedman, “The Methodology of Positive
Economics,” in The Philosophy of Economics, 3rd ed., ed. Daniel Hausman
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2008), 145–78.
(33.) Hay, Political Analysis, 40; Hay, “Theory, Stylized Heuristic, or Self-
Fulfilling Prophecy?”
(36.) John Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Penguin, 1995);
John Searle, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization
Page 18 of 19
Introduction
(Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2010); Colin Hay, “Social Constructivism,” 99–
105, 110.
(38.) For example: Frank Fischer, Democracy and Expertise (Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2009).
(39.) Mark Bevir, The Logic of the History of Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1999).
Page 19 of 19
Philosophical roots
Philosophical roots
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0002
Page 1 of 28
Philosophical roots
(p.19) The interpretive turn calls on social scientists to radically reform their
approach to the study of social and political reality. Our anti-naturalist
framework synthesizes claims made by phenomenologists, analytic philosophers,
social constructivists, Hegelians, pragmatists, post-structuralists, and many
others who have gone before us in advocating an interpretive turn. At the same
time, anti-naturalist premises can also be used to draw critical contrasts
between our approach and some of the other major advocates of interpretivism.
In the first part of this chapter we introduce readers to some of the basic
philosophical features of the anti-naturalist approach, including meaning holism,
the relationship between beliefs and actions, the self-interpreting aspects of
human agency, the role of the social background, and the importance of history.
Along the way we also show how anti-naturalist philosophy implies social
constructivism, bottom-up studies, and historical explanations (terms which will
be defined).
Page 2 of 28
Philosophical roots
Before we start we need to make one brief point about our use of the term
“naturalism.” In philosophy this term often refers to the overriding authority of
the natural sciences over the social ones.2 But in some areas of sociology and
particularly ethnography, the term “naturalism” instead refers to a rejection of
scientism in favor of beginning from the natural, conversational life-world of
social agents.3 Such a confusing reversal of a word’s usage across academic
communities is unfortunate, especially if it leads to misunderstandings and a
failure to build larger intellectual solidarities. But as long as readers keep in
mind that our use of the word is born out of the philosophy of social science and
not to be confused with other deployments, this basic misunderstanding should
be averted.
Page 3 of 28
Philosophical roots
the principle that “we must understand the whole in terms of the detail and the
detail in terms of the whole” such that there is a circular structure to the “art of
understanding.”5 In other words, this view implies that meanings are not
atomistic and freestanding in nature but rather are the function of holistic
relationships between parts. This holistic nature of meaning is of great
importance to an anti-naturalist approach to social science and we will elaborate
upon it throughout the course of this chapter. Specifically, we will do so by
examining four major assumptions of anti-naturalism: first, that human beliefs
and actions are holistic in nature; second, that these beliefs are subject to
continual change; third, that individuals are always embedded within a larger
social background; and fourth, that history is the horizon of human meanings.
Let us begin by analyzing beliefs and then afterwards consider the case of
actions. Anti-naturalists believe that human beliefs might be understood in light
of the philosophical doctrine of meaning holism—a doctrine that emerged out of
debates in analytic philosophy of language and epistemology (p.21) over the
last century (especially in the later work of Ludwig Wittgenstein) but which has
important consequences for social science research.6 According to meaning
holism, beliefs simply hold no meaning in perfect, atomistic isolation. Rather, the
meaning of beliefs is a function of their place within a wider context or web of
beliefs that sustain and inform them. The status of this hugely important claim
can be clarified with an example that is also pertinent to social science research.
Consider the case of a social scientist who wishes to understand the fascist
slogan “el silencio es salud” (silence is health) expressed by so many Argentines
living under the military junta during that country’s Dirty War.7 At the most basic
level, the very meaning of the slogan el silencio es salud requires some
background knowledge of the meanings of words and grammar in the Spanish
language. Although such background knowledge normally remains tacit to social
inquiry, it is no less true that the content of these beliefs is filled out in relation
to such wider webs of belief. But our inquirer into this fascist slogan cannot stop
at webs of belief concerning the Spanish language. Rather, the meaning of this
belief also needs to be related to the relevant historical and social contexts—
things like Argentine ultra-nationalism in the 1970s and 80s, practices of state
terrorism, the Cold War, and so on. More concretely, this might mean relating
the slogan el silencio es salud to any number of related beliefs that were part of
the Dirty War—beliefs captured in such terms as los desaparecidos, tratamiento,
and vuelo. The point is that because the meaning of particular beliefs is only
Page 4 of 28
Philosophical roots
filled out in relation to other beliefs, social scientists will often need knowledge
not only of the languages but also of the social milieus and ways of life that
inform particular beliefs. Because beliefs are holistic in this way, social scientists
are necessarily involved in an interpretive act—that is in the hermeneutic circle
of relating parts to various wholes.
(p.22) Thus, to return to our example, the explanation for why different
Argentines adopted the authoritarian slogan el silencio es salud will vary
depending on the particular reasons of individuals. So, in one case, an
individual’s reasons for adopting the slogan “silence is health” might be
explained by referring to his belief that Argentina’s national security is being
undermined by noisy dissenters and subversives. For such an individual the
silencing of dissidents in the form of intimidation, torture, and killings is the
“health” of the Argentine nation, ensuring its restoration to greatness and
underwriting a politics of terror. By contrast, another person’s reasons for
espousing this slogan might be very different—for example, driven by the belief
that life is about survival at all costs, and that surviving in a police state means
quietly conforming to the will of the powerful. In such a case, this slogan might
be held ironically to mean that one’s own silencio is necessary for preserving
one’s own salud. The crucial point for social science is that the reasons for
espousing this slogan change along with the varying web of supporting beliefs.
And as meaning holism would lead us to expect, a change in the relevant web of
beliefs can also lead to important shifts in the very meaning of the slogan (i.e.,
from a fascist expression of terroristic intimidation to a cowardly and ironic
expression of self-preservation).
Page 5 of 28
Philosophical roots
Anti-naturalists therefore insist that the holistic nature of beliefs renders social
science an interpretive discipline—one in which meanings are ascertained
through the hermeneutic circle of relating parts to wholes. At its furthest
extreme, the consequence of abandoning holism is that there is no access
whatsoever to a slogan like el silencio es salud. But a more common error among
contemporary social scientists is to isolate a given belief from the relevant webs
that inform it. For instance, social scientists might mistakenly rush to assume
the expression el silencio es salud means the same thing across a subset of
individuals, when in fact the meanings are quite different. Such a lack of
sensitivity to the holistic nature of beliefs is essentially a failure of
interpretation. But it is also a failure to properly achieve social science. The
lesson for social scientists is that in order to keep their research and findings
from the warping effects of wrongly imposed meanings, they must cultivate a
heightened awareness of the holistic nature of particular beliefs. That is, they
should be careful not to rush to the conclusion that beliefs that at first blush
appear the same necessarily translate across different webs. The latter also
means that anti-naturalists tend to prefer inquiries into social reality that are
sensitive to belief formation at the local level, working from the bottom up. As
we will see in Chapters 5 and 7 on methods and historical sociologies, this
doesn’t mean that social scientists cannot make grand generalizations, use mass
surveys, or employ large-N statistics in their explanations. It simply means that
whether they work on small or large-scale studies, they will need to remain
sensitive to the way that beliefs are formed in local contexts and thus be aware
that all generalizations (p.23) form from the bottom upward and are not to be
ahistorically imposed by the social scientist from the top down.
The problem with this response, however, is that it involves a faulty conception
of human action. Anti-naturalists hold that actions are not simply brute givens
that can be plainly observed. Rather, actions are expressive of beliefs, and so no
less holistic than beliefs themselves. Specifically, anti-naturalists hold that
beliefs are constitutive of actions, such that changes in belief can transform the
identity of actions.
How is this so? One way that anti-naturalists commonly argue for the
constitutive relationship between beliefs and actions is by drawing a basic
distinction between actions versus movements. Take, for example, the
Page 6 of 28
Philosophical roots
One crucially important aspect of our discussion so far is that both actions and
beliefs are a function of the human capacity for self-interpretation. Because
beliefs always come bundled in webs, when individuals alter and modify one
belief it has the power to alter and modify the meaning of related beliefs and
actions. And there are at least two important consequences of self-interpretation
for social scientific research.
Page 7 of 28
Philosophical roots
The importance of this point for social science is that rendering beliefs and
actions intelligible requires placing them in the context of such enacted
sequences. A person may have adopted the slogan el silencio es salud on a
particular occasion because he hopes to avoid being persecuted by his
neighbors, while another might express it repeatedly in pursuit of his goal of
bullying those around him into political conformity and complicity. Beliefs and
actions occur within a wider narrative stream, such that social scientists are
faced with the task of constructing narratives about actual, lived-out narratives.
What they do not face is a series of isolated facts upon which they impose a
narrative for aesthetic or some other reasons of their own.12 (p.25) Rather, the
stories told by social scientists succeed or fail, to varying degrees, in capturing
the enacted sequences of beliefs and actions that are the ongoing stuff of social
life. A story explains a given slice of social reality. Sometimes a social scientist’s
story will reinforce, sometimes extend, sometimes question, sometimes
contradict the conscious, official stories told by those studied. But making sense
of human beliefs and actions requires some sense for the spontaneously
narrative dimension of human agency itself. Explanation in the social sciences—
as in history and literature—is narrative.
Page 8 of 28
Philosophical roots
Because human beings hold beliefs for particular reasons, those beliefs are
vulnerable to change whenever the supporting webs of belief are challenged,
pressured, invalidated, or in any other way presented with dilemmas. Dilemmas,
in this sense, are any authoritative understanding that puts pressure on existing
beliefs. Because new beliefs can be generated by any experience, any experience
is capable of generating a dilemma. Thus, dilemmas in our sense of the term
mark the entry of any new belief or beliefs that challenge an existent web, and
can set off all kinds of revisions from the utterly trivial to the dramatic and life
changing. The anti-naturalist concept of a dilemma is therefore helpful for social
scientists seeking to explain why humans alter their beliefs in particular cases.
To say that humans hold beliefs for specific reasons is not the same as
subscribing to a rationalist view of the human mind in which every belief has
been subject to systemic rational interrogation. On the contrary, reasons are
often loosely, inconsistently, or vaguely held as simply an inherited way of being
in the world or a form of embodying certain understandings.13 Readers should
make no mistake: interpretive philosophers in general, and anti-naturalists in
particular, are not committed to some ultra-rationalist conception of the human
mind or social life. Rational is being used here in a very weak sense to simply
indicate beliefs and actions that are the result of other beliefs, reasons,
intentions, and desires.
Page 9 of 28
Philosophical roots
Of much more central concern to social scientists, however, are the pathological
effects of ideology, repression, rogue desires, and other like phenomena which
interact and enmesh with normal belief formation. Such distortions of belief can
be understood as forms of self-deception—that is, as changes in belief that are
driven by unacknowledged or hidden motives. The cause of such repressed
changes in belief might be a hidden desire, physical need, or reason that leads
the individual to form an entire sub-system or web of inauthentic rationalizing
beliefs, while remaining unaware of the unconscious driving motive.15 For
example, a social scientist might try to argue that a given group’s belief in
libertarian ideology as a highly rationalized system of meanings might reflect a
post-hoc justification for an underlying, not fully acknowledged desire to retain
disappearing class privileges.16 Famously, Fyodor Dostoevsky’s novel Demons
catalogued an enormous variety of such unacknowledged reasons or beliefs
generating commitments to the increasingly radical political ideologies of late
nineteenth-century Russia.17 The point is not whether any of these cases of
ideological distortion are persuasive on their own account. Rather, the point is
philosophical: that some systems of belief are accommodated within an existing
web of beliefs in a normal way while nonetheless being distinguished by the fact
that the change is driven by a pathological process or repressed motive (i.e.,
some hidden need, desire, or unacknowledged reason).
For a clear case of this phenomenon consider the Nazi or “Aryan physics”
developed by Philipp Lenard and Johannes Stark, two world-renowned (p.27)
physicists and Noble laureates. In such a case, a social scientist might wish to
argue that Lenard’s and Stark’s development of this Aryan physics was distorted
by a repressed or unacknowledged motive that led them to unreasonably
discount the contributions of Jewish physicists like Albert Einstein. Social
scientists could argue that although otherwise excellent in their field, Lenard
and Stark developed a sub-system of rationalizing beliefs (i.e., Aryan physics)
that were driven by an irrational resentment and unwillingness to accept Jewish
contributions to human culture and science. Note that in such a case the
acquisition of anti-Semitic beliefs might still be explained in dilemmatic terms.
But the important difference is that the motivating force of such a sub-system of
rationalizing beliefs remains self-deceptively operative. So, where Lenard and
Stark might have thought Aryan physics was simply another way of saying
“good” or “proper” physics, a social scientist could claim that they were in fact
carrying out the development of a system of beliefs under a kind of false
consciousness or inability to see the true, distortive sources of their own
thoughts. This suggests that social scientists might explain ideology, neurosis,
and other forms of distorted rationalization as cases of self-deception (one of
Dostoevsky’s literary obsessions).
Page 10 of 28
Philosophical roots
The social background is a source of stability and regularity that also places
strong limits on human autonomy. It is composed in part out of complex matrices
of practices and inter-subjective beliefs. Practices are any collective or shared
pattern of human action that remains relatively stable across time. Democratic
elections, car ownership, duels, the English language, chess tournaments, social
networks, holiday shopping, and even various forms of warfare are all examples
of practices. That is, they are all stable forms of patterned action into which
individuals are socialized.
Page 11 of 28
Philosophical roots
bring the inter-subjective beliefs that inform his practice into articulacy,
nevertheless he is sharing in the expression of a certain conception of freedom,
individuality, sovereignty, and so on. Likewise we often make use of our language
in patterned ways, without being able to bring into full articulacy the shared
meanings and beliefs that inform our words or grammar. So, for example, a man
might be quite fond of the adage “time is money,” and repeat it often, while
being unable to give full articulacy to the inter-subjective beliefs and practices
that make this adage attractive to him (e.g., the emergence of capitalism, the
Protestant-Calvinist ethos of individual productivity, neoliberal notions of
efficiency, etc.).
The social background thus helps comprise the particular worlds within which
individuals are socialized. Some philosophers have been so impressed by the
inescapability of the social background that they have argued human agency is
essentially determined or limited by it. In Chapter 3 we will argue that such
views (particularly among post-structuralists) have gone astray and that our
anti-naturalist framework offers a better conceptual basis for studying social
science. For now it is enough to emphasize that we heartily affirm post-
structuralism’s insistence that individuals are not autonomous over the
meanings they express and that the social background should never be
neglected in the study of society and politics. We also affirm the tremendous
genius and creativity of Michel Foucault in particular in studying such
background matrices of meaning.
(p.29) But why are individuals limited in their autonomy by the social
background? Individuals are not fully autonomous in terms of their meanings
because some social background is the inescapable starting point for all
individual belief formation. This is not only due to the obvious fact that
individuals are born and socialized into communities of meaning and languages
that precede them. It is also because, as we saw in the case of dilemmatic belief
formation, individuals always form new beliefs against a background of existent
beliefs. Some readers may have noticed that the latter claim presents us with a
kind of paradox. Namely, if beliefs must always exist in webs, then how does
anyone come to hold any one belief in the first place? Wouldn’t they need to
begin with just one belief and then add onto it one belief at a time?
This apparent paradox is dissolved because human beings always inherit a great
number of their beliefs from a particular social background or tradition.19 This is
most apparent in the case of languages, which are never the product of a single
mind, but instead the fruit of a history of social interaction. But it is no less true
of any other domain of life. So, some of us may spend much conscious energy
revising our inherited beliefs within a particular area, say, astrophysics,
automotive repair, or American government. But in most domains we will largely
adopt complexes of inherited beliefs and traditions.
Page 12 of 28
Philosophical roots
Page 13 of 28
Philosophical roots
The fact that contingency can be deployed critically against various forms of
historical determinism does not preclude the power of history to shape and limit
human subjectivity. Indeed, we have already seen that self-interpretive activity
does not entail the absolute autonomy of the human subject. Rather, history has
the power to shape and form particular subjects through the practices and inter-
subjective beliefs that comprise a given tradition or social background.
Page 14 of 28
Philosophical roots
This conception of power allows social scientists to give both critical and
vindicatory accounts of history. So, for example, the genealogies developed first
by Friedrich Nietzsche and later by Foucault are critical histories of the way in
which the past contingencies of history shape, distort, and inhibit present human
practice.23 But likewise, social scientists might instead attempt to vindicate the
shaping power of past traditions or practices and seek to justify their
influence.24 We will have much more to say about the anti-naturalist conception
of genealogy and the important contributions of Nietzsche and Foucault in a
later chapter. For now the point is that anti-naturalists believe history is both
contingent and exercises a certain power over human agents who find
themselves circumscribed within an existing ambit of meanings and practices.
The reader will recall that we began our analysis with arguments about the
holistic nature of beliefs and actions, then noted the role of narratives in
orienting human agency, which itself is embedded in a social background. We
have now seen why anti-naturalism maintains that all these forms of human
meaning are the result of contingent historical change. In this way, individual
beliefs and actions fit in various widening concentric circles with history as their
outermost horizon. Indeed, history is even the horizon that inscribes the beliefs,
practices, and inter-subjective presuppositions of the social scientist.25 To
engage in social science is therefore to seek the explanation of particular
historical processes from within the historical process itself. History—in both its
contingencies and shaping power—marks the horizon of human meanings and
understanding.
Page 15 of 28
Philosophical roots
Naturalists, then, are philosophers, social scientists, and laypeople that assume
that a mechanistic, law-like form of explanation inspired by the natural sciences
is in some senses universal and hegemonic. This assumption is what brings them
into conflict with anti-naturalists. For anti-naturalists are philosophers, social
scientists, and laypeople that assume there is a basic difference in the forms of
explanation appropriate to the human versus the natural sciences. In particular,
anti-naturalists reject various recurrent premises of naturalist research
programs. We will critically examine three (p.33) such recurrent assumptions,
in light of the concepts developed in the first part of the chapter, including the
assumptions that: human beliefs and actions can be treated as a kind of brute
data; human life is governed by causal laws; and the goal of social science is
prediction and social engineering. Having explained why anti-naturalism rejects
these doctrines, our opening exposition of anti-naturalism will be complete.
However, in later chapters we will see just how complex and multi-faceted the
anti-naturalist rejection of naturalism really is. In some senses, each subsequent
chapter will add a new layer to this determinate negation of naturalism.
Page 16 of 28
Philosophical roots
But we have already seen there is a fatal problem with this naturalist attempt.
Namely, meaning is the function of holistic relations that requires entering the
hermeneutic circle. In the case of beliefs and actions, social scientists must
explain them in light of a wider web that links them to further, sustaining
reasons and beliefs, embedded in a particular social background. Meaning is a
holistic set of relations, such that, strictly speaking, perfectly atomized units of
belief and action have no meaning. Verification of brute data is therefore not the
proper model for grasping and explaining beliefs and actions.
In order for critics to show anti-naturalism is mistaken on this point, they might
try to overturn meaning holism, showing that in fact there are pure experiences,
which comprise the foundational units of language. Philosophically speaking,
such critics would have to show that words and concepts directly represent
objects. This would then allow them to argue that human beliefs and actions can
be treated as brute data because they are not holistic in nature, but rather
atomistic bits of language that directly relate to atomistic bits of reality. The
problem with this rebuttal, however, is that so far this move has not been shown
to be a philosophically valid conception of meaning. To the contrary, (p.34) the
philosophical edifice that sustains such atomistic views has more or less
collapsed. Instead, a commonplace within various leading schools of philosophy
today has been the truth of meaning holism.30
There have also been much more recent attempts to reduce meanings to brute
facts. The famed MIT computer scientist, Alex Pentland, has claimed to discover
a predictive science of human behavior he calls “social physics” that is largely
built on the ability to aggregate data on an unprecedented scale. For Pentland
the only obstacle to developing a predictive science of human behavior is having
enough data to capture the complexity of social reality. What the new era of “big
data” offers are the computing tools and data troves (“call records, credit card
transactions, and GPS location fixes, among others”) to finally “view society in
all its complexity” and render human behavior predictable.33 However, from the
above discussion we can see that Pentland’s mistake is philosophical: namely, to
Page 17 of 28
Philosophical roots
neglect the way in which data is not rendered meaningful or explanatory until it
is interpreted within a wider web of meanings and against a historical
background. In this sense, more or less data is neither here nor there in
achieving the naturalist goal of a science of society. Bits of data can be important
to interpretive inquiry but they must be integrated into narratives capturing the
contingency of human belief within a social world. Pentland’s claims on behalf of
“big data” are at best exaggerated.
At present, then, the aspiration toward a total science of human behavior based
on indisputable brute facts remains a goal or hope but not an actual present
reality.34 In the meantime, anti-naturalism is well within its philosophical rights
to continue to see further corroboration of its own views in naturalism’s inability
to produce a brute-data-based science of human behavior. Indeed, one of the
best reasons for social scientists to adopt anti-naturalism is precisely this
inability of naturalism to provide an alternative that does not make recourse to
interpretive forms of explanation. Anti-naturalists have for this reason often
argued that even those who most wish to rid the social sciences of interpretive
influence are in reality thus far unable to ever fully free themselves of its most
basic concepts.35 Hermeneutics (p.35) continues to be inescapable. Even social
scientists who refuse to let it in through the front of the house must secretly let
it in through the back door. Otherwise, their sociological data (big or not) would
be bereft of all meaning.
Page 18 of 28
Philosophical roots
This draws attention to a second, closely related problem with the naturalist
attempt at general laws of explanation—namely, the inadequacy of the concept
of cause that formulating such laws involves. The naturalist conception of cause
is ahistorical in that it attempts to establish the way certain antecedent
conditions are connected to consequent outcomes by a necessary causal link.
General laws thus take the form of “whenever a given set of antecedent
conditions X are obtaining (all other things being equal), a given consequent
event Y follows.” But as we have seen, this necessary causal link runs afoul of
the historically contingent nature of human beliefs. Human beliefs are not the
result of ahistorical causal links, but rather have contingent, context-specific
origins that reflect particular webs of meanings. Because beliefs and actions are
contingent and context specific, we cannot adequately subsume them under
purportedly trans-historical causal mechanisms. The historical contingency (p.
36) that informs belief formation is incompatible with naturalism’s ahistorical
notion of cause.
Page 19 of 28
Philosophical roots
democracy, and public policy. But one egregious example should suffice for
present purposes. The contemporary field of behavioral genetics, which has vied
(albeit not always successfully) for a kind of symbolic power over public policy
and discourse, generates a particular claim to technocracy. According to Aaron
Panofsky’s detailed critique, behavioral genetics has made a power grab that has
been tied to the popular rise of a “geneticized” discourse, in which the broader
public treats genes as fully determinant of human behavior, and a kind of
“astrological genetics” pervades public discourse.39 These claims to genetic
expertise over human behavior have been marshaled to varying ends—by
elements of the American Right to advance racist ideas of intelligence and (p.
37) by sectors of the American Left to scientifically resolve the controversies
over sexual orientation.40 But generally it has been more broadly tied to efforts
to neoliberalize and marketize the public sector by claiming that behavior is
fundamentally individually determined such that social programs attempting to
reshape behavioral outcomes are predictably futile.41
Beyond the many problems with behavioral genetics’ claims to scientific status,
there are at least two deeper philosophical problems with the naturalist goal of
strong prediction. First, it does not in fact seem possible to gain a strong form of
predictive power, and second, when this is linked to a program of social
engineering or technocracy, it becomes anti-democratic and anti-humanistic as a
politics. The predictive goals of naturalism are unlikely insofar as even our most
reliable social science generalizations have not furnished a strong form of
prediction. Some anti-naturalists have attributed this failure to ineliminable
sources of unpredictability within social life—most of these arguments center on
the human capacity to creatively change beliefs and radically innovate in a way
underdetermined by the antecedent set of conditions.42 Nearly all theorists
involved (both anti-naturalists and naturalists) see the question of strong
prediction in the social sciences as ultimately resting on whether determinate,
law-like generalizations governing social reality can indeed be formulated. And
as we have discussed, anti-naturalists believe the prospects of such laws are
unlikely at best because they misunderstand the nature of human beliefs—their
contingency and holism.
set of antecedent conditions. The conditions do not lock belief or action into
place. Rather, because of the human ability to weigh different beliefs, the result
could always have been otherwise than it is. This contingency makes the
formulation of necessary causal laws (and with it strong, scientific prediction) in
the domain of human social and political life impossible.
Indeed, Hay makes a similar point about naturalist uses of rational choice theory
in which social scientists assume that “structure determines agency” because “a
rational actor in a given context will always choose precisely the same course of
action” that optimizes their strategy.46 We will have much more to say (and much
nuance to add) to our views of rational choice theory in later chapters. For now
it is worth noting that this kind of predictive deployment of rational choice
theory is very common in both contemporary political science and especially
economics.47 Yet it falls short of its own goals for similar reasons as other
naturalist approaches—namely, it neglects the contingency of human belief
formation, assuming instead that there are necessary causal mechanisms that
must be the case within certain incentive environments. Hay notes that a big
irony of rational choice used in this way is that what appears to be a theory of
rationality (and thereby freedom) is actually being subordinated to an
“opportunity structure [that] dictates the rational choice…for any agent in any
context.”48 In other words, the rational choice model assumes a predictive
determinacy. Indeed, even indeterminacy in rational choice games is conceived
of naturalistically as dictated by the context itself and not by human creative
agency.49
Page 21 of 28
Philosophical roots
A further irony of the naturalist quest for a strong form of prediction is that anti-
naturalist approaches not only remain better at accounting for the kinds of weak
prediction we in fact have at our disposal when facing social reality, but they are
also able to explain (even predict) the ongoing failure of naturalism to reach its
own goals. So, for example, anti-naturalists are not surprised in the least by the
fact that all major paradigms of international relations failed to predict the
collapse of the Soviet Union.50 Nor are anti-naturalists bewildered by the
ongoing failure of the social sciences from anthropology to economics to achieve
strongly predictive power. Indeed, the most recent empirical studies have found
that social science experts claiming predictive expertise are no better at
predicting phenomena like GDP growth or election outcomes than are well-
informed amateurs or even random algorithms.51 And (p.39) yet despite anti-
naturalism’s superiority in this regard, the allure of the predictive powers
promised by naturalism remains strong. Indeed, the persistence of naturalist
research programs might well have more to do with the promise of such
predictive powers than with its ability to actually deliver on its goals at present.
In this chapter the goal has simply been to argumentatively outline some of the
central philosophical features of anti-naturalism and contrast it with its main foil
—this will provide crucial premises for later arguments. We will see that in fact
the conflict with naturalism is far more complex than this starting point. Anti-
naturalism does not simply challenge naturalism’s philosophical starting points,
Page 22 of 28
Philosophical roots
However, before seeing how this is so, there is still a little more basic
philosophical work to be done. Thus far we have articulated our anti-naturalist
framework by relating our position to the work of other interpretive
philosophers and social scientists. This has helped highlight that there are many
family resemblances across the different philosophical schools pushing for an
(p.40) interpretive turn. However, in Chapter 3 we will turn our attention to the
philosophical differences among thinkers and approaches that are otherwise
unified in their rejection of naturalism. This means examining some of the main
philosophical debates internal to the interpretive turn, which have a major
bearing on social scientific practice. Our claim will be that anti-naturalism is the
best framework on offer, drawing insights from but also contrasting with rival
philosophies justifying hermeneutics and the interpretive turn.
Notes:
(1.) Alex Pentland, Social Physics: How Social Networks Can Make Us Smarter
(New York: Penguin Books, 2014); Auguste Comte, The Positive Philosophy of
Auguste Comte, vol. 1., ed. and trans. Harriet Martineau (London: George Bell &
Sons, 1896).
(2.) For a highly influential early discussion see: Richard Bernstein, The
Restructuring of Social and Political Theory (Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1976) 117–18, 138.
(3.) Yvonna S. Lincoln and Egon G. Guba, Naturalistic Inquiry (Beverly Hills, CA:
SAGE Publications, 1985).
(4.) For one elaboration of this important point see social constructivists like:
John Searle, The Construction of Social Reality (London: Penguin, 1995); John
Searle, Making the Social World: The Structure of Human Civilization (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2010); Ian Hacking, The Social Construction of What?
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1999); Colin Hay, Political Analysis:
A Critical Introduction (New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2002); Colin Hay, “Social
Constructivism,” in Routledge Handbook of Interpretive Political Science, eds.
Mark Bevir and R. A. W. Rhodes (New York: Routledge, 2016) 99–112.
(5.) Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method (second, revised edition), trans.
Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum, 2004) 291.
Page 23 of 28
Philosophical roots
(10.) Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, trans. Joan Stambaugh (Albany, NY:
State University of New York Press, 1996) 292–304; Paul Ricoeur, Time and
Narrative, 3 vols., trans. K. McLaughlin and D. Pellauer (Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press, 1984–8).
(11.) Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue, 3rd ed. (Notre Dame, IN: University of
Notre Dame Press, 2007) 216, 211–12.
(14.) However, it is important to note that even in the case of some overriding
physiological factors, the content of particular beliefs might not necessarily be
fixed. Thus although physiological determinants might pervade and distort belief
formation in predictable ways, just exactly what the content of, say, a given
schizophrenic’s paranoid delusions are might continue to depend on contingent
belief formation (this is, of course, a question for psychologists to determine).
(15.) For further justification of this position see: Mark Bevir, The Logic of the
History of Ideas (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999) ch. 7.
(16.) For an example of something like this claim, see: Nancy MacLean,
Democracy in Chains (New York: Penguin Random House, 2017) 39.
(18.) For a detailed version of this argument, see: Jason Blakely, “The Forgotten
Alasdair MacIntyre: Beyond Value Neutrality in the Social Sciences,” Polity 45:3
(2013): 445–63.
Page 24 of 28
Philosophical roots
(19.) The reader might then wonder if the paradox has not been pushed back on
the entire human species. Would not some generation of homo sapiens need to
have been born without a social background and therefore formed beliefs prior
to any inherited web or tradition? But this again is a false paradox, as it assumes
that inherited traditions are something definite, rather than a phenomenon that
arises along a continuum with other forms of inherited behavior like birds
migrating, chimpanzees cooperating to capture other monkeys, and hunter-
gatherers following weather patterns. For this argument see: Bevir, The Logic of
the History of Ideas, 193–5.
(20.) Gadamer famously argued this case in terms of the necessary role of both
“tradition” and “prejudice” in human understanding: Truth and Method, 265–85.
(21.) Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, 2007) chs. 12–14.
(23.) See for example: Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, trans. Alan
Sheridan (New York: Vintage Books, 1977).
(26.) See, for example, the pragmatist treatment of this by Richard Bernstein,
The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory (Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1976) 117–18, 138.
(27.) For example, compare with Otto Neurath, “Physicalism: The Philosophy of
the Viennese Circle,” in Philosophical Papers: 1913–1946, eds. and trans. Robert
Cohen and Marie Neurath (Boston, MA: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1983) 48;
as well as the manifesto of the Vienna Circle: Rudolf Carnap, Hans Hahn, and
Otto Neurath, “Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung: Der Wiener Kreis,” in The
Emergence of Logical Empiricism, ed. Sahotra Sarkear (New York: Garland
Publishing, 1996) 331.
(28.) A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic, second edition (New York: Dover
Publications, 1952) 48. Despite the pervasiveness of such a sentiment, it is
important to emphasize that naturalism is neither monolithic nor is it an
uncontroversial way to conceptualize the natural sciences. Indeed, there are
those who dispute naturalism is even the correct view of how the natural
sciences carry out their practice. See for example the exchanges between
Hubert Dreyfus, Thomas Kuhn, and Richard Rorty, in David R. Hiley, James F.
Bohman, and Richard Shusterman, eds., The Interpretive Turn (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press, 1991).
Page 25 of 28
Philosophical roots
(32.) This is the importance (beyond mere historical interest) in the dramatic
collapse of early behaviorist psychology, which loomed large over the human
sciences of the early and mid-twentieth century. For a devastating critique of
this research program see: Charles Taylor, The Explanation of Behavior (London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1964).
(33.) Alex Pentland, Social Physics: How Social Networks Can Make Us Smarter
(New York: Penguin Books, 2014) 8, 11.
(34.) Such hope was prefigured (as was so much of naturalism) in the path-
breaking work of the Vienna Circle. It is evident, for example, in the
overcharged rhetoric of their manifesto: “Everything is accessible to man; and
man is the measure of all things…The arrangement of the concepts of the
various branches of science into the constitutive system can already be
discerned in outline today, but much remains to be done.” Carnap, Hahn, and
Neurath, “Wissenschaftliche Weltauffassung,” 328, 331.
(35.) For an extended defense of this claim, see: Jason Blakely, Alasdair
MacIntyre, Charles Taylor, and the Demise of Naturalism: Reunifying Political
Theory and Social Science (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press,
2016) ch. 3.
(36.) See, for example, Karl Marx, “Preface to A Critique of Political Economy,”
in Karl Marx: Selected Writings, ed. D. McLellan (Oxford: Oxford University
Press) 388–91. Of course, Marx is also often read as a historicist. For more on
these two Marxs, see Georg Henrik von Wright, Explanation and Understanding
(London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1971) 7–8, 31–2. For this naturalist
assumption among analytic philosophers see: Ayer, Language, Truth, and Logic,
48; Carl Hempel, “The Function of General Laws in History,” in Aspects of
Scientific Explanation (New York: The Free Press, 1965); Neurath, “Sociology in
the Framework of Physicalism,” in Philosophical Papers. For a historical account
of the importance of Hempel’s views for the “behavioral approach” in
mainstream political science see John Gunnell, Philosophy, Science and Political
Inquiry (Morristown, NJ: General Learning Press, 1975) 65–7, 84.
Page 26 of 28
Philosophical roots
(38.) For example, compare: Hempel, “The Function of General Laws in History,”
234.
(47.) For a famous defense of rational choice modeling as predictive, see: Milton
Friedman, “The Methodology of Positive Economics,” in The Philosophy of
Economics, 3rd edition, ed. Daniel Hausman (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2008) 145–78. For examples of the influence of neoclassical
understandings of rational choice in political science, see: Anthony Downs, An
Economic Theory of Democracy (New York: Harper Collins Publishers
Incorporated, 1957); David R. Mayhew, Congress: The Electoral Connection
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2004).
(51.) Philip E. Tetlock, Expert Political Judgment: How Good Is It? How Can We
Know? (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2005)). For a further
philosophical discussion of this point see also: MacIntyre, After Virtue, ch. 8.
Page 27 of 28
Philosophical debates
Philosophical debates
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0003
Keywords: interpretive turn, anti-naturalism, Edmund Husserl, Alfred Schutz, Michel Foucault, Hans-
Georg Gadamer, Charles Taylor
Page 1 of 23
Philosophical debates
Page 2 of 23
Philosophical debates
enriched sense of what it means to work within the anti-naturalist approach that
builds on the philosophical roots elaborated in Chapter 2.
However, before beginning, one brief disclaimer is in order: namely, our critical
dialogue with thinkers like Husserl, Schutz, and Foucault in this chapter is part
of our wider goal of clarifying certain theoretical points about an anti-naturalist
approach to the social sciences. In this regard, these thinkers serve as points of
contrast to the type of anti-naturalism we wish to promote. But we are perfectly
happy to concede from the outset that Husserl, Schutz, and Foucault are subject
to a wide and plural set of readings. There are multiple Foucaults and Husserls
out there, not just one. Different readings of these thinkers might well render
them closer to the anti-naturalist position we prefer. Indeed, toward the end of
his life, Foucault appeared to be moving toward a more humanistic conception of
agency that we find amenable.2 Our goal here, however, is not a survey of the
rival interpretations of Husserl and Foucault, but rather to philosophically clarify
certain features of anti-naturalism as an approach. These anti-naturalist
positions will be both explicitly and tacitly evoked in the subsequent arguments
made throughout the book.
Subjectivity
All social science assumes some basic view of the human subject. In particular,
how much agency we grant the human subject is of great consequence to our
explanations of social and political life. So, for example, if human beings are
considered little more than cogs in social and political structures, then this will
undoubtedly shape the kinds of explanations we offer about their lives. Likewise,
if we assume individuals are fully autonomous, absolute (p.46) sovereigns over
their beliefs and actions, then our explanations will look accordingly different.
Anti-naturalism is no exception in this regard. It too must come to terms with the
puzzle of how much agency, if any, to credit to the human subject. Within
interpretive debates this problem often arises in the context of questions of
meaning. We have already noted that anti-naturalism views the social sciences
as interpretive because social reality is expressive of meanings in a way that is
not true of the natural sciences. But the many philosophical schools advocating
for an interpretive turn also differ sharply over how to parse the relationship of
the individual subject to these social meanings. Are individual subjects fully
autonomous over the meanings expressed in social and political reality? Or are
the meanings encoded in these realities limiting or somehow determinant of
individual expression?
Page 3 of 23
Philosophical debates
On the other are post-structuralists who argue that systems of social meaning
and discourses severely limit the agency of individual subjects.
The problem with this individually autonomous view of meaning will perhaps be
made clear if we temporarily shift our attention to the opposing camp of
interpretive philosophers—one that rejects individual autonomy in terms of
meaning in favor of an anti-humanistic vision of life. Foucault is widely held to be
the most notable thinker to have arisen out of French post-structuralism and its
famous, anti-humanist call for the “death of the subject.” According to Foucault,
historical inquiry reveals all human subjectivity to be the product of collective
systems of meaning, epistemes, or regimes of power that comprise a given social
background. In Chapter 2 we noted that anti-naturalism holds the view that
humans live against a background of some social inheritance or tradition that
makes belief formation possible. Foucault is (p.47) notable for pushing the role
of the social background to a radical conclusion, arguing that it essentially
abolishes independent subjectivity.6 Thus, during his early “archaeological”
years Foucault argued that researchers should eliminate the role of human
agency from their investigations, instead focusing on epistemes or discourses as
determinant of particular historical subjectivities.7 This hostility to the human
subject also remained present at times in Foucault’s later genealogical writings,
where he exhorted researchers to “get rid of the subject” and pursue genealogy
as “a form of history which can account for the constitution of knowledges,
discourses, domains of objects etc., without having to make reference to a
subject.”8
Page 4 of 23
Philosophical debates
of meaning. We will return to the problems with Foucault’s position shortly, but
first it is worth noting how his critique of the subject draws attention to a fatal
flaw in phenomenology’s autonomous theories of the subject. Namely, Foucault
makes us aware of the way that Husserl’s and Schutz’s theories of meaning fail
to account for the role of the social background. To posit meaning as the fruit of
autonomous self-reflection not only ignores the social dimensions of language, it
also occludes them with the illusory picture of an ego creating meaning in
herculean isolation. In this way, overly autonomous accounts of human agency
largely erase the social features of language and belief formation. Meaning
suddenly becomes the ahistorical achievement of individual psyches, as opposed
to the shared and ongoing inheritance of particular language communities. Part
of the value of Foucault’s radical critique of Husserl and early phenomenology’s
autonomous subject is that it forces far more suspicion about such claims to
ahistorical autonomy, drawing attention to the power and shaping influence of
the social background.
(p.48) The problem with Foucault’s anti-humanist position can be shown by the
fact that wherever a given social background or tradition is the same,
individuals may still hold vastly different beliefs. So, for example, two individuals
who are shaped by a given tradition (or episteme or discourse) X, and therefore
share beliefs A, B, and C, may still hold incompatible beliefs D, E, and F. The
existence of such differences in belief implies that post-structuralists should
allow that individuals can at least to some degree reason creatively against their
inherited social background. Discourses, epistemes, and other such concepts do
not over-determine the content of particular beliefs. Therefore, the subject’s
agency is not reducible to a discourse. The discourse is the starting point for
understanding a given individual’s beliefs, but it can never be the full story.
Instead, human beliefs must be looked at on their own terms, albeit always
deeply sensitive to the inherited social background.
Page 5 of 23
Philosophical debates
In doing so, anti-naturalism follows those like Gadamer who have argued that all
human belief formation occurs against a background of an inherited tradition. As
we discussed in Chapter 2, a tradition in this sense is an ideational background
against which individuals adopt an initial web of beliefs. Traditions thus capture
the way our inherited social background can strongly influence the beliefs we
hold without utterly determining them. So Gadamer (p.49) emphasizes the way
in which human understanding and agency exist on the “horizon” of a given
tradition. The concept of a horizon metaphorically captures the way in which
individuals are born into the limits of some historically inherited tradition, but
these limits can change and move as individuals creatively choose their own
paths within belief. Our horizon, as Gadamer notes, travels with us.12
Page 6 of 23
Philosophical debates
background. There is no exit from history for human belief, action, practice, and
thought.
Thus, the anti-naturalist point of the foregoing debate is now clear. Social
science must resist twin temptations. First, it must be careful not to treat human
subjectivity as autonomous and ahistorical, free of all social backgrounds. But
second, and no less important, it must avoid the anti-humanist temptation of
dissolving subjectivity altogether in favor of impersonal systems of power,
meaning, or other such mechanistic devices. Rather, an anti-naturalist approach
that is humanistic and historicist must keep in mind that people are the source
of beliefs and practices, while at the same time affirming that all human life
begins from an inherited history of beliefs and practices. In this way, the
concepts of situated agency, local reasoning, and tradition help social scientists
avoid the philosophical problems of an ahistorical subjectivity on one side, and
the anti-humanist reduction of the subject to the social background on the other.
Explanation
Controversies over human agency are closely related to a second area of great
importance to any social science—namely, how to explain social reality. Once
again, we maintain that anti-naturalism’s assumptions are philosophically
superior to the tendency to render the explanation of human life either
somewhat ahistorical (Schutz) or somewhat anti-humanistic (Foucault). Once
again, we accept that there are rival interpretations of these thinkers (p.50)
that are not susceptible to our critiques. If other scholars are able to reformulate
Schutz’s or Foucault’s philosophies so as to make them more compatible with
anti-naturalist insights, then we are happy to affirm their philosophical validity.
The point, however, is to see the way that ahistoricism and anti-humanism, no
matter where they arise, are philosophically problematic. Interpretive social
science is thereby best justified by anti-naturalist insights.
Inspired by Max Weber’s notion of ideal types, Schutz argued that what he
called “puppets” could reconcile the interpretive constructs of social reality with
Page 7 of 23
Philosophical debates
We will return to the question of ideal types and other such aggregate concepts
for the social scientific enterprise in our discussion of anti-naturalist concept
formation as well as in our critical treatment of neoclassical economics and
rational choice. For now we wish to show that the problem with Schutz’s
proposal does not reside in his notion of abstraction per se. Rather the problem
is his attempt to legitimize naturalism’s ahistorical approach as the standard
model of explanation for the social sciences. For as we argued in Chapter 2,
naturalistic explanation may be appropriate in outlying cases of physiological
pathology, but otherwise it fails to deal with the contingent or volitional links
that inform human beliefs and actions. The reader will recall that we argued
beliefs and actions are the result of contingent streams of reasoning and
cognition, not of necessary, law-like bonds. But the naturalist model of
explanation, championed by Schutz, assumes regularities between variables that
have necessary links. Schutz’s effort at squaring interpretive approaches with
naturalist explanations therefore runs afoul of this basic conceptual distinction.
That is, Schutz fails to recognize that naturalist and interpretive modes of
explanation are philosophically antithetical because the former assumes
necessary links between beliefs, and the latter contingent ones.16 Social
scientists should not follow Schutz’s lead because it is contradictory at the
conceptual level. Research programs built on such assumptions will therefore be
Page 8 of 23
Philosophical debates
We have already noted that Foucault is one of the most creative and
thoroughgoing historicists of the last century. His works investigating the
historical nature of social meanings are nearly unrivaled. For this reason it is
especially ironic that when it comes to social explanations, Foucault’s post-
structuralist approach sometimes goes awry in a similar way to Schutz. This
irony is made even deeper by the fact that in Foucault’s case it is the very anti-
humanist quest to demolish the subject (and abandon early phenomenology’s
transcendental ego) that leads to an overly formal and synchronic form of
explanation that neglects historical context.
For example, in his early, archaeological period Foucault sought to explain social
reality in terms of formal discursive rules that governed the beliefs and actions
of individuals across varied contexts without their being aware of it. As Foucault
put it, the rules of a discourse do not operate primarily “in the mind or
consciousness of individuals, but in discourse itself…according to a sort of
uniform anonymity, on all individuals who undertake to speak in this (p.52)
discursive field.”17 Thus social science explanation focuses neither on “an
individual, nor…some kind of collective consciousness,” but rather on “an
anonymous field whose configuration defines the possible position of speaking
subjects.”18 In this way, particular human beliefs and actions are reduced by
Foucault to a synchronic form of explanation that locates them like sites within
the larger map of the relevant discourse. Social scientific explanation consists of
placing the right belief, action, practice, or event within the proper discursive
scheme. Discourses in this way come to be abstract, transcendent entities,
neglecting the contingent meanings of more localized contexts. This synchronic
form of explanation thus neglects subtle variations in meaning at the individual
and local level.
Page 9 of 23
Philosophical debates
Second, those who adopt such explanatory frameworks appear unable to self-
narrate. That is, explanatory concepts like discourse and power seem inadequate
to the task of explaining why, for example, Foucault shifted emphasis after 1968
from a more archaeological-inflected approach to a genealogical one. But a form
of social explanation that cannot explain the very researcher’s own beliefs and
actions needs philosophical revision.
Page 10 of 23
Philosophical debates
Fortunately, once again a social science that is at once humanistic and historicist
avoids being snagged in these traps. This can be seen by briefly revisiting the
form of explanation introduced in Chapter 2. In brief form, social explanation
ought to be conceptualized in terms of the humanistic conception of situated
agents and the historicist conception of a tradition. Explanation ought to consist
of seeking the contingent connections (as opposed to either law-like bonds or
structural determinants) that agents form between their beliefs. But social
scientists must also stay aware of the fact that agents always act within the
horizon of a historically inherited tradition. Individuals can creatively change
and modify that inheritance in the face of dilemmas, but they might also
transform their inherited beliefs in response to some pathology or distorted
unconscious process as discussed above.
Page 11 of 23
Philosophical debates
because social reality is the product of situated agents who creatively modify
their beliefs and practices in light of shared traditions that form their ongoing
social inheritance.
Objectivity
One reason social scientists have been reluctant to accept the primacy of
narratives is that they can seem intellectually arbitrary and lacking in scientific
rigor. Are not stories a genre for children, one extending back to humanity’s
most primitive stages, and to be told around a campfire, not as a serious form of
scientific explanation? How could stories possibly make objective progress in the
knowledge of social and political reality? This skepticism about the relationship
between narratives and objectivity is widespread among naturalist social
scientists and even sometimes amid those otherwise sympathetic to an
interpretive turn. Yet anti-naturalist philosophy can help dispel this confusion by
providing social scientists with a clear justification for treating narrative and
interpretive inquiry as objectively rigorous. This anti-naturalist framework can in
turn be contrasted with two mistaken tendencies among advocates of
interpretivism: a return to naïve naturalistic views of the social world (as seen
sometimes in the work of Schutz) or an adoption of a radically skeptical anti-
humanism (sometimes evident in the thought of Foucault).
(p.55) Advocates of the interpretive turn have not always clearly broken away
from naturalist ideas. In search of a resolution to the problem of objectivity, old-
style phenomenologists like Schutz made recourse to an ahistorical, quasi-
naturalist approach. Specifically, Schutz hoped to treat meanings as if they were
immediately accessible facts about the world that could be straightforwardly
verified, more or less on par with empirical sense data. This led him to criticize
logical positivist philosophers for restricting empirical experience to sensory
observation alone. Instead, Schutz argued that what was considered
immediately and empirically given needed to be broadened to include the
meanings and actions of the social domain. Where our eyes were the organs of
observable sense perception, Schutz argued that meanings and actions were
perceived by “our commonsense thinking…without any difficulty” such that “the
experience of the existence of other human beings and of the meaning of their
actions is certainly the first and most original empirical observation man
makes.”25 Once the data of immediate experience had been expanded to include
the perception of meanings, Schutz believed that social science could be placed
on no less an objective footing than the natural sciences. As Schutz expressed it,
social scientific explanations “can be verified by empirical observation, provided
that we do not restrict this term to sensory perceptions of objects…but include
the experiential form by which commonsense thinking in everyday life
understands human actions.”26
Page 12 of 23
Philosophical debates
In other words, for Schutz objectivity consisted in the empirical adequacy with
which social scientists represented the meanings of those they studied. The key
was to remain sensitive to the fact that such constructions were the meanings of
other subjects. But once this was taken into account, there was nothing
especially tricky or vexed in picking out their objective meaning. This
straightforward empiricism concerning meanings was likewise adopted by those
who followed Schutz in the social sciences. So, for example, David Bidney
argued that the “life-world of a given society must be taken as empirically
given,” such that the task of a social scientist is largely to “describe in detail,
and ‘objectively,’ the life-world of his subjects as he has observed it.”27
That theories are buffered from any one empirical observation in this way should
not come as a surprise. Individuals often hold to a given theory with greater
certainty than any particular datum that might come along to disprove it. For
example, if one observes a shamelessly power-hungry politician suddenly make a
sweeping gesture of generosity and self-abnegation, this would not necessarily
upend the theory that this leader is calculating and self-serving. Instead, one
would likely fit the contradicting evidence into the wider theory. Perhaps this
leader was trying to recourse to populism, curry favor, or some other subterfuge.
Of course this does not mean that theories are utterly impregnable to new
Page 13 of 23
Philosophical debates
experiences (to the contrary, they might be undermined by any number of such
experiences); it simply means that the objectivity of a theory cannot be justified
by a straightforward appeal to empirical observation, but only by appealing to
further beliefs. Objectivity cannot rest on single commonsense units of
perception.
Another pitfall in the search for objectivity in the social sciences is to let holistic
and anti-foundational philosophical insights lead to relativism. We already noted
how Foucault’s hostility to humanism led to the demotion of subject agency in
favor of largely synchronic structures of discourses or power. Foucault often put
aside the philosophical problem of truth and objectivity in favor of the
sociological study of such structures of knowledge-power. Many of (p.57) these
sociological inquires have been nothing less than revolutionary. However, in
doing so Foucault sometimes came close to suggesting that social inquiry was
characterized by two forms of relativism: one based on a critique of individual
rationality and the other on incommensurability. We will look briefly at each one.
At times Foucault writes as though no one could have objective knowledge in the
social sciences because human beliefs are not rational but the product of non-
rational structures of power. So, for example, he famously wrote that: “Truth
isn’t outside power…each society has its own régime of truth, its ‘general
politics’ of truth: that is, the type of discourse which it accepts and makes
function as true.”30 One common interpretation of this passage is that truth has
been reduced to power. If this is the case then Foucault runs into the same
dilemma of the inability to self-narrate that we explained above. This position
would leave social scientists with no way to claim Foucault’s own works were
objectively better than the very rival historical narratives he did so much to
dispel.
Page 14 of 23
Philosophical debates
scientists with a way to think about the objectivity of their own inquiries. If this
reading is correct then Foucault is not interested in the philosophical question of
how to establish truth. This means readers should not be surprised, angry, or
disappointed to find Foucault is of no help on the question of objectivity because
it is not his question.
Page 15 of 23
Philosophical debates
critic would pressure the proponent by arguing that democratic peace theory
had failed to comprehensively ascertain certain shared facts. The existence of
shared facts therefore allows social scientists to judge which theory best meets
criteria such as accuracy, comprehensiveness, consistency, and opening new
possibilities for inquiry.
But what about cases of more radical disagreement in which few if any facts are
agreed upon or serve to judge between theories? For example, what if the
proponent of democratic theory disputes the very facts cited by the critic? Such
an advocate of democratic theory might argue that the critic has distorted the
facts because his theory of democracy is faulty, leading him to a mistaken set of
facts.
Yet even in extreme cases, where there is radical disagreement over the very
nature of the facts in question, comparison is still possible. For instance, in such
cases theories might still be rationally assessed according to their ability to
resolve anomalies or dilemmas internal to a competitor’s own conceptual
framework. In this way, the move from theory X to theory Y might be considered
either an “error-reducing” move or else some kind of epistemic gain in
comparative terms.34 Here the criteria are not necessarily shared facts, but
rather the ability to deal with a rival’s dilemmas and anomalies. Such
comparative objectivity consists of an immanent assessment of each theory’s
ability to resolve problems and advance aims.
For example, critics of democratic peace theory might argue that the theory’s
very historical development betrays the continual tweaking of definitions in
order to exclude counter-examples (like the Spanish–American War (p.59) of
1898 and the U.S. Civil War). Critics might therefore hold that the career of the
theory suffers from the internal dilemma of definitional circularity. Such
circularity, they might add, does not reflect a concern with accurately defining
democracies but with buffering the theory from anomalies. Such a critic might
then argue that their own preferred theory of democracy allows for a more
historical account of democracy that does not suffer the dilemma of definitional
circularity. The point, of course, is not whether democratic peace theory is
wrong or right. It is rather that anti-naturalist philosophy makes clear how both
proponents and critics of particular social scientific theories have recourse to
comparative forms of objective justification that steer clear of the two pitfalls of
foundationalism and relativism.
Page 16 of 23
Philosophical debates
Critique
Objectivity, according to anti-naturalism, is a function of comparison. Appeals
are made not to absolute criteria, but to relative gains or losses in occupying one
position over another. Now we add that insofar as objectivity consists in making
arguments about the relative rationality versus irrationality of holding particular
positions, it has an inescapable evaluative streak. As anti-naturalist philosophers
have noted, there is an ad hominem dimension to this kind of objectivity insofar
Page 17 of 23
Philosophical debates
as it is directly aimed at the holders of some theory X, and rests on the claim
that “whatever else turns out to be true, you can improve your epistemic
position by moving from X to Y.”36 In this way, theories in social science are
justified by the comparative truth or falsity of rivals. Moreover, because political
actors are inevitably guided (whether implicitly or explicitly) by some kind of
theory about social reality, social scientific theories are always closely tied to the
critique of the rationality guiding actual political actors.
This is an argument we will return to and elaborate upon at far greater length in
our discussion of ethics and the fact–value dichotomy. For now it is important to
emphasize that this anti-naturalist line of reasoning runs directly against the
grain of much mainstream social science, which maintains that social research is
more or less independent of the project of political and normative critique. Yet
anti-naturalism also challenges the value-neutrality latent in both ahistorical and
anti-humanist forms of social science that otherwise support an interpretive
turn. Old-style phenomenologists, for instance, defended the naturalist doctrine
that scientists must cultivate a stance of value-neutrality. These theorists
contrasted the disengaged objectivity of the scientist with the normatively
engaged perspective of ordinary political actors. In this vein, Schutz wrote that
the social scientist must be a “disinterested scientific onlooker of the social
world,” who limits him or herself to trying to observe, describe, and classify
social reality “with the same detached equanimity as physicists contemplate
their experiments.”37
(p.61) But arguably a kind of value-neutrality has also crept in from time to
time in the work of post-structuralists like Foucault. This may be surprising
because it is undoubtedly true that Foucault is extremely sensitive to the
pervasiveness of normativity within social theory. Indeed, his many inquiries into
the intersection of knowledge and power have often illuminated how normativity
and science are subtly intertwined. Nevertheless, various scholars have
plausibly suggested that especially in his early, archaeological period, Foucault
had a tendency to slide into the mode of writing as if from a completely
descriptive, even ideological neutral vantage point.38 For example, this tendency
is evident in Foucault’s method of “archaeological description” as a way of
unearthing the “systematic description of a discourse-object” as well as his
bracketing of questions of normativity and ideology.39 Once again, this is partly
the result of Foucault’s anti-humanist campaign to eliminate the subject in favor
of impersonal explanatory structures like discourses and epistemes. For, once
human reality has been reduced to these “discourse-objects,” it seems that more
or less straight value-neutral description might be attainable.
Page 18 of 23
Philosophical debates
We have argued that social scientists would do best to navigate debates within
the interpretive turn by adopting an anti-naturalist philosophical framework. In
the case of human subjectivity, this means social scientists should think of
human agency as situated, capable of creative agency while always embedded in
historical traditions. This situated view of human agency, moreover, suggests
that social scientists employ historical, narrative forms of explanation that
remain sensitive to the contingent reasons why agents form and inherit
particular beliefs. Anti-naturalist philosophy also helps social scientists avoid the
two pitfalls of foundationalist certainty and skeptical relativism. Rather,
objectivity is possible in the social sciences through comparing rival theories.
Finally, anti-naturalism points to a social science that is normatively engaged
and critical—this means moving beyond the naturalist assumption that inquiry
must be value-free. Indeed, social scientists should remain alive to the various
ways in which all forms of social explanation involve comparative judgments that
concern questions of rationality, irrationality, and ideology. Neither should they
forget that anti-naturalism itself is philosophically incompatible with, and
therefore implicitly critical of, absolutist forms of justification of political and
Page 19 of 23
Philosophical debates
Notes:
(1.) See: Maurice Natanson, ed., Phenomenology and the Social Sciences, 2 vols.
(Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1973); George Psathas, ed.,
Phenomenological Sociology (New York: Wiley and Sons, 1973).
(2.) Cf. Foucault, “The Subject and Power,” in Michel Foucault: Beyond
Structuralism and Hermeneutics, 2nd ed., eds. Hubert Dreyfus and Paul
Rabinow (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1983) 225.
(3.) For Husserl in particular “to buttress humanistic science with natural
science so as to make it supposedly exact is absurd.” Edmund Husserl, “The
Attitude of Natural Science and the Attitude of Humanistic Science, Appendix
III” and “Vienna Lecture, Appendix I,” in The Crisis of European Sciences and
Transcendental Phenomenology, trans. David Carr (Evanston, IL: Northwestern
University Press, 1970) 326, 272. Also, Brian Fay has written an insightful
historical summary of phenomenology and meaning in the social sciences, which
we are indebted to here: Brian Fay, “Phenomenology and Social Inquiry: From
Consciousness to Culture and Critique,” in The Blackwell Guide to the
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, eds. Stephen Turner and Paul Roth (Oxford:
Blackwell Publishing, 2003) 42–63.
(5.) Alfred Schutz, The Phenomenology of the Social World, trans. George Walsh
and Frederick Lehnert (Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1967) 69,
cf. 31–44, 69–71. It is well known but important to note that late in his career
Schutz grew increasingly skeptical of Husserl’s transcendental subject.
(8.) Foucault, “Truth and Power,” interview by Alessandro Fontana and Pasquale
Pasquino in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 1972–
1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon Books, 1980) 117.
Page 20 of 23
Philosophical debates
(9.) Charles Taylor, “Foucault on Freedom and Truth,” in Philosophy and the
Human Sciences: Philosophical Papers 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1985) 169–70.
(11.) Colin Hay, Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction (New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2002) 205–8.
(12.) For further discussion see Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, rev.
ed., trans. Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (New York: Continuum,
2004) II:1.
(13.) Alfred Schutz, “Concept and Theory Formation in the Social Sciences,” in
Sociological Theory and Philosophical Analysis, eds. Dorothy Emmet and
Alasdair MacIntyre (New York: Macmillan Company, 1970) 12.
(16.) Cf. Alfred Schutz, “The Problem of Rationality in the Social World,” in
Sociological Theory and Philosophical Analysis, 96–7; Thomas Luckmann,
“Philosophy, Science, and Everyday Life,” in Phenomenology and the Social
Sciences, vol. 1, 174, 179, 180. For a powerful critique of phenomenology’s
flirtation with ahistorical, natural kinds see: Richard Bernstein, The
Restructuring of Social and Political Theory (Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1978) 158–61.
(19.) Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish, trans. Alan Sheridan (New York:
Vintage Books, 1995) 27–8.
(22.) Jacques Derrida, “Structure, Sign, and Play in the Discourses of the Human
Sciences,” in The Languages of Criticism and the Sciences of Man, eds. Richard
Macksey and Eugenio Donato (Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins Press, 1970) 249.
Page 21 of 23
Philosophical debates
(30.) Foucault, “Truth and Power,” 131. See also: Foucault, “Two Lectures,” in
Power/Knowledge, 93; Foucault, “Nietzsche, Genealogy, History,” 150.
(32.) See for example: Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism:
Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis (Philadelphia, PA: University of Pennsylvania
Press, 1983); Alasdair MacIntyre, “Epistemological Crises, Dramatic Narrative
and the Philosophy of Science,” in The Tasks of Philosophy: Selected Essays,
Volume I (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2006); Charles Taylor,
“Explanation and Practical Reason,” in Philosophical Arguments (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1995) 34–60.
(33.) For a standard reference book on these debates see the essays in: Michael
E. Brown, Sean M. Lynn-Jones, and Steven E. Miller, eds., Debating the
Democratic Peace (Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1996).
(35.) Allan Bloom, The Closing of the American Mind (New York: Simon and
Schuster, 1987).
Page 22 of 23
Philosophical debates
Page 23 of 23
Concept formation
Concept formation
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0004
Page 1 of 25
Concept formation
We would now like to show how the basic concepts used to describe and explain
social reality can either take a naturalist or anti-naturalist bent.1 This means
that neutrality about philosophy in empirical work is impossible. Social scientists
might ignore philosophy but this does not free them from philosophical
commitments and responsibilities. Our task is to draw off the arguments made
so far in order to demonstrate the problems with naturalist concept formation
and offer an anti-naturalist alternative for empirical research. In particular we
will focus on recent developments in the methodological debates in political
science—though these discussions will clearly have much broader implications.
In the last two decades concept formation has received significant attention
from qualitative political science methodologists such as Giovanni Sartori and
David Collier. These methodologists have articulated perhaps the most
sophisticated defense of a qualitative approach to concept formation to date.
And yet their treatment of concept formation remains entangled in certain
philosophical problems. Although Collier’s approach to concept formation is
more flexible than Sartori’s, both men remain attached to philosophical
naturalism. Specifically, we will claim that a lingering philosophical naturalism
has inspired leading political science methodologists to slip into three kinds of
(p.66) faulty concept formation, which we will analyze in detail: reification,
essentialism, and linguistic instrumentalism.
As part of our discussion of Sartori and Collier, we will also survey how these
faulty types of concept formation are evident in some of the most prominent
research programs of empirical political science. We will then conclude by
proposing an alternative set of anti-naturalist descriptive and explanatory
concepts. By the end of the chapter, the reader should have a clear sense of the
drawbacks of naturalist concept formation and the virtues of an anti-naturalist
alternative for empirical inquiry.
Reification
In previous chapters we explained why anti-naturalists believe that social reality
is expressive of the webs of meaning of creative human agents. But not everyone
conceives of language and social reality in this way. Indeed, the reification of
social science concepts is the result of neglecting the holistic nature of beliefs
and meanings and instead rendering social reality as if it were composed of
Page 2 of 25
Concept formation
mere things. Reified concepts are attractive to some researchers because they
allow for a vision of social reality as free of interpretive controversy. Meanings
always involve hermeneutic conflicts over how to relate constituent beliefs and
actions to wider narrative wholes. By contrast, the allure of treating social
reality as consisting of mere things is that ostensibly these can be verified with
little interpretive debate, and then perhaps plugged into the mechanistic and
law-like models of explanation inspired by the natural sciences. For example,
political scientists studying American voter behavior might reify demographic
concepts like “age,” “race,” or “social class” by not taking into account how
members of those demographic groups actually construe the significance of
their social situation or the variant cultural meanings informing these terms.
Once this has been accomplished, age, race, class, and other such demographic
facts can then be correlated and eventually formed into supposedly law-like
causal explanations.2 In this way, reification is one of the building blocks of a
certain widespread approach to the naturalist project in the social sciences.
We will illustrate this series of points using the case of American voter behavior
in greater detail below. But first we must engage the methodological writings of
Sartori and Collier in order to clarify how the reification of concepts can take
one of two forms. The first form we will call brute fact reification. This type of
reification occurs whenever social scientists strip their concepts of meanings
and instead present them as brute facts—demographic, biological, social, or
otherwise. This approach is found in the methodological writings of Sartori.
Page 3 of 25
Concept formation
reification, in which social objects are not properly distinguished from mere
physical things. Indeed, his theory of concept formation does not adequately
discriminate between the referents of concepts in the social sciences and
physical objects.
Page 4 of 25
Concept formation
that the key feature of reification consists of stripping the objects denoted by
social science concepts of holistic meanings and beliefs. What Collier’s
discussion of reification misses is the way that social science concepts must
refer to objects constituted in part by meanings or beliefs.
This slide into naturalist reification is evident in Collier’s coauthored work with
Steven Levitsky on concepts of democracy in comparative research. This essay
tries to determine how appropriate various definitions of democracy are when
applied to differing historical and geopolitical contexts. Notably, Collier and
Levitsky argue that a “procedural minimum” definition of democracy is
insufficient in several Latin American countries where civilian government, even
when freely elected, is without the effective power to rule. In such cases, they
believe that political scientists would need to add effective power to rule to the
procedural minimum definition of democracy.13 But although Collier and
Levitsky display sensitivity to context, they ignore the meanings of the specific
actors involved in the democracies in question. Their conceptualization of
democracy is thus devoid of agents’ meanings as constitutive of actions and as
crucial to the contextual diversity. Nor is this concept of democracy sufficiently
embedded in a particular tradition and recognized as in conflict with other
traditions of democracy. Rather, they treat the problem of properly
conceptualizing democracy as one of adding or subtracting the right reified
attributes in the quasi-ahistorical space of a political science lab. In this regard,
no less than Sartori, they commit themselves to a naturalistic reification of
concepts.
Page 5 of 25
Concept formation
naturalist agenda. The goal is for political scientists to correlate this brute
biological notion of “age” as a mere thing with other ostensibly brute facts in the
hope that some more fundamental causal inference can be achieved. What starts
with the seeming innocence of descriptive correlations ends with attempts to
frame mechanistic causal laws. In this way, the reified fact of age plays a key
role in the effort to model and predict voter behavior via naturalist explanations.
Page 6 of 25
Concept formation
But the problem here (similar to Glenda Patrick’s work above) is that the
concept of age is still being made to serve and fit within a naturalist formation.
Indeed, although meanings are now referenced within the concept of age, this is
still done while excluding the holistic beliefs of the actual agents involved. What
if the meanings of age are defined by being part of a clique of young people
actively involved in politics (e.g., the Hitler Youth)? Or what if instead, a given
milieu of the elderly depoliticize because they believe all is lost in the current
country’s polity? Of course, it might be that the meaning of increased
participation has to do with a certain set of contingent developments within
American history where aging allowed for more civic engagement. But this
would have to be grasped and conceptualized by wrestling with the meanings of
actual agents in the culture—not stipulated free of any connection to the webs of
belief constituting actual social reality. Thus, the concrete meanings and beliefs
constituting political reality cannot be ignored. In this regard, there is a
lingering reification that persists. Rosenstone and Hansen have simply shifted
from a brute fact reification to a slightly more defensible atomistic kind.
Of course, none of this excludes the possibility that anti-naturalists might accept
Rosenstone and Hansen’s finding that older Americans voted in higher numbers
between 1956 and 1988. Indeed, as a starting point, Rosenstone and Hansen’s
work gathering data about American elections is a substantive and valuable
contribution to social science research. But anti-naturalists would insist that the
conceptual grid imposed on social reality is causing neglect of holistic webs and
leading to some disfigurations. Moreover, the actual work of explanation is yet to
be done as no narrative has been constructed that grasps the beliefs and
meanings of these groups that generate their actions.
Essentialism
Reification results when social scientists ignore the constitutive role of holistic
meanings and beliefs from the concepts they use to denote social reality. (p.71)
Essentialism, by contrast, is the result of stripping away the historical
specificity from concepts. Anti-naturalist philosophy implies that meanings and
actions are historically contingent and can only be understood in particular
contexts or life-worlds. By contrast, naturalism promotes the view that essential
attributes occur cross-temporally and cross-culturally, transcending historical
contingency. Freed of specificity, essentialist concepts are designed to capture
historical and cultural constants, which might then form the basis for naturalist
causal explanations.
Page 7 of 25
Concept formation
then with an example from empirical research. Again this approach reveals the
way that naturalist philosophical assumptions inform and mar even some of the
best work conducted by contemporary social scientists.
Page 8 of 25
Concept formation
“classical categories.” Two other types of concepts they consider are “radial
categories” and “family resemblance categories.” Radial categories echo the
strong essentialism of classical categories, as they are defined in terms of
certain core attributes (or a “central subcategory”) that comprise a prototype.
This prototype is then said to apply in actual cases only in combination with
other “noncentral subcategories” such that relevant cases may share core
attributes with the prototype but not with each other.23
Collier and Mahon’s break from Wittgenstein becomes clear once we draw a
distinction between two senses of the concept of “family resemblance.” On the
one side, a family denotes a clearly demarcated group that contrasts with
nonfamily members; but, on the other, a family might instead be considered a
dynamic set of relations with adoptive, honorary, and step members. Collier and
Mahon use the “family” metaphor in the former, essentialist sense, while
Wittgenstein used the metaphor in the second, anti-essentialist sense. Indeed,
Wittgenstein was skeptical about the ability to draw a sharp boundary around all
family members.26
For Wittgenstein, family resemblances lack any single, fixed set of attributes to
begin with, and therefore the problem of conceptual stretching doesn’t even (p.
73) arise as there is nothing to stretch. Instead, Wittgenstein’s notion of a
family resemblance allows for potentially limitless empirical diversity, in which
concepts must always be considered within specific contexts. By contrast, Collier
and Mahon commit themselves to a weak essentialism insofar as they insist on
clearly identifiable commonalities. This is also why Collier and Mahon must
consider conceptual stretching as a central problem even in family resemblance
concepts.
Page 9 of 25
Concept formation
But Collier and Mahon’s essentialism also appears in their proposed solutions to
the problem of conceptual stretching. They attempt to allow for concepts that
can capture greater empirical diversity by “emphasiz[ing] that the category is an
analytic construct which the researcher should not expect to be a perfect
description of each case,” and also by “identifying attributes that are present to
varying degrees in particular cases, rather than being simply present or
absent.”27 But this effort at diversity is undermined by their insistence that
social scientists not violate the requirement of evident commonalities. Indeed,
this insistence is precisely what keeps Collier and Mahon’s analysis trapped
within a weak form of essentialism.
Page 10 of 25
Concept formation
For example, consider the criteria that all forms of political contention must be
episodic. True to the logic of strong essentialism, this feature is used to exclude
all political phenomena that exhibit regularity. Thus, regularly recurring actions
like elections, parliamentary debates, and associational meetings are all placed
by Tilly and company outside the boundary lines of the concept of contentious
politics. Indeed, because of their regularity, not even the most embattled
elections are instances of contentious politics. Likewise, an essentialist logic
informs Tilly, McAdam, and Tarrow’s criterion that politically contentious
phenomena be public. In this case, the aim is to exclude from the concept any
actions that occur inside “well-bounded organizations, including churches and
firms.”30
Some readers may have already guessed the reasons why an anti-naturalist
approach rejects the strong essentialism upon which the concept of contentious
politics is based. Because anti-naturalists believe that actions are expressive of
historically specific webs of meaning, they are skeptical of claims to the
existence of a universal class of action, which transcends historical and cultural
context. Indeed, they would argue that the attempt to posit this universal class
runs the risk of hiding the very beliefs and actions social scientists wish to bring
to light. Because human beliefs and actions are expressive of contingent
contexts of meaning, the imposition of a nucleus of essential features eclipses
the true object of study. Rather than helping describe the social world, this
search for a logic of commonality instead leads to problems such as
anachronism, ethnocentrism, and other such forms of misunderstanding. The
strongly essentialist formation of concepts like contentious politics thus clashes
with and occludes empirical reality. The process by which the essentialist core is
articulated by political scientists is itself part of the stream of history. So, the
historically contingent beliefs of political scientists run the risk of being
mistaken for universal meanings. One limited set of meanings (those of the
political scientist) are imposed. In the case of the study of radically alien
cultures, this means that the social scientist’s own beliefs disfigure that of the
actual life-world being investigated. Strong essentialism almost inevitably sets
up social scientists for misinterpretations in which their own views are being
studied and imposed upon others.
Page 11 of 25
Concept formation
Adopting a numeric grading scale, Russett and Maoz allowed for a spectrum of
how democratic versus authoritarian actual regimes might be. The regimes in
question were then to be graded on the basis of certain essential core criteria,
like competitiveness of political participation and constraints on the chief
executive. On one extreme, a score of minus 100 represented the most
authoritarian regime, while on another a plus 100 represented the most
democratic. The lower threshold for classing regimes as democratic was plus 30
and the upper threshold for judging them authoritarian was minus 25. As
Russett and Maoz observed, such a grading scale allowed that in empirical
reality “a state can have mixed characteristics” where “some features may be
democratic at the same time that others are highly autocratic.”31 Nevertheless,
these conceptualizations of democratic versus authoritarian regimes were also
essentialist insofar as they remained defined by core features considered to
migrate from context to context.32 In this way, democratic peace theorists
attempted to stretch their concepts across the sheer complexity and nuance of
the actual empirical world, without giving up on the basic essentialist logic of
commonality.
Page 12 of 25
Concept formation
Linguistic instrumentalism
This last line of thought brings us to a final form of naturalist concept formation:
linguistic instrumentalism. Linguistic instrumentalism occurs whenever social
scientists divorce their concepts from their own language and from the language
of those they study. Rather than letting the concepts of social science arise in
dialogue (through a process of textual, archival, or empirical research),
linguistic instrumentalism attempts to impose a formal language that has been
constructed beforehand.33 This formal language is meant to be shielded from the
life-worlds of both researcher and subject, serving as a neutral instrument or
tool.
The tendency to instrumentalize language once again follows clearly from the
basic ambitions of naturalist philosophy. Naturalism suggests that theory
building in the social sciences is detached and descriptive. Scientific language is
transparent and yields a universal picture of the world. In this view, the task of
the scientist is to carefully build this neutral conceptual language. The more the
language of science can disburden itself of particular viewpoints, the better.
There are two major kinds of linguistic instrumentalism. The first is subject-side
instrumentalism, which results from social scientists blocking out their own
historical situatedness from the construction of concepts. Subject-side
instrumentalism encourages social scientists to purge their concepts of personal
traces of their home culture or life-world, rendering the speech anonymous and
supposedly universal. This kind of instrumentalism is evident in the writings of
Sartori. Specifically, Sartori’s essays focus on the internal dynamics of social
science concepts as an analytic tool. He thus explores the relationship between
term, meaning, and referent; between intension and extension; between
declarative, denotative, precising, operational, and ostensive definitions;
between “accompanying properties” and “defining properties”; and between
homonymy and synonymy.34 But in all of this, Sartori’s analysis of social science
concepts remains completely internalist. That is, he leaves no room for his
readers to consider how the place of the scholar within a particular historical
and cultural world might affect the internal aspects of social science concepts.
In this way, Sartori seems to imply that social scientists occupy a space outside
of any particular historical and cultural context.
Page 13 of 25
Concept formation
Unfortunately, however, Collier and Adcock slip into a second kind of linguistic
instrumentalism, which we will refer to as object-side. Object-side
instrumentalism occurs when social scientists treat the social world as a more or
less mute object, on which the conceptual language of social science can be
superimposed. Object-side instrumentalism neglects the fact that human beings
always have their own language and concepts for explaining beliefs, actions, and
practices. Rather than a dialogue, object-side instrumentalism encourages social
scientists to exclude or at least neglect the self-interpretations of those studied
from an active role within concept formation.
These instrumental tendencies within social science concept formation are far
from limited to the methodological writings of Collier and Sartori. Rather, (p.
78) they are found in prominent examples of empirical research. Consider, in
this light, the concepts of so-called “selectorate theory.” Selectorate theory
Page 14 of 25
Concept formation
These theorists begin from the assumption that “the self-interested calculations
and actions of rulers are the driving force of all politics.”40 Politics is then
analyzed in terms of three constituent groups said to face all leaders. The first
group is what these theorists call the “nominal selectorate,” or
“interchangeables,” who have the legal right to select the leader but are not
essential to his or her maintaining power. The second group consists of the “real
selectorate,” or “influentials,” whose support is important to the attainment of
power. The final group is what these authors dub the “winning coalition” or
“essentials,” and is composed of those individuals without whose support it
would be impossible to remain leader. Out of these three constituencies,
selectorate theory then endeavors to explain how politics is chiefly organized
around the rational calculations of self-interested leaders.
We have already noted how anti-naturalist philosophy maintains that all human
belief formation occurs against the background of inherited traditions, which
bear particular linguistic, historical, and normative content.43 Social scientists
are no exception to this. Therefore, the attempt to devise an ahistorical
language, free of all tradition, is ultimately self-defeating. Instead, researchers
are better served by reflecting thoughtfully on the sources of (p.79) their own
thought, identifying the traditions they have inherited, and considering the ways
Page 15 of 25
Concept formation
in which this might be reflected in the construction of their concepts. The point
is not to avoid all jargon or neologisms, but to be consciously self-aware of one’s
own linguistic, philosophical, ideological, and other inheritances. The
construction of an ideal scientific language outside all of history is simply not
possible. Social scientists need to become more comfortable embracing and
reflecting critically on the natural languages of their own communities and how
these will inevitably color their concept formation. This once again implies that
interpretive disputes cannot be eliminated from the social sciences. The
language of the social scientist can be contested by relating it hermeneutically
to other beliefs and meanings. The apparent neutral, universal prestige of
scientific language is not available. As with ordinary citizens, the language of
politics is itself subject to political criticisms.
Yet at this point the objection might be raised that Bueno de Mesquita and Smith
do in fact allow the language of their own home culture to shape at least some
key concepts. After all, their work makes heavy use of concepts like democracy,
dictatorship, and other such distinctions between regimes. The problem here,
however, is that selectorate theory largely vacates these terms of their
traditional meanings. In a telling passage, these authors emphasize the difficulty
of fully purging language of ordinary meanings, but nonetheless encourage
those who study politics to do so to the greatest extent possible:
In other words, Bueno de Mesquita and Smith concede that a complete subject-
side instrumentalism may not actually be attainable. But they do so only on the
strict understanding that they have done their best to completely redefine the
meaning of these terms, granting their normal understanding of this language
only the thinnest “heuristic” value.45
Perhaps readers will not be surprised to find that selectorate theory is also
engaged in object-side instrumentalism insofar as it discounts the specific beliefs
and viewpoints of the very leaders that are the focal point of its inquiries. For
example, Bueno de Mesquita and Smith admit they do not care very much what
particular leaders think because this is “not terribly important.”46 Instead of
Page 16 of 25
Concept formation
giving the language of those studied an active role within concept formation, the
concepts of selectorate theory exclude these self-understandings.
Page 17 of 25
Concept formation
Page 18 of 25
Concept formation
Different purposes will often lead to different descriptive foci. The hermeneutic
circle allows any one part in a web of meaning to be related in new and creative
ways to other aspects of the whole. This dynamic of playful insight is deeply
familiar to literary scholars and other sensitive readers in the (p.82)
humanities; it also represents one of many places social scientists could learn a
great deal from others in humanities disciplines like art history, literature, film,
drama, classics, and so on. In social reality, as in a work of art, there is no single,
officially scientifically sanctioned description. The only rule from an anti-
naturalist perspective is that family resemblance concepts must remain
answerable to the particular contexts of meaning they purport to capture. In this
way, social scientists remain free to tackle whatever aspect of social life fits their
wider aims and curiosities.
Page 19 of 25
Concept formation
The point, of course, is not whether Bellah’s ideas about American civil religion
are justified. Rather, the point is the way that Bellah’s concept gives us a
prominent example of how anti-naturalist social scientists might construct their
own concepts—and this in at least four ways.
Page 20 of 25
Concept formation
Second, civil religion emerges for Bellah out of a dialogic rather than linguistic
instrumentalist approach to language. Specifically, Bellah goes to some lengths
to argue that the very idea of a civil religion is part of “the self-conception” of
Americans, and can be traced back to the nation’s founding and the “cultural
climate of the late eighteenth century.”54 Bellah’s use of the concept of a civil
religion therefore emerges out of his own fieldwork, and is (p.84) the result of
a kind of collaborative dialogue with the language of those he studies, and not
simply imposed from the outside. This means that unlike many of the social
scientists we criticized above, Bellah’s concepts are not built beforehand and
then kept as clean of contamination from other meanings as possible (as if they
were tools kept clean for surgery). Rather, Bellah understands that the
explanations of the social scientist must always begin from the language and
self-interpretations of those studied. In this respect, Bellah avoids an object-side
linguistic instrumentalism, which mutes or ignores people’s language and self-
understanding.
us from the need for further thought, innovation, and open-ended dialogue. The
goal of social science is not a final set of explanatory laws, but always better and
better explanatory stories and descriptive insights.
In sum, social scientists must form concepts in order to study the social world.
This is an inescapable need for anyone conducting empirical research. Yet what
kinds of concepts they will craft depends largely on the philosophical (p.85)
assumptions and intuitions they bring to the task. The foregoing philosophical
analysis is offered in the hope that an anti-naturalist framework helps to sharpen
and hone social scientific approaches to concept formation. Rather than
uncritically slipping into forms of naturalism, social scientists should remain
alert to the philosophical aspects inherent in their choice of concepts.
Otherwise, they run the risk of detracting from what are often highly valuable
contributions to our knowledge of the social world. That such distortions might
be taken on board by social scientists “as if” they were true for heuristic
purposes is an argument we will consider at greater length in our treatment of
rational choice theory and even more so in Chapter 9 on public policy.57 For now
it is important to see that practicing social scientists ignore certain philosophical
controversies at their own peril. Part of what this chapter has established are
the high amounts of distortion that come along with any shift toward naturalist
concepts. But concepts are only one small area where this is apparent. The
effects on the debates over methods and the approaches to empirical topics are
no less dramatic. The time has ended when social scientists could afford to be
oblivious to philosophy—itself another vestige of naturalism, which looked upon
the natural sciences and imagined a domain finally free of philosophical
controversy.
Notes:
(1.) This chapter draws significantly on: Mark Bevir and Asaf Kedar, “Concept
Formation in Political Science: An Anti-Naturalist Critique of Qualitative
Methodology,” Perspectives on Politics 3 (2008): 503–17. Although substantially
altered from the original article, we heartily thank Asaf for his permission to
build on that earlier work.
(2.) For an example of such an attempt see: Steven Rosenstone and John Mark
Hansen, Mobilization, Participation, and Democracy in America (New York:
Macmillan, 1993).
Page 22 of 25
Concept formation
(13.) David Collier and Steven Levitsky, “Democracy with Adjectives: Conceptual
Innovation in Comparative Research,” World Politics 49:3 (1997): 434, 443.
(14.) S. Kernell, G. Jacobson, and T. Kousser, eds., The Logic of American Politics,
5th ed. (Washington, DC: CQ Press, 2011) 496–7.
(20.) David Collier and James E. Mahon, Jr., “Conceptual ‘Stretching’ Revisited:
Adapting Categories in Comparative Analysis,” American Political Science
Review 87:4 (1993): 845.
Page 23 of 25
Concept formation
(28.) Charles Tilly, Sidney Tarrow, and Doug McAdam, Dynamics of Contention
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 2001) 5.
(29.) McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly express skepticism at the possibility of general
laws but preserve the naturalist hope that identifying the essential properties of
political contention will help them discover the recurring causal sequences
behind political phenomena. McAdam, Tarrow, and Tilly, Dynamics of
Contention, 345–6.
(31.) Zeev Maoz and Bruce Russett, “Normative and Structural Causes of
Democratic Peace, 1946–1986,” American Political Science Review 87:3 (1993):
624–38, 628.
(33.) Many interpretivists have criticized this tendency to cut off dialogue by
creating concepts beforehand. See: Peregrine Schwartz-Shea and Dvora Yanow,
Interpretive Research Design: Concepts and Processes (New York: Routledge,
2012) 17–18.
(39.) Bruce Bueno de Mesquita, Alastair Smith, Randolph Siverson, and James
Morrow, The Logic of Political Survival (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2005).
(40.) Bruce Bueno de Mesquita and Alastair Smith, The Dictator’s Handbook:
Why Bad Behavior Is Almost Always Good Politics(New York: Public Affairs,
2011) xxiii, xxiv.
(41.) Bueno de Mesquita and Smith, Dictator’s Handbook, xxii; see also: ix, xix,
113, 135, 137, 253.
Page 24 of 25
Concept formation
(43.) Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, Second Revised Edition, trans.
Joel Weinsheimer and Donald Marshall (New York: Continuum, 2004) 265–307.
(45.) Bueno de Mesquita et al., The Logic of Political Survival, 72, 55.
(46.) Bueno de Mesquita and Smith, Dictator’s Handbook, 135; see also: 253.
(52.) Indeed, Bellah even worries that if his research fails to be sensitive enough
to history, it risks distortion precisely by “reifying” the meaning of civil religion.
This serves to emphasize the way in which interpretive social scientists must
always be wary of the ongoing risk of slipping into distorted concept formation.
Bellah, “Civil Religion,” 179.
(57.) For an insightful example of such an argument, which we will engage later,
see: Colin Hay, “Neither Real Nor Fictitious but ‘As If Real’? A Political Ontology
of the State,” The British Journal of Sociology 65:3 (2014): 459–80.
Page 25 of 25
Methods
Methods
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0005
Social science today has largely reduced the interpretive turn to a commitment
to “qualitative” methods. Unfortunately, this narrow and mistaken view of the
interpretive turn is widespread among many of the most influential practitioners
of social science. For example, three of the most eminent methodologists
working in political science today equate interpretivism with deep immersion in
the customs, practices, and institutions of a particular group of people.1 In this
way, interpretive research becomes synonymous with ethnography and
immersive, onsite fieldwork.2 Viewed from this perspective, the opposite of
“interpretive” is quantitative methods like mass surveys, statistics, and various
Page 1 of 29
Methods
forms of modeling. The interpretive turn is then thought of as little more than an
attempt to have qualitative methodologies reign supreme. The entire
methodological debate becomes limited to a highly polarized discussion about
“quantitative” versus “qualitative” research. So widespread is this confusion
today that even those who defend the interpretive turn in social science often do
so in the name of qualitative methods.3
analysis, and heuristics, it does nothing to prohibit the use of any one particular
technique. Social scientists determine what method is best for their research
goals by exercising their experienced judgment within context. Provided social
scientists steer clear of naturalism, they are free to creatively make use of
whatever method best serves their research goals and purposes. Anti-naturalism
makes clear the way in which multi-methods is fully compatible with the
interpretive turn.
Page 3 of 29
Methods
Ethnography is clearly an extremely powerful tool for the study of social science.
The vast and diverse body of successful research that currently employs
ethnographic techniques confirms the strength and fruitfulness of (p.91) this
method. To choose only a few of many examples, the sociologist Kenneth
MacLeish has used ethnographic techniques to track the effects of the Iraq war
on military communities far beyond the frontlines of the battlefield. He
accomplished this through the use of both observer-participation and long-form
interviewing at Fort Hood, Texas. What MacLeish found is that the violence of
war extends into the life of the communities far beyond the battlefield and mixes
into the ordinary lives of military families. The otherwise invisible tolls of war
are therefore made concrete.9
Page 4 of 29
Methods
Indeed, longer stays and intensive language training would not necessarily have
freed this kind of ethnography from naturalist distortion. Many ethnographers
spend their entire lives specializing in a few cultural subgroups and carry out
forms of immersive observer-participation that last years and even decades.
Such practices often make for good workmanship and generate important
insights about social reality, but they do not guarantee an escape (p.93) from
naturalist distortions. After all, a researcher could spend years mastering the
appropriate language, and decades in the field engaged in observer-
participation, and still adopt essentialist, ahistorical structures of explanation.
Arguably, many naturalist social scientists working across modern societies
today live out de facto just such an immersive experience in their own home
cultures. But while long-term exposure to a cultural group may enrich
ethnographic data, it does not guarantee its freedom from naturalist
conclusions.
Page 6 of 29
Methods
Ultimately, ethnography is not any more immune to naturalism than other forms
of data collection. The fact that it can be classified as a “qualitative” method
does not resolve the deeper philosophical issues of which social scientists must
remain aware. Because naturalism and anti-naturalism are philosophies and not
mere techniques, they can subordinate any number of methods into their
service. Furthermore, because all methods are compatible with one another,
Page 7 of 29
Methods
ethnography is easily paired with other kinds of data generation that are less
immersive. For example, ethnography and long-form interviewing are often used
by social scientists in conjunction with mass surveys and questionnaires.22 So
researchers conducting a mass census survey might supplement their work with
in-depth interviews of particular subgroups within that population in order to
gain a more nuanced sense of their beliefs. Similarly, a mass survey registering
widespread dissatisfaction with a given public figure can be combined with in-
depth interviewing to uncover the specific and myriad reasons for this
dissatisfaction. Thus, ethnography can be joined with other more “quantitative”
methods in the social sciences by providing contextual, local knowledge that
might otherwise remain inaccessible. How this mixing and matching can be
realized will become clearer by briefly scrutinizing a second form of data
collection—mass surveys.
such fact. When one atomistic bit of social reality occurs, another bit is said to
necessarily follow (or at least be correlated in some way). Indeed, often survey
research is erroneously presented by naturalist methodologists as tied to just
such “multivariate analysis.”24 When framed by such concepts and ambitions,
mass surveys are thought to simply generate data for mechanistic, naturalist
explanations.
But there is no logical link binding mass surveys to such atomism and
mechanism. Instead, social scientists may affirm the descriptive validity of
particular mass survey research (for example, X percent of white female
Christians voted for the rightwing candidate) while recognizing that any attempt
at explaining these beliefs will require further exploration of the reasons and
beliefs held by these agents. In other words, explanation requires placing beliefs
in a wider web of meanings. In order to move from description to explanation,
mass survey research might benefit from supplementing its findings with
ethnographic research or panel studies that take a sample of respondents in
order to delve into their reasons for holding the beliefs that they do.25
Page 9 of 29
Methods
This is not the place for an extended exposition on the statistical theory that
supports the inference from the small subset to the total population—but in
general terms, this inference is possible because a distribution of samples takes
on a fixed, normal shape. For example, support for the Green Party in a given
population may be 7 percent. A sample of the wider population might instead
Page 10 of 29
Methods
Both the promise and the peril of random sampling statistical methods can be
clarified with an example from the social science literature. In 2005, sociologists
Christian Smith and Melinda Lundquist Denton conducted a deep analysis of the
National Survey of Youth and Religion—a random-digital-dial sample of teens
across the United States ages thirteen to seventeen.31 The fruit of this research
was the single largest trove of statistical data on U.S. teen attitudes toward
religion and spirituality at that time. Such a massive random sample survey can
be embraced by anti-naturalists as providing an important descriptive map of
certain features of social reality. For example, anti-naturalists can affirm Smith
and Denton’s finding that contrary to widespread belief at that time, U.S. teens
were not trending away from traditional churches and congregations; indeed,
Page 11 of 29
Methods
the “vast majority of U.S. teenagers profess to be theists.”32 This could be taken
as a descriptively valid finding at the time of the survey research.
(p.99) The lesson for an anti-naturalist social science is clear: mass surveys,
random sampling, and statistical inference are valuable for large-scale sketches
of social reality but they do not replace an analysis of the deeper beliefs and
traditions that create a given status quo. As Smith and Denton observe, mass
statistical surveys provide an “overarching sense of our social world,” but they
are also “oversimplifying” and must be supplemented with deeper engagement
of cultural meanings and textures.34 In this respect Smith and Denton’s work
serves as a model to anti-naturalist researchers—expertly employing both mass
survey statistics and ethnographic inquiry. In doing so, they also make clear our
point that all methods are compatible and can be effectively mixed and matched.
The move from so-called “quantitative” to “qualitative” methods presents no
impassable boundaries to the working social scientist.
However, Smith and Denton’s research also serves as a cautionary tale insofar
as it occasionally creeps toward naturalism. To pick just one example, Smith and
Denton propose possible “empirical correlations and causal relations” between
the intensity of religious belief and adolescent wellbeing or good life
“outcomes.”35 Of course, the idea that there would be a mechanistic causal
relationship between teenage belief in religion and wellbeing commits a number
of the errors we have already discussed in prior chapters. Not only can such an
explanation not cope with anomalies, but it also neglects the contingency of
meanings and the basic narrative structure of human agency. Yet the point at
Page 12 of 29
Methods
present is not to rehash these arguments. Rather, the point is to make clear the
way that statistical data can be both used and abused. Random sampling and
statistical inference are powerful tools for anti-naturalist social science provided
researchers keep clear of the temptation to impose mechanistic explanations
between atomized, essentialized, or reified variables (here “religiosity” and
“wellbeing”). Instead, social scientists should explore the inherited traditions
and contingent reasons and beliefs that have helped create a particular
distribution of beliefs, attitudes, and behaviors. They should connect a given set
of findings to wider webs of belief and meaning. This means engaging in the
hermeneutic circle, and explaining a particular pattern through the construction
of a holistic narrative of meanings, not formulating mechanistic laws. Agents
should be situated within traditions, and stories told about how they inherited or
modified their beliefs, actions, and practices.
For example, if religious U.S. adolescents are outperforming their peers in terms
of “wellbeing,” the anti-naturalist social scientist should consider a whole
battery of questions that remain obscured by the tacit naturalist assumptions of
Smith and Denton. This means looking at questions like: Are certain religious
traditions more likely to create certain kinds of wellbeing (for example, Max
Weber’s famous link between Calvinist theology and capitalist prosperity)? Such
cultural links might then reveal that the term “wellbeing” is not simply neutrally
descriptive. Whose definition of “wellbeing” is being granted priority in such (p.
100) research? After all, varying traditions have starkly opposed conceptions of
“wellbeing.” The term is not essentially or atomistically self-evident, but must be
related to wider webs of meaning in ways that produce rival and contestable
conceptions of wellbeing and not just one. In this vein, a reader of Smith and
Denton’s study whose philosophical intuitions have been honed by anti-
naturalism might ask: Is the study neglecting rival definitions of “wellbeing”
held by other religious traditions or teens who do not necessarily have religious
beliefs? Perhaps atheistic and agnostic teens simply do not share the same
conception of wellbeing (this would mean Smith and Denton might be
committing conceptual errors like essentialism and object-side instrumentalism).
Yet even if the concept of wellbeing is widely shared, the link is not mechanistic,
but involves contingent belief formation and self-interpretation. An anti-
naturalist social science must be prepared to explore the complex matrices of
meaning, belief, tradition, and practice that have created certain descriptive
relationships and not move to the oversimplifying, distortive mechanistic
explanatory forms of naturalism. As with mass surveys more generally, data
analysis like random sampling and statistical inference can be accepted as a
powerful tool provided social scientists do not mistakenly begin to atomize and
correlate such findings into mechanistic forms of explanation.
Page 13 of 29
Methods
A parallel set of problems arises with tools of analysis like case studies, which
are often conversely thought to be a guarantee of more historically and
interpretively sensitive inquiry than statistical inference and random sampling.
Case studies are employed across the social sciences, but in political science are
most often identified with the more “qualitative” subfields, especially
comparative politics. One of the most widely cited methodologists of case studies
is the political scientist, John Gerring. Briefly scrutinizing his influential claims
will help clarify the naturalist dangers and anti-naturalist potential of this tool of
analysis.
Page 14 of 29
Methods
For instance, in the case of weak, probabilistic causal bonds between variables
Gerring writes of “democracy” and “the economy” as if they were formal,
ahistorical variables: “democracy, if it has any effect on economic growth at all,
probably has only a slight effect over the near-to-medium term, and this effect is
probably characterized by many exceptions.”38 What this passage reveals is
Gerring’s naturalist tendency to treat political reality as reified, essentialized,
and atomistic units. Gerring’s defense and articulation of case-study analysis is
certainly not without merit but needs to be disentangled from these naturalist
tendencies. By contrast, interpretive social scientists analyze cases not for the
sake of setting up mechanistic and ahistorical causal bonds, but for the
construction of contingent narratives, family resemblances, and patterns of
meaning. So the case study, far from being inherently interpretive or historical,
is (like the other methods of data analysis) subsumable under either one of the
competing philosophical paradigms.
Of course, all this can be taken in a very naturalist direction if meanings are
treated as self-evident, brute bits of empirical reality in little need of context or
interpretation. Indeed, under the philosophical sway of naturalism there is a
serious danger that the coding categories or labels will become completely
exogenous to the social world supposedly being studied. When this happens
researchers will be more likely to ignore the holistic, contingent, and historical
dimensions of meanings. Instead, under the spell of naturalism, researchers
might start treating coded terms like reified, essentialist, or atomistic objects
ready to be plugged into mechanistic explanations. Researchers can correct this
mistake by always remaining aware of the way their coded categories should be
derived from the contingent beliefs and meanings of the interview subjects. Anti-
naturalism implies that coded concepts should be the fruit of a dialogue between
the interviewer and interviewee—as such, the concepts should have a bottom-up
sensitivity to agent language and self-understandings. Coded concepts that fail
to capture the contingent meanings and beliefs of the subjects in question are
philosophically defective. For this reason, the most recent handbooks on
grounded theory have rightly stressed the need for an “iterative” process in
Page 15 of 29
Methods
A final method that combines both elements of data collection and data analysis
is Q methodology. Q methodology has mostly been developed and employed by
psychologists in order to study configurations of opinions and beliefs within a
group. Carrying out this method involves several steps, beginning with selecting
a sample collection of items (these can be pictures, objects, or statements) for
participants in the study to then rank along a continuum. The continuum can be
devised along any number of scales like “most agree to most disagree, most
characteristic to most uncharacteristic, most attractive to most unattractive.”42
The participants then assign the series of items selected by the researchers a
number along the scale (for example, +5 or “I strongly agree” with this
statement). The significance of statements on a given theme (like love or crime
or moods) can in this way be organized and studied by researchers across a
group of participants. A key feature of Q methods is the exit interview in which
“open-ended comments” are requested to discover “how the participant has
interpreted the items.”43 The results of the various rankings can then be
mathematically sorted, ordered, and analyzed into various patterns that are
subject by researchers to interpretation.
By contrast, interpretive philosophy shows that meanings are always the product
of the contingent reasons and intentions of particular agents. Reification
happens when features of social reality are stripped and disconnected from
agent intentions, purposes, reasons, and beliefs. Researchers should never be
mystified into treating meanings as objects ascribable to a group “gestalt” that
hovers above any one participant. For this involves a basic naturalist
philosophical confusion over the nature of meanings. Fortunately, the same
methodological writers provide the antidote to bring Q methods in a more
interpretively sound direction. This can be done by keeping the rankings and
configurations of Q methods embedded within the reasons and beliefs that
Page 16 of 29
Methods
participants gave in their interviews. This can be used to “fill out” the various
competing meanings and reasons that have led to certain rankings of items.45
The formal configurations must not be allowed to turn into formal, ahistorical
features of social reality that have no connection to the thought-world, beliefs,
meanings, and practices of the participants in the study.
In sum, the various methods of data analysis offer highly valuable research tools
for working social scientists. A social science without the tools of random
sampling, statistical inference, and case studies would be deeply impaired.
Moreover, there is no reason why interpretive social scientists cannot make
careful and selective use of Q methodology if it helps them answer a particular
research question or explore the meanings and beliefs of those they are
studying. However, when using these tools social scientists must also be
philosophically cautious and resist the temptation to atomize, reify, or mechanize
political reality. The task of the social scientist is not to hunt down correlations
that might yield the holy grail of ahistorical causal bonds, but rather to
historicize findings by placing them within the scope of a particular narrative
and world of meaning.
In the social sciences, heuristics most often take the shape of formal modeling
and rational choice theory. Of all the heuristics used by social scientists today,
perhaps none is more often thought to be the antithesis to an interpretive
approach than rational choice theory. After all, what could be more contrary to
interpretive philosophy than creating a model of rationality completely divorced
Page 17 of 29
Methods
from the actual beliefs of individuals in their life-worlds? And we already saw
that scholars like Colin Hay have insightfully linked this kind of project to a
deterministic view of social reality as fixed by certain option or incentive
environments. Yet, like the other methods we have examined in this chapter,
rational choice theory can be put to either naturalist or anti-naturalist uses. Anti-
naturalist social scientists will be able to appreciate this once they view rational
choice theory as a heuristic and not foremost an attempt to conduct data
collection or analysis. Once social scientists realize that rational choice theory is
a heuristic, they are free to playfully make use of this method within certain
limited contexts and as suits their purposes—again, they must steer clear of
naturalist snags. This series of points will become clearer by taking a closer look
at the specifics of rational choice.
Rational choice theory does not begin by looking at the actual social world but
instead by building an ideal conception of human rationality. Like randomization
and statistical inference, rational choice is a way of organizing and reasoning
about certain features of social reality. But unlike data analysis, rational choice
does not begin by paying very much attention to the actual features of social
reality. Instead, rational choice proposes an ideal theory of decision-making and
strategic game scenarios. In the case of rational choice, this is achieved by
formulating axioms about how a certain kind of rational agent makes decisions—
a process known as “axiomatization.”46 Two key (p.105) axioms of rational
choice modeling are the assumptions that individual preferences are complete
and transitive. Completeness assumes that a rational actor will always be able to
compare and rank preferences (though ties and indifference are both allowed).
What is not allowed by the completeness axiom is that a rational actor will be
unable to compare and rank two preferences. In addition, the transitivity axiom
assumes that a rational actor can transfer the preference of one object over
another to other objects. So, a rational actor who prefers x to y and y to z must
also prefer x to z.
What does anti-naturalist philosophy make of such formal models built before
researchers have even had a chance to consider the actual self-understandings
and webs of meaning of particular individuals out in the social world? First, anti-
naturalism stresses the way in which rational choice theory’s axiomatization and
idealization of social reality is effective only within a very limited domain.51 The
biggest naturalist pitfall for rational choice theory is to mistakenly assume that it
offers a universal, historically transcendent account of the human subject.
Indeed, many rational choice theorists have themselves begun to affirm that this
kind of formal model can in no way be taken as a universal theory of human
agency. The best way to see this, and avoid naturalist pitfalls, is by
understanding some of the limits of axiomatization—many of which have been
mapped out by rational choice theorists and their (p.106) critics. We will focus
on only a couple of examples of such limits in order to impress upon readers the
importance of treating rational choice as a heuristic and not as a universal
theory explaining human action. We will then turn to possible anti-naturalist
uses of rational choice as a heuristic.
The completeness axiom assumes that any two objects can be compared or else
are simply objects of indifference. Pairs of objects, in other words, no matter
how different, are comparable and susceptible to ranking. But this excludes from
the outset all goods that are incommensurable or unable to be compared to one
another. Critics of rational choice have attempted to establish the existence of
incommensurable goods in various ways. One influential way is the “small
improvements” argument.52 The small improvements argument asks us to
imagine a person who is unable to decide between two preferences—say,
seriously endangering the life of a loved one versus saving his small bankrupt
country one trillion dollars. The completeness axiom holds that all goods are
comparable, granted there may be ties. This means that if one million dollars
were added to the one trillion then the individual, so long as he or she is a
rational decision-maker under this definition, should at that point prefer the
money to keeping the loved one safe. Yet because such incremental changes
might not break the stalemate, this shows that the goods in question are not in
fact comparable. And yet neither can it be said that the individual was
indifferent to the economic fate of his country or the wellbeing of this person.53
The completeness axiom is therefore not a psychologically valid description of
human attachment to certain goods, which individuals can resist subordinating
Page 19 of 29
Methods
This is a larger problem than it may at first appear because human life abounds
in incommensurable goods. For example, can we compare one person we love
dearly to another? What of competing political and ethical goods like security
and freedom, justice and mercy? Utilitarian philosophers often argue that all
goods are subject to completeness and ordering. What is certain is that society is
not made up exclusively of utilitarian philosophers. Individuals daily deal with
what they perceive as incommensurable goods that comprise their distinctive
ethical outlooks. Moreover, what counts as an incommensurable good will
depend on the self-understandings of the individual or group. Social scientists
cannot legislate this beforehand. In one culture newborns, totems, and the land
will be incomparable goods; in another a particular species of animal, a
tabernacle, a piece of bread. From a sociological perspective, completeness of
preference is simply not always an accurate or even useful way to look at human
decision-making.55 Thus, the basic axioms of rational choice should not be taken
as universal descriptions or explanations of human action. The idealization of
one kind of formal rational structure is not a successful or universal human
anthropology. In fact, in a (p.107) very different way, it veers back into the
problematic universal, ahistorical, and autonomous subject critically examined
earlier in the debates between old-school phenomenologists and Foucault.
Foucault’s radically historicist critique applies here as well.
Page 20 of 29
Methods
The above line of reasoning makes clear why the domain in which rational
choice has met with the greatest success is contemporary economics. This is
because economic actors often aspire to approximate the type of decision-maker
offered by neoclassicism and rational choice. The practices of modern (p.108)
consumer capitalism have habituated individuals to the treatment of goods as
complete and transitive. Likewise, the discourses of rational choice have seeped
into the self-understandings of many in market societies who learned these
discourses in economics and business schools. By contrast, rational choice and
modern economics have been much less successful in domains that deal with
incommensurable goods and non-strategic, non-calculative self-understandings
and practices. But economics is only an autonomous domain in academia. The
actual economic world is always embedded in values, practices, and institutions
that extend beyond the market and its calculative practices.58 Human social,
economic, and political reality are permeated by incommensurable goods as well
as non-strategic forms of reasoning that can make the assumed axioms a
stumbling block to effective social research. This perhaps goes a long way
toward explaining the intense combination of successes and disappointments
that is the modern discipline of economics.
The anti-naturalist upshot of all of this is clear: rational choice is an effective but
also highly limited tool. Social scientists should employ rational choice when
there is some approximate fit between the actual self-understandings of the
agents involved and the idealized model. They must never mistake what is a
heuristic for actual explanation or description. The thin or minimalist sociology
generated by rational choice must be evaluated in light of thick understandings
and descriptions. And even in those limited cases where rational choice is found
Page 21 of 29
Methods
In addition to this domain-limited use of rational choice theory, Hay has drawn
attention to the ways in which rational choice can be employed to illuminate
hypothetical, what-if scenarios. The purpose of the rational choice method in this
case would be “hypothetical thought experiments” that ask the question “what if
the world were like this?”59 If social scientists are careful to not mistake rational
choice theories as naturalistic and explanatory, then these models might
“provide timely and powerful warnings about the likely consequences of existing
political trajectories.”60 Vicious cycles and perverse incentives that encourage
the squandering of shared goods in the environment (like water and climate)
might be clarified using rational choice models. Similarly, the consequences of
neoliberalizing or marketizing goods like public education or welfare might be
explored in this way—not as “predictive hypotheses” but as “precautionary
political warnings.”61 These are what Hay dubs “as-if” uses of naturalist
assumptions and theories, and we will return to them at length in our treatment
of public policy. For now the point is that Hay adds (p.109) another important
sense in which rational choice may be employed as a heuristic method, divorced
from naturalist philosophical assumptions.
relationship to political life.63 Such uses of rational choice are more explicable in
terms of the insularity of much of modern scholarship than a genuine effort to
respond to social reality.64
But advocates of the interpretive turn and qualitative methods should also take
note. Social scientists should not squeamishly cut themselves off from the uses
of rational choice analysis. Such models can and have generated insights into
the ramifications of strategic and calculative reasoning within human practices,
particularly in market scenarios where individuals are highly habituated to
thinking in this way. The successes of modern economics as a discipline are
often tied to the strength of rational choice as a heuristic. Once again, anti-
naturalism is uniquely placed to identify both the strengths and the weaknesses
of this tool. Anti-naturalism rejects the overblown antagonism between rational
choice scholars and their opponents. Instead, anti-naturalism is able to absorb
and integrate rational choice into a vast array of social science methods. This is
accomplished, moreover, without ever giving way to the naturalist myth that
rational choice is anything like an adequate philosophical anthropology. Indeed,
rational choice must never be mistaken for an actual anthropology or even a
very good account of how humans across history form their beliefs (a mistake
made all too frequently by neoclassical economists).65 But even economists need
anti-naturalists concepts like traditions, beliefs, practices, and the social
background. This will tune them into whether a (p.110) particular actor or set
of actors within a context might be more given to rational choice strategic
thinking because they themselves were instructed in this heuristic or learned
approximations of it through long iterative decisions in the marketplace.
We have seen that data collection, data analysis, and heuristics can all be
reconciled. This means tools as diverse as observer-participation, in-depth
interviews, mass surveys, random sampling, statistical inference, case studies, Q
methodology, grounded theory, and rational choice modeling can all be either
used or abused. Anti-naturalism is uniquely placed to create a vast synthesis of
the data collection, data analysis, and heuristics that have been developed by
social scientists in the last two centuries.
Of course, within the limits of a single research project, mixing methods (like
advanced econometric analysis and ethnography) could be difficult because of
the practical unlikelihood of finding this kind of knowledge in a single
Page 23 of 29
Methods
The anti-naturalist case for multi-methods does in this regard seem to imply a
shift toward much greater levels of cooperation across research communities
than has thus far been the case. Unfortunately, scholarly communities clustered
tribalistically around method-expertise and technical wizardry currently serve as
the norm. Each tribe claims for itself the one true path to social science via a
particular method or methods. By contrast, future anti-naturalist ethnographers
and statisticians might collaborate in the construction of a narrative social
science. But even in lieu of this more cooperative future, current anti-naturalists
working under intellectual isolation are free to learn from the research of both
hard-nosed quants and linguistically adept qualies. Anti-naturalist social
scientists can employ philosophy to help them sift through the mountains of
empirical findings generated by current researchers. What is distorted by
naturalism can be carefully separated out from what is valid and admirable but
still in need of interpretive and historical (p.111) contextualization. The
repurposing of existing findings into interpretive and narrative forms of
explanation is arguably an enormous area of untapped research potential. An
entire generation of social scientists could devote itself to taking the many
bricks and isolated pieces of information generated by the naturalist focus on
data and build them into narrative, sociological edifices.
Notes:
(1.) The authors call this “soaking and poking.” Gary King, Robert O. Keohane,
and Sidney Verba, Designing Social Inquiry: Scientific Inference in Qualitative
Research (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1994) 38–9. For another
widely used textbook that makes a similar assumption, see: John W. Creswell,
Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches, 3rd
ed. (Los Angeles, CA: SAGE Publications, 2009) 8.
(3.) For example: Henry Brady and David Collier, Rethinking Social Inquiry:
Diverse Tools, Shared Standards, 2nd ed. (Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield,
Page 24 of 29
Methods
(4.) A similar point about a pluralist approach to methods has been echoed in the
action research literature. For example: Davydd James Greenwood and Morten
Levin, Introduction to Action Research, 2nd ed. (Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE
Publications, 2007).
(5.) For a usage similar to our own see: David Marsh and Gerry Stoker, eds.,
Theory and Methods in Political Science, 3rd ed. (New York: Palgrave Macmillan,
2010) 3.
(6.) The famous phrase is from Clifford Geertz, “Thick Description: Toward an
Interpretive Theory of Culture,” in The Interpretation of Cultures (New York:
Basic Books, 1973) 6. See also: John Van Maanen, “Ethnography as Work,”
Journal of Management Studies 48:1 (2011): 219–20.
(9.) Kenneth MacLeish, Making War at Fort Hood: Life and Uncertainty in a
Military Community (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2013).
(10.) Alice Goffman, On the Run: Fugitive Life in an American City (Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press, 2014). For a recent overview of urban ethnography
see: Mitchell Duneier, Philip Kasinitz, and Alexandra Murphy, eds., The Urban
Ethnography Reader (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014).
(12.) Arlie Russell Hochschild, Strangers in Their Own Land: Anger and
Mourning on the American Right (New York: The New Press, 2016); Matthew
Desmond, Evicted: Poverty and Profit in the American City (New York: Penguin
Random House, 2016).
Page 25 of 29
Methods
(17.) Dvora Yanow, Sierk Ybema, and Merlijn van Hulst, “Practicing
Organizational Ethnography,” in The Practice of Qualitative Organizational
Research: Core Methods and Current Challenges, eds. Catherine Cassel and
Gillian Symon (London: Sage, 2012) 331–50. See also: James Clifford, “On
Ethnographic Authority,” 125.
(22.) See, for example, our extended discussion below of: Christian Smith and
Melinda Lundquist Denton, Soul Searching: The Religious and Spiritual Lives of
American Teenagers (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2005) 67.
(23.) For further discussion see: Earl Babbie, Survey Research Methods, 2nd ed.
(Belmont, CA: Wadsworth Publishing Company, 1998) 56–9; John W. Cresswell,
Research Design: Qualitative, Quantitative, and Mixed Methods Approaches, 3rd
ed. (Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE, 2009) 146.
(24.) Babbie, Survey Research Methods, 52. Another example of this naturalist
error can be seen in: Arlene Fink, The Survey Handbook, 2nd ed. (Thousand
Oaks, CA: SAGE, 2003) 55–60.
(27.) See: Simon Watts and Paul Stenner, “Doing Q-Methodology: Theory,
Method, and Interpretation,” Qualitative Research in Psychology 2 (2005): 67–
91.
(29.) For a more detailed discussion, see: Kellstedt and Whitten, The
Fundamentals of Political Science Research, 126–7.
Page 26 of 29
Methods
(30.) Lesley Andres, Designing and Doing Survey Research (Thousand Oaks, CA:
SAGE Publications, 2012) 9.
(36.) John Gerring, “The Case Study: What It Is and What It Does,” in The Oxford
Handbook of Political Science, ed. Robert E. Goodin (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2011) 1137–8.
(39.) Kathy Charmaz and Linda Liska Belgrave, “Qualitative Interviewing and
Grounded Theory Analysis,” in The SAGE Handbook of Interview Research: The
Complexity of the Craft, 2nd ed., eds. Jaber Gubrium, James Holstein, Amir
Marvasti, and Karyn McKinney (Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE, 2012) 349.
(46.) Itzhak Gilboa, Rational Choice (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2010) 39–40.
(47.) See: Julian Reiss, Philosophy of Economics (New York: Routledge, 2013) 6;
Daniel M. Hausman, “Philosophy of Economics,” in Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy, vol. 3, ed. Edward Craig (London: Routledge, 1998) 211–22.
(48.) This has been a key finding of behavioral economics. For famous early
pieces disputing the transitivity of human preferences on psychological grounds,
see: Amos Tversky and Daniel Kahneman, “The Framing of Decisions and the
Page 27 of 29
Methods
(49.) Colin Hay, Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction (New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2002) 9.
(51.) See Donald Green and Ian Shapiro’s important critique of rational choice’s
pretensions toward “universalism.” Green and Shapiro, Pathologies of Rational
Choice Theory (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1994) 54.
(54.) For one extended account of goods not susceptible to rational calculation,
see: Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity
(Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press, 1989) Part I.
(55.) Rational choice theorists have similarly found that individuals do not
always hold transitive preferences but in some contexts hold cyclical
preferences. Peterson, An Introduction to Decision Theory, 290.
Page 28 of 29
Methods
(62.) Iain Hampsher-Monk and Andrew Hindmoor, “Rational Choice and Inter-
pretive Evidence: Caught Between a Rock and a Hard Place?”, Political Studies
58 (2010): 49.
(63.) Ian Shapiro, The Flight From Reality in the Human Sciences (Princeton, NJ:
Princeton University Press, 2005).
(64.) Because of our concern with rational choice as a social science method, we
have intentionally avoided the related debate over whether rational choice ought
to be normative for decision-making.
(65.) For a famous articulation of this erroneous view see Nobel laureate, Gary
S. Becker, The Economic Approach to Human Behavior (Chicago, IL: University
of Chicago Press, 1976).
(66.) These issues have been extensively and provocatively discussed in action
research literature: Morten Levin and Davydd Greenwood, “Revitalizing
Universities by Reinventing the Social Sciences: Bildung and Action Research,”
in The SAGE Handbook of Qualitative Research, eds. Norman Denzin and
Yvonna Lincoln (Thousand Oaks, CA: SAGE Publications, 2011) 27–42.
Page 29 of 29
Synchronic empirical research
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0006
Keywords: interpretive empirical research, culture, identity, political resistance, Islam, Race,
globalization
Ignoring philosophy does not spare social science from philosophy. It only means
that choices are made without proper critical reflection. In the case of tacit
naturalist philosophical assumptions, this can cause problems with explanation
and concept formation that distort otherwise highly valuable research efforts.
Anti-naturalist critique of much of the mainstream in social science today makes
clear that in the future social scientists need to become more conversant in
certain philosophical issues. Graduate schools in social science should
emphasize philosophical education as much as methodological skills like
numeracy, fluency in native languages, and the ability to take random samples or
Page 1 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
model strategic rationality. The latter remain important, but they are never
substitutes for philosophical training. To the contrary, whether social scientists
know it or not, philosophy is what allows for a coherent treatment and execution
of those very methodologies.
But then what does a specifically anti-naturalist empirical research agenda look
like? The next two chapters seek to give a philosophically informed answer to
this question. Anti-naturalism is a completely alternative paradigm of research in
the social sciences. It conceptualizes empirical reality in a way that breaks away
from naturalism’s essentialism, atomism, and instrumentalism. In what follows
we will argue that the topics that have been taken up by researchers who are
hostile to naturalism are not purely accidental or random, but actually flow out
of basic philosophical commitments. Anti-naturalist philosophy does not merely
serve as an approach to topics, but helps shape the topics themselves. While
undoubtedly the entire world of phenomena is open to anti-naturalist social
science research, the way this research is conducted is expressive of particular
philosophical assumptions and commitments.
Page 2 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
following topics thus represent some of the most promising research areas in the
social sciences, whose potential remains largely untapped.
Some examples will help clarify this point. Consider, for instance, the current
debates raging in both academia and American society over the role (p.117) of
Islam in politics. This has become one of the most intense areas of argument
since the attack in New York City on the World Trade Center towers in 2001. Yet
what is rarely appreciated is the way these debates can be seriously
compromised and distorted by naturalist philosophical assumptions, which lead
to particular conceptualizations of empirical reality.
In this vein, consider the influential work of Samuel Huntington, the late
Harvard political scientist, whose work on Islam and global conflict was taken up
by many after the September 11 attacks. Writing well before 2001, Huntington
argued that the major source of global conflict post-Cold War would be what he
referred to as “civilizations.” In particular, Huntington argued that the twenty-
first century would be characterized by a violent “clash” between nine essential
civilizational types—including very prominently the “West” versus “Islam.”1 No
more would the competing secular ideologies of Marxism and liberal democracy
fuel global wars. Instead, civilizational identity rifts would determine the
frontiers of human warfare, and fighting would be particularly intense between
Islamic civilization and secular Western civilization.
Page 3 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
Page 4 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
In reality, scholars like Haddad, Smith, and Moore show that there are an
enormous number of ways of being a Muslim woman today—including not only
all the rival varieties of Sunni, Shi’ite, and Sufi theology but also creative new
self-interpretations in terms of feminism, Qur’anic interpretation, Islamic
women’s roles in public life, dress, education, and gender. There is no single way
of being a Muslim woman. For this reason “Muslim women in the West should
not be subsumed under any such stereotypes” but instead recognized as
“members of American society who act in conformity neither with Western
assumptions nor, necessarily, with the dictates of Islamic traditionalism.”8
An interpretive sensibility concerning political beliefs and identities has also led
scholars like Mary Habeck to wrestle with the specific ideologies and beliefs
behind politically radicalized variants of Islam like al-Qaida. According to
Habeck, Americans after September 11 did not adequately consider the identity
of the attackers: “Not all Muslims chose to carry out the attacks,” but rather the
advocates of a very specific minority and militant tradition within Islam, with its
own particular concepts, political theology, and lineage.9 Habeck refers to this
minority view as “jihadi” and argues that it has conducted a hostile takeover of
key Muslim theological concepts like jihad and tawhid in order to pursue the
overthrow of the current international system in the hope of establishing an
Islamic state.10 One of the key motives animating Habeck’s research is her belief
that knowing the identity of those who conducted the September 11 attacks is
Page 6 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
In short, there is good reason to believe that research into the threat posed by
certain heterodox offshoots of Islam is far better served by anti-naturalist
assumptions than by Huntington’s naturalism. In comparative terms, an anti-
naturalist research agenda is able to steer clear of dilemmas besetting naturalist
rivals. Of course, such social scientific research is also of urgent political
importance because failure to properly ascertain this reality will leave
governments, policy makers, and citizens shadowboxing with cartoon versions of
reality (enemies will be created unnecessarily and opportunities for vital
alliances missed). Anti-naturalism is thus able to overcome dilemmas facing
Huntington’s naturalism both at the theoretical level and as concepts for guiding
public policy.
(p.121) For example, although racism has certainly been around for centuries,
more recently various forms of folk naturalism are used to prop up racist
worldviews, which attempt to essentialize a kind of inferiority into the biology of
non-whites. Such folk naturalisms view races analogously to the way Huntington
views civilizations—self-contained entities or natural types that do not allow for
politically significant mixtures or variations. To be black, white, Hispanic, or
Asian is said to necessarily entail certain essentialized features of belief and
identity. A biological feature of skin tone supposedly signals a necessary pattern
of beliefs and certain kind of identity when it comes to areas like criminality,
politics, intellectuality, sexual drive, aggression, and so on.
Page 7 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
notion of contingency makes clear the ways in which race is a socially, culturally,
and politically interpreted category. Far from reducing human identity to
biological features of skin tone, anti-naturalism asks those who wish to
understand race in the modern world to wrestle with the effects of contingently
formed beliefs and identities about what it means to be black, white, Hispanic,
etc. Racial identities are in fact traditions of inherited beliefs and practice. As
such they are continually being creatively modified by those who inherent them.
This means that, for example, assumptions that Hispanic identity must
necessarily be characterized by an essential core set of features like sensuality,
passion, and musicality prove to be the results of particular histories and not
biological necessity. This focus on racial identity as a product of historically
contingent formed beliefs is clearly employed in the burgeoning branch of anti-
naturalist social science research that critically investigates the political role of
race in America.
Consider, for example, Michelle Alexander’s The New Jim Crow. Alexander notes
that while the sale and use of drugs occur at remarkably similar rates across
racial groups in America, blacks have been subject to far more punishment
(including incarceration rates twenty to fifty times higher than whites).12 This
massive discrepancy between crime and punishment, violation and enforcement,
leads Alexander to delve into the types of identity formation that have made this
possible. Here Alexander offers an extensive historical account and
interpretation of the role of beliefs and racial biases that shape the perception of
black identity among police officers, prosecutors, the courts, and the wider
public. In the public imagination, young African American males from the ghetto
have been envisioned as the main culprits in the War on Drugs. Indeed, black
youth have been so identified with illicit drug use that their dress,
communication, music, and even hairstyles have come to be falsely identified as
necessarily related to criminality and illegal drug activity. This false
essentialization of young African American identity as necessarily delinquent or
disordered is one of the most destructive ideological fictions within (p.122)
contemporary American life. Yet, as Alexander helps us see, this essentialist way
of looking at race also has concrete consequences for political reality: “from the
outset, the drug war could have been waged primarily in overwhelming white
suburbs or on college campuses” (since usage rates among these groups are
comparable) but this would have been seen as misdirected because drug use
among whites is often, paradoxically, not viewed as really criminal.13 In fact, the
War on Drugs—while officially colorblind—is largely driven by a particular set of
beliefs about who the “real” criminals within society are.
Alexander goes on to show how beliefs that criminalize black identity in turn
shape Supreme Court jurisprudence, congressional legislation, and police and
incarceration tactics.14 The overall effect of this racially biased notion of identity
has been the historically unprecedented round-up of racial minorities into
America’s prisons—a phenomenon known as mass incarceration. What look to be
Page 8 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
The point once again is not whether the reader agrees or disagrees with this line
of research into race per se, but to see that an anti-naturalist philosophical
conception of identities and beliefs generates a critique of naturalist concept
formation and explanation. At the same time, anti-naturalist conceptions of belief
and identity as contingently formed entities open up what would otherwise have
gone unnoticed by both other social scientists and the wider public. A new kind
of research program into identities and beliefs becomes possible. Suddenly
sociologists and political scientists have historical and cultural histories as part
of the depth of meanings they engage when investigating beliefs and identities.
By comparison, ahistorical, essentialized notions of identity appear both
intellectually and politically inadequate.
Cultural practices
Another empirical topic made possible by anti-naturalist philosophical
commitments is a focus on cultural practices. Practices are defined as any stable
patterns of action—from particular forms of marriage and worship to (p.123)
education and political procedures. Studying practices is one way that anti-
naturalist social science can move from the micro-level examination of human
beliefs to mid- and macro-level analysis of institutions, structures, and systems.
As was the case with identities, interpretive social scientists treat practices as
historically contingent and expressive of a holistic web of meanings. Because
these meanings are the fruit of creative human intentionality, practices are in a
continual state of change and modification. Although practices are relatively
stable, a history of a given practice oftentimes reveals various iterations and
even ruptures in meaning.
Page 9 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
Take, for example, the big social scientific debate over civic participation in the
United States and other liberal democracies. There is now widespread
agreement among social scientists that Western electoral democracies are
experiencing a steep decline in voting.17 The question is what this means for
democracy more generally. Robert Putnam has argued for a thesis of complex
but general civic decline in America. He has added to the findings on voter
turnout a sophisticated empirical analysis of the decline in engagement in
informal civic institutions (like bowling leagues, neighborhood associations, and
charitable groups).18
(p.124) The problem is that this concept of “social capital” reifies the meaning
of America’s informal civic institutions, creating a kind of naturalist neglect of
the beliefs and intentions of actual individuals. Specifically, Putnam is reifying
social capital as a form of networking power as the meaning of institutions and
informal practices. What individuals actually believe becomes less important.
The meaning of social capital floats above all their actions like a cloud they
almost never touch (this cloud is what naturalists call “institutions”).
To avoid this mistake, social scientists need to keep in mind the way practices
are the result of human self-interpretive activity and therefore capable of
constant changes and gradations of meaning. Practices are generated by human
actions and not the other way around. A question thus arises: What happens if
social scientists actually focus on the self-interpretations, beliefs, and practices
of individual agents when investigating all these recent dropouts from voting
and bowling leagues? Does an anti-naturalist sensitivity to practices at all
Page 10 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
Page 11 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
Rosanvallon also argues that citizens today frequently carry out the counter-
democratic practice of “prevention” or a form of “negative sovereignty” that is
capable of blocking or thwarting elite representative action.25 Naturalist social
science with its reified notion of civic institutions thus misses the rise in informal
ways that a “democracy of rejection” emerges in which “increasingly…popular
sovereignty manifests itself as a power to refuse.”26 In this way, surveillance,
judgment, and prevention together encompass a plethora of counter-democratic
practices that comprise the “invisible institutions” of democracy that have been
neglected by other social science researchers because of insensitivity to
meanings.27
Page 12 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
Too often mainstream political science deems this kind of minute phenomenon to
be primarily of sociological interest and bear no real political significance.
Practices like the spread of standardization are ignored in favor of studying
certain institutions almost exclusively: interest groups, lobbying, the presidency,
Congress, the courts, and so on. Anti-naturalist philosophical concepts, by
contrast, help social scientists see that politics is a far more complex, sprawling,
and even confusing phenomenon than something merely limited to a few
canonized institutions. Indeed, inquiry into neglected micro-practices of this
kind can in turn shed fresh light on the practices of traditional public and private
sector institutions (for example, why certain congressional actors who otherwise
disfavor federal regulation might favor the imposition of standardized norms on
public schools). Anti-naturalism thus makes possible an interpretively enriched
perspective on institutions that otherwise gain the appearance of overly
straightforward entities that are easy to grasp and describe.
Page 13 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
In this way, Porter’s study of minute practices and meanings opens up surprising
insights into central economic and political patterns of action in government and
private sector corporations. These patterns of action are not reducible to
ahistorical, reified institutions, but rather are continually being modified by the
introduction and development of new meanings. Porter’s investigation into the
politics of standardization and quantification can help social scientists come to
grips with much broader phenomena like the spread of public policies of
neoliberalism and networks in the modern state and corporations (a topic we
return to at length in our discussion of democratic governance and public
policy). Quantification, auditing, benchmarks, and standardization are all part of
a deeper politics that has transformed the major political institutions of
modernity.
The point again is to see how anti-naturalist philosophical concepts (in this case
practices) make this empirical discovery possible. By contrast, naturalism has
devoted too many talented researchers to a narrowed study of institutions. No
doubt much of this work is valuable. But the de facto treatment of these
institutions as the totality of the study of modern politics betrays a naturalist
reduction. In reality, there is an entire subterranean world of human political (p.
128) activity in need of illumination. The work of anti-naturalist social scientists
has already yielded surprising insights about seemingly mundane and
uncontroversial patterns of action like standardization and measurement by
numbers. These in turn might come to radically reshape how we think of
quantification and standardization in major political institutions like state
legislatures or international federations. Yet without an anti-naturalist
philosophical sensibility, such insights go unseen.
Page 14 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
In this vein, consider the famous work of American political scientist Louis Hartz
who argued that the liberal tradition in the United States has been completely
dominant since the country’s inception. Hartz drew inspiration for this thesis
from reading Alexis de Tocqueville, who implied that Americans shared a kind of
uniform ideological consensus or what is commonly referred to as an American
“creed.” This creed consisted of the affirmation of certain (p.129) basic tenets
of liberal ideology like the primacy of the individual to pursue his or her
preferences, the contractual nature of society, and the canonization of certain
basic rights. As Hartz put it, liberalism is so dominant in the United States that
“there has never been a ‘liberal movement’ or a real ‘liberal party’” but only “the
American Way of Life, a nationalist articulation of Locke.”32 Indeed, in this view,
even when anti-liberal ideologies form in the United States like Edmund Burke’s
conservatism, Karl Marx’s socialism, or various populist kinds of racist or
authoritarian ideology, they have in fact been liberalized in terms of their
fundamental assumptions about individual rights and the source of the
government’s legitimacy. Thus, in Hartz’s view the liberal tradition is the
uniform, homogenous starting point for American political ideology—a kind of
Page 15 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
Page 16 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
of Hartz, the force of Gray’s rebuke of Fukuyama comes from being able to
philosophically grasp the contingency of human-inherited beliefs and traditions.
Where Fukuyama sees a necessary growing convergence, Gray is able to
observe empirical countercurrents. Specifically, Gray saw very early on that
globalization involved not convergence but the formation of conflicting
indigenous capitalisms—to varying degrees illiberal—in Russia, Japan, China,
and Singapore, to name only a few. For example, Japan developed an indigenous
capitalism and path to modernization that confounded the widespread Western
assumption that individualism and capitalism must necessarily go hand in hand.
Japan accomplished this through a culture of firms that “grafts on institutions
inherited from its medieval age” such that “Japanese market institutions rely on
networks of trust rather than upon a culture of contract.”37 Gray argues that
Japanese stances toward employment, career security, and the role of firms
within civic life are capitalist without being individualist. Similarly, in Russia,
Gray analyzes the emergence after communism of an “anarcho-capitalism” with
an “enfeebled, corrupt and, in some regions and contexts, virtually non-existent
state” together with “the pervasive presence throughout economic life of
organized crime.”38 This has itself developed into a “state-led Russian
capitalism” that draws on the tradition of economics from the “last decades of
the Tsarist regime.”39 In this way, an anti-naturalist sensitivity to multiple
traditions reveals the error in Fukuyama’s view of modernization as necessarily
developing toward a single set of beliefs that match North Atlantic liberal
democracies.
Anti-naturalist philosophy makes clear that the reason such multiplication and
diversification of traditions is possible is because humans can modify and resist
their inherited traditions.40 This notion of “resistance”—or the ability to change
and subvert even the most long-held inherited beliefs—is a further anti-
naturalist concept that is able to aid empirical inquiry. A few examples will help
illustrate how this philosophical concept proves empirically fruitful in ways that
elude naturalism.
(p.131) Consider, for instance, the work of social theorists like E. P. Thompson,
Raymond Williams, and other members of the First British New Left who
insisted on a humanistic brand of socialism against the naturalist, structural
determinism of mainstream Marxism. Thompson focused on history from below,
and studied the lived experiences of various subordinate groups including
peasants, women, racial minorities, and especially the English working class. In
his famous study, The Making of the English Working Class, Thompson argued
that nineteenth-century Luddites, croppers, handloom weavers, and utopian
artisans all played a part in the emergence of a modern English working-class
tradition of popular resistance to the dominant political ideologies of the age.41
In this way Thompson brought attention to neglected streams of meaning and
practice that helped shape English political life.
Page 17 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
What Williams and Thompson shared was a view of human agency as able to
modify and resist inherited and even hegemonic beliefs. This empirical study of
resistance fueled by certain philosophical commitments has gone on to inspire a
number of very fruitful research programs in the social sciences. Two in
particular are worth mentioning.
First, Stuart Hall formed a school of cultural studies, which focuses on questions
of race and gender and also made significant contributions to the debates over
Thatcherism and New Labor in England. Hall drew on Antonio Gramsci’s
concept of hegemony to claim that popular culture can also reinforce dominant
ideas and identities, at the same time that resistance is still possible.
Thatcherism in 1980s England was an example of one such hegemonic tradition
that managed to present neoliberal economic ideas as a kind of populist
movement. This was accompanied, however, by an authoritarian style of
government, which according to Hall was met with popular resistance.43 Hall
was thus able to bring attention to the way that ruling ideologies almost
inevitably meet with some form of resistance in modern societies—whether
planned or ad hoc, conservative or radical. Culture, Hall showed, should not be
mistaken for a uniform entity spreading evenly and unchanging over the whole
of society like a blanket.
Page 18 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
The backlash to these dominant modernizing trends is what Scott calls “the
peasantry’s ‘little tradition’ of moral dissent and resistance.”44 Although large-
scale action like peasant revolts is thwarted more often than not, peasants have
developed tenacious “everyday forms of resistance,” including “the ordinary
weapons of relatively powerless groups: foot dragging, dissimulation, desertion,
false compliance, pilfering, feigned ignorance, slander, arson, sabotage, and so
on.”45 Such tiny techniques of resistance may seem insignificant but have the
potential to “in the end make an utter shambles of the policies dreamed up by
their would-be superiors in the capital.”46
Although Scott’s work is not entirely free of naturalism (as when he slides into
discussing peasant psychology and identity as if it were a more ahistorical form
of subjectivity), nonetheless his work helps show how an anti-naturalist
philosophical conception of human agency as capable of resistance in turn can
generate a tremendously dynamic field of empirical research.47 Again, where
naturalist social scientists see only an overarching system or structure of beliefs,
anti-naturalist researchers can focus on the actual empirical complexity that
comprises the world.
Synchronic study of the political and social world is therefore best served by
anti-naturalist philosophical concepts like beliefs, identities, practices,
traditions, and resistance. Indeed, in addition to freeing research from errors
like reification, essentialism, instrumentalism, and reductivism, anti-naturalist
concepts actually open new domains for inquiry. Far too often social scientists
led by naturalist intuitions view empirical diversity as an enemy that must be
vanquished on the road to true universal science. Naturalists are thus
continually haunted by the inevitable anomalies and empirical diversity that
spoil their attempts at a uniform and ahistorical treatment of society. By
contrast, anti-naturalist philosophy allows social scientists to embrace the deep
complexity and multidimensional meanings of social and political life. What was
once the bane of scientific theory (empirical diversity) becomes another avenue
into renewed discovery.
Notes:
(1.) Samuel Huntington, “The Clash of Civilizations?”, Foreign Affairs 72:3
(1993): 22–49.
(4.) Edward Said, “The Clash of Ignorance,” The Nation 273:12 (2001): 12.
Page 19 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
(6.) Yvonne Yazbeck Haddad, Jane Smith, and Kathleen Moore, Muslim Women
in America (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006) 22.
(9.) Mary Habeck, Knowing the Enemy: Jihadist Ideology and the War on Terror
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 2006) 2.
(14.) For example, see: Alexander, The New Jim Crow, 108, 112, 115–17, 119–23,
139.
(15.) Victor Rios, Punished: Policing the Lives of Black and Latino Boys (New
York: New York University Press, 2011) xiv; Alice Goffman, On the Run: Fugitive
Life in an American City (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2014).
(18.) Robert Putnam, Bowling Alone (New York: Simon & Schuster, 2000) 27.
(28.) Martha Lampland and Susan Leigh Star, eds., Standards and Their Stories:
How Quantifying, Classsifying, and Formalizing Practices Shape Everyday Life
(Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press, 2009) 6.
(29.) Theodore Porter, “Speaking Precision to Power: The Modern Role of Social
Science,” Social Research 73:4 (2006): 1282.
(32.) Louis Hartz, The Liberal Tradition in America (New York: Harcourt, 1955)
11.
(34.) Smith, Civic Ideals, 38, 37. This is not to say that Smith’s social scientific
work is completely free of naturalist influences. It is worth noting that
unfortunately Smith sometimes flirts with naturalistic concepts such as the
deployment of “dependent variables” (p. 8). In addition, critics have noted that
Smith missed an opportunity to complicate the history of liberalism itself. Thus,
in Smith’s book: “it is an idealized and purified, even essentialized, liberalism
that makes an appearance. Whenever racism rears its ugly head, this showing is
taken as confirmation of a nonliberal strand rather than as a commentary on the
liberal tradition itself.” See: Ira Katznelson, “Review: Civic Ideals: Conflicting
Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History,” Political Theory 27:4 (1999): 568. None of
this negates the virtue in Smith’s basic shift toward multiple traditions and away
from an essentialized picture of American ideological belief.
(35.) Francis Fukuyama, “The End of History,” The National Interest 16 (1989):
4.
Page 21 of 22
Synchronic empirical research
(36.) John Gray, False Dawn: The Delusions of Global Capitalism (New York: The
New Press, 1998) 2.
(40.) There are some important affinities here with: Steven Griggs, Aletta J.
Norval, and Hendrik Wagenaar, eds., Practices of Freedom (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2014).
(41.) E. P. Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class (New York:
Random House, 1964) 12.
(42.) Raymond Williams, The Long Revolution (London: Chatto and Windus,
1961).
(43.) Stuart Hall, “The Great Moving Right Show,” in Stuart Hall and Martin
Jacques, eds., The Politics of Thatcherism (London: Lawrence and Wishart,
1983).
(44.) James C. Scott, The Moral Economy of the Peasant: Rebellion and
Subsistence in Southeast Asia (New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1976) viii.
Page 22 of 22
Historical sociologies
Historical sociologies
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0007
Even those who concede the validity of anti-naturalist critiques often question
whether this form of social science really offers a full-blown alternative. After all,
how can a philosophy that emphasizes individual beliefs as central to
understanding social reality ever get beyond fine-grained, micro-level case
studies? Don’t concepts like belief, identity, practice, and tradition require
examining meanings at a very local and limited level? Naturalism may have its
shortcomings, this line of reasoning goes, but at least it is able to make large-
scale generalizations by transcending particular historical contexts. Yet this
objection to hermeneutics, as we now hope to show, is seriously mistaken. The
interpretive turn, understood in anti-naturalist terms, is capable of large-scale
Page 1 of 23
Historical sociologies
Page 2 of 23
Historical sociologies
This much has been established by the foregoing analysis. What still requires
further exploration, however, is the way that this commitment to narrative
explanations opens up the capacity for anti-naturalist empirical research to
make large-scale generalizations about nations, history, civilizations, and the
seismic shifts in human culture and politics. There is nothing that philosophically
limits anti-naturalist social scientists to telling stories about small groups or
individuals. So long as social scientists’ narratives capture contingent formations
of meaning, then they are free to paint on as large or small a canvas as they like.
Page 3 of 23
Historical sociologies
In this way, anti-naturalist social scientists are able to construct what might be
called meta-narratives. Meta-narratives are interpretive stories about the
contingent formation of meanings, practices, traditions, and social worlds that
work at a large scale of generalization.
(p.138) The first and most important philosophical feature of genealogy is its
radical historicism. Genealogy emerged in the nineteenth century against the
backdrop of the widespread belief that history was developing according to a
natural set of organic stages (an intellectual paradigm discussed in Chapter 1 as
a form of developmental historicism). Figures as diverse as Auguste Comte, Karl
Marx, and John Stuart Mill all assumed history was unfolding according to a
progressive logic with convergence upon a universal set of final world-historical
institutions and societal forms. In other words, the historicism of the nineteenth
century was what we might call developmental, assuming that all human
societies passed through natural developmental phases akin to those of a life
form passing through infancy, maturity, and old age. History on this view was
locked into inescapable epochs or stages leading toward some final form. In this
way, the developmental view of history was a type of naturalism that took
inspiration from the biological sciences in order to try to causally predict the
course of human societies and events.
Page 4 of 23
Historical sociologies
A belief or action could always have transpired differently based on the human
exercise of this creative faculty. This implies that collective human action is also
contingent and need not follow a necessary, locked-in sequence. Where most of
Nietzsche’s contemporaries saw history as a natural, developmental process, he
saw that beliefs, practices, institutions, and the major features of human social
reality emerged out of the contingent and even accidental reasoning of
particular individuals and groups. His form of explaining historical changes thus
ceased to be naturalist and developmental and instead became genealogical—
seeking out narratives of contingency for the birth of specific features of social
and political life.
Page 5 of 23
Historical sociologies
Page 6 of 23
Historical sociologies
Page 7 of 23
Historical sociologies
form. In the imagined rational choice world of Pinker’s theory it is only when the
modern state and markets come on the scene that violence is finally beaten back
into the caves of the primitive past. There is here a neo-Fukuyaman end-of-
history faith in a certain set of Anglo-European institutions as the end-goal or
telos of rational human development. Once the thesis is in place, the violence of
the modern state and the inevitability of market capitalism is leveraged against
communities and peoples resisting its authority.
But these lines of criticism (though certainly worth pursuing) are not necessarily
where an anti-naturalist critique begins. From an anti-naturalist perspective,
Pinker’s initial error is his misuse of rational choice theory. Rather than treating
it as a hypothetical thought experiment that does no actual explaining, Pinker
seems to be turning rational choice into a descriptive, quasi-universal human
anthropology. His entire analysis seems to tacitly assume that human beliefs
necessarily have a certain calculative and preference-maximizing structure. And
the latter runs afoul of the philosophical contingency of human beliefs and
actions as self-interpreting animals. Yet Pinker’s entire explanatory argument
depends on positing this very ahistorical, transcendental human subjectivity that
more or less makes decisions via the same method of rational-actor arithmetic
(be she a Lakota-Sioux, a Latin American campesino, or a New York
stockbroker).
Pinker tries to prove his claims that this form of strategic, rational choice
reasoning actually motivated the key transition in history to the modern peaceful
period by offering evidence of correlations between the market and declining
violence, as well as the advent of the state and purported declines in
aggression.13 But Pinker seems unaware of the fact that this does not at all (p.
142) establish his explanatory thesis for the alleged decline in violence. Instead,
what Pinker needs to show is that actual historical actors (across many varying
cultural contexts and in huge numbers) did in fact reason in this prisoner’s
dilemma-type way. The structural exposition of a particular ahistorical, rational
choice subjectivity needs to be linked up with the actual contingent reasoning
and concrete psychologies of historical actors. Otherwise Pinker is simply left
with an idealized model floating in the air. There is no reason to believe this
idealized model has anything to do with empirical history and the actual
causality driving it. In other words, Pinker’s theoretical generalizations are not
at all properly linked up to human beliefs, reasons, meanings, and motives,
which anti-naturalism shows are necessary for any true social science
explanation. Pinker seems fundamentally philosophically confused about what
counts as a social science explanation. He also seems confused about the status
of rational choice theory as a method that idealizes certain features of human
rationality and thereby puts considerable distance between itself and actual
empirical reality. Does Pinker realize that his major explanatory thesis for the
Page 8 of 23
Historical sociologies
Pinker would have benefited from meditating on Foucault’s famous dictum that
the work of historical sociology must be “gray, meticulous, and patiently
documentary.”14 Instead, Pinker makes no effort to ground the meta-psychology
of rational choice theory within the contingent causes of beliefs and reasons of
key actors—let alone the mass-scale changes he has burdened himself with
explaining. Thus, at a philosophical level, Pinker’s ahistorical, transcendental
subjectivity does not in fact explain the empirical historical particulars that it
claims to. He fails at his own task because he does not understand what is
philosophically at stake in social science explanation. Instead, history becomes
the unfolding of a particular set of institutions that correspond to humanity’s
basic predicament vis-à-vis violence. Naturalism here becomes an engine for
oversimplification, obscurantism, and befuddlement as to what actually does
explanatory work. Once human beliefs are assumed to have a certain necessary
pattern or structure, history itself is treated as having a linear, developmental
arrow. The fact that rational choice is a heuristic with hypothetical insights into
social reality and not descriptive power is lost from view.
Page 9 of 23
Historical sociologies
(p.145) Likewise, as with Pinker, the standard secularization thesis with its
ahistorical, formal correlations tends to hide a much more complex reality of
meanings, beliefs, and practices beneath the surface. Taylor recognizes this
problem and turns to meta-narratives as a way to capture some of the contingent
transformations in meanings. He begins his account with the medieval world in
which religion imbued all aspects of life—political, economic, natural, and so
forth—and then tries to make clear what kinds of ruptures in religious belief and
practice have actually occurred between now and then. According to Taylor, the
naturalist correlations between modernity and unbelief miss how the new social
landscape of our time has not resulted in the disappearance of religion but
instead in its multiplication and diversification. Engaging the contingent beliefs
of actual people reveals that a secular age does not necessarily entail the
breakdown of human spiritual life but instead has so far meant the spread of a
vast array of options. New Age spiritualities have mushroomed (what Taylor calls
“novas”) but there have also been returns to traditional sources of faith. The
Page 11 of 23
Historical sociologies
Page 12 of 23
Historical sociologies
Consider first the way that naturalism often leads to a neglect of the historical
contingency of social imaginaries, instead positing eternal, ahistorical
background structures to human agency. A particularly dramatic example of this
naturalist error is the entire research program known as “sociobiology.”
Sociobiology was launched by the Harvard evolutionary biologist, E. O. Wilson.
Wilson argued that those studying human social behavior ought to seek the
general underlying biological structures that patterned beliefs and actions
according to Darwinian fitness. Wilson referred to these structures as the
“biogram.”22 For example, Wilson believed that modern nationalist passions
were the result of primordial evolutionary forces like the human need for
territory, breeding, shelter, and food. Nationalism, in Wilson’s sociobiological
conception, is essentially a form of tribalism in which fear of “hostile groups” as
well as “increases in real and imagined threats congeal the sense of group
identity and mobilize the tribal members.”23 In this way, the background
condition for modern nationalist ardors becomes biologically universal and
ahistorical. Nationalism is reduced to tribalism and tribalism a perennial feature
of human biology.
Wilson’s views were later developed by other naturalist social scientists into a
number of detailed research programs that hoped to explain modern ethnic
strife and warfare.24 For example, R. Paul Shaw and Yuwa Wong followed Wilson
in rejecting the notion that nationalism is a modern phenomenon and (p.147)
instead claimed it is the product of a universal biological mechanism. The
specific biological and Darwinian structure fueling nationalist identity formation
is what Shaw and Wong call the inclusive fitness logic. Inclusive fitness holds
that individual humans act not only in terms of maximizing their own personal
survival and reproduction, but also in light of sacrifice for a kinship group that
shares common genetic roots.25 In the case of nationalism, this kinship
mechanism becomes strongly identified with a much broader group: “Inclusive
fitness and kin selection dictate the family unit as the center of love and
solidarity throughout evolution…the nation is similarly conceived.”26 Although
Shaw and Wong admit that modern communications are a necessary condition
for the shift from family to nation, they nevertheless maintain that in essence
ethnic violence and nationalism are explicable in terms of a primordial
evolutionary motive for genetic fitness. So once again nationalism is naturalized
into an eternal feature of human sociality.
What has gone wrong with the sociobiological reduction to a perennial biological
motive will become clear if we consider anti-naturalist research into the
phenomenon of nationalism. Instead of subtracting away meanings to try to find
biograms and primordial urges, more interpretive-minded social scientists have
studied the rise and emergence of nationalism through meta-narratives, seeking
to capture the formation of social imaginaries. Probably the most important
example of such a sensibility is Benedict Anderson’s Imagined Communities,
which argues that nationalist consciousness is not simply reducible to primordial
motives repackaged in a new modern form. Rather, (p.148) “nation-ness, as
well as nationalism, are cultural artifacts” that have “come into historical
being…towards the end of the eighteenth century.”28 The motives structuring
nationalism are part of a large-scale social imaginary—or background set of
meanings which modern people inherit. Specifically, modern people have
learned to imagine themselves as part of communities that “never know most of
their fellow-members” within a secularized, “horizontal comradeship” which is
understood as existing in an immanent, simultaneous present.29 Anderson
narrates the way this represents a break with the enchanted, cosmic worldviews
of the pre-modern age, whose social imaginaries were not horizontal and
immanent within homogenous time. Instead, pre-modern social imaginaries
often assumed a vertical dimension in the community (like the mystical doctrine
of the king’s two bodies in Foucault’s work).
Anderson also narrates the way the social imaginary that made nationalism
possible also produced a unique conception of power—one in which this
immanent, horizontal, bounded group conceives of itself as the ultimate and only
source of legitimate political sovereignty. This leads Anderson to argue that
nationalism is part of a social imaginary that only emerged in a democratic age.
Anderson’s narrative of this shift is complex and far from uncontroversial—
evoking the advent of print capitalism, broad literacy, the homogenization of
linguistic communities, and massive reading publics.30 But at the center of his
research is an anti-naturalist sensibility that the rise of nationalism requires a
story—a meta-narrative of the contingent emergence of new background
meanings that displace older ones. This keeps his work clear of the philosophical
Page 14 of 23
Historical sociologies
Page 15 of 23
Historical sociologies
Page 16 of 23
Historical sociologies
The only antidote for these deep shortcomings is a turn to anti-naturalist large-
scale narrative sociologies that emphasize the historically contingent nature of
the background social imaginary. Unlike the naturalist examples treated above,
the anti-naturalist study of social imaginaries is able to offer broad explanations
(of the rise and fall of entire civilizations and societies, for example) while
remaining in good faith before the empirical diversity of the human past. The
concept of a social imaginary thus facilitates research possibilities that are not
available within a naturalist grid. The empirical and philosophical once again
work in close tandem. Social scientists need not fear history and its
overwhelming strangeness and diversity.
Page 17 of 23
Historical sociologies
After having criticized the monolithic fiction of the state as the object of study,
governmentality shifts attention to diverse practices of power—or what (p.152)
Foucault refers to as the “conduct of conduct.”43 Specifically, governmentality
focuses on the practices by which subjects are normalized into stable patterns of
rule. Modern governmentality, according to Foucault, emerged as part of
practices of bio-power and pastoral power.44 In the seventeenth century,
European societies developed a broad concept of “police” as a form of power
that exerted disciplinary control over people and their everyday activities in
school, work, family life, and the market economy. These disciplines had their
origins in the pastoral practices of the ancient church. Yet European societies in
the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries took these disciplines in novel
directions—inculcating industry, efficiency, and orderliness into masses of
citizens. In addition, Foucault argued that modern governmentality was the
result of various practices of bio-power, developed contemporaneously to the
disciplines: human sciences of health, longevity, and productivity that monitored
populations for mortality rates, epidemics, fertility, and other signs of biological
vitality. In other words, what we call the state is an aggregation of various
cultural practices (with roots in religion, the human sciences, and the
disciplines, among other places). Governmentality’s focus on contingency and a
disaggregated picture of the state as a cultural form thus displaces the
naturalist, essentialist vision of state institutions propounded in Hobbesian and
neo-Hobbesian theories.
Page 18 of 23
Historical sociologies
It should now be clear that the claim that anti-naturalist social science is unable
to advance research on a large-scale level of generalization is not credible. In
fact, the exact opposite is true. We have seen through various examples in the
large-scale study of violence, religion, secularity, nationalism, markets, and the
state that anti-naturalists are able to generalize through meta-narratives and
genealogies in a way that remains explanatory while naturalist generalizations in
these domains are plagued by certain problems. Indeed, naturalist
Page 19 of 23
Historical sociologies
Notes:
(1.) Charles Taylor, “Understanding the Other: A Gadamerian View on
Conceptual Schemes,” in Dilemmas and Connections: Selected Essays
(Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2011) 32.
(2.) Charles Taylor, “The Future of the Religious Past,” in Dilemmas and
Connections, 214.
(3.) Colin Hay, Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction (New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2002) 247.
(8.) Steven Pinker, The Better Angels of Our Nature: Why Violence Has Declined
(New York: Viking, 2011) 694.
(12.) For examples of critics of Pinker’s empirical findings, see: John Gray,
“Steven Pinker Is Wrong About Violence and War,” The Guardian, March 13,
2015, <http://www.theguardian.com/books/2015/mar/13/john-gray-steven-
pinker-wrong-violence-war-declining> (accessed October 7, 2015); Jeff Lewis,
Media, Culture and Human Violence: From Savage Lovers to Violent Complexity
(London: Rowman & Littlefield International, 2015).
(15.) Michel Foucault, Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan
Sheridan (New York: Vintage Books, 1995) 28.
(17.) Michelle Alexander, The New Jim Crow: Mass Incarceration in the Age of
Colorblindness (New York: The New Press, 2012) 6.
(19.) For a classic and seminal (if primitive) version of this thesis, see: Auguste
Comte, The Positive Philosophy of Auguste Comte, vol. 1, trans. Harriet
Martineau (London: George Bell & Sons, 1896).
(20.) José Casanova, Public Religions in the Modern World (Chicago, IL:
University of Chicago Press, 1994) 214.
(21.) Charles Taylor, A Secular Age (Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of
Harvard University, 2007) 3.
(24.) See, for example: Vernon Reynolds, Vincent Falger, and Ian Vine, eds., The
Sociobiology of Ethnocentrism: Evolutionary Dimensions of Xenophobia,
Discrimination, Racism and Nationalism (London: Croom Helm, 1987); Pierre L.
van den Berghe, The Ethnic Phenomenon (New York: Elsevier, 1981) 11–12.
(25.) R. Paul Shaw and Yuwa Wong, Genetic Seeds of Warfare: Evolution,
Nationalism, and Patriotism (London: Unwin Hyman, 1989) 26–7.
(27.) Clifford Geertz, “The Impact of the Concept of Culture on the Concept of
Man,” in The Interpretation of Cultures: Selected Essays (New York: Basic
Books, 1973) 37.
(36.) Karl Polanyi, “The Economy as Instituted Process,” in Trade and Market in
the Early Empires: Economies in History and Theory, eds. K. Polanyi, Conrad
Arensberg, and Harry Pearson (Glencoe, IL: The Free Press, 1957) 243.
(37.) Karl Polanyi, The Great Transformation: The Political and Economic Origins
of Our Time (Boston, MA: Beacon Press, 2011) 46.
(39.) As Polanyi puts this insight: “The relation between formal economics and
the human economy is, in effect, contingent.” Polanyi, “The Economy as
Instituted Process,” 247.
(40.) Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan (New York: P.F. Collier & Son Company, 1909–
1914) ch. XIII.
Page 22 of 23
Historical sociologies
(44.) See Michel Foucault: Discipline and Punish and the History of Sexuality:
Vol. 1 An Introduction, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Vintage Books, 1990).
Page 23 of 23
Ethics and democracy
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0008
Page 1 of 25
Ethics and democracy
see themselves as inheriting the legacy of Clifford Geertz and the “cultural
approach.”2 In the study of race, we find common cause with the famous work of
Stuart Hall and more recently Paul Spickard who insist on a constructivist
approach to racial politics.3 In short, anti-naturalism offers philosophical
resources to a diverse and dynamic range of research programs.
At the most general level our claim is that because ethical and political theories
often imply substantive anthropological conceptions of human agency, there is
an overlap between the concerns of empirical and normative disciplines in the
human sciences.4 However, we must be especially careful in the use of anti-
naturalist terminology when entering into such controversy. (p.157) Most
ethicists today use the term “naturalism” to refer to the rejection of
supernatural sources for ethical life.5 This is clearly not our sense of the term
and we are not taking a position on those particular ethical debates in this
chapter. Instead, we want to focus on the way social scientists have compelling
ethical and political motives for turning to anti-naturalism. We will advance this
argument in three interrelated parts.
Page 2 of 25
Ethics and democracy
One caveat before beginning: our goal is to clarify the ways social scientists are
free to engage in the critical and evaluative study of ethical and political life, but
this does not mean we believe social science is the same thing as ethics or
ethical critique. Social science, generally speaking, is concerned with the study
and explanation of human behavior. This need not have overt ethical concerns. It
is perfectly valid, for instance, for social scientists to simply set out to describe
the economic features of globalization or rising authoritarian attitudes in North
Atlantic societies. In other words, social scientists are free to concentrate their
efforts on factual claims and explanations. However, anti-naturalism does give us
a much subtler, more nuanced account of the distinction between facts and
values in social scientific inquiry. But this does not imply that the distinction
should be thrown out altogether. Rather, anti-naturalism shows how one of social
science’s valid research concerns might be ethical and political critique. That is,
social scientists who adopt anti-naturalism are able to critically engage and
normatively evaluate human (p.158) ethical positions. This opens up a shared
space of inquiry between political theory, ethics, and empirical social science.
Many modern accounts of ethics and values operate on the tacit assumption that
human normative life will eventually reach some kind of objective, normal
science akin to physics, chemistry, and the other hard sciences.6 In particular,
under the sway of naturalism, those concerned with ethics are too often engaged
Page 3 of 25
Ethics and democracy
in a quest for what Thomas Kuhn dubbed a “normal science.” Kuhn defined
normal science as “research firmly based upon one or more past scientific
achievements, achievements that some particular scientific community
acknowledges for a time as supplying the foundation for its further practice.”7
For example, in chemistry or physics today research is carried out within a wider
accumulated set of theoretical assumptions and foundations that are taken as
given. Introductory students can be taught from textbooks in which the
foundations of the discipline are set for all practitioners. In the natural sciences
such agreed-upon foundations are the norm. Those who study ethics, influenced
by naturalism, have often expected or at least hope for a normal science of
human values to develop analogous to the historical progress of the natural
sciences. Then ethics too might have universal foundations that all students of
human values and ethical life would master before inquiring any further into the
subject.
The naturalist drive for a normal science is evident in the founders of some of
the most influential theories of modern ethics. For example, a central premise of
the utilitarian account of ethical life is that the ultimate goal of human action is
happiness defined as pleasure or utility-maximizing. One of the classical figures
of utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill, implied that this crucial assumption could be
established in the form of an empirical “proof” from the observation of “fact and
experience.”8 A straightforward claim to empirically brute facts thus grounds
Mill’s utilitarianism. There is the belief in Mill (and (p.159) much of
utilitarianism thereafter) that ethics will begin from a set of completely
stabilized assumptions. After all, if chemistry enjoys stability around the periodic
table and physics around Newtonian mechanics, why shouldn’t ethics find a
similar foundational core around utility? As is well known, this set of empirical
assumptions in utilitarian ethics in turn had a massive influence on the social
sciences through neoclassical economics. The conception of human agency
developed by utilitarian philosophers helped create a later affinity for an
idealized model of preference-maximizing rationality within the market.
But utilitarian philosophers are not the only ones who try to ground a theory of
human values on claims that are akin to a normal, objective science. Such
naturalist tendencies are also found (albeit in much different form) in
utilitarianism’s biggest rival in the Anglophone world, deontology. Deontology
holds that all ethical actions comply with universal rules of conduct or duties as
formulated by an ideally rational agent (the word deontology literally means the
study of duty). The founder of deontology, Immanuel Kant, argued that any true
duty could be universalized without contradiction. These duties were to “hold for
every rational being as such” and do so “completely a priori and free from
everything empirical in pure rational concepts only.”9 For example, famously
Kant argued that lying was always morally wrong and that this could be
determined by reason alone because this action could not be universalized.
Ethics thus achieved foundations in what Kant called “apodictic” or absolutely
Page 4 of 25
Ethics and democracy
certain duties that every rational agent would know he or she had to follow.
Where Mill argued the indisputable foundations of ethics were empirical, Kant
claimed they were evident to reason. Yet the goal was remarkably similar: a
normal science or knowledge achieved among all reasonable practitioners.10 The
first move when studying human values thus becomes to recognize that they are
objectively grounded in a universal framework. Social scientists might go on
studying the empirical diversity of values in the world, but rational inquiry into
ethics on its own terms demonstrates a quasi-scientific convergence. Such
expectations can then fuel empirical expectations about the progress of history
toward a unity of values as modernization and rationalization take place. Indeed,
both Kant and Mill in their own ways expected a sociology of modernity to
involve a kind of developmental logic. These developmental logics were critically
scrutinized at length earlier, but they highlight the way that certain assumptions
about the objective status of ethics can inspire particular visions of how
modernity will develop.
The upshot of this set of anti-naturalist arguments is that the very stuff of ethics
differs from the natural sciences because it is shaped by the creative use of
language. For this reason anti-naturalism emphasizes the radical historicity of
human belief and practice. Individual agents form their beliefs contingently and
creatively against rival inherited traditions. There is an inherit contestability to
meanings that does not allow for a more straightforward convergence of the
kind found in the natural sciences. This is because ethical systems are the fruit
of contingent forms of causality that can be contested. The model of a good life
or a just society might be expressed in one way but it can be challenged by a
rival set of contingent meanings. Thus, anti-naturalism teaches social scientists
Page 5 of 25
Ethics and democracy
The serious philosophical point behind Nietzsche’s quip is that the utilitarian
definition of happiness as pleasure through maximizing preferences is peculiar
to a particular historical time and place. In other words, the beliefs and desires
that Mill took to be objectively necessary are in fact internal to a historical
tradition. Indeed, Nietzsche is drawing on a pessimistic strain of German
Romanticism that does not seek universalizing maxims or feelings of utilitarian
pleasure or perhaps even rational consistency. Rather, Nietzsche (p.161)
believed some Europeans might pursue a heroic life while renouncing the
pleasures and perhaps even the wellbeing of the rest of humanity. The point is
not whether there is something objectionable in Nietzsche’s elitist ethical vision
(we believe that there is), but only that he is right to see the starting point for
ethical theory is the field of contingent history and not Mill’s or Kant’s search for
the stable objective assumptions of a normal science. The form of causality
typical of human agency therefore has a massive effect on how social theorists
should conceptualize human values. History and contingency are central to the
proper conceptualization of human values; a normal science akin to the natural
sciences is not.
But there is another important way to draw this key distinction between the
natural sciences and knowledge of human values. Where the facts of ethics are
centrally concerned with phenomena that are part of a particular cultural and
linguistic world, the natural sciences seek facts that exist outside any one of
these worlds. In this vein, Bernard Williams has drawn attention to the
difference between what he dubs the “absolute conception” of facts appropriate
to the natural sciences and the kind of knowledge possible within ethics. The
“absolute conception” of facts in the natural sciences refers to some feature of
reality that exists independently of our experience of it.13 The circumference of
the earth, the velocity of a falling object, and the temperature at which a
Page 6 of 25
Ethics and democracy
particular liquid turns into a gas all exist independently of our perceptions of
these phenomena.
The proper conception of ethical values also involves claims about facts. For
example, as Williams argues, there is a fact of the matter as to what counts as a
lie or being a coward or expressing gratitude or exercising brutality within a
particular cultural context. These facts about values, moreover, are identifiable
by outsiders to a particular culture so long as they are familiarized with the
relevant criteria.14 This means that within the horizon of a particular social
world there are facts of the matter as to whether a particular political leader is a
habitual liar or acted like a coward (albeit like all facts, they can be disputed).
However, apprehending these ethical facts requires what Williams—following a
pioneer of interpretive social science, Clifford Geertz—dubs “thick” knowledge
of the cultures in question.15 As we saw in our analysis of ethnography, thick
knowledge is a grasp of beliefs and actions within their nuanced webs of
meaning and significance within a life-world.
It follows that there is a deep disanalogy between the natural sciences and the
world of human values. Namely, ethical facts (unlike their counterparts in the
natural sciences) cannot be construed in terms of an absolute conception of the
world. Ethical facts can and do guide all human agents through particular social
worlds—for example, the world of Japanese culinary if someone eats at a sushi
shop in Tokyo or the realm of Latin American Catholicism if a traveler enters a
cathedral in Bogota, Colombia. But these facts about values cannot orient us
within the practices of every social-cultural world. (p.162) Indeed, even when
highly homogenous societies exhibit a great deal of agreement about ethical
facts (something which is not typically part of the experience of pluralistic
modernity), they still do not attain a convergence of the kind achieved in the
natural sciences because their ethical facts are dependent on meanings and
beliefs, not necessary causal features of the physical universe.16
Does it follow from these arguments that the proper way for social theorists and
ethicists to conceptualize values is in terms of a full-blown relativism? Are values
to be treated by those studying human ethical life as completely subjective?
Ironically, this opposite extreme view is also often inspired by naturalism. In the
modern social sciences it was popularized by Max Weber’s famous claim that
Page 7 of 25
Ethics and democracy
facts and values “are completely heterogeneous” such that “whenever a man of
science brings in his own value-judgment, a full understanding of the facts
ceases.”17 Weber’s work was enormously influential in spreading the view that a
true science of society requires treating values as purely subjective (although
this is likely a misreading of Weber).18 Here the basic naturalist idea is that
values are not part of the factual, mind-independent furniture of the universe
but are completely mind-dependent. A firm logical distinction is therefore
created between facts on one side and values on the other.
Page 8 of 25
Ethics and democracy
The insight that human beliefs are historically contingent does eliminative work
in the field of ethics as to what sorts of selves we ought or ought not to pursue.
Naturalist conceptions of selfhood and values are excluded from consideration.
Definitely off the table are any ethical theories that rely in some essential way on
naturalist social scientific knowledge to make good on their claims. This is
almost certainly the case for some varieties of utilitarianism. Utilitarianism tries
to maximize happiness or pleasure for the greatest number by calculating the
consequences of particular actions.20 For this reason, utilitarianism is often
entangled in making mass-scale predictions about cause and effect. For example,
will enacting a particular educational policy on standardized testing maximize or
minimize the pleasure of the greatest number within society? What about
employing automated speed enforcement traps to keep drivers from surpassing
the speed limit on streets and highways? Does launching something as complex
as a war increase or decrease utility? Answering such questions requires having
some strongly predictive knowledge of cause and effect in the realm of human
actions and beliefs. The social reforms sought by utilitarians are thus closely tied
to the ability to produce predictive scientific results in the social sciences.21 This
is because for utilitarians the value of actions lies “in their causal properties of
producing valuable states of affairs” as assumed by the utilitarian criterion of
pleasure or utility-maximizing.22
naturalism, history and its empirical diversity becomes an obstacle to ethical and
social scientific inquiry alike.23 Complex webs of belief, meaning, and
significance come to appear as stumbling blocks on the road to achieving
scientific and objective status. Once again, primary examples of this naturalist
impairment come from two of the most influential schools of modern ethics,
utilitarianism and deontology.
We have already seen that utilitarianism bases itself on the assumption that
human action should be guided by maximizing the greatest happiness/pleasure
for the greatest number of individuals, while Kant proposed that the goal of
ethical life is to follow universal duties that can be applied equally to all rational
agents. The problem with both traditions, in this respect, is a reduction of
human ethical life to following rules or what others have referred to as
“moralism.” It appears in both cases that the problem of ethical life is
discovering which rules, maxims, or calculus to follow for decision-making.
Moralism marks an intense narrowing of what counts as ethics by modern
philosophers who have focused on rules and obligations. As Williams has put it,
“theorists have particularly tended to favor the most general expressions used in
ethical discussion—good, right, ought,” instead of thick conceptions like lie,
coward, or gratitude, in part because they have been driven by the “reductionist
belief” that the former concepts contained the “more specific ethical
conceptions.”24 So naturalism becomes the vehicle for the narrowing of ethics to
a perennial, ahistorical set of concepts and rule-following concerns. Ethical
motives (insofar as they can be properly called “ethical”) are always and in all
places concerned with, say, maximizing utility or universalizing moral maxims.
Human ethical agency is thus reduced to a set of ahistorical motives that lose
sight of historicity and contingency.
(p.165) Taylor has also been key in criticizing the naturalist reduction of ethics
to morals. In particular he has observed the way this naturalist drive toward
reduction is evident in Kant’s search for a set of formal rules that can sufficiently
guide human action. A formal imperative that gives criteria for universalizing
moral maxims or an imagined original position outside of all historically
contingent beliefs and desires captures the ethical mind. In this way, the
interpretively rich languages of thick historical traditions “get marginalized or
even expunged altogether” in favor of an “epistemologically motivated reduction
and homogenization of the ‘moral.’”25 In this way, “a naturalist account of man
[that] comes in the wake of the scientific revolution” encourages “eschewing
what we might call subject-related properties” or those that cannot be
accounted for from an absolute standpoint free of all historically embedded
perspectives.26 Once again, anti-naturalist philosophical insights give social
theorists and ethicists alike a fuller account of values in human life. The
reduction of ethics to morals proves to be the contingent result of a particular
Page 10 of 25
Ethics and democracy
We have already seen that anti-naturalist philosophy assumes that human beings
creatively and contingently form beliefs against the background of (p.166)
historically inherited traditions. This means human agency is radically historical
in character. Because human agency is radically historical in this way, anti-
naturalist social science research into the past can generate, inspire, and reveal
new untapped sources for ethics and politics. This means history is not a mere
hindrance to theory-building because of its empirical diversity and complexity.
Nor is history simply a descriptive set of past cases. Rather, from the
interpretive viewpoint, history contains certain ethical and political
potentialities. Indeed, some of the most important ethicists of the last two
centuries have made this creative turn toward the interpretive recovery of
history as a vital source for ethics. A few brief examples of actual ethical
programs that take into account anti-naturalist insights will make this point
clear.
Page 11 of 25
Ethics and democracy
A wide range of philosophers has taken this historical and more interpretive turn
with regard to ethics developing an impressive array of views. Perhaps
Nietzsche’s most famous acolyte, Michel Foucault, insisted that historical
inquiry could be put to ethical uses by denaturalizing what is considered natural
and rendering contingent what is believed to be necessary. Foucault thus worked
for much of his life to show that institutions like the asylum, the hospital, the
school, and the prison were the result of particular cultural histories, and not
inescapable features of human social and political life.29 But Foucault likewise
believed that history could be put to inspirational or vindicatory uses in the
search for values to orient human life. Thus, Foucault encouraged his readers to
adopt a “limit attitude,” one that treated the past as a source for the
“experimental” adoption of new values.30 In the latter part of his (p.167) life,
Foucault immersed himself in the ethics of the ancient Greeks and Romans as
part of an effort to formulate new conceptions of self for the present.31
Nietzsche and Foucault return to history to formulate an ethics that breaks with
many of the values of the Enlightenment and of the Christian and Jewish
religions. But this need not be the case. Charles Taylor has also taken this
historical turn in order to discover deeper ethical sources for the project of
modernity and some Enlightenment values. He has also argued that the recovery
of Christian humanism is a better ethical source for modern commitments such
as democracy and human rights.32 Although far more condemnatory about the
nature of modernity, Alasdair MacIntyre has returned to past ethical sources in
order to argue that the virtue ethics of Aristotle provides the most promising
alternative to what he sees as the moral incoherence of late capitalist
societies.33 The point is that the return to history made possible by anti-
naturalist conceptions of social reality can take various rival forms depending
upon which traditions are tapped. The examples here are various and impressive
—for instance, Heidegger’s call for a return to history in order to overcome
modern “homelessness” or in a very different vein, Philip Pettit’s attempt to
Page 12 of 25
Ethics and democracy
revive the tradition of ancient republicanism.34 Such examples show that anti-
naturalist theory, in addition to critically eliminating certain distorting naturalist
features from ethics, opens up historical sources for self-interpretation and
critique that go far beyond the possibilities of the many ahistorical and reductive
approaches to ethics that are inspired by naturalism.
Page 13 of 25
Ethics and democracy
Currently the dominant paradigm for politics in North Atlantic societies is a form
of representative democracy buttressed by the claims of naturalist experts and
advisors. In the early twentieth century new kinds of ahistorical and formal
naturalism became highly enmeshed in the study of the state. This, we saw, was
a dramatic departure from late nineteenth-century views of politics and the
state, which were conceived in terms of developmental narratives of the
progression of a nation through certain fixed stages.41 Suddenly, social theorists
turned from grand narratives to ahistorical models, correlations, and
classifications said to hold across time and place. Political, social, and economic
outcomes were explained by reference to functional requirements, psychological
typologies, general features of human rationality, and formal analyses of
processes.42
But this set of intellectual developments was also tightly related to actual
changes in power and authority within the flesh-and-blood world of politics. One
of the first groups to recognize this fact was the first British New Left. This was
a group of intellectuals headed by figures like E. P. Thompson, Raymond
Page 14 of 25
Ethics and democracy
Williams, and Stuart Hall that hoped to articulate a more humanistic form of
socialism.43 What was unique about this movement was the critique it generated
of both Western liberal democracies and Soviet communist regimes as relying on
authority that drew from naturalist theory.
Page 15 of 25
Ethics and democracy
The turn toward governance strategies began when intellectuals and activists
argued that the twentieth-century state was beleaguered by overload and
inefficiency in a way that required the implementation of fiscal austerity,
monetary control, and the rolling back of services and institutions.50 These
critics drew on rational choice theory to argue that the market or quasi-markets
should replace bureaucracy because of their purported superior efficiency. The
bureaucracy was bankrupt and needed to be replaced with an “entrepreneurial
government” based on competition, markets, customers, and measured
outcomes.51
At the level of national politics, these reforms were inaugurated in the English-
speaking world via Thatcher in Britain and Reagan in the United States.52 The
policymakers brought to power by these movements drew on rational choice
theories like public choice and the principal–agent problem to argue that just as
private sector corporations needed to ensure managers acted on behalf of
shareholders, so too did public administration need to ensure elected
representatives acted on behalf of voters.53 In this manner, a tight analogy was
drawn between the organization of the state and that of markets. Specifically,
the public sector needed to be redesigned by policy elites who understood
rational choice theory to create new incentive environments and quasi-market
setups that aligned the interests of agents (managers/representatives) with their
principals (shareholders/voters). Along with this shift came the popular political
polemics denouncing old-style bureaucracy and public officials, and
championing markets and entrepreneurs.54 Governments (p.171) needed to be
run like businesses not only because the old modes were inefficient, but also
because public officials could not be trusted to work according to bygone
motives like civic self-sacrifice and the public good. A science of rational
behavior would radically overhaul the institutions of the state in the name of
efficiency and economic rationality. In this way, the critique of the state may
have changed the content of naturalist expertise called upon for political power,
but it did not actually challenge the technocratic form. From the perspective of
anti-naturalist social science, one kind of naturalist authority waned even as the
other waxed.
The second type of shift toward governance came later and was in some ways a
critical response to rational choice. These advocates of governance accepted
neoliberal arguments about the inflexible and unresponsive nature of the
traditional hierarchical bureaucracy. They also added their belief that the crisis
of the state was aggravated by globalization, which showed the state could not
go at it alone, but needed to pursue coordinated action with groups within civil
society and across borders. However, unlike the rational choice theorists, these
advocates of networks rejected that good governance comes from individual
Page 16 of 25
Ethics and democracy
Once again, social science naturalism became a form of power and not simply
description. Drawing on sociologists ranging from Emile Durkheim and Pierre
Bourdieu to Herbert Marcuse, advocates of networks claimed that alternative
forms of rationality to those proposed by neoclassical economics needed to be
brought into the picture. Specifically, they championed theories of social norms
and roles within institutional frameworks as shaping human behavior. For
example, so-called new institutionalists argued that individual beliefs and
actions needed to be explained in terms of the institutional settings that
generated them.56 In this way, agency was downplayed in these theories in favor
of the right kinds of social norms shaping institutions as fixing the content of
individuals’ preferences, beliefs, and reasoning.57 Institutions, broadly
understood, became actors themselves, transcending time and space to create
certain social and political outcomes. For this reason, despite all their
differences, advocates of networks were no less naturalistic than rational choice
theorists, rejecting historical contingency and using ahistorical forms of analysis
to identify midlevel or universal generalizations that transcended space and
time. A new kind of naturalist expertise was ushered in to remake the modern
state.
(p.172) In Britain this new policy trend clearly took hold through the New
Labor government of Tony Blair. Under his government, policymakers often
adopted network and institutional theories that emphasized that in areas like
terrorism, the environment, and urban blight, the state faced problems that
crossed too many boundaries and jurisdictions for it to handle alone. These were
so-called “wicked problems” that no one sector of society could face by itself.58
Applying the social science of network governance, these reformers argued that
coordination across agencies as well as public–private partnerships were needed
instead of centralized bureaucracy.59 As with rational choice, the turn away from
the centralized state did not mean renouncing naturalist expertise. Thus, for all
the differences with prior waves of naturalist power, what continued unabated
was the basic project of mechanistically engineering social reality in order to
determine human conduct. In this way, anti-naturalist social science continues to
unmask the false claims to expertise of these later forms, while also shedding
light on how social science has never been a simple observer on political life but
has actually entered into it and transformed it.
Page 17 of 25
Ethics and democracy
Page 18 of 25
Ethics and democracy
The foregoing arguments make clear that the relationship of facts to values is
much more complex than this naturalist assumption would have us believe. After
all, anti-naturalist philosophy begins from certain factual claims about human
anthropology (contingency, self-interpretation, narrativity) and ends with
Page 19 of 25
Ethics and democracy
Notes:
(1.) Philip Cushman, “Why the Self Is Empty: Toward a Historically Situated
Psychology,” American Psychologist 45:5 (1990): 599–611; Philip Cushman,
“Psychotherapy as Moral Discourse,” Journal of Theoretical and Philosophical
Psychology 13:2 (1993): 103–13; Philip Cushman, Constructing the Self,
Constructing America: A Cultural History of Psychotherapy (New York: Perseus
Books Group, 1995).
(2.) Jeffrey C. Alexander, Philip Smith, and Matthew Norton, eds., Interpreting
Clifford Geertz: Cultural Investigation in the Social Sciences (New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2011).
(3.) Stuart Hall, “Race, The Floating Signifier,” transcript, Media Education
Foundation, 1997: <http://www.mediaed.org/transcripts/Stuart-Hall-Race-the-
Floating-Signifier-Transcript.pdf>; Paul Spickard, Race in Mind (Notre Dame,
IN: University of Notre Dame Press, 2015).
(4.) For an extended discussion of this claim see: Jason Blakely, Alasdair
MacIntyre, Charles Taylor, and the Demise of Naturalism: Reunifying Political
Theory and Social Science (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press,
2016) chap. 5.
(5.) For example: Bernard Williams, Ethics and the Limits of Philosophy
(Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1985) 121.
(6.) As Bernard Williams notes, ethicists are too often drawn to the idea that “in
a scientific inquiry there should ideally be convergence on an answer…the
answer [that] represents how things are.” Williams, Ethics and the Limits, 136.
(7.) Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 3rd ed. (Chicago,
IL: University of Chicago Press, 1996) 10.
Page 20 of 25
Ethics and democracy
(10.) Arguably the early John Rawls also followed Kant in assuming ethics begins
from a modified version of this rationalist certainty with his notion of an original
position: “The original position may be viewed, then, as a procedural
interpretation of Kant’s conception of autonomy and the categorical imperative.”
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice: Revised Edition (Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press
of Harvard University Press, 1999) 226.
(11.) For one of the most recent extended accounts of the relationship of
language to human action and social reality, see: Charles Taylor, The Language
Animal: The Full Shape of the Human Linguistic Capacity (Cambridge, MA: The
Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2016) 264–84, 292–3.
(12.) Friedrich Nietzsche, Twilight of the Idols in The Portable Nietzsche, trans.
Walter Kaufmann (New York: Penguin Books, 1982) 468.
(13.) The line of argument that follows is greatly indebted to Williams’ important
work (albeit we integrate it into our own concern with social science anti-
naturalism). Williams, Ethics and the Limits, 139; see also: 149–50.
(14.) Williams, Ethics and the Limits, 140; see also: 150.
(15.) Williams, Ethics and the Limits, 128, 140; Clifford Geertz, “Thick
Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture,” in The Interpretation of
Cultures (New York: Basic Books, 1973) 3–30.
(16.) As Williams rightly notes: “I cannot see any convincing theory of knowledge
for the convergence of reflective ethical thought on ethical reality in even a
distant analogy to the scientific case.” Williams, Ethics and the Limits, 152.
(17.) Max Weber, “The Vocation of Science,” in The Essential Max Weber, ed.
Sam Whimster (New York: Routledge, 2004) 279–80.
(18.) This tendency within political science dates back to the birth of the modern
discipline and the behavioral revolution. For a brief account, see: James Farr,
“Remembering the Revolution: Behavioralism in American Political Science,” in
Political Science in History: Research Programs and Political Traditions, eds.
James Farr, John Dryzek, and Stephen Leonard (Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press, 1995) 203, 205.
Page 21 of 25
Ethics and democracy
(21.) For the relationship of social science positivism to Mill’s ethical and
political philosophy, see: Evaldas Nekrašas, The Positive Mind: Its Development
and Impact on Modernity and Postmodernity (Budapest, Hungary: Central
European University Press, 2016) 88.
(24.) Williams, Ethics and the Limits, 128; see also: 8, 16–17.
(25.) Charles Taylor, “The Diversity of Goods,” in Philosophy and the Human
Sciences, 234. See also: Charles Taylor, Sources of the Self (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1989) 71–90.
(27.) Friedrich Nietzsche, “On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life,”
in Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J. Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1983) 57–123.
(29.) Michel Foucault: Madness and Civilization, trans. Richard Howard (New
York: Vintage Books, 1988); Discipline and Punish, trans. Alan Sheridan (New
York: Vintage Books, 1977).
Page 22 of 25
Ethics and democracy
(31.) Michel Foucault, The Hermeneutics of the Subject: Lectures at the College
de France 1981–1982, trans. Graham Burchell (New York: Picador, 2001).
(33.) Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame Press, 2007).
(36.) Even late in his career Foucault insisted that researchers should “get rid of
the subject” and conduct “a form of history which can account for the
constitution of knowledges, discourses, domains of objects etc., without having
to make reference to a subject.” Michel Foucault, “Truth and Power,” interview
by Alessandro Fontana and Pasquale Pasquino in Power/Knowledge: Selected
Interviews and Other Writings 1972–1977, ed. Colin Gordon (New York:
Pantheon Books, 1980) 117.
(37.) Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2nd ed. (New York: Continuum,
2004) 276–7.
(40.) For more comprehensive account see: Mark Bevir, Democratic Governance
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010); Blakely, Alasdair MacIntyre,
Charles Taylor, and the Demise of Naturalism, chaps. 1–2.
(41.) See: Mark Bevir, “Political Studies as Narrative and Science, 1880–2000,”
Political Studies 54 (2006): 583–606.
Page 23 of 25
Ethics and democracy
(42.) For the detailed historical background on this shift, see: William Everdell,
The First Moderns (Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 1997); Theodore
Porter, Trust in Numbers: The Pursuit of Objectivity in Science and Public Life
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1995); Dorothy Ross, The Origins of
American Social Science (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1991) chaps.
8–10; and Margaret Schabas, A World Ruled by Number: William Stanley Jevons
and the Rise of Mathematical Economics (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
Press, 1990).
(43.) The best histories of the first British New Left are: Michael Kenny, The
First New Left: British Intellectuals After Stalin (London: Lawrence & Wishart,
1995); Dennis Dworkin, Cultural Marxism in Postwar Britain: History, the New
Left, and the Origins of Cultural Studies (Durham, NC: Duke University Press,
1997).
(49.) E. P. Thompson, “The Long Revolution,” New Left Review 9 (1961): 33.
(51.) David Osborne and Ted Gaebler, Reinventing Government: How the
Entrepreneurial Spirit Is Transforming the Public Sector (Reading, MA: Addison-
Wesley, 1992).
(52.) For an account of the rise of neoliberalism in Britain and the United States,
see: David Harvey, A Brief History of Neoliberalism (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005) chaps. 2–3. On public sector reform, see: Donald Savoie, Thatcher,
Reagan, Mulroney: In Search of a New Bureaucracy (Pittsburgh, PA: Pittsburgh
University Press, 1995).
(53.) For literature relating congress to the bureaucracy in the United States,
see, for example: D. Roderick Kiewiet and Matthew McCubbins, The Logic of
Delegation: Congressional Parties and the Appropriations Process (Chicago, IL:
Page 24 of 25
Ethics and democracy
(54.) For one history of these developments in the United States, see: Nancy
MacLean, Democracy in Chains (New York: Penguin Random House, 2017).
(56.) For the varieties of new institutionalism see: P. A. Hall and R. Taylor,
“Political Science and the Three Institutionalisms,” Political Studies 44 (1996):
936–57; Kathleen Thelen and Sven Steinmo, “Historical Institutionalism in
Comparative Politics,” in Structuring Politics: Historical Institutionalism in
Comparative Analysis, eds. Sven Stienmo, Kathleen Thelen, and Frank
Longsttretch (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992) 1–32.
(58.) See: Horst Rittel and Melvin Webber, “Dilemmas in a General Theory of
Planning,” Policy Sciences 4 (1973): 155–69; Jeff Conklin, Dialogue Mapping:
Building Shared Understanding of Wicked Problems (Chichester: Wiley, 2006).
Page 25 of 25
Public policy
Public policy
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0009
Keywords: deliberative policy, dialogical approaches, rule by experts, humanism, public policy
There has been a dramatic and important shift in public policy in the last twenty-
five years. Scholars inspired by a wide variety of philosophical sources—from
phenomenology to post-structuralism, from Habermas’s discourse theory to
Dewey’s pragmatism—have converged on the view that policymaking needs to
take an interpretive and deliberative turn.1 This means rejecting the widespread
naturalist conception of public policy as composed of a technical science.
Instead, these scholars insist that policymaking be rethought as an interpretive
Page 1 of 23
Public policy
We heartily affirm these efforts for an interpretive turn in public policy and have
learned a great deal from these path-breaking scholars. However, we also
believe there is a little bit of confusion lingering as to what philosophically
justifies this paradigm shift. Even some of the best works calling for an
interpretive turn still claim that part of what is at stake is methodological and
the need to shift from quantitative to more qualitative research methods.2 This
echoes the larger methodological battle between “quants” and “qualies” that we
have questioned throughout. Alternatively, many interpretive policy scholars also
suggest that an interpretive turn is legitimized by globalization and the
complexity of this phenomenon.3 Yet although we remain highly indebted to the
work of these scholars, we want to quibble with these methodological and
sociological bases for the interpretive turn. Anti-naturalism gives policy scholars
a far better justification for converting to more deliberative approaches.
Philosophy unearths the major issues (not methodology or sociology). The
current debate could benefit from this philosophical clarification and a de-
escalation of quant versus qualie polarization of the field.
At the most general level public policy is defined as a set of actions, plans, laws,
and strategies adopted by governments. The norm in most North Atlantic states
today is to treat public policy as the privileged domain of (p.180) technocratic
and scientific authorities, experts who formulate solutions to the problems
facing society in a highly specialized and inaccessible language of law or
economics.5 We want to join deliberative policy scholars (Frank Fischer, John
Forester, Maarten Hajer, Hendrik Wagenaar, Dvora Yanow, and many others) in
arguing that policy should move away from technocratic modes. Of course, as
should by now be familiar, our anti-naturalist brand of interpretivism holds that
grasping human beliefs and actions involves deciphering meanings and not
primarily uncovering technical scientific laws. Our framework thus generates six
major consequences for policy analysis and implementation that support the
deliberative policy turn. First, anti-naturalism justifies policies centered on
narratives or storytelling; second, it reveals policy to be inherently contestable;
third, it shows that policymaking should be more self-consciously normative;
Page 2 of 23
Public policy
Policy narratives
Those calling for a deliberative turn in public policy agree that narratives or
storytelling should become the central genre or form for crafting policy. So, for
example, John Forester notes that in the world of policymaking stories are
absolutely necessary in order to do certain “kinds of work: descriptive work of
reportage, moral work of constructing character and reputation…political work
of identifying friends and foes…deliberative work of considering means and
ends, what is relevant and significant, what is possible and what matters.”6
Deborah Stone has similarly argued that public policy problems only emerge
against some background narrative about how a phenomenon relates to human
action and responsibility.7 However, sometimes this laudable work is justified in
terms of replacing “quantitative policy analysis” and the “neutral (p.181)
methods” of the natural sciences with more qualitative approaches.8 The
problem, however, is not one of stigmatizing or jettisoning quantitative methods.
As we have already argued at length, method pluralism allows for social
scientists and policy actors to use both qualitative and quantitative methods in
good faith. Rather, philosophical reasons are what legitimize the shift toward
using narratives or stories in policymaking.
So, why are stories so important to policymaking? Readers will recall that one of
anti-naturalism’s major premises is that human beliefs and actions are the result
of what we referred to as a (weak) rational agency. Normal human agency
involves deliberation over beliefs, reasons, desires, and motives. This means
human beings believe, act, or embody meanings in one way, but if they reflected
differently, they might also believe, act, or embody meanings in a completely
different manner. In other words, any one belief, action, or practice is contingent
upon other beliefs and meanings. Thus, human agency spins holistic webs of
meaning that cannot be explained by formal causal laws. Instead, stories or
narratives are the genre or form that captures the meaning holism of a
Page 3 of 23
Public policy
purposeful agent. This is because stories recount beliefs and meanings as only
one possible set of happenings or state of affairs. A story always implies that
given other beliefs, meanings, and actions, the whole chain of events may have
gone very differently.
One of the central findings of the Bouchard-Taylor report was that Quebec’s
media had dangerously and inaccurately circulated a story of crisis. This
narrative was in turn championed by “hardline secularists and conservative
Catholics” to advance “hostility towards foreigners, cloak[ing] itself in liberal
values such as gender equality and the protection of civic space” while “the
media fanned the embers.”10 In fact, contrary to the impression created by
Quebec’s media at that time, Bouchard and Taylor argued that cases of (p.182)
minority accommodation were “relatively rare” and the wider “situation is
under control.”11 Indeed, “a warm, cordial atmosphere and obvious pleasure in
engaging in debate prevailed at almost all” of the citizen forums held by the
commission.12 So, Bouchard and Taylor’s approach to the public policy problem
was in part to challenge a dominant narrative of crisis by presenting a counter-
narrative of de-escalation and a sense of civic health and unity across cultural
lines.
Needless to say, Bouchard and Taylor’s critique of the crisis narrative generated
controversy in Quebec. But for our purposes it is important to highlight the
inescapability of a narrative for trying to account for the significance of
accommodating minority religious communities in Quebec. The meaning of a
little Muslim girl wearing a headscarf while playing soccer depends on how this
action is related to other meanings and actions in the web. Is this headscarf a
sign of social disintegration and loss of identity? Or is it instead a reasonable
and healthy symbol of civic pluralism? Against the crisis narrative’s view that
Muslim headscarves are anti-democratic, the Bouchard-Taylor commission
Page 4 of 23
Public policy
instead found that “women who wear the headscarf attach different meanings to
it and respond to different motives,” with only a small minority in Quebec
signaling anti-democratic attitudes while for many the headscarf symbolized a
“strong feminist current” albeit one that “differs from the feminism prevailing in
Quebec.”13 The point is that some narrative must be implicitly adopted to
characterize the significance of the actions. Thus Forester, Stone, and other
scholars calling for a narrative turn in policy analysis are right to claim that
narrativity is inescapable.14 The question is always which narrative is the best
one, and not whether to have narratives at all.
(p.183) Finally, recall that narratives are neither here nor there when it comes
to the ongoing debates between quantitative versus qualitative methods. One
can tell a story that incorporates quantitative methods like statistics and the
latest opinion polling; likewise, one can try to build stories drawn from
qualitative methods like doing ethnographic fieldwork. The point is not to drop
expert knowledge altogether but to stop using it to cloak an underlying narrative
in the prestige of science. Instead, expert knowledge in the social sciences
should be put in the service of openly popular uses of narrative. This means the
ordinary citizen can better grasp the place of technical method within the larger
narrative whole.
Contestability
Narrativity is closely related to another feature of deliberative policymaking—
namely, contestability. The literature on deliberative policymaking is rightly
insistent that policies must stop being presented as the single, official scientific
account, and instead recognize the contestability and argumentative dimensions
of all policy formation.17 Policymaking is not about unveiling a universal
Page 5 of 23
Public policy
mechanics. Instead, “the policy process is—at least in part—a struggle to get one
or another meaning established as the accepted one.”18 However, sometimes it
is mistakenly claimed that this interpretive turn has to do with a sociological
shift undergone by globalization or post-modernity. So some authors have
suggested that a turn toward contestability better matches “today’s decentered
world of governance” and is related to the advent of the “Information Age.”19
But the underlying reasons to opt for this turn are not relative to a particular
age or set of sociological developments. Instead, they are the result of more
abiding philosophical issues.
For example, what is the effect of naming a policy the “war on terror” or “radical
Islamic extremism” versus a “war on Wahhabism” or a “war on ISIS”? How do
these meanings effect the accomplishment of military objectives that require the
cooperation of highly heterogeneous groups of both Sunni and Shiite Muslims
spanning different ethnic and theological groupings? How do the different
Page 6 of 23
Public policy
Clearly, if this is the case, then the contestability of policy is a perennial feature
of human social and political life, and not the result of a particular shift in era
toward globalization, networks, post-modernity, information, or any other
dramatic sociological change we are currently undergoing. Instead, as anti-
naturalism makes clear, contestability is a philosophical feature of expressivity.
This line of thought links up to the anti-naturalist argument we made in the prior
section: because policies are expressive of meanings (and not some brute
mechanics) they can be contested for what they dub significant and worthy of
attention and achievement. Is the accommodation of religious minorities in
Quebec symptomatic of the breakdown of liberal norms or is it an innocuous
instance of religious freedom calling for democratic tolerance? Are minority
Muslims and their religious practices antagonists to democracy or signs of
Page 7 of 23
Public policy
But our anti-naturalist framework also points to further, deeper ethical affinities
between the interpretive turn and policymaking. In particular, we have argued
that because anti-naturalism assumes a humanistic view of individual agency, it
is inherently critical of reductively technocratic treatments of human beings.
Humans, anti-naturalism holds, are creative agents whose reasons for action
need to be understood and engaged on their own terms. Their creativity makes
them inappropriate objects for mechanistic manipulation akin to engineering in
the natural sciences. The relevance of these arguments to public policy is that all
policies treating humans as inert, (p.186) mute objects subject to manipulation
are at one and the same time philosophically illusory and unethical. In this
sense, anti-naturalism self-consciously ties the deliberative scholars’ critique of
technocracy to the deeper historical tradition of humanism. The new deliberative
policy turn has roots in prior humanisms and their defense of the integrity of the
human subject.
Page 8 of 23
Public policy
The point is that there simply is no necessary causal bond that forces a story of
unwantedness to also end up being a tale of criminality, instead of another (p.
187) set of contingently related beliefs and actions. Whether the story of an
unwanted child will lead a predictable cohort of the poor inexorably toward
criminality cannot be decided beforehand via a supposedly value-free science of
social mechanics. The creative agency of individual human beings defies this
technocracy.
Cultural context
In addition to narrativity, contestability, and ethical engagement, an interpretive
turn in policymaking also means paying more attention to cultural context.
Scholars like Dvora Yanow have done crucial work highlighting the need for
“local knowledge” when conducting policy analysis.26 And our discussion of the
imposition of terms like “unwantedness” on those in poverty underscores the
need for such inquiry to avoid massive and politically sinister
misunderstandings.
Once again, our anti-naturalist philosophical framework justifies the calls made
by pioneers like Yanow. However, as philosophers we must quibble when Yanow
sometimes implies that the “presuppositions” differentiating an interpretive
approach to policy are “interpretive methods” that contrast with “analytical
methods” modeled after the “scientific method.”27 The problem is there is no
such thing as a logically binding “interpretive method” versus a naturalist one.
Our anti-naturalist framework instead arrives at the need for local knowledge
without this reduction to method polarization.
Page 9 of 23
Public policy
In our view, the reason policymakers should not neglect local knowledge is
because human actions, practices, and institutions are embedded within
particular traditions, backgrounds, and life-worlds. These life-worlds and
traditions are the result of certain historical trajectories and past legacies of
beliefs and practices of other agents. It follows that social reality is composed of
worlds of meaning such that the actions and practices of specific individuals or a
societal milieu can be badly misunderstood if they are not viewed in light of the
specific matrices of beliefs, meanings, and traditions held by those agents.
Yanow remains a vital source for chronicling the misunderstandings and self-
defeating actions that ensue when policymakers neglect these local contexts. To
take only one example, Yanow recounts the case of the development of drought
remedies that called for the digging of more wells in a region with nomadic tribe
peoples. The policymakers neglected the local traditions and practices of the
tribesmen who attached social prestige to the size of their herds, and therefore
increased their livestock to match the available new wells. In doing so, the policy
of more wells actually worsened the drought conditions it was intended to
address.28 By contrast, an anti-naturalist framework for (p.188) policymaking
always encourages familiarity with a particular problem as embedded in the
cultural contexts of a specific place. This local knowledge can save policymakers
from the spell of a naïve ethnocentrism, which superimposes the same structure
of belief everywhere. One cannot assume that more wells will be met by the
same actions regardless of the people involved. What the local people valorize
will have much to do with how they respond to the increase in well access.
Note that in our version of this argument, we do not rely on any claim about
methods. Say the contextual knowledge a policymaker wants to extract is from
the census data of Los Angeles or London. There is nothing philosophically
barring the use of quantitative methods as part of a wider research strategy
aimed at local knowledge. So an urban planner could use mass surveys or
statistics to gain some picture of public opinion in L.A. or London. Of course,
sometimes this might lead to a neglect of local knowledge, but in other cases it
might be an important factor in acquiring it. Quantitative methods are not fated
or determined to neglect local knowledge—it is all in how they are used.
Likewise, a policymaker could spend months doing ethnographic research on the
customs and habits of Los Angelenos and still leap to naturalist explanations and
modes of thought that neglect particular beliefs and meanings of actors. As we
established in Chapter 5 on methods, there is nothing that prohibits
ethnographic means from being used for naturalist ends.
If the problem is not quantitative methods, how then does naturalism neglect
local knowledge? Naturalist-inspired public policy tends to neglect context in
favor of formalism. Naturalists often make claims to necessary causal bonds that
link two formal variables together as they migrate through highly heterogeneous
cultural and historical contexts. Other times, naturalists set up formal decision
Page 10 of 23
Public policy
Once more, this turn away from naturalist technocracy is not contingent upon an
epochal sociological shift to the age of globalization as some scholars suggest,
nor is it the result of the “complexity” of the issues involved in the social
sciences.32 What in fact legitimizes the turn toward more dialogical and
deliberative forms of public policy is the conceptual critique of naturalism.
Technocratic and elite policy expertise depends on claims to a special scientific
knowledge of society. The assumption is that policy elites have access to a
specialized science of society that allows them to strongly predict outcomes. But
if anti-naturalism is correct, then the kinds of causal relationships needed for
strong, predictive technocratic expertise are simply unavailable in the social
sciences. As the philosopher Alasdair MacIntyre has succinctly put it: “our social
order is in a very literal sense out of our, and indeed anyone’s [scientific]
control.”33
Page 11 of 23
Public policy
Some readers might be thinking that all this sounds a bit wooly and idealistic.
After all, did we not say that the deliberative and dialogical turn is also
accompanied by a heightened awareness of the inherent contestability of all
social and political reality? At this point an objection might be raised against our
attempt to legitimize this turn in policymaking. Namely, is this call for
democratic deliberation viable in practice? And what of the many policy debates
that exist at the intersection of society and the natural sciences and undoubtedly
involve highly technical knowledge? For example, is the interpretive and
deliberative model really helpful when governments must resolve some dilemma
with the economy or the environment? Is not rule by experts and technocrats
still necessary in such cases?
Perhaps the best way to begin addressing doubts about the practical viability of
a deliberative and dialogical turn in policymaking is to briefly analyze an actual
example of this kind of policy succeeding. If this paradigm in policymaking can
be shown as successful in an actual concrete situation, then perhaps this goes
some way toward allaying this type of objection. As Rousseau once famously
quipped: “it seems to me good logic to reason from the actual to the possible.”38
In this context, Sarah Connick and Judith E. Innes provide an especially helpful
case study of deliberative policy approaches when dealing with California’s
complex water laws. Briefly summarizing this case—while also integrating it into
an anti-naturalist framework—will help address these doubts.
Page 12 of 23
Public policy
What is of great value in Connick and Innes’s work is their confirmation that
deliberative policy can outperform naturalist paradigms in the technically
complex domains like California’s water laws. California is infamous nationwide
for the complexity and intensity of conflict around its water policy (sometimes
colloquially referred to as “water wars”). The issues involved almost always
include highly technical economic factors and problems in the environmental
sciences. This poses the question of whether the policy problems are simply too
difficult for anyone but scientific elites to handle. In this light, we will briefly
consider Connick and Innes’s findings studying the San Francisco Estuary
Project (SFEP).
SFEP was a policy group assembled by the government in the early 1990s to
attempt a consensual proposal for environmentally restoring and managing this
important waterway. The group consisted of diverse stakeholders and
governmental agencies, many with intensely conflicting interests, including
environmentalists, agriculturalists, urban water users, business leaders, and
developers. Indeed, so ferocious was the initial disagreement that Connick and
(p.191) Innes report there was no consensus on “the estuary’s problems” or
even “that there was a problem.”39 This conundrum should not surprise readers
given what we have been arguing about the interpretive nature of political
phenomena. Policymaking is always an interpretive issue about human beliefs,
meanings, actions, and practices. In the world of policy, some evaluative story
must be told about the existence of a problem, what this problem means to the
political community, and who if anyone can or should fix it. Problems do not
appear on the radar of governments as value-neutral facts. In this sense, the
deep disagreement that Connick and Innes report is ultimately centered on the
contested meaning or significance of the estuary for political life. This involves
technical issues of the natural sciences, but these are always embedded within a
narrative stream of contested political meanings.
The reality that the world of political action is composed of contested meanings
helps shed light on Connick and Innes’s finding that the deliberative approach to
policy formation adopted by SFEP exhibited a number of concrete advantages
over naturalist approaches. First, for all their differences, the diverse
stakeholders comprising SFEP were able to learn from one another. The
deliberative policy processes educated all involved in how agreement over both
scientific facts and cultural meanings is achieved (something lost sight of in the
naturalist mindset that attempts to simply apply a scientific solution devised by
experts to social reality). So, for example, the scientists in the group were able
to shed light on the technical problems of the estuary in a way that enriched and
informed laypeople’s own positions on the issue. This information was then
translated into more democratically accessible language about the estuary that
was communicated to the public.40 No less important, the scientists on SFEP
learned from the laypeople about the nature of the political process. Scientists
reported that they had become overly accustomed to an “experimental mode” of
Page 13 of 23
Public policy
Finally, Connick and Innes argue that the above features of a deliberative
approach to policy can also result in high-quality decisions. So SFEP developed a
water quality index that became a major point of reference among rival
constituencies in ongoing debates over water policy.45 Technical findings of the
natural sciences were successfully embedded into the world of cultural and
political meanings. This is not to say that simply implementing a deliberative and
interpretive approach to policy guarantees success. Like all human endeavors,
interpretive policy is a risk that must deal with the freedom of human agency
and vulnerability to everything from slight errors to spectacular failures.46 But
only a particularly crude form of naturalism would expect to see policy as simply
the resolution of problems like solving arithmetic or building a piece of
infrastructure. As Connick and Innes rightly note, a deliberative approach has
Page 14 of 23
Public policy
Performativity
One of the main features of all policymaking that becomes apparent in the turn
toward interpretivism is the way that particular policy styles enact different
kinds of political realities. As we just saw, an anti-naturalist policy style has the
potential to reinforce deliberative democratic values and educate participants in
what it means to self-rule. By contrast, a naturalist approach (p.193) might
enact forms of political reality that are technocratic and based on claims to
expert rule and power, in which a populace largely becomes a passive spectator
on democracy with diminishing senses of efficacy. This brings us to the
performative dimensions of policymaking.
Scholars like Maarten Hajer and Hendrik Wagenaar have written perceptively on
how people can be described by a given policy (for example, as “protestors”
versus “collaborators”) in such ways that have a huge impact on politics itself.
As they put it, in the case of public policy so often “representation of an issue…is
the issue.”48 Fischer dubs this the “constructing [of] target populations” in
which certain groups and individuals are conceptualized as a threat, a help, a
problem, neutral, etc.49 However, as in the other features of the interpretive turn
in public policy, there could be more clarity over what justifies such awareness
of performativity.50
Page 15 of 23
Public policy
A concrete example occurs in the work of Bernard Harcourt, who has argued
that the “Broken Windows” policing instituted by Mayor Rudolph (p.194)
Giuliani in New York City carried with it certain conceptions of “order” versus
“disorder.” In particular, minor crimes more typically committed by the urban
poor (e.g., turnstile jumping, loitering, graffiti painting) were policed far more
heavily than those frequently committed by the rich (e.g., tax evasion, white-
collar fraud, not cleaning up when walking a dog). In other words, the concept of
“disorder” was enacted in such a way that it led to far more punitive treatment
of the poor and racial minorities than the white upper class.55 The construction
of Broken Windows categories therefore had strongly performative dimensions
when enacted as a form of policing and policy that have entrenched racial
discrimination and unequal treatment of citizens.
Page 16 of 23
Public policy
Page 17 of 23
Public policy
problem.62 The purpose of such a use of rational choice theory should not be
mistaken (as social scientists under the sway of naturalism often do) for a
description of reality, but instead as a kind of thought experiment that can
“reveal the consequences of a world (unlike our own) in which the hypothecated
assumptions were true.”63 This basic move might also apply to a broad swath of
the naturalist concepts and theories we have studied so far in this volume.
A similar point might be made about the naturalist concept formation treated in
earlier chapters. In particular, we established at length that essentialism,
atomism, and reification are highly distortive of social reality. So in our
discussion of Foucauldian governmentality, we saw that treating the state as an
ahistorical, unitary agency is highly distortive of the actual historical
contingency of the state. Indeed, shifting to an anti-naturalist, interpretive
analysis of the state not only frees social scientific concepts of distortions but
also yields new insights. However, Hay notes that the “conceptual abstraction”
of the state might for heuristic purposes be treated by social scientists “as if” it
possessed a certain unity and agency.65 Doing so might be more convenient for
certain policy discussions or could yield certain insights as to the institutional
constraints that politicians face when they enter into office.66 Indeed, Hay even
suggests that “the majority of self-proclaimed political scientists proceed as if a
natural science of the political were possible” even as “far fewer would now
regard this as much more than a convenient, simplifying and perhaps necessary
assumption.”67
Page 18 of 23
Public policy
pursuing this as-if line of inquiry would have to present themselves as builders
of elaborate thought experiments, not rigorous, empirically minded scientists.
One of the ongoing labors of this book has been to catalogue the many ways in
which naturalist philosophy distorts political and social reality. Surely many
working social scientists and researchers would very much like to accurately
describe and explain political reality. For them the cost of as-if naturalist
research may very well be too high. This points to certain inherent limitations in
an as-if treatment of naturalism. Moreover, as-if naturalists must also consider
how helpful false or purposefully distortive theories are when navigating in the
world. Although nothing keeps an as-if naturalist from using his or her findings
to bolster humanistic or deliberative political ends, we have (p.197) also seen
that there is the risk that these forms of understanding be used to make false
claims to hierarchical and scientistic authority. In short, even if social scientists
and policymakers wanted to simply adopt naturalism on an as-if basis, the reach
and importance of such a research program would be greatly diminished. It is
difficult to imagine a society whose entire public policy is willingly run on the
basis of a turn away from social reality in favor of abstract academic models and
thought experiments. Meanwhile, the interpretive turn offers an entire paradigm
of social research with the advantage of knowledge about the world that is both
more philosophically defensible and more likely to generate insights into
practical human affairs.
Notes:
(1.) For an approach inspired by John Dewey’s pragmatism see: Frank Fischer,
Democracy and Expertise: Reorienting Policy Inquiry (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2009); for one drawing on selected elements of Habermas see: John
Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political Science (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1990). For books that effectively convey the range
and diversity of interpretive approaches to public policy analysis, see: Frank
Fischer and John Forester, eds., The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and
Planning (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 1993); Frank Fischer and
Herbert Gottweis, eds., The Argumentative Turn Revisited: Public Policy as
Communicative Practice (Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2012); Hendrik
Wagenaar, Meaning in Action: Interpretation and Dialogue in Policy Analysis
(Armonk, NY: M.E. Sharpe, 2011); Maarten Hajer and Hendrik Wagenaar, eds.,
Deliberative Policy Analysis: Understanding Governance in the Network Society
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2003).
(2.) For example: Hajer and Wagenaar, Deliberative Policy Analysis, xiii.
(3.) Hajer and Wagenaar, Deliberative Policy Analysis, xiv; Judith E. Innes and
David Booher, “Collaborative Policymaking: Governance Through Dialogue,” in
Deliberative Policy Analysis, eds. Hajer and Wagenaar, 35–6; Sarah Connick and
Judith E. Innes, “Outcomes of Collaborative Water Policy Making: Applying
Page 19 of 23
Public policy
(4.) Dvora Yanow, Conducting Interpretive Policy Analysis (Thousand Oaks, CA:
Sage Publications, 2000) 20–93; Wagenaar, Meaning in Action, 241–74.
(5.) For a more detailed account of these forms of naturalist power see: Mark
Bevir, Democratic Governance (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 2010)
178–87.
(6.) John Forester, “Learning From Practice Stories: The Priority of Practical
Judgment,” in The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis, 195.
(7.) See: Deborah Stone, “Causal Stories and the Formation of Policy Agendas,”
Political Science Quarterly 104:2 (1989): 281–300.
(10.) Gérard Bouchard and Charles Taylor, Building the Future: A Time for
Reconciliation (Quebec City: Gouvernement du Quebec, 2008) 187, 186.
(16.) Frank Fischer, Reframing Public Policy: Discursive Politics and Deliberative
Practices (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003) 169–71.
(17.) Fischer and Forester, eds., The Argumentative Turn in Policy Analysis and
Planning.
(19.) Hajer and Wagenaar, Deliberative Policy Analysis, xiv; Innes and Booher,
“Collaborative Policymaking,” 35–6.
Page 20 of 23
Public policy
(21.) Fischer cites the work of Deborah Stone to make this claim: Fischer,
Democracy and Expertise, 206.
(23.) John J. Donohue III and Steven D. Levitt, “The Impact of Legalized Abortion
on Crime,” The Quarterly Journal of Economics CXVI:2 (2001): 379–420.
(24.) See, for example: Charles Dickens, Oliver Twist (New York: Penguin Books,
2002).
(25.) For a memoir that is one part autobiography and another part social
commentary of this kind, see: J. D. Vance, Hillbilly Elegy: A Memoir of a Family
and Culture in Crisis (New York: HarperCollins, 2016).
(29.) For a seminal early tract in public choice theory of this kind, see: James M.
Buchanan and Gordon Tullock, The Collected Works of James M. Buchanan, Vol.
3: The Calculus of Consent (Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund, 1999).
(30.) Hajer and Wagenaar, Deliberative Policy Analysis, xiii. See also: Connick
and Innes, “Outcomes of Collaborative Water Policy Making,” 178.
(32.) Hajer and Wagenaar, Deliberative Policy Analysis, xiv; Innes and Booher,
“Collaborative Policymaking,” 35–6; Connick and Innes, “Outcomes of
Collaborative Water Policy Making,” 179–80.
(33.) Alasdair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre
Dame, 2007) 107.
(34.) See, for example: Fischer, Reframing Public Policy, 221; Frank Fischer,
“Beyond Empiricism,” in Deliberative Policy Analysis, eds. Hajer and Wagenaar,
224–5; Innes and Booher, “Collaborative Policymaking,” 38, 40.
Page 21 of 23
Public policy
(38.) Jean-Jacques Rousseau, The Social Contract, trans. Maurice Cranston (New
York: Penguin Books, 1968) 137.
(39.) Sarah Connick and Judith E. Innes, “San Francisco Estuary Project,” in The
Consensus Building Handbook: A Comprehensive Guide to Reaching Agreement,
eds. Lawrence Susskind, Sarah McKearnan, and Jennifer Thomas-Larmer
(Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 1999) 805.
(42.) Connick and Innes, “San Francisco Estuary Project,” 822. See also:
Connick and Innes, “Outcomes of Collaborative Water Policy Making,” 185.
(44.) Connick and Innes, “San Francisco Estuary Project,” 814, 824; Connick and
Innes, “Outcomes of Collaborative Water Policy Making,” 186–7.
(46.) For example, see Connick and Innes’s critiques of the shortcomings of
SFEP: “San Francisco Estuary Project,” 821, 823.
(47.) Connick and Innes, “Outcomes of Collaborative Water Policy Making,” 184–
5.
(51.) Here we have some similarities with: S. D. Noam Cook and Hendrik
Wagenaar, “Navigating the Eternally Unfolding Present: Toward an
Epistemology of Practice,” The American Review of Public Administration 42:1
(2012): 3–38.
Page 22 of 23
Public policy
(62.) See also: Colin Hay, “Theory, Stylized Heuristic, or Self-Fulfilling Prophecy?
The Status of Rational Choice Theory in Public Administration,” Public
Administration 82:1 (2004): 39–62.
(63.) Colin Hay, Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction (New York: Palgrave
Macmillan, 2002) 39.
(65.) Colin Hay, “Neither Real nor Fictitious but ‘As If Real’? A Political Ontology
of the State,” The British Journal of Sociology 65:3 (2014): 459.
(66.) Hay, “Neither Real nor Fictitious but ‘As If Real’?” 472–5.
Page 23 of 23
Conclusion
Conclusion
Mark Bevir
Jason Blakely
DOI:10.1093/oso/9780198832942.003.0010
Page 1 of 3
Conclusion
this has been to achieve greater philosophical clarity and consensus about what
social scientists are doing when they set out to study and explain human beings
and their societies from an interpretive perspective.
For this reason, the future holds new, yet unknown understandings of the
present and the past. The future is even the bringer of new pasts. And this is not
due to the historical provisionality of a march toward absolute science, but
rather is the result of the very nature of social and political reality itself. What
Jorge Luis Borges said of literary fiction is indeed true of social reality, as well:
“literature is not exhaustible, for the sufficient and simple reason that a single
book is not.”1 The same can be said of the density of events and everyday
happenings, wars and treaties, practices and habits, institutions and social
spaces, religions and mores that are the stuff of human life. The meaning of
human society is not exhaustible for the simple reason that the meaning of a
single human life has not yet been exhausted.
Notes:
(1.) Jorge Luis Borges, “A Note on (Toward) Bernard Shaw,” in Labyrinths (New
York: New Directions Publishing Company, 2007) 213–14.
Page 2 of 3
Index
(p.203) Index
actions 66–67, 116
and beliefs, constitutive relationship between 23–24
as brute data 33–35
contingent 35–36, 51, 54, 138, 142
holistic nature of 23–24
and narrative 24–25
Adams, Herbert 3–4
Adcock, Robert 77
age, and voter behavior 68–70
agency 45–48, 53, 116, 156–157, 181
situated 48–49, 53–54, 62
ahistoricism 44–45, 49–51, 54
Alexander, Jeffrey 156
Alexander, Michelle 121–122
Al–Qaida 120
American Way of Life 128–129
analytic philosophy 13–14, 35
Anderson, Benedict 147–149
Anglo-Foucauldians 152
anti-essentialism 72–73, 80
anti-humanism 44–50, 53–54, 61–62
anti-naturalism 2, 9–15, 18–19, 44–45
basic philosophical features 19–20
concept formation 80–85
and naturalism contrasted 32–33
anti-Semitism 26–27
Aristotle 167, 180
Aryan physics 26–27
atomism 5–6, 8, 95, 196
authoritarianism 75–76
autonomy 27–28, 45–48
Page 1 of 13
Index
civic engagement 123–125
civil religion 83–84
civil society 171
clash of civilizations thesis 117–119
Collier, David 65–68, 71–73, 77
colonialism, and ethnography 93–94
communism 147, 169–170
community 147–149
completeness axiom 104–107
(p.204) Comte, Auguste 3–4, 138
concept formation 10, 65–85
anti-naturalist 80–85
naturalist 65–66, 196
essentialism 70–76, 164, 196
linguistic instrumentalism 76–80
reification 66–70, 196
concepts
descriptive 80–82
explanatory 80, 82–83
family resemblance 72–73, 80–82
conceptual stretching 71–73
conceptual traveling 71
Connick, Sarah 190–192
contentious politics 10, 73–74
contestability 139, 142–144, 153, 160
in policymaking 183–185
contingency 30–31, 35–36, 49, 51, 53–54, 82, 99–100, 138–139, 142, 151–152, 160–161,
174
counter-democracy 124–125
criminal identity 121–122
criminality 186–187
critique 45, 60–62
cross-sectional surveys 94–95
cultural approach 156
cultural practices 122–128
cultural studies 131
culture(s) 6, 131, 172
popular/mass 131
and public policy 187–188
Cushman, Philip 156
Darwinism 3–4, 146–147
data analysis methods 89, 96–103
case studies 7–8, 96–97, 100–101
grounded theory 96–97, 101–102
Q methodology 96–97, 102–103
random sampling 96–100
statistical inference 96–100
data collection methods 89–96
ethnography 19, 88–94
Page 3 of 13
Index
interviews 90, 94–96
surveys 5–6, 94–96
Davidson, Donald 13–14, 55–56
death of the subject 44–47, 53
deductive theory 6
definitional circularity 58–59
deliberative democracy 168, 172–173
deliberative public policy 179–180, 183, 189–192
democracy 68, 75–77, 79, 92, 101, 167
deliberative 168, 172–173
participatory 168
representative 169, 173, 189 see also counter-democracy
democratic peace theory 58–59, 74–75
democratic theory 27, 157, 168–173
Denton, Melinda Lundquist 98–100
deontology 159–160, 164, 167–168
Derrida, Jacques 53
Descartes, Rene 3
descriptive concepts 80–82
Desmond, Matthew 91
developmental historicism 3–5, 138
devolution 172–173
Dewey, John 12–14
diachronic research 11–12, 116, 135–136
dialogical policy formation 172–173, 189–192
dictatorship 79
dilemmatic beliefs 25–27, 29–30, 82
discontinuity 138–139, 142–144, 153
discourses 46–48, 51–53, 56–57, 61
disenchantment thesis 30–31
Donahue, John 186
Dostoevsky, Fyodor 26–27
Demons 26
drugs 121–122
Dryzek, John 189
Dubner, Steven 149–150
Durkheim, Emile 171
duty see deontology
Easton, David 6
economics 4–5, 105, 107–108, 149–150, 158–160
Einstein, Albert 26–27
empiricism 5–8, 55–56
end of history thesis 129–130
Enlightenment 166–167
entrepreneurial government 170–171
epistemes 46–48, 52, 57, 61
epistemology 13–14
essentialism 70–76, 117, 196
strong 71–74
Page 4 of 13
Index
weak 71–75
ethical critique 12, 157–158
ethical engagement, of public policy 185–187, 189
ethical neutrality 162–163
ethics 27, 156–165, 174
deontological 159, 164, 167–168
facts of 161–162
Greek/Roman 166–167
historical turn in 165–168
utilitarian 4–5, 106–107, 158–161, 163–164, 167–168
virtue 167
(p.205) ethnography 19, 88–94
and colonialism 93–94
and naturalist research 92–93
post-colonial turn in 93–94
ethnomethodology 44
evolutionary theory 3–4, 146–147
experts/expertise 39, 168–170, 172, 179–180, 189, 193
explanation 21–22, 35–36, 45, 49–54, 61, 67–68, 103–104
explanatory concepts 80, 82–83
facts 6, 12
ethical 161–162
natural sciences 161
shared 58–60
fact–value dichotomy 162, 174
family resemblance concepts 72–73, 80–82
Finer, Herman 5
Fischer, Frank 179–180, 182–183, 185, 189–190, 193
Flyvbjerg, Bent 14
folk naturalisms 120–121
folk psychology 32
Forester, John 179–182, 185
formalism 4–5, 8
formal modeling 104–110
Foucault, Michel 28, 44–53, 56–57, 61, 106–107, 142–144, 147–148, 167–168, 201
anti-humanist position 46–48, 54, 61
death of the subject 46–47, 53, 167
discourses 46–48, 51–53, 56–57, 61
epistemes 46–48, 52, 57, 61
and ethics 166–167
genealogical approach 31, 46–47, 138–140, 143–144
governmentality 151–153
power, regimes of 46–48, 52–53
foundationalism 58–62
Freeman, Edward 3–4
free-rider problem 105
French peasant communities 148–149
Fukuyama, Francis 129–130
Gadamer, Hans-Georg 13–14, 20, 29, 44, 48–49, 167–169
Page 5 of 13
Index
Galileo 3
game theory 105, 109
Geertz, Clifford 147, 156, 161
genealogy 31, 44–47, 135–140, 143–144, 152–153
Gerring, John 100–101
Giuliani, Rudolph 194
globalization 129–130, 171, 179
Goffman, Alice 91, 122
Gordon, Colin 151
governance 170–172
market 170–171
network 170–172
governmentalities 151–153, 196
Gramsci, Antonio 131
Gray, John 129–130
Greek ethics 166–167
Green, J. R. 3–4
grounded theory 96–97, 101–102
Habeck, Mary 120
Haddad, Yvonne Yazbeck 119
Hajer, Maarten 179–180, 193
Hall, Stuart 131, 156, 169
Hansen, John Mark 68–70
happiness/pleasure 158–161, 164
Harcourt, Bernard 194
Hartz, Louis 128–130
Hay, Colin 7–8, 12–13, 37–38, 48, 104–105, 108–109, 195–196
Hegel, G. W. F. 3–4, 167, 201
Hegelianism 14–15, 44
hegemony 131
Heidegger, Martin 24, 44–45, 167, 201
Hempel, Carl 67
hermeneutic circle 20–23, 33, 75–76, 99
heuristics 89, 103–110
high culture 131
Hispanic identity 121
historical institutionalism 7–8
historical sociologies 135–153
historicism 53–54, 82
developmental 3–5, 138
history 29–31, 160–161
ethical significance of 157, 165–168
and social background 29–30
Hobbes, Thomas 3, 151
Hochschild, Arlie Russell 91
homo economicus 150
horizon, Gadamer’s concept of 48–49
humanism 39, 185–186 see also anti-humanism
human rights 167
Page 6 of 13
Index
Hume, David 174
Huntington, Samuel P. 117–120
Husserl, Edmund 44–48
hypothesis testing 6–7
idealism 3–4
ideal types 50
identity 116–122
criminal 121–122
(p.206) Islamic versus Western 116–120
racial 121–122
ideology 12, 26–27, 61–62
incarceration of racial minorities 122, 144
inclusive fitness logic 146–147
incommensurability 57–58
incommensurable goods 106–108
induction 6–7
Ingram, Helen 77
Innes, Judith E. 189–192
institutional theory 171–172
institutions 123–128
invisible 125
interpretive turn 2, 9–15, 44–45, 201
interviews 90, 94–96
in-depth 90
semi-structured 95–96
structured 95–96
Islam 116–120
Japan 130
Jevons, William Stanley 4–5
Jewish culture 166–167
judgment 124–125
Kant, Immanuel 159, 164–165, 167
kinship 146–147
knowledge-power 56–57, 61
Kuhn, Thomas 158
ladder of abstraction 71
ladder of generality 72
Lampland, Martha 126
language 28–29, 47 see also linguistic instrumentalism
large-N statistics 7–8
law-like explanation 35–37
legitimacy 124–125, 192
Lenard, Philipp 26–27
Levitsky, Steven 68
Levitt, Steven 149–150, 186
liberalism 128–129, 147
linguistic instrumentalism 76–80
object-side 77, 79, 117–118
subject-side 76–79
Page 7 of 13
Index
Lippmann, Walter 6
Locke, John 128–129
logical positivism 55
longitudinal surveys 94–95
Lyotard, Jean-Francois 136
McAdam, Doug 73–74
MacIntyre, Alasdair 24, 37, 167–170
MacLeish, Kenneth 90–91
Mahon, James 71–73
Maoz, Zeev 74–75
Marcuse, Herbert 171
markets 150, 152–153, 170–171
Marx, Karl 3–4, 128–129, 138
Marxism 35, 163–164, 169
mass incarceration 122, 144
mass/popular culture 131
mass surveys 94–96, 99
materialism 3
Mead, Margaret 92–93
meaning 46–47, 55–56, 67–68
age and voter behavior 69–70
contestability of 139, 142–144, 153, 160, 183–184
meaning holism 20–21, 33–34, 55–56, 67, 99
Merriam, Charles 5–6
meta–narratives 135–140, 153
methods 10–11, 14, 88–111
heuristics 89, 103–110
multi–methods 89, 94, 96, 108, 110–111 see also data analysis; data collection
methods; qualitative methods; qualitative–quantitative debate; quantitative
methods
midlevel theory 6–7
Mill, J. S. 4–5, 138, 158–159
modernity 144–145, 157, 160–161, 167–168
Moore, Kathleen 119, 159
moralism 164–165
Morrow, James 77–78
multi-methods 89, 94, 96, 108, 110–111
narratives 24–25, 54, 62, 82–83, 173
and objectivity 44–45
and public policy 180–183, 189 see also meta-narratives
nationalism 146–149
National Survey of Youth and Religion 98
nation-ness 147–148
naturalism 2–9, 18, 50–51
as anti-democratic 39
as anti-humanistic 39, 153
and anti-naturalism contrasted 32–33
“as if” defense of 195–197
assumptions
Page 8 of 13
Index
Siverson, Ralph 77–78
small improvements argument 106
Smith, Adam 150
Smith, Alastair 77–79
Smith, Christian 98–100
Smith, Jane 119
Smith, Rogers M. 129–130
social background 27–29, 31, 33, 46–49, 54
and belief formation 29
and history 29–30
social capital 123–124
social choice theory 105
social constructivism 13–14, 19–20
Social Darwinism 163–164
social engineering 37, 169–170
social imaginaries 145–150, 153
socialism 129–131, 169
social physics 18, 34
sociobiology 146–149
Southeast Asia, peasant resistance 131–132
Soviet Union 169
Spencer, Herbert 150
Spickard, Paul 156
Stalinism 169
standardization 126–128
Stark, Johannes 26–27
Star, Susan Leigh 126
state 170–171, 196
governmental approaches to 151–153
naturalist study of 151
statistical inference 96–100
statistics 5–6, 88–89
large-N 7–8
Stone, Deborah 180–182, 185
strong essentialism 71–74
Stubbs, William 3–4
subjectivity 45–49
surveillance 124–125, 143–144
survey research 5–6, 94–96, 99
synchronic research 11, 116, 135
Tarrow, Sidney 73–74
Taylor, Charles 13–14, 24, 30–31, 44, 48, 61, 136, 139–140, 144–145, 165, 167–168,
181–182, 194–195, 201
(p.209) technocracy 36–37, 39, 168–172, 179–180, 189, 193
Thatcherism 131
Thatcher, Margaret 170–171
theory 57–60
midlevel 6–7
thick descriptions 90–92, 161
Page 12 of 13
Index
Page 13 of 13