African Political Philosophy PDF
African Political Philosophy PDF
Albert Kasanda
Abstract: The paper analyzes the nature, objectives and trends of African
social and political philosophy. It distinguishes two major axis: identity and
emancipation of Africa as well as democracy and cultural diversity. The
former includes theories such as negritude, African socialism, African
humanism, pan-Africanism, while the latter concentrates on ideas of
democracy, civil society and cultural diversity. 1
Introduction
African social and political philosophy is deeply interlaced with the daily life of
African people. Therefore, the paper explores the development of this philosophy
in agreement with some major events characterizing African history from the
colonial period up to now. The paper is divided into four sections. The first
section explores both the object and nature of African social and political
philosophy. Three objectives are considered: the well-being of African people,
the issue of power and the search for a suited paradigm of social and political
organization. This section also examines the relationship between African social
and political philosophy and ontology as well as it reminds some neglected
sources of this philosophical thought, such as literature, music and art. The
second section concentrates on antecedents of today’s African social and political
philosophy, introducing personalities such as Africanus J. B. Horton and the issue
of modern African states, Edward W. Blyden about African regeneration, J. E.
Casely Hayford with regard to the claim for African self-governance. The third
section analyzes ideas of African identity and African emancipation. It puts
emphasis on notions such as African socialism, African Humanism, African
liberation, and African modernization. The fourth section focuses on the current
context of Africa exploring challenges such as African rush towards democracy,
African civil society, and cultural diversity. African social and political
philosophy is an important field of research. The paper concentrates on its
panoramic presentation, evoking main trends and suggesting new debates and
challenges. The expression “African political philosophy” will stand for “African
social and political philosophy”.
Dr. ALBERT KASANDA, Centre of African Studies and International Research,
Brussels, Belgium. Email: [email protected].
1
This paper was written with the support of the Centre of Global Studies, a joint centre of
the Institute of Philosophy at the Academy of Sciences of the Czech Republic and the
Faculty of Philosophy at Charles University in Prague. I express my deep gratitude to the
authorities of this academic institution for their support. I also would like to give special
thanks to Dr Marek Hrubec, who encouraged me to carry out this research and also for his
illuminating suggestions.
other hand, the political sphere is viewed as only a space of empirical attitudes
and pragmatism.
The debate on Tempels’ work, Bantu Philosophy (1947), contributed to denounce
epistemological and cultural imperialism denying the existence of any particular
philosophy beyond that inherited from the Greek genius. It also revealed the
difficulty for African philosophers to formulate a consensual definition of African
philosophy (Bell 2002, 21-22). However, it is convened –at expenses of the
concept of philosophy- that African philosophy exists even before the work of
Tempels (Bidima 1995, 9). This assertion can be also considered valid about
African political philosophy, as this philosophy has always accompanied African
people in their search for a better polis. The evoked debate allowed the
systematization of premises underlying this search. Theories of African
humanism and African socialism, for example, rest on this premise. For many
scholars and political leaders the ontology as sustained by Tempels constitutes an
invaluable vade mecum. The idea of Senghor concerning African peculiarity, for
example, rests on this background (Bidima 1995, 13).
This ascendancy of ontology in African political philosophy rises suspicion
about two stumbling blocks of political philosophy, formerly denounced by
Strauss in his famous lecture: Qu’est-ce que la philosophie politique? (Strauss
1992). First of all, it can be mentioned the temptation to consider political
philosophy as a particular application or a subcategory of general philosophy, by
transposing problems and concepts of the latter in the sphere of politics. The
search for African quintessence characterizing political reflection of many
African thinkers made this deviation more than likely. Theories such as negritude,
African socialism and African humanism are likely the most affected by this
criticism, because they put more emphasis on ontological speculation than on the
daily struggles of African people (Adotevi 1998, 51-80). This attitude can be
compared to what Arendt denounced in her criticism of Plato’s political
philosophy: the withdrawal of the thinker from the world (Arendt 1994).
According to Arendt’s view, the concept of “world” refers to the notion of
“common world” which includes factors that are essential and essentially not
philosophical at a time, and they cannot be reduced to metaphysical category.
Such is the case of poverty, social exclusion and gender, for example.
The second stumbling block concerns the propensity to perceive political
philosophy as a systematization of opinions that are already present in the polis.
This perception is the Achilles' heel of trends of African political philosophy
relying on the exhumation of African past and the rehabilitation of African
cultures.
2
The expression «professional philosophers» is not here opposed to «ethnophilosphers» as
it is the case for many scholars classifying African philosophy in categories such as
ethnophilosophy, ideological philosophy, and professional philosophy (Smet 1980,
Mudimbe 1988). It just refers to the institutionalization of African philosophy.
protagonists and also its modalities of diffusion. More and more studies claim the
relationship between African philosophy and other disciplines such as literature,
music and art. Scholars such as Appiah (2004), Bidima (2004), Okolo (2007), and
Rettová (2013) denounce the prejudice confining mentioned disciplines to the
sphere of entertainment, and consequently denying them all aptitude to conceive
and express philosophical ideas. As an illustration, let us explore the relationship
between African political philosophy and literature.
According to Bidima, “both literature and philosophy have a number of
intertextual relationships, particularly as regards three domains: namely, political
philosophy, philosophy of history, and aesthetics. One illustrative fact in
particular should be emphasized. The political tendency of the critique of
ethnophilosophy among African francophone philosophers (…) owes a great deal
to numerous passages in Discours sur le colonialisme by the poet Aimé Césaire;
which is yet another confirmation of the extent to which philosophy and literature
both journey along similar paths” (Bidima 2004, 557).
Taking stand on the existentialist philosophy developed by Sartre (1905-1980)
for whom the main broadcasting mode of ideas was theater, Rettová shows both
the aptitude and the relevance of literature to express philosophical questions, to
reach the public and to call it to an interactive and productive debate (Rettová
2013). In the same vein, Okolo examines the relationship between African
literature and political philosophy (Okolo 2007). For Okolo, both these
disciplines are equally interested in dealing with ideas. The affinity between them
is noticeable in areas such as their moral influence on human behavior, their
effect on language, their contribution to development, their social incidence and
political criticism (Okolo 2007, 13-22).
The proliferation of African writers interested in African political philosophy
strengthens the previous hypothesis that the overlooking of African literature –as
well as areas such as music and art- as one of the major loci of production and
diffusion of this philosophy is a prejudicial attitude.
The history of ideas cannot oversee events that have marked the development of
Africa, such as slavery and slave trade, colonization, African emancipation and
globalization. This section introduces some antecedents of today’s African
political philosophy, particularly personalities such as Africanus J. B. Horton
(1835-1883), Edward W. Blyden (1832-1912) and J. E. Casely Hayford (1866-
1930).
II-1. Africanus J. B. Horton: The Plea for the Constitution of Modern African
States
The interdiction of the slave trade propelled England to the rank of the most
active marine police in tracking recalcitrant slave-traders. The concern to assure a
land of freedom for freed slaves and to re-locate “slaves to become” captured in
the triangular trade led British authority to establish, in 1787, the colony of Sierra
Leone whose capital city took the name of Freetown (Wesseling 1991, 142).
According to Ilife, approximately 74,000 freed slaves were deported to this
colony that they dominated soon after thanks to the education received from
Church Missionary Society (Ilife 1998, 203), which was based on British cultural
model. Taking stand on this education, many people from Sierra Leone dreamed
about their political freedom. Horton embodied this aspiration.
Horton was born from parents of Igbo origin who have been captured by
British police on their crossing to slavery, and were relocated in Sierra Leone. He
studied at King’s College of London and at University of Edinburgh where he got
his doctorate in medicine. During his stay in London and Edinburgh, he adopted
the nickname of Africanus which will be associated with his identity and his
political engagement. This choice was very challenging in a context where to be
different – to be "someone colored" - was not the best asset, as it was during this
period that pseudo-scientific racist doctrines, of which Gobineau is one of the
striking names, were expanding (Delacampagne 2000, 164 -174).
A report of the House of Commons of 1865 proposing the disengagement of
British in Western Africa was the opportunity for Horton to express his political
concern. This report stipulated that British policy “should be to encourage in the
native the exercise of those qualities which may render it possible for us more and
more to transfer to the natives the administrations of all the Governments, with a
view to our ultimate withdrawal from all, except probably Sierra Leone”(Boele
van Hensbroek s.d., 39). In reaction to this report, Horton published, in 1868,
West African Countries and Peoples. This work includes a description of Western
British African communities and proposals for the implementation of African
institutions. Horton aimed at the creation of autonomous West-African British
colonies built according to the example of Australia and Canada. Concerning his
own native land, for example, he notes that: «constitutional form of government
must form the basis of his administration, consisting of House of assembly which
should be composed of men elected by the people, as it will be difficult for his
Government to stand without popular confidence, and the only means by which
that can be secured is by giving the people the power to elect one branch of the
Legislature… Each member should have landed property, be over the age of
twenty-two, and be properly educated» (Ibid., 44).
Horton was persuaded of the possibility to modernize African States in
agreement with the principle of self-government. For him, the mediation of a
modern State with a similar experience was necessary to implement such a
project. Therefore, he insisted on that British authorities should rather consider it
a duty to promote and to oversee the advent of modern African States as part of
their mission.
Some people considered Horton as either a paternalist thinker or a voice of
British domination because of his favorable attitude about British protectorate.
Let’s note that the issue of Western protectorate has been very present in the mind
of various African freedom fighters, as many of them considered it as a good
strategy towards emancipation. This idea was proposed, for example, by the
Belgian scholar, Professor Van Bilsen, concerning Congolese independence. The
“Van Bilsen plan” recommended to Belgian Kingdom to keep his Congolese
colony for about thirty years more, the necessary period of time to prepare
Congolese to assume and manage themselves. Some Congolese leaders accepted
this project and included it in their political agenda (M’Bokolo 1985, 201).
III-1. Ethnophilosophy
The Word and the Thing. The term Ethnophilosophy was successful in the
euphoria subsequent to the debate on the existence of African philosophy.
Contrary to a wide-spread opinion (Appiah 1992, 85-106; Hallen 2009), this
concept did not appear in the 1970s, particularly as a consequence of the usage
that thinkers such as Hountondji (1970) and Towa (1971) made of it. Its earliest
usage in African philosophy is attributed to Nkrumah. After his Master's degree
in philosophy, in 1943, Nkrumah intended to present a doctoral thesis in
Ethnophilosophy at the American university of Pennsylvania. He drafted a
doctoral dissertation entitled: “Mind and Thought in Primitive Society: A Study
in Ethno-Philosophy with Special Reference to the Akan Peoples of the Gold
Coast, West Africa” (quoted in Hountondji 2004, 533. See also: Hallen 2002, 72).
Out of the evoked reference, there is no comment about the meaning of this
expression. Considering this want of explanation, Hountondji formulated the
hypothesis to search for the meaning of this word in the domain of “ethnic
sciences”. For him, when Nkrumah elaborated his doctoral project
“l’ethnophilosophie (…) était une de ces disciplines nées aux Etats-Unis dans la
foulée des ethnosciences, qui s’étaient elles-mêmes développées à partir de
l’étude ethnolinguistique des langues et cultures amérindiennes: ethnobotanique,
ethnozoologie (…), l’originalité du chercheur qu’était Nkrumah était donc
d’appliquer à sa propre société la théorie et la méthodologie de cette discipline
déjà reconnue”3. In using this expression, Nkrumah sought to promote the idea
according to which anthropology should, by going beyond its traditional topics,
set up "a synthetic ethno-philosophy" through which “[elle] s’efforcerait de
3
www.exchoresis.refer.ga./IMG/P.J._Hountondji.pdf.
pénétrer les significations les plus fondamentales et les plus profondes qui sous-
tendent toute culture, en sorte qu’elle atteigne une Weltanschauung culturelle de
base par laquelle l’humanité reconnaîtrait que, malgré les différences de race, de
langue et de culture, elle est une en ce sens qu’il n’y a qu’une race: l’Homo
sapiens.” (Ibid. Underlined in the text).
The attempt to trace the genesis of the concept Ethnophilosophy clarifies the
very contribution of Hountondji and Towa, which consisted in that these two
philosophers diverted this expression of its previous and positive meaning, and
they consequently assigned to it a pejorative content consisting in a criticism of
some philosophical method and attitude. They denounced «une pratique de la
philosophie qui se donnait pour tâche de décrire les visions du monde collectives,
pratique qui (…) trahissait la vision première de la philosophie qui est non de
décrire, mais de démontrer ; non de reconstituer de manière conjecturale le
système de pensée de tel ou tel peuple, de telle ou telle société, de tel ou tel
groupe de personnes, mais de prendre soi-même position, de manière responsable,
sur des questions posées en acceptant la contrainte de justifier de manière
rationnelle ces prises de position» (Hountondji, art. cit.). According to
Hountondji’s own words: “Le mot existait bien avant les années soixante-dix.
Towa et moi ne l’avons pas forgé. Notre seule originalité était de l’utiliser dans
un sens péjoratif et polémique pour stigmatiser une pratique que nous rejetions,
alors qu’il était jusque-là, quand il était employé, le nom d’un projet
consciemment revendiqué” (Ibid. Underlined in the text).
It is advisable to note that Hountondji and Towa evolved in their perception
and criticism of ethnophilosophy, as they both recognize some positive
contribution of this trend of thought to the development of African philosophy
(Ibid.). However, some scholars denounce the silence of Hountondji and Towa on
the limits of scientific methods that both thinkers consider as essential to African
philosophy. Bidima, for example, criticizes the positivist attitude underlying the
thought of both the mentioned thinkers and their lack of coherence regarding
epistemological imperialism and obscurantism. He notes: “Hountondji et Towa
ont le réflexe d’un positivisme du XIXème siècle qui faisait de la science le
sauveur. On surprend chez une attitude bizarre se traduisant par la suspension de
l’esprit critique. Tout se passe comme si la réflexion critique qui les anime
s’arrêtait au seuil de la science (…) Towa et Hountondji se taisent quand il s’agit
de la technoscience, on ne critique plus, on fait confiance à la science qui sauve
des impérialismes et obscurantisme. Il y a un glissement d’une attitude critique
(…) à une attitude de foi. Leur discours sur la technoscience est celui de
l’idéologie dominante qui, pour mieux capter, saisit chaque objet en le coupant de
la réalité de ses contradictions” (Bidima 1995, 99).
Ethnophilosophy and African Political Philosophy. Ethnophilosophy is based
on the assumption that “there is a metaphysical system, and an ideology,
embodied in the traditional wisdom, the institutions and the languages of Africa”
(Kaphagawani 2000, 89). It aims at trashing out from myths, folktales, beliefs,
proverbs, and languages, “the quintessential African approach to the world”
(Ibid.). This project aims at disqualifying the racist discourse defending the ruling
system. Thinkers such as Hegel, Kant, Hume, count among those who shared this
discourse. Hegel’s attitude to reject Africa from the world history under the
pretext that this continent doesn’t have any contribution to the history of the
world is one of the most frequently evoked illustration in this respect (Eze 1997,
The concern for African identity rests on two premises: the rehabilitation of
African cultures and the threat of cultural homogenization due to globalization.
Let’s focus on Senghor’s perception of African peculiarity.
Negritude: A Struggle for Recognition and Cultural Rehabilitation. 4
Negritude is one of the best known movements struggling for both African
recognition and rehabilitation. For its protagonists, it is essential to assume being
black, to cultivate ones pride and self-appreciation. That is the reason why, being
themselves in a situation of despair, contempt and powerlessness, the founders of
this movement didn’t have another choice than the courage “to get rid of (their)
loaned clothes, those of the assimilation, and to assert their being, that is (their)
negritude.” 5 Sartre saw in this movement a kind of paradox consisting of a
“negation of the negation of black people”6.
The claim for the recognition of black peculiarity put the question of identity
in the heart of negritude’s concern, as it implies the statement of constituent
features of this peculiarity. Senghor remains one of the most enlightening thinkers
on the issue. According to him, contrary to Western people for whom Reason
constitutes the fundamental characteristic, black people are characterized by the
ascendancy of emotion. Emotion defines their epistemology and configures their
world vision (Senghor 1995). The famous aphorism according to which "the
emotion is as negro as the reason is Hellenic" seems to be the best synthesis of
this perception of African peculiarity (Kasanda 2013, 213).
This theory of Senghor provoked a general outcry of African intelligentsia.
Some people considered it as the continuation of Western racism towards black
people (Adotevi 1998, 99-105). Others denounced the essentialism characterizing
this perception (Eboussi-Boulaga, 1977) that puts all black people of the planet in
the same and unique category of black race, and this without any consideration
for specific trajectories of various social groups and individuals (Kelman 2005).
Some others thought of this analysis as a treason of African struggle. 7
Senghor is aware of those criticisms. He wrote : “ Some (…) Negro
intellectuals (…) have reproached me for having reduced the knowledge of the
African negro to pure emotion, and for having denied that African negro is
endowed with reason and technical knowledge” (Senghor 1995, 121). In his
own defense, he sustains that Reason is unique and common to everybody, but its
articulations and modalities of application depend on psychological and
physiological features of every race. Therefore, he maintains his idea according to
which West is characterized by its reference to analytical reason, whereas African
universe is based on intuitive and participative reason. He notes: “They have read
me absent-mindedly (…) Reason has always existed (…) Reason is one, in the
sense that it is made for the apprehension of the Other, that is, of objective reality.
Its nature is governed by its own laws; but its modes of knowledge, its ‘forms of
though’- are diverse and tied to the psychological and physiological make up of
each race (…) The reason of classical Europe is analytic through civilization, the
reason of the African negro, intuitive through participation.” (Ibid.).
4
This section is based on our work: Kasanda (2013).
5
http://www.tidiane.net/culture/afrique-negritude.htm.
6
http://www.tidiane.net/culture/afrique-negritude.htm.
7
http://www.africamaat.com/SENGHOR-le-Ya-bon-Blanc.
The reaction of Senghor is far from calming down criticisms due to his
perception of African peculiarity. Let’s leave aside this interesting debate, and
underline the originality of Senghor’s intuition. Senghor developed his reflection
in a racist context. In the first half of the twentieth century, France or rather
Europe was under influence of racist theories inherited from the nineteenth
century, for which thinkers such as Blumenbach (1752-1840) and Gobineau
(1816-1882) are among the most representative (Delacampagne 2000). Senghor
was aware of these surrounding theories. His originality consists in the reversal of
stigmas and claiming for racial difference. It is in this perspective that he
interprets emotion not as the reign of low instincts, but as a source of high
spirituality and deep sense of artistic creativity (Mosley 1995, 219).
The concern for the emancipation of African cultures is still relevant even
nowadays, as numerous studies postulate a potential disappearance of cultural
diversity because of globalization (Barber 1996. Fornet-Betancourt 2011). In this
respect, it is worth assuming that the point here is not only the defense of black
people and cultures for themselves, but also the claim for recognition of human
diversity and defense of otherness.
Senghor doesn’t consider difference as a sign of exclusion nor as an
expression of any antagonism. On the contrary, it is and it should be the hyphen
between peoples and cultures, because it contributes to their mutual enrichment.
Therefore, he pleads for a civilization of the universal: “Le rendez-vous du
donner et du recevoir”. Such a civilization doesn’t absorb other people and
cultures, but it calls for the knowledge of values of the other cultural and
geographical areas through dialogue (Senghor 1995. Shutte 1998).
The Zambian leader, Kaunda (1914 - ) develops his humanist vision on the
basis of two roots: Christian faith and African cultural heritage (Smet 1980,
54). For him, human being is the final purpose of all political initiative. He
declared: “I am deeply concerned that this high valuation of Man and respect
for human dignity which is a legacy of our [African] tradition should not be
lost in the new Africa. However “modern” and “advanced” in a Western sense
the new nations of Africa may become, we are fiercely determined that this
humanism will not be obscured. African society has always been Man-centred.
We intend that it will remain so” (quoted in Eze 1997, 42).
8
See also: Memmi (1985).
very essence of the human being. When we want to give high praise to someone
we say, ‘Yu, U nobuntu’; ‘Hey, he or she has ubuntu’. This means they are
generous, hospitable, friendly, caring and compassionate. They share what they
have. It also means my humanity is caught up, is inextricably bound up, in theirs.
We belong in a bundle of life. We say, ‘a person is a person through other people’.
It is not ‘I think therefore I am’. It says rather: ‘I am human because I belong.’ I
participate, I share.” (Tutu 1999, 34 – 35. Underlined in the original).9
African Socialism. It is worth keeping in mind that since the last decade of
the twentieth century, African socialism is no longer an appraised topic in African
political and philosophical landscape. However, this trend of thought is still
significant as an original contribution to African intellectual history as well as a
specific address of African intellectuals on “issues of (…) colonialism,
neocolonialism, Africa as a victim of the so-called cold war (…) where Africa’s
best interests lie when it comes to contemporary social, political, and economic
development” (Hallen 2009, 94).
African socialism was a syncretic attempt to reconcile Marxism, Christianity,
modern economic theories and African values. The Dakar Colloquium 10 revealed
two major trends of this socialism: humanitarian socialism and scientific
socialism. The former relied on precolonial African values and traditions as the
starting point to tackle African people’s needs and to build a new Africa. This
option rested on the idea that socialism is closed to African world vision. In this
respect, the Ujamaa Project launched by Nyerere is an illuminating illustration.
The latter form of African socialism puts emphasis on scientific objectivity and
considers socialism as a universal doctrine that is free from all cultural admixture.
National peculiarities are not important, as they are only a result of social praxis,
and in any case they are not contrary to the ideal of universal brotherhood.
Nkrumah can be mentioned as one of the leading figures in this respect. To
disentangle a bit this distinction, let us sketch the vision of African socialism
developed by these two statesmen: Nyerere and Nkrumah.
Nyerere is also known as “Mwalimu”, the Swahili term standing for
“Teacher”. He was the leader of the party 11 that led Tanzania to national
emancipation in 1961. Like many leaders of his generation, he became the first
president of this new country. His Tanzanian socialism, qualified as Ujamaa (the
Swahili concept for “family-hood”), drew on African culture and traditions. For
Nyerere, there was an African style of life, traditions and values in precolonial
Africa, particularly in Tanzania. These values and traditions must be regenerated
in order to build a new African nation-state free from the spirit of capitalism.
According to Hallen, traditional values of greatest significance for Nyerere were:
“that every member of society was expected to do work of some form as a
contribution to their own well-being and thereby that of the community, and for
that reason every one deserved to be rewarded sufficiently to satisfy their needs;
that the sense of being a community (ujamaa), on the part of the people was
9
See also: Coetzee and Roux (1998, 41-50), Derrida (2004), More (2004, 156-157),
Ramose (1999).
10
J. Schleimann.1963. Colloque sur les politiques de développement et les diverses voies
africaines vers le socialisme. In The Journal of Modern African Studies, 1, 242-248.
11
The Tanganyika African Union (TANU) was created in 1954. It became later «Chama
Cha Mapinduzi» (The Revolutionary Party).
conscious and was significant in terms of determining their relationship with and
regard for one another” (Hallen 2009, 97).
In Nyerere’s opinion, capitalism could destroy this humanitarian worldview
because of both its individualism and propensity for the exploitation of other
people. Nyerere is distrustful of theories that value class antagonism (capitalists
against workers, for example) and present this conflict as motivating force for
social change. For him, this way of thinking is not relevant to Africa (Tanzanian)
because there are very few capital owners, and subsequently majority of people
are subsistence farmers. Nyerere wanted an ideology that is pragmatic and
tailored for African context. He encapsulated his socialist project in One-party
rule, which he thought to be representative of African way of living.
Nkrumah also assumed the existence of precolonial African values. He
equally insisted on the opposition of these values to Western world vision, as he
considered them more communally than individually oriented. Subsequently, he
thought of capitalism as not able to bring development for African people. For
political reasons, he served both the masters at a time: capitalism and socialism.
Hallen notes in this respect: “Nkrumah was no overt enemy of the so-called West
but, obviously, he was no champion of it either since he had negotiated the
liberation of his country from European (British) rule. The Cold War between
East and West unquestionably had an effect on his international policies and
status. In certain respects he was forced to play both ends (East and West) against
the middle (himself and his country’s interests), eventually at some cost” (Hallen
2009, 96).12
Contrary to Nyerere, Nkrumah was more theoretically and a speculatively
inclined. For him, African cultural heritage must be systematized prior to all
usage and philosophical considerations. He insisted on African Consciencism that
he considered to be not a psychological attitude, but the “effect, the expression,
the articulation (…) of a people’s cultural predispositions at a particular point in
time. Once articulated (…), it can then be refined and explicitly instituted by
deliberate social and political programs” (Hallen 2009, 96-97. Hence, for him,
African socialism has “to be a formalized, (economically and politically)
institutionalized expression of indigenous humanitarian social and moral values.”
(Ibid.)
African socialism didn’t survive its founders. This disappearance doesn’t
imply the end of the search for a suited paradigm of social and political
organization. Many former defenders of socialism have recycled themselves
joining alternative trends of thought and critical of liberalism such as post-
colonial theory, ecology and sustainable development, global justice and debt
issue, intercultural dialogue, and so forth.
Pan-Africanism. Pan-Africanism originated in African Diaspora at the end of
the nineteenth century, and spread in Africa in the beginning of the twentieth
century. It relies on the premise that black people all over the world constitute a
single race; they have a common destiny and therefore they must unite to fight
against humiliation, injustice and discrimination inflected on them by the West.
The paternity of this thought is commonly attributed to Blyden. This movement
had many leaders, different philosophical interpretations and political strategies.
People such as Booker T. Washington (1856-1915), for example, considers that
12
See also : Appiah 1992, 158-172.
this solidarity has to begin with the sensitization and education of Blacks; for
Marcus Garvey (1887-1940), the emancipation of black people includes their
return to Africa. W.B. Du Bois (1868-1963) structured this movement giving to it
a theoretical frame and defining its objectives. He chaired the five first Pan-
African congresses.
The torch of Pan-Africanism was transmitted to African leaders thanks to the
support of G. Padmore (1903-1959). Nkrumah became the chief proponent of the
movement, sometimes to the detriment of the interests of his own country
(Appiah 1992, 158-172). He organized both the sixth and the seventh Pan-
African congresses in Ghana, Kumasi (1953) and Accra (1958). Several African
leaders also joined the movement such as Fanon, Diop, Sekou Touré, Modibo
Keita, to quote a few. For African Diaspora, racial solidarity aimed at the
rehabilitation of black people and the claim for their civil rights, while for African
leaders, this solidarity aimed at African emancipation. Two tendencies shaped
pan-Africanist movement in Africa: «maximalist» pan-Africanism and
«minimalist» pan-Africanism.
«Maximalist» pan-Africanism contests the division of Africa inherited from
the Conference of Berlin (1884-1885). It aims at the recomposition of African
geopolitics through the creation of a wide state structure susceptible to transform
Africa into a major economic, political and cultural level: the " United States of
Africa ". Nkrumah, Nasser, Modibo Keita, Sekou Touré were among defenders of
this tendency. «Maximalist» pan-Africanist project came up against two obstacles:
first, the resistence of former colonial powers who saw in this project an
infringement on their interests; secondly, the lacking support from the world
leading countries, such as the Soviet Union, China and the United States.
«Minimalist» pan-Africanism insists on the right of every African state to be
autonomous and sovereign. This tendency defends the intangibility of frontiers
inherited from colonization and it advocates for the principle of non-intervention
in the internal affairs of every African country. Houphouët-Boigny and Senghor
are representative of this trend which gave rise to the Organization of African
Unity (1963), which later became the African Union (2001).
The search for African unity on account of the idea of race has been a topic
of severe criticism. According to Appiah, for example, the definition of African
unity on such a basis follows Crummel’s world vision which claims both racial
purity and community. Taking a stand on the experience of Nazism, Appiah
considers this form of pan-Africanism to be a threat for common life and African
unity itself. For him, Africa should unite more on basis of common issues such as
ecological challenges, struggles against poverty and underdevelopment, than
around the idea of race (Appiah 1992, 180).
However, the concern for the rehabilitaion of African cultures remains a
preoccupation for many scholars and researchers on African studies: Appiah;
People such as Molefi Kete Asante and Kemi Seba lean on the intellectual legacy
of C.A. Diop to claim the cultural unity of Africa, while scholars such as Appiah
(1992; 2006), Karp and Masolo (2000), Eze (1997), Wirdu (1996), Wamba-dia-
Wamba (1994) and many more explore challenges such as democracy, African
cultural diversity and globalization.
African political landscape has dramatically changed in the two last decades of
the twentieth century due to factors such as the collapse of communist system, the
change of development aid policies by the international financiers and Western
countries, the disappearance of one party rule, the liberalization of African
economies (Mbembe 2005). This change originated new challenges for African
political philosophy; consequently, topics such as democracy, good governance,
cultural diversity, ecology, gender, peace, justice and reconciliation, have become
of major interest. This section explores three topics: democracy, African civil
society and African cultural diversity.
Conclusion
This paper explored the nature, features and trends of African political philosophy.
This philosophy is rooted in everyday life of African people, and it has as main
objectives the well-being of African populations, both the nature and
legitimization of power, as well as the search for a well-suited paradigm of social
organization. Topics analyzed included the question of negro-African identity and
solidarity, African revival and the building of modern African states. The struggle
against colonization put forward ideas of African emancipation and cultural
rehabilitation, particularly through discourses of negritude, African humanism,
African socialism and Pan-Africanism. Standing on the changes which occurred
at the end of the twentieth century, we examined new challenges including
democracy, human rights, cultural diversity, gender, sustainable development and
globalization. These challenges represent a long-term duty for African thinkers
who are called to get out of their ivory tower and join the common world,
assuming a permanent reflexive equilibrium between their philosophical
intuitions and constraints of people’s daily life, in order to bring successfully to
completion such a mission. The future of African depends on such a critical
attitude.
References