Choreographic Objects
Choreographic Objects
July, 2015
Thesis submitted in accordance with the requirements for the degree of
Doctor of Philosophy in Digital Media,
specialization: Production of Audiovisual and Interactive Content,
under the scientific supervision of Prof. Carla Fernandes, Ph.D.
Financial Support
This work is dedicated to the infinity of potentials reserved in life,
and to all those who committedly resist becoming disconnected from it.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
The present text synthesizes a multifarious research, which was to a great extent
marked by a growing indiscernibility between work and life. Not only formal contexts
of artistic and academic research have contributed to it, but also the many people with
whom this path was, in one way or another, shared, are too here present. The following
remarks are intended to manifest my deep appreciation for all those who have affected
and have been affected by the stream of forces moving me throughout this period.
I would like to thank Prof. Carla Fernandes—my supervisor—for her
unconditional support, despite all difficulties. I would like to thank the Transmedia
Knowledge Base for Performing Arts' team for allowing me to accompany their work. I
would like to thank the UT Austin|Portugal International Collaboratory for Emerging
Technologies (CoLab), for supporting this research. And I would like to thank the
Portuguese Foundation for Science and Technology (FCT), for having sponsored it. I
would like to thank Prof. Nik Haffner—director of the Inter-University Dance Centre
Berlin—for all the opportunities he has offered me. And I would like to thank all the
people at this school, for having had me around and allowing me to be part of the
adventure of their lives. I would like to thank Kattrin Deufert and Thomas Plischke—
artists and choreographers—for having invited me to work with them. I would like to
thank João Fiadeiro—artist, choreographer, researcher and friend—for the sympathy in
feeling, for the learning in management, and for the resonance in process. I would like
to thank the AND_Lab—Lisbon's Laboratory for Anthropology and Dance—for having
provided me with an honest context of work. I would like to thank Alex Baczynski-
Jenkins—dancer and friend—for all the adventures we have shared. I would like to
thank Ana Trincão—friend and housemate—for having eased up my life. I would like to
thank Diethild Meier—lover and friend—for having been there throughout the storm. I
would like to thank Urândia Aragão and David Leitão, for having provided me a cozy
home, whenever I needed. And, finally, I would like to thank my parents—Carlos and
Alice—for conserving some of my roots.
CHOREOGRAPHIC OBJECTS
ABSTRACT
KEYWORDS: Expanded Choreography, Process Philosophy, Dance and Technology,
Choreographic Knowledge, Digital Media, Transductive Thought.
RESUMO
PALAVRAS CHAVE: Coreografia Expandida, Filosofia do Processo, Dança e
Tecnologia, Conhecimento Coreográfico, Media Digitais,
Pensamento Transdutivo.
Esta tese tem por fim não só definir as principais características dos objectos
coreográficos, mas também determinar como pode o conhecimento coreográfico ser
expresso com novidade. Por um lado, porque todos os casos aqui estudados expressam
conhecimento por meios digitais, tais especulações serão enquadradas pelo “encontro
entre a dança e a tecnologia”. Por outro lado, porque a novidade resulta necessariamente
do desenvolvimento de processos, tais especulações serão enquadradas por uma série de
questões fundamentais da filosofia do processo.
O método de pesquisa aqui seguido é, sucintamente, um encontro em si mesmo.
Ao colocar a filosofia do processo em contacto com o encontro entre a dança e a
tecnologia este método problematiza as relações que potencialmente daqui resultam e,
com isto, estabelece as condições necessárias para que tais problemas sejam resolvidos
na forma de proposições. Neste sentido, o próprio encontro entre a dança e a tecnologia
é problemático. Nos casos aqui estudados, cada nova expressão de conhecimento afirma
a resolução de problemas na relação entre corpos dançantes e máquinas digitais. Da
perspectiva da filosofia de processo, tais expressões são soluções particulares relativas
aos problemas potenciais. A potência é assim entendida tanto enquanto condição
fundamental da novidade como enquanto capacidade geral de relação. Com isto, a
resolução de um problema corresponde sempre à expressão da sua potência na forma de
uma proposição. Isto não é nem indução nem dedução. É transdução.
Enquanto modo de pensamento, a transdução será aqui afirmada como
característica fundamental da transmissão coreográfica. Ou seja, para um objecto
coreográfico ser novo, necessita de ser transduzido juntamente com o meio em que o
seu conhecimento se formou. A transdução opera assim a passagem de um estado de
conhecimento a outro, mobilizando um meio potencial que afecta o que é sabido com o
que não se pode saber (i.e. as potências, porque são indeterminadas). Neste sentido, a
coreografia em si mesma não pode senão resultar de um encontro entre dança e
tecnologia. A coreografia estrutura o conhecimento (logos) do dançar (tekhné) de
maneira determinada e transmissível. Por isto mesmo, será proposto que os objectos
coreográficos são tanto diagramáticos como algorítmicos. Ou seja, mesmo antes de
serem expressos, estes objectos são estruturados em abstracto, i.e. diagramaticamente. E
podem apenas ser expressos em diferentes meios devido à iterabilidade da sua estrutura
(i.e. são algorítmicos). O digital coloca-se então como meio optimamente adequado à
expressão do conhecimento coreográfico. Não obstante, aqui, a questão da novidade
permanece: como entender as potências da coreografia digital? Ao seguir tal problema,
este estudo proporá que a computação algorítmica de ideias coreográficas é
necessariamente infectada por incomputabilidades, e que a novidade pode ser facilitada
com a saturação das relações entre estrutura e potência ou, por outras palavras, entre o
cognoscível e o incognoscível.
LIST OF CONTENTS
INTRODUCTION........................................................................................................1
Chapter 1 -A TOPOLOGICAL ENCOUNTER..........................................................26
1.1 -Multiplicities in Movement............................................................................27
1.2 -Creativity in Encounter...................................................................................37
Chapter 2 -SIMONDON ON INDIVIDUATION.......................................................50
2.1 -Ontogenesis.....................................................................................................51
2.2 -Physical Paradigm...........................................................................................58
2.3 -Transindividuation..........................................................................................64
2.4 -Analogical Knowledge...................................................................................70
2.5 -Networks.........................................................................................................76
Chapter 3 -CHOREOTECHNICS...............................................................................87
3.1 -Choreography's Excess...................................................................................88
3.2 -The Choreographic Object..............................................................................96
3.3 -Topological Continuity, Differential Expressivity........................................102
Chapter 4 -DIAGRAMMATIC IDEAS....................................................................112
4.1 -From Idea to Proposition...............................................................................113
4.2 -Individuating Choreo-Knowledge................................................................121
4.3 -Between Abstraction and Expression...........................................................131
Chapter 5 -ALGORITHMIC CHOREOGRAPHIES................................................149
5.1 -Diagramming Gesture...................................................................................150
5.2 -Gestural Bodies, Extended............................................................................160
Chapter 6 -DIGITAL POTENTIAL..........................................................................181
6.1 -Problems in Potential....................................................................................182
6.2 -Algorithmic Complexity...............................................................................191
6.3 -Object Orientation.........................................................................................201
6.4 -Process Orientation.......................................................................................213
6.5 -Thoughtful Character....................................................................................223
6.6 -Speculative Proposition................................................................................233
CONCLUSION.........................................................................................................241
LIST OF REFERENCES..........................................................................................253
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS....................................................................................260
LIST OF ABREVIATIONS
CT Creation Tool
GF Gesture Follower
KB Knowledge Base
MB Motion Bank
The recent years have witnessed a growing number of research projects that,
either stemming from the side of academic and scholarly work or from the side of
artistic practices and the various types of economy in which these exist, strive for
asserting choreographic knowledge in yet unexplored ways.1 This is a growth that can
be said to manifest a general intent of proliferation, an expansion towards a larger
diversity in practices, knowledge and networks, and towards a better adequacy of all of
these to the fast-paced changing economic environment. Together with the
establishment of a globalized, distributed and networked cognitive capitalism, the
production of choreographic knowledge has been changing towards novel forms of
expression. With this, not only have these projects been contributing to the overall and
ongoing expansion of choreographic practices, but they have also been expanding the
very notion of choreography.
1 A list of paradigmatic examples can be found at the online knowledge-base of the “ Motion Bank”
(http://motionbank.org/en/content/knowledge-base), a project which will be discussed in Section 5.2.
1
of tools that can be used in a generic capacity for both analysis and production” and as
“an expanded practice, a practice that is political in and of itself”. A statement made
against a background of knowledge fields2, which were summoned to set the conference
off to explore how “Situations, Movements, Objects …”, and all the more that the
ellipsis holds in potential, can express choreography beyond what choreographers
traditionally do.3
It is from the equation made here between choreography's expansion and its
politics that this study has proceeded. And not just in any way. For it is its contention
that such equation problematizes the affective conditions of knowledge production and
the effects of its circulation. Despite expanded choreography's proffered disassociation
from skill and craft, its instantiations necessarily implicate an epistemological
dimension in process. The assertion that choreography is no longer bounded to the
expression and reiteration of subjectivity can therefore be understood from the
viewpoint of knowledge's political dimension. A knowledge that is neither a stable
reality nor an immutable set of axioms, but rather an intricate dynamism of affects and
effects in the political realm of the social. A knowledge that, in sum, is the trans-
subjective resolution of a series of problems constitutive, in this case, of choreography.
2 Some of the conference's speakers were: performance theorist and practitioner Bojana Cvejić, art
historian Dorothea von Hantelmann, philosopher Graham Harman, curator Ana Janevski, dance
scholar and performance theorist André Lepecki, choreographer and performer Xavier Le Roy,
curator and theorist Maria Lind, dance researcher Isabel de Naverán, media theorist Luciana Parisi,
dramaturge and performer Goran Sergej Pristaš, choreographer and theoretician Mårten Spångberg,
sociologist Francisco Tirado, and curator and dance researcher Christophe Wavelet.
3 All quotes retrieved 24/03/2014, from the conference's webpage, at the Museu d’Art Contemporani
de Barcelona's website (www.macba.cat/en/expanded-choreography-situations).
4 At the choreographer's website one can read the following description of this exhibition:
“'Retrospective' by Xavier Le Roy is an exhibition conceived as a choreography of actions that will be
carried out by performers for the duration of the exhibition. These actions will compose situations
that inquire into various experiences about how we use, consume or produce time. This exhibition
employs retrospective as a mode of production rather than aiming to show the development of an
artist’s work over a period of time. It seeks to recast the material from the solo choreographies in
situations with live actions where the apparatuses of the theatre performance and the museum
exhibition intersect. Based on solo works by Xavier Le Roy created between 1994 and 2010, the
work unfolds in three time axes: the duration of the visit composed by each visitor, the daily basis of
labor time of 16 performers and the time of the growth of a new composition during the length of the
exhibition.” Retrieved 14/02/2014, from www.xavierleroy.com.
2
choreographic knowledge. In this sense, “Retrospective” can be said to be a sort of
performative knowledge base, one that is charged with potentials belonging to the
choreographer's work and that, instead of foreclosing the experience of the work with a
predetermined set of definitions, allows for these potentials to resolve into expressions
explicitly determined by the political conditions of their context of occurrence.
With “Retrospective”, Le Roy proposes different ways for the memory of some
of his previous works (notably, a series of solos) to be reactivated. Not for re-enacting
any sort of identity proper to each work, but for allowing these works to be rediscovered
and, ultimately, known anew. In “Retrospective”, what is exhibited together with some
documental registers of Le Roy's first performances, are sixteen performers to whom the
knowledge of these works has been transmitted. Each of them is then capable of re-
enacting the potentials of what they know and, together with the visitors, discover what
choreography can do.5 For the duration of the exhibition, the performers' remember Le
Roy's works by conversing with visitors, by re-enacting scores and performing dances,
by showing artifacts related with the work, and other actions of this kind. Perhaps
precisely because of being like a performative knowledge base, “Retrospective” has
been argued by dance and technology scholar Johannes Birringer to be an exhibition
that epitomizes the principles of expanded choreography. In his words: “this exhibition
proposed to investigate new discourses specific to dance/choreography, but also to the
curatorial remit, challenging us to connect a body of work to research processes and
reinterpretation-as-production, i.e. approaching specific structures and strategies of
performance disconnected from subjectivist bodily expression, style and representation
– re-transforming them from a set of protocols or tools used in order to produce
something predetermined (a dance) to an open cluster of tools that can be used in a
5 This question, “What can choreography do?”, was taken up by choreographer and theoretician Petra
Sabisch as a guideline to write the book “Choreographing Relations: Practical Philosophy and
Contemporary Choreography, in the Works of Antonia Baehr, Gilles Deleuze, Juan Dominguez, Félix
Guattari, Xavier Le Roy and Eszter Salamon”. “Rather then delimiting the field of choreography to a
definition of what choreography is – definition which then functions as prescriptive exclusion of that
which choreography can also be, this book attempts to stretch ontology to the capacity of
choreography, which is expressed in the practical question: what can choreography do? By shifting
the focus from an inventory of the empirically given to the potential of choreography, a potential
which encompasses the capacity of creating new relations, a stable demarcation of the object of
choreography can be deviated from. This is a key aspect to an onto-ethical agenda of choreography:
to unfold with precision that which choreography actually does as a can-do-determination of what
choreography is. The question what can choreography do thus opposes the predetermination of
choreographic operations and their generalization into a static and merely actual image of
choreography's ontology. A consideration of the ontological modes of existence of choreography
requires an analysis of the specific procedures of choreographies whilst encompassing,
simultaneously, the genetic conditions through which their 'doing' comes into being and provides new
options. Depriving the ontology of choreography of the ethical aspect of what can choreography do
means to subtract from choreography the power to let new relations emerge and to divest from
philosophy the capacity to explain the conditions of the new.” (2011, p. 8).
3
generic capacity for both public observation/analysis and production” (2013, p. 10).
That for Birringer the generic capacity of choreography for analysis and
production is public should be understood as a recognition of this exhibition's capacity
to individuate knowledge in a trans-subjective and processual way. In other words, it
individuated instances of knowledge that were not given in advance, but which instead
resulted from potentials and possibilities that could only be activated under the
condition of a political relationship between all implicated agents (including, of course,
choreographer, performers and visitors). Together with expanded choreography's
disconnection “from subjectivist bodily expression, style and representation”, what is
put at stake is the very substance of choreography. As with the question “What can
choreography do?”, the focus here moves from a substantialist and ontologically
deterministic approach to choreography (i.e. choreography being this or that closed set
of unchanging attributes) to an exploration of how, with each event, choreography can
become not only what is known to be capable of becoming but also what cannot be
known in advance.
Implicitly, it is here being suggested that the political dimension of any technical
process whatsoever—including choreographic ones—is a necessary condition for the
constitution of knowledge. In other words, it is being suggested that the political
dimension of affect and relation precludes knowledge from being only individual (i.e.
subjective or objective) and instead introduces at its very definition a transindividual
(i.e. trans-subjective and transobjective) dimension. The political should thus be here
understood as corresponding to conditions which allow for the formation of a
transindividual whose knowledge is characteristically processual. A knowledge that is
not given in advance, completely, but that corresponds instead to a collective field of
potentials from which both reactivations and novel experiences can emerge.
4
affective reality of relation. This reality does not require pre-constituted subjects and
objects, for it corresponds to process itself. Process, here defined as a dynamic whole
where virtuality verges towards actuality and actuality towards virtuality, can very well
occur without any sort of cognitive apprehension. The emergence of correlated subjects
and objects in a process of transindividuation is but one way for the latter to be realized.
In this one way, knowledge individuates amidst the excess of process's creative
potentials. It cannot but be embedded in the field of creative potentials from which it
results and in relation to which it remains; not as an unchanging reality, but rather as the
dynamic unity of subjective and objective standpoints. Once this unity is disrupted by
the excessive forces of process, knowledge transforms. And, together with it, so do its
subjects and objects (which are just circumstantial perspectives of one particular
relationship attained by the ongoing dynamisms of process). Hence, it is from process's
perspective that both subjects and objects must be tackled. For they are in process,
embedded in it, rather than the opposite. This is their political reality.
Simondon's philosophy has been a guideline for the inquiry synthesized in this
text. It has offered a conceptual framework to approach choreography as a system of
potentials and to inquire into the processes by means of which choreographic
knowledge is constituted. In contrast to other theoretical standpoints, such as idealism
and realism, Simondon's theory of individuation offers the possibility of taking that
which most fundamentally defines expanded choreography—i.e. potentiality as such—
to be a necessary condition for the constitution of knowledge (which is also the
transindividual co-constitution of its subjects and objects). As such, it will be argued
here that the political transindividuation of choreographic knowledge can only be
understood together with a constitutive field of potentials, i.e. a field that pervades
individuals to the point of being the very ground of their relation.
5
To think the expansion of choreography potentially corresponds to thinking how
the different contexts where knowledge is produced and transmitted condition these
same processes. It is to think how a field of relations transports potentials that, though
undetermined, allow for knowledge to emerge in determinate ways. Xavier Le Roy's
“Retrospective” can be situated at the intersection of different contexts where
choreography has been expanding. There is the context for which re-enactment is only
one possible designation—the re-enactment of previous performance art works—, there
is the context of the encounter between dance and the museum—by means of which
dance is brought into spaces traditionally dedicated to the visual arts—, and there is the
context of remediation6—the one making use of media other than performance to
convey choreographic knowledge. In each of these contexts, choreography is reaching
beyond what is known to be and towards the constitution of novel instances of
knowledge. In many cases these contexts overlap: re-enactments have occurred at art
galleries but they also have occurred at theatres; theatres on their turn have received the
occurrence of durational events, the character of which is closer to art exhibitions than
to traditional theatrical formats; the remediation of choreographic knowledge has been
used both to set up exhibitions and to create theatrical performances; in turn, both
exhibitions and theatrical performances have sourced the creation of remediated
archives and transmedia knowledge-bases. It is against this background that this study
must be situated. It is in relation to this variety of expansions that it must be thought.
For if it can be read as a thesis, then it is one about the transformative capacities of
choreography. In order to facilitate this, a commentary on each of these contexts will
now follow.
If seen as a context that has been growing throughout the last ten to fifteen years,
the wave of re-enactments in dance and choreography can be pinpointed as having had a
marking beginning when, in 1994, the French constellation of dance-related artists
designated as Quatuor Albrecht Knust7 performed what were by then somewhat
forgotten choreographies, notably by Doris Humphrey and Kurt Jooss. In this particular
case, there were scores written in Labanotation8 that allowed for the works to be re-
6 To name this context in such a way is to frame it under the auspices of new media theory, as this has
been formulated by Jay David Bolter and Richard Grusin in their famous book “Remediation:
understanding new media” (1998).
7 The Quatuor Albrecht Knust included, at different moments of its life span, artists such as Christophe
Wavelet, Jerome Bel, Xavier LeRoy, Boris Charmatz, Emmanuelle Hyunh, Anne Collod, Dominique
Brun, Simon Hecquet, Martha Moore, Matthieu Doze and Alain Buffard. Notably, Albrecht Knust is
the name of a renowned German dancer, choreographer and Labanotation specialist, who lived
between 1896 and 1978.
8 As explained by Labanotation specialist Ann Hutchinson Guest, “Labanotation, or Kinetography
Laban, is the system of recording movement originated by Rudolf Laban In the 1920's. By this
6
incarnated and performed again (Burt, 2004). By the same token, the Quatuor
reconstructed, in 1996, both Steve Paxton's “Satisfyin' Lover” (1967) and Yvonne
Rainer's “Continuous Project Altered Daily” (1970), and finally, in 2000, three versions
of “L'Après midi d'un faune”, outsourced from Vaslav Nijinsky's choreographic
notations of the piece, in a single work titled “....d'un Faune (éclats)”. From this
moment onwards, a series of seminal examples engaged in reactivating iconic
choreographic works from dance's history can be found. Drawing from Quatuor
Albrecht Knust's experience, the French choreographer and dancer Boris Charmatz has
curated, in 2000, an open air event at Annency, in the French Alps, named “Ouvrée –
artistes en alpage” (in the guise, it could be said, of the same kind of event that Rudolf
Von Laban used to organize at Monte Verita). Here, pieces such as “Feierlicher Kanon”
(1933) by Grete and Harry Pierenkämper, and “Die Welle” (1935) by Albrecht Knust,
were too reinterpreted with the aid of Labanotation scores. In 2001, dancer and by now
most influential British-German artist Tino Seghal, performed an “Untitled”9 piece that,
while being announced as a “museum of dance”, instead of artifacts and concrete
objects, exhibited movements and gestures from iconic western dance styles of the
twentieth century. More recently, in 2008, French dancer Anne Collod, one of the
members of the Quatuor Albrecht Knust, dedicated herself to the remaking of “Parades
and Changes”, a 1965's piece by Anna Halprin. From the same year, two other pieces
produced in Germany are worth noting: one is Ecuadorian dancer Fabian Barba’s
“Schwingende Landschaft”, a reinterpretation of Mary Wigman’s seven solo pieces from
1929; the other is German dancer and choreographer Martin Nachbar’s “Urheben
Aufheben”, a revival of Dore Hoyer 1962-64's dance series “Affectos Humanos”. Even
more recently, in 2012, Spanish dancer and choreographer Olga de Soto realized a
scientific method all forms of movement, ranging from the simplest to the most complex, can be
accurately written. Its usefulness to dancers is obvious. The system has also been successfully applied
t o every field in which there is the need to recor d motions o f the human body – anthropology,
athletics, and physiotherapy, to name just a few.” (1977, p. 6). Further, scholar Natalie Lehoux has
recently described it in the following way: “Labanotation is documented on vertical staffs that are
read from bottom to top [...]. The staffs are made up of three lines that are divided by a centreline, to
indicate the left and right side of the body. This results in a visual representation of the symmetry of
the body in which each column of the staff is reserved for a specific body part. Information pertaining
to the time, direction, level and specific body part, which perform movement, are contained within a
single Labanotation symbol [...]. This is identified by the particular shape, shading and size of each
symbol. Hutchinson Guest (1977) tells us that such an economy of information cannot be found in
other notation systems. Labanotation represents the duration of movement through the length of its
symbols that is proportional to the time it takes to perform. The design of a system that embodies
elements of time in this manner eliminates the need for a visual reference to a musical score
alongside the movement notation.” (2013, p. 162).
9 It is worth noting that this was the last work Tino Sehgal created for theatre before he moved into
visual arts. Moreover, recently (twelve years after), this piece was presented in the form of three
different solos performed by dancers Andrew Hardwidge, Frank Willens and Boris Charmatz.
7
research-creation titled “Débords: Reflections on The Green Table”, which, as the name
indicates, took Kurt Jooss's piece as its focus of concern.
Other curatorial initiatives of this sort, such as conferences and symposia, but
also theatrical programmes dedicated to the general themes of re-enactment and the
archive in contemporary dance and performance, can be listed as follows: the
“re.act.feminism” curatorial project, which started in 2009 with an exhibition at the
Akademie der Künste, in Berlin, and continued as a “performing archive, a growing
archive and exhibition project on feminism and performance art travelling through
Europe, from 2011 to 2013”12; the symposium “Archive/Practice”, which took place at
the Dance Archive in Leipzig, in 2009; also in the same year, the “Re-constructions and
Re-imaginations” event at the Performance Space in New York; the research project
“Performing the Archive: The Future of the Past”, hosted from 2009 to 2012 by the
University of Bristol Theatre Collection’s Live Art and focused on developing “the
interrelationship and interactivity between the archives and the communities of
practitioners and scholars: to extend how academics and artists use documents of
performance to inflect and inspire their own particular concerns” 13; the 2010's
8
“Re:Move” festival at the Kaai Theater in Brussels, dedicated to “presenting performers
who make transmitting or reconstructing dance the subject of their production” 14; the
“Re-mix” cycle, at the Komuna Warsawa, in Warsaw, which ran from 2010 to 2012, and
which “consisted of new productions that refer to classic works, primarily of theatre and
dance, but also literature and film”15; and more recently, in 2013, the “Sacre 100”
festival, at the Hebbel am Ufer theatre, in Berlin, exclusively dedicated to restagings of
Les Ballets Russes' production “The Rite of Spring”.
Some of the works presented at the “Re:Move” festival are as marking to the
context of choreographic re-enactments as the ones already listed. Some notable works
are: Xavier Le Roy's restaging of Igor Stravinski's orchestral work “The Rite of Spring”,
which instead of reviving Nijinsky's choreography, allowed for the choreographer
himself to dance to the music as if he was conducting an orchestra; Boris Charmatz's
“Flip Book”, a dance performance made from a series of photos included in the book
“Merce Cunningham: Fifty Years”, by David Vaughn; British dancer and choreographer
Rachel Krische's re-adaptation of a solo by Deborah Hay; and French choreographer
Jérôme Bel's biographical staging of dancer Lutz Förster's experiences while working
with Pina Bausch.
As these references suggest, some choreographers have been busy with dance
repertoires in a consistent and iterative way. Beyond the already mentioned projects by
Xavier Le Roy and Boris Charmatz, Jerome Bel has been an important figure in what
regards the staging of dance history. In a series of pieces dedicated to the self-
presentation of remarkable performers, Bel has managed to provide the audiences with
insights into the singular life of dancers. Notable examples are: “Véronique Doisneau”,
commissioned from Bel by the Paris Opera in 2004 (where the ballet dancer with the
same name tells the audience stories from her dance career); “Isabel Torres”, a show in
the guise of the previous one, but with the Brazilian dancer; “Pichet Klunchun &
Myself”, a dialogue between Bel and the traditional Thai dancer Pichet Klunchun; the
already mentioned “Lutz Forster” show; and “Cédric Andrieux”, a solo piece for and
with Lyon Opera's dancer Cédric Andrieux, who danced for a long time with the Merce
Cunningham's dance company.
9
solo dance from Deborah Hay. She guided and coached them in the performance of the
solo during an 11-day period in a residency setting. At the conclusion of the residency
each participant signed a contractual agreement to a daily solo practice of the new piece,
for a minimum of three months before their first public performance.”16 Rachel Krische
was one of these dancers. She learned from Hay the solo “The Swimmer”, which she
presented at the“Re:Move” festival.17
This list of initiatives, from artistic projects to curatorial ones, is not intended to
be comprehensive of the context of choreographic re-enactments. It has the sole purpose
of demonstrating the large investments that have been recently made by the dance
community to deal with its own history. Another perspective that reflects this great
investment regards theoretical practices and scholarly work. The context of re-
enactments has been extensively discussed by scholars such as Gabriela Brandstatter
(2000), Diana Taylor (2003), Myriam van Imschoot (2005), Rebecca Schneider (2011),
Inge Baxmann (2007), André Lepecki (2010) Amelia Jones and Adrian Heathfield
(2012), amongst others. Both from this perspective and from the perspective of artistic
research, re-enactment is only one possible designation for this context. In fact, the
variety of procedures used by artists to activate past choreographies is great and many
different approaches can be depicted in them. Reactivation, re-performance,
reinterpretation, revisitation, remaking, revival, restaging, reformulation, resetting,
reappropriation, retrospective, retransmission, retranslation, reconstruction,
reimagination, reactualization, reproduction, remix, and so on, are all possible notions
for understanding what these artists and initiatives have been doing and how.
Importantly, all these notions can be said to share an archaeological character. All of
them perform the archaeology of choreographic sites, a methodological umbrella that
allows for artists, theoreticians and institutions to not only bring into the present what
has been generated in the past, but also to assure that such reactivation is to some extent
performative.
The second context mentioned above regards the encounter between dance and
the museum. In a way, many of the examples already mentioned fit into this category.
The fact that Tino Sehgal conceived his 2001's “Untitled” piece as a “museum of dance”
can be seen as corresponding to the same approach that later took him to develop an
10
influential series of “situations” for art galleries. Sehgal, who studied dance and
economy, has not ceased imprinting in his own artistic work the mark of a
choreographic thought. Furthermore, the fact that the context of re-enactments is
fundamentally based on an archaeological drive, one that is engaged in creating the
necessary tools, methods and dispositifs for transducing choreographic knowledge from
the past into the present, attests its museological character. It attests its attunement to
methods of excavation and exhibition, which are proper to the museological drive.18
Insofar as the encounter between dance and the museum shows in the latter are the re-
enactments of the former, both this context and the one of re-enactments are to a large
extent inextricable from one another.
A most outstanding example of how these two contexts conflate with one another
can be found not in a museum of dance but in a “Dancing Museum”, the project
initiated with Boris Charmatz's uptaking of Rènnes's Choreographic Centre, in France.
This is not a museum where artifacts are exhibited. It is rather one that exhibits the
movements of dance, to the point of itself dancing. The character of this project, and of
what is being her designated as the encounter between dance and the museum, is well
conveyed in some passages Charmatz's “Manifesto for a Dancing Museum”. In it, the
choreographer and curator writes: “We are in an exciting era in which museography is
opening itself up to ways of thinking and technologies which are enabling something
completely different to emerge rather than simply having exhibitions of remnants, faded
costumes, models of stage settings, and rare photographs of productions. We are at a
time in history where a museum can be alive and inhabited as much as a theatre, can
include a virtual space, and offer a contact with dance that can be at the same time
practical, aesthetic and spectacular. We are at a time in history where a museum in no
way excludes precarious movements, nor nomadic, ephemeral, instantaneous ones. We
are at a time in history where a museum can modify BOTH preconceived ideas about
museums AND one’s ideas about dance. Because we haven’t the slightest intention of
creating a dead museum, it will be a living museum of dance. The dead will have their
place, but among the living. They will be held by the living, brandished at arm’s
length.”19
All in all, this is a plea for the potentials of knowledge, i.e. for the conditional
18 Here, I'm thinking of this museological drive as an archival drive—the museum as archive—, a
dynamic dispositif of enunciation whereby specific regimes of visibility are conveyed. For more on
the archive as a dispositif of enunciation see page 91.
19 The full Manifesto can be downloaded from www.borischarmatz.org/sites/borischarmatz.org/files/im
ages/manifesto_dancing_museum100401.pdf.
11
basis of novelty in the shared ground of the political. The “Dancing Museum” is a site
of transindividuation. It is a site where the subjects and the objects of knowledge
emerge from processual and political conditions. It is a site where knowledge can
emerge without being predetermined by a given model or by images of what it could
possibly be like. The very conflation of dance with the museum, in the processual
project of the “Dancing Museum”, blurs the distinction between the two to the point that
dance cannot result but from an archaeological endeavour and the museum cannot be
but the very process by means of which the memory of the past is made active in the
present. The conflation of the two puts things into movement. By mobilizing the politics
of dance, it makes of the “Dancing Museum” a political movement for dancing
knowledge.
Recently (June-July, 2014), the “Dancing Museum” was a focus at the festival
“Foreign Affairs”, in Berlin. In its program featured some examples of how the
“Dancing Museum” is realizing its manifesto. It is enough mentioning two: the “Expo
Zéro” and the “20 Dancers for the XX Century”. The latter, as the name indicates,
consists of twenty dancers who, individually, “perform, recall, appropriate, and transmit
solo works of the last century that were originally conceived or performed by some of
the most significant modernist and postmodernist artists, dancers, and choreographers.
Each performer presents his or her own museum of sorts, wherein the body becomes the
primary museological container and object.”20. On its turn, the “Expo Zéro” “is an
exhibition without works: there are no photos, no sculptures, no videos, and no
installations. Zero things, no stable object. There are, instead, artists. Spaces occupied
by the gestures, by the bodies, by the stories and by the dances that each artist might
think of.”21 Both projects not only exhibit dance but, like LeRoy's “Retrospective”, act
as performative knowledge bases. They convey the necessary conditions for
choreographic knowledge to be discovered anew, time and again.
The encounter between dance and the museum can be traced back to a series of
exhibitions that, in contrast to Charmatz's “Dancing Museum”, have shown performance
by means of objects. Notable examples are the exhibition “Outside the Frame:
Performance and the Object”, at the Cleveland Centre for Contemporary Art in Ohio, in
1994, and the exhibition “Out of Actions: Between Performance and the Object, 1949–
1979”, at the Museum of Contemporary Arts in Los Angeles, in 1998. The emphasis on
20 Retrieved 24/10/2014, from the website of the Museum of Modern Art of New York, where this
exhibition has also been hosted (http://www.moma.org/visit/calendar/events/18898).
21 Retrieved 24/10/2014, from the “Dancing Museum's” website (http://www.museedeladanse.org/fr/arti
cles/expo-zero).
12
the relation between performance and objects that these exhibitions' names indicate is
somewhat telling. For if one considers the transient character of performative events and
its resistance to the requirements of traditional museological exhibitions, according to
which, for anything to be exhibited, it must persist throughout the exhibition's duration,
then performance itself must become permanent, that is, it must be expressed in ways
determined not by its own bias but rather by the bias of the context of its presentation. It
is, of course, in reaction to this exercise of power of the museum over performance that
a project such as the “Dancing Museum” stands up as an alternative. Notwithstanding,
these exhibitions are a link between the conflation of dance with the museum and the
context previously referred to as the one of remediation.
From this standpoint, the subject of this study can be now clarified:
“Choreographic Objects” correspond to the potentials that certain political conditions
have to individuate choreographic knowledge. This individuation can result from
learning how to move across a room full of suspended rings (the very disposition and
size of which limits the possibilities of movement and its quantitative range) or from
learning a complex choreographic pattern by means of a choreographic score. In any
22 Namely, Tania Bruguera, Rosemary Butcher, William Forsythe, Dan Graham, Isaac Julien, Mike
Kelley, Xavier le Roy, Mårten Spångberg, Wayne McGregor, Robert Morris, Bruce Nauman, La
Ribot, Franz West, Lygia Clark, and the OpenEnded Group with Wayne McGregor.
23 Retrieved 24/10/2014, from http://move.southbankcentre.co.uk/microsite.
13
case, the individuation of choreographic knowledge corresponds here to the
transmission of potentials and possibilities of movement. Choreographic objects allow
both for a choreographer to express thoughts and for a dancer to learn how to move
accordingly. Choreographic objects will thus be argued to correspond to the vectorial
arrangement of forces by means of which what is potential in thought, i.e. in a
choreographic thought, is transmitted to bodies capable of learning anew how they can
move.
Here implied is the fact that an object can be both concrete, such as the ones
exhibited at the art gallery, and abstract, such as the virtual image of a choreographed
dance. Inasmuch as a choreographic object must be imagined before being expressed, its
expressions necessarily implicate its abstractions. The actual determination of a
choreographic object requires that the concepts of the understanding regarding a
determinate arrangement of ideas are transposed, from their virtual and abstract reality,
to the concrete reality of material expressions. Notwithstanding, in order to exist, the
choreographic object does not require concretization, it can exist solely in abstraction.
The fact that one can remember a dance without recourse to external supports attests the
abstract autonomy of a choreographic object. But insofar as expression brings the
fuzziness of ideas into a higher degree of determination, it is a fundamental condition
for the transmission of choreographic ideas between bodies. From abstraction to
abstraction, necessarily through expression.
It is from the perspective of process itself that this study will approach the
excessive and transindividual character of choreographic objects. Choreography will be
considered as a system of individuation where abstractions and expressions dynamically
relate to one another, i.e. where what most fundamentally defines it is both its
14
processual character and its transductive potential. Following from this definition, this
study will proceed by inquiring into the dynamisms of choreography. It will explore
how transduction operates in particular choreographies and how in fact both
abstractions and expressions exist in such dynamic system of transindividuation. The
whole study can be said to consist in various approaches to the processual character of
choreographic objects. It both iterates the concern with the ingression of undetermined
potentials into determinate instances of knowledge and follows the relation between
abstract and concrete structures in order to provide a means of understanding how the
transduction of potentials is conditioned by what is given in process. All in all, it tries to
tackle in different rounds how novelty exists in process and how it exceeds the
determination of any object whatsoever.
The concern with novelty in choreographic processes has been here approached
under the general frame of process philosophy, of which some of the main references
are the works of Henri Bergson, Alfred N. Whitehead, Gilbert Simondon, Gilles
Deleuze, Felix Guattari, Brian Massumi, Erin Manning, Stamatia Portanova and
Luciana Parisi. It should be noted that the novelty here at stake does not concern the one
that the art markets came to praise as the very substance of their capitalistic
development. Instead of being understood as what result from a theological capacity
that the artist performs in the process of making art, it should be viewed as what results
from a process that, far from being under control or serving artistic intents, manifests
the very powers of its more-than-human dimensions. Therefore, it is not the novelty that
comes to be recognized as such according to a set of historically situated values, but the
novelty that allows for any development to occur, be this the development of processes
that only create what is already known or the development of processes from which the
unrecognisable itself emerges. Novelty is only another name for potentiality and
creativity. This study should be viewed in accordance with such equation. Novelty
doesn't regard the result of artistic production, but rather the infection of processes by
undetermined potentials. It is the manifestation of an immanent capacity of processes to
drive change and continuously reconfigure the conditions of their own development.
Novelty as such is the antithesis of commodification. It is the anarchy within all that
doesn't rest. Many writings of the authors just mentioned conform to this. This is the
ground that this work shares with them.
To say that this study iterates concerns or that it inquires in different rounds is
saying that it proceeds by trials where what is at stake is the encounter between some
key notions of process philosophy and a series of choreographic examples. All the
15
choreographic objects discussed in this study resulted from interdisciplinary research
projects. All of them correspond to the individual resolution of problems in technical
individuations committed to assert choreography in the form of objects. Throughout this
study, the references to the research projects in case will help to provide glimpses into
the conditions of emergence of the choreographic objects discussed. For now, it matters
only to indicate that the latter are: “Improvisation Technologies, a Tool for the
Analytical Dance Eye”, a collection of choreographic objects meant to be used as
modular tools for the composition of choreographed dances, devised by choreographer
William Forsythe and published in the form of a CD-ROM (1999) by the Centre for Art
a n d Media (ZKM) i n Karlsruhe; “Double Skin | Double Mind” (2004-2010), a
choreographic object devised by choreographer Emio Greco together with dramaturge
Pieter C. Scholten and expressed in different ways, such as a dance workshop, an
interactive installation and a CD-ROM; the choreographic objects of the “Motion Bank”
project (2009-2013), namely, “Synchronous Objects, for One Flat Thing Reproduced”
by William Forsythe, “No Time to Fly” by Debora Hay, “Seven Duets” by Jonathan
Burrows and Matteo Fargion, and “Two” by Bebe Miller and Thomas Hauert; and
finally the choreographic objects of the “Reactor for Awareness in Motion” (2011-...), a
research project of the Yamaguchi Centre for the Arts intended to develop software and
hardware tools for dance creation and education.
The encounter between some key notions of process philosophy and a series of
choreographic objects is not here intended to provide an interpretation of the latter with
the notions of the former. It is rather intended to create a field of tensions by means of
which a whole other level of individuation is to be attained. In this sense, this text is a
synthetic resolution of the tensions that this encounter has engendered. It is by
confronting the ideas of process philosophy with a series of choreographic ideas that
this study will proceed. It will strive to posit the problems of this encounter and bring
them into some sort of resolute determination, i.e. into the point at which possible cases
of solution can be proposed, if not as definite answers, at least as indicative orientations.
16
in its regard is its history. For if choreography can be, to a great extent, equated with the
encounter between dance and writing,24 then it can be said that, since the moment in
which it appeared as an “apparatus of capture” (Lepecki, 2007), choreography didn't
stop making use of technological modes of retention, creating mnemonic artifacts for
the transmission and remembrance of dances. Out of the three, it is perhaps this one
context that is most endemic to choreography. But despite its historical character, it
matters here to approach it as a specific mode of expanding choreography. This is not to
say that choreography's history doesn't matter. It is in contrast to and in relation with its
history that choreography's expansion can be best tackled. For this reason,
choreography's history will be briefly discussed throughout this study, specially in
regard to the problematic relation between the excess of the dancing body and the
limitations of writing. The expansive remediations of choreography should be thought
as relaying this relation and as striving to deal with its problematic structure in new
ways, i.e. to explore novel solutions for an old problem. Such capacity does not come
without an activation of technology's potentials. The remediated expansion of
choreography proceeds by interweaving its technological potentials with the potentials
of a broader field of technical transindividuation. The very notion of choreographic
expansion finds in this interweaving its fundament. It is in relation to the potentials of
technology at large that choreography enhances its capacity to transform and differ from
itself.
The particular cases approached in this study are not the only examples of
choreography's remediated expansion. In order to provide a glimpse into the
contemporary context of research-creation where the remediation of choreographic
knowledge is a main focus, it is worth mentioning a series of other projects. One of
these projects is the “Enhancing Choreographic Objects” (EChO). Co-directed by social
anthropologist James Leach and dance and new media scholar Scott DeLahunta at the
University of Aberdeen, this was a research-creation project running in between 2012
and 2013 and intending to bring into collaboration scholars from various fields, digital
artists, exhibition and performance venues, and the Wayne McGregor | Random Dance
Company (WM|RD). This collaboration resulted in a variety of things: the dance
performance “Atomos”, which premièred at Sadler's Wells in London; the exhibition
“Thinking with the body: Mind and movement in the work of Wayne McGregor |
Random Dance”, which took place at the Wellcome Collection, in London as well; the
construction of a choreographic software named “Choreographic Language Agent”
24 See reference to the beginnings of choreography in the European Renascence on page 89.
17
(CLA); the digital installation “Becoming”, which was created with the CLA software
and featured at the afore mentioned exhibition; and the “Mind and Movement –
Choreographic Thinking Tools” publication, a “choreographic resource [...] designed to
develop students' personal imagination skills in order to enhance the creation of new
and original dance movement”25. All of these outcomes can be seen as choreographic
objects. But specially those expressed with writing, be this digital or not, were said to
provide “insights into the valuable knowledge that choreographers and dancers create
when they investigate form and structure through movement in the context of making
dances. The result is that 'choreographic thinking' is becoming available not only for the
purpose of educating audiences, but also in ways that scientists and philosophers can
study, architects and designers can utilize, and other artists can draw upon.”26
18
the “Transmedia Knowledge Base for Performing Arts” (TKB). Coordinated by
cognitive linguist Carla Fernandes at the New University of Lisbon, from 2010 to 2013,
the TKB was “a transdisciplinary project at the crossings of cognitive linguistics, video
annotation, performing arts documentation and new media technologies, [aimed] at
building a dynamic “Knowledge-Base” (KB) to host different kinds of working
materials, annotated documents and complete pieces of all interested authors in sharing
their creative processes […].”28 With such intent, two software tools were developed: a
video annotation software for tablet computers called “Creation Tool” (CT) and the KB,
a web based platform conceived to host contents of various sorts and specially those
created with annotation softwares such as the CT or the ELAN29. In the frame of this
project, what is perhaps the closest expression to an object capable of conveying
choreographic knowledge, is the annotation made on the video registers of Rui Horta's
choreographic piece “Set Up” by a group of linguists.30 This choreography has been
dissected into sections and categories where each remarkable event is indexed and
commented upon. In this way, the implicit knowledge of a complex choreographic work
was meant to become more explicit.
In this guise, the “Siobhan Davies Archive” project, dedicated to the work of the
choreographer and co-ordinated both by her and by dance scholar Sarah Whatley, in a
collaboration between the Siobhan Davies Dance and the Coventry University, “began
in January 2007, with the aim of bringing together all of the materials and
documentation associated with Davies' choreographies into a single collection.” In
regard to the transmission of choreographic knowledge, this archive holds what have
been called “Kitchens”—“prototyped new presentations of the digital objects”—for
Davies' choreographies “Bird Song” and “In Plain Clothes”. These are digital objects
that bring together the “'ingredients' organised according to their role in the making or
the 'cooking' of a work”.31
Perhaps it is not by chance that all these projects, and the ones to be further
discussed, have explored in unprecedented ways the possibilities that digital
programming offers to the creation of choreographic objects. On the one hand, the
multimedia capacities of the digital domain allow for hosting and interrelating the
different knowledge fields brought together by these projects. On the other hand,
19
inasmuch as digital programming is capable of automating procedures, it can simulate
creative processes, being as such a most suitable platform for conveying the
transduction of choreographic knowledge and stimulating learning. The coincidence
between the capacities of both choreographic and digital objects has been a guideline
for this study. Because, if in a first approach the two can be said to be fundamentally
different, at a closer look the transductive capacities of choreographic objects can be
addressed to the determination of ideas, in the same way as the algorithms of digital
programming can. In fact, to say that the coincidence between choreographic objects
and digital objects has guided this study is to say that its main problem resulted from
bringing into relation the notion of diagrammatic ideas and the notion of algorithmic
procedures. Both these notions can be said to characterize choreographic objects: for a
dance to become choreographed, an idea of coordinated movement needs to acquire
determination, i.e. to acquire a structure that is both knowable and transmittable. The
structure of an idea is its diagram, it “maps the interrelation of relations” (Massumi,
1992, p. 16) necessary for a determinate field of potentials to participate in the
individuation of a corresponding expression. As it will be argued here, the
choreographic object itself cannot be considered without the dynamic processes by
means of which an idea and its expressions are related. And precisely because of this,
i.e. because of the fact that the same diagrammatic arrangement of ideas can give birth
to a series of different expressions (such as the many results of the EChO project, all of
which express differently the same choreographic object or, in other words, the same
assemblage of choreographic ideas), the choreographic object must be acknowledged to
have an iterative character, i.e. to be capable of resuming itself in accordance with a
determinate model of transduction. Which brings us to one of the definitions of
choreographic objects used throughout this study: a choreographic object is a “model of
potential transition from one state to another in any space imaginable” (Forsythe, 2008,
pp. 5 – 6). The fact that this definition was proffered by choreographer William
Forsythe to define all the objects of his choreographic work (i.e. installations,
performances and digital objects) attests not only the general potentials of
choreographic objects but also their iterability. Saying that a model is iterative
corresponds to saying that it is algorithmic, i.e. that it can be repeated automatically or
not for generating a series of expressions. In sum, it will be the contention of this study
that the choreographic object is both diagrammatic and algorithmic. Or, in other words,
that it is because of the algorithmic character of its diagrammatic ideas that the
choreographic object can acquire a technological status, i.e. that it can be said to
20
correspond to a knowledge (logos) pertaining to a way of dancing (tekhné).
In order to pursue such thesis, this study will start by laying out the fundamental
concerns to any thought of choreographic knowledge. It will inquire into the ontology
of bodies and movement because they are fundamental for the constitution of
choreographic objects. But instead of asking “what is a body?” and “what is
movement?”, the initial questions here posed are processual, such as “how does a body
move?” and “what happens to a body when it moves?”. Such concerns are expressly
addressed throughout Chapters 1 and 2. The first Chapter will discuss the relationship
between time and space in the movement of bodies via the philosophy of Henry
Bergson (Section 1.1). It will specifically address the philosopher's take on the theory of
multiplicities and, with this, discuss the relationship between intensity and extension.
This will serve to make the case that bodies in movement are irreducible to positions
and that, therefore, they must be granted to implicate undetermined potentials, which
are unaccountable only in terms of extension. Moreover, this first Chapter will also
introduce the encounter between dance and technology as a problematic field of
potentials (Section 1.2). It will argue that such encounter is only capable of creating
novel instances of choreographic knowledge if the indetermination of its constitutive
potentials is not only acknowledged but also inclusively mobilized. How can this be
done and, in particular, how can it be done when choreographic knowledge is to be
expressed by digital means, will be the question posed here. In a sense, this study's
remaining Chapters will build upon one another to answer such question. In relation to
the hypothesis that choreographic objects are necessarily diagrammatic and algorithmic,
such question can be understood in the following way: a diagram is a structure of
potentials that can be resumed algorithmically. Hence, it is the question of how to create
choreographic objects that express novel instances of knowledge.
This question has been formulated by philosopher Erin Manning (2009, pp. 61–
76) in terms of how to create a truly “technogenetic body” by means of the encounter
between dance and technology. The answer she essays by drawing from Simondon's
philosophy is somewhat expectable: the virtuality of movement must be tapped into, by
the encounter itself. Even when the case regards the digital computation of gestural
data, the encountering parts must be made to affect one another beyond what is given by
each of them. Only in this way are the potentials of the encounter between dance and
technology to be mobilized beyond what is known and knowable. Only this will allow
for the encounter to be truly technogenetic, i.e. technically creative, and individuate
novel instances of knowledge. In this argument, one question remains problematic: how
21
do digital media and potentials relate? Manning's approximation to this question is
short: “Techniques for technogenetic emergence must become part of the technology’s
interface: we must develop techniques that create new associated milieus never distinct
from the ontogenetic body. Technological recomposition must no longer be inserted into
a body-system: it must be emergent with it.” (Ibid., p. 75). In fact, this does not really
answer the question. Rather, it is a corollary that expresses how the encounter between
dance and technology must be thought and developed in order to be creative. From this
standpoint, this study will follow Manning's direction in drawing from Simondon's
philosophy in order to develop it further. As already mentioned, this will allow for
defining choreographic objects in terms of potentiality, i.e. as processes that implicate
the potentials mobilized by the encounter between dance and technology. Since all the
choreographic objects here studied express knowledge by digital means, such definition
brings to the fore the question of a digital potential, i.e. does the digital domain have
potentials of its own? A question to be addressed in Chapter 6.
Chapter 3 will develop concepts with regard to choreography that can only be
properly understood under the light of Simondon's philosophy. Or, better yet, it is not
that choreography is here to be thought in accordance with this one philosophical
system of thought. Rather, it will be argued that, insofar as choreography can be
creative, the fundamental concerns of Simondon's philosophy are most apt to
22
conceptualize it. Hence, this philosophy will be used to approach choreography and
inquire into the dynamisms by means of which it comes to express itself in novel ways.
Throughout this chapter, the notion that choreography is not tied to the performance of
dance will serve both the assertion that one same choreographic object can be expressed
in many different ways and the argument that, in order for this to be so, the object must
be topological, that is, it must be a continuum of potentials capable of expressing itself
differently while remaining the same (Section 3.2 will discuss such definition). The first
case to be discussed is the generic relationship between dancing and writing,
constitutive of Western choreography (Section 3.1). It will be shown that, when these
different domains express one same object, such expressions necessarily derive from
one same structure of potentials. They express identical instances of choreographic
knowledge, according to the limits of the matters in individuation. The second case to
be discussed is William Forsythe's seminal collection of choreographic objects:
“Improvisation Technologies: A Tool for the Analytical Eye” (Section 3.3). By looking
into one of this technologies' topological character, the choreographic object will be
defined as being, first and foremost, an abstract system of potential transductions. The
choreographic object will be shown to be apt to transfer its potentials across domains
and, with this, not only express itself differently but also instantiate the individuation of
knowledge. For such reasons, it will be contended that the choreographic object is
irreducible both to its expressions and to its abstractions. It is as an open whole that
always exceeds its own determinations.
23
Scholten's Double Skin/DoubleMind choreographic object. Since this is expressed in
different domains, the relationships between its topology, its problematic potentials, its
conceptual structure and its expressions will be tackled via the notion of diagram.
Section 4.3 will continue developing this notion, still in relation to Deleuze's
philosophy, but also in relation to its use by philosophers such as Charles S. Peirce,
Michel Foucault, Deleuze & Guattari, Brian Massumi and Manuel DeLanda. Such
discussion is intended to provide the means for better understanding how, in the
encounter between dance and technology, that which cannot be known is determinant
with regard to the emergence of individuals. The unconscious diagram of ideas—
designated here as “abstract machine”, cf. Deleuze & Guattari (1987)—will in this way
be argued to be not only a fundament of choreography, but also the very ground of
novelty as such.
The expression of novel cases of solution with regard to the problematic ideas of
choreographic objects will be addressed from the perspective already posed (Section
3.1) of the asymmetry between dancing and writing. In order to do so, Chapter 5 will
discuss a series of choreographic objects, which were programmed as digital algorithms.
This will allow both for defining gesture as the representation of movement and for
discussing these examples as cases of solution for the problematic relation between the
dancing body and what will be here designated as gestural body. It will also allow for a
better understanding of how different choreographic ideas can be computed and
digitally expressed. Throughout Sections 5.1 and 5.2 the choreographic objects to be
discussed are the “Gesture Follower”—a software built into the digital expressions of
the “Double Skin/Double Mind”—, the already mentioned “Motion Bank's” online
scores and the “Reactor for Awareness in Motion's” motion capture and animation
software. Since these choreographic objects' have been transduced into automations of
the digital domain, their diagrammatic ideas will be posited as being characteristically
algorithmic and, therefore, resumable across domains. Hence, in accordance with
William Forsythe's definition, choreographic objects can be seen as diagrammatic
algorithms capable of transducing problematic ideas (of movement).
24
be embedded in a milieu of potentials other than its own, i.e. in an analog milieu,
Chapter 6 will pursue the notion that there is more to digital computation than itself can
compute. As it will be shown, this is tantamount to the hypothesis that digital
computation is infected by random quantities of data and that, precisely because of this,
it is open to an infinity of quantitative potentials that grant it the very status of thought.
In contrast to reductionist perspectives of the digital domain, the algorithmic
computation of data will be argued to be always excessive in relation to itself. Such
notion will be supported by Andrew Goffey's conception of algorithms, Gregory
Chaitin's theory of algorithmic complexity and Luciana Parisi notion of “soft(ware)
thought”. Such perspectives will be contrasted upon two different approaches to objects:
Graham Harman's object-oriented ontology and Alfred N. Whitehead's process-oriented
ontology. With this, it will not only be shown that digital potentials must be conceived
as random and irreducible quantities of data, but also that algorithmic objects must be
defined as the physical and conceptual prehension of these same quantities. Even if
choreographic objects are digitally expressed, this will make the case that they are
capable of more than what, at any moment, might have been determined as a case of
solution for the problems of their ideas. In short, choreographic objects as the excessive
but yet structured potential to individuate novel instances of knowledge with regard to
the movement of bodies.
Finally, this study will conclude with a proposition regarding the necessary
conditions for activating potentials in processes of technical individuation. It will be
argued that, inasmuch as potentiality is a conditional force of technogenesis, the latter
can only come about by means of a constitutive, yet subjectable to enhancement,
openness to infinity. This infinity is none other than the one of the undetermined
potentials of ideas existing amidst, immanently, the actual possibilities of technical
individuation. The more this indetermination is made to ingress, affectively, into the
technical resolution of the problems of ideas, the more novelty will appear and the more
the overall development of a system of individuation will become infected with its
creative potentials. Hence, it will be argued that, though novelty as such is, by
definition, not predictable and thus not subjectable to direct regulation, there are actual
conditions that can intensify its occurrence and amplify the technical system's capacity
to be truly creative and evolutive.
25
Chapter 1 - A TOPOLOGICAL ENCOUNTER
This first Chapter will open this study not only by inquiring into the relationship
between movement and bodies, but also by doing so in a speculative manner.
Speculation can be said to have marked much of this study's writings, mostly because it
is a characteristic mode of thought in process philosophy. 32 Not only has this study
inherited this mark from such tradition, but it has also used it as a means to discuss a
reality of movement and bodies that cannot be tackled otherwise, i.e. their incorporeal
reality. The purpose of inquiring into the relationship between the incorporeal and the
corporeal realities of movement and bodies is here twofold: on the one hand, it aims at
establishing a first approach to ontology (Section 1.1); on the other, it aims at
establishing a conceptual ground to better tackle what will be here designated as “the
encounter between dance and technology” (Section 1.2). The ontology of movement
and bodies will be explored via French philosopher Henry Bergson's work on
movement, space and duration. His take on the theory of multiplicities, according to
which bodies must be acknowledged to comprise potentials that are, not only irreducible
to stationary perspectives of extension, but also fundamental to their very movement,
will serve the purpose of conceiving the incorporeal reality of moving bodies precisely
in terms of potentiality. From this standpoint, this Chapter's second section will be
dedicated to positing the problem of creativity in the encounter between dance and
technology. Inasmuch as this encounter can and will be defined as the constitution of
choreographic knowledge, the question of how can knowledge be created anew will be
posited in terms of the potentials that such encounter can mobilize.
32 In this regard, it should be noted that philosopher Alfred N. Whitehead's series of lectures on
“Speculative Philosophy”, published under the title “Process and Reality” (1978), not only are, still
today, a canonical landmark in process philosophy, as they also define what, in this tradition, means
to think speculatively. In the philosopher's words: “Speculative Philosophy is the endeavour to frame
a coherent, logical, necessary system of general ideas in terms of which every element of our
experience can be interpreted. […] It i s the ideal of speculative philosophy that its fundamental
notions shall not seem capable of abstraction from each other. In other words, it is presupposed that
no entity can be conceived in complete abstraction from the system of the universe, and that it is the
business of speculative philosophy to exhibit this truth. […] Thus the philosophic scheme should be
necessary, in the sense of bearing in itself its own warrant of universality throughout an experience,
provided that we confine ourselves to that which communicates with immediate matter of fact. But
what does not so communicate i s unknowable, and the unknowable i s unknown; and so this
universality defined by 'communication' can suffice. This doctrine of necessity in universality means
that there is an essence to the universe which forbids relationships beyond itself, as a violation of its
rationality. Speculative philosophy seeks that essence.” (Ibid., p. 3).
26
1.1 - Multiplicities in Movement
27
subtracting actual positions from virtual potentials. Or, in other words, that movement's
expressions are subtracted from the infinity of potentials that implicates the virtual in
the actual. Between virtuality and actuality, i.e. between the one's continuous potentials
and the other's discontinuous extensions, movement is key. It is through movement that
Bergson relates coordinated positions with the experience of continuous change. For
him, only movement unites virtuality with actuality. Conversely, movement cannot be
approached exclusively by either one of its poles. What can be said to correspond to the
subjective experience of movement, i.e. to the durational experience of a non-spatial
and virtual time, must be acknowledged to necessarily correspond to movement's
objective expression. The unity between the one and the other, i.e. the implication of
virtuality in actuality and the explication of virtuality by actuality, is realized in
movement. Here, neither subjects nor objects can be said to be stable and unchanging
unities, distinct from one another from the outset. Rather, they must be seen as resulting
from movement's dual reality.
The point here is that movement can be neither reduced to emergent positions
nor it can be fully abstracted from a physical ground. Their relation, i.e. the relation
between actuality and virtuality, must be thought immanently. The force of movement
must be granted to belong to movement itself. Movement must be understood as the
common ground against which all forces can be considered. The principle of
immanence can be also expressed in the following way: virtuality is immanent in
actuality and actuality is immanent in virtuality. Which is to say that, in movement,
there is one same “plane of immanence” 33 where actuality becomes virtual and virtuality
becomes actual, simultaneously and interdependently. In order for virtual movements to
occur, there must exist somewhere an actual ground conditioning them, coincident but
disjunct. Likewise, for any displacement to take place there must exist somewhere an
opening towards virtuality, towards the infinity that necessarily feeds the actuality of
movement.34 From this standpoint, movement's virtual-actual dynamisms can be
33 The “plane of immanence” is a concept developed by philosopher Gilles Deleuze in order to facilitate
the understanding that movement, with its virtual-actual dynamisms, necessarily opens the world's
finitude to an inexhaustible source of renewal and creativity. As the author himself explains: “The
plane of immanence is the movement (the facet of movement) which is established between the parts
of each system and between one system and another, which crosses them all, stirs them all up
together and subjects them all to the condition which prevents them from being absolutely closed. It
is therefore [...] a mobile section, a temporal section or perspective. It is a bloc of space-time, since
the time of the movement which is at work within it is part of it every time. There is even an infinite
series of such blocs or mobile sections which will be, as it were, so many presentations of the plane,
corresponding to the succession of movements in the universe. And the plane is not distinct from this
presentation of planes. This is not mechanism, it is machinism. The material universe, the plane of
immanence, is the machine assemblage of movement-images.” (Deleuze, 1986, p. 59).
34 Though this study will not dwell upon the possibility of a radical reduction of virtuality to actuality
28
summarized as follows: whereas the virtual contributes to actuality, actuality constrains
such contribution. Loops of feedback and feedforward are thus prevalent modes of
affectivity between movement's multiple dimensions. Movement cannot be accounted
for without this dynamic character, i.e. it cannot be properly understood if not with the
virtual implications of actuality and the actual explications of virtuality.
How virtuality and actuality relate to one another when a body moves can be
further understood by reading, with Bergson, Zeno's paradoxes of motion. Such
paradoxes have been ascribed to pre-socratic philosopher Zeno of Elea, who hasn't left
any known writings of his own, by Aristotle (1999). Though Bergson commented upon
several of these paradoxes—four in total—, it is here enough to mention the “Paradox
of the Arrow” (1944, pp. 335–338).35 In Aristotle's “Physics” (Ibid., p. 161), this paradox
is described as follows: “if everything when it occupies an equal space is at rest, and if
that which is in locomotion is always occupying such a space at any moment, the flying
arrow is therefore motionless”. With such formulation, it becomes clear why Zeno's
paradoxes are designated as such. All of them equate the metric divisibility of space
with the movement of bodies. An equation from which results, in a very straightforward
way, the very impossibility of movement. Such impossibility can be further explained in
the following terms: if space is given, then the arrow in flight can only reiterate it.
Movement's impossibility therefore depends on the conflation of time with space. In
Zeno's “Paradox of the Arrow”, space is given such prevalence over time that time itself
cannot be thought but in spatial terms. By coinciding with a preformed and metric
space, the flying arrow cannot but be static at any point of its transition between two
other points (e.g. before being shot and after having hit the target). Here implied is the
fact that, between any two given points of the arrow's trajectory, an infinite number of
other points can be found. This is the infinitesimal divisibility of space after which only
the transcendental image of a non-chronological time is to be found. But precisely
(for it assumes from the outset a holistic approach to process, bodies and the world), atomism will be
briefly criticized when accounting for Gilbert Simondon's understanding of creativity (see Section
2.1). It will be argued that it is only by virtual means that actuality can partake movement, i.e. that
extension can only unfold by means of intensive contributions. Moreover, a brief critique of idealism
will also be posited from the perspective of immanence's principle. It will be argued that, for a
movement of thought to occur, an immanent and actual ground is required. Actuality will thus be
defined as the constraining order by means of which the virtual contributes in determinate ways to
movements in extension. For such reasons, this study will take neither the side of a radical
materialism nor the side of a radical idealism. Rather, it will make its stand based on the inextricable
relation between virtuality and actuality, i.e. it will proceed with a focus on process.
35 It is worth noting that Alfred N. Whitehead (1978, pp. 68–69), the English mathematician and
philosopher who would soon after Bergson set the agenda for thinking the world from a processual
perspective, has also chosen to comment upon this one paradox. The differences between Bergson's
theory of duration and Whitehead's conception of movement will be briefly discussed in Section 6.4.
29
because the flying arrow is not a transcendental object, it is said to coincide with the
spatial discontinuities that it traverses. In this sense, whatever the magnitude
considered, the unchanging self-coincidence of space determines all actuality as static
reality. In which case, the arrow cannot really fly.
Zeno's equation of space with movement has been commented upon by Aristotle
himself in the following way: “[t]his [equation] is false, for time is not composed of
indivisible moments any more than any other magnitude is composed of indivisibles”
(1999, p. 161). What is here at stake is therefore the relation between continuity and
discontinuity, i.e. between qualities and quantities. For if movement is said to be
discontinuous and thus impossible, then it is time itself that is said to not exist. After the
infinitesimal division of space, nothing but space remains. Or, which amounts to the
same thing, in between any two given points there is only a succession of restful,
spatially self-coincident instants. The assertion that time is not composed of indivisible
moments should therefore be understood in the sense that positions are gregarious with
one another and, as such, inconsiderable in isolation. If they are gregarious, they are
continuous with one another. For if movement is to occur, i.e. if change is to overcome
the metric divisibility of space, then any instant whatsoever must be considered as being
possibly continuous with any other instant in its vicinity. This continuity corresponds, of
course, to the very indivisibility of time. But this shouldn't be understood as
contradicting Aristotle's comprehension of a divisible time. Rather, this argument should
be understood to assert both the metric character of magnitudes and the gregarious
character of quantities. To say that time is not composed of indivisible moments is to
argue for a necessary and reciprocal implication of quantities in one another. Precisely
because of being divisible, quantities open the metric character of space to the non-
metric character of time (granted that a function of gregariousness is applicable to the
relation between discontinuous elements). From this, change unfolds. This might still
appear to be a contradiction, for time is being said to be both divisible and indivisible.
And it is true that, in order for positions to be gregarious (and not only non-
communicating unities), divisibles must relate in some way with indivisibles. What is
missing both from Zeno's account of motion, and from Aristotle's commentary upon it,
is a conception of relation between quantities and qualities that includes change in
space.
30
the standpoint of the variations undergone by the relation between time and space. As
such, instead of the arrow's movement being equated with space's discontinuous
invariability, it is to be thought as transitioning between states: from a null velocity
(before being shot) to a positive one (when in flight) and back again to a stop (after
having hit the target). In this way, movement is seen to result from the difference
between a body's dimensions of space and time. As it will be argued below, 36 related
terms cannot be said to preexist their relation. Inasmuch as any relation is processual,
what it relates cannot be given in advance. Whatever is of the relation, necessarily
emerges with it. Hence, space and time are here seen to result from the arrow's
differential of movement. In other words, the arrow's movement is seen under the light
of determinate ratios, such as velocity's rate of change (i.e. acceleration). According to
this non-positional view, the flying arrow constitutes, with its differentials of movement,
the spatio-temporal conditions of its own experience. A corollary that led Bergson to
propose a different image for the traversing of space: “Suppose an elastic stretched from
A to B, could you divide its extension? The course of the arrow is this very extension; it
is equally simple and equally undivided. It is a single and unique bound.” (1944, p.
335). Notably, this is also one of Bergson's definitions of “duration”, a concept which he
devised to account for what in movement is indivisible (2001, pp. 85–87). The unique
bound of movement corresponds therefore to the durational becoming of an
indecomposable mobile section of space and time.37
Still in contrast to this, when considering that, in order for the arrow to go from
A to B, it needs to cross two different halves of the total space traversed (or any number
of parts resulting from the latter's division), it can be argued that a determinate
articulation needs to be included in the elastic duration of the arrow's whole movement.
From to this perspective (which is Zeno's), each mobile section resulting from the
division of space needs to be articulated by some means with the mobile sections in its
vicinity. From which it follows that, with articulation, the indivisible duration of
movement is disrupted. Once again, the infinitesimal divisibility of space brings to the
fore the realization that, if any mobile section is infinitely decomposable, what results
31
after such division is but a radical reduction of movement to discontinuous positions. In
Bergson's words: “To suppose that the moving body is at a point of its course is to cut
the course in two by a snip of the scissors at this point, and to substitute two trajectories
for the single trajectory which we were first considering. […] it is to attribute to the
course of the arrow itself everything that can be said of the interval that the arrow has
traversed, that is to say, to admit a priori the absurdity that movement coincides with
immobility.” (1944, p. 336). This is Bergson's direct answer to Zeno's paradoxes of
motion. Hence, instead of movement being thought as coinciding with the immobile
character of space, it should be thought as corresponding to an elastic interval capable
of connecting all its transient states.
It should be noted that movement can only be divided after it has occurred. To
say that the flying arrow coincides with any given point of its trajectory is an
affirmation that can only be made after the fact, i.e. after the arrow has in fact come to
connect a determinate point of rest with its preceding ones. Importantly, the
retrospection of movement can only be performed by adding an abstract idea of
succession to the given space. In this sense, succession corresponds to a spatial idea of
time: a homogeneous, mechanical spatialization that subsumes the continuity of interior
change to the measurability of exteriority. In succession, no real movement occurs,
except for the thought that abstracts an idea of time from the space given. In regard to
the arrow's real movement, such thought is but a representation. Because of this,
Bergson affirms that we habitually think according to a “cinematographic mechanism of
thought” (Ibid, pp. 335–343). Which is to say that, frame by frame, thought proceeds on
retrospecting the representation of what might have happened in the intervals of
perception.
32
a multiplicity of exteriority, of simultaneity, of juxtaposition, of order, of quantitative
differentiation, of difference in degree; it is a numerical multiplicity, discontinuous and
actual. The other type of multiplicity appears in pure duration: It is an internal
multiplicity of succession, of fusion, of organization, of heterogeneity, of qualitative
discrimination, or of difference in kind; it is a virtual and continuous multiplicity that
cannot be reduced to numbers.” (1988a, p. 38). With such distinction, the discontinuous
elements of an actual multiplicity can only be said to be gregarious if granted that the
two types of multiplicity are related to one another by a principle of immanence. The
antidote to the cinematographic mechanism of thought, from which result paradoxes
such as Zeno's, is the relation of immanence between actuality and virtuality. Only by
reason of them being immanent in one another can the discontinuity of metric space be
said to include a field of succession that is qualitative rather than quantitative,
durational rather than organized in frames. In short, for movement to occur the
continuity of duration must exist together with and inextricably from the same
conditions of experience that allow space to be abstracted in numerical terms.
38 The mathematical calculus of topological multiplicities developed by Riemann can be traced back to
the works of mathematicians such as Euler, Listing, Mobius and Gauss (Riemann's mentor). It was
nonetheless earlier, in the 17th century, that Gottfried Wilhelm von Leibniz worked towards making
topology a rigorous mathematical discipline. Topology can be generally defined as the study of the
properties preserved in processes of deformation and of the objects that might possess such
properties. A common example is the deformation of a coffee cup into a doughnut (or vice-versa).
From the one to the other, deformation can unfold without any break in the continuity of the
intervening points. Both the coffee cup and the doughnut belong to the same topological figure.
Topological studies bring to the fore functions of deformation. They give prevalence to the ways in
which a form becomes another by means of continuous changes. Since it encompasses the potential to
be expressed in multiple forms, the same topological figure is in itself a multiplicity. And precisely
because topological variations are continuous, without cuts in the set of intervening points, it is
impossible to account for the infinity of intermediary states in any interval of space-time considered.
Topological continuity thus refers to what two different states of one same system share with one
another. It refers to invariabilities in processes of deformation. This continuity of the same, at the
same time that connects the actual expressions of form, presupposes difference as discontinuity, i.e.
as the interruption of invariance. Therefore, topology poses the problem of how to reconcile
continuity with discontinuity, similitude with difference, infinity with finitude, and so on.
33
changing in kind, that which is susceptible to measurement only by varying its metrical
principle at each stage of the division” (Deleuze, 1988a, p. 40). In fact, it is only
because duration divides and differentiates itself that multiplicities can be considered as
being implicated in continuity, i.e. in non-numerical multiplicities. For Deleuze, this
means that “there is other without there being several; number exists only potentially. In
other words, the subjective, or duration, is the virtual” (1988a, p. 42). By asserting the
coincidence between duration and virtuality, that which is heterogeneous in kind is
reconciled with what is continuous in nature.
34
the virtual multiplicities from which actuality results. The immanence between
virtuality and actuality corresponds therefore to the inextricable relation between space
and time in movements that simultaneously quantify and qualify their own effects. If the
mobility of bodies in space corresponds to changes of state, it is only because
movement as such cannot be reduced to numerical successions. The series of spatial
instants (be them constitutive of geometric relations or of temporal mechanisms) do not
account for the reality of change that necessarily accompanies displacements. To
account for such reality, the initial conditions of a movement-event must be considered.
Already in the conditions that allow for a movement to initiate, a plane of differentiation
must occur, for it is from the event of difference that both the spatialization of
movement and its durational becoming are energized. Whatever makes a body move
necessarily corresponds to forces that partake its changes. As an example of the action
of such forces in the dislocation of bodies, Bergson talks about survival impulses and
the movement that follows from them (1944, pp. 274–278). Animals move to feed
themselves, to occupy more favourable climacteric conditions, to procreate, and so on.
Such movements correspond not only to spatial displacements, but also to
transformations that, when completed, have changed the difference of potentials that
initially forced them to occur. This intensive change is no different in the case of
planets, plants and bacteria. Intensive forces are the necessary condition for any body to
actually move.
35
When a meteorite enters the gravitational pull of a planet to the point of collision, it is
the whole that changes and not only one of its parts. The numerical reduction of
movement to the spatial parts that it explicates cannot account for the changes in
potential of a whole encompassing all the forms and all the forces of an ecology of
relations. Altogether, the intensities and extensions of a whole ecology of relations are
necessarily open to what is not yet formed as a possibility of movement, i.e. to what
exists as potential and cannot be anticipated.
39 In regard to the indetermination of potentials as a necessary condition for real movement, Deleuze
says the following: “In fact, to recompose movement with eternal poses [ideal images] or with
immobile sections [after-images] comes to the same thing: in both cases, one misses the movement
because one constructs a Whole, one assumes that 'all is given', whilst movement only occurs if the
whole is neither given nor giveable. As soon as a whole is given to one in the eternal order of forms
or poses, or in the set of any-instant-whatevers, then either time is no more than the image of eternity,
or it is the consequence of the set; there is no longer room for real movement.” (1986, p. 7).
36
duration to the objects of the system which it forces to open up” (1986, p. 11).
40 For a small collection of seminal examples of the encounter between dance and film see
http://www.ubu.com/film/dance-with-camera.html.
41 There was a series of conferences held between 1992 and 1995 in North America that later gave place
to the “International Dance and Technology Conference”, which has been happening since 1999 (also
under the name of “Dance Tech Inc.”). Not only this, but some key figures in this field's
development, namely Scott deLahunta, Marc Coniglio and Scott Sutherland, were responsible at the
time for setting up a website called “Dance & Technology Zone” (http://art.net/~dtz/), which served
as an important platform to reify and support this convergence.
42 The advent of which will be briefly discussed in Section 3.1.
37
can be expressed both by dancing bodies and by choreographic notations). By being
organizable and resumable in space and time, dance becomes complied to be the object
of a knowledge that, because it regards ways of doing, it is technical (i.e. tekhné as skill
or craft). The knowledge of dance that choreography has allowed to transmit across
generations of dancing bodies is, literally, its main legacy. As such, it is its main
capacity. The encounter between dance and technology must be understood in relation
to this historical frame, i.e. it must be understood in relation to the constitution of
choreographic knowledge within the overarching project of Western epistemology.
From this standpoint, it can be proposed that using digital tools to express dance-
related knowledge is but one specific mode of choreographing. Of course digital tools
offer possibilities to represent dance that are far more complex and varied than simpler
modes of symbolic expression, such as systems of choreographic notation. 43
Notwithstanding, in relation to the overall historical project of choreography, such
specification remains tied to the representation of dance-related knowledge.
Choreography as such remains unchanged by the use of digital tools. The digital domain
continues to serve the same technological character of dance that choreography has
always served, but with more and new possibilities.
43 For a series of examples regarding the digital representation of dancing bodies, see Chapters 4 and 5.
44 For a discussion of the digital as a domain of possibilities see Chapters 5 and 6.
38
metrical principles of organization,45 principles that regard, first and foremost, the
workings of computational machines. Many times the dancing body has been
automatically captured into the digital domain only to become a determinate set of
numbers in representation of its movement wholeness. In this case, due to the reduction
of analog media to arrays of 0's and 1's, whatever is hold intensively and durationally in
the source domain remains cast out of numbers. The digital, which is discontinuous and
coded according to Boolean46 logics, can only represent the analog. Conversely, the
analog is to a large extent incompressible.47
This regards the argument that what has no external organization cannot be
transposed to a domain exclusively based on numbers. The virtual reality of the dancing
body has no parallel in digital arrays. The dancing body is always more than all the
extensions that from it might be derived, not only because it comprises too many
variables, but also because it possesses varieties of reality that are not quantifiable and,
as such, not organizable in extension. The analog's incompressibility regards as well the
argument that qualities and quantities are irreducible to one another, leaving aside in any
translation that which is untranslatable. It is true that the representation of the dancing
body in domains other than its own is necessarily expressive, for the sake of being
perceivable, and therefore comprises its own qualities. But these are to be
acknowledged as corresponding to events of perception that discard the dancing body's
presence. The digital domain is, in this respect, a multilayered and multidimensional
mediatic domain wherein code is translated into code and, eventually, into audio-visual
expression. Each translation overrides what the digital cannot articulate, only to bring
into expression qualities that are but a resumption of given quantities. Translation can
be here defined as the reduction of perception into arrays of binary code. From
45 In this regard, all possible examples share one same aspect: the digital representations of the dancing
body are constructed solely on the basis of computation. “Lifeforms”, a seminal software in digital
choreography, is a paradigmatic example of this. Being a digital program for animating and notating
choreographic ideas, “Lifeforms” allows for representing dancing bodies in a euclidean fashion. Here,
the dancing body is reduced to a series of computational possibilities, which notwithstanding can be
creative of choreographic ideas impossible for real dancers to perform. There is no input apart from
user-determined data, to be computed according to built-in parameters. On the other hand, throughout
the years, choreographic softwares became more prone to compute motion-capture data (see Chapter
5). Motion-capture devices do no more than sampling data from sensed variations, i.e. they organize
the numerical representation of these variations according to predetermined parameters of
articulation. Which is to say that, for motion data to be computed, it first needs to be structured. Such
structuration is itself computed by parametric algorithms predetermined into the devices' software.
Hence, this passage from raw to structured data corresponds to the articulation of numbers with one
another in accordance with digital representations of space and time. All in all, the digital demands
the analog to be reduced to a binarism that is but a metrical mode of organizing space and time.
46 See footnote 147.
47 For a discussion regarding incompressible quantities of data existing together with finite quantities of
data, see Chapter 6.
39
perception to abstraction and from abstraction to expression, translation proceeds first
as reduction, and then as additive speculation. Reduction, because various quantities of
data are synthesized into the limited articulation of numbers. Additive speculation,
because whatever is missed by the discrete quantities of data needs to be generated
anew when expressively qualified.48 This necessity of adding data to what is given
attests the reduction that occurs when going from qualitative experiences to quantitative
expressions. The digital samples the analog and simulates it to the point of coincidence.
But this neither means that they are one nor that they are the same. The possibilities of
the digital domain are sufficient neither to constitute a whole dancing body nor to
reproduce the analog in its full depth. Translating the dancing body into digital code is
always to register data predetermined to be of choice and to compose a double of reality
defined only to the extent of its useful participation in the field of perception (i.e. what
cannot be perceived can be discarded).
If the digital representation of dancing bodies always misses their virtuality, how
is it then that choreographic knowledge can be constituted anew? Clearly, the
speculative addition of reality has a role in creativity. But if the invention of digital
machines only adds to preconceived notions of what dance is, translations from the
analog to the digital can only represent what the dancing body is assumed to be. In this
case, before the encounter, dance is given as a preformed idea. Additive speculation can
then only follow its own biases, which pertain to specific points of view, each informed
by a past of its own. For novel instances of choreographic knowledge to emerge in the
encounter between dance and technology, translations need to be infected by potentials
with the capacity to constitute what cannot be predicted. If novelty is to occur, neither
what dancers know nor what anyone else might suppose to be dance should be assumed
to define the encounter between dance and technology. For such encounter to be the site
of novelty, choreographic potentials must be activated. This is to be done by means of
transduction, rather than translation. As it will be argued below, 49 transduction is an
48 Speculative addition can be understood both as abstract invention and as concrete operation. The
latter case regards the addition of inexistent data that, if it were to exist, would probably be as it is
added. In this sense, what is added is what the present lacks for experience to be consistent with its
past. This can also thought as recollection: whatever lacks in the present is filled with past memories.
In this way, the present becomes consistent and coherent with its own past. As an example,
philosopher Brian Massumi's take on the field of vision can be mentioned: “The 'pure' field of vision
is a virtual field. No matter how carefully an experimental setup approximates it, actual 'impurities'
will sneak in. For there will always already have been experience. What are the formlike emergences
of the "pure" field of vision as isolated in the laboratory if not traces of past intermodal experiences
straining to reactualize their ratio of constancy, to refresh already-objects they have been, to regain
the world, preknown anew?” (2002, p. 155). See Ibid, pp. 144-161.
49 See page 74, Section 2.4.
40
operation that, rather than proceeding only on the basis of what is given (having to fill
what is not), proceeds as well on the basis of what is not given (including, or practically
acknowledging, the unconscious as a constitutive part of the process). Transduction is
energized by undetermined potentials, which can bring novelty into emergence. Here,
speculation does not add what is already known, but rather what is not. It expresses the
difference implied in potentials that cannot resemble the past. Which is to say that
novelty necessarily results from differences between potentials implicated in the
encounter between dance and technology. Novelty speculates the resolution of such
differences with what cannot be known in advance.
It is therefore from the interplay between what dance is known to be and the
unknowable itself that choreographic knowledge can be constituted as what regards,
41
simultaneously, the emergence of experience and the necessary conditions for the latter
to eventuate in this or that particular fashion. Since the constitution of this sort of
knowledge necessarily results from focusing corporeal potentials towards the
determination of repeatable parameters, it is in itself processual. Additionally, it
objectifies the very process by means of which dance is experienced, a process that
unfolds in-between the cognitive and the uncognizable towards the resolution of
problems related with such indeterminate in-betweenness.
42
that the enabling conditions of the becoming of things (i.e. ontogenesis) are the same
that enable the knowledge of them (i.e. epistemology).
43
multiplicity of a whole that, at the same time that it is open to and by undetermined
potentials, it is actually composed by a variety of extensions. It is not worth at this point
to discuss possible definitions of transduction and their related implications. 54 It is
enough to say that it is through transduction that problems are transferred across scales
and domains. Transduction regards the transference of diagrammatic ideas across the
possible resumptions of choreographic expression. 55 It knows nothing about
representation but instead informs unfolding processes with problems and resolutions.
In short, transduction resumes problematic conditions throughout the iterative
expression of correlated resolutions. It gives prevalence to creative differences rather
than to the image of what might express the resolution of a problem.
54 For a discussion of the notion of transduction within the frame of French philosopher Gilbert
Simondon's philosophy of individuation, see Sections 2.4 and 2.5 (a definition is given on page 74).
Transduction, and more specifically Simondon's definition of it, has been a key notion throughout the
development of this study, and it can be perhaps best understood in relation to the subject matters
here discussed in the final Sections of Chapter 4.
55 For a discussion of problems as the objects of ideas, see Section 4.1.
56 For a series of examples of such computational systems, see Chapter 5.
44
potentials in a process of technological individuation that novel instances of knowledge
can come about. Not as the iterative resumption of determinate cases of solution, but
rather as the transduction of diagrammatic ideas that, notwithstanding, can be iterated
without end. That which is without measure, without extension and without formal
organization must be assumed to have a generative role and to be a constitutive
dimension of creativity. The encounter between dance and technology, like any other
creative encounter, must be acknowledged as having at its core a differential relation
between indeterminate forces and determinate forms. Because, if the dancing body is
defined according to a finite set of axioms out of which only a series of possibilities is
renderable, nothing but that which conforms with what is already known can emerge as
a valid proposition. Presumptions restrict potentials with possibilities that can be
imagined beforehand. Predetermining the terms of a relation precludes creativity by
setting possibility as the ground from which any development can occur. Possibility, as
large as the set may be, is always limited and finite. It preforms images of what the
future may bring, foreclosing the openness towards that in regard to which there is no
possible anterior image. Assuming what dance and technology can do corresponds to
premapping what their encounter can generate as a possibility that can be known in
advance. As much as the results of this encounter can be imagined in anticipation to its
particular resonances, no true novelty can be expected. In such conditions, creativity is
subsumed by technical reproduction.57
57 Let us briefly recall that Walter Benjamin, like many after him, saw in the technical reproduction of
the work of art a process that destroys the “aura” of the object. In other words, for the author,
technical reproduction is but a mechanism that dispossesses the object of creation from “its unique
existence in a particular place” (2008, pp. 19–55). The uniqueness of creativity can thus be thought in
terms of the interpenetration of particular conditions that allow for the emergence of singularities.
45
intensity in extension and of extension in intensity, corresponds to the order of process
whereby potentials escape the containment of their formal structuration and resolve
themselves into the emergence of novel structures. Only by means of an encounter can
potentials energize processes of creation. Encounter is the event of self-differentiation
of its own initial conditions. When these conditions are moved by what in them is
potential to the point of becoming different from themselves, what remains in relation
can no longer be what it was. Hence, the emergence of novelty corresponds to a
determinate transformation of its own enabling conditions.
For the encounter between dance and technology to be open to the potential
creation of the unpredictable, neither dancing bodies nor apparatuses of capture can be
given in advance. This means to move from a set of predictable possibilities to the
indetermination of potentials in a creative movement, i.e. to activate an a-parallel
evolution of dancing bodies and technical objects. From this, only one expectation can
be maintained: that a creative process, rather than following a hylomorphic
determinism, modulates its constitutive forces towards the creation of novelty. The
constitutive creativity of an encounter regards not what might result from one given part
entering in relation with one other, but rather what can result from a whole's openness:
novelty not as what regards the absolutely different, but rather as what instead follows
from conditions that involve both the possible and the potential. Indetermination is
therefore a fundamental condition of an encounter's creativity. Only with the potentials
of an encounter can what is given in possibility become different from itself and what is
not yet given come to be. A true encounter engenders the unimaginable, it foregrounds
what cannot be known in advance.
46
dance and technology not as an encounter between self-identical parts, supplementing
one another in what each one lacks, but rather as a becoming that, far form being
predictable, holds in itself an excessive potential, a potential for becoming “more” than
itself. Whereas possibility comprises images that can be concretized without differing
from themselves, potentiality is the force of self-differentiation that opens the becoming
of each encounter to the indetermination of what cannot be predicted. But what does it
mean for a body to be “more-than” itself? What are the conditions that enable a body's
capacity to create novel appearances? Perhaps the most complete answer given to these
questions can be found in the theoretical works of philosopher of science Gilbert
Simondon (1969, 2005)58. For, while striving to understand the dynamisms by means of
which domains such as the physical, the vital, the psychic and the collective come into
existence, Simondon has proffered that the potentials of an individual exist in it as a
reserve for more (2005, pp. 9–30). From this perspective, due to its own potentials, the
individual can differ from itself and become other.
58 Because these texts are written in French, it should be noted that most of the quotes used in this study
were in fact taken from partial translations of other authors. As such, the main translations from
where references were taken are Simondon (1992), Lamarre (2012), Combes, (2013).
Notwithstanding this adequation, when quoting Simondon, this text will reference primary sources
(his own texts).
47
the source of the movement by means of which an individual comes to be. It is what
comes before the individual, but not in a chronological sense. The preindividual is a
reserve for more that the individual can access whenever becoming incompatible with
itself. It is either dormant or active, but always contemporary to the individual. As such,
in what regards the latter, the preindividual is a non-temporal anteriority.59 It is the
movement by means of which the pattern of a higher dimension resolves itself into the
pattern of a lower dimension, i.e. force giving birth to form. Individuation—the
becoming of an individual—should thus be understood as the process whereby the latter
accesses its preindividual share, only to become something else: the effect of a
transductive resolution. Transduction occurs while the individual and the preindividual
are kept in communication. It transfers the force of disparity into the metastable
agreement of forces and forms. Conversely, the individual should be understood as
corresponding to a state of compatibility between potentials. In a state of self-
compatibility, no communication between the individual and the preindividual occurs.
For this reason, it is said in Simondon's theory of individuation that being does
not exhaust itself with its actual expressions. After each individuation, the order of
potentials is kept in the formed individual, exceeding its actuality and endowing it with
the capacity to participate in subsequent individuations. In this sense, a system of being
corresponds not only to its actual expressions but also to its developmental processes.
As much as potentials exist in actuality, being cannot be reduced to its individuals. It is
more than them, for it encompasses all the individuals that it can potentially form. The
same system of being can become different individuals, changing with each
individuation the structures that keep in form its own potentials. The excess of a body
over itself can thus be conceived as a preindividual “more-than-unity and more-than-
identity” coexisting with and conditioning the “unity and identity” of “the phases of
being, subsequent to the operation of individuation”. (Simondon, 2005, pp. 25–26).
Having said this, a couple of questions must be posed: Which kind of conditions
enable technogenesis? Or, to be more precise, what are the necessary conditions for the
encounter between dance and technology to individuate a technogenetic body, i.e. for it
to bring forth an ecology of relations between dancing bodies and technical objects that
is charged with potentials? How should the preindividual potentials of a technogenetic
body be thought, given that its specificities are necessarily tied to what actually
constitutes dancing bodies and technical objects? In order to essay some answers, this
59 As Simondon points out, even time “develops out of the preindividual just like the other dimensions
according to which the process of individuation takes place” (Simondon, 2005, p. 34).
48
study will now turn towards Simondon's philosophy, not only because of what has been
indicated, but also because his theory of individuation deserves to be granted the status
of being one of the most thorough inquiries made throughout modernity regarding the
problematic relation between man and machines, from the standpoint of the relationship
between potentiality and actuality. Or, as Simondon himself says, because technology,
as the scientific study of technics, serves to reintroduce into culture—“that by which the
human being regulates its relation to the world and its relation to itself” (1969, p. 227)
—“a consciousness of the nature of machines, of their mutual relations and their
relations with the human being, and of values implied in these relations” (Ibid., p. 13).
Before proceeding, one remark regarding the encounter between dance and
technology must be made: there is no general category of this encounter from which
principles of technogenesis could be extracted. What exists instead are series of singular
encounters, each of which with its own ecology of relations. In each encounter, there is
the potential for singular dances and technologies to emerge, as what results from an
affective individuation between parts that do not remain unaltered. And in spite of
dancing bodies and technical objects being capable of existing on their own and
possibly coming together in order to compose functional aggregates, this doesn't assure
the activation of their potentials. The fact of contact between encountering parts does
not necessarily stand for incompatibilities in the choreographic system and therefore
does not assure resolutions into novelty. In the set of mutually inclusive possibilities
shared by dancing bodies and technical objects nothing more than what is already given
can occur. The singularity of an encounter thus requires more than possibility. It
requires the activation of potentials that, belonging to each of the encountering parts,
can affect one another to the point of realizing an encounter's creativity. Affect is the
fundamental order of the creative encounter. It exceeds the possibilities of contact
between the encountering parts with unimaginable events.
49
Chapter 2 - SIMONDON ON INDIVIDUATION
50
2.1 - Ontogenesis
51
related to one another by a shared field of potential affects. As already mentioned, such
field comprises what Simondon designates as “preindividual”—the primary force of
individuation. It is at the level of the preindividual that the plurality of individuation is
unified. Not as set, but as whole. As the continuous charge that underlies any of the
system's individuals, which is also the principal cause of their individuation. The
different individuals of one same system of individuation correspond in this way to “the
phases of being, subsequent to the operation of individuation” (Simondon, 2005, pp.
25–26). They express the system's potentials to endure under different conditions and
manifest one same preindividual potential.
As an example, one can think of water: its molecules are the same but they can
be arranged in different ways. Water can be solid, gaseous and liquid, depending on the
intensity of forces such as temperature and pressure. The system of being named water
encompasses all of this: its molecules and its states, its transitionings and the necessary
conditions for different individuations to occur. Water, as being, is a multiplicity. It
relates its many expressions to one another as different phases of one same system.
Solid, gaseous and liquid are all such expressive phases, granted that they are
continuous to one another by means of some preindividual share. The very potential of
ice to become liquid, for example, attests water's irreducibility to each of its expressions
and calls forth the necessity of acknowledging that the whole of it includes ever present
potentials. Being as becoming encompasses all of this, it encompasses the plurality of
its system's whole development.
The opposition between being and becoming that the ontogenetic perspective
52
overcomes generally results from a perspective that gives prevalence to the static over
the mobile. From this perspective, the individual first needs to be given in order for its
individuation to be known, after the actual fact. In a kind of reverse engineering,
individuation is reduced to a succession of facts, connected to one another by means of
actual causalities. Qualitative change is subsumed by quantitative variation, i.e. by the
after-effect of change itself, to which only formed individuals correspond. For
Simondon (2005, pp. 23–24), this oppositional standpoint between being and becoming
can be reduced to two different perspectives: substantialism, which considers the
individual as self-coincident and separated from others; and hylomorphism, which
considers the individual as a conjunction of matter and form. Both perspectives assume
a principle of individuation, but one which derives from stable things, from the formal
invariance of individuals. In this way, the significance of individuation is overridden.
Both substantialism and hylomorphism ignore the potential becoming of being, i.e. that
being develops with each individuation, but only partially. Both perspectives do not
account for the excess of individuals, i.e. for what impedes them from being the total
expression of the system to which they belong. The plurality of individuation, in its
continuous multiplicity, is missing. By ignoring this intrinsic force of self-
differentiation, both substantialism and hylomorphism postulate the self-identity of
individuals as a fundamental definition of being.
53
relativity between phases corresponds to the reality of being as phase consistent with the
latter's plurality, but also consistent with what in it is without phase—i.e. the
preindividual. In this sense, the multiphasic reality of being can be said to be immanent
in its system's preindividuality, and vice-versa. The passage from one phase of being to
another must correspond to a transference of potentials between the preindividual and
the individual levels of an individuating system. “Dephasing”, a term borrowed by
Simondon from thermodynamics, denotes such passage. It depicts the event whereby
being becomes self-incompatible and falls out of phase with itself. A dephasing is a
phase-shift; it remarks the point at which two phases intersect and charge the system
with preindividual potentials. Its aftermath is none other than the most adequate solution
for the problem posed, a singularity corresponding to one of the concurrent phases'
expression. Because in Simondon's theory of individuation being is conflated with
becoming, and because becoming is necessarily polyphased, then any system of being
can be said to comprise its many phases in potential.
54
being shouldn't be thought as being at rest. It continues to individuate by reason of its
openness to undetermined potentials. In fact, as Simondon says, “the sole principle by
which [individuation] is guided is that of the conservation of being through becoming”
(1992, p. 301). Which amounts to saying that individuation is the process by means of
which the potentials of one system of being are conserved. In each of its phases, the
system holds the potentials to individuate further phases and, by doing so, resolve
inescapable problems. Difference is a necessary condition for being to become and to
conserve itself through becoming. If the system of being conserves itself through
becoming, the disparity of its potentials is fundamental to its existence because only by
resolving an internal problematic can it transfer its own potentials (i.e. the potentials to
continue becoming) to yet another unproblematic phase. In sum, in order to endure, the
system of being must remain potentially incompatible with itself.
55
between them, followed by a subsequent communication between orders of magnitude
and stabilization” (1992, p. 304). The becoming of being is tantamount to the internal
resonance of its system. As long as potentials belonging to different orders of magnitude
keep affecting one another, the system of individuation can access its preindividual
share and individuate adequate resolutions to its self-incompatibility. The principle of
individuation is a principle of resonance.
61 Philosopher Brian Massumi recently gave a brief explanation of the term “milieu” that is worth
mentioning: “The word, often qualified by 'associated', is a favourite of both Simondon and Deleuze
and Guattari for its double entendre in French. In French milieu means both 'middle' and
'surroundings'. To put the two meanings together without falling back into an outside/inside division
that calls for a subject or object to found or regulate it, you have to conceive of a middle that wraps
around, to self-surround, as it phases onward in the direction of the “more” of its formative
openness.” (Manning, 2013, p. xii).
56
And, where terms such as 'contrast' and 'spacing' have largely spatial and static
connotations, the associated milieu is energetic, charged, potentiality. [...] In sum, the
associated milieu is the energetically charged field running across internal spacing and
external contrast.” (2012, p. 40). The associated milieu is a fundamental condition of
individuation. It is the very ground from which and on which the internal resonance of
an individuating system unfolds. In order for individuation to occur, the internal milieu
and the external milieu need to communicate with one another. Without their
communication, the system remains charged with potentials, but latent in a metastable
phase. The individual's associated milieu facilitates the communication between the
system's potentials; it is its medium. It's activation is tantamount to the inevitable
exchange between milieus that follows from a disparity between potentials. Only by
means of an associated milieu can a system of individuation resolve its self-
incompatibility.
62 In order to feel the metastability of any standing posture, one just needs to stand, close the eyes,
breath into any part of the body that feels tight, and let the weight fall down through the vertical
stacking of the bones. By doing this, one can easily feel the ongoing movement occurring at the level
of the hip joints, knees and ankles. In order for the body to stand, the muscles crossing these joints
can't stop moving. Notably, dancer and choreographer Steve Paxton has developed this exercise as a
dance practice, with the name of “Small Dance”. Similarly to what has just been described, the
“Small Dance” exercise consists in bringing one's attention to the ongoing adjustments of the body's
musculoskeletical system, while this keeps the distribution of energies throughout the body in a
standing balance (Paxton, 2008).
57
moving floor, such as in a bus, with all its variations in acceleration, is all is needed).
While standing, there is movement. In fact, this is one possible definition of
equilibrium: a state of relatedness in which a multiplicity of forces is kept under a
determinate threshold of transformation. In the case of the standing body the negotiating
forces can be located, for example, at the level its musculoskeletal system. And the
reason for this is that muscles work in antagonistic pairs: whenever one group of
muscles shortens (e.g. the hamstrings), another one stretches (e.g. the quadriceps).
There is, even at this level of muscular antagonism, a metastability between different
regions of the body (e.g. anterior and posterior, left and right, high and low). While
standing, the body remains charged with potentials that can bring it whenever required
into novel states of resolution.
58
differences that can be found between domains. What differs from the paradigm of
individuation to the individuation of non-paradigmatic domains are the dynamisms that
unfold beyond the ones characteristic of the physical domain. A differentiation which is
grounded on what is most paradigmatic to individuation and which unfolds into the
concretization of more-than-physical expressions. In this sense, when individuating
more-than-physical domains, the paradigmatic schema of physical individuation is
further composed with aspects of different and more complex individuations.
(Simondon, 2005, p. 319).
59
held between the crystal's remarkable points. The absence of contrast either defines the
crystal or its associated milieu. And when this absence defines the crystal, it defines as
well its internal spacing, that is, it defines the crystal's remarkable points relation to one
another. For these reasons, both internal spacing and external contrast can be said to
belong to one same order of magnitude. The associated milieu is therefore
distinguishable from the preindividual, which brings into relation different orders of
magnitude.
Further, crystallization depends neither only on the internal milieu nor only on
the external milieu. Rather, it depends on their affective relation. The very fact that
crystallization can only occur as long as the crystal's internal and external milieus are
kept communicating with one another attests precisely this. When taken out of its
solution, the crystal stops growing. When put back into it, it restarts its growth. What
matters then for individuation is the reciprocal affectiveness between internal spacing
and external contrast. Their exchange allows for the system to access its preindividual
reality and resolve itself into novel states. Again, the preindividual is distinguishable
from the associated milieu as what is activated when internal and external milieus
communicate with one another.
In this guise, LaMarre (2012, p. 38) tells us that the preindividual is “a disparity
between orders of magnitude that is deeper than or prior to potentiality or potential
energy itself”. What does this mean? Here we are confronted with the problem of
understanding what exactly triggers individuation. As mentioned before, individuation
follows from an initial incompatibility between potentials belonging to different orders
of magnitude within one same system of individuation. But in order to understand why
the resulting individual acquires a specific form, i.e. this one and not that other, it is
important to account for the fact that the initial conditions of individuation necessarily
implicate developmental tendencies. While Simondon talks about a “seed of form”,
LaMarre talks about a “neutral point”. Both terms refer to structural tendencies
implicated in the initial conditions of individuation, from which result individual
expressions. It is by means of a structural seed that is nowhere to be found (which is
why it is a neutral point) that the resolutions of individuation express determinate
structural characteristics.
When a crystal forms, for example, it follows the shape of the surfaces on which
it depends as structural support. In the case of supersaturated solutions, such as
supercooled water or sodium acetate, the potentials to individuate a determinate
60
structure are all there, latent in the solution itself. But in order for crystallization to
commence, the solution needs to become impure, to become disparate relatively to
itself. Crystallization follows from this disparity, forming structures that directly depend
on the formal tendencies implicated in the initial impurity. This does not mean that the
resulting crystals will necessarily be isomorphic to whatever form the impurity has.
Other variables, such as the concentration of salt and temperature, also enter in the
processual equation. Whatever results from this, from the process of individuation itself,
follows from the system's internal resonance and therefore from non-localized relations.
Which means that the shape of an individual does not result directly from a process's
seed of form. The relation between the two must rather be thought in accordance with
structural tendencies that the seed of form implicates in individuation itself.
Notwithstanding this non-localisable relation, what here matters is that potentiality is
not tantamount to preindividuality. The system can be charged with potentials, yet
without moving them into other states of metastability. For individuation to unfold, a
disparity between potentials needs to occur. The assertion that the preindividual is
“deeper than or prior to potentiality” (Simondon, 1995, p. 203) can be therefore
understood in the same way that disparity is deeper than the terms in relation.
This is a depth that can be approached with regard to a process's initial location.
The fact that a difference between concentrations of salt belonging to different regions
of the individual's associated milieu can be infinitely divided in order to precise the
location of the seed of form or, in other words, the very beginning of process, means
that at the end of the infinitesimal division of space only a virtual image of what that
might be will be found.63 As such, the actual seed can only be accessed by an
imagination based on what is actually perceived. Difference remains inaccessible
throughout the infinitesimal regression of a negative dialectics (i.e. this is this because it
is different from that, and from that, and from that, and so on ad infinitum). The self-
coincidence of each actual form corresponds to a difference that is always external to it.
63 It is worth noting that, with this division, qualities are overridden in order to give place to the
absolute extension of actuality. A difference between concentrations might very well be understood as
a qualitative multiplicity, one that is continuous and that therefore cannot be divided. Nonetheless,
inasmuch as a process can be reduced to expressions, the qualitative relations hold between any terms
can be cast into the intervals of actual space, i.e. into the in-betweenness of ever smaller and
discontinuous parts. Hence, when dividing space according to a fundamental difference between
quantities and qualities, nothing but a virtual image is to be found beyond given forms: the image of
an origin. In this way, a crystal is defined exclusively in accordance with quantitative determinations
(concentration as a relation between quantities) and the qualitative dimension of relations is cast way
from any actuality whatsoever. The conception of a difference between potentials is as problematic as
the very split between the virtual and the actual, which is a split between quantities and qualities. For
more on this split see Section 1.1, in articulation with Sections 6.3 and 6.4.
61
This is a virtual difference. It is nowhere to be found in actuality. The “absolute origin”
of individuation, as Simondon (1969, pp. 40–43) calls it, is therefore the transcendental
difference located at the heart of process. Implicit, but imperceptible; generative, but
inaccessible. Fated to be known only by means of what is possible to imagine.
With regard to the difference between the neutral point and the absolute origin of
individuation, Thomas LaMarre writes the following: “We can think of the neutral point
in relation to the physical form of the crystal, as a given, while the absolute origin refers
to the eventfulness that is triggered by the neutral point, the activation of the field of
potential energy. The proximity of neutral point and absolute origin helps us to
understand how this neutral point functions: the relations triggered or activated by the
neutral point are relative, but the entire set of relations, potential and actual, are relative
to an absolute origin (an eventfulness), which allows for them to be operative as well as
measurable within a frame of reference, or more precisely, within a concerned relation.”
(2012, p. 37). As such, the event of initiation simultaneously generates individuating
structures and that which acts as their seed. Before its commencement, what will have in
fact initiated individuation cannot be known. And after its initiation, the origin of
process can only be idealized in abstraction. There is thus in each beginning of
individuation a concrete point—the seed of form—and an abstract point—the absolute
origin of individuation. From which it follows that individuation corresponds to a
passage from the formless to the formal, which simultaneously determines the seed of
form and its subsequent structures.
This passage depends on potentials. In spite of the possible split between the
virtual and the actual—so characteristic of topology, differential calculus and Leibniz's
theory of infinitesimals—, potentials belonging to different orders of magnitude do
enter in relation with one another. Only this allows for individuation to commence and
terminate. This is clearly explained by Simondon in the following passage: “There is a
'disparity' when two twin sets that cannot be entirely superimposed, such as the left
retinal image and the right retinal image, are grasped together as a system, allowing for
the formation of a single set of a higher degree which integrates their elements thanks to
a new dimension” (1995, p. 203). It is therefore the conjunction of what is disjunct and
not compatible in absolute that allows for the emergence of novel dimensions in the
overall development of a system of individuation. Only on the condition of this sort of
incompatibility can a system of potentials access its preindividual reality and
individuate what is not yet completely determined. In sum, the preindividual can be
distinguished from a system's potentials insofar as it corresponds to the activation of an
62
amplification in resonance.
From this standpoint, and confirming what has already been said, it can be
posited that the preindividual is activated only on the condition of a disparity between
potentials belonging to an individual's associated milieu. From such activation follows
the structuration of a new individual order. In regard to such order, what is most
important to retain is the fact that the novel structure is primarily defined as relation, i.e.
as being both the relation of its remarkable points to one another and the relation of the
structure to its ground. This definition of the individual as relation results in fact from
the system's internal resonance. For, as Simondon recalls, relation is “an aspect of the
internal resonance of a system of individuation” (2005, p. 29). The individual is not
determined relatively to an external world, such as an outside observer, but determined
relatively to itself. This aspect of the internal resonance of individuation can be best
understood together with the following passage of French philosopher Muriel Combes's
commentary on Simondon's theory of individuation: “Unless we grasp the importance
of its relation with an associated milieu, we do not understand what the reality of the
individual consists in: the individual, in effect, is not an absolute; by itself alone, it is an
incomplete reality, incapable of expressing the entirety of being; and yet it is not
illusory either, and, associated with a milieu of the same order of magnitude retaining
the preindividual, the individual acquires the consistency of a relation.” (2013, p. 21).
Being relative to itself, the individual consists with itself by reason of its difference to
itself. The difference between its remarkable points and its associated milieu assures the
individual's self-consistency. From which it follows that relation itself emerges with the
constitution of individuals. Relation shouldn't be conceived as what is established
between two preexisting individuals, but rather as what individuates with the
constitution of individuals as relation. Simondon adverts: “it is because terms are
conceived as substances that relation is a relationship between terms, and being is
separated into terms because it is conceived as substance, primitively, prior to any
examination of individuation.” (2005, p. 32). Hence, if individuation is granted to
encompass as many individuals as allowed by the plurality of a system of being,
individuals themselves must be conceived as relation. And how could it not be so, if
what defines an individual is the internal spacing and the external contrast of an
associated milieu?
63
2.3 - Transindividuation
When passing from the physical domain to the domain of living beings,
Simondon asserts one major difference: while the individuation of the physical being
happens “in one step, […] the living being conserves in itself an activity of permanent
individuation” (1992, p. 305). The reason for this lies precisely in what the living stands
for: an ongoing constitution of problems, from which follows the continuous emergence
of novel states of resolution. “[I]n order to exist, [the living being] needs to be able to
continue individualizing by resolving problems in the milieu surrounding it, which is its
milieu” (Ibid., p. 305).
64
pace. From which it follows that the dephasing of breath corresponds to the
individuation of a novel period in the cycles of respiration.
These two domains, the psychic and the somatic, are here said to result from a
series of correlated individuations, rather than pertaining to an irreducible
psychosomatic unity. Which is by no means a “body-mind” Cartesian duality. The
reason why Simondon doesn't understand the psychosomatic individual as a seamless
unity should rather be understood in terms of the rhythm of individuation that occurs in
a heterogeneous field of potentials. Such rhythm follows from the conjunction of
disjunctive series (psychic and somatic) in the system's overall development. There is an
affective correlation between series that punctuates their differences and creates a
singular psychosomatic nexus. Rhythm is key for understanding the differences between
nexus and unity. When capturing one another, the series intensify their correlative
differences and pose problems for the system to cancel. But since the system continues
to individuate, because it is alive, these series can continue to affect one another and to
intensify their differences. The result is a psycho-somatic rhythm of problematization
Another example are breathing techniques used in yogic traditions (i.e. pranayama): they also effect
changes at the level of cellular metabolism, to the point of being used by apnea divers to lower the
body's consumption of oxygen and prolong the duration of aquatic submersion.
65
and resolution that, inasmuch as it results from the remarked correlation of one same set
of series, has a proper nexus.65 Hence, the psychosomatic nexus, instead of being a
homogeneous unity, as it tends to be considered by some holistic approaches, or what
results from a relation between distinct systems, as proponents of the body-mind duality
such as Andy Clark (1998) would have it, is to be thought as a heterogeneous field that,
even after individuation, does not cease to be plural and differentiated. In each living
system there is a characteristic nexus composed by disparate series of somatic and
psychic resolutions that, while intensifying their difference by means of a reciprocal
affectivity, structure the individual across different levels of psychosomatic resonance.66
65 It is worth noting that, later on this study, choreography will also be discussed according to this
definition of nexus. See Section 3.1.
66 The upshot of this being that what distinguishes man from animal is not a difference in nature but a
difference in degree of structuration (Simondon, 2005, p.272).
66
challenge in which the individuated being explores the dimensions of its being without
being able to progress beyond them.” From which it follows that the conditions of
psychic individuation, whereby the individual resolves its self-incompatibility,
necessarily comprise potentials other than those of the system in tension. The conditions
of psychic individuation coincide with the conditions of what Simondon calls
“collective individuation”. This corresponds to saying that the resolution of the living
individual cannot take place without the plural dimension of its affective-perceptive
nexus, i.e. without the fact that, in order to individuate thought, a living individual must
enter in relation with other individuals. As such, psychic individuation is necessarily
accompanied by the individuation of a collective, that is, by the constitution of a field of
relations comprising different individuals.
The affective problematic can thus be seen as a tendency in the living individual
towards participating in collective individuations. And inasmuch as the collective is a
fundamental condition for the individuation of psychic resolutions, both individuations,
the psychic and the collective, cannot be accounted for but in relation to one another.
Precisely because of their inextricable relation, the affective-perceptive field of a living
system should be understood as belonging to one overall psychic-collective
individuation. This overall character of the living is explained by Simondon in the
following way: “the psyche is composed of successive individuations, which allow the
being to resolve its problematic states by effectuating permanent communications
between that which is larger than it and that which is smaller than it” (1992, p. 310). In
a sense, this posits that the external milieu of the psychic individual cannot be but a
collective of other psychic individuals with which the former communicates and co-
individuates. Similarly, in the individuation of the living in general, any individual is the
intermediate process of an ongoing communication between individuals belonging to
orders of magnitude that are larger and smaller than it.
67
individuates”, it is not the relation between individuals that constitutes the collective but
rather the “individuation of the collective that is relation between individuated beings”
(2005, p. 313). Relation, as event, does not precede the collective. Instead, it coincides
with its very individuation. It emerges in the individuating system together with the
terms that will end up relating. Neither relation nor its terms precede one another. And
neither the one nor the others anticipate the individuation that constitutes them.
As with the physical individual, after having individuated, the living individual
keeps with itself the potentials that first allowed for its structuration. There is a process
that goes from the individuation of the physical domain to the individuation of the vital
domain and further into transindividuation, all by means of the potentials that each
individual conserves with itself after cancelling an initial difference. Accordingly, there
is for Simondon an individuation of the universe that comprises in its different phases
its multiple manifestations. In transindividuation, the animal and the human, the
individual and the collective, rather than being different in nature, are conceived as
different phases of one same big system of individuation. The human, “having available
more extended psychic possibilities, in particular due to the resources of symbolism,
more frequently calls on psyche [...]”. Conversely, “[...] the vital situation is exceptional
in the human, and thus humans feel more destitute. But it is not a matter of a nature, an
essence serving to found an anthropology; it is simply that a threshold is crossed”.
68
(2005, p. 165). The same goes for the history of technics, in regard to which the
philosopher identifies different phases of development: the phase “anterior to the use of
the tool and the instrument”; the phase “of the tool, the instrument”; the phase “of the
machine-tool and the machine”; and the phase of “reticulation” (2006b, p. 104).67 All
these different phases of one same system of individuation result from its progressive
structuration across domains. From which it follows that the domains of
transindividuation cannot be considered separately from one another. As Simondon
notes, there is a “persistence of the primitive and original phase of being in the second
phase, and this persistence implies a tendency toward a third phase, which is that of the
collective” (2005, p. 305). All domains, as phases of one overall individuation, share
this primitive and original phase, which is the very field of their immanent and
continuous relationship.
69
not only the nature of the collective as reality in becoming, but also the nature of
psychic individuality.” (2013, pp. 40–41).
69 That the human is constitutively deficient and that it depends on technical individuation to
supplement this originary lack is a premise that has guided French philosopher Bernard Stiegler in his
theoretical project “Technics and Time” (1998). Since Stiegler's philosophy is much influenced by
Simondon's theory of individuation, it is here worth noting that, notwithstanding this influence,
Stiegler has been pointed to misread Simondon and to not account for the creative capacities of the
transindividual. This critique is, for example, addressed to Stiegler by Combes in the follow ing way:
“While he thoroughly stigmatizes those who 'do not accept that […] humans are prosthetic beings',
Stiegler does not seem to countenance the possibility that humans share more than default or lack. Yet
such a possibility seems to me to be the lesson to draw from Simondon's hypothesis on the existence
of preindividual potential associated with individuals, on their common belonging to an ontological
dimension preceding them; and nothing in it forces us to conceive of preindividual as technological.
If human individuals should not be conceived on the basis of fixed bioanthropological nature, I do not
see why they should be conceived on the basis of original defect that we then take pains to call
originary in entirely metaphysical nostalgia for foundations.” (2013, p. 69).
70
the individuation of knowledge depends on the constitution of a transindividual order,
knowledge cannot but result from the relation between two distinct individuations: the
one of the subject and the one of the object. Hence, as Simondon puts it, “[i]t is neither
immediate nor mediate knowledge that we can have of individuation, but a knowledge
that is an operation that runs parallel to the known operation. We cannot, in the common
understanding of the term, know individuation, we can only individuate, individuate
ourselves, and individuate within ourselves.” (2009, p. 13). Knowledge is a relation
between two operations, of the analogical kind.
71
554), knowledge is said to result from “an initial tropistic or taxonomic unity, a pairing
of sensation and tropism, an orientation of the living being in a polarized world” (Ibid.,
p. 4). As such, it is not something that occurs inside an individual. The very notion of
transindividual invalidates any idealistic conception of representation positing that the
external world is reproduced, or even reproducible, by an individual's thought. This is a
notion similar to the ones of embeddedness and embodiment, as these were developed
by theories that strived both to put aside the Cartesian split between idealism and
materialism and to reconsider the co-implication of individuals and environment in the
constitution of knowledge (Maturana, 1975; Varela et al., 1992; Johnson, 1987, 2012;
Clark, 1998, 2008; Noë, 2004; Gallagher, 2005). And here too, in Simondon's theory of
individuation, this co-implication is a fundamental condition for the constitution of
knowledge. The polar forces that pervade an individual because of its embeddedness in
an associated milieu are the ground on which both problems and resolutions can occur,
providing therefore the system of individuation with the capacity to generate novel
states of relation. Be it from the perspective of perception or from the perspective of
thought, these novel states of relation correspond to determinate orientations of the
individual in its milieu. They correspond to the tendencies that the relation between the
two generates within the mediation of what is both larger and smaller than the
individual.
72
knowledge finds its own validity. Or, in other words, the resolution of a problem of self-
incompatibility in the system of being finds its emergent sense in the latter's tropisms
relatively to the charged ground of its associated milieu. Any instance of knowledge is
therefore most valid when with regard to the inextricable relation between individual
and milieu from which it stems and to which it belongs. Valid knowledge must be
situated.
73
the individuation, rather than the individuation through the individual.” (Simondon,
2009, p. 5). The entirety of process must be acknowledged and accounted for. For if an
individual is never only a structure, coincident with itself, but also the contrasting
ground of its associated milieu, then the intricate relation between sameness and
difference needs too to be accounted for in what regards the constitution of knowledge.
The point is that the conditional problems of individuation can only appear at the level
of this relation, that is, at the level at which the individual's excess over itself marks not
only its self-coincidence but also its self-differentiation. Only by taking into
consideration this relationship between identity and difference, between structure and
milieu, can individuation be properly understood. Likewise, knowledge needs to be
approached in accordance with the dynamisms of affect between what is both different
and identical to itself in the process of its own individuation.
74
transduction is used “to understand a domain of reality, indicates that this domain is
indeed the location of a transductive structuration” (1992, pp. 313–314). In fact, only
because the individuation of being unfolds through a progressive structuration of
potentials, can knowledge receive from this same individuation the principles necessary
for its own constitution. “Logically”, concludes Simondon, transductive knowledge
“can be used as the foundation of a new species of analogical paradigms so as to enable
us to pass from physical individuation to organic individuation, from organic
individuation to psychic individuation, and from psychic individuation to the subjective
and objective level of the transindividual [...]” (Ibid., pp. 311–314).
In order to account for the fact that knowledge individuates with the
individuation of the being known and that, as such, it depends on the fundamental
conditions of transindividuation, Simondon engendered the concept of the
“allagmatic”70. In itself a theory of knowledge, the allagmatic strives to account for
constitutive differences in the relationship between structures and processes. It is based
on the speculation that transduction transfers information not only across domains but,
primarily, across states of structural organization. The neutral point of individuation
necessarily occurs together with the seed of form and therefore with structures of
remarkable points. From which it follows that the individuation of knowledge depends
on transfers of energy between the given and the emergent, i.e. between the initial
conditions of individuation and what emerges from them. The allagmatic refers to this
70 The Greek root of this term is allagma, which can mean either change or vicissitude. But in
Simondon's use of it, allagma is more correctly understood as that which can be given or taken in
exchange.
75
conversion of structures into processes and of processes into structures. It refers to the
primacy of relation in process, which regards the inextricable affectivity between the
determinate and the undetermined. The mutual convertibility between structures and
operations that the allagmatic proposes regards the transfer of information in dephasing:
from one phase to the next the system operates its potentials for resolution, enhancing
the power of undetermined potentials over determinate structures (structure-operation
conversion) and resolving co-related problems with the structuration of potentials
(operation-structure conversion). For this reason, Simondon tells us that the allagmatic
is “prior to any distinction or opposition between operation and structure” (1992, p. 29).
Because it is mostly concerned with “the rigorous and valid relation between structural
knowledge and operative knowledge” (2005, p. 565), it strives for encompassing the
whole of individuation, that is, for encompassing both analytical perspectives, which
reduce the whole to parts, and analogical ones, which equate the whole with structural
change. The pertinence of the allagmatic derives therefore from the fact that neither
structural knowledge nor operational knowledge suffice to know the whole of being.
Only their relation, which is an individuation in itself, can provide the necessary
insights into the immanent principle of relation between structures and operations,
which is the very unity of being.
2.5 - Networks
When considering the relation between humans and machines and the possibility
of technogenesis, one of the first questions that comes to mind is: how should the
associated milieu of machines be understood? In other words, if a technical system is to
be granted the capacity of changing, how is it that the potentials of individuation are
related to technical individuals, such as machines and larger technical ensembles? How
is the becoming of technical individuals to be understood if, in any case, it is arguable
that technics are a mere result of humans' cognitive life? In order to address these
questions, the notion of machine in Simondon's theory of individuation must be first
addressed.
76
abstraction to expression, what emerges with invention is both a technical individual
and its associated milieu. Whereas the abstraction of the machine lacks concreteness
and therefore possesses no associated milieu, the concrete machine individuates
together with its own internal and external milieus. Technical individuation thus opens
the internal character of pure abstraction to the indetermination of potentials belonging
to the machine's associated milieu. Simondon approaches the machine's internal milieu
in terms of its “recurrent causality” (Ibid., p. 53). When being invented, the machine
becomes progressively concrete and, in this way, determined. With such progression, a
set of possibilities is formed and limited by the actual affordances of the elements in the
composition. If subtracting possibilities corresponds to building one particular machine,
the resulting affordances relate its elements to one another according to an equally
particular mode of recurrence. In short, the machine recurs in the possibility of its own
functioning. On its turn, the external milieu of the machine corresponds to what
Simondon calls a “technogeographical milieu” (Ibid., p. 48). Only by being open to
what is different from itself can the machine exchange information and be in relation
with, most notably, other machines. In this case, and because each machine has its own
internal milieu, the associated milieu is that which connects an internal spacing of
recurrent causality to an external contrast of recurrent causality. It is by exchanging
information between internal and external milieus that machines can assure their
metastability. The machinic character of technical individuals assures a dependence
between the recurrent causalities of different milieus. This dependency attests that
variations in the recurrence of internal milieus necessarily induce changes in the
recurrence of external milieus, if granted that machines are to be kept in form. This is a
metastable self-regulation that brings machines closer to living beings than to physical
ones, for what results from it is their very capacity to process information.
Simondon also defines the machine as that “which carries tools and directs
them” (1969, p. 78). For the author, there are “simple, passive machines”, such as “the
handle”, defined by being capable of transforming movement; there are “machine-tools”
or “active machines”, which are “semi-autonomous”, that is, “autonomous for their
energy and heteronomous for information”; and finally there are “reflexive and
informational machines”, defined by being “autonomous for both alimentation and
information during its functioning, with information being delivered as a ground before
the functioning”. (2006, pp. 97–98). And in regard to the latter, he establishes an
important distinction between the automaton of cybernetics and that which he calls the
open machine: “The notion of a perfect automaton conceals a contradiction: the
77
automaton would be a machine so perfect that the margin of indetermination in its
functioning would be non-existent, while it would still be able to receive, interpret, or
send out information” (1969, p. 140). Being that, for Simondon, information is the
process whereby an incompatibility between potentials is resolved, the inherent
contradiction of the automaton lies precisely in the fact that its closure doesn't allow for
the indetermination of the potentials in information. Being closed in itself, the pure
automaton is incapable of accessing its preindividual reality and cannot therefore
transform and resolve its own disparities. For this reason, Simondon proffers that “there
is no such thing as a robot” (1969, p.10).
78
permanent inventor and coordinator of the machines around him.” (1969, pp. 11–12).
This description is somewhat close to examples given by theories of distributed
cognition, such as the one proffered by Edwin Hutchins (1995a), which focus on the
interaction between the external and internal structures of representation. “Distributed
cognition allows the examination of the role of the material media in which
representations are embodied, and the physical processes that propagate representations
across media” (Hutchins, 1995b, p. 226). It emphasizes the fact that cognizing processes
are not exclusive of any single, isolated agent, but rather occur across the interiority of
human agents and the exteriority of media. A paradigmatic example of distributed
cognition is the way in which an airplane's cockpit remembers its speeds: the cockpit
performs this task via a system of memory comprising both humans and machines (i.e.
pilots, co-pilots, air controllers, satellites, on-board and on-ground computers); no
single part of the system is sufficient for retaining and further remembering the
airplane's speed. Like with Simondon's example of the orchestra, here, the human
coordination of technical objects and machines assures that information is intensive
enough to prompt the technical system into a state of metastability.
79
ensembles is not a fundamental characteristic to them. What is most fundamental to the
technical system are instead the conditions of emergence from which norms individuate.
Such conditions are primary in regard to individuated norms, which are but an
expression of those same conditions. This stands for the case that the technical
individual is more-than-individual, i.e. that it is excessive in relation to itself. The very
fact that the technical individual can only emerge out of already existing networks
attests its incompleteness and specifies that its excess regards the technical network
itself.
It follows that the technical preindividual can only become active by means of
networking. At whatever scale of technical systems, reticulation is what allows them to
become incompatible with themselves and resolve into novel phases. Networks are in
this sense opposed to the kind of hylomorphism that determines the formality of tools.
For, as Simondon says, “we cannot change networks or construct a network ourselves,
[as we do with tools, but only] join up with the network, adapt to it, participate in it”
(1969, p. 221). In short, we can only be an element in the life of technical ensembles.
But it is by means of information that networks are established. Only the self-
incompatibility of a technical system assures necessary conditions of its own internal
resonance. Networks are informed, but they are also the very condition of informational
exchange and resolution. The reticular character of technical systems allows for the
propagation of information, which is the very means by which networks become
topographically determined. In this sense, says Muriel Combes, “[r]eticularity [...] takes
us from a normative horizon to a horizon of amplification of action” (2013, p. 66).
Which means that networks constitute the very condition for information to be
transferred and amplified, without normative predetermination.
Precisely because of this, networks can be seen as the ground of an ethics. For
Simondon, ethics does not pertain to any model of norms imposed on the networkability
of individuals. Rather, it corresponds to the technical act's capacity to transfer and
amplify itself across networks. As the author says, “[e]thical reality is indeed structured
in a network, that is, acts take on resonance in relation to one another […] within the
system they form, which is becoming of being” (2005, p. 333). Since the individuating
system's internal resonance is the conditional network of technical transfers and
amplifications, it is as well the very condition of an ethical relation between different
acts of resolution. Further, it is what results from this same relation. Ethics, as an
individuating resonance that goes “from one act to others in the same way that one may
go from yellow-green to green and to yellow through augmentation in the amplitude of
80
the band of frequencies” (1995, p. 245), depends therefore upon the network's
materiality. The value of an ethical act is given by the amplitude of its effects in a
network of informational exchanges.
81
which is its milieu, both its constitutive principles and its technical character.
There is, according to this, a variable degree of structuration that follows from
transduction. At lower degrees of structuration, the general schema of potentials tends to
71 For a compelling account of soccer's transductive character, see Massumi (2002, pp. 71–83).
82
remain at its own phase, i.e. it is not informed otherwise. 72 The more complexity is
brought to the network, by ingressing and emergent individuals, the more tendencies
will form in the process of transduction itself. With this, novel phases can arise and
reconfigure the system's technicity. At higher degrees of structuration, in which the
formation of an individual does increase the complexity of the network to which it
belongs, technicity changes. There are limit-points in the process of technical
transduction where the progressive structuration of potentials moves from a lower level
of complexity to a higher one. These are the singularities—attractors and bifurcations—
in the vicinity of which an accumulation of tendencies occurs, towards dephasing. When
dephasing, the technical system goes from one state of recurrence to another through a
reconfiguration of its own technicity.
If technicity is, as Simondon says, “the quality of an element by which what has
been acquired in a technical ensemble expresses and conserves itself in being
transported to a new period” (1969, p. 73), then it corresponds to the potentials moved
with each transduction. But since these potentials implicate their own schema,
technicity also needs to be considered in abstraction, that is, in accordance with the
abstract facet that, beyond potentiality, thinks technics. As mentioned before in regard to
the invention of machines, the concretization of technical thought necessarily moves
from the inexistence of a milieu to the creation of one associated with the emergent
individuals. At the level of pure abstraction, there is no technicity whatsoever. But for
what matters here, i.e. for the relation between abstract schematics and concrete
technics, what is important to retain is the fact that abstraction is not temporally anterior
to concretization. Abstraction is immanent in this process and in the resulting
individuals. It is immanent in the potentials mobilized with transduction and in the
emergent technicity. From this standpoint, it is important to acknowledge that the
abstractions from which invention draws its predicaments are transformed with the
process of invention itself. The technical qualities expressed and conserved by
transduction not only correspond to the moved potentials but also to the virtual ideas
from which actual solutions are drawn. With the inventive restructuration of potentials,
abstractions can themselves change. For technical novelty can actually convey ideas
capable of reforming previous ones. Hence, it is here, at the level of technicity's
72 This is the case when, for example, in the serial fabrication of technical elements at an industrial
facility, a novel element comes to being, but only as one amongst a discrete multiplicity of many
others like it, which in themselves don't change the technicity of the system to which they belong.
Any element repeating without difference the technicity already present in its own enabling
conditions cannot be said to contribute to changes in the technicity of the system to which it belongs,
i.e. it cannot be said to change the schema of the larger technical ensembles conditioning it.
83
immanent relation between abstraction and expression, that its transduction can be fully
understood: while transferring and amplifying resolutions and their implicated
problems, transduction simultaneously prompts the emergence of novel expressions and
the determination of implicated ideas.
84
diagrammatic structure has been transmitted from body to body. What happens in the
body-to-body transmission of physical skills is precisely a transduction. The diagram
that organizes the potentials of one's body will in the same way organize the potentials
of someone else's body, despite their different expressions (just think of a dance class).
The technical act's transductive character is manifested in the different expressions that
different bodies can yield by affecting one another. As such, it is not guided by
principles of formal identity but rather by principles of individuation. More than
knowing the technical act by its results, it matters to know it by the forces of resonance
with which its abstractions affect its expressions. It matters to know it in accordance
with the mode by which its technicity ingresses into the actual constraints of bodily
expression. Only in such processual way can a technique be known, not as static form,
but as generative force.
85
for the understanding that choreographic knowledge can only be constituted anew by
means of a dynamic and affective interplay between abstraction and expression. In this
sense, choreographic objects can and will be defined as technical objects. Because of
their networks, they can be understood neither exclusively in abstract terms nor
exclusively in concrete terms. Their processual character calls for the understanding
that, only by means of a difference between potentials, can they be determined and
expressed as singular movements of choreographic thought.
From this standpoint, it matters to continue unfolding the resonance that the
thought of technical individuation might have with choreography in general and with a
series of choreographic objects in particular. The following Chapter will follow this
relation and start to layout the terms of a theory of choreography that looks upon objects
as processes and upon processes as movements of thought.
86
Chapter 3 - CHOREOTECHNICS
This chapter's three sections will essay a conception of choreography under the
light of Simondon's philosophy. More specifically, the notions of choreographic system,
choreographic knowledge and choreographic object will be explored in accordance with
the abstractions, transductions and expressions of individuation. First, the potentials of
choreography will be tackled from the perspective of dance's relationship with writing.
Such relationship will be conceived as being problematic and, precisely because of this,
potential with regard to the individuation of novel instances of choreographic
knowledge. Moreover, the resolution of such problematic potentials will be defined in
terms of a continuous differentiation of serial parts that, inasmuch as the latter regard
movement-events, expresses choreography as such. Second, the choreographic object
will be defined after the argument that choreography can exist without dance. Such
argument allows not only for thinking choreography in abstraction, but also for defining
the choreographic object as a diagrammatic structure of potentials, from which many
different expressions can result. By defining the choreographic object is this way, it will
be emphasized that, rather than this being an ideal form, it is a system of potential
transductions most apt to elicit the transindividuation of subjective and objective
perspectives upon one same epistemological relation. Third, the notion of choreographic
object will be further explored by analyzing a paradigmatic example of how
choreography can be expressed by means other than dance. By looking into William
Forsythe's collection of choreographic objects “Improvisation Technologies”, it will be
argued that the choreographic object is characteristically topological and, as such,
capable of expressing the same diagram of potentials, not only in different ways but
also, and more importantly, in different domains of expression. From this, the
choreographic object's topological character will be explored together with notions of
memory and rhythm. It will be argued that only by means of conceiving memory both in
terms of perception and forgetting can the choreographic object's topological potentials
be understood to be creative. Additionally, it will be argued that neither abstraction nor
expression suffice to define choreography. Their affective becoming needs to be
considered as an irreducible whole, most fundamentally defined by rhythmic ideas of
movement.
87
3.1 - Choreography's Excess
88
resolutions.
Amidst the general becoming of technics, and alongside its many different
expressions, the encounter between dance and technology must be defined by means
with a proper character. The question is: which kind of networks are proper to this
species of encounter? Or, in other words, what is its characteristic technicity? The
answer resides in what has been, from its first manifestations to the present, a prevalent
mode of individuation in the history of encounters between dance and technology,
namely, choreography. From the outset, choreography has established a relation
between dance and writing: Thoinot Arbeaus's “Orchesography” (1925), choreography's
first treatise, founded the writing of dance in the European Renaissance as a technology
of transmission and regulation; from this moment onwards, the organization of gestures
and bodies in time and space had no longer to be passed directly from a dance master to
his students, but could be learnt at a distance, via writing. About this fundamental
project, dance scholar André Lepecki comments that it was established on the basis of a
“semiotic symmetry between writing and dancing that guarantees the unproblematic
traffic from one to the other” (2004, p. 126). This equation, between dancing and
writing, served to further establish conventional codes, such as Feuillet's notation (1701),
the use of which facilitated choreographers' hermeneutic authority over the dances. In
this sense, what might have been first a drive to not forget and remember the dances, led
to an “apparatus of capture” that mostly served their regulation. “To conceive
choreography as an apparatus”, says Lepecki, “is to see it as a mechanism that
simultaneously distributes and organizes dance’s relationship to perception and
signification. For it is precisely this kind of organization of the perceptive-linguistic
field that apparatuses perform” (2007, p. 120). But the incapacity of writing to transmit
the essential traits of dance was a preoccupation that soon became manifest, most
notably with dance master Jean-Georges Noverre. Identifying this transition, Lepecki
further writes: “[...] from a perception of dance as unproblematically translatable from
code to steps, and from steps back to code again (a peacefully symmetry between
inscription and dancing that characterizes […] Arbeau's and Feuillet's perception), we
arrive, with Noverre, to an understanding of dance as elusive presence, dance as the
fleeting trace of an always irretrievable, never fully translatable motion: neither into
notation, nor into writing.” (22004, p. 127). Which is an argument that came to define a
longstanding tradition in claiming that performance is fundamentally irreducible and
irretrievable; a tradition that has had as prominent advocates figures as influent as
Antonin Artaud (Derrida, 1978), Richard Schechner (2011, p. 50) and Peggy Phelan
89
(1993, p. 146). This is the argument that performance is defined as that which comes
into presence—a unitary, self-identical, and non-linguistic presence conveying that
which nothing but performance itself can convey. In this sense, and in spite of possible
recursions of the live event, immediate presence is taken to be that which holds the
truth-value of performance, for only through performance can there take place an
irreducible experience that cannot be mediated otherwise. Reinforcing the irreducibility
of performance is the argument that the event of presence in performance is a fleeting
one, vanishing at the very moment of its appearance. Performance, as such, is
irretrievable, for it is impossible to retain it without loosing its fundamental character,
that of being always transient.
73 For a list of reenactments of “Le Sacre du Printemps”, see “Stravinsky: The Global Dancer: A
Chronology of Choreography to the Music of Igor Stravinsky”, in http://ws1.roehampton.ac.uk/stravi
90
of that time, it is symptomatic that 2013 was the year in which a wide range of
expressions took place, commemorating the work's centenary and showing its influence
to this date. Today, not only all sorts of artistic reformulations and reinterpretations of
“Le Sacre du Printemps” can be seen, from video works to performances and festivals
dedicated to it (many due to the fact of its everlasting influent and still today actual
soundtrack), but also discursive embeddings of the work can be found allover, notably
in the theoretical production of disciplines such as performance and dance studies. “Le
Sacre du Printemps” can be seen as one big system of performance, encompassing all of
its variable expressions and potentials of transformation.
With all its creative capacities, choreography corresponds in a very precise way
to what French philosopher Michel Foucault has defined as “archive”. For the author,
the archive is that which “reveals the rules of a practise that enables statements both to
survive and to undergo regular modification. [The archive] is the general system of the
formation and transformation of statements” (2007, p. 102). In this sense, the
ontological predicate according to which performance is irreducible and irretrievable
nsky/index.asp.
91
must give way to the ontogenetic depiction of choreography's overall development as a
system of assertion. Which is not to say that the event of performance does not possess
a singular and irretrievable character, but rather to affirm that this uniqueness partakes
in a larger context of enunciation that also conditions its transformed recursions. As
archive, choreography can be said to be a system of assertion that most fundamentally
regards ideas of movement. Between a field of potentials and a series of assertions, what
forms and transforms in the archive of choreography are problems and resolutions of
movement. Choreography's capacity for expressing movement ideas in different ways
attests its excessive reality, i.e. it attests the fact that it is itself a system of individuation
including both a preindividual reality and an individual order of assertion. The very
asymmetry between dancing and writing corresponds to the problems that determinate
ideas of movement posit to the system to which they belong in the process of their own
assertion. When asserted in several instances, the same idea can differ from itself by
creating problems to the choreographic system. Once again, it should be acknowledged
that what intensifies the becoming of a choreographic system is the dynamic interplay
between the virtual and the actual, i.e. the interplay between an idea of movement and
the actual constraints exerted upon its own assertion. The asymmetry of choreography's
expressions, rather than revealing the incompleteness of each of them relatively to one
another, simply manifests the system's transformative capacities. With each
individuation, choreography expresses differently the problematic reality of its own
ideas. Writing and dancing do not complete one another for the expression of one
choreographic totality, but rather correspond to the expression of ideas that, moving
through different conditions, express each time anew the ground from which they stem.
The argument that writing supplements the event is in this way converted into a
productive relation between the two. The asymmetry between writing and dancing
corresponds precisely to choreography's capacity for activating potentials, resolving
itself into the emergence of yet another actual expression. Even Jacques Derrida's
deconstructions accord to this in their own way: having extensively dwelt upon the
conception that writing supplements the event, compensating its irretrievability, Derrida
has shown how in fact the “supplement” is “undecided [between] accretion and
substitution”; it is “not a signified more than a signifier, a representer than a presence, a
writing than a speech” (1976, p. 315). This undecidability of writing marks the fact that
what recurs with its assertion can both supplement its referent, and thus remain indexed
by it, and substitute it with its own autonomy, as a generative regime of signs. Writing
can both depend on the contexts of its inscription and be an autopoietic system. Beyond
92
the supplementary logic that writing may be said to commit to, adding to the event,
writing is also capable of generating reality by its own means. Regarding its autonomy,
Derrida further says that “[f]or a writing to be a writing it must continue to 'act' and to
be readable even when what is called the author of the writing no longer answers for
what he has written, for what he seems to have signed, be it because of a temporary
absence, because he is dead or, more generally, because he has not employed his
absolutely actual and present intention or attention, the plenitude of his desire to say
what he means, in order to sustain what seems to be written 'in his name'.” (1982, p.
307). An argument that, at once, invokes the fact that the intentions of a writer aren't
assured to be accessed via the written, and that the written can in fact act on its own,
away from hermeneutic regulations. In the cases where dances are transmitted via
writing, not only characteristic of the Renaissance but also of such massive projects as
the development of Labanotation throughout the twentieth century, or even of more
recent projects such as those discussed throughout in this study, this autonomy of
writing attests the fact that, regarding the overall system of assertion that it partakes,
writing stands on its own feet as the choreographic expression of movement ideas.
Hence, writing doesn't require supplements of any sort. It is fully capable of expressing
movement ideas. A corollary that, in relation to the ontological definition of
performance as transient and irreducible, posits as well the singular capacities of other
modes of expression. If performance conserves an irretrievable character, then writing
itself is capable of conveying that which only writing can convey. Both dancing and
writing are fully capable of problematizing and resolving ideas of movement.
93
been performing repeatedly for some time, what necessarily takes place is a resolution
of the problems posed by the emergent relation between what is actuality given (e.g. the
muscular memory, or patterned habit, of each dancing body) and what is not (i.e. the
indetermination implied in recollecting what had not been remembered until that very
moment). Despite the fact that each performance necessarily corresponds to the singular
resolution of problems, what is transposed from one event to the next is precisely this
problematic potential of choreographic memory, as it persists in each dancing body.
The invariant functions of choreography are not the substances of its identity. To
say that a system of choreographic individuation does not vary throughout its
development and across its expressions corresponds to saying that a principle of
individuation is transduced throughout the multiple modulations of the system's
potentials. To ask what is a choreographic principle of individuation is to ask “what is a
choreography?”, a question to which Portuguese philosopher José Gil answers with: “it
is a nexus of movements” (2001, p. 81, my translation) . With this answer, the author
already acknowledges that movement is double. On the one hand, movement is virtual
and contributory, ingressing into actuality and traversing all occasions of experience
(what the author calls “whole movement”). On the other hand, it corresponds to the
actual expressions of the ongoing transformation of states. Understanding choreography
as a nexus of movements is to acknowledge the dynamic interplay between the virtual
and the actual. In this way, choreography is understood as comprising simultaneously
the movements of thought initiated by a problematic idea and the expressive movements
of the latter's resolution. Furthermore, for Gil, a nexus “is dictated neither by its
expressivity nor by its finality” (Ibid). Rather a nexus is said to result from the
combination of series that, notwithstanding the fact of being divergent, are continuous
to one another. This is no paradox, for their continuity is the continuity of their
differences. Only by means of relating continuously to one another, can divergent series
intensify their differences. From which it follows that a nexus can be defined as the
rhythmic intensification of differences between series that, in this way, become
continuous to one another as the multiple parts of one whole. According to Gil, “[t]he
rhythm assures the distances [between the series] in continuity, allowing for an
uninterrupted movement of differentiation that modulates time [...] and the internal
distance to the intervals” (Ibid., pp. 86–87, my translation). This can be understood by
simply considering a dancing body and the movement of its musculoskeletal regions.
For example, the movement of one foot and the movement of one hand involve different
regions of the musculoskeletal system. While moving simultaneously, the different
94
series of each movement region form a rhythm by continuously intensifying their
differences. The differential intensification of the series actually defines each of them in
the continuous relation to the other. This is the nexus of their choreography, be the
dance a more or less determinate one.74 The nexus, rather than being given, is emergent.
From which one possible conclusion can be drawn: the choreographic nexus is not
given and emerges with each choreographic process that it comes to define because of
being relative to the absolute event of its own appearance.75 What is transduced
throughout a choreographic system's development is the relativity of its nexus' formal
structure to its own “absolute origin”. This allows for one same principle of
individuation to resume itself across different events of expression. Hence, the invariant
function of choreography, which is its principle of individuation, corresponds to the
event of rhythm, which is the recurrent intensification of differences between the series
of a multiplicity. Choreography is the nexus that forms when the series of movement-
events intensify their differences to the point of becoming continuous to one another
and, by these means, constituting a whole.
From this standpoint, it can be said that the technicity of the encounter between
dance and technology regards most fundamentally the rhythm of individuation of
movement ideas. Which is also to say that choreography's associated milieu, its
technical network, is informed with the resolution of the problems posed by such ideas
to the dedicated domains of individuation. And if the principle of choreographic
individuation corresponds to a nexus' relativity to its own “absolute origin”, then this
relativity must be related to what lies at the heart of an incompatibility between
potentials, notably the disparity of a movement idea. This disparity can be thought as
pertaining to the problems posed to a process when in face of its actual conditions. A
movement idea is never exactly the same as its possible expressions because, in
individuation, undetermined potentials persist in exerting their force upon what is given.
Despite the margins of indetermination built into a system, movement ideas will always
bear a difference in regard to the possibilities of their own expression. Besides, this
disparity can be thought as pertaining to the fact that, without actuality, an idea cannot
acquire a resolute definition. Its abstract reality is fundamentally indefinite and therefore
74 For Gil (2001, p. 81), the requirements of a choreographic nexus are as strong in improvised dances
as in choreographed ones, a demand that attests how much choreographic individuation involves a
multiplicity of processes and structures (i.e. a whole of which the choreographic nexus is only one
part), each of them with its proper nexus.
75 Much in the same way as the “seed of form” of individuation is not given but nonetheless determines
the tropisms of the individuating system where it comes to occur. For more on this subject see pages
60-62.
95
assures its openness to the potentials of the system to which it belongs,. Only by means
of this relation can a movement idea be not only relative to its different modes of
expression but also relative to the absolute potential of its own appearance. It is
disparate in relation to itself because it mediates between the virtual and the actual the
rhythm of its own choreographic nexus. And if, as Adrian Mackenzie tells us, “[t]o think
transductively is to mediate between different orders, to place heterogeneous realities in
contact, and to become something different” (2002, p. 18), then the nexus of the
encounter between dance and technology is that which results from this very mediation.
Choreography can thus be said to correspond to a transductive mode of thought that
differentiates its movement ideas according to a rhythm of individuation: it
differentiates them in relation to themselves with the disparition of the problematic
conditions of their own appearance; and it differentiates them and in relation to the
progressive structuration of potentials, by means of which multiple series
simultaneously diverge and intensify their differences. In sum, the technicity of
choreography corresponds to the rhythm with which a network of movement ideas is
(in)formed, to the point of expressing a determinate nexus.
96
object as “a model of potential transition from one state to another in any space
imaginable” (Ibid.). A definition which accords with the theory of individuation
expounded before insofar as the model in it included corresponds to the diagram of
choreographic individuation. As already mentioned,76 such diagram is virtual as long as
its potentials are kept apart from concrete individuals. But when mobilized, these are
potentials that tend to be expressed as network: the diagram becomes concrete as a
network of technical objects, of which the choreographic one is a keypoint. Despite its
possible expressions, the choreographic diagram is always abstract and more-than-
individual. In abstraction, it verges towards possibility, creating tendencies in an
otherwise flat field of potentials. This is an asymmetric distribution of possibilities, of
which only particular nexuses can result.77 Hence, to each choreographic object
corresponds a diagram of forces and a rhythm of individuation.
97
onto the virtual. It opens it onto potentials that, though not choreographic per se, assure
the object's capacity to express a determinate nexus of movements.
98
signal whatsoever into different domains of expression. In this sense, it is more likely
for a musical object to be perceived as being as well choreographic than the opposite.
Insofar as music conveys movements with nexus, it can be read as choreographic. To
say that choreographic transductions occur between “any space imaginable” not only
stands for acknowledging the body's capacity to perceive movements with nexus out of,
virtually, anything, but also for acknowledging its capacity to transduce such nexus into
other domains of individuation.
99
orientations (Lingis, 1993). Any sufficiently strong change in the latter will inevitably
change the former, such when the subject experiences the absence of echo (in an
anechoic chamber), only to notice how much its own proprioception depends on the
perception of sound. To a large extent, the synaesthetic resonance of the senses can only
be felt in effect. In the case of heightened synaesthesia, for example, perception informs
the subject of ongoing affects between that which, from a habitual perspective, might be
said to be disjunct, but which from the eventful disruption of the associative habit
indisputably reveals itself as associate and in some way dependent, even if the logic of
such dependence remains unknown, because inaccessible (Campen, 2010).
100
only does this comply with the immanence of abstraction in expression, but more
specifically with the immanence of choreographic thoughts in a relationship between
individual and milieu, where the resolution of problems in perception corresponds to the
individuation of movements with nexus. And how could it not be so, if for there to be a
correspondence between thought and nexus both must individuate from one same
preindividual reality. They both follow from the transductive analogy of their own
processes. An analogy which accords with Simondon's argument that knowledge does
not follow from an inexplicable relation between subjects and objects given by “a priori
forms of sensibility”, but rather from their co-individuation “from the same primitive
reality”.80 To equate choreographic principles with “models of potential transition”
regards not only the fact that any relation between subjects and objects has its proper
nexus, but also the fact that any principle of individuation can only be understood
together with what it gives birth to. Once more, this is the case of the nexus' relativity to
its own absolute origin.81 The case that choreographic principles are not given in
advance to the individuations that they come to energize and structure, but that they are
defined only with the process of individuation itself. A choreographic principle is the
choreographic nexus that comes to be known, it is the diagrammatic arrangement of
forces implicit in the thoughts that from them might result.
It should nonetheless be made clear that, because of its technical character, the
choreographic object relies upon the application of technical acts. Only by becoming a
keypoint in a technical network can the choreographic object transduce its potentials
and become known as such. In contrast to other technical acts, the choreographic one
can be defined by its potentials for eliciting synaesthetic resonances. Only by these
means can thoughts which are truly choreographic acquire some resolute determination.
And due to the analogies of transductive knowledge, what will have become a
choreographic thought must necessarily regard actual forms of informational exchange
defining the relative nexus of movements. The choreographic object is known as such
only within the limits defined by its margins of indetermination, which are determined
by the act itself. The choreographic act modulates the ingression of undetermined
potentials into processes of individuation by determining parameters that will define
each object's choreographic nexus. The readership of choreographic notation makes a
good case for what is a technical act, in the choreographic sense. Once a choreographic
object has been notated, it can only elicit transductions if the body coincides with a
101
signifying agent, i.e. if the subject is constituted on the basis of a capacity to read
notations according to a particular nexus. Choreographic readership is a capacity which
focuses the “wholly design [of the body] to persistently read every signal from its
environment” towards the justification of what it reads as a nexus of movements. It
allows for the body to access choreographic rhythms of intensification and
differentiation, in a continuous relation between signifying series. Such continuity is
assured by the act of reading itself. Reading transduces the choreographic principles
implied in written parameters and allows for modulating processes with determinate
margins of indetermination.
When accounting for the choreographic object's features, for the fact that it is
capable of eliciting technical action, for the fact that it does so with an emphasis on
synaesthesia, and for the fact that synaesthetic indetermination is limited by a set of
parametric constraints, its expression in domains other than the dancing body becomes
somewhat problematic. After all, if all these aspects are to be attained, it is necessary
that the choreographic object is expressed in ways that are worthy of the body's
complexity. Despite Forsythe's assertion that “[c]horeography and dancing are two
distinct and very different practices” (2008, pp. 5–6), in most cases they still remain
bound to each other. Even if they are taken to be autonomous practices, it is via their
102
relationship that the powers and limitations of the one are transferred to the other. When
dancing is put in relation with choreography, the latter's expressions must necessarily
comply with the dancing body's potentials. As such, to express choreography in
domains other than the dancing body while keeping it as referent, i.e. as a possible
receptacle of choreographic transductions, stands for solving the problem of how to
individuate expressions as potential as the dancing body itself.
This is a problem well known to dance notators. As much as the dancing body
implies a variety of infinities, the notation of dance is primarily defined by an exclusive
selection of data. Already in 1930, choreographer Fritz Klingenbeck wrote: “The dance
notator must, along with a trained eye for the rapid perception of movement events,
possess above all an understanding of the actual elements of the dance movement. In
this consideration three factors stand out as particularly important, which the dance
notator must be able to keep apart reliably. First, the actual composition, the naked,
clear structure of the dance, second, the performance, the personal interpretation of the
artist, and third, there are in most cases the factors determining style. It may not be
entirely simple to draw the boundaries between these three factors, especially between
the first two, the composition and the interpretation. […] Thousands of small
movements, phrasings, head, feet, are mainly idiosyncrasies of the performing artist, for
whom it would be absurd to prescribe something else. Thus, there falls on the dance
writer the same difficult and responsible task, namely to strip away all these secondary
manifestations from his notation score and to leave them out of consideration. To
recognise what must be written down, and what not, is not entirely easy, because the
boundaries are always fluid and in most cases it is exactly the secondary manifestations
belonging to the interpretation, which can make a dance interesting and valuable.
Nevertheless, composition and interpretation must be clearly separated from each other
by the dance notator, if another artist is to be able to recreate thereafter.” (1990). More
recently, dance notator Marion Bastien also wrote: “When I was notating with some
maturity [...], I was often thinking that my expertise was not based on how many details
I could write down in the score, but on what I was able to throw away. My greatest
expertise was the ability to filter, to select.” (2007, p. 51). From this standpoint, it
should be noticed that what is actually written from the performance of dance is its
choreographic character. What is selected from the dancing body's varieties are the
parameters of its structured movement. And inasmuch as such parameters individuate
amidst a milieu of bodily potentials, their recognition and notational inscription must
necessarily subtract all that in the dancing body is indivisible. The writing of dance
103
must go from the body's continuous infinity of potentials to the finite and discontinuous
articulation of symbolic notations. In this passage, the notator selects what appears to
define the choreographic nexus, leaving aside all the rest. A subtraction of all that is not
accessible and of all that does not appear to define the nexus of movements. From
which it follows that the choreographic score cannot be but a partial fragment of what
moves when a body dances. A fragment that nonetheless implicates potentials for a
choreographic principle to be further transduced.
The choreographic objects of this collection (around 60) are expressed in the
form of short video recordings over which graphemes are further laid. In each video,
one can watch both Forsythe himself explaining the object's parameters and the graphic
(animated) notation of their formal results. At once, these objects resonate with the
practice of choreographic notation and with the practice of dancing as drawing, a double
82 This CD-ROM was a follow up of a digital archive of movement material used in the making of
performances such as “Loss of Small Detail” (1991) and “Self Meant to Govern” (1994), by the
Ballet Frankfurt.
83 For a listing of these projects, see pages 15-19.
104
connection that is synthesized in the notion of writing, as previously argued. 84 To say
that a gesture can be traced by mapping parameters corresponds to saying that it can be
written for further use. Correspondingly, what in the case of Forsythe's IT is in fact
written are less the resulting forms, as traced by the graphemes, than the ideas
underlying the dancing body's parametric constraining. In this sense, to move the body
according to the idea of, for example, “Dropping Curves” (see Illustration 1, below) is
less to move it in accordance with a given form than with potentials capable of
expressing it. And this is so simply because the diagram of this choreographic object
doesn't map this or that specific curved line, but rather the general potential of any
dropped curve whatsoever.85
In this respect, it is worth noticing that this specific collection of objects results
from an analytical approach to dance where movements are geometrically organized.
This is an approach that can be traced back to Rudolf von Laban’s “kinesphere” (1956),
a geometry which depicts the constant limits of the dancing body. Simply described, this
is a volume the centre of which is placed over the dancer's centre of gravity and further
defined by the multiple points that the body can reach while unchanging its centre. In
short, it is a sphere located around the body, at the distance of its centred reach. In
contrast to this univocal approach, Forsythe grants the body with the capacity to
Illustration 1: William Forsythe exemplifying the object “Dropping Curves”, plus the graphic
notation of the curved line, in “Improvisation Technologies'” CD-ROM (Forsythe, 2012).
105
displace its centre or even to have multiple centres. Its geometries are mobile and
transformative. Not only can the centre of movement migrate throughout the body, but
also can its relative geometries be converted into one another, much in the manner of a
topological form. In fact, it seems to be more correct to consider Forsythe's analysis of
movement in topological terms than in terms of euclidean geometries. After all,
inasmuch as the dancing body serves here as a transducer of abstract potentials, it
cannot know them but by moving (with) them. Such transductions do not occur when
movement just conforms to the reproduction of static figures.
It is perhaps the IT's topological character that is better attained with the
multimodality of each videogram. If on the one hand each choreographic object is
irreducible to danced expressions, verbal explanations and graphemes, on the other hand
it is their articulation that offers insights into the object's potentials. This insight, of
course, is here enhanced by the fact that these expressive modalities are overlapped onto
one another in one same plane of expression. In this way, not only each modality offers
insights into the object's parameters, but their relation forms a nexus with the
multimodal possibilities of digital articulation. What results from the object's
multimodal expression is a relation between nexuses: there is the nexus of each
expressive modality and there is the nexus of their articulate relation. The more nexuses
are articulated, the better the object that they all express becomes defined. The
choreographic object's multimodal expression allows for its parameters to be defined as
what remains invariant across the different modalities involved. As mentioned before,
this invariant function of choreography corresponds to its principle of individuation,
which in turn corresponds to the nexus' relativity to its own absolute origin.86 Insofar as
the nexus' absolute origin is inaccessible, this relativity is nowhere to be found. It is a
virtual potential that can only be accessed in effect. Therefore, if the multimodality of
each IT's videogram expresses invariant parameters, it is only because it implicates
virtual potentials. And it is only by reason of these potentials, which assure each
parametric structure's topology, that a nexus is expressed.
106
following parameters can be depicted: a starting point, a final point and a series of
intermediate points connecting the previous two, not in a straight line, but in a
descendent arc (the final point being lower than the starting point). This structure can be
depicted as well in the dancing body's expressions. But whereas the grapheme doesn't
express data with regard to the dancing body, it is with the latter that the object's
parameters acquire further definition: all the points of the descendent arc coincide with
one single bodily point—in this case, the right hand. Despite its appearance, this is not a
simple parameter. For here it is implied that, while the hand follows the descendent arc,
there occurs a progressive structuration throughout the rest of the body, which organizes
its movements with spiralling forms. This is somewhat inevitable, since spiralling is the
organizational tendency of the musculoskeletal system in movement. In this sense, the
descendent arc, rather than being given, emerges when the dancing body follows the
given parameters, determining in this way the arc's amplitude and length. From this
organizational tendency follows a final parameter, which is made explicit with the
videogram's multimodal nexus: the arc's final point corresponds to the place where the
body's spiralling movement can no longer progress (i.e. most probably the floor). It is
the multimodal nexus that defines most clearly the object's parameters. What is not
expressed with one modality can be made explicit with others. And their relation in
continuity can definitely express what remains without variation.
107
the past as such and the past of every time. In this manner, the forgotten thing appears in
person to the memory which essentially apprehends it.” (1994, p. 140). In a sense, this
notion of transcendental memory corresponds to the general potentials without which no
actualization can ever occur. Only because the potentials of abstraction are in fact the
objects of transcendental memory, can these ingress into particular forms. In contrast,
empirical memory is always relative to the objects of perception. What is given in
perception will become a referent for recognition and prediction. Which implies that the
potentials of the one and the potentials of the other affect one another in the same way
that the virtual and the actual do. In fact, transcendental memory and empirical memory
are just alternative designations for the virtual and for the actual, respectively.
Individuation is conditioned both by what is determinately given—empirical memory as
the actuality of what has already individuated and got to be inscribed in the experience
of the world—and by the indetermination of an initial disparity, which in a sense
equates the absolute origin of individuation with the potentials of transcendental
memory.
108
expressions. The fact that one same diagram allows for the emergence of different
expressions (as different as dancing, speaking and writing) can thus be said to result
from a differentiation of tendencies that depends on its relation with actual conditions of
individuation. Depending on the domain of individuation and on its possibilities of
expression, the diagrammatic forces of abstraction will be differently expressed. If the
domain is the dancing body, the expression of a choreographic diagram's will conform
to its possibilities. Conversely, there are choreographic objects that are beyond the
expressive possibilities of the dancing body.87 If the domain is the kind of graphical
writing that, at the time of the IT's release, was available to be used with video
recordings, then the choreographic diagram will conform to the possibilities offered by
the technical devices in use. Insofar as each domain limits virtual potentials with
determinate possibilities, each diagram can be expressed differently. Which is not to say
that several recurrences of one same diagram in one same domain will, in contrast, be
expressed similarly. This depends much on the domain's degree of indetermination. The
dancing body, for example, implicates such a degree of indetermination that it will
never express one same diagram the same way twice.
Arguing that indetermination is precisely what both idealism and realism fail to
acknowledge in relation to the necessary conditions of individuation, dance and media
theorist Stamatia Portanova argues in her book “Moving without a Body: Digital
Philosophy and Choreographic Thoughts” (2013) that in both perspectives “[t]he
fundamental question that remains unanswered is how to explain difference and
repetition, what persists and what mutates in the form of a step, or how to preserve
immanent patterns of being and becoming, of nature and reason, in dance.” (Ibid., p.
66). Both from the perspective that repetition is transcendentally determined and from
the perspective that repetition follows from physical laws, the fact that difference
occurs, even when identity and similitude seem to prevail, is largely neglected. Both
views override the indetermination of potentials, only to posit an identitary mode of
causality at the heart of process. If this would be so in the case of choreography, neither
could the perception of dance be forgotten nor could its remembrance be expressed with
a difference. For Portanova, choreography has always been “afflicted by an essential
87 It is enough to recall that choreographer Merce Cunningham used such strategy to challenge the
dancers with whom he worked. It is well known that “the first choreographer of international renown
who routinely utilized the computer as a choreographic tool” (Copeland, 2004, p. 168) used the
choreographic software “LifeForms” (www.charactermotion.com) to generate improbable and even
impossible images of movement that the dancers would then try to execute. Importantly, these
computer generated images were not intended to be reproduced as such, but rather to act as catalysts
for the dancers to discover new ways of moving.
109
form of forgetting” (Ibid. p. 65), which accords with the already mentioned excess of
the body over writing. Forgetting, in this sense, corresponds to the definition of
performance as that which is transient and irretrievable. But, beyond this, it corresponds
as well to the non-actualized potentials of movement. A potentiality that, for Portanova,
constitutes the very heart of a movement that is not a repetitive mode of differentiation,
i.e. repetition without difference, but rather a differentiating mode of repetition, i.e.
repetition with difference. In her words: “one step is always in relation not only to the
following one, but to a multiplicity of potential steps not actually taken. It is this
particular relation of the step to its intensive potential that constitutes movement’s
rhythm: the in-between of movement continuously folding into a centrifugal vortex or a
spiral. Impossible to repeat.” (Ibid. p. 65). It is the immanence between virtual
potentials and actual constraints that not only allows for the virtualization of actuality
but also for the continuous, i.e. rhythmic, relation of what would otherwise be
discontinuous (because perceived as such). The rhythmic character of repetition attests
the return of difference within individuation. “It is the difference that is rhythmic”, say
Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, “not the repetition, which nevertheless produces it:
productive repetition has nothing to do with reproductive meter” (1987, p. 314).
110
“[r]ather than being physically contingent and external to the abstract concept, or rather
than being conceptually programmed and external to the physical body, the difference of
a dance form becomes internal to an idea”. (Ibid.). A corollary from which it follows
that the choreographic diagram is in itself an idea of dance. And insofar as an idea is
neither fully removed from actuality nor fully disconnected from what is, the
choreographic object can be said to be an idea of movements with nexus. It is a dynamic
whole primarily defined by the creative relation between its general and relative
potentials. A whole that can be reduced neither to pure abstractions nor to pure
expressions, but which is a topology with the capacity of expressing itself differently
without ceasing to be itself.
111
Chapter 4 - DIAGRAMMATIC IDEAS
The choreographic object has been here defined as an idea that, because it
necessarily pertains to a nexus of movements, is problematic and therefore potential
with regard to being expressed differently across domains. This next chapter will start
by exploring French philosopher Gilles Deleuze's theory of ideas in order to provide a
better understanding of how the choreographic object's topology behaves in between
abstraction and expression. This will lead the discussion towards a definition of ideas as
propositions, which will allow for better tackling the relationship between
choreographic ideas and the processes by which a dancing body learns how to move
accordingly. Moreover, this chapter's second Section will look into a concrete study case
—Emio Greco and Pieter Scholten's “Double Skin / Double Mind” choreographic object
—in order to exemplify how a choreographic object is charged with potentials and how
these can be resolved into different kinds of expression. Since this one object has been
created with the intent of transmitting determinate instances of choreographic
knowledge, its transductive character will be approached via the relationship of its
topology with the conceptual structure used to express it across domains. This will
provide a basis upon which to conceptualize the notion of diagram, to be developed
throughout this chapter's third Section. Such development will continue to draw upon
Deleuze's philosophy, articulating it with sources that itself draws from: Charles S.
Peirce semiotic framework, Michel Foucault's work on the social diagram, and Brian
Massumi and Manuel DeLanda's commentaries upon this notion (which are directly
related to Deleuze's joint work with Felix Guattari). Dwelling upon the notion of
diagram will not only allow for a better understanding of the dynamisms by which ideas
come to determine concrete cases of solution with regard to their own problematic
structure, but also of how encounters and their results are never only a matter of
determination but also a matter of indetermination. This will make the case that, in order
for the encounter between dance and technology to be truly creative, it must openly
engage with unconscious forces that, despite being inaccessible, are absolutely
determinant in regard to the ingression of novelty into the expression of choreographic
ideas.
112
4.1 - From Idea to Proposition
113
can only be found by means of actual experimentation. For the author, “the Idea is not
the element of knowledge but that of an infinite 'learning', which is of a different nature
to knowledge. For learning evolves entirely in the comprehension of problems as such,
in the apprehension and condensation of singularities and in the composition of ideal
events and bodies. Learning to swim or learning a foreign language means composing
the singular points of one's own body or one's own language with those of another shape
or element, which tears us apart but also propels us into a hitherto unknown and
unheard-of world of problems. To what are we dedicated if not to those problems which
demand the very transformation of our body and our language? In short, representation
and knowledge are modeled entirely upon propositions of consciousness, which
designate cases of solution. But those propositions by themselves give a completely
inaccurate notion of the instance which engenders them as cases, and which they resolve
or conclude. By contrast, the Idea and 'learning' express that extra-propositional or sub-
representative problematic instance: the presentation of the unconscious, not the
representation of consciousness.” (1994, p. 192). As such, technical experimentation
involves not only what is possible to concretize but also the preindividual depth of the
individuating system. It implicates the continuum of affects engendered intensively
between encountering elements. It encompasses both what is proposed to the encounter
and what exceeds the possibilities of knowledge by reason of belonging to the very
plane of disparition where potentials differentiate. Learning pertains, therefore, to the
resolution of problems in potential. It pertains to the resolution of what cannot be
known in advance but which notwithstanding can come to constitute novel instances of
knowledge. The presentation of the unconscious in the problematic encounters of
technical individuation regards therefore an experience that must be lived, processually,
rather than represented as a proposition of resolution.
Accordingly, for Deleuze, ideas implicate the sensible by difference rather than
by identity. For him, “[a]n Idea is an n-dimensional, continuous, defined multiplicity” 88
88 A definition in all too close to Bergson's concept of “duration”. Already in Section 1.1, Deleuze was a
guiding voice for discussing this concept. Which not only attests the direct influence of one's work on
the other's, but more broadly the fact that Deleuze, like Bergson, was also concerned with the insights
brought about by the fundamental sciences, most notably mathematics and physics. Besides Deleuze's
well known take on topology, it is worth noting the one he took on the work of René Thom, the
french mathematician who in the sixties formulated the mathesis of catastrophe or chaos theory
(Deleuze, 1993, p. 16). In this regard, philosopher of science and known commentator of Deleuze's
philosophy, Manuel DeLanda remarks that: “In [Difference and Repetition], Deleuze repeatedly
makes use of these 'spaces of energetic possibilities' (technically referred to as 'state spaces' or 'phase
spaces'), and of the topological forms (or 'singularities') that shape these spaces. [...] Since these ideas
reappear in his later work, and since both the concept of 'phase space' and that of 'singularity' belong
to mathematics, it is safe to say that a crucial component of Deleuzian thought comes from the
philosophy of mathematics. And, indeed, chapter four of Difference and Repetition is a meditation on
114
(1994, p. 182), a formula which entails that, rather than being a homogeneous unity, an
idea necessarily organizes heterogeneous elements in relations of difference.
Remarkably, these are intensive differences. Problems internal to the continuous
multiplicity where potentials belonging to different orders of magnitude relate to one
another in one single field of heterogeneous composition. Technical resolution must
implicate a durational experience which relates the past with the present for the sake of
relating an idea's virtual potentials with its actual cases of solution. Technical
individuation is a perfectly positive process of invention, it knows nothing about
negation. In fact, this is clearly a standpoint that disables the possibility of a dialectical
negativity, for which an idea, being identical with itself, can negate another self-
identical idea. For Deleuze, an idea has neither form nor identity: it is without “sensible
form, conceptual signification, nor any assignable function” (Ibid., p. 183). It is a
differential variety that is always more-than-itself, a general potential which exceeds
representation. Because of this, the idea is potentially problematic. It is the differential
field of problematization from which determinate solutions can be drawn. The idea is a
necessary condition with regard to technical resolution, a condition that goes together
with what is possible to be resolved in each domain of individuation. Experimentation
results out of such condition. It is the necessary procedure for individuating instances of
knowledge that both attain and not attain the resolution of a given problem.
Additionally, the idea's problematic stance implicates in process the extra-propositional
and unconscious reality of virtual potentials. This allows for determining solutions that
cannot be but singular expressions of unpredictable affects. The need to experiment
results as well out of such reality. To access in effect to what, being inaccessible, can
notwithstanding contribute to resolute determinations. Both problems and possibilities,
affects and effects, are a condition of technical experimentation. On its turn, technical
experimentation is the means by which both resolution and the knowledge of how to
attain it can come about.
the metaphysics of the differential and integral calculus. On the other hand, given that 'phase spaces'
and 'singularities' become physically significant only in relation to material systems which are
traversed by a strong flow of energy, Deleuze's philosophy is also intimately related to that branch of
physics which deals with material and energetic flows, i.e. with thermodynamics. And, indeed,
chapter five of Difference and Repetition is a philosophical critique of nineteenth-century
thermodynamics, an attempt to recover from that discipline some of the key concepts needed for a
theory of immanent morphogenesis.” (2000, p. 35).
115
identity of an 'I think' or something thought. Internal multiplicity, by contrast, is
characteristic of the Idea alone” (1994, p. 183). Which is a distinction that facilitates a
better understanding of Stamatia Portanova's assertion that the difference of a dance
form is internal to its idea.89 The idea is different from the concepts of the understanding
because these correspond to the subjective side of the transindividual. They result from
a process that, even if it does not solve the problems of ideas, individuates subjective
instances of knowledge. They “retain interiority, but lose multiplicity” precisely because
they attest the self-compatibility of a subject. They attest the state at which there's a
minimum exchange of information between the subject and the milieu that the concepts
regard. In addition, the idea is different from spatio-temporal relations because these
correspond to the objective side of the transindividual. In contrast to the concepts of the
understanding, they are the objective side of determinate instances of knowledge. They
“retain multiplicity, but lose interiority” because they express the objective reality that
the concepts of the understanding regard. The idea pertains neither to the one side nor to
the other. Rather, it pertains to the differential variety of problems implicit in the
constitution of a transindividual relation. It pertains to the problematic condition
underlying both the concepts of the understanding and determinate spatio-temporal
relations. It is not an external factor of determination but an immanent force of
individuation. In fact, “[i]t is sufficient to understand that the genesis takes place in time
not between one actual term, however small, and another actual term, but between the
virtual and its actualization – in other words, it goes from the structure to its incarnation,
from the conditions of a problem to the cases of solution, from the differential elements
and their ideal connections to actual terms and diverse real relations which constitute at
each moment the actuality of time.” (Deleuze, 1994, p. 163). The idea is a genetic
element in regard to solutions.
Noteworthy is the fact that Deleuze's theory of ideas inherits much from
Immanuel Kant's philosophy. “Kant likes to say that problematic Ideas are both
objective and undetermined” (Ibid., p. 169). From which Deleuze draws both the
postulate that problems are “the real object of the Ideas” (Ibid.) and the postulate that
ideas are divided in three distinct moments. In their “first objective moment”, ideas are
“undetermined with regard to their object” (Ibid.). Importantly, for Deleuze, “[t]he
undetermined is not a simple imperfection in our knowledge or a lack in the object: it is
a perfectly positive, objective structure which acts as a focus or horizon within
perception” (Ibid.). Hence, the idea is undetermined with regard to its problems because
116
its differential variety connects heterogeneous elements in non-localisable relations. In
its second moment, the idea becomes “determinable with regard to the objects of
experience” (Ibid.). Which is to say that it becomes relative to the possibilities of
representation. Its potentials become limited by what has been given to experience.
From which it reversely follows that “an object outside experience can be represented
only in problematic form” (Ibid.). The third moment of the idea, in which this bears “the
ideal of an infinite determination with regard to concepts of the understanding” (Ibid.),
corresponds to the resolution of its problems in thought. Here, the idea becomes
objective and thus acquires its highest degree of determination. While in a first moment
the problems of ideas are undetermined and in a second moment determinable with
regard to the objects of experience, in a third moment they acquire a positional status.
Problems are posited together with determinate cases of solution. To say that the idea
has an infinite capacity of determination with regard to the concepts of the understating
thus stands for saying that the cases of solution determinable with thought can be many.
Despite its three moments, the idea is one single whole. It is continuous with
itself because it is primarily a differential variety. The unity of the idea's three different
moments is the continuity of its topology. As such, the undetermined problems of the
idea's first moment are not withdrawn from the cases of solution objectified in its third
moment. As Deleuze notes, “[a] problem does not exist, apart from its solutions. Far
from disappearing in this overlay, however, it insists and persists in these solutions. A
problem is determined at the same time as it is solved, but its determination is not the
same as its solution: the two elements differ in kind, the determination amounting to the
genesis of the concomitant solution. (In this manner the distribution of singularities
belongs entirely to the conditions of the problem, while their specification already refers
to solutions constructed under these conditions.) The problem is at once both
transcendent and immanent in relation to its solutions. Transcendent, because it consists
in a system of ideal liaisons or differential relations between genetic elements.
Immanent, because these liaisons or relations are incarnated in the actual relations
which do not resemble them and are defined by the field of solution.” (1994, p. 163).
Whereas the differential distribution of singularities attests the problem's ideal character,
its concomitant solution attests the distribution of particular cases, which are but
possible cancelations of the problem's implicit disparity. The difference between
determinate problems and their cases of solution is one of kind, not only because
problematic potentials are general and their specification relative to actual conditions,
but also because problems are propositions for a subject to learn how to solve them
117
accordingly. Individuating cases of solution requires experimenting with possibilities of
representation and concretization. It requires an exclusive selection of what might
possibly stand both as solution and as problematic expression.
118
reproduction of givens could be concretized, i.e. to be “produced after the fact, as
retroactively fabricated in the image of what resembles it” (Ibid., p. 21).90 In such case,
there is no invention. Because for invention to occur, for an idea's potentials to manifest
the unpredictable, its problematic structure needs to be active throughout the whole
process. The idea's unity must be prehended so that, together with the proposition of its
solutions, problems remain potential, differentiating in this way what would be
otherwise a reproduction of the same. To solve a problem is to learn how to determine
conditions capable of integrating the problem itself in the form of its relative solutions.
This requires the necessary trials for not only solving the problem, but to solve it in
relation to the idea to which both problem and solution belong. Technical resolution
discontinues what nevertheless remains in relation to the idea. It individuates cases of
solution that necessarily imply a constitutive difference. This is why it is always a
creative act.
From the perspective of Deleuze's theory of ideas, choreographic objects are but
ideal systems of individuation. Each choreographic object corresponds to a differential
variety with the capacity to problematize the encounter between virtual potentials and
actual possibilities. Subsequently, it corresponds as well to the potential of expressing
cases of solution in accordance with what the dedicated domains actually allow for. To
express choreographic objects is to learn how to posit their constitutive problems in
relation to determinate conditions. Different possibilities of expression will necessarily
conduce to learning how to posit choreographic problems in different ways. And
inasmuch as the problems of ideas are implicated in the cases of solution, different
choreographic expressions can only be said to pertain to one same object if they share
the same problematic structure. In this sense, in spite of being expressed
discontinuously in relation to one another, the different cases of solution of one same
problematic choreography belong to the same topological continuity, i.e. they share the
same potentials of problematization. From which it follows that the choreographic
problem is necessarily propositional. Its capacity to instigate action is as well the
capacity of the subject to learn how to posit problems. To express choreographic objects
is to experiment with possibilities and concretize given solutions with regard to the
problems posed. An aspect that is clearly emphasized in Erin Manning's following
90 Importantly, for Deleuze, the relation between the possible and the actual is organized in accordance
with principles of “identity with regard to concepts, opposition with regard to the determination of
concepts, analogy with regard to judgement, and resemblance with regard to objects” (1994, p. 137).
According to such principles, the realization of the possible-actual relation cannot but double the
images of what is possible with the actualization of determinate cases of solution.
119
commentary on William Forsythe's choreographic object “Dropping Curves”: “When
Forsythe proposes 'drop a curve' what he means is not 'reconfigure the habit' but 'move
through contrast'. If you tend to drop through your side, creating a curve from hip to
shoulder, begin there. But go elsewhere with it – let it take you elsewhere. Feel the
movement’s differential and move with its inflection in the event, letting it move the
you you are becoming.” (2013, p. 77). Though this is not necessarily what Forsythe
himself would say (despite the fact that in the quoted text there's a clear confusion
between the two authors' words), what is most important to retain from this passage is
the fact that, in this way, propositions are made to be a necessary condition to the
transduction of choreographic knowledge. Importantly, Manning's notion of proposition
derives from Alfred N. Whitehead's philosophy. For the latter, as for Deleuze, 91
propositions are not added to the solutions, but they are of and with the solutions. They
work as intensive catalysts for learning what is yet unknown. A proposition “is a datum
for feeling, awaiting a subject feeling it. Its relevance to the actual world by means of its
logical subjects makes it a lure for feeling. In fact many subjects may feel it with
diverse feelings, and with diverse sorts of feelings” (Whitehead, 1978, p. 259). What
becomes a proposition is thus what the subject makes of it. The proposition itself is not
given and what it will have become depends on the feeling subject, which also
individuates with the feeling. “If [...] the proposition has been admitted into feeling,
then the proposition constitutes what the feeling has felt” (Ibid., p. 186). From which it
follows that both the subject and the proposition co-individuate to become the dialogical
poles of one system of co-determination. Or, if one is to say instead that what
individuates is both a subject and an object, then the proposition is the very movement
of their co-constitution. The proposition constitutes the feeling subject as much as what
is felt. The proposition is an idea in movement. The formal conditions of the idea's
propositional movement can, and to a certain extent must, be given. But the proposition
itself is not giveable. Though any form can become propositional, it needs a subject to
make it so.
It is precisely from this standpoint that it is possible to say, with Manning, that
the proposition “drop a curve” does not stand for “reconfiguring a habit” but rather to
“moving through contrast”. Manning's own reading of Whitehead's notion of
proposition is here too elucidative: “The proposition, for Whitehead, works as an
inflection that affects how a given occasion comes to expression: propositions elicit
91 For Deleuze's comments upon Whitehead's philosophy, see his book on “Leibniz and the Baroque”,
titled “The Fold” (1993).
120
action in an environment of change. The proposition is a lure. It is a force that cuts into
the incipient event to alter its experiential vectorization. The proposition, however, is
never added on to an occasion. It is of and with the occasion – its immanent cleaving.
This cleaving activates the force of contrast within the occasion, opening the occasion to
its difference. Contrast is here understood as the force of difference that activates the
dephasing through which the occasion is felt as such.” (2013, p. 77). In this guise,
Manning further explains that to “[d]rop a curve reaches its propositional potential
when contrast is activated such that the becoming-body fields the curving of space-time
in a new way, itself co-constituted by this newness. If this happens, what is experienced
is the creation of a previously unfelt sensation that now permeates the welling occasion.
[…] Drop a curve is propositional not when a body has been defined but when the force
of movement-moving activates a field of relation that alters the affective and
compositional ecology of the larger event of movement-moving.” (Manning, 2013, p.
78). The choreographic object becomes propositional when its differential variety is felt
by its logical subject. While emerging from the encounter between a dedicated domain
and the difference internal to an idea of dance, the proposition participates in the
“distribution of the sensible” (Rancière, 2004, 2010) occurring within the individuating
system where both the feeling and what the feeling feels co-constitute one another. The
proposition of choreography therefore attests the latter's creativity. It attests the fact that
the becoming propositional of the choreographic object necessarily divests the
reproduction of what is already known, only to increase the potentials for something
new to be learnt.
121
developed from 2004 to 2007 the “Notation Research Project” (NRP).92 With this
project, the two artists and a multi-disciplinary team of specialists strived for finding a
notation system capable of capturing “the inner intention as well as the outer shape of
gestures and [dance] phrases” (Delahunta, 2007b, p. 5). Remarkably, this research
generated multiple outcomes: a documentary, a DVD-ROM, a book and an interactive
installation, all published together under the title “(Capturing Intention):
Documentation, Analysis and Notation Research Based on the Work of Emio
Greco/PC” (CI).93
The workshop DS/DM was intended to facilitate the transference, from Emio
Greco's dancing body to the body of other dancers, of a series of movement principles.
As it can be seen in the DS/DM documentary,94 such transference is based on
exemplification and reproduction. The dancers watch Greco dancing, listen to his oral
instructions and then try to dance in accordance with the same movement principles. To
say that a movement principle is reproduced from body to body is not the same as
saying that one body mimics another. Rather than formal outcomes, what is here
transferred across bodies is a principle of individuation. In dance, movement principles
are principles of individuation. To transfer movement principles across bodies is a
transductive process.
92 This project was followed by the “Inside Movement Knowledge” Project (IMK), which occurred
between 2008 and 2010. For a detailed account of both projects' history see
www.insidemovementknowledge.net.
93 I had the chance to meet part of the NRP's team at the first Annual Arts and Sciences Laboratory of
the “Transmedia Knowledge Base for Performing Arts” Project (TKB), which took place at the
choreographic centre “O Espaço do Tempo” in Montemor-o-Novo, Portugal, between 22 and 28 May
2010. For more on the TKB Project, see http://tkb.fcsh.unl.pt/. By then the NRP had already finished,
but its outcomes were still being developed in the frame of the IMK Project. Since this Laboratory
was dedicated to “New models of documentation for contemporary dance”, the NRP/IMK's team had
there the opportunity to set up the interactive installation DS/DM and present their remaining work.
This was the only time I accessed the interactive installation's actual set up and experienced its
workings.
94 The DS/DM documentary can be watched at https://vimeo.com/38974588, or found enclosed in the
publication “(Capturing Intention): Documentation, Analysis and Notation Research Based on the
Work of Emio Greco/PC” (Delahunta, 2007a).
122
fundamental and apparently unsurmountable difference between qualitative and
quantitative multiplicities. Because of this, each of these objects can be said to express,
if not a solution, at least an approximation to the problem itself. To transfer principles of
intensive movement, either across bodies or from the dancing body to each of the CI's
different domains, is tantamount to transduce choreographic problems. First, this
regards the fact the intensive body is constitutively problematic and therefore capable of
transducing the principles according to which itself moves. Second, it regards the fact
that the expressive resolution of such intensive problems necessarily implies problems
that are of the domain of expression itself. When the ones do not coincide with the
others, i.e. when the problems of the source domain do not coincide with the problems
of the target domain (e.g. the transduction of movement principles from the dancing
body to the digital domain), not only is the heterogenous multiplicity doubled with a
difference, as it is also submitted to conditions of individuation that require different
modes of experimentation. In this sense, EG|PC's knowledge of the DS/DM's movement
principles is much more easily (i.e. without other kinds of problems) transferred to other
dancing bodies than to the target domains used to express the CI's objects. Expressing
movement principles in these latter domains requires specific modes of experimentation
and the resolution of problems that are foreign to the knowledge that comes with the
experience of dancing. It should nonetheless be noticed that, of the four CI's objects
mentioned above, only the DVD and the Interactive Installation were in fact created
with the intent of being autonomous transducers of the DS/DM's movement principles.
Which is to say that, even if all the CI's objects resulted primarily from the knowledge
that EG|PC had of the DS/DM workshop, only these two expressions have individuated
from the resolution of problems posed by the encounter between determinate ideas of
dance and the domains targeted to express these same ideas. With such resolution, these
objects acquired a truly choreographic character. They have become choreographic
propositions. With them, it is possible to learn how to dance according to the DS/DM's
movement principles, similarly to what happens in a workshop delivered by EG|PC
themselves. These two objects are capable of transducing the DS/DM's movement
principles into other dancing bodies, facilitating in this way the individuation of a
renovated knowledge with regard to the intended dancing. Together with the workshop
itself, these two choreographic objects attest once more the actual variability that one
same system of choreographic individuation if capable of.
In spite of this, it is here worth following the NRP's development and the fact
that its first objective expression was the workshop's video documentary, filmed and
123
directed by Maite Bermúdez in 2005. Curiously, the structure of the documentary
follows the structure of the workshop, as delivered at ImPulsTanz Festival, in August
that year. The latter is shown to be divided in five main parts, designated respectively in
regard to their succession as: 1) “Breathing”; 2) “Jumping”; 3) “Expanding”; 4)
“Reducing”; and 5) “Transfer”. Whereas the first four of these parts correspond to
different principles of movement (or, in other words, movement qualities), the last part
is shown to be structured by a dance phrase that is to be filled with (or fuelled by) them.
The fact that these successive parts are designated like this shouldn't be understood in
any general way whatsoever. Their names are not meant to correspond to the common
understanding that they might pertain to in any other particular context. Rather, they are
meant to specifically depict the problematic structure of the DS/DM's movement
qualities. The fact that there is a tension between the territorialization that signifiers
perform over signified multiplicities and the latter's characteristic deterritorialization, is
remarked by Scott deLahunta—one of NRP's specialists in dance and technology—as
having been one of the difficulties faced by EG|PC when naming and describing the
workshop's structure. “This difficulty of finding the right words and explanations was,
in part, due to the dialectical tension between [the artists] that is inherently a feature of
their artistic work [...]. To ‘decide’ what and how to name or explain these parts of
DS/DM, was to allow it to become fixed, to make it concrete in terminology. However,
as mentioned, the result of this difficult work served the needs of the making of the
documentary. It also produced the hierarchy of sections and subsections so that the
DVD and Installation versions of DS/DM could be created.” (2007b, p. 21). Which is to
say that the tension between signifieds—the variable experiences and expressions of
dance—and signifiers—the words used to name the workshop's movement qualities—
was sufficiently problematic to foster the technical individuation of these two
choreographic objects. After all, despite their possible reduction to the homogeneous
explication of phonetic or graphic signifiers, monemes are but multiplicities of
heterogeneous elements.
With no regard with the structures that followed from naming movement
principles in this way, the DS/DM workshop always had a linguistic dimension. As
dancer (of the EG|PC dance company) and researcher Bertha Bermúdez explains,
“passing these dances onto others is [normally] done through instruction with the body
and words. [As such] the body has to be clear and the words have to be right.”
(Delahunta, 2007b, p. 6). And it is to this latter requirement that the specification of
names attends. If both the DVD and the Interactive Installation are to be capable of
124
transmitting the DS/DM's dance ideas, their expressions have to be structured in a
precise and determinate manner. It could nonetheless be argued that, instead of being
given names, the different parts of the workshop could have been given numbers. But in
contrast to numbers, what the artists' endeavour to find the right words for each of the
workshop's movement qualities attests, is the existing connection between the somatic
experience of the moving body and the ways in which language and conceptual
knowledge are structured, in and by the body. In this sense, the oral explanation of
dance ideas is directly related to the conceptual structures according to which the
DS/DM's movement principles are organized. It allows for understanding both the
knowledge that the artists have of what they do and how this is structured.
That both the NRP and the IMK have turned towards cognitive linguistics to
think and analyse the conceptual structures implicated in the DS/DM's movement
qualities, attests not only these projects' concern with the underlying principles of
dancing but also the acknowledgement that the latter are known both somatically and
conceptually. Bertha Bermúdez and cognitive linguist Carla Fernandes, two of the
researchers here involved, claim to be “interested in searching for the implicit
knowledge that is embedded in choreographic processes and the possible ways of
presenting or expressing it. In practice this means [to] start from the premise that the
translation and transmission of the imagetic thought of a contemporary choreographer
into an embodied-type of thought, via the dancers’ bodies, is above all metaphoric (cf.
Johnson, 1987 on image schemata in the human brain as being prior to awareness).”
(2010, p. 29). This metaphorical character of choreographic transductions can be
understood both in regard to the dancing body's orientation relatively to the charged
ground of its perceptive-affective milieu (i.e. imagetic thought being structured in
accordance with this orientation) and in regard to the influence that knowledge has on
dancing (i.e. expressive movement being determined by the structures of thought). It
regards both the transfer of physical resolutions to the resolution of thought and the
transfer of conceptual resolutions to the resolution of dance. After all, “the essence of
metaphor is understanding and experiencing one kind of thing in terms of another”
(Lakoff & Johnson, 1980, p. 5). Notwithstanding, this is not a symmetric process. The
process by means of which the resolutions of thought follow from the body's physical
orientation is not the same as the one whereby conceptual structures affect the actual
organization of dance. On the basis of this asymmetry is the assumption that knowledge
is characteristically imagetic. It structures images (or imagines structures) that are
neither the body's actual orientation in its milieu nor any of its other possible
125
expressions. To better understand these processes and the relation between metaphors
and the images of thought, it is here worth quoting a long passage from cognitive
linguist Mark Johnson's seminal book “The Body in the Mind” (1987). “To illustrate the
important and undervalued notion of embodied, imaginative understanding, let us
consider two types of imaginative structure [...]: image schemata and metaphorical
projections. An image schema is a recurring, dynamic pattern of our perceptual
interactions and motor programs that gives coherence and structure to our experience. 95
The VERTICALITY schema, for instance, emerges from our tendency to employ an
UP-DOWN orientation in picking out meaningful structures of our experience. We
grasp this structure of verticality repeatedly in thousands of perceptions and activities
we experience every day, such as perceiving a tree, our felt sense of standing upright,
the activity of climbing stairs, forming a mental image of a flagpole, measuring our
children's heights, and experiencing the level of water rising in the bathtub. The
VERTICALITY schema is the abstract structure of these VERTICALITY experiences,
images, and perceptions. […] experientially based, imaginative structures of this image
schematic sort are integral to meaning and rationality. A second, related type of
embodied imaginative structure […] is metaphor, conceived as a pervasive mode of
understanding by which we project patterns from one domain of experience in order to
structure another domain of a different kind. So conceived, metaphor is not merely a
linguistic mode of expression; rather, it is one of the chief cognitive structures by which
we are able to have coherent, ordered experiences that we can reason about and make
sense of.96 Through metaphor, we make use of patterns that obtain in our physical
experience to organize our more abstract understanding. Understanding via
95 Elsewhere Johnson writes: “I call these patterns 'image schemata' because they function primarily as
abstract structures of images. They are gestalt structures, consisting of parts standing in relations and
organized into unified wholes, by means of which our experience manifests discernible order. When
we seek to comprehend this order and to reason about it, such bodily based schemata play a central
role. For although a given image schema may emerge first as a structure of bodily interactions, it can
be figuratively developed and extended as a structure around which meaning is organized at more
abstract levels of cognition. This figurative extension and elaboration typically takes the form of
metaphorical projection from the realm of physical bodily interactions onto so-called rational
processes, such as reflection and the drawing of inferences from premises. […] what are often
thought of as abstract meanings and inferential patterns actually do depend on schemata derived from
our bodily experience and problem-solving. There are two especially controversial aspects […]
concerning the centrality of image schematic structures in the organization of meaning and in the
nature of our inferences. The first is their apparently nonpropositional, analog nature. The second is
their figurative character, as structures of embodied imagination.” (1987, p. xx).
96 Another prominent cognitive linguist, George Lakoff, with whom Johnson wrote the book
“Metaphors We Live By” (1980), argues that metaphors can be considered as a mode of thought in
their own right because of three fundamental characteristics: “1) The systematicity in the linguistic
correspondences; 2) The use of metaphor to govern reasoning and behaviour based on that reasoning;
3) The possibility for understanding novel extensions in terms of the conventional correspondences”
(2006, p. 191). From these characteristics follows that metaphors organize the experience of the
world in specific ways and that they can be expressed by means other than speech.
126
metaphorical projection from the concrete to the abstract makes use of physical
experience in two ways. First, our bodily movements and interactions in various
physical domains of experience are structured (as we saw with image schemata), and
that structure can be projected by metaphor onto abstract domains. Second,
metaphorical understanding is not merely a matter of arbitrary fanciful projection from
anything to anything with no constraints. Concrete bodily experience not only
constrains the 'input' to the metaphorical projections but also the nature of the
projections themselves, that is, the kinds of mappings that can occur across domains.”
(Johnson, 1987, p. xv).
From this standpoint, it is possible to understand how dance and speech are both
capable of providing access to underlying conceptual structures and implicit instances
of knowledge. Since the focus here is the dancing body, both modes of expression can
be said to correspond to resolutions that not only implicate movement principles but
also the thoughts that with them arise. Insofar as knowledge in general can be addressed
on the basis of image schemata, and therefore as being grounded on bodily experiences,
both knowing how to dance and knowing how to verbalize this experience necessarily
correspond to one same conceptual structure. It follows that it is possible to not only
address this relation between expressions and abstractions on the basis of the mappings
that occur across domains, but also to use these mappings to further express choreo-
knowledge. It is precisely this that both the DVD and the Interactive Installation
express. By determining the ideas of dance in the form of concepts, here synthesized by
words, and by using these structures to individuate digital expressions, the
concretization of these objects has extended the knowledge of the DS/DM workshop
into domains that, because they are problematic on their own, have allowed for novel
resolutions and renovated perspectives on the workshop. As Pieter Scholten remarks,
the knowledge of the workshop didn't change “but it has gotten more layers through this
research project” (Delahunta, 2007c, p. 21). Such layers correspond both to a glossary
that, beyond the names already mentioned, was fabricated with the intent of
discontinuing movement qualities into a greater degree of resolution, and to the
multimodal contents created to provide different perspectives on the DS/DM, as
structured by the glossary.
“The DS/DM's glossary has been the first attempt by EG|PC to break down the
creative process through the use of words. Such a process provided the different
127
disciplines involved97 within the research project with a common basis of understanding
around the Double Skin/Double Mind workshop.” (Fernandes & Bermudez, 2010, p.
31). Not only this, but it allowed to depict the conceptual structure of the workshop to a
point that was new even to the artists. As much as the DS/DM's glossary comprises a list
of interrelated terms—a signifying double of the heterogeneous multiplicity that it
represents—, and each of these terms implicates a concept, the glossary can be said to
represent the conceptual structure of the workshop. A fact reiterated by the very process
of its individuation, since that, in order for the glossary to result as it did, “[d]efinitions
and descriptions were constructed through interviews and different transcriptions of the
live transmission of the workshop, in some cases complemented by visual
demonstrations. Divided in two parts, Inside and Outside, the glossary tried to present
the language used by the company (Inside section) versus a more general definition of
the same terms gathered from dictionaries (Outside section)” (Ibid.). It is not of interest
here to consider the specificities of the lexicon used in the DS/DM's glossary. It rather
matters to acknowledge that all its terms refer to resolutions of the dancing body. The
glossary didn't result from a random depiction of choreographic expressions, but rather
from a knowledge that primarily regards the dancing body's capacity to differentiate
movement qualities. Rather than being an external factor of determination imposed on
the workshop for the expression of resolute forms, the glossary should be understood as
a possible expression of the diagram according to which the dancing body develops and
undergoes phase-shifts, from one movement quality to the next. It is nonetheless
noticeable that, in order to create it, much effort was put into defining the terms in
relation to the narrow context of the DS/DM workshop, in relation to the broader
context of EG|PC's artistic work, and in relation to the even broader context of dance
and movement analysis. Here, there are different individuations at stake. There is the
individuation of the DS/DM's movement qualities and there is the individuation of the
concepts created by the multi-disciplinary team of specialists. Whereas the results of the
former correspond to the glossary's structure, the results of the latter correspond to its
contents. The one condition that these two individuations share is the DS/DM's dancing
body. After all, both take it to be a body capable of moving ideas with the potential to
determine conceptual and physical resolutions. By using the glossary for indexing and
organizing the different contents of the DS/DM's DVD (as shown in Illustration 2,
below) and of the Interactive Installation, it became possible to express digitally not
97 Dance notation, motion capture, new media design, cognitive neuroscience, cinematography and
dance analysis (Delahunta, 2007a).
128
Illustration 2: “Double Skin / Double Mind” DVD-ROM's conceptual structure. Sections and
subsections as seen from the perspective of the videos' folder and as named after the glossary.
129
only the workshop's structure but also the diagram of its potentials. Precisely because of
this, says Bermúdez, “[t]he structure that is used in the Installation and the DVD
contains the core of what DS/DM [i.e. N R P and IMK] has achieved in ten years”
(Delahunta, 2007b, p. 21).
Illustration 3: Interface of the “Double Skin / Double Mind” DVD-ROM, showing one of the
workshop's sections (with the dancing body's full figure, oral and written explanations, close ups,
notational scores and the “Gesture Follower” software).
98 The designer of these interfaces is the same who designed William Forsythe's “Improvisation
Technologies'” DVD-ROM, namely, Chris Ziegler.
130
discussed “Improvisation Technologies'”,99 the expressive multimodality of these
graphic interfaces not only explicits the contents' similarity but also the ways in which
they differ. In fact, it is precisely this contrast between the same and the different that
offers an insight into the DS/DM's invariant functions, that is, into the principles of
individuation of the choreographic ideas that these objects simultaneously express and
hold in potential.
These terms, matters of content and functions of expression, have been used by
Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari to depict the workings of what they call the “abstract
machine” (1987, pp. 510–514). This concept is intrinsically related to their conception
of the notion of “diagram” (Ibid. pp. 141–143), which they borrowed from American
131
philosopher Charles S. Peirce. For the latter, the diagram is a tool for knowledge-
making. To be more correct, Peirce considered diagrams to be a special case of “icons”,
which he defined as signs with the capacity to generate kinds of knowledge different
from the ones implicated in their use. “For a great distinguishing property of the icon is
that by the direct observation of it other truths concerning its objects can be discovered
than those which suffice to determine its constructions.” (1895, p. 2.279). In Peirce’s
1903 “Syllabus”, the diagram is said to be a “hypoicon”, a subspecies of the icon.
Hypoicons are defined by the fact that they cannot stand out in purely formal terms. As
such, all the three species of hypoicons identified by Peirce—“images, diagrams and
metaphors”—are operational, rather than formal. They can only be considered with
regard to the processes that they comprehend. In this sense, an image is not a pictorial
form, but rather a qualitative becoming; a diagram is not a visual scheme, but rather the
processes by it depicted; and a metaphor is not the linguistic expression of one thing in
terms of another, but rather the abstract projection of determinate structures across
domains. Furthermore, the three species of hypoicons are distinguished from one
another in the following way: an image is defined in terms of an object's qualities; a
diagram is defined in terms of the knowledge that it provides of the object in
representation; and a metaphor is defined in terms of the relation that it establishes
between objects. (Ibid., p. 2.277).
Peirce also distinguishes icons from “indexes” and “symbols” (1998, pp. 258–
299), a distinction that Deleuze and Guattari commented upon, in their famous book “A
Thousand Plateaus” (1987), in the following way: “The distinction between indexes,
icons, and symbols […] are based on signifier-signified relations (contiguity for the
index, similitude for the icon, conventional rule for the symbol); this leads [Peirce] to
make the 'diagram' a special case of the icon (the icon of relation). Peirce is the true
inventor of semiotics. That is why we can borrow his terms, even while changing their
connotations. First, indexes, icons, and symbols seem to us to be distinguished by
territoriality-deterritorialization relations, not signifier-signified relations. Second, the
diagram as a result seems to have a distinct role, irreducible to either the icon or the
symbol.” (Ibid., p. 531). To say that the diagram is irreducible both to the symbol and to
the icon is thus to say that it does not operate by means of similarity or convention.
Conversely, it is to say that it rather operates on the basis of a constitutive difference.
For Deleuze, the diagram “is the map of relations between forces, a map of destiny, or
intensity, which proceeds by primarily non-localizable relations and at every moment
passes through every point, or ‘rather in every relation from one point to another'”
132
(1988b, p. 36). The diagram is preindividual and, as such, pre-subjective and pre-
objective. To say that it maps relations between forces is to say that it distributes affects
throughout the intensive field of relatedness where potentials differ from one another.
Rather than depicting tendencies of individuation, the diagram is the very plane where
they take place. It is the plane where the differentiation of potentials is engendered with
the highest intensities. The diagram is a cause, not an effect. It is “a cause which is
realized, integrated and distinguished in its effect. Or rather the immanent cause is
realized, integrated and distinguished by its effect. In this way there is a correlation or a
mutual presupposition between cause and effect, between abstract machine and concrete
assemblages” (Ibid.). From which it follows that, not only is the diagram distinct from
indexes, icons and symbols, but also from Peirce's remaining hypoicons, that is, from
images and metaphors. In this sense, the diagram is the very plane where both the
qualitative becoming of images and the structures of metaphorical projection are
engendered. The diagram underpins both imagetic and metaphorical thinking. After all,
inasmuch as both images and metaphors rely on the problematic reality of ideas, they
rely as well on the diagrammatic structurarion of potentials. Hence, movements of
thought are diagrammatically structured.
133
unmaking preceding realities and significations, constituting hundreds of points of
emergence or creativity, unexpected conjunctions or improbable continuums. It doubles
history with a sense of continual evolution.” (1988, p. 35). The diagram recomposes
metastabilities for the becoming of others. In Foucault's writings (2012a), the most
famous example of a social diagram is the panopticon, a “dispositif” where determinate
matters of content, i.e. prisoners, encounter determinate functions of expression, i.e.
laws. The social expression of the panopticon, its life, results from the encounter
between the prisoners' bodies and the abstract laws to which they must comply. The
panopticon is an idea with a difference. Diagrammatically, it is the plane where the
difference between functions of expression and matters of content is intensified, only to
bring into expression a disciplined life. From this standpoint, it is possible to better
understand why for Foucault, as for Deleuze and Guattari, the diagram is an abstract
machine. The diagram corresponds to the differential distribution of potentials
underlying any individuation whatsoever. As such, it is virtual. It runs throughout the
plane of immanence where the dynamisms of affect between the virtual and the actual
occur with the highest intensities. In fact, it is the very topology according to which
these dynamisms occur. It is the territory of singularities and bifurcations,
intensifications and disparitions, where problems are drawn. In Deleuze's words, “[t]he
diagram is no longer an auditory or visual archive, but a map, a cartography that is
coextensive with the whole social field. [...] If there are many diagrammatic functions
and even matters, it is because every diagram is a spatio-temporal multiplicity” (1988b,
p. 34). The diagram is as much a preindividual absolute as the expressive varieties that
from it might emerge. Qualities, images, objects and metaphors can all result from it,
but not the other way around. Notwithstanding, as it is the case with any affective
dynamism between the emergent and the emerged, all these results can condition the
diagram's activity.
134
only partake individuation if informed from the outside, i.e. by an external factor of
determination, a theory of abstract materialism affirms matter's immanent
morphogenetic capacities and its undetermined potentiality. Only under these conditions
can novelty emerge. In contrast, this is also to say that transcendent determinations
preclude the emergence of novelty by giving in advance what is possible to occur.
Contrary to hylomorphic determinations, matter's diagrammaticality implies
autonomous potentials of creativity. It implies its own potentials of abstraction and
possibilities of expression. A good example of matter's diagrammaticality is given by
philosopher of science and known commentator of Deleuze's philosophy, Manuel
DeLanda, when arguing that embryogenetic processes are not fully determined by
genetic information. In his words, “the DNA that governs the process does not contain,
as it was once believed, a blueprint for the generation of the final form of the organism,
an idea that implies an inert matter to which genes give form from the outside. The
modern understanding of the processes, on the other hand, pictures genes as teasing out
a form out of an active matter, that is, the function of genes and their products is now
seen as merely constraining and channeling a variety of material processes, occurring in
that far-from-equilibrium, diagrammatic zone, in which form emerges spontaneously.”
(2000, p. 37). The diagram must be considered from the perspective of this encounter
between formal constraints and spontaneous processes of emergence. Like with the
panopticon, there is here a function of expression—the genes—and a matter of content
—matter's forces. Matter's intensive multiplicities are in this way focused towards the
resolution of what, out of this encounter, is given a predominant probability of
occurrence. In a sense, the function of expression is responsible for the asymmetric
distribution of probabilities, favouring some possibilities in detriment of others. Yet, this
does not occur without matter's latent potentials, i.e. without the fact that, for an
individuation to occur, a plane of indetermination, differentiation and disparition must
be constitutive of matter itself. For “it is only in these far-from-equilibrium conditions
that the full variety of immanent topological forms appears (steady state, cyclic or
chaotic attractors). It is only in this zone of intensity that difference-driven
morphogenesis comes into its own, and that matter becomes an active material agent,
one which does not need form to come and impose itself from the outside.” (Ibid., p.
37). Here, preindividual potentials diagrammatically verge towards a tendentiously
distribution of topological singularities. An activity prior to the conscious determination
of ideas. Which is to say, with Deleuze and Guattari, that the diagram “has no way of
making a distinction within itself between a plane of expression and a plane of content
135
because it draws a single plane of consistency, which in turn formalizes contents and
expressions according to strata and reterritorializations. The abstract machine in itself is
destratified, deterritorialized; it has no form of its own (much less substance) and makes
no distinction within itself between content and expression, even though outside itself it
presides over that distinction and distributes it in strata, domains, and territories. An
abstract machine in itself is not physical or corporeal, any more than it is semiotic; it is
diagrammatic (it knows nothing of the distinction between the artificial and the natural
either)” (1987, p. 141). It is process in its most acute definition. And if the encounter
between matters of content and functions of expression is a necessary condition for
positing problems, then the abstract machine is a necessary condition for their
resolution. In their encounter, matters of content and functions of expression mutually
presuppose one another. They are defined by the individuation that they give rise to.
From this standpoint, it can be posited that the choreographic object can only be
said to be a model of potential transition inasmuch as it is capable of acting as a
function of expression over matters of content belonging to different domains (i.e. any
space imaginable). Not only does this capacity grant choreography with the necessary
autonomy for it to be expressed in domains other than the dancing body, but also with
the abstract character of formal constraints, i.e. with ideas that, because they have
acquired a certain degree of determination, remain unchanged regardless of the domain
into which they are transduced. According to this, choreography is primarily defined by
the formal abstraction of each of its objects. It is a function of expression disjunct from
the means by which it might be expressed. A fact that does not prevent its expressions
from depending on specific matters of content. A law of discipline, for example,
generates different results depending if it is applied on humans or animals. Likewise, if
the DS/DM workshop is considered, its conceptual structure constrains the emergence of
different expressions depending if the domain is the dancing body or digital media. But
insofar as these expressions follow from one same function of expression, a structural
similitude can nonetheless be depicted from them. This, of course, depends as well on
the degree of indetermination of the matters of content in case: different recurrences of
one same idea will be expressed with a variability higher in the case of the dancing body
than in the case of digital media. Whereas in the former case such variability derives
from the body's constitutive indetermination (of potentials), in the latter case it derives
from digital media's constitutive determination (of possibilities). The choreographic
diagram is therefore not the choreographic model, but rather what results from the
latter's encounter with specific matters of content. It is the abstract machine of
136
differentiation and disparition activated when determinate functions of expression
constrain matters of content charged with potentials. Nonetheless, it can be said that the
choreographic model is diagrammatic, for it is the structure which modulates matter's
potentials towards resolutions that, rather than being contingent, are constrained by an
asymmetric distribution of probabilities.
100 Knoespel acknowledges having discussed with George Lakoff the functions of metaphorical thinking
in cognitive processes. A discussion “particularly directed by his work with Mark Johnson,
Metaphors We Live By (1980) and by his recent book with Rafael E. Nunez, Where Mathematics
Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being (2000).” (2002, p. 35). More
specifically, he notes that “[t]he cognitive setting provided by Lakoff provided a means not only for
linking diagram to metaphor but for seeing both diagram and metaphor as vehicles of bodily
extension.” (Ibid., p. 26).
137
without implicating as well iconic potentials. The symbols of choreographic notation
articulate discontinuities, implicating simultaneously imagetic and metaphorical
potentials. The “movement-images”101 of the dancing body presented with each video
also implicate the workshop's conceptual structure. Finally, the written explanations
make an explicit use of images and metaphors. This confusion of indexes, symbols and
figures (of the dancing body) with icons shouldn't come as a surprise. Insofar as icons
correspond to movements of thought, they are implicated in indexical, symbolic and
figurative expressions. As such, not only are these expressions cases of solution with
regard to the workshop's problems, as they also implicate the diagrammatic potentials of
the abstract machine from which they derive. For these reasons, it should be
acknowledged that the actual representation of the DS/DM's diagrammatic structure
necessarily depends on non-iconic signs.
In relation to the abstract machine, each type of sign works differently. To each
sign its function. Insofar as indexes function by contiguity, they can be used to indicate
a whole field of relations. Each of the terms of the DS/DM's glossary not only indexes a
movement principle, but also its subsequent expressions. Indexation works here as a
function of remembrance, which can be used both by humans and machines. Once a
series of past events has been registered, it can be recalled by means of an index. In this
way, remembrance and recollection make of the index the very medium through which
what was once given to experience can once again be brought into it. Once a word such
as “Breathing” is given an indexical function, it can be used both by a team of
researchers and by computers to recall what is contiguous to the index. On their turn,
symbols work by convention. To know that, in Labanotation, horizontality stands for
simultaneity and verticality for succession, is a requirement without which the
diagrammatic implications of these symbols cannot be comprehended. Additionally, in
the DS/DM's choreographic objects, metaphors and images can be found in each of the
written explanations. For example, in the DVD the movement quality “Breathing” is
described as follows: “A very thin line of air runs inside your body. Visualize the
101 This term has been poignantly reintroduced by Gilles Deleuze when discussing cinema through the
lens of Henri Bergson's philosophy. Simply put, the movement-image regards the fact that, in cinema,
it is not a series of figures that describes movement (which would be the case of the infinitesimally
divisible space of Zeno's paradoxes), but rather the continuity of movement that describes figures. In
Deleuze's words: “Cinema proceeds with photogrammes—that is, with immobile sections—twenty-
four images per second (or eighteen at the outset). But it has often been noted that what it gives us is
not the photogramme: it is an intermediate image, to which movement is not appended or added; the
movement on the contrary belongs to the intermediate image as immediate given. […] In short,
cinema does not give us an image to which movement is added, it immediately gives us a movement-
image. It does give us a section, but a section which is mobile, not an immobile section + abstract
movement.” (1986, p. 3).
138
internal path of the air and feel it running through all your joints. Start from the toes,
move up through your feet, ankles, knees, pelvis, lower back, stomach, spine, chest,
shoulder, arms and then, at the end, reach beyond your fingertips. Grow, keep growing
inside this thin line. Imagine an endless sense of reaching, reach the limit of your body
and try to go even further. Release the length of the body, while disappearing inside
yourself. Go back through the same thin line, very deep inside and become very small,
always ready to appear again”. The imperative tone of this proposition marks the
intention for it to act as a transducer of the movement principles from which itself
stems. The images and metaphors that it proposes are in this way to be incarnated by the
dancing body of the learning subject. They are to be experimented with, a model with
which to focus potentials towards resolute expressions. The DS/DM's transduction by
means of all these expressions—metaphorical descriptions, choreographic notations,
videographic registers and indexical organizations—attests their common potential.
They are diagrammatically consistent with one another. Which doesn't mean that they
express the same knowledge as the dancing body. The differences between the instances
of the ones and the instances of the other remarks the abstract machine's meaningful
capacity. Insofar as a content-expression encounter is capable of individuating
knowledge, it is a meaningful process.
When commenting upon Deleuze and Guattari's joint project “Capitalism and
Schizophrenia”, Massumi relates the emergence of meaning with the workings of the
abstract machine in the following way: “Meaning is not in the genesis of the thing, nor
in the thought of that genesis, nor in the words written or spoken of it. It is in the
process leading from one to the other. […] If meaning is a process of translation from
one substance to another of a different order and back again, what it moves across is an
unbridgeable abyss of fracturing. If meaning is the in-between of content and
expression, it is nothing more (nor less) than the being of their “nonrelation.” (1992, pp.
15-16). Paradoxically, meaning is in this way related with the indetermination of an
individuating system. Rather than being associated with the resolution of problems in
potential, it is associated with their very disparition. It is the process of resolution, rather
than the resolution itself. Which is also why Simondon postulates that the knowledge of
individuation can provide insights with regard to the resulting individuals but not the
other way around. Meaning necessarily regards the topological depth of translation's
continuity. It regards the continuity of potentials underlying transduction. From which it
follows that meaning can be understood as the continuity of relatedness between that
which emerges as knowledge and the abstract machine's unconscious reality. The non-
139
relation of content and expression is precisely this topological depth of the abstract
machine. A depth that, because it is preindividual, cannot be known as such. In Deleuze
and Guattari's words, it is the very plane of consistency where the highest intensities are
engendered. For “the plane of consistency is the abolition of all metaphor; all that
consists is Real. These are electrons in person, veritable black holes, actual organites,
authentic sign sequences. It's just that they have been uprooted from their strata,
destratified, decoded, deterritorialized, and that is what makes their proximity and
interpenetration in the plane of consistency possible. A silent dance. The plane of
consistency knows nothing of differences in level, orders of magnitude, or distances. It
knows nothing of the difference between the artificial and the natural. It knows nothing
of the distinction between contents and expressions, or that between forms and formed
substances; these things exist only by means of and in relation to the strata.” (1987, pp.
69–70). The plane of consistency is the plane of immanence is the abstract machine. It
is where all consists and from which all forms derive. It is a preindividual disparity
resulting from the communication between matters of content and functions of
expression. Such communication can create problems and solutions, but never the
knowledge of what, virtually, underpins their determination. One cannot know what is
outside of thought.
Equating the abstract machine with the being of the nonrelation between matters
of content and functions of expression can be better understood with the following
passage from Massumi's own take on the notion of diagram, where he uses the example
of carpentry to argue about its duplication in time and space: “What the diagram
diagrams is a dynamic interrelation of relations. The dynamism occurs twice: once as
genesis in a state of things (tool to wood), and again in ideality (concept to concept).
The diagram combines a past (the working of the wood) and the future of that past (the
thought of the woodworking), but it skips over its own genesis – the present of the
content-expression encounter constitutive of thought (the unthought of thought).
Actually, the dynamism occurs twice twice: after being translated into ideality (concept
to concept) it is reexternalized in words (phoneme to phoneme; letter to letter) to resume
its life among things in a new capacity. The diagram again combines a past (the thought
of the woodworking) and the future of that past (pronunciation, publication), skipping
over its own genesis, in this case the present of the content-expression encounter
constitutive of speaking or writing (the unsaid of communication: afterthought). In each
instance, the elided present, like the in-between of tool and wood, is at any rate a
140
void.102 In skipping it, the diagram reduplicates the process it diagrams. The diagram is
false, in that it contracts a multiplicity of levels and matters into its own homogeneous
substance. But it is true, in that it envelops in that substance the same affect, and
because it reproduces the in-betweenness of the affect in the fracturing of its own
genesis. The expression of meaning is true in its falseness to itself, and false in its
trueness to its content. Translation is repetition with a difference. If meaning is
becoming, it is a becoming-other. It is the alienation of the same in the different, and the
sameness of the different in its alienation from itself. The (non)relation is a separation-
connection.” (1992, p. 16).
102 This conforms with what Thomas Lamarre identifies as being “the neutral point of the event (absolute
origin) of individuation that simultaneously sets off individuation and arises in it” (2012, p. 40). See
page 59.
103 Jacques Derrida famously made the case that it is not articulation that results out of language, but
precisely the other way around. “It is once again the power of substituting one organ for another” he
writes, “of articulating space and time, sight and voice, hand and spirit, it is this faculty of
supplementarity which is the true 'origin'—or nonorigin—of languages: articulation in general as
articulation of nature and convention, of nature and all its others.” (1976, p. 241). For Derrida's own
reading of Martinet's concept of double articulation, see Derrida, 1976, p. 228.
141
generates. The diagram diagrams the interrelation of relations, but on the condition that
it remains inaccessible. Conversely, any diagrammatic expression can be considered a
map of what the diagram diagrams. In fact, to say that the diagram diagrams is to say
that, rather than corresponding to expressive mappings, it corresponds to the content-
expression encounters of thought and language. The constitution of thought by the
diagrammatic encounter of content and expression conforms with Simondon's theory of
psychic individuation. It corresponds to the resolution of problematic states in the
affective reality of a self-reflecting organism. As such, it corresponds to the movements
of thought by means of which knowledge is determined. On its turn, the content-
expression encounter constitutive of linguistic expression corresponds to language's
double articulation, as just presented. The diagram's topological continuity assures the
different encounters' relation. It assures the implication of diagrammatic potentials
across movements of thought and linguistic expressions. Nevertheless, to say that in this
process the diagramming occurs twice twice is the same as saying that in each encounter
the diagram's problematic potentials are resolved differently. When transferring the
DS/DM's conceptual structure into the digital domain, there necessarily occur
resolutions with regard to the content-expression encounter of thought and resolutions
with regard to the content-expression encounter of language. To say that knowledge can
derive from the formation of novel instances of language is to say that this does not
occur without a parallel individuation of thought. Only in this way is it possible to learn
with technical individuation, that is, to learn not only about what is expressed but also
about how it is expressed. Only in this way is it possible to experiment and learn how to
faithfully express a determinate idea, regarding the many potentials of its diagrammatic
structure. One cannot learn how to speak or write if not through actual experimentation.
A process the potentials of which are also of error. When expressions do not conform to
the intended idea, there also individuates the knowledge of how to not do it.
Experimentation and learning: two poles of technical individuation that necessarily
resonate with one another.
From this standpoint, the diagram can be related with Deleuze's three moments
of the idea. It can be said to be unconscious, i.e. undetermined with regard to its
problems; it can be said to be sensible, i.e. determinable with regards to the objects of
experience; and it can be said to be intelligible, i.e. determinate with regard to the
concepts of the understanding. The first diagrammatic moment corresponds to the
fracture of the content-expression encounter. It is the abstract machine's very plane of
composition. The second diagrammatic moment corresponds to the association between
142
problems in potential and the possibilities of representation. It is the mapping of
contrasts between the unknown and what has already come to knowledge. The third
diagrammatic moment corresponds to the objective determination of cases of solution,
which can be both immaterial and material. In either case, it is always a conceptual
structure, either a diagram of speculation or a diagram of confirmation. All these
moments are diagrammatic not only because they are related to one another by means of
the abstract machine's topological continuity, but also because they are structured in
relation to this same topology's singular problems.
Here implied is the assumption that objects can have no correlate expression.
Structures can be thought without being expressed, and still be objective. Mermaids,
unicorns and pure mathematical objects are abstract objects. But by a principle of
immanence between abstractions and expressions, such objects are necessarily related
with materials grounds. They are the partial effect of metaphorical projections. Unicorns
are imagined to stand upright and mermaids to swim horizontally. Imagination proceeds
on the basis of material experiences: the concrete body of an imagining mind. Image
schemata and bodily tropisms, co-individuating together from the plane of composition
where no distinction can be made between content and expression. From this, much can
be imagined, even if with no concrete correlation. Such abstractions are,
notwithstanding, potentially expressible. Unicorns and mermaids can be drawn and
spoken, a process which necessarily requires learning and experimentation. Such
requirement follows not only from the idea's potentials of infinite determination with
regard to the concepts of the understanding, but also from the multiplicity of expressive
possibilities. The idea of a unicorn can be expressed with water-colours on paper, with
sand at the beach, or with computer graphics, all being different cases of solution for
one same problem of expression. Even the impossibility of expressing the same idea in
the same way twice entails the necessity of technical experimentation. If one
experiments drawing a unicorn but instead gets a horse, other experiments need to
follow until what is expressed conforms to what is imagined. Infinite cases of solution
can be drawn, but also infinite expressions can disconform to determinate ideas. Many
are the possibilities and the potentials of individuation.
104 Diagramma is the Greek word for diagram. Knoespel explains that “[t]he root verb of diagramma
means not simply something which is marked out by lines, a figure, form, or plan, but also carries a
secondary connotation of marking or crossing out. In contemporary Greek the verb diagrapho, noun
diagraphe, means to write someone off.” (2002, pp. 20–21).
143
embodies a practice of figuring, defiguring, refiguring, and prefiguring. What is
interesting is that the diagram participates in a geneology of figures that moves from the
wax tablet to the computer screen. From a phenomenological vantage point, the Greek
setting of diagram suggests that any figure that is drawn is accompanied by an
expectancy that it will be redrawn. Within such a dynamic framework, such expectancy
must also be accompanied by an understanding of the ways in which diagram can shift
in status. Here diagram may be thought of as a relay. While a diagram may have been
used visually to reinforce an idea one moment, the next it may provide a means for
seeing something never seen before. Because diagrams mark a gesture or momentum
toward definition, they function as vehicles that employ and invite elaboration through
narrative.” (2002, p. 21). Diagrammatic relaying regards not only a capacity of such
objects to foster the individuation of cases of solution but also a capacity to repeat with
a difference their own constitutive topology, in continuity. Diagrams are therefore
capable of creating expressive nexuses across different cases of solution. Their
expressions are iterations of their potential structure. In its most basic expression,
diagrammatic iterability corresponds to language's expressive variability. Singular
expressions for singular encounters. To say that the relaying of an object's diagram can
“shift its status” (Ibid.) means that the knowledge by it provided can be constituted
anew. The individuation of knowledge that comes with a diagram's objective expression
attests its participation in transducing what it represents. Which is not to say that such
expressions are by themselves capable of informational exchange. It is rather to say that,
insofar as they partake of technical individuation, they are correlated with the
conceptual structures that they represent. After all, an objective diagram is but one
possible case of solution for an idea's problems. It emerges with knowledge as much as
knowledge can also emerge from it. It is a vehicle of technical transduction because it
can condition learning. As media theorist and artist Sher Doruff notices, “one of many
ways that transduction is actualized is through the diagrammatic contours of conceptual
space in which diverse realities are connected, coupled and erased” (2006, p. 92). From
this perspective, even the most simple representation of an abstract schema conserves
with itself the necessary potentials to become different from itself and, with this
movement, individuate novel instants of knowledge. This, of course, is an operation
based on the condition of an intrinsic difference. And what is perhaps most evident in
regard to this difference is the fact that, as much as individuation comprises a
preindividual share, there is always more to it than what can be known. The concepts of
the understanding can only regard what is somewhat determinate in individuation. Not
144
only has this to do with the limits of experience, i.e. with what a body can in fact access,
but also with the fact that, because of being by definition undetermined, potentials
cannot be known as such.
If there is the case of what cannot be empirically known, there is also the case of
what can come to be known only by means of abstraction. In this latter case,
metaphorical projections are used to abstract knowledge from the body's concrete
experiences. Even what cannot be directly experienced can come to be known,
indirectly. This is, for example, the case with mathematical reductions of matter and
energy, which allow for non-empirical instances of knowledge to be attained. But
insofar as mathematical abstractionism proceeds by a speculative type of reasoning, it
can only be said to constitute knowledge that is proper to technical invention, if this is
to some degree consistent with what can be empirically experienced. The limits of
technics are therefore coincident with the limits of the body, be these concrete or
abstract. This does not mean however that the body's limits are the limits of technics.
Mathematical abstractions can generate knowledge that goes beyond the possibilities of
technical experience. And the former can only condition the latter if correlated in any
way to what can be actually experienced by the technical subject.
145
abstracted from intentionality itself. Either knowledge is taken to be experiential and
thus dependent on its conditions of possibility, or it is taken to be mathematical and thus
abstractable from concrete experience. With this, and in what regards the pursue of
eidetic knowledge, it is easy to understand why mathematics have become so pervasive
in modern science. The sole fact that mathematics are designated as fundamental
sciences points towards the very assumption of a fundament of things, i.e. of an
essential kernel constituting the invariable and self-coincident identity of things. And
despite possible criticisms upon the conceptual fundaments of eidetic reductionism,
what is perhaps most striking and informing in regard to the relation between abstract
and concrete diagrams is the fact that it is both possible to know, through mathematical
abstraction, objects that are beyond any possibility of concrete experience, and possible
to experience things that cannot be known in abstraction. In contrast, it can also be said
that there are many experiential events, i.e. objects of intentionality, that coincide with
what is possible to be abstracted from experience. For example, computational models
can simulate processes, yielding results similar to their referents. In order to do so, they
must share the same possibility space (DeLanda, 2011, pp. 17–21).
A process's possibility space is its topology. It is the state space where the many
potentials and possibilities of occurrence are distributed according to a function of
probability. In any content-expression encounter there is a distribution of probabilities
regarding the affective relation between matters and functions. The topological
definition of each encounter is also singular because of this: to each encounter, its
singular distribution of probabilities. The diagrammatic identity of the DS/DM is
assured by the probability that it has of relating different contents to one another in
specific ways. Its possibility space is determined by the way in which expressive
functions constrain the contents of its expression. If other diagrams are considered,
different problems will be posed to their expression. This, of course, regards the fact
that each content-expression encounter not only unfolds in accordance with the
topological distribution of its probabilities, but also in accordance with an individuation
of thought that is necessarily determined by such structure. And if it can be argued that
each topological structure is invariable in the way that it constrains its own
choreographic expressions, it can also be argued that what comes to be known with each
choreographic idea is necessarily singular. Since a problem's resolution cannot unfold
but in accordance with the singularity of each encounter, any co-individuating thought
will be equally singular.
From this standpoint, there are a couple of aspects that can be further
146
problematized. First, it seems necessary to look into the resolution of different problems
in the expression of choreographic ideas by digital means. In this respect, the two case
studies till now discussed have allowed for the understanding that choreographic objects
are diagrammatic, but not for the understanding that they are algorithmic. Of course the
resumption that these objects endured into the digital domain already attests such
character. Nevertheless, the digital domain seems to be capable of confirming the
algorithmic capacity of choreography by reason of its own workings. Since the digital
domain functions on the basis of algorithmic programming, it can be that an object's
possibility space, instead of being expressed just as one case of solution (as it is with the
“Improvisation Technologies” and with the DS/DM, as till now discussed), can be
expressed as a series of solutions, all related to one another by one same algorithmic
function of expression. The difference between this and the previous examples regards
the fact that, here, the matters of content are the same. As such, what digital
programming offers as a possibility of expression is the very algorithmic computation of
choreographic ideas. Between such possibility and the digital expression of the previous
examples what differs is the automatic degree of computation. Choreographic ideas can
in this way be programmed into the digital domain so that such algorithms compute a
multiplicity of expressions. In order to pursue such confirmation, this study's next
Chapter will look upon a series of digital choreographies, which have expressed
determinate ideas by means of algorithmic computation. The parametric automation of
choreographic ideas will make the case that its topological structure is not only
diagrammatic, but also algorithmic. A case that shouldn't be understood in the sense that
a choreographic idea is algorithmic because it is digitally programmable, but rather in
the other way around: the choreographic idea is digitally programmable because it
already is, in itself, algorithmic. After all, an algorithm is but a determinate structure of
potentials. Second, it will be also necessary to tackle the question of novelty from the
perspective of digital choreography. This regards not only the overarching problem (that
this study has been dealing with from the beginning) of technogenesis in the encounter
between dance and technology, but also the more specific problem of a digital sort of
potentiality. In other words, in regard to the algorithmic computation of choreographic
ideas, it matters to ask: are there, in the digital domain itself, the necessary potentials for
novel instances of choreographic knowledge to be expressed? And, if so, how are these
potentials to be thought if, in any case, it is arguable that the digital domain is based
upon possibilities rather than potentials, i.e. on binary sets rather than continuous
multiplicities? In regard to the encounter between dance and technology, such questions
147
are pertinent not only to pursue a better understanding of how this encounter is to
individuate a technogenetic body, but also to broaden the scope of the creative modes
that itself is capable of. This, of course, regards the understanding that thought
individuates in ways that are as different as the modes of relation between the topology
of ideas and the material constraints of each domain. Such variety of thoughts entails
the hypothesis that the creative potentials of digital programs are as well thoughtful
potentials. As such, it is also the hypothesis that, if this is to occur, computation must be
open to what it cannot compute, in the same way that any movement of thought is open
to what it cannot know—the unconscious. Such questions and hypotheses will be
pursued throughout Chapter 6 and, hopefully, result in propositions for teasing creativity
and individuating novel instances of choreographic knowledge.
148
Chapter 5 - ALGORITHMIC CHOREOGRAPHIES
This fifth Chapter will focus upon a series of examples that express
choreographic knowledge by digital means. In contrast to the examples previously
mentioned, these choreographic expressions result from algorithmic procedures that, as
particular cases of solution to the problems of choreographic transduction, were
automated digitally. The first case to be discussed (Section 5.1) is the “Gesture
Follower”, a software built into the digital expressions of the “Double Skin/Double
Mind”. As the name indicates, this is a software apt to recognize and follow the
performance of gesture. This will allow for essaying a distinction between the dancing
body and the gestural body and, from the perspective of digital algorithms, discuss once
more the relationship between dancing and writing in the constitution of choreographic
knowledge. The following Section will unfold by considering a series of choreographic
algorithms retrieved from two distinct projects: the “Motion Bank” and the “Reactor for
Awareness in Motion”. Different aspects of the so called online scores, created in the
frame of the first project, will be discussed in order to assess how, from different bodies
of artistic work, the problems of choreographic transduction have been resolved into the
algorithmic generation of digital expressions. These are the online scores of William
Forsythe's “One Flat Thing, reproduced” (called “Synchronous Objects”), Deborah
Hay's “No Time To Fly” (with the same name), Jonathan Burrows and Matteo Fargion's
series of duets (called “Seven Duets”), and Bebe Miller and Thomas Hauert's strategies
of choreographic improvisation (called “Two”). Insofar as the digital algorithms used in
these scores synthesize instances of choreographic knowledge, their transductive
capacity will be looked upon by considering instead the “Reactor for Awareness in
Motion's” software. Since this software's algorithms are meant to be “danced with”, in
real-time by dancing bodies, they will facilitate a better understanding of how all these
algorithms are capable of conveying choreographic knowledge.
149
5.1 - Diagramming Gesture
Regarding the encounter between dance and technology, Erin Manning notes
that one recurrent problem has to do with the definition of gesture. In her words,
“[e]xplorations of new technologies and dance, led by Mark Coniglio, Scott DeLahunta,
Antonio Camurri, and others, have often focused on the difficulty of locating gesture-as-
such” (2009, p. 61). Despite the fact that, here, the philosopher is specifically referring
to the encounter between dancing bodies and digital computers and, precisely because
of this, to the “embedding into the software program” (Ibid.) of gesture's definition, this
difficulty is common to all practices of dance notation. In fact, in what regards the
definition of gesture, between automated processes of gesture recognition and non-
automated ones, the difference is hardly one of quality.106 And this is not to say that the
subjective experience of someone who translates dance into choreographic notation is
not a qualitative one. Qualitative experience is necessarily implicated in the
transductions of knowledge conveyed by subjects for whom indetermination (of the
body) is a fundamental condition. It is rather to say that, insofar as in both cases the
content-expression encounter of writing is conditioned by symbolic conventions, what
can in fact come to be defined as gesture remains within the limits of what language can
possibly express. This is a quantitative limit. Whereas in the case of computers these
possibilities are necessarily located at the level of binary code, in the case of notational
systems they are located at the level of the symbols used to express choreography. And
of course that, if the former is used to express the latter what one necessarily gets is a
possibility space resulting from the concurrent set of binary code and choreographic
notations. In sum, besides being conceptually determined, gesture is here defined by
what is possible to be written.
From this standpoint, the written expressions of gesture can be said to coincide
with its conceptual structure. By limiting the possibilities of expression both with
discrete signs and with the articulatory nexuses of its significations, writing
discontinues the dancing body and, in this way, defines gesture as such. Conversely,
106 To say that computers recognize and notate gesture automatically is just a matter of expression. For,
as Simondon asserts, “there is no such thing as a robot” (1969 p.10). As such, computational
machines must be considered from the perspective of the context from which they result and in which
they evolve. In other words, as technical individuals, they must be considered together with the
associated milieu of their technicity. After all, what a computer comes to recognize as gesture needs
first to be defined by its inventors. Not only this, but the very definition of gesture embedded within a
computer's software depends as well on what the computer can in fact recognize as gesture. In this
sense, both computer and its definition of gesture individuate depending on one another.
150
such writing does not occur without the implicit determination of the concepts of the
understanding. At once, the definition of gesture regards what gets to be determined
when a body dances and the limits of writing itself. In regard to this relationship of the
dancing body with writing, through the determination of concepts, Manning quotes
dance and technology scholar Scott DeLahunta, for whom “the best way of coming to
an understanding of gesturality is to work collaboratively with dancers such that 'the
choreographic and computational processes are both informed by having arrived at this
shared understanding of the constitution of movement. This means descriptions (what
we think of as co-descriptions) of movement that can exist in both its own terms (as in
physical) as well as in the symbolic abstractions that are necessary in order to use these
techniques of gesture modeling, simulating, learning, following etc. with the computer.”
(Manning, 2009, p. 61; Delahunta, 2006). Though in the writing of gesture the
determination of concepts does not go without expressive determinations, they differ
and can therefore be distinguished from one another. First and foremost, this difference
regards the fact that the dancing body moves on the basis of continuous and
undetermined potentials. As mentioned before, the determination of concepts proceeds
from this bodily excess and cannot be understood without it, at least from a processual
perspective. Though writing occurs as well in relation to a degree of indetermination,
which ultimately is of the body itself, its limits are different and depend on the domain
of expression. Nonetheless, and regardless of this latter dependence, a written gesture
can only only come about with the discontinuous expression of determinate
possibilities. If the dancing body is the plane where undetermined potentials and
determinate concepts are related, the gestural body is the plane where the determination
of concepts gets to be related with determinate expressions. The one is unbounded and
the other limited, for example, by convention.
107 The GF started to be developed by Frédéric Bevilacqua, in the end of 2009, in the frame of his
research in gesture analysis and interactive music systems, at the IRCAM (Institute for
Music/Acoustic Research and Coordination in Paris), as included in the Real Time Musical
Interactions team (Bevilacqua, 2007, p. 27). The GF “is implemented as a collection of modules in
the Max environment [...], taking advantage of the data structures of the FTM library such as matrices
and dictionaries. Recently, the core algorithm was developed as an independent C++ library and can
therefore be implemented in other environments.” (Bevilacqua et al., 2010, p. 9).
151
the system's user, they are known by the computer itself. Specific definitions of gesture
have been embedded into the software so that this can recognize which user's
movements conform with them. As computer scientist Frédéric Bevilacqua writes,
“[t]he general idea behind the Gesture Follower is to compare a performance with
prerecorded ones. Basically, the first step corresponds to choosing one or several
phrases that will be recorded and stored in the computer memory. The choice of these
phrases is a crucial step; they should be representative of a gesture vocabulary or
contain meaningful qualities for the artist. The second step occurs during the
performance: the computer program assesses in real-time whether similar
vocabulary/qualities are present. The results can be output as ‘likelihood scores’
expressing the similarities of a given performance to the stored ones in the database.”
(2007, p. 28). As such, this software follows gestures on the basis of what it already
knows. The definitions of gesture embedded into it are digital memories that can be
recalled for the sake of recognition, memories that consist not only of registered events
but also of their indexation. “Finding similarity between the performance and stored
ones in a database can be one mechanism to characterize motion qualities, if each
phrase of the database has been labeled.” (Ibid., p. 30). Moreover, what allows for the
software to compare the two datasets is an algorithmic procedure of calculation that
takes each definition of gesture to be quantitatively determined. The G F converts the
DS/DM's movement qualities into determinate quantities of binary code and defines
each gesture as a digital patch against which to compare the real-time displacements of
the user's body. Such comparison serves to inform the system's user if the movements
performed conform or not with the given definitions and to instigate him or her to move
accordingly.
There is, notwithstanding, a determinant difference between the DVD and the
Interactive Installation versions of the DS/DM, which regards the sensors used by each
system to create motion data from the user's activity. Whereas in the Interactive
Installation the dancing body is captured with video cameras, in the DVD it is captured
with the computer's mouse. Such difference necessarily results in different types of
dataset, for their structure depends upon the input device. Whereas the computer mouse
is capable of capturing motion with regard to one moving point, the motion capture
made with video cameras can create arrays of data regarding the many moving points of
one pixelated plane of expression. If infrared cameras are instead considered, it is
possible that the datasets from them derived are structured in accordance with a three-
dimensional grid of variable points. These differences necessarily imply that the
152
datasets in comparison must be structured similarly. The GF's gestural definitions must
be structured as to be compared with the datasets derived from the input devices in use.
Which is to say that the very possibilities of motion capture play a part in structuring the
definitions of gesture embedded into the software. They act as a frame of reference that
limits and determines the quantities that the GF must calculate out of the examples to it
provided. In this sense, given gestures can only be recognized if the memory of what
has been previously registered is mappable onto the novel data. Of course that on both
sides this occurs on the basis of algorithmic calculations, which structure data in
determinate ways. The datasets reciprocal mappability depends on how raw data is
structured by the softwares in use, i.e. belonging both to the G F and to the motion
capture devices.108 It is also here that the conventional agreement of what gesture is
comes in. The structuration of data occurs both in accordance with what is possible to
be computed and in accordance with what gesture is known to be. This mixed procedure
is explained by Bevilacqua to be “based on the recognition that both our abstract gesture
representation and actual gesture data generally share common time properties, and the
links between them can be expressed as time relationships. For example, features
occurring simultaneously in both representations can be made explicit. This can
correspond to adding markers and profiles to a timeline [...]. The gesture follower
108 To say that the captured data is raw stands for saying that there is a structure to it. If such structure is
to be computed with determinate functions of expression (i.e. the algorithms themselves), it needs to
be transformed. That the data provided by motion capture systems does not correspond to an intuitive
image of the dancing body and that, for this reason, if it is to be rendered into the expression of a
recognizable figure, it needs to be processed and restructured, is noted by Frédéric Bevilacqua in the
following way: “Making links between our abstract gesture representation and the gesture data is
problematic. I always find it difficult to explain this to people who have little experience with motion
capture systems: they often do not realize this frustrating gap between how they think about gesture
and how actual capture systems behave. As a matter of fact, data often corresponds to a sparse and
non-intuitive representation of what body motion is. This leads to practical difficulties when working
with gesture capture technology, which sometimes gives the impression that the problem is with the
technology itself, while it is more often with the methods of tool use.” (2007, p. 30). As such, to say
that datasets' structures are raw stands for saying that they need to be restructured, for the purpose of
recognition. Likewise, it stands for saying that they are already structured in ways that are determined
by the algorithms of motion capture themselves, notwithstanding the fact that such structures do not
comply with the purposes of recognition. For example, the infrared camera of a Kinect sensor has
been used in the DS/DM's Interactive Installation for capturing the movements of the system's user
(Alaoui, 2012, p. 72). This sensor infers the position of the dancing body in two steps. It first
computes a depth map (using structured light) and then infers body position (using machine learning)
(Freedman et al., 2012; Khoshelham & Elberink, 2012). It is not worth here to describe these
computations in detail. It is enough to note that the image of the dancing body generated by such
sensor is the result of a set of algorithmic procedures belonging to the motion capture system itself.
As computer scientist Sarah Fdili Alaoui notes, “these data need to be subjected to a supplementary
treatment in order to be possible to extract from them, for example, the positions of certain parts of
the body”. In other words, these data need to be restructured in order to be used for determinate
purposes. “In the frame of the DS/DM”, says Alaoui, “we have developed a patch in Max/MSP/Jitter,
which makes use of the cv.jit library (for image processing), in order to subtract the background of
the captured image and, with this, generate a silhouette of the dancing body defined by certain
geometrical characteristics.” (2012, pp. 79–80).
153
embodies such an approach, as it considers phrases as temporal objects we can observe
– we can ‘look inside the phrase’ to find salient moments or try to predict what is going
to happen. These temporal objects can also interact with other objects, sounds for
example. This represents a different view on the usual interaction paradigm considering
frame/posture as basic elements. Typically, the relationship between gesture data and
sound or visuals is referred to as ‘mapping’, a clear reference to the consideration of
primarily spatial relationships”. (Bevilacqua, 2007, pp. 30–31). Such mapping onto
sound files is used by the GF to inform the system's user of the coincidence between the
movements performed and the salient moments of a temporal digital object. In this way,
all three datasets are mapped onto one another so that the software is capable of
following the movements performed by stretching or shortening both the reproduction
of sound and the reproduction of the registered examples.
The conventional representations of gesture used in the DVD for the workings of
the GF exemplify how the problem of their expression had to comply with the fact that
motion data is here retrieved from the computer's mouse. Instead of being defined with
video registers of the dancing body, each of the DS/DM's movement qualities is
represented by an ideogram (see Illustration 4, below) which allows it to be defined as a
determinate succession of points across one or several lines. Though such ideograms
have been specifically created for this software, they derive from a system of
choreographic notation used in Japanese Butoh-Fu, called Butoh-Kaden109. The reason
for this choice is explained by Bertha Bermúdez in the following way: “The issues
treated in the Notation Research Project that EG|PC initiated in 2004, deal with dance
documentation, notation and their relation with movement intentionality – the inner
motivation for the movement. It is around the very problematic question of how to
notate intentionality that the Butoh-Fu system shares some principles and tools with this
research project.” (2007, p. 59). It follows that the GF's ideograms are meant to convey
the movements of thought implicated in each of the DS/DM's movement qualities.
Though expressed symbolically, they implicate the metaphorical, imagetic, and
diagrammatic character of the choreographic ideas intended to be transduced. 110 They
109 In Bertha Bermúdez's words, “Butoh-Kaden is based on the idea that 'physicality exists through
acquired knowledge. The images refer to form and the words refer to symbols. Words are important
in the Butoh-Kaden system because they express matters that cannot be symbolized and they are the
medium to expand physicality through the use of imagination. [Yukio Waguri, Butoh-Kaden's creator]
has structured eighty-eight Butoh-Fu (i.e. scores) that are connected to seven different worlds. These
seven worlds have different qualities that are described through images, words, sounds, workshop
experiences and performance demonstrations.” (2007, p. 59)
110 It should be noted that, in order to facilitate the transduction of choreographic ideas, both the DVD
and the Interactive Installation allow for the GF to be used in different ways. In both cases, one can
“watch” examples of how to move, one can “learn” how to move by following the registered cases of
154
Illustration 4: The symbolic notations of each of the
DS/DM's movement qualities, as seen on the GF's
interface of the DVD. Here, the black dots represent the
mouse's cursor. (Delahunta, 2007a).
are specific cases of solution with regard to these ideas. Also, it is worth noting that
determinate patterns of displacement along the lines of these ideograms were registered
in order to be compared with the displacements of the computer's mouse. These are the
referential definitions of gesture given to the software to be compared with what this
may capture from the user's activity. What here gets to be recognized as gesture is but
the synthetic resolution of a point's expressive displacements along the lines of
symbolic notations.
solution, and one can “play” freely with the different movement qualities in order to be signalled by
the software about which one is being performed. All these modalities of use complement one another
with regard to the transduction of the different choreographic ideas being expressed. By watching,
learning and playing with the G F, the user experiences the workshop's movement qualities in
different ways and can therefore more consistently learn how to move accordingly.
155
sound, with the body movements. The dancer is then ‘followed’ by a breathing sound,
either stretched or shortened, depending on how slow or fast the phrase is performed.”
On the other hand, “[s]everal phrases from the workshop Double Skin/Double Mind
were recorded with a mixed capture system using both sensors attached to the body and
video analysis (EyesWeb). In particular [they] focused on two choreographed phrases
danced by Bertha Bermúdez and Emio Greco (around 30 seconds long) that [were]
recorded several times. This choice was driven by the need for having phrases with
precisely specified movements, which greatly facilitates the comparison mechanism of
t h e gesture follower. Different tests were tried. First, [they] segmented one of the
recorded phrases into subsections [..]. When performing the phrase again, the gesture
follower was set to recognize these subsections and output a sonic signal (a ‘click’).
According to both the dancer (Bertha Bermúdez) and the viewers, the sound was heard
at the right time, indicating that the system was able to segment the phrase correctly”.
(2007, pp. 29–30). One of the differences between these two notation methods thus
regards the moment in technical transduction when cases of solution for the
structuration of movement qualities are determined. In the first case, gesture is
determined with notation itself. Drawing the contour of a dance form on video is a
qualitative determination that depends both on the chosen registers and on the specific
way in which the contours themselves are drawn. Here, the determination of gesture
occurs after the dance event and in concomitance with the conventional agreement that
gesture can be defined as it is drawn. In the second case, gesture is determined with the
structuration of a dance phrase by the dancing body, constraining already here the
undetermined potentials of each movement quality with a given form. In this case, the
digital definition of gesture then just simply remarks a structure defined from the outset,
in the very moment of the dance event. Such definition corresponds to the conversion of
the dance's remarkable points into definite quantities of data. It is the conversion of this
choreography's conceptual structure into determinate quantities of data retrieved from
the dance's video registers. In both methods, the definition of gesture by means of video
attests that, for the GF to recognize and follow the movements performed by the
system's user, it must take as reference gestures depicted from the same kind of data
generated with the input sensors in use, that is, video data. The positional character of
these models cannot be emphasized enough. Gesture is defined by an array of points,
each with a determinate value. Regardless of the fact that these values can vary in
accordance with given probabilities, the models at stake discontinue movement into a
series of numbers. They not only discontinue movement into measurable quantities but
156
do this by codifying them with determinate arrays of binary states. At the level of
computation, this is gesture's conceptual structure. If granted that gesture's matters of
content belong to the computational system's electronic circuits (including the
interfacial and qualitative expressions of sounds and visuals), then its functions of
expression must be granted to belong to the mathematical abstractions of computational
algorithms. From which it follows that, computationally, choreographic objects are
mathematical abstractions. In other words, they are the algorithmic models that bring
electronic circuits into qualitative expressions capable of conveying choreographic
ideas.
Both in regard to the data structured from the referential examples of dance and
in regard to the data structured via input sensors, the GF's algorithms act as functions of
expression. They restructure the datasets by computing them in accordance with
determinate parametric constraints. “The system outputs continuously parameters
relative to the gesture time progression and its likelihood. These parameters are
computed by comparing the performed gesture with stored reference gestures. The
method relies on a detailed modeling of multidimensional temporal curves.”
(Bevilacqua et al., 2010, p. 1). What is compared are the quantities calculated from
treating the datasets with these constraining parameters. Such computation not only
allows for predicting gesture's progression according to a statistical distribution of
probabilities (associated with each calculated value), as it also allows for the datasets to
be compared precisely on this basis. The GF's algorithms sample points from the
temporal profile of the video registers, translating them into values that define gesture in
each specific location of its development. It can therefore be said that the interest here is
both “in computing the time progression of the performance, or in other words
answering the question 'where are we within the gesture?'” and “in computing
likelihood values between a performed gesture and pre-recorded gestures stored in a
database. This can be used to perform a recognition task, but also to characterize
gestures. [...] Moreover, the estimation of both the time progression and likelihood
values enable another important feature of such a system: the possibility to predict the
evolution of the current gesture.” (Ibid., pp. 1-2). The parameters computed by the GF's
algorithms rely on the calculation of temporal and spatial descriptors of the dancing
body. This is described by computer scientist Sarah Fdili Alaoui in her doctoral thesis,
dedicated to the problems of gesture's analysis in the context of the DS/DM's research
projects, in regard to the use of infrared cameras.111 “The spatial descriptors define the
111 It is worth noting that Frédéric Bevilacqua was Alaoui's thesis co-supervisor.
157
geometries of the dancing body, in relation to its surrounding space. The temporal
descriptors define the gesture's temporal evolution.” (Alaoui, 2012, p. 81, my
translation). The spatial descriptors are: 1) body's verticality (calculated as the ratio
between the silhouette's height and width); 2) shoulder's angle (calculated as the angle
held between one arm and the silhouette's vertical axis); 3) body's extension (calculated
as the maximum distance between the silhouette's centre of mass and the sum of its
extremities); 4) legs' width (calculated as the distance held between the two feet); 5)
weight transference (calculated as the distance between the mass centre's abscissa and
the centre of the segment connecting the two feet). The temporal descriptors are: 1)
periodicity and frequency (calculated as the average of the coefficient of statistical
correlation between the four extremities of the silhouette); 2) increment and decrement
(calculated as the temporal evolution of any of the previous spatial descriptors); 3)
quantity of movement (calculated as the frame-by-frame variation of the silhouette's
number of pixels, when translated into a digital display). (Ibid., pp. 81–82). From the
calculation of such descriptors, the GF can then express the gestural body as a series of
solutions with regard to the problem of how to represent the movement qualities in case
with digital possibilities. According to Alaoui, “[t]he reason for this choice has to do
with the fact that the descriptors […] allow for the GF to account for the very fine
nuances of movement that are characteristic of the DS/DM's dancing body. The
algorithms are in this way capable of recognizing movement qualities that more general
approaches, such as Labanian ones, aren't.” (Ibid., pp. 80–81). Since such descriptors
are calculated relatively to the dancing body's silhouette in order to output visual
representations of gesture, i.e. quadrilateral shapes, which allow for the system's user to
grasp how the computational system is processing such translation (see Illustration 5,
below), it can in fact be said that this is a Labanian method of analysis. Expressively,
this is a method which reduces the dancing body to a geometrical form that, despite
being different from Labanotation, results from the same kind of movement analysis.
The GF's capacity of recognizing nuances in movement can instead be addressed to
gesture's temporal progression, since the 30 frames per second that these sensors output
allow for movement to be notated with a resolution much greater than the one usually
attained by traditional methods of choreographic notation.
This notation method is somewhat different from the two previous ones, for the
calculation of descriptive variables is from the outset a quantitative procedure. Of
course all these methods rely on the conversion of conceptual structures into structured
quantities of data. But in this latter method definitions of gesture are not given to the
158
Illustration 5: In this picture, it can be seen how the learning subject is placed in front of a screen,
where two different figures are displayed. There is the figure of Emio Greco's dancing body, as
recorded with video. And there is also the silhouette of the dancer's body, as processed by the
software after motion capture. As it can also be seen, the software not only extracts the silhouette
of the dancer's body from motion capture data, but also draws its geometries with moveable boxes.
Such boxes describe gestures parametrically. Retrieved 04/06/13, from http://sarah.alaoui.free.fr
(Alaoui's Ph.D Webpage).
software on the condition of being relative to a set of examples, but rather on the
condition of being primarily unrelated to actual matters of content. In this sense, the
algorithms that structure the sensors' raw data can be understood as definitions of
gesture in themselves. And though these algorithms are specifically designed to act as
functions of expression, what will come to be defined as gesture depends solely on the
descriptive values computed by them. As such, they are perfect examples of what a
choreographic object can be like in the digital domain. They express the DS/DM's
conceptual structure independently from the matters of content generated with the input
sensors.112 Conversely, the definitions of gesture necessary for the workings of the GF
112 It should be noted that, in her doctoral thesis, Alaoui develops still another method where gesture is
defined with the computation of determinate parametric structures (2012, pp. 66–78). This is a
method said to follow from the intuition that the DS/DM's movement qualities correspond to the
dynamic behaviours of spring-mass systems (Ibid., p. 64). A spring-mass system is defined on the one
hand by an object composed with a mass attached to a spring and on the other hand by the fact that
this object's displacements, in one dimension only, are conditioned by forces of elasticity and
viscosity. With this method, gesture is first coordinated in regard to the relative position of body parts
to be analysed (i.e. the extremities of the dancing body) and then calculated according to differential
equations in regard to variables such as speed and acceleration. Since these differential equations are
capable by themselves of modeling gesture, this is a model that neither requires that the software is
provided with a set of referential gestures (and therefore with a learning phase) nor that it is
programmed to work according to a set of gestural descriptors (Ibid, pp. 65–66). Even without such
159
can only be determined after the calculation of cases of solution for the problems
implicit in the software's algorithmic functions of expression. From which it follows
that, because such choreographic objects are constrained by the possibilities of the
digital domain, instead of being just models of potential transition, they can also be
thought as models of possible transition. For as much as the GF acts as an insert of
possibilities amidst the potentials of a milieu of technical individuation, it limits the
latter with what the software can in fact calculate. The abstract character of
choreographic objects is in this way reduced to the possibilities of the digital domain. A
constraining of potentials with the possibilities of digital code. Nonetheless, such
choreographic objects should be seen as being embedded in a milieu of technical
individuation, full with undetermined potentials. After all, not only are these algorithms
technical individuals, as they are also the necessary condition for a choreographic
transduction to occur into dancing body's domains.
The capacities of algorithmic calculation have been used for writing dance in
ways that extend the image of the body in space and time. This is not new to
choreographic notation. Writing dance with symbols not only gives form to the
problems in translation, as it brings past experiences into spatial juxtaposition. What in
the dancing body unfolds in succession, in traditional notation stands side-by-side.
Accordingly, one of the problems that is possibly solved with choreographic notation
regards the sense-making of what in experience is both immediate and diachronical. The
individuation of thought is mirrored by the individuation of writing and resolved into
expressions that convey both their own logic and a sense proper to the ideas in regard to
which they stand as solution. What is mirrored between individuations is the idea's
diagrammatic structure, i.e. the same problems that relate the different modes of
expression. In regard to memory, the expressive variations of choreography can result in
different instances of retention, each with its proper character. Whereas dance is
experienced empirically only to be, sooner or later, forgotten, writing retains such
experience by representing its diagrams. Without writing, memory remains abstract.
requirements, it was concluded that “spring-mass models are good candidates for the visual
presentation of dynamic renderings of the DS/DM movement qualities” (Ibid, p. 64, my translation).
For more developments on the expression of spring-mass models in the context of the DS/DM's
Interactive Installation, see Chapters 5 and 7 of Alaoui's doctoral thesis (Ibid., pp. 87–115, 131-149).
160
Writing overwrites the actual conditions of its own individuation by compressing
memory into the actuality of the present.
161
The possibilities of algorithmic computation are many. As many as the ones
comprised by the possibility space of the content-expression encounter calculated
between two datasets. Even in the case where both functions of expression and matters
of content remain the same, relatively to one another, differences in expression can
occur. The same set of actual expressions can vary in space and time, contracting or
expanding the perception of a first calculated order of magnitude. In regard to
choreographic notation, this stands for the fact that the gestural body can be contracted
or expanded and, with each of these procedures, express otherwise imperceptible data.
In fact, these are not two distinct procedures but only different perspectives upon one
same operation. Insofar as this operation is characteristic of choreographic notation, any
of its expressions serves to understand the duality in case. It suffices to say that, because
writing compresses time into one same plane of expression, it also expands space. This
duality is, for example, expressed when the graphic symbols of choreographic notation
are used to inscribe the memory of a succession of states onto one same surface,
accreting in this way matters of content to the plane of their own expression. The more
time is compressed onto the surface of graphic inscription, the more space is created.
The compression of time into one same plane of expression can in this way densify or
disperse the number of occurrences within one same referential metric. In either case,
the objective space is extended.
113 Retrieved from the MB's website (http://motionbank.org). All references from online sources quoted
in this section were retrieved during August, 2014.
114 http://synchronousobjects.osu.edu
115 http://scores.motionbank.org
162
In the case of William Forsythe's choreographic work, the website SOfOFTr
represents a series of efforts for “visualizing choreographic structure from dance to data
to objects”116. Such efforts were coordinated by Forsythe himself, together with artist
and scholar Norah Zuniga Shaw, from the Ohio State University’s Department of
Dance, and Maria Palazzi, the director of Ohio State University’s Advanced Computing
Centre for the Arts and Design. Together with a group of designers and scientific
researchers, they “worked with the Forsythe Company to unearth the choreographic
building blocks of OFTr, quantify them, and repurpose this information visually and
qualitatively” (Forsythe et al. 2009, pp. 2–3). The result was a series of digital objects
that, because they are all mapped onto the same spatiotemporal grid (i.e. the
choreographic metric depicted from the dance performance), are synchronous in regard
to one another. Because their temporality is organized with the same metric, they can be
seen not only as different expressions of one same topological object, but also as the
overall expression of the OFTr's multidimensionality. To visualize the different objects
synchronously is to relate in perception the many nexuses that the OFTr not only
expresses, but also holds in potential. Also, such objects can be synchronized with one
another because all of them have taken the video registers of the OFTr's performance as
the referential data from which to depict this choreography's diagrammatic (i.e.
temporal and spatial) character.117 Many of the SOfOFTr are but choreographic notations
of the OFTr's performance, made on its video registers. Such notations resulted from
two specific types of data. They resulted from the spatial data generated “by tracking a
single point on each dancer in both the top and front views of the source video of OFTr.
By combining the coordinates from both views, [the animators] were able to generate a
three-dimensional data point for each dancer’s location at every moment of the dance”.
And they resulted as well from the attribute data “built from the dancers’ firsthand
accounts. […] The attribute data catalogs the three systems of the dance: movement
material, cues, and alignments”. (Forsythe et al. 2009, pp. 2–3). Whereas attribute data
served the dance's qualitative notation, spatial data served its algorithmic notation. Both
modes of notation are expressed digitally in the SOfOFTr's website, together with the
video recordings, on top of which they are drawn. But whereas the notation derived
from attribute data has been subjectively drawn, the notation derived from spatial data
has been objectively drawn, that is, it has been drawn by means of digital algorithms
163
programmed to compute the quantities of data retrieved from analyzing the dance's
video recordings.
It is therefore with the spatial data used to create the SOfOFTr that the issues of
spatial compression before mentioned can be best understood. Not only has this to do
with the fact that, “[a]s in many forms of inquiry, quantification requires a reductive
process that necessarily obscures certain aspects of knowledge (the dancers’ intentions,
performance quality, and kinaesthetic awareness) in order to reveal others (in this case,
choreographic structure)” (Ibid.), as it has to do with the fact that the SOfOFTr created
with spatial data resulted precisely from the accretion of data on data. The objects
created with the “Video Abstraction Tool” (VAT)118 (see Illustration 6, below) are
examples of this. This tool was invented “to demonstrate novel ways of visualizing the
dance itself. [With it] patterns that are hidden due to the overall complexity of the entire
scene can be brought out by visually emphasizing movement so that both the short- and
long-term patterns of the dance, temporal relationships between movements, and spatial
information regarding how the performance area is being utilized, are revealed”
(Andereck, 2009). This is done by applying a number of possible algorithms, i.e. filters,
Illustration 6: Video Abstraction Tool's GUI. The yellow circles, here designated as “crumbs”,
trace each dancer's displacements within the video frame according to a determinate temporal
metric. The filter “crumbs” has been used to create the “Difference Marks” object.
118 This tool is available for download at the SOfOFTr's website (http://synchronousobjects.osu.edu/cont
ent.html#/VideoAbstractionTool). Notably, it is a piece of software programmed with the
MAX/JITTER environment.
164
to the choreography's video recordings. When a filter or a combination of filters is used
as a function of expression for processing video, this is brought into results that, rather
than expressing the transformation of what is given, i.e. the video itself, express the
accretion of novel data onto it. In this way, new datasets can be mapped from and onto
the very video from which they result. Space is mapped onto space. Not just any space,
but the space formed with choreographic resolution. Each of the VAT's filters compress
spatio-temporal data in order to double the video's movement-images with other images
of movement. These latter images can be described as deformations of the spatio-
temporal patterns belonging to the referential movement-images. Space is extended in
order to be perceived as an extension of time. When time (i.e. a spatial time) is
extended, what wasn't perceived by reason of being either too fast or too small, or even
either too large or too slow, becomes information. It informs subjects with novel
perceptions regarding the OFTr.
All the objects created with the VAT express differentials belonging to the
performance of the OFTr. This is so not only because the performance itself expresses
the OFTr's choreographic system, i.e. the differential topology to which it belongs, but
also because this tool's algorithms are programmed to compute the frame-by-frame
variation of its video registers. As Norah Zuniga Shaw (2009) notices, the VAT was
created “in order to share aspects of the software filters used in making the 'Difference
Forms', 'Difference Marks' and 'Noise Void' animations.119 Each small adjustment in the
filters [used] for these animations creates interesting aesthetic results and analytical
discoveries”. Further, these objects' names indicate the algorithmic computation of
differences in the video's frame-by-frame progression that they express. Perhaps the
most clear expression of this is the “Difference Marks” object. As shown in Illustration
6 (above) the expression of this object notates, with a series of small circles, the
displacements of each dancing body. As the dance develops, the graphemes accumulate,
expressing in simultaneity what is given with the frame-by-frame videographic
succession. As it can be read in the SOfOFTr's website: “This object visualizes the
accumulation of the dancers' motion over time. Here the duration of the dance is
compressed from 15 mins. 30 secs. to 1 min. 30 secs., and any instance of motion (what
we call localized difference) is noted with a small mark. The colours of these marks
change over time from red to blue, revealing distinct layers and patterns of motion as
165
the piece progresses. One of the goals for this object, which looks down at the dance
from above, was to see how much the dancers both reinforce the grid of tables and
subvert it. As the animation progresses, outlines of the tables grow distinct as the
dancers interact with them.”120
Illustration 7: “Cues and Themes - Graphic score of movement material, cueing and sync-ups
generated from the data gathered from One Flat Thing, reproduced. Credit: Synchronous Objects
Project, The Ohio State University and The Forsythe Company.” Retrieved from
http://synchronousobjects.osu.edu.
166
objects have been created after such notation. There are the objects where these
notations are overlaid on the OFTr's video registers and visually synchronized with the
dancers' performance (as seen, for example, in Illustration 8, below), and there are the
objects that translate the OFTr's attributes into parametric structures, which can be
operated by altering the parameters' values (for example, the “Cue Visualizer Tool”, as
seen in Illustration 9, below). The latter are generative tools, similar to the VAT, which
allow for visualizing the different possibilities of expression that the rearticulation of the
OFTr's attributes allows for.
Illustration 8: “Cueing System - Still from annotated video illustrating the complex system of
cueing in One Flat Thing, reproduced Credit: Synchronous Objects Project, The Ohio State
University and The Forsythe Company.” Retrieved from http://synchronousobjects.osu.edu.
121 The full MB's score of No Time to Fly can be accessed at http://scores.motionbank.org/dh/.
122 The full explanation of this procedure can be accessed at http://motionbank.org/en/event/deborah-
hay-score-project-solo-filming.
167
Illustration 9: Cue Visualizer Tool's GUI. Retrieved from http://synchronousobjects.osu.edu/tool
s/cueVisualizer.html.
leaving space for highly variable expressions. Whereas the OFTr is a choreography with
a great degree of formal structuration, one which assures its invariance across different
instances of performance, the N T T F is a choreography with large margins of
indetermination, i.e. its expressions in performance are highly variable (given that it is
nonetheless determined by constraints such as being a stage performance for one dancer
only). In order to deal with this problem, the M B project video recorded a series of
performances by three different dancers—Ros Warby, Juliette Mapp and Jeanine
Durning—so that their differences could be juxtaposed and, in this way, facilitate the
perception of this choreography's nexus. One of the expressions rendered after the
motion capture of this choreography's different interpretations is the overlay of all the
pathways performed across the stage (see Illustration 10, below), a sort of visualization
that does not differ much from the ones created with the quantitative analysis of the
SOfOFTr's spatial data.
The transduction of the NTTF's movement qualities into the digital domain has
instead rendered a sort of algorithmic expression that is nowhere to be found on the
SOfOFTr's website. This is a 3D digital animation of algorithmic parameters, designed
by programmer Amin Weber (see Illustration 11, below), after the experience that the
168
Illustration 10: “21 solos overlaid. 7 x 3 performers.” (seen from
above). Retrieved from http://motionbank.org/sites/motionbank.org/fil
es/glossary.pdf.
Illustration 11: Still from the final version of the digital adaptation of the solo “No Time to Fly”
by Deborah Hay, as programmed by Amin Weber. Retrieved from http://scores.motionbank.org/d
h/#/set/digital-adaptation-of-no-time-to-fly.
169
dancers, the choreographer and the programmer had of the different performances.123 In
contrast to quantitative analyses of motion data, what is here expressed by digital means
is the programmer's own conception of this choreography. Which is why this digital
animation is referred to as an “algorithmic metaphor”. It expresses the resolution of
problems located at the many levels of a transduction, which goes from the dance to the
viewer and from the viewer turned programmer into the digital domain. This is really
not a matter of translation. It is a process that unfolds on the basis of thoughts, which
move towards resolutions of the problems at stake. Such problems necessarily pertain
both to the content-expression encounter of thought and to the content-expression
encounter of writing. And if the problems of the former can be located at the level of the
affective-perceptive order of subjective experience, the problems of the latter
necessarily pertain to the relationship between the excessive potentials of thought and
the limited possibilities of digital coding. If what is transferred between domains are not
only forms but also forces, what in the end attests the transductiveness of such process
is the metaphorical character of its digital expressions. What is expressed is less what
was seen to be danced, but more what was experienced as a whole, that is, the very
openness of the dancer to its excessive reality. What is expressed are the principles of
individuation felt by the viewer when acting upon the dancer. It can even be said that
the kinds of image schemata underlying the many metaphorical projections taking place
in this whole process are the ones that mirror in the viewer the forces active in the
dancer. Empathy in kinaesthesia. And from the internal resonance of such senses in the
body follows the challenge of expressing within the limits of writing the forces in
transduction.
The gestural bodies created by the MB from the joint work of choreographer
Jonathan Burrows and composer Matteo Fargion are also algorithmic metaphors. The
“SEVEN DUETS”, dedicated to “[f]ragments, movements and insights from the
interplay between”124 the two artists, comprises collections of what have been
designated as “Generators” and “Performers”.125 “Generators” are pulse patterns used
170
to animate the digital “Performers”. These pulse patterns were created by adding
markers to the video recordings of different works with the “Piecemaker”, a video
annotation software developed by David Kern for The Forsythe Company to “support
the organization and recall of materials created in the rehearsal studio” 126. With this
software, time markers output pulse patterns, which are then used for animating the
digital “Performers”. At the “Meanwhile in parallel worlds...”127 set (where the
collection of “Generators/ Performers'” is presented), one can watch how animated
“Performers” respond to the video registers of dance events. Illustration 12 (below),
shows a montage of the “Piecemaker's” GUI with the digital “Performers”. The latter
are simple algorithms, programmed with Javascript, which animate the figures with
each pulse received. In this illustration it can also be seen how the software's GUI
comprises a video frame and the video's annotated timeline. Each of the timeline's
coloured bands (in grey) corresponds to an annotation, which is also part of a list
disposed below the timeline. Whenever the annotated video is read, the software outputs
corresponding values. Such triggers can also be visualized while the annotations are
highlighted on the list.128
171
Illustration 12: Montage with the GUI of the Piecemaker software and the figures of the animated
“Performers”, which have been programmed to react to the software's cues. Images retrieved
from the “Meanwhile in parallel worlds ...” set (http://scores.motionbank.org/jbmf/#/set/aparallel-
world) and from the video explanation of the workings of the Generator/Performer's pairs
(http://vimeo.com/93275260).
that these “Performers” have reduced degrees of freedom. For example, the “Performer
Watcha Looking At?”129, figured as two round eyes (see Illustration 12, above), and its
paired “Generator”, drawn only from video registers where Jonathan Burrows performs
a series of arms' movements, has only eight degrees of freedom—closing the eyes,
moving the eye balls to the right, and so on. These degrees of freedom are this
“Performer's” expressive range. The data computed from the video recordings
eventuates only the possibilities programmed into their digital determinations.
Moreover, this figure's animation iterates its expressive possibilities in different
combinations of succession according to the distribution of annotations in the temporal
profile of the video registers used to create its “Generator”. Which is to say that,
because the “Performers” are spatial objects, possessing no determination with regard
129 http://scores.motionbank.org/jbmf/#/set/watcha-looking-at.
172
to the temporal disposition of events, their animated expressions depend on temporally
determined objects, i.e. the “Generators”. Though such temporal objects can have no
correspondence with Burrows and Fargion's dancing,130 if the “Performers” are to be
animated in accordance with the patterning structures of these choreographic works,
they must be fed with the digital expression of representative conceptual structures, i.e.
the discrete data of the video annotations. In regard to the formal differences expressed
between these digital objects and the dancing bodies to which they refer, it seems most
adequate to define the former as algorithmic metaphors. After all they express one thing
in terms of another.
The notion of “algorithmic metaphor” seems to have been key for developing
some choreographic objects of the “TWO” score.131 This score “begins and ends with
two choreographers, unrelated to each other. Bebe Miller (North America) and Thomas
Hauert (Europe). […] two working strategies from each of the two choreographers
[were selected], that together [deal] with the dancing mind and the thinking body”. Or,
in other words, this score “examines choreographic thinking in the construction of
performance improvisation for small groups”.132 This score's algorithmic metaphors are
designated as “Attentive Agents”. They represent an improvisational practice, called
“Assisted Solos”, which is used by choreographer and dancer Thomas Hauert to
generate movement material. The “Assisted Solos” practice consists in a series of
exercises where “partners or assistants provide external impulses for a soloist in a series
of different improvisation strategies from the introductory Light Touches to more
complex forms involving several people and changing roles”133. For each improvisation
strategy, an “Attentive Agent” was developed.134 Each “Attentive Agent” is expressed by
a GUI (as seen, for example, in Illustration 13, below) where gestural forms
representing the dancing bodies are animated both according to the parametric structure
of determinate algorithms and according to the “tactile” inputs that the system's user
might provide to them (by clicking with the mouse's cursor on one of the GUI's
remarkable points). If the latter case occurs, the gestural form reacts, simulating in this
way the touches that might occur in dancing the “Assisted Solos”. But this is not to say
that these algorithmic metaphors simulate the dancing body as such. Rather, they
130 Which is the case of the object named “Count for Nothing”. This object's generator is a Youtube
video with no apparent relation with Burrows and Fargion's choreographic work. This object can be
accessed at http://scores.motionbank.org/jbmf/#/set/count-for-nothing.
131 http://scores.motionbank.org/two.
132 Retrieved from http://motionbank.accad.ohio-state.edu/about.
133 Retrieved from the same address where the “Assisted Solos” data can be accessed:
http://scores.motionbank.org/two/#/set/impulse.
134 The different “Attentive Agents” can be viewed at http://scores.motionbank.org/two/#/set/impulse.
173
Illustration 13: “Interactive Attentive Agent, an algorithmic metaphor for the Pressure Assisted
Solo strategy devised by Thomas Hauert.” Retrieved from http://motionbank.accad.ohio-state.edu.
simulate the parameters derived from knowing how to improvise in such a manner.
They are digital objects primarily defined by parametric structures that express
determinate conceptions of choreography.
135 In her book “Moving Without a Body”, Stamatia Portanova asks: “Can objects be processes?”, which
is the title of one of the book's chapters (2013, pp. 85–96). In this chapter, the author engages herself
in a discussion about choreographic objects, from the perspective of Alfred N. Whitehead's process
174
In contrast to these algorithmic metaphors, the TWO's 3D animations simply
represent dancing bodies, after they have been motion captured.136 Though these
animations reproduce determinate expressions of dance, they do not necessarily express
the choreographic thoughts that moved with the dancers' performance. They correspond
more to the result of a translation than to the result of a transduction. Of course motion
capture itself follows from technical transductions, which determine the kinds of
gestural bodies that in the end will be expressed. But such gestural bodies only serve the
presentation of what, after the dances have been registered, is possible to reproduce. The
animation of these gestural bodies is no more than the reproduction of the motion
capture registers. There is no parametric structure by them expressed that derives from
transducing choreography's conceptual structure, that is, from resolving with a process
of transduction the implicit problems of choreographic ideas. When motion data is used
only to replay what has been registered, these procedures of digitalization cannot be said
to be choreographic. If, in any case, the dance's choreographic structure is expressed
with these animations, it is not because novel choreographic solutions were attained
with digitalization, but only because what has already been determined (in dancing) has
also been retained (digitally). The algorithms involved in capturing the dance and
animating derivative gestural bodies are therefore functions of reanimation. They render
the motion data in terms of what is necessary—a gestural figure recognizable as the
dancing body—and sufficient—no deformations beyond the expression of these
recognisable forms—to express the memory of past experiences.137
The possibilities that these 3D spaces of digital animation allow for, both in
relation to the dancing body and in relation to the gestural body, have been far more
explored by the “Reactor for Awareness in Motion” (RAM) project. Developed since
philosophy, taking as a case study the work of choreographer William Forsythe and the digitalizations
performed on it with the “Synchronous Objects for One Flat Thing Reproduced” platform. Here, it
matters to emphasize that Portanova looks at the algorithmic character of choreographic objects and
discusses the possibility of considering both their parametric structure and their generative capacities
from the standpoint of a potentiality that exists not only with dancing bodies but also with numbers.
In this regard, Whitehead's philosophy allows for thinking algorithms, even digital ones, not only as
finite sets of instructions, but rather as processes that are open to and by undetermined potentials
(from which results the possibility of radical novelty in whatever case of algorithmic computation).
136 These animations can be view in each of the TWO score's sets (http://scores.motionbank.org/two/#/set
/sets).
137 It should nonetheless be noted that the “TWO” score's 3D animations allow both for zooming in and
out the scene and for changing the viewpoint in all cardinal directions. The fact that one can roam
freely throughout the three-dimensional space allows for visualizing the motion capture registers in
ways that video registers don't. If programmed into the animation space, different modes of
interaction are possible as well. For example, in the animation “Redux Interactive” the user can
generate a random series of objects which become actual constraints for the animated gestural bodies,
by clicking with the mouse's cursor on the animation space (see http://scores.motionbank.org/two/#/s
et/memory).
175
2011, by the Yamaguchi Centre for Arts and Media (YCAM), together with Yoko Ando
(a dancer from The Forsythe Company), the RAM comprises a kit of digital tools for
dance research, creation and education. The “RAM Dance Toolkit” is an open-source
software application, written in C++, which contains a “graphical user interface and
functions to access, recognize, and process motion data to support creation of various
environmental conditions”138. This toolkit can be fed by motion capture systems such as
the MOTIONER139 or the “Kinect” sensor140. With these data, its algorithms can
represent the gestural body in various ways, from more common expressions of
choreographic writing, such as Labanotation, to all sorts of geometrical abstractions.
The gestural bodies generated with the RAM algorithms can then be fed-back to the
dancers through audio-visual displays (as seen in Illustration 14, below). With the
creation of such responsive environments, the dancers are said to “decide their next
movement” on the basis of what is calculated and expressed by the software's
algorithms. In this way, together with the RAM, they create the “rules” by which they
move. Dancing with the RAM “is a means to create and clarify problems, and to address
deeper issues”. For such reasons, the RAM is said to be “a technological inquiry into the
nature of dance”, driven by questions such as: “how do contemporary dancers
themselves decide on their next movement?” and “what pattern of thought underlies
their movement?”.141
138 Retrieved from http://interlab.ycam.jp/en/projects/ram/. For all the information on the RAM project,
see the same address.
139 “MOTIONER is the inertial motion capture system developed for RAM. The computer captures the
dancer’s movements via 18 sensors attached to the dancer’s body. […] Using MOTIONER, you can
capture, record and playback body movements, and send the data via OSC messages over a network.
MOTIONER is designed to work with RAM Dance Toolkit using openFrameworks, and will work
with creative coding environments that provide OSC. […] In general, motion capture systems are
very expensive and very accurate, or very cheap and very inaccurate. To address this problem [the
RAM team] designed one which is relatively low in cost and fairly accurate. MOTIONER has been
developed with feedback from Yoko Ando and other dancers that resulted in a light weight, low-
stress, and low latency system. Because it’s an inertial system, users can attach the sensors inside or
outside their clothing. [...] Special straps for the sensors were developed. The straps allow the sensors
to be installed properly and flexibly, regardless of the dancer’s body shape. This makes effective
measurement possible.” Retrieved from http://interlab.ycam.jp/en/projects/ram/motioner and from
https://github.com/YCAMInterlab/MOTIONER/wiki/Overview. For a complete and detailed
description of the whole system (including hardware and software) see https://github.com/YCAMInte
rlab/MOTIONER/wiki.
140 See footnote number 108 on page 153 for a short description of the workings of the “Kinect” sensor.
141 Retrieved from http://interlab.ycam.jp/en/projects/ram/.
176
Illustration 14: Still from a movie where it is shown how “dancers react to the information from
'Line', which is one of the 'scenes' programmed into the environmental conditions of the 'RAM
Dance Toolkit'”. Retrieved from https://vimeo.com/64772291.
in relation to motion data. In the same way, the digital algorithms already programmed
into the software express the choreographic ideas developed in the context of the RAM
project. These can be divided into two categories. Those regarding possibilities of
visualization and those regarding expressive derivations from motion data. In regard to
the former there is here too the possibility of roaming freely across the 3D space while
the animation is rendered, i.e. visualizing it from different perspectives. But beyond
this, there is also the possibility of addressing functions to the viewpoint's perspective
(here designated as camera). For example, there is the possibility of constraining the
camera with one of the gestural figure's nodes (i.e. articulations). It is both possible to
direct it towards the figure's nodes and to make it coincide with them (in which case the
animation is viewed from the gestural body's perspective). Moreover, it should be
noticed that the RAM's scenes also allow for different motion registers to be reproduced
simultaneously. Since each dancing body is here represented with a dataset of its own,
different gestural bodies can be animated independently from one another, while still
being viewed together in one same animation space. In regard to the expressive
derivations from motion data, is it notable that the RAM software is equipped with
algorithms that allow both for creating extensions, which respond to the gestural body 's
expressions, and for notating the latter's displacements. At once, these algorithms
express choreographic ideas and allow for the expression of new ideas. In the RAM
177
software, the expression of each choreographic idea is designated as “scene”. There are
nineteen scenes programmed into the available software,142 each expressing a
choreographic idea of how to extend the gestural body. The correspondence between
each scene's algorithmic set and a determinate choreographic idea is confirmed by the
project's team when affirming that, by “[t]aking advantage of the power of computer
programming, RAM externalizes the scenes dancers have in their minds. With RAM,
dancers can visually observe their ideas and gain a real-time feedback of their
movement from the environment. It enables them to experiment more with their
perception and movement”143. Each of these scenes is therefore a case of solution for
determinate choreographic problems.
The RAM software also comes with a series of presets, which combine different
scenes. For example, one of the presets combines the choreographic idea of dancing
with a temporal delay and the choreographic idea of snap-shooting the gestural body (as
seen in Illustration 15, below). The algorithm that here computes the temporal delay is
called “Hasty Chase”. This scene is rendered after the algorithmic compression of the
gestural body into a buffer, which is then computed into a replicant expression, but in
delay. This delay can be stretched or shortened and reproduced faster or slower,
according to the user's determinations. Moreover, it is possible to visualize the two
Illustration 15: Still from RAM's motion capture registers of one of Yoko Ando's dancing sessions.
Processed with the algorithms “Hasty Chase” (the figure in blue), “Stamp” (the black boxes), and
“Natto” (the lines in blue).
178
figures' connection with the elastic strings of the “Natto” scene. With it, it can be seen in
a precise way how this choreographic idea is expressed digitally while being thought
(i.e. moved) by the dancing body. Here, as in many other RAM's scenes, the gestural
body's extensions depend directly on the dancing body's responses. Finally, this preset
combines these algorithms with the scene “Stamp”. This scene allows for the user to
define a temporal metric according to which the gestural body's position is marked with
a box. While the dance develops, the animation space gets increasingly populated with
these boxes, which can contain (or not) the gestural body's figure as captured by the
snapshot. Both this one combination and the remaining presets are but a few examples
of the variety of ways in which the RAM software is capable of extending the gestural
body.
Importantly, the RAM is said to “provide the dancers with a way to recognize
their subconscious movements by altering the dimensions of their everyday physical
perception and creating a disparity from what they are used to”. As such, this is a
software that “inspires new ideas for dance”.144 This could not express more bluntly how
much the RAM is a system of technical individuation. There is the choreographic
individuation of this software's scenes and there is the individuation of ideas expressed
by those who learn how to dance with the software. In this sense, the RAM is a whole
system of choreographic individuation, one that co-individuates choreographic ideas in
the digital domain and in the domain of the dancing body. In fact, as much as the
algorithmic determinations of choreographic ideas in the digital domain consist of
different possibilities, the learning subjects can think differently of their movements. In
these conditions, it is possible for the dancing body to know itself on the basis of a
difference regarding not what it can perceive immediately of itself, but rather what it
can perceive of what is digitally computed. At the same time that the content-expression
encounter of choreographic writing provides the conditions for a difference to be
expressed, the content-expression encounter of choreographic thinking individuates the
knowledge of an extended perception. In this guise, perception can be seen as a variety
of differences that condition the individuation of knowledge. Differences that, in
relation to one another, bring the overall system of individuation to novel states of
resolution.
All these examples of digital choreography attest one thing: the diagrammatic
topology of choreographic ideas is also algorithmic. As mentioned before, this shouldn't
179
be understood as the choreographic object being algorithmic because it is digitally
programmable, but precisely the opposite: it is programmable because it is algorithmic
in itself. Such algorithmic character of choreographic objects regards the fact that they
are resumable across domains. It regards the fact that they are known and, as such,
conceptually structured. In relation to technical individuation, it is this intelligibility that
allows for choreographic objects to be transduced across domains and, in this case,
digitally programmed and expressed. All the algorithms discussed above are
choreographic functions of expression. They not only express choreographic diagrams,
but they also express how such functions are manifested when in relation with given
quantities of data, i.e. matters of content. The fact that both parts in this content-
expression encounter are sets of digital data attests their codification and
programmability. It is this last feature that allows for digital data to express the dynamic
character of choreographic objects. A program, instead of just expressing one possible
solution for the problems in case, can iterate computations and express the many
solutions existing in the content-expression encounter of each digital choreography.
180
Chapter 6 - DIGITAL POTENTIAL
181
6.1 - Problems in Potential
It is important to notice why, for Manning, such grammar holds the status of a
paradox. On the one hand, as much as “[a]n engagement with technology and dance
demands an encounter with the syntax of the moving body” (2009, p. 61), the body
182
needs to be approached grammatically, that is, it needs to be understood as being
articulable with itself by means of expression. On the other hand, as much as the
dancing body is defined by a plane of movement where actuality and virtuality
rhythmically co-compose one another, it necessarily resists articulatory reductions. In
this sense, the dancing body is unmappable. Its expressions are but partial samples of its
whole movement. To create gestures with the dancing body is thus to cut the latter's
potentials into discrete and articulable sections. Which is the reason why “a focus on
gesture (defined as extensive displacement of body parts divisible from a wholeness of
movement) tends to lose sight of movement’s incipiency, thus overlooking the virtual
opening [that] sensitive technologies wish to encounter.” (Manning, 2009, p. 62).
It is true that digital technologies such as the ones discussed in the previous
chapter are not always developed together with dancing bodies. In such cases, dancing
bodies and digital softwares can only encounter one another by means of what is
possibly given, i.e. predetermined and preset before their encounter. This is, for
example, the case of the relation between the “Gesture Follower” (GF) software,145
which requires being given determinate definitions of gesture to recognize determinate
expressions of motion, and the learning subject's dancing body. From the latter's
perspective, the definitions of gesture given to the software determine what is to be
learnt. Even if granted that what is learnt is not a given form but a principle of
individuation, the dancing body remains nonetheless limited by the possibilities
inscribed into the software's algorithms. It needs to conform with the software's
definitions of gesture for this to recognize its motion and for it to learn what its relation
with the software holds in potential. The dancing body can, notwithstanding, express
more than what is defined as gesture. Its excess can easily not conform to the definitions
of gesture inscribed in the software (just think of all that is too small or too large for the
motion devices to capture). But if a determinate gesture is to be learnt, then what is
expressed with an excessive body needs to conform to what has been programmed into
the software.
This doesn't regard, of course, the fabrication of the software itself. If, from the
perspective of the learning subject, the GF corresponds to a set of possibilities, from the
perspective of its own individuation there's necessarily more to it than possibility only.
After all, the definitions of gesture embedded into the software express the knowledge
that, in a first moment, existed with the dancing body and that, in a second moment, has
183
been transduced into the digital domain. The fact that such transduction individuated
novel instances of knowledge with regard to the dancing body itself, attests that this was
not a unilateral process. The GF's concretization individuated instances of knowledge
that were expressed digitally and understood abstractly (by the dancing body itself).
This process can therefore be said to have been a co-individuation through which the
resolutions of the one domain depended on the resolutions of the other. A technical
individuation that, while moving the potentials of its system's multiplicities, co-
individuated dancing bodies and gestural bodies.
The same can be said in regard to the other examples discussed in this study.
Though these projects might not have been specifically focused on Manning's call for
the constitution of a grammar of process, all of them have notwithstanding individuated
instances of knowledge that, while concerning the dancing body, became expressed
gesturally. Moreover, as exemplified by the GF, some expressions of gesture
individuated precisely from dwelling upon the dancing body's emergent character and
its principles of individuation. But what Manning proposes is of another order. It is of
the order of technogenesis itself: a vocabulary that, rather than only objectifying the
dancing body for the purpose of transducing its principles of individuation, can express
the very processes by means of which dancing bodies and gestural bodies co-
individuate with and co-constitute one another. In her words: “If a vocabulary of gesture
is to be reclaimed as part of what can be stimulated in the encounter between dance and
new technology, I believe it must be done through the continuum of movement, through
the body’s emergence in the realm of the virtual becoming of preacceleration. Rather
than moulding the body to the measure of motion-detecting technology, I propose we
begin with pure plastic rhythm, situating the sensing body in movement in a mutating
matrix of technological becoming. Let’s call this body-emergent technogenetic.” (2009,
p. 62).
What Manning's plea stresses is the fact that, in this movement of co-
individuation, there is a continuum where both dancing bodies and digital technologies
are in contact with one another and where they affect one another, reciprocally, for a
mutual becoming. Hence, this continuum of movement does not correspond only to the
dancing body's plane of composition. It is also the continuum of movement through
which technogenesis unfolds and therefore the very plane of composition from which its
expressions derive. This is also what Manning understands by preacceleration, i.e. the
movement before expression. It is the process through which the abstract machine
ingathers potentials and engenders the greatest forces. A process with a topology where
184
tendencies inform the system to compress the virtual into the actual present. Whereas
acceleration can be understood as a relation between metric spaces, preaccelaration is
the very movement by means of which the virtual tends towards actual incipiency.
Insofar as this is a durational movement, preaccelaration is the movement through
which the unconscious tends to become sensible and intelligible. Hence, it is an
intensive movement, of intuition, rather than an extensive one, of expression.
The virtual-actual continuum through which dancing bodies and gestural bodies
co-compose one another should therefore be thought in terms of the individuating
system's associated milieu. It is with the system's excessive reality, i.e. its technicity,
that both dancing bodies and gestural bodies can come into relation, not as
supplementary extensions of one another, but rather as different actualizations of one
same field of potentials. It is in this sense that, according to Manning, “[w]e must move
beyond the prosthetic as an external category toward an exploration of the originary
technicity that technogenesis taps into” (2009, p. 66). This originary technicity
corresponds to the system's capacity to compose technical individuals. It corresponds to
its capacity to bring into emergence the resolution of its implicit problems in different
domains. This is a capacity that only acquires an operative value by means of
transduction. It is only through transduction that the system's abstract machine becomes
capable of acting out resolutions in different domains. It is only by its means that
dancing bodies and gestural bodies can be said to derive from one same choreographic
idea.
185
in movement. […] There is no doubt this already happens – but still too rarely.
Techniques for technogenetic emergence must become part of the technology’s
interface: we must develop techniques that create new associated milieus never distinct
from the ontogenetic body. Technological recomposition must no longer be inserted into
a body-system: it must be emergent with it.” (Manning, 2009, pp. 74–75).
It is for this reason that, if dancing bodies and gestural bodies are to co-
individuate, such must happen in relation to one same associated milieu. In this sense,
the associated milieu of the technical individuals in formation is a condition of their
differentiation and of their choreographic nexus. This is also to say that the co-
individuation of dancing bodies and gestural bodies corresponds to the emergence of
different species of technologies. There are technologies that allow for choreographic
transductions to occur and there are technologies that allow for choreographic
transductions to be resolved in domains of mnemonic extension. In technogenesis, the
informational exchange between what will have become a dancing body and what will
have become a gestural body is key for the process to tap into the system's originary
technicity. With the exertion of problematic forces onto what is given, both the dancing
body and its gestural expressions can emerge from one same relation. Both of them can
result from and belong to one same problematic field, which is the system's very
technicity. If dancing bodies and gestural bodies are not to supplement one another,
these different technologies must become one another's associated milieu. Their
individuation must result from an exchange of information between potentials
belonging to different orders of magnitude, but yet belonging to the same topological
continuum.
186
actuality and the virtuality of movement. As Manning puts it, the question is then
“[h]ow to create functioning parameters for software development on the basis of
something that cannot be known, that can only be felt in its effects? Technology
becoming technogenetic involves inflecting the digital with virtual potential, bringing to
the fore movement’s incipiency and its relational matrix. How does a movement that
cannot yet be seen make itself known?” (2009, p. 72).
From the examples discussed throughout this study, it is perhaps the G F that
attends the most to these concerns. After all, its algorithms strive to depict what cannot
be computed as such, i.e. qualities of movement. To invent digital algorithms that define
movement qualities in terms of discrete quantities of data is to necessarily undergo a
process of transduction. If the software is to recognize gesture on the basis of a
quantitative definition, it needs to be set according to parameters that express the
subjective and conceptual diagrams of gesture, as known from and with the dancing
body's experience. For such transduction to occur, movement needs to be experienced in
all its varieties. An experience tantamount to a subject constituted together with the
constitution of what it comes to know. A subject that, because of being embedded in the
same milieu of potentials from which movement comes to be expressed, necessarily
experiences movement's intensive incipiency towards the actualization of extension.
187
probably not allow for such a degree of variation.
But this position also entails the credo that digital algorithms, in themselves, are
but a set of programmed possibilities with no relation whatsoever with the virtual. What
this view perhaps dismisses is the capacity of digital computation to stand by itself as a
mode of thought. In which case the compression of data into data, i.e. the calculation of
possibilities for the expression of determinate cases of solution, would necessarily
comprise the ingression of virtuality into computation itself. It is a condition for digital
computation to occur within the limits of its own possibilities. Digital algorithms
compute data according to determinate parametric structures and within the possibilities
of digital coding itself. But if the result of algorithmic computations in the digital
domain is the accretion of data on data, it can be argued that, being this an event, it
necessarily holds at some point a relation with virtuality. The temporal vector that is
188
formed with the accretion of data can be argued to correspond not only to the
progression of a metric time, but also to the durational experience of the computational
system. Hence, the question is: can experience be addressed in any way to digital
computation? In other words, and besides the technogenetic mixing of analog and
digital domains, can the very process of digital computation regard the durational
progression of a virtual experience? If so, the digital domain would comprise in itself
unmappable dimensions. It would be excessive in relation to itself and its algorithmic
computations could be understood as modes of thought in their own right.
189
extension, but rather on the basis of a continuum of potentials where these dualities no
longer hold. In this sense, this is a hypothesis that dismisses the Bergsonian distinction
between duration and space, only to call for yet another way of conceiving the
relationship between qualities and quantities.
190
individuation in general, the extensive continuum's potentials can only be understood as
data that is not structured, that is, as the unstructured kind of data that pervades
whatever determinate form.
191
space of digital simulations coincides with the simulated processes' space, it can act as
the condition after which cases of solution that are also possible in regard to the
referential process are expressed. Notwithstanding, the digital simulation of a cooking
recipe does not result in edibles. Hence, it does not resolve the problematic structure of
the diagram to which it belongs. In the same way, a mathematical problem might very
well be better resolved by means of digital computation than by the exercise of cooking.
But beyond the adequacy of domains of expression in regard to the problematic
structure of determinate diagrams, the transferability that the latter's abstractions assure
in regard to the former attests the fundamental core of an algorithm. If one same
algorithm can be expressed in different domains, it does not depend on them. As such, it
is determinate and abstract. It is the diagrammatic arrangement of a knowledge that
pertains to the ways in which a given problem can be solved.
192
Already in the beginnings of computer science, Alan Turing had acknowledged
the existence of incomputable problems within computation. The British mathematician
conceived of the Turing machine, the first prototypical computer, as an algorithmic
application capable of determining whether a problem was susceptible of being solved
mechanically or not (Herken, 1995). The algorithmic set of instructions given to it was
in this case, as well as in the case of the computers that would follow, the basic
condition on which this could solve a problem or not. In this sense, and as much as
computation can be defined in terms of problem solving, algorithms are its fundamental
condition. Algorithms are the model with which a given problem can be computed and
actually solved. Symbolically, this is expressed by means of a procedure that computes
whether a given number belongs to an algorithmic set or not. By making use of Boolean
logic,147 computer science has dedicated itself to investigating how to answer to sets of
questions by means of a binary logic, always answering either yes or no. In the binary
language of digital code, this means that all the possible variables of a given set are
defined as 1 (the universal set), whereas 0 defines an empty set containing no variable
of the algorithmic set defined by 1. Digital computation therefore corresponds to the
mathematical calculation of whether a variable corresponds to the universal set defined
by 1 or not (in which case it is defined as 0). And it is at this very level, which is the
level of the formal languages with which algorithms can be both abstracted and
expressed, that the openness required for their operation manifests the incompleteness
of calculation. For, as media theorist Luciana Parisi reminds us, “Alan Turing
demonstrated that there is no computable function (no finite binary set) that could
correctly answer every question in the problem set. This meant that not every set of
natural numbers is computable, and Turing’s description of the halting problem (the set
of Turing machines that halt on input 0) is one example, among many, of an
incomputable set” (2013, pp. 260–261).
147 This modality of logics, which also goes by the name of pure mathematics, was theorized by British
mathematician George Boole in 1847. This is a logics that favours abstract and universal operations,
instead of concrete and relative ones (such as those involving quantities and magnitudes). From this
dismissal, the mathematician formulated an algebraic system, known as Boolean algebra, which
represents sets and subsets of abstract or actual things and the operations relating them (i.e.
coincidence, intersection, inclusion, exclusion and so on). Importantly, for what regards digital
programming, these operations are represented with symbols which indicate values such as OR, AND
and NOT.
193
incomputable data in computation. Moreover, the fact that an algorithm's operations
cannot be considered independently from its data structures determines that its action
necessarily implicates all the data that it cannot compute. The upshot of such
implication is that algorithmic indetermination is a fundamental condition of
computation, a postulate that Parisi also acknowledges by defining computation as “the
capacity of algorithms to compress infinite amounts of data”, whereby “incomputable
data must be the condition, and not the result, of computation” (2013, pp. 260–261).
Even modern computers should be understood according to the indetermination that in
them is implicit. Algorithms are not pure automatic procedures working with absolute
sets of data. Rather, they are technical individuals programmed with limits that regard
the range of possible commutations in the electronic circuits which mediate them.
Algorithms are technical objects designed for operating within the margins of
indetermination given to the computational system.
It is with these random and incomputable quantities of data that the potentials of
algorithmic emergence can be thought. As potentials they remain undetermined. As data
they are given. And though this might seem a paradox according to what has until now
been expounded, what the notion of given potentials entails, is the actual redefinition of
what potentials are and how they exist amidst systems of individuation. In other words,
these are potentials that no longer can be thought only in qualitative terms, resulting
only from the intensive interplay of forces constitutive of continuous multiplicities, but
that need to be thought in quantitative terms. In this way, actuality itself becomes
potential: not the actual remarkable points of individuated structures, but rather the
actuality of all those points of an individual that are not remarkable but yet constitute
the charged ground against which the individual is remarked. From this standpoint, it
can be argued that what is potential still remains qualitative, since it necessarily results
from intensive forces that relate random and structured quantities of data between one
another. Under these conditions, potentiality can be argued to remain relational and thus
dependent on the intervallic forces with which forms (random or non-random) affect
one another. But what the notion of incomputabilities brings forth is the very idea of a
past that, despite being given to the constitution of novel facts, is not determinately
given. In other words, what is given is not known, it is random and, as such,
unpredictable in regard to the ways in which it might come to ingress into novel facts of
unity. For this very reason, Goffey writes that: “just because the development of an
algorithm requires a level of de facto formal abstraction, which then allows that
algorithm to be applied to other kinds of content, does not mean that we have exhausted
194
everything that we need to know to understand the processes of which it is a part”
(2008, p. 18). What the notion of given potentials thus proposes is a redefinition of the
relation between quantities and qualities. In other words, if potentials can be thought as
pertaining both to what is given, but yet unknown, and to the intensive forces with
which disparities amidst these random quantities of data come to occur, what
necessarily needs to be acknowledged is the processual character of potentiality. The
constitutive immanence between qualities and quantities needs to be considered from an
affective point of view, according to which a permanent rhythm of actualization and
deactualization, quantification and qualification, forces the individuating system to
inform the future (individual) with what is given from the past. Given potentials thus
concern the unknown both in actuality and in virtuality. And, as it will be discussed
ahead, because the past can be given undeterminably, virtuality can also be seen as
random quantities of data, rather than only as a transcendental kind of memory.
Goffey points out two different aspects that offer a mode of approaching these
incomputabilities. First, the structuration of data implicates an “incorporeal
transformation”148 that, by definition, cannot be computed. This means that the passage
from raw data to structured data, necessary to the operation of algorithms, implicates a
change in the status of the things to which they correspond. Take the example of a
personal name inscribed on an online form for a journal's subscription. Before the array
of alphanumerical characters is included in the server's database, the person in question
is not yet a subscriber. After the name has been included, the person has become a
subscriber. The transformation of the person's status, which corresponds for example to
a change in the way the person thinks of itself, is missed by the structuration of finite
sets of data. In spite of occurring together with the algorithmic procedure, this
incorporeal transformation is not accounted for by the structuration of data. Algorithmic
procedures effect changes that are neither compressible nor computable. In Goffey's
words: “Algorithms act, but they do so as part of an ill-defined network of actions upon
148 This expression, “incorporeal transformation”, is used by Goffey with the precise effect of echoing
both J. L. Austin's speech act theory and Michel Foucault's philosophy of the event. In regard to the
former, it is known how Austin differentiated the constantive and the performative elements of an act
of speech. On the one hand, a speech act does describe things in the world, but on the other hand it
also effects changes in the world. In this sense, the performative speech act refers only to itself,
enacting the semantic value of speech (Austin, 1975). In regard to the latter, it is here enough to quote
how Foucault implicated incorporeality at the heart of the event: “[…] certainly not immaterial; it
takes effect, becomes effect, always on the level of materiality. Events have their place; they consist
in relation to, coexistence with, dispersion of, the cross-checking accumulation and the selection of
material elements; it occurs as an effect of, and in, material dispersion. Let us say that the philosophy
of event should advance in the direction, at first sight paradoxical, of an incorporeal materialism.”
(2007, p. 231).
195
actions, part of a complex of power-knowledge relations, in which unintended
consequences, like the side effects of a program’s behaviour, can become critically
important” (2008, p. 19). This can be better understood when recalling Simondon's
theory of networks. The very networkability of algorithms (with data structures, other
algorithms, machines, machine's users, and so on), implicates resonances that can easily
involve regions of the network that are not directly implicated in a given computation.
The “side effects” of a computation can in this way be located at any point whatsoever
of the network partaken by an algorithm.
196
an openness towards the self-excess of being and the objective structures with which
this excess is kept in form, ceases to exist. It is in terms of a system's overall
development that an object must be considered. Neither only as form nor only as
process, but rather as a dynamic entity with structural points and contrasting grounds,
which exchange energies with and are converted into one another, from metastability to
metastability.
Information theorist Gregory Chaitin (2005) has been a major proponent of the
notion that random numbers are intrinsic to algorithmic computation. The author argues
that there are quantities of data underlying computation that cannot be counted. Even
the most simple algorithm used for sorting a list of numbers is “infected”149 with random
149 This term, “infection”, is characteristic of the way in which philosopher Alfred N. Whitehead thinks
of the inevitable ingression of abstractions into actual occasions of experience. In philosopher of
science Isabelle Stengers' words: “'Infection' is the term Whitehead chooses to designate, in a generic
way, what the poets celebrate as 'presence'. Celebration refers to the fact that it is a poet's experience
that is infected by the mountain, gloomy and ancient. [...] This infectious holding-together is not a
fusion but a valorization, a determinate shaping, conferring a value-that is, a role-on what is
prehended. The fact that the variables of a function, in the same way as the poet's experience, require
a 'value' thus ceases to belong to linguistic contingency. Far from being a mere quantity, the value of
a variable presupposes the stability of the role that one thing plays for something else and measures
197
quantities of data that cannot be sorted and grouped into a finite set of numbers. As
such, any computation operates amidst an infinity of discrete quantities of data. The
incomputability of the infinity of numbers underlying computation can in a way be said
to be an intrinsic quality of algorithms. This is not the kind of infinity of a numerical
interval's infinitesimals. It does not correspond to the transcendental numbers of an
uncountable infinity.150 Rather, it corresponds to an infinity of discrete quantities of data
that are random and thus uncountable. Their randomness corresponds to the fact that, in
spite of being discrete, they are not structured. In Chaitin's words, “something is random
if it can’t be compressed into a shorter description.” (2001, p. 18). The infinity of
random quantities in computation consists of unstructured data that cannot be
compressed either into finite numbers or into finite sets of instructions. Indetermination
is made to be a necessary condition to computation. A condition from which it follows
that both algorithms and the mathematical axioms that underly computation are
incomplete.
the importance of that role. […] The term 'infection' is thus technical, that is, neutral with regard to
the differences we attribute to what endures.” (2011, pp. 157–158). Interestingly for this study,
Stengers also points out how Whitehead uses the term “infection” to think the body. She writes that:
“For Whitehead, the parts do not constitute the whole without the whole infecting the parts. In other
words, the identity, or the enduring pattern, of the whole and the parts is strictly contemporary. This is
why the same term, 'infection', can be used both to designate the relations between the whole and the
parts, and to describe the relations of a living organism with its environment. If the body exists for its
parts, it is because its parts are infected by such-and-such an obstinate aspect of what we call the
body, but which, for them, is a portion of their environment; if the parts exist for each other and for
the body, it is because the respective patterns of each are highly sensitive to any modification of the
environment they constitute for one another.” (Ibid., p. 174).
150 As mentioned before, when accounting for Bergson's concept of virtuality (see Section 1.1), the
topological space of an infinitesimal continuity (consisting of transcendental, and thus undetermined,
factors of determination) is non-actual in absolute. As such, it is uncountable and, ultimately, virtual.
Hence, the virtual, considered in this way, can never belong to the random quantities of data that
underly algorithmic computation (if the smooth space of continuous variation is to be kept). Precisely
because of the constitutive incompleteness of algorithmic objects, which is tantamount to an
immanence between random quantities and determinate numbers, actuality is neither finite nor it can
contain the totality of space and time. Contrary to the topological variation of the spatio-temporal
continuum, what this immanence attests is the very fact that infinity exists as quantitative potentials
amidst the definiteness of actuality. In other words, the additive sequencing of instructions through
which algorithms “array alternative states for sequencing into alternative routines” (Massumi, 2002,
p. 137) not only creates data, but creates it with a constitutive difference.
198
computations group countable numbers for the execution of finite sets of instructions.
From this standpoint, algorithms can be conceived both as finite sets of instructions and
as being pervaded and conditioned by random quantities of data. Algorithms can only
be defined by determinate sets of structured data as much as they are also defined by the
infinity of random quantities of data existing together with any set of finite numbers.
This is clearly a standpoint that differs from a universal computation, according to
which finite sets of instructions are enough to generate all the complexity of the world.
Chaitin argues that the world's complexity corresponds to its incalculability, that is, to
the real number by means of which virtuality and actuality become immanent in one
another and which is to be found in all strings of countable numbers. Accordingly, the
binary logic of probabilities with which cybernetics approached Turing's conception of
the computer, as much as it is based on the idea that complexity is reducible to the finite
numbers of algorithmic computation, cannot account for the intrinsic incompleteness of
knowledge. The binarism of algorithmic objects does not consider the complex infinity
constitutive of random quantities of data existing at the heart of any computation. What
Chaitin's notion of Omega brings forth is the idea that algorithms are not only finite sets
of instructions but also random quantities of data that, notwithstanding their discrete
character, are incomputable.
151 It should be reminded that, as mentioned before (see page 56, Section 2.1), Gilbert Simondon also
criticized the cybernetic conception of information, since it did not account for information's intrinsic
infinity. While characterizing information as the process by which a difference between potentials
belonging to different orders of magnitude is resolved, Simondon instead introduces infinity at the
heart of information. In this way, instead of being a unified entity, information is considered from the
standpoint of the differences underlying intensive quantities. As much as these differences are
potential conditions of individuation, information is necessarily heterogeneous or, in other words,
made of different parts, and pervaded by uncountable infinities.
199
The upshot of this, in what regards the problems that such complex notion of
information poses to the cybernetic logic of control, is that in this way parts can be
considered as being larger than wholes. Because they necessarily comprise discrete
infinities, the random quantities of data underlying algorithmic computation are
necessarily larger than the finite forms of those same algorithms. Conversely, not only
are finite quantities smaller than their immanent infinities, but also parts, such as simple
algorithms, are irreducible to the systems that they might partake, such as full blown
software programs. According to Chaitin's theory, algorithmic objects are not reducible
to finite series of simpler parts, due to their openness to an infinity of discrete and
random quantities of data. With such infinity, the notion of universal computation is no
longer possible. The mathematical reduction of every single factor of determination
(quantitative and qualitative) into finite sets no longer holds. Chaitin's theory of
algorithmic complexity demonstrates that the limits of computation are not given only
by the digital domain's limits of possibility, but also, and more fundamentally, by the
random quantities of data pervading algorithms. As much as incomputable quantities of
random data are irreducible to the necessary finitude of algorithmic instructions, it is
here, in this irreducibility, that computation finds, first and foremost, its limits.
152 Let us recall Deleuze's statement on the inscription of time in wholes: “According to Bergson, the
whole is neither given nor giveable. […] if the whole is not giveable, it is because it is the Open, and
because its nature is to change constantly, or to give rise to something new, in short, to endure. […]
So that each time we find ourselves confronted with a duration, or in a duration, we may conclude
that there exists somewhere a whole which is changing, and which is open somewhere.” (1986, p. 9).
200
quality made of an infinity of discrete quantities. On the basis of all that was previously
expounded in relation to Simondon's notion of technicity, 153 it becomes possible to
conceive of algorithms not only in terms of finite numbers arrayed in iterative
sequences, to which an infinity of steps can always be added, but also in terms of the
infinity with which they are open to exchange information between one another.
Recently, the American philosopher Graham Harman (2002, 2005, 2011) has
proffered an “object-oriented metaphysics”154 that tries to conciliate the individual
autonomy of objects with their capacity to be in relation with one another. For him,
objects do not change and are discontinuous with one another. A condition that impedes
any sort of approach taking direct relations between objects as being the ground on
which objects themselves are to be explained. From this standpoint, and regardless of its
possible variations, an object remains unchanged because it does neither depend on its
201
variable expressions (e.g. the different ways to construct a chair) nor on its variable
appearances (e.g. the different ways in which a chair can be perceived). In Harman's
words: “When I circle an object or when it rotates freely before me, I do not see a
discrete series of closely related contents and then make an arbitrary decision that they
all belong together as a set of closely linked specific profiles. Instead, what I experience
is always one object undergoing accidental, transient changes that do not alter the thing
itself.” (2005, p. 98). The qualities of an object, such as colour, fragrance, weight, and
so on, are therefore for Harman distinct from one another and from the object itself.
They are said to constitute a field of relatedness that can be thought and experienced
without objects. “In this way the fleshly medium of loose qualities is placed everywhere
in the world” (Ibid, p. 91). To the point of being that which allows for objects to enter in
relation with one another. The problem of explaining how objects are related to one
another, when granted the case that they are radically distinct from one another, finds in
their own qualities the field of potentials and the space of possibilities by means of
which relations can come to be established. From which two different questions arise: if
qualities are different from the objects that they qualify, then how are they related, not
only to objects, but also to one another?; and, does the relation between qualities
belonging to different objects constitute a novel object? In order to answer to these
questions, Harman's object-oriented philosophy divides the world in two different kinds
of objects. There are real objects, characterized by their radical discontinuity relatively
to one another and to the qualities existing in the world, and there are sensual objects, a
designation which discloses the fact that they exist only in relation to qualities.
Harman's notion of real objects is his own take on the problem of how to explain
the independence of objects from qualities. One can say that a chair does not need to be
made out of wood in order to be a chair, but also that there are some minimal
requirements for it to be a chair. Meaning that, without a surface capable of supporting a
person's back and another capable of supporting the person's buttocks, simultaneously,
any object will hardly qualify as a chair. In this sense, there is a relatedness of parts that
necessarily includes a minimum of different qualities. An object can be defined by
determinate relationships between qualities, rather than by the qualities themselves. In
Harman's words: “An object is real not by virtue of being tiny and fundamental, but by
virtue of having an intrinsic reality that is not reducible to its subcomponents or
exhausted by its functional effects on other things” (2009, p. 215). From this, what is
most important to retain is the implicit tension between the fact that objects are
independent from their qualities and the fact that they cannot be thought without them.
202
With such formulation, what seems to be most determinant for an object's definition is
(perhaps not surprisingly) relation. Relation both as the constitutive excess of objects
and qualities and as what cannot be reduced to either the one or the other. Conversely,
this is to say that objects are irreducible to qualities, since qualities are irreducible to the
relations that they partake and which express objects.
It follows that an object's intrinsic character results from a process that cannot be
fully known because it is simply too complex. For Harman (2005, p. 174), an object's
intrinsic character results from “indirect or vicarious” relations, a notion depicting the
non-linearity of the qualitative relations underlying any objective formation. Indirect
relations explain why it is possible for objects to loose certain attributes and still remain
what they are. They assure that an object's attributes are not interchangeable and that
what therefore results from a bundle of qualities is but the object's singular and
unrepeatable expression. In this sense, an object can endure as long as its qualitative
relations are not destroyed. In contrast, one singular object can never be repeated in the
exact same way, for its qualitative self-affection cannot be known as such. Hence, it is
vicarious. It remains inaccessible, in spite of being determinant for what may result
from the resolution of problems posed at the diagrammatic level of materiality. For
example, though the flowers of one same species of plant may be similar to one another,
no one flower is alike. Each results from singular movements of individuation where the
actual resolution of problems in potential expresses the undetermined, unconscious and
unknowable depth of the material abstract machine. The indetermination of potential
relations in a continuum of qualitative affects is the indirect or vicarious cause of
individuation. Any object is unrepeatable because its vicarious cause, being
unknowable, remains inaccessible. Its constitution is irreproducible and, therefore,
singular. Which also means that no object can be reduced to a sum of parts. There is
always more to it than its actual resolution. It is excessive over itself, but not in any
determinate way. It is vicariously excessive, since the source of its individuation (i.e. its
preindividual reality) remains implicit in its resolute actuality. Hence, no object can be
fully known. Any object is only accessible up to a certain point. Beyond this, it is
vicariously undetermined with regard to itself. If objects are somewhat inaccessible, it is
only because qualities are fundamentally inaccessible too. To say that objects and
qualities are inaccessible is not the same as saying that they don't exist. “The
inaccessibility of the subterranean depth of the sun does not entail its nonexistence.”
(Harman, 2005, p. 86). It is rather to say that they exist as a potential to be in relation
with one another. From which it follows that only determinate modes of association
203
between qualities and objects can be accessed. Such association, which is expression
itself, is understood by Harman as being a “phenomenon”. A notion that Harman (Ibid.,
pp. 7–70) owes to the work of the so called “carnal phenomenologists”, a strand of
philosophers including Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Emmanuel Levinas and Alphonso
Lingis.
It is, nevertheless, by making use of the notion of substance that Harman defines
objects. For him, “[e]very object is both a substance and a complex of relations”. Not
only this, but if “[w]hen two objects enter into genuine relation, even if they do not
permanently fuse together, they generate a reality that has all of the features that we
require of an object”, then “any relation must count as a substance”. (2005, pp. 85).
According to this view, relations are objects. Which accords with the fractal geometry
that the regressive wrapping of objects into one another proposes. Moreover, according
204
to Harman, “[t]he reason we call these objects 'substances' is not because they are
ultimate or indestructible, but simply because none of them can be identified with any
(or even all) of their relations with other entities. None of them is a pristine kernel of
substantial unity unspoiled by interior parts. We never reach some final layer of tiny
components that explains everything else, but enter instead into an indefinite regress of
parts and wholes.” (Ibid.). For this reason, the notion of substance regards here relations
that, in spite of assuring an object's identity, are inaccessible. For Harman, it is this
inaccessible character of objects that constitutes not only their reality, but the real as
such. Which is a standpoint that goes directly against a metaphysics of presence. In this
sense, real objects are withdrawn from any possibility of knowledge. “It is not even
possible to get 'closer' to the things in such a way that presence could provide some sort
of measuring stick for how nearly we have approached reality”, says Harman (Ibid.,
p.86). Because such inaccessibility doesn't say much of the world except for the fact
that it resists both material and conceptual reductions, it can be said to be the reason
why Harman's philosophy has such a speculative tone. In fact, it is precisely because of
this that his work can be included in the recent trend in continental philosophy
designated as “speculative realism”, which results precisely for various tentatives to
overcome the shortcomings of “philosophies of human access” (Harman, 2005).
In contrast, objects are accessible via relations. One can see how yellow the sun
is, or feel its warmth, but only insofar as the conditions of sensation necessarily include
a number of other objects, such as the atmosphere, sensorial organs, a nervous system,
and so on. In this sense, perception requires more than one object. Colour does not
happen without an eye, weight does not happen without a difference between masses,
proprioception does not happen without muscles, and so on. To define an object in terms
of qualities is to define it in terms of its relation to other objects. In Harman's
philosophy, this is how sensual objects differ from real ones: they exist in relation.
Insofar as they are accessible, they comprise relations between different objects, from
which their qualifying attributes emerge. The fractal geometry of objects proposed by
Harman's object-oriented metaphysics, i.e. the wrapping of objects into one another, is
simultaneously the cause and the effect of a phenomenon of exteriority. Only because
objects exist outside of themselves, with other objects, can they be defined by indirect
relations within a bundle of qualities. Sensual objects coincide with their presence in
other objects. In opposition, a real object has no exteriority. It is inaccessible and
therefore cannot exist together with the interior reality of other objects. Real objects
coincide only with themselves. Harman's understanding of the world as being divided
205
between real and sensual objects corresponds to a metaphysics that is itself divided in
terms of absence and presence (being that, here, absence regards a lack of exteriority
and presence a qualitative relation between objects). Since, in this way, presence
coincides with relation, relations themselves are granted an objective status. Relations
are objective because they coincide with the exteriority of presence, which unifies the
emergence of different qualities in an act of perception.
206
this way, objects are defined by a codetermination between their own vicarious depth
and the accessible surface of their qualitative attributes. This sort of codetermination
should be thought to regard as well general relations between parts and wholes. As
Harman explains, for example, “it cannot really be said that windmills are made of
ladders, pumps, rotating blades, and wire-mesh crow's nests. Or rather, it is made of
these things only in a derivative, material sense. Although the windmill needs these
smaller parts in order to exist, it never fully deploys these objects in their total reality,
but makes use of them only by reducing them to useful caricatures. That is to say, a
windmill does not fully sound the depths of its own pieces any more than a human
observer does. It merely siphons away the needed qualities from these objects, just as
animal stomachs reduce the sparkling allure of fruits to brutal, one-dimensional fuels.”
(Ibid., pp. 93–94). From this, Harman extracts the formula that “the sum of parts is
always greater than the whole” (Ibid.), since each part is only related to the whole to the
degree that the whole reduces it. As much as an object is part of a whole, it can only be
to that whole a part of what itself is as a whole. This partiality of access between two
different objects coincides with the depth that each one possesses and which is
inaccessible to the other. Conversely, only the surface of an object can be directly
accessed by another object.
“If objects exceed any of their perceptual or causal relations with other objects,
if they inhabit some still undefined vacuous space of reality, the question immediately
arises as to how they interact at all. More concisely: we have the problem of nonrelating
objects that somehow relate” (Harman, 2005, p. 91). In order to deal with this problem,
Harman conceives of objects as modules that are capable of connecting to one another.
In his words, “objects do not fully manifest to each other but communicate with one
another through the levels that bring their qualities into communion” (Ibid., p. 68). The
paradigmatic example of this are atoms, for atoms can combine with one another in as
many ways as the objects known to result from their assemblages. This is where
Harman's object-oriented metaphysics can start being related to processes of algorithmic
computation. Because what determines the ways in which non-relating objects do in fact
relate are rules as simple as quantitative relations of electric attraction and repulsion. In
this regard, it is possible to compute relations without further knowledge about the
intrinsic reality of the objects involved. Or, which amounts to the same thing, “the levels
that bring qualities into communion” can be thought quantitatively. Harman himself
doesn't do this. What he inherits from phenomenology is a concern with perception (and
thus accessibility) and with what might exist beyond its variations, that is, with the
207
eidetic core of objects. Nonetheless, in his object-oriented metaphysics, quantities are
conflated with the levels of inter-objective communication. They are thought spatially,
but not in a way that specifies their relation to qualities.
208
through which objects signal to one another, and transfer energies for the benefit or
destruction of one another.” (Ibid., p. 70). In order for two different atoms to relate to
one another, a medium is required. Importantly, the medium cannot be thought without
the atoms themselves. And to the extent that one same type of atom can participate in
different types of molecules, and these in different types of compounds, and these in
different types of bodies, and so on, what necessarily results from this style of
organization is a multimediatic structuration of connectivity or, in other words, from an
object's perspective, connections at different levels. Ultimately, for Harman, such
connections remain inaccessible. “Since no causation between [objects] can be direct, it
clearly can only be vicarious, taking place by means of some unspecified intermediary.”
(Ibid.). Which is to say that the causal relations occurring throughout the different levels
that mediate the communication between objects are indirect and inaccessible. Despite
its real dimension, an object can in this way be thought to be structured by the different
levels throughout which it is in fact related to other objects. The levels of an object are
neither internal nor external to it. Rather, they are the object's very spatiality. They
correspond to the spatial structures throughout which the events of one given scale are
communicated to other scales. In an object-oriented metaphysics, there is no relation
outside of objects. Across different scales, objects comprise the different levels of their
relatedness. For example, one can think of the body's joints. They simultaneously
connect and separate different regions of the body. Whereas they can be seen as objects
in themselves, they can also be seen as being part of any of the connected regions. A
joint is both an object and a medium. In fact, fractal geometries like this can be found in
whatever kind of network. Every object is a multimediatic cluster. Every medium is an
object. Objects within objects, media within media, ad infinitum.
The fractal geometry according to which objects are wrapped around and into
one another results therefore from a levelled exchange of energies. A novel object can
only come about by means of a communication of events between levels. A perspective
which is close to Simondon's understanding of relations on the basis of notions such as
information and metastability. Notwithstanding, Harman himself is critical of the idea
that potentials constitute an intrinsic dimension of objects. For him, objects do reserve a
capacity to establish novel relations, but this potential is necessarily actual. In his
words: “This secret reservoir cannot be the ‘potential’, because the potential needs to be
inscribed somewhere actual right now, and if the actual is entirely determined by its
relations then this gets us nowhere” (2009, p. 187). Here, at the same time that
potentiality is conflated with actuality, it is also conflated with resolute determinations.
209
“The potential can only mean a potential for future relations, and the actual can only
mean what is in and of itself actual apart from any relations” (Ibid.). This understanding
of potentials conforms to the idea that actuality is relative to itself and potentiality
relative to future objects. But, in contrast to Simondon, Harman understands potentials
as being determinately given. From which it follows that he grants to virtuality no
special value. Of the notion of virtuality he says that it “merely plays the double game
of saying that true reality in the universe is both connected and separate, both
continuous and heterogeneous” (Ibid.). But by saying this, what Harman seems to
dismiss is the immanent factor of determination implied in the conjunctive article “and”,
which he uses. For such conjunction between disjunctive parts implies not only their
relation, but more specifically, their relation in potential, which necessarily implicates
an immanent factor of determination between what is given and what is not. What
Harman dismisses is the general potential of constitution that is actually nowhere to be
found but that, notwithstanding, is real. As such, it is undetermined. For if novelty is to
occur, the world needs to include a general potential of creativity. Hence, what
Harman's philosophy overrides is the constitutive indetermination of affect. Instead of
accounting for this reality, Harman instead engages himself with a renewal of
occasionalism, not by making use of any notion of transcendence, but rather by using
the notion of “vicarious causation”. Instead of an indeterminate cause, what this notion
implies is the idea that all causation is actual but, inasmuch as it is inaccessible, non-
linear and too complex to be known. According to the author, if neither potentiality nor
virtuality qualify for the task of causation and for a distinction between real and sensual
objects, “[t]he only thing that will fit the bill is a non-relational actuality: objects that
exist quite apart from their relation to other objects, and even apart from their relation to
their own pieces” (Harman, 2009, p. 187).
210
this is by no means to say that an object-oriented metaphysics, as theorized by Harman,
conceives of process in terms of undetermined potentials and of individuals with
associated milieus. In fact, as much as such metaphysical approach conceives of all
reality as actual, novelty is hardly made to be a part of the picture. This approach
postulates an ontology of possibilities, regardless of what cannot be known because of
being vicarious. In the actual spaces of an object-oriented world, novelty is more
correctly seen as the outcome of possibilities that, because of being vicarious, cannot be
anticipated. It could be argued that, in this case (like with the principles of an universal
computation), objects are combinable with one another in as many ways as possible. In
which case, emergents would merely correspond to the outcomes of a combinatorics
that, despite being possibly unpredictable, is determinately given and therefore
knowable. Whereas this is the case of a computable possibility space, the vicarious
causation that Harman argues to be fundamental for the understanding of an object-
oriented world precludes this ontology's possibilities from being computed. This factor
of unknowability at the heart of possibility is the very incomputability of objects. But,
in contrast to Chaitin's theory of algorithmic complexity, this is not an incomputability
made out of random quantities of data. In fact, as much as in Harman's philosophy this
randomness pertains to the unknowable core of objects, what the notion of vicarious
causation overrides is the very necessity to define the indetermination constitutive of
this lack of knowledge. If the notion of vicarious causation pertains to process's
indetermination, then the quality of such indetermination remains to be discussed. A
lack that corresponds as well to an absent discussion on the relationship between
quantities and qualities.
211
this way be conceived as a multimediatic module throughout which information is
transmitted. But even here, with the notion of information, Harman's philosophy leaves
no space for indetermination. In an object-oriented metaphysics, information cannot but
correspond to the serialization of data. In short, what this theory overlooks is
indetermination in general. More specifically, it does not account for an actuality that is
itself random and undetermined. It does not strive to consider the kinds of quantities
that are unaccountable by the qualitative expression of objects and their relations. If one
is to take Chaitin's proof of Omega seriously, then a whole field of excessive quantities
must be considered. And instead of equating actuality with what is determined, as
Harman does, one needs to consider it as well in undetermined terms. From which it
follows that, instead of a qualitative continuum resulting out of a total quantitative
determination, what one gets is an extensive continuum pervaded by incomplete and
undetermined quantities. In order to discuss the notion of the extensive continuum,
which comprises both the spatiotemporal distribution of objects and an infinity of
random quantities, bigger than the realized qualities, this study will now turn to Alfred
N. Whitehead's process philosophy. In this way, not only objects will be conceded a
processual character, but also and precisely because of this, their parts will be conceived
as being bigger and more random than their determinate and qualitative expressions.
But before this, it is perhaps worth noting that an inquiry on the relationship
between qualities and quantities, from the perspective of algorithmic objects, shouldn't
be understood as pertaining only to digital computation. One should bear in mind that
digital simulations are feasible not only because they share the possibility space with the
systems of reference, but also because their algorithms coincide with these systems's
processes.155 Be it on the side of digital simulations or on the side of their systems of
reference, algorithms can be found as what results from the co-individuation of subjects
and objects, that is, as the knowledge of the models according to which processes
unfold. If, for example, there would not be a specific sequence of genes responsible for
producing a specific protein, we wouldn't be able to create this same protein by means
of computational procedures. Which is simply to say that the genetic code itself is the
basis of a complex ecology of algorithmic procedures by means of which determinate
syntheses are actualized. In this regard, the field of biotechnology is most exemplary.
One moves from conceiving of the world as a set of autonomous algorithmic
155 For a philosophical incursion into, not only all sorts of digital simulations, but also more broadly the
synthetic style of reasoning underlying them, see Manuel DeLanda's book “Philosophy and
Simulation: The Emergence of Synthetic Reason” (2011).
212
procedures, from which we can only derive simulations, to the practice of programming
with its own codes. In this manner, instead of just simulating processes, we become able
to create systems that, unlike any others before them, result from a knowledgeable
manipulation of the world's most intrinsic algorithms. Thus, to inquire into the mode of
relation between quantities and qualities, from the perspective of algorithmic objects,
corresponds more to a given take on the world, i.e. to the assumption that its processes
unfold according to an algorithmic architecture, than to a specific focus on digital
computation. It is nonetheless from such scope that digital computation might come to
be understood under a new light.
213
to an infinite series of discrete points, rather than to a continuous infinity. At the same
time that it abstracts ideas from actuality, it remains implicit in its discrete multiplicities.
This results in virtual-actual dynamisms that correspond to infinite extensions of
inclusion and exclusion between wholes and parts, rather than to rhythmic pulsations
between movements of actualization and deactualization, in the sense of topological
processes. Mereotopology—a mode of thought that articulates mereology with topology
—refers to the study of extensive relations between parts and wholes (Whitehead, 1978,
pp. 281–333). Media theorist Luciana Parisi explains Whitehead's use of this method in
the following way: “Whitehead’s analysis of parthood relations (mereology, from the
Greek mero, 'part') was an ontological alternative to set theory. It dispensed with
abstract entities and treated all objects of quantification as individuals. As a formal
theory, mereology is an attempt to set out the general principles underlying the
relationships between a whole and its constituent parts, as opposed to set theory’s search
for the principles that underlie the relationships between a class and its constituent
members. As is often argued, mereology could not explain by itself, however, the notion
of a whole (a self-connected whole, such as a stone or a whistle, as opposed to a
scattered entity of disconnected parts, such as a broken glass, an archipelago, or the sum
of two distinct cats). Whitehead’s early attempts to characterize his ontology of events
provide a good exemplification of this mereological dilemma. For Whitehead, a
necessary condition for two events to have a sum was that they were at least 'joined' to
each other, i.e., connected (despite being or not being discrete). These connections,
however, concerned spatiotemporal entities, and could not be defined directly in terms
of plain mereological primitives. To overcome the bounds of mereology, the
microscopic discontinuity of matter (and its atomic composition) had to be overcome.
The question of what characterized an object required topological and not mereological
analysis. From this standpoint, two distinct events could be perfectly spatiotemporally
colocated without occupying the spatiotemporal region at which they were located, and
could therefore share the region with other entities. The combination of mereology and
topology contributed to Whitehead’s articulation of the notion of the extended
continuum.” (Parisi, 2013, pp. 309–310).
214
partakes with other entities. Their contact generates concrete limit-points and surfaces
of contact that no longer fall into the topological infinity of infinitesimals. Rather, these
are discrete conditions of transition from one spatiotemporal region to another,
organized in accordance with a continuity of potential discontinuities (i.e. discrete
points of contact). Here, connection concerns the critical limits at which the state of a
regional system is altered to the point of having to change. The passage from one state
of affairs to another is designated by Whitehead as “concrescence”, which “is the name
for the process in which the universe of many things acquires an individual unity in a
determinate relegation of each item of the 'many' to its subordination in the constitution
of the novel tone” (1978, p. 211). As such, the transitory connectivity of spatiotemporal
regions corresponds to the unification of a multiplicity of actual entities. It is the
constitution of a mereotopological space where parts and wholes are related to one
another in extension.
215
divisibility” and an “unbounded extension”, which according to Whitehead are the main
features of the extensive continuum, comprises in itself the infinity of virtual potentials.
216
For Whitehead, ideas “exhibit the definiteness of mathematical relations” (1978,
p. 327). Only this allows abstraction to measure the physical world in an exact way. In
contrast to relativity theory, which conflates the laws of physics with geometry and
relegates abstraction to the limits of space's infinitesimal divisibility, Whitehead
proposes a disarticulation between abstractions and expressions so that the measurement
of space can occur in purely formal terms (1978, pp. 283–289, 294–301). On the one
hand, this amounts to saying that only the potentials of pure abstractions can define the
mathematical relations actually established between the different parts of one extensive
whole. On the other, it is to say that the contact between the different entities cannot
actually express the definiteness of mathematical relations. It follows that there is
necessarily a degree of indetermination constitutive of the extensive continuum's
mereotopological relations. If one were to perform, concretely, the partition of a whole,
one would necessarily find impossible to express the definiteness of mathematical
relations. To the same extent that this is concretely impossible, it is possible in
abstraction. Only in abstraction can the definiteness of mathematical relations be
defined. Notwithstanding, the potentials of such relations do exist immanently in
extension. The pure potentials of eternal objects are immanent in the extensive
continuum's mereotopology. Abstraction in general and the definiteness of mathematical
relations in particular, rather than doubling in potential what can in fact come to occur,
simply correspond to yet undetermined relations of contact between the extensive
continuum's actual regions of space-time. As such, mathematical relations are pure
potentials.
217
actual continuum of extensive relations between parts and wholes.
218
continuum” (Ibid., pp. 61–82). This continuity of extension is a potential for indefinite
division, which grants it with the capacity to express the definiteness of mathematical
relations. The general potentials of ideas are here granted an actuality that, rather than
being determined, is undetermined. It is through such indetermination that the extensive
schema of general expression ceases to relate only discrete and discontinuous entities, to
not only relate them in a continuous field of potentials but also relate them to these
same potentials, i.e. to the ideal patterns of occurrence that they express each time anew.
From which it follows that each determinate expression necessarily implicates
undetermined quantities of data that allow for it to connect to all other actual entities, if
not in fact, at least in potential. Conversely, it is only by means of these potentials'
ingression into the concrescence of novel facts of unity that the continuum becomes
extensive, i.e. that it acquires determinate standpoints with regard to its overall
development. Whitehead explains the relationship between the extensive continuum and
the concrescences that in it take place in the following way: “The real potentialities
relative to all standpoints are coordinated as diverse determinations of one extensive
continuum. This extensive continuum is one relational complex in which all potential
objectifications find their niche. It underlies the whole world, past, present, and future.
[…] the properties of this continuum are very few and do not include the relationships
of metrical geometry. An extensive continuum is a complex of entities united by the
various allied relationships of whole to part, and of overlapping so as to possess
common parts, and of contact, and of other relationships derived from these primary
relationships. The notion of a 'continuum' involves both the property of indefinite
divisibility and the property of unbounded extension.” (Ibid., p. 66).
219
Accordingly, “[w]e have always to consider two meanings of potentiality: (a) the
'general' potentiality, which is the bundle of possibilities, mutually consistent or
alternative, provided by the multiplicity of eternal objects, and (b) the 'real' potentiality,
which is conditioned by the data provided by the actual world. General potentiality is
absolute, and real potentiality is relative to some actual entity, taken as a standpoint
whereby the actual world is defined.” (Ibid., p. 65).
In order to better understand the relationship between general and real potentials,
let's once again consider the example of colour. Once granted that whatever expression
of blue cannot be but a singular event, and that it can only be so insofar as the general
potential of blue exists as a potential of relatedness between the multiplicity of actual
entities in concrescence, it must be acknowledged that absolute and relative potentials
are immanent in one another. The eternal object blue exists in actuality as much as
actual entities exist in the continuum of eternal objects. There is no one singular
expression of blue that doesn't implicate the eternal object blue. Reciprocally, the
general idea of blue does not exist without being implicated in actuality, i.e. without
being somehow expressed. Real, local and relative potentials are intrinsic to the objects
of eternity, since these constitute the continuum that each actual occasion cuts. Each
actual cut realizes potentials relatively to the concrescent data, which are themselves
approximations, in continuity, to the general potentials of relatedness that the continuum
provides.
220
geometrization of space and time that, contrary to Harman's object-oriented
metaphysics, depends on the immanent relation between random quantities of data and
the continuum's determinate standpoints.
221
by the present. This actualization, tells us Whitehead, is initiated with the “pure
reception of the actual world in its guise of objective datum for aesthetic synthesis”, a
movement that necessarily comes to include in the actual occasion a multiplicity of
previous entities. This process, in which “the many become one, and are increased by
one”, is guided by what the author calls “the ultimate metaphysical principle”, that is,
“the advance from disjunction to conjunction, creating a novel entity other than the
entities given in disjunction. The novel entity is at once the togetherness of the 'many'
which it finds, and also it is one among the disjunctive 'many' which it leaves; it is a
novel entity, disjunctively among the many entities which it synthesizes.” Each creative
process is therefore determined by the actual data that it can receive into concrescence.
The concrescence resolves the extensive continuum's indetermination into a coherent
coordination of different standpoints and, in this way, synthesises it aesthetically. (Ibid.,
p. 21).
Whitehead's extensive continuum undoes the split between space and time that
was still so prevalent in Bergson's theory of duration, to give prevalence to the notion of
an infinity of discrete points. In contrast to Bergson's philosophy, which understands
experience according to duration, Whitehead's notion of the extensive continuum
provides the possibility of conceiving the relation between intensive and extensive
multiplicities in terms of an atemporal depth (of affect). Here, resonance is key. For it is
through the processual resonance of the extensive continuum that a multiplicity of
spatio-temporalities can co-exist. Contrary to the continual flow of becoming so
characteristic of durational experience, the extensive continuum's actual entities come to
be in contact with one another by selecting the potentials of eternity into the vibratory
resonance of the concrescent becoming. The extensive continuum is a field of
becoming, the internal resonance of which assures the affective prehension between
actuals entities.
From this standpoint, algorithmic objects can be seen under a different light. In
contrast to Harman's object-oriented metaphysics', Whitehead's philosophy offers the
possibility of understanding algorithmic objects as processes. Algorithms can be thought
in terms of both physical and conceptual prehensions of data. They can actually prehend
data, but not without prehending as well, conceptually, the eternal objects available to
be selected into concrescence. Moreover, instead of relegating algorithms' mathematical
definiteness to some inaccessible depth, it understands it as belonging to extension
itself, while it remains undetermined and, therefore, just a general potential. To say that
algorithms prehend the general potentials of ideas is to say that they reorganize the
222
extensive continuum by constituting, out of the immanent relation between random data
and determinate standpoints, novel facts of unity. As such, they are actual entities. They
are the very concrescence through which what is given into process, both determinately
and indeterminately, comes to be selected for the latter's termination. For, as Whitehead
explains, “[t]he ‘formal’ constitution of an actual entity, is a process of transition from
indetermination towards terminal determination. But the indetermination is referent to
determinate data. The ‘objective’ constitution of an actual entity is its terminal
determination, considered as a complex of component determinates by reason of which
the actual entity is a datum for the creative advance.” (1978, p. 45). In the guise of
Chaitin's theory of algorithmic complexity, Whitehead's notion of the extensive
continuum provides a consistent framework to conceive of the incomputability of
algorithms. Instead of just random quantities of data, Chaitin's Omega is seen, under the
light of Whitehead's philosophy, as an infinite series of eternal objects.
223
dynamism whereby incomputable quantities of data are prehended into the resolution of
initial disparities between the extensive continuum's potentials. As actual occasions of
experience, algorithms cannot be fully synthesised into expression. The parts of an
algorithmic object are necessarily larger than the whole, because of their constitutive
infinity. To prehend the eternal objects of such infinity into the concrete resolutions of
computation means nothing else but to think. This is the major outcome that can be said
to result from approaching the algorithms of digital computation with the extensive
schema of Whitehead's philosophy. Inasmuch as algorithms prehend, not only
physically but also conceptually, the many potentials of the extensive continuum where
they exist, they are the conditional basis of a thoughtful character that must be granted
to digital computation. Since algorithms prehend the incomputable quantities of data
constitutive of the extensive continuum's series of infinite ideas, digital computation
does not occur without being infected with ideas that it cannot compute. With such
incomputabilities, digital computation is assured with a capacity to eventuate
concrescences that cannot be fully predicted. It is granted the capacity to generate facts
of togetherness that are truly novel. Further, the irreducibility of those infinite ideas
potentially given to the concrescences of algorithmic computation confers to the latter
the very status of thought. Inasmuch as algorithmic computation prehends the
conceptual infinity of the extensive continuum where it occurs and to which it belongs,
it does not occur without abstracting its own procedural determinations with ideas that
cannot be known as such.
157 In his book “Software Studies”, Matthew Fuller notes that “[r]ecent etymological research credits
John W. Tukey with the first published use of the term 'software'. In a 1958 article for American
Mathematical Monthly he described how the mathematical and logical instructions for electronic
calculators had become increasingly important [in the following way]: 'Today the ‘software’
comprising the carefully planned interpretive routines, compilers, and other aspects of automative
programming are at least as important to the modern electronic calculator as its ‘hardware’ of tubes,
transistors, wires, tapes and the like'.” (2008, p. 2).
224
immanent construction of digital spatiotemporalities. From this standpoint, soft thought
cannot be simply disqualified for being a mechanical calculation of possibilities. At the
same time, it may also be misleading to assume that computation is yet another
extension of living thought. Soft thought is instead the mental pole of an algorithmic
actual object. It is the conceptual prehension of infinite data that defines computational
actualities or spatiotemporalities as the point at which algorithms stop being determined
by the efficient order of sequences and rather prehend their incomputable limit. Soft
thought thus explains algorithmic computation as an actual mode of thinking that cannot
be reproduced or instantiated by the neuroarchitecture of the brain (the neurosynaptic
network), or to the neurophenomenology of the mind (the reflexive ability of the mind
to become aware of its actions on the world). Soft thought, in consequence, is
autonomous from cognition and perception.” (2013, p. 169).
158 It is worth noting that Parisi, by using both the expression “neuroarchitecture” and the expression
“neurophenomenology”, is referring to what she designates as “the split between the neurocognitive
and the neuroperceptual understanding of thought” (2013, p. 177). This split can be synthetically
understood with the following passage: “If neuroarchitecture aims at designing the experience of
space according to adaptive neural responses to the environment, neurophenomenology argues that it
is the structure of experience – and not the cognitive mapping of the brain’s adaptation to space – that
leads us to view cognition as enacted experience. According to enactivism, the interaction between
thought and space – between experience and architecture – cannot coincide with a neural pack of
connections, but rather needs to be studied in terms of first-person, experiential evidence of spatial
phenomena or of variations such as depth, height, volume, temperature, colour, sound, etc. For
neuroarchitecture on the other hand [...] the data collected on these variations [...] are enough to
qualify these elements of interaction as first-person […]. Neurophenomenology instead employs
specific first-person methods in order to generate original first-person data, which can then be used to
guide the study of physiological processes.” (Parisi, 2013, p. 182).
225
insofar as algorithms convey the influence of random quantities of data over the various
degrees of their own determination and of the determination of their effects that they
can be said to be the subject of soft-thought. And this is not to say that soft-thought is to
be understood as the kind of reflexive cognition so typical of neurophenomenologies,
such as the enactivist theories of cognition, perception and the mind (Parisi, 2013, pp.
180–185). On the contrary, because soft-thought is defined as “a manifestation of
incomputable infinity or the conceptual prehension of incompressible data that suspends
the order of algorithmic sequences.” (Ibid., p. 17), it can only be experienced either non-
consciously or in terms of its unpredictable effects.
This requires perhaps a twofold explanation, one that explains the unconscious
experience of thought and the novelty that from it might result. In the case of
algorithmic computation, novelty corresponds to what results from the infection of
incomputable quantities of data in computation itself, a creative capacity that can be
best understood when accounting for the structure of parametric algorithms. As
previously mentioned, the space of parametric algorithms can be approached either
topologically or mereotopologically. If the relation between parameters is approached
from a topological perspective, expression is seen as the result of determinate
parametric variations. But if the relation between parameters is approached from a
mereotopological perspective, it must be acknowledged that the computation of finite
datasets is pervaded by and infected with an immanent and constitutive infinity of
discrete and random quantities of data. In this way, variations in parametric expression
are seen to result not from direct causes but rather from the mobilization of
undetermined potentials. If the information exchanged between parameters is
considered to be undetermined and random, then its effects on the overall structure of
algorithms cannot be said to result exclusively from direct causations. Instead, a whole
process of individuation needs to be acknowledged. Between the general potentials of
ideas and the actual entities which express them, there necessarily needs to occur an
exchange of information that, not only is the means by which a novel resolution can
come into being, and therefore constitute a determinate standpoint in the historicity of
the extensive continuum, but also the very cancellation of an initial disparity between
potentials. In this sense, the algorithmic processing of information from which
determinate quantities of data can emerge, necessarily corresponds to the resolution of
problems in potential. Novelty can then appear as the expression of more than what has
been algorithmically programmed. An expression which asserts algorithms as the very
prehension of incomputable quantities of data. With this, it must be acknowledged that
226
only the conceptual prehension of random quantities of data realizes computation's
potential to “deploy new actualities of relation or space events that are new and invisible
to parametric programming” (Parisi, 2013, p. 171). The effective deployment of novel
relations without perceivable effects thus regards the already mentioned presupposition
of experience by consciousness. As such, in the extensive continuum, novelty is
constant. It is always already there, not only potentially but also as the actual
deployment of relational events that, even if unperceivable, are real and contributive.
227
procedures, as codes that perform thoughts upon a material substratum, or which cause
thoughts to emerge from the latter. Yet regardless of whether these thoughts emerge
from neural connections or are constructed throughout the sensorimotor schema of
perception, algorithmic procedures remain the executers of thought. In short, the
conditions for algorithmic processing are established by the sense in which the physical
architecture of the brain is always already set to ensure the performance of thought.
What is missing from these approaches is the possibility of conceiving algorithmic
processing as a mode of thought, an expression or finite actuality, and not as the
instrument through which thought can be performed, whether through neural nets or
enacted via embodiment.” (2013, pp. 185–186).
228
concrescence, these excessive quantities of data correspond to what is negatively
prehended into process. As already mentioned, a “negative prehension holds its datum
as inoperative in the progressive concrescence of prehensions constituting the [novel
fact of] unity [...] (Whitehead, 1978, pp. 23–24). As such, it is a function of subtraction.
It doesn't subtract eternal objects from the actual occasions of experience, but rather
actual occasions from the extensive continuum's eternal objects. Some general
potentials are positively prehended into the actual occasions of experience, some are
negatively prehended. But never the extensive continuum's eternal objects can be said to
be inaccessible to the occurrent concrescences. They are of process and, as such, one of
its fundamental conditions. Which is the very reason why it is possible to conceive of
soft-thought as a fundamentally abstract process. Inasmuch as algorithms can be defined
as conceptual prehensions of incomputable quantities of data, the structuration of soft-
thought owes more to what is negatively prehended into computation than to what is
positively prehended. Incomputabilities can then be defined as those quantities of data
that, despite being a fundamental condition to computation, are negatively prehended
into concrescence.
159 “The 'ontological principle' broadens and extends a general principle laid down by John Locke in his
Essay (Bk. II, Ch. XXIII, Sect. 7), when he asserts that 'power' is 'a great part of our complex ideas of
substances'. The notion of 'substance' is transformed into that of 'actual entity'; and the notion of
'power' is transformed into the principle that the reasons for things are always to be found in the
composite nature of definite actual entities – in the nature of God for reasons of the highest
absoluteness, and in the nature of definite temporal actual entities for reasons which refer to a
particular environment. The ontological principle can be summarized as: no actual entity, then no
reason.” (Whitehead, 1978, pp. 18–19). As such, “[t]his ontological principle means that actual
entities are the only reasons; so that to search for a reason is to search for one or more actual entities.
It follows that any condition to be satisfied by one actual entity in its process expresses a fact either
about the 'real internal constitutions' of some other actual entities, or about the 'subjective aim'
conditioning that process.” (Ibid., p. 24).
229
the philosopher says: “The actual entity terminates its becoming in one complex feeling
involving a completely determinate bond with every item in the universe, the bond
being either a positive or a negative prehension. This termination is the 'satisfaction' of
the actual entity.” (Ibid., p. 44). Thus, everything in concrescence is a positive affect, be
it a positive prehension or a negative one. The satisfaction of actual entities assures the
determinate bond by which they come to be part of the whole extensive continuum.
Negative prehensions assure that, when satisfied, the actual entity remains bonded with
the extensive continuum. They assure that its concrescence conveys unlived, unknown
and unexpressed potentials. Only in this way it is possible to conceive of concrescence
as a process that, at once, feeds off from the potentials of the extensive continuum and
feeds back into them, becoming as such a relative standpoint amidst the general
potentials of all eternal objects. Only in this way is possible to assure that, after
concrescence, negatively prehended eternal objects remain available, as general
potentials, for further concrescences. The relevance of negative prehensions “must
express some real fact of togetherness among forms. The ontological principle can be
expressed as: All real togetherness is togetherness in the formal constitution of an
actuality. So if there be a relevance of what in the temporal world is unrealized, the
relevance must express a fact of togetherness in the formal constitution of a non-
temporal actuality.” (Ibid., p. 32). In other words, actual entities must become part of the
extensive continuum via the negative prehension of eternal objects. In any actual
occasion of experience, what is not lived is as constitutive of it as what is.
230
prehensions explain that computation is not simply a form of cognition that constructs
cognitive maps as recipes for action. On the contrary, the negative prehension of infinite
incomputable algorithms leads us to conclude from the understanding of random,
patternless, or contingent data that [software is] irreducible to one overarching system
of thought qua cognition. Instead, this negative prehension reveals that there are infinite
modes of thought, involving a multiplicity of predictive capacities that correspond to
nonunified (chemical, physical, biological, digital) patterns of decision making. In order
to address the existence of these heterogeneous modes of thought, which are not always
already referable to an eternally unchangeable being, it is important to conceive of
algorithmic procedures as actualities that are defined by both physical and conceptual
prehensions. This means that the sequential order of programming is only an aspect of
computation. Yet we must bear in mind that any algorithmic execution is conditioned by
the conceptual prehension of incomputables.” (2013, p. 222).
231
in the extensive continuum's determined actuality if not through the notion of process.
In the frame of media theory, the extensive continuum has been characterized by Steve
Goodman and Luciana Parisi in terms of a “rhythmic anarchitecture”. In their words:
“To the becoming of continuity we call rhythmic anarchitecture, where anarchitecture
denotes a method of composition, which feeds off the vibratory tension between
contrasting occasions. A rhythmic anarchitecture is amodal and atemporal. Rhythm
proper, cannot be perceived purely via the five senses but is crucially transensory or
even nonsensuous. Rhythmic anarchitecture is concerned with the virtuality of quantum
vibration. It is necessary here to go beyond the quantification of vibration in physics
into primary frequencies. For us, it is rhythm as potential relation, which is key. If
rhythm defines the discontinuous vibrations of matter, then we must also ontologically
prioritize the in-between of oscillation, the vibration of vibration, the virtuality of the
tremble. The rhythmic potential that is an eternal object, cannot be reduced to its
phenomenological corporeality. The vibratory resonance between actual occasions in
their own regions of space-time occurs through the rhythmic potential of eternal objects,
which enables the participation of one entity in another. The rhythmic potential of an
eternal object exceeds the actual occasion into which it ingresses. To become, an actual
entity must be out of phase with itself.” (2009).
Not only the negative prehension of eternal objects assures the bond between
actual entities, but concrescence itself is only possible because of the extensive
continuum's indetermination. Concrescences can only occur by means of an affective
resonance of non-localized relations between actual entities. These are clearly
Simondonian terms. For, if actual entities must fall out of phase with themselves in
order to come into being, then dephasings are only possible when potentials of different
orders come to affect one another. From this perspective, the concrescence of
prehensions can be seen as a movement of transduction: it transfers principles of
individuation and amplifies them in a network of vibratory resonances. The extensive
continuum's rhythmic anarchitecture therefore regards the ingression of what cannot be
sensed into the order of the sensible and of the virtual-actual dynamisms that result from
this. From which it follows that, in the case of algorithmic objects, rhythm necessarily
pertains to the prehension of what cannot be computed into determinate algorithmic
expressions. This notion of rhythmic anarchitecture is most adequate to understand the
workings of soft-thought. The conceptual prehension of infinite quantities of random
data assures the ground on which the resonance of contrasting entities can take place. If
positive prehensions contribute to expression, negative prehensions assure the implicit
232
endurance of eternal objects amidst actual entities. Only the vibratory resonance of
affect between actual entities assures that the latter can, not only be inscribed in the
extensive continuum as local, relative and historical potentials, but also be connected to
one another by means of mereotopological relations of extension. The negative
prehension of discrete and random quantities of data relates actual entities, such as
algorithms, to one another via the extensive continuum's general potentials.
233
conserves, in the whole's structured parts, the enabling potentials of the latter's
connection. By means of information, the unknown remains immanent in the
technogenetic body, i.e. it remains immanent in the individuating system's sensitive and
cognitive capacities.
234
of its own potentials, the more this will confuse its implicated domains. The
technogenetic body can be defined by this very heterogeneity. The more heterogeneous
it is, the more unpredictable it becomes. As such, heterogeneity is here tantamount to
the prehension of infinity. It corresponds to the vibratory activity of technogenesis'
rhythmic anarchitecture, and it is equally proportional to the individuating system's
creativity. The more heterogeneous a system becomes, the more it is capable of
overcoming the limits of its own possibilities. In sum, only because connectivity is a
determinant function of technical individuation, can the increment of connections be
said to enhance the technogenetic body's technicity.
235
There is no other way to conceive of allagmatics but as a dynamism constitutive of
technical transduction. And, notwithstanding the fact that information is here conceived
as being undetermined, it is through the conceptual prehension of what cannot be
compressed into concrescence that the workings of the abstract machine in allagmatics
can be best understood.
236
designations that depict the immanent character of the abstract machine at the heart
process. They all depict an undetermined reality existing not at the end of an
infinitesimal division of space, but rather at the level of actuality itself (actual
indetermination being itself just another name for the indefinite divisibility with which
Whitehead defines the unbounded extension of the continuum). But this is not a plea to
either render the invisible visible or expand consciousness and knowledge. Rather, it is
the following proposition: in order to overcome the dictates of regulation, prediction
and control, all of which are organized solely in accordance with determinate sorts of
actuality, the unknown must be not only accepted as constitutive of developmental
processes but also as a potential to connect all that is known or knowable. There is no
other way for technical individuals to become than through the concrescence of negative
and positive prehensions. And the more data is prehended into concrescence, the more
the extensive continuum is restructured.
160 Though a review of algorithmic strategies in the history of choreography has not been made here,
other cases beyond Forsythe's choreographic procedures can be mentioned as being paradigmatic of
237
From this standpoint, and together with the argument that algorithms are not
exclusive of digital programming, but that they rather express a specific way of
thinking, the individuation of choreographic knowledge must be granted to comprise
what is negatively prehended into concrescence. Choreographic knowledge must be
considered together with the technological milieu of its own individuation. The fact that
the cases discussed here have used digital technologies to assert choreographic
knowledge is just one example of the interdisciplinary conditions of these same
assertions. Though the interdisciplinary character of these projects has been just briefly
mentioned, this remark is enough to consider the difference in connectivity conveyed by
them in contrast to less interdisciplinary or transindividual approaches. Regardless of
the domains of abstraction and expression summoned by the projects in case, what
matters to acknowledge is the tendency that these projects demonstrated towards the
complication of process, i.e. towards the saturation of process with general and relative
potentials of connectivity. In fact, it seems evident that the larger a research project is—
i.e. the more people, technologies, time frames, geographical scales, knowledge fields,
and so on, it involves—the more complicated it gets. 161 But rather than this complication
being a burden, the argument here is that it potentiates the creation of novelty in
technical individuation. It is with such complication that the individuation of knowledge
can yield unanticipated results.
algorithmic choreography. It is here enough to mention that it was Merce Cunningham, the American
choreographer who, from the fifties onwards, set himself to emancipate dance from all other forms of
theatrical expression (and thus to modernize it as an autonomous artistic form, where “movement is
only about movement”), that pioneered the use of algorithmic procedures to compose dance.
Cunningham’s drive to de-subjectify choreography brought him to experiment with compositional
procedures involving chance. Since chance procedures require the calculation of ideas, choreographic
composition became in this way equated with computation. This would bring Cunningham to work
with computers for the calculation of complex conditions of possibility, making him “the first
choreographer of international renown who routinely utilized the computer as a choreographic tool”
(Copeland, 2004, p. 168). But more fundamentally, what Cunningham activated when applying the
faculty of computation to the composition of dance, was the very idea of choreographic software.
When commenting upon the software-like methodologies and aesthetics of Merce Cunningham's
choreographic work, Stamatia Portanova has conflated these two terms, i.e. composition and
computation, into one: “compu-sition” (2013, pp. 97 – 132). With this term, Portanova indicates how
much the procedural character of many choreographic practices quantifies not only spatio-temporal
actualities but also of virtual infinities. Which is to say that, because choreographic compu-sition
(like any other composition) involves both determinate quantities and the immanent infinity of
random data, it can be said to be a mode of thought in its own right. After these first compu-sitional
experiments, the field of dance expanded considerably, most notably with the next generation of New
York based choreographers, such as Trisha Brown, Steve Paxton, Simone Forti, Yvonne Rainer,
Douglas Dunn and David Gordon, most of whom had danced with Cunningham.
161 The paradigmatic case being the Motion Bank project, the documentation of which, accessible at
http://motionbank.org/en/documentation, indicates the inherent complexity.
238
determined and undetermined data. It opens the system of individuation to its self-
excess and it intensifies its tendencies towards dephasing. And what remains most
acknowledgeable in regard to such increment is the intensification of affect between
different quantities of data. If negative prehensions are as determinant to concrescence
as positive ones, the increment of actual connections does not only correspond to the
increment of physical data but also to the increment of conceptual data. The more actual
connections are built into the system, the more the system will generate its own ideas
(be them known or not). From which it follows that the more connections are built into
the system, the more the system will be capable of conceptually prehend eternal objects
into the concrescent resolution of differences in potential.
162 Though this study has only dealt with examples that make use of digital media, similar examples that
don't could also be discussed. Some of these are: the already mentioned (see Page 18) “Mind and
Movement: Choreographic Thinking Tools”, by Wayne McGregor/Random Dance; Anne Teresa de
Keersmaeker's “A Choreographer’s Score”, edited by dance theoretician Bojana Cvejic; the
“FUNKTIONEN” toolbox, by choreographer Thomas Lehmen; the “Everybody’s Performance
Scores”, published by www.everybodystoolbox.net; and the publication series “Scores”, by
Tanzquartier Wien (http://www.tqw.at/en/scores).
239
the reciprocal and affective implication of quantities and qualities. In relation to one
another, they constitute the fundamental condition for the becoming of a rhythmic
anarchitecture. And inasmuch as rhythm is not constant, but rather subjectable to the
intensification of problems and to the constraints of extension, it is by these very means
that the continuum's becoming can generate novel knowledge and ideas that cannot be
known as such.
240
CONCLUSION
If seen as a map of the encounter between dance and technology, this study's
topology entails a number of entangled problems. First, there is the problem of novelty:
on which conditions can choreographic novelty occur? Second, there is the problem of
objecthood: how are choreographic objects to be understood if the conditions of novelty
necessarily implicate potentials? Third, there is the problem of potentiality: how are
potentials to be understood if the objects to which they belong are expressible in
different domains? Fourth, there is the problem of transmission: how are objects
transmitted from one domain to another and what happens there? Fifth, there if the
problem of relation: how is abstraction related to expression? Of course all these
questions can be formulated differently, and the list can also go on. But what matters
here to understand is that all these problems are implicated in one another. Precisely
because of this, the present study can be seen as diagramming the plane of composition
of the encounter between dance and technology. Framing these study's concerns with
novelty, potentiality and process with the work of process philosophers, being that such
tradition is fundamentally concerned with the relationship between continuity and
discontinuity, quantities and qualities, virtuality and actuality, can also be said to have
biased its own development. Expressing by means of writing, i.e. discontinuously, the
reality of choreographic processes, i.e. a real continuity, attests that it is itself a diagram
and that it maps the topology of the encounter between dance and technology.
If the logic of relation between problems and solutions presented before (e.g. in
Section 4.1) is to be followed, then it should be possible to synthesize at this point a
series of solutions for the problems just mentioned. Not only this, but all the remaining
hypotheses followed throughout this study should by now have acquired a determinate
degree of resolution. In order to expose such resolutions, a brief concluding summary
will be now addressed to each of the previous chapters.
Chapter One – It could be asked: “Why should an inquiry into the digital
expressions of choreographic knowledge start with ontological concerns about
movement and bodies?”. The answer has been given and is quite simple: it is not
possible to inquire into a kind of knowledge that concerns moving bodies if not by
inquiring as well into the latter's definitions. After all, specific understandings of
moving bodies necessarily condition what is to be understood by choreographic
knowledge. In this respect, it can be said that the incursion into Henry Bergson's take on
241
the theory of multiplicities has proved to be telling. Not only has movement been
argued to be more than dislocation, but also such excess has become equated with what,
in movement, is irreducible to space. As such, it has been shown that movement
necessarily implicates a temporal dimension of change, which Bergson defines as
“duration”—the elastic interval where bodies move as a whole. Such notion of whole
remained echoing throughout this study's development. Already here, it became equated
with the very infinity of potentials to which, in order to move, bodies must open. As
indicated by Gilles Deleuze, the whole of a moving body is neither given nor giveable.
It is absolutely irreducible to extension, but yet conditional to and encompassing of its
transformations. Hence, movement must be thought in terms of virtual-actual
dynamisms that express space, but not without abstracting it with the constitution of
memory. There is a most fundamental point to this: such virtual-actual dynamisms are
only assured by a constitutive principle of immanence. Such principle assures that space
and time cannot be thought without one another and that the mode of their relation is
fundamentally undetermined. Here, such indetermination has been addressed to
potentiality itself. From the perspective of Bergson's theory of duration, potentials are
more correctly seen as being virtual, rather than actual. Notwithstanding, throughout
this study, such view has been contested. If, for example, potentials are to be granted to
the digital domain, they must be actual and, somehow, compose the continuum whereby
virtuality and actuality relate, immanently, to one another. Furthermore, it matters to say
that this relation's indetermination has been also addressed in different ways throughout
the study. Most importantly, it has been conceptualized in terms of affect—the reality of
relation that, being undetermined, is irreducible to finite expressions, but that
nevertheless assures a continuous exchange between the memory of time and the
expressions of space.
With this in mind, this study proceeded with a focus on the encounter between
dance and technology. To inquire into such encounter, while considering the virtual-
actual dynamisms of movement, is to ask how the memory of time gets to be contracted
into spatial expression. Already here, the notion that the encounter between dance and
technology is in fact choreography (as this is commonly understood) started to be laid
out. To think dance technologically is to necessarily constitute instances of knowledge
that regard ways of dancing. The fact that such knowledge must, at some point of its
determination, be expressible by means of dancing, attests its transmissibility. It is a
knowledge that can be transmitted from body to body and from dancing to writing. As
such, here, the problematic concern with the virtual-actual dynamisms of movement is
242
not only a concern tantamount to how the memory of dance can be expressed, either by
means of the dancing body or by means of writing, but also a concern with how such
dynamisms unfold in the very process of choreographic transmission. The definition of
such dynamisms by a constitutive principle of immanence and, therefore, by a potential
that can create what cannot be predicted, because it is yet undermined, indicates that the
encounter between dance and technology is capable of creating novel instances of
choreographic knowledge. Such capacity is notwithstanding problematic when it comes
to consider that what can be transmitted has necessarily to be known and, therefore,
determined. If it is already determined, it cannot be new. Hence, the question posed
here: how can the encounter between dance and technology create of novel instances of
choreographic knowledge? Not new for given subjects and objects, but new in a way
that brings into constitution the very subjects and objects of novel and emergent
relations. In a sense, this first Chapter served to pose this problem.
Chapter Two – Simondon's theory of individuation has been presented here with
the intent of explaining, on the one hand, how the virtual-actual dynamisms of
movement unfold in the case of technical systems and, on the other hand, how such
processes can be modelled towards the expression of new individuals. Though this
constituted the ground upon which the topological character of choreographic objects
has been later approached (facilitating in this way the understanding that such objects
can be expressed in infinite ways without loosing their diagrammatic character, i.e.
technicity), it can be argued that all things here said with regard to this philosophical
system have been scarcely developed. To put it more bluntly, from all the concepts
exposed, only some resulted in being fundamental to the subsequent analysis and
discourse. This is not to say that the incursion here essayed into Simondon's philosophy
is not of value. Rather the contrary. It is to say that this philosophy has such far-reaching
implications with regard to the thought of process and transindividual life that it
demands further investments. This study's focus on choreographic objects barely
indicates some possible ways of coping with this author's challenging thought. Even in
regard to the conceptualization of choreography, the outcomes here proposed can be
said to be short of what it might be possible. This study only opens the field of relations
between choreographic thought and the fundamental concerns of process philosophy.
An opening that is not exclusive. The references used here from Erin Manning's work
indicate her engagement with such relation. In this regard, she's only one amongst
several. Such interest is recent and therefore still pregnant with potentials. This study
partakes this interest and strives to contribute to the understanding of its potentials. In
243
this respect, Simondon's work stands as an inevitable reference due to its dedication to
technics. Of course other names could be summoned. For example, Martin Heidegger.
But this requires further investigations. Up to this point, what can be said in regard to
Simondon's philosophy is that it provides a unique standpoint for thinking the relation
between the different kinds of individuals involved both in the process of knowledge
making and in the process of choreographic creation. The prevalence given by
Simondon to the transductive character of thought, with its analogical mode of
individuating knowledge, seems to be fundamental to understand how choreography can
in fact be granted the status of thought. The choreographic object's irreducibility to its
abstractions and to its expressions results in the corollary that it is also, necessarily,
processual. As such, it must be approached in accordance with its potentials and seen
from the perspective of its whole movement. To say that an object moves is to say that
its very existence depends on the relation between determinate structures and
undetermined potentials. A relation that, insofar as it allows time to be inscribed in the
developmental system where it occurs, constitutes the object as the non-subjective pole
of one choreographic idea. The choreographic object is therefore the logical result of a
choreographic movement of thought. The correspondence between such movement and
technical individuation is one insight that Simondon's philosophy allows to be followed,
together with all the implications that come along with it. In sum, only by having
incurred into Simondon's work, could this study come to the point of understanding the
processual dynamisms of choreographic creation. Which amounts to saying that the
Simondonian notions of individual, information, transduction and technicity seem to be
fundamental for a definition of choreography as a movement of thought.
244
this, resolve itself into novel expressions. Here, whereas writing has been equated with
spatiotemporal structures, dancing has been equated with the movement that pervades
them. Of course this is a somewhat loose distinction, which should be further explored.
Notwithstanding, such distinction sufficed to assert that, in this way, choreographic
writing can be understood as the creation of invariant functions of expression.
Regardless of being abstract or concrete, such functions assure the choreographic
system's continuity, i.e. they assure that the system's structures endure throughout
transitions between domains of individuation. Because of this, choreography—the
writing of dance—has been defined as the choreotechnical formation of mnemonic
structures capable of enduring throughout the many processes of their own
transmission. Such invariant functions have been defined both in terms of potentiality
and in terms of rhythm. They regard the kinds of problems that, in potential, can be
posed to choreographic individuation. They regard the continuity of potentials that,
while connecting abstractions to expressions, is capable of transferring one same
problematic structure across different domains. Such structure is problematic because it
necessarily relates an idea with determinate conditions of individuation. The problem is
therefore always a difference between abstract potentials and concrete possibilities. On
the other hand, positing choreographic problems necessarily occurs by means of a
rhythmic differentiation of potentials and possibilities, which has been designated as
nexus. Such nexus corresponds to the problematic structure of one choreography's
invariant functions. Its expressions are always singular but, insofar as they are related to
one another by a continuity of potentials, they have in common the same kind of
problems. Hence, the different expressions of one same choreography correspond to
different resolutions of one same problematic structure.
245
individuation, will express itself differently. The multimodal expression of each of the
“Improvisation Technologies” attests precisely this: it attests that one same
choreographic object can express itself in different ways, all conveying the structure of
its own potentials, a structure which is generically defined by determinate margins of
indetermination (i.e. parameters). Such multimodal expression attests as well the other
two aspects of the choreographic object: when its different expressions are juxtaposed,
its parametric structure becomes explicitly defined as what, between them, does not
change; the fact that such definition results from the different expressions' relationship
attests that it is precisely by means of relating the different modalities of sense that the
choreographic nexus becomes better perceived. In this respect, the most clear example
of a choreographic act given till this point regards the act of reading, i.e. it regards the
learning subject's capacity to perceive a nexus of movements in an assemblage of signs.
The capacity of choreography's multimodal expressions to elicit such perception has
been here formulated in the following way: the concurrence of different nexuses defines
a common structure, which is the structure of the very choreographic object to which
they belong.
246
then it is propositional. Such equation has been here argued by drawing from Gilles
Deleuze's theory of ideas, which also allowed for defining the object's diagrammatic
character with three distinct phases: it is formless, subjective and expressive. The
formless diagram of choreography corresponds to the unconscious of process. It regards
the very continuum through which what cannot be known relates itself to potentials that,
even if argued to be actual, are nonetheless undetermined. Inasmuch as choreographic
transduction individuates instances of knowledge, the formless diagram of a
problematic idea is the continuity that assures the many resolutions' connection. As
such, it assures as well the connection between subjective and expressive diagrams. The
choreotechnical act necessarily co-relates these two diagrams: it determines them as the
subjective and objective poles of one epistemological relation. Whereas the subjective
diagram corresponds to the idea's conceptual determination, the expressive diagram
objectifies it in extension. This led this study to consider the means by which diagrams
can be expressed and to explore how both the abstract diagram of potentials and the
subjective diagram of concepts participate in such process. This allowed for making the
case that, because choreographic transduction necessarily intertwines, in a dynamic and
affective manner, the diagram's three phases (which, as argued in Chapter 2, are
necessarily contemporary to one another), there is always in this process an implicated
potential to express unpredictable and therefore novel facts. In short, only because there
is an unconscious and undetermined potential in process, can this express novelty. The
choreographic object's propositional character is therefore related with the potentials
that it always implicates, regardless of its phase. Nevertheless, it is only by being
determined that the object can in fact become propositional. For the choreographic
proposition elicits the feeling of a contrast that necessarily corresponds to the object's
differential topology. Since such feeling is charged with potentials, it can serve the
resolution of their differences into novel determinations.
This study proceeded by discussing Emio Greco and Pieter Scholten's “Double
Skin/DoubleMind” choreographic object, not only to look upon its propositional
character, but also to exemplify how such dynamic diagrammatism partakes
choreographic transduction. Out of this, it was realized that, insofar as the digital
domain is coded, it is the object's conceptual diagram that assures its nexus' preservation
across expressions. This has to do with the fact that the knowledge transduced from
dancing to writing is necessarily conceptual. Of course dance can be said to implicate
many other kinds of knowledge, such as all those pertaining to kinetic automatisms. But
it is the very conceptualization of the dancing body that allows choreography to be
247
expressed by means other than dance (as argued by Forsythe, in Chapter 3).
Additionally, it has to do with the fact that the digital domain is itself conceptually
structured. As such, it requires that what is not discrete and quantifiable becomes so. If
there is a logic in expressing this one choreographic object by digital means, it is
precisely that of dealing with the problems implicated in such transduction. Such
problems necessarily regard the difference between what is continuous in experience
and what is discontinuous in expression. Here, choreography's characteristic problem of
the difference between dancing and writing has been specified with a difference
between the qualities of the dancing body and the quantities of digital media. Such
problem was resolved both with the conceptual structuration of media objects (i.e.
videos, scores and texts) and with the digital programming of algorithms meant to
represent the dancing body's movement qualities. This latter case was discussed only in
the following Chapter. What matters here to retain is that the different matters of content
used to represent in the digital domain this one choreographic object, had to be
subjected to the dictates of a conceptual structure, without which the object's nexus
could not be expressed in such a definite manner. As with the case of Forsythe's
“Improvisation Technologies”, such conceptual structure acts as a function of expression
and assures that the different matters of content are related to one another according to
the choreographic nexus that it represents.
Chapter 5 resulted in a distinction between the dancing body and its written
representations, in terms of gesture. Since most of these algorithms were programmed
to structure videographic data and compute representations of the dancing body, such
248
representations were said to correspond to determinate definitions of gesture used to
define the algorithms themselves. The parametric structure of such algorithms
represents therefore the very structure of the concept of gesture used to programmed
them. From which it follows that the distinction between the dancing body and its
written representations—here designated as gestural body—is also a distinction between
qualities and quantities, i.e. a difference between the continuity of qualitative potentials
and the discontinuity of quantitative possibilities. Here again, such distinction
corresponds to the fact that, for choreo-knowledge to be transmitted, it needs to be not
only determined, but also conceptually structured. Only the conceptualization of choreo-
knowledge allows for its expression in the form of gestures and, as such, in linguistic
forms. It is precisely because dance's conceptual structures are resumable across
domains that choreographic objects can be said to be algorithmic. They are algorithmic
with regard to the diagram of their own ideas. As shown, in the cases in question, the
digital representations of gesture have been expressed by parametric descriptors that
serve the computation of many cases of solution for one same choreographic problem.
Such gestural bodies are therefore fundamentally different from dancing bodies because
they express choreography's determination in the form of discrete quantities of digital
data. As already argued and confirmed here, it is this very difference that allows for
choreographic transduction to individuate novel instances of knowledge and, in this
case, for gesture's conceptual structure to be digitally expressed. The fact that such
determination is here used to compute, iteratively, the content-expression encounter
constitutive of writing, attests both such algorithms' dynamic character and the fact that
their expressions correspond to the many possibilities of the encounter's set. The limits
of possibility of gesture's parametric structure are the limits of what can come to be
known by digital means in regard to choreographic ideas. Notwithstanding, designating
such algorithms as metaphors entails the notion that their possibility space is open to
undetermined potentials. These potentials belong to the choreographic environments
where such algorithms are embedded. But they also correspond to the hypothesis that,
beyond possibility, computation can create novel and unpredictable expressions. Once
more, this is the problem of a digital potential, which in this Chapter was just indicated
to belong to algorithmic computation.
Chapter Six – From this standpoint, this study's final chapter set itself off to
pursue the notion of a digital potential and, with this, to open the scope of the varieties
of thought present in choreographic creation. What here seems to be most clear is that,
despite the digital having been defined as being exclusively possibilistic, computation
249
cannot synthesize all digital data into countable quantities. Which is to say that, even
when considering the digital domain in terms of discrete quantities of data, it must be
granted that computation cannot structure all such data and that, therefore, it remains
under the influence of a certain degree of indetermination. As such, in computation
itself, there must exist incomputabilities.
250
Such notion of affect in the extensive continuum has been here conceptualized in
terms of prehension. In fact, it was such notion that allowed for the understanding of
digital computation in terms of process. For if the digital domain is pervaded by random
and incomputable quantities of data, then it is the affective prehension of data in process
(i.e. concrescence) that allows it to be creative. To look upon digital algorithms in this
way is to define them as prehensions of data that are both physical and conceptual. They
are physical because they correspond to computations of concrete data (i.e. computation
is expressive). They are conceptual, not only because the content-expression encounter
constitutive of digital writing implicates the ideas programmed, but also and primarily
because they are infected by random quantities of data, which are their very condition,
but which they cannot synthetically express. Ultimately, and according to Whitehead's
notion of eternal objects, the ideas implicated in digital algorithms necessarily
correspond to the random quantities of digital data. As such, in digital computation, it is
the conceptual prehension of data that allows for algorithms to comprehend ideas and,
therefore, explicate the resolution of their problematic potentials. In this way, digital
algorithms can, not only convey their programmed ideas, but also convey new ideas (as
the very result of digital computation). Together with Luciana Parisi's notion of soft
thought, the conceptual capacity of digital computation has been here argued to be a
mode of thought in its own right. One that coincides with the rhythm of affect in the
extensive continuum's becoming.
From this study's central arguments (i.e. that the encounter between dance and
technology is choreography itself, that choreography can be creative only on the
condition of a constitutive indetermination of potentials, and that the choreographic
expression of such potentials is necessarily diagrammatic and algorithmic) a concluding
251
remark can now be made: Choreography is undergoing a veritable revolution. It is
emancipating itself from traditional notions of dance and becoming something more.
Most importantly, such mobilization of potentials affirms choreography itself as mode
of thought. More than yielding this or that expressive and revolutionary result,
choreography's potentials are its strongest force, especially when on the move. They
move ideas that only choreography can convey and, in this way, change its modes of
existence within the all encompassing transindividuation that we all are currently living.
Choreography is becoming, and we are becoming with it: we are becoming
choreographic. If there is anything that can follow from this study, it is the thought of
choreography in parallel to its developments as a mode of thought. Concretely, this can
regard any domain whatsoever. It can follow choreography into the domain of art, it can
follow it into the social domain, and it can follow it still into the domain of machines
(especially in what regards the increasing complexification their networks).
Notwithstanding, all such possibilities share one horizon: to not only accompany
choreography's developments, but to also contribute to its expansion.
252
LIST OF REFERENCES
Alaoui, S. F. (2012). Analyse du geste dansé et retours visuels par modèles physiques :
apport des qualités de mouvement à l’interaction avec le corps entier.
Université Paris Sud – Paris XI.
Andereck, M. (2009). Video Abstraction Tool / Process Catalog. http://synchronousobje
cts.osu.edu/content.html#/VideoAbstractionTool.
Arbeau, T. (1925). Orchesography: a treatise in the form of a dialogue whereby all
manner of persons may easily acquire and practice the honourable exercise of
dancing. New York: Dance Horizons.
Aristotle. (1931). De Anima. In J. A. Smith (Trans.), The Works of Aristotle (W. D.
Ross, Vol. III). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Aristotle. (1999). Physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Austin, J. L. (1975). How to Do Things with Words. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard
University Press.
Bastien, M. (2007). Notation-in-Progress. In S. Delahunta (Ed.), (Capturing Intention):
Documentation, Analysis and Notation Research Based on the Work of Emio
Greco/PC. Emio Greco/PC and AHK/Lectoraat, 48–55.
Baxmann, I. (2007). The Body as Archive. In Knowledge in Motion: Perspectives of
Artistic and Scientific Research in Dance (pp. 207–216). Berlin: Tanz Scripte.
Benjamin, W. (2008). The work of art in the age of its technological reproducibility, and
other writings on media. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Belknap Press of Harvard
University Press.
Bergson, H. (1944). Creative Evolution. New York: The Modern Library.
Bergson, H. (2001). Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of
Consciousness. Mineola, NY: Dover Publications.
Bergson, H. (2002). Henri Bergson: Key Writings. London: Continuum.
Bergson, H. (2007). The Creative Mind: An Introduction to Metaphysics. Mineola, NY:
Dover Publications.
Berlinski, D. (2001). The Advent of the Algorithm: The 300-Year Journey from an Idea
to the Computer. New York: Harcourt.
Bermúdez, B. (2007). Butoh-Kaden: a notation system for Butoh-Fu. In S. Delahunta
(Ed.), (Capturing Intention): Documentation, Analysis and Notation Research
Based on the Work of Emio Greco/PC. Emio Greco/PC and AHK/Lectoraat, 58–
61.
Bevilacqua, F. (2007). Momentary notes on capturing gestures. In S. Delahunta (Ed.),
(Capturing Intention): Documentation, Analysis and Notation Research Based
on the Work of Emio Greco/PC. Emio Greco/PC and AHK/Lectoraat, 26 – 31.
Bevilacqua, F., Zamborlin, B., Sypniewski, A., Schnell, N., Guédy, F., &
Rasamimanana, N. (2010). Continuous realtime gesture following and
recognition. In Gesture in embodied communication and human-computer
interaction. Springer, 73–84.
Birringer, J. (2013). What score? Pre-choreography and post-choreography.
253
International Journal of Performance Arts & Digital Media, 9(1), 7–13.
Birringer, J. H. (1998). Media & Performance: Along the Border. Baltimore, Maryland:
Johns Hopkins University Press.
Bolter, J. D., & Grusin, R. (1998). Remediation: Understanding New Media.
Cambridge, Massachussets: MIT Press.
Burt, R. (2004). Undoing postmodern dance history. Brussels: Sarma.
Campen, C. van. (2010). The Hidden Sense: Synesthesia in Art and Science. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Chaitin, G. (2005). Meta Math!: The Quest for Omega. New York, NY: Pantheon.
Chaitin, G. J. (2001). Exploring RANDOMNESS. New York, NY: Springer.
Clark, A. (1998). Being there: Putting brain, body, and world together again.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Clark, A. (2003). Natural-born cyborgs: Minds, technologies, and the future of human
intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, USA.
Clark, A. (2008). Supersizing the mind: Embodiment, action, and cognitive extension.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Combes, M. (2013). Gilbert Simondon and the philosophy of the transindividual.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Copeland, R. (2004). Merce Cunningham and the Modernizing of Modern Dance.
Routledge.
Crutzen, C., & Kotkamp, E. (2008). Object Orientation. In M. Fuller (Ed.), Software
Studies: A Lexicon (pp. 200–220). Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Delahunta, S. (2003). Open Source Choreography? In Code: The Language of Our
Time. Katalog zur Ars Electronica 2003 (pp. 304–310). Ostfildern: Hatje Cantz.
Delahunta, S. (2006). Co-descriptions and Collaborative Composition. Presented at the
Opening presentation at Choreographic Computations (a NIME06/IRCAM
workshop), Paris.
Delahunta, S. (Ed.). (2007a). (Capturing Intention): Documentation, Analysis and
Notation Research Based on the Work of Emio Greco. PC. Emio Greco | PC and
Amsterdamse Hogeschool voor de Kunsten.
Delahunta, S. (2007b). The body has to be clear and the words have to be right. In S.
Delahunta (Ed.), (Capturing Intention): Documentation, Analysis and Notation
Research Based on the Work of Emio Greco/PC. Emio Greco/PC and
AHK/Lectoraat, 5–9.
Delahunta, S. (2007c). The moment to question... Double Skin | Double Mind. In S.
Delahunta (Ed.), (Capturing Intention): Documentation, Analysis and Notation
Research Based on the Work of Emio Greco/PC. Emio Greco/PC and
AHK/Lectoraat, 58–61.
De l and a, M . (2 000 ). D el eu ze , di agr am s , an d th e ge ne si s of fo rm .
Amerikastudien/American Studies, 45(1), 33–41.
DeLanda, M. (2011). Philosophy and Simulation: The Emergence of Synthetic Reason.
London: Continuum.
Deleuze, G. (1986). Cinema 1: the movement-image. Minneapolis, MN: University of
Minnesota Press.
254
Deleuze, G. (1988a). Bergsonism. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Zone Books.
Deleuze, G. (1988b). Foucault. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Deleuze, G. (1993). The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque. (T. Conley, Trans.). London:
Continuum.
Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and repetition. Columbia University Press.
Deleuze, G., & Guattari, F. (1987). A thousand plateaus: capitalism and schizophrenia.
Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
Derrida, J. (1973). Speech and Phenomena, and Other Essays on Husserl’s Theory of
Signs. Illinois, IL: Northwestern University Press.
Derrida, J. (1976). Of grammatology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Derrida, J. (1978). The theater of cruelty and the closure of representation. Theater,
9(3), 6–19.
Derrida, J. (1982). Margins of Philosophy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Doruff, S. (2006). The Translocal Event and the Polyrhythmic Diagram. Central Saint
Martins College of Art & Design, University of the Arts, London.
Elo, M. (2012). Digital finger: beyond phenomenological figures of touch. Journal of
AESTHETICS & CULTURE, 4(0).
Fernandes, C., & Bermudez, B. (2010). Inventing the interactive glossary: an approach
to documenting contemporary dance. Notation: Special Issue of RTRSRCH
Journal, 2(2), 29 – 31.
Feuillet, Raoul Auger (1968). Choréographie: Ou l’art de décrire la danse, New York:
Broude Bros.
Forsythe, W. (2008). William Forsythe: Suspense . New York, NY: Distributed Art Pub
Incorporated.
Forsythe, W. (2012). William Forsythe: Improvisation Technologies A Tool for the
Analytical Dance Eye. Karlsruhe, Ostfildern: ZKM/Hatje Cantz Verlag.
Forsythe, W., Shaw, N. Z., & Palazzi, M. (2009). The Dance, The Data, The Objects.
http://synchronousobjects.osu.edu/assets/objects/introduction/danceDataObjectE
ssays.pdf
Foucault, M. (2007). Archaeology of knowledge. London: Routledge.
Foucault, M. (2012a). Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison. New York, NY:
Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.
Foucault, M. (2012b). The History of Sexuality: An Introduction. New York, NY: Knopf
Doubleday Publishing Group.
Fuller, M. (2005). Media Ecologies: Materialist Energies In Art And Technoculture.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Fuller, M. (Ed.). (2008). Software Studies: A Lexicon. Cambridge, Massachusetts:
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Gallagher, S. (2005). How the Body Shapes the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Garelick, R. K. (2007). Electric Salome: Loie Fuller’s Performance of Modernism.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Gil, J. (2001). Movimento Total, O Corpo e a Dança. Lisboa: Relógio d’Água.
255
Goffey, A. (2008). Algorithm. In M. Fuller (Ed.), Software Studies: A Lexicon.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Guattari, F. (1995). Chaosmosis: An Ethico-aesthetic Paradigm. Bloomington, IN:
Indiana University Press.
Guattari, F. (2012). Schizoanalytic cartographies. New York: Bloomsbury.
Guest, A. H. (1977). Labanotation: Or, Kinetography Laban : the System of Analyzing
and Recording Movement. London: Taylor & Francis.
Harman, D. U. P. of P. G., & Harman, G. (2011). The Quadruple Object. Lanham, MD:
National Book Network.
Harman, G. (2002). Tool-being: Heidegger and the metaphyics of objects. Chicago:
Open Court.
Harman, G. (2005). Guerrilla metaphysics: phenomenology and the carpentry of things.
Chicago: Open Court.
Harman, G. (2009). Prince of networks: Bruno Latour and metaphysics. Prahran,
Victoria: Re.press.
Hayles, N. K. (2008). How We Became Posthuman: Virtual Bodies in Cybernetics,
Literature, and Informatics. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Heijenoort, J. V. (1967). From Frege to Gödel: A Source Book in Mathematical Logic,
1879-1931. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Heller-Roazen, D. (2007). The inner touch: archaeology of a sensation. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: Zone Books.
Herken, R. (1995). The Universal Turing Machine: A Half-Century Survey. Vienna:
Springer.
Husserl, E. (1960). Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. (D.
Cairns, Trans.). Leiden: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.
Husserl, E. (2013). Logical Investigations. London: Routledge.
Hutchins, E. (1995a). Cognition in the Wild. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Hutchins, E. (1995b). How a cockpit remembers its speeds. Cognitive Science, 19(3),
265–288.
Johnson, M. (1987). The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination,
and Reason. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Johnson, M. (2012). The Meaning of the Body: Aesthetics of Human Understanding.
Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Jones, A., & Heathfield, A. (2012). Perform, Repeat, Record: Live Art in History.
Bristol: Intellect Books.
Khoshelham, K., & Elberink, S. O. (2012). Accuracy and Resolution of Kinect Depth
Data for Indoor Mapping Applications. Sensors, 12(12), 1437–1454.
Klingenbeck, F. (1990). What Should one Write Down and What not. In V. Preston-
Dunlop & S. Lahusen (Eds.), Schriftanz – A View of German Dance in the
Weimar Republic. London: Dance Books.
Knoespel, K. J. (2002). Diagrammatic Transformation of Architectural Space.
PHILOSOPHICA-GENT, (70), 11–36.
Laban, R. von. (1956). Principles of dance and movement notation: With 114 basic
256
movement graphs and their explanation. Macdonald & Evans.
Lakoff, G. (2006). Conceptual metaphor. Cognitive Linguistics: Basic Readings. Berlin:
Mounton de Gruyter, 185–238.
Lakoff, G., & Johnson, M. (1980). Metaphors We Live By. Chicago, IL: University of
Chicago Press.
Lakoff, G., & Núñez, R. E. (2000). Where Mathematics Comes from: How the
Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics Into Being. New York, NY: Basic Books.
LaMarre, T. (2012). Humans and Machines. Inflections, 5, 29–67.
Latour, B. (1996). On actor-network theory. Soziale Welt, 47(4), 369–381.
Lehoux, N. (2013). Dance literacy and digital media: Negotiating past, present and
future representations of movement. International Journal of Performance Arts
& Digital Media, 9(1), 153–174.
Lepecki, A. (2004). Inscribing Dance. In A. Lepecki (Ed.), Of the presence of the body:
Essays on dance and performance theory. Middletown, CT: Wesleyan
University Press, 124–139.
Lepecki, A. (2007). Choreography as Apparatus of Capture. The Drama Review, 51(2),
119–123.
Lepecki, A. (2010). The Body as Archive: Will to Re-Enact and the Afterlives of
Dances. Dance Research Journal, 42(2), 29.
Lingis, A. (1993). Bodies that Touch Us. Thesis Eleven, 36(1), 159–167.
MacKenzie, A. (2002). Transductions: Bodies and Machines at Speed. London:
Continuum.
Manning, E. (2009). Relationscapes movement, art, philosophy. Cambridge,
Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Manning, E. (2013). Always More Than One: Individuation’s Dance. Durham, NC:
Duke University Press.
Martinet, A. (1984). Double articulation as a criterion of linguisticity. Language
Sciences, 6(1), 31–38.
Massumi, B. (1992). A user’s guide to capitalism and schizophrenia: derivations from
Deleuze and Guattari. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Massumi, B. (2002). Parables for the Virtual: Movement, Affect, Sensation. Durham,
NC: Duke University Press.
Maturana, H. R. (1975). The organization of the living: a theory of the living
organization. International Journal of Man-Machine Studies, 7(3), 313–332.
Noë, A. (2004). Action in Perception. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Parisi, L. (2013). Contagious Architecture: Computation, Aesthetics, and Space.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Parisi, L., & Goodman, S. (2009). Extensive Continuum – Towards a Rhythmic
Anarchitecture. Inflexions. A Journal for Research Creation, (2).
Peirce, C. S. (1895). Manuscripts on Existential Graphs (Vol. CP 2.279).
Peirce, C. S. (1998). The Essential Peirce: Selected Philosophical Writings.
Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
257
Phelan, P. (1993). Unmarked the politics of performance. London: Routledge.
Portanova, S. (2013). Moving without a body: digital philosophy and choreographic
thought. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Rancière, J. (2004). The Politics of Aesthetics. London: Continuum.
Rancière, J. (2010). Dissensus on politics and aesthetics. London: Continuum.
Riemann, B. (1873). On the Hypotheses which Lie at the Bases of Geometry. Nature,
3(183, 184), 14–17, 36, 37.
Sabisch, P. (2011). Choreographing Relations. Practical Philosophy and Contemporary
Choreography. München: epodium.
Schechner, R. (2011). Between Theatre and Anthropology. Philadelphia, PA: University
of Pennsylvania Press.
Schneider, R. (2001). Archives: Performance Remains. Performance Research, 6(2),
100–108.
Schneider, R. (2011). Performing remains: art and war in times of theatrical
reenactment. London: Routledge.
Shaw, N. Z. (2009). Video Abstraction Tool / Process Catalog. http://synchronousobject
s.osu.edu/content.html#/VideoAbstractionTool.
Simondon, G. (1958). Psycho-sociologie de la technicité. Bulletin de l’Ecole Pratique
de Psychologie et de Pédagogie de Lyon.
Simondon, G. (1969). Du mode d’existence des objets techniques. Paris: Aubier-
Montaigne.
Simondon, G. (1992). The genesis of the individual. Incorporations, 6, 296–319.
Simondon, G. (1995). L’individu et sa genèse physico-biologique. Bernin: Editions
Jérôme Millon.
Simondon, G. (2005). L’individuation à la lumière des notions de forme et
d’information. Bernin: Editions Jérôme Millon.
Simondon, G. (2006a). Cours sur la Perception. Chatou: Editions de la Transparence.
Simondon, G. (2006b). L’Invention dans les techniques. Paris: Seuil.
Simondon, G. (2009). The position of the problem of ontogenesis. Parrhesia, 7, 4–16.
Smith, B. (1996). Mereotopology: A theory of parts and boundaries. Data & Knowledge
Engineering, 20(3), 287–303.
Stengers, I. (2011). Thinking with Whitehead: a free and wild creation of concepts.
Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Stiegler, B. (1998). Technics and time: the fault of Epimetheus. Redwood, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Taylor, D. (2003). The Archive and the Repertoire: Performing Cultural Memory in the
Americas. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.
Valverde, I. C. (2004). Interfacing Dance and Technology: A Theoretical Framework
for Performance in the Digital Domain. University of California, Riverside.
Van Imschoot, M. (2005). Rests in Pieces: On Scores, Notation and the Trace in Dance.
Multitudes, 2(21), 107–116.
Varela, F. J., Rosch, E., & Thompson, E. (1992). The embodied mind: Cognitive science
258
and human experience. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT press.
Watson, J. (2011). Guattari’s Diagrammatic Thought: Writing Between Lacan and
Deleuze. London: Continuum.
Weisstein, E. W. (2002). Algorithm. http://mathworld.wolfram.com/Algorithm.html
Whitehead, A. N. (1961). The Interpretation of Science, Selected Essays. (Johnson, A.
H., Ed.). Indianapolis, New York: The Bobbs-Merrill Company, Inc.
Whitehead, A. N. (1978). Process and reality: an essay in cosmology : Gifford Lectures
delivered in the University of Edinburgh during the session 1927-28. New York:
The Free Press.
Wiener, N. (1965). Cybernetics Or Control and Communication in the Animal and the
Machine. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press.
Zizek, S. (2014). Event: A Philosophical Journey Through A Concept. Brooklyn, NY:
Melville House.
259
LIST OF ILLUSTRATIONS
260