Types of Students' Justifications: Resumen (Abstract)
Types of Students' Justifications: Resumen (Abstract)
Sowder, Larry; Harel, Guershon . The Mathematics Teacher ; Reston Tomo 91, N.º 8, (Nov 1998): 670-
675.
RESUMEN (ABSTRACT)
Students often have a difficult time articulating their justifications for arriving at mathematical conclusions.
Sowder and Harel offer a framework for thinking about students' justifications in an effort to help shape their
mathematical reasoning.
TEXTO COMPLETO
The comments above, from the inarticulate "I just know it" to the sophisticated reference to a proof, present
different ways that students might justify particular mathematical results. Our aim in this article is to give a
framework for thinking about students' justifications, with an eye toward shaping their mathematical reasoning.
The framework has arisen from our teaching and our interviews with secondary school and college students, but it
also relects the work of others (e.g., Chazan [1993]; Goetting [1995]; Yerushalmy [1993]). A more elaborate version
of the framework appears in Harel and Sowder (1998).
Mathematical proofs are perhaps the ultimate in justifications, but the traditional approaches to them have been
unsuccessful for many students, including college students as well as those at the high school level. When we
have asked college mathematics majors about their experience with proof, too often they have responded with
such comments as, "What the words `mathematical proof' mean to me is a necessary evil" or "I remember hating
those proofs in high school geometry. I remember thinking, `Why do I need to prove this? It's so obvious"' or "For
what reason? I guess I really never felt they were that important, since I was willing to trust whatever brilliant
mathematician thought up the theorem." Research studies of secondary students' proof understanding and
performance (e.g., Senk [1985]; Silver and Carpenter [1989]; Thompson [1996]; Tinto [1988]; Williams [1980])
substantiate that in the past we have not been very successful with this aspect of the curriculum.
Standard 3, Mathematics as Reasoning, of the NCTM's Curriculum and Evaluation Standards for School
Mathematics (1989) recognizes the importance of students' reasoning. The standard states that we cannot
continue to settle for results like many that we obtain from the traditional curriculum. Hence, if the Standards
document's call for student justifications in all areas of mathematics, rather than just in geometry, results in
students' learning that reasoning in mathematics is as important as the facts of mathematics, then we will have
made progress. If the Standards document's support for activities in which students generate conjectures leads
naturally to questions of justification, then we have set a stage for mathematical reasoning.
The framework in this article uses the notion of a student's proof scheme. Proving, or justifying, a result involves
ascertaining-that is, convincing oneself-and persuading, that is, convincing others. An individual's proof scheme
consists of whatever constitutes ascertaining and persuading for that person. Arguments by the same person but
in different contexts or at different times might fall into different categories, and a specific line of reasoning might
involve a combination of proof schemes. Hence, even though some schemes are clearly more sophisticated than
others, the categories of proof schemes described in this article should not be considered as a hierarchy in which a
given person always operates at the "highest" level. The word proof in proof scheme is used in the broader,
psychological sense of justification rather than in the narrower sense of mathematical proof.
References
Tinto, Patricia P. "Students' Views on Learning Proof in High School Geometry." Paper presented at the meeting of
the American Educational Research Association, New Orleans, April 1988. Williams, Edgar. "An Investigation of
Senior High School Students' Understanding of the Nature of Mathematical Proof." Journal for Research in
Mathematics Education 11 (May 1980): 165-66. Yerushalmy, Michal. "Generalization in Geometry." In The
Geometric Supposer: What Is It a Case Of? edited by Judah L. Schwartz, Michal Yerushalmy, and Beth Wilson, 57-
84. Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1993.
AuthorAffiliation
Larry Sowder, [email protected], taught high school mathematics in Indiana and is presently teaching
at San Diego State University, San Diego, CA 92182-7720. He is interested in students' proof writing and, in general,
in their problem-solving performance. Guershon Harel, [email protected], is a professor at Purdue University
and associate editor of the American Mathematical Monthly. His research centers on the epistemology of
mathematics and its application in mathematics curricula.
DETALLES
Tomo: 91
Número: 8
Páginas: 670-675
ISSN: 00255769
CODEN: MATAAP
ENLACES
Linking Service
Copyright de la base de datos 2019 ProQuest LLC. Reservados todos los derechos.