2.chapter 1 Histry As Narrative Originl
2.chapter 1 Histry As Narrative Originl
HISTORY AS NARRATIVE
structure of the world and dehumanization brought out by the Second World
cannot have an objectively superior lifestyle or belief. This idea was taken
15
to emerge.
academia that the theory gained some of its strongest ground in its early
use the term in its present sense in his book The Dismemberment of Orpheus:
popularizing the postmodern theory in the 1970s. Jean Francois Lyotard and
postmodernism.
simulacra. The mass media and other forms of mass cultural production
symbols and images. This shifts human experience away from “reality” to
advertising has led to a loss of the distinction between the real and the
imagined. The same is true of the distinction between reality and illusion, and
the precursors to postmodernism. For the postmodernists, the three, with their
the nature of truth and reality. Modernist authors moved away from the
nineteenth century “realist” notion that a novel must “tell a story,” from an
Postmodernism stretches and breaks away from the idea that man can
experience.
object of that discourse, the term history encapsulates a posited reality and its
representation. The problems of the term are not just related to the efforts of
historians, but to the issues of representation and reality. Most of the attempts
The word “history” refers to two things: narration of past events, and
writing and historiography has been the subject of debate from Aristotle to the
present day. History as a specifically textual concern has entered the domain
of literary studies for the past twenty five years. Historicism, in some form or
New Criticism turned literary studies towards textual analysis in the 1940’s.
In the 1980s, the dominant textualism of the Western critics gives way
by Foucault, the New Historicists argue for a view of history that emphasizes
the role of representation and discourse in life and art. They take a position
that neither history nor literature offers a firm ground from which the other
can be independently studied. The term “New Historicism” refers to all those
and its stress not upon the direct recreation of the past, but
They mean that historical text is not simply a narration of events and objects
and resistance. New Historicism rules out a direct, simple unitary past: history
in the 1970s and 1980s, largely as a reaction to the lingering effects of New
discourses at work in any given age. These various “texts” are unranked;
20
that is, any text may yield valuable information in understanding a particular
any given time affect both the author and his/her text: both are inescapably
With New Historicism, all texts are created equal: anything written,
and literary studies, starts with the assumption that rather than a set of
provable facts, history is a story which a culture tells itself about its past.
influences and motivations, the rhetorical devices employed, and the implied
that any text can be deconstructed to reveal its own ideological assumptions,
Thomas Pynchon, Salman Rushdie and Angela Carter have also forced a
understanding” (Time and Narrative: Vol I 162). Historical facts are normally
the relationship between texts and the world, and of critical practice.
systems of knowledge production. Truth or reality exists within the text; it can
power.
has been dealt with in epistemological terms: how the past is constructed and
understood. We have access to the past only through its traces: its documents,
have only partial representations of the past from which we have to construct
the postmodern situation is that a “truth is being told with ‘facts’ to back it up,
but a teller constructs that truth and chooses those facts” (67). In fact, the
particular meaning to the events. Facts do not speak for themselves in either
form of the narrative: the tellers speak for them, making these fragments of
the past into a discursive whole. In this regard, Linda Hutcheon remarks:
“… all past ‘events’ are potential historical ‘facts,’ but the ones that become
facts are those that are chosen to be narrated” (73). Facts are not ascertained
like sense impressions and they do not speak for themselves. They are not
entirely the creation of historians. Facts exist apart from the historians, but
they become “historical facts” only when they are judged as historically
What is History? observes: “The facts speak only when the historian calls on
them: it is he who decides to which facts to give the floor, and in what order
their interests and experiences, but the facts that they study may also lead
them to change their views. Historians are thus engaged in what Carr calls
“an unending dialogue between the past and the present” (30). The past does
not present itself ready packaged in narratives that historians have only to
transmit. Rather, historians approach the past with present-day beliefs and
aspirations that cannot be put aside. Histories, in short, are statements of the
historian’s present rather than studies of the past. Histories are best described
not as “empathetic” descriptions of the past, but as readings of the past that
readers cannot put aside their own beliefs and aspirations when they approach
histories. The past that we know is always contingent on our own views, our
own present. Just as we are the products of the past, the known past (history)
domain of the past, but in reality it fabricates that past in its own present. In
“…the past is the fiction of the present” (10). So, history is of the past as
thereby making its machinations more visible and its content less verifiable.
article, he seeks to dissolve the distinction between fictional discourse and the
literary composition of the data into a narrative where the historian creates a
philosophical assumption that history can correspond with the reality of the
history. The first one is a question of perspective. In this matter, History (the
From the point of view of narration, there are different kinds of history.
form of politics perpetuated through forms like education. The type of history
called genealogy. So, there are different histories narrated from the
the politics of the perspective and the degree of subjectivity. So, any type of
of histories.
content of the past determines the form of history in the pattern of the
historical narrative. This means that modernist history prioritizes content over
form. But postmodernists have reversed the priority of content over form.
26
This reorientation has produced a linguistic turn that has moved historical
and shaping the meaning of historical events. This is what the American
philosopher Richard Rorty calls “making true” (4). The argument is about the
extent to which truth, objectivity, and justified descriptions are feasible once
the priority of content over form is reversed. The result of the rethinking on
the priority of content over form is the dissolution of the divisions among
history, fiction, perspective and ideology. Placing form above content means
that what is highly significant in creating a sense of the past are the ways in
which historians organize, configure and prefigure the historical events. What
It is first and foremost a deliberate and calculated written act on the part of the
about narrative and about the nature of mimetic representation. In this regard,
form” (20). The form of narrative can be graphic or written or oral. Arthur
27
the ‘narratives’ of historians do not significantly differ from the novels of the
novelists” (12). He says that the historian’s task is similar to that of the
novelist’s. Marwick argues that “historical writing must in some sense tell a
draw together past, present and future: our experiences are shaped by our
hopes and previous experiences, and which in turn shape future experiences
and hopes.
others including Dominick LaCapra, Frank Ankersmit and Patrick Joyce, are
often described as part of a shift or movement called “the linguistic turn” that
explores the textuality of history. The historians who have initiated the
linguistic turn work with ideas from literary theory and argue that, far from
historians’ sense of the role and future of their discipline. White argues that
28
historians do not find the meaning of the past by examining the facts,
they invent or make meanings through their use of language. They do not
reconstruct or translate lived stories into prose stories, but create meaningful
They moralize
In order to give the past “continuity, coherency, and meaning,” histories turn
the past into stories with well-defined plots. White believes that Western
historians, like Western writers of fiction, use five basic plots. Historians
related to . . . the impulse to moralize reality, that is, to identify it with the
social system that is the source of any morality that we can imagine” (Tropics
of Discouse 14). Histories, however accurate they may be, however faithful
29
they are to the evidence and to the experiences of people in the past,
are always allegories. They are stories not only about the past but also about
the present. They are stories not only about the particular experiences of
particular people at a particular time and place in the past, but about the
human experiences in all times and at all places. Symbolic characters, actions,
and settings connect stories about the past to the present, as do the mythic
plots through which those stories unfold. Every history has an aesthetic. It has
In short, historians turn the past into “histories” by writing stories that impose
means. And this is true even of the most ludic and seemingly
Literary Artifact”:
Discourse 82)
White argues that historical narratives are more closely linked with
literature than with the sciences. This is not because historical narratives are
31
historical events in ways that the audience can relate to. Historians re-emplot,
sense of their past. Histories, then, are similar to fiction because figurative
similar strategies in making sense of past events whether they are real or
general take the form of a narrative, in the sense of a coherent and ordered
identified with the linguistic turn, which refers to the priority given to
their use of language. His defense of this idea appears very controversial:
(Tropics of Discourse 121). White argues that historical studies are best
32
White has developed his argument through the cases of four historians-
historian at every stage. He identifies four rhetorical styles through which the
kind: Romance, Tragedy, Comedy and Satire. Each of these figures has its
Europe, White extends the use of tropes from linguistic usage to general
him, metaphor is the most useful trope, and historical explanation “can be
judged solely in terms of the richness of the metaphors which govern its
imagination of the historian, or the greater is his poetic talent, the greater will
be the literary quality and readability of the historical narrative. In this regard,
influenced by Paul Ricoeur. White echoes Ricoeur in the same work: “plot is
elements because the historian has his own choices. His processes of selection
are personal and subjective. The historian takes some past events and makes
story out of them. The events selected will be his personal choice. In that
prominence.
Histories are “not only about events but also about the possible sets of
A,b,c,d,e,…n;
a,B,c,d,e,…n;
a,b,C,d,e,…n;
a,b,c,D,e,…n and
a,b,c,d,E…n
certain event or set of events. These sets of relationships are not inherent in
the events themselves. Rather, they are a part of the language that the
the two preliminary steps before processing the material into a plot which
past structures and processes in the interest of explaining what they were by
events that happened and makes a story out of them. In order to make a story
questions like what happened? When? How? Why; stressing some events and
Emplotment is the literary genre into which the story falls. According
their success in making stories out of mere chronicles; and stories in turn are
in precisely the way that Frye has suggested is the case with “fictions” in
authors do when they tell stories, but this is also what historians do when they
write reports. They do not just report the facts - they create a narrative, a story
is one among many alternative plots. Barry and Elmes have applied the
strategy more visible: Who gets to write and read strategy? How are reading
process? (Barry and Elmes 430) They point to the possibility of having many
vast array of possible characterizations, plot lines, and themes” (Barry and
Elmes 433). In emplotment, the plot is not just a chronology of events or the
arrangement of events within the text, and the epistemology of time and
being-within-time.
meaningful story. An event has meaning in its relation to other events and
plot, which organizes and (re) configures event networks into an intelligible
heterogeneous events and factors into a whole story and into one grand
the narrative of time is not. Plot (re)configures chronological time into storied
succession. The synthesis can occur in the conclusion of a story where all the
contingencies, factors, and events are given a point of view and formed into a
whole understanding.
irreconcilable element of human affairs, and laments the loss of the good
in human life; human affairs display no pattern, and for the most part they are
Argument is the historian’s view of what history ought to be. The four
that individual units are determined by their place in a larger whole and by a
common spirit; for example, the zeitgeist. The mechanistic mode looks for
reference.
Ideology reflects ethics and assumptions which the historian has about
life, how past events affect the present, and how we ought to act in the
present. There were ideologies which did not claim science as an authority
authoritarian ideology now. Conservative, liberal, radical and anarchist are the
four types of ideologies that exist now. White thinks that in principle any of
argument and any of the modes of ideology. Thus, in principle one can have a
This has the important corollary that there is no further, scientific, correct,
neutral way of writing history which can be found outside this grid. Rather,
choose. Within the grid, no one mode has a closer relation to truth than any
or as romance, and there is no way to prove that one of these is the right way
of narrating it.
writing within a particular trope. In this regard, White observes: “Tropes are
Tropes help historian to make his language metaphoric, which enables them
to construct meanings, obtuse and vicarious. In other words, tropes create the
White thinks that the way the “historical field,” or the given set of
mind is ultimately determined at a deep level, deeper than that on which the
modes operate. Each person's mind is biased towards a certain way of making
links between data. White borrows terms from rhetoric to describe them:
metonymic, by making a part represent or stand for any other part of a whole;
the synecdochic, by making the part represent the whole. The ironic mind is
and satiric on irony. White’s tropes are not turns of speech in the sense of
The historian gathers data and assembles them toward a form. Part of
distinction between the elements of a story and the story itself. The story takes
implicit in the events, as Collingwood suggests. Rather, the form comes from
the combination of the historian’s choices in telling the events and the
Historical narratives serve not only as a “reproduction” of the events but also
(Tropics of Discourse 88). Form limits the coherence of the story, which is
the coherence of the events. The facts must be tailored to the form, while
the sequence and by the omission of some events from the sequence. The
choices of emphasis and omission come from the historian’s sense of possible
sets of relationships among the events. The historian begins with “ordinary
much of his later work. Arguing for a sustained examination of the figurative
synecdoche, and irony. Each of these figures has its own characteristic way of
organizing pieces of information into a larger whole. White argues that this
perspective and interpretation. Thus, for White, the power of these different
of history. If one assumes a base level of honesty and skill on the part of the
another based only on historical evidence. White asserts that the kind of
history one chooses to tell is based on moral and aesthetic values that stand in
not only between historiography and the philosophy of history but also
hence, at this formal level, no differences exist between these two kinds of
and to reconnect history with its “literary basis.” This allows the incorporation
discipline of history (Tropics of Discourse 99). History can sustain itself with
textual creatures and as such they can prefigure the historical field
established and made manifest as the historian brings his narrative, and the
past. This is managed through the activity of the historical imagination in the
between the documents but also couples the past, the present and the future.
44
the place of past agents, seeing things from their point of view,
epoch.
asserts that all of these relationships can be ascertained through the analysis of
the language in which histories are written, and the gaps or contradictions
present in that language, rather than the content of the histories themselves.
History 10)
He means that the effect created by a historical narrative is more than the total
defined:
White states that history fails, if its intention is the objective reconstruction of
for the use and abuse of power and authority. In this context, Mark T.
of narrative. His theory calls for emerging models in the realm of historical
narration. History constructs sense of the past events in the present through
models.
interpretive framework that guides much of his later work. Arguing for a
White asserts the importance of four tropes of consciousness that shape the
to develop a less relativistic stance by arguing that the deep structures that
define human consciousness have a certain stability that allows for the
needs to rely only on those modes of discourse that will most accurately
poststructuralist theorists with whom he has been associated, they also raise
between life and narrative found in his early works, emphasizing instead the
works of Proust and Freud, arguing that history cannot serve as neutral
ground for the interpretation of varied texts. White also examines the
the Holocaust.
between history and story. According to him, authors have other messages
that they want to convey so that the historical past is the medium but not the
historical works carry the reader smoothly but directly to the conclusion the
contents are as much invented as found and their forms have more in common
with their counterparts in literature than they have with those in the sciences.
coherent story; they also represent only a selection of historical events. His
insistence that history is as much how you narrate as what you narrate, opens
system of tropes, such as the metaphorical and the ironic, allows for the
critical theory.
49
sign systems and the mode of representation that humans use to convey
feelings, thoughts, ideas and ideologies. It is the study of signs and signals,
any messages whatever and the system of signs that underlie them” (42).
Semiotic analysis looks for the cultural and psychological patterns that
underlie language, art and other cultural expressions. Umberto Eco jokingly
The term semiotics has its roots in Greek semeiotike. Although it has
become the word most commonly used to designate this area of study,
ironically, it was employed by neither of the two great theorists who most
indicate its derivation from the Greek. And the French structuralist Ferdinand
called semiology.
its own method and determinate subject matter. In this case, the semiotician
50
will attend most directly to the basic structure of the sign relation, the
formal logic, and to theoretical linguistics. More typically, semiotics has been
upon philosophy and linguistics but also with vital links to literary and
sciences.
philosophy led by Charles Sanders Peirce. Saussure sought to explain how all
categories of signs and the manner by which we extract meaning from them.
the verbal signs which constitute the language we use. He saw language as
51
laid the foundation for the structuralist school in linguistics and social theory.
A structuralist looks at the units of a system and the rules of logic that are
applied to the system, without regard to any specific content. The smallest
sensory pattern, and a signified, the concept that is elicited in the mind by the
signifier. Saussure emphasized that the signifier does not constitute a sign
and what it stands for. The link between the sign and what it stands for is
written languages; they may not be so for other types of signs such as visuals
Pierce shared the Saussurian observation that most signs are symbolic
and arbitrary, but he called attention to iconic signs that physically resemble
their referent and indexical signs that possess a logical connection to their
referent. To Peirce, the relationship of the sign to the object is made in the
which is not the final signified object, but a mediating thought that promotes
itself becomes a sign that can elicit yet another interpretant, leading the way
the focus of semiotics from a relational view of signs and the objects they
process.
object which stands for another to some mind” (141). In other words, his
triadic model of a sign identifies the word or image sign that stands for some
other object or concept. In line with his philosophical focus, the most basic
premise of his semiotic theory states that all we can know is mediated by
signs. This very important “stands for” process is the point where meaning is
the receiver (reception), and this relationship is the focus of the process of
given by the Italian semiotician, Umberto Eco, who further defines a sign as
“something that is interpreted” (Eco 15). Eco defines a sign as anything which
unit consisting of an expression and a content which are connected with each
view, because every signifier can be translated into other signifiers and
verbal. Contrary to conventional wisdom which suggests that if you can see,
many visual messages may be more complex and more demanding on the
rests. Visual interpretation involves more than simple inference. Eco suggests
(things or events) to which they refer, and he rejects the notion that “iconic”
signs must be likenesses of their objects. He argues that the meaning of signs
signification as the semiotic event whereby a sign “stands for” something, and
for sign production and interpretation in that it determines how the expression
Eco also argues that the content and not the referent of a sign is the
that the meaning of every sign is culturally defined. “Semiosis,” the term
he admits that subjective factors are also involved in each individual act of
semiosis. This notion is then pertinent to the two main emphases of current or
the signifier. The other is a semiotics concerned to stress the social aspect of
(Peirce, 258). According to Peirce, signs are not just words and meaning is
words, iconic signs carry some quality of the thing they stand for as a portrait
that means there is a fire. Symbolic signs arbitrarily stand for something
such as a leaf on a flag, is linked by convention with its object. We learn that
a maple leaf stands for the country of Canada. Symbols, therefore, are
conventional like most spoken and written words and subject to a more closed
that is, they are more likely to resemble their object in some way rather than
being created by convention. In this regard, John Fiske and John Hartley
explain in Reading Television: “…the greater the motivation, the smaller the
role played by socially based convention; and the weaker the motivation, the
more constraining is the convention” (39). Icons and indexes are also more
complex, but once the meanings are understood, they are less subject to
always a rose.
The distinctions between and among icon, index and symbol are not
summer), and a symbol (the War of Roses). Photographs are indexical as well
and reception, the meaning may shift from one to another as the
iconoclastic tearing up of the picture of Pope Paul illustrates how conflict can
called the signifier, and the concept for which it stands, called the signified.
who work in the Saussurian model, the “stands for” relationship is often seen
as arbitrary. In other words, the link between the sign, or expression, and what
languages. Obviously, with language, there is room for interpretation, but the
The concept of open and closed texts, which originated with linguistic,
movie, for example, is a closed text where the code is known and the cause
and effect chains are not open. All that the reader does is to supply a sense of
the rules of the game. “Open” texts, on the other hand, such as most poetry
and tales like Finnegan’s Wake make complex demands on the reader.
The metaphor holds for visual communication as well. The stop sign is a
painting, or our perceptions of the natural environment are much more open
to individual interpretation.
The idea that visuals are primarily open texts and subject to
Rutherford Smith points out in a review of works by Eco and Sebeok: “It is in
the field of open texts, from the work of Joyce and Brecht to the music of
Berio and Stockhausen, that the important work of the twentieth century is
being accomplished” (209). He points out that Eco’s notion that the reader
interpretation.
physical universe), and phytosemiosis (plant life). The two dominant strands
arguments.
language. Semioticians are interested in any system that uses signs to create
meaning and most of them argue that communication should include sign
visually from nature and the reality around us; we also perceive visual
through experience rather than education. This is a fact that apparently makes
the process seem suspect and less sophisticated than language-based meaning
systems. Almost a hundred years ago, Peirce made a plea that scholars ‘not be
observation” (258).
skills, even if they are grounded in observation, rather than language. In other
space of convention.
argue that it is possible to apprehend signs and make sense of them without
for it.
repeated observations for us to make sense of the patterns around us and that
interpretation involves both the eyes and the brain: what we understand is
other words, much of what we know from language or code based signs
including most visual symbols is derived from social learning. For example,
from internal to external. So we understand things not only by using both the
eyes and the brain but also by using internally derived information learned
messages are constituted in two ways: through denotation, the literal meaning
and reference of a sign, and connotation, the meanings that are suggested or
claims that the denotative status of a photo “has every chance of being
meaning. But Barthes explains: “The press photograph is an object that has
Although the photo itself holds many connotative messages, the text around
the photo also contributes to its connotation. Barthes describes the text as
“parasitic” on the image. In other words, the text borrows the objectivity of
the image, while at the same time loading the image with hidden
connotations. Thus, words are not merely duplicating messages within the
Ultimately, it is not the photo that is significant, but the historical and
that one uses to identify the ideologies and messages. The first is perceptive,
know about. For example, they identify with a particular place and time of an
last is the ideological or ethical mode when one recognizes a certain value
providing only one tool for understanding - namely, rhetoric. Rhetoric was
sense of the word, the art of persuasion. Rhetoric operates as the truth,
secondary system.
65
speech, we introduce a natural order into a mass that lends itself to no other
Its substance does not lie in its style, its original music, or its
them. For example, the portrayal of wine in French society as a robust and
that wine can be unhealthy and inebriating. He has found semiotics, useful in
these interrogations. Barthes explains that these bourgeois cultural myths are
But the bourgeoisie relate it to a new signified: the idea of healthy, robust,
between all aspects of a sign system that constructs meaning around cultural
assumptions embedded in the form. The process necessarily begins with the
carries assumptions that appear at once natural and historical. Myth blends in
with a message and denies its own existence through its apparent
subordination to the content of the first and second order signifiers. When we
that shift between watching a play and watching someone in the audience
engaged in reading the play. The play constructs an internal narrative, but
watching the reader shifts attention away from the story content to the form of
play and its relationship to its audience. Myth is related to associated concepts
within speech, folklore, stories, ritual and tradition. Myths are, according to
with the articulation of the core concerns and preoccupations of their host
our culture.
evident.
68
film theory. But it is Christian Metz, one of the giants of French film theory,
who is best known for the use of semiology as a method to analyze cinema.
equivalent to that of the written or spoken word. Unlike the written word,
film’s basic unit, as Metz argues, is the shot, which is neither symbolic nor
arbitrary but iconic, and is, therefore, is laden with specific meaning. Metz
suggests that film is a language in which each shot used in a sequence works
supported Metz’s views. Metz’s ideas are controversial and they become the
catalyst for the heated debate among the theorists during the 1970s and the
1980s, especially among Left Wing cultural theorists in Britain and the United
takes issue with some of Metz’s key statements while calling for a continued
Saussure in the early part of the century. Linguistics has become one of the
most rigorous and fruitful sciences of this century. Metz ultimately discards a
theoretical model for film based on verbal language, although he still believes
that cinesemiotics can learn much from linguistics. His primary reason for
rejecting rigid analogies to language is based on his claim that the image,
unlike the word, is not a discrete unit that can be reduced into smaller basic
units and analyzed. According to him, the image discourse is an open system,
and it is not easily codified, with its non-discrete basic units (the images), its
intelligibility, its lack of distance between the significate and the signifier.
Metz sees the image as being too close an analogue of the thing in the real
the thing.” The mechanical nature of the basic filmic operation (photographic
(Film Language 18-19). This mimetic notion of the image is the opposite of
that held by Umberto Eco, whom Metz cites as responsible for many of his
later changes. Eco proposes the rather startling idea that the iconic
properties of the object represented; still the iconic sign reproduces some of
the conditions of perception. Eco analyzes the codes of the image which allow
of Eco’s is a very important one: for Metz, there is little distinction between
“inside” the film and “outside” the film. He precludes an analysis of the ways
such that a given ideology in the film may be mediated through the codes of
easily extracted from the film. The idea that ideology cannot be separated
from the cinematic codes which mediate, transform and deform it, can be
used to argue against the political efficacy of “popular radical” films like
71
Costa-Gravas’ State of Siege. This film has a “correct” ideology at the level of
content but its message must pass through the sieve of bourgeois codes of
analysis. So he looks to larger units in the film text and decides that the
essence of cinema and the units most amenable to study are the large units of
the narrative. He says that there is a methodological urgency that favors the
invention of the camera in 1895 and states that of all the possibilities that
cinema could have evolved into (as a means of preserving records, as for use
the memory of dead loved ones), it evolved into a “machine for telling
Umberto Eco’s. Eco sees semiology as a tool for revolutionary activity and
talks about “semiotic guerilla warfare.” If you cannot seize or change the
institutions of production, you can at least change the way they are perceived.
72
enables a response to that thought using the degrees and kinds of signs and
signifiers produced by the language. Film uses not only words but also
different kinds of shots, angles and speeds. Therefore, the audience can react
to a film’s semantic intent, but cannot address its concerns regarding the film
in the same language that the film used to convey its argument. For the same
Christian Metz’s argument that while the means by which film expresses
expression. In support of this point, Raymond Bellour argues that film is the
‘Unattainable Text’:
– film and film analysis do not. While the film medium entails
(Stam 56)
of his or her own, using the same methods employed by the director in a
manner dialogic to the film being addressed. But this is problematic for most
semiotics makes us critically aware of the language being used. This results in
conference calling where role play is being done by either party- either of
further argues that cinema is not a language system because “it lacks the
“motivated” sign. So, the relationship between signifier and signified differs
from literature to film (Stam 35). Metz argues against the idea that the
camera/cinematic shot is like the word while the sequence is like the sentence.
He states as evidence that “(1) shots are infinite in number…(2) shots are the
not gain meaning by paradigmatic contrast with other shots that might have
Also, cinema “does not constitute a language widely available as a code;” for,
while all speakers of English can produce English, not all can produce
75
the talent, training and access produced by filmic utterances (Stam 35). Again,
Stam argues further that language and film are both discursive “through
increasingly lost favour and became largely replaced in film studies debates
factors, including the waning interest in the radical leftist politics espoused by
The cultural theorist Jean Baudrillard also argues that postmodern culture
with its rich, exotic media is a world of signs that have made a fundamental
about the cultural structures and human motivations that underlie perceptual