Hans Kelsen in America - Selective Affi Nities and The Mysteries of Academic Infl Uence
Hans Kelsen in America - Selective Affi Nities and The Mysteries of Academic Infl Uence
D.A. Jeremy Telman Editor
Volume 116
Series editors
Francisco J. Laporta
Department of Law, Autonomous University of Madrid, Madrid, Spain
Frederick Schauer
School of Law, University of Virginia, Charlottesville, Virginia, U.S.A.
Torben Spaak
Department of Law, Stockholm University, Stockholm, Sweden
The Law and Philosophy Library, which has been in existence since 1985, aims to
publish cutting edge works in the philosophy of law, and has a special history of
publishing books that focus on legal reasoning and argumentation, including those
that may involve somewhat formal methodologies. The series has published
numerous important books on law and logic, law and artificial intelligence, law and
language, and law and rhetoric. While continuing to stress these areas, the series has
more recently expanded to include books on the intersection between law and the
Continental philosophical tradition, consistent with the traditional openness of the
series to books in the Continental jurisprudential tradition. The series is proud of the
geographic diversity of its authors, and many have come from Latin America, Spain,
Italy, the Netherlands, Germany, and Eastern Europe, as well, more obviously for an
English-language series, from the United Kingdom, the United States, Australia,
and Canada.
v
vi Contents
Part V Conclusions
17 In Defense of Modern Times: A Keynote Address ............................... 331
Clemens Jabloner
18 The Free Exercise Clause and Hans Kelsen’s
Modernist Secularism ............................................................................. 343
D.A. Jeremy Telman
Brian H. Bix is the Frederick W. Thomas professor of law and philosophy at the
University of Minnesota. Professor Bix’s published books include Jurisprudence:
Theory and Context (6th ed., Sweet & Maxwell, 2012); Contract Law: Rules,
Theory, and Context (Cambridge, 2012); Oxford Introductions to U.S. Law: Family
Law (Oxford, 2013); A Dictionary of Legal Theory (Oxford, 2004); and Law,
Language, and Legal Determinacy (Oxford, 1993). Among his 100 articles is
“Kelsen and Normativity Revisited,” which will appear in Carlos Bernal & Marcelo
Porciuncula (eds.), Festschrift for Stanley L. Paulson (Marcial Pons, Forthcoming).
vii
viii About the Authors
Clemens Jabloner is the Hans Kelsen Professor at the University of Vienna, which
is also where he studied law. He then served in the Austrian Federal Chancellery
from 1978 until 1991. From 1993 to 2013, he served as president of the Austrian
Supreme Administrative Court. Since 1993, he has also served as director of the
Hans Kelsen Institute. From 1998 to 2003, he chaired the Commission of Historians
dealing with issues of looting of property in Austria during the Nazi regime. He has
published broadly in the areas of legal theory, public law, and legal history.
Nicoletta Ladavac studied philosophy and law in Milano, Italy, and earned her
Ph.D. in Catania, Italy, with a dissertation on Hans Kelsen’s federalism. In 1995,
she founded Thémis, Centre d’Etudes de Philosophie du droit, de Sociologie du
droit et de Théorie du droit, an institute for research in philosophy of law, sociology
of law, and theory of law in Geneva. From 1997 to 2001, she served on the executive
board and as secretary of the Swiss section of the Internationale Vereinigung für
Rechtsphilosophie and, in 2005, as its vice president. She has been an international
correspondent of the Hans Kelsen Institute in Vienna since 2002. Her current
research focuses on legal positivism, legal sociology, Hans Kelsen, Norberto
Bobbio, Theodor Geiger, and Niklas Luhmann.
Thomas Olechowski studied law at the University of Vienna and earned his habil-
itation there with “Die Entwicklung des Preßrechts in Österreich bis 1918” (“The
Development of Press Law in Austria till 1918”). Since 2003, he has been an associ-
ate professor at the University of Vienna, and since 2004, he has also been a lecturer
at the Pan-European University in Bratislava. In 2008, he was chosen as a member
of the Austrian Academy of Sciences, and since 2011, he has served as a director of
the Hans Kelsen Institute. He has published five monographs and edited or co-
edited numerous volumes on legal history and constitutional history in the nine-
teenth and twentieth centuries.
Bettina K. Rentsch earned law degrees from the University of Freiburg (2013)
and the University of Geneva (Certificat de Droit Transnational, 2010). She cur-
rently holds a Ph.D. researcher’s position at the Institute for Private International
Law and International Commercial Law, University of Heidelberg. Her Ph.D. thesis
reevaluates the role of connecting factors in European conflict of laws, taking into
account their regulatory function and drawing on, inter alia, Albert Ehrenzweig’s
lex fori approach.
Hans Kelsen arrived in the United States in 1940. He was, in the words of Roscoe
Pound, “undoubtedly the leading jurist of the time” (Pound 1934: 532). When he
left his position at the University of Vienna just a few years earlier, the Austrian
politician and jurist Karl Renner hailed Kelsen as “the most original teacher of law
of our time” (Métall 1969: 59). And yet, when Kelsen arrived in the United States,
he was not able to find a permanent teaching position at a U.S. law school. In the
end, he took a position in the University of California, Berkeley, Department of
Political Science.
He taught, lectured and published in the United States until his death in 1973.
After World War II, Kelsen taught and/or held visiting professorships abroad, but
also at U.S. universities, and he received honorary degrees from Harvard, Chicago,
and Berkeley (Ladavac 1998: 392). However, while Kelsen continues to play a
large role in legal education, in jurisprudence and in international legal theory in
other parts of the world (Walter et al. 2010),1 he is almost completely unknown in
the legal academy and the legal profession in the United States (Telman 2010: 353).
Moreover, Kelsen remains an obscure figure in other parts of the U.S. academy,
such as political science, international relations, sociology and political philosophy,
despite his extensive writings on those topics and the significant international recep-
tion of his ideas in those fields as well (Aliprantis and Olechowski 2014).
1
Volume 33 of the Schriftenreihe des Hans Kelsen-Instituts is the third volume in the series focus-
ing on Kelsen’s influence abroad. Earlier volumes on the subject appeared in 1978 (Volume 2) and
1983 (Volume 8). Volumes 12 (1988) and 22 (2001) also include contributions addressing the
international reception of Kelsen’s pure theory of law.
D.A.J. Telman (*)
Valparaiso University Law School, Valparaiso, IN 46383, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
Many of the chapters in this volume deepen our understanding of the reasons
why Kelsen’s mode of thought did not find fertile ground within the U.S. academy.
At the same time, this volume includes chapters that illuminate unexplored connec-
tions between Kelsen and other giants of twentieth century social science and sug-
gests ways in which Kelsenian insights can contribute to a richer understanding of
the intellectual milieu in the post-war United States. Inevitably, the narrative
explored in those chapters expands beyond the geographic territory of the United
States, and we are fortunate to be able to include in this volume contributions that
supplement the story of Kelsen’s reception in the United States with novel insights
into the similar problems involving the reception of Kelsen’s work in post-war
Europe.
This Introduction explores three distinct modalities of Kelsen’s scholarship.
Those familiar with Kelsen’s pure theory of law are confused—or think that Kelsen
is confused—when they read some of his other works, in which Kelsen expressed
clear preferences in the realms of moral and political philosophy. While Kelsen
believed that legal science must maintain its neutrality in such matters, he did not
limit his scholarship to legal science. Many of the contributions to this volume
explore Kelsen’s relationship with other mid-twentieth century thinkers on subject-
matters beyond legal theory. In particular, having lived in times and places where
such views were not a foregone conclusion, Kelsen was a vocal supporter of democ-
racy. His ruminations on the nature of justice have less in common with the techni-
cal analyses in the pure theory than they do with the philosophical and theological
works with which our contributors have placed Kelsen in dialogue. Finally, Kelsen
wrote about international law at a time when its modern contours were in the pro-
cess of being established. As the contributions to this volume indicate, while the
international legal order did not arise in Kelsenian form, Kelsen contributed to some
of the first international legal institutions to arise in the aftermath of World War II.
The purpose of this volume is to introduce readers who may be unfamiliar or
only dimly familiar with Kelsen’s work to that work and the man who created it.
After a brief review of Kelsen’s biography, this Introduction explores some of the
constellations of theoretical insights that are at the core of Kelsen’s work and thus
inevitably arise repeatedly in the chapters that follow.
Kelsen was born in Prague in 1881. He received his doctorate in 1906 and com-
pleted his Habilitationsschrift, which was the first book-length articulation of his
legal theory, in 1911 (Métall 1969: 8, 14). Those two milestones roughly corre-
sponded with Kelsen’s two religious conversions, first to Catholicism in 1905 and
then to Protestantism in 1912 (Staudacher 2009: 46, 48).2 Also in 1911, Kelsen
2
Kelsen’s conversions seem not to have been motivated by religious belief; he seems to have been
agnostic. The second conversion came at the time of his marriage to Margarete Bondi, who con-
1 Introduction 3
verted from Judaism to Protestantism. Austrian law did not permit intermarriage, and as Anna
Staudacher’s research indicates, the Catholic conversion ritual included a stark denunciation of
Judaism, which may explain why most Jews preferred to convert to Protestantism.
4 D.A.J. Telman
First, Kelsen came to the United States at a time when Legal Realism had estab-
lished itself as the newly ascendant, dominant paradigm in legal theory. To Legal
Realists, Kelsen’s approach looked like the legal formalism they had so decidedly
rejected and defeated (Telman 2010: 360–362). Interestingly enough, Christoph
Bezemek’s contribution to this volume takes on the question of whether Kelsen’s
pure theory is in fact a form of legal formalism. He concludes that it is not.
Second, the American academy (and not just the legal academy) rejected Kelsen’s
approach as politically anemic. The inability of the Central European legal positiv-
ist tradition to stand up to Nazism was cited as evidence that its legal relativism
easily elided into moral relativism (Telman 2010: 362–363).
A third set of problems that Kelsen faced in the United States had to do with the
differences between legal education in the United States and most of the rest of the
world. Legal education elsewhere is part of a general university-style education in
which students begin with foundational courses on the nature of law and legal rea-
soning. In the United States, by contrast, students get their general grounding in the
humanities and social sciences as undergraduates and come to law school for pro-
fessional training (Telman 2010: 365–367). In the current environment, which
places increased emphasis on client-centered lawyering, experiential learning and
practical skills training, courses on jurisprudence and legal philosophy are moving
further and further toward the periphery of the curriculum.
In addition, Kelsen’s approach was incompatible with American legal pedagogy,
which was based on Langdell’s case method. Never having taught before in a com-
mon law system, Kelsen did not think about the development of the law in terms of
the slow accretion of common law decisions. Kelsen’s way of thinking about the
law was, to a certain degree, incommensurate with the U.S. approach to legal educa-
tion (Telman 2010: 367–369). Finally, given that students come to law school with
a great variety of backgrounds and trainings, most U.S. law students lack either the
ability or the desire to think about fundamental legal principles in Kelsenian terms.
It is not that U.S. students lack abilities generally, but very few have philosophical
training, and many, by the time they arrive at law school, have a very practical and
pragmatic approach to legal education. U.S. law schools are pluralistic and do not
inculcate students into any particular way of viewing the law, and most U.S. law
schools do not require students to study theoretical approaches to the law in a sys-
tematic way (Telman 2010: 369–370).
This book broadens the focus considerably. While some of the chapters explore
in greater detail Kelsen’s reception in the U.S. legal academy and among U.S. legal
theorists, most chapters look beyond the legal academy and beyond law. We explore
Kelsen’s interactions with political scientists, social critics, sociologists and theolo-
gians, and we also look at Kelsen’s practical contributions to the development of the
law while he was living in the United States. We also are happy to have a contribu-
tion from Frieder Günther that details the neglect of Kelsen among West German
scholars of public law. The book brings to light some of Kelsen’s achievements and
influences that have hitherto not been known or highlighted, and it also suggests
ways in which Kelsen posthumously still can exert some influence on legal thought.
1 Introduction 5
In order to set up the chapters that follow, this introduction quickly reviews some of
the major theoretical themes that make Kelsen’s pure theory of law unique.
The idea behind the pure theory of law is not difficult to grasp, but its ramifications
can be so unsettling as to render the concept mind-boggling. Kelsen sought to pro-
vide a theory of law that was free from impurities derived from theology, sociology,
ethics, politics or any other systematic body of knowledge other than logic (Kelsen
1934: 1, 7–8). In the U.S. context, there are two main wellsprings of resistance to
the pure theory of law. First, pure theory can be downright obnoxious to those who
assume that laws are derived from moral or ethical systems. Second, Legal Realists
dismiss the pure theory as naïve, given the tendency among Legal Realists to treat
law as a superstructure erected on a conscious or unconscious base. Legal Realism
consisted of a diverse group of legal scholars (Green 2005: 1919) committed to the
view, as Frederick Schauer put it, that legal decision-making turned on “something
other than, or at least much more than, positive law, legal rules, legal doctrine and
legal reasoning as traditionally conceived” (Schauer 2013: 756). There was no con-
sensus as to what that “something” was, but Legal Realists rejected (and reject) the
idea that law can be an autonomous subject matter, independent from social reality
and from politics.
Most people who write about Kelsen take it as a given that Kelsen’s pure theory of
law is a version of legal positivism. Kelsen himself describes the pure theory as a
theory of positive law (Kelsen 1960: 1). That is, Kelsen’s pure theory assumes that
law is a product of human institutions. Various impulses, including moral and politi-
cal impulses, may contribute to the substance of legal norms, but the norms are not
obeyed because they are moral or ethical. Their force derives from the reality that
they were promulgated by an appropriate authority.
Because of its normative character, law has certain formal resemblances to ethics
or morality. The structure of legal systems, according to Kelsen, is that they consist
of certain normative rules that instruct the subjects of law how they ought to behave.
Law differs from ethics or morality, however, in that it is indifferent to the substance
of those rules and in that the consequence of violating a legal norm is legal sanction
rather than moral or ethical sanction (Kelsen 1934: 15–19). Law is for Kelsen an
independent normative system. In order to understand how that normative system
works, one need not consider it by the criteria of other, non-legal normative sys-
tems. This is what we mean when we associate Kelsen’s pure theory of law with
legal positivism.
6 D.A.J. Telman
In his contribution to this volume, Michael Steven Green makes the important
and powerful argument that Kelsen’s pure theory is different from both natural law
and positivism in that, from the perspective of the pure theory of law, law exists
independent of social facts. That is, just as we could hypothesize that certain con-
duct (for example, murder) is immoral independent of the existence of human
beings who might engage in such conduct, law would continue to exist even if
human beings did not. This point is important for Green’s project of showing that
Kelsen’s pure theory does not turn on any particular legal regime’s efficacy. While
Green rejects the term positivism as applicable to the pure theory of law, one need
not choose between his understanding of the pure theory and those of other con-
tributors to the volume who routinely refer to the pure theory as a form of legal posi-
tivism. Such references describe the pure theory as a form of legal positivism in
order to highlight the distinction between legal positivism and natural law
approaches to the sources of legal authority.
It asks, say, what prompts a legislator to decide on exactly these norms and to issue no oth-
ers, and it asks what effects his regulations have had. It asks how religious imagination, say,
or economic data influence the activity of the courts, and what motivates people to behave
or to fail to behave in conformity with the legal system (Kelsen 1934: 14).
Similarly, with respect to the relationship between law and morality, Kelsen rejects
not “the dictate that the law ought to be moral and good; that goes without saying…
Rather, what is rejected is the view that the law as such is part of morality, and that
therefore every law, as law, is in some sense and to some degree moral” (Kelsen
1934: 15). As the natural law theorist John Finnis puts it, Kelsen’s position was that
“there may be moral truths, but if so they are completely outside the field of vision
of legal science or legal philosophy” (Finnis 2000: 1598).
The point is that, from the perspective of the legal system, the original source of
the basic norm is generally accepted or not subject to question. The basic norm is
the source of the entire legal normative order, and as such it is also the presupposed,
not legislated, ground for its own authority. Kelsen thus concedes (not that it is any
great concession) that something external to the static legal system gives rise to the
basic norm. But once the system of law is set in motion by the establishment of the
basic norm, law can function autonomously or at least legal science restricts itself
to an analysis of law as such. Because Kelsen views all law as flowing from the
basic norm, he regards all law as part of one normative system. This is Kelsen’s
doctrine of the unity of law.
Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of the law leads him to regard international law and
domestic (municipal) law as part of one normative system. Kelsen could not accept
that legal orders could be in fundamental conflict with one another. That is, local
authorities might promulgate lower norms that would contradict higher norms.
Such norms could be enforced and would in fact be binding on local authorities. But
they would also be subject to review by higher authorities that would test them
against higher norms. Lower norms that cannot be reconciled with higher norms are
invalid.
Kelsen identified three basic theoretical possibilities that might describe the rela-
tionship between international and municipal law (Kelsen 1960: 328–347). Within
monism, Kelsen entertained two options: either international law or domestic law
could be at the top of the hierarchy of legal norms (Kelsen 1960: 332–344). Kelsen
associated the primacy of domestic law with the ideology of imperialism and that
of international law with the ideology of pacifism (Kelsen 1960: 346–347).
Although Kelsen himself claimed not to prefer one form of monism over the other,
8 D.A.J. Telman
However, the Supremacy Clause’s reach is severely limited by the Supreme Court’s
recognition that non-self-executing treaties do not have automatic effect within the
domestic system (Foster v. Neilson, 27 U.S. (2 Pet.) 253, 314 (1829); Whitney v.
Robertson, 124 U.S. 190, 195 (1888)), a doctrine greatly expanded in Medellín v.
Texas (552 U.S. 491 (2008)).4 The status of customary international law as part of
3
The Supremacy Clause provides that all “Treaties made, or which shall be made, under the
Authority of the United States, shall be supreme Law of the Land.”
4
While the majority opinion in Medellín is not a model of clarity on this point, the majority posi-
tion seems to be that a treaty is self-executing and thus effective as domestic law only if the treaty
itself, the legislative history underlying the Senate’s “advice and consent” to the treaty, or the
instrument of ratification expressly indicates a desire or understanding that the treaty was to be
self-executing.
1 Introduction 9
law has been severely limited, at least since Sosa v. Alvarez Machain (542 U.S. 692
(2004)).5
One might be tempted to regard the status of international law as part of U.S. law
to illustrate the unlikelihood if not the implausibility of Kelsen’s monism. Lars
Vinx’s contribution to this volume suggests that Kelsen’s approach does not require
that international law be supreme in a monist system but only recognizes interna-
tional monism as a possibility. Vinx defends a “weak monism” while conceding that
Kelsen’s strong monism has found very little support in the world of legal scholar-
ship. Weak monism claims only that, even if Kelsen was wrong to claim that all law
must be part of one legal system, it is possible and plausible to claim that all law in
fact is part of one legal system.
In addition, Drury Stevenson’s contribution to this volume is also relevant to the
question of monism and dualism. Stevenson emphasizes Kelsen’s insistence that the
law is addressed not to ordinary citizens but to the state actors who implement and
enforce the law. If the unity of law is to be realized, the responsibility to do so falls
upon such state actors who would prevent any conflict from arising between inter-
national and municipal obligations.
As the chapters in this volume by Jochen von Bernstorff and Thomas Olechowski
indicate, Kelsen’s involvement with international law was by no means merely theo-
retical. In a manner very different from his approach in the pure theory of law, Kelsen
drafted his own plan for a post-war international order. Kelsen’s “Draft Covenant”
for the Permanent League for the Maintenance of Peace and his “Treaty Stipulations
Establishing Individual Responsibility for Violations of International Law” can be
found as annexes to his book, Peace Through Law (Kelsen 1944: 127–148). Kelsen’s
disappointment with the international legal order established through the United
Nations Charter is evident in his treatise on the Charter (Kelsen 1950).6
5
According the majority opinion in Sosa, rules of customary international law can give rise to
claims under the Alien Tort Statute only if the rules express norms of customary law as universally
recognized today as were the prohibition on piracy, the right of safe passage and protections for
ambassadors at the time Congress adopted the Alien Tort Statute in 1789. Very few rules of cus-
tomary international law can claim such universal acceptance. Norms of customary international
law rarely come up in U.S. litigation apart from litigation relating to the Alien Tort Statute.
6
I am grateful to Jörg Kammerhofer for his skepticism regarding my reading of Kelsen’s treatise
on the United Nations. Kammerhofer points out that the purpose of treatises in the European tradi-
tion to which Kelsen was contributing is to pinpoint all ambiguities in the law so that attorneys and
judges can know what they are dealing with. This insight leads me to question my assumption that
Kelsen’s disappointment with the substance of the Charter informed his view of the weaknesses in
its drafting. In my own defense, my reading was influenced in part by Kelsen’s preface to his trea-
tise, in which he stated that his ultimate goal was to improve the law governing the United Nations.
10 D.A.J. Telman
There are three main elements to Kelsen’s vision for a post-war international
order: centralization, collective security, and an international court. Centralization
is the key legal technique that Kelsen believed differentiated national from interna-
tional law and the ultimate means for international law’s development. Kelsen’s
views on collective security are not that different from those envisioned in the
U.N. Charter. The most idiosyncratic element of Kelsen’s design for a post-war
international order was his focus on the establishment of a court of universal and
compulsory jurisdiction, as Jochen von Bernstorff details in his contribution to this
volume.
Kelsen did not think that a military alliance would be the main engine of interna-
tional centralization. According to Kelsen, in the national context, the rule of law
was not introduced through the executive and legislative branches of government;
it was introduced through courts (Kelsen 1948: 161). Kelsen contends that the his-
tory of both Roman and Anglo-American law shows that for much of history it was
judicial decisions rather than legislatures or executive decrees that made law
(Kelsen 1948: 162). Kelsen was convinced that because courts arose first in the
domestic context, they must also be the starting point for the global rule of law
(Kelsen 1948: 150). Thus, his own design for an international order, which he called
the Permanent League for the Maintenance of Peace, had as its centerpiece an inter-
national court empowered to exercise compulsory jurisdiction over all member
states as well as jurisdiction to try individuals accused of violations of international
criminal law (Kelsen 1944: 13).
Despite the fact that the institutions of the international legal order departed
sharply from Kelsen’s model, he continued to play a role as a consultant to the U.S.
government in connection with the establishment of the International Military
Tribunals in the aftermath of World War II. Jochen von Bernstorff’s contribution to
this volume details Kelsen’s critique of the Nuremberg Tribunals and highlights the
areas in which Kelsen’s criticisms overlapped with those of Hans Morgenthau. The
two men came to questions of international law from very different perspectives.
However, at least when it came to the foundations of the post-war international
criminal legal order, they arrived at similar conclusions.
Thomas Olechowski’s contribution to this volume discusses previously unknown
memoranda that Kelsen composed as an advisor to various U.S. agencies towards
the end of World War II. The memoranda illustrate Kelsen’s attempts to translate his
ideas about international law into reality. It is not clear to what extent the U.S.
authorities relied on Kelsen’s memoranda in formulating their policies, but the doc-
uments are in any case of interest in illustrating how Kelsen, the great theoretician,
was able to grapple with the practical problems of international institutions just as
he had been willing to grapple with the practical drafting challenges that he faced in
his contributions to Austria’s constitution after World War I.
1 Introduction 11
Kelsen took advantage, as best he could, of his time in the United States. Although,
as Nicoletta Ladavac’s contribution to this volume makes clear, the continuities in
Kelsen’s work far exceed the changes, Kelsen’s scholarly interests were clearly
stimulated by his intellectual exchanges in the United States. It would be difficult to
beat Vienna during the first three decades of the twentieth century for the richness
and variety of its intellectual and cultural milieu. Still, Kelsen’s time in exile brought
him into contact with a different cast of intellectual interlocutors, and his scholar-
ship grew in response to these new impulses.
In some instances explored in the chapters that follow, the connections between
Kelsen and his contemporaries were largely indirect. Still, they grappled with com-
mon problems and often arrived at surprisingly similar conclusions, despite their
very different points of departure. For example, Elisabeth Lefort’s chapter demon-
strates that, in their ruminations on justice, Kelsen and Leo Strauss seemed to reject
each other’s positions. Kelsen rejected natural law; Strauss rejected relativism.
However, Lefort points out, both were in agreement in ultimately concluding that
the nature of justice was elusive, insufficiently captured by any one ethical or politi-
cal perspective.
Bettina Rentsch’s narrative has a different flavor. Kelsen was friendly with Albert
Ehrenzweig, his colleague at the University of California at Berkeley. Nonetheless,
Rentsch suggests that Kelsen’s work, especially his attempts to grapple with the
concept of justice, would have benefitted from serious consideration of Ehrenzweig’s
Pscyhoanalytic Jurisprudence (Ehrenzweig 1971). Kelsen’s inquiries on justice
concluded at an impasse. Kelsen could not deny the human need for a satisfactory
sense of what is just, but he found the pursuit of a universal definition of justice
“irrational.” Ehrenzweig’s work helped explain the sociological and psychological
sources of the impulse for justice. Rentsch contends that Ehrenzweig’s theory could
have filled some gaps in the pure theory of law by providing a more satisfying
grounding for Kelsen’s theory of justice.
Other chapters in the volume indicate the ways in which our academic debates
about the nature of law, conceptions of justice, and the operations of legal and ethi-
cal norms could be enriched were Kelsen’s ideas included. Joshua Felix’s contribu-
tion to this volume also focuses on Kelsen’s work on the theory of justice. Felix’s
work highlights the ways in which contemporary debates, in this case among politi-
cal philosophers, are enriched by a serious consideration of Kelsen’s work. Felix
views Kelsen’s General Theory of Norms (Kelsen 1991) as raising significant chal-
lenges to political philosophers, such as John Rawls, who defend the thesis that the
objectivity of value judgments can be verified by means of a rational procedure, a
position Felix terms “constructivism.”
Jeffrey Lipshaw’s contribution poses fundamental questions, from a Kantian
perspective, regarding the neo-Kantian model at the core of the pure theory of law.
As his work so often does, Lipshaw’s contribution draws on his extensive experi-
ence as a transactional lawyer to test a complex theoretical model for understanding
12 D.A.J. Telman
References
Aliprantis, Nikitas, and Thomas Olechowski. 2014. Hans Kelsen: Die Aktualität eines großen
Rechtswissenschafters und Soziologen des 20. Jahrhunderts. Vienna: Manz.
Ehrenzweig, Albert A. 1971. Psychoanalytic jurisprudence. New York: Oceana Publications Inc.
Finnis, John. 2000. On the incoherence of legal positivism. Notre Dame Law Review 75:
1597–1611.
Green, Michael Steven. 2005. Legal realism as a theory of law. William and Mary Law Review 46:
1915.
Gross, Raphael. 2013. Der Parallelismus als Gefahr: Zur “jüdischen Biographie” von Hans Kelsen.
In Secular religion: Rezeption und Kritik von Hans Kelsens Ausinandersetzung mit Religion
und Wissenschaft, ed. Clemens Jabloner et al., 113–129. Wien: Mainz.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. B.L. Paulson,
S.L. Paulson 1996. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944. Peace through law. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1948. Law and peace in international relations. Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1950. The law of the united nations: A critical analysis of its fundamental problems.
New York: Praeger.
Kelsen, Hans. 1955. Foundations of democracy, 66/I, II. Ethics: An International Journal of Social
Political and Legal Philosophy 66(1), Part 2: 1–101.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. M. Knight 1967. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1991. General Theory of Norms. Trans. M. Hartney 1991. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 2012. Secular religion. A polemic against the misinterpretation of modern social
philosophy, science and politics as “new religion”. Wien/New York: Springer.
Ladavac, Nicoletta Bersier. 1998. Bibliographical note and biography. European Journal of
International Law 9: 391.
Laski, Harold. 1938. A grammar of politics, 4th ed. London: Allen & Unwin.
Llewellyn, Karl N. 1962. Jurisprudence: Realism in theory and practice. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Métall, Rudolf Aladár. 1969. Hans Kelsen: Leben und Werk. Vienna: Verlag Franz Deuticke.
Morrison, Wayne. 1997. Jurisprudence: From the Greeks to post-modernism. London: Cavendish.
Pound, Roscoe. 1934. Law and the science of law in recent theories. Yale Law Journal 43: 525.
Schauer, Frederick. 2013. Legal realism untamed. Texas Law Review 91: 749.
Staudacher, Anna L. 2009. Zwischen Emanzipation und Assimilation: Jüdische Juristen im Wien
des Fin-de-Siècle. In Hans Kelsen: Leben—Werk—Wirksamkeit, ed. Robert Walter, Werner
Ogris, and Thomas Olechowski, 41–53. Wien: Manz.
Telman, D.A. Jeremy. 2010. A path not taken: Hans Kelsen pure theory of law in the land of the
legal realists. In Hans Kelsen anderswo/Hans Kelsen abroad, ed. Robert Walter, Clemens
Jabloner, and Klaus Zeleny, 353–376. Vienna: Manz.
von Bernstorff, Jochen. 2010. The Public International Law Theory of Hans Kelsen: Believing in
International Law. Trans. T. Dunlap. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Walter, Robert, Clemens Jabloner, and Klaus Zeleny (eds.). 2010. Hans Kelsen anderswo/Hans
Kelsen abroad. Vienna: Manz.
Part I
Hans Kelsen and American Legal
Philosophy
Chapter 2
Kelsen in the United States:
Still Misunderstood
Brian H. Bix
2.1 Introduction
Hans Kelsen has been described as “the most internationally famous legal philoso-
pher of [the twentieth] century” (Harris 1996: 95). Yet, in American legal philoso-
phy—even if one narrows one’s focus to careful consideration of the sub-category,
American analytical legal philosophy—the ideas of Hans Kelsen are generally
ignored. And on the rare occasions when Kelsen’s ideas are not ignored, they are
almost always discussed quickly, and, more often than not, erroneously (there are,
of course, prominent exceptions, including works by participants in the Conference
on which this Collection is based).
Section 2.2 of this paper gives examples of Kelsen’s works being overlooked,
offers some misreadings by prominent theorists, and considers possible explana-
tions for this indifference and ignorance. Section 2.3 then turns to some more subtle
(and controversial) questions of correct and incorrect readings, focusing on Kelsen’s
Basic Norm.
1
I should note that at this conference Scott Shapiro expressed an intention to write about Kelsen at
length in a forthcoming work on international law.
2
The “exclusive” entry in that text is by Andrei Marmor; the “inclusive” entry is by Kenneth Einar
Himma.
2 Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood 19
There are, of course, overlaps between Kelsen’s work and Hart’s, and these are well
worth noting—though they are best noted in the context of considering the sharp
differences as well. However, it is hard to discuss differences between Hart’s work
and Kelsen’s when no effort has been made to summarize Kelsen’s work. Both
Kelsen and Hart emphasized (each in his own way) the normativity of law, both
rejected Austin’s empirical approach, and both emphasized the systematic and hier-
archical nature (as they saw it) of law. However, Kelsen’s neo-Kantian analysis
differs sharply from Hart’s empirical and ordinary language-based analysis, differ-
ences in approaches that are displayed in the different natures of the concepts that
might seem similar at first glance: Kelsen’s Basic Norm and Hart’s Rule of
Recognition.
Another very able contemporary theorist, Leslie Green, Professor of the
Philosophy of Law at Oxford University, offers the following dismissal of Kelsen’s
Basic Norm:
There are many difficulties with this, not least of which is the fact that if we are willing to
tolerate the basic norm as a solution it is not clear why we thought there was a problem in
the first place. One cannot say both that the basic norm is the norm presupposing which
validates all inferior norms and also that an inferior norm is part of the legal system only if
it is connected by a chain of validity to the basic norm (Green 2003).
One expects better from a scholar like Green, who is usually very careful in his
analyses even of views with which he disagrees. As most of us explain to our stu-
dents, if you are interpreting a prominent scholar as saying something foolish, the
chances are good that you are not understanding that scholar correctly. Contrary to
Green’s analysis, why would one assume that Kelsen was trying to solve a difficult
problem through mere fiat and declaration?3
The obvious response to Green’s misreading is to point out that Kelsen was
working on problems different from those that concern Green and many of his
contemporaries. The perspective of contemporary Anglo-American legal positiv-
ists on the “normativity” issue is often one that seems analogous to alchemy: how
can the “ought” conclusions of law arise from the “is” facts that make up law
(Coleman 2001: 70–102; Shapiro 2011: 118–153)? Kelsen is not trying to offer a
formula for this alchemical transformation, because he is confident that no such
formula exists: he is a firm believer in the Humean division of “is” and “ought”
(Hume 1978: Section 3.1.1, at 469–470) (a point I will return to in Sect. 2.3).
Because he accepts this sharp division, his theme is not how law can transform “is”
to “ought,” but what follows (in a neo-Kantian way) from the fact that we do treat
the actions of legal officials in a normative way, that is, as creating norms (again,
more on this in Sect. 2.3).
Of course, many explanations have been offered to account for (some portion of)
the lack of interest and attention to Kelsen’s work, some of which point to Kelsen’s
neo-Kantian approach, which is less familiar to American readers than the more
3
Marmor offers a slight variation of Green’s too-quick dismissal: “Instead of telling us something
about the foundations of the basic norm, Kelsen simply invites us to stop asking” (Marmor 2011:
146).
20 B.H. Bix
empirical and pragmatic approaches of the likes of Hart and Dworkin. One recent
and novel explanation for Kelsen’s poor reception was offered by Dan Priel in the
course of a longer argument for why theories of the nature of law are tied to particu-
lar legal systems (in particular, Priel argued that H. L. A. Hart’s theory is assertedly
connected with the English legal system, and Ronald Dworkin’s with the American
legal system). Priel commented in passing that the “obvious” explanation for the
disregard of Kelsen was that “Kelsen’s legal thought, despite his many years in the
United States, remained firmly rooted in a particular conception of law that is closer
to what one finds in civil law systems” (Priel 2013: 339). Unfortunately, Priel does
not develop his argument beyond that mere assertion, and the claim remains far
from self-evident. Certainly, Kelsen refers to concepts like “desuetude” (Kelsen
1992: § 30(d), at 63) that are more at home in some civil law systems than they are
in the Anglo-American legal systems, and he does not spend much time discussing
common law judicial law-making, but the core ideas of Kelsen’s theory (eg, presup-
position of the Basic Norm, the hierarchy of norms, static and dynamic validity,
legal norms as authorizations to impose sanctions, etc.) seem as applicable to com-
mon law systems as to civil law systems.
One should of course note once again that there are exceptions to the indifference
and ignorance to Kelsen in Anglo-American legal philosophy—though the excep-
tions may be more in Britain than in the United States. Beyond the contributors to
this volume, one should certainly mention Stanley Paulson, who has devoted much
of his career to explication of Kelsen’s works, as well as translation of many of
those works into English.4 J. W. Harris was another influential expositor of Kelsen’s
works,5 and Joseph Raz (though some of Raz’s readings of Kelsen are subject to
challenge) gave Kelsen’s work the sort of careful attention that most prominent
legal theorists have failed to offer.6
4
See, eg, (Kelsen 1992), (Paulson 1992a), (2012), (2013a).
5
See, eg, (Harris 1977), (1986), (1996); see also (Paulson 2006).
6
See, eg, (Raz 1976), (1980: 93–120), (1986). Raz’s reading of Kelsen is challenged in (Paulson
2012).
7
See, eg, (Kelsen 2013: 217).
2 Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood 21
That division between “is” and “ought” creates certain implications for norma-
tive systems like law (and morality and religion). Whenever one asserts a normative
claim that something ought to be done, that claim can only be justified by some
more basic or more general normative premise. Thus, specific normative claims
lead to, or require, or presuppose, ever more general or ever more basic norms, step
by step through a hierarchy8 until one reaches a foundational normative premise.
This structure can be exemplified in a variety of normative systems. For example,
the rules in a religious system will be grounded ultimately in the norm, “do what-
ever the creator God tells you to do”; one’s secular ethical standards may be
grounded ultimately on either the Kantian norm, “so act that the maxim of your will
can be a universal law,” or the Utilitarian norm, “maximize the greatest good of the
greatest number”; and legal norms may be grounded ultimately on the norm, “act
according to what has been authorized by the historically first constitution.” Kelsen
called this foundational norm for legal normative systems “the Basic Norm”
(“Grundnorm”).9
Once one views normative systems as hierarchical structures that are grounded
ultimately on a foundational norm that (by definition—as a foundational norm) is
not subject to any further (direct) proof, the implications are potentially significant,
and potentially skeptical. If the important normative systems of one’s life, like
morality, religion, and law, are perhaps grounded on an ultimate norm that cannot
be proven, and can be accepted or rejected with seemingly equal legitimacy, then
those important guideposts of our life suddenly seem less sturdy. However, these
implications must be left to others to discuss, or for other occasions.10
In Kelsen’s “science” of (legal) norms,11 every “ought” claim implies the (pre-
supposition of the) foundational norm of that normative system—the Basic Norm.
8
This is the Stufenbaulehre that Kelsen adopted from Adolf Julius Merkl. See (Kelsen 1992: § 28,
at 57), (Jakab 2007), (Paulson 2013b).
9
There is a common confusion in understanding both Kelsen’s “Basic Norm” and H. L. A. Hart’s
analogous concept, the “rule of recognition” (Hart 2012: 94–95, 100–110). While there is an
understandable temptation to equate these fundamental norms with foundational texts of a legal
system (like the United States Constitution), this equation is at best imprecise. First, as Kelsen
points out, the current foundational text may have been created under the authority of a prior foun-
dational text of the same legal system, so the Basic Norm should refer to the historically first
foundational text. Second, there remain questions of how to interpret the provisions of the founda-
tional text, and to determine what priority it has in that legal system in relation to other national
and international legal norms. Third, at least with the case of Kelsen’s Basic Norm, the norm is an
instruction to act in accordance with a particular legal text, a prescription that is in principle sepa-
rate from the legal text itself.
10
There are, of course, numerous responses in the philosophical and jurisprudential literature to
this potential skeptical challenge.
11
Kelsen refers more commonly to “the science of law” (or “legal science”)—“Rechtswissenschaft.”
The reference to “science” in Kelsen’s work, and in German generally, means objective academic
inquiry, without necessarily implying all the extra baggage that the term “science” carries in
English (such that one might comfortably refer to literary theory in German as a “science,” while
it would be an unlikely, and certainly controversial, description in English) (Paulson 1992b:
127–129).
22 B.H. Bix
The same point can be seen in Kelsen’s discussions of the “objective” and “subjec-
tive” meanings of lawmaking acts: “For the pure theory strongly emphasises that the
statement that the subjective meaning of the law-creating act is also its objective
meaning—the statement, that is, that law has objective validity—is only a possible
interpretation of that act, not a necessary one” (Kelsen 2013: 218–219 (emphasis
added)).16 And in the systematic aspect of legal interpretation: “The Pure Theory
aims simply to raise to the level of consciousness what all jurists are doing (for the
12
See also (Kelsen 1949: 116–117): “The basic norm is the answer to the question: how—and that
means under what condition—are all these juristic statements concerning legal norms, legal duties,
and so on, possible?”
13
I recognize that there may be other passages in Kelsen’s text that support a different reading. For
a good overview of the different tenable readings of Kelsen’s writings on the Basic Norm, see
(Paulson 2012).
14
In a later edition of the same text, he clarifies that an anarchist who was also a law professor
“could describe positive law as a system of valid norms, without having to approve of this law”
(Kelsen 1967: 218 n. 82). This idea corresponds with Joseph Raz’s idea of a detached normative
statement, or statements from a legal point of view (Raz 2009: 156–157), and is fully consistent
with the analysis offered in this article.
15
Kelesen writes:
The problem that leads to the theory of the basic norm…is how to distinguish a legal command
which is considered to be objectively valid, such as the command of a revenue officer to pay a
certain sum of money, from a command which has the same subjective meaning but is not
considered to be objectively valid, such as the command of a gangster (Kelsen 1965: 1144).
16
Later in the same passage, Kelsen adds, helpfully: “The concept of normative validity is, rather,
an interpretation; it is an interpretation made possible only by the presupposition of a basic norm,”
2 Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood 23
and that such an interpretation is well-grounded “if one presupposes the…basic norm.” (Kelsen
2013: 219 (emphasis in original)).
17
The omitted text states: “[they] reject natural law as the basis of validity of positive law.…”
(Kelsen 1992: §29, at 58). And once more: “This presupposition [of the Basic Norm] is possible
but not necessary.…Thus the Pure Theory of Law, by ascertaining the basic norm as the logical
condition under which a coercive order may be interpreted as valid positive law, furnishes only a
conditional, not a categorical, foundation of the validity of positive law” (Kelsen 1960b: 276).
18
For Hart, “accepting” is accepting the legal system as giving reasons for action. As Michael
Steven Green pointed out to me, it is probably too strong to see the normative reading of official
action within Kelsen as similarly involving any view that the law gives reasons for action.
24 B.H. Bix
legal officials in a normative way), even if that lawyer or scholar saw the actions of
legal officials only in a non-normative way, as mere acts of power.19
As Kelsen sometimes states, and at other times implies, that seeing the actions of
officials as (legally) normative is a matter of choice, it may be useful to look at other
writers who have written similarly about the normativity of law. In a recent work,
John Gardner has observed that law is voluntary in a way that morality is not.
Gardner argued that morality’s claim upon all of us, as human beings, is “inescap-
able” (Gardner 2012: 150).20 According to Gardner, one cannot reasonably ask
whether one should follow the dictates of morality.21 But one can reasonably ask
that question of law (Gardner 2012: 160–176).22 However, it may be that the refer-
ence to “inescapability” is too vague to be useful here. One might argue that the
sanctions pervasively and importantly present in all (or almost all) legal systems
(past and present)23 make law, in a sense, “inescapable.”24 One might choose not to
perceive the actions of legal officials as creating valid norms, but law (at least in
systems that are generally efficacious) is not something that a practically reasonable
person could ignore, the way that she could ignore (say) fashion, etiquette, or chess.
Still, while one may be unable to “escape” or ignore the coercive power of the State,
one can choose not to think of the State’s actions in a normative way.
Under the reading offered here, I do not think that Kelsen would declare morality
to be “inescapable,” for morality (or one’s moral system) would be, under this anal-
ysis, just one more normative system that one could choose or not choose, internal-
ize or not internalize, assert or not assert. And that conforms, in a way, with a
modern view of morality; around us there are a wide variety of (secular and religion-
based) moral systems being advocated, practiced, or assumed—with, for example,
a broad range of variations on consequentialism, deontological ethics, and virtue
ethics (and mix-and-match combinations of the three), just among the secular
approaches to morality, even without noting the approaches to morality that are
more theologically based. People choose one among the alternatives, and may later
change to another (and then another, etc.).
19
When one says that one can choose to view the (legal) actions of officials normatively or not, it
is important to note that this does not mean that this “choice” is always or necessarily a conscious
choice. The reference to “choice” indicates primarily that there is an option; one could do (or
think) otherwise.
20
Foot also refers to morality’s purported “inescapability” in the course of her discussion question-
ing the view of morality as a categorical imperative (as opposed to hypothetical imperative) (Foot
1978: 160–164); cf. (Raz 1999: 94–105), on whether reasons are optional.
21
Gardner here reflects the conventional position, though, of course, thinkers ranging from Philippa
Foot to Friedrich Nietzsche have raised exactly the question Gardner’s quotation implies cannot or
should not be raised: whether one should follow the dictates of morality. See (Foot 1978: 157–173)
(on whether morality is merely a “hypothetical imperative”), (Foot 1978: 181–188) (questioning
whether moral considerations are “overriding”), (Nietzsche 1998).
22
Robert Alexy points out similarly that “[o]ne can of course refuse … to participate in the (utterly
real) game of law.” (Alexy 2002: 109).
23
Cf. (Schauer 2010).
24
I am indebted to Frederick Schauer for this suggestion.
2 Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood 25
25
Cf. (Marmor 2007: 153–181), comparing law and chess.
26
See (Kant 1998). The particular way of phrasing the matter in the text above (eg, the reference to
“sense data”) is likely not a way most Kantians would choose, but it should suffice for the rough
summary needed here.
26 B.H. Bix
out (Paulson 2012, 2013a), is that transcendental arguments depend on there being
only one available explanation for the matter being examined (in Kant’s case, the
unity of experience; in Kelsen’s case, the normativity of law), and, arguably, Kelsen
did not come close to proving that his approach was the only available explanation.
Paulson argued, correctly in my opinion, that Kelsen’s analysis was far too quick to
dismiss natural law approaches and was not convincing in its effort to show that
there was no possible explanations beyond the limited number of alternatives he
considered (Paulson 2012, 2013a).
However, the approach discussed in this work does not require the full machin-
ery of a (neo-)Kantian transcendental deduction: it needs only the basic and gener-
ally accepted Humean division of “is” and “ought,” combined with a comparably
conventional idea that law is a normative system (with the emphasis both on “nor-
mative” and on “system”). Where one asserts the validity of any lower-level norm
in a legal system,27 one implicitly asserts or presupposes the validity of the founda-
tional norm of the system.
In an earlier work, Paulson expressed concerns about the sort of reading of
Kelsen’s work I am offering here (Paulson 2012). His primary worry was that this
reading leaves the basic norm in particular, and Kelsen’s pure theory of law in gen-
eral, doing little work, and not the important task that Kelsen seemed to set for
himself.28 Kelsen seems to offer the Basic Norm (and its presupposition) as the key
to explaining the objective meaning of norms generally, not just for those who hap-
pen to choose to interpret official actions in a normative way. However, I disagree
that my proposed reading of Kelsen leaves Kelsen’s theory unimportant, and the
reading has the distinct benefit of being more defensible than more ambitious read-
ings of Kelsen’s aims.29 Kelsen’s pure theory, as I read it, is offering important
insights about the logic of norms, about what follows from the fact that someone
perceives the actions of officials normatively, and it offers related insights regarding
the connections (or lack thereof) between law and morality, and regarding whether
(or not) one has an obligation to accept or presuppose the Basic Norm of one’s legal
system.
2.4 Conclusion
The ignorance and avoidance of Hans Kelsen’s approach to law is likely attributable
to the usual suspects: foreign-language texts badly served by translators, and a style
of writing and thinking too different from the empirical and pragmatic approach that
27
A comparable point could be made, as earlier mentioned, for a moral or theological normative
system, or any other kind of normative system.
28
My reading of Kelsen is very close to J. W. Harris in (Harris 1996), though Harris—like
Paulson—expressed concern that this Kelsenian view of legal normativity might leave the theory
with limited practical significance.
29
As Paulson shows, indirectly, by his sharp critique of other readings (Paulson 2012).
2 Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood 27
dominates Anglo-American thinking (and not just legal thinking). Add to this the
fact that Kelsen is a writer from a century ago, rather than being the “new, new
thing”—he is at a sharp competitive disadvantage to the fashionable theorists, and
legal theorists, of today.
Of course, that relatively few understand, or try to understand Kelsen, does not
mean that his works are not worth studying. Kelsen’s writings wrestle with central
problems about the nature of law that remain equally important and unsolved today,
including the nature of legal normativity. In the second part of this work, I suggested
a minimalist reading of Kelsen’s view of legal normativity—one that is concededly
controversial, both on exegetical grounds (though it has substantial textual support)
and on its own merits, but one that I assert is both faithful to Kelsen’s argument and
defensible on its terms.
References
Adams, David M. 2013. Philosophical problems in the law, 5th ed. Independence, KY: Cengage
Wadsworth.
Alexy, Robert. 2002. The Argument from Injustice. Trans. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Arthur, John, and William H. Shaw. 2010. Readings in the philosophy of law, 5th ed. Upper Saddle
River, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Barzun, Jacques. 2000. From dawn to decadence: 500 years of western cultural life, 1500 to the
present. New York: HarperCollins.
Bix, Brian H. 2015. Rules and normativity in law. In Problems of normativity, rules and rule fol-
lowing, ed. Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki, Krzysztof Płeszka, Michał Arszkiewicz, and Paweł
Banas, 125–146. Dordrecht: Springer.
Coleman, Jules. 2001. The practice of principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Coleman, Jules, and Scott Shapiro (eds.). 2002. The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence & philoso-
phy of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Feinberg, Joel, Jules Coleman, and Christopher Kutz. 2014. Philosophy of law, 9th ed.
Independence, KY: Cengage Wadsworth.
Finnis, John. 2002. Natural law: The classical tradition. In The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence
& philosophy of law, ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 1–60. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Foot, Philippa. 1978. Virtues and vices. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Gardner, John. 2012. Law as a leap of faith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Green, Leslie. 2003. Legal positivism. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta.
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/. Accessed 24 Nov 2014.
Harris, J.W. 1977. Kelsen’s concept of authority. Cambridge Law Journal 36: 353–363.
Harris, J.W. 1986. Kelsen and normative consistency. In Essays on Kelsen, ed. R. Tur and
W. Twining, 201–228. Oxford: Clarendon.
Harris, J.W. 1996. Kelsen’s pallid normativity. Ratio Juris 9: 94–117.
28 B.H. Bix
Hart, H.L.A. 2012. The concept of law, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Himma, Kenneth Einar. 2002. Inclusive legal positivism. In The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence
& philosophy of law, ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 125–165. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Hume, David. 1978. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon.
Jakab, András. 2007. Problems of the stufenbaulehre: Kelsen’s failure to derive the validity of a
norm from another norm. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 20: 35–67.
Kant, Immanuel. 1998. In Critique of pure reason, ed. P. Guyer and A. Woods. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1949. General theory of law & state. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press.
(Transaction Publisher Reprint, 2006).
Kelsen, Hans. 1960a. Reine rechtslehre, 2nd ed. Vienna: Deuticke.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960b. What is the pure theory of law? Tulane Law Review 34: 269–276.
Kelsen, Hans. 1965. Professor Stone and the pure theory of law. Stanford Law Review 17:
1128–1157.
Kelsen, Hans. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. M. Knight. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1992. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. B.L. Paulson and
S.L. Paulson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 2013. A ‘realistic’ theory of law and the pure theory of law: Remarks on Alf Ross’s
on law and justice. In Kelsen revisited: New essays on the pure theory of law, ed. Luís Duarte
d’Almeida, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, 195–221. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Marmor, Andrei. 2002. Exclusive legal positivism. In The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence &
philosophy of law, ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 104–124. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Marmor, Andrei. 2007. Law in the age of pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Marmor, Andrei. 2011. The conventional foundations of law. In New essays on the normativity of
law, ed. Stefano Bertea and George Pavlakos, 143–157. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Morawetz, Thomas. 1999. Law as experience: Theory and the internal aspect of law. SMU Law
Review 52: 27–66.
Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Jules L. Coleman. 1990. Philosophy of law, rev. ed. Boulder, Colorado:
Westview Press.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1998. On the Genealogy of Morality. Trans. M. Clark and A.J. Swensen.
Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.
Paulson, Stanley L. 1992a. The neo-Kantian dimension of Kelsen’s pure theory of law. Oxford
Journal of Legal Studies 12: 311–332.
Paulson, Stanley L. 1992b. Supplementary notes. In Introduction to the problems of legal theory,
ed. Hans Kelsen, Bonnie Litschewski Paulson, and Stanley L. Paulson, 127–137. Oxford:
Clarendon.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2006. J. W. Harris’s Kelsen. In Properties of law: Essays in honour of Jim
Harris, ed. Timothy Endicott, Joshua Getzler, and Edwin Peel, 3–21. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2012. A ‘justified normativity’ thesis in Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law?:
Rejoinders to Robert Alexy and Joseph Raz. In Institutionalized reason: The jurisprudence of
Robert Alexy, ed. Matthias Klatt, 61–111. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2013a. A great puzzle: Kelsen’s basic norm. In Kelsen revisited: New essays
on the pure theory of law, ed. Luís Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, 43–61.
Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2013b. How Merkl’s stufenbaulehre informs Kelsen’s concept of law. Revus
21: 29–45.
2 Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood 29
Priel, Dan. 2013. Is there one right answer to the question of the nature of law? In Philosophical
foundations of the nature of law, ed. Wil Waluchow and Stefan Sciaraffa, 322–340. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Raz, Joseph. 1976. Kelsen’s general theory of norms. Philosophia 6: 495–504.
Raz, Joseph. 1980. The concept of a legal system, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon.
Raz, Joseph. 1986. The purity of the pure theory. In Essays on Kelsen, ed. Richard Tur and William
Twining, 80–97. Oxford: Clarendon.
Raz, Joseph. 1990. Practical reason and norms. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Raz, Joseph. 1999. Engaging reason: On the theory of value and action. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Raz, Joseph. 2009. The authority of law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schauer, Frederick. 2010. Was Austin right after all?: On the role of sanctions in a theory of law.
Ratio Juris 23: 1–21.
Shapiro, Scott J. 2011. Legality. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Chapter 3
Marmor’s Kelsen
Michael S. Green
3.1 Introduction
1
Alfred Verdross was another member, with Kelsen, of the “Vienna School” of legal theory. Fritz
Sander, a former student of Kelsen’s, became one his most prominent critics.
2
And to the extent that Kelsen offered insights that can be appreciated without accepting a pure
theory of law, they assume that the same insights can be found, more clearly presented, in
H.L.A. Hart’s writings (Murphy and Coleman 1990: 27).
M.S. Green (*)
Dudley W. Woodbridge Professor of Law, College of William and Mary,
8795, Williamsburg, VA 23187, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
by and large employ and abide by the system’s norms. And that means that law
depends upon social facts. There would be no legal system in the absence of an
actual human community that makes the system efficacious. Why bother spending
time on someone who, while purporting to offer a pure theory of law, unwittingly
offered an impure theory?
I begin by describing a genuinely pure theory of law and why it appears so
implausible to philosophers of law in this country. Next I offer Andrei Marmor’s
reading of Kelsen in the first chapter of his book, Philosophy of Law (Marmor
2011), as a good example of the second reading of Kelsen, in which he fails to offer
a pure theory. I then argue that Marmor misinterprets Kelsen in three ways, each of
which makes him look as if he thought the law fundamentally depends upon social
facts. Kelsen’s theory of law, I conclude, really is pure. But with that conclusion, we
return to the first response to Kelsen. What his theory of law gains in consistency it
loses in plausibility. As a first step in responding to these doubts, I end by briefly
offering evidence in favor of a pure theory of law. There are some legal judgments,
I argue, that cannot be made sense of unless the law is independent of all social
facts.
American philosophers of law believe that the existence and content of the law fun-
damentally depend upon social facts about a community. This dependence is some-
thing about which both sides of the most prominent debate in the philosophy of law
in the United States agree. On one side there are positivists, who believe that the
existence and content of the law are ultimately determined solely by social facts
about a community.3 On the other side there are those, whom we can call natural
lawyers, who believe that the existence and content of the law are ultimately deter-
mined by a combination of social facts about a community and evaluative facts
(Greenberg 2004: 157–58). For a positivist, if evaluative facts somehow disappeared
(say God extinguished them), law could still exist.4 For a natural lawyer, law would
disappear with the evaluative facts. But both positivists and natural lawyers agree
that law is fundamentally constituted by social facts about a community to some
extent. If human beings disappeared, there would be no law.
By contrast, under a pure theory law would exist even if there were no human
beings. An analogy with morality is helpful here. Some philosophers hold a pure
3
I describe positivists as believing that law is ultimately determined solely by social facts, because
inclusive legal positivists concede that social facts can make evaluative facts relevant to law’s
existence and content. For exclusive legal positivists, by contrast, law always depends solely on
social facts.
4
For an inclusive legal positivist, if evaluative facts disappeared, law that depends upon such facts
could not exist (or its existence would be indeterminate). But there could still be law, for it is not
necessary that law depends upon evaluative facts.
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 33
theory of morality, in the sense that morality is independent of human beings’ beliefs
and attitudes.5 This position is supported in part by our judgments that murder is
morally impermissible no matter what our views about murder happen to be.6
Murder would be morally impermissible even if we thought it was morally permis-
sible, or obligatory. In making such judgments, we are arguably committed to mur-
der’s being morally impermissible independent of human beings. Murder would be
morally impermissible even if human beings had never existed.
Of course, under a pure theory of law, law is independent of morality too. But,
like a pure theorist of morality, a pure theorist of law insists that law would exist in
the absence of human beings. And that is not an idea that American philosophers of
law think has any chance of success.
Notice that one cannot argue against a pure theory of law simply by pointing to
social facts (such as people in a legislative chamber raising their hands) that make a
difference to legal facts. The pure theorist can accept that social facts trigger legal
norms, by satisfying conditions for the norms’ applicability. If there is a legal norm
of the form If social fact X obtains then one legally ought to Y, the existence of
social fact X will make a difference to legal facts. Without X, it would not be a legal
fact that one ought to Y. But, the pure theorist can argue, that does not mean that the
legal norm that was triggered itself depends upon social facts.
Here too an analogy with morality is appropriate. Having promised to take you
to the zoo, I arguably have a moral obligation (if only a pro tanto obligation) to take
you to the zoo—an obligation that I would not have had in the absence of my prom-
ise. Recognizing that social facts are relevant to moral facts in this way is compati-
ble with insisting that the fundamental moral norms in the light of which social facts
are morally relevant do not themselves depend upon social facts. The social fact that
I promised to take you to the zoo made a difference to moral facts because of a
moral obligation to keep one’s promises—an obligation that existed before there
were human beings.
But my guess is that philosophers of law in this country wouldn’t think that the
distinction between social facts triggering and their constituting legal norms makes
a pure theory of law any more plausible. It is true that we should dissociate the
social fact that people in a legislative chamber raised their hands from the law they
enacted. The legislators’ raising their hands was a social fact that triggered a law,
namely a constitutional provision authorizing the legislators to pass statutes. But as
one goes back in the history of a legal system, at some point social facts must be
understood as constituting laws, for there will be no preexisting law in place to be
triggered.
5
An example here is the “robust realist” and non-naturalist David Enoch, who believes that “there
is no metaphysically possible world where the basic norms [of morality] are different.” (Enoch
2011: 146). It follows that the basic norms of morality were in place when dinosaurs roamed the
earth.
6
An example is Enoch’s argument that robust realism about morality is supported by our willing-
ness to “stand our ground” in cases of moral conflict, that is, to not arrive at an “impartial” resolu-
tion that seeks to accommodate the disputants’ actual preferences (Enoch 2011: 23–24).
34 M.S. Green
Assume, for example, that the validity of the United States Constitution is justi-
fied on the basis of Article VII, which was created by the Constitutional Convention
and which authorized nine of the thirteen original states, by ratifying the Constitution,
to make it law for the ratifying states.7 One cannot justify Article VII’s status as law
by other enacted laws. No enacted law authorized the Constitutional Convention to
create a new method of constitutional ratification. Indeed, Article VII was contrary
to the amendment procedures in the preceding Articles of Confederation, which
required consent by the Congress of the Confederation and the legislatures of all the
states (Ackerman and Katyal 1995). In that sense, Article VII was revolutionary.
If the Convention’s actions triggered preexisting law, there would have to be
some unenacted law authorizing the Convention to create a new method for ratify-
ing a constitution. And, to retain a pure theory, this authorizing law would have to
be independent of all social facts. It would have to be no less existent when dino-
saurs roamed the earth than it was in 1787. Just as it was a moral fact in the Jurassic
Era that promises ought to be kept, so it would have to be a legal fact in the Jurassic
Era that the Constitutional Convention had the power to create a method of consti-
tutional ratification.8
But to American philosophers of law, that sounds crazy. It is much more plausi-
ble to understand the validity of Article VII as constituted by or dependent on social
facts about American legal practices. For example, one can understand Article VII
to be valid law because it is actually used by American officials for assessing the
validity of the United States Constitution. Rather than concluding that a law autho-
rizing the Constitutional Convention existed in the Jurassic Era, we can understand
the entire American legal system as coming into being only in the late eighteenth
century.
Another problem with a pure theory of law is the existence of multiple legal
systems. Many legal systems (American, French, Uzbek) currently exist. Many
legal systems (Soviet, Prussian, Ancient Roman) have existed in the past. And many
legal systems will undoubtedly come into being in the future. This plurality of legal
systems suggests that the law of each system must be constituted by social facts
about a community. Ancient Roman law must depend upon social facts about the
Ancient Romans, because if there had been no Ancient Romans, there would have
been no Ancient Roman law.
The pure theorist of law must insist that the multiplicity of independent legal
systems is somehow illusory. He need not deny, of course, that there is a sociologi-
cal concept of a legal system (call it a legal systemsoc) under which a legal system is
reducible to a particular community’s beliefs and attitudes. When one employs that
7
This would mean treating Article VII as, in some sense, independent of the rest of the Constitution.
It preceded the Constitution by providing the method for its enactment.
8
Granted, the positivist can accept that it was a conceptual truth even in the Jurassic Era that if the
social facts that constitute the American legal system are in place, Article VII will be law. But he
would deny that any legal facts existed in the Jurassic Era, in particular, that anyone was legally
authorized to create Article VII. For the positivist, the existence of a legal authorization would
require an actual human community.
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 35
concept, there are as many legal systemsocs as there are relevant communities.
Nevertheless, he will argue, when one speaks about what is valid law, as opposed to
what people in a community think is valid law, one is committed to a timeless uni-
tary legal system.
Again an analogy with morality is appropriate here. The pure theorist of morality
can admit that there is a sociological concept of a moral system (a moral systemsoc)
under which a moral systemsoc is reducible to a particular community’s beliefs and
attitudes. A plurality of moral systemsocs exists. As one makes one’s way around the
world or considers the course of history, one encounters different moral systemsocs.
There is, for example, the moral systemsoc of pre-modern Japan, in which ritual
suicide is condoned, and the moral systemsoc of contemporary Christians, in which
it is not. Nevertheless, a pure theorist of morality will argue that when one thinks
about what morality actually requires—rather than what various communities think
it requires—one conceives of the fundamental moral norms as unchanging and
independent of social facts.
But if there is only one timeless legal system, how can one make sense of the fact
that had France never existed, not only would no one think that French law applies
to Frenchmen in France, there would have been no French law that actually applies
to them? Valid French law depends upon the existence of the French legal systemsoc.
Here too the pure theorist will have to claim that social facts have triggered preexist-
ing legal norms. The existence of the French legal systemsoc is relevant to legal facts
about Frenchmen in France only in the light of timeless legal norms that make it
relevant.
Once more, an analogy with morality is helpful. To say that a unitary and
unchanging moral system exists independently of any moral systemsoc, does not
mean that the existence of a moral systemsoc cannot be relevant to moral facts. For
example, there might be moral principles of tolerance, according to which one must
respect the moral systemsoc of the person affected by one’s actions. But the pure
theorist of morality will insist that these principles of tolerance are themselves bind-
ing independently of any moral systemsoc. The relativity of moral obligation to a
moral systemsoc is not itself relative to a moral systemsoc.
The pure theorist of law can argue, analogously, that the existence of a legal
systemsoc is relevant to legal facts only in the light of legal norms that make it rele-
vant—legal norms that are independent of any legal systemsoc. The existence of the
French, American, or Ancient Roman legal systemsoc simply triggers the timeless
legal norms of a unitary legal system.
The pure theorist’s strategy is, in essence, the following: For each social fact that
makes a difference to legal facts, the pure theorist will explain the social fact’s rel-
evance in terms of its triggering legal norms that do not depend upon social facts
(von Bernstorff 2010: 91–92). Notice that, by using this strategy, the pure theorist
can accept that legal facts supervene upon social facts, in the sense that possible
worlds cannot differ from one another with respect to their legal facts without also
differing with respect to social facts. The pure theorist can explain such superve-
nience by arguing that any difference in legal facts between possible worlds must be
36 M.S. Green
the result of the way that different social facts in those worlds triggered fundamental
legal norms—norms that cannot themselves differ between possible worlds.9
But to Americans, the notion that there are eternal legal norms waiting to be trig-
gered by the existence of human communities is absurd. That is why I do not think
it is fair to chalk up the prevailing attitude toward Kelsen among American philoso-
phers of law to ignorance about his views. Americans have come to the philosophi-
cal conclusion that his theory is a non-starter.
To a large extent, Kelsen himself is to blame here, for in his major writings he
fails to focus sufficiently on why the law is independent of social facts. Pure theo-
rists of morality take great pains to emphasize moral judgments that are arguably
inexplicable if morality is constituted by social facts about human beings (Enoch
2011: 16–49). For example, they point to our judgment that murder would be imper-
missible even if every human being believed it to be permissible. This suggests that
the impermissibility of murder is independent of human beings and their beliefs and
attitudes.
The same strategy is pursued by natural lawyers, who emphasize judgments
about the law that arguably cannot be made sense of if law is reducible solely to
social facts about a community. Ronald Dworkin’s preferred examples were theo-
retical disagreements, in which participants in a legal system consider a legal ques-
tion to have a determinate answer, even though they disagree about the criteria for
law upon which the answer would be based. To do justice to such disagreements,
Dworkin argued, we cannot understand the law as determined solely by the social
facts to which positivists seek to reduce it, in particular, agreement among partici-
pants in a jurisdiction’s legal practices. We must instead understand the existence
and content of the law as determined conjointly by social facts about a community’s
legal practices and evaluative facts (Dworkin 1986: 66, 2006: 144).
What would catch the attention of American philosophers of law is if Kelsen had
devoted his major works to focusing on legal judgments that cannot be made sense
of except through a pure theory of law, that is, judgments in which certain legal facts
are understood as obtaining independently of all social facts. To be sure, Kelsen did,
at times, attempt to identify such judgments in his writings (Kelsen 1922). But,
particularly in his major works, he generally presumed that a theory of law should
be pure instead of arguing for this conclusion. His main goal was to explore the
consequences of a pure theory, not to convince the skeptic that the law is fundamen-
tally independent of social facts.
I am not sure why Kelsen adopted this approach. Perhaps the general resistance
to psychologism and naturalistic reductionism in Viennese philosophical circles at
the time he formulated his theory made sustained arguments for the fundamen-
tal independence of law from social facts appear unnecessary. But whatever the
reason, the absence of such arguments is a big problem for Americans.
9
The pure theorist of law is analogous to a robust moral realist like Enoch, who accepts that moral
facts supervene upon natural facts, but who argues that this supervenience relation follows from
moral principles that do not themselves depend upon natural facts (Enoch 2011: 140–50).
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 37
To repeat, I think American philosophers of law with only a passing familiarity with
Kelsen are unsympathetic, not out of ignorance, but because they see no reason to
adopt a theory in which law is fundamentally independent of social facts. The notion
that there would be legal facts in the absence of any human beings has no resonance
for them, and Kelsen’s writings do not seem to address their doubts.
In this context, let us now consider Andrei Marmor’s reading of Kelsen in the
first chapter of his book Philosophy of Law (Marmor 2011).10 Marmor’s reading is
promising, for he takes Kelsen’s antireductionism seriously. An overarching theme
of Marmor’s book is that a great deal in the philosophy of law that purports to be
about the proper analysis of the content of the concept of law (that is, the identifica-
tion of the necessary and sufficient criteria for law wherever it might occur) really
concerns reductionism, in particular, the extent to which the law can be reduced to
social facts. The two questions are importantly different. Just as a reduction of con-
sciousness to brain states, even if successful, may not be an accurate account of the
concept of consciousness, so a reduction of law to social facts, even if successful,
may not be an accurate account of the concept of law.
In keeping with this reductionist theme, Marmor’s book begins with Kelsen,
whom he rightly describes as attempting to offer an antireductionist theory of law
(Marmor 2011: 12), that is, a theory in which the law is reducible neither to morality
nor to social facts (Marmor 2011: 13–14). To be sure, social facts are relevant to law
for Kelsen. As Marmor puts it, the social fact that a majority of the members of a
group of people that calls itself “the California state legislature” raised their hands
can make a difference to what, legally, is the case within the borders of the state
(Marmor 2011: 15). But that social fact is not itself law. Rather, it has legal conse-
quences in the light of law—in particular, the California Constitution, which autho-
rizes the California legislature to make law. By the same token, the social facts to
which one might point as constituting the ratification of the California Constitution
are also not themselves law. They too have legal consequences only in the light of a
higher authorizing law.
Marmor describes this law as the United States Constitution (Marmor 2011:
16). Although this is clearly wrong,11 the important point is that either there is a
positive legal norm authorizing the creators of the California Constitution or
there is not. And even if there is, the chain of positive authorizations must end
somewhere. Eventually one will reach a positive authorization that was created
by those who were not themselves authorized by positive law. Kelsen speaks of
10
I will also occasionally refer to his article on the pure theory of law in the Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Marmor 2010), which overlaps substantially with his book.
11
The United States Constitution contains no provision authorizing the creation of state law. It
presupposes state law’s existence. It does contain a provision (Art. IV, § 3) for the creation of new
states, but it is not clear that this should be understood as the authorization of state law. And even
if it is so understood, this authorization could not apply to the law of the thirteen original states.
38 M.S. Green
12
The first constitution need not be written. Kelsen argued, for example, that the first constitution
of international law is that the custom of states creates valid law. Furthermore, this constitution was
itself created through custom (Kelsen 1960a: 226, 323).
13
Marmor argues that, for Kelsen, someone treating the law as valid thereby also treats the law as
providing a practical reason for action, that is, “a justified demand on practical deliberation”
(Marmor 2011: 25). According to Marmor, Kelsen rejects sociological accounts of the law because
of their inability to explain the reason-giving character of legal norms. Later in the chapter, Marmor
argues that Kelsen should have distinguished between the question of the validity of law and its
normativity (in the sense of its practical reason-giving character). In fact, it is unclear whether
Kelsen believed that someone who recognizes a legal norm as valid thereby takes himself to have
a reason for action in the sense relevant for practical deliberation (Paulson 2012; Delacroix 2004;
Wilson 1982).
14
Although Kelsen described his philosophy of law as positivist (Kelsen 1960a: 217), he is not a
positivist in the sense that I define it, for he does not think law is ultimately reducible solely to
social facts about a community.
15
See also Kelsen 1934, 60 (“[A] normative system to which reality no longer corresponds to a
certain degree will necessarily lose its validity. The validity of a legal system…depends in a certain
way…on the efficacy of the system.”).
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 39
explicitly admits that efficacy is a condition of the validity of the basic norm: A basic
norm is legally valid if and only if it is actually followed in a given population”
(Marmor 2011: 20).16 The basic norm validating the first constitution is not itself
valid unless there are people around actually following and applying the first consti-
tution and the laws made pursuant to it. Thus, Marmor argues, Kelsen was ultimately
forced into a sociological approach to law, in which the law is fundamentally based
upon social facts about a community.
Marmor notes in passing that Kelsen “toyed with the idea that perhaps changes
in the basic norms of municipal [that is, national] legal systems legally derive from
the basic norm of public international law” (Marmor 2011: 23). If this is true, there
would be only one basic norm from which the valid laws of all national legal sys-
tems (past, present, and future) are derived. The fact that efficacy is considered a
condition for the validity of national legal systems would be compatible with a pure
theory of law. The national legal systems would be understood as subsystems of the
international legal system, which would not itself depend upon efficacy for its
existence.
But Marmor quickly dismisses Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law. First of all,
he argues that Kelsen presented the doctrine with “much more hesitation” by the
time he wrote the second edition of the Pure Theory, in 1960 (Marmor 2011: 23
n.18). This hesitation, he argues, is understandable: “[A]fter all, the idea that all
municipal legal systems derive their legal validity from international law would
strike most jurists and legal historians as rather fanciful and anachronistic” (Marmor
2011: 23 n.18). But more fundamentally, he argues, the doctrine of the unity of law
does not make a pure theory of law any more plausible.
The reason is that “it is very difficult, if not impossible, to maintain both a pro-
found relativist and an antireductionist position with respect to a given normative
domain” (Marmor 2011: 23):
If you hold the view that the validity of a type of norm is entirely relative to a certain van-
tage point—in other words, if what is involved here is only the actual conduct, beliefs/pre-
suppositions, and attitudes of people—it becomes very difficult to detach the explanation of
that normativity from the facts that constitute the relevant point of view (the facts about
people’s actions, beliefs, attitudes, and such) (Marmor 2011: 23).
Even if Kelsen thought all valid laws are part of a unitary legal system, he con-
sidered the laws of this system to be valid only relative to the vantage point in which
a basic norm is presupposed. As a result, the validity of law is still due to social facts
(namely the facts standing behind the vantage point). What is more, because Kelsen
thought that the basic norm of the unitary legal system would not be presupposed
unless it was efficacious, efficacy remains a condition for the validity of law.
16
Marmor is not as careful as he could be in describing what efficacy is for Kelsen. The question is
not merely whether those subject to the mandatory norms of the legal system generally comply
with them but also whether relevant officials apply the norms of the system (Navarro 2013: 79
n.12). In Marmor’s defense, he might understand such application as officials “following” the
norms, however.
40 M.S. Green
Marmor concedes that not all relativism in a particular normative domain leads
to reductionism. Morality can sometimes be understood as relative in an antireduc-
tionist way: “[S]ome moral reasons for action are relative to some contingent condi-
tions (for example, reasons to care about friendship are contingent upon our
psychological makeup and social realities)” (Marmor 2011: 24). But in such cases
relativity can be explained in terms of “elements of the theory that are not relative
to contingent facts” (Marmor 2011: 24). As we have seen, the fact that my moral
obligation to take you to the zoo is relative to my act of promising can be explained
in terms of an obligation to keep one’s promises that is not relative to social facts.
But Kelsen, Marmor argues, is a relativist “all the way down” (Marmor 2011: 24).
For this reason, he is compelled to be a reductionist. “If all the elements of a norma-
tive explanation are relative to some constitutive facts, then those facts provide you
with all the explanation you need. In other words, a position that is relativist all the
way down is, ipso facto, reductionist as well” (Marmor 2011: 24).
Things would be different, Marmor acknowledges, if the adoption of a basic
norm were rationally inescapable. But choosing a basic norm is “not something that
is dictated by Reason” (Marmor 2011: 22). We are free to presuppose no basic
norm. For example, we can conceive of political events in a country alegally, that is,
as “mere power relations” (Marmor 2011: 22).17 This is why, Marmor argues, Kelsen
cannot be understood as offering a Kantian transcendental argument, which would
require Kelsen to insist that the basic norm is “something like a necessary feature or
category of human cognition” (Marmor 2011: 21).
If Marmor is right, American philosophers of law who are unfamiliar with the
details of Kelsen’s works have even less reason to be interested in him than they
thought. The problem is not merely that Kelsen’s pure theory of law is implausible.
It doesn’t even manage to be pure. Why take a pure theory of law seriously when
even its most earnest advocate in the end could not maintain it consistently?
In what follows, I argue that Marmor fundamentally misreads Kelsen’s legal
theory in three (interconnected) ways. First, he misunderstands Kelsen’s doctrine of
the unity of law. Rather than being an idea that Kelsen “toyed” with, the doctrine
stands at the heart of his legal theory. Second, Marmor misreads how efficacy is
relevant to the adoption of the basic norm of the unitary legal system. The fact that
only an efficacious basic norm is presupposed does not mean that efficacy is a con-
dition for the validity of the basic norm. Kelsen’s statements about the role of effi-
cacy in the adoption of a basic norm are compatible with a pure theory of law. Third,
Marmor misunderstands the Neo-Kantian dimensions of Kelsen’s thought. When
17
Marmor quotes A General Theory of Law and State: “[A]n anarchist, for instance, who denied
the validity of the hypothetical basic norm of positive law…will view its positive regulation of
human relationships…as mere power relations.” (Kelsen 1945: 413). It is worth noting that Kelsen
later explicitly rejected this reading of the anarchist. He concluded that the anarchist, despite
rejecting the law politically, could still presuppose the basic norm and therefore understand it as a
system of valid norms (Kelsen 1960a: 218 n.82). This is a reason to conclude that Kelsen did not
think that someone who treats the law as valid thereby also treats it as providing practical reasons
for action. See note 13 above.
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 41
Let us begin with Marmor’s discussion of Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law. It is
important here to distinguish between three positions. The first is pluralism, under
which multiple legal systems, each with valid laws, are possible (indeed actual)
(Kelsen 1960a: 328). For the pluralist, the American, French, and Uzbek legal sys-
tems all exist independently of one another. Furthermore, the international legal
system can also be understood as existing independently of the various national
legal systems. By contrast, under monism, all valid laws must be seen as part of the
same legal system (Kelsen 1960a: 333).18
There are two versions of monism. Under the international version—which
Kelsen sometimes calls “objectivism” (Kelsen 1945: 386, 1960a: 344)—the unitary
legal system is international. This international legal system assigns to all past,
18
Monism as described here is different from a homonymous term used by international lawyers.
If a nation’s law is monist in this other sense, international law has a direct effect upon the legal
rights and obligations of individuals under national law (Waters 2007; 641). A citizen may, for
example, successfully challenge the validity of a statute on the grounds that it is contrary to a treaty
entered into by the nation. If a nation’s law is dualist, by contrast, such a challenge cannot succeed,
unless there is a particular national law that has given the treaty such an effect. In the absence of
such a law, the statute is binding on the individual, even though the nation might recognize the
treaty’s validity as a matter of international law—for example, by acknowledging that the statute’s
conflict with the treaty makes sanctions against it by other nations legally permissible. Thus, it is
sometimes said that under dualism national and international law form two separate systems, with
international law’s effect confined to the relationship between nations (Henkin 1987: 864).
These positions are not the monism and pluralism described here. Monism, as Kelsen under-
stands it, is compatible with legal phenomena that are described by international lawyers as “dual-
ist.” The fact that a treaty recognized by a nation provides individuals with no grounds to challenge
the validity of a statute simply speaks to the legal relationship between those two types of law. It
does not mean that international law and the domestic laws of each nation are not part of the same
legal system.
Likewise, pluralism is compatible with legal phenomena that are described by international
lawyers as “monist.” Assume that under a nation’s law an individual can invoke a treaty against the
validity of a statute. The pluralist can still insist that the international and the national legal systems
are separate. Facts about the nation’s law, she can argue, are reducible to facts about the national
community, whereas facts about international law are reducible to facts about an international
community (the community of nations or officials of those nations, considered collectively). The
individual arguing that the treaty invalidates the statute is making an argument under national law,
not international law. Social facts about the national community are ultimately the reason that the
statute’s conflict with the treaty makes it invalid. To be sure, the fact that the statute conflicts with
the treaty is a matter of international law, determined by social facts about the international, not the
national, community. But simply because a criterion for the validity of national law refers to inter-
national law does not mean that the national and international legal systems are one.
42 M.S. Green
present and future national legal systems, through the principle of efficacy,19 a cer-
tain sphere of lawmaking authority in space and time (Kelsen 1960a: 214–215).
Under the national version—which he sometimes calls “state subjectivism” (Kelsen
1934: 116, 1945: 386, 1960a: 345)—the unitary legal system is a national order, and
international law is valid by virtue of being recognized by that nation’s law. The
principle of efficacy under international law still validates the laws of other national
legal orders, but the principle is ultimately valid by virtue of the foundational
nation’s law.
We can now consider Marmor’s claim that in the second edition of The Pure
Theory of Law Kelsen presented his doctrine of the unity of law with “much more
hesitation” (Marmor 2011: 23 n.18; see also Marmor 2010). In the passage Marmor
cites (Kelsen 1960a: 214–15), Kelsen does not express any hesitation about monism.
Nor does he “toy” with the idea. He makes it very clear throughout the second edi-
tion that a monistic construction of all valid law is “inevitable” (Kelsen 1960a: 333),
and a dualistic or pluralistic construction is “impossible” (Kelsen 1960a: 335) and
“untenable” (Kelsen 1960a: 328). To the extent that American, Uzbek, and Ancient
Roman law are all considered valid within their own temporal and spatial spheres,
they must be seen as part of a single legal system. This is the very same position that
can be found in Kelsen’s earlier works (Kelsen 1934: 111–114, 1945: 363–364,
373).
What Kelsen expresses in the passage is agnosticism concerning the choice
between the international and national versions of monism, for either approach
brings all valid law into the same legal order. Incidentally, the same agnosticism is
present in Kelsen’s earlier writings, going back at least to 1920 (Kelsen 1920: 317,
1934: 117, 1945: 388).20 So Marmor is clearly wrong in claiming that Kelsen
changed his position concerning the unity of law in the second edition of the Pure
Theory.
What is more important, by ignoring the national form of monism, Marmor
makes it appear as if Kelsen were somehow attracted to pluralism in the second edi-
tion. Because he was hesitant about the international version of monism, Marmor
suggests, Kelsen must have been sympathetic to the idea that a multiplicity of inde-
pendent legal systems exists, each system being dependent upon social facts about
a particular community. The result is that an absolutely foundational element of
Kelsen’s legal theory—his doctrine of the unity of law—is falsely treated as
marginal.
As Kelsen himself insisted, his pure theory of law and his doctrine of the unity
of law are essentially related (Kelsen 1934: 113). Anyone who claims that multiple
legal systems exist independently—rather than existing as subsystems of a larger
legal system that coordinates their relationship to one another—must be tying law
19
That the principle must be one of efficacy is questionable. Because the principle is itself a matter
of positive law (Kelsen 1945: 121), there is no reason why it would have to have that particular
content.
20
Kelsen’s view that monism did not entail the primacy of international law was the focus of a
debate among Austrian legal scholars back in the 1920s (von Bernstorff 2010: 104–107).
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 43
to social facts about a community in a way that is incompatible with a pure theory
(Kelsen 1934: 114, 1945: 375–376).
The structure of Kelsen’s argument in his major works can mislead one into con-
cluding that he is a pluralist. This is because he generally brings up the unity of law
toward the end of each work (Kelsen 1934: 111–125, 1945: 363–388, 1960a; 320–
347). He begins with a national legal order, understood as having its own basic
norm. From that perspective, when he speaks of efficacy as a condition for the adop-
tion of a new basic norm—for example, after a revolution (Kelsen 1960a: 50)—he
appears to have accepted a pluralistic approach to the law, in which independent
legal systems, each with its own basic norm, exist. But he always ends with the
unity of law, where he makes it clear that insofar as we are considering these mul-
tiple national legal systems as each possessing valid laws, we must be viewing them
as subsystems of an overarching legal order.
Because Kelsen insisted on the unity of law, we have reason to believe, contrary
to Marmor’s reading, that his theory of law is indeed pure. Of course, that also
increases the theory’s implausibility. To Marmor, the idea that there “is only one
basic norm in the world, the basic norm of public international law,” is “incredible”
(Marmor 2011; 23 n. 18). Things do not appear any better if one notes that legal
monism might be national. Under the national version, all valid law would funda-
mentally be American law (assuming the American legal system is the foundational
one). The law of other national legal systems would be valid only because they are
recognized by principles of international law that are themselves valid only because
American law recognizes them.21 My guess is that Marmor would find this version
of monism, under which Ancient Roman law is valid because American law says so,
equally incredible.22
But the fact remains that Kelsen was a monist. Marmor, in the guise of articulat-
ing Kelsen’s own views, adopts the very perspective on the law that Kelsen thinks is
impossible:
The problem [that Kelsen’s relativism leads to sociological reductionism] stems from the
fact that Kelsen was right about the law. Legal validity is essentially relative to the social
facts that constitute the content of the basic norm of each and every legal order. As noted
from the outset, legal validity is always relative to a time and place. And now we can see
why: because legal validity is determined by the content of the basic norm that is actually
followed in a given society. The laws in the United Kingdom, for example, are different
from those in the United States because people (mostly judges and other officials) actually
follow different rules, or basic norms, about what counts as law in their respective jurisdic-
tions. Once Kelsen admits, as he does, that the content of a basic norm is fully determined
by practice, it becomes very difficult to understand how the explication of legal validity he
offers is nonreductive (Marmor 2011; 24–25).
21
Curiously, American subsystem law would also reappear within the unitary American legal sys-
tem, because American law as a subsystem would also be recognized by international law.
22
A national monist might take the position that the law of no other nation is valid. But I doubt that
Marmor would be inclined to find that position, under which only American law is valid, any more
attractive.
44 M.S. Green
One problem with this passage is that it misdescribes the person to whom the law
is relative. Kelsen never says that the validity of the law is relative to the perspective
of the participants in a particular set of legal practices. The validity of the law is
instead relative to the perspective of the legal scientist—the person cognizing the
law—who need not be a participant in any legal practices at all (Kelsen 1934; 58,
1960a; 204–205). Kelsen argues that any person who judges norms to be valid law
must be presupposing a unitary basic norm. Because Marmor conceives of the
United Kingdom and the United States as each possessing laws that are valid within
their own time and place, Kelsen would say he is presupposing a unitary basic norm.
It is in the light of this norm that the activities of American and British officials can
be seen as law-creating acts. But Marmor takes himself to be thinking of the
American and British legal systems as independently valid, precisely the perspec-
tive that Kelsen thinks is impossible.
that “a norm that is not effective at least to some degree, is not regarded as a valid
legal norm” (Kelsen 1960a: 11) or that “a normative order is considered valid only if
it is by and large effective” (Kelsen 1960a: 86). Statements about what is regarded or
considered are psychological, not legal.
Consider as well Kelsen’s description of a revolution:
A band of revolutionaries stages a violent coup d’état in a monarchy, attempting to oust the
legitimate rulers and to replace the monarchy with a republican form of government. If the
revolutionaries succeed, the old system ceases to be effective, and the new system becomes
effective…And one treats this new system, then, as a legal system, that is to say, one inter-
prets as legal acts the acts applying the new system, and as unlawful acts the material acts
violating it…If the revolutionaries were to fail because the system they set up remained
ineffective…then the initial act of the revolutionaries would be interpreted not as the estab-
lishing of a constitution but as treason, not as the making of law but as a violation of law
(Kelsen 1934: 59, see also Kelsen 1960a: 210–11).
Here too, Kelsen speaks psychologically about how one treats the new system or
interprets the acts of the revolutionaries.
When understood psychologically, Kelsen’s statements about efficacy are com-
patible with a pure theory. It is true that people would not presuppose the basic norm
of the unitary legal system if it were not efficacious. But it is also true that we would
not judge slavery to be morally impermissible if all sorts of social and psychological
conditions were not in place. That does not mean that the moral impermissibility of
slavery depends upon those social and psychological conditions.
Indeed, there is substantial evidence in Kelsen’s writings that the distinction
between psychological and legal judgments was of crucial importance to him.
Because legal norms stand outside space and time,23 they cannot causally interact
with human beings. Thus, in his more careful moments, he denied that legal norms
can be efficacious at all, because that suggests such a causal connection. What is
efficacious is instead a psychological entity, the idea of the norm: “One must there-
fore distinguish clearly between the norm, which is valid, and the idea of the norm
[Norm-Vorstellung], which is effective” (Kelsen 1926: 7; see also Kelsen 1945: 43).
A pure theorist of morality would draw an analogous distinction between moral-
ity, which exists independently of human beings, and our beliefs about morality.
Our beliefs have causes; morality does not. Thus it would not matter to a pure theo-
rist of morality that correct beliefs about morality arose only at a late date. The
historical contingency of our beliefs about morality does not mean that morality
itself is historically contingent. Analogously, it should not matter for Kelsen if cor-
rect beliefs about the law (for example, acceptance of those principles of interna-
tional law that validate national subsystems) arose at a relatively late date.
So far, I have offered two readings of Kelsen’s statements about efficacy that
allow us to understand his theory of law as pure. Under the first, efficacy is simply
the factual condition for the validity of the laws of a national legal subsystem. The
23
A legal norm, Kelsen argues, “does not exist in space and time, for it is not a fact of nature”
(Kelsen 1934: 12).
46 M.S. Green
legal norms triggered by efficacy are part of a unitary legal system, a system that
does not itself depend upon efficacy. The second reading addresses those statements
in which Kelsen seems to be speak of efficacy in connection with the basic norm of
this unitary legal system. Here we can understand him as making psychological
judgments about when the basic norm is presupposed, judgments that are likewise
compatible with a pure theory of law.
But at times Kelsen speaks of a justificatory rather than a causal relationship
between the basic norm of the unitary legal system and efficacy. The idea is that
when making a choice of how to interpret social events legally, we do so with the
aim of satisfying the requirement of efficacy. We refuse to presuppose a basic norm
with content that would make the resulting legal system inefficacious:
To understand the nature of the basic norm it must be kept in mind that it refers directly to
a specific constitution, actually established by custom or statutory creation, by and large
effective, and indirectly to the coercive order created according to this constitution and by
and large effective; the basic norm thereby furnishes the reason for the validity of this con-
stitution and of the coercive order created in accordance with it. The basic norm, therefore,
is not the product of free invention. It is not presupposed arbitrarily in the sense that there
is a choice between different basic norms (Kelsen 1960a: 201).
reducible to the principle of charity. She can insist that the beliefs of the person
interpreted are independent of our best means of arriving at judgments about those
beliefs.
By the same token, Kelsen’s principle of efficacy can be understood as the epis-
temological demand that one interpret the legal meaning of events in a manner that
enriches this meaning. It need not follow that law is reduced to social facts. The
condition for the validity of the law remains the presupposed basic norm, a norm
that stands outside the causal order and so does not depend for its existence upon
social facts.
To sum up, there are three methods of reading Kelsen’s statements about efficacy
as compatible with a pure theory of law. Efficacy can be understood as (1) a legal
condition for the validity of a national subsystem under international law, (2) a psy-
chological condition for judgments about the law, or (3) an epistemological condi-
tion for arriving at justified judgments about the law. Each method allows us to
avoid reading Kelsen as having abandoned a pure theory of law.
Marmor has one more argument in the offing. Even if Kelsen is a consistent monist
and even if his statements about efficacy are compatible with a pure theory, reduc-
tionism about the law still follows from Kelsen’s relativism. For Kelsen, presuppos-
ing the basic norm is not rationally compelled. Law’s validity is relative only to a
contingent perspective in which the basic norm is presupposed. And that makes it
difficult, as Marmor puts it, to detach the law “from the facts that constitute the
relevant point of view (the facts about people’s actions, beliefs, attitudes, and such)”
(Marmor 2011: 23).
As a preliminary matter, it is worth noting that even if Marmor is correct, Kelsen
would be compelled to reduce the law to the beliefs and attitudes of an individual—
of the person thinking about the law (whom we can call a jurist). It would not follow
that the law would be reduced to social facts about a community. Marmor’s argu-
ment that Kelsen reduces the law to social facts about a community relied upon
Kelsen’s doctrine of efficacy and his (alleged) abandonment of the unity of law. All
Marmor is left with now is Kelsen’s view that the validity of law is relative to the
jurist’s presuppositions, which at most suggests that the law should be reduced to
the jurist’s beliefs and attitudes. An appropriate analogy here is the metaethicist who
claims that morality is relative to the presuppositions of the person making judg-
ments about morality. For such a metaethicist, morality should arguably be reduced
to that person’s beliefs and attitudes.
In addressing the relationship between reductionism and Kelsen’s normative
relativism, we should distinguish between two questions. The first is whether Kelsen
thought that the relativity of law to the jurist’s perspective leads to reductionism.
The second question is whether Kelsen ought to have concluded this. I take it that
Marmor is primarily seeking to answer the first question. Not only does relativism
48 M.S. Green
lead to reductionism, Kelsen thought it did, even though this conclusion was uncom-
fortable for him because it required him to abandon a pure theory of law.
I do not think it could be any clearer, however, that Kelsen did not think that the
relativity of law to the jurist’s presupposition of a basic norm is incompatible with
a pure theory, that is, that it is incompatible with an understanding of the law as an
objective order not dependent upon human beings. Indeed, it is precisely through
the idea that law is relative to a jurist’s presuppositions that Kelsen sought to explain
how the jurist makes objective judgments about the law:
The question: ‘Who presupposes the basic norm?’ is answered by the Pure Theory as fol-
lows: The basic norm is presupposed by whoever interprets the subjective meaning of the
constitution-creating act, and of the acts created according to the constitution, as the objec-
tive meaning of these acts, that is, as objectively valid norm (Kelsen 1960a: 204 n.72).
The objective legal meaning about which the jurist makes judgments is a meaning
independent of anyone’s beliefs and attitudes, including the jurist’s own: “The law
of normativity is…like the law of nature, in that it is directed to no one and valid
without regard to whether it is known or recognized” (Kelsen 1999: 6; see also
Kelsen 1960a: 7–8, 20–21).
It is true that Kelsen was a relativist in the sense that he thought that the jurist, in
a sense, creates his object of knowledge. This makes the law, in some sense, subjec-
tive. But Kelsen thought such relativism was true of all knowledge: “[T]he science
of law as cognition of the law, like any cognition, has constitutive character – it
‘creates’ its object insofar as it comprehends the object as a meaningful whole”
(Kelsen 1960a: 72). Kelsen’s relativism is due to his Neo-Kantianism, which is
present even as late as the second edition of the Pure Theory.24
But how can Kelsen adopt a Neo-Kantian approach, when—as Marmor notes—
he accepted that no one is rationally compelled to think legally? One can, after all,
simply look at political events as mere power relations.
It is true that Kelsen does not purport to offer a progressive transcendental argu-
ment of the sort in Kant’s first Critique, that is, an argument that seeks to refute the
skeptic (in Kant’s case, the skeptic about the existence of causal relations or sub-
stances in nature) by starting with an indubitable fact (for Kant, the unity of con-
sciousness) and showing that what the skeptic denies is a condition for the possibility
of the indubitable fact. But Kelsen never claimed to offer a transcendental argument
of this sort. Indeed, to my knowledge, he never used the phrases “transcendental
argument” or “transcendental deduction” (“transzendentaler Beweis,” “transzen-
dentales Argument,” “transzendentale Deduction”) in connection with his theory of
law. The fact remains that he adopted a Neo-Kantian approach, in which the law is
dependent upon or constituted by the jurist, to explain how we can know an objec-
tive legal order.
24
For example, Kelsen repeatedly speaks of the basic norm as transcendental-logical (Kelsen
1960a: 201–02, 218, 223, 226). Kelsen’s Neo-Kantian approach is even more explicit in passages
from the German version of the second edition, omitted in the English translation, eg Kelsen
1960b: 208 n.**, where he explicitly draws an analogy between his method and Kant’s.
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 49
Stanley Paulson has helpfully offered two possible interpretations of the sense in
which Kelsen can be understood as a Neo-Kantian. Under the first, Kelsen sought to
offer a regressive transcendental argument. Under this reading, he took for granted
that we make judgments about objective legal norms and tried to explain how such
judgments are possible. Kelsen can still be understood as having offered a transcen-
dental argument under this reading, because the jurist is understood as creating his
object of knowledge, with the basic norm acting as the analogue of a Kantian cate-
gory (Paulson 2013: 49–57).
The second approach is more closely associated with the Marburg Neo-Kantian
Hermann Cohen,25 as well as the Schopenhauerian intellectual environment in
Vienna within which Kelsen—and Wittgenstein (Janik and Toulmin 1973)—wrote.
Under this approach, which might be described as quietist, Kelsen abandons any
transcendental argument, although not transcendental idealism. Kelsen’s goal is
simply to explicate, without any grounding or justification, what jurists in fact do
(Paulson 2013: 57–61). The presupposition of the basic norm is a description of
what jurists do when they think of valid law. I have argued for this reading myself
(Green 2003: 389–405, 2009).
To be sure, Paulson thinks that, under the second (quietist) approach, Kelsen
would have to abandon his language about the constitutive role of the knowing sub-
ject (Paulson 2013: 60–61). Thus he would likely say that Kelsen’s relativism pre-
sumes the first approach. For the record, I disagree.26 But even if Paulson is right,
Marmor’s reading is still mistaken, for Paulson clearly does not think that under the
first approach Kelsen thought that his relativism leads to reductionism.
What both approaches have in common is that Kelsen assumes that jurists do
indeed take themselves to be cognizing objective legal norms, even if they are not
compelled to do so by “Reason” (Marmor 2011: 22) or the requirements of self-
consciousness. Kelsen recognizes that our commitment to objective legal norms
might be “senseless or merely ideological fallacy” (Kelsen 1960a: 101; see also
Kelsen 1934: 33). But he nevertheless thought that denying the existence of such
norms would render “[t]he thousands of statements in which the law is expressed
daily…senseless” (Kelsen 1960a: 104; see also Kelsen 1945: 436).
Of course, the question remains whether Kelsen’s Neo-Kantian approach suc-
ceeds.27 Perhaps Marmor is right that Kelsen should have drawn reductionist con-
clusions from his Neo-Kantianism. But we have now moved beyond what Kelsen
did think to what he should have thought. It is unquestionably true that Kelsen did
think that his Neo-Kantian relativism was compatible with nonreductionism.
25
For Kelsen’s reliance on Cohen, see Paulson 1992, 2013; Green 2003: 389–402; Edel 1999.
26
A quietist might speak about the knowing subject creating her objects of knowledge as a means
of foreclosing Platonist theories in which the objects of knowledge are given independent meta-
physical status. For a discussion of how the quietist must walk a fine line between subjectivism on
the one hand and metaphysical realism on the other, see Green 2003: 396–398, 2009: 367–368.
27
Paulson has argued that the first approach fails, on the ground that Kelsen has not shown that the
basic norm is the only means of explaining what is presumed, namely cognition of objective legal
norms (Paulson 1992, 2013: 55–57).
50 M.S. Green
So Marmor has given us no reason not to take Kelsen at his word: His theory of law
really is pure. But the important question remains: Why accept it? Are there any
legal judgments that cannot be made sense of unless the law is independent of all
social facts? Such focused arguments for the independence of law from social facts
seem lacking in Kelsen’s works.
In my own writing on Kelsen, I have tried to fill this gap by identifying judg-
ments about the law that suggest its independence from social facts. Assume, for
example, that the validity of the United States Constitution is justified by Article
VII. As we have seen, one cannot justify Article VII’s status as law by other enacted
laws. The creation of Article VII was a revolutionary act. For a positivist, therefore,
the validity of Article VII—as well as the validity of the Constitution and laws
enacted pursuant to it—must be based upon social facts about American legal prac-
tices. Article VII is valid law, roughly, because it is actually used by American offi-
cials for assessing the validity of American law. But given the revolutionary nature
of Article VII, the requisite legal practices were probably in place in the United
States only sometime after the ratification process was completed, when American
officials had established a practice of justifying the validity of the Constitution and
other American law by reference to Article VII. Thus, the positivist would appar-
ently be compelled to say that the Constitution was valid sometime after
ratification.
But I doubt many American lawyers would say that the Constitution became
valid law when such practices had emerged. They would say that the Constitution
became valid on June 21, 1788, when the ninth state (New Hampshire) ratified it.
The irrelevance of American legal practices to the validity of American law suggests
that American law cannot be reduced to social facts about American legal practices
(Green 2003: 387–389, 2009: 361–365).
Although this example is primarily directed at positivist theories of law, it can
cast doubt upon natural law theories as well. After all, it is likely that on June 21,
1788, there were insufficient social facts about American legal practices in place to
justify the validity of Article VII, even when those facts are combined with evalua-
tive facts.
It is possible, however, that positivists and natural lawyers would be comfortable
understanding lawyers’ judgment that the Constitution was valid when ratified, not
as a statement about the law at the time of the ratification, but as a statement about
how events occurring at the time of the ratification ought, legally, to be treated now.
What is more, there remains the apparent independent existence of legal systems
other than the American. Legal pluralism, as we have seen, is incompatible with a
pure theory.
In another attempt to give life to the Kelsenian approach, I will briefly consider
other judgments that provide, I believe, evidence of a commitment to law that tran-
scends social facts, namely judgments in the conflict of laws (or private interna-
tional law, as it is known outside the United States). The law of the conflict of laws
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 51
28
My argument supports the international rather than the national version of monism. Indeed, like
a number of Kelsen’s Austrian critics in the 1920s—such as Alfred Verdross and Josef Kunz (von
Bernstorff 2010: 105)—I find the national version of monism questionable. To the extent that one
treats other national legal systems as having validity under principles of international law, I cannot
see how one could not consider one’s own national legal system as fundamentally subject to those
same principles.
29
The Court of Appeals reversed the trial court’s dismissal of a second cause of action, according
to which the defendant failed to abide by a provision in the contract that stated that “in the event
the plaintiff should die or become unable, without fault on his part, to serve during the period of
the contract the defendants would pay to him or his heirs the sum of 120,000 marks, in discharge
of their obligations, under the hiring aforesaid.”
52 M.S. Green
and their officials. Let us call this a rule of authorization. For example, it might say
that German officials have exclusive regulatory power over everything that happens
within Germany’s borders. If so, any court adjudicating a case with facts occurring
in Germany is arguably legally obligated to look to German officials to decide the
case. That is one way of understanding the rule used in the Holzer case. According
to the rule, New York officials lacked the power to apply New York law.
Alternatively, we might understand the rule used in Holzer, not as claiming that
New York officials lacked regulatory power over the event being adjudicated, but
only that they chose, at their discretion, not to exercise their power. The New York
Court of Appeals was saying, not that New York law cannot, but that it does not
apply to the facts in Holzer. Let us call this a rule of scope.30
Finally, let us assume that two or more jurisdictions have concurrent regulatory
power over the event being adjudicated and both have chosen to exercise their
power. Assume, for example, that German and New York officials both have the
power to extend their laws to Germans who enter into contracts in Germany and
both have enacted laws that have such contracts within their scope. If that is the
case, the forum will have legal discretion to apply German or New York law to the
facts. The rule it uses when exercising this discretion is a rule of priority.
One might think that a New York state court’s decision not to apply New York
law to facts over which New York has lawmaking power must mean that the facts
are outside the scope of New York law. But such a conclusion is too hasty. It is con-
ceivable that a New York state court might refrain from applying New York law due
to a rule of priority. Even though it does not apply New York law, it might accept
that the facts are within the scope of New York law, as evidenced by its permitting
the courts of other jurisdictions (with different rules of priority) to apply New York
law to the facts (Roosevelt 2005: 1874; Kramer 1991: 1029).
Let us now return to the claim that the conflicts rule used by the Court of Appeals
in Holzer was New York law. Understood as a rule of scope, the rule was indeed
New York law. When a New York court chooses, at its discretion, not to extend
New York law to facts, that decision is a matter of New York law. Even a monist like
Kelsen can accept that, understood as a rule of scope, it was New York law, in the
sense that it was the result of New York officials exercising their authority.
The same point is true if the rule used by the Court of Appeals in Holzer was a
rule of priority. When a New York court, after concluding that the facts are within
the scope of both German and New York law, chooses, at its discretion, to give
German law priority, its choice is a matter of New York law. This again is something
with which Kelsen can agree.
30
When conflicts rules are understood as rules of scope, one must then confront the question of
whether other jurisdictions ought to respect them. (This is commonly called the problem of renvoi
or désistement.) If New York officials have said, through their conflicts rules, that the facts are
beyond the scope of New York law, it would appear that other jurisdictions are not permitted to
apply New York law to the facts. I argue, however, that this reasoning is mistaken at Green 2013:
869–884.
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 53
But I think it is pretty clear that the Court of Appeals thought it was applying a
rule of authorization, not a rule of scope or priority. It thought German officials had
exclusive lawmaking power over the contract, and thus that it had to look to German
officials to decide the case. As the Court of Appeals put it, “Within its own territory
every government is supreme” Holzer v. Deutsche Reichsbahn-Gesellschaft (277
N.Y. 474, 479 (1938)).
Understood as a rule of authorization, it is hard to see how the rule could possibly
be New York law. To say that New York officials lack the power to extend their law
to such contracts is to say that no change in New York legal practices could make
the extension of New York law to such contracts legally permissible. So put, this
restriction could not possibly be dependent itself upon New York legal practices.
To be sure, the Court of Appeals cited a case from the United States Supreme
Court in favor of the principle that foreign governments are supreme within their
own territory (United States v. Belmont, 301 U. S. 324 (1937)). What is more, the
application of New York law to the facts would pretty clearly be in violation of the
Due Process Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment (eg, Home Insurance Co. v.
Dick, 281 U.S. 397 (1930)). Thus, one might argue that the rule of authorization it
was articulating, although not New York law, was federal law.
But if the rule was federal law, in the sense that it was dependent upon American
legal practices, that would mean that those practices could change in a way that
would permit the court in Holzer to extend New York law to the contract. And my
guess is that the rule was not conceived this way. To the extent that the rule was
federal law, such law simply recognized preexisting monistic legal restrictions on
American officials.
That this division of lawmaking authority was, and is, conceived of monistically
is evident in the possibility of intercommunity disagreement. Assume a German
court claimed that it possessed the power to apply German law to contracts entered
into by New Yorkers in New York. I take it that this is something about which an
American court could meaningfully disagree. But under a pluralistic approach,
German and American officials cannot meaningfully disagree about the distribution
of lawmaking power between them. They can only articulate what the distribution
is within their own legal system.
Thus, even if there is significant disagreement between participants in various
legal communities about what the correct rules of authorization are, the very exis-
tence of such disagreement presumes that the rules bind communities independently
of what their legal practices happen to be. And that means that the rules of authori-
zation are conceived of as monistic law.
My argument is not changed if one decides that the New York state court in
Holzer was not legally obligated to apply German law. Assume, for example, that a
court is legally permitted to apply forum law at will. This still assumes a monistic
distribution of lawmaking authority, namely one in which a community’s officials
have complete authority over the activities of their courts (including their choice-of-
law decisions). This new principle also stands above and binds all communities, for
it too is a matter about which meaningful intercommunity disagreement is possible.
If a German court were to claim that New York officials lacked the legal power to
54 M.S. Green
apply New York law in Holzer, New York officials could think the German court
was wrong (not that it was right for Germany).
I don’t want to suggest that either the territorial approach that appeared to be
employed in Holzer or a forum-based alternative is correct. The proper approach to
the distribution of lawmaking authority between jurisdictions arguably cannot be
captured by any such simple rule. My goal here is not to get the distribution of law-
making authority right. It is to render plausible the monist’s view that there is such
a distribution that stands above and binds every community. This distribution is
employed not merely when someone makes a judgment about how a New York
court should deal with facts that arise in Germany. It is employed even when one
makes a judgment about how a New York court should deal with facts that arise in
New York, for it is only in the light of the distribution that one can explain why the
court should look to New York rather than German legal practices. Kelsen’s monism
is not as crazy as its sounds.
Acknowledgments Thanks for helpful comments from the participants in the Kelsen in America
Conference, organized by Jeremy Telman. Thanks for further aid to Brian Bix, David Enoch,
Andrei Marmor, Stanley Paulson, and Lars Vinx
References
Ackerman, Bruce, and Neal Katyal. 1995. Our unconventional founding. University of Chicago
Law Review 62: 475–573.
Delacroix, Sylvie. 2004. Hart’s and Kelsen’s concepts of normativity contrasted. Ratio Juris 17:
501–520.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, Ronald. 2006. Justice in robes. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Edel, Geert. 1999. The hypothesis of the basic norm: Hans Kelsen and Hermann Cohen. In
Normativity and norms: Critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes, ed. Stanley L. Paulson and
Bonnie L. Paulson, 195–220. Oxford: Clarendon.
Enoch, David. 2011. Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Green, Michael Steven. 2003. Hans Kelsen and the logic of legal systems. Alabama Law Review
53: 365–413.
Green, Michael Steven. 2009. Kelsen, quietism, and the rule of recognition. In The rule of recogni-
tion and the United States constitution, ed. Matthew D. Adler and Kenneth E. Himma, 351–
378. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Green, Michael Steven. 2013. Law’s dark matter. William and Mary Law Review 54: 845–884.
Greenberg, Mark. 2004. How facts make law. Legal Theory 10: 157–198.
Henkin, Louis. 1987. The constitution and United States sovereignty: A century of Chinese exclu-
sion and its progeny. Harvard Law Review 100: 853–886.
Janik, Allan, and Stephen Toulmin. 1973. Wittgenstein’s Vienna. New York: Simon and Schuster.
Kelsen, Hans. 1920. Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts. Beitrag zu
einer Reinen Rechtslehre. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.
Kelsen, Hans. 1922. Der Soziologische und Juristische Staatsbegriff. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.
Kelsen, Hans. 1926. Das Wesen des Staates. Revue Internationale de la Theorie du Droit 1: 5–17.
3 Marmor’s Kelsen 55
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the problems of legal theory. A translation of the first edition
of the Reine Rechtslehre or pure theory of law. Trans. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson, 1997.
Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945. General theory of law and state. Trans. A. Wedberg. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960a. Pure theory of law, 2nd edn. Trans. M. Knight 1967. Berkeley: University of
California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960b. Reine Rechtslehre: Mit einem Anhang: Das Problem der Gerechtigkeit.
Tubingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Kelsen, Hans. 1999. Foreword to the second printing of the main problems in the theory of public
law. In Normativity and norms: Critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes, ed. Stanley
L. Paulson and Bonnie L. Paulson, 3–22. Oxford: Clarendon.
Kramer, Larry. 1991. Return of the renvoi. New York University Law Review 66: 979–1044.
Marmor, Andrei. 2010. The pure theory of law. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://
plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/lawphil-theory. Accessed 22 Jan 2015.
Marmor, Andrei. 2011. Philosophy of law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Jules L. Coleman. 1990. Philosophy of law: An introduction to jurispru-
dence. Boulder: Westview Press.
Navarro, Pablo E. 2013. The efficacy of constitutional norms. In Kelsen revisited: New essays on
the pure theory of law, ed. Luis Duarte d’Almeida, Gardner John, and Green Leslie, 77–100.
Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Paulson, Stanley L. 1992. Introduction. In Introduction to the problems of legal theory. A transla-
tion of the first edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or pure theory of law. Trans. B.L. Paulson and
S.L. Paulson, 1997. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2012. A ‘justified normativity’ thesis in Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law?
Rejoinders to Robert Alexy and Joseph Raz. In Institutionalized reason: The jurisprudence of
Robert Alexy, ed. Klatt Matthias, 61–111. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2013. The great puzzle: Kelsen’s basic norm. In Kelsen revisited: New essays
on the pure theory of law, ed. Luis Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, 43–62.
Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Roosevelt, Kermit. 2005. Resolving renvoi: The bewitchment of our intelligence by means of
language. Notre Dame Law Review 80: 1821–1891.
von Bernstorff, Jochen. 2010. The public international law theory of Hans Kelsen: Believing in
universal law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Waters, Melissa A. 2007. Creeping monism: The judicial trend toward interpretive incorporation
of human rights treaties. Columbia Law Review 107: 628–705.
Wilson, Alida. 1982. Joseph Raz on Kelsen’s basic norm. American Journal of Jurisprudence 27:
46–63.
Part II
Hans Kelsen and the Development
of Public International Law
Chapter 4
The Kelsen-Hart Debate: Hart’s Critique
of Kelsen’s Legal Monism Reconsidered
Lars Vinx
4.1 Introduction
Legal monism is the view that there is only one legal system. Hans Kelsen defended
a particularly strong version of that view. Kelsen did not simply hold that there is
only one legal system, as a matter of fact. He argued, rather, that it is impossible for
a legal science to recognize the existence of more than one legal system. Legal-
scientific cognition, as a form of normative cognition, must assume, according to
Kelsen, that no two valid legal norms conflict, ie, that there are no two legal norms
that make incompatible demands on the behavior of one and the same agent. And
the absence or at least the resolvability of such conflict between legal norms can be
assured, Kelsen argued, only if all legal norms that exist are understood as belong-
ing to one and the same legal system. Legal pluralism, in other words, is deemed to
be juristically inconceivable (Kelsen 1934: 111–125, 1920: 107–111, 1952: 404,
424–428).
This exceptionally strong version of legal monism has found few followers
(Somek 2007, 2012). It seems to have been unanimously rejected by the leading
Anglo-American analytical legal positivists, in the wake of Hart’s highly influential
critique of the Pure Theory of Law (Hart 1983).1 Contemporary constitutional the-
ory generally endorses this rejection and has turned thoroughly pluralist
1
Hart’s arguments have been developed in more detail by Joseph Raz. See Raz (1970: 95–109) and
Raz (2009a: 127–129). Hart’s and Raz’s arguments against Kelsen’s theory of legal system are
fairly similar. This paper, therefore, focuses on Hart’s initial development of the critique. For a
discussion of Raz’s version of the critique, see Vinx (2007: 184–194).
L. Vinx (*)
Department of Philosophy, Bilkent University, 06800 Ankara, Turkey
e-mail: [email protected]
2
MacCormick subsequently modified his rejection of Kelsen’s monism and argued that the
European legal order might be understood as a form of “monism under international law.” See
MacCormick (1999, 113–121). The view that is advocated here is close to MacCormick’s later
position.
3
See for instance Culver and Giudice (2010, 38) who argue—though they sympathize with
Kelsen’s view that international law is real law—that Hart’s criticism of Kelsen’s monism is “deci-
sive.” This assessment is upheld in Giudice (2013, 161–164).
4
I have tried to explain why I do not hold Kelsen’s strong monism to be defensible in Vinx (2011).
5
For a comprehensive account of Kelsen’s theory of international law see von Bernstorff (2010). A
recent defense of the continuing relevance of Kelsen’s approach to the theory of international law
is given in Kammerhofer (2014).
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 61
related to one and the same basic norm by what Hart calls a “relationship of validat-
ing purport” form part of the same legal system (Hart 1983: 317–321). It is this
criterion of identity, in Hart’s view, that allows Kelsen to offer a monist account of
global legal order, because it appears to imply that international law validates
national law. But according to Hart, it is wrong to claim that all laws related to the
same basic norm by a relationship of validating purport must form part of the same
legal system. Hence, monism is unsustainable even in its weaker form.6
Hart is right to argue that the criterion of the identity of legal systems that he
attributes to Kelsen must be insufficient. However, the attribution of the criterion to
Kelsen is false. I also argue that, rightly understood, Kelsen’s monism can accom-
modate the observations that Hart takes to establish the falsity of weak monism.
Consequently, it is not as clear as Hart makes it out to be that the world is not gov-
erned by a monist system. The question why we should prefer a Hartian, legal-
pluralist account of global legal order to a weak form of Kelsenian monism therefore
persists. An answer to this question, however, cannot be given on purely theoretical
grounds, by appeal to considerations of descriptive accuracy or logical coherence.
In a somewhat modified form, I will thus uphold Kelsen’s view that the choice
between monism and pluralism (portrayed by Kelsen as a choice between different
monisms) depends on questions of value (Kelsen 1934: 116–117, 1920: 314–320,
1952: 444–447).
Weak monism, to repeat, does not claim that all laws belong to one and the same
legal system by logical necessity. What it claims is that it is possible (and plausible)
to interpret the existing international legal order in a monist way. In his influential
article, Kelsen’s Doctrine of the Unity of Law, Hart rejected Kelsen’s monism in its
weak variant as based on an inadequate account of what it means for two (or more)
legal norms to belong to the same legal system (Hart 1983: 311–321).
Hart’s argument rests on the attribution to Kelsen of the following principle,
which we can call the “principle of validating purport:”
[PVP] If two norms are related by a relationship of validating purport, they both belong to
the same legal system.
6
Ronald Dworkin’s mild critique of Hart’s attack on Kelsen conceded this key point to Hart. See
Dworkin (1968).
62 L. Vinx
the following passage describing the “principle of effectiveness” from Max Knight’s
translation the second edition of Kelsen’s Pure Theory of Law:
A norm of general international law authorises an individual or a group of individuals on
the basis of an effective constitution, to create and apply as a legitimate government a nor-
mative coercive order. That norm thus legitimises this coercive order for the territory of its
actual effectiveness as a valid legal order and the community constituted by this coercive
order as a “state” in the sense of international law (Kelsen 1960: 215 (cited in Hart 1983:
318)).
Kelsen’s point here, as portrayed by Hart, is that there is a norm of customary inter-
national law, the principle of effectiveness, that determines the conditions under
which the political rule of a person or group of persons counts as legitimate under
international law, with the consequence that the rules enacted by that person or
group of persons will then have to be recognized as valid law. The condition in ques-
tion is simply that the coercive order established by that person or group of persons
must enjoy actual effectiveness in some territory (Kelsen 1952: 414–415). Through
the principle of effectiveness, international law, then, purports to validate national
law. And, given the principle of validating purport, this is sufficient, according to
Hart’s Kelsen, to establish that national laws are validated by international law and
that national and international law therefore form parts of one and the same legal
system. In Hart’s reading of Kelsen, this alleged appeal to the relationship of vali-
dating purport is Kelsen’s only argument for the view that national and international
law form parts of one integrated legal system. If the principle of validating purport
can be shown to be false, Kelsen’s monism must consequently fail.
To establish that the principle of validating purport is false, Hart introduces a
hypothetical example, which is supposed to make it evident that the principle of
validating purport can at best be a necessary, but clearly not a sufficient, condition
for the membership in the same legal system of the norms that it connects.
Suppose the British Parliament […] passes an Act (the Soviet Laws Validity Act, 1970)
which purports to validate the law of the Soviet Union by providing that the laws currently
effective in Soviet territory, including those relating to the competence of legislative and
judicial authorities, shall be valid (Hart 1983: 319).
If the British Parliament passes the act, British law will purport to validate Soviet
law. However, it would obviously be false to argue that the Soviet legal system has
thereby become part of British law. Hence, the existence of a relationship of validat-
ing purport between the Soviet Laws Validity Act and the laws of the Soviet Union
is insufficient to make Soviet law part of the British legal system. If a relationship
of validating purport is insufficient to ensure that the laws that it relates belong to
the same legal system in this case, Hart concludes, the principle of validating pur-
port must be false. It follows that the principle of effectiveness, which purports to
validate national law, is insufficient to establish the unity of international and
national law.
Hart also offers a diagnosis of what he takes to be Kelsen’s “central mistake”
(Hart 1983: 318). The reason why it makes no sense to claim that the Soviet Laws
Validity Act validates Soviet law is that “the courts and other law-enforcing agen-
cies in Soviet territory do not, save in certain special circumstances, recognize the
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 63
operations of the British […] legislature as criteria for identifying the laws that they
are to enforce” (Hart 1983: 319). A little earlier in his paper, Hart asks the reader to
imagine that the “Vice-Chancellor of Oxford University dispatched to me a docu-
ment purporting to order me to write a paper on Kelsen’s Doctrine of the Unity of
Law” (Hart 1983: 312). As Hart points out, it wouldn’t follow from this fact, and the
fact that he, Hart, did indeed write a paper on Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law
that, in so doing, he obeyed the Vice-Chancellor of Oxford University or that he
recognized the Vice-Chancellor’s authority to order him to write papers on a certain
topic. Hence, we cannot infer from the fact that the Vice-Chancellor purported to
order Hart to do something he in fact ended up doing that the Vice-Chancellor had
any authority in the matter over Hart.
Similarly, we cannot infer from the fact that the principle of effectiveness pur-
ports to validate national law that the validity of national law in fact depends on the
principle of effectiveness. Whether that is the case or not must depend, in Hart’s
view, on whether the legal officials in the coercive order established by national
authorities recognize their laws to have been validated by international law. If they
do not, the fact that international law purports to validate national law will not suf-
fice to establish that the validity of national law depends on international law.7
In accepting the principle of validating purport, Hart argues, Kelsen focused too
narrowly on the content of laws purporting to validate others and failed to pay suf-
ficient attention to the circumstances that attend the enactment of such norms, to
whether they are recognized as authoritative and by whom. As a result, Kelsen lost
sight of the distinction between a norm that merely purports to validate another
norm and one that does in fact validate another norm. The pure theory, Hart argues,
lacks the resources to draw this crucial distinction. This establishes the superiority,
in Hart’s view, of a theory of legal system built on the idea of a practice of recogni-
tion. A norm validates another norm, in that view, if is recognized to do so, by the
relevant legal officials, and does not merely purport to do so (Hart 1983: 312–313,
335–336).
What are we to make of this criticism of the pure theory? At first glance, it is
unlikely that Kelsen would have failed to see the distinction between a norm pur-
porting to validate and a norm that really validates, or to appreciate its importance.
After all, Kelsen put heavy emphasis on the distinction between objective and sub-
jective legal meaning,8 and he famously denied that the fact that the Captain of
Köpenick managed, for some time, to order people around gave him real legal
authority (Kelsen 1934: 9–10). He would therefore surely have rejected the idea that
the Vice-Chancellor of Oxford can put himself in a genuine position of normative
authority over Hart merely by purporting to give orders to Hart. It is, therefore,
prima facie implausible to attribute to Kelsen anything like the principle of validating
7
Needless to say, Hart argues on the basis of his theory of the rule of recognition. See Hart (1961:
97–107).
8
I have tried to argue elsewhere that the distinction is crucial to Kelsen’s conception of legality. See
Vinx (2007: 78–100). Kelsen’s most interesting and sustained discussion of the issue is Kelsen
(1914).
64 L. Vinx
purport, as formulated by Hart, because the principle involves a rather too obvious
confusion of subjective and objective legal meaning.
More to the point, Hart’s attribution of the principle of validating purport to
Kelsen abstracts from the fact that, for the Kelsenian legal scientist, any description
of relationships of validation presupposes the prior choice of and commitment to
one of several possible variants of legal monism. As is well known, Kelsen argued
that there are two different ways, in the framework of a monist theory of law, to
conceive of the relationship between national and international law: national
monism and international monism. In the first view, the legal scientist assumes a
national basic norm and treats international law as valid only to the extent that it has
been (indirectly) validated by that national basic norm. It is only in the second ver-
sion of monism that the legal scientist, by appeal to the principle of effectiveness,
comes to endorse international law’s claim to validate national law.9 Both of these
options, according to Kelsen, are equally compatible with all available empirical
data for which a theory of legal system for the contemporary world would have to
account. Both are therefore descriptively possible choices for the construction of a
theory of legal system. Hart himself was aware of Kelsen’s “choice-hypothesis,” but
he argued that it had no bearing on his argument against Kelsen’s doctrine of the
unity of law (Hart 1983: 311–312). In this Hart was quite clearly mistaken.
The availability of two different monist perspectives implies that Kelsen was not
committed to the principle of validating purport. To illustrate the point, let us take
another look at the example of the Soviet Laws Validity Act. Hart’s reasoning here
starts out from the claim that the purported validation of Soviet law by the Soviet
Laws Validity Act is not really what validates Soviet law (at least if we discount the
marginal scenario of the use of Soviet law in British courts). This claim must surely
be true, and I do not wish to dispute it. But Hart appears to assume that it follows
from the fact that the Soviet Laws Validity Act does not validate Soviet law that
British law and Soviet law cannot form part of one and the same legal system. This
second step is an obvious a non-sequitur. A Kelsenian legal monist can argue, after
all, taking the point of view of international monism, that both British and Soviet
law form parts of one global legal system, because they are both validated by the
principle of effectiveness. This does not commit the Kelsenian to the view that there
is a relationship of validation between British and Soviet law (or vice versa). He is
therefore as free as a pluralist to deny that the Soviet Laws Validity Act validates
Soviet law.
It would also be possible, of course, for the Kelsenian legal scientist to adopt a
national monist perspective that might be either Soviet or British. In the first case,
he would of course deny, as Hart wants him to, that Soviet law is validated by the
Soviet Laws Validity Act, because he will hold that Soviet law, validated by the
basic norm of the Soviet legal system, or law recognized by Soviet law, is all the law
there is. In the second case, he will make the same claim about British law. Perhaps
he will then treat the Soviet Laws Validity Act as validating Soviet law within the
9
On Kelsen’s ‘choice hypothesis’ see ibid., 113–122, Kelsen (1920: 102–320, 1952: 401–447), von
Bernstorff (2010: 104–107), and Langford and Bryan (2012).
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 65
British legal system. But the claim that the validity of Soviet law within the British
legal system might come to depend on a British statute is, as Hart would have to
admit, quite obviously true.
The upshot of this discussion is that Kelsen’s monist approach can accommodate
Hart’s example of the Soviet Laws Validity Act as well as other, similar examples
that have been put forward in the literature, as I have shown elsewhere (Vinx 2007:
184–194). Hart was right about one thing: If the British Parliament decided to enact
a statute validating Soviet law, it would fail to make the validity of Soviet law
depend on that British statute. But this is a claim the Kelsenian monist can acknowl-
edge without the slightest embarrassment and without having to abandon monism.
Hart’s example, I conclude, proves nothing against (weak) monism.
Hart’s use of the example of the Soviet Laws Validity Act goes wrong for the
reason that it disregards an important element of Kelsen’s theory of legal system:
the theory of legal hierarchy first developed by Kelsen’s pupil Adolf Merkl (Kelsen
1934: 55–75; Merkl 1931). The theory of legal hierarchy claims, in a nutshell, that
the norms that belong to one and the same legal system form a hierarchy of autho-
rization in which higher-level norms determine the conditions for the valid enact-
ment of lower-level norms. It follows from the theory of legal hierarchy that a
relationship of validation can exist only between a superior and an inferior norm,
but not between two norms that are on the same level of legal hierarchy, or between
an inferior and a superior norm.
Every construction of legal system makes assumptions about the structure of
legal hierarchy, in that it assigns all valid norms to one or another level of hierarchy.
These assignments, as we have just seen, will allow us to distinguish, on a perfectly
principled basis, between authentic and spurious relationships of validating purport.
The Soviet Laws Validity Act, for instance, could not be an authentic validation of
Soviet law, in an international monist construction, because British law and Soviet
law are, in that construction, situated on the same level of legal hierarchy. It could
not be an authentic validation of Soviet law in a national monist Soviet perspective,
because that perspective derives all valid law from the basic norm of the Soviet legal
system.
It should now be clear that Kelsen is not committed to Hart’s principle of validat-
ing purport. Whether some relationship of validating purport will have to be regarded
as an objective relationship of validation, in the context of legal-scientific descrip-
tion, will depend on which of the different available monist perspectives is chosen
by the Kelsenian legal scientist. And these choices impose restrictions on the
authenticity of relationships of validation that go beyond the mere existence of a
relationship of validating purport, as Hart defines it. Hence, those choices can
always be taken in such a way as to accommodate the intuitions about authentic and
inauthentic validation that underpin Hart’s examples.
Let us now move to a discussion of the principle of effectiveness, and the relation
of national to international law. Hart, as we have seen above, challenges Kelsen’s
claim that international law can be understood to validate national law by arguing
that Kelsen’s claim is based on nothing more than the principle of validating pur-
port. Because that principle is false, Hart concludes that Kelsen’s monism must be
66 L. Vinx
rejected as well. For Hart, the practices of recognition in the national context are
what determine the nature of the relationship of national and international law, at
least in the absence of an international practice of recognition. National practices of
recognition, however, typically do not recognize any dependence of the validity of
national law on international law.
This attack fails due to Hart’s misattribution of the principle of validating purport
to Kelsen. The point can be spelled out both from a national monist and from an
international monist perspective.
To start with national monism, the mere fact that international law purports to
validate national law does not by itself force the Kelsenian legal theorist to accept
that international law validates national law. If the legal officials of some nation, and
perhaps the population at large, do not recognize that their law is validated by the
principle of effectiveness, they will, presumably, come to embrace a jurisprudential
perspective akin to national monism. A Kelsenian legal theorist who thinks that a
lack of recognition of international law’s claim to validate national law on the part
of national officials and citizens undermines international law’s claim can of course
do the same. A monist, then, can go along with Hart’s view that the claim that inter-
national law validates national law is deeply implausible, and yet hold on to monism,
if he is willing to pay the price of embracing national monism.
The fact that Kelsen is not committed to the principle of validating purport also
helps defend the viability of international monism. The international monist con-
struction of legal order does not simply claim that national law must form part of a
global legal order because the principle of effectiveness purports to validate national
law. Rather, it makes the claim that we can conceive of national and international law
as forming a hierarchical structure that gives superiority to international law. This
claim, pace Hart, is not based on an appeal to the principle of effectiveness alone.
Hart’s presentation of Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law fails to take proper
account of Kelsen’s oft-repeated view that the existence of a legal system—or,
rather, the defensibility of a certain construction of legal system—depends on con-
straints of effectiveness. It makes no legal-scientific sense, according to Kelsen, to
postulate the existence of a certain legal system unless the behaviour that it purports
to govern exhibits sufficient conformity with the norms of the system (Kelsen 1920:
94–101, 1952: 412–414). International monism, then, will have to meet constraints
of effectiveness to qualify as a viable description of legal order.
It would make no sense to postulate the existence of a global legal order that
subordinates national to international law if there weren’t a system of states that
regularly interact with each other, and that tend to do so in recognition of a number
of principles—such as the principle that national law cannot derogate from interna-
tional legal duties—that can plausibly be seen to imply a superiority of international
law to national law. It is therefore wrong for Hart to assume that international
monism depends on nothing but a relationship of validating purport between the
principle of effectiveness and national law. The question, rather, is whether the
system of public international law can, under an international-monist interpretation,
account for enough state behaviour to make international monism descriptively
plausible. Hart has not established that this is not the case.
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 67
The basic norm of the American constitution is (roughly) that the constitution is valid; but
unless we have some independent criterion of what it is for laws to belong to one system we
cannot trace the validity of laws back to the constitution and thence to its basic norm; we
can only trace relationships of validating purport, and these, as we have seen, cut across
different legal systems (Hart 1983: 339).
10
For Hart’s general development of this attack on the rule of recognition see Hart (1961:
107–110).
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 69
explanation that relies on norms of international law for why the British Parliament
did not have the authority to validate or invalidate Soviet law. According to his view,
both British and Soviet law are validated by international law, but not by each other.
To be sure, Kelsenian legal science still does not resolve the choice between
national and international monism. In that sense, it fails to give a perfectly determi-
nate answer to the question of the identity of legal system. But is this a shortcoming
of the pure theory? Kelsen may well be have been right to argue that the facts and/
or examples that Hart considers to be determinative of the question of the identity
of legal systems are, in fact, incapable of providing an unambiguous determination
of that question. The fact, for instance, that the Soviet Laws Validity Act would not
have come to be the validating ground of Soviet law if it had been enacted does not
show that monism is false, and it does not help us to choose one version of monism
over the other.
There is one final Hartian objection to monism that we have to consider. I conceded
at the outset that Kelsen is wrong to claim that all valid legal norms must necessar-
ily belong to one and the same legal system. I do not deny that one can coherently
picture a world, from a Hartian external point of view (Hart 1961: 86–88), which
contains several legal systems that are not connected in such a way as to provide
any basis for a monist construction of global legal order. A pluralist description of
global legal order might, given certain circumstances, even turn out to be the only
plausible one. It would make no sense, for instance, for a legal historian to argue
that the legal system of the Roman Empire and of the Chinese Empire formed parts
of one global legal system. But it would make no sense either for the historian to
choose the perspective of one of the two and then to deny that the other was a genu-
ine legal system, containing valid norms. Any plausible description of the legal
state of the world in late antiquity the legal historian might come up with will have
to be pluralist.
In recognition of this point, I have done nothing more than to try to clear the way
for the defense of a weaker form of monism, one that merely holds that monism is
a plausible and perhaps attractive interpretation of current global legal order. What
characterizes the current historical situation is that it has become possible, while
taking a Kelsenian normative point of view, as opposed to a Hartian external or a
sociological point of view, to interpret all law that now exists on the globe as belong-
ing to one system. But this possibility is historically contingent on a certain degree
of global legal interconnection. It is not implied by the conditions of the possibility
of legal cognition.
As Hart rightly points out, Kelsen’s monism, even in this modified form, is still
committed to a “weaker version of the ‘no conflict’ theory” (Hart 1983: 332). A
monist interpretation of global legal order, according to Kelsen, will have to show
that there are no legally irresolvable conflicts between national and international
70 L. Vinx
law. If an apparent conflict between two norms that are both to be regarded as legally
valid were not amenable to a legal solution, through the application of some legal
rule or principle that gives priority to one over the other, the two norms in question
would, in Kelsen’s view, have to be regarded as belonging to separate systems of
legal authority, neither of which can claim recognized superiority over the other. In
other words, Kelsen would, in describing the relation of the two norms, be forced
back into the external point of view and would have to embrace some form of legal
pluralism.
Because international monism holds international law to be hierarchically supe-
rior to national law, and to authorize the enactment of national law, Kelsen would
seem to be committed to the claim that purported national laws that conflict with
international law ought to be regarded as invalid. The problem with this view, of
course, is that national legislatures often enact laws that appear to conflict with
norms of international law, but that are not therefore treated as lacking legal validity.
The most natural explanation of this fact, it would appear, is that conformity with
norms of international law is not typically a condition of the validity of national
statutes. These conditions, rather, depend on a national legal system’s own practice
of recognition. Such a practice may or may not take account of international law,
but, even if it does, international law’s standing as a condition of the validity of
national laws will itself depend on the national practice of recognition. The national
practice of recognition is an ultimate standard of validity that turns the national legal
order into an independent legal system.
To deal with this challenge, Kelsen attempts to show that, from a monist perspec-
tive, there are no real conflicts between national and international law, ie, that all
such conflicts can be shown to be merely apparent (Kelsen 1934: 117–119). Kelsen’s
main strategy for achieving this goal is to assimilate apparent conflicts between
national and international law to apparent conflicts between a constitution and stat-
utes that violate constitutional norms (Kelsen 1929). A statute that apparently con-
flicts with a national constitutional provision will, unless it fails to pass the threshold
of absolute nullity, enjoy legal validity. That the statute is unconstitutional means
either that it can be invalidated on grounds of unconstitutionality by a constitutional
court or—if the political system does not provide for that possibility—that the
organs that enacted the statute can be held liable for violating the constitution, even
while the statute itself continues to enjoy validity. As Kelsen points out, there is no
conflict between the constitutional norm that allows for the invalidation of the
unconstitutional law or for the punishment of its enactors, and the demands, what-
ever they may be, of the unconstitutional statute.
Similarly for the relationship of national to international law: That a national law
fails to conform to a provision of international law that the state is under a duty to
observe need not entail that it is not valid, even from a monist and internationalist
point of view. The legal significance of the international norm, rather, consists in the
fact that its violation makes the violating state liable to a sanction under interna-
tional law that may be applied by the injured state. Once again, there is no conflict
between the national and the international norm. Imagine that two countries A and
B enter into a treaty in which A undertakes to grant political rights to the members
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 71
Hart argues here that Kelsen’s “ingenious argument” does no more than to elimi-
nate the possibility that one and the same act may turn out to be legally mandated
by one law, so that its non-performance is the condition for the application of a
sanction, and be legally prohibited by another, so that its performance is the condi-
tion for the application of a sanction. However, Kelsen’s elimination of the possibil-
ity of this first kind of conflict, according to Hart, does not rule out the possibility of
another, second kind of conflict between national and international norms. The
British principle of parliamentary sovereignty permits the enactment of laws with
any content, even with a content that constitutes an international delict. As a result,
an act of legislation that is permitted under British law, and thus not a condition for
the application of a sanction in British law, may turn out to be impermissible under
international law, being a condition for the application of an international sanction.
Of course, this second kind of conflict is in one respect less serious than the first:
it does not make it impossible for the British Parliament to exercise its power in
such a way as not to violate either British or international law. But it does bar
Parliament, assuming it wants to avoid breaking international law, from making full
use of the permission to legislate granted by the British constitution. Or put differ-
ently: One and the same act may still turn out to be legally permissible and legally
impermissible at the same time, depending on whether we evaluate it from a national
or an international perspective, and that must surely be regarded as sufficient proof
of the possibility of conflict between British and international law.
Note, however, that Hart’s description of the legal situation seems to presuppose
the truth of legal pluralism. Hart, in claiming that one and the same act may turn out
to be both legally permissible and impermissible, clearly assumes that British law
and international law are independent legal systems with their own ultimate and
72 L. Vinx
potentially conflicting criteria of validity. But the internationalist monist view, need-
less to say, must be that international law and British law are both to be interpreted
as parts of one and the same legal system, in which British law is a mere subordinate
part of an international system of law. And it is not at all clear whether, in that inter-
pretive context, the principle of parliamentary sovereignty ought to be understood
as permitting the enactment of statutes that conflict with international law.
Hart, in the passage just cited, appears to understand permission as the absence
of prohibition. Under British law, as Hart points out, “it is not an offence to enact or
procure the enactment of any statute.” Let us assume, moreover, that it is not pos-
sible, under the British constitution, to introduce a law that would make it an offence
to do so. From the perspective of international monism this plainly does not entail
that it is not an offence for the British parliament to enact or to procure the enact-
ment of any statute. For an enactment not to be an offence, it would of course have
to conform to all law that forms part of the legal system, including—from the point
of view of international monism—international law. Hence, all that is implied by
Hart’s observations about the British Constitution is that the prohibition to enact
some law, if there is any, cannot be grounded in British law.
Kelsen need not concede that the enactment of a national statute that violates an
international treaty is legally permissible. In fact, Kelsen explicitly argues that such
an enactment would be an illegal act and, as such, subject to a sanction, notwith-
standing the fact that the statute in question may acquire legal standing, as a result
of the fact that the system of international law does not provide well-developed
guarantees of legality, such as an international legal mechanism to invalidate
national statutes that violate international law (Kelsen 1934: 118). From an
international-monist perspective, then, it is legally impermissible for the British leg-
islator to enact a law that violates an international treaty. Hence, Hart is simply
wrong to claim that the monist must admit that, in the scenario outlined by Hart, one
and the same act may turn out to be both permissible and impermissible. That
description will only apply to the scenario if we have already adopted a pluralist
perspective that treats British law as a separate legal system with its own ultimate
standards of validity. However, in doing that, we rather obviously beg the question
against the monist.
Hartians are likely to reply that Kelsen fails to take seriously enough the fact that
British courts are committed to treating the principle of parliamentary sovereignty
as an ultimate standard of validity. It is often held that this supposed fact (as well as
analogous supposed facts about the courts of other nations) alone suffices to estab-
lish the falsity of Kelsen’s international monism.11
11
See, for example, Kumm (2012: 42):
If the highest court of a legal order insists on applying the law of the more encompassing
legal order only under conditions defined by its legal order and the decisions of that court
are generally taken as authoritative by other officials of that legal order, then the relation-
ship between the legal orders is pluralist as a matter of fact.
Kumm goes on to argue the relationship should not be pluralist as a matter of right. But I think
he concedes the descriptive point too readily. His own cosmopolitan ambitions would be better
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 73
served by taking the view that the facts he talks about here do not establish that there is no unified
global legal order as a matter of fact.
12
See Dicey (1982: 87):
The principle then of Parliamentary sovereignty may, looked at from its positive side, be
thus described: Any Act of Parliament, or any part of an Act of Parliament, which makes a
new law, or repeals or modifies an existing law, will be obeyed by the Courts. The same
principle, looked at from its negative side, may be thus stated: There is no person or body
of persons who can, under the English constitution, make rules which override or derogate
from an Act of Parliament, or which (to express the same thing in other words) will be
enforced by the Courts in contravention of an Act of Parliament.
74 L. Vinx
The rebuttals of Hart’s critique of Kelsen that were offered here leave us with a
further question that our dialectical moves on behalf of Kelsen have only made
more pressing: Why monism? Let us assume that Hart’s specific attacks on Kelsen’s
weak monism can be parried. Perhaps it is true that Hart implicitly assumes the truth
of pluralism and that his arguments thus beg the question against weak monism.
Perhaps it is true that the kinds of facts that Hart invokes to establish the falsity of
monism fail to lend sufficient support to his rejection of Kelsen’s doctrine of the
unity of law, for the reason that they can be accommodated by that doctrine. This
still leaves a simple and powerful final question in the hands of the Hartian. Why
adopt a monist interpretation of global legal order?
What I have argued throughout is that Hart’s attempts to establish the descriptive
inadequacy of weak monism fail. If such attempts fail, and if it is possible—as
Kelsen himself demonstrated—to offer a rich and nuanced description of contempo-
rary global legal order on a monist basis, we are entitled to assume that weak
monism is at least a descriptive possibility and that Kelsen’s normativist theory of
legal system might, pace Hart, turn out to be viable. But this is not to say, I concede,
that legal pluralism is false. To prove that legal pluralism is false, one would have to
defend Kelsen’s strong monism, which I did not set out to do, because I am not
convinced that this would be a promising endeavor. It is certainly as possible to give
a nuanced and rich description of contemporary global legal order on a legal-
pluralist basis as it is to give a monist description. In describing contemporary
global legal order, then, we appear to have a real choice, as far as descriptive ade-
quacy is concerned, between a Kelsenian monist view and a pluralist account stem-
ming from Hart’s theory of legal system.
If both weak monism and legal pluralism are descriptively viable as accounts of
contemporary global legal order, then the choice between the two descriptions must,
it seems, come to depend on normative factors. Even Hart himself supported the
idea, in one of his moods, that the choice of an adequate legal theory might come to
depend, within the restrictions set by a requirement of descriptive adequacy, on a
theory’s practical consequences and thus on our practical interests (Hart 1958:
615–621).
Admittedly, this way of addressing the choice between monism and pluralism
conflicts with the purity of the pure theory of law, as it is normally understood, and
I certainly would not want to claim that mine is the only plausible way to take
Kelsen’s ideas on international law forward. But to safeguard the purity of the pure
theory, we would either have to defend strong monism, or choose purity over
monism and become Kelsenian legal pluralists (Kammerhofer 2009, 2011: 230–
240). I am inclined to reject both of these options: The first because I am not con-
vinced that strong monism is defensible, and the second because I would nevertheless
like to uphold monism, if it is descriptively viable, for what I suspect may be good
normative reasons. At the point where Kelsen’s commitment to a value-neutral legal
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 75
science and his commitment to monism come to pull apart, I prefer to stick to
monism and to work out what I take to be its implicit moral content (Vinx 2007).
This approach is open to the charge that one must not make the choice between
two different conceptions of law depend on the moral consequences of that choice.
Julie Dickson, who has developed this charge most forcefully, claims that to choose
a conception of law over another for its beneficial moral consequences must amount
to “wishful thinking” and “utopian scheming” (Dickson 2001: 83–102).13 Dickson
argues that the choice for some conception of law can have morally beneficial con-
sequences only if that conception is independently true. Moreover, even if choosing
a false conception of law could have morally beneficial consequences, we would, in
choosing that conception for its morally beneficial consequences, impair the accu-
racy of our theoretical understanding of what the law is.
I am perfectly happy to concede that we should not advocate the adoption of a
conception of law, on the ground that it has beneficial moral consequences, if that
conception can be shown to be descriptively inadequate, ie, if it can be shown to fail
to make sense of intuitions or observations that an accurate account of legal system
would have to accommodate. Kelsen’s monist theory would have to be rejected,
even if its adoption had morally beneficial consequences, if it was true that it cannot
distinguish between mere relationships of validating purport and genuine relation-
ships of validation. The thrust of my argument, however, has been that Kelsen’s
monist theory is not descriptively inadequate, or at least that Hartians have so far
failed to show that it is. And if considerations of descriptive adequacy do not suffice
to distinguish between two conceptions of law or legal system, then it is hard to see
how we could make a cognitive mistake, or be accused of wishful thinking, in
choosing between them on moral grounds.
Note that Kelsen himself adopted an argument from beneficial moral conse-
quences in advocating the cosmopolitan version of legal monism. According to
Kelsen, both national monism and international monism are descriptively adequate:
All incontestable facts that a theory of the structure of legal order would have to
explain can, in Kelsen’s view, be accommodated by either perspective. The choice
between the two perspectives must consequently come to depend on one’s assess-
ment of the moral consequences of the choice. The problem with the national monist
approach, as Kelsen sees it, is that it cannot conceive of different states as equal
members of a legal community of nations. The idea of a legal community of nations
that enjoy equal standing under international law, irrespective of their size and de
facto power, however, is described by Kelsen as “an eminently ethical idea and one
of the few genuinely valuable and uncontested constituents of modern cultural con-
sciousness” (Kelsen 1920: 204).
Kelsen is concerned that adoption of a national monist perspective is going to
have the consequence of impeding the further institutional development of public
international law, and in particular of the introduction of a compulsory system of
international adjudication, which Kelsen regards to be highly desirable from a moral
13
Dickson’s argument is phrased as a critique of Schauer (1996). See also Schauer’s reply to
Dickson in Schauer (2005).
76 L. Vinx
point of view. Adoption of the international monist perspective, on the other hand,
is likely to favor such a development. After all, if we already agree that there is an
objectively valid system of public international law that authorizes national law and
to which nation states are already subject, there seems to be no good reason to
oppose the introduction of institutions that can efficiently adjudicate and enforce the
norms of that system (Kelsen 1942, 1944).
Kelsen’s own argument from beneficial moral consequences, to be sure, assumes
the truth of what I have called strong monism. It assumes, in other words, that legal
pluralism can be rejected on a priori grounds of incoherence. Because monism, in
either its national or its international form, is, in Kelsen’s view, the only logically
coherent description of legal order, we can choose only between the two forms of
legal monism. Once this is granted, the choice for national monism can be portrayed
as a flat denial of international law, ie, of a law that coordinates states that enjoy
equal legal status, for the reason that national monism cannot recognize any law that
is not validated by, and thus subordinated to, the basic norm of one’s own national
legal system. International monism is thus made to appear as the only description of
legal order that a civilized and progressive person could wish to embrace (Kelsen
1920: 151–204).
I concede that the argument offered here does not allow us to employ this gambit
against a Hartian approach. The defense of weak monism offered here does not
entail, to repeat, that Hartian legal pluralism can be rejected on a priori grounds, or
that it is descriptively less adequate than a Kelsenian theory of legal system. A
Hartian legal pluralism remains on the menu of available descriptions of legal order.
Hart, in contrast to the authors whom Kelsen accuses of embracing national monism,
is not committed to a denial of the possibility of the co-existence of national and
international legal systems. And though Hart refused to recognize public interna-
tional law as a paradigm-case of legality, his theory clearly leaves open the possibil-
ity that public international law might develop into a full-fledged legal system, and
possibly even into one that comes to subordinate and incorporate national legal
orders, so as to create a monist global legal order (Hart 1961: 213–237).
A second charge against my suggestion that the choice between a Hartian legal
pluralist and a weak monist approach to the description of international legal order
ought to be made on moral grounds, then, is that the differences between a weak
monist and a Hartian description of international legal order do not run deep enough
to make that choice very consequential, as regards its moral consequences. This
criticism seems to me to understate the differences between a Hartian and a weak
monist perspective.
To begin with, the two views arrive at fundamentally different assessments of the
status of the current system of international law. Hart, in the last chapter of The
Concept of Law, suggested that existing public international law does not amount to
a full-fledged legal system, as it lacks a sufficiently developed and unified practice
of recognition (Hart 1961: 232–237). The weak monist assessment, by contrast,
denies that the system of international law fails to attain the full quality of law. As
long as it is possible to construct all law as part of international legal order, and to
show that the construction meets a constraint of effectiveness, the assumption that
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 77
14
To be more precise, a normative system is a legal system, according to Kelsen, if it successfully
claims a monopoly of legitimate force, ie, if the behavior of the purported subjects of the law is
sufficiently in line with the principle that the use of coercive force is legitimate only in response to
a prior delict or violation of the law. For instance, Kelsen claims, with respect to international law,
that:
international law is true law if the coercive acts of states […] are, in principle, permitted
only as a reaction against a delict, and accordingly the employment of force to any other end
is forbidden; in other words, if the coercive act undertaken as a reaction against a delict can
be interpreted as a reaction of the international legal community (Kelsen 1952: 18).
This condition could be fulfilled, Kelsen holds, in the absence of centralized adjudication and
enforcement of a system’s norms, because injured parties (or their allies) could apply sanctions for
delicts committed against them by way of (legally authorized) self-help.
15
Kelsen’s line of argument here is strictly analogous to his argument for the introduction of con-
stitutional adjudication in a domestic context. See Kelsen (1929).
78 L. Vinx
force on the part of a state that claims that its rights under international law have
been violated (Kelsen 1944; von Bernstorff 2010: 191–220). Adopting the interna-
tional monist perspective, then, is likely to favor our willingness to institutionally
strengthen the system of public international law.
There might be objections that this line of reasoning presupposes a normative
standard of the proper functioning of legal order and that it is wrongheaded to attri-
bute such a standard to Kelsen, who often adopted the posture of a hard-nosed
demystifier of our understanding of law. But the fact is that Kelsen, at times, rather
unambiguously commits himself to such a normative standard, namely to the ideal
of legal peace.16 This commitment is made most explicit in Kelsen’s assertion that
the essential function of a legal order is to secure peace, by submitting all use of
coercive force to constraints of legality (Kelsen 1944: 3, 1952: 17–18). This view is
tied to Kelsen’s account of the structure of legal norms (as authorizations of the
application of sanctions) and to his claim that public international law is complete,
in the sense that it provides legal grounds for resolving any possible conflict between
states (Vinx 2011). A condition of full legal peace exists where coercive force is
used only in response to a prior delict and after an impartial judicial decision. The
attraction of international monism, to Kelsen, is that it promises, in contrast to
national monism or legal pluralism, to help subject the use of force on the part of
states to comprehensive and effective legal regulation and impartial judicial arbitra-
tion that Kelsen hopes will pacify international relations (Vinx 2007: 176–207).
In pointing out that Kelsen was committed to the ideal of legal peace, I do not
mean to imply that Kelsen embraced international monism over pluralism for the
reason that he thought it would serve that ideal. For Kelsen, the adoption of one or
another form of monism, as I have emphasized already, is required on a priori
grounds, in virtue of a demand for the normative consistency of all law that Kelsen
considered to be a theoretical and not a practical postulate (Kelsen 1920: 107–111).
From that perspective, the fact that the adoption of the international form of monism
can be expected to have morally beneficial consequences is a mere by-product,
though undoubtedly to Kelsen a highly welcome one, of the only theoretically
defensible understanding of the nature of legal order.
My point is that the commitment to the ideal of legal peace must take on a height-
ened significance for those who think that Kelsen’s a priori case for monism is
unconvincing but who are nevertheless attracted to monism, and in particular to
international monism. It might be argued that it is perfectly possible to adopt an
international monist perspective on global legal order without thereby expressing a
normative commitment to the ideal of legal peace, like the anarchist law professor
who adopts an internal point of view to explain to his students what the law is with-
out thereby endorsing its normative claims. But what would be the point of doing
that if an institution-centred and pluralist description of legal order is equally avail-
able? If a descriptively accurate account of what the law is need not rely on a monist
perspective, then why adopt it over a pluralist description that equally serves any
purely expository interest? This question will be especially pressing if the adoption
16
On the importance of the idea of peace for Kelsen’s theory of legal system see Notermans (2015).
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 79
of monism has morally salient consequences that differ from the consequences of
the adoption of the Hartian alternative.
That this is indeed the case appears obvious. For Hart, and authors working in the
Hartian tradition, the existence of law is a matter of moral indifference. Whether
more law or more unified law—in the international sphere or elsewhere—is better,
we are told, depends on whether that law is going to be used as an instrument for
good or bad (Raz 2009b). The further strengthening of the system of public interna-
tional law, from a Hartian perspective, cannot be desirable per se. And because
public international law, according to Hart, is not as yet a full-fledged legal system,
we cannot, on Hartian grounds, argue from the existence of an international legal
system to a commitment to make it work. The Hartian perspective, then, like the
national monist perspective, is much less conducive than international monism to
the goal of the realization of international legal peace. The choice between a weak
form of international monism and legal pluralism, I conclude, must depend on one’s
estimation of the moral value of an international rule of law.
Let me finish by making some tentative suggestions concerning the normative rea-
sons that might come to bear on a choice between monism and pluralism, assuming
that both are descriptively viable. Of course, it is by no means obvious that weak
monism will prevail over a pluralist theory of legal system once we accept that the
choice between the two approaches must depend on moral consequences. In what
follows, I do not offer a comprehensive discussion of the question. Rather, I suggest
that some common arguments for the moral attractiveness of legal pluralism might
be misconceived.
Legal pluralists frequently talk as though monism was inseparably connected to
the monolithic and homogenizing political form of state sovereignty.17 But this
portrayal of monism is a clear misrepresentation of Kelsen’s monism. If deployed
against Kelsen’s monism, it is question-begging in much the same way as Hart’s
descriptive objections. Of course, if we adopt a legal-pluralist point of view that ties
the identity of a legal system to an institutionalized practice of recognition, then the
development of monism is imaginable only as a consequence of prior political cen-
tralization. In order to rely on the theory of the rule of recognition to determine the
identity of a legal system, we must know beforehand whose recognition is to count
17
See for instance Neil Walker (2012: 18–19) who describes monism as “a tendency towards a new
manifestation of closure and a new reduction to unity; towards the old familiar of everything
deemed constitutional being contained—‘constituted’ indeed—within the one hierarchically lay-
ered legal and political system.” Such talk assumes, without offering much in the way of argument,
that legal unity must be tied to the kind of political unity we associate with the modern state. It also
assumes that all forms of unity and closure are equally bad. Kelsen’s willingness to challenge such
assumptions strikes me as more progressive and more intellectually enterprising than contempo-
rary legal or constitutional pluralism.
80 L. Vinx
as constitutive of the rule of recognition in question. And we can only know whose
recognition counts if we already have an understanding of the boundaries of the
political institutions of the legal systems we investigate. Given a legal-pluralist per-
spective, the call for monism must, then, appear to be a call for a kind of imperial-
ism. Monism must be the arbitrary claim that one of the many institutionalized
normative systems or practices of recognition, and thus one particular polity, should
lord it over the others.
Kelsen’s monism, however, claims that there can be global legal unity without
much in the way of political centralization. The only institution necessary for the
efficient functioning of the order of public international law, Kelsen argued, is an
international court with compulsory jurisdiction over all disputes under interna-
tional law (Kelsen 1942, 1944). If Kelsen’s conception of legality describes a real
possibility, a global legal system need not resemble the dreaded world state.18 And
because Kelsen’s monism, as I have argued, may well turn out to be descriptively
adequate, the normative worry that monism must resemble sovereignty may well
turn out to be ungrounded.
My second suggestion is that legal pluralism implicitly disavows the goal of
making political conflict between states amenable to legal resolution. In a monist
interpretation of global legal order, as Kelsen points out, there are no political con-
flicts that do not have a legal solution (Kelsen 1931: 184–185). From a monist point
of view, all political conflicts between states are in principle open to be settled
through the use of legal procedures. The idea here is not, however, that political
conflicts are to be made to disappear, perhaps through a prior homogenizing exer-
cise of political violence of the sort that would be needed to found a world state,
before legal arbitration begins. Rather, the idea is that they are to take on a different
form, one that, hopefully, is going to be more peaceful than purely political conflict,
while being open for political difference within legal unity.
Whether hope for such a civilizing power of international law can still be shared
today is of course a doubtful question. Kelsen himself may have thought that the
danger of the employment of law as a means of oppression and hegemony is less to
be feared in the framework of public international law—at least if it comes to be
supported by the binding adjudicative settlement of all international disputes—than
in the framework of a sovereign nation state that has a legislator who is unhampered
by formal constitutional constraints. This stance, in retrospect, may strike us as
politically naïve. But it is important to remain aware of the fact that the legal plural-
ist alternative does little more than to consign the settlement of inter-systemic con-
flict to the sphere of power politics.
Legal pluralists like to sing the praises of the progressive attitudes that propo-
nents of different systemic perspectives are allegedly going to exhibit to one another
as soon as they have come to recognize the inescapable plurality of legal systems.
Tolerance, understanding, and mutual respect are regularly portrayed as likely con-
sequences of an adoption of the legal-pluralist mindset (Krisch 2012; Barber 2010:
170–171).
18
We are perhaps too afraid of this at any rate. See Scheuerman (2011: 149–168).
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 81
Acknowledgments This paper was first presented at a seminar on Kelsen’s international theory
organized by Robert Jan Witpaard at Radboud University in Nijmegen. It was presented again at
the 2013 Christmas meeting of the Norwegian Association for Legal Philosophy, at the invitation
of Jørgen Stubberud, and then at the workshop in Chicago organized by Jeremy Telman. I am very
grateful to Jeremy, Robert Jan, and Jørgen for giving me the opportunity to participate in these
events. I received a wealth of feedback on all three occasions: Svein Eng’s meticulous comments
at Oslo were extremely helpful. I am also indebted to Jochen von Bernstorff, Joseph Fleuren,
Michael Steven Green, Jörg Kammerhofer, Christoph Kletzer, Thomas Mertens, Thomas
Olechowski, Scott Shapiro, Jørg Stubberud and Jeremy Telman for their valuable questions and
suggestions.
82 L. Vinx
References
Barber, Nick. 2010. The constitutional state. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Culver, Keith C., and Michael Giudice. 2010. Legality’s borders. An essay in general jurispru-
dence. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dicey, A.V. 1982. In Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution, ed. Roger E. Michener.
Indianapolis: Liberty Fund.
Dickson, Julie. 2001. Evaluation and legal theory. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1968. Comments on the unity of law doctrine. In Ethics and social justice, ed.
Howard E. Kiefer and Milton K. Munitz, 200–206. Albany: State University of New York
Press.
Giudice, Michael. 2013. Hart and Kelsen on international law. In Oxford studies in philosophy of
law: Volume 2, ed. Leslie Green and Brian Leiter, 148–174. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hart, H.L.A. 1958. Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review 71:
593–629.
Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford: Clarendon.
Hart, H.L.A. 1983. Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law. In Essays in jurisprudence and philoso-
phy, ed. H.L.A. Hart, 309–342. Oxford: Clarendon.
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2009. Kelsen—which Kelsen? A reapplication of the pure theory to interna-
tional law. Leiden Journal of International Law 22: 225–249.
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2011. Uncertainty in international law. A Kelsenian perspective. Routledge:
Abingdon.
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2014. Hans Kelsen in today’s international legal scholarship. In International
legal positivism in a post-modern world, ed. Jörg Kammerhofer and Jean D’Aspremont,
81–113. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1914. Über Staatsunrecht. In Die Wiener rechtstheoretische Schule. Schriften von
Hans Kelsen, Adolf Merkl, Alfred Verdross, eds. Hans R. Klecatsky, René Marcic and Herbert
Schambeck, 2010, vol. 1, 785–865. Wien: Verlag Österreich.
Kelsen, Hans. 1920. Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts. Beitrag zu
einer Reinen Rechtslehre. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck).
Kelsen, Hans. 1929. The nature and development of constitutional adjudication. In The guardian
of the constitution: Hans Kelsen and Carl Schmitt on the limits of constitutional law, ed. and
Trans. Lars Vinx, 22–78. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Kelsen, Hans. 1931. Who ought to be the guardian of the constitution?. In The guardian of the
constitution: Hans Kelsen and Carl Schmitt on the limits of constitutional law, ed. and Trans.
Lars Vinx, 174–221. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2015.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. A Translation of the First
Edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or Pure Theory of Law. Trans. B. Litschewski-Paulson and
S.L. Paulson, 1997. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1942. Law and peace in international relations: The Oliver Wendell Holmes
Lectures, 1940–1941. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944. Peace through law. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1952. Principles of international law. New York: Rinehart & Company.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. The Pure Theory of Law, 2nd edn. Trans. M. Knight 1967. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Krisch, Nico. 2012. The case for pluralism in postnational law. In The worlds of European consti-
tutionalism, ed. Grainne de Burca and J.H.H. Weiler, 203–261. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kumm, Matthias. 2012. Rethinking constitutional authority: On the structure and limits of consti-
tutional pluralism. In Constitutional pluralism in the European Union and beyond, ed. Matej
Avbelj and Jan Komarek, 39–65. Oxford: Hart Publishing.
Langford, Peter, and Ian Bryan. 2012. Hans Kelsen’s theory of legal monism. A critical engage-
ment with the emerging legal order of the 1920’s. Journal of the History of International Law
14: 51–86.
4 The Kelsen-Hart Debate 83
MacCormick, Neil. 1993. Beyond the sovereign state. Modern Law Review 56: 1–18.
MacCormick, Neil. 1999. Questioning sovereignty. Law, state, and nation in the European
Commonwealth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Merkl, Adolf. 1931. Prolegomena einer Theorie des rechtlichen Stufenbaues. In Die Wiener
rechtstheoretische Schule. Schriften von Hans Kelsen, Adolf Merkl, Alfred Verdross, eds. Hans
R. Klecatsky, René Marcic and Herbert Schambeck, 2010, vol. 2, 1071–1111. Wien: Verlag
Österreich.
Notermans, Mathijs. 2015. Social peace as conditio tacita for the validity of the positive legal
order. Law and Philosophy 34: 201–227.
Raz, Joseph. 1970. The concept of a legal system. An introduction to the theory of legal system.
Oxford: Clarendon.
Raz, Joseph. 1990. Practical reason and norms, 2nd ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Raz, Joseph. 2009a. Kelsen’s theory of the basic norm. In The authority of law, 2nd ed, ed. Joseph
Raz, 122–145. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Raz, Joseph. 2009b. The rule of law and its virtue. In The authority of Law. Essays on law and
morality, vol. 2, ed. Joseph Raz, 210–229. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schauer, Frederick. 1996. Positivism as pariah. In The autonomy of law. Essays on legal positivism,
ed. Robert P. George, 31–55. Oxford: Clarendon.
Schauer, Frederick. 2005. The social construction of the concept of law: A reply to Julie Dickson.
Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 25: 493–501.
Scheuerman, William E. 2011. The realist case for global reform. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Somek, Alexander. 2007. Kelsen lives. European Journal of International Law 18: 409–451.
Somek, Alexander. 2012. Monism: A tale of the undead. In Constitutional pluralism in the
European Union and beyond, ed. Matej Avbelj and Jan Komarek, 343–379. Oxford: Hart
Publishing.
Vinx, Lars. 2007. Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law. Legality and legitimacy. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Vinx, Lars. 2011. Austin, Kelsen, and the model of sovereignty. Canadian Journal of Law and
Jurisprudence 24: 473–490.
von Bernstorff, Jochen. 2010. The Public International Law Theory of Hans Kelsen. Believing in
Universal Law. Trans. T. Dunlap. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Walker, Neil. 2012. Constitutionalism and pluralism in global context. In Constitutional pluralism
in the European Union and beyond, ed. Matej Avbelj and Jan Komarek, 17–37. Oxford: Hart
Publishing.
Chapter 5
Peace and Global Justice through Prosecuting
the Crime of Aggression? Kelsen
and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials
and the International Judicial Function
5.1 Introduction
At various junctures, Hans Kelsen’s academic career was closely linked with that of
the Hans Morgenthau, who was 15 years younger than Kelsen. Both had to emigrate
from Germany and came to the United States via Geneva in the late 1930s. In
Geneva, Kelsen held a professorship at the Institute of Graduate Studies, while
Morgenthau wrote his Habilitation at the Institute. Kelsen actively promoted
Morgenthau’s academic career during this time despite the fact that the two men
held fundamentally different positions on the potential of international law as a
means of conflict resolution in international politics.1 One area where these diverg-
ing approaches to international law became particularly apparent was the issue of
the role of the judiciary in international relations. Despite the experiences of two
world wars, Kelsen’s wartime publications on the new post-war world order still
demonstrate an unwavering trust in the pacifying role of the international judiciary.
By contrast, Hans Morgenthau’s writings on the future role of the international judi-
cial function in the 1940s became even more sceptical than they already had been at
the time of his 1929 dissertation on the “Internationale Rechtspflege.”
Conceptually, both authors started from opposing premises. For Kelsen, peace
was the potential consequence of a judicially controlled international legal order,
whereas for Morgenthau a functioning international judiciary was the potential con-
sequence of a politically secured state of peace in international relations. Kelsen’s
1
For an explanation of why Kelsen (in contradistinction to Morgenthau) after his emigration to the
United States did not influence mainstream legal scholarship in the United States, see Telman
2010: 353–376.
J. von Bernstorff (*)
Constitutional Law, International Law and Human Rights, University of Tübingen,
Tübingen, Germany
e-mail: [email protected]
From the middle of the 1930s to the end of the Second World War, Kelsen devoted
most of his scholarly attention to the question of a political reform of the interna-
tional legal community’s institutional structure. Before the outbreak of the Second
World War, his publications engaged with ideas for reform of the League of Nations.2
Later, Kelsen’s work on League of Nations reform contributed to the debate over a
new, peace-securing world organization that got under way during the war (Kelsen
1941a, 1944a, 1945). At the center of these publications stood the de lege ferenda
call for the establishment of an international court with compulsory jurisdiction
over member states. Kelsen’s blueprint of a constitutive document for the new world
organization made the court the central organ, the decisions of which would be
enforced by a Council of the great powers. The creation of such a court rendering
binding decisions was the institutional core of Kelsen’s cosmopolitan project.
Having witnessed two world wars, Kelsen saw in the rule of law in international
relations, secured by courts rendering binding decisions, the only way to a more
peaceful world order. For Kelsen, the state of peace pursued by compulsory juris-
diction3 did not mean the complete absence of violence, but merely a state of rela-
tive peace (Kelsen 1941b: 81). In that sense Kelsen set himself apart from a “utopian
pacifism,” which he regarded as a serious threat to international politics (Kelsen
1944b: VIII). In the future, the decision to use force would no longer remain within
the competency of individual legal subjects, but would be transferred to central
organs of the community for the purpose of sanctioning violations of the law. The
final, binding decision about the existence of a violation of the law subject to sanc-
tion, referred to by Kelsen as a “delict,” would be made by a central court organ ex
officio or at the request of the contending parties.
2
Kelsen (1934); idem (1939a); with a critical revision of the various provisions of the Charter,
idem (1939b); idem (1936).
3
See the programmatic title of his 1944 book Peace through Law, Kelsen (1944b).
5 Kelsen and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials 87
The central place that Kelsen accorded compulsory jurisdiction within the legal
system had already manifested itself clearly in the twenties with respect to national
law in his scholarly analysis of the dispute over the reach of constitutional jurisdic-
tion in the Weimar Republic (Kelsen 1929). Kelsen’s approach to the role of courts
in both the international and domestic context seems to be marked by his general
faith in the peace-creating function of constitutional adjudication, which he helped
to develop and introduce in Austria after World War I.
The real originality in Kelsen’s works on international law from this period lies
in the direct combination of concrete de lege ferenda proposals and his own socio-
historical studies that buttressed his policy proposals. As a constructive justifying
strategy, Kelsen developed his own theory of the evolution of legal systems, which,
applied to international law, made the establishment of compulsory international
jurisdiction seem like the next step in a progressive development of the international
legal order. According to this theory decentralized “primitive” legal orders histori-
cally started to centralize their legal functions by introducing centralized, compul-
sory jurisdiction. A centralized legislature and executive branch followed as a
second step (von Bernstorff 2010: Chap. 6A). To further underpin his legal-political
convictions, he trained his critical eye on the traditional international legal doctrine
concerning the function of international courts in international relations, such as the
doctrine of the non-justiciability of political disputes. For him, every political dis-
pute could conceptually be turned into a legal one. Kelsen thus solicited support for
the establishment of compulsory jurisdiction on three different levels: first, through
the constructive articulation of a draft charter for the new world organization; sec-
ond, through the equally constructive development of his own general theory of the
evolution of legal systems; and third, by deconstructing those doctrinal elements in
international legal scholarship that could be marshalled against his de lege ferenda
proposal.
In 1944, Kelsen published a draft charter for a “Permanent League for the
Maintenance of Peace” as the successor organization to the League of Nations
(Kelsen 1944b: Annex I, 127–140). Kelsen’s new world organization had four main
organs: Assembly, Court, Council, and Secretariat (Kelsen 1944b: Art. 2, 127). The
charter consisted of clear procedural rules governing the working relationships
between the four organs. The only substantive regulation was a comprehensive pro-
hibition of the use of force on the part of members of the new organization (Kelsen
1944b: Art. 34, 134). If a state wanted to enforce international legal rules through
war or forcible reprisals against another member state, it was up to the Court, at the
request of the affected state or the Council, to decide whether the charter had been
violated. Only after the Court had determined that the law had been broken could
the Council impose the necessary military and economic sanctions on the respon-
sible member states. In Kelsen’s draft charter, the Council could take action on the
sanction question only on the basis of and in conformity with the Court’s finding
that the state conduct in question had been illegal. The Court became the central
organ, the actions of which obligated the Council. The eruption of violence in
88 J. von Bernstorff
4
With this, Kelsen was reviving the Hague Movement’s strategy of juridifying international rela-
tions through obligatory arbitration. Much to the chagrin of the pacifist movement, the Second
Hague Conference in 1907, because of the alleged obstructionist attitude of the Reich government,
had been able to agree only on a voluntary form of arbitration by the Court of Arbitration in The
Hague. If the pacifists would have their way, the Third Hague Conference would finally remedy
this shortcoming. On this see, from the perspective of someone involved in the pacifist movement,
Nippold (1917, 12–27).
5
Excluded from this, according to Article 35c of the draft, were representatives of states belonging
to the Council of the organization (Kelsen 1944b: Annex II, Art. 35a, 145).
5 Kelsen and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials 89
Annex I, Art. 35b, Section 1, 144). Member states were obligated to hand over indi-
viduals prosecuted by the court.
In light of the widespread violations of international humanitarian law and the
indescribable horrors of the Holocaust committed during the Second World War,
Kelsen did not believe that the doctrine of the functional immunity of state actors
was in any way legally sacrosanct. He argued that the new charter could completely
revoke immunity of heads of states as a treaty under international law. Direct obliga-
tions of individuals, as well as individualized prosecution, indictment and convic-
tion through international courts, were perfectly in line with the concept of
international law as articulated by the Vienna School through the concept of a
monist global legal order according international law primacy over national law.6
The court that Kelsen envisioned was composed of five criminal lawyers and 12
international lawyers. It had not only the power to decide any dispute brought before
it by the organs or individual member states but also functioned as a two-tiered
criminal court for individual representatives of governments who could be charged
with violations of international law. The proposed powers of the new international
court were Kelsen’s political response to the “failure” of the League of Nations and
the need to prosecute and punish war crimes and crimes against humanity commit-
ted during the Holocaust.
In the late 1930s, the international relations realist movement expressed suspicions
that the demand for an international court that rendered compulsory decisions was
a utopian aspiration out of step with political realities. As early as his 1929 disserta-
tion, Morgenthau had set out his own understanding of the limited role of interna-
tional adjudication in international politics (Morgenthau 1929; Koskenniemi 2006:
152–158). In Morgenthau’s perception of the international judiciary, the interwar
reform movement’s demand for compulsory jurisdiction in international law was
based on a mistaken analogy to national legal systems. His critical assessment of the
role of the international judiciary was based on the assumption that the language of
international law faced inherent limits when confronted with political “tensions,” in
which one party sought to transform the existing legal status quo. In such situations,
the international judge faces the dilemma of either turning the court into a political
body by acting (ultra vires) as a legislator or rendering a meaningless formalist
judgment and thereby failing to ease the political tensions at the core of the
dispute.7
6
On the individual within Kelsen’s doctrine of international law, see J. von Bernstorff (2010, Chap.
4 B).
7
Later, in a similar vein, E. H. Carr, in his famous book The Twenty Year’s Crisis, 1919–1939,
noted, with reference to Lauterpacht, that the view of international law as a legal system that was
90 J. von Bernstorff
From this perspective, Kelsen’s assumption that courts would be able to admin-
ister international law to address pressing societal needs in individual cases over-
taxed the legal system. For Morgenthau, a legal process is fundamentally different
from a political one in that it blocks out the question of power. Before the law, the
parties are equal, regardless of the asymmetries of power. This legal fiction contra-
dicts the inherent logic of international politics, where the strength of the individual
states has to be considered a crucial factor in the resolution of conflicts of interest.
The introduction of a compulsory international jurisdiction encompassing jurisdic-
tion over existential questions of international politics would exceed the capacity of
the law. Morgenthau does not per se rule out a functioning international judiciary,
but it is dependent on stable and relatively harmonious political preconditions.
As Martti Koskenniemi has convincingly illustrated, Morgenthau’s critique of
international legal validity as an autonomous concept is based on Weimar intellec-
tual influences. Morgenthau—like Carl Schmitt—developed an approach to inter-
national law that tended to treat international legal validity as always dependent on
its congruence with the interests of the strongest political actors.8 For him, effective
constraints on state action could only derive from common interests in a given situ-
ation or from a balance of power Morgenthau (2006: 10 et seq.). Morgenthau ruled
out the idea of an autonomous international legal system guiding the conduct of
states, at least for all situations in which diverging and essential interests of strong
states were at stake. Despite these realist commonalities with Carl Schmitt, which
played out predominantly in questions of adjudicating questions of war and peace,
Morgenthau should not be associated with Schmittian authoritarian thinking in
general.9
For Kelsen, the problem of international jurisdiction before and during the
Second World War revolved above all around the future institutional development of
international relations; that development could be achieved only by way of an inter-
national treaty and thus via international law. Exploiting the theoretical insights of
the legal scholar into the specific inherent rationality of highly evolved legal sys-
tems, the Vienna School in international law favoured the creation of a court that
rendered binding decisions. The reasonableness of applying their system-oriented
approach to the law to international law was beyond question for them. Because
international law had the quality of law, it had to be conceptualized as a complete
system of norms. In this respect, the relatively small number of general international
legal norms was no obstacle to the creation of a compulsory jurisdiction. Had the
League of Nations not given excessive consideration to the power logic of politics
in the structure of its organs? As they saw it, the existing international legal frame-
work was in dire need of better judicial support. Irrational power politics had
brought war; now a unified international legal system was to bring peace.
International legal validity, which came with the criticized notion of formal equal-
ity, had an irreplaceable function and value for taming and civilizing the irrational
forces of nationalism and unrestrained pursuit of alleged national interests. The last
sentence of the lectures on “Law and Peace in International Relations” that Kelsen
delivered at Harvard in 1942 epitomized the Vienna School’s approach during the
Second World War: “The idea of law, in spite of everything, seems still to be stron-
ger than any other ideology of power” (Kelsen 1942: 170).
In 1945, Kelsen must have been deeply disappointed by the position and competen-
cies the founders of the United Nations accorded to the International Court of
Justice (ICJ).10 As in 1918, strong judicial controls were not the central concern of
the Allies when erecting the edifice of the new world organization during the last 3
years of World War II. Regarding the jurisdiction of the new Court, the drafters of
the U.N. Charter and the Statute of the ICJ relied heavily on the jurisdictional rules
of its predecessor from the interwar period, the Permanent Court of International
Justice (PCIJ). Hence, jurisdiction of the Court was only foreseen on the basis of
voluntary acceptance of the respective state parties, and confined to “legal” disputes
as opposed to “political” ones. In addition, individuals had no standing before the
court, neither as applicants nor as defendants. Unlike in Kelsen’s wartime blueprint,
the new court could thus not render judgments in cases of individual criminal
responsibility for war crimes. Instead, the Allies opted for a special ad hoc tribunal
outside the U.N. framework based on a separate agreement concluded amongst
them (London Agreement). This agreement foresaw jurisdiction of the temporarily
erected International Military Tribunal for individual “crimes against peace,” “war
crimes,” and “crimes against humanity.” The notion of the “crimes agianst human-
ity” made it possible to prosecute crimes committed during the German
“Menschheitsverbrechen” of the Holocaust. Only the establishment and application
of the first notion—the “crimes against peace” gave rise to Kelsen’s as well as
Morgenthau’s harsh critique of the Nuremberg trials.
10
On Kelsen’s critical stance regarding the UN-Charter, see Telman Introduction: Hans Kelsen for
Americans (in this volume). I agree that Kelsen’s sharp critique of the institutional system erected
by the UN-Charter in his methodologically unorthodox Charter Commentary can be explained by
his own idiosyncratic methodological beliefs and his vision of the new World Organization
(Bernstorff 2010: 225–228).
92 J. von Bernstorff
“Crimes against peace” are defined in the Nuremburg Charter, which was annexed
to the London Agreement, as “planning, preparation, initiation, or waging a war of
aggression, or a war in violation of international treaties, agreements or assurances,
or participation in a common plan or conspiracy for the accomplishment of any of
the foregoing.” In the first trial against 24 of the most high ranking German war
criminals, which began on November 20, 1945, and continued until October 1946,
12 defendants were found guilty of, inter alia, either waging “aggressive war” or
conspiring to do so. The majority of this group was sentenced to hang, all of them
having been convicted on additional charges (Frick, Göring, Jodl, Keitel, Ribbentrop,
Rosenberg, Seyss-Inquart) or given life sentences (Hess, Räder and Funk).11 In the
judgment, the Tribunal maintained that individual responsibility for crimes against
peace had existed already before the London Agreement gave the Tribunal jurisdic-
tion over these crimes. Otherwise, it would have had to apply Article 6 of the
Nuremberg Charter retroactively. In order to avoid the nullum crimen problem, the
Tribunal thus needed to find a norm, which had stipulated international criminal
responsibility of state officials for waging war before the Nazis began their interna-
tional acts of aggression in 1938.
The first international treaty that attempted to outlaw war as means of national
policy was the Kellogg-Briand Pact of 1928 (Roscher 2004). In article 1 of that
treaty, the “High Contracting Parties solemnly declare in the names of their respec-
tive peoples that they condemn recourse to war for the solution of international
controversies and renounce it, as an instrument of national policy in their relations
with one another.” No explicit references to collective or individual criminal respon-
sibility were to be found in the Kellogg-Briand Pact. Nonetheless, it constituted the
only international treaty that could serve as an applicable pre-war rule restricting the
ius ad bellum for the Tribunal.
But how could the Nuremberg military Tribunal deduce criminal responsibility
of individuals from the Pact, which had merely declared war waged by states under
specific circumstances illegal under international law? The Tribunal at the outset
conceded that the Kellogg-Briand Pact had not explicitly foreseen individual crimi-
nal responsibility but nonetheless attempted to develop individual responsibility by
interpretation. The main argument for individual criminal responsibility under the
Pact was a constructed analogy with existing national practices of individual crimi-
nal prosecution for violations of the rules of The Hague Conventions on interna-
tional humanitarian law. The Tribunal thus sought to transfer legal developments in
the criminalization of the ius in bello (Hague Conventions) in the early twentieth
century to the ius ad bellum area (Kellogg-Briand Pact):
[I]t is argued that the Pact does not expressly enact that such wars are crimes, or set up
courts to try those who make such wars. To that extent the same is true with regard to the
11
Two defendants found guilty of “crimes against peace” successfully pleaded for mitigating cir-
cumstances: Neurath was sentenced to 15 years and Dönitz to 10 years imprisonment.
5 Kelsen and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials 93
laws of war contained in the Hague Convention. The Hague convention of 1907 prohibited
resort to certain methods of waging war. These included the inhumane treatment of prison-
ers, the employment of poisoned weapons, the improper use of flags of truce, and similar
matters. Many of these prohibitions had been enforced long before the date of the
Convention; but since 1907 there have certainly been crimes, punishable as offences against
the laws of war; yet the Hague Convention nowhere designates such practices as criminal,
nor is any sentence prescribed, nor is any mention made of a court to try and punish offend-
ers. For many years past, however, military tribunals have tried and punished individuals
guilty of violating the rules of land warfare laid down by this Convention (The Trial of
German Major War Criminals. Proceedings of the International Military Tribunal sitting at
Nuremberg, Germany: Judgement of 30th September–1st October 1946: 40).
With this justification, which the Tribunal used to overcome the nullum crimen
problem, for the first time in history international judges tried the “crime of
aggression.”
It needs to be mentioned at the outset that both Kelsen and Morgenthau did not
oppose the conviction of Nazi Officials in general. Both defended the need to try
high-ranking Nazi officials for the crimes committed inside and outside of Germany
since 1933. And neither saw the at least partly retroactive character of the judgment
as a legally insurmountable obstacle to the Tribunal. Kelsen expressed two main
criticisms of the judgment: first, its flawed attempt to deduce international criminal
94 J. von Bernstorff
responsibility from the Kellogg-Briand Pact; second, the insufficient legal founda-
tion of the trial in absence of the consent of the vanquished states and the related lost
opportunity for the international community to establish individual criminal respon-
sibility in international law generally via a universal multilateral instrument.
As to “crimes against peace,” Kelsen clearly rejected the Tribunal’s attempt to
justify the assumption, by way of an analogy with the Hague conventions, that crim-
inal responsibility could be inferred from the Kellogg-Briand Pact:
The differences between the Hague Convention on the rules of warfare and the [Kellogg-
Briand] Pact is that the former can be violated by acts of state as well as by acts of private
persons, whereas the latter can be violated only by acts of states. The [Kellogg-Briand] Pact
does not—as does the Hague Convention—forbid acts of private persons (Kelsen 1947:
161).
Given that the Kellogg-Briand Pact, unlike the Hague Conventions, did not oblige
or authorise the state parties to punish under their own laws the individuals, who in
their capacity as organs of a State waged war in contravention of the Pact, Art. 6 of
the Nuremberg Charter in Kelsen’s view had created genuinely new law, instead of
applying the Pact.
According to his interpretation of the events in Nuremberg, the application of the
newly established “crimes against peace” to acts of aggression that were committed
during the “Third Reich” through the Nuremberg judgment was clearly a form of
retroactive legislation and punishment. However, international law did not have a
clear rule recognizing the prohibition on retroactive legislation, and in most domes-
tic legal systems the rule was only valid with important exceptions. Because it was
not an established rule of international law, the Allies in 1945 did not violate inter-
national legal rules by authorising the application of these newly established crimes
to acts committed during the war (Kelsen 1947: 164). There were simply no appli-
cable rules that prohibited the new rules established by the London Agreement.
Kelsen at this juncture did not explicitly refer to the Lotus Principle or the Kantian
negative rule according to which, in the absence of a specific prohibition, restric-
tions upon the freedom of the Allies to establish retroactive legislation through the
London Agreement could not have been presumed (S.S. Lotus (Fr. v. Turk.), 1927
P.C.I.J. (ser. A) No. 10 (Sept. 7)). But in the absence of a legal prohibition, the ques-
tion for Kelsen could now indeed be assessed on moral grounds or based on “gen-
eral principles of justice.” And for him there were good “moral” reasons to allow
retroactive punishment of those persons “who are morally responsible for the inter-
national crime of the second World War” (Kelsen 1947: 165) The fact that there was
no clear rule against retroactive legislation in international law and that there was a
demand of moral justice to punish the perpetrators led Kelsen to endorse retroactive
punishment in Nuremberg.
Much more worrying for Kelsen seems to have been his second main point of crit-
icism, namely the limited value of the Tribunal for the advancement of international
law. Very much in the late nineteenth century German international law tradition,
Kelsen had always judged international law against the background of highly devel-
oped and formalised Western national legal systems. Hence his labelling of
5 Kelsen and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials 95
international law as a “primitive” law, which still had to rely on custom and decen-
tralised legislation, enforcement and adjudication.12 The move from collective to
individual responsibility was a decisive evolutionary step in turning a primitive legal
order into a developed one. Analogous to the development of the modern state, inter-
national law was supposed to move from the phase of privately declared vendettas or
blood feuds to the stage of judicially-controlled individual criminal responsibility.
The problem with Nuremberg thus was that the Allies had failed to advance gen-
eral international law to that desired stage of development. They had failed to do so
due to various shortcomings in the legal architecture of the Nuremberg Tribunal.
There was first the missing consent to the London Agreement of those states that
had lost the war and whose nationals were being tried. The Allies, exercising sover-
eign rights for Germany through the Allied Control Council, had not made the effort
to formally declare Germany’s consent to the trial. For Kelsen, the absence of the
consent of the European Axis powers was problematic:
If, however, a tribunal is instituted to make individuals criminally responsible for their
State’s violation of a treaty, it is not exactly an improvement of general international law to
establish that tribunal without the consent of the State accused of the treaty violation.
(Kelsen 1947: 168). While admitting that this was more a formal rather then a sub-
stantive charge against the judgment, Kelsen moves on to the main point of his cri-
tique. What really impaired the authority of the judgment was that the rules
established by the London Agreement had not been established as general principles
of international law but as rules applicable only to vanquished states by the victors
(Kelsen 1947: 170). Through its asymmetrical establishment and application, the
London Agreement had the character of a “privilegium odiosum.” This impression
was aggravated by the fact that the Tribunal was exclusively composed of represen-
tatives of victorious states directly affected by the crimes over which the Tribunal
had jurisdiction. Representatives of neutral states were excluded from the bench.
The Allies became judges in their own cause.13
The Nuremberg trials in their basic architecture had not lived up to the principle
of formal equality before the law, which for Kelsen was the very essence and unique
12
Kelsen agrees with the argument put forth by the Tribunal itself:
In the first place, it is to be observed that the maxim nullum crimen sine lege is not a limita-
tion of sovereignty, but is in general a principle of justice. To assert that it is unjust to punish
those who in defiance of treaties and assurances have attacked neighboring states without
warning is obviously untrue, for in such circumstances the attacker must know that he is
doing wrong, and so far from it being unjust to punish him, it would be unjust if his wrong
were allowed to go unpunished
property of law as a specific social technique that was distinguishable from every
other form to exercise power over human beings (Kelsen 1941c: 70 et seq.). All in
all, Kelsen in 1947 saw Nuremberg as a lost opportunity to move from collective
responsibility to individual responsibility in general international law. Not only had
the Allies failed to enshrine this principle in a legal document of general application,
such as the U.N. Charter, they also had missed the opportunity of providing a his-
torical example for the neutral application of this principle in line with the ideal of
formal equality.
According to Morgenthau, the Allies in Nuremberg were not only judging in their
own cause, three of them even were accomplices of the Nazi move towards war at
one time or another.
By comparing the Nuremberg trial to a “punitive trial” in the scholastic tradition,
Morgenthau reminded the Allies that the scholastic just war tradition had limited
and qualified the right of the princes to pass judgment on the justice of the enemy’s
cause in war (Morgenthau 1962: 378). Morgenthau polemically observed a “flood
of moralizing legend” and criticized the Allies for mistaking “the voice of the victor
for the voice of Divine Justice.” A crime of aggression adjudicated by the victors in
a punitive trial was inherently problematic in its inclination to hypocritical condem-
nation of the enemy by those who win the war. A modern and thus secular revitaliza-
tion of a just war concept in international relations was a dangerous undertaking.
The reason was that the foundational circumstances of the scholastic concept had
long vanished; namely the moral unity of Christendom and the originally rather
strict doctrinal limitations of punitive wars (Morgenthau 1962: 378). Without these
preconditions, a modern punitive war was problematic in its inherent tendency to
demonise the opponent and to absolve itself of any wrongdoings by moralizing its
own cause for, and conduct in, war. Both of Morgenthau’s main intellectual reference
5 Kelsen and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials 97
points, namely Carl Schmitt’s concept of the political and Kelsen’s pure theory of
law, shared his Nietzschean critical sensibility with regard to the moralisation of
politics and law.
In his seminal Politics Among Nations of 1948, Morgenthau only devotes a few
lines to the Nuremberg Trials. According to his reading of the legal debate on
Nuremberg there was:
…no way of stating with any degree of authority whether any country which went to war
after 1929 in pursuance of its national policies has violated a rule of international law and
is liable before international law for its violation; or whether only those individuals respon-
sible for preparing and declaring the Second World War are liable in this way; or whether
all countries and individuals which will prepare for, and wage aggressive war in the future
will thus be liable.
14
Also critical of the qualification of the breach of the ius ad bellum Paulus (2010, 1121).
98 J. von Bernstorff
violations of the ius ad bellum in the future. This highly flexible substantive stan-
dard comes with the institutional privilege of the Great Power: the ability to domi-
nate U.N. Security Council decisions and to block investigations into alleged
violations of the crime of aggression.15 As long as it seems politically unimaginable
or even technically impossible for the ICC to indict leaders of the most powerful
nations for waging illegal aggression, the promise of peace and global justice
through international criminal law is likely to remain a distant dream at best and
another “moralizing legend” at worst.16
References
Carr, Edward Hallet. 1939. The twenty year’s crisis, 1919–1939 An introduction to the study of
international relations. London: Macmillan.
Kelsen, Hans. 1929. Wesen und Entwicklung der Staatsgerichtsbarkeit. Überprüfung von
Verwaltungsakten durch die öffentlichen Gerichte. H. Triepel, H. Kelsen and M. Layer (eds.),
Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer, Heft 5, Tagung vom 23.
und 24. April 1928 in Wien, Berlin und Leipzig: W. de Gruyter: 30–88.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. The legal process and international order. London: The New Commonwealth
Research Bureau Publications.
Kelsen, Hans. 1936. Sanktionen sind Sache des Gerichts. Geneva Press Service 10 July 1936: 1–3.
Kelsen, Hans. 1939a. Les resolutions de la S.D.N. concernant la separation du Pacte et des Traités
de Paix. Revue de Droit International et de Législation Comparée 20: 101–113.
Kelsen, Hans. 1939b. Revision des Völkerbundstatus. In Legal technique in international law. A
textual critique of the League Covenant. Geneva: Geneva Research Center.
Kelsen, Hans. 1941a. International peace by court or by government? American Journal of
Sociology 46: 571–581.
Kelsen, Hans. 1941b. The Law as a specific social technique. The University of Chicago Law
Review 9: 75–97.
Kelsen, Hans. 1941c. The essential conditions of international justice. Proceedings of the Thirty-
fifth Annual Meeting of the American Society of International Law 35: 70–98.
15
In general, the “determination of an act of aggression by an organ outside the Court shall be
without prejudice to the Court’s own findings under this Statute” (Art. 15bis (9)) ICC Review
Conference, Resolution RC/Res.6, The Crime of Aggression, adopted at the 13th plenary meeting,
on 11 June 2010, by consensus and annexes, Annex I. Hence, the Court is not bound by the assess-
ment of the UN Security Council. However, the UN Security Council can always block the inves-
tigation (Art 15bis (8)), RC/Res.6 Annex I.
16
The jurisdiction of the Court over the crime of aggression is further limited by the two following
provisions of the “Kampala compromise”:
The Court may, in accordance with article 12, exercise jurisdiction over a crime of aggres-
sion, arising from an act of aggression committed by a State Party, unless that State Party
has previously declared that it does not accept such jurisdiction by lodging a declaration
with the Registrar. The withdrawal of such a declaration may be effected at any time and
shall be considered by the State Party within three years.
(15bis (4)) “In respect of a State that is not a party to this Statute, the Court shall not exercise
its jurisdiction over the crime of aggression when committed by that State’s nationals or on its ter-
ritory”; (15bis (5)).
5 Kelsen and Morgenthau on the Nuremberg Trials 99
Kelsen, Hans. 1942. Law and peace in international relations. The Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures
1940–41. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944a. The strategy for peace. American Journal of Sociology 49: 381–389.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944b. Peace through law. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945. The old and the new league: The Covenant and the Dumbarton Oaks propos-
als. American Journal of International Law 39: 45–83.
Kelsen, Hans. 1947. Will the judgement in the Nuremberg Trial constitute a precedent in interna-
tional law? The International Law Quarterly 1: 153–171.
Koskenniemi, Martti. 2000. Carl Schmitt, Hans Morgenthau, and the image of law in international
relations. In The role of law in international politics. Essays in international relations and
international politics, ed. M. Byers, 17–34. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Koskenniemi, Martti. 2006. Morgenthau’s books on international law with Kelsen. In Twenty-five
year memorial commemoration to the life of Hans Morgenthau (1904–2005), ed. G.O. Mazur,
152–174. New York: Semenko Foundation.
Kreß, Claus, and Leonie von Holtzendorff. 2010. The Kampala Compromise on the crime of
aggression. Journal of International Criminal Justice 8: 1179–1217.
Morgenthau, Hans Joachim. 1929. Die internationale Rechtspflege, ihr Wesen und ihre Grenzen.
Leipzig: Noske.
Morgenthau, Hans Joachim. 1948 revised 2006. Politics among nations. The struggle for power
and peace, revised by K. W. Thompson and W. D. Clinton, 7th ed., New York: McGraw-Hill.
Morgenthau, Hans Joachim. 1962. The decline of democratic politics. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
Nippold, Otfried. 1917. Die Gestaltung des Völkerrechts nach dem Kriege. Zürich: Institut Orell
Füssli.
Paulus, Andreas. 2010. Second thoughts on the crime of aggression. European Journal of
International Law 20: 1117–1128.
Roscher, Bernhard. 2004. Der Briand Kellogg Pakt von 1928. Baden- Baden: Nomos.
Scheuerman, William E. 2009. Hans J. Morgenthau: Realism and beyond. Cambridge: Polity
Press.
Telman, D.A. Jeremy. 2010. A path not taken: Hans Kelsen pure theory of law in the land of the
legal realists. In Hans Kelsen anderswo/Hans Kelsen abroad, ed. Robert Walter, Clemens
Jabloner, and Klaus Zeleny, 353–376. Vienna: Manz.
von Bernstorff, Jochen. 2010. The public international law theory of Hans Kelsen. Believing in
universal law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chapter 6
Hans Kelsen, The Second World War
and the U.S. Government
Thomas Olechowski
6.1 Introduction
Does the pure theory of law enable lawyers to solve legal problems, or is it just an
academic theory, highly sophisticated, but without practical relevance? Whoever
thinks that the latter is true should be aware that Hans Kelsen himself worked not
only as a university professor, but also as a legal advisor. In addition to Kelsen’s
years as an advisor for the Austrian state chancellery, drafting the Austrian federal
constitution of 1920, his service during World War I (WWI) and World War II
(WWII) must also be highlighted.
Indeed, both wars were of the highest importance for Kelsen’s career. During
WWI, Kelsen worked in the Austro-Hungarian ministry of war. In its last months
Kelsen served as a personal legal advisor to Rudolf Stöger-Steiner, the last minister
of war of the Habsburg monarchy. In this capacity, he wrote several memoranda on
practical legal problems, which gave him the opportunity to apply some results of
the pure theory.1 The minister was very satisfied and supported him in securing a
professorship at the University of Vienna, which was the real starting point of
Kelsen’s career (Busch 2009).
Twenty-seven years later, much had changed. Kelsen now lived as a refugee in
the United States. But, once again, the military and other federal institutions—this
time, not Austro-Hungarian, but American institutions—needed the expertise of the
1
One example: In 1917, Kelsen was ordered to write on some special problems resulting from the
seizure of horses for the army – and wrote an extensive memorandum on a highly theoretical level
concerning the question whether an administrative decision can be revoked. The text of this memo-
randum has been published in Oberkofler and Rabofsky (1988: 154–158).
T. Olechowski (*)
University of Vienna, Vienna, Austria
Hans Kelsen Institute, Vienna, Austria
e-mail: [email protected]
world-famous legal philosopher to solve legal problems resulting from a war. And,
once again, they thanked him by helping him to find a university.
Kelsen came to the United States for the first time in 1936. He came to help cele-
brate the Tercentenary of Harvard College. On this occasion, Kelsen was to be
awarded an honorary degree.2 His professional and personal situation at this time
was very difficult. Dismissed from the University of Cologne by the Nazi Regime
in 1933, the 55-year-old scholar could find only temporary shelter at the Institute
Universitaire des Hautes Etudes Internationales in Geneva. Of the German-speaking
universities, only the German University in Prague offered him a new professorship,
where he was supposed to start his lectures in the fall of 1936. But Kelsen knew of
the strong anti-Semitic tendencies present also in Czechoslovakia and so he used the
occasion of his trip to America to ask if he could stay there permanently—at first
without any success.
Back in Europe, his worst fears came true. In Prague, anti-Semitic students not
only boycotted his lectures but also started riots, so that the minister had to close the
university for several weeks. Kelsen taught in Prague for only three semesters before
Hitler occupied Czechoslovakia and Kelsen had to return to Geneva (Olechowski
and Busch 2010: 1122). On September 1, 1939—the day Hitler attacked Poland—
Kelsen was in the United States again, participating in the International Congress
for the Unity of Sciences, and again he tried to get in contact with American univer-
sities (Ehs and Gassner 2012). His friends in America also looked for opportunities
for Kelsen to stay in the United States, for example at Columbia University,
Princeton University or Harvard University. It is notable that they asked the elite
universities first, which made the search for a place to stay even more difficult. But
lesser-known universities, such as the University of Illinois, also rejected Kelsen.
Kelsen and his pure theory of law appeared to be badly suited to American legal
education, and there were many younger and more flexible lawyers from Europe,
who fled to the United States and competed with Kelsen for the few free positions
at U.S. law schools (Feichtinger 2009).
In the end, the New School for Social Research made it possible for Hans Kelsen
and his wife to emigrate from Europe. A “University in Exile” had been founded at
this New York City college in 1933, with the purpose of bringing scholars from
Europe to America (Rutkoff and Scott 1986). It gave them a first engagement—
which was necessary for a permanent visa—and supported them in finding a perma-
nent position at another school in the United States. Kelsen indeed never wanted to
stay in New York. Only a few weeks after his arrival in the United States (June 21,
1940), he moved on to Harvard, where his friend Roscoe Pound had established the
“Oliver Wendell Holmes lectureship,” which still exists today, with the support of
2
The ceremony is documented in The Tercentenary of Harvard College (1937), Cambridge (Mass.).
6 The Second World War and the U.S. Government 103
the Rockefeller Foundation, and Hans Kelsen delivered the inaugural Holmes lec-
ture. He stayed in Harvard for 2 years, from 1940 to 1942, and lectured on the topic
of “Law and Peace in International Relations.” He was building upon ideas that he
had previously articulated during his time in Geneva and then developed further in
numerous articles, which finally led to the publication of his monograph, Peace
through Law, in June 1944 (Kelsen 1934, 1944a; Olechowski 2014: 123).
Kelsen was of the opinion that the law should directly serve the cause of peace.
The League of Nations should be replaced by a “Permanent League of the
Maintenance of Peace,” and this league should be equipped with an International
Court of Justice that should have extensive jurisdiction. It would punish war crimi-
nals and those who wage illegitimate wars. To put it more precisely, the court would
not only have jurisdiction over states but also over individuals. Kelsen’s book, which
was published shortly after the Allied invasion of Normandy, must have received
quite some resonance outside of the world of experts in international law. It must
have been these writings that introduced Kelsen’s name to Washington, D.C.—how
exactly this occurred, we unfortunately do not know. However, there is a letter in
Kelsen’s estate that was written to him by Michigan professor Lawrence Preuss,
who worked for the State Department at that time, in which Preuss informed Kelsen
that his book, Peace through Law, had been recommended to him by an unnamed
U.S. Senator.3
At this stage, Kelsen had already ceased to teach at Harvard and had moved on
to Berkeley. His endeavors to gain a permanent position at Harvard had failed; in
Berkeley, too, he was only a “visiting professor” for 1 year in 1942/43, and then,
from 1943 to 1945, a simple “lecturer.”4 In addition, his employment was not at the
Law School but at the Political Science Department. His career and financial situa-
tion were in a desperate state, and we may assume that the 63-year-old scholar was
genuinely happy to accept the invitation to serve the U.S. government in some
capacity in Washington, D.C.
The first governmental agency that asked Kelsen for his cooperation was the Bureau
of Areas of the President’s Foreign Economic Administration. This office had been
established in September 1943 to unify and consolidate governmental activities
3
Hans Kelsen Institute Vienna, Hans Kelsen Estate 16c9.61. Lawrence Preuss (1905–1956) was
professor of international law at the University of Michigan and legal advisor to the State
Department as well as the UNWCC; see Bishop 1956. I want to thank Jason Kropsky, participant
of the 2014 Kelsen conference in Chicago, for the identification of Lawrence Preuss. The name of
the Senator, though, is still an enigma.
4
University of California, Berkeley, personal files Hans Kelsen, letters from June 30, 1942, July 2,
1943 and May 26, 1944.
104 T. Olechowski
relating to foreign economic affairs. The Bureau of Areas made broad program deci-
sions regarding Foreign Economic Administration operations in all areas, coordi-
nating such programs and harmonizing them with State Department foreign policy
and with military activities and requests (United States Government Manual
Summer 1944, Washington 1944, 68).
On May 5, 1944, Kelsen, by invitation of the Bureau of Areas, took part in a State
Department meeting and then also summarized his thoughts in a memorandum.5
The topic of this meeting was the fate of Austria after the end of the war. Just a few
months earlier, the Allies had stated in the Moscow Declaration of October 30,
1943, that Austria “[should] be liberated from German domination.” The annexation
of 1938 was regarded as “null and void.” Surprisingly, Kelsen aimed to narrow the
legal meaning of this Declaration as much as possible. If the “annexation” was
indeed “null and void” and Austria would only have been “occupied,” as a result,
then, at the end of the war, Austria would revert to the political status that it had had
when it lost its independence in 1938. The legal consequence of this would be that
Kurt Schuschnigg’s Austro-fascist regime, which had controlled Austria from 1933
to 1938, would return to power! “It is evident that the three Powers do not intend to
establish a fascistic State” (Kelsen, Austria (see footnote 5) page 6). Thus, clearly a
political motive led Kelsen to argue that the annexation, while illegal, had neverthe-
less been effective and valid in terms of international law. Accordingly, Austria
would have to emancipate itself from Germany by means of a revolutionary act,
preferably in a referendum.
As a preliminary question, Kelsen had to deal with the problem of Germany’s
future after the war. And in this case, too, he argued in favor of a radical breach with
the NS regime, which at this point in time was still in power there. Kelsen also
warned of making the same mistake as in 1919 by signing a peace treaty with the
defeated Germany; such a treaty could once again only take the form of a dictate, as
it had been the case with the Treaty of Versailles, and no German politician could
sign it without having to fear for his life. Rather it should be the Allies’ aim to inflict
a complete military defeat onto Germany—he used the term “debellatio”—and then
to establish a condominium of the Allied Powers over Germany. This condominium
could then build a new German state, which would not be linked to the old regime,
and regulate all relationships to this new state at the Allies’ pleasure. Also, this
would make it possible to bring the German war criminals before an Allied court—
Hans Kelsen later also published parts of this memorandum in the American Journal
for International Law, but only the parts that concerned Germany, not those on
Austria (Kelsen 1944b).
Almost exactly 1 year later, on June 5, 1945, the Allies postulated in what came
to be known as their Declaration of Berlin that they had gained “the supreme author-
ity and powers with respect to Germany”. Kelsen was of the opinion that the Allies
5
The 15-page memorandum bears the title Austria: Her actual legal status and re-establishment as
an independent State and is dated Berkeley, June 1, 1944. It has been published in Olechowski
(2016) 130–140.
6 The Second World War and the U.S. Government 105
had done exactly what he had suggested 1 year ago. He interpreted the wording of
the Declaration of Berlin, which stated that the German land and air forces as well
as the German navy were “completely defeated,” as referring to a “debellatio”
(Kelsen 1945a: 518). The purpose of assuming “supreme authority” was hence not
to avoid further aggression, but to re-establish law, order and administration in the
country. He further argued that it was not a “belligerent occupation,” because that
would necessarily lead to the conclusion that Germany had not ceased to exist. In
Kelsen’s point of view it was problematic that the Allies had deliberately declared
not to intend an annexation of Germany, because according to the traditional doc-
trine of international law a “subjugation” was only possible after the annexation of
the losing party’s territory by the winning party. This was obviously not the case
because Germany had clearly ceased to exist as a state; therefore, it appeared as if
the only solution to this problem was to qualify Germany as “no state’s land,” which,
in Kelsen’s opinion, was “simply absurd” (Kelsen 1945a: 521). In order to solve the
problem, Kelsen suggested assuming that a condominium of all four Allied Powers
had been established.
Unfortunately we know very little about the reactions of the U.S. authorities to
Kelsens’ approach. In contrast to Kelsen’s conception the American military gover-
nor Lucius D. Clay declared that Germany still existed as a state. Some members of
the Office of Military Government for Germany (OMGUS) were impressed by
Kelsen’s theories because he denied the applicability of the Hague Convention
(Menzel 1947: 1015). Also, an officer of the Judge Advocate General of the
U.S. Army stated that Kelsen’s suggestions were “excellent” and “appear[ed] to be
legally unimpeachable,” especially in respect to the punishment of war criminals
(Smith 1982: 84). But an official statement does not survive. A series of articles
published under supervision of the U.S. authorities in the Berlin daily newspaper
“Der Tagesspiegel” seems to have picked up and followed Kelsen’s ideas. Apart
from that, however, it appears as if the Americans only wanted to exploit some of
Kelsen’s ideas but not to adopt them (and their consequences) in their entirety
(Olechowski 2013: 546). For instance, a legal opinion by the U.S. military govern-
ment dating from March 17, 1947, only quotes the wording of the Declaration of
Berlin, without drawing any conclusions at all. This opinion compared the situation
in Germany to the occupation of Cuba by the United States after the war with Spain,
which obviously was a poor comparison, as in 1948 the U.S. Supreme Court would
declare that the United States was still at war with Germany.6
In Germany, Kelsen’s propositions were received with far greater skepticism.
There, a storm of indignation greeted Kelsen’s view that Germany had ceased to
exist as a sovereign state. At the first post-war congress of German international law
scholars in 1947, the participants overwhelmingly adopted the view that Germany
had never ceased to exist. However, at the 1954 congress, only a minority of the
participating scholars still thought so (Olechowski 2013: 547).
6
International lawyers differed on this issue. See for example Kunz (1950). Kunz had been a dis-
ciple of Hans Kelsen in Austria and later professor at the University of Toledo, Ohio.
106 T. Olechowski
Since then many things, such as the Cold War and the reunification of Germany,
have taken place. Nevertheless the German Constitutional Court ruling of 1973,
finding that Germany had at all times continued to exist, continues to be valid.7
The second field of studies where Kelsen was quite active concerned the punish-
ment of war criminals. To this end, the Allies had set up the “United Nations War
Crimes Commission” (UNWCC) in 1943.8 The main duty of this commission was
to prepare the trials of war criminals that were supposed to take place once the war
was over. In addition, the Judge Advocate General of the U.S. Army had set up a
“War Crime Office” (WCO) with Brigadier General John M. Weir as its director.
The WCO had to prepare the works of Judge Robert H. Jackson, member of the
UNWCC and chief prosecutor in Nuremberg in 1946.
Kelsen had already dealt with the problem of the punishment of war criminals,
not only in his book, but also in a special article on “Collective and Individual
Responsibility in International Law with Particular Regard to the Punishment of
War Criminals,” published in the California Law Review in 1943 (Kelsen 1943).
It is not clear whether the WCO contacted Kelsen, or if Kelsen made efforts to
get in touch with it. The only thing known for sure is that Kelsen from April 1945
on—maybe even earlier—was sending letters to the WCO, and in the summer of
1945 he travelled to D.C. twice to participate in meetings.9 The results of these
meetings were eight memoranda published by Hans Kelsen on request of the
WCO. The memoranda were:
1. On the Draft Executive Agreement Relating to the Prosecution of European Axis
War Criminals,
2. On the Agreement for the Prosecution of European Axis War Criminals,
3. On the Rule against Ex Post Facto Laws,
4. On the Definition of Aggression,
5. On the Question: “Is Launching a War of Aggression a Crime?”,
6. On the Instrument of Surrender Signed by the Japanese Government,
7. On the Punishment of War Criminals and the Charter of the United Nations,
8. On War Crimes as Related to the Preparation, Launching, and Opening of
Hostilities without Previous Warning.
7
Decision of the German Bundesverfassungsgericht, July 31, 1973, Entscheidungen des
Bundesverfassungsgerichts 36, 1.
8
See the homepage of a new research project of the Centre for International Studies and Diplomacy:
www.unwcc.org [online February 5, 2014].
9
Hans Kelsen Institute Vienna, Hans Kelsen Estate 15p.58.
6 The Second World War and the U.S. Government 107
Memoranda no. 2, 4 and 5 have been located at the National Archives in College
Park, Maryland.10 Memorandum no. 3 could be identical to an article that Kelsen
published in the “Judge Advocate Journal” in 1945 (Kelsen 1945b). The list itself
was kept with the files and bears no date. It might be the case that Kelsen produced
other memoranda as well, which might be identical with his other relevant publica-
tions. On the other hand, the contents of some of the memoranda, such as the one on
the Japanese surrender, remain unknown.
The individual texts should not be read in isolation. Although they deal with dif-
ferent aspects of international criminal law, they are interrelated in many ways.
Some of the propositions go back to ideas published earlier in his book, Peace
through Law, or in his other, previously mentioned articles on international criminal
law. They are of great interest also from the perspective of legal theory, as Kelsen
was able to apply his pure theory to address practical problems.
In particular, Kelsen was able to solve one of the main problems of the Nuremberg
trials: How can the war criminals be punished if the legal basis for the trial was
established after the crimes had been committed? The problem is well known in the
United States as the problem of “ex post facto laws,” as it is regulated in article 1,
section 9 of the U.S. constitution: “No Bill of Attainder or ex post facto Law shall
be passed.” Kelsen discussed the genesis of this provision and its meaning in the
context of natural law. If the law is “a rule prescribing future conduct of man,” the
prohibition on ex post facto laws would be “a logical necessity” (Kelsen 1943: 8).
But legal positivism—Kelsen does not use the term “pure theory” at all—has a dif-
ferent understanding of the essence of law. The law is only “an indirect regulation
of the conduct of the subject,” but directly a prescription, under which conditions
“the organ [is] authorized to execute a sanction” (Kelsen 1945b: 8). So, for legal
positivism, the rule on ex post facto laws is not a logical necessity but only a provi-
sion of positive law.
The next argument, Kelsen was aware, was even more curious: “Retroactive laws
are held to be unjust because it hurts our feelings of justice to inflict upon an indi-
vidual a sanction which he did not foresee, since it was not yet attached to his con-
duct, and consequently this conduct was not yet illegal,” Kelsen stated. But what
about the opposite situation? If a law repeals or softens an older criminal law, or is
advantageous to the subject in any other way, it would be unjust not to apply it in
cases committed before the new law was made. The third argument is that the law
must be known in order to applicable. This is also not true, stated Kelsen, quoting
Blackstone to the effect that ignorance of the law is no excuse (Kelsen 1945b: 9).
“The result of the preceding analysis is that the rule against ex post facto legisla-
tion must be interpreted as restrictively as possible” (Kelsen 1945b: 10). From this
general statement, Kelsen went on to discuss the London Agreement of the four
10
See the acknowledgments at the end of this article. Together with the full text of three memo-
randa, we also found a list including the titles of the others: National Archives and Records
Administration (NARA), RG 153, Records of the Office of the Judge Advocate General (Army),
War Crimes Branch, General and Administrative Records (Set-Up Files) 1944–1949, Box No. 11.
108 T. Olechowski
Allied Powers of August 8, 1945, concerning war criminals. He was of the opinion
that it was permitted by international law to establish rules with retroactive force by
an international treaty. By passing a retroactive law, it was possible not only to bring
the German Empire but also individuals such as politicians, journalists and industri-
alists to justice.11 Precedents for this had already been set after WWI, when the
“Leipzig trials,” in which German war criminals were condemned by the German
Supreme Court (Reichsgericht), took place (Segesser 2010: 225; United Nations
War Crimes Commission 1948: 48–51). However, concerning the “Leipzig trials,”
the Allies were of the opinion that the verdicts rendered there had been too mild.
Probably for this reason, Article 227 of the Treaty of Versailles stated that Emperor
Wilhelm II had to be surrendered to the Allies for trial.12
Closer examination reveals that the only problem was to establish international
jurisdiction for the prosecution of the crimes, not the prosecution of the crimes as
such, because all of the crimes were established as criminal violations long before
they were committed. Starting WWII had been a violation of the Kellogg-Briand
Pact. Most of the atrocities were “ordinary crimes according to the municipal law of
the persons to be accused, valid at the moment they were committed. […] Even if
the atrocities are covered by municipal law, […] they are certainly open violations
of the principles of morality generally recognized by civilized peoples and hence
were, at least, morally not innocent or indifferent when they were committed”
(Kelsen 1945b: 10).
Only as far as the crime of “starting a war of aggression” was concerned, Kelsen
had to admit that so far there had been no law establishing the penal responsibility
of a particular person who committed this crime.13 Generally speaking, Kelsen did
not favor the term “war of aggression,” as he considered it misleading—interna-
tional law using the term in a way very different from its original, military
meaning.
Kelsen convincingly supported this position with several examples, beginning
with the draft Treaty of Mutual Assistance submitted to the member states of the
League of Nations by the Council of the League on September 29, 1923, leading to
the Geneva Protocol for the Pacific Settlement of International Disputes of October
22, 1924, and ending with the Convention for the Definition of Aggression of July
3, 1933, signed by the U.S.S.R. and seven of her neighbors. Although the first two
instruments never came into force and the third was a regional convention only, they
11
In his book, Peace through Law, Kelsen (1944a: 91) had stated that only the “Führer” should be
held accountable. When he wrote his memorandum in 1945, the suicide of Hitler was already
known in the States; Kelsen did not name the specific persons who should be held accountable and
said that this question was “very difficult”; see also Kelsen (1943: 530).
12
There was never such a trial, because the Netherlands granted asylum to the former Kaiser.
13
Hans Kelsen, Memorandum “Is’Launching a War of Aggression‘a Crime?”, in: Letter from John
M. Weir to the U.S. Chief of Counsel, dated July 13, 1945, with three documents: The mentioned
memorandum, a second memorandum by Kelsen on “The Definition of Aggression” and a third,
anonymous memorandum on “Aggression”. NARA, RG 0238, World War II War Crimes Records,
Office of the U.S. Chief of Counsel for the Prosecution of Axis Criminality, Entry# PI-21 52,
Personal Files (Lindenstrasse Files) 1945–1946, Container 2, ARC# 6120160.
6 The Second World War and the U.S. Government 109
all showed that aggression in international law did not merely refer to the “beginning
of hostilities” but was defined in a much more complex manner. For example, the
Geneva Convention of 1924 established several obligations for states to settle their
disputes peacefully. Therefore, the refusal to submit the dispute to a procedure of
pacific settlement or the refusal to comply with the decision or recommendation of
the agency competent to settle the dispute was an act of “aggression.”14 Wars waged
against states that failed to comply with the methods of peaceful settlement of dis-
putes would thus be considered “aggressive wars in the true and original sense of
the term,” but they would be legal. Even under the Kellogg-Briand Pact, which was
supposed to outlaw all aggressive wars, the war against a state that had violated the
pact was lawful even if a state not attacked by the violator of the pact initiated war
against this violator.”15
This led Kelsen to the conclusion that the principle of bellum justum (just war)
still existed in positive international law. This theory had been very controversial, at
least since the Kellogg-Briand Pact, when 62 states had “condemn[ed] recourse to
war for the solution of international controversies” and declared “that the settlement
or solution of all disputes or conflicts of whatever nature or of whatever origin they
may be, which may arise among them, shall never be sought except by pacific
means.” However, Kelsen (who noted that the Kellogg-Briand Pact did not use the
term “aggression” at all) showed that the Pact itself required its members to take up
arms in defense of peace, as no centralized executive power existed to enforce the
law in inter-state relations.
Indeed, when Nazi Germany started WWII in 1939, Germany did not declare
war on the United Kingdom and France; rather, these two declared war on Germany
(September 3, 1939). But Germany was the real aggressor, as it had attacked Poland
2 days earlier (September 1, 1939). This attack was a violation of the Kellogg-
Briand Pact and also a violation of a special non-aggression pact, concluded on
January 26, 1934, between Germany and Poland.16
“As to the question what kind of tribunal [should] be authorized to try war crimi-
nals, national or international, there can be little doubt that an international court is
much more fitted for this task than a national civil or military court”, Kelsen stated
already in 1943, calling to mind the Leipzig trials, which were held after WWI and
had very little effect (Kelsen 1943, 562). The punishment should be “an act of inter-
national justice, not the satisfaction of a thirst for revenge.” Therefore, also the
subjects of the victorious states who had committed war crimes should be trans-
ferred “to the same independent and impartial international tribunal” (Kelsen 1943,
564).
An international court corresponding to Kelsen’s idea was never set up in reality.
The Treaty of London, dating from August 8, 1945, which was signed by France,
Great Britain, the U.S.S.R. and the U.S.A, only provided for the punishment of
German war crimes. On the one hand, this tribunal was not what Kelsen had wished
14
Kelsen, Definition of Aggression (see footnote 13), p. 6.
15
Kelsen, Definition of Aggression (see footnote 13) p. 1.
16
Kelsen, Definition of Aggression (see footnote 13) p. 14.
110 T. Olechowski
6.5 Consequences
Kelsen’s work for the U.S. government had some positive effects for him. General
Weir, for instance, campaigned for Kelsen so that he very quickly received U.S. citi-
zenship (July 28, 1945).18 At the same time, the University of California decided
that Kelsen—in spite of his age—was a productive and “useful” teacher, and so it
offered him a full professorship.19 On June 21, 1945—more than 12 years after his
dismissal from Cologne in 1933—he was appointed full professor.
It is hard to say whether Kelsen’s work was an academic or political success.
Some developments were disappointing. For example, his memorandum on the con-
cept of aggressive war was forwarded to Justice Jackson, but at the Nuremberg
Trials, Jackson made only passing references to the meaning of “aggression,” which
were obviously not influenced by Kelsen’s thesis.20 On the other hand, Kelsen’s
opinion that it should be possible to set retroactive laws in force was adopted. The
Berlin Declaration of June 5, 1945, through which the Allies gained the supreme
authority with respect to Germany, can be seen as the implementation of Kelsen’s
ideas (although other interpretations are possible). Few lawyers had such a strong
influence on the development of international law in the war and post-war periods
as Hans Kelsen did.
Acknowledgments The article contains results of my project “Kelsen’s life in America (1940–
1973) and the diffusion of his legal theory across the globe”, funded by the Austrian Science Fund
(FWF; Project No. P 23747-G16). With this support, I made two trips to the National Archives in
College Park, Maryland, in 2012 together with Dr. Miriam Gassner, and in 2013 together with Dr.
Stefan Wedrac. I have to thank both of them for their support. Some parts of this article follow
Olechowski and Wedrac (2015). Special thanks also to Ramon Pils, DipTrans for the translation
and Dr. Gassner for the proof-reading of large parts of the text.
17
Kelsen, The Agreement for the Prosecution of European Axis War Criminals, NARA RG 153,
Box No. 11.
18
Hans Kelsen Institute Vienna, Hans Kelsen Estate 16c13.
19
University of California, Berkeley, personal files Hans Kelsen, Budget Committee Comments,
March 1945.
20
In his closing address at the Palace of Justice in Nuremberg on July 26, 1946, Jackson stated:
“We need not trouble ourselves about the many abstract difficulties that can be conjured up about
what constitutes aggression in doubtful cases.” See Jackson (1947) 127 and also the harsh criticism
of Jackson by Kelsen (1947).
6 The Second World War and the U.S. Government 111
References
Bishop Jr., William W. 1956. Lawrence Preuss, 1905–1956. The American Journal of International
Law 50: 907–909.
Busch, Jürgen. 2009. Hans Kelsen im Ersten Weltkrieg—Achsenzeit einer Weltkarriere. In Hans
Kelsen: Leben—Werk—Wirksamkeit, ed. Robert Walter, Werner Ogris and Thomas Olechowski,
57–80. Wien: Manz.
Ehs, Tamara and Miriam Gassner. 2012. Hans Kelsen (1881–1973). Legal scholar between Europe
and the Americas. In Transatlantic Perspectives. [http://www.transatlanticperspectives.org/
entry.php?rec=132] (online since 11/8, 2012; read 5/2, 2015).
Feichtinger, Johannes. 2009. Transatlantische Vernetzungen. Der Weg Hans Kelsens und seines
Kreises in die Emigration. In Hans Kelsen: Leben—Werk—Wirksamkeit, ed. Robert Walter,
Werner Ogris and Thomas Olechowski, 321–338. Wien: Manz.
Jackson, Robert H. 1947. The Nürnberg Case. New York: Knopf.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Die Technik des Völkerrechts und die Organisation des Friedens. Zeitschrift
für Öffentliches Recht 14: 240–255.
Kelsen, Hans. 1943. Collective and individual responsibility in international law with particular
regard to punishment of war criminals. California Law Review 31: 530–571.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944a. Peace through law. Chapell Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944b. The international legal status of Germany to be established immediately
upon termination of the War. The American Journal of International Law 38: 689–694.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945a. The legal status of Germany according to the Declaration of Berlin. The
American Journal of International Law 39: 518–526.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945b. The rule against ex post facto laws and the prosecution of Axis war criminals.
The Judge Advocate Journal 2/3: 8–12.
Kelsen, Hans. 1947. Will the judgment in the Nuremberg Trial Constitute a precedent in interna-
tional law? The International Law Quarterly 1: 153–171.
Kunz, Josef L. 1950. The status of occupied Germany under international law: A legal dilemma.
The Western Political Quarterly 3: 538–565.
Menzel, Eberhard. 1947. Zur völkerrechtlichen Lage Deutschlands. Europa-Archiv 2:
1009–1016.
Oberkofler, Gerhard, and Eduard Rabofsky. 1988. Hans Kelsen im Kriegseinsatz der k.u.k.
Wehrmacht. Frankfurt et al: Peter Lang.
Olechowski, Thomas. 2013. Kelsens Debellatio-These. Rechtshistorische und rechtstheoretische
Überlegungen zur Kontinuität von Staaten. In Gedenkschrift Robert Walter, ed. Clemens
Jabloner et al., 531–552. Wien: Manz.
Olechowski, Thomas. 2014. Kelsen als Pazifist. In Hans Kelsen: Die Aktualität eines großen
Rechtswissenschafters und Soziologen des 20. Jahrhunderts, ed. Nikitas Aliprantis and Thomas
Olechowski, 119–129. Wien: Manz.
Olechowski, Thomas. 2016. Hans Kelsens Gutachten zur Neugestaltung Österreichs und
Deutschlands nach dem Zweiten Weltkrieg. In Das internationale Wirken Hans Kelsens, ed.
Clemens Jabloner, Thomas Olechowski, and Klaus Zeleny, 121–140. Wien: Manz.
Olechowski, Thomas, and Jürgen Busch. 2010. Hans Kelsen als Professor an der Deutschen
Universität Prag. Biographische Aspekte der Kelsen-Sander-Kontroverse. In Československé
právo a právní věda v meziválečném období (1918–1938) a jejich místo ve střední Evropě, ed.
Karel Malý and Ladislav Soukup, 1106–1134. Praha: Nakladatelství Karolinum.
Olechowski, Thomas, and Stefan Wedrac. 2015. Hans Kelsen und Washington. In Bananen, Cola,
Zeitgeschichte. Oliver Rathkalb und das lange 20. Jahhundert, ed. Lucile Dreidemy and Maria
Wirth, 280–295. Wien: Böhlau.
112 T. Olechowski
Rutkoff, Peter M., and William B. Scott. 1986. New School. A History of the new school for social
research. New York/London: The Free Press/Collier Macmillan Publishers.
Segesser, Daniel Marc. 2010. Recht statt Rache oder Rache durch Recht? Die Ahndung von
Kriegsverbrechern in der internationalen wissenschaftlichen Debatte 1872–1945. Schöningh:
Paderborn et al.
Smith, Bradley. 1982. The American road to Nuremberg. Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.
United Nations War Crimes Commission. 1948. History of the United Nations War Crimes
Commission and the development of the Laws of War. London: His Majesty’s Stationery Office.
Part III
Kelsen in Unexplored Dialogues
Chapter 7
Arriving at Justice by a Process
of Elimination: Hans Kelsen and Leo Strauss
Elisabeth Lefort
7.1 Introduction
Dealing with the lack of reception of Hans Kelsen’s writings in the United States
(and maybe even beyond its borders), means pursuing at least two goals. The first
consists of formulating hypotheses concerning the reasons for such a lack of recep-
tion. The second is trying to overcome this situation, at least in part, by rereading
Kelsen’s texts in order to demonstrate how his thought is still relevant to our con-
temporary context. In this spirit, the following paper aims at a philosophical1 con-
frontation between Hans Kelsen and another author from the same period, namely
Leo Strauss.
The choice of comparing Kelsen with Strauss requires a justification straight-
away. One main justification for such a comparison lies in the fact that, despite their
similar backgrounds and experiences, the two thinkers pursued similar subject mat-
ters from very different theoretical perspectives.
1
One can find a comparative reading between Kelsen and Strauss in David Novak’s article,
Haunted by the Ghost of Weimar: Leo Strauss’ Critique of Hans Kelsen (2012). This chapter obvi-
ously benefits from Novak’s work, although it takes a different approach. The goal here is a philo-
sophical, not a historical, comparison of the two authors. More precisely, this presentation intends
to discover a common view on justice, and to go beyond the differences between Kelsen and
Strauss. Therefore, it aims at an interpretation of their texts. Moreover, the starting point here is
Kelsen’s moral relativism, while in David Novak’s article, the reading focuses more on Strauss’s
philosophy. The two respective comparative readings are not in conflict; they pursue different goals
and pose different questions.
E. Lefort (*)
University of Luxembourg, Luxembourg, Luxembourg
Catholic University of Louvain, Louvain-la-Neuve, Belgium
e-mail: [email protected]
On the one hand, they share strong biographical similarities. Both Kelsen and
Strauss left Europe around the same time to escape Nazism.2 On the other hand, a
look at their works reveals a strong theoretical antagonism that definitively sepa-
rates Kelsen from Strauss. This antagonism is so firm that it seems to prevent a
priori any attempt to reconcile their respective thoughts, especially when they deal
with the concepts of law and morality.
Moreover, even though the two scholars never directly confronted one another,
the theoretical opposition that divides them is surely well known. Kelsen’s name is
associated with his Pure Theory of Law, a book that had a decisive impact on the
juridical tradition of the twentieth century. In this work, Kelsen attempts to build a
pure legal science safeguarded from any ideological contamination. In fact, when he
mentions ideology, one of the things he is referring to is natural law theory. For his
part, Strauss is strongly associated with the denunciation of historicism. According
to him, historicism is the discourse responsible for the loss of natural right and its
meaning. Historicism holds that the world and human beings are necessarily linked
with, and determined by, their historical and cultural context. For Strauss, this idea
has contaminated all the modern human sciences and has thereby thrown people
into a practical world without any guiding principle(s). For Strauss, historicism
leads directly to nihilism.3 Due to this fact, Strauss calls for a rediscovery of natural
right, which can and should be accomplished with the help of philosophy.
From this standpoint, the opposition between the two authors seems to be diffi-
cult to overcome. While Kelsen rejects natural law and endorses moral relativism,
Strauss calls for a rediscovery of natural right and rejects moral relativism.
How can this evident opposition with Strauss aid one in understanding Kelsen’s
lack of reception in the United States? Strauss’s book, published contemporane-
ously with Kelsen’s writings, is a perfect reflection of the latter’s reception in the
United States. In his book, Strauss criticizes historicism for introducing moral rela-
tivism into the modern social sciences. While doing so, Strauss quotes Kelsen only
once, in a footnote, as an illustration of the instrumental nature of modern social
sciences. In fact, Strauss claims that Kelsenian legal positivism—because it con-
ducts its knowledge under an imperative of neutrality—does not recognize any dif-
ferences between democracy and tyranny.4
Natural Right and History, precisely because of its scant reference to Kelsen, is
a perfect illustration of how the latter’s writings were largely ignored and soon for-
gotten by scholars in the United States. This limited reference to Kelsen cannot be
2
Strauss left Germany for France in 1932, supported by a grant from Rockefeller Foundation.
Then, he went to England in 1934, before definitely leaving Europe for the United States in 1938.
See Smith (2009: 18–34). For a more detailed biography on Strauss, see Sheppard (2006). For a
biography of Kelsen, see Metall (1969).
3
Strauss (1953a: 3): “The contemporary rejection of natural right leads to nihilism—nay, it is
identical with nihilism.”
4
As David Novak mentions (2012: 394): “the University of Chicago at that time provided Strauss
with a congenial atmosphere for his anti-positivism/anti-historicism.”
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 117
attributed to the fact that Strauss did not know his texts.5 If Strauss rejects the
Kelsenian position but at the same time does not allocate too much space for this
rejection, it is because he judges that the latter position is an expression of the domi-
nant Zeitgeist.
In the political context of post Second World War, which witnessed the hitherto
unseen emergence of totalitarian phenomena, one can clearly see why the Kelsenian
position did not excite much popular adherence. At a time when people expected a
commitment from their intellectuals, ie, a clear denunciation of Nazism, Kelsen
defended scientific neutrality and asserted that a rational moral evaluation is impos-
sible. Even though one should refrain from a “reductio ad Hitlerum,”6 one must
nevertheless admit that the Kelsenian legal science does not deliver the expected
denunciation of totalitarianism. This failure to offer a clear denunciation of totalitar-
ian phenomena might have contributed to his writings’ lack of reception.
If Kelsen’s legal theory was a victim of its weak reception, the same thing can be
said about his writings that deal with moral questions. The latter, nonetheless, and
the Berkeley Farewell Lecture in particular seem susceptible to readings that render
them still relevant today for moral and political philosophy. What is particularly
interesting in this text is the ambiguity that attends to the kind of moral relativism
defended by Kelsen. It is precisely this ambiguity that one can interpret as relevant
to contemporary philosophical debates.
Contrary to preconceived ideas about his moral standpoint, What is Justice? is
not a radical defense of moral relativism. In fact, in this lecture, Kelsen explicitly
presents moral relativism as a simple personal opinion. The conclusion, in which he
expresses his own preferences for democracy and for tolerance, must be read in this
light.
Since science is my profession, and hence the most important thing in my life, justice, to
me, is that social order under whose protection the search for truth can prosper. “My” jus-
tice, then, is the justice of freedom, the justice of peace, the justice of democracy—the
justice of tolerance (Kelsen 1957: 24).
However, if the moral relativism Kelsen defends is merely the expression of his own
personal preference, then Jes Bjarup is right to ask: “Why does Kelsen take all the
trouble to inform others about his emotional state of mind?” (Bjarup 1986: 298) It
is possible to explain the interest in Kelsen’s emotional state of mind if one consid-
ers that Kelsen’s attempt to resolve the moral question matters less than the question
he raises concerning the essence of justice.
5
It is well established that Strauss had read Kelsen. The preface that he wrote to Isaac Husik’s
Philosophical Essays (Strauss 1953b) is proof of that, because one can find in it many references
to Kelsen. Let us remember that at the time, Kelsen already enjoyed a good reputation as a jurist in
the United States (see Telman (2008: 2)), while Strauss had only begun his career (see Novak
(2012: 393), and Smith (2009: 32)). Strauss’s reputation in the United States only got stronger after
his arrival in Chicago, and after the publication of Natural Right and History: “This book—along
with Persecution and the Art of writing published the year before—turned Strauss from an
unknown into a major voice in American political philosophy.”
6
This is a popular Straussian expression. Strauss uses it in Natural Right and History to designate
a new form of rhetorical fallacy. See Strauss (1953a: 42–43).
118 E. Lefort
A philosophical reading of Kelsen that tries to compare his thoughts with Strauss’s
seems relevant, when one looks at such a reading as a way to conceive our contem-
porary political context. Both texts of Kelsen and Strauss reveal themselves as an
essential reminder of how important the question of justice is.
7
Strauss (1978: 23): “I myself regard the book as a preparation to an adequate philosophic discus-
sion rather than settling the question.”
8
In his book about Claude Lefort’s political philosophy, Bernard Flynn recounts the discussion
between one of his friends and Hannah Arendt: the discussion probably dealt with Rawls’ Theory
of Justice, and most certainly with the possibility of determining what justice is. The quotation of
what Arendt reportedly said is taken from Flynn (2005: 228).
9
This conceptual terminology comes from the political philosophy of Claude Lefort. According to
him, the symbolic characteristic of a society designates its system of representations. See Flynn
(2005: 117–120).
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 119
In order to justify this hypothesis, two texts will be considered in this chapter:
Kelsen’s What is Justice? as well as Strauss’s Natural Right and History.10 The
analysis of these texts reveals three main points of antagonism. Kelsen and Strauss
obviously disagree on: the political question (§ 7.2); the question of relativism (§
7.3); and the question of natural right (§ 7.4). A further reading also reveals that the
opposition between Kelsen and Strauss can be overcome if one considers that the
two authors are less interested in defending a strong standpoint and providing
answers than in formulating the question of the essence of justice (§ 7.5).
7.2.1 Inconsistencies
Kelsen sought to prove that theories of natural law are inconsistent because natural
law theories can potentially justify any political regime. Thus, natural law’s defend-
ers never succeeded in agreeing either on which political regime is the best, or even
on which one is good. Defenders of natural law have justified different and opposed
political regimes. Robert Filmer argued in favor of absolute monarchy, while John
Locke was convinced democracy was the only just and legitimate option.11 Natural
law can also defend communism, as well as private property; namely one thing and
its diametric opposite. This is the proof that natural law theories fall victim to error
and that they are not scientific.
If nature is supposed to be created by God, the norms immanent in nature, natural laws, are
the expression of the will of God. Then the natural-law doctrine has a metaphysical charac-
ter. If, however, the natural law is to be deduced from the nature of man as being endowed
with reason, (…) then the natural-law doctrine pretends to assume a rationalistic character.
From the point of view of science, neither the one nor the other view is tenable (Kelsen
1957: 20).12
Natural law’s history of ideas does not indicate a universal moral criterion. Ironically,
the quick genesis of mutually contradictory natural law theories, each of which
claims universality, is itself an indicator of the impossibility for human cognition to
specify unconditional moral values.
In a symmetrical way, the only reference to Kelsen in Strauss’s book, Natural
Right and History, serves to criticize legal positivism because of its instrumental
10
Concerning the latter, this chapter will only focus on the Introduction and the first chapter that
deals with historicism.
11
See Kelsen (1957: 21). The same argument is also presented in Kelsen (1955: 98 n.70).
12
Kelsen stated:
Hence it is not astonishing that the various followers of the natural-law doctrine deduced
from nature, or found in human reason, the most contradictory principles of justice (Kelsen
(1957:21).
120 E. Lefort
nature. In Strauss’s view, Kelsenian legal science can justify any political regime13
because “it derives its strength ultimately from the generally accepted historicist
premise” (Strauss 1953a: 10).
In order to demonstrate that the loss of natural right is a bad thing, Strauss under-
lines the problems raised by the substitution of nature’s sense (a sense implied by
such a conception of law) with the historical one. For Strauss, this substitution puts
into question the possibility of moral evaluation. Indeed, according to historicism,
all moral evaluations are relative to a historical and cultural context. Therefore,
moral evaluations can only have a relative weight because a determined moral eval-
uation can never prevent itself from being contradicted by another. In historicism’s
view, all moral judgments have, strictly speaking, the same weight and the same
value. Modern social sciences:
(…) [A]ppear to believe that our inability to acquire any genuine knowledge of what is
intrinsically good or right compels us to be tolerant of every opinion about good or right or
to recognize all preferences or all “civilizations” as equally respectable. Only unlimited
tolerance is in accordance with reason (Strauss 1953a: 5).
If all moral evaluations are condemned to have only a relative validity, this also
means that the moral (or immoral) value of political regimes cannot be determined
with certainty. Our modern social sciences are potentially efficient instruments that
can serve the interest of any political regime—including tyrannical interests—
because of this complete lack of differentiation between what is legitimate and what
is illegitimate. However, in actuality, they are not as versatile because they only
serve the interest of a “generous liberalism,”14 and this affiliation with liberalism
proves their lack of consistency.15
13
Strauss is not the first scholar to criticize the Kelsenian theory in this way. Since its first formula-
tions, legal positivism aroused this suspicion. As Kelsen mentions in his Preface to the first edition
of the Pure Theory Law, one of the main claims raised against his legal science deals with its
independence from politics. Many political orientations have been attributed to his legal science,
and he perceives this fact as a proof that it is not politically orientated. See Kelsen (1934: 3). See
also: Kelsen (1955: 97 n.70, 1957: 376 n.20).
14
For Strauss, the only thing that prevents modern social sciences to serve “tyrants” as well as “free
peoples” is that they “prefer—only God knows why—generous liberalism to consistency…”
(Strauss 1953a: 4).
15
On the affiliation of the Kelsenian theory with liberalism, see Herrera (1995). In his article,
Herrera argues that such an affiliation is not self-evident.
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 121
The reader familiar with Kelsenian legal science cannot be surprised by the idea
contained in this quototation. What is at stake here is, in the end, one of the main
claims of his Pure Theory of Law, the identity of State and Law. According to
Kelsen, a despotic state is, from a scientific point of view, a legal state, and more-
over, any state is a legal state regardless of its political nature, as well as regardless
of any individual’s moral approval of it. Thus, the legality of an existing political
regime is not dependent on any individual’s moral approval of that regime. This
distinction between the legality of a State and its moral standing is a consequence of
the Kelsenian definition of legal science.
Indeed, according to Kelsen, knowing the law and evaluating it morally are, by
definition, two contradictory operations. The former’s principles are grounded in the
legitimate limits of human cognition, while the latter’s principles directly emanate
from the human will. The former is rational, while the latter is irrational. Moreover,
the first is a descriptive operation, while the second is a prescriptive one. This oppo-
sition between description (legal science) and prescription (moral evaluation) is in
fact a development of Kelsen’s main distinction, the difference between Sein and
Sollen.
This distinction plays a double role in Kelsen’s work. We can find it at two dif-
ferent levels. The first is theoretical, concerning the definition of law itself Kelsen
(1967: 4–10). The second level is meta-theoretical, pertaining to the definition of
the theory of law. At the meta-theoretical level, the separation between Sein and
Sollen means the limitation of human rational knowledge to the world of Sein. Thus,
the Kelsenian scientific perspective excludes any evaluative or justificatory aim.18 It
also entails the condemnation of any attempt of establishing natural law.
16
Strauss notes: “Since Kelsen has not changed his attitude toward natural right, I cannot imagine
why he has omitted this instructive passage from the English translation” (Strauss 1953a: 4). David
Novak notices another passage omitted from the English translation of the Pure Theory of Law’s
second edition (Novak 2012: 406 n.6).
17
Strauss directly quotes Kelsen in German (Strauss 1953a: 4 n.2). Therefore, I use and complete
David Novak’s translation here (Novak 2012: 395).
18
See how Kelsen characterizes his own legal science in his Pure Theory of Law (Kelsen 1967: 9).
122 E. Lefort
This review of Kelsen’s legal epistemology is helpful in order to show that, from
Kelsen’s point of view, being scientific means remaining politically neutral.
It is significant that it is in the same political and historical context that Kelsen reaf-
firms axiological neutrality that Strauss denounces the instrumental nature of mod-
ern social sciences. To use Strauss’s formulation (from another context), the
common political climate they shared was “darkened by the shadow of Hitler”
(Strauss 1953a: 42). With this in mind, one will easily understand how the Kelsenian
reaffirmation of axiological neutrality in 1945 can be problematic, and even
unpopular.
In the name of science, Kelsen discredits any moral evaluation of political
regimes. His science is therefore an indirect affirmation that all political regimes are
undifferentiated. His standpoint leads to the impossibility of any moral denuncia-
tion of the mid-twentieth century totalitarian regimes. In this serious context, the
expectation of a clear standpoint concerning historical and political events runs
against Kelsen’s reaffirmation that a neutral standpoint concerning facts is the only
rational and legitimate option. This reaffirmation and Kelsen’s consequent refusal to
intervene intellectually are easily perceived as disappointing, if not rejected as
absurd.20
It would not be fair however to say that Kelsen did not have a clear perception of
this historical and political context or that he did not worry about the questions
regarding the moral evaluation of political regimes. Significantly, his writings after
1945 considerably develop his standpoint on the moral question. His Farewell
Lecture, which is emblematically entitled What is Justice? (1952), was already
mentioned. The second edition (1960) of Pure Theory of Law was extended in tell-
ing ways. First, the chapter dealing with Law and Morals is more developed.
Second, Kelsen later supplemented the book with two addenda titled respectively
The Problem of Justice21 and Justice and Natural Law. Finally, there is his
Foundations of Democracy published in 1955, as well as the collection of some of
Kelsen’s articles in the book What is Justice? Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror
of Science (1957).
19
This part was added to initial drafts, thanks to the suggestions of Peter Caldwell.
20
The concept of intellectual intervention has different meanings. The one used here is the one
Marc Maesschalck points at, namely: contemporary ethical meaning. From this perspective, intel-
lectual intervention means not only to produce discourses but also to take part in the ethical field,
to consider actions as well as discourses and doctrines. This means adopting a standpoint within
the ethical field, within the field of human actions. One can therefore easily understand how Kelsen
refused an intellectual intervention in this sense. See Maesschalck (2010: 9–10).
21
Nicoletta Bersier Ladavac provides a close reading of this Kelsenian article (Ladavac 2008:
19–52). For a detailed bibliography regarding the question of justice in Kelsen’s works, see in
particular, 38.
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 123
In his lecture, Kelsen considers five practical dilemmas (Kelsen 1957: 5–7). He
explores five situations, each of which requires decision making, and his treatment
of these situations illuminates his position on moral relativism. Kelsen uses these
situations to prove that human decisions are in fact choices based on preferences.
From that perspective, one’s decision is nothing more than the election of a certain
value. Because each particular decision is a personal preference or a selection based
on a determined value, it cannot have enough strength to exclude the possibility of
a different choice, which would itself be based on an opposed value. Kelsen wants
to prove that the supposition of an absolute value is not a matter of science, because
it is not a rational operation, but a matter of choice based on emotions.
One of the five dilemmas is the case of the doctor.22 A doctor is facing a patient
who will soon die. He is therefore facing two contradictory practical options: should
he reveal the truth to his patient and tell him about his imminent death, or should he
hide this painful truth from him? According to Kelsen, in order to decide which
option would be better, the doctor has to establish a hierarchy between two values.
In other words, in order to be able to make his choice, the doctor has to decide which
value, truth or compassion, is more important. If he judges that truth is a higher
value, then he will inform the patient of his health despite the fear of what this news
might cause. In this first scenario, the doctor judges that one should always try to be
truthful, even if truthfulness can be unpleasant. However, if the doctor considers, for
example, fear of death to be the worst feeling one can have, he will lie to his patient,
22
Even though the figure of the doctor mentioned in What is Justice? is quite outdated, this fact
does not affect the example, because what Kelsen aims to do here is to show the dilemma in every
human practical decision.
124 E. Lefort
intentionally hiding from him the fact that he does not have much time to live. In
this second situation, compassion is valued over truthfulness. In Kelsen’s opinion,
this dilemma illustrates well how value judgments are emotional and not the result
of human cognition. The doctor does not decide with the help of logical thinking but
by consulting his emotions: the will to be truthful on the one hand, or his compas-
sion on the other.
In Natural Right and History, Strauss presents Kelsen’s position concerning the
lack of objectivity in moral judgments and thus their relativity as a common per-
spective shared by modern social sciences.23 In other words, according to Strauss,
Kelsen and the modern social sciences hold that the standard one uses to make
practical decisions is not rational. Hence, it is also not universal, because it depends
on non-universal circumstances. It is relative to one’s emotions, culture, time, and
place. In short, our moral standard is nothing more than an ideal adopted by our
society.
This relativist perspective raises two main problems, according to Strauss. First,
this definition of justice makes it impossible to have a reasonable critical distance
from society. Furthermore, if one agrees with the idea that the criteria that allow one
to make just decisions are given by society, then: (1) this relative standard is not so
much superior to society as it is identified with it; and (2) this relative standard is not
a way to evaluate society because it derives directly from it. This is obviously not a
good thing because political life needs to leave the door open to evaluation and criti-
cism in order to prevent excesses.
[S]ince the ideal of our society is admittedly changing, nothing except dull and stale habit
could prevent us from placidly accepting a change in the direction of cannibalism. If there
is no standard higher than the ideal of our society, we are utterly unable to take a critical
distance from that ideal (Strauss 1953a: 3).
Moreover, Strauss thinks that this identification between individuals and the moral
ideal given by society is a false assumption. The simple fact that one can question
one’s own social environment is proof that humans are not completely identified
with, and determined by, society. If humans were entirely absorbed by society and
defined by it, they would be unable to think of society as an object. They would be
unable to feel a need for justice (Strauss 1953a: 3).
The second main problem raised by moral relativism concerns the world it
builds—a world without references, a world that is confused and absurd. In other
words, according to Strauss, moral relativism leads directly to nihilism. From the
standpoint of moral relativism, human cognition cannot access knowledge of
23
Others writings of Strauss deal with the same idea. For instance, see Social Science and
Humanism (Strauss 1956: 3–12), Relativism (Strauss 1961: 13–26), as well as What is Political
Philosophy (Strauss 1957: 343–368).
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 125
absolute justice. And this postulate not only condemns human beings to be alone
with their choices but also condemns all human choices to be equal and undifferen-
tiated. If it is impossible for people to know what is just and what is not, does this
not mean that all possible choices are equivalent? Because there is no unconditional
standard, this somehow means that there is no standard at all. A determined choice,
or act, is qualified as just only because it corresponds to an ideal that is itself rela-
tive. In this world where everything is relative, every behavior and every judgment
is weak and therefore meaningless (Strauss 1953a: 3).
Therefore, justice is void of meaning. Herein lies all the irony for Strauss: our
modern social sciences are efficient only in determining things that have merely
secondary importance for us. This is because they are unable to access what is most
important for us, namely, our practical life. Rationality becomes synonymous with
voluntary blindness, and we are condemned to choose blindly: all our choices are as
good as they are bad.
We are then in the position of beings who are sane and sober when engaged in trivial busi-
ness and who gamble like madmen when confronted with serious issues—retail sanity and
wholesale madness (Strauss 1953a: 4).
Regarding the question of whether or not natural law is a legitimate rational option
for human beings, Kelsen’s negative answer is expected. His rejection of natural law
in What is Justice? is the rejection of a certain form of moral absolutism.24 According
to Kelsen, natural law requires an absolute ground: this ground is what allows the
validity of human moral judgments. An absolute ground means the determination of
a non-relative standard, one that is valid in any possible situation and in an uncon-
ditional way. Therefore, this standard is a universal concept of justice.
In Kelsen’s view, it is precisely this universality that is problematic, because an
unconditional moral standard or concept is, by definition, unreachable for human
cognition. The rejection of moral absolutism is grounded on a particular epistemol-
ogy. Because human knowledge is limited, it cannot access absolute values. This
limitation also plays an essential role in the knowledge of law. In order to be scien-
tific, one should be aware of the limitations of human reason. This is why Kelsenian
legal science uses empirical experience as its raw material.25 Regarding the question
24
One cannot accuse the Straussian philosophy of being absolutist, if one looks closely at these
lines of Natural Right and History: “There is a universally valid hierarchy of ends, but there are no
universal rules of actions” (Strauss 1953a: 162).
25
One can find this idea of the theoretical need for empirical facts in Kant’s first Critique when he
deals with the pure categories (Kant 1781: 346). Regarding the question of the Kantian influence
on Kelsen, see Wilson (1986: 37–64).
126 E. Lefort
of values, the same principle applies: in order to correctly know the nature of values,
one should look at the question of values without ignoring one’s cognitive limita-
tions. What human experience shows is not absolute values or unconditional practi-
cal standards but multiple, temporary, and changing values or concepts. The world
of facts illustrates the relativism of values.
The absolute in general, and the absolute values in particular, are beyond human reason, for
which only a conditional, and in this sense relative, solution of the problem of justice, as the
problem of justification of human behavior, is possible (Kelsen 1957: 10).
The second argument Kelsen offers in What is Justice? against natural law is the
famous “is/ought” logical problem (Kelsen 1957: 20–21).26 According to him, natu-
ral law is constructed under a logical mistake: it tries to deduce norms from the
nature of things or of human beings. It deduces from what is, how things ought to
be. It deduces normative statements from factual ones. But the factual world (Sein)
is ontologically different from the normative world (Sollen) (Kelsen 1957: 20).
This is why natural law is nothing but a rationally illegitimate philosophical and
metaphysical enterprise that fulfills the same function as religion. In fact, both reli-
gion and natural law succeed in satisfying the human need for justification by pos-
tulating an absolute justice, albeit through fallacious reasoning. Their reasoning
necessarily transgresses the limits of human reason, because the postulate of a tran-
scendent concept is, by definition, beyond our reach. The pretense that one can
surpass the limits of human cognition leads both religion and natural law into
inconsistency.
Despite his rejection of natural law, Kelsen seems to avoid Strauss’s critique of
nihilism, because he does not conclude with the absence of moral values. Rather, his
conclusion is that tolerance is a moral principle. In Kelsen’s opinion, tolerance
should be the ultimate value of our moral choices: it is the only rational value pos-
sible. It is the only one that can respect the diversity and multiplicity of moral con-
ceptions existing worldwide. One could qualify as tolerant if one welcomes every
moral, religious, and political view, particularly opposing ones. Being tolerant
means trying to understand the opinions of others, especially those with whom one
does not agree. In other words, “[t]olerance means freedom of thoughts” (Kelsen
1957: 23).
Echoing modern social sciences, Kelsen thinks that natural right does not consider
the world of facts. Strauss’s opposition to this argument is particularly strong.
Humans did not wait for historicism and its moral relativism to realize that several
26
One can find this distinction in Hume’s Treatise (Hume 1888: 469–470). Strauss discusses both
the Humean and the Kantian influences on modern social sciences in his article titled Relativism
(Strauss 1961: 22–24).
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 127
conceptions of justice exist. In fact, far from being an argument against natural
right, this empirical fact is an argument in its favor, because natural right builds
itself precisely on this diversity of experience. Its essence is to search beyond this
empirical perspective for a universal standard, and this search is conducted with the
help of human reason. Therefore, natural right does not ignore empirical facts, but,
on the contrary, considers them in order to transcend them.
Above all, knowledge of the indefinitely large variety of notions of right and wrong is so far
from being incompatible with the idea of natural right that is the essential condition for the
emergence of that idea: realization of the diversity of notions of right is the incentive for the
quest of knowledge (Strauss 1953a: 10).
Political philosophy (Strauss 1957: 343–368) and natural right emerged when
human beings realized the radical difference between convention and nature. That is
the reason that one cannot say that the lack of universal agreement about what natu-
ral right states is the proof of its impossibility. Given its essence, the theory of natu-
ral right cannot be accessible to every human being. First, it is only an attempt;
second, it involves the use of reason (Strauss 1957: 343–344).
Furthermore, from the perspective of modern social sciences, every theoretical
position is historically determined. Does the claim that all theories are historically
determined not imply the adoption of a point of view that is not itself historically
determined? Therefore, and by definition, is historicism not a trans-historical per-
spective? How can one assert such a historicist statement without adopting a trans-
historical perspective? (Strauss 1953a: 25)
In the best-case scenario, if historicist relativism were true, then it would prove
that human cognition could transcend its historical limitations and access a trans-
historical point of view. This would obviously contradict the premise of historicism
and its moral relativism. This clearly shows that historicism and moral relativism
are victims of a logical error. If these theories were consistent, they would not
exclude themselves from the historical determination they claim as truth.
In Strauss’s opinion, a similar error can be found with the concept of tolerance.
This concept is defended by modern social sciences with the hope of escaping nihil-
ism. But in fact, this concept leads them to a contradiction.27
Moral relativism has excluded the possibility of absolute values for, from its
perspective, all values are relative. Because all values are supposed to have the same
legitimacy, why should intolerance be considered a “bad” value? Moreover, why
should tolerance be considered better than intolerance? Why does, and how can,
tolerance escape relativity? If all human actions are motivated by blind choices or
preferences, then why be tolerant?
Historicism chooses here an easy out: it avoids the problem in a dogmatic way.
Historicism simply decides, arbitrarily, to place tolerance above all values without
any justification. This gesture is an unconscious return to natural right, the very
concept that historicism emphatically rejected (Strauss 1953a: 6).
27
Bjarup also raised this problem (1986). For a charitable reading, see Pettit (1986).
128 E. Lefort
In the texts under discussion here, neither Kelsen nor Strauss appears as a strong
defender of moral relativism, or of natural right. Both Kelsen and Strauss are more
occupied with discrediting theoretical positions that they judged problematic than
with positively defending their own positions. Both scholars seem to give a “nega-
tive” answer to the question of justice. When Kelsen analyzes classical philosophi-
cal concepts of justice in his Farewell Lecture, and when Strauss traces the genesis
of historicism in his lectures, both of them say what justice is not.
The first argument in favor of such an interpretation is the way both authors
themselves define their approaches. Thus, at the end of What is Justice?, Kelsen
insists that moral relativism and tolerance are only his personal preferences as a
scientist. In a similar way, Strauss warns his reader about the question of natural
right at the beginning of his book (Strauss 1953a: 6). Finally, the only things the
reader can be assured of at the end of this comparative reading are that Kelsen is
strongly rejecting natural right and that Strauss is firmly fighting against moral
relativism.
Kelsen’s criticism of natural right and Strauss’s attack on moral relativism leave us,
it seems, with unsatisfactroy theoretical positions. Both natural right and moral rela-
tivism appear problematic, and choosing one position over the other seems to be
impossible. Nonetheless, one should not consider the value of these writings from
this perspective. On the contrary, what is crucial is that they both aim to open a
debate by asking the same question. Both affirm the indeterminacy of justice, and
that seems the most interesting point for philosophy. Following Claude Lefort, their
conclusion relating to justice’s indeterminacy is characteristic of modern political
philosophy.
According to Lefort, modernity is the era of the dissolution of the ultimate mark-
ers of certainty. Monarchy is defined as the system of representations according to
which society constitutes a mystical body; one where the king is “both the organic
and the mystic unity” of society.
[T]he society of the ancien régime represented its unity and its identity to itself as that of a
body—a body which found its figuration in the body of the king, or rather which identified
itself with the king’s body, while at the same time it attached itself to it as its head. As Ernst
Kantorowicz has shown in a masterly fashion, (…) [t]he image of the king’s body as a
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 129
double body, both mortal and immortal, individual and collective, was initially underpinned
by the body of Christ (Lefort 1979: 302).
The important idea here, relative to the question of justice, is the fact that Lefort
defines modernity in opposition to such a symbolic conception of the political
power. Thus, modernity is understood as this new social configuration where the
king no longer exists. As such, there is no one to inform the society what is just and
what is not. Because of the democratic revolution, modernity can be defined as the
theater28 of the disincorporation of power.
The democratic revolution (…) burst out when the body of the king was destroyed, when
the body politic was decapitated and when, at the same time, the corporeality of the social
was dissolved (Lefort 1979: 303).
This means there no longer exists a tutelary figure to give reality’s meaning, and
to ensure society’s unity.
Democracy inaugurates the experience of an ungraspable, uncontrollable society in which
the people will be said to be sovereign, of course, but whose identity will constantly be open
to question, whose identity will remain latent (Lefort 1979: 303–304).
This analysis can help in the interpretation of Kelsen’s and Strauss’s positions.
According to the latter, justice is not relative; in Kelsen’s view, it is not absolute.
Both negative definitions seem to imply in fact, the refusal of a definitive definition
of justice. Both authors are fighting a common enemy, dogmatism. Both agree on
the impossibility of solving the question of justice once and for all. Both reject the
claim that justice could be given as “ready-made.” In that sense, despite the fact that
Kelsen and Strauss’s thoughts are antagonistic, they seem nevertheless to demon-
strate modernity’s embrace of uncertainty and indeterminacy.
In addition, Lefort interprets this indefinite wondering itself as the condition of
possibility of democracy. Here, democracy is not defined as a political regime, or as
a system of institutions.29 Lefort gives a symbolic definition: democracy is a way of
living modernity.30 Democracy is the acceptance of modern, radical indeterminacy.
The indeterminacy of justice can, therefore, be interpreted as the condition of pos-
sibility of our contemporary democracies.31 Such an interpretation fits quite well
with Kelsen’s thoughts on the subject, because his works contain a favorable opinion
28
Claude Lefort uses the word “theatre” since what he tries to do is to analyze the symbolic essence
of the political, namely, the representations that drive society.
29
See Lefort (1994: 200):
Let anyone who doubts that simply observe how difficult it is, for a people accustomed to
living under a despotic regime, to regain the will to be free. A change of institutions does
not suffice to achieve it. It is Strauss’s judgment that the modern philosophers’ presupposi-
tions are amoral, but these philosophers have made this difficulty a primary object of their
reflection.
30
See Flynn (2005: 152): “Democracy and totalitarianism are ways of living modernity.”
31
One can find this idea in Kelsen (1955: 70).
130 E. Lefort
of democracy, and maybe even a defense of it.32 Strauss, however, is more skeptical
about democracy.33
The fact that the essence of justice is undetermined does not imply that one
should believe in moral relativism, or that one should consider natural right as a
choice. There is another option: the democratic one, which requires the individual’s
moral and political responsibility.34 And this option is precisely what both Kelsen
and Strauss point to because they both “firmly [assume] the question that our time
imposes on us” (Lefort 1986: 567).35
7.6 Conclusion
This chapter had two goals. The first was to remain as close as possible to the
respective meanings of Kelsen’s and Strauss’s texts. In this spirit, it was important
not to deny the real opposition separating them. One can restate the opposition
between the two authors with the help of Plato’s philosophy. Philosophy for Strauss
means getting out of Plato’s cave, and trying to find a way out can only mean seek-
ing a perspective that goes beyond empirical experience. Kelsen contrarily holds
that human beings should be aware of the limits of their own cognitive powers, for,
without this awareness, it is impossible to build legitimate and consistent theories.
Thus, if people want to achieve any scientific knowledge, they have to admit that
32
Regarding Kelsen’s political theory, see Vinx (2007); De Angelis (2009); Baum (2012) and
Herrera (1997).
33
See Strauss (1968: 5):
[T]he salt of modern democracy are those citizens who read nothing except the sports page
and the comic section. Democracy is then not indeed mass rule, but mass culture. A mass
culture is a culture which can be appropriated by the meanest capacities without any intel-
lectual and moral effort whatsoever and at a very low monetary price.…Liberal education
is the counterpoison to mass culture.…Liberal education is the necessary endeavor to found
an aristocracy within democratic mass society. Liberal education reminds those members of
a mass democracy who have ears to hear, of human greatness.
Lefort also mentions this difficulty. He deplores that Strauss does not recognize modern
democracy as a new form of political society. See Hilb (2013: 71–86).
34
Despite Strauss’s scepticism about democracy, one can still qualify his philosophical fight
against dogmatism as “democratic” provided one uses Lefort’s symbolic definition of democracy.
35
One can find an expression of the same idea in his article about Human Rights:
[T]he view that naturalism and historicism are equally inappropriate tools for conceptual-
izing the rights of man does not simplify the basic problem; it complicates it. It would seem
that we can neither say that these original rights make up a bedrock because we have
rejected all belief in human nature, nor that they and the rights that were subsequently won
form a chain each link of which is similarly marked by circumstances, because we have
discovered in the institution of those first rights a foundation, the emergence of a principle
of universality (Lefort 1984: 38).
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 131
they can only know with certainty what is empirical. In other words, human cogni-
tion is strictly limited to Plato’s cave.
The study of the points of antagonism between Kelsen and Strauss revealed one
important outcome of their thinking, the absence of a definition of the essence of
justice. Regarding this negative approach to justice, their thoughts seem similar.
Both note the arguments with which they disagree, question them, and demonstrate
their irrelevances and inconsistencies. Both authors appear as fighters against dog-
matic thought. In other words, when Kelsen rejects natural law, it is because he
considers it a form of dogmatism. Similarly, Strauss criticizes historicism for pre-
cluding any discussion, debate, or judgment.
If modernity is this era of the dissolution of the markers of certainty, then the
indeterminacy of justice can be understood and accepted. In the end, it matters little
if philosophy has an answer to the question of justice; providing such answers is
probably not its role (Strauss 1953a: 36). From this perspective, the comparative
reading of Kelsen and Strauss appears as a reminder of the authentic meaning of
philosophy and of its importance. Its role is to remind us of how important the ques-
tion of justice is. As long as we are trying to look for an answer to that question, we
are actually trying to create a democratic space in which to live together, while also
trying to accept and embrace the absence of reference points for our era.36 If we do
not wonder anymore about justice, then we will probably reach “the point at which
[we] have become tired of thinking.”37 We will most likely reach the borders of the
dogmatic world: the world of “ready-made” thoughts and concepts. And with the
same gesture, we will presumably have opened the door to extreme and totalitarian
movements. This is the lesson one should retain from this comparative reading of
the two scholars. These texts briefly presented are an energetic call to continuously
consider and rethink the question of justice. This also means questioning every
answer one could give to that question. Because:
[I]t seems that [the question of justice] is one of those questions to which the resigned wis-
dom applies that man cannot find a definitive answer but can only try to improve the ques-
tion (Kelsen 1957: 1).
Genuine knowledge of a fundamental question, thorough understanding of it, is better
than blindness to it, or indifference to it, be that indifference or blindness accompanied by
knowledge of the answers to a vast number of peripheral or ephemeral questions or not
(Strauss 1957: 344).
36
See Strauss (1957: 344):
Philosophy is essentially not possession of the truth but quest for the truth. The distinctive
trait of the philosopher is that “he knows that he knows nothing,” and that his insight into
our ignorance concerning the most important things induces him to strive with all his power
for knowledge.
37
This is a quote of Lessing’s letter to Mendelssohn (9th January 1771) as found in Strauss (1953a:
22).
132 E. Lefort
with a grant from the Botsiber Institute for Austrian-American Studies. This academic event took
place in Chicago, in June 2014. To revive the philosophy of Strauss in this “geographic context”
was an undeniably charming experience. It would not have been possible without Pr. Jeremy
Telman. I could never thank him enough for the trust he manifested while accepting me in this
common reflection. I am also indebted to the other participants, for their warm welcome and
insightful remarks.
I would also like to thank the University of Luxembourg and the Botstiber Foundation for mate-
rial support of my travel; Pr. Lukas Sosoe and Shaun Colley for their comments on earlier drafts.
Thanks to the friendly “invisible hands” for their improvements and corrections: Yara Darwich,
Matthew Gardhouse, and Frédéric Seyler. And last but not least, I am grateful to Farhat Chcayra,
who helped me translate my thoughts into English.
References
Baum, Sandrine. 2012. Hans Kelsen and the case for democracy. Colchester: ECPR Press.
Bjarup, Jes. 1986. Kelsen’s theory of law and philosophy of justice. In Essays on Kelsen, ed.
Richard Tur and William Twining, 273–304. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
De Angelis, Gabriele. 2009. Ideals and institutions. Hans Kelsen’s political theory. History of polit-
ical thought 30(3): 524–546.
Flynn, Bernard. 2005. The philosophy of Claude Lefort. Interpreting the political. Evanston:
Nothwestern University Press.
Herrera, Carlos Miguel. 1995. Kelsen et le libéralisme. In Le droit, le politique: Autour de Max
Weber, Hans Kelsen, Carl Schmitt, ed. Carlos Miguel Herrera, 37–68. Paris: L’Harmattan.
Herrera, Carlos Miguel. 1997. Théorie politique et juridique chez Hans Kelsen. Paris: Kime.
Hilb, Claudia. 2013. Claude Lefort as reader of Leo Strauss. In Claude Lefort: Thinker of the
political, ed. Martin Plot, 71–86. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Hume, David. 1888. A treatise of human nature. 1960. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1781. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. P. Guyer and A.W. Wood 1999. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. B.L. Paulson and
S.L. Paulson 1997. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1955. Foundations of democracy. Ethics 66(1): 1–101.
Kelsen, Hans. 1957. What is justice? In What is justice? Justice, law and politics in the mirror of
science. 2013. 1–24. New Jersey: The Lawbook Exchange LTD.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. Reine Rechtslehre. 2000. Wien: Verlag Österreich.
Kelsen, Hans. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. M. Knight. 2008. New Jersey: The Lawbook
Exchange LTD.
Ladavac, Nicoletta Bersier. 2008. Recht, Moral und Gerechtigkeit bei Hans Kelsen. In Recht,
Moral und Faktizität: Festschrift für Walter Ott, ed. Sandra Hotz and Klaus Mathis, 19–52.
Zürich: Dike.
Lefort, Claude. 1979. The image of the body and totalitarianism. In The Political Forms of Modern
Society. Bureaucracy, Democracy, Totalitarianism. Trans. A. Sheridan. 1986. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Lefort, Claude. 1984. Human rights and the welfare state. In Democracy and Political Theory.
Trans. D. Macey 1988. 21–44. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Lefort, Claude. 1986. La dissolution des repères et les enjeux démocratiques. In Le Temps présent.
Ecrits de 1945—2005. 2007. 551–570. Paris: Belin.
Lefort, Claude. 1994. Three notes on Leo Strauss. In Writing, the Political Test. Trans. D.A. Curtis.
2000. 172–206. Durham: Duke University Press.
7 Arriving at Justice by a Process of Elimination 133
Daniel F. Rice
8.1 Introduction
1
G. O. Mazur, who has edited two books on Hans Morgenthau, assured me in an April 21, 2005,
letter that the Kelsen essay “was the product of Kelsen’s and Morgenthau’s correspondence of over
25 years since they first met in Europe, and was finally penned by Kelsen himself.”
D.F. Rice (*)
Department of Philosophy and Religious Studies, University of Wisconsin-Eau Claire,
Eau Claire, WI, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
who, at the time, was the ranking Protestant theologian addressing social and politi-
cal issues.2 Kelsen definitely viewed the democracy/religion issue as a problem
because he disputed the claims that Christianity had an intimate and constructive
connection to democracy.
Nadia Urbinati, who co-edited the recent translation of the 1926 edition of
Kelsen’s The Essence and Value of Democracy, noted that “the article Kelsen pub-
lished in 1955 in the journal Ethics, in which he explicitly reformulated and further
expanded his theory of democracy for an English-speaking audience, failed to gen-
erate much interest and debate, and has been largely ignored both by the secondary
literature on Kelsen’s work and by Anglo-American theorists of democracy in
general” (Kelsen 1926: 4). Urbinati attributes this to the Cold War ideological
confrontation between a form of liberalism conceptually grounded on the notion
of “natural law,” and the Marxist critique of constitutional democracy as merely
“formal.” In that context, Ubbinati notes:
there was not much conceptual space left for a theory of democracy resolutely challenging
the premises of both. Moreover, throughout the 1950s and early 1960s, American political
science departments were dominated by a form of methodological behaviorism which
severely restricted the scope of normative political theory itself, due to its insistence on the
purely “scientific” and “non-evaluative” dimensions of the discipline (Kelsen 1926: 3–4).
It is thus not entirely surprising that there is no evidence that Niebuhr ever saw
or responded to Kelsen’s essay. Thus, I am left on my own to formulate a response
to Kelsen’s criticisms consistent with what I believe to be Niebuhr’s views. It is also
unfortunate that Kelsen’s critique of Niebuhr’s view of religion and democracy is
confined to Niebuhr’s 1944 book, Children of Light and Children of Darkness.
Because this book involves a direct and sustained treatment of the subject and is
subtitled “A Vindication of Democracy and a Critique of its Traditional Defense,”
Kelsen’s choice is, to a large degree, understandable. What proves unfortunate,
however, is that Kelsen fails to take into consideration crucial reflections Niebuhr
provides on the subject of democracy that were extant prior to the publication of
Kelsen’s article, eg, The Nature and Destiny of Man II: Human Destiny, chapter IX
(Niebuhr 1943), The Irony of American History (Niebuhr 1952a), and key portions
of both Christian Realism and Power Politics (Niebuhr 1952b) and Christian
Realism and Political Problems (Niebuhr 1953a). Would it have altered or
moderated Kelsen’s criticisms of Niebuhr? I don’t know. Would it have increased
2
Kelsen’s section “Democracy and Religion” also included analyses of the views of the European
Protestant Emil Brunner and the Roman Catholic theologian Jacque Maritain. Kelsen chose these
three men for good reasons. Emil Brunner, second in reputation among Protestant theologians in
Europe only to Karl Barth, had published his book on Justice and the Social Order in 1945.
Reinhold Niebuhr, the ranking indigenous Protestant voice in America during this period, had
authored his “vindication of democracy” and “critique of its traditional defense,” in The Children
of Light and the Children of Darkness in 1944. And the French Roman Catholic philosopher/
theologian Jacques Maritain, writing to his French compatriots suffering through the Nazi terror,
published his little book on Christianity and Democracy in 1943. All three books, seeking to connect
democracy to Christianity in crucial ways, were published near the end of World War II.
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 137
It is precisely in the American context that Niebuhr is engaging where one finds
liberalism’s tendency toward excessive and exaggerated forms of naïve idealism in
abundance. Kelsen himself once noted that “there are truths which are so self-
evident that they must be proclaimed again and again in order not to be doomed to
oblivion” (Kelsen 1944: vii–viii). Although he was speaking in the context of war
being mass murder, the content of Kelsen’s observation can easily play both ways.
For Kelsen misses the point that is crucial for Niebuhr: so pervasive is America’s
proclivity for sentimental naiveté and for perpetuating illusions about both politics
in general and itself as a nation in particular that speaking truth to America is an
ongoing obligation. The historical context of Niebuhr’s Children of Light and
Children of Darkness is crucial here. Based on lectures delivered at Stanford in
early 1944 as the war in Europe was winding down, Niebuhr’s book is responding
to diverse attacks on the democracies stemming from fascism, communism, and
other forms of radical disaffection. Confronted with what he believes to be a weak
and flawed defense of democracy, Niebuhr is convinced that the bourgeois liberal
West was ill-prepared to meet the challenge.
Kelsen writes that Niebuhr believes the view of human nature supplied by
Christianity is “infected with a sinful corruption.” However, Kelsen notes that
Niebuhr also partakes of “a Christian belief in man as the image of God, which is
certainly more optimistic than any liberal view of human nature could be” (Kelsen
1926: 56). Kelsen does not seem to recognize that Niebuhr leveled the same type of
sharp criticisms of the cynical and optimistic tendencies within Christianity as he
leveled against the secular extremes. The fact that Niebuhr chooses to employ
extremes to illustrate his point seems quite appropriate, for it is in the extremes that
the real danger resides. Yet he is aware of the ambiguity of the terms he chooses, for
while writing on Augustine’s political realism, Niebuhr observes that “the defini-
tions of ‘realists’ and ‘idealists’ emphasize disposition, rather than doctrines; and
they are therefore bound to be inexact” (Niebuhr 1953a: 120). In the case of his
stereotype of liberalism, Niebuhr’s juxtaposition of extremes is a typical dialectical
device that allows him to focus upon a realistic alternative that avoids the “logic” of
the extremes between the Scylla of moral cynicism and the Charybdis of utopian
idealism. And while Niebuhr appeals to what he sees as a Christian understanding
of human nature as a way out of the extremes, he applies his criticism to the same
extremes within the Christian tradition as he does to secular culture—a point Kelsen
does not appear to recognize. After all, it is Niebuhr who, in a 1958 interview with
Mike Wallace, states that “it is significant that it is as difficult to get charity out of
piety as to get reasonableness out of rationalism.” For Niebuhr the true state of
affairs requires the balancing of things. According to Robert Good, for example:
Niebuhr sees man in part free, and in part bound by necessity; as sinful, yet knowing him-
self to be a sinner; as capable of justice (which makes democracy possible) and inclined to
injustice (which makes the balance of forces by democratic means necessary); as “a lion
who devours the lamb,” but “a curious kind of lion who dreams of the day when the lion and
the lamb will lie down together” (Good 1965: 289).
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 139
Kelsen also feels that Niebuhr ought not to have it both ways when Niebuhr
insists that modern secular culture is both too cynical and too naively optimistic in
its assessment of human nature. Kelsen even seems untactful as he accuses Niebuhr
of inconsistency, at once faulting Niebuhr for blaming skeptical secularism for its
excessive pessimism, in regard to man’s rational capacity for justice, and at the
same time accusing liberal culture for being excessively optimistic in its estimates
of human nature. Niebuhr is not being inconsistent but is identifying extremes—
both of which are clearly evident in Western secular tradition and tend toward the
kind of “typology” Daniel Day Williams has noted. Niebuhr’s “Children of
Darkness” are those within the Western tradition (men such as Machiavelli and
Hobbes) who had the wisdom of the serpent in knowing the power of self-interest.
Their vision was “evil” in part because it knew no law beyond the self and tended to
see human nature in such negative terms that they would opt for a tyrannical order
in fear of anarchy. “Children of Light,” on the other hand, (John Dewey, for exam-
ple) do see a higher law than their own will but are “usually foolish because they do
not know the power of self-will” (Niebuhr 1944a: 9–10). Both stereotypical
extremes can be found in Western history, and Niebuhr’s use of this typology aims
at what is dominant in the American scene where his “vindication” of democracy is
most highly focused. Niebuhr’s dialectical balancing act focuses primarily on the
sentimentalism and utopian idealism he finds endemic to the American scene. If, in
the process Niebuhr gives short shrift to the moral cynics, such as Hobbes, it is
because moral cynicism has not been a major problem in American politics.
Kelsen is on somewhat firmer ground when he criticizes Niebuhr for laying
totalitarianism at the doorstep of those who disavow traditional religions. For while
there is a form of skepticism that, as Niebuhr puts it, “stands on the abyss of moral
nihilism,” the alleged “demonic religions” that he believes come rushing in to fill
the vacuum of traditional faith’s “melancholy, long withdrawing roar” (to borrow an
image from Matthew Arnold’s Dover Beach) do not necessarily follow from skepti-
cal relativism. In challenging Niebuhr for blaming secular skepticism for opening
up the floodgates to nihilism and the demonic furies of false faiths, Kelsen offers a
contrary view. For Kelsen, in agreement with Matthew Arnold, a failed Christianity
created the vacuum permitting the inrush of the secular “demonic” religions that
Niebuhr so deplores. Whether Kelsen believes this or is merely being eristic, per-
haps the truth was more properly grasped by Nietzsche whose announcement of the
“death of God” included the double-death of all absolutes, classical and Christian
alike. No such final wisdom comes from Kelsen’s pen on this point, however.
Somewhat pointedly he recommends holding the “relativism of religion, such as
advocated by Niebuhr, responsible for the victory of another religion (National
Socialism), which in its demonism maintains the illusion of absolutism” (Kelsen
1955: 62).3
3
Two things should be noted here. First, there are certainly instances within the traditional reli-
gions (Christian and Islamic, for example) that are as authoritarian, intolerant (tyrannical even) as
the “demonic religions” that Niebuhr contends that secularism has spawned. Niebuhr, of course, is
acutely aware of this tendency within the religious traditions and has written brilliantly on the need
140 D.F. Rice
Niebuhr also resists those secular versions of life that tend to idolatrize either the
nation or specific values within the social process. At one point he notes that “we
tend to identify our particular brand of democracy with the ultimate values of life”
(a tendency most evident in America) and proceeds to caution against those who
“know no other dimension of existence except the social one” and whose “loyalty
to democracy might dull the critical edge with which they approach their own
institutions” (Niebuhr 1947a: 1–2). While believing that no societal arrangement,
including democracy, can fulfill the needs of the human spirit (and that, therefore,
one’s true end is in God) Niebuhr is careful to warn against using religion as a shield
with which to sanctify the nation.4
Kelsen is perfectly correct in observing that Niebuhr wishes to do far more than
merely claim that the absence of religious faith leads to nihilism and totalitarianism.
His major criticisms of Niebuhr center upon his twofold judgment that Niebuhr is
wrong in thinking that “there is an essential connection between democracy and
Christian religion” and that therefore, Christian theology can “furnish a foundation
for democracy.” Certainly at the very best, Christian theology “can justify democ-
racy only as a relative value” (Kelsen 1955: 41).
There is, of course, no consistent view in Christian history as to how Christians
should relate to the political order. Niebuhr’s contention that “the most effective
opponents of tyrannical government today, as they have been in the past, are men
who can say ‘We must obey God rather than man’” (Niebuhr 1944a: 82) is certainly
questionable. Just because such belief provides a vantage point from which to
oppose the pretensions of our mortal Leviathans does not at all guarantee that
Christians will draw that conclusion. With sardonic (and appropriate) understate-
ment Kelsen maintains that “If this statement means [that] Christian theology does
and always did effectively resist tyrannical governments, its truth is not beyond
doubt” (Kelsen 1955: 54). Niebuhr, of course, is well aware that such a vantage
point was not always applied in this way. He knows that Pauline tradition augured
for subservience to the “powers that be,” and that there is a theocratic tradition
for humility, toleration, and self-criticism on the part of a responsible Christianity. Second, there
are many relativists and skeptics who neither clamor for substitute faiths nor conclude that dis-
criminatory moral judgments are impossible to make.
4
Niebuhr insists that a proper understanding of authentic religious belief is crucial for giving
meaning to human existence. So strongly does Niebuhr believe that pessimism leads to despair that
his writings are replete with the claim (almost a plea) that life is meaningless without the ultimate
meaning that only belief in God can provide. Not all religious skeptics lapse into the utter despair
Niebuhr believes to be their lot. Bertrand Russell and John Dewey are good examples. Neither
would gainsay the fact that a world without ultimate meaning is a tragic world. However, they
would dispute the notion that a life devoid of ultimate meaning is a life devoid of meaning.
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 141
within Christianity that aims, in the very name of God, to impose a coercive order
on society. After all, it is Niebuhr who confesses that even at its best the “Christian
tradition itself seldom stated” its position relative “to the political order in such a
way that it would give guidance in the complexities of political and social life”
(Niebuhr 1943: 278). Not only have the “great portions of Christianity” contributed
very little to the development of democracy,” as Gordon Harland puts it, but “the
story of religious authoritarianism and fanaticism is such a sorry chapter in the his-
tory of Western culture that any claims for the necessity of the insights of biblical
faith must begin with a contrite confession of the depths of Christian betrayal of
those insights” (Harland 1960: 171).
To some extent Kelsen is being somewhat obligatory here. However, he is cer-
tainly correct in stating an obvious point that Niebuhr himself has made, namely,
that “Christian theology cannot claim to be recognized as an advocate of a definite
political regime, because it can and actually did justify contrary regimes, just as it
can and actually did defend as well as attack the distribution of property, as Niebuhr’s
excellent chapter on ‘The Community and Property’ shows” (Kelsen 1955: 54).
Kelsen’s viewpoint, therefore, is reasonable enough. What he seems to miss, how-
ever, is that Niebuhr is expressing an exaggerated hope, and not a logical proposi-
tion. If and only if the Christian properly understands and applies his or her faith can
this transcendent perspective bear the fruit Niebuhr thinks it ought to. Niebuhr, who,
as noted earlier, reminded Mike Wallace that “it is as difficult to get charity out of
piety as to get reasonableness out of rationalism,” seems to have fallen prey to his
own form of wishful thinking.
Kelsen also criticizes Niebuhr for having said “democracy is the only alternative
to injustice and oppression” (Kelsen 1944: xiv). If that is the case then, as Kelsen
sees it, the task of showing “that democracy is the only alternative to injustice…
means the realization of absolute justice. For if democracy is demonstrated as rela-
tively just only, it cannot be the ‘only’ alternative to injustice.” Surely only an abso-
lute justice can exclude the possibility of another justice (Kelsen 1955: 56).
Kelsen’s way of putting this is curious to the theological reader. Niebuhr, as
Kelsen himself recognizes, holds that “there are no living communities which do
not have some notions of justice, beyond their historical laws, by which they seek to
gauge the justice of their legislative enactments” (Niebuhr 1944a: 67). This state-
ment alone undermines the force of Kelsen’s charge. Niebuhr is not saying that
there is an absolute justice nor is he so audacious as to claim there is no justice
whatever outside democracy. His view of the indeterminacy of human freedom and
the resultant openness of history precludes any such notion. Niebuhr is, however,
unabashedly willing to maintain that “ideally democracy is a permanently valid
form of social and political organization” for the reason that it “does justice to two
dimensions of human existence: to man’s spiritual stature and his social character;
to the uniqueness and variety of life, as well as to the common necessities of all
men” (Niebuhr 1944a: 3). And, as a form of social organization that maximizes
liberty, the relative freedom of its social and political life corresponds to, and allows
for, the endless elaboration of the individual and collective vitalities that rise
142 D.F. Rice
“in indeterminate degree over all social and communal concretions of life” (Niebuhr
1944a: 49). Indeed, democracy is, for Niebuhr, “a perennially valuable form of
social organization” precisely because, by its wisdom, “freedom and order are made
to support, and not contradict each other” (Niebuhr 1944a: 1).
Kelsen’s formulation of the problem seems, prima facie, nonsensical. For
Niebuhr justice is not an absolute but only an approximation and expression of love
in history; and, as an approximation of love, it is forever open to being drawn
beyond any momentary formulation to new heights. Justice, then, has no absolute
character or embodiment. It does not even possess a separate status. For Niebuhr,
“any definition of moral rules beyond those which mark the minimum obligation of
the self to the neighbor are discovered, upon close analysis, to be rational formula-
tions of various implications of the love commandment, rather than fixed and pre-
cise principles of justice” (Niebuhr 1949: 189). Moreover, while Niebuhr clearly
advances democracy as the best form of government for creating and maintaining
structures of justice, he clearly maintains that “the higher possibilities of love,
which is at once the fulfillment and the negation of justice, always hover over every
system of justice” (Niebuhr 1941: 302). It is arbitrary and irresponsible power from
which the injustices of life flow. Thus, Niebuhr is correct in claiming that democ-
racy is that system of government that has most successfully achieved ways of
checking power through a separation of powers, balancing conflicting forces and
factions within society, and, by means of maximizing freedom and equality, creat-
ing the maximum opportunities for social justice. It is his view that there is a tran-
scendent love that is the norm for the embodiment of justice in all historical forms
that defies crediting Niebuhr with absolutizing anything within history.
Perhaps Niebuhr is careless in using the word “only” in regard to democracy’s
role as providing an alternative to injustice and oppression. Elsewhere, while speak-
ing of our “self-righteous attitudes in international affairs,” he is still willing to
assert that “an open society is…the only condition for justice in society.” But he
does add that to present the value of “the peculiar form of the open society which
has developed in the West” in such a guise as our own “is to make the unique forms
of relativism in western life the basis of a false ultimate” (Niebuhr 1959a: 297).
Niebuhr does use language carelessly here. He says more than he means and some-
times means something slightly different from how he says it.
Kelsen wants to make the substantive charge that Niebuhr is, theologically, an
honest if reluctant relativist in spite of his attempt to argue that the vindication of
democracy rests on religion. What Kelsen is really aiming at in his critique of
Niebuhr is the issue of relativism and Niebuhr’s relationship to it. This issue arises
most vividly in Niebuhr’s struggle with concepts of natural law—an area where
there is enough ambiguity to draw the attention of several critics other than Kelsen,
one of whom, Paul Ramsay, I shall consider later. Kelsen makes the case that
Niebuhr is a relativist in spite of his disclaimer that “against relativists” a Christian
morality “must insist that no man or nation, no age or culture can arbitrarily define
its own law” (Niebuhr 1949: 194). Seemingly, Niebuhr’s appeal to general princi-
ples of justice, ie, in his own terms the “natural law,” exempts him by means of his
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 143
“notions of justice, beyond their historic laws” (Niebuhr 1944a, 67). But when
Niebuhr talks that way he insists that:
the principles of “natural law” by which justice is defined are, in fact, not so much fixed
standards of reason as they are rational efforts to apply the moral obligation, implied in the
love commandment, to the complexities of life and the fact of sin, that is, to the situation
created by the inclination of men to take advantage of each other.
Consequently, “[a]ny definition of moral rules beyond those which mark the mini-
mal obligation of the self to the neighbor are discovered, upon close analysis, to be
rational formulations of various implications of the love commandment, rather than
fixed and precise principles of justice” (Niebuhr 1949: 188–189 (emphasis added)).
Niebuhr’s discomfort with universals and absolutes stems, in part, from his
agreement with the pragmatic tradition of James and Dewey. Yet, in basic ways,
Niebuhr’s position is far more congruent with the temporal-mindedness of histori-
cism than with the illusions of a value-free scientism he finds in Dewey (Rice 1993).
In his reply to his friend Paul Ramsey, Niebuhr feels that Ramsey does not do justice
to his two main criticisms of both classical and modern versions of the natural law
theory. Tellingly, Niebuhr’s first point is that natural law “concepts do not allow for
the historical character of human experience,” being rooted instead “in a classical
rationalism which did not understand history.” They, therefore, do not understand
the uniqueness of historical occasion or the historical biases that creep into the defi-
nitions of natural law. This criticism is not met (as Ramsey attempts) by calling
attention to the distinctions between the jus natura, the jus gentium, and the jus
civilis. Of course, every natural law theory allows for the application of general
principles to particular situations, “[b]ut the question is whether its general princi-
ples are not too inflexible on the one hand and their definitions too historically
conditioned on the other hand.” In his second point, Niebuhr faults the Catholic
tradition for treating the law of love as a superadditum—something added onto as a
mere “addendum to the natural law.” He concludes by claiming that “[j]ustice is an
application of the law of love. The rules are not absolute but relative. They are appli-
cations of the law of love and do not have independence apart from it. They would
be independent only if they were found in an ‘essential’ social structure” (Niebuhr
1984: 711).
In 1940 Niebuhr published an article insisting that “it is not possible to state a
universally valid concept of justice from any particular sociological locus in history.
Nor is it possible to avoid either making the effort or making pretenses of universal-
ity which human finiteness does not justify.” We reside in “a tragic world, troubled
not by finiteness so much as by ‘false eternals’ and false absolutes, and expressing
the pride of these false absolutes even in the highest reaches of spirituality” (Niebuhr
1940: 88). And 6 years later, in an important published sermon, Niebuhr pens the
following lines echoing a view consistent with Kelsen’s own:
Just as there are only vantage points of relative impartiality in time from which we view the
past, so there are only vantage points of relative impartiality from which we view the pres-
ent scene. All human justice depends upon the organization of relatively impartial judicial
instruments, through which the endless conflicts of interest between men are arbitrated
(Niebuhr 1946: 9).
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 145
The concluding part of Kelsen’s critique of Niebuhr is, I believe even more pointed.
He maintains that “since Niebuhr is in favor of democratic tolerance which presup-
poses a relativistic view, he has recourse to the contradictory construction of
146 D.F. Rice
“the very meaning of the expression of the faith in God is that the truth or value
expressed is absolute” and “the expression of an idea is absolute if by this expres-
sion an absolute truth or value is meant.…Hence if the object to which the expres-
sion refers is supposed to be absolute—the object to which the expression of
religious faith refers, God, is the absolute—the expression cannot be characterized
as relative” (Kelsen 1955: 60). To discuss absolute symbols or absolute language is,
in my judgment, utterly nonsensical. Expressions are not absolute. Certainly they
cannot be meant, but only intended, because language and meaning involve quite
another set of relations.
Kelsen equates “having a religious character” with being “in possession of an
absolute truth,” and “having an absolute truth is” having a truth “founded upon
statements or expressions of ultimate truth” (Kelsen 1955: 60). Kelsen, as a con-
summate legalist, comes across as something of a scholastic fundamentalist (if this
is possible). Worse yet, he is unwilling to entertain even the possible discrepancy
between God’s “revelatory statements” (as he puts the meaning of revelation) and
the somewhat distanced role of the believer as an interpreter of those statements.
Neither does he pay heed to the context, both literary and historical, in which such
expressions are made. Even the Roman Catholic Church, which tends to believe, as
does the convert Kelsen, in a propositional theory of faith to which the believer is
merely called upon to subscribe, recognizes the problem and purports to solve it by
insisting that the Pope, under inspiration of the Holy Spirit, finally interprets cor-
rectly God’s revealed language.
Nonetheless, Kelsen’s contention that the view of toleration that Christianity
offers “is not necessarily the most consistent ideology” or “the most effective one”
seems well taken (Kelsen 1955: 61). Let us grant that Niebuhr’s view of toleration
is not as Kelsen represents it, but instead is entirely appropriate in light of the rela-
tive forms of all expressions of the ultimate. Still, such a basis for democracy is,
indeed, a difficult one. Niebuhr knows full well that the real test regarding toleration
is twofold: to possess the “ability to hold vital convictions which lead to action; and
also the capacity to preserve the spirit of forgiveness towards those who offend us
by holding to convictions which seem untrue to us” (Niebuhr 1943: 227). Moreover,
he admits religious tolerance is, without question, a most difficult and rare achieve-
ment. Niebuhr laments that not only has the Reformation shown “little advantage
over other versions of the Christian faith,” but that “Christian history in general has
frequently generated fanaticisms as grievous as the idolatries of other cultures”
(Niebuhr 1943: 227). He cites Milton’s Areopagitica and Saltmarsh’s Smoke in the
Temple as examples of those within the tradition who have understood the need for
toleration based on “the relativity of human knowledge”—focusing on Saltmarsh’s
advice given in 1646 that we not “assume any power of infallibility to each other;…
for another’s evidence is as dark to me as mine to him…till the Lord enlighten us
both for discerning alike” (Niebuhr 1943: 244–245). But these are rare voices aris-
ing out of the religious struggles in England leading up to the Civil War. They were
obvious exceptions to the rule. It is significant that they arose out of the tendencies
of left-wing Puritanism, and its evolution in the Levelers and Diggers, to ever more
secular modes of thought.
148 D.F. Rice
Knowing this, Niebuhr confesses that these provisional understandings were “an
integral part of the recovery of the sense of the historical in Renaissance thought”
and are causally related to “the ability of the Renaissance to meet one of the two
tests of the problem of toleration: the willingness to entertain views which oppose
our own without rancor and without the effort to suppress them” (Niebuhr 1943:
244–245). Nonetheless, “it is in meeting the other test: the ability to remain true to
and act upon our best convictions” that Niebuhr contends modern culture most fre-
quently fails. “It finds difficulty in avoiding irresponsibility and skepticism on the
one hand and new fanaticisms on the other” (Niebuhr 1943: 246).
Niebuhr’s sensitivity to the complex historical origins of democracy is evident
when he writes:
[T]he culture and climate, the “ideology” which supports democratic authority in the
Western world is thus drawn partly from the peculiar flexibilities and necessities of a techni-
cal society, partly from the Christian tradition which valued the individual as transcending
any social process and political community, and partly from modern secularism and empiri-
cism which generated the temper of criticism and punctured the religious tensions which
were the source of so much political authority (Niebuhr 1959b: 110).
Writing in 1961, Niebuhr stresses that “Christian humanism must make common
ground with the different kinds of secular humanism to protect the dignity of the
person against the peril of dehumanization in an increasingly technical age.” And “it
must do so in contrite awareness that the secular humanist may be more honest and
courageous in meeting large ethical problems than religious people” (Niebuhr
1961a: 120).
Niebuhr is keenly aware that, because of mixed evidence for both, the debate
“waged between Christian and secular leaders on the question whether democracy
is the product of the Christian faith or of a secular culture” is inconclusive. And
while contending that forces within both traditions helped establish democratic
institutions and furnish the resources of modern free societies, Niebuhr reminds the
reader that “there are traditional non-democratic Christian cultures to the right of
free societies which prove that the Christian faith does not inevitably yield demo-
cratic historical fruits” (Niebuhr 1953b: 19).
However he might have misrepresented Niebuhr’s view of toleration, Kelsen
seems quite right in pointing out what a feeble reed the Christian plea for humility
and toleration is as a basis for democracy. When Niebuhr returns to the matter of the
relevance of “the law of love to the collective relationships of mankind” 9 years
after Children of Light and Children of Darkness, he once again contends that only:
The heedlessness of love, which sacrifices the interests of the self-, enters into the calcula-
tions of justice by becoming the spirit of contrition which issues from the self’s encounter
with God. In that encounter it is made aware of the contingent character of all human claims
and the tainted character of all human pretensions and ideals. This contrition is the socially
relevant counterpart of love. [Breaking one’s pride,] this spirit lies at the foundation of what
we define as democracy. For democracy cannot exist if there is no recognition of the frag-
mentary character of all systems of thought and value which are allowed to exist together
within the democratic frame. Thus the agape of forgiveness as well as the agape of sacrifi-
cial love become a leaven in the lump of the spirit of justice (Niebuhr 1953c).
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 149
A feeble reed, indeed, such an expectation must be. Niebuhr expects neither perfect
love nor perfect justice in this world. What he recognizes, however, is that some-
thing more than discrimination and self-interested reason is necessary for the kind
of justice to which a democracy aspires.
Kelsen is partially correct in suggesting that Niebuhr’s position is “not much dif-
ferent from” what Niebuhr calls that “more sophisticated form of secularism”—a
form of skepticism “which is conscious of the relativity of all human perspectives”
(Kelsen 1955: 61–62). I, for one, am not much disturbed by the forthrightness of
Niebuhr’s “perspectival relativism,” based as it is on his understanding of history.
And I certainly consider it a plus that Niebuhr, unlike those who flirt with irrele-
vance by staking their claims on abstract revelatory dicta, knows full well that the
relevance of religion must make its way in the marketplace of experience where the
contest for a genuine hearing resides.
Kelsen suspects that Niebuhr ends up showing that there exists “a relationship
between democracy and certain moral-political principles which,” by his own light
“but without sufficient reason,” he identifies with, or considers “to be in harmony,
with the evangelical law as the specific Christian morality” (Kelsen 1955: 64). If so,
Kelsen seems to miss an important point. He agrees with Niebuhr in holding that
there is “only one principle of morality which is specifically Christian…the princi-
ple of love.” However, unlike Niebuhr, who claims this love has everything to do
with the relevance of Christianity to political life, Kelsen concludes that “this prin-
ciple is inapplicable in political reality” (Kelsen 1955: 65). Kelsen’s view is, “If
love, the love of Christ were really the moving force of democracy, then and only
then could it be maintained that democracy is essentially connected with Christianity”
(Kelsen 1955: 65). Niebuhr, as we have seen, devotes his entire career to making
precisely that case. Avoiding such language as “essential connection” and the
“moving force,” Niebuhr is content to argue that the law of love is related to justice
and that, therefore, Christianity has something important to say about democracy.
It is important to look briefly at the views of Kelsen and Niebuhr regarding the
preconditions for democracy and the prospects of expanding democracy around
the world.
Kelsen’s view of democracy is inseparable from, and dependent on, his primary
aim of establishing what he called a “Pure Theory of Law.” By “pure,” he means a
theory of law that has itself as its sole object, thus freeing “legal science of all for-
eign elements—elements such as ethics, religion, politics, and sociology” (Kelsen
1934: 7). Kelsen’s objective is thus a formal one in that he approaches democracy
as “only a form, a method for the creation of the social order” (Kelsen 1926 (2013
ed.: 101)). He felt that the independence afforded by his formal approach to
150 D.F. Rice
Kelsen’s formal, legal emphasis reveals his focus on the constitutional precondi-
tions for democracy. Writing a good constitution, as Kelsen did in helping to draft
one for Austria in 1920, is the sine qua non for establishing future democracies.
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 151
What Niebuhr has to say specifically about the situation in America highlights
his emphasis on the organic preconditions to democracy that he finds missing in
Kelsen’s constitutional focus. Commenting on why America has “produced so
many constitutionalists in international political theory,” Niebuhr concludes that
such a pattern relies on the fact that “American history encourages the illusion that
152 D.F. Rice
the nation was created purely by constitutional fiat and compact” (Niebuhr 1944a:
166). This is an illusion:
because the constitution was the end and not the beginning of an historical process which
began with a common conflict against an imperial overlord. In this conflict the separate
colonial entities gradually coalesced into a single community. In its course a military leader
emerged, in the person of Washington, whose prestige was of immeasurable importance as
a rallying point for the nation. Most modern nations do not have as clear a constitutional
beginning as the United States. It is therefore the more significant that even in the history of
the United States the real beginning is more organic and less constitutional than is usually
assumed (Niebuhr 1944a: 166–167).
According to Niebuhr, the highly developed degree of integration that both imperial
and national communities worldwide have achieved have:
all have had some core of ethnic homogeneity, though various and heterogeneous elements
may be on the periphery. They have also been bound together by particular and unique
cultural forces and by the power of a common tradition and of common experiences. The
authority of the government in such communities is not infrequently derived from the same
history from which the community derived its unity (Niebuhr 1944a: 165).
to allow the free play of competitive interests without endangering the unity of the
community itself; (2) a belief in the freedom of the individual and appreciation of
his worth; and (3) a tolerable harmony and equilibrium of social and political and
economic forces necessary to establish an approximation of social justice (Niebuhr
and Sigmund 1969: 73).
8.4.2.1 Justice
Niebuhr and Kelsen differ in terms of the time and attention they give to the issue of
justice. This reflects a different emphasis between them. For Niebuhr, the dominant
theme of social justice in democracy arises out of his primary emphasis on the
political sphere; whereas Kelsen chooses to separate the question of justice for phil-
osophical and metaphysical reflection in order to allow his pure theory of law to
stand on its own two feet.
In Kelsen’s essay, What is Justice?, based on his May 27, 1952, farewell lecture
as an active member of the University of California at Berkeley, he surveys history
for answers to the question of justice without finding any resolution. Convinced that
“absolute justice is an irrational ideal or, what amounts to the same, an illusion—
one of the eternal illusions of mankind,” (Kelsen 1957: 21) Kelsen claims we are left
with only a conditional solution of the problem of justice as “a judgment of value,
determined by emotional factors, and therefore, subjective in character—valid only
for the judging subject and therefore relative only” (Kelsen 1957: 4). In his final
reflection on justice Kelsen concludes:
I cannot say what justice is, the absolute justice for which mankind is longing. I must acqui-
esce in a relative justice and I can only say what justice is to me. Since science is my profes-
sion, and hence the most important thing in my life, justice, to me, is that social order under
whose protection the search for truth can prosper. “My” justice, then, is the justice of freedom,
the justice of peace, the justice of democracy—the justice of tolerance (Kelsen 1957: 24).
In the end, Kelsen settles on opting for the relative justice that democracy can
guarantee in bringing about the greatest possible degree of individual freedom.
Kelsen regards freedom as a spiritual matter. He writes that “The life principle of
every democracy is…spiritual freedom, freedom to express opinions, freedom of
belief and conscience, the principle of toleration, and more especially, the freedom
of science, in conjunction with the belief in its possible objectivity. The constitu-
tions of all democracies bear witness to this spirit” (Kelsen 1973: 101–102).
Niebuhr agrees with Kelsen that absolute justice is a chimera and that whatever
justice is attainable in history is tentative and temporary, relative to a never-ending
balancing of social forces. Niebuhr also probes the spiritual element of democracy
in claiming that, speaking ideally, “democracy is a permanently valid form of social
and political organization which does justice to two dimensions of human existence:
to man’s spiritual stature and his social character; to the uniqueness and variety of
154 D.F. Rice
life, as well as to the common necessities of all men.” However, in emphasizing the
“common necessities of all men,” Niebuhr seeks to emphasize that while “the com-
munity requires liberty as much as does the individual,” it is also true that “the
individual requires community more than bourgeois thought comprehended.” It is
precisely for this reason, Niebuhr concludes, that democracy cannot “be equated
with freedom. An ideal democratic order seeks unity within the conditions of free-
dom; and maintains freedom within the framework of order” (Niebuhr 1944a: 3).
For Niebuhr freedom is required for social organization on the grounds that man is
essentially free—namely, capable of indeterminate transcendence over nature to
which he also belongs. However, while “a free society is justified by the fact that the
indeterminate possibilities of human vitality may be creative,” the limitations soci-
ety places upon freedom are also justified “by the fact that the vitalities may be
destructive” (Niebuhr 1944a: 63–64).
For Niebuhr, injustice, rooted in the destructive forces of inordinate self-love, is
the fundamental problem in social and political life. He claims that democratic soci-
eties seek to bring political power into the service of justice in three ways. First,
“they have tried to distribute economic and political power and prevent its undue
concentration” (Niebuhr 1952a: 135) Second, “they have tried to bring it under
social and moral review.” Third, “they have sought to establish inner religious and
moral checks upon it” (Niebuhr 1952a: 135). In Niebuhr’s view this “effort to coerce
competitive and contradictory human aspirations and interests into some kind of
tolerable order and justice” is “a highly moral one” (Niebuhr 1959c: 116). While
Niebuhr maintains that “there is no Christian economic or political system,” he does
claim that there is “a Christian attitude towards the claims of all systems of justice.”
This consists of maintaining “a critical attitude towards the claims of all systems
and schemes, expressed in the question whether they will contribute to justice in a
concrete situation,” and also in adopting “a responsible attitude, which will not pre-
tend to be God nor refuse to make a decision between political answers to a problem
because each answer is discovered to contain moral ambiguity in God’s sight”
(Niebuhr 1957: 253–254).
When Kelsen attends to the question of what is just and what is unjust in a soci-
ety, as a matter of diverging value judgments, he concludes on the basis of rational
judgment that:
there are only interests of human beings and hence conflicts of interest. The solution of
these conflicts can be brought about either by satisfying one interest at the expense of the
other, or by a compromise between the conflicting interests. It is not possible to prove that
only the one or the other solution is just. Under certain conditions the one, under others the
other may be just. If social peace is supposed to be the ultimate end—but only then—the
compromise solution may be just, but the justice of peace is only a relative, and not an
absolute, justice (Kelsen 1957: 21–22).
Niebuhr certainly concurs with Kelsen’s viewpoint, as far as it goes, but he is not
willing to let matters rest here. For Niebuhr the issue of balancing conflicting inter-
ests is precisely the point where a serious concern with justice surfaces in political
life. Justice, for Niebuhr, comes down to the issue of balancing power among groups
holding opposing interests in order to achieve a modicum of social harmony. While
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 155
Niebuhr sees “no neat principle which will solve the relation of power to justice and
of justice to freedom,” (Niebuhr 1952a: 100) he insists that we have:
achieved such justice as we possess in the only way justice can be achieved in a technical
society: we have equilibrated power. We have attained a certain equilibrium in economic
society itself by setting organized power against organized power. When that did not suffice
we used the more broadly based political power to redress disproportions and disbalances
in economic society (Niebuhr 1952a: 101).
Insofar as democracy has proven itself capable of holding all cultural viewpoints
under criticism and of achieving an uncoerced harmony among the various social
and cultural vitalities, it has demonstrated itself to be the most adept political answer
to the problem of accommodating and balancing the interests of competing groups.
To the degree that democracy succeeds in holding “all claims to truth under critical
review” and balancing “all social forces, not in an automatic, but in a contrived
harmony of power…it distills a modicum of truth from a conflict of error” (Niebuhr
1952b: 51).
Niebuhr sees justice as something beyond the mere balance of power. He views
it as an approximation of love, as the relative embodiment of love in society. Kelsen
clearly understands the radical nature of Christian love. However, he re-categorizes
the discussion of justice for the philosophical domain so as to separate it from legal
science. This results in disregarding the possible relevance of love to the realities of
human nature that is so prominent in Niebuhr. Kelsen is convinced that Jesus pro-
claimed a justice that “is beyond any social order to be established in reality; and the
love which is the essence of this justice is evidently not the human instinct we call
love.…The love taught by Jesus is not human love” (Kelsen 1957: 12). Kelsen’s
view finds him in agreement with the position Anders Nygren took in his highly
influential book, Agape and Eros, published in 1969. Niebuhr’s understanding of
Nygren would also apply to Kelsen. Niebuhr points out that the “rigorous distinc-
tion” Nygren makes “between the ‘unmotivated’ self-giving love which the Gospels
ascribe to a merciful God and the classical idea of eros which, according to Nygren,
is always a calculating love, seeking to complete the self from the standpoint of the
self and which therefore makes love the servant of self-love” results in Nygren’s
agape as “a complete impossibility and irrelevance for man. It describes the charac-
ter of God but has no real relation, as source and end, toward philia and eros, toward
either mutual love or expressions of love, tainted with self-interest, which are the
actual stuff of our human existence” (Niebuhr 1949: 178). Niebuhr, as opposed to
both Kelsen and Nygren, finds agape as having perpetual relevance to the structure
of human existence:
in the fact that it is both the fulfillment of the self’s freedom and the contradiction of every
actual self-realization insofar as every actual self-realization is partly an egoistic and there-
fore a premature closing of the self within itself. Agape is thus, as the final norm of the self
as free spirit, a perpetual source of judgment upon every other norm which may be used
tentatively to describe the self’s duties and obligations. At the same time, it refutes the
lawlessness of those theories which imagine that the freedom of the self entitles it to have
no law but its own will. Such a proud assertion of the self’s freedom and disavowal of its
finiteness leads to self-destruction (Niebuhr 1949: 179).
156 D.F. Rice
Kelsen sets his view of democracy in sharp contrast to democratic theories based on
the principle of “equality.” While not opposed to recognizing the value of “political”
equality, Kelsen wants to point out that those who insist on grounding political
legitimacy on the notion of justice—understood as equality—end up contrasting a
formal notion of equality with a substantive notion in a way that undermines democ-
racy itself. Kelsen views democracy as a process, not as a fact—a process in which
equality has the appropriate political meaning that everyone should have an equal
right in participating in the process of collective self-government. According to
Kelsen:
The idea of equality certainly plays its own role in democratic ideology. Yet, as we have
seen, it does so only in a completely negative, formal, and secondary sense. The demand for
preferably universal, and therefore equal, freedom requires universal and therefore equal
participation in government. Historically the fight for democracy has been a fight for politi-
cal freedom, that is, for popular participation in the legislative and executive spheres.
Insofar as the idea of equality is meant to connote anything other than formal equality with
regard to freedom (i.e. political participation) that idea has nothing to do with democracy.
This can be seen in the fact that not the political and formal, but the material and economic
equality of all can be realized just as well—if not better—in an autocratic-dictatorial form
of state as it can in a democratic form of state (Kelsen 1926: 97).
(Kelsen 1973: 99). What is at stake for Kelsen is the goal of achieving equality, ie,
universal freedom, for all members of society. Kelsen rules out any other notion of
equality as relating to the foundational meaning of democracy.
Niebuhr’s views on justice within democracy are much more complex and
nuanced than those of Kelsen. Niebuhr insists that both liberty and equality are
involved as “regulative principles of democracy and fraternity” (Niebuhr 1947b:
65). He expands on this thought as follows:
Without liberty a community ceases to be a community of persons and becomes a forcibly
unified mass. Without equality as the regulative principle of justice, the community allows
either ancient or hereditary or newly created inequalities of privilege and of power to
destroy the community of persons. If the middle-class democratic movement of the eigh-
teenth and nineteenth century emphasized primarily the value of liberty as contrasted with
the two repressive cohesions of feudal society, the modern democratic impulse borne pri-
marily by the industrial workers in expressing itself in socialism has emphasized particu-
larly the value of equality. The emphasis was important because one of the ironic effects of
an industrial society which had promised emancipation from the inequalities of a feudal
agrarian society, was the creation of more dynamic forms of inequality than were possible
in an agrarian society (Niebuhr 1947b: 68).
Niebuhr knew that, if taken to extremes, liberty and equality would negate the other.
Total liberty—because of the wiles of the wise, the powerful, and the cunning—
results in gross inequalities. Total equality—because of its need to be coerced—
destroys liberty. Healthy democracies involve recognition of both liberty and
equality as components of justice in the perennial struggle of balancing power and
interest with the body politic.5 They are consistently in tension with each other in
the conflicting give and take of a viable democracy.
As Niebuhr sees it, the “principle of ‘equality’ is a relevant criterion of criticism
for the social hierarchy, and the principle of ‘liberty’ serves the same purpose for the
community’s unity. But neither principle could be wholly nor absolutely applied
without destroying the community” (Niebuhr 1958: 62). He is aware that while
inequalities of privilege are somewhat proportioned to prestige and function, they
never correspond exactly to these inequalities of function. In the end:
We thus confront the two basic realities of the community’s social hierarchy. The one is that
such a hierarchy is necessary, and the other is that the prestige, power and privilege, particu-
larly privilege, of its upper levels tend to be inordinate. That is why there can be no simple
solution for the problem of social gradation. That is why equality must remain a regulative
principle of justice and why equalitarianism is the ideology of the poor. They resent the
inequalities, rightly because of their inordinate character; but they wrongly imagine that all
inequalities could be abolished (Niebuhr 1958: 64).
5
For Niebuhr, justice demands something more than merely balancing power. Central to his
thought is the claim that the quest for justice be related to the norm of love. Niebuhr is well aware
that what he calls the “law of love” (agape) is a normative ideal and not something historically
realizable. Such love is heedless, uncalculating, sacrificial—devoid of the careful calculations so
essential to adjudicating conflicts of interest. Niebuhr once called such love an “impossible
possibility”—and recognizes that its “impossibility” is far more obvious in collective life than in
individual life.
158 D.F. Rice
In the final analysis Niebuhr cautions against believing liberty and equality to be
simple historical possibilities. The two are “in paradoxical relation to each other and
that it is possible to purchase the one only at the price of the other” (Niebuhr 1958: 69).
References
Good, Robert C. 1965. National interest and moral theory: The ‘debate’ among contemporary
political realists. In Foreign policy in the sixties: The issues and instruments—essays in honor
of Arnold Wolfers, ed. Hilsman Roger and Robert C. Good. Baltimore: The Johns Hopkins
University Press.
Harland, Gordon. 1960. The thought of Reinhold Niebuhr. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1926. The essence and value of democracy. 2013 edition by Nadia Urbinati and
Carlo Invernizzi Accetti. Trans. B. Graf. Plymouth: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. B.L. Paulson and
S.L. Paulson 1996. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944. Peace through law. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1955. Foundations of democracy. In Ethics: An international journal of social polit-
ical and legal philosophy, ed. Charner Marquis Perry, Supplement, 1–101. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1957. What is justice? In What is justice: Justice law, and politics in the mirror of
science. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1973. State-form and world-outlook. In Hans Kelsen: Essays in legal and moral
philosophy, ed. Ota Weinberger. Boston: Reidel.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1939. Ten years that shook my world. Christian Century 56: 545.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1940. Christian faith and natural law. Theology 89: 88.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1941. The nature and destiny of man, volume I, Human Destiny. London:
Nisbet & Co. Ltd.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1943. The nature and destiny of man, volume II, Human Destiny. London:
Nisbet & Co. Ltd.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1944a. Children of light and children of darkness. New York: Charles Scribner’s
Sons.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1944b. Sovereignty and peace. The Nation, November 18.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1946. Discerning the signs of the times: Sermons for today and tomorrow.
New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1947a. Democracy as religion. Christianity and Crisis, 1–2. August 4.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1947b. Christianity as a basis of democracy. The Listener 37.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1949. Faith and history. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1952a. Irony of American history. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1952b. Christian realism and power politics. New York: Charles Scribner’s
Sons.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1953a. In Christian realism and political problems. New York: Charles
Scribner’s Sons.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1953b. Democracy, secularism, and Christianity. In Christianity and Crisis,
March 2.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1953c. Christian faith and social action. In Christian faith and social action,
ed. J.A. Hutchison. New York: Scribner.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1957. Theology and political thought in the western world. Ecumenical Review,
April 1957.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1958. Liberty and equality. In Pious and secular America. New York: Charles
Scribner’s Sons.
8 Kelsen and Niebuhr on Democracy 159
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1959a. The structure of nations and empires. London: Nisbet & Co. Ltd.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1959b. Power and ideology in national and international affairs. In Theoretical
aspects of international relations, ed. W.T.R. Fox. South Bend: University of Notre Dame.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1959c. Education and the world scene. Daedalus 88(1): 107–120.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1961a. How my mind has changed. In How my mind has changed, ed. Harold
E. Fey. New York: Meridian.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1961b. Well-tempered evangelism. New Republic, June 26.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1962. Can democracy work? New Leader, May 28.
Niebuhr, Reinhold. 1984. Reply to interpretation and criticism. In Reinhold Niebuhr: His religious,
social and political thought, ed. Charles W. Kegley. New York: Pilgrim Press.
Niebuhr, Reinhold, and Paul Sigmund. 1969. The democratic experience: Past and prospects.
New York: Frederick A. Praeger.
Rice, Daniel. 1993. Reinhold Niebuhr and John Dewey: An American Odyssey. Albany: State
University of New York Press.
Vinx, Lars. 2007. Kelsen’s theory of democracy—reconciliation with social order. In Hans
Kelsen’s pure theory of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Watson, Philip. 1966. Let God be God: An interpretation of the theology of Martin Luther.
Minneapolis: Fortress Press.
Williams, Daniel Day. 1984. Niebuhr and liberalism. In Reinhold Niebuhr: His religious, social
and political thought, ed. Charles W. Kegley. New York: Pilgrim Press.
Chapter 9
Hans Kelsen’s Psychoanalytic Heritage—An
Ehrenzweigian Reconstruction
Bettina K. Rentsch
9.1 Introduction
The significance of Hans Kelsen’s impact in Europe is evident both in his influence
on numerous scholars in a wide range of fields and in the widespread acceptance of
his substantial findings (Cf. Jestaedt 2008: XXII). Conversely, in the United States
of America, there was never a second generation of U.S. scholars who explored
Kelsenian approaches to the law or even commented, whether appreciatively or
critically, on Kelsen’s body of work. Also, while some of his contemporaries show
great respect for Kelsen’s outstanding qualities,1 most of American scholarship is,
at best, critical with regard to the pure theory of law (cf. Meiklejohn 1958: 543
(545); Northrop 1958: 815; Halbach 1973:957).
From a scholarly perspective, controversies involving Hans Kelsen in the United
States prove very useful for a thorough understanding of his work. Putting one of
the most renowned European legal scholars of the twentieth century under the con-
siderable pressure of justification, American scholarship not only motivated Kelsen
to refine the pure theory of law (Meiklejohn 1958: 543; Ross 1957: 564) but also
forced him to reconsider the jurisprudential underpinnings of his legal theory. In
response to the challenges he faced in the United States, Hans Kelsen adopted more
of a legal realist point of view than the orthodox label “normative legal positivism”
captures (Jestaedt 2008: XXII).
1
As Halbach stated: “A giant of the law has left us” (Halbach 1973: 957).
B.K. Rentsch (*)
Institute for Private International Law and International Commercial Relations,
University of Heidelberg, Heidelberg, Germany
e-mail: [email protected]
2
Cf. the subtitle to Kelsen (1957) essay collection What is Justice?—Justice, Law and Politics in
the Mirror of Science.
9 Hans Kelsen’s Psychoanalytic Heritage 163
Ehrenzweig’s academic record does not evidence strong ties to either jurisprudence
or to legal theory. In contrast, Ehrenzweig’s treatise on the conflict of laws (1962),
together with several publications on the subject matter, elaborated the so-called lex
fori approach, a prominent, though nowadays minority realist position within the
“Conflicts Revolution” (Siehr 1957: 585).
Adhering to legal realism, the lex fori approach departs from the finding that
courts tend to neglect foreign elements when adjudicating legal issues. Consequently,
courts apply the law of their own jurisdiction, the lex fori, to a much higher number
of cases than they should (Ehrenzweig 1962: § 21 ff). As a remedy, Ehrenzweig first
develops normative and inclusive criteria for finding the appropriate forum. In so
doing, Ehrenzweig treats together two questions—jurisdiction and applicable law—
that are usually kept separate by all possible means. In Ehrenzweig’s opinion, ques-
tions like those of jurisdiction and choice of law not only tend to raise the same
3
Barton/Hill/Riesenfeld, 1977, University of California: In Memoriam.
164 B.K. Rentsch
issues, they also tend to influence one another in practice. Ehrenzweig next estab-
lishes criteria for how to appropriately identify foreign elements (data) in a case
with foreign elements, and provides guidance as to the question of how to determine
whether foreign law or forum law should be applied to those foreign elements.
Despite its negligible scholarly impact, Ehrenzweig’s treatise is of great value for
current discussions, as it offers a thorough comparative analysis of contemporary
scholarship on legal sociology and legal realist jurisprudence in Europe and the
United States (Ehrenzweig 1971; Friedmann 1972: 1718, 1721). Indeed,
Ehrenzweig’s policy objective was to initiate a transatlantic dialogue on legal meth-
odology (Ehrenzweig 1971: § 75). In order to achieve his objective, Ehrenzweig
first concisely summed up the leading ideas of German-speaking legal sociology
(Friedmann 1972: 1718, 1720) and second introduced his readers, through a com-
parative study, to contemporary analytic U.S. scholarship, such as critical legal
studies and legal realism (Ehrenzweig 1971: § 75). He intended to get U.S. scholars
to become more receptive to current developments in European legal theory. By
means of a German translation of his treatise (Ehrenzweig 1972: Vorwort des
4
This may also be due to the criticism in the treatise’s substantial vagueness (Friedmann 1972:
1718, 1721).
5
For direct references to Ehrenzweig’s influence, see Bienenfeld 1965: 957; Part II: Analysis,
1254; Goldstein (1968: 1053).
9 Hans Kelsen’s Psychoanalytic Heritage 165
Verfassers, 18 ff), Ehrenzeig also thought to introduce scholars working in the tradi-
tion of European legal sociology to U.S. versions of the legal realism and critical
legal studies (Ehrenzweig 1972: Vorwort des Verfassers, 18 ff).
In sum, the psychoanalytical jurisprudence tends to combine both: A comparison
and a transatlantic reunion of jurisprudence. Beyond a new approach to jurispru-
dence, the author intended to create the foundation to a transnational school of legal
sociology (Ehrenzweig 1965: 1331, 1335, 1971: § 75f.).
6
By using “false conflicts,” this article borrows from contemporary conflicts of laws methodology,
following Currie (1963: 33, 159, 181, 582; reflection see Cavers 1983: 471).
166 B.K. Rentsch
methods of legal and jurisprudential inquiry (Ehrenzweig 1965: 1331, 1337). Both
schools, as Ehrenzweig concludes, are rooted in unsubstantiated, hence unreliable
hypotheses (Ehrenzweig 1965: 1331, 1337).
The author then argues that psychoanalytical jurisprudence can overcome these
uncertainties. It does so first, by means of an explicit disclosure of its hypotheses,
and second, by the express relativity of its presumptions. Psychoanalytical jurispru-
dence avoids the use of normative arguments. Hence, by using psychoanalytic
methodology, Ehrenzweig does not intend to find the right answer to an open value
controversy or support one among several jurisprudential positions on a given ques-
tion. His main objective is instead to disclose the underlying emotional conflict
between the three categories of psychoanalysis, id, ego, and super-ego, to which
controversies among competing jurisprudential schools can be reduced. Like other
partisans of psychoanalytical approaches (Bienenfeld 1965: 957, 1254; Goldstein
1968: 1053), Ehrenzweig considered his method a unique and, therefore, revolu-
tionary attempt to build up a sustainable meta-order to legal and trans-legal dis-
course (Ehrenzweig 1971: Synopsis § 7, § 75). For Ehrenzweig, psychoanalysis
embodied and improved upon all other methodologies previously used to evaluate
or describe legal phenomena and discourse.
As he raises the question of justice, Kelsen sets the stage for fundamental criticism
of his approach to legal science. Reviewing What is Justice, the 1952 essay collec-
tion that starts by a print version of Kelsen’s farewell lecture, Donald Meiklejohn
(Chicago) states that:
…Kelsen himself clearly feels the need to find the normative principle which can underline
the law, though not at the cost of corrupting the scientific study of the law. I propose to raise
the question, in considering the book as a whole, whether in his enthusiasm for science he
has not improperly rejected or repressed his concern for justification (Meiklejohn 1958:
543).
Meicklejohn’s critique ignores the fact that not only Kelsen’s Pure Theory of
Law, but also the essay collection that Meiklejohn reviewed were dedicated to
logic-based, analytic inquiry that does not seek to prove but to confront normative
claims.
to ask for and define justice: This is the irrational assumption of a divine power that
dictates duties of justice and injustice (Kelsen 1957: 1, 10 f.). If we assume absolute
justice to be, on the other hand, profane and not divine in its nature, we come to
grips with a human need to externally justify and, by doing so, falsely rationalize
individual, and by their very nature, subjective needs (Kelsen 1957: 1, 10 f.).
7
Rephrasing cf. Kelsen, Justice (1957, 1, 3); on the original Bentham, A Fragment on Government,
preface, 393: “it is the greatest happiness of the greatest number that is the measure of right and
wrong, been as yet developed.”
9 Hans Kelsen’s Psychoanalytic Heritage 169
mines any possibility that it could be used to calculate the highest shared set of
values in sum (Kelsen 1957: 1, 3). The soundness of Kelsen’s opposition becomes
manifest when considered in the light of Bentham’s heritage in modern welfare
economics. Pareto (2014 (summarized by Cirillo 1979: 94 ff)) efficiency, located at
the highest number of intersecting sets of individual happiness, builds upon the
faulty assumption that human behavior is rational and that degrees of happiness are
readily quantifiable (Kelsen 1957: 1, 9). “If a man is a more or less rational being…,”
Kelsen states, “he tries to justify his behavior, motivated by the emotions of his fear
and desire, in a rational way, that is to say, through his intellect” (Kelsen 1957: 1, 8).
The attempt to rationalize fear and desire, however, does not end up changing their
irrational nature.
As a result, even an inter-subjective and concrete definition of justice, such as
any attempt to define its content analytically, cannot generate reliable results, as it
carries the bias of humankind’s expectation. In fact, any human expectation regard-
ing justice ends up being created by human consciousness, which itself is inacces-
sible to analytic research (Kelsen 1957: 1, 10). The longing for an objectively
accessible version of justice is irrational, as trying to define justice means trying to
rationalize the irrational.
Although he rejects the rational nature of justice in principle, Kelsen admits that “…
very many individuals agree in their judgments of value” (Kelsen 1957: 1, 7). Value
concepts, therefore, may happen to be similar in substance if the societal and cul-
tural circumstances that generate them converge (Kelsen 1957: 1, 7). The substan-
tial coherence of a purely subjective value set can generate a moral order of
quasi-absolute coercive command that can be equivalent to what is considered to be
justice in substance (Kelsen 1957: 1, 22). A relativist concept of justice, therefore,
is neither amoral nor immoral (Kelsen 1957: 1, 22).
These systems of justice, despite being born out of parallel human needs, can by
no means be objective or absolute. Instead, they are fugitive constructions that prove
justice as a concept to be relative in scope, time, and substance (Kelsen 1957: 1, 21):
“If the history of humankind proves anything, it is the futility of the attempt to
establish, in the way of rational considerations, an absolutely correct standard of
human behavior…” (Kelsen 1957: 1, 21).
In a later essay, Kelsen would use the Holy Scriptures to exemplify the relativity
of morals (Kelsen 1957: 25). The intrinsic relativity of justice, according to Kelsen’s
reading of the Bible, is displayed in the gap between God’s omnipotence and his
absolute justice (Kelsen 1957: 25). Kelsen also highlights the difference between
the moral convictions displayed in biblical times and their alteration in modern
societies.
170 B.K. Rentsch
While rejecting the existence of absolute justice and moral orders, Kelsen acknowl-
edges the practical difficulties in accepting relative concepts of justice (Kelsen
1957: 1, 22).
[R]elativism imposes upon the individual the difficult tasks of deciding for himself what is
right and what is wrong. This, of course, implies a very serious responsibility, the most seri-
ous moral responsibility a man can assume (Kelsen 1957: 1, 22).
As mentioned above, my principal scholarly objective here was not to pursue the
question of justice but to show that Kelsen saw that the underpinnings of the claim
for absolute justice are rooted in human emotion. On this basis, Ehrenzweig’s anal-
ysis begins where Kelsen’s ends.
We have undertaken to still the battle between those claiming and those denying the “exis-
tence” of a natural law as a “valid” legal order based on justice. Any such undertaking must
accept that this battle, insofar as it is not one of words, is based on and carried by deep-
seated emotions (Ehrenzweig 1971: 197, § 166).
Ehrenzweig’s second claim is by far more important for this chapter. To understand
what the need for justice is based on means to analyze and investigate the origins of
as many of the different justice conceptions as we are able find in human interac-
tion. In sum, these justices may disclose the basic principle from which they stem
(Ehrenzweig 1971: 198, § 167).
In doing so, we identify the same conflict in different shapes and contexts.
Reason fights un-reason. The super-ego fights the id. Acknowledging that an indi-
vidual’s longing for objective categories, such as justice, results from an internal
conflict between different categories of human consciousness enables us to explain
why we desperately seek an external justification of our behavior. It also explains,
why Kelsen, admitting the irrationality in justice and obliging the human being to
individually justify his behavior, neither answers our question nor fulfills its under-
lying needs. The same is true for his inclination towards democracy as a political
system, which, due to its value neutrality, is a feasible means to maintain and
develop individual justice (Kelsen 1957: 1, 23).
Finally, Ehrenzweig’s reasoning offers an alternative option of conflict resolu-
tion regarding the relationship between diverging conceptions of justice and the
political systems generating them: According to a psychoanalytical approach to the
law, different understandings of “just” societal organizations can be traced back in
their divergence as analogies to human beings’ mental development (Ehrenzweig
1971: 199 f., § 169). Borrowing from Rudolf Bienenfeld, one of Ehrenzweig’s lead-
ing sources on psychoanalysis and the law (Bienenfeld 1965: 1254), Ehrenzweig
outlined possible parallels between a child’s continuous emancipation from its
mother (Bienenfeld 1965: 1254, 1255) and political systems. The first stage of
development is analogous to a theocracy, where the child lives under omnipotent
parental authority, which the child cannot overcome because it lacks independent
critical reasoning skills (Bienenfeld 1965: 1254, 1257). Next, a child’s physical
(Bienenfeld 1965: 1254, 1257) and emotional emancipation from its mother first
results in anarchy (Bienenfeld 1965: 1254, 1259). Finally, a model of social coop-
eration between mother and child emerges (Bienenfeld 1965: 1254, 1260;
Ehrenzweig 1971: 200, § 170). Likewise, after a phase of declared communism
9 Hans Kelsen’s Psychoanalytic Heritage 173
ignorant towards values like property, children, developing a sense of privacy, adopt
a more individualistic position to delimit their sphere from that of others (Ehrenzweig
1971: 197, 200 f., § 171). To sum up, one might argue that every social order and
the justice concept on which it is based mirrors the development of human con-
sciousness. The more we understand human consciousness, the better we can ana-
lyze the foundations of what we establish as a social order.
9.5 Conclusion
One might ask whether the relativism that results from Ehrenzweig’s work and the
ecclecticism it seems to justify is even less satisfying than simply admitting that
absolute justice is irrational. I share Ehrenzweig’s view that it is not.
“Our vital task is to reduce our ancestors’ conflict of justness by reconquest”
(Ehrenzweig 1971: 197, 198, § 169), he states. Investigating the determining factors
for individual conceptions of justice reveals psychological processes that have thus
far been run in disguise. Thanks to psychoanalytic jurisprudence, we no longer have
an excuse to end the inquiry when it bumps up against irrationality. Just as analytical
legal theory can help us find appropriate conclusions to how law works, a discipline
dedicated to the irrational can explain why we have expectations that a just legal
order could and does exist. This appreciation for the psychological origins of our
conceptions of justice helps us not only to understand but also to acquiesce in the
relativity of a given social norm. Hence, Ehrenzweig’s perspective is supportive of
Kelsen’s concluding argument: A social order has to be as open as possible to allow
the development of multiple individual conceptions of justice.
Psychoanalytical jurisprudence assists us when we wish to discover whether a
time-resistant and society-neutral, and thus absolute concept of justice is possible.
This task does not seem impossible, but it certainly requires a significant amount of
further research (Ehrenzweig 1971: 200, § 169). Altering Hans Kelsen’s answer to
the question of what justice is, one might dare say, “We don’t know—but we will
find out.”
References
Bezemek, Christoph. 2016. Pure formalism? Kelsenian interpretive theory beyond textualism and
originalism. In Hans Kelsen in America: The anxieties of non-influence. Ch. 13, ed. D.A. Jeremy
Telman. Springer (forthcoming).
Bienenfeld, Rudolf. 1965. Prolegomena to a psychoanalysis of law and justice: Preface. 53
California Law Review 53: 957; Part II: Analysis. California Law Review 53:1254.
Cirillo, Renato. 1979. The economics of Vilfredo Pareto. London: Routledge
Cavers, David F. 1983. A correspondence with Brainerd Currie, 1957–1958. Mercer Law Review
34: 471.
Currie, Brainerd. 1963. Selected essays on the conflict of laws. Durham: Duke University Press.
Ehrenzweig, Albert. 1962. Treatise on the conflict of laws. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Ehrenzweig, Albert. 1965. Psychoanalytical jurisprudence: A common language for Babylon.
Columbia Law Review 65: 1331.
Ehrenzweig, Albert. 1971. Psychoanalytic jurisprudence. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Ehrenzweig, Albert. 1972. Psychoanalytische Rechtswissenschaft. Berlin: Springer.
Feichtinger, Johannes. 2001. Wissenschaft zwischen den Kulturen—Österreichische
Hochschullehrer in der Emigration 1933–1945.
Friedmann, Wolfgang. 1972. Review Ehrenzweig, Psychoanalytic jurisprudence. California Law
Review 60: 1718.
Goldstein, Joseph. 1968. Psychoanalysis and jurisprudence. The Yale Law Journal 77: 1053.
Halbach Jr., Edward C. 1973. In memoriam Hans Kelsen. California Law Review 61: 957.
Hart, H.L.A. 1962–1963. Kelsen visited. UCLA Law Review 10:709.
Jestaedt, Matthias. 2008. Hans Kelsens Reine Rechtslehre—Eine Einführung. In Kelsen, Reine
Rechtslehre, Studienausgabe zur 1. Auflage 1934. I-LVII.
Kelsen, Hans. 1957. The idea of justice in the Holy Scriptures. In What is justice? ed. Hans Kelsen.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 2008. Reine Rechtslehre, Studienausgabe der 1. Auflage 1929.
Meiklejohn, David. 1958. Book review: Hans Kelsen, “What is Justice?”. The University of
Chicago Law Review 25: 543.
Northrop, F.S.C. 1958. Book review: Hans Kelsen, “What is Justice?”. Virginia Law Review 44:
815.
Pareto, Vilfredo. 2014. Manual of political economy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ross, Alf. 1957. Book review Hans Kelsen, “What is Justice?”. California Law Review 45: 564.
Siehr, Kurt. 1957. Ehrenzweigs lex fori-Theorie und ihre Bedeutung für das deutsche und
amerikani-sche Kollisionsrecht. Rabels Zeitschrift für ausländisches und internationales
Privatrecht 34: 585.
Zaremby, Justin. 2014. Legal Realism and American Law. New York: Bloomsbury.
Chapter 10
A Morally Enlightened Positivism? Kelsen
and Habermas on the Democratic Roots
of Validity in Municipal and International Law
David Ingram
Renowned are the many writings in which Habermas excoriates positivism in gen-
eral and legal positivism in particular. So the following tribute to a founding figure
in modern legal positivism requires some parsing.
Hans Kelsen is best known for his legal theory. But he is equally important as a political
philosopher and intellectual of the social sciences. During the Weimar period he was one of
the few prominent academics who were engaged in the defense of liberal democracy. In a
famous controversy with Carl Schmitt, Kelsen was an early advocate of the idea of a
Constitutional Court. Even in advance of the foundation of the United Nations, Kelsen
developed the design for a cosmopolitan model of compulsory jurisdiction…As much as I
admire the fervent spirit of the interventions of the democratic law professor and legal paci-
fist, so much also can I appreciate Kelsen’s philosophical motivation for developing a the-
ory of legal positivism. I agree with his arguments against classical natural right theories, in
particular against the Platonist idea of a normative order that is founded in nature rather
than invented by the will of human beings. (Habermas 2012a: 1)
Habermas’s tribute to Kelsen is noteworthy for being one of the very few places
where he discusses Kelsen’s positive contributions to legal philosophy at any length.
Indeed, most of his scattered references to Kelsen in writings leading up to and
including Faktizität und Geltung (Habermas 1992), were largely critical in tone,
underscoring the normative deficits of and inconsistencies in Kelsen’s legal positiv-
ism. That changed once Habermas shifted his attention to international law and
human rights. Here he enlists the support of Kelsen as an ally against a common
nemesis, Carl Schmitt, whose attacks on liberal democracy, constitutional courts,
D. Ingram (*)
Loyola University of Chicago, Chicago, IL 60660, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
international law, and human rights continue to draw support from both Left and
Right. In keeping with Habermas’s change of heart, we will here examine how
Habermas further develops Kelsen’s “scientific” analysis of democracy, interna-
tional governance, and human rights in advancing Christian Wolff’s vision of a
civitas maxima. Conversely, we will examine how Habermas’s embrace of Kelsenian
legal monism forces him to confront the political nature of constituting and apply-
ing international law in all of its humanitarian dimensions.
To situate our comparison of these thinkers it might be useful to recall Schmitt’s
argument against liberal democracy and human rights (Dyzenhaus 1997). Schmitt
argued that law is an empty vessel that derives its entire force from the sovereign
will of a person, group, nation, or other extra-legal source of power. This “might
makes right” argument seemed especially plausible to Schmitt in light of his
Hobbesian analysis of the impotence of the rule of law in modern liberal democra-
cies. In liberal democracy riven by unresolvable ideological conflicts between par-
ties who view the world through the bipolar lens of “friend and foe,” the indecisiveness
of legislative will inclines toward a permanent constitutional crisis. In such a state
of national emergency—which Schmitt imputed to the Weimar regime - only a chief
executive who has the supreme power to “decide the exception” can rise above the
law, suspend part or all of the constitution, and restore through martial decree the
political order and unity without which legal order itself is meaningless (Schmitt
1996: 46, 1985: 5–35). For Schmitt, this “commissarial dictatorship” is legitimated
by the presumption of a political will, personified in the nation state, the identity and
membership of which is defined solely by a majority that exists in its own right,
independent of, and therefore sovereign over, the law. Schmitt also argued, like
Hobbes and Hegel before him, that beyond the plurality of national wills there can
be no sovereign, for each nation possesses an identity and will that is also irreduc-
ibly unique. The impossibility of assimilating nations to a single humanity, possess-
ing its own universal will and sovereign power to decide, renders talk of international
law and human rights utterly meaningless, except as an ideological rationale cover-
ing up acts of aggression that are undertaken exclusively to advance national inter-
ests (Schmitt 1923/1988: 11–17, 1987: 73–89).
Kelsen and Habermas counter Schmitt’s realist assault on the rule of law with
realist arguments of their own. Departing from the same Hobbesian premises as
Schmitt, they acknowledge the weakness of moral motivations and the inadequacy
of abstract ideals in resolving modern conflicts between self-interested individuals
who subscribe to opposing conceptions of justice and human goodness. But like
Kant (Kant: 1996), they insist that the only solution to a state of war wherein per-
sons are disposed to seek unlimited power over others is the rule of law, fully insti-
tuted in liberal democracy at the level of state law and in a cosmopolitan human
rights regime at the level of international law.1
1
In Zum Ewigen Frieden (Kant 1900), Kant departed from Hobbes’s hypothetical state of nature,
which Hobbes famously characterized as “a war of all against all,” in arguing—along thoroughly
realist lines—that even a “race of devils” would find it in their mutual self-interest to establish a
lawful republic in which their individual rights would be protected. Continuing this realist argu-
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 177
Kelsen and Habermas argue that such “idealism” appears eminently more suit-
able to realizing the psychological aspirations underlying Hobbes’s political realism
than Schmitt’s political-theological postulation of a homogeneous, metaphysical
source of national sovereignty that exists above the law. While the Kantian project
promises a realistic framework for achieving peace and freedom, the Schmittian
project portends imperial warfare and totalitarian genocide in the service of ideol-
ogy. In the wake of so many horrors that have been committed in the name of
national security conducted under the banner of absolute sovereignty, it is no won-
der that Habermas looks to Kelsen’s monistic theory of law as the pre-eminent
exemplar of Kant’s project for the twenty-first century.
Kant’s argument in defense of an international legal order as a pre-requisite for
the secure enjoyment of any rights whatsoever (and therewith, as a pre-requisite for
morality as such) is often described as a variant of natural law reasoning from moral
premises. Habermas and Kelsen subscribe to this judgment as well, albeit in a quali-
fied way (Kelsen 1946: 445; Habermas 1996: 101).2 The status of Kantian legal
theory is important for both thinkers given their rejection of what Habermas, in the
passage cited above, refers to as the Platonism underlying natural law reasoning.
For them, law is a human technique (to use Kelsen’s terminology) that can be used
for many ends besides those conformable to morality, and even laws that originate
from just procedures or are supported by moral reasons need not, upon further
reflection, be morally justified. But given the important role that natural law reason-
ing has played in the human rights movement and in the social contractarian defense
of liberal democracy, denying the importance of moral justice as a basic require-
ment for legal validity and legal duty seems antagonistic to their support for a global
civitas maxima based on democracy and human rights. Leaving aside their own
ment further, Kant observed that republican governments protect the freedom of their citizens by
enabling them to channel their acquisitive urges through mutually beneficial economic competi-
tion. The appetite for commerce, in turn, inclines republican nations to seek peaceful relations
among themselves. By promoting general freedom and happiness, liberal democracy cultivates the
peaceful moeurs douces observed by Montesquieu. As Kelsen remarks, “the democratic type [of
foreign policy] has a definite inclination towards pacificism, the autocratic, towards one of impe-
rialism” (Kelsen 1933/1973: 106). Indeed, according to Michael Doyle, since 1800 no liberal
democracies have warred against one another, although powerful democracies have engaged in
imperialist ventures against weaker governments with less secure liberal democratic credentials.
Kant culminates his realist vision by defending a cosmopolitan legal order as the ultimate guaran-
tor of peace and basic rights. However, against Hobbes’s narrow realism, Kant (Kelsen and
Habermas concurring) insists that the social contractarian idea underpinning his theory of law
cannot be adduced from the empirical psychology of strategically calculating egoists but
requires an a prior normative foundation (Doyle 1997: 277–284).
2
In defense of Kant’s legal positivist credentials, Ingeborg Maus (2009: 53) notes that Kant’s use
of “moralisch” in the opening passages of the Metaphysik der Sitten designates all “Gesetze der
Freiheit” in opposition to deterministic laws of nature. Kant subdivides morality into ethics (natu-
ral morality) and law. Contrary to a natural law theorist such as Locke, Kant insists that the moral
right to possession (first occupancy) is superseded by the legal right to acquire and own property:
“Original acquisition can only be provisional—Conclusive acquisition takes place only in the civil
condition” (Kant 1996: 52). According to Maus, Kant’s concept of “morality” occupies a neutral
status between law and ethics not unlike Habermas’s own discourse principle (D).
178 D. Ingram
3
John Finnis criticizes Kelsen’s view that natural law theorists “from church fathers down to Kant”
derive the entire validity and content of positive law from morality and therefore enter into a con-
tradiction when they derive the authority to make law from natural law (Kelsen 1946: 412–413,
416). Finnis rightly notes that this description does not apply to Aquinas’s natural law theory,
which allows law makers discretion to make laws for all sorts of useful ends, so long as they stay
within the broad framework of morally just procedure (Finnis 2011: 26–29). This view is conso-
nant with Habermas’s proceduralist (and otherwise positivist) account of legal validity, which I
argue is not (pace Habermas) fundamentally different from Kelsen’s own.
4
See n.3. Indeed, in Between Facts and Norms, Habermas expressly rejects an argument he devel-
oped in Law and Morality (1988) that, in natural law fashion, assimilates the discourse principle
(D), which according to Habermas founds the democratic legitimacy of law, to the Kantian moral
principle of universalizability (U) (Habermas 1996: 108–109).
5
H.L.A. Hart (1959) criticized the German Courts’ post-war deployment of the principle of
humanitarianism involving cases where Nazi informants were convicted for following statutes that
were (in the opinion of one court) “contrary to the sound conscience and sense of justice of all
decent human beings.”
6
Natural law reasoning allegedly runs afoul of scientific reason in deriving an “ought” from an “is”
while its “derivation” of law from unchanging morality ostensibly limits or violates positive law’s
essential instrumental flexibility and alterability (Kelsen 1934/67: 64–69, 219; Habermas 1996:
106). As Kelsen notes, without the law/morality distinction civil disobedience makes no sense
(Kelsen 1934/67: 69).
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 179
features [of which]…rather than the more or less arbitrary choice of the lawmaker,”
qualifies the result’s having a “presumption of validity, or the reasonable expecta-
tion of intersubjective recognition” based on “rational acceptability” (Habermas
2012a: 2). Connected to this observation is Habermas’s additional concern that “[i]
n Kelsen’s analysis the moral content of individual rights expressly lost its referent,
namely the free will (or ‘power to rule’) of a person, who from the moral point of
view, deserves to be protected in her private autonomy” (Habermas 1996: 86).
Kelsen is here alleged to believe that a dictator’s command is as binding as a law
authorized by a fair democratic procedure. This allegation, I submit, is true only if we
focus, as Habermas does, on Kelsen’s theory of law in its pure form, abstracted from
his legal sociology. Kelsen orients his pure theory of law around a normative under-
standing of legality that reflects the austere assumptions of a jurist who is tasked with
distinguishing laws from other types of norms. In explaining the special way law
obligates, a jurist must assume that law comprises a hierarchical system of valid
authorizations anchored by a constitution. This static aspect of law concerns law
“only in its completed form and in a state of rest” as a system of norms. It concerns
the essence of law as a normative system distinct from other normative social systems
in its attachment of “a criminal or civil sanction” to norm violations (Kelsen 1946:
39, 122). The validity of the first constitution, not having been authorized by a prior
law, must be presupposed as having been authorized by a basic norm (Grundnorm).
In the normative syllogism leading to the foundation of the validity of a legal order,
the major premise is the ought-sentence which states the basic norm: “One ought to
behave according to the actually established and effective constitution”; the minor
premise is the is-sentence which states the facts: “The constitution is actually estab-
lished and effective”; and the conclusion is the ought-sentence: “One ought to behave
according to the legal order, that is, the legal order is valid”(Kelsen 1934/1967: 212).
As formulated above, the basic norm appears to endow any constitution—how-
ever despotic—with binding force so long as it meets a threshold of effective recog-
nition. But, as we shall see, meeting this latter threshold in modern societies may
require that a constitution be democratic rather than despotic.
This becomes apparent when we turn to Habermas’s legal theory. In contrast to
Kelsen’s juridical standpoint, Habermas, orients his thinking around the more robust
moral expectations of legal subjects inhabiting a modern society who are tasked
with finding good reasons why they should voluntarily submit to the law. From this
normative perspective, the procedure by which the constitution is generated must
satisfy minimal democratic requirements.
Here we encounter an additional layer of validating reasons that pertain exclu-
sively to the dynamic creation of law. According to Kelsen, the dynamic aspect of
law “furnishes an answer only to the question whether and why a certain norm
belongs to a system of valid legal norms, forms part of a certain legal order” (Kelsen
1946: 122) Key to understanding the dynamic aspect of law “in its movement” is the
fact that law “regulates its own creation” through legally authorized acts of legisla-
tion and adjudication (Kelsen 1957: 245).
Despite their different points of departure—the universal essence of law as a
valid form of coercion versus the capacity of a democratic form of legislation to
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 181
scientific theory of pure legal doctrine, but as a practically oriented theory that
anticipates the global revolution of the [twentieth century]” (Brunkhorst 2009: 232).
It may well be that this understanding of the relationship between morality, law,
and democracy, which incidentally very few critics have sufficiently appreciated in
Kelsen’s writings,7 reaches beyond the purely descriptive status that Kelsen himself
accords his scientific legal philosophy.8 However, if we take seriously his functional
definition of law as a tool for securing peaceful cooperation as well as his theory of
7
Many critics of Kelsen repeat Habermas’s (in my opinion, mistaken) criticism that “Kelsen’s type
of legal formalism is not sufficiently dynamic to ensure that the imperatives of administrative
power remain accountable to the democratic will” (McCormick 1997: 737). Others (Kalyvas 2006:
584–586) argue that Kelsen traces the legitimacy of the constitution to “the contingent act of a first
legislator,” despite the fact he and Habermas both conceive modern constitutional law as a reflex-
ive learning process that draws its full legitimacy from in-built normative expectations. Also see
Gümplová (2011: 17).
8
Lars Vinx, for example, asserts that “Kelsen’s position, is in some important respects, not positiv-
ist because it affirms, rather than denies, a necessary connection between legality and legitimacy”
(Vinx 2007: 214–215). In arguing that Kelsen “tries to…read autocratic legal systems as anticipa-
tions of a legal order that more fully realizes the ideal of the rule of law” (Vinx 2007: 212)—what
Vinx elsewhere refers to as a “utopia of legality” (Vinx 2007: 73–74)—Vinx in fact comes close to
interpreting Kelsen as a natural law theorist. In Vinx’s opinion, to presuppose a basic norm “is to
postulate that exercises of coercive force that take place under the authorization of that basic norm
are, in some sense and to some extent, morally justified” so that “without this assumption,
Kelsenian normative legal science would be pointless” (Vinx 2007: 56). As Neil Duxbury (2007)
notes, the main textual evidence Vinx offers to support this revisionist interpretation of Kelsen’s
theory (which he concedes flies in the face of Kelsen’s own self-understanding as a legal scientist)
is a passage from Kelsen’s early Rechtsstaat und Staatsrecht, where Kelsen writes, “Die
Rechtsstaatsidee aber ist noch nicht überwunden, ihre allseitige rechtslogische Entwicklung bleibt
aufgabe der Zukunft” (The “idea of the rule-of-law state…is not yet vanquished (überwunden); its
comprehensive legal-logical development remains the task of the future”) (Kelsen 1913/2010:
155). Duxbury correctly notes that whatever this statement might have meant prior to Kelsen’s
mature development of the pure theory of law in 1920, the meaning Vinx attributes to it stands in
stark contrast, not only to Kelsen’s vision of legal science as purely descriptive and value free but
also Kelsen’s belief that majoritarian governments may be lawfully replaced by autocratic govern-
ments—objections to his interpretation that Vinx himself notes (Vinx 2007: 56, 131, 217). In fact,
Vinx’s interpretation of Kelsen would better apply to Habermas’s reconstructive approach to law,
which sees a kind of normative (even moral) teleology at work in legal evolution (see below), one
that enables him to establish a conceptual co-originality between rights and democracy, while at
the same time acknowledging that this necessary link remains implicit and undeveloped (or antici-
pated) in the pre-liberal, pre-democratic Rechtsstaat. I suggest that a better way to defend Kelsen’s
support for a “utopia of legality” is by appealing to Kelsen’s sociology of law and especially his
Weberian account of social evolution (modernization). According to this reading, liberal democ-
racy is the legal form that best accords with the peace-seeking motivations and moral expectations
of modern, rationalized (scientifically enlightened) societies. Of course, this argument—which
matches normatively imbued, legal ideal types (autocracy v. democracy) with social, ethico-polit-
ical Weltanschauungen—also relies on purely descriptive premises, which is to say that its
“defense” of liberal democracy is premised on the latter’s empirical (adaptive) efficiency in
response to integration problems peculiar to modern social complexity. I think a similar kind of
reading can be extended to Kelsen’s earlier “ethico-politico” preference for a civitas maxima
anchored in a world state; for here, too, evolutionary changes in international relations leading to
the universal aspiration for equality and independence among all nations flies in the face of the
older, Westphalian regime of unrestricted state sovereignty.
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 183
legal evolution, it becomes clear that the totality of his legal theory strongly inclines
toward a positive moral assessment of liberal democracy and cosmopolitan law as
twin pillars of a fully realized rule of law.
9
In Strukturwandel der Öffentlichkeit (Habermas 1962) Habermas accepted much of Schmitt’s
indictment of mass democracy as well as Schmitt’s concern about the tendency of liberal ideology
to “suppress” politicized conflict behind the veneer of a transcendent rational harmony of interests
or, conversely, behind the veneer of an atomization of private interests (Habermas 1962/89: 81,
205). In this respect he followed in the footsteps of earlier critical theorists. Despite Schmitt’s
disdain for Marxism, which espoused corporatist conceptions of representation that he thought
were corrosive of any unified state, some of his most famous students were Marxists who shared
his critique of the modern state. Franz Neumann and Walter Benjamin both came under Schmitt’s
spell. Otto Kirchheimer, who, along with these thinkers, would later associate himself with the
Frankfurt School, argued in his dissertation (written under Schmitt’s direction) that parliamentary
democracies instituted on a capitalist base inevitably lack legitimacy. In his opinion, the sphere of
private law allows capitalist enterprises to contest the sovereignty of the state in asserting their
own partial interests in the form of statutory protections. The solution to this problem, Kirchheimer
argued, was the abolition of an autonomous sphere of private law immune from democratic regula-
tion by the state. Thirty odd years later Kirchheimer’s Schmittian diagnosis of capitalist democ-
racy would resurface in Habermas’s Strukturwandel, which documented the decline of a liberal
public sphere grounded in rational, open debate in the face of propagandistic class democracy.
Habermas’s later masterpiece, Legitimation Crisis (1973), continued to frame this diagnosis in
terms of a vaguely Schmittian conception of legitimacy, understood as a process of democratic will
formation having legal results that reflect a unitary consensus on common interests, as distinct
from a strategic compromise that balances plural interests according to their relative degree of
political power. This notion of legitimacy —which Habermas has since considerably qualified—
was presented in a way that opposed the separation of powers, the private law/public law distinc-
tion, the grounding of legal policy in class compromise, and other liberal principles.
184 D. Ingram
sent as a criterion of validation: “just those action norms are valid to which all
possibly affected persons could agree as participants in rational discourse”
(Habermas 1996: 107). More precisely, Habermas adduces (D) from the require-
ments of a “post-conventional” ethos of individual accountability. This ethos
requires that persons coordinate their actions by offering to defend the reasonable-
ness and reliability of their commitments to each other beyond asserting a desire to
pursue personal ends. In so doing they claim (tacitly if not expressly) that the facts
and norms around which they orient their behavior reflect beliefs, the truth (or right-
ness) of which, can be justified to others.
Justification of such claims (Geltungsansprüche) here has both a vertical (hierar-
chical) and horizontal (symmetrical) structure. The substantive arguments persons
present to each other must be capable of being made at ascending levels of general-
ity and depth. Most importantly, within a post-conventional moral setting, persons
will typically suppose some higher normative principles (such as human rights) in
justifying the permissibility or necessity of their actions. A moral principle of uni-
versalizability (U) thus functions as a kind of foundational basic norm, which fol-
lows “abductively,” Habermas believes, from other assumptions regarding rational
discourse and communicative interaction (Habermas 2012a: 17).
Superficially, Habermas’s appeal to one of these assumptions, the principle of
discourse (D) noted above, looks suspiciously like the social contractarian principle
of self-authorized obligation:
With the loss of the religious promise of salvation…“validity” now signifies that moral
norms could win the agreement of all concerned [as being] in the equal interest of all. This
agreement expresses…the freedom of legislating subjects who understand themselves as
the authors of those norms to which they subject themselves as addressees (Habermas
2012a: 13).
Stated thus without further qualification, the argument contained in this passage
appears to succumb to Kelsen’s following objection:
The doctrine of the basic norm is not a doctrine of recognition as is sometimes erroneously
understood. According to the doctrine of recognition positive law is valid only if it is recog-
nized by the individuals subject to it, which means: if these individuals agree that one ought
to behave according to the norms of positive law. This recognition, it is said, actually takes
place, and if this cannot be proved, it is assumed, fictitiously, as tacit recognition. The the-
ory of recognition, consciously or unconsciously, presupposes the ideal of individual liberty
as self-determination, that is, the norm that the individual ought to do only what he wants
to do. This is the basic norm of this theory. The difference between it and the theory of the
basic norm of a positive legal order, as taught by the Pure Theory of Law, is evident (Kelsen
1934/1967: 218 n.83).
Kelsen here reiterates his familiar logical point that an “ought” cannot be derived
from an “is.” The fact that people all want something and therefore agree to it, as in
the fiction of the social contract, does not mean that they ought to want it. Will or
collective might cannot constitute right. For the social contractarian conception of
legal validity to get off the ground, logically speaking, some prior basic norm would
have to be presupposed, such as “the individual ought to do only what he wants
(agrees) to do.” This “basic norm,” however, is entirely incompatible with any sys-
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 185
In light of modern value pluralism, the only neutral (universally shared) norma-
tive principle people can rely on for settling disputes and reaching agreement must
be “some intrinsic feature of the practice of deliberation” itself—Habermas’s prin-
ciple (D). But an agreement reached according to this principle “cannot be under-
stood as a contract (Vereinbarung) which is rationally motivated from the egocentric
perspective of each individual” (Habermas 2012a: 17). For (D) refers to a concep-
tion of procedural justice that captures not only the equality and autonomy of speak-
ers but also their empathetic solidarity (or friendship) toward each other (Habermas
2012a: 8, 9, 12); viz., their willingness to alter their interests and perspectives to
reasonably accommodate the interests and perspectives of consociates.
More precisely, (D) requires:
(a) that nobody who could make a relevant contribution may be excluded, (b) that all par-
ticipants are afforded an equal opportunity to make contributions, (c) that the participants
must mean what they say, and only truthful utterances are admissible, and (d) that commu-
nication must be freed from external and internal compulsion so that “yes”/“no” stances the
participants adopt on criticizable validity claims are motivated solely by the rational force
of better reasons (Habermas 2012a: 19).
be compensated by coercive law” (Habermas 2012a: 13). Indeed, (D) itself is neutral
between the kinds of norms—moral, ethical, and legal—to which it might apply.
When applied to moral discourses, it assumes the role of a principle of argumenta-
tion (U) that requires a strong cognitive orientation toward reaching universal con-
sensus. When applied to ethical discourses, (D) loses this strong cognitive orientation
in recognition of the fact that values and other desired ends are intersubjectively
valid only for a specific group or community. As we shall see, contrary to Habermas’s
depiction of him as a value skeptic, Kelsen himself generally interprets ethical life
as evincing just this kind of weak cognitivism (Habermas 2012a: 4–7).
When applied to law rather than to moral or ethical deliberation, (D) loses its
status as a principle of argumentation. Linked to the modern legal form of “subjec-
tive” (or permissive) rights, it becomes a principle of democratic legitimation (PD)
which asserts: “Only those [freedom-granting] statutes may claim legitimacy that
can meet with the assent of all citizens in a discourse process of legislation that in
turn has been legally constituted” (Habermas 1996: 110). (PD) thus presupposes a
system of basic rights: a legal code specifying, in addition to subjective rights (free-
dom from non-interference), rights to membership and legal due process. Giving
determinate meaning and prescriptive force to this abstract legal code requires leg-
islation, and (pursuant to PD) democratic participatory rights. Finally, securing the
“fair value” of these rights requires social rights to education, health, and welfare
(Habermas 1996: 123).
Constitutions entrench these rights as well as the legislative, judicial, and execu-
tive institutions that apply them according to institution-specific democratic proce-
dures. Following Habermas, we detect a kind of Kelsenian monism in the way that
the constitution authorizes all law (even customary or common law), as well as in
the way that “communicative power” authorizes state power generally. On one hand,
validation descends from (D) through (PD), the system of basic rights, the constitu-
tion, and the various levels of law creation and application. On the other hand, a
uni-directional constitutional flow of political power is set in motion from the
“periphery,” located in the informally organized public sphere, and directed toward
the formally organized legal system, or “center.” Thus, public opinion remains the
supreme authority for setting the legislative agenda (Habermas 1996: 150, 170,
182). Social concerns originating in the periphery are suitably reformulated as poli-
cies and modified on the basis of negotiated compromises by the center. However, to
comply with the stringent procedural justice embedded in (D), compromises that
balance competing interests should only be negotiated after good-faith attempts at
reaching consensus on generalizable interests have failed. Habermas accordingly
rejects the skeptical presumption that competing interests cannot be transformed
into harmonious or shared interests. This presumption would permit the imposition
of “pseudo-compromises” that enable the majority to impose its will unilaterally
without considering the minority’s interests (Habermas 1975: 112). By contrast, (D)
requires “an equal opportunity for pressure, that is, an equal opportunity to influence
one another during the actual bargaining, so that all the affected interests can come
into play and have equal chances of prevailing”(Habermas 1996: 167).
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 187
Finally, Habermas warns that this impression of a Kelsenian Stufenbau (or hier-
archical authorization of subordinate acts) within a legitimate circulation of legal
power should not obscure the genuine circular (or reflexive) nature of the legal
system. Not only do official decision-makers unavoidably reformulate the concerns
and arguments drawn from public deliberation, but judges and administrators refor-
mulate and develop the laws that limit their individual actions. Far from being a
mechanical process of application that rigidly preserves legal contents without addi-
tion, such decision-making, Habermas insists, is unavoidably interpretative
(Habermas 1996: 182).
As I noted above (and as I shall argue below) Kelsen’s own understanding of the
reflexive creation of law as a process involving judges and administrators departs
from the image of a Stufenbau to the point of rendering otiose any practical pre-
sumption of a Grundnorm. That said, Habermas’s philosophical reconstruction of
the conceptual linkage of law, democracy, and justice finds no parallel in Kelsen’s
writings. But a parallel does exist when we turn to the functional linkages between
democracy and modernity elaborated in their respective sociological treatments of
law. Drawing from Weber’s account of modern law, Habermas and Kelsen regard
liberal democracy as a logical correlate to cultural “rationalization.” For Kelsen and
Habermas, bureaucratic administration and parliamentary systems of political rep-
resentation—no less than the constitution of the individual as a legal holder of
rights—emerge as adaptive responses to cultural changes that accompany revolu-
tionary socio-economic transformations. Citing Weber against Marxists and
Schmittian romantics, Kelsen warns that “the abolition of a professional bureau-
cracy (Berufsbeamtentums), no less than the rejection of parliamentarianism, is sim-
ply a negation (Aufhebung) of the division of labor and therewith of that progressive
development, that cultural differentiation within political life” (Kelsen 1920b: 24).
No doubt Marxists and their reactionary counterparts are right to worry that the
stratification and ideological fragmentation of capitalist societies premised on the
rational notion of a modern legal subject threatens to undermine the legitimacy of
the legal order. But Kelsen maintains that social and political integration based on
shared moral principles can be advanced by means of democratic institutions that
protect minorities and vulnerable economic classes while encouraging discursive
will-formation through compromise. In a remarkable passage that could have been
penned by Habermas, Kelsen writes:
Here precisely resides a decisive advantage of democracy and its majoritarian principle,
that it nonetheless secures by means of the simplest organization a certain political integra-
tion of a society legally regulated by a state (Staatsgesellschaft)…That the “will of the
state” created juristically is supposedly the “will of the people” is thus itself a fiction—
albeit a fiction closest to reality—so long as the procedure for creating the will is demo-
cratically organized (Kelsen 1920b: 28 (emphasis added)).
It should be added that, although Habermas and Kelsen reject proletarian democ-
racy as a regression to premodern Gemeinschaft, they regard social welfare as an
188 D. Ingram
10
After criticizing the Marxist idea of a radical workers democracy, Kelsen makes the following
comment: “Doubtless the ideal of the greatest economic equality is a democratic ideal. And there-
fore social democracy is a perfect (vollkommene) democracy” (Kelsen 1920b: 35).
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 189
of respect for its intrinsic goodness would require grounding the authority of law in
the sacral realm of absolute ends. Contrary to Kelsen’s evolutionary account of law
out of tribal custom, Habermas insists that tribal societies that resolve internal con-
flicts through magical oracles, trials of endurance, ritual combat, self-defense, ven-
detta retribution, or non-binding peaceful arbitration, have yet to evolve any
distinctly normative conception of law, because they have not infused their pre-
conventional morality with an understanding of divine ends that transcend immedi-
ate interests. In order to become a medium of normatively sanctioned coercion, law
needed to be infused with an evolutionarily more advanced morality that judges
actions by their intentions and not solely by their consequences and that places cos-
mic justice and the highest good above the immediate satisfaction of interests
(Habermas 1988: 264–267). Compelled by an internal logic of rationalization, such
conventional moral-legal systems, eventually evolved (Habermas speculates) into
post-conventional, natural law-founded, legal orders.
From this perspective, Habermas claims, positivists like Kelsen fail to appreciate
the extent to which morality is not simply exported into law by positive fiat but
constitutes law’s very normativity. In modern conceptions of the rule of law, this
normativity encompasses a basic respect for the dignity of the individual legal sub-
ject as an autonomous agent (Habermas 1988: 274). Conceptions of legal due pro-
cess in Anglo-American law emerging as early as the seventeenth century already
embody an argumentative procedure that evinces this respect. Civil and political
rights likewise constitute the procedure of democratic legislation from within (viz.,
conceptually) and not merely as adventitious moral contents that just happen to be
legally posited by a first legislator (Habermas 1988: 268–279) Despite this internal
connection between law and morality, which liberal natural law theory conceptual-
izes in its foundational understanding of human rights, basic rights (including
“intrinsically valuable” liberal rights to life, property, freedom of movement, etc.)
are not external limits upon democratic procedure, as liberal natural law theory
would have it; they are rather its enabling conditions (Habermas 2001a: 770–771,
776–780). Every subsequent legal act “reflexively” expands the inclusiveness,
equality and freedom vouchsafed by this foundational right, so that we may speak
of the constitution as a learning project, the binding force (justice) of which actually
increases over time (Habermas 2001a: 774–776).
Although we might concede Habermas’s point that Kelsen under-appreciates the
conceptual link between post-conventional morality and constitutional law,11 it
would be wrong to conclude that Kelsen overlooks the functional conjunction of
11
Kelsen’s legal theory, Habermas claims, converges with the legal systems theory developed by
Niklas Luhman and his epigones (Habermas 1988: 263, 1996: 86), thereby offering no resistance
to the “colonization of the lifeworld” (Habermas 1975: 40–50, 71–92, 1987: 356–373).
Notwithstanding this objection, Habermas concedes that“autochthonously functioning” subsys-
tems depend on democratic input for their optimal coordination and functioning (Habermas 1996:
350–352). What Habermas adds to Kelsen’s functionalist defense of democracy is his grounding
of modernization in a distinctly normative theory of communicative action (Habermas 1987: 142–
43, 341–342, 359–360).
190 D. Ingram
these terms within modern democracy. Kelsen observes that legal institutions
become democratic in response to modern social complexity; furthermore, he
agrees with Habermas that basic rights and minority protections are intrinsic quali-
ties of modern democracy. Finally, like Habermas, he notes that modern democra-
cies are dynamic learning processes that reflexively realize their emancipatory
potential:
If we define democracy as a political method by which the social order is created and applied
by those subject to the order, so that political freedom, in the sense of self-determination, is
secured, then democracy necessarily, always and everywhere, serves this ideal of political
freedom. And if we include in our definition the idea that the social order, created in the way
just indicated, in order to be democratic, must guarantee certain intellectual freedoms, such
as freedom of conscience, freedom of press, etc., then democracy necessarily, always and
everywhere, serves the ideal of intellectual freedom (Kelsen 1955: 4).
The above citation strongly suggests that Kelsen and Habermas share remarkably
similar views about how democratic procedural justice advances a rational learning
process in which mutual (self-) criticism leads to moderation and accommodation
of differences. Thanks to the mutual enlightenment of one’s own and others’ inter-
ests vouchsafed by deliberative democracy, citizens have a right to expect that the
law will respect, if not advance, each of their interests equally.
12
Habermas and Kelsen assess the cognitive advantages of deliberative democracy somewhat dif-
ferently. For Habermas, democracy generates an ideal expectation that laws and official decisions
are (or could be) singularly just and correct. For Kelsen, by contrast, “[o]nly if it is not possible to
decide in an absolute way what is right and what is wrong is it advisable to discuss the issue and,
after discussion, to submit it to a compromise” (Kelsen 1955: 39). I discuss the implication of this
disagreement in Part 8.4.
192 D. Ingram
13
Kelsen’s monism, in both its domestic and international applications, has come under attack by
pluralists such as F. Rigaux, H.L.A. Hart, and Joseph Raz (Rigaux 1998; Hart 1983: 309–342; Raz
1979: 122–145). Raz, for instance, raises two main counter-examples to the thesis: the presence of
distinct customary and statutory sources (basic norms) of law within the same legal system and, in
the case of former colonies being granted independence, the authorization of a new state constitu-
tional order (basic norm) by another state constitutional order, in which both orders (basic norms)
are considered distinct yet equally authoritative. As Vinx notes, for Kelsen, the first counter-exam-
ple is not compelling because any legal system will designate a higher (constitutional) authority as
a common source specifying how conflicts between customary and statutory law are to be resolved
(usually in favor of the latter) (Vinx 2007: 184). The second counter-example fails because it can
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 193
be interpreted in two ways that comport with Kelsenian monism: if a former colony sees itself as
breaking with the mother country in a revolutionary manner, it will not regard its constitution as
standing in a relationship of continuity with the constitution of the mother country, in which case
its constitution will be seen as grounding an entirely separate order. If it does not see itself as
breaking with the mother country (as perhaps exists in the case of British Commonwealth coun-
tries today), then by definition it recognizes its order as in some sense co-extensive with the basic
norm of the mother country (some British Commonwealth countries may recognize the British
monarch as the titular if symbolic authority behind their law).
14
The trajectory from Schmittian subjectivism to Kelsenian objectivism laid out here defines the
career of the founder of the realist school of international relations, Hans Morgenthau (Morgenthau
1948; Jütersonke 2010; Koskenneimi 2002; Engel 1964).
194 D. Ingram
regionally extensive states, such as the United States, China, and Russia, as well as
regional governing bodies, such as the EU) and non-governmental entities. Non-
governmental bodies would include entities that address specifically political issues,
such as non-governmental organizations (NGOs) and global economic multilaterals
(the World Trade Organization, the World Bank, the International Monetary Fund,
etc.) as well as entities that address technical coordination problems concerning
international health, energy, telecommunications, and so on (Habermas 2008b:
446). Owing to the dearth of democratic institutions of legislation at this level, states
with elected representative bodies would retain a vital legitimating role at the bot-
tom rung of global governance.
From a Kelsenian perspective, this model leaves several questions unanswered.
As Rainer Schmalz-Bruns and others (Scheuerman 1994) have observed, delegating
responsibility for negotiating treaties on trade, greenhouse emissions, and other
matters of global domestic policy to persons representing the interests of states and
their corporate clients creates a legitimation gap (Schmalz-Bruns 2007: 269–293;
Scheuerman 2008: 133–151). Even if these negotiators indirectly represent the
interests of their own fellow citizens, whose livelihood depends on the governments
and businesses that provide them with services and jobs, they do not represent the
interests of foreigners, much less the interests of humanity—especially the poorest
two-thirds of the world’s population who have a greater stake in reducing poverty
and greenhouse emissions. Although the distribution of benefits and burdens regard-
ing global development and environmental security raises sensitive political ques-
tions that must be negotiated, the reigning imbalances in power between rich and
poor nations, and between powerful and weak clienteles, hardly inspire confidence
that the terms agreed upon will fairly advance the interests of humanity, let alone the
most vulnerable portion of it.
The legitimation gap becomes even wider if, following the Universal Declaration
of Human Rights and other United Nations’ proposals, we include rights to subsis-
tence, environmental security, and development among the basic human rights, the
severe and widespread lack of enjoyment of which amounts to a human rights viola-
tion. If Habermas was once unclear about whether these rights deserved protection
at the highest supranational level, his recent pronouncements on the matter suggest
that he no longer is. Having linked the concept of human rights with the concept of
a dignified human life in which human development and environmental security are
guaranteed, he can no longer convincingly argue that supranational human rights
protection and transnational global domestic policy are neatly separable.
Habermas must now endorse something closer to Kelsen’s world state once mat-
ters of global domestic policy are acknowledged as impacting the basic rights of a
world citizenry. That means that political negotiations over global domestic policy
must be democratically institutionalized and regulated at the supranational level as
well. For,
only in a world state would the global political order be founded upon the will of its citi-
zens. Only within such a framework could the democratic opinion- and will-formation of
the citizens be organized both in a monistic way, as proceeding from the unity of world citi-
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 197
zenry, and effectively, and hence have binding force for the implementation of decisions and
laws (Habermas 2008b: 448).
However, in light of the fact that the international arena is currently organized
around states, the governments of which ought to advance the interests of their own
citizens, Habermas recommends a more realistic vision of global governance that
would allow for the equal representation of a world citizenry and a nationally identi-
fied citizenry. Any “thought experiment” regarding the possibility of constituting a
world state out of a “second state of nature” composed of legitimately recognized
nation states must serve three major ends. First, the contradiction between the nor-
mative orientations of cosmopolitan and national citizens “must be defused in a
monistic constitutional world order.” Second, this monistic construction should not
implement a world republic that would violate “the loyalty of citizens to their
respective nations.” Finally, “consideration of the distinctive national character of
states…must not, in turn, weaken the effectiveness and the binding implementation
of the supra- and transnational decisions (Habermas 2008b: 449).”
Habermas proposes the following institutional design for implementing these
ends:
A General Assembly, composed of representatives of cosmopolitan citizens, on the one
side, and delegates from the democratically elected parliaments of member states, on the
other (or alternatively, of one chamber for the representatives of the cosmopolitan citizens
and one for the representatives of states) would initially convene as a Constituent Assembly
and subsequently assume a permanent form—within the established framework of a func-
tionally specialized world organization—as a World Parliament, although its legislative
function would be confined to the interpretation and elaboration of the Charter (Habermas
2008b: 449).
cial and executive decisions would be indirect, passing through global public opin-
ion. Habermas suggests that the legitimation of executive decisions be enhanced
through the “veto rights of the General Assembly against resolutions of the
(reformed) Security Council (UNSC), on the one hand, and rights of appeal of par-
ties subject to Security Council sanctions before an International Criminal Court
equipped with corresponding authority, on the other” (Habermas 2008b: 451).
Indeed, as of 2009, thanks to the unprecedented judicial review and reversal of
Security Council sanctions, as well as pressure from lobbying groups in the wake of
Kadi I, Kadi II, and similar cases, reform of the UNSC had partly met Habermas’s
stipulation, albeit by non-judicial means, through the creation of an ombudsperson
to address individual challenges to the UNSC’s 1267 sanction’s regime.15
Finally, Habermas believes that the legitimation deficit plaguing transnational
negotiations could also be reduced by submitting them to supranational regulation.
Given the political nature of such negotiations, which unavoidably advance national
as well as cosmopolitan interests and cultural perspectives, legitimation will mainly
be indirect (contingent on the approval of global public opinion) rather than direct
(contingent on the approval of legislatures and judges).
Power politics would no longer have the last word within the normative framework of the
international community. The balancing of interests would take place in the transnational
negotiation system under the proviso of compliance with the parameters of justice subject
to continual adjustment in the General Assembly. From a normative point of view, the
power-driven process of compromise formation can also be understood as an application of
the principles of transnational justice negotiated at the supranational level. However,
“application” should not be understood in the judicial sense of an interpretation of law. For
the principles of justice are formulated at such a high level of abstraction that the scope for
discretion they leave open would have to be made good at the political level (Habermas
2008b: 452 (emphasis added)).
I will return to the italicized part of this passage at the conclusion of this essay
insofar as it suggests a qualification of and departure from the monist world order
Habermas and Kelsen ideally endorse. It suffices to note in summation that
Habermas proposes to strengthen the democratic legitimation deficit of the current
world order by increasing centralized regulation on behalf of the often-neglected
domestic interests of world citizens without sacrificing the domestic interests of
national constituencies. This combination of realism and cosmopolitan idealism
finds a precedent in Kelsen’s thinking as well. In his discussion of the U.N. Charter
and the U.N. Declaration of Human Rights (Kelsen 1950; 1951), Kelsen urges legal
recognition of individuals as cosmopolitan subjects of international law. Such rec-
ognition would require granting individuals rights to bring claims against other indi-
viduals and states before international courts. Yet neither the United Nations Charter
nor the Universal Declaration of Human Rights defines human rights as actionable
claim rights; for although Article 8 of the Declaration states that “[e]veryone has the
right to an effective remedy by the competent national tribunals for acts violating
15
UNSC Resolution 1904 (adopted 1 December 2009 and most recently extended by Resolution
2161 in 2014). For further discussion of the Kadi case and recent changes in oversight of the
UNSC sanctions regime, see Ingram (2014).
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 199
16
Habermas’s use of human dignity here—as an inventive source for human rights that grows out
of and unifies the “plethora of human experiences of what it means to get humiliated and be deeply
hurt” (Habermas 2010: 467–468)—finds earlier mention in Between Facts and Norms (Habermas
1996: 426) without, however, designating the evolving complementarity of rights (Ingram 2010:
171).
17
Although Habermas accepts a monistic understanding of the complementarity of moral elements
underlying the concept of human dignity and, therewith, of human rights (see n16), he rejects a
monistic understanding of human rights as having a common moral foundation in, for example, a
“right to justification” of the sort proposed by Rainer Forst (Forst 2012). Such a monism of moral-
ity and law, Habermas argues, neglects the essentially juridical form of human rights as specifying,
first and foremost, “subjective rights,” or permissions to act without need of justification that can
be enforced against government and non-government agents. Moral rights, by contrast, derive
directly from moral duties, so that, properly speaking, the moral right to justification follows from
a prior moral duty to justify one’s actions to others (Habermas 2012b: 296–298). By conceiving
human rights as permissions to act without interference, Habermas commits himself to interpreting
human rights violations as violations of reciprocal negative duties to desist from causing harm,
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 201
Taking legal monism this far would require rethinking the role of international
courts in a way that neither Habermas nor Kelsen envisages. Human rights courts
would no longer be conceived exclusively as criminal tribunals for prosecuting
crimes against humanity. They would also be conceived as fora where individuals
could sue governments, global economic multilaterals, and other entities for violat-
ing (or inadequately securing) their rights to subsistence, environmental security,
and human development. The European Court of Justice’s (ECJ) recent decision (18
July 2013) to uphold the European General Court’s earlier removal of Yassin
Abdullah Kadi from a UNSC-imposed sanctions list targeting suspected terrorists
(Kadi I and Kadi II), shows that the courts have asserted their prerogative to subject
UNSC decisions to substantive and procedural review.
The ECJ’s decision is ambiguous: Does it reflect a regional rebellion against an
international legal order or a move to bind an international executive body to inter-
national norms of legal due process and human rights? Interpreting the ECJ’s deci-
sion in this latter sense suggests a stronger analogy between global and domestic
models of governance and the peculiar problems of constitutional hierarchy that
attend all governmental regimes. In particular, the ever-present worry that vulnera-
ble persons of all categories—not just the poor but immigrants, aboriginal peoples,
ethnic minorities, women, children, and ostracized castes—will remain marginal-
ized in transnational negotiations and other forums where human rights are debated,
defined, and applied suggests that a system of higher courts for appealing decisions
and reviewing legislation may also be necessary. But, as in the domestic case, a
perennial question arises: if judicial review is problematic from the standpoint of
democratic legislation in general, is it not more so when conducted at the level of
supranational democratic governance?
Habermas and Kelsen defend judicial review not only in dealing with appeals and
inconsistent rulings but also in reviewing the constitutionality of legislative and
executive resolutions. Constitutional review, they argue, is not opposed to
specifically by interfering with the agency of others. Human rights to subsistence, by contrast,
have traditionally been understood as entailing reciprocal positive duties to aid others in need. This
distinction (typically exemplified in the difference between civil and social rights), however, is
hardly decisive; for Habermas, like many others, observes that fulfilling negative duties generally
requires that agents do more than refrain from interfering with others. Legal agents, especially,
must actively protect against rights violations as well as aid those whose rights have been violated.
Finally, besides showing how negative duties imply positive duties, Habermas argues that “viola-
tions” of human rights to subsistence, human development, and environmental integrity are viola-
tions of negative duties insofar as legal and economic institutions effectively harm the poor by
denying them free access to resources necessary for a minimally decent human life (Ingram 2010:
170–189).
202 D. Ingram
democracy when properly limited to guarding the institutions, rights, rules, and
discursive processes (formal and informal) that make up democratic procedure. But
because such review addresses matters of justice normally taken up by the legisla-
ture (eg, the impact of electoral map-drawing on minority representation) and
because annulment of a statute typically accompanies a reinterpretation of constitu-
tional language, constitutional review makes (legislates) as well as applies the law.
It is this impression—that electorally unaccountable courts are legislating from the
bench—that generates the legitimation problem.
Constitutional review abrogates the relatively strict separation of powers that
Habermas, in particular, feels must be respected in order to retain the democratic
legitimation of laws. The Austrian Constitution of 1920 that Kelsen helped design
mitigated the democratic deficit attendant on having Platonic philosopher kings leg-
islate from the bench in its provision for the election of constitutional judges by the
House and Senate. At the same time, it rendered more visible the political nature of
review. But executive appointment of judges with legislative approval is also politi-
cal, and reducing political pressures on the judiciary through life appointments or
term limits without opportunity for future political advancement does not eliminate
the impact of politics on judicial decision-making. For this reason, Kelsen and
Habermas contemplate review of pending legislation by a constitutional advisory
committee, initiated, perhaps, by a special prosecutor or a legislative minority.
Combined with delayed enforcement of judicial annulments, these provisions miti-
gate the intrusive nature of constitutional review (Kelsen 1942: 183–200; Ingram
2014).
Because Kelsen and Habermas defend the rights of individuals and states to
appeal to international courts based on an analogy with the state model of constitu-
tional law, it would seem that they should endorse constitutional courts at the supra-
national level for these same reasons. Is this realistic?
To answer this question it behooves us to revisit their response to Schmitt’s rejec-
tion of constitutional courts. Schmitt’s rejection of constitutional courts hinges on
the theoretical assumption that abstract review violates the logic of judicial applica-
tion, according to which courts apply a general norm to a particular “fact situation.”
Schmitt argued that constitutional review “makes comparisons among general
norms, but does not subsume one norm under another or apply one to another”
(Schmitt 1931: 42). In Schmitt’s reading, judicial review appears to be either an
imaginary exercise of philosophical interpretation without application to the factual
world (and hence irrelevant to resolving real political disputes) or a disguised act of
political legislation. Schmitt accordingly recommended that the supreme executive
(eg, the President, exercising dictatorial powers under Article 48 of the Weimar
Constitution), and not the judiciary, be entrusted with “guarding” the constitution
against the threat of parliamentary politicization and anarchy by dissolving parlia-
ment or suspending the constitution.
Kelsen rejects the idea that the supreme executive is better positioned to guard
the constitution than the judiciary. To quote Kelsen on this score: “Since precisely
in the most important cases of constitutional violation the parliament and the execu-
tive branch (Regierung) are the disputing parties, to decide the dispute it makes
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 203
sense to call upon a third authority that stands apart from this conflict and is not
itself involved in any way in the exercise of power” (Kelsen 1931: 609). Habermas,
of course, agrees with Kelsen, but defending the supremacy of the judiciary because
it is less political than the supreme executive and the legislature depends, once
again, on the dubious assumption that judicial review, like any ordinary act of adju-
dication, involves applying the law and not creating it. Habermas’s occasional ten-
dency to construe adjudication as a technical form of applying rather than creating
law not only runs afoul of common law jurisprudence (judge-made law) but it
occludes the way in which constitutional courts unavoidably develop the law by
providing novel justifications and interpretations not expressly contemplated in leg-
islative debates and subcommittee hearings (Zurn 2007: 243–252).
In his response to Schmitt, Kelsen likewise falls back on the idea that judicial
review, no less than ordinary adjudication, is a species of law application, albeit
with a difference: “the fact situation that is to be subsumed under the constitutional
norm in decisions about the constitutionality of a legal statute is not the norm…but
the production of the norm” (Kelsen 1931: 590). Following Habermas’s paraphrase,
Kelsen here argues that it is not the political content of the statute that is in question
in abstract review, but the factual act by which it was made. The legislative act under
review must not only be undertaken by a body that has been specifically authorized
as competent to act in this way by the constitution (the legislature), but the act must
respect constitutional rights, which as Habermas argues, are constitutive of the very
procedure of democratic lawmaking. Habermas and Kelsen thus reject Schmitt’s
contention that judges on constitutional courts legislate from the bench. Their func-
tion is to guard a legal procedure that ensures respect for the rights of minorities,
mainly by nullifying statutes that threaten to undermine them.
That said, there is no disputing that constitutional courts do not stop at nullifying
statutes but undertake acts of interpretation that extend and deepen the meaning of the
constitution (Habermas 1996: 243). It might therefore be asked why this creative
dimension of interpretation is not itself a political act of legislation. Habermas
responds to this concern (following Ronald Dworkin’s (1986) narrative conception of
law) by insisting that the discretion exercised by constitutional judges in interpreting
the constitution is constrained by other, largely non-political normative principles that
inform a tradition of legal reasoning. To quote Habermas at length on this subject:
When Dworkin speaks of arguments of principle justifying judicial decisions externally, in
most cases he has legal principles in mind in any case, that is standards that result from the
application of the discourse principle to the legal code. The system of rights and constitu-
tional principles are certainly indebted to practical reason, but they are due in the first
instance to the special shape this reason assumes in the principle of democracy (Habermas
1996: 206).…This explains why landmark decisions and important precedents usually
admit reasons of extralegal origin, hence pragmatic, ethical, and moral reasons, into legal
discourse (Habermas 1996: 207).…Rules and principles both serve as arguments in the
justification of decisions, though each has a different status in the logic of argumentation.
Rules always contain an“if” clause, specifying the typical situational features that consti-
tute the features of application, whereas principles either appear with an unspecified valid-
ity claim or are restricted in their applicability only by general conditions that require
interpretation (Habermas 1996: 208).…From Dworkin’s perspective, positivists are forced
to reach decisionistic conclusions only because they start with a one-dimensional concep-
204 D. Ingram
18
For Habermas’s confrontation with legal realism and critical legal scholarship (CLS), see Ingram
(2002).
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 205
As we have seen, this reflexivity (circularity) in the way law is validated, inter-
preted, and created belies the hierarchical image of a self-contained legal system
grounded in a basic norm. The infusion of indeterminacy in the meaning of law gener-
ated by its reflexive application is nonetheless subject to several qualifications. First,
although Kelsen accepts the realist critique of formalist (or deterministic) conceptions
of legal certainty, he rejects the view that the law is unknown until the judge decides
its application to a particular case (Kelsen 1946: 150). Even in hard cases a judge’s
discretion is limited by the law. Second, one can affirm that there are no gaps in the
law and yet allow that judges sometimes legislate. Such “retroactive laws” (prece-
dents) are the natural products of constitutional review (Kelsen 1946: 145, 150).
Whatever else one might say about Kelsen’s jurisprudential philosophy, it is
clear (pace Habermas) that it does not privilege legal certainty over rightness. At
most, it can be charged with allowing for more than one right decision. This conces-
sion, of course, runs afoul of Habermas’s Dworkinian view of law as a coherent
system of general moral principles and concrete rules that ideally determines pre-
cisely one right decision for any given case.
Whether Habermas’s or Kelsen’s model of jurisprudence is to be preferred as a
more realistic model for domestic (let alone international) law is a question to which
I shall return shortly. It suffices to note for our present purposes, that Habermas
himself harbors a few Kelsenian doubts about Dworkin’s model of jurisprudence.
To begin with, it is impossible to conceive a system of law that retains its ideal unity,
identity, and determinate meaning throughout historical acts of reconstructive
interpretation.
In criticism of Dworkin’s version of the coherence theory, it has been objected that a ratio-
nal reconstruction of past decisions requires their revision from case to case, which would
amount to a retroactive interpretation of existing law.…[T]he element of surprise in each
new case now seems to draw theory itself into the vortex of history. The problem is obvious:
the political legislator must adaptively react to historical processes, even though the law
exists to erect walls of stable expectations against the pressure of historical variation
(Habermas 1996: 219).
certain amount of ‘existing reason’ in the universe of existing law meets it halfway.
According to this presupposition, then, reason must already be at work—in however
fragmentary a manner—in the political legislation of constitutional democracies”
(Habermas 1996: 232). In other words, the degree to which law possesses integrity
at any given moment is a function of the shared reasons that legislators bring to bear
in defending it. But legislators as well as judges are divided on the substantive back-
ground theories of justice—Habermas mentions liberal and welfare paradigms—by
means of which they defend and interpret the entire body of law “as a coherent
narrative.”
Each of these paradigms helps mitigate the problem of indeterminacy by pre-
defining the meaning of certain general types of application situations in accordance
with a fixed ranking of competing normative principles. For instance, in American
law questions regarding the scope of individual civil liberties and questions regard-
ing equal protection of minorities are framed in opposing ways, one limiting the
regulatory power of the state, the other extending it. In many situations calling for
legal regulation (eg, hate speech) it is far from clear which of these paradigms
claims priority. Applying them in tandem is ruled out by the fact that each retains its
internal narrative integrity by excluding the other (Habermas 1996: 221).
The ideological rigidity characteristic of legal paradigms, Habermas remarks,
provides “sufficient incentive for a proceduralist understanding of law to distinguish
a level at which reflexive legal paradigms can open up for one another and prove
themselves against a variety of competing interpretations mobilized for the case at
hand” (Habermas 1996: 221–222) A proceduralist (discourse theoretic) paradigm of
adjudication should thus determine which contexts call for a given paradigm and
which call for hermeneutically fusing multiple paradigms in a novel synthesis.
Yet even with this reflexive turn in the judiciary, there is no reason to believe that
judges must interpret legislation as if it embodied a single conception of justice. In
order to avoid imposing a single conception ideologically, judges must mediate lib-
eral and welfare paradigms by being attentive to the most extensive information
available. For Habermas, this will require converting their courts into quasi-political
fora, in which (to paraphrase Klaus Günther) all relevant perspectives that bear on
the interpretation of disputed facts are represented. The outcome of deliberation,
with judges mediating multiple legal paradigms and multiple perspectives (and, at
higher levels doing so in communication with fellow judges, jurists, and the various
“publics” impacted by the decision), is far from certain—so much so that it stretches
credulity to think that those involved will presume that the decision reached is the
only right one that could have been decided. Hence, Habermas himself concludes
that what remains of our “certainty” that legal decisions are right is the expectation
that “in procedures issuing judicial decisions only relevant reasons will be decisive,
and not arbitrary ones” (Habermas 1996: 220, 224, 232).
Kelsen seems to endorse a similar proceduralist jurisprudence: judges facing
hard decisions will be reluctant to read any single theory of justice into the law.
Kelsenian judges serving on constitutional courts will therefore do what Habermas
says judges generally ought to do, which is mediate adversarial contests between
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 207
competing justice paradigms wherein all affected have equal standing to argue and
appeal.
For Kelsen, the “most radical way to satisfy legal-political interests (rechtspoli-
tische Interesse) following the [constitutional court’s] setting aside of unconstitu-
tional laws and decrees (nach Beseitigung rechtswidrige Akte)” is to require that the
constitutional court institute a procedure of constitutional review (Verfahrung der
Prüfung der Rechtmässigkeit) “pursuant to an appeal made by or on behalf of any
private party (auf jedermanns Antrag)” (Kelsen 1929/1968: 1857). In addition to
allowing an “acto popularis” of this sort, it is of the greatest importance, to permit a
“qualified minority within parliament” to challenge parliamentary resolutions that
may be deemed unconstitutional—“all the more so, as constitutional courts in par-
liamentary democracy must necessarily serve to protect minorities” (Kelsen
1929/1968: 1859). This stipulation regarding constitutional procedures comple-
ments Kelsen’s insistence that parliamentary procedure guarantee representation of
electoral minorities. Finally, Kelsen shares Habermas’s discourse theoretic under-
standing of judicial decision-making as a public process of joint deliberation:
The principle of publicity and oral argument (Mündlichkeit) is generally to be recom-
mended for courtroom procedure in cases involving constitutional review, although it
chiefly deals with pure questions of law…The public interest concerning the affairs of the
constitutional court is so weighty that in principle oral argumentation before the court might
be necessary to fully guarantee the publicity of the proceedings. Indeed it might be neces-
sary to guarantee the publicity of judicial deliberation and judgment by considering extend-
ing said deliberation to include an assembly of lectures and hearings (Gerichtskollegium)
(Kelsen 1929/1968: 1860).
Given that judges must interpret the constitution principally as setting forth the
procedural conditions of liberal democracy and not as specifying a single concep-
tion of justice, they will be reluctant to nullify statutes unless it is necessary to
protect basic rights. This position—which in American jurisprudence is associated
with the view espoused by John Hart Ely—receives a ringing endorsement from
Habermas in the following passage, where Habermas highlights the dangers of jur-
isprudential idealism.
Ely is justified in taking a skeptical view of a paternalistic understanding of constitutional
jurisdiction (Habermas 1996: 266)…[I]t is the exceptionalistic description of political prac-
tice—how it really ought to be—that suggests the necessity of a pedagogical guardian or
regent.…the exceptionalist image of what politics should be is suggested by…[ethically]
virtuous citizens…oriented to the common good.…[D]iscourse theory insists, by contrast,
on the fact that democratic will formation does not draw its legitimating force from the prior
convergence of settled ethical convictions…[but from] procedures that secure fair bargain-
ing conditions (Habermas 1996: 278–279).
Indeed, such an expectation encourages precisely the kind of natural law reasoning
that both he and Kelsen oppose to democratic proceduralism.
19
For example, in opposition to the Israeli government’s insistence that building the Palestine Wall
flowed from its right to defend against terrorist attacks, the International Court of Justice’s
Advisory Opinion on the Legal Consequences of the Construction of a Wall in the Occupied
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 209
shopping” and global influence peddling behind the façade of institutional exper-
tise, as if law were the “technical production of pre-determined decisions by some
anonymous logic” (Koskenneimi 2009: 29).
Koskenniemi places hope in the redefinition and democratization of functional
legal regimes (“giving voice to those not represented in the regime’s institutions”).
However, he remains dubious about whether instituting a legal hierarchy of the sort
proposed by human rights monists such as Kelsen and Habermas would circumvent
elitism or politicization. Unfortunately, there are no simple, unproblematic recipes
for implementing global constitutional review. Instituting this function within the
legislature or executive administration threatens politicization; instituting it within
the judiciary threatens politicization and elitism.
Even when intervening in disputes that center on a single legal vocabulary, such
as human rights, courts are loath to enter into philosophical or cultural debates
about interpretation. At most, they condemn as violations only those criminal
actions on which there is broad agreement: slavery, torture, ethnic cleansing, geno-
cide, and so on. In many cases, such as the U.S.-backed sanctions regime against
Iraq (Gordon 2010) or the decision by the U.N. High Commissioner for Refugees to
forcibly repatriate refugees to war-torn areas in central Africa, the line separating
legal violation from legal enforcement is vague, which just goes to show how much
more politicized human rights enforcement is in comparison to humanitarian assis-
tance (Barnett 2010).
Fragmentation of international law clearly threatens legal monism. But the uto-
pian image of a centralized legal hierarchy commonly associated with Kelsenian
Palestinian Territory (2004) interpreted this act as a violation of the Palestinians’ right to self-
determination as well as a violation of their human rights to liberty of movement (as specified
under Article 12 of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights [ICCPR]) and to work,
to health, to education, and to an adequate standard of living (as specified by the International
Covenant on Economic, Social, and Cultural Rights). In the Al Jedda case (2005), by contrast, the
High Court of Justice of Britain appealed to the law of security in denying relief under the British
Human Rights Act of 1998 to the plaintiff—a dual Iraqi-British citizen, who had been detained for
10 months without charge. In another case, Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons
(1996), the ICJ observed that both the law of armed conflict and the ICCPR applied equally to the
strategic use of nuclear weapons. In deciding that the law of armed conflict was more directly
relevant to the use of nuclear weapons (applying the principle of lex specialis), it favored a narrow
interpretation of ICCPR Article 6’s clause concerning the “arbitrary deprivation of life.” Critics of
this interpretation argued that the ICJ had made an error in its judgment about which legal regime
was more relevant to the “arbitrary deprivation of life” inasmuch as nuclear weapons are weapons
of mass destruction that technically have no strategic military use. Finally, the case involving the
environmental impact of the MOX Plant nuclear facility at Sellafield, U.K. illustrates how differ-
ent legal institutions, each with its own jurisdiction, frame the issue of impact from their own
perspective. Is the issue to be decided by the Arbitral Tribunal responsible for adjudicating matters
that pertain to the United Nations Convention on the Law of the Sea (UNCLOS), the tribunal
established by the Convention on the Protection of the Marine Environment of the North-East
Atlantic (OSPAR Convention), or the European Court of Justice (ECJ) under the European
Community and Eurotom Treaties? As the Arbitral Tribunal for UNCLOS observed, even if the
other two tribunals applied rights and obligations that were similar or identical to those of
UNCLOS, they would do so relative to their own peculiar context, objective, purpose, case law,
and historical experience (Koskenneimi 2007: 7).
210 D. Ingram
and Habermasian monism is misleading.20 Given the logical gap between higher-
order norms and their lower-order applications, any constitutionalization of interna-
tional law will perforce permit flexibility in the choice of which legal systems are
best suited for addressing legal problems. However, it will also have to recognize
that the choice of system is itself largely political. And when a situation clearly falls
under the jurisdiction of human rights, it will have to recognize that the concrete
application of such rights will be institutionally and politically conditioned.
Practically speaking, the development of human rights will be from the ground up—
dispersed among many institutions—rather from the top-down.
The same might be said for institutionalizing constitutional review in the legisla-
tion, adjudication, and execution of international law. The reasons that compel insti-
tuting constitutional review in a separate court, namely, that doing so facilitates
philosophical examination of human rights impartially, also compel institutionaliz-
ing such review in legislative and executive bodies (Ingram 2014).21 Although these
latter institutions lack the greater political autonomy of a separate court, they are
better equipped as sensors of injustice and discontent, and can respond to concrete
cases of conflict more readily. Ultimately, a global public sphere will also share in
this review. It goes without saying that global social movements representing cos-
mopolitan concerns should have the right to initiate formal review at the level of the
highest court.
This realism in the flexibility of human rights application may still not counter
all objections to monism. One might object that there remains an inextricable ten-
sion between human rights and domestic rights. Even stalwart monists like Kelsen
and Habermas concede that the juridification of human rights at the international
level works at cross purposes to their juridification at lower levels of regional and
state governance. Trade-offs between multicultural flexibility and centralized juridi-
fication are thus to be expected. Given current political realities, that means post-
poning centralized juridification. But without this further step toward
constitutionalizing international law, we find ourselves once again staring at the
Schmittian abyss (Koskenneimi 1990: 4–32; Fischer-Lescano and Teubner 2004).
Acknowledgement The author thanks George Mazur, who greatly helped in navigating the sub-
tleties of Kelsen’s legal theory.
20
“Monism” can mean either the constitutional incorporation of international law into domestic
law (as in the case of the Netherlands or South Africa) in contradistinction to its selective domestic
inclusion by way of treaty ratification (as in dualist systems such as the United States), or it can
mean the centralization (constitutionalization) of an international legal order analogous to the
state-centered organization of domestic law—the meaning intended here.
21
As noted above, Kelsen’s understanding of the reflexive continuity (Stufenbau) linking legisla-
tion and application undermines notions of institutional supremacy and separation and also dis-
perses democratic accountability in a way consonant with Habermas’s tri-level institutionalization
of international law under aegis of a centralized (monistic) human rights regime (Kelsen 1920b:
19–26; Brunkhorst 2009: 232; Zurn 2007).
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 211
References
Hart, H.L.A. 1983. Kelsen’s doctrine of the unity of law. In Essays in jurisprudence and philoso-
phy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Ingram, D. 2002. The sirens of pragmatism versus the priests of proceduralism: Habermas and
American legal realism. In Habermas and pragmatism, ed. M. Aboulafia, M. Bookman, and
C. Kemp. New York: Routledge.
Ingram, D. 2010. Habermas: Introduction and Analysis. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Ingram, D. 2014. Pluralizing constitutional review in international law: A critical theory approach.
Revista Portuguesa de Filosofia: Special Double Issue on Philosophy of Law 70(2–3):
261–286.
Jütersonke, O. 2010. Morgenthau, law and realism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kalyvas, A. 2006. The basic norm and democracy in Hans Kelsen’s legal and political theory.
Philosophy and Social Criticism 32(5): 573–599.
Kant. 1900. Zum Ewigen Friede: Ein Philosophischer Entwurf. Gesammelte Schriften. Band VIII,
341–386, Berlin.
Kant, I. 1996. The metaphysics of morals. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kelsen, H. 1913/2010. Rechtsstaat und Staatsrecht. In Hans Kelsen Werke. Band 3. Veröffentliche
Schriften 1911–1917. Ed. Matthias Jestaedt with the cooperation of the Hans Kelsen Institut.
Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck: 147–155.
Kelsen, H. 1920a. Das Probleme der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts: Beitrag zu
einer reinen Rechtslehre. Tübingen: Mohr.
Kelsen, H. 1920b. Vom Wesen und Wert der Demokratie. Tübingen: J.C. Mohr.
Kelsen, H. 1929/1968. Wesen und Entwicklung der Staatsgerichtsbarkeit. In Die Wiener
Rechtstheoretischer Schule. Ausgewählte Schriften von Hans Kelsen, Adolf Julius Merkl und
Alfred Verdross. Zweite Band, ed. Hans. Klecatsky, René Marci, and Hans Schambeck:
1813–1872.
Kelsen, H. 1931. Wer Soll der Hüter der Verfassung sein? Die Justiz 6: 576–628.
Kelsen, H. 1933/1973. State-form and world-outlook. In Essays in legal and moral philosophy, ed.
O. Weinberger. Dordrecht/Boston: Reidel.
Kelsen, H. 1934/1967. Pure Theory of Law. 2nd and Rev. Edition. Trans. M. Knight. Berkeley:
University of California.
Kelsen, H. 1942. Judicial review of legislation. A comparative study of the Austrian and American
constitutions. Journal of Politics 4(2): 183–200.
Kelsen, H. 1944a. Peace through law. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina.
Kelsen, H. 1944b. The principle of sovereign equality of states as a basis for international organi-
zation. Yale Law Journal 53(2): 207–220.
Kelsen, H. 1946. General Theory of Law and State. Trans. H. Wedberg. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University.
Kelsen, H. 1950. The law of the United Nations. London: Stevens & Sons.
Kelsen, H. 1951. Recent trends in the law of the United Nations. New York: Stevens.
Kelsen, H. 1952. Was ist ein Rechtsakt? Österreichscher Zeitschrift für Öffentliches Recht.
Kelsen, H. 1952/1966. Principles of International Law, 2nd edn., ed. R. Tucker. New York: Holt
Rinehart &Winston.
Kelsen, H. 1955. Foundations of democracy. Ethics 66(1): 1–101.
Kelsen, H. 1957. What is justice? Justice, law, and politics in the mirror of science. Collected
essays. Berkeley: University of California.
Koskenneimi, Martti. 1990. The politics of international law. European Journal of International
Law 1(4): 4–32.
Koskenneimi, Martti. 2002. The gentile civilizer of nations. The rise and fall of international law
1870–1960. Cambridge: Cambridge University.
Koskenneimi, Martti. 2007. The fate of public international law: Between technique and politics.
Modern Law Review 17: 1–30.
10 A Morally Enlightened Positivism? 213
Koskenneimi, Martti. 2009. The politics of international law—Twenty years later. European
Journal of International Law 20(1): 7–19.
Landauer, C. 2003. Antinomies of the United Nations: Hans Kelsen and Alf Ross on the Charter.
European Journal of International Law 14(4): 767–799.
Maus, I. 2009. I. Recht und Kant. In Habermas Handbuch, ed. H. Brunkhorst, R. Kreide, and
C. Lafont. Stuttgart: Metzler.
McCormick, J. 1997. Habermas’ discourse theory of law: Bridging Anglo-American and continen-
tal legal traditions? The Modern Law Review 60(5): 734–743.
Morgenthau, H. 1948. Politics among nations: The struggle for power and peace. New York:
Knopf.
Paulsen, S.L. 1994. Lon Fuller, Gustav Radbruch, and the ‘Positivist Thesis’. Law and Philosophy
13: 313–359.
Paulsen, S.L., and B.L. Paulsen. 1998. Normativity and norms: Critical perspectives on Kelsenian
themes. Oxford: Clarenden Press.
Radbruch, G. 1946. Gesetzliches Unrecht and Übergesetzliches Recht. Süddeutsche Juristen-
Zeitung 1: 105.
Raz, J. 1979. The authority of law. Essays on law and morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Rigaux, F. 1998. Hans Kelsen on international law. European Journal of International Law 9:
325–343.
Scheuerman, W. 1994. Between the norm and the exception. The Frankfurt School and the rule of
law. Cambridge: MIT.
Scheuerman, W. 2008. Global governance without global government? Habermas on postnational
democracy. Political Theory 36(1): 133–151.
Schmalz-Bruns, R. 2007. An den Grenzen der Entstaatlichung. Bemerkungen zu Jürgen Habermas’s
Modell einer Weltinnenpolitik ohne Weltregierung. In Anarchie der kommunikativen Freiheit,
ed. P. Niesen and B. Herborth, 269–293. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.
Schmitt, C. 1922/1985. Political theology. Four chapters on the concept of sovereignty. Cambridge,
MA: MIT.
Schmitt, C. 1923/1988. The crisis of parliamentary democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Schmitt, C. 1931. Der Hüter der Verfassung. Tübingen: Mohr.
Schmitt, C. 1932/2007. Constitutional theory. Durham: Duke University.
Schmitt, C. 1934/1996. The concept of the political. Cambridge, MA: MIT.
Schmitt, C. 1978/1987. The legal world revolution. Telos 72: 73–89.
Vinx, L. 2007. Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law. Legality and legitimacy. Oxford: Oxford
University.
Zurn, C. 2007. Deliberative democracy and the institution of judicial review. Cambridge:
Cambridge University.
Part IV
Kelsen’s Legacies
Chapter 11
The Neglect of Hans Kelsen in West German
Public Law Scholarship, 1945–1980
Frieder Günther
11.1 Introduction
Mass murder, concentration camps, expulsions from home, tortures, tears of innocent peo-
ple, bold lies of public institutions, all this is legally acceptable for Kelsen, because for him
the order of the state and the legal order, law and justice are identical. At the same time you
can find here the practical consequences of a theory of the state, that cannot differentiate
between good and evil, justice and injustice.
This dismissive judgment of Hans Kelsen and his legal theory comes from Ernst
von Hippel’s popular textbook “General Theory of the State” (“Allgemeine
Staatslehre”) in 1963 (Hippel 1963: 154). Hippel’s opinion of Kelsen was wide-
spread among West German scholars of public law between 1945 and 1980. The
majority of scholars of public law in Germany refused to either discuss or work with
the ideas of Hans Kelsen, because they considered his theory ideologically inade-
quate and wrong. Among the German members of the renowned Association of
German Scholars of Public Law (Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer),
which meets annually and publishes its academic discussions,—with two excep-
tions that I will discuss later—no single statement was made about Kelsen’s theory
between 1949 and 1980. Hence, Kelsen’s ideas existed in a vacuum or a non-space
in the debates about public law. Since the mid-1980s, Kelsen’s scholarship has
enjoyed a renaissance among German scholars of public law, which raises questions
as to the reasons underlying this decades-long silence and disregard of his legal
theory. In this chapter, I argue that it is not enough to concentrate just on Kelsen’s
work to answer this question. Rather, in order to understand the contempt for
Kelsen’s ideas among West German scholars, we also need to consider Kelsen’s
F. Günther (*)
Institute of Contemporary History, Berlin, Germany
e-mail: [email protected]
Historical research has shown that anti-Semitism was widespread within bourgeois
and national-conservative circles during the Weimar Republic. In the field of public
law during that time, scholars could assume anti-Semitic prejudices among their
colleagues even if such views were not explicitly pronounced in everyday conversa-
tions (Berding 1988; 165–225; Peukert 1987; 161–163; Wehler 2003; 495–511).
Carl Schmitt is only the most prominent figure among the legal scholars with an
abiding hatred of Jews (Mehring 2009: 113–302; Gross 2000). This widespread
anti-Semitism helps explain the often sharp reactions to Kelsen’s legal ideas during
the Weimar period. The level of hostility to Kelsen’s ideas was academically moti-
vated in part but it must be understood against the background of racism that per-
vaded the legal academy during the Weimar Republic.
After the Nazi seizure of power, a large number of scholars of public law included
decisively anti-Semitic statements in their academic works (Günther 2010: 141–
142; Stolleis 1999: 250–299; Lösch 1999). Such statements should not be trivial-
ized as minor adaptations to Nazi ideology but must be understood as expressions
of deeply-rooted racist mentalities among scholars of public law. The majority of
legal scholars thought that the influence of Jews in law should be diminished and
that the number of Jewish students at universities should be reduced. Hans Kelsen
himself was the victim of anti-Semitic measures. Despite the efforts of many of his
colleagues in the department of law at the University of Cologne who tried to inter-
vene on his behalf, Kelsen was forced to retire in the summer of 1933.
Anti-Semitic resentments did not disappear with the end of the Nazi rule,
although racial arguments could no longer be found in the publications of the schol-
ars of public law. In order to further advance their careers, anti-Semitic scholars
made subtle adjustments in the new editions of their books and erased all racial
references. Anti-Semitism, however, remained an undercurrent in their legal think-
ing. For example, in the letters of Ernst Forsthoff or Carl Schmitt, one can still
notice that they used anti-Semitic phrases such as “canine behavior” (“hündische
Beflissenheit”) or “deficient abilities to fit in” (“mangelnde Anpassungsfähigkeit”)
when they characterized their Jewish colleagues (Meinel 2011: 312; Forsthoff and
Schmitt 2007). In an article of 1960, Rudolf Smend, one of the most recognized
scholars after 1945, reproduced anti-Semitic stereotypes when he characterized the
appointment of his colleague Hermann Heller at the Humboldt University of Berlin
in the year 1928 as “politically motivated.” Smend objected that Heller’s appoint-
ment destroyed the homogenous and consensual atmosphere at the department,
because Heller was a social climber, a Social Democrat, and most importantly a Jew
(Smend 1994: 542; Sälzer 2010: 81–83).
11 The Neglect of Kelsen 219
Apart from anti-Semitic resentments, there also existed feelings of guilt among
the scholars who had stayed in Germany during the Nazi period. They simply had a
bad conscience in respect to those who were forced to emigrate, because they had
not protested loudly enough against the dismissal of their Jewish colleagues. They
had not supported them on their way to emigration and did not even try to contact
them afterwards. Many also had used the forced Jewish emigration to accelerate
their own careers, as they succeeded to the academic positions of those who were
forced to leave. And nearly everybody had concealed the achievements and intel-
lectual contributions of former Jewish colleagues or identified such former col-
leagues as Jews if they decided to cite them in their publications.
Kelsen and his ideas were thus disregarded based on his Jewish descent. He was
a prototype of an assimilated Jew, and that undermined his reputation before and
after 1945.
In addition to his Jewishness, Kelsen’s legal positivist position also prevented his
ideas from being taken seriously after the Second World War. After 1945, West
Germany experienced a renaissance of natural law. In order to avoid the perverse-
ness of law under the Nazi rule, the majority of the scholars believed that law should
be subordinated to some general principles of justice. Therefore, they extensively
discussed legal concepts such as a system of eternal values, ethical principles of
justice, or a continuous right to revolution. However, legal positivism, with which
Kelsen was associated, was considered responsible for the lack of legal defense
against the injustice of National Socialism. Many scholars argued that, by consider-
ing “law just as law,” lawyers had become defenseless against the arbitrary and
criminal content of Nazi laws (Radbruch 2002; Hippel and Voigt 1952; Walther
1998; Rückert 1998; Kühl 1998: 614–619).
But this argumentation deserves reconsideration. It was not the positivist under-
standing of law that enabled the Nazis to influence the legal system with their ideol-
ogy; rather, it was the willingness to leave positivism behind and be open to methods
of interpretation based on general values and natural law. In general, Nazi legal
scholars, including Carl Schmitt, were hostile to legal positivism and saw its former
popularity as a result of Jewish influence (Schmitt 1934, 2006; Rüthers 1988:
91–322; Stolleis 1999: 323–325).
Legal positivism played the role of a scapegoat in West German legal discourse
after 1945. By blaming legal positivism for the aberration of law during the Nazi
years, legal scholars avoided facing the question what really made their works sus-
ceptible to Nazi ideology and to what extent they bore individual responsibility for
Nazi rule. Blaming positivism also provided some measure of relief of personal
guilt, which scholars had accumulated during the Nazi years. The association of
positivism with complicity with or passivity in the face of the Nazi legal regime led
to the further repudiation of Kelsen’s legal theory because he was a major advocate
220 F. Günther
for legal positivism. As a result, the end of the Nazi regime did not mean a positive
reevaluation of his legal scholarship. On the contrary, scholars continued to accuse
him of ignoring the necessities of reality and relativizing the values of democracy.
As we have seen in the passage of Ernst von Hippel’s textbook at the beginning of
this chapter, West German legal scholars criticized Kelsen’s ideas on two grounds:
their susceptibility to totalitarianism and their inability to differentiate between
good and evil legal normative systems.
The work of a younger scholar of public law argued in the same way as von
Hippel. Horst Ehmke, who later became the West German Minister of Justice under
Chancellor Kurt Georg Kiesinger, wrote in his dissertation in 1954 that Kelsen’s
pure theory of law showed a lack of connection with reality and a relativism of val-
ues, which did not fit the necessities of modern democracy. For Ehmke, Kelsen’s
theory—in accordance with the ideas of Carl Schmitt—failed to differentiate
between law and power. Instead of Kelsen’s formal relativism, Ehmke called for
general integration and an orientation towards values in order to create cohesion and
solidarity in a society that was still shaped by deprivations and economic shortages
as a consequence of the Second World War (Ehmke 1981: 37–42).
In general, emigrants who had left Germany for political reasons during the Nazi
years were treated with suspicion and seen as traitors to the fatherland. In addition,
emigrants were regarded as not being able to understand the specific situation in
post-war Germany. The most prominent target of such resentments was the writer
and Nobel Prize laureate Thomas Mann. At the same time, emigrants, who decided
to return to Germany, had difficulties reintegrating into their old home country and
revitalizing their old networks. People assumed that the emigrants sought some
form of revenge against the Germans who had remained in Germany during the
Third Reich, and they were not viewed as representatives of a morally “better
Germany” (Krauss 2001).
Kelsen, too, must have realized that West Germans did not welcome him with
open arms. As early as 1945, the British occupying authorities asked him to return
to the University of Cologne, where he had been dismissed in 1933, but he declined.
Apart from this early initiative, no other German university offered Kelsen a posi-
tion afterwards. Search committees preferred expelled persons, refugees from the
GDR and dismissed colleagues who had lost their job due to their Nazi past, because
these people were seen—in comparison to returning emigrants—as more reliable in
questions of national interest.
In this context, Kelsen seemed especially unreliable because of his statements
about the end of the Second World War and the legal status of defeated Germany. In
two articles published in the renowned American Journal of International Law in
1944/45, he argued that the allied powers had not just occupied Germany at the end
of the war but had taken over—in the sense of a condominium—its territorial
11 The Neglect of Kelsen 221
sovereignty. Therefore, with the Berlin Declaration of the allied powers of June 5,
1945, the German state had ceased to exist and had to be re-established at a later
date (Kelsen 1944, 1945). Kelsen argued here as an emigrant who wanted the allied
powers to be as free and legally unfettered as possible so that they would be able to
reconstruct a democratic order and punish the Nazi perpetrators in their sole discre-
tion. His position was the result of his experience after the First World War when the
Germans proved to be incapable of solving the problems of the post-war era by
themselves.
Kelsen’s opinion, however, was incompatible with the conviction of the majority
of West German scholars of public and international law at that time (Diestelkamp
1985; Rückert 2006; Möllers 2008: 34–37; Stolleis 2003: 283–287, 2012: 32–37;
Dreier 2001: 27–28). Among German lawyers, nationalism and etatism were still so
strong that an end of the unified German state was simply unimaginable. They
developed a theory that the German Empire in its boundaries of December 31,
1937—despite its military defeat—continued to exist. Hence these scholars aimed
to establish strong legal limits for the allied powers, contending that the rules of the
Hague Convention respecting the laws and customs of war on land applied. They
argued that the allied powers should treat their control of Germany as a temporary
occupation and administer the territory with an eye to returning it to the Germans in
the same condition it was in at the outset of the occupation. Scholars of international
law unanimously adopted this opinion at a conference in Hamburg in 1947. At a
conference of the Association of German Scholars of Public Law on the legal status
of Germany in 1954, the vast majority again confirmed this idea. They directly
attacked Kelsen in absentia. On the one hand, they contended that his views on
Germany’s legal status resulted from his inadequate formal theory. On the other
hand, they argued that his ideas about the end of the German state were incompati-
ble with his own theory of pure law, because his conclusions followed from the facts
and not from legal data (Dürig and Heydte 1955).
Inadvertently, Kelsen’s statement about the legal status of the German state con-
firmed the prejudice about the unreliable patriotism of emigrants and Jews, which
was widespread among the majority of West German scholars of public law. Kelsen
supported the position of the allied powers and, therefore, positioned himself out-
side the national consensus.
The disregard for positivism among scholars of public law was accompanied by a
de-liberalization of political opinions that already started during the 1920s. The
political system of the Weimar Republic experienced a continuous decline of politi-
cal liberalism (Langewiesche 1988: 233–286). The younger generation of scholars
of public law who began their academic careers during the 1920s regarded the lib-
eral political system of the Weimar Republic with critical eyes. Politically, they
stood at the far right and, academically, they followed an anti-positivist method of
222 F. Günther
legal interpretation in order to politicize the debates in their field and promote anti-
liberal concepts. The determining feature of their ideas was holistic thinking, which
juxtaposed the chaotic political reality to a visionary expectation of salvation, prom-
ising an alternative stable, value-based, united, and harmonious order (Lepsius
1994; Stolleis 1999: 171–186).
After the Second World War, the anti-positivist concepts that were developed
during the Weimar Republic were revitalized. These concepts lost their original
anti-parliamentary orientation and were no longer directed against the democratic
constitutional system. But they were still determined by a yearning for harmony,
unity, and stability. At the same time, the revitalized anti-positivist concepts of the
Weimar period maintained their anti-liberal and anti-pluralist orientation. They
aimed to reinforce the “conserving forces” (“haltende Mächte”) that could limit the
negative aspects of modernity and absorb the de-personalization and alienation that
they associated with modern mass society. In general, scholars of public law tried to
promote conservative concepts such as community, state, order, traditional values,
and eternal justice by referring to the anti-positivist legal concepts of the Weimar
period (Günther 2004: 191–192; Schildt and Siegfried 2009: 122–161; Hacke 2009:
17–24).
A good example of this development is Rudolf Smend’s theory of integration.
The main thrust of Smend’s theory is that the state constitutes itself by a quotidian
integration of the individuals into the state. The process of integration was the
essence of the constitution in order to overcome the separation of individual and
collective, between ego and state in the dis-integrated political culture of the Weimar
Republic. In contrast to its original anti-parliamentary and folkish orientation, the
theory of integration was reinterpreted after 1945 in a normativistic way and became
a popular theory of the reformable West German state. Still, the theory of integra-
tion did not lose its focus on unity and integration and thus remained indebted to the
harmonistic and nationalist ideas that informed theories of public law in the Weimar
Republic (Korioth 1990; Günther 2004: 159–191; Stolleis 2012: 216–246).
As part of this development, liberal ideas were pressed onto the defensive during
the 1950s. The debate about basic rights reflected this development. In this context,
the majority of scholars of public law emphasized the necessity to limit individual
legal protection in order to ensure the interests of the community. During the 1950s,
the Federal Constitutional Court consciously established an understanding of basic
rights as an order of values as an alternative to a liberal and positivist understanding
of rights (Schmidt 1994; Günther 2004: 193–195, 202–204). Liberal and neo-liberal
attitudes, which dominated West German economic policy during the 1950s, were
also in a minority position in the debate about the economic system that was derived
from the Basic Law. The majority of scholars of public law argued that the Federal
Republic should be a strong state and that the government should not refrain from
interfering in society in order to secure social justice and the interests of the com-
munity (Scheuner and Schüle 1954; Kübler 1994; Günther 2004: 204–206).
The scholars of public law also had reservations about pluralist ideas during the
1950s. In fact, they gradually accepted the central role of the political parties and
pressure groups in the process of political decision-making, but they also emphasized
11 The Neglect of Kelsen 223
that political parties and pressure groups had to subordinate themselves to the com-
mon good and that their influence should not surpass a certain degree (Günther
2004: 200–202; Möllers 2008: 47–50). The field of public law resisted socio-
political and legal developments in which the rest of West German academia largely
acquiesced. As a result, other academic disciplines regarded scholars of public law
with deep mistrust. Political scientists frequently dismissed the majority of public
law scholars as conservative partisans of the authoritarian state who refused to come
to grips with the fact that West Germany was developing into a modern democracy
(Fraenkel 1990: 297). This opinion is slightly exaggerated, but it remains an acute
observation of the situation at that time.
Kelsen stood in contrast to nearly everything the scholars of public law wanted
to reestablish during the 1950s. Due to his liberal and pluralist political opinions, he
had formulated a radical alternative to many legal problems that were discussed
during the Weimar years, and this situation did not change during the 1950s.
Whereas the scholars of public law emphasized the necessity for harmony, unity,
and stability of state and society, Kelsen understood society as a pluralist entity. His
democratic theory was based on liberty and emphasized the relativity of all values.
The atmosphere of the 1950s, which I have just described, changed gradually during
the 1960s. A new generation of scholars of public law now raised their voices
because they aimed to break from the stifling situation in their discipline. These
younger scholars, who were born around 1930, had different experiences from the
older generation during the Nazi years, the Second World War, and the years of
reconstruction, and they accordingly offered different perspectives on that era. After
experiencing the defeat of the Weimar democracy, the older generation considered
the vulnerability of parliamentary democracy the most important topic for their
work. For the younger generation, the Basic Law was the appropriate response to
the Nazi past. In contrast to the older generation, which had accepted the Basic Law
only with reluctance and reservation, the new generation saw no better alternative
than the present constitution and thus embraced it with muted enthusiasm (Günther
2004: 211–234; Stolleis 2012: 317–322, 395–403).
This generation developed a methodological and theoretical basis for their disci-
pline that differed sharply from that of their teachers. They discussed such funda-
mental questions as methods of interpretation, the doctrine of basic rights, the
expansion of the welfare state, and the understanding of the state, of the rule of law,
and of democracy in general. They were open to discussing and reviewing the old
doctrines of the Weimar period instead of completely discarding them. Accordingly,
they advocated continued modernization and progress, in which people still believed
224 F. Günther
during the 1960s (Günther 2004: 243–264, 277–283, 295–309; Stolleis 2012:
379–394).
The new generation was no longer skeptical about the role of political parties and
pressure groups in the decision-making process. In their eyes, state and society were
closely linked. Therefore, parties and pressure groups should have a public charac-
ter when they participate in elections or advise government agencies (Hesse and
Kafka 1959; Leibholz and Winkler 1966; Günther 2004: 295–298; Stolleis 2012:
322–332). While the theories of Carl Schmitt and Rudolf Smend had dominated the
theoretical debates of the 1950s, the new generation started to work with other clas-
sic theorists of the Weimar period including Hermann Heller, Erich Kaufmann, and
Heinrich Triepel (Häberle 1962: 76–80; Lerche 1961; Hollerbach 1966).
The reception of Kelsen, however, has continued to follow a difficult path since
the 1960s. Some members of the new generation started to have a closer look at the
Kelsen’s ideas. In particular, two scholars of administrative law, Hans Heinrich
Rupp and Dietrich Jesch, referred to Kelsen in their books in order to expand the
provision of legality (Gesetzesvorbehalt) to all acts of administration. Yet these
books were widely challenged and received very critical reviews, in part because
they referred explicitly to Kelsen (Jesch 1961; Rupp 1965; Schönberger 2006: 79;
Ipsen 1972: 409–413; Günther 2004: 257–267; Stolleis 2012: 249–250). Something
similar happened 20 years later, when Norbert Achterberg referred several times to
Kelsen’s theory in a presentation at the annual meeting of the Association of German
Scholars of Public Law in 1980. His colleagues reacted either with strong criticism
or deliberately ignored Achterberg’s presentation (Bernhard and Achterberg 1980;
Schulte 2013).
Apart from these sporadic examples, there was no other positive reception of
Kelsen’s ideas among scholars of public law. At first glance, this is surprising,
because the breakthrough of a more pluralist opinion in the Federal Republic would
have been compatible with Kelsen’s theory of pure law. I explain the continued
disregard for his ideas with respect to the social networks among scholars of public
law and the sociology of knowledge within that field. Legal concepts and theories
are not timeless designs of an independent and grand genius; rather, they are devel-
oped in a process of exchange with teachers, students, and colleagues on the basis
of political and social circumstances (Fleck 1999). Since the teachers of the new
generation had been hostile toward Kelsen’s positivism, their students avoided
direct reference to his work because they knew that doing so could provoke sharp
criticism and hurt their chances for a successful academic career. Kelsen himself did
not have any students in Germany after the beginning of the 1930s, and he also had
no followers or supporters of his ideas in his own discipline after 1945. Moreover,
the majority of the new generation continued to argue on the basis of values in order
to implement the main ideas of the Basic Law in state and society (Günther 2004:
264–276, 309–319; Meinel 2011: 400–429; Stolleis 2012: 356–361, 506–510). But,
Kelsen’s relativistic theory was regarded as completely inadequate for such battles
over proper values. The disregard for Kelsen demonstrated that the yearning for
unity continued to be popular even after the 1950s.
11 The Neglect of Kelsen 225
This disregard for Kelsen prevailed until Horst Dreier published his dissertation
on Kelsen’s theory of democracy in 1986 and received very positive reviews (Dreier
1986). From then on, a rethinking of Hans Kelsen’s ideas started to take off among
scholars of public law and spread widely during the 1990s. This new open-
mindedness towards Kelsen took place in a context of growing interest in questions
of legal theory and the publication of Anglo-American legal literature in the German
language (Dreier 2001: 30–33, 2013; Lepsius 2003: 371–372).
In retrospect, if I may comment as a historian, Kelsen’s liberal and pluralist the-
ory should have been well-suited to the atmosphere of the transition in the 1960s.
But the field of public law proved to be much more oriented toward the past than the
self-understanding of the younger generation of scholars would suggest.
Additionally, the systematization of the decisions of the new Federal Constitutional
Court precluded extended theoretical debates which would have become conducive
to a positive reception of Kelsen (Schlink 1989). Still, the period between 1960 and
1985 was decisively different from the 1950s, and resentments against Jews, emi-
grants, pluralists and liberals no longer dominated German public law. In general,
the disregard for Kelsen is a vivid example of how the legacy of the Weimar Republic
and Nazi Germany still dominated the history of the Federal Republic of Germany
after 1949, and the decisive break only happened after the 1980s.
References
Lepsius, Oliver. 2003. Die Wiederentdeckung Weimars durch die bundesdeutsche Staatsrechtslehre.
In Weimars lange Schatten—“Weimar” als Argument nach 1945, ed. Christoph Gusy, 354–
394. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Lerche, Peter. 1961. Stil, Methode, Ansicht: Polemische Bemerkungen zum Methodenproblem.
Deutsches Verwaltungsblatt 76: 690–701.
Lösch, Anna-Maria Gräfin von. 1999. Der nackte Geist: Die juristische Fakultät der Universität
Berlin im Umbruch von 1933. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Mehring, Reinhard. 2009. Carl Schmitt: Aufstieg und Fall. Eine Biographie. Munich: C. H. Beck.
English Edition: Mehring, Reinhard. 2014. Carl Schmitt: A Biography. Trans. D. Steuer.
Cambridge/Malden: Polity Press.
Meinel, Florian. 2011. Der Jurist in der industriellen Gesellschaft: Ernst Forsthoff und seine Zeit.
Berlin: Akademie.
Möllers, Christoph. 2008. Der vermisste Leviathan: Staatstheorie in der Bundesrepublik.
Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
Peukert, Detlef J. K. 1987. Die Weimarer Republik: Krisenjahre der Klassischen Moderne.
Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp. English Edition: Peukert, Detlef J. K. 1993. The Weimar Republic:
The Crisis of Classical Modernity. Trans. R. Deveson. New York: Hill and Wang.
Radbruch, Gustav. 2002. Gesetzliches Unrecht und übergesetzliches Recht. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Rückert, Joachim. 1998. Zu Kontinuitäten und Diskontinuitäten in der juristischen
Methodendiskussion. In Erkenntnisgewinne, Erkenntnisverluste: Kontinuitäten und
Diskontinuitäten in den Wirtschafts-, Rechts- und Sozialwissenschaften zwischen den 20er und
50er Jahren, ed. Karl Acham, Knut Wolfgang Nörr, and Bertram Schefold, 113–165. Stuttgart:
Franz Steiner.
Rückert, Joachim. 2006. Die Beseitigung des Deutschen Reiches—die geschichtliche und
rechtsgeschichtliche Dimension einer Schwebelage. In Strukturmerkmale der deutschen
Geschichte des 20. Jahrhunderts, ed. Anselm Doering-Manteuffel, 65–95. Munich: Oldenbourg.
Rupp, Heinrich. 1965. Grundfragen der heutigen Verwaltungsrechtslehre: Verwaltungsnorm und
Verwaltungsrechtsverständnis. Tübingen: Mohr.
Rüthers, Bernd. 1988. Die unbegrenzte Auslegung: Zum Wandel der Privatrechtsordnung im
Nationalsozialismus, 3rd ed. Heidelberg: Müller.
Sälzer, Gerd. 2010. Martin Drath: Ein Bericht über Lebensabschnitte mit vorwiegend hessischem
Einschlag und über Draths Verhältnis zu Rudolf Smend. In Moderne Staatswissenschaft:
Beiträge zu Leben und Werk Martin Draths, ed. Michael Henkel and Oliver W. Lembcke,
29–122. Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.
Scheuner, Ulrich, and Adolf Schüle. 1954. Staatliche Intervention im Bereich der Wirtschaft.
Veröffentlichungen der Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer 11: 1–152.
Schildt, Axel, and Detlef Siegfried. 2009. Deutsche Kulturgeschichte: Die Bundesrepublik von
1945 bis zur Gegenwart. Munich: Carl Hanser.
Schlink, Bernhard. 1989. Die Entthronung der Staatsrechtswissenschaft durch die
Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit. Der Staat 28: 161–172.
Schmidt, Walter. 1994. Grundrechte—Theorie und Dogmatik seit 1946 in Westdeutschland. In
Rechtswissenschaft in der Bonner Republik: Studien zur Wissenschaftsgeschichte der
Jurisprudenz, ed. Dieter Simon, 188–226. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.
Schmitt, Carl. 1934. Nationalsozialistisches Rechtsdenken. Deutsches Recht 4: 225–229.
Schmitt, Carl. 2006. Über die drei Arten des rechtswissenschaftlichen Denkens. 3rd ed. Berlin:
Duncker & Humblot. English Edition: Schmitt, Carl. 2006. On the Three Types of Juristic
Thought. Trans. J.W. Bendersky. Westport: Praegar.
Schönberger, Christoph. 2006. “Verwaltungsrecht als konkretisiertes Verfassungsrecht:” Die
Entstehung eines grundgesetzabhängigen Verwaltungsrechts in der frühen Bundesrepublik. In
Das Bonner Grundgesetz: Altes Recht und neue Verfassung in den ersten Jahrzehnten der
Bundesrepublik Deutschland (1949–1969), ed. Michael Stolleis, 53–84. Berlin: Berliner
Wissenschafts-Verlag.
228 F. Günther
Nicoletta Ladavac
Within the history of Western thought, in particular its modern currents, […] the natural law
school has amounted to the greatest attempt ever made to construct a rational theory of
morality and law (Norberto Bobbio 1972)
If a man could write a book on Ethics which really was a book on Ethics, this book
would, with an explosion, destroy all the other books in the world (Ludwig Wittgenstein
1989)
Two scientific structures are conceivable: one determined by natural laws and the other
by rules. Which of these two structures will be chosen by men is dependent upon their level
of rationality. The more irrational man is, the more he tends towards a natural law structure
(Friedrich Dürrenmatt 1991)
12.1 Introduction
When Hans Kelsen decided to leave Europe in 1940 and to emigrate to the United
States, he knew that he was leaving behind a world full of certainty, and that he was
seeking refuge in a new world that was unknown and foreign to him. This deci-
sion—which Kelsen hoped would perhaps not be definitive—represented a radical
departure in his animated life, although he would never have grounds to regret it, as
he himself acknowledged in his autobiography (Kelsen 2006: 92). It was not easy
for him to adapt because, especially at the start, he ran up against a number of dif-
ficulties, including those relating to the English language, which Kelsen could read,
but he could not speak fluently, let alone write. However, the American academic
world, which exhibited a striking intellectual resistance, showing scant interest for
his theories or his writings, imposed the greatest obstacles on him. For Kelsen, it
N. Ladavac (*)
Thémis Centre d’Etudes de Philosophie du droit,
de Sociologie du droit et de Théorie du droit, Geneva, Switzerland
e-mail: [email protected]
was therefore not easy to find tenured employment and a suitable position within a
university.1 Kelsen ended up being highly disillusioned at this lack of appreciation,
in addition to his many concerns related to his precarious financial circumstances
(Nitsch 2009: LVIII–LXXII).
The first university to welcome him during the initial years was Harvard Law
School, where Kelsen gave the Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures in 1940 and 1941.2
He stayed in Harvard into 1942 as a research associate teaching sociology of law,
after which he taught at Wellesley College near Cambridge as a visiting professor.
During the years spent at Harvard, Kelsen dedicated himself intensely to research,
writing mainly in English. Out of a desire to adapt to his new environment, Kelsen
also displayed an interest in English-speaking legal science, for example in his essay
The Pure Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence (Kelsen 1941c), which was
published in the Harvard Law Review. As he had already taught at Harvard, albeit
only for a short time, Kelsen hoped very much that he would be hired there on stable
terms, and he found it very hard to understand the university’s reasons for not acced-
ing his request. He thus decided to accept an appointment as visiting professor in the
Political Science Department at the University of California Berkeley, even though
it was not a law school. He taught at Berkeley until 1945 as a fixed-term Political
Science lecturer, teaching international law, jurisprudence, and the origins of legal
institutions. It was only in 1945 that he was appointed as a full professor at the
University of California, where he remained until his retirement in 1952. The experi-
ence of teaching at Berkeley was gratifying (he would continue to teach mainly
international law, the origins of legal institutions, and elements of jurisprudence),
although Kelsen would have preferred to teach at a law school. As he himself said:
With my Pure Theory I would fit in better at a law school. However, American law schools
aren’t particularly interested in a scientific theory of law. They are training schools; their
function is to prepare students for practical work as an attorney. They teach almost exclu-
sively American law, which they do according to the case method. Since the American
courts base their decisions essentially on precedents, it is understandable that the law
schools see it as their goal to acquaint their students with as many cases as possible.[…] The
law as an object of scientific knowledge would perhaps be more at home in a faculty of law,
history or social science (Kelsen 2006: 94)
He also stressed that his students had very little interest in scientific research, above
all in jurisprudence, given that they were students in the Political Science
Department.
During the years he spent in the United States, Kelsen was able to dedicate a
great deal of time to scientific research and to publish, also in English (Kelsen
1942b, 1943), various new works that brought him success and recognition. In order
to introduce the pure theory in his adoptive country, he published Law as a Specific
1
See the detailed account and introduction by Nitsch in Kelsen (Kelsen 1942b, 2009: V- LXXX),
Nitsch (2012: 71–135), Métall (1969: 77–94), and Kelsen’s autobiographical notes in Kelsen
(2006: 92–94).
2
The Oliver Wendell Holmes lectures were published in 1942 in the book Law and Peace in
International Relations, see Kelsen (1942b).
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 231
Social Technique (Kelsen 1941b) and the essay entitled Value Judgments in the
Science of Law (Kelsen 1942c). In 1941, he published in English, albeit in abridged
form, the previously published paper Causality and Retribution (Kelsen 1941a),
followed in 1945 by the English language version of General Theory of Law and
State (Kelsen 1945), a publication that Kelsen considered to be of central impor-
tance. During his years in America, he published widely above all in the area of
international law (Kelsen 1944), a field that undoubtedly lent itself better to his new
academic life. His most renowned works on international law include Principles of
International Law (Kelsen 1952), published in 1952. The interest in positive law,
including in particular legal theory, in any case went hand in hand with the study of
international law.
Alongside his numerous publications, Kelsen participated in various confer-
ences3 in both the United States and in Europe, and it was around 1954 that American
academics, including above all international law scholars, started to take an interest
in his work. In 1953/1954, Kelsen participated in various conferences on the issue
of justice and legal theory, including the important conference on the foundations of
democracy, as part of the Walgreen Lectures at the University of Chicago in 1954.
Alongside theoretical problems, he also studied political theory and the relationship
between natural law and positive law, to which he dedicated a range of important
papers published in English (Kelsen 1957). He continued to work relentlessly up
until the end. The two principal works published late in life were the second edition
of the Pure Theory of Law (Kelsen 1967) in 1960 and the General Theory of Norms
(Kelsen 1991), published posthumously in 1979 by the Hans Kelsen Institute
(Kelsen 1979) in Vienna. Several years ago, after resolving various complex edito-
rial issues, the Hans Kelsen Institute published Secular Religion (Kelsen 2012), a
study on which Kelsen had worked for many years, but which he had decided
against publishing.
When Kelsen came to the United States, he was already in his sixties and had a
markedly central-European cultural mindset along with legal training rooted in the
Austro-German tradition and European civil law. It was obviously inevitable that he
would engage with the common law and the analytical jurisprudence of his new
country, although it would have been naive to expect Kelsen to cast aside his
classically-informed theories. Because the legal cultures and legal traditions of
3
In 1948 he contributed to a conference at Stanford University, which resulted in the later publica-
tion on Absolutism and Relativism in Philosophy and Politics in The American Political Science
Review, vol. 42; the year before he expounded his theoretical interest in an important essay in
honor of Roscoe Pound on The Metamorphoses of the Idea of Justice in Interpretations of Modern
Legal Philosophies. Essays in Honor of Roscoe Pound (New York: Oxford University Press,
390–418).
232 N. Ladavac
Europe and America were so different, it was inevitable and evident from the outset
that they would be radically irreconcilable (Telman 2010). Nevertheless, Kelsen
made an effort to understand analytical jurisprudence and expressed his ideas con-
cerning it in various articles, such as The Pure Theory of Law and Analytical
Jurisprudence (1941), in which he analyzes in detail the thinking of John Austin and
Anglo-American analytical jurisprudence.
The article on Austin include’s Kelsen’s detailed analysis of English speaking
analytical jurisprudence and a comparison between it and his own theories. The
study also contains a broad analysis of justice (an issue that Kelsen would consider
in greater depth during the years spent in the United States) and its relationship with
law, as well as a digression into American Legal Realism. Kelsen does not reject
Legal Realism entirely; rather, he takes issue with its claim to be the exclusive sci-
ence of law:
The Pure Theory of Law by no means denies the validity of such sociological jurisprudence
but it declines to see in it, as many of its exponents do, the only science of law. Sociological
jurisprudence stands side by side with normative jurisprudence; neither is able to replace
the other because each deals with different problems (Kelsen 1941c: 268)
Analyzing the theory of John Austin (Kelsen 1941c: 271–283), Kelsen makes an
even more interesting observation, pointing to a parallel between his theory as pre-
sented in the Reine Rechtslehre and analytical jurisprudence. Although analytical juris-
prudence did not have any influence on the pure theory of law, the two ideas coincide
in various important ways, and the discrepancies are due more to the different premises
on which they are grounded than on how they are developed. Kelsen states:
While the pure theory of law arose independently of Austin’s famous Lectures on General
Jurisprudence, it corresponds in important points with Austin’s doctrine. It is submitted that
where they differ the Pure Theory of Law has carried out the method of analytical jurispru-
dence more consistently than Austin and his followers have succeeded in doing (Kelsen
1941c: 271).
In fact, Kelsen argues that Austin does not clearly distinguish between the con-
cept of duty and responsibility. He argues that “[t]he liability rests upon the indi-
vidual against whom the sanction is directed. The duty rests upon the potential
delinquent who may by his behavior commit the delict” (Kelsen 1941c: 276).
However, says Kelsen, according to Austin it is not the legal norm that establishes a
legal duty; it is the command that obliges the individual, and this concept of com-
mand prevents Austin from distinguishing between duty and liability. Austin’s the-
ory also contains no concept of right different from that of duty.
While there are certain overlaps between Kelsen’s and Austin’s approaches, there
is an absolute difference with respect to at least two questions. The first concerns
nomodynamics. For Austin, the concept of nomodynamics does not exist, just as his
theory offers no legal concept of the state. For Kelsen on the other hand, the oppo-
site is the case:
Analytical jurisprudence, as presented by Austin, regards law as a system of rules complete
and ready for application, without regard to the process of their creation. The Pure Theory
of Law recognizes that a study of the statics of law must be supplemented by a study of its
dynamic, the process of its creation (Kelsen 1941c: 278–279)
According to Kelsen, nomodynamics, the notion that the law regulates its own pro-
duction, is necessary in order to move beyond the limits imposed by a static norma-
tive system. This is due above all to the two jurists’ differing concepts of the state.
For Austin, the state, or rather the concept of the state, is structured according to
the sovereign/subject framework, namely according to a division between two dis-
tinct entities:
One characteristic of Austin’s doctrine is its lack of a legal concept of the state. The concept
of an “independent political society” plays a certain role in his teachings, but it is not a legal
234 N. Ladavac
concept, and Austin himself does not call this “independent political society” a state. By it
he means a society consisting of a sovereign and subjects” (Kelsen 1941c: 280)
For Kelsen on the other hand, the state is the system that brings together in unitary
form, without any hierarchical distinctions, all of the subjects who belong to it. In
contrast to Austin, Kelsen thus wished to assert the absolute unity and identity of the
state and the law, and the subjection of individuals to one single legal order. Kelsen’s
pure theory of law:
shows that a number of individuals can form a social unit, a “society” or, better, a “com-
munity,” only on the basis of an order, or, in other words, that the element constituting the
political community is an order. The state is not its individuals; it is the specific union of
individuals, and this union is the function of the order regulating their mutual behavior.
Only in this order does the social community exist at all (Kelsen 1941c: 273–281)
Kelsen’s interest in the common law was in any case always limited more to a
cultural interest. Kelsen engaged with Anglo-Saxon law almost certainly in order to
reassert his own viewpoint. The reasons why Kelsen was never truly able to inte-
grate into the American legal world, in terms of both teaching and legal reasoning,
have been clearly illustrated in an interesting article by Jeremy Telman (Telman
2010). Other scholars have focused on Hans Kelsen’s reception in the United States,4
the problems and difficulties encountered, as well as the criticisms, disinterest, and
stark rejection by Anglo-American academics. The difference between Kelsenian
and Anglo-Saxon legal thinking was the main reason that Kelsen was never inte-
grated into American law schools and was practically “relegated” to teaching only
in political science faculties, even though opinions differ on this issue.5 The criti-
cisms, and a substantial refutation of Kelsen’s thought, up until the decisive engage-
ment with H.L.A. Hart, continued even after his death in 1973.6
Kelsen in any case engaged with his adoptive country’s legal community above all
through his numerous important writings in English on international law, even though
these too did not meet with any great success or receive the recognition they were due
from American academics. However, in the area of philosophy of law and legal
4
For the reception of Hans Kelsen in the United States of America, see Nitsch (2012) and Kelsen
(2009), in particular the detailed introduction by Carlo Nitsch to the Italian translation of Law and
Peace in International Relations, The Oliver Wendell Holmes Lectures, 1940–41; see also Paulson
(1988). See Losano (2011).
5
See the introduction by Carlo Nitsch describing the many problems concerning his career that
Kelsen encountered when he moved from Europe to America in Kelsen (2009: V–LXXX).
6
See Tur and Twining (1986). In this volume, leading experts in Kelsen from different countries
present and discuss interpretations and evaluations of Kelsen’s work not only as a whole, but espe-
cially his ideas on law, logic, social theory, legal science, legal sociology, jurisprudence, justice,
and international law.
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 235
7
The two new publications are Aristotle’s Doctrine of Justice and Why should the Law be Obeyed?
(1957). See also the important review of What is Justice? by Alf Ross (Ross 1957).
8
Kelsen (1998), see in particular about Kelsen’s concept of justice the introduction by Mario
G. Losano (XXXIV–XLI). See also Losano (1981, 152–175).
236 N. Ladavac
the Pure Theory of Law has never claimed to be the only possible or legitimate sci-
ence of law. Sociology of law or history of law are others. They, together with the
structural analysis of law, are necessary for a complete understanding of the com-
plex phenomenon of law” (Kelsen 1957: 294).
When engaging with the issue of justice, Kelsen applied to the theory of values the
same methodology used when elaborating his theory of law. In fact, in comparing
the problem of justice with the problem of law, Kelsen identifies a common charac-
teristic, discerning both to be scientific in nature by virtue of their non-evaluativeness.
In this way, arguing in favor of the non-evaluative nature of this theory, Kelsen
claimed that it is possible to describe all possible values of justice without charac-
terizing any particular value as preferable or superior to others.
The premise upon which Kelsen bases his position, and the entire conceptual
framework of the Rechtslehre, is his relativist conception of values. For Kelsen, it is
not possible to decide rationally which value is objectively superior because the
value is based on an internal subjective and psychological choice, and is not related
to an objectively and universally valid norm of justice. Moreover, Kelsenian relativ-
ism is premised on an all-inclusive and even more fundamental value, namely the
value of tolerance. For Kelsen, such tolerance not only has political value, but, on the
contrary, also entails a liberation from all politics and the assertion of politics as the
“foundation of a universal order of peace and rationalization of human existence.”9
As Kelsen repeated time and again, justice is an irrational ideal, which cannot be
accessed by rational consciousness (Kelsen 1957: 21). Thus, Kelsen’s neutrality
with regard to values, which was already asserted in the Reine Rechtslehre in rela-
tion to the distinction between law and morals (Kelsen 1934: 12–18, 1960: 60–113),
is taken to extremes within the analysis of justice, because for him absolute justice
cannot be apprised by human reason (Kelsen 1957: 20–21). Consequently, the ideal
of absolute justice is an irrational and subjective ideal for Kelsen. Indeed, according
to his radical non-evaluative conception of law, any value judgment will be irratio-
nal, as it is based on faith and not on reason (Kelsen 1957: 20–21). It is therefore
impossible to assert that any one value is scientifically, ie rationally, preferable over
any other. Thus, a scientific theory of justice must be limited to indicating the pos-
sible values of justice, but without stating that any one is better than the others.
In his essay on justice, contained in the second edition of the Reine Rechtslehre,
Kelsen identifies and analyzes various principles of justice from which all norms of
justice may be inferred. Moreover, polemicizing with natural law, Kelsen does not
deny that human beings have always been searching for an answer to the problem of
absolute justice, but only asserts that the Reine Rechtslehre is unable to provide such
an answer, thus acknowledging the limits inherent within the methodological purity
9
See introduction by Agostino Carrino in Kelsen (1989, XII).
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 237
For Kelsen, the ideal of justice thus becomes an ideal of peace and the social task
of positive law is to guarantee peace between the individual subjects of the legal
order (Kelsen 1985: 103–105), whereby the legal order transforms the ideal of abso-
lute justice into the relative justice of legality, of compliance with positive legal
norms (see Carrino in Kelsen 1989: XI).
238 N. Ladavac
But Kelsen has also analyzed a sociological concept of justice, which is connected
more with politics than with law. In particular the book, Society and Nature (Kelsen
1943), and especially its preface, is important because Kelsen sets out in it what
Renato Treves has correctly referred to as a “sociology of the idea of justice” (Treves
1981). In this book, he distinguishes between a normative theory of law and a soci-
ology of phenomena understood in terms of cause and effect for natural events, ie,
the interplay between legal and natural reality. The legal order, ie, the normative
order, determines how people ought to behave. However, the actual behavior of men
is determined by the laws of nature according to the principle of causality. Kelsen
defines this as natural reality and claims that, insofar as sociology deals with this
reality, sociology is a branch of natural science. Moreover, just as actual behavior
may or may not comply with the legal order, positive law may or may not corre-
spond to an ideal law of justice, which means that it should be conceived in terms of
a sociology of the idea of justice, of an idea which is conceived as an ideal. Thus, a
science of law is only possible if the theory of law is separated from a sociology and
philosophy of justice (Treves 1981: 10 n.8). In particular, in Society and Nature
Kelsen stresses the sociological origins of natural law theories when explaining how
the animist interpretation of nature, based on the principle of retribution, gives rise
to the idea of nature as an ideal society and how this in turn leads to the idea of a
natural law understood as an absolutely just law. While on the one hand Kelsen
assesses and criticises natural law theories and sociological theories in the same
terms, on the other hand he takes account of the needs to which these theories must
provide an answer, namely the requirements of a legal policy that is interested in
issues related to ends and values.
In the important preface to Society and Nature and also in the important intro-
duction to the General Theory of Law and State (Kelsen 1945), Kelsen argues in
relation to a sociological idea of justice. The sociology of justice is undoubtedly a
discipline that deserves to be investigated with reference to the ideas that effectively
determine it, or, at the very least, from a moral point of view, should determine the
formation of the norms that we call legal. For Kelsen, moreover, a study of the soci-
ology of justice proves to be useful in that it also identifies the social function of
certain ideas that exist in the minds of human beings and function as a cause for
their behavior. In particular, in the second edition of Reine Rechtslehre (Kelsen
1960; see Anhang), he stresses the fact that the idea of justice is of crucial importance
for legal policy and that the sociology of the idea of justice must analyze a broader
field, as does the sociology of knowledge and the sociology of values.
The sociology of the idea of justice cannot give any objective and absolute value
to any theory and must conceive of values in relativist terms. It is well known that
Kelsen’s relativism from the 1930s was no different from his relativism in the
1960/1970s, which argues in favor of a sociology of the idea of justice that is based
on relativism. Kelsen inferred his viewpoint regarding the relativity of values, which
he always defended, from that concept. That idea may be used to infer the principle
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 239
Until this point, we have analyzed Kelsen’s concept of justice within the Reine
Rechtslehre as related to the legal order. In fact, Kelsen was a great jurist and saw the
world above all through the eyes of a legal scholar. However, Kelsen was also a man
of culture, hailing from that deep-rooted central European culture that profoundly
shaped the Viennese milieu. He was also typical of the Jewish intelligentsia, a typical
example of the Viennese elites predominant at the time, driven on by continuous
attempts at inclusion due to previous marginalization. The culture and values of
Great Vienna thus constituted a fundamental element of Kelsen’s intellectual bag-
gage, and it is certain that this way of being and of feeling continued to mark his
personality, even after his emigration. While his world view remained predominantly
that of a jurist, his legal reasoning concealed a deeper Weltanschauung, which was
philosophical in nature, and which undoubtedly continued to guide his legal think-
ing. His thought is thus a synthesis of philosophy, specifically moral and social phi-
losophy, and legal theory. One is inconceivable without the other, even though
Kelsen the jurist has prevailed within the collective imagination of legal doctrine.
Moreover, if analyzed over and above the context of the Reine Rechtslehre and
the standard interpretation of Kelsenian thought, the issue of justice covers an idea
that Kelsen has of justice that goes beyond its legal and social aspect, revealing pro-
found reflections related to the issue of ideology. As Friedrich Dürrenmatt once
remarked, “An ideology is not a science” (Dürrenmatt 1991: 371), which is what
Kelsen appears to be saying in all of his writings (Kelsen 1947, 1957) on the issue
of justice. This is because, if analyzed in detail, Kelsen’s entire thinking—and not
solely that concerning justice—runs against any ideology. Examining significant
religious, political and metaphysical texts, Kelsen directed his rigorous critique of
ideology in an extremely decisive manner, classifying all that is ideological as lack-
ing in substance and logical support in the face of scientific criticism in general, and
more specifically, the Reine Rechtslehre. His critique of ideology is predominantly
directed against religion (any religion), and seeks to purify science—and for Kelsen
legal science in particular—from all theological and metaphysical remnants that
perform an anti-scientific role. It would be misleading if we were to consider
Kelsen’s criticism exclusively as part of his broader theoretical project, which only
provided for the abandonment of metaphysics and theology. In reality, the critique
of ideology was also made within the context of a highly precise political project,
10
Kelsen (1953 and 1973), in particular the introduction by O. Weinberger, XXV-XXVI regarding
Kelsen’s legal positivism and value-relativism, and the ideological and democratic consequences.
240 N. Ladavac
which went beyond the abandonment of metaphysical and theological claims, ie, as
a necessary way of overcoming the dichotomies of good/evil, true/false, being/not
being, science/magic, and rationality/irrationality. Thus, Kelsen’s critique of ideol-
ogy was the critical annulment of everything related to mythology, magic, archaism,
and totemism and, on the other hand, the assertion of the law as a structure based on
logical and scientific propositions: in short, science as a process of self-determination
of reason (see Carrino in Kelsen 1989: XII), the pure theory as a means of destroying
all mythological, metaphysical and mystic residues inherent within human society.
Moreover, for Kelsen, the critique of ideology, of which the critique of justice is
a constituent element, is the result of an atavistic and magical vision man has of
himself, which is rooted in his primitive origins, and, as Agostino Carrino has cor-
rectly noted (see Carrino in Kelsen 1989: IX), leads him to adopt a social ideology
and an ideology of retribution as an instrument of justice (Kelsen 1985: 248). Within
Kelsen’s analysis, which is focused on good and evil, analyzing above all Plato
(Kelsen 1942a) from the starting point of justice, this vision transforms into a vast
discourse on ethics, which is juxtaposed with the dissolution of existential relations
due to European affairs of the time, focusing on the normative as a value as such.
Kelsen’s discourse on justice is thus primarily critical of classical and traditional
views. We recall the concise critique of religions, including in particular secular
religions and philosophies (Kelsen 2012), along with Platonic and Aristotelian phi-
losophies, which are regarded as ideologies and, as such, as having a negative social
function. Kelsen directs a central criticism against Plato, whom he studied assidu-
ously. It is aimed in particular at the metaphysical conception of the soul and the
belief in its immortality, which is typical of Greek and Christian philosophies.
For Kelsen, souls considered in a metaphysical sense are conceived of ideologi-
cally and hence perform an anti-scientific and anti-rational function. Kelsen’s entire
discourse on the soul is a discourse on superstition, on magic, and on ideology as a
magical vision with social ends. In fact, he writes that “faith in souls is first and
foremost an ideology of retribution and as such an instrument of justice” (Kelsen
1985: 248). Thus, the soul is directly related to ethics and must engage with a need
for justice. For Kelsen, all other illusions, such as the existence of God or justice,
are born out of the soul as a primitive and totemic concept. Moreover, when under-
stood in this way, for him the soul and other illusions belong to an irrational meta-
physics, which is seen as an emotive postulate and a moral requirement stemming
from a subjective need, which has nothing to do with the objective reality. Thus,
justice too is born out of an internal need of the individual, who in this way seeks to
justify a subjective value by associating that subjective value with a value, or a norm
of justice, that is regarded as objective and universally valid. The lack of objectivity,
of possible corroboration within an external reality not merely constrained to the
subjective sphere, renders the ideal of justice an irrational ideal which, like all other
ideals, is inaccessible to human consciousness (Kelsen 1957: 10) and anti-scientific.
For Kelsen, such a conception of justice is alien to a rational science, the only form
of science capable of providing true knowledge.
Although justice may be classed under irrational ideals and ideologies, it never-
theless performs a useful and socially positive function for Kelsen as it promotes the
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 241
ideal of peace, which is without doubt a consistent and mandatory aspect of a posi-
tive legal order. In order to ensure good social cohabitation, the legal order seeks to
promote peace. In attempting to manifest itself within the practice of social reality,
the ideal of absolute justice transforms itself into an ideal of relative justice, attempt-
ing to engage with positive legal norms. When understood in these terms, Kelsen’s
positivism and natural law, which endorse the concept of justice in its two principal
forms—the metaphysical-religious concept of Plato and the rationalist concept of
Aristotle (Ross 1957)—arrive at the same postulate, namely the meaning of justice
as legality and obedience to the laws of the state. However, as Agostino Carrino
explains, “…while natural law ideology is forced to engage in a metamorphosis of
its starting postulates, Kelsen remains consistent from the outset with the postulate
of the value of veracity and thus has no need to abandon the scientific method in
order to champion requirements of possible justice” (see Carrino in Kelsen 1989:,
XIX, and Kelsen’s article on justice and metamorphosis in Kelsen 1947).
The complexity of Kelsenian doctrine, also as regards the discourse on justice, is
due to a complex interaction between various ideals, which sought to satisfy two
types of requirement. On the one hand, the Reine Rechtslehre has a neo-Kantian
philosophical basis in the purely descriptive and non-evaluative meaning of its con-
ception; on the other hand, his theory is tied to historical values and must therefore
be interpreted also in an ideological light, as the reflex of a political vision and a
certain political design of Kelsen. These two opposing visions, which have perhaps
not been fully acknowledged, have hindered an understanding of the true meaning
of the historical and theoretical project of the Kelsenian construction. It would be a
mistake to regard the two conceptions as countervailing. In reality, they are per-
fectly in tune with and complement each other. Moreover, it would be limiting to
consider Kelsen’s theory as legal or political only because it was also a philosophi-
cal enterprise, characterized by a strong moral valence. It must, of course, be con-
sidered as a reflection on what is normative, on that which must be. However, it
must also be viewed as being juxtaposed to a conception of existence understood as
pure contingency, as having a merely mutable nature, as the “is” juxtaposed to the
“ought.”
When understood in this way, Kelsen’s project, which is characterized by various
aporias, is without doubt ambiguous, and almost contradictory. Indeed, on the one
hand, there is the rigorously formal side to the Kelsenian conception expressed in
the pure theory of law, such as purity, system, order, norm, ought, coercion, validity,
efficacy, etc.; yet, on the other hand, there is a clear political and legal theory
designed for the achievement of particular legal and political ideals. Here Kelsen’s
variegated and unstinting commitment related to his legal and political activity,
including in particular the important involvement in constitutional issues and his
work as a legal consultant during the years spent in Europe, needs to be recalled and
not downplayed. Perhaps this contradiction within his theory simply expressed the
contradictions within Kelsen himself. In fact, his existential and cultural roots were
also grounded in a theological and religious conception of life and history. As was
rightly hypothesized by Agostino Carrino in an interesting study (see Carrino in
Kelsen 1989), perhaps Kelsen elaborated his legal and political theoretical
242 N. Ladavac
conception in order to counter the setbacks of human society and history, opposing
the formal categories of the pure theory of law with history itself and religious
archaism, ie, the ought against the is, form against fact, purity against the contradic-
tory reality of being, and order against disorder. It is only in this way that the absorp-
tion of God into nature (along with its natural law ramifications) and of the state into
pure normativity and formal abstractness can be understood. In rejecting any sub-
stantive conception of the state—thereby taking an intellectual step that was by no
means insignificant—Kelsen used his pure, rational, and formal concepts to destroy
any residual mythological and archaic element present within an archaic-substantive
state characterized by age-old ideologies, which also required de-substantivisation,
as occurred, for example, with justice. For Kelsen, in fact, mythological thinking,
and with it ideology, acted as a brake on the emancipation of a critical view of the
human sciences. Moreover, a normative conception of the state is only possible
against a conception of the world and of life that resulted in a de-substantivisation
from any substantive category, including in particular that of God.
If this interpretation is correct, we have to ask why Kelsen wanted to debunk all
metaphysics, all theology, all ideology, and all archaic sacredness. We can hypothe-
zise that his project was not only theoretical-philosophical but also ethical, because
in deconstructing the absolute values of absolute ideologies Kelsen in fact advanced
his own relativist view of values with the goal of promoting more peaceful and more
ethical cohabitation (the idea of civitas maxima), which was morally better. Thus
Kelsen did not want to engage in an absolute deconstruction of values, ethics and
morals, but attempted to change the viewpoint from which ethics, morals and values
were to be considered. He simply proposed another vision, a relativist vision of
values, ethics and morals (Bersier Ladavac 2008). This relativist vision was consis-
tent with the requirements of modern science and was in keeping with Kelsen’s
legal and philosophical construct. With his concise critique, Kelsen undoubtedly
sought to debunk and desacralize existing ethics and morals, not in order to destroy
but in order to propose different morals and ethics. The aim of this was to promote
tolerance and an improved social order, and probably also to promote interests
regarded as socially useful. Yet its purpose was not to guarantee a utopian well-
being—Kelsen naively defines it as happiness (Kelsen 1957)—for all subjects as an
ethics based on absolute values seeks to achieve. Kelsen thus relativized absolute
values, reducing them to relative values. In reducing values from an absolute level
to a relative level, Kelsen achieved an epistemological shift: from value absolutism
to gnoseological relativism.
This relativization of values also implied a different concept of the state, which
transformed it from a state of substance and sovereign into a legal norm. The con-
ceptual transformation of the state is perhaps the most deep-seated and revolution-
ary legal argument proposed by Kelsen. The traditional concept of the sovereign and
substantive state is superseded by the pure law, the pure norm according to the
canons of the Reine Rechtslehre. Consequently, this demetaphysicalization, desa-
cralization and demystification of the state (Herrera 1997, 2001: 13–28), also
entailed a metamorphosis in the concept of justice: from an absolute value, as an
expression of state and substance, it transformed into a category of positive law.
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 243
The Kelsenian ideological reduction of the state and of values was possible
because it was essentially based on a dual vision of reality. God on the one side and
the world on the other; the state on the one side and the law on the other; justice and
values on the one side and positive law on the other, thereby positivizing the former.
This is not a pure and simple cancellation of the archaic-ideological reality, but its
incorporation into a new gnoseological dimension; in other words, for Kelsen there
can be two parallel truths, as the science of nature is in any case a value, a positive
value which cannot be demonstrated by reason, just as its opposite—evil—is also
indemonstrable. In Kelsen’s view, the values of natural science appear on the same
plane as the formal values of legal science, there being no clear distinction within
them. However, Kelsen claims that it is necessary to distinguish between them. As
a positivist, Kelsen endeavors to make that distinction a typological division. For
example, the legal value of justice is different from the value of justice of traditional
ethics. Values are relativized and compared and contrasted with one another, with
the result that all values are broken down and reconstructed within one single plural-
ity. Agostino Carrino explains:
[T]his conscious departure from the classical systems, from all forms of thinking under
such systems, encapsulates the legal positivism of Kelsen and the very positivity of law,
which as such appears as the product and result of the “disintegrating” scientific method,
which separates, tears, divides and analyses what was once part of the universality of things,
the totality of the world, including also the world of values and their hierarchy (Carrino in
Kelsen 1989: XVI)
Kelsen’s position and his relativist theory of values is therefore a vast and detailed
proposal because it includes an infinite possibility of values and possible choices
and decisions. However, at the same time it is ideologically neutral in that it is able
to endorse a pluralist view of values and to promote weltweit the ideal of tolerance
within a society inspired by democratic ideals (Bobbio 1992). Within that perspec-
tive, the pure theory and its positivism may be regarded as “the highest and most
consistent point of a worldly rationalization, of a definitive immanentization of the
vital processes of man” (Carrino in Kelsen 1989: XII).
12.7 Conclusions
creation and absolute values. Inspired by democratic political ideals, Kelsen thus
considered the problem of dominance (Herrschaft), seeking to unmask the ideolo-
gies of dominance (Herrschaftsideologien), which had long dominated society
through positive law in order to implement the absolute norms of natural law (Cf.
Kelsen 1964, in particular the introduction by Ernst Topitsch). Analyzing the rea-
sons at the base of religious and social ideologies, which had endured through the
archaic depths of human consciousness, Kelsen had identified the role played by
myth, which on an ontological level does not admit any difference between nature
and society. In fact, the nature of mythological Weltanschauung had found its natu-
ral outlet in the social community (Gesellschaft), that is within a union between
human beings, an entity that must abide by a universal system of norms. Within this
social universe, Kelsen conceived of humans in an ethical and normative sense as
Normadressaten (ie, addressees of norms).
However, such a conception of the world did not enable Kelsen to draw a distinc-
tion between social and religious elements, and the society with which individuals
were confronted also represented divine authority, which may authorize and pro-
hibit. Natural law is naturally derived from the same dynamics, ie, the conception of
the universe as a social community dominated and regulated by a superior being.
Moreover, it was this superior being’s laws that held together the cosmos, the legal
community, in a regulated and ordered manner. These norms, which were posited by
God, reason or nature, had supreme status—that which is truly good and truly right,
over and above positive law. Kelsen thus highlighthed the close link between theo-
ries of natural and metaphysical absolutism.
His critique of ideology undoubtedly sought to deconstruct the use by positive
law of substantive norms of natural law which, according to the Ideologiekritik, was
regarded as a right law and compliant with justice. Moreover, it sought to debunk
the authority that defended positive law by asserting that it maintined the norms of
natural law, and of justice in particular, thus attempting to legitimize positive law
with reference to natural law. On this view, positive law and natural law authority
overlapped with each other.
Kelsen demonstrated with many examples drawn from history that natural law
ideologies were systems essentially based on empty formulae, which were used in
order to legitimize any legal and political order whatsoever, and above all in order
to legitimize structures of social domination. With his analyses of the mythical and
religious foundations of natural law ideologies, with his analyses of the metaphysics
of morals of Plato and Aristotle, along with his studies on the sociology of the
Seelenglauben, Kelsen directed his critique against the convictions that made up the
core of European spiritual life. The ideological critique revealed the weaknesses
within those ways of thinking. Kelsen sought above all to demonstrate in his work
Causality and Retribution (Kelsen 1941a) from 1946 that the social metaphysics of
the West was derived essentially from the sociomorphic Weltdeutung (interpretation
of the world) of primitive thought, from the conception of the world understood as
a vast social structure.
Paradoxically, Kelsen’s opponents objected that his relativism could legitimize
any legal, political or social order whatsoever—not only positive systems such as
democracy but also authoritarian, autocratic and other systems based on coercion.
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 245
This was an unfair charge against a man who, with the Reine Rechtslehre, had only
sought to give prominence to the Wertfreiheit (value freedom) of science by placing
it in the service of a liberal and humanitarian political ideal, theorizing a liberal and
democratic state as the maximum political expression of humanity. As Karl Larenz,
accusing Kelsen from his National Socialist perspective, put it, “It was objected that
the liberal-democratic theory of the state found its purest and most consistent
expression in Kelsen’s theory of law, and that as the ultimate conceptual pinnacle of
positivism it was in actual fact nothing other than an embodiment of spiritual alien-
ation (Überfremdung),” and could no longer conceptualize the metaphysical sense
of the concepts of national spirit (Larenz 1934: 11).
The role and function of Kelsen’s theoretical contribution to Austro-German—
and European—spiritual history is beyond doubt, including in particular the fact of
having raised the question of value relativism, which had far-reaching consequences
for the political and social philosophy of the twentieth century, contributing to dis-
enchantment with modernity and nihilism, value polytheism and the crisis of uni-
versalism (Bolaffi 2002: see in particular n.4, XXV). Although natural law doctrines
have always dreamt of being able to demonstrate their premises with precise cer-
tainty, those doctrines are self-defeating and hence untenable. However, if every-
thing is relative and nothing can be demonstrated, then the same too applies for
Kelsen, and we can consistently conclude with Werner Maihofer:
Nevertheless, the proposition that natural law ideologies cannot be proven must be placed
alongside the corresponding proposition for positivism. Positivism too has proved to
amount to an approach to science that is ultimately based on a value decision (the decision
of not wanting to make value judgments). The attempt to achieve objectively valid knowl-
edge in this manner reveals itself to be a pretext, which can only be formulated by con-
straining the concept of reality. On the contrary, all new knowledge obtained in this manner
as a continuation of exact natural science does not show the principal revealability, but the
essential immunity from disclosure of the deepest relations of being (Maihofer 1969: 113)
Acknowledgements This paper, including all quotations, was translated by Thomas Roberts,
Edinburgh, to whom I would like to express all my gratitude. I would like to express my gratitude
to Jeremy Telman for having organized such an interesting event about Hans Kelsen. I had the
opportunity not only to attend to the conference in Chicago but also to learn a lot more about
Kelsen. I am especially grateful to Carlo Nitsch and Jürgen Busch for the detailed information and
the many discussions we have had about the life of Hans Kelsen. These discussions proved to be
very useful in clarifying the difficult period of his career following his move from Europe to the
United States. I am also grateful to Stanley L. Paulson and Agostino Carrino whose long discus-
sions helped me to understand the complex thought of Hans Kelsen. However, I am especially
grateful to Morris L. Ghezzi for introducing me to the work of Hans Kelsen many years ago.
References
Austin, John. 1885. The Province of Jurisprudence Determined. All references are to the fifth and
last edition published in 1885, reprint in 1995. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Bersier Ladavac, Nicoletta. 2008. Recht, Moral und Gerechtigkeit bei Hans Kelsen. In Festschrift
für Walter Ott, ed. Sandra Hotz and Klaus Mathis, 19–52. Zürich-St. Gallen: Dike.
246 N. Ladavac
Bersier Ladavac, Nicoletta. 2013. Zur Interpretationstheorie von Hans Kelsen. Die Auslegungslehre
im Verhältnis zur Reinen Rechtslehre. In Gedenkschrift Robert Walter, ed. Clemens Jabloner,
Dieter Kolonovits, Gabriele Kuckso-Stadlmayer, Hans René Laurer, Heinz Mayer, and Rudolf
Thienel, 51–67. Wien: Manz.
Bobbio, Norberto. 1972. Giusnaturalismo e positivismo giuridico. Milano: Edizioni di Comunità.
Bobbio, Norberto. 1992. Diritto e potere. Saggi su Kelsen. Napoli: Edizioni Scientifiche Italiane.
Bolaffi, Angelo. 2002. Il crepuscolo della sovranità. Filosofia e politica nella Germania del
Novecento. Roma: Donzelli.
Dürrenmatt, Friedrich. 1991. Das Dürrenmatt Lesebuch. Zürich: Diogenes.
Herrera, Carlos Miguel. 1997. Théorie juridique et politique chez Hans Kelsen. Paris: Kimé.
Herrera, Carlos Miguel (ed.). 2001. Actualité de Kelsen en France. Paris: L. G. D. J.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Reine Rechtslehre. Einleitung in die rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik.
Leipzig/Wien: Franz Deuticke.
Kelsen, Hans. 1941a. Causality and Retribution. Philosophy of Science 8: 533–556. Reprint in:
What is Justice? Justice, Law, and Politics in the Mirror of Science. Collected Essays. Berkeley
and Los Angeles University of California Press: (1957, 533–556).
Kelsen, Hans. 1941b. The Law as a Specific Social Technique. University of Chicago Law Review
9: 75–97.
Kelsen, Hans. 1941c. The Pure Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence. Harvard Law Review
55: 44–70. Reprint in: What is Justice? Justice, Law, and Politics in the Mirror of Science.
Collected Essays. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press: (1957, 266–287).
Kelsen, Hans. 1942a. Platonic Love. Trans. G.B. Wilbur. The American Imago. A Psychoanalytical
Journal for the Arts and Sciences 3: 3–110.
Kelsen, Hans. 1942b. Law and Peace in International Relations. The Oliver Wendell Holmes
Lectures, 1940–41. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Italian Edition, Hans Kelsen,
Diritto e pace nelle relazioni internazionali, a cura di Carlo Nitsch, Milano, Giuffré 2009.
Kelsen, Hans. 1942c. Value Judgments in the Science of Law. Journal of Social Philosophy and
Jurisprudence 7: 312–333. Reprint in: What is Justice? Justice, Law, and Politics in the Mirror
of Science. Collected Essays. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press: (1957,
209–230).
Kelsen, Hans. 1943. Society and Nature. A Sociological Inquiry. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1944. Peace through Law. Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945. General Theory of Law and State. Trans. A. Wedberg. 20th Century Legal
Philosophy Series vol. 1. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1947. The Metamorphoses of the Idea of Justice. In Interpretations of Modern Legal
Philosophies. Essays in Honor of Roscoe Pound, ed. Roscoe Pound and Paul Lombard Sayre,
390–418. New York: Oxford University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1952. Principles of International Law. New York: Rinehart.
Kelsen, Hans. 1953. Was ist Gerechtigkeit? Wien: Franz Deuticke.
Kelsen, Hans. 1957. What is justice? Justice, law, and politics in the mirror of science. Collected
essays. Berkeley/Los Angeles: University of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. Reine Rechtslehre. Mit einem Anhang: Das Problem der Gerechtigkeit,
Zweite, völlig neu bearbeitet und erweiterte Auflage. Wien: Franz Deuticke.
Kelsen, Hans. 1964. Aufsätze zur Ideologiekritik (ed. by Ernst Topitsch). Neuwied am Rhein/
Berlin: Luchterhand.
Kelsen, Hans. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. (Without the appendix DasProblem der Gerechtigkeit).
Trans. by M. Knight, Second Revised and Enlarged German Edition. Berkeley/Los Angeles:
University of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1973. Essays in Legal and Moral Philosophy. Selected and Introduced by Ota
Weinberger. Trans. P. Heath. Dordrecht/Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Society.
Kelsen, Hans. 1979. Allgemeine Theorie der Normen. Edited from the estate of Hans Kelsen on
behalf of the Hans Kelsen-Institut by Kurt Ringhofer and Robert Walter. Wien: Manz.
12 Continuity of Kelsen’s Years in America 247
Kelsen, Hans. 1985. Die Illusion der Gerechtigkeit. Eine kritische Untersuchung der
Sozialphilosophie Platons. Edited from the estate of Hans Kelsen on behalf of the Hans Kelsen-
Institut by Kurt Ringhofer and Robert Walter. Wien: Manz.
Kelsen, Hans. 1989. L’anima e il diritto. Figure arcaiche della giustizia e concezione scientifica
del mondo. Trans. and ed. A. Carrino. Roma: Edizioni Lavoro.
Kelsen, Hans. 1991. General Theory of Norms. Trans. and edited by M. Hartney. Oxford: Clarendon
Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1998. Il problema della giustizia. Trans. and edited by M.G. Losano. Torino:
Einaudi.
Kelsen, Hans. 2006. Hans Kelsen im Selbstzeugnis. (ed. Matthias Jestaedt). Tübingen: Mohr
Siebeck.
Kelsen, Hans. 2009. Diritto e pace nelle relazioni internazionali. Le Oliver Wendell Holmes
Lectures, 1940–1941. Trans. and ed. C. Nitsch. Milano: Giuffré.
Kelsen, Hans. 2012. Secular Religion. A Polemic against the Misinterpretation of Modern Social
Philosophy. Science, and Politics as “New Religions.” Edited from the estate of Hans Kelsen
on behalf of the Hans Hans Kelsen-Institut by Robert Walter, Clemens Jabloner and Klaus
Zeleny. Wien/New York: Springer.
Larenz, Karl. 1934. Deutsche Rechtserneuerung und Rechtsphilosophie. Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr.
Losano, Mario G. 1981. L’interpretazione, ovvero come descrivere una prescrizione. In Forma e
realtà in Kelsen. Milano: Edizioni di Comunità.
Losano, Mario G. 2011. Gli anni americani di Hans Kelsen. Materiali per una storia della cultura
giuridica XLI(1): 253–258.
Maihofer, Werner (ed.). 1969. Ideologie und Recht. Frankfurt: Vittorio Klostermann.
Métall, Rudolf Alẚdar. 1969. Hans Kelsen, Leben und Werk. Wien: Franz Deuticke.
Nitsch, Carlo. 2009. In Hans Kelsen, Diritto e pace nelle relazioni internazionali. Milano: Giuffré.
Nitsch, Carlo. 2012. Diritto e forza nella comunità degli Stati: Studio su Hans Kelsen e la teoria
del diritto internazionale. Napoli: Satura.
Paulson, Stanley L. 1988. Die Rezeption Kelsens in Amerika. In: Reine Rechtslehre im Spiegel
ihrer Fortsetzer und Kritiker. Edited by Ota Weinberger and Werner Krawietz. Wien/New York:
Springer (179–202).
Ross, Alf. 1957. Review of What is justice? Justice, law and politics in the mirror of science.
Collected essays. In California Law Review 45(4): 564–570.
Telman, Jeremy D.A. 2010. A path not taken: Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law in the land of the
legal realists. In Hans Kelsen anderswo. Hans Kelsen Abroad. Der Einfluss der Reinen
Rechtslehre auf die Rechtstheorie in verschiedenen Ländern, Teil III, Schriftenreihe des Hans
Kelsen-Instituts 33, ed. Robert Walter, Clemens Jabloner, and Klaus Zeleny, 353–376. Wien:
Manz.
Treves, Renato. 1981. Sociologia del diritto e sociologia dell’idea di giustizia nel pensiero di Hans
Kelsen. In Sociologia del diritto, 7–24. Milano: Franco Angeli.
Tur, Richard, and William Twining (eds.). 1986. Essays on Kelsen. Oxford: Clarendon.
Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1989. Ein Reader. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp Verlag, 354.
Chapter 13
Pure Formalism? Kelsenian Interpretative
Theory between Textualism and Realism
Christoph Bezemek
As a graduate student in the United States I was quite surprised at how often I found
myself in a position defending my positivist theoretical approach. A surprise, it may
be argued, owed to a quite guileless view: “The faculty of Yale,” as Frank Easterbrook
stated in 1998, “little loves positivists” (Easterbrook 1998: 119). At least to a certain
extent, this proved to be true still 10 years later. I guess some of my professors had
fun bantering me that some of my remarks in class were owed to me being a positiv-
ist of the Kelsenian variety. And the discussions following such attributions proved
to be quite entertaining, particularly as I, an Austrian lawyer, trained in a Kelsenian
perspective on law, never really saw the problem.
Perhaps that was naïve, undertheorized even, given the tradition of the law school
I attended: Yale Law School, so closely related to the realist movement,1 was at least
not destined to be eager to embrace arguments suspicious of being based on Kelsen’s
pure theory of law (see, in particular, Telman 2010: 362); as legal positivism and
legal realism, so often described as opposing views in legal scholarship, would just
not match.2
1
See the classical account by Myres McDougal (1947). For the interesting background of the
establishment of legal realism at Yale in opposition to “formalism […] practiced most successfully
at Harvard” by former YLS Dean Harry Wellington, see Posner (1980: 1118–1119).
2
And, of course, the Kelsenian seems to be particularly opposed to realist ideas:
[P]ositivists, especially those of the Kelsen school, have adopted an extreme conceptual-
ism: Consistency of legal norms is for them the only criterion of legality once a sovereign
lawmaker is postulated. At the opposite pole of positivist jurisprudence, self-styled
American legal realists and many adherents of the Critical Legal Studies movement treat
C. Bezemek (*)
WU (IOER), Welthandelsplatz 1, D3, 1020 Vienna, Austria
e-mail: [email protected]
Thus, many of my assigned readings implied that things were not as simple as I
thought. And the consequences of positivist deficiency, it seemed, were crucial; in
particular with regard to method: A formalist, or even “hyperformalist” theory, posi-
tivism, it was suggested in one of my favorite assigned readings, was destined to
entail a “hypertextualist” approach to interpretation.3
Such assumptions, to borrow from Frederick Schauer, are generally based on the
following consideration:
Formalism merges into ruleness, and both are inextricably intertwined with literalism, i.e.,
the willingness to make decisions according to the literal meaning of the words or phrases
or sentences or paragraphs on a printed page, even if the consequences of that decision
seem either to frustrate the purpose behind those words or to diverge significantly from
what the decisionmaker thinks—the rule aside—should be done. (Schauer 1988: 538)
legal rules as rationalizations of the empirical behavior of legal officials and find the sources
of that behavior in economic, political, and other non-legal factors. (Berman 1998: 781)
(footnote omitted)
See, for further references of the wide spread claim that positivism and realism are opposing
theories, Leiter (2001).
3
Ackerman (1998: 92): “[M]y hypertextualist interlocutor builds on a jurisprudential school that
has been (more or less) dominant throughout the twentieth century: legal positivism.”
4
Hardly a novel claim, of course. See, ie, Gardner (2001: 518) or Schauer (1996: 32).
5
See, for example, Ely (1980: 1): “‘interpretivism’ […] indicating that judges deciding constitu-
tional cases should confine themselves to enforcing norms that are stated or clearly implicit in the
written Constitution.” Continuing in the annotation to this remark: “Interpretivism is about the
same thing as positivism.”
6
Dworkin states:
Could the advocate of the ‘text’ do better by appealing, not to political theory, but to the
concept of law? None of the standing philosophical theories of law supplies the necessary
arguments. Not even positivist theories, which seem the most likely. Neither Bentham’s nor
Austin’s theory of positivism will do. Nor even Kelsen’s (Dworkin 1985: 37).
A belief held not only in U.S. academia of course—see, for example, Brugger (1994: 405
n.22): “Positivism, formalism, and textualism form the main elements of Begriffsjurisprudenz and
Hans Kelsen’s Reine Rechtslehre.” For further references as to the allegation in European aca-
demia that Kelsen’s theory of law was particularly formalist, see Paulson (2005: 213–214).
13 Pure Formalism? 251
The question that needs to be raised in order to address the problems outlined above
in the first place is, of course: What does the appreciation of a lawyer or a method
as “formalist” actually mean? It hardly comes as surprise that it is far from simple
to answer this, as the term “formalism does not really have an identity of its own”
(Sebok 1998: 57). It does rather exist as a target to be attacked than a goal to be
achieved. It has opponents rather than proponents.7 And it thus, generally speaking,
serves as an umbrella term for a plurality of intermingled reproaches, differing,
while not in their core, still at least on their fringe—and quite a fringe that is8:
“Formalist,” Richard Posner (1986” 180–181) found nearly 30 years ago, “can
mean narrow, conservative, hypocritical, resistant to change, casuistic, descriptively
inaccurate (that is, ‘unrealistic’ in the ordinary-language sense of the word), ivory-
towered, fallacious, callow, authoritarian—but also,” focusing on the political stance
underlying a formalist position,9 “rigorous, modest, reasoned, faithful, self-denying,
restrained.”
In any case: “[a]ccording to the Realists,” Jeremy Telman (2010: 361) tells us,
“[f]ormalist legal theorists […] believed that judges mechanically applied the law
without reference to their own policy preferences or ideological beliefs.”10 Still it
does obviously come in nuances: “At its most extreme,” so Jim Chen (1995: 1270)
stipulates, “formalist dogma posits that identifying all of the ‘established’ canons of
interpretation and subjecting them to brute Euclidian logic will yield one and only
one answer to every legal problem.” Finally, “Pure Formalists,” to refer back to the
title of this essay, as Burt Neuborne (1992: 421) explains, “view the judicial system
as if it were a giant syllogism machine with a determinate, externally-mandated
legal rule supplying the major premise, and objectively ‘true’ pre-existing facts pro-
viding the minor premise.”
It may suffice to leave it with those impressions that allow for a general idea of
the direction the diverse criticism of the formalist approach takes. Against that back-
drop it seems preferable, rather than to give another definition of formalism, to sum
up by again quoting Frederick Schauer’s approximation to the problem (1988: 510):
“whatever formalism [actually] is, it is not good.” I think all the critics of a formalist
7
Even though there obviously are, (few) “self-described formalists in America today” (Leiter
2010: 131).
8
To give just a few examples of the variety of definition in legal scholarship: While Malkan (1998,
1393) holds that “formalism usually refers to the claim that wellcrafted rules embodied in authori-
tative texts will constrain the choice of an impartial decisionmaker” (For a quite similar apprecia-
tion, see, ie, Eskridge 1990: 646); “Formalism,” according to Burton (2007: 3), “insists that legal
reasoning should determine all specific actions required by the law based only on objective facts,
unambiguous rules, and logic.” According to Strauss (1987: 488) the formalist approach is thus
essentially anti-functionalist. For a further display of a wide number of different accounts of for-
malism, see Leiter (1999: 1144–1145) or Schauer (1988: 510).
9
For these arguments, see Hayek (1944: 117–123).
10
On this approach, see in particular Kennedy (1973: 359).
252 C. Bezemek
approach to legal interpretation can agree on that, whatever their particular position
or quarrel might be. In fact, one has to add, it is so not good, that even those authors
like Ernest Weinrib, who try to defend an approach closer to one or another defini-
tion of formalism, feel obliged to justify their endeavor as “not merely a perverse
theoretical indulgence” (Weinrib 1988: 951).
Fighting formalism, broad coalitions had been formed in the first half of the
twentieth century to tackle legal positivism: “Both the natural lawyer and the realist
said they disavowed legal positivism” (Sebok 1995: 2068). Little one has to wonder
then, why even non-realist academics like Morris Cohen (1927: 237–38) already
back in 1927 sneered at “formalists like Kelsen” and their “fiction that the law is a
complete and closed system, and that judges and jurists are mere automata to record
its will or phonographs to pronounce its provisions.” And little one has to wonder
then, why “‘Formalism’ is, like ‘Positivism’ frequently used as an ephithet” (Leiter
1999: 1144).
One has to wonder, however, how all this adds up: H.L.A. Hart dedicated a whole
chapter of his seminal Concept of Law to battle formalist simplifications (Hart 1961:
121–150),11 which seems strange, not only because Hart is arguably the most impor-
tant representative of legal positivism in the English-speaking world, not only
because Hart evidently drew on Kelsenian thought (see, ie, Summers 1963: 631),
but also because Kelsen himself on the other hand, openly remarked that he agreed
with Hart’s general position (Hart 1963: 710).
This is quite confusing, taking into account what has been stated before: How
can positivism join the choir of critics of formalist approaches and at the same time
stand accused of having forged the archetype of formalism?
But is Kelsen’s pure theory of law actually a formalistic theory? And does that
make Kelsen actually a formalist according to the definition provided above? The
correct answer needs to be twofold: yes, of course, but no. Such an ominous state-
ment evidently is in need of specification.
Let us start with the affirmative part of the answer. When Ota Weinberger (1982: 31)
weighed, as the title of the essay here referred to states, “the Pros and Cons of the
Pure Theory of Law” back in 1979, he described its method as “anti-ideological and
formalistic”; candidly, one may add, as this appraisal did not refer to the allegations
sketched above nor to the “methods” of interpretation some critics construe from
them.
11
See in particular Hart’s critique: “The vice known to legal theory as formalism or conceptualism
consists in an attitude to verbally formulated rules which both seeks to disguise and minimize the
need for […] choice, once the general rule has been laid down” (Hart 1961: 126). Also see Hart
(1958: 606–615).
13 Pure Formalism? 253
Jeremy Telman (2008: 17–18) surely is correct when he observes that against
that backdrop Kelsen’s “legal positivism could only have struck his Legal Realist
colleagues as a return to the naïve formalism of […] previous generations.”15 But it
becomes clearer now that the ample and variant use of the term “formalism” may be
one of the chief causes for some confusion,16 as “[i]t has to be ascertained whether
the derogatory value judgment implied in the claim of formalism is directed at the
conception of law and consequently against a theory of law or whether this claim is
intended to apply to the generation of law, its creation and evolution, ie, legal prac-
tice.” (Kelsen 1929: 1723).
Depending on the perspective, the allegation that the pure theory of law takes a
formal/formalist/formalistic approach is either a presumably unwarranted accusa-
tion or a truism, both of which—this is important to note—are not necessarily con-
nected to one another. The formalism Kelsen talks about is a necessary precondition
to define the object of his pure theory, “confining jurisprudence to a structural anal-
ysis of positive law” (Kelsen 1961: XV). Kelsen argues in favor of a formalistic
12
For a short account focusing on this “formalistic” character, see Stewart (1990: 273).
13
See, for a more recent account, Kammerhofer (2011): 147–148).
14
My—quite literal—translation. Kelsen continues by referring verbatim to Hermann Cohen
(1922, 587): “Nur das Formale ist sachlich[;] je formaler eine Methodik ist, desto sachlicher kann
sie werden. Und je sachlicher in der ganzen Tiefe der Sache ein Problem formuliert wird, desto
formaler muß es fundamentiert sein.” [Only what is formal is objective; the more formal a method,
the more objective it can be. And the more objective a problem is defined in its depth, the more
formal it has to be founded]. Kelsen then continues by stating: “Whoever does not grasp that, does
not know what science is about.” For the second essay mentioned above, see Kelsen (1953: 512).
15
For the historical background of this claim, see Tamaha (2010: 60–62).
16
My—quite literal—translation.
254 C. Bezemek
theory of law, not a formalist theory of legal interpretation.17 His approach is about
formalizing the concept of law, not its content (see Schreier 1927: III). Thus,
because, as Kelsen (1929: 1723) explicitly stated, “the allegation of formalism as a
negative value judgment is directed at some specific legal practice,”18 “‘[f]ormalism’
can be no objection to a general theory of law, although, as a matter of fact, it is
frequently brought forward against the Pure Theory of Law.” (Kelsen 1966: 4).
This argument, however, has another edge: “Realism,” as Brian Leiter (2001:
301) pointed out, itself “a […] theory of adjudication,”19 does not per se have to be
an objection to a general theory of the Kelsenian variety: “[T]he typical interest of
a genuine legal positivist is in logic and form, while the interest of the legal realists
in these aspects of law is in a degree incidental to their interest in the function,
operation, and consequences or, in other words, the substance, of law.” (Yntema
1941: 1164).
17
Which is, of course, generally true for the relation of formalism and positivism—see, for exam-
ple, Leiter (1999: 1150) “Positivism is a theory of law, while formalism is a theory of
adjudication.”
18
My translation. Continuing: “Judgments or decisions by administrative bodies are referred to as
formalist in order to point to some specific deficiency” [my translation], showing quite the same
understanding as Posner or Schauer quoted above. For [nearly] the identical remark, see Kelsen
(1953: 511).
19
Also see Jeremy Telman (2013: 6).
20
Kelsen, however, did later consider some of his remarks in that preface as “unfortunate” [“ver-
unglückt”] (Kelsen 1929: 1725).
21
In the essay mentioned above, however, Kelsen indicated that the “Pure Theory of Law had […]
until recently not commented on the problem of interpretation” [my translation] (Kelsen 1929:
1725). For this “recent comment,” Kelsen refers to Fritz Schreier (1927: III), who also points to the
fact “that the Vienna School had disregarded the problems of interpretation to some extent” [my
translation]. It seems worth noting that unlike Schreier (Schreier 1927: 6), Kelsen does not men-
tion Adolf Merkl, Zum Interpretationsproblem, Grünhutsche Zeitschrift für das Privat- und
Öffentliche Recht der Gegenwart 1916, 535, even though later scholarship on this question (see
Mayer 1992: 63 or Günther Winkler 1990: 208) treats this essay as starting point of the pure theo-
ry’s stance on interpretation.
13 Pure Formalism? 255
had not yet published his thoughts on interpretation.22 Still, he remarks “the Pure
Theory of Law [had] never opposed any of the possible methods of interpretation in
the first place[; while at the same time] in no way arguments in favor of a formalist
interpretation may be derived from the Pure Theory of Law.” (Kelsen 1929: 1725).
Examined from the angle of his personal credibility—already at that time this
claim is quite impressively corroborated by the way Kelsen acted as a member of
the Austrian Constitutional Court23 as well as by his doctrinal work24—Kelsen was
emphatically not a representative of a dreary as well as short-witted mechanical
approach to legal problems.25
And this is clearly reflected in his theoretical encounters with the problem of
legal interpretation published from 1934.26 Not to be misunderstood, Kelsen never
actually did expound a theory of interpretation,27 which scholars as intimately
acquainted with his work as Robert Walter (1983: 189–190) or Stanley Paulson
(1990: 136, 137) already emphasized (also see Thaler 1982: 18 n.38 or Mayer 1992:
61).28 What Kelsen did was (merely) to point at the imponderabilia of the result of
interpretation, which are—at least to a certain extent—inevitable according to his
opinion.29
In order to be able to relate to this position, it is important to see that Kelsen’s
approach to interpretation is essentially based on the hierarchical perception of the
legal system (see Bersier 2013: 53) originally developed by Adolf J. Merkl (1931:
252–294). “Interpretation,” Kelsen (1934: 9) defines against this background, “is an
intellectual activity accompanying the law-creating process as it moves from a
22
Which he published separately for the first time 1934. For Kelsen’s prior “phase on interpreta-
tion,” see Paulson (1990: 141–143).
23
Where he at one point was even defamed to act based on political motives—see Christian
Neschwara (2005: 368) which, albeit quite simply put, eventually led to Kelsen not being re-
appointed to the Constitutional Court after the Constitutional reform of 1929 (BGBl 392/1929,
393/1929) in 1930. Id. at 374–382.
24
To link both aspects of his professional life at that time (cf. the prior note), see, for example,
Kelsen’s defense of the Court’s approach in a highly controversial question of jurisdiction (Kelsen
1928a: 105–110, 1928b: 583–599).
25
To give just one example that proved to be particularly important for Austrian Constitutional
doctrine: It was Hans Kelsen who drafted the Constitutional Court’s judgment introducing the non-
delegation doctrine to Austrian Constitutional Law (VfSlg 176/1923)—(Öhlinger 2008). The
wording of Article 18 § 1, however, on which this judgment is based does not state any require-
ments to be observed by the legislator when providing a legal foundation of administrative action
(also the earlier commentary by Kelsen, Fröhlich and Merkl (1922: 85) does not make any refer-
ence to such an assessment).
26
These—generally speaking—do not differ significantly regarding their core assessment as to the
“achievement potential” of legal interpretation (see Christoph Schwaighofer 1986: 233).
27
Kelsen, overall, gave limited attention to the problem of interpretation as such (see Jackson 1985:
88 with further references).
28
Which makes it pointless to elaborate on this here any further.
29
This is not necessarily common to any positivist theory of law (see Leiter 1999: 1150).
256 C. Bezemek
higher level of the hierarchical structure to the lower level governed by this higher
level.”30
This may be confusing, at least at first glance, given the effort made in this essay
to argue in favor of the non-formalist character of a Kelsenian view of interpreta-
tion, as to perceive interpretation embedded in this hierarchical system would
indeed indicate a mere deductive process of legal reasoning typically proclaimed
“formalist,”31; applying law “all the way down” as Elena Kagan put it during her
confirmation hearings (see Leiter 2010: 128 and n.76).
However, this is not Kelsen’s thinking. He explains:
[t]he relation between a higher and a lower level of the legal system—as between constitu-
tion and statute, or between statute and judicial decision—is a relation of determining or
binding. The higher-level norm governs the act whereby the lower-level norm is created.
[…] This determination, however, is never complete, for a norm cannot be binding with
respect to every detail of the act putting it into practice. (Kelsen 1990: 127–128)
Indeterminacy is therefore inevitable (Grimm 1982: 151; also see Paulson 1990:
143); according to Kelsen “no legal decision is completely determined by the law”
(see Schauer 2004: 1949). This, of course, may be intended by the lawmaker in the
first place, granting discretion to whomever is to act based on his commands. Putting
that aside, however, indeterminacy is owed to “the ambiguity of a word or a phrase
used in expressing the norm,” Kelsen (1990: 129) argues closely related to what
H.L.A. Hart (1961: 124–125) should term later as the “open texture [as a general
feature of human] language.”32
In addition to that, Kelsen continues (1990: 129–130), “discrepancies between
the linguistic expression of the form and the will of the norm-issuing authority are
to be assumed,” as “[i]n spite of every effort, traditional jurisprudence has not yet
found an objectively plausible way to settle the conflict between will and the expres-
sion of will. Every method of interpretation developed thus far invariably leads
merely to a possible result, never to a single correct result.”33
One has not to wonder that theorists of the Dworkinian kind have their quarrel
with such statements, particularly with regard to Kelsen’s anticipative rejection of
the right answer thesis. One has to wonder, however, why such statements should
necessarily contravene realist thought, or at least some of its adepts of the less
extreme kind; we shall get back to that after having finished the survey of Kelsen’s
thoughts on interpretation:
Given this predicament the “result [of interpretation],” so Kelsen continues:
can only be the discovery of the frame that the norm to be interpreted represents and, within
this frame, the cognition of several possibilities for implementation. Interpreting a statute,
30
I will rely on and refer to the English translation by Bonnie Litschewski Paulson and Stanley
L. Paulson (1990: 127–135) unless explicitly stated otherwise. Id. at 127.
31
For the perception of “formalism” as a mere process of legal deduction, see Sebok (1998:
57–112).
32
For a deeper discussion, see, ie, Brian Bix (1991: 51–72).
33
Lastly, to give a full account, Kelsen argues, “purportedly valid norms [may] contradict one
another wholly or in part” (Kelsen 1990: 129–130).
13 Pure Formalism? 257
then, leads not necessarily to a single decision as the only correct decision but possibly to
several decisions, all of them of equal standing measured solely against the norm to be
applied, even if only a single one of them becomes, in the act of the judicial decision, posi-
tive law. That a judicial decision is based on a statute means in truth only that the decision
stays within the frame the statute represents, means only that the decision is one of the
individual norms possible within the frame of the general norm, not that it is the only indi-
vidual norm possible (Kelsen 1990: 129–130).
To be clear, the question whether the frame referred to has to or can be defined in
the first place is subject to dispute,34 even among his followers (Ringhofer 1971:
205; Paulson 1990: 151; Mayer 1992: 65–67; also see Jackson 1985: 86–88). It is
not for this essay to address the rigor of Kelsen’s approach.35 For more important are
the conclusions he draws from it, emphasizing that:
[f]rom the standpoint of […] positive law […] there is no criterion on the basis of which one
of the possibilities given within the frame of the norm to be applied could be favored over
the other possibilities. In terms of […] positive law, there is simply no method according to
which only one of the several readings of a norm could be distinguished as “correct”—
assuming, of course, that several readings of the meaning of the norm are possible in the
context of all other norms of the statute or of the legal system (Kelsen 1990: 130).
34
For more recent encounters, see, for example, Lindahl (2003: 769) or Kennedy (2007: 296).
35
It is important to note, however, that in his later writings on interpretation Kelsen emphasized
that in cases of authentic interpretation (ie interpretation by a law applying organ—see, for exam-
ple, Kelsen (1960: 351)), norms—albeit cognitively outside the frame—are to be considered valid;
also see Kelsen 1950: xv—for this argument see Paulson’s (1990: 151–152) analysis.
Taking this into account, of course, Richard Posner (2003: 270) is correct in stating that in
Kelsen’s thought “law does not dictate the outcome of judicial decisions.” See, for an earlier ver-
sion of this argument, Posner (2001: 23) adding: “provided only the judge does not stay outside the
boundaries of his jurisdiction. […] He may be mistaken, but he is not lawless.”
36
This was particularly emphasized by Kurt Ringhofer (1971: 205) who argued that “in order to
interpret the norm its meaning must not be clear from the very outset.” [my translation]
It is, however, not certain (or rather, far from certain) that Kelsen adhered to the principle “in
claris non fit interpretatio.” For this maxim, see Meder (2004: 17–21) or Tosato (2000: 157 n.94).
For background and origin, see Masuelli (2002: 402).
258 C. Bezemek
distance from the claim he was a formalist, but also quite unfair. Kelsen—to draw
from Feyerabend (2010)—was not “Against Method,” and he would agree, it is to
be assumed (see in particular Walter 1983: 191), that there are indeed “easy cases”
(see Schauer 1985).
What he did was to emphasize the limited capacity of legal methodology when
evaluated by a standard of cognition (Walter 1990: 51–52)—particularly so by tak-
ing a stand against embellishing interpretative arguments as focal point of objective
discovery thereby often disguising mere political preferences:
The conservative professor—strictly scientific, of course—deduces from the concept of the
state that democracy is impossible and some kind of fascism or “corporate state” is neces-
sitated; while the revolutionary Marxist argues—based on some equally “scientific” social-
ism—that the law of causality is to bring about the dictatorship of the proletariat.” (Kelsen
1929: 1724).37
If, however, “[t]he most important of Realism’s multiple facets is its denial of [the]
traditional [formalist] view” (Schauer 2013: 754), not only is Kelsen’s pure theory
of law not in conflict with aim and scope of core arguments of the forerunners and
members of the legal realist movement,38 his views on interpretation and on what
may be achieved by its means at some point take quite the same direction as their
critique.
Of course this claim is bold as well as it is naïve, as most bold claims are, particu-
larly because—as common wisdom has it—the term “Realism” is as much unde-
fined, maybe even undefinable as the term “Formalism” proved to be.39 It is perhaps
even more so due to the fact that realism not only had opponents but—albeit quite
diverse —proponents as well.40 And, of course, as we have seen, Kelsen would not
concur with the more extreme forms of rule-skepticism41; the claim, as Hart (1961:
133) describes it, “that talk of rules is a myth.” He would not say that the outcome
37
My translation. Hart’s argument, analyzing the allegation of “formalism” takes the same direc-
tion. (Hart 1958: 611).
38
As generally “[t]he pure theory of law by no means denies the validity of […] sociological juris-
prudence” (Kelsen (1941: 52).
39
See, for the classical account, Llewellyn (1931).
40
Citing some of the more common definitions, Brian Leiter (1997: 267–268).
41
Which—as Brian Leiter (2001: 294) explains—few realists would in the first place.
13 Pure Formalism? 259
of a case may merely depended on “what the judge had for breakfast,”42 even though
it seems that nobody, not even Jerome Frank,43 really assumed that.44
But, as we have seen, the critical view of how adjudication actually works,
beyond what has been the formalist caricature, common to the Realist movement
(Leiter 1999: 1147), is not alien to Kelsen. He would easily agree with Oliver
Wendell Holmes that “general propositions do not decide concrete cases” (Lochner
v. New York, 198 U.S. 45, 76 (1906) (Holmes, J., dissenting)—judges do, Kelsen
would submit,45 by their decisions effecting what he should term “authentic inter-
pretation” in his later work (see, in particular, Kelsen 1960: 351–352). And Kelsen
would agree that in adjudicating, there is indeed “a concealed half conscious battle
on the question of legislative policy” that cannot “be settled deductively” (Holmes
1997: 999). “Even the judge,” Kelsen would argue:
creates law, even he is relatively free in his capacity.[…] In applying a statute, there may
well be room for cognitive activity beyond discovering the frame within which the act of
application is to be confined; this is not cognition of the positive law, however, but cognition
of other norms that can now make their way into the law-creating process, the norms,
namely, of morality, of justice—social value judgments customarily characterized with the
catch-phrases “welfare of the people,” “public interest,” “progress.” and the like (Kelsen
1990: 131).
42
For a quasi-empirical take on this question, see Kozinski (1996): 993).
43
See, however, Jerome Frank’s statement:
Out of my own experience as a trial lawyer, I can testify that a trial judge, because of over-
eating at lunch may be so somnolent in the afternoon court-session that he fails to hear an
important item of testimony and so disregards it when deciding the case. “The hungry
judges soon the sentence sign, And wretches hang that juryman may dine,” wrote Pope.
Dickens’ lovers well remember Perker’s advice to Pickwick: “A good, contented, well-
breakfasted juryman, is a capital thing to get hold of. Discontented or hungry jurymen, my
dear sir, always find for the plaintiff.” (Frank 1973: 162)
44
However, empirical evidence suggests that there is indeed some truth to this claim (see Danziger
et al. 2011: 6889–6892).
45
Even though judges, of course, would typically present the result as conclusion based on a
“sophisticated formalist” manner (Brian Leiter 2010: 112).
260 C. Bezemek
considers “the Pure Theory of Law [was] not in conflict with the German Free Law
Movement (Freirechtsschule),”46 a movement related to (or rather, preceding) legal
realism (see Herget and Wallace 1987). In fact, Fritz Schreier (1927) dedicated a
whole book to the effort to realign the Free Law Movement and the pure theory of
law, in order to complement one with the other. Kelsen (1929: 1725) approved.
All this is not to say that Kelsenian thinking and Realism are to be natural allies,
they may be to some extent—possibly, to quote Frederick Schauer once more, in a
rather “tamed version” (Schauer 2013: 774). They surely don’t have to.
It is to say, however, that Kelsen shared many of the core concerns articulated by
members of the realist movement and that the pure theory of law does provide the
structure to act on them.47 Let us not forget that, even if not natural allies, legal real-
ism and legal positivism were fighting a common enemy of the formalist kind: “The
view that interpretation is cognition of the positive law, and as such is a way of
deriving new norms from prevailing norms,” so Kelsen (1990: 132) explains, “is the
foundation of the so-called jurisprudence of concepts (Begriffsjurisprudenz), which
the Pure Theory of Law also rejects. […] The illusion of legal certainty is what
traditional legal theory, wittingly or not, is striving to maintain.”
Kelsen, however, sure was not.
References
46
For some of the core writings of the Free Law Movement, see Rümelin (1891) or Ehrlich (1903).
47
On the compatibility of Legal Positivism and Legal Realism in general, see Brian Leiter (2001:
278).
13 Pure Formalism? 261
Chen, Jim. 1995. Law as a species of language acquistition. Washington Law Quarterly 73:
1263–1309.
Cohen, Hermann. 1922. System der Philosophie Vol. I. In Logik der Reinen Erkenntnis, 3rd ed.
Berlin: Cassirer.
Cohen, Morris. 1927. Positivism and the limits of idealism in the law. Columbia Law Review 27:
237–250.
Danziger, Shai, Jonathan Levav, and Liora Avnaim-Pesso. 2011. Extraneous factors in judicial
decisions. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America
108: 6889–6892.
Dworkin, Ronald. 1985. A matter of principle. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Easterbrook, Frank. 1998. Textualism and the dead hand. George Washington Law Review 66:
1119–1126.
Ehrlich, Eugen. 1903. Freie Rechtsfindung und freie Rechtswissenschaft (Reprint 1973). Leipzig:
Scientia.
Ely, John Hart. 1980. Democracy and distrust. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Eskridge, William. 1990. The new textualism. UCLA Law Review 37: 621–691.
Feyerabend, Paul. 2010. Against method, 4th ed. London: Verso.
Frank, Jerome. 1973. Courts on trial, 3rd ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gardner, John. 2001. Legal positivism: 5½ myths. American Journal of Jurisprudence 46:
199–227.
Grimm, Dieter. 1982. Zum Verhältnis von Interpretationslehre. Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit und
Demokratieprinzip bei Kelsen, Rechtstheorie Beiheft 4: 149–157.
Hart, H.L.A. 1958. Positivism and the separation of law and morals. Harvard Law Review 71:
593–629.
Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hart, H.L.A. 1963. Kelsen visited. UCLA Law Review 10: 709–728.
Hayek, F.A. 1944. The road to serfdom. Ed. Bruce Caldwell 2007. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Herget, James, and Stephen Wallace. 1987. The German free law movement as the source of
American legal realism. Virginia Law Review 73: 399–455.
Holmes Jr., Oliver Wendell. 1997. The path of the law (Reprint). Harvard Law Review 110:
991–1009.
Jackson, B.S. 1985. Kelsen between formalism and realism. The Liverpool Law Review 7: 79–93.
Kammerhofer, Jörg. 2011. Hans Kelsen’s place in international legal theory. In Research handbook
on the theory and history of international law, ed. Alexander Orakhelashvili, 143–167.
Northhampton: Edward Elgar Publishing.
Kelsen, Hans. 1911. Hauptprobleme der Staatsrechtslehre entwickelt aus der Lehre vom
Rechtssatze. Tübingen: Mohr.
Kelsen, Hans. 1928a. Der Begriff des Kompetenzkonfliktes nach geltendem öffentlichem Recht.
Juristische Blätter 57: 105–110.
Kelsen, Hans. 1928b. Zum Begriff des Kompetenzkonfliktes. Zeitschrift für Öffentliches Recht 7:
583–599.
Kelsen, Hans. 1929. Juristischer Formalismus und reine Rechtslehre. Juristische Wochenschrift 58:
1723–1726.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Zur Theorie der Interpretation. Internationale Zeitschrift für Theorie des
Rechts 8:9–17. Trans. B.L. Paulson & S.L. Paulson 1990. On the Theory of Interpretation.
Legal Studies 10:127–135.
Kelsen, Hans. 1941. The pure theory of law and analytical jurisprudence. Harvard Law Review 55:
44–70.
Kelsen, Hans. 1950. The law of the United Nations. New York: Praeger.
Kelsen, Hans. 1953. Was ist die Reine Rechtslehre? In Demokratie und Rechtsstaat. Festgabe zum
60. Geburtstag von Zaccaria Giacometti, 143–162. Zürich: Polygraphischer Verlag.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. Reine Rechtslehre (2d ed—Reprint 2000). Vienna: Verlag Österreich.
262 C. Bezemek
Kelsen, Hans. 1961. General theory of law and state. New York: Russel & Russel.
Kelsen, Hans. 1966. On the pure theory of law. Israel Law Review 1: 1–7.
Kelsen, Hans, Georg Fröhlich, and Adolf Merkl. 1922. Die Bundesverfassung vom 1. Oktober
1920. Vienna: Deuticke.
Kennedy, Duncan. 1973. Legal formality. Journal of Legal Studies 2: 351–398.
Kennedy, Duncan. 2007. A left phenomenological critique of the Hart/Kelsen theory of legal inter-
pretation. Kritische Justiz, Vierteljahresschrift für Recht und Politik 3: 296–305.
Kozinski, Alex. 1996. What I ate for breakfast and other mysteries of judicial decision making.
Loyola of Los Angeles Law Review 26: 993–999.
Leiter, Brian. 1997. Rethinking legal realism: Toward a naturalized jurisprudence. Texas Law
Review 76: 267–315.
Leiter, Brian. 1999. Positivism, formalism, realism. Columbia Law Review 99: 1138–1164.
Leiter, Brian. 2001. Legal realism and legal positivism reconsidered. Ethics 111: 278–301.
Leiter, Brian. 2010. Legal formalism and legal realism: What is the issue? Legal Theory 16:
111–133.
Lindahl, Hans. 2003. Dialectic and revolution: Confronting Kelsen and Gadamer on legal interpre-
tation. Cardozo Law Review 24: 769–798.
Llewellyn, Karl. 1931. Some realism about realism—Responding to Dean Pound. Harvard Law
Review 44: 1222–1264.
Llewellyn, Karl. 1950. Remarks on the theory of appellate decision and the rules and canons about
statutes are to be construed. Vanderbilt Law Review 3: 395–406.
Llewellyn, Karl. 2011. The theory of rules. Ed. Frederick Schauer. Chicago: The University of
Chicago Press.
Malkan, Jeffrey. 1998. Literary formalism, legal positivism. Cardozo Law Review 19:
1393–1439.
Masuelli, Saverio. 2002. In claris non fit interpretatio‘—Alle Origini del brocardo’. Rivista di
Diritto Romano 2: 401–424.
Mayer, Heinz. 1992. Die Interpretationstheorie der Reinen Rechtslehre. In Schwerpunkte der
Reinen Rechtslehre, ed. Walter Robert, 61–70. Wien: Manz.
McDougal, Myres. 1947. The law school of the future: From legal realism to policy science in the
world community. The Yale Law Journal 56: 1345–1355.
Meder, Stephan. 2004. Mißverstehen und Verstehen—Savignys Grundlegung der juristischen
Hermeneutik. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Merkl, Adolf. 1916. Zum Interpretationsproblem. Grünhutsche Zeitschrift für das Privat- und
Öffentliche Recht der Gegenwart 42: 535–556.
Merkl, Adolf. 1931. Prolegomena einer Theorie des rechtlichen Stufenbaues. In Festschrift für
Hans Kelsen zum 50. Geburtstag, 252–294. Vienna: Springer.
Neschwara, Christian. 2005. Kelsen als Verfassungsrichter. Seine Rolle in der Dispensehen-
Kontroverse. In Hans Kelsen—Staatsrechtler und Rechtstheoretiker des 20. Jahrhunderts, ed.
Stanley L. Paulson and Michael Stolleis, 353–384. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Neuborne, Burt. 1992. Of sausage factories and syllogism machines: Formalism, realism, and
exclusionary selection techniques. N.Y.U Law Review 67: 419–450.
Öhlinger, Theo. 1978. Bemerkungen zur Verfassungsdogmatik. Zeitschrift für Verkehrsrecht 23:
257–261.
Öhlinger, Theo. 2008. Hans Kelsen—Vater der österreichischen Bundesverfassung? In Festschrift
für Wilhelm Brauneder zum 65. Geburtstag, 407–424. Vienna: Manz.
Paulson, Stanley L. 1990. Kelsen on legal interpretation. Legal Studies 10: 136–152.
Paulson, Stanley L. 2005. Zwei radikale Objektivierungsprogramme in der Rechtslehre Hans
Kelsens. In Hans Kelsen—Staatsrechtler und Rechtstheoretiker des 20. Jahrhunderts, ed.
Stanley L. Paulson and Michael Stolleis, 191–220. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck.
Posner, Richard. 1980. The present situation in legal scholarship. The Yale Law Journal 90:
1113–1130.
Posner, Richard. 1986. Legal formalism, legal realism, and the interpretation of statutes and the
Constitution. Case Western Reserve Law Review 37: 179–217.
13 Pure Formalism? 263
Posner, Richard. 2001. Kelsen, Hayek, and the economic analysis of law. Lecture at the
XVIII. Annual meeting of the European Association of Law and Economics in Vienna, Sept 14.
Posner, Richard. 2003. Law, pragmatism, and democracy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Ringhofer, Kurt. 1971. Interpretation und Reine Rechtslehre—Gedanken zu einer Kritik. In
Festschrift für Hans Kelsen zum 90. Geburtstag, 198–210. Vienna: Deuticke.
Rümelin, Gustav. 1891. Werturteile und Willensentscheidungen im Civilrecht. Freiburg: Lehmann.
Schauer, Frederick. 1985. Easy cases. Southern California Law Review 58: 399–440.
Schauer, Frederick. 1988. Formalism. The Yale Law Journal 97: 509–548.
Schauer, Frederick. 1996. Positivism as pariah. In The autonomy of law ed. Robert P. George
(Reprint 2005) 31–56. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Schauer, Frederick. 2004. The limited domain of the law. Virginia Law Review 90: 1909–1956.
Schauer, Frederick. 2009. Thinking like a lawyer (Paperback 2012). Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Schauer, Frederick. 2013. Legal realism untamed. Texas Law Review 91: 749–780.
Schreier, Fritz. 1927. Die Interpretation der Gesetze und Rechtsgeschäfte. Vienna: Deuticke.
Schwaighofer, Christoph. 1986. Kelsen zum Problem der Rechtsauslegung. In Untersuchungen
zur Reinen Rechtslehre, ed. Stanley L. Paulson and Robert Walter, 232–251. Vienna: Manz.
Sebok, Anthony. 1995. Misunderstanding positivism. Michigan Law Review 93: 2054–2132.
Sebok, Anthony. 1998. Legal positivism in American jurisprudence. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Stewart, Iain. 1990. The critical legal science of Hans Kelsen. Journal of Law and Society 17:
273–308.
Strauss, Peter. 1987. Formal and functional approaches to separation of powers—A foolish incon-
sistency? Cornell Law Review 72: 488–526.
Summers, Robert. 1963. Professor H. L. A. Hart’s concept of law. Duke Law Journal: 629–670.
Tamaha, Brian. 2010. Beyond the formalist-realist divide: The role of politics in judging. Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Telman, Jeremy. 2008. The reception of Hans Kelsen’s legal theory in the United States: A socio-
logical model, Valparaiso University Legal Studies Research Paper No. 08–03.
Telman, Jeremy. 2010. A path not taken: Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law in the land of legal real-
ists. In Hans Kelsen Anderswo/Hans Kelsen Abroad, ed. Robert Walter, Clemens Jabloner, and
Klaus Zeleny, 353–376. Vienna: Manz.
Telman, Jeremy. 2013. International legal positivism and legal realism, Valparaiso University
Legal Studies Research Paper No. 13–9.
Thaler, Michael. 1982. Mehrdeutigkeit und juristische Auslegung. Vienna: Springer.
Tosato, Angelo. 2000. The Catholic rule for interpreting the Bible. In Journal of Legal Hermeneutics
ed. Giuseppe Zaccharia, 129–206. Münster: Lit.
von Bernsdorff, Jochen. 2010. The public international law theory of Hans Kelsen: Believing in
universal law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Walter, Robert. 1983. Das Auslegungsproblem im Lichte der Reinen Rechtslehre. In Festschrift für
Ulrich Klug zum 70. Geburtstag, 187–197. Cologne: Dr. Peter Deubner Verlag.
Walter, Robert. 1990. Philosophische Hermeneutik und Reine Rechtslehre. In Beiträge zur jurist-
ischen Hermeneutik, ed. Helmuth Vetter and Michael Potacs, 41–52. Vienna: Literas.
Weinberger, Ota. 1982. Reine Rechtslehre: Pro und Contra (Bilanz aus Anlaß eines Doppeljubiläums).
In Memoria del X. Congreso Mundial Ordinario de Filosofía del Derecho y Filosofía Social Vol.
VI, Symposia II, 23–37. Mexico City: Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico.
Weinrib, Ernest. 1988. Legal formalism: On the immanent rationality of law. The Yale Law Journal
97: 949–1016.
Winkler, Günther. 1990. Rechtstheorie und Erkenntnislehre. Vienna: Springer.
Yntema, Hessel. 1941. Jurisprudence on parade. Michigan Law Review 39: 1154–1181.
Chapter 14
Cognition and Reason: Rethinking Kelsen
in the Context of Contract and Business Law
Jeffrey M. Lipshaw
14.1 Introduction
One rarely finds an essay that links academic consideration of a legal philosophy
like Hans Kelsen’s positivism with the rough-and-tumble world of an American
business lawyer’s practice. As Tevye said in Fiddler on the Roof (with regard to
intermarriage), a bird may love a fish, but where would they build a home together?
(Stein et al. 2004). Rather than bemoaning the fact that finding an audience for the
topic is as likely as finding guests for the bird-fish marriage, I am going to press
ahead. Thinking explicitly about legal positivism, and particularly Kelsen’s version
of it, is a salutary exercise not just for legal philosophers, but also for those of us
who educate Anglo-American deal-making lawyers.
To use a corporate expression, there is an unexpected bit of synergy here. Kelsen’s
conception of positivism is particularly appealing to those of us who traffic in con-
tract and business law. The usual philosophical debate revolves around law and
morality, ie, whether the justification for contract law—the state’s involvement in
the resolution of wholly voluntary and private transactions—arises from the moral
affirmation of promise keeping, the welfare-maximization that voluntary contrac-
tual commitments promote, or something else entirely.1 The more mundane aspects
of contract law doctrine often have less to do with grand theories about promise-
keeping and more to do with determining how the parties meant to order their inter-
ests or, alternatively, with the imputation of what, as a rule, their objective
manifestations are understood to signify about that ordering (Craswell 1989). In this
more prosaic arena, one of Kelsen’s reasons for articulating a pure theory of law
1
For a review of this debate, see Lipshaw (2012a) and the essays that follow in the symposium
issue dedicated to Charles Fried’s iconic book.
J.M. Lipshaw (*)
Suffolk University Law School, Boston, MA 02108, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
resonates with those of us who teach and practice it. Law, as the parties use it in
private ordering, is indeed separate from morality. As he observes, “there are only
interests and thus conflicts of interests…That only one ordering of interests has
absolute value (which really means ‘is just’) cannot be accounted for by way of
rational cognition” (Kelsen 1934: 17). As I often tell my first year law students, the
courts’ articulation of contract law doctrine in hard cases may well reflect a tension
between coherence and consistency, on one hand, and fairness, on the other, but
from the litigants’ standpoint, the rules of contract law are merely arrows in a quiver
meant to advance the underlying interest of the parties. Not surprisingly, each of the
opposing parties argues its application of the rules fits more coherently within the
system, promotes fairness, and just happens to dictate a result in favor of that party.
Reading Kelsen again,2 it has dawned on me that the interesting insight in the
pure theory for contract and business law involves not the usual positivist focus on
the separation of law and morality, but Kelsen’s additional emphasis on the separa-
tion of law—part of the normative realm of the “ought”—and fact—the empirical
realm of the “is.” As Stanley Paulson’s instructive matrix showed (Paulson 1997:
xxvi), Kelsen was ambitious. He sought not only to isolate pure law from questions
of morality, but also to create a science of positive law, even while recognizing that
the science will operate on the ideal and normative reality that is the law, and not on
natural or physical reality (Kelsen 1934: 15). In short, “a cognitive science of the
law is what the Pure Theory aims to be.” (Kelsen 1934: 19). The key to that sci-
ence—indeed, to the very idea of “pure” law—was Kelsen’s analogy to the a priori
categories in Kant’s schematic of cognition.
To make my thesis clear, I need to review briefly the significance of the “catego-
ries” in Kant’s epistemology. Under David Hume’s radical empiricism (to which
Kant was reacting), the only a priori judgments we make about objects or things are
analytical. That means the predicate of our thought about the object says no more
than what we thought in the subject of the judgment. “All bodies are extended; they
take up space.” That is an analytical judgment because everything I need to know
about a body taking up space is already subsumed in the concept of a body (Kant
1783: 14). Knowing that something is a ball or even that it is a moving ball does not,
however, in and of itself dictate the predicate of movement of another ball. Hence a
judgment that one thing causes another—that the cause of the billiard ball striking
the rail was its collision with another ball—is an example of a synthetic judgment,
one in which the predicate of the proposition is not implicit in its subject (Kant
1783: 15). Hume contended there are no synthetic a priori judgments; what we
perceive, for example, as cause-and-effect is simply the result of “common experi-
ences marked with a false stamp” (Kant 1783: 4)—ie, with (false) metaphysics of
causation. In his view, all such judgments are a posteriori—they derive wholly from
experience (Kant 1783: 15). There is no necessary or metaphysical reason why the
ball has to carom that way; our ability to predict that it will occurs only because of
our repeated experience that billiard balls always so carom.
2
In Lipshaw (2007), I discussed the difference between an “ought” of moral freedom and the
“ought” of legal compulsion implicit in Kelsen’s pure theory.
14 Cognition and Reason 267
Kant’s fundamental contribution was to assert, pace Hume, that synthetic a pri-
ori judgments must be possible in order even to be skeptical (as was Hume) about
knowledge itself (Kant 1783: 26–31). How we make sense subjectively of an objec-
tive world depends on an a priori cognitive faculty that does not derive from experi-
ence. Kant’s “categories”—concepts like substance, plurality, unity, existence, and
causation—are what constitute the cognitive faculty (Kant 1781: 210–213). That
faculty corresponds to, and is in harmony with, an objective world of experience
and possible experience that exists independently of our perception of it.3
Kelsen contended there is an a priori faculty in making legal judgments akin to
Kant’s a priori faculty of cognition. In Kelsen’s pure theory, this is the human abil-
ity to recognize a legal (as opposed to moral) norm as a specific linking of condi-
tioning material fact and conditioned consequence. Kelsen wrote:
Just as the laws of nature link a material fact as cause with another as effect, so positive laws
[in their basic form] link legal condition with legal consequence (the consequence of a so-
called unlawful act). If the mode of linking materiality is causality in one case, it is imputa-
tion in the other, and imputation is recognized in the Pure Theory of Law as the particular
lawfulness, the autonomy, of the law (Kelsen 1934: 23).
This was Kelsen’s crucial step. He saw the imputation of an “ought,” a normative
connection between conditioning fact and legal outcome, as an a priori category for
comprehending the reality of law in the world (in his words, “empirical legal data”),
different from causality in nature, “but just as inviolable” (Kelsen 1934: 24–25).
Moreover, like Kant’s categories, this faculty for imputing legal consequence pur-
ports to be “transcendental” not “transcendent.” It tells us nothing about metaphysi-
cal or natural law; instead, the faculty acts formally to have us identify what is a
legal and not merely a moral norm, just as Kant’s categories act to order our sense
perceptions of manifold reality (Kelsen 1934: 25).
Others before me have questioned this move.4 What I intend to do here, in my
bird-fish incarnation as a business lawyer, contract law theoretician, and Kant-
influenced epistemologist, is different. I want to focus on the difference in Kantian
3
Kant wrote:
Thus although in synthetic judgments we cognize a priori so much about space in general
or about the shapes that the productive imagination draws in it that we really do not need
any experience for this, still this cognition would be nothing at all, but an occupation with
a mere figment of the brain, if space were not to be regarded as the condition of the appear-
ances which constitute the matter of outer experience; hence those pure synthetic judg-
ments are related, although only mediately, to possible experience, or rather to its possibility
itself, and on that alone is the objective validity of their synthesis grounded (Kant 1781:
282–283).
This is about as pithy a statement as we get in the Critique of Pure Reason on the relationship
of our subjective cognition to the objective world. What follows thereafter is Kant’s extensive and
difficult argument—the balance of the Transcendental Analytic—why the assertion is necessarily
true. As Paulson notes (1997: xxix–xxx), this is Kant’s argument “that the notion of ‘a world of the
senses existing of itself’—existing absolutely—amounts to a self-contradiction, and must be
replaced by the notion that the world exists not ‘of itself’ but only in relation to mind.”
4
See the discussion below of Paulson (1997) and Wilson (1986).
268 J.M. Lipshaw
epistemology between the kind of knowledge that arises, on one hand, merely by
the faculties of cognition and, on the other, through the exercise of theoretical rea-
son. The most problematic aspect of legal positivism, whether Kelsen’s or Hart’s, is
the sense that law cannot be studied merely by observations of patterns of actors’
behavior. Rather, the idea of something being imbued with legal significance invokes
the subjective point of view of the legal actor. To me, the most significant “Kantian”
benefit of the pure theory is precisely this grappling with the relationship between,
on one hand, the actor’s subjective assessment of the legal consequence of a set of
conditions and, on the other, the objective existence in the world of something char-
acterizable as “law.” But the most significant “Kantian” problem in the pure theory
is not the a priori nature (or not) of such subjective legal judgments, but Kelsen’s
focus on cognition rather than reason as the source of any knowledge that purports
to be science, whether of law or anything else. And the key to understanding the
problem in the context of contracts and contract law is returning directly to Kant to
challenge Kelsen’s separation of fact and law—the dichotomy between the “is,” the
empirical and natural, on one hand, and the “ought,” what is normative, on the
other.5
Transactional lawyers create contracts as a matter of empirical fact, but that is a
trivial observation. Resort to contract law in business transactions, it turns out,
whether before- or after-the-fact, is an odd amalgam of descriptive and normative
undertakings. The prevalent mythology among academics and practitioners alike is
that resolution of contract disputes is a search for an empirical “is”—either the
expressed mutual intention of the parties or the inference of such intention by way
of default rules reflecting what, as a rule, the objective manifestations of the parties
would mean. What makes contract law unique, as Kelsen observed, is the minimal
intrusion of the state into the creation of the specific legal norm at issue. “Here the
parties who are subject to obligation participate in creating the norm that imposes
obligations, and therein lies the essence of the contractual creation of law” (Kelsen
1934: 93). But, as Kelsen also observed, this is not a wholly normative inquiry.
Ironically, to decide a contract case a court has to determine the applicable norms as
a matter of fact.6
As a contract law teacher and business lawyer, I wholly concur in Kelsen’s skep-
ticism about the connection between law and justice. As an epistemologist strongly
influenced by Kant, I am not wholly satisfied with H.L.A. Hart’s adoption of the
“internal point of view” so as to explain the subjective impact upon actors of the law
qua law (thus distinguishing law as experienced subjectively from mere patterns of
5
As Alexander Somek suggested to me, I am confronting Kelsen directly with Kant systematically,
and not intermediated by the historical circumstance of Kelsen’s relationship with neo-Kantians
like Hermann Cohen. For a short and readable account of that history, see Green (2003:
395–398).
6
“Exercising powers delegated to them by statute, [private] parties set concrete norms for their
own behavior, norms that prescribe reciprocal behavior and whose violation constitutes the mate-
rial fact to be established by the judicial decision” (Kelsen 1934: 70).
14 Cognition and Reason 269
behavior) (Hart 1997: 56–57, 89–91). Kelsen was onto something when he
analogized to Kant’s epistemology. Yet I am troubled by his appropriation of the
Kantian categories of cognition to what I understand contract and business lawyers
to be doing when they practice law. The problem with transposing the Kantian cat-
egories to law, at least in contract law, is the implication that what one knows a
priori as a result of the categories is meaningful in any way other than trivially so.
Instead, what is significantly meaningful in contract law is the knowledge we obtain
by exercise of the faculty either of theoretical or practical reason, an aspect of Kant’s
epistemology that Kelsen does not appear to have adopted (or even considered) in
the pure theory. As Kant viewed it, our faculty of reason is a regulative process—a
way of thinking that may or may not produce knowledge. It is distinct from cogni-
tion—the process of judgments by which we have constitutive knowledge of the
objective world of experience. The problem with reason when not used merely as a
way of assessing experience or possible experience, as Kant inveighed in the First
Critique, is that it is capable of creating transcendental illusion, having us think we
know things that truly must be consigned to faith.7 In other words, when we focus
on reason rather than cognition, the line between the “is” and the “ought” blurs.
My aim in this essay is therefore to reconsider the pure theory in the context of
contract and business law. In Sect. 14.2, I discuss what the experience of contract
and business law really is. Kelsen was right: there is a separation of fact and law.
Transactions are observable empirical events. Whether undertaken after the fact in
litigation or before the fact in planning a transaction, law is an exercise of mind,
consistent with the basic norm, in which we apply particularly legal rules of infer-
ence in modus ponens8 logic to particular circumstances—those observable empiri-
cal events—to impute legal conclusions from antecedent conditions. The very core
of modus ponens logic may well be a priori in the same sense as is pure mathemat-
ics. But the actual rules of law (at least in contracts and business) constituting the
connection between “if” and “then” in the major premise must be a posteriori, ie,
derived wholly from experience.
In Sect. 14.3, I attempt something not often done, which is to reconsider the core
analogy in the pure theory, and to examine the relationship of cognition and reason
7
Hence, Kant’s oft-quoted statement from the Preface to the Second Edition of the Critique of Pure
Reason:
Thus I had to deny knowledge in order to make room for faith;…to see this we need merely
to compare the culture of reason that is set on the course of a secure science with reason’s
unfounded groping and frivolous wandering about without critique, or to consider how
much better young people hungry for knowledge might spend their time than in the usual
dogmatism that gives so early and so much encouragement to their complacent quibblings
about things they do not understand, and things into which neither they nor anyone else in
the world will ever have any insight…(Kant (1781: 117).
8
Modus ponens is a rule of inference as follows:
If a, then b.
a.
Therefore b.
270 J.M. Lipshaw
as they relate to knowledge, not as Kelsen or his critics might or might not have
done it, but in a way I believe is more faithful to Kant.9 This is necessary if we are
going to think of contract and business law as a kind of science, whether descriptive
or normative, under Kantian conceptions of cognition and reason. While giving
credit to Kelsen for understanding that there was something about the relationship
of subject and object that evoked Kant, there is a problem with treating the core of
Kelsen’s basic norm as a Kantian category of cognition. Thinking legally is an exer-
cise of entirely different faculty: reason, of which the law’s modus ponens logic is
perhaps one of the best examples.10
In Sect. 14.4, I consider the practical implications of the foregoing somewhat
obscure and arcane distinction if not for the contract and business lawyers who actu-
ally do the practicing then at least for those who teach them. Facing reality before
one decides on a course of action is often the hardest task for lawyers and their cli-
ents. I am thus skeptical of a legal “science” that seeks an ironically and paradoxi-
cally abstract positive law of contracts, an ideally coherent doctrine that exists
somewhere “out there,” removed from its application to real world experience.
When we use theoretical and practical reason to solve problems, whether norma-
tively or descriptively, we are lawyers. When we reason speculatively on the coher-
ence of the doctrine, removed from the reality of a set of facts, as though we could
know the law as a “thing-in-itself,” we are theologians.
Finally, I conclude with some brief thoughts on legal positivism in the context of
“lawyering as doing” rather than the more academic project of the demarcation and
classification of law.
9
I cannot say “as Kant did,” because Kant’s views on the “role reason plays in his theoretical phi-
losophy” is less clear than in his moral philosophy, and those views are the subject of a good deal
of secondary work by Gerd Buchdahl, Susan Neiman, and others, much of which I adopt here
(Williams 2013). I acknowledge that I am adopting a particular view of what Kant meant, whether
or not he meant it, but my aim here is not to resolve that issue. I do find these interpreters’ distinc-
tions between cognition and reason both consistent with my own reading particularly of Kant’s
Appendix to the Transcendental Dialectic in the First Critique and the Critique of Teleological
Judgment in the Third Critique. Indeed, because I think Kant is clearer on these points than his
reputation for abstruse writing would make one think, I have quoted him liberally in the footnotes
to this essay. More importantly, I find the distinction between cognition and reason to be powerful
in assessing my own bouts of transcendental illusion as well as what seems to me to be the confla-
tion of truth and belief in others. Undoubtedly there is a distinction between cognition and reason
in Kant’s work, and my aim is to explore how that distinction, in light of Kelsen, might inform, if
not contract jurisprudence, then the role contract law and contract lawyering play in light of all the
other norms that operate among contracting parties.
10
It is perhaps only incidental to my analysis of Kelsen that Kant himself probably thought so
(Weinrib 1987: 478–491).
14 Cognition and Reason 271
11
Thus Peter Goodrich (2009: 480) has criticized traditional legal theory, insulated from the other
disciplines, as “a normative order that is predominantly choral and liturgical, as much propelled by
acclamation as celebration.”
12
Kelsen encapsulated the basic norm:
The basic norm confers on the act of the first legislator—and thus on all other acts of the
legal system resting on this first act—the sense of ‘ought’, that specific sense in which legal
condition is linked with legal consequence in the reconstructed legal norm, the paradig-
matic form in which it must be possible to represent all the data of the positive law (Kelsen
1934: 58).
13
To be clear, I am reticent to apply the adjectives “true” or “false” to all but the most obvious and
intellectually trivial statements about what the law “is.” I know the United States Code and the
language of Restatement of Contracts (Second) § 90(1) in Georgia (it was codified) are law as an
empirical matter, but any proposition of law seems to me to be not so much meaningless as sterile
272 J.M. Lipshaw
In the usual case, an expression of the law and an expression of the facts will eventually be
brought together as the major and minor premises of the modus ponens, which constitutes
the ideal-typical final form of normative justification in general. An expression taking the
form of the modus ponens typically characterizes the end-moment of legal justification
regardless of what went before—that is, regardless of how elaborate, messy, and/or con-
fused the actual process of judicial decision making may have been.14
What contract lawyers do before the fact is to translate messy experience (or the
contingencies of future experience) into models (some more complex than others)
consisting of premises that would support after the fact use of modus ponens logic
to resolve disputes: If A, then B. A. Therefore B. That is no less the case in contract
law than in any other form of law, notwithstanding the fact that the parties may have
had something to do with the creation of the law. For example, in a merger agree-
ment, the indemnification clause deals with breaches of warranty. If there is a breach
of warranty, then Seller shall indemnify Buyer (If A, then B). There was a breach of
warranty (A). Therefore Seller shall indemnify (B).
There is little doubt these are synthetic judgments. Are they, however, in Kantian
terms, a priori as well as synthetic? One of the problems with analogy between the
Kantian conception of causation and Kelsen’s of legal imputation is that the a priori
aspect of law in action is limited to the most general logical relation between the
“if” and the “then” statements in the modus ponens inference. To give appropriate
credit to the basic norm and rules that take its form, there is a seed of a priori judg-
ment in what we do to apply the law. Regardless of the subject matter to which we
apply modus ponens, we cannot determine B merely as something contained within
A. If “the predicate B belongs to the subject A as something that is (covertly)
without its application to something in the world. The closest view to my own is Dennis Patterson’s
(1999) conception of law as argumentation—what lawyers do. That is, worrying about whether a
proposition of law is true is largely a waste of time. Patterson’s assessment largely concerns itself
with the usual stuff of jurisprudence, constitutions, statutes, and judicial decisions, and not the
private law the parties create for themselves in a contract. In the spirit of a Kantian analysis, I sug-
gest that what lawyers do when they create private law or when they argue to a judge is to use
reason to make demands upon experience—they are either applying theoretical reason to construct
a model of experience or possible experience (ie, drafting a contract) or practical reason to deter-
mine or argue what it is that somebody ought to do.
14
Getting to the operative expression of the law for purposes of the important modus ponens infer-
ence may take some unpeeling. For example, suppose a claimant contended that a promisor com-
mitted himself legally by a series of eye blinks. Under the rules in the Restatement (Second) of
Contracts, we might have the following progression. It is a contract under § 1 if there was a prom-
ise for the breach of which the law provides a remedy. But was it a promise? Section 2 tells us a
promise is a manifestation of an intention to act in a specified way so made as to justify a promisee
in understanding that a commitment has been made. There is no definition in the Restatement of a
“manifestation” or a “commitment.” But one of the issues may be whether the eye blinking consti-
tuted a manifestation or a commitment justifiably so understood by another. At some point, there
will be a determination in the following form: If A, then B; A; therefore B. If there was a physical
movement having a sensible pattern, then it is a manifestation. There was such a physical move-
ment. Therefore, there was a manifestation. There is no getting around the infinite regress of mean-
ing, but at each level it is a modus ponens exercise. As to the inevitability of the infinite regress,
see Stumpff (2013).
14 Cognition and Reason 273
contained in this concept A,” the judgment is analytic (Kant 1781: 141). If “B lies
entirely outside the concept A, though to be sure it stands in connection with it,”
then the judgment is synthetic (Kant 1781: 141). The form of a logical statement,
which in modus ponens presumes a relation between the subject A and the predicate
B, but which relation does not inhere in the concept of the subject A and needs no
experience to bear it out, is, like mathematics, the epitome of what Kant terms a
synthetic a priori judgment (Kant 1781: 145).
So our most fundamental ability to perceive a connection between an antecedent
condition and a consequence does strike us as something akin to an a priori judg-
ment of cause-and-effect. But that is as far as it goes. It is far more problematic to
extend the analogy to the legal rules of inference themselves. It strikes me as the
very antithesis of legal positivism to believe that any particular rule, at least in con-
tract and business law, arises independent of experience. That is, all legal rules serv-
ing as the major premise of the modus ponens sequence—ie, the statement of the
legal consequence that arises from the antecedent condition—must be a posterio-
ri.15 There is simply no necessary reason that the legal consequence of a breach of
warranty, for example, is a right to relief. If there is such a right, whether by default
rule or private ordering, and whether or not the right accords with a sense of moral-
ity, it seems to me beyond any serious debate that it is a contingent and not a neces-
sary happenstance.16
In my experience as teacher and practicing lawyer, the modus ponens form of the
basic norm is valuable in characterizing how lawyers think both after the fact of a
transaction in litigation and before the fact in writing the contracts. As to litigation,
15
This is consistent with the dictum in Holmes (1881) about the relationship of logic and experi-
ence to the life of the law (“The life of the law has not been logic: it has been experience” (Holmes
1881: 1)). However, Holmes is aware that the mechanism of the law is indeed logic. He concludes
his derivation of the modern law of civil liability with this observation:
The foregoing history…illustrates the paradox of form and substance in the development of
law. In form its growth is logical. The official theory is that each new decision follows syl-
logistically from existing precedents. But…precedents survive in the law long after the use
they once served is at an end and the reason for them has been forgotten. The result of fol-
lowing them must often be failure and confusion from the merely logical point of view
(Holmes 1881: 35).
How the rules themselves develop and adapt is indeed a posteriori, a matter of experience. But
their final expression as rules maintains the syllogistic form.
16
Michael Steven Green (2003: 379) has captured this relationship, perhaps more articulately than
I, as one in which the form of legal sentences provide the underlying logic that links the antecedent
conditions and the legal consequence, but the content of the sentences is contingent on social facts
that provide “primitive legal meaning.”
274 J.M. Lipshaw
I am less interested in the precise holding than the method Cardozo used to reach
it. There were four possible models or legal theories within which to fit this case
from a judicial frame of reference, all of which Judge Cardozo mentioned in the
opinion: charitable subscription, promissory estoppel, gift, and contract supported
by consideration. Twice Judge Cardozo referred to legal theories as “moulds,” first
to suggest that the mould as fixed by the old doctrine had been expanded, and sec-
ond to say that this particular transaction “can be fitted within the mould” (Allegheny,
159 N.E. at 175). What is a “mould”? It is a British spelling of “mold,” for which
the Oxford Dictionary Online gives one definition as “a hollow container used to
give shape to molten or hot liquid material when it cools and hardens…” The origin
of the word is “Middle English: apparently from Old French modle, from Latin
modulus.” In short, consideration as a legal doctrine is a model—a mould—into
which we pour the facts (Oxford Dictionaries 2014).
We may express each of those moulds in the form of modus ponens argument: if
A, then B; A; therefore B.
17
I am fairly sure that I came to this reading of Allegheny College independently, but I have since
discovered that Konefsky (1987) anticipated me in large part by about 20 years. I believe Professor
Konefsky was correct from stem to stern in his unraveling of Cardozo’s supposedly elliptical,
convoluted, and incomprehensible opinion. My approach follows his in spirit though it varies in
technique, and I credit Judge Kellogg’s dissent somewhat more affirmatively than he did.
14 Cognition and Reason 275
18
“The law of charitable subscriptions has been a prolific source of controversy in this state and
elsewhere. We have held that a promise of that order is unenforceable like any other if made with-
out consideration” (Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 174).
19
The best Cardozo could come up with was the notion that, absent the promise, the college might
have simply applied the funds to purposes specified under its charter, and not have created a special
fund that would only become sufficient to make the scholarship if others contributed to it after Mrs.
Johnston’s death (Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 177).
276 J.M. Lipshaw
the implied request of the promisor,” then the conditional promise is legally
enforceable, ie, “the result was the creation of a bilateral agreement.”
The “if/then” statements for consideration and gift are reverse images of each
other. Either the promise invites a bargain or it does not. The consequence of the
former is a contract; the consequence of the latter is a gift. It is clear that Cardozo
did not like the implications of imposing the “gift” mould over the transaction for
the same policy reasons that he believed promissory estoppel arose in the charitable
subscription context: these were important promises for which the promisor ought
not easily be let off the hook. So if he was not inclined to let the estate renege, the
moulds expressed in modus ponens logic gave him three choices, two of which—
charitable contribution without reliance and promissory estoppel—he did not want
to apply either for policy reasons or because the fact needed to supply the anteced-
ent condition of reliance was so weak.
The facts did support the idea that the college promised something, even if the
something was as fleeting as naming the fund for her as a memorial. Mrs. Johnston’s
conditional promise was to the effect, “If you name a fund for me, I will contribute
to the college.” When the college promised to do so, it made a bargain. Because the
bargain came about as the result of a promise in exchange for a promise, it was a
bilateral agreement and, under the appropriate rule of inference for such agreement,
legally enforceable from the moment of the return promise.20 And for Cardozo, that
concluded the overlay of theories of positive law—expressed in the form of the
basic norm—upon these facts.
That law is separate from fact is apparent from Judge Kellogg’s dissent. There
was no dispute over the facts; the only question was the appropriate insertion of
those facts into the moulds of positive law theories, those a posteriori rules of infer-
ence that constitute the common law. Judge Kellogg focused on two.
3. Gift. If a conditional promise does not invite a bargain (ie, it merely induces the
promisee to act or refrain from acting without the promise and the act having
been motive for each other), then the conditional promise constitutes a gift and
is not legally enforceable.
Judge Kellogg was not inclined in the first instance to see Mrs. Johnston’s prom-
ise even as stating a condition capable of inviting a bargain. She stated merely that
“this gift shall be known as the Mary Yates Johnston Memorial Fund,” and the col-
lege “was not requested to perform any act through which the sum might bear the
title by which the offeror states that it shall be known. The sum offered was termed
a ‘gift’ by the offeror” (Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 177).
But even if the court were to use consideration theory, in Judge Kellogg’s view,
the facts still did not justify a legal conclusion that there was a contract. There are
two rules expressible in the form of modus ponens rules for contract formation in
20
“A bilateral agreement may exist though one of the mutual promises be a promise ‘implied in
fact,’ an inference from conduct as opposed to an inference from words.…The fair implication to
be gathered from the whole transaction is assent to the condition and the assumption of a duty to
go forward with performance” (Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 176).
14 Cognition and Reason 277
the classical expression of the common law. These rules operate to supply a conclu-
sion whether the parties actually formed, in an objective sense, a mutual under-
standing, regardless whether the understanding related to what turns out to be an
enforceable contract or an unenforceable gift. The naked offer is simply a promise
to enter into a contract if the promisee accepts according to the terms of the offer.21
The offer becomes binding if the offeree accepts by exercising the power of accep-
tance that the offer creates in the offeree.22
The two rules on formation differ, and they depend on the nature of the consid-
eration for the offeror’s otherwise unenforceable promise, ie, whether the original
offer invites acceptance by way of a return promise or return performance,23 or is
silent on the manner of acceptance.24 Cardozo applied the former.
5. Bilateral contract. If a conditional promise (ie, to contribute) invites a bargain by
way of a return promise (ie, if the offeree promises to perpetuate the name of the
donor of the scholarship), and the offeree “subjected itself to such a duty at the
implied request of the promisor,” then the conditional promise is legally enforce-
able, ie, “the result was the creation of a bilateral agreement.”
Judge Kellogg’s objection was that there was no evidence of the required ante-
cedent condition, namely a return promise from Allegheny College so as to form an
immediately enforceable promise-for-promise bilateral contract. If the transaction
fit into any mould of contract formation, it would have been promise-for-
performance—a unilateral contract.
6. Unilateral contract. If a conditional promise (ie, to contribute) invites a bargain
by way of a return performance (ie, if the offeree perpetuates the name of the
donor of the scholarship), and the offeree “subjected itself to such a duty at the
implied request of the promisor,” then the conditional promise is legally enforce-
able, ie, the result was the creation of a unilateral agreement.
As Judge Kellogg observed, “she proposed to exchange her offer of a donation in
return for acts to be performed” (Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 177). Allegheny College
never actually named a scholarship for her. Thus, “although a promise of the college
to make the gift known, as requested, may be implied, that promise was not the
21
Compare the definition of “promise” in Restatement of the Law Second, Contracts § 2 (“A prom-
ise is a manifestation of intention to act or refrain from acting in a specified way, so made as to
justify a promisee in understanding that a commitment has been made”) with the definition of offer
in § 24 (“An offer is the manifestation of willingness to enter into a bargain, so made as to justify
another person in understanding that his assent to that bargain is invited and will conclude it”). See
also Hogg et al. (2008: 148–149).
22
Restatement of the Law Second, Contracts §§ 38, 50. See also Hogg et al. (2008: 154).
23
Restatement of the Law Second, Contracts § 30(1) (“An offer may invite or require acceptance
to be made by an affirmative answer in words, or by performing or refraining from performing a
specified act, or may empower the offeree to make a selection of terms in his acceptance.”).
24
Id. § 30(2) (1981) (“Unless otherwise indicated by the language or the circumstances, an offer
invites acceptance in any manner and by any medium reasonable in the circumstances.”).
278 J.M. Lipshaw
acceptance of an offer which gave rise to a contract” (Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 177).
But there is one more link in the logical chain.
7. Revocation of offer in unilateral contract. If (a) an offeree under a power of
acceptance created by an offer that invites performance has not performed the
requested act, and (b) the offeror receives a manifestation of an intention not to
enter into the proposed contract from the offeree, then the offeree’s power of
acceptance is terminated.25
In July 1924, Mrs. Johnston repudiated the gift. As Judge Kellogg would have
applied the rules of inference, because she revoked her offer before the rules would
have caused the legal consequence of a binding contract, there was no contract and
she was not obliged to contribute: “the donation was not to take effect until after the
death of the donor, and by her death the offer was withdrawn” (Allegheny, 159 N.E.
at 177).26
What separates law from fact is the judges’ post hoc application of logical sen-
tences in the form of the basic norm to the narrative. Nobody knew or could know,
except by extrapolation and interpretation, what either Mrs. Johnston or the officials
of Allegheny College meant to have happen immediately after she made her original
statement public. Perhaps she never thought about revocability at all. The process of
legal judgment only takes account of any of that to the extent that the underlying
facts satisfy (or not) the modus ponens logic of the a posteriori rules constituting the
proffered legal theories.
The form of the basic norm, its modus ponens logic, is no less significant on the
transactional side of the lawyering house. To be sure, some of what we do as law-
yers is to create artifacts that have meaning wholly independent of the language
employed in the artifacts (Suchman 2003). The Jewish marriage contract hanging in
our home is significant as ritual and not because we refer to it as a guide to our
spousal duties. In my experience, even the execution of a corporate acquisition
agreement—something for which the linguistic content ought to be paramount—
has a ritual or symbolic meaning (Lipshaw 2012b). Whether the contract is ritual or
metaphoric map of the transaction, and even considering that the longest contract
will still fail fully to embody all of the understandings of the parties, the contract is
still an artifact the form of which is set in language, a narrative, part of which the
25
Restatement of the Law Second, Contracts § 42 (“An offeree’s power of acceptance is terminated
when the offeree receives from the offeror a manifestation of an intention not to enter into the
proposed contract.”)
26
There is the question of the $1000 Mrs. Johnston paid on account before she died. Judge Cardozo
cites this as evidence a bilateral contract had been previously formed, and that by accepting it, the
college was saying implicitly that it would fulfill its promise to name the scholarship fund after her.
(Allegheny, 159 N.E. at 176–177). Judge Kellogg must have considered the $1000 as a gratuity,
given that Allegheny College had not yet performed the act invited in the offer.
14 Cognition and Reason 279
27
An example is IBP, Inc. v. Tyson Foods, 789 A.2d 14 (Del. Ch. 2001).
280 J.M. Lipshaw
will read them into the agreement because, in the absence of any indication other-
wise, most people in the community would do so as well.28 The terms or conditions
can be implied in fact. That means that there is enough evidence to justify to a third
party that the parties actually meant the term or condition to be included, even if
they did not expressly state it.29 Or the terms and conditions can be express. I often
tell my contract law students there are whole sections of the course that they may
never encounter in practice (like the doctrine of consideration or promissory restitu-
tion), but that the essence of before-the-fact contract lawyering is to substitute
express terms for implied terms. There are very few substantive terms or conditions
that courts will be willing to imply as a matter of law, and the deal lawyer’s night-
mare is explaining (either to a court or to one’s client) why a term not made express
and not so obviously sensible as to be implied in law is one that the court should
imply in fact.
The practice of transactional lawyers, then, is to create law by using a language,
the form of which derives from the basic norm in Kelsen’s conception of positive
law. The result is an objective manifestation of the parties, one hopes made express
but, at the very least, implied in fact.
28
Judge Cardozo also wrote two of the iconic opinions on this subject. In Wood v. Lucy, Lady Duff-
Gordon, 222 N.Y. 88, 118 N.E. 214 (1917), he held that an exclusive marketing agent had an
obligation to use reasonable efforts when he did not so commit either expressly or “in so many
words.” In Jacob & Youngs v. Kent, 230 N.Y. 239, 129 N.E. 889 (1921), the issue was the extent to
which one party had to perform in order to trigger the other party’s obligation. Judge Cardozo held
that, “where the significant of the default is grievously out of proportion to the oppression of the
forfeiture” (Jacob & Youngs, 230 N.Y. at 243–44), the implied in law condition was substantial, not
perfect performance.
29
Bloomgarden v. Coyer, 479 F.2d 201, 208 (D.C. Cir. 1973) (“An implied-in-fact contract is a true
contract, containing all necessary elements of a binding agreement; it differs from other contracts
only in that it has not been committed to writing or stated orally in express terms, but rather is
inferred from the conduct of the parties in the milieu in which they dealt.”).
14 Cognition and Reason 281
30
Making one’s way through the Transcendental Deduction is notoriously difficult, but Michael
Steven Green’s (2003: 389–395) synopsis is very good.
31
Professor Wilson delivered a devastating critique of Kelsen’s analogy between “imputation” (in
German, Zurechnung) and Kant’s categories (Wilson 1986: 54–58). She then proceeded to a dis-
cussion of the difficulties in Kelsen’s attempts to ground the science of law in Kant’s insights as
they pertain to the kind of systematic knowledge that we would call science (as opposed to mere
perception) (Wilson 1986: 58–61). I think her primary point was that, tracking what Kelsen wrote
over the years, Zurechnung was a moving target, at least in the analogy to causality. Professor
Wilson touched briefly, however, on what I am saying more fully here: Kant’s categories may be
the a priori faculties by which the human mind puts any order at all to sensible intuition, but they
“are not co-ordinating concepts…in the way some scientific concepts are” (Wilson 1986: 61, quot-
ing Walsh 1975: 42). In short, if we really want to talk about contract law in Kantian terms, then
we need to be focusing on reason and not cognition.
32
Professor Wilson (Wilson 1986: 38–45) also delivered a devastating critique of Kelsen’s adher-
ence (or lack thereof) to the “is-ought” distinction, namely that in Kant’s practical philosophy, a
rational being’s “ought” implies freedom from compulsion or constraint of the natural world, and
Kelsen seems to adopt a kind of moral determinism.
282 J.M. Lipshaw
Moreover, the observation that law requires judgments having a synthetic a pri-
ori component (ie, the modus ponens form) does not in itself vindicate Kelsen’s
analogy to Kant. One could observe that a moral or other practical judgment also
boils down to a modus ponens expression, except that a moral or practical, rather
than legal, rule of inference applies. If there is no a priori basis for distinguishing a
legal rule of inference from a moral or practical one, then the answer would indeed
seem to be that Hart’s reduction of law to the Rule of Recognition by way of com-
monly accepted social facts must necessarily trump Kelsen’s derivation (Hart 1997:
94–95). But we ought not end there. We might instead assess the kind of judgment
one makes when one distinguishes a legal rule from a moral rule, the whole point of
the Kelsenian and Hartian exercises. Is that a synthetic a priori judgment of cogni-
tion alone? Or is it the exercise of reason? So what we are analyzing now is a sen-
tence like:
8. The inference from antecedent facts to consequence in connection with the
application of UCC 2-207 [to take an example of a contingent rule of law with-
out a shred of morality attached to it] to circumstances is necessarily legal and
not necessarily moral.
That is clearly a synthetic judgment. Is it a priori or a posteriori? Do we “cog-
nize” the difference between legal and moral without more, or do we have to pro-
ceed to integrate contingent facts and other cognitions to draw a conclusion? My
inclination is to say that we have now started down an infinite regress, looking for
the rule for following a rule, and will return ultimately to a seed of synthetic a priori
cognition from which we then reason our way to a conclusion about the rule that
determines the difference between an inference that is legal and one that is moral.
Kant himself recognized that these questions take us to the very edge of our ability
to talk at all about things like pure reason or freedom at all: “But Reason would
overstep all its bounds if it undertook to explain how pure reason can be practical,
which would be exactly the same problem as to explain how freedom is possible”
(Kant 1785: 216).33
To give full credit to Kelsen, and to say why his pure theory struck a chord in me,
it is indeed his recourse to Kant as a way of dealing with the subjective or internal
point of view that is a hallmark of something being law rather than a mere pattern
of behavior. Even from his more sociological perspective, Hart’s later articulation of
the “internal point of view” was an attempt at reconciling the objective reality of
positive law as social fact with the subjective processes that legal actors undertake
when doing law.34 Kelsen, like Hart, saw that law had something to do with how
33
I suspect it is precisely this regress that leads many to conclude pursuing it is a waste of time, to
abjure the smell of metaphysics, and to turn to sociology (read: Hart).
34
A nice summary consists of the essays collected in connection with the Fordham Law Review’s
2006 symposium, and introduced by Benjamin Zipursky (2006). Richard Holton (1998) made a
brief and prescient remark at the end of his essay on the seeming schizophrenia of legal positivism.
Referring to the semantic thesis of legal positivism, ie that “the sense of normative terms in legal
claims is different from their sense in moral claims” (Holton 1998: 609) he asked why it should be
the case that to have a legal system (in Hartian terms) it is even necessary to have participants who
14 Cognition and Reason 283
actors (whether state officials or private parties) perceived it, and could not be sat-
isfactorily understood merely by observation of the actors. The problem, however,
with the Kantian analogy in Kelsen’s pure theory lies in his focus on cognition
rather than reason. Reason is the Kantian faculty by which we systematize cogni-
tions into something we might call science. And it is the teleological impulse of
reason—its inclination to see purposiveness in the “is” of nature as well as the
“ought” of morality—that muddies the dichotomy. My proposal is that we will far
better understand what contract and business lawyers do in their lawyering—to
explore if there is anything like science to it—if we rethink the analogy between the
basic norm and Kantian cognition, and focus on how thinking legally is an exercise
in Kantian reason, of which the law’s use of modus ponens logic (deftly applied in
Allegheny College) is perhaps one of the best examples. Contract law provides a
nice laboratory for this for the very reason so little of it has to do with the commands
of a sovereign, and so much has to do with the rules the parties would have seemed
to legislate for themselves.
Let us consider this in the context of a common and powerful metaphor in con-
tract law and interpretation, the notion that the objective manifestation of the parties
in a contract reflects a “meeting of the minds.” The metaphor suggests that there
really was some objective joinder of hitherto subjective intentions, a kind of Vulcan
mind-meld of self-legislated norms that the litigation process is capable of uncover-
ing. If we take the metaphor seriously, this is not a normative “ought” exercise, but
instead an exercise of constitutive knowledge—an example of phenomenological
experience, whether the source of our knowledge is words on paper or actions of the
parties from which we can imply the “meeting.”
What is our best theory about the shared intentions (if any) of Mrs. Johnston and
Allegheny College regarding the contribution? Judges Cardozo and Kellogg each
wanted to establish what was true about the transaction between Mrs. Johnston and
Allegheny College. But, as a matter of Kant’s epistemology, the real work in acqui-
sition of that constitutive knowledge occurs not in the process of cognition, to which
the categories apply, and which was the basis of Kelsenian analogy for the basic
norm. The work of the categories in simple cognition (ie, cognitive judgments) is
merely to permit the subjective perception of objective reality. The Kantian question
there is “how can there be knowledge in principle of empirical objects or of objec-
tive happenings at all?” (Buchdahl 1969: 483). As Buchdahl noted:
This question is answered by [Kant’s] claiming that we ourselves necessarily inject the logi-
cal character corresponding to this objectivity (the categories) into the perceptual situation.
take the internal point of view. And, assuming that it is necessary, why is the internal point of view
so central? Holton answers his own question:
I suspect the answer lies in the role that we want the notion of law to play in our account of
practical reasoning. We want to explain the distinctive way that the law guides action; and
we want to explain the kinds of pressures that lead practitioners to reform the law (Holton
1998: 625).
That is precisely the kind of answer, unsatisfying as it may be, I am trying to provide here.
284 J.M. Lipshaw
At the same time, the empirical significance of this logical character (here: the categories)
is entirely linked to, and exhausted by, the injective function (Buchdahl 1969: 483).
In other words, what we might perceive by operation of the categories is the most
obvious (and trivial) physical aspects of making contracts: the conversation, the fax,
the e-mail, execution of a written document, Mrs. Johnston’s letter, her statements
constituting repudiation, or the handshake.
Distinguishing reason from the faculties of cognition in Kant’s epistemology is
significant. The knowledge the categories permit is minimal. The categories permit
us to know (ie to make judgments) sufficient enough to make to make our way
through the physical world.35 Susan Neiman (1994: 58–59) observes that without
reason we might still make causal judgments, for example, that one billiard ball
caused another to roll. But it would take reason (for example, the exercise of induc-
tive logic) to assess whether the next collision would have the same result (Neiman
1994: 58). When I assert that knowledge in the sense of Kantian cognition is trivial
in business or contract, I mean that Kant’s categories are the basis upon which we
have any public language in which to express our commonly held subjective percep-
tions of objective things in the world.36 For example, we know the legislature
enacted the Uniform Commercial Code and it is located in the state’s general laws,
a phone conversation took place, two people signed a paper, a truck loaded with
orange crate traveled from Florida to Massachusetts, and the oranges got sold at the
Whole Foods in Cambridge. In contrast, however, what all that means legally, if
anything, goes beyond the mere cognition in which the categories do their concep-
tual work of ordering perceptions.
The assertion that we can know something like the “meeting of the minds” or
“mutual intention of the parties” is far more sophisticated in Kantian terms than the
knowledge provided by mere cognition. To take Kelsen at his word, the creation of
a legal science (at least if we are going to be Kantian about it) means systematiza-
tion of our perception of events in the real world such that we are able effectively
and seriously to use metaphors like “meeting of the minds” to describe what has
happened.37 Scientific claims of knowledge are something quite different from the
kind of knowledge, for example, that allows us to walk down a sidewalk and pro-
cess the information of the world so as to avoid bumping into others or wandering
into the street. Mere cognition, in the sense of the application of Kantian categories
35
Understanding is incapable of anything other than this meager performance because it lacks
autonomy, and its mechanical nature is inseparable from the abstractness of its results. Routinely
and automatically, understanding applies the twelve categories to the given manifold (Neiman
1994, 59).
36
[W]ithout conceptual principles (whose domain is the field of what Kant calls ‘the understand-
ing’) there would be no public language, no ‘nature,’ regarded as the concatenation of things and
happenings, nor any ‘pure science’… (Buchdahl 1969: 476).
37
As Michael Steven Green points out, Kelsen did not think primitive legal meaning, as the analog
to mere cognition, was the end of the story. “Kelsen’s goal is instead to show how the primitive
meanings can be conjoined, through rules of imputation, to generate complex legal meanings or
sanctionability conditions” (Green 2003: 379). My argument, however, is that we cannot be true to
Kant without assessing the role of reason in generating those meanings.
14 Cognition and Reason 285
of a priori synthetic judgments by which we order the objective world, and thereby
walk down the street, is not enough for science.38 Science is not mere cognition, but
instead the exercise of theoretical reason, a series of reflective judgments in which
we apply generalizations about cause-and-effect to empirical circumstances in the
real world. Hence, when we engage in something like an empirical reconstruction
of the parties’ own private legislation to assert they had a “meeting of the minds,”
we use reason to make theoretical claims upon experience, that either what did hap-
pen or what ought, under normal expectations, to have happened, or what will hap-
pen is explicable by natural or social systems.39 As Buchdahl noted, “The existence
of such systems…is not ‘given’ but merely ‘demanded’ by the searching (or ‘regula-
tive’) activity of the scientist, of what Kant calls ‘theoretical reason’” (Buchdahl
1969: 476). For all Kant’s extensive critique of the illusions that pure reason could
create when divorced from experience or possible experience, he viewed this as
reason’s legitimate knowledge-creating use.40
In Kantian epistemology, science is the far more advanced and subtle capability
of determining not just what is, but why it is, and what things could be. Science calls
on the scientist to do something more than merely observe occurrences in the world.
This is the critical difference between Kant’s approach to science and that of Hume.
Hume rejected any metaphysical connection (as, say, in the principle of sufficient
reason articulated by Leibniz) between antecedent and consequent events. That is,
Hume believed there was no metaphysical (or sufficient) reason for something else
to have been just because something is now. Instead, we perceive and attribute cause
and effect merely by the repetitive and constant conjunction of such seemingly
cause-and-effect events (Buchdahl 1969: 473). Kant’s view, on the other hand, was
that empirical science, ie, the subsuming of experience under scientific laws,
requires more than merely the observation of constant conjunction of cause-and-
effect events. Rather, the work of the scientist involves mental activity that operates
a priori and separate from the observations that may or may not bear out the think-
ing. This is what distinguishes scientific knowledge from mere cognitive ordering of
38
Buchdahl (1967: 210) suggests the notion that the categories of the understanding supply a jus-
tification for science, rather than merely the basis for a public language for reporting on events in
the real world, arises from concentration on the Transcendental Aesthetic and Transcendental in
the Critique of Pure Reason rather than the Transcendental Dialectic and its “Appendix” wherein
Kant explains the role of reason in providing foundations for scientific laws.
39
It is not so different, in a far less sophisticated way, than observing that microwave radiation at
far ends of the cosmos is uniform, despite the theory that that universe was already so big when the
radiation was released that there was insufficient time for the ends of the cosmos to communicate
with each other. So despite the absence of evidence and the apparently implausibility of the
hypothesis, Alan Guth suggested in 1980 there was a period of “inflation” when the universe
expanded faster than the speed of light. Other scientists first observed empirical evidence consis-
tent with the inflation theory in 2014 (Overbye 2014).
40
It is easy to miss. In the 1998 Guyer and Wood translation of the Critique of Pure Reason, Kant’s
exposition of the problems created by the exercise of pure reason—the “transcendental dialec-
tic”—runs 205 pages. Kant relegated his discussion of the appropriate use of reason in science,
however, to a mere 33 pages in an “appendix to the transcendental dialectic” (Kant 1781:
384–623).
286 J.M. Lipshaw
41
Buchdahl (1969: 495–506) also offers a detailed account of Kant’s distinction between mere
cognition of nature and theorization by way of reason.
42
Larry Solum (2014: 84) has recently published an insightful essay on this point. The meaning of
a legal text created by a group of individuals has, in his coinage, artificial meaning, ie, a meaning
that is something other than the natural meaning we would impute to speech uttered by a natural
person. Professor Solum focuses on public law—the text of constitutions, statutes, regulations, and
ordinances—but the point applies equally to the text of a negotiated contract. Indeed, consider the
following insight as applied to the putative “mutual intention of the parties” that courts regularly
invoke as the goal of contract interpretation and enforcement:
Legal interpretation is (usually) the parsing of artificial meanings. Grasping these meanings
is not a matter of inferring the mental states of a particular individual or group of individu-
als. When it comes to group agents, mental states play a role in the production of artificial
meanings, but the meanings themselves cannot be reduced to those mental states.
14 Cognition and Reason 287
the deal or after the fact in resolving disputes about it, we are making empirical
judgments about what happens as a rule. In contract litigation, what the parties seek
to determine is not just “what was?” but often an imputation of “what should have
been,” based on our experience of the world given the objective manifestations of
the parties to the transaction.
In Kantian terms, whether theoretical or practical, it is the same faculty of reason
applied to different ends. Kant (1790) treated the implicit “ought” of legitimately
employed theoretical reason (ie, in deriving empirical laws) most significantly in
the Critique of Judgment (and particularly the critique of teleological rather than
aesthetic judgment that constitutes the final third of the work). This normativity
reflects either (i) the “ought” of prediction arising from an observer’s reasoned
expectations about how the world usually operates empirically, and/or (ii) the
“ought” of the observer’s sense of a well-ordered empirical world. As Susan Neiman
(1994: 6) elucidates, proposing ends beyond experience is the fundamental human
capability, and reason, rather than mere cognition, is the means by which the
observer so proposes. Reason stands apart from mere experience and makes
demands upon it, not only morally but theoretically as well. The concepts of the
understanding—our judgments of mere cognition—allow us to synthesize objects
in the world, and to make our way in it, but “reason’s province is freedom.” By that,
Neiman means that freedom is not just the freedom of the autonomous moral agent
to make a moral choice. Reason’s freedom from experience is precisely what allows
us to theorize, to take the data of experience and to impute regularities. The differ-
ence between reason’s operation in the moral and theoretical spheres is the differ-
ence between its constitutive and regulative use. In the moral sphere, reason is free,
“without depending on any purpose as material condition,” to permit us to fathom
the constitutive practical ends to which we strive (Kant 1790: 225).43 But in the
theoretical sphere, reason only serves regulative purposes, even if the nature it seeks
to explain appears to be the product of an intelligent being’s design.44 We seem to be
able to theorize effectively about nature, using reason’s power, because nature
seems to have a purposiveness to it that is comprehensible by human judgment,
even though we have no basis whatsoever for believing that causality in nature has
anything to do with subjective purposiveness. In other words, it is fine to presume
what looks like a subjective purpose to create order when we investigate nature, but
43
Pure Reason, as a practical faculty, i.e., as the faculty of determining the free use of our causality
by Ideas (pure rational concepts), not only comprises in the moral law a regulative principle of our
actions, but supplies us at the same time with a subjective constitutive principle in the concept of
an Object which Reason alone can think, and which is to be actualised by our actions in the world
according to that law. The Idea of a final purpose in the employment of freedom according to moral
laws has therefore subjective practical reality (Kant 1790: 227).
44
But a final purpose is merely a concept of our practical Reason, and can be inferred from no data
of experience for the theoretical judging of nature, nor can it be applied to the cognition of nature
(Kant 1790: 228).
288 J.M. Lipshaw
we need to make sure we remember that we are merely analogizing to such a pur-
pose, and have no empirical basis for assuming one (Kant 1790: 153–154).45
It is not surprising, then, that we conflate the descriptive and the normative, the
“is” and the “ought,” when we deal with the law of contracts. Debates over, say, the
common law mirror image rule versus UCC 2-207 have little to do with the ought
of morality as might, for example, a discussion of unconscionability. In the latter
instance, the positive law incorporates a moral imperative: contracts ought not to be
enforced when they reflect, among other things, a gross imbalance of bargaining
power, information, consideration, etc. The former instance has far more to do with
a view of how the rules ought best to reflect the empirical realities of the business
world. In other words, in any dispute over a contract, we can never really know what
the parties intended subjectively (even what they say they intended is an objective
manifestation), and the notion of an inter-subjective intent is little more than mysti-
cal nonsense. Hence, contract litigation is rarely about knowing the positive law in
the sense of Kantian cognition; instead it is about employing reason in the applica-
tion of legal rules to theorize what did happen or what normally (and, in that sense,
normatively) ought to have happened.
In short, the “ought” of normativity expressed in moral or legal imperatives, and
the “ought” of description expressed in theory, spring from the same source: the
freedom reason affords us not just to perceive but also to adjudge experience. That
is the important Kantian insight.
What, if any, are the implications of these somewhat arcane distinctions for contract
law teachers and practitioners? I do believe there is a payoff. We need to tweak
Kelsen’s positivism to account for the little about contract law itself that is really
knowable in Kantian terms through the faculties of cognition. We do not know the
law; we use its tools to reason to conclusions about experience or possible experi-
ence, to create theories that explain descriptively or theories that adjudge norma-
tively. And because reason itself does not distinguish between descriptions of
experience and normative imperatives, our understanding of the kind of law the
parties make for themselves quite naturally melds the empirical and the ideal. For
45
…[T]here must then have preceded a rationalising subtlety which only sportively introduces the
concept of purpose into the nature of things, but which does not derive it from Objects or from their
empirical cognition. To this latter it is of more service to make nature comprehensible according to
analogy with the subjective ground of the connexion of our representations, than to cognise it from
objective grounds (Kant 1790: 153).
14 Cognition and Reason 289
46
Alida Wilson (1986: 49–50) suggests that Kelsen’s commitment to the idea of law as an “ideal
reality” was fleeting. As she correctly points out, the first line of both versions of the introduction
to the Critique of Pure Reason is Kant’s statement to the effect that all cognition begins with
experience.
David Gray Carlson (2009: 23–24) has made a similar point regarding H.L.A. Hart’s expres-
sion of positivism—one that has largely crowded out Kelsen’s in Anglo-American jurisprudence.
Professor Carlson’s thesis is (a) the core of Hart’s positivism is to take the official’s internal point
of view—her acknowledgment that something is law according to the rule of recognition—as
empirically present in the world; (b) making a judgment from an internal (and subjective) point of
view is never, in Kantian terms, an empirical matter, but rather “a matter of belief, as licensed by
theoretical reason; (c) the Hartian internal point of view is morality—ie the exercise of reason with
respect to the question “what to do”—from a Kantian perspective; and (d) therefore Hart’s separa-
tion thesis (of law from morality) fails.
47
Per one of the leading philosophers of business in the twentieth century, John F. Welch, Jr., the
former chairman and CEO of General Electric: “Face reality as it is, not as it was or as you wish it
to be” (Welch).
290 J.M. Lipshaw
And what is the end result of all this hard thinking about nature? Strangely, by the
very nature of reason itself, there is always another question to ask, another particu-
lar to try to fit within the systematic whole, and our entire experience of seeking
reasoned explanation operates “asymptotically, as it were,” finding more and more
systematic unity, but without ever reaching the final unifying principle of everything
(Kant 1781: 601–602). Whether it is making a demand of order upon nature (its
appropriate theoretical use) or seeking a correct answer to the practical question
“what to do next” (its appropriate practical use), reason looks to subsume the mani-
fold of experience in fewer and fewer rules.
Though I never speak of it in those terms to my first-year contract law students,
it is transcendental illusion about which I caution them almost from the first day of
class. In the real world of working lawyers and business people, the end of the legal
process in contract is something we can know because it is a document or a judg-
ment or an order that has conventional meaning. The legal process itself, in the
sense of contracts, pleadings, discovery, motions, trial, and appeals, is as well
empirically knowable. Why? Because they are constitutive of experience or possible
experience, whether we know them as a matter of cognition or the exercise of theo-
retical reason. We employ the tools of the law in making legal judgments; that
employment is the regulative exercise of reason. To mistake either the a priori
regulative process of reason or the ends to which we can reason for constitutive
48
Even Quine and Ullian, while rejecting synthetic a priori knowledge as a helpful concept,
thought there were five “virtues” underlying hypotheses: conservatism, modesty, simplicity, gen-
erality, and refutability. “Hypothesis, where successful, is a two-way street, extending back to
explain the past and forward to predict the future. What we try to do in framing hypotheses is to
explain some otherwise unexplained happenings by inventing a plausible story, a plausible descrip-
tion or history of portions of the world.” (Quine and Ullian (1998: 405).
14 Cognition and Reason 291
49
It is fashionable now to criticize Langdell (1871: vi–vii), but his statement of purpose in the first
contracts casebook still resonates with me as an apt description of law as the product of reason,
whether applied descriptively or normatively:
Law, considered as a science, consists of certain principles or doctrines. To have such a
mastery of these as to be able to apply them with constant facility and certainty to the ever-
tangled skein of human affairs, is what constitutes a true lawyer; and hence to acquire that
mastery should be the business of every earnest student of law.…[T]he number of funda-
mental legal doctrines is much less than is commonly supposed.…If these doctrines could
be so classified and arranged that each should be found in its proper place, and nowhere
else, they would cease to be formidable in their number.
292 J.M. Lipshaw
50
Robin Kar has recently undertaken a thoughtful and original attempt at a unified theory (as well
as a summary of the extant descriptive and normative theories) of contract law (Kar 2014). The
paper proposes to respond to the observation of Professors Schwartz and Scott that there is no
“complete” descriptive or normative theory. What is interesting to me, beyond the specifics of
Professor Kar’s very interesting take on the philosophical underpinnings of contract law, is the
question why we feel the need, as he suggests in the introduction, to “harmonize certain core areas
of doctrine,” to “provide[] unified answers,” or why it is a problem that contract law has no com-
plete descriptive or normative theory, or that the theories “fail to offer a unified understanding of…
seemingly disparate features of contract law.” As I have made clear here, I believe the answer to
that question has less to do with contract law than with our seemingly hardwired inclination to
teleology: that there are unified explanations, that doctrine ought to be harmonized, that the world
ought to be seen as coherent.
51
It is the assumption required “at first” because it is possible that the cases may not be reconcil-
able. “Hence, in your matching of cases, you may, as a last resort when unable to make the cases
fit together, fall back upon the answer: here there is a conflict; these cases represent two different
points of view” (Llewellyn 2012: 51).
52
One of the difficulties with Ronald Dworkin’s (1996) critique of positivism is the fact that he
seems to tap into precisely this kind of noumena as justification for single correct answers in hard
cases. Hence, Dworkin seems to believe that single correct answers are possible because we can
know objective moral facts (Lipshaw 2006: 991–993).
14 Cognition and Reason 293
the other side who seemed to be less concerned about the underlying deal and more
concerned about winning the game of contract drafting (ie, outscoring the other
lawyer on the number of his or her competing provisions ultimately included).
14.5 Conclusion
Perhaps as the result of a long career in doing law “purely” as a law firm lawyer and
“not-so-purely” as an interdisciplinary law-and-business practitioner, I am far more
inclined to think of law in the context of lawyering, and thus doing, rather than
thinking of it as an object of demarcation and classification. This is the conundrum
at the heart of the positivist project at least as it appears in the law of contracts: that
cognition of the “law” on the books or the physical reality of contracts is each trivial
from an epistemological standpoint, and the whole game is in the theories, some-
times descriptive and sometimes normative, that constitute the systematic applica-
tion of rules to circumstances, whether before or after the fact. No single label
serves us particularly well. To call what we are doing mere practical reason, for
example, suggests that our only goal is to decide what to do, and fails to acknowl-
edge the descriptive theorizing we often need to do about what actually happened in
the creation of the legal norms.53 “Formalism,” for example, in the sense of a pre-
sumption that the parties are best served by a derivation of their rights and obliga-
tions from the text of the document, is simply a practical guide to the exercise of
both practical and theoretical reason in resolving the issue. Even after Hart’s over-
shadowing of Kelsen, the pure theory and the basic norm open the door to an assess-
ment of what it means to do law that is, to me, more satisfying than Hart’s approach,
even if I wonder from time to time about the aridness of the entire philosophical
project of distilling legal norms from all the other “oughts” by which we live.
My pluralism as to exploration of the objective and the subjective knows few
bounds. Reason may well be the slave of the passions in employment of legal doc-
trine (and I do teach it that way because we live in a passionate world), but long
experience at the intersection of law and business inclines me to think we are free
and autonomous moral agents when we make the choice in the first instance to turn
to law rather than all the other possible norms that inform relationships. That is, the
reasoning we happen to do as lawyers is not particularly privileged, notwithstanding
the efforts of Kelsen and others to distill and fence off law as an academic or profes-
sional discipline. Kant wanted to deny knowledge of that which is not knowable to
make legitimate room for faith; I prefer to deny that law (at least for the business
lawyer) is something we know as a matter of a priori cognition so as to make room
53
In other words, I do not believe contract and business lawyering is only an exercise in practical
reason, at least in the Kantian sense. I acknowledge there is a long history of jurisprudential debate
about law as the product of practical reason or theoretical reason; it should be obvious by this point
that I believe it is the product of human reason of some kind, but it is no more or less “real” on
either account. For a brief overview of this particular issue, see Burton (1988).
294 J.M. Lipshaw
for theoretical and practical reason that takes account of law, morality, principle,
compromise, civility, and pragmatism. Even more radically, I see Kant’s account of
reason itself as merely one of a number of cognitive processes—among them, for
example, the kind of metaphoric thinking and cognitive blending proposed by
George Lakoff, Mark Turner, Gilles Fauconnier, Mark Johnson, Steven Pinker and
others—that mediate between our cognition of the world around us and acting in
response to it (Gibbs 2008; Lakoff and Johnson 1980 and 1999; Turner 2001; Pinker
2007).
They will all be on my guest list for the bird-fish wedding.
References
Kant, Immanuel. 1781. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. P. Guyer and A.W. Wood 1999. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Kant, Immanuel. 1783. Prolegomena to Any Future Metaphysics. Trans. P. Carus 1949. Chicago:
Open Court.
Kant, Immanuel. 1785. Fundamental Principles of the Metaphysics of Morals. Trans. F.M. Muller.
In Basic writings of Kant, ed. Allen W. Wood, 2001. New York: Modern Library.
Kant, Immanuel. 1790. Critique of Judgment. Trans. J.H. Bernard 2005. Amherst: Prometheus
Books.
Kar, Robin Bradley. 2014. Contract as empowerment. Social Science Research Network. http://
papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=2476148. Accessed 13 Aug 2014.
Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. B.L. Paulson and
S.L. Paulson 1996. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Konefsky, Alfred S. 1987. How to read, or at least not misread, Cardozo in the Allegheny College
case. Buffalo Law Review 36: 645–700.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1980. Metaphors we live by. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Lakoff, George, and Mark Johnson. 1999. Philosophy in the flesh: The embodied mind and its
challenge to western thought. New York: Basic Books.
Langdell, C.C. 1871. Selection of cases on the law of contracts. Clark: The Lawbook Exchange,
Ltd.
Lipshaw, Jeffrey M. 2006. Law as rationalization: Getting beyond reason to business ethics.
University of Toledo Law Review 37: 959–1020.
Lipshaw, Jeffrey M. 2007. Freedom, compulsion, compliance and mystery: Reflections on a duty
not to enforce a promise. Law Culture and the Humanities 3: 82–101.
Lipshaw, Jeffrey M. 2012a. Contract as meaning: An introduction to “Contract as Promise at 30”.
Suffolk Law Review 36: 601–625.
Lipshaw, Jeffrey M. 2012b. Metaphors, models, and meaning in contract law. Penn State Law
Review 116: 987–1042.
Llewellyn, K.N. 2012. The bramble bush: On our law and its study. New Orleans: QuidPro Books.
Neiman, Susan. 1994. The unity of reason: Rereading Kant. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Overbye, Dennis. 2014. Space ripples reveal big bang’s smoking gun. New York Times, March 18.
Oxford Dictionaries, s.v. “Mould”. Accessed 13 Aug 2014. http://www.oxforddictionaries.com/
definition/english/mould.
Patterson, Dennis. 1999. Law and truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Paulson, Stanley. 1997. Introduction. In Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans.
B.L. Paulson., and S.L. Paulson, 1996. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pinker, Steven. 2007. The stuff of thought: Language as a window into human nature. New York:
Penguin.
Quine, W.V., and J.S. Ullian. 1998. Hypothesis. In Introductory readings in the philosophy of sci-
ence, 3rd ed, ed. E.D. Klemke, Hollinger Robert, and Rudge David Wÿss, 404–414. Amherst:
Prometheus Books.
Solum, Lawrence B. 2014. Artificial meaning. Washington Law Review 89: 69–86.
Stein, Joseph, Jerry Bock, and Sheldon Harnick. 2004. Fiddler on the roof: Based on Sholom
Aleichem’s stories. Milwaukee: Limelight Editions.
Stumpff, Andrew Morrison. 2013. The law is a fractal: The attempt to anticipate everything.
Loyola University Chicago Law Journal 44: 649–682.
Suchman, Marc C. 2003. The contract as social artifact. Law and Society Review 37: 91–142.
Turner, Mark. 2001. Cognitive dimensions of social science: The way we think about politics,
economics, law, and society. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Walsh, W.H. 1975. Kant’s criticism of metaphysics. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.
Weinrib, Ernest J. 1987. Law as a Kantian idea of reason. Columbia Law Review 87: 472–508.
Welch, Jack, Goodreads, https://www.goodreads.com/author/quotes/3770.Jack_Welch.
296 J.M. Lipshaw
Williams, Garrath. 2013. Kant’s account of reason. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy,
2013 ed., http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/kant-reason/.
Wilson, Alida. 1986. Is Kelsen really a Kantian? In Essays on Kelsen 37–64, ed. Richard Tur and
William Twining, 37–64. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Wolcher, Louis. 2008. Law’s task: The tragic circle of law, justice, and human suffering. Burlington:
Ashgate Publishing Company.
Zipursky, Benjamin. 2006. Introduction—symposium, the internal point of view in law and ethics.
Fordham Law Review 75: 1143–1156.
Chapter 15
Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law:
Primary and Secondary Norms
Drury D. Stevenson
15.1 Introduction
Hans Kelsen argued that all individual laws primarily address state actors rather
than the citizens. Ancient edicts or imperatives, such as, “Thou shalt not murder,”
address the whole citizenry. Modern laws, in contrast, address state actors who must
execute, apply, or implement the law. For example, consider the opening line of
New York’s first-degree murder statute: “A person is guilty of murder in the first
degree when, with intent to cause the death of another person, he causes the death
of such person or of a third person, and…the defendant was more than 18 years old
at the time of the commission of the crime” (N.Y. Penal Law § 125.27). Kelsen’s
observation, even taken in isolation rather than as a component of Kelsen’s grand
theories, has significant implications; it has received too little attention in the academic
literature in the United States.1 The point also presents some difficult challenges to
popular American ideas about the law, so it may help explain why Kelsen’s works
have not gained more traction among American legal theorists.
Kelsen’s view of the addressee of laws is also important for understanding
Kelsen’s larger theories overall. On the one hand, the passages where Kelsen bears
down on the point are those where he comes closest to solving Hume’s “is-ought”
problem—he verges on describing an “ought” (a legal norm) without invoking
another “ought” besides the Grundnorm. These are passages where the discussion
becomes purely positive. On the other hand, Kelsen often lapses from this rigorous
position throughout his writings and routinely gives examples of norms
1
For a typical criticism, see Ota Weinberger (Weinberger 1985: 321), “strongly opposing” Kelsen’s
view.
D.D. Stevenson (*)
Hutchins Research Professor, South Texas College of Law, Houston, TX 77002, USA
James A. Baker III Institute, Rice University, Houston, TX 77005, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
communicating rules directly to the citizens, a contradiction that makes his work
confusing.2 Kelsen himself attempted to smooth over this problem by suggesting
that every law actually contains two inherent legal norms: a primary norm (instructing
a state actor to sanction certain conduct) and a secondary norm (deterring citizens
from engaging in sanctionable conduct, or committing the delict).
From a formalist perspective, Kelsen’s observation is robustly descriptive of
modern statutes (legislative laws), which nearly all use indicative rather than imper-
ative verbs forms. Earlier legal philosophers, such as Bentham3 (Bentham 1999:
119–123) and Austin (Austin 1832: 12–20), had recommended a shift from impera-
tive to indicative verbs, but were unwilling to concede that the primary addressee of
each law is the government organ that must apply or execute it, rather than those
whose conduct the law ultimately seeks to control. This author has traced the his-
torical development of these concepts elsewhere (Stevenson 2003: 105).
My discussion fleshes out these points, and develops Kelsen’s addressee concept
a bit further. Section 15.2 surveys what Kelsen actually said about this issue. This
concept is not one of Kelsen’s better-known tenets, and even some readers who
consider themselves Kelsenians might benefit from reviewing these oft-ignored
excerpts. Section 15.3 explores the implications of Kelsen’s addressee concept for
understanding the persistence of technical terms and jargon within laws, for under-
standing certain interpretive rules pertaining to legislative delegations to executive
agencies, and for understanding the boundaries of executive and judicial power.
Section 15.4 applies the concept to the inherent problems with executive sub-
delegations of state functions to private corporations.
2
The same problem seems to beset those who write about Kelsen’s ideas, referring to the citizenry
as the “addressees” of the law under Kelsen’s system (Somek 2006: 765–772; Stewart 1990: 284;
Wilson 1981: 275).
3
Bentham believed that his great project for modern codification would only work if the citizens
knew exactly what was expected of them” (Bentham 1999: 122). To this end, he proposed that
codes follow a logical organization, in part to facilitate memorization by those governed (Bentham
1999: 119–123). Part of his attempt to create a comprehensive utilitarian code was the division of
laws into categories of those that affect everyone and those that affect only some people, so that
people could readily identify the sections that they should know by heart regardless of their
situation.
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 299
In Kelsen’s magnum opus, Pure Theory of Law, he introduced the concept of the
law’s addressee (without using that term in this book) by observing that each statute
technically contains two “norms”—one commanding certain behavior from the citi-
zenry, and another directing legal organs, such as the executive or courts, to sanction
violations (Kelsen 1960: 55). The latter, he maintained, was the one that truly mat-
tered and that could stand alone in the legal formulations of modern laws. The for-
mer (the “command” or prohibition that is what most people mean when they speak
of a “law”) is impliedly (even tacitly) present in the latter (the sanction provision),
making the former “superfluous” or unnecessary verbiage in a modern code.
Kelsen’s argument in Pure Theory on this point unfolded as follows: suppose that a
statute contains two legal norms, one prescribing certain behavior by the citizenry,
and another norm imposing sanctions when citizens violate the first norm. In this
case, Kelsen says, the first norm is inherently dependent on the second norm—the
proscribed behavior is merely a triggering condition for the imposition of a punish-
ment by the state. Taking the point a step further, Kelsen then says, “[T]he first one
is superfluous from the point of view of the legislative technique” (Kelsen 1960:
55). As an example, Kelsen posits a debtor with a legal obligation to repay a credi-
tor; the relevant statute directs the courts to execute judgment on the possessions of
the delinquent debtor in order to repay the debt, at least under certain circumstances.
The fact that a statute orders execution on debtors under certain circumstances auto-
matically implies (or “contains,” as Kelsen says) the fact that the debtor has an
obligation to repay the debt under those circumstances (Kelsen 1960: 55). In fact,
including statutory language declaring debtors’ legal duties would be superfluous,
because the sanctioning provision is sufficient standing alone. Modern statutes,
unlike ancient codes, favor the succinct sanctioning form and often skip the com-
manding language that would address the citizens directly. Kelsen reaches a rather
dramatic conclusion: “This shows clearly that a norm like, ‘You shall not murder,’
is superfluous, if this other norm is also valid: ‘He who murders ought to be pun-
ished’” (Kelsen 1960: 55). In other words, a legal order prohibits behaviors merely
by imposing sanctions for their occurrence, and requires whatever behavior is the
opposite of that which triggers the statutory punishments.
Kelsen’s terminology evolved over time—here, he uses “independent norm” and
“dependent norm” for what he would later call “primary” and “secondary” norms,
respectively. Yet the core idea is that the real “law” is the rule directing the state
actor to carry out a certain action (sanction) against certain individuals (those who
commit the delict). While he seems to be focusing on “legislative technique,” that is,
stylistic conventions in drafting, the forcefulness of his argument hints that there is
something more profound at work here, something closely tied to his overall theory
about the state and the nature of law. What most people call “the law” is merely the
dependent norm of a given statute, and the fact that it is “superfluous” suggests that
intuitions (or common parlance, if the two are distinguishable) about the “law” are
commonly mistaken.
300 D.D. Stevenson
In The General Theory of Law and State, Kelsen develops the idea more extensively,
beginning with his point from Pure Theory that it was superfluous to include the
part of a law directed at the would-be offender (Kelsen 1945: 61–62). The “ought”
of any legal norm, Kelsen claims, is “an epiphenomenon of the ‘ought’ of the sanc-
tion” (Kelsen 1945: 61). He challenges the conventional notion that legal norms
4
See, eg, other examples of imperatives to the rulers that imply a dependent norm, such as Exodus
21:15 (“Anyone who attacks their father or mother is to be put to death.”); Exodus 21:29 (“If,
however, the bull has had the habit of goring and the owner has been warned but has not kept it
penned up and it kills a man or woman, the bull is to be stoned and its owner also is to be put to
death.”); Exodus 22:18 (“Do not allow a sorceress to live.”); Exodus 22:19 (“Anyone who has
sexual relations with an animal is to be put to death.”); Exodus 31:15 (“Whoever does any work on
the Sabbath day is to be put to death.”). Lest the reader think that all Old Testament sanctions
involved death, there are many requiring restitution instead. See, eg, Leviticus 24:21 (“Whoever
kills an animal must make restitution, but whoever kills a human being is to be put to death.”);
Exodus 22:3 (“Anyone who steals must certainly make restitution, but if they have nothing, they
must be sold to pay for their theft.”); Exodus 22:6 (“If a fire breaks out and spreads into thorn-
bushes so that it burns shocks of grain or standing grain or the whole field, the one who started the
fire must make restitution.”); Exodus 22:14 (“If anyone borrows an animal from their neighbor and
it is injured or dies while the owner is not present, they must make restitution”).
More interesting, from the standpoint of Kelsen’s view of norms and the state, are divine edicts
that are general rules or limitations on sanctioning, without any “secondary” or “dependent” norm
for the citizenry. See, eg, Numbers 35:30 (“Anyone who kills a person is to be put to death as a
murderer only on the testimony of witnesses. But no one is to be put to death on the testimony of
only one witness.”); Deuteronomy 17:6 (same); or Deuteronomy 24:16 (“Parents are not to be put to
death for their children, nor children put to death for their parents; each will die for their own sin.”).
All foregoing biblical quotes are from the New International Version. Other modern writers have
developed more thorough literary discussions of other Old Testament mandates (Bartor 2012: 292).
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 301
contain two “ought” statements, one directed at the citizenry (mandating or forbidding
some action on their part), and one for the state officials with a duty of enforcement,
that is, a first norm and a second norm. In rebuttal, Kelsen invokes an example of
theft, similar to his use of murder as an example previously in Pure Theory: “One
shall not steal; if somebody steals, he shall be punished. If it is assumed that the first
norm which forbids theft is valid only if the second norm attaches a sanction to
theft, then the first norm is certainly superfluous in an exact exposition of law.”
Kelsen concludes that the supposed first norm (the rule the citizen must obey) is
already contained in the second norm (the imposition of punishment when certain
conduct has occurred). This second norm, Kelsen insists, is truly “the only genuine
legal norm” (Kelsen 1945: 61). Kelsen argued that the “law” is not the prohibition
of a given act, but the mandate to the state to sanction the act, because the former
cannot exist without the latter (Kelsen 1945: 61).
In the same chapter, Kelsen then introduces the terms “primary norm” and “sec-
ondary norm,” which are somewhat counterintuitive, or at least run counter to usual
conventions of writing or parlance, conceding that it greatly facilitates legal discus-
sions “if we allow ourselves to assume also the existence of the first norm. To do so
is legitimate only if one is aware of the fact that the first norm, which demands
omission of the delict, is dependent upon the second norm, which stipulates the
sanction” (Kelsen 1945: 61). Somewhat confusingly, Kelsen proposes designating
“the second norm as the primary norm, and the first norm as the secondary norm”
(Kelsen 1945: 61). The former refers to the citizens’ behavior that the law seeks to
incentivize by threat of sanctions (what we normally refer to as the “unlawful
behavior,” or in Kelsen’s jargon, the “delict”). Kelsen contends that it is untenable
to have a legal system comprised only of these secondary norms; instead, law in
reality is “a coercive order which stipulates sanctions,” not merely prohibitions, or
actions that elicit punishment (Kelsen 1945: 61).
Kelsen then takes a strong turn, designating law itself as “the primary norm,
which stipulates the sanction, and this norm is not contradicted by the delict of the
subject, which, on the contrary, is the specific condition of the sanction” (Kelsen
1945: 61). A state entity or official is the only actor that can truly “counteract” a law,
by refusing to implement or apply it. Even so, Kelsen concedes, when we speak of
an act as “unlawful,” we normally do not have in mind the behavior of the state
actors who apply and enforce the law, but the citizen whose behavior has triggered
the sanctions prescribed by the law (Kelsen 1945: 61).
Kelsen argues that the technical obligation or duty imposed by the law itself is
toward state actors; the idea that a citizen “ought” to avoid a prohibited act is an
indirect implication of the statute’s plain language requiring the state to impose a
penalty on individuals engaged in the prohibited act. Only by referring to a “second-
ary norm” can one say that a citizen “ought” to do something required by the law (or
avoid something prohibited) (Kelsen 1945: 61). The governmental entity or officials
entrusted with applying and implementing the law are those who truly obey or
disobey the primary legal norm. Moreover, Kelsen says that it is necessary to use
this terminological distinction to define the law’s relationship to the citizens and the
state (Kelsen 1945: 61). From this vantage point, the law “is efficacious if it is
302 D.D. Stevenson
applied by the organ—if the organ executes the sanction. And the organ has to apply
law precisely in the case where the subject ‘disobeys’ law: this is the case for which
the sanction is stipulated” (Kelsen 1945: 62).
5
The original title was Allegemeine Theorie der Normen . This lengthy work was among Kelsen’s
unpublished papers at the time of his death in 1973, and first appeared in German in 1979.
6
Kelsen goes on to say that no subject of the law can decide whether she has obeyed or violated
the law. Rather, only the relevant legal organ can make that determination (of compliance or viola-
tion)—at least, a determination that is legally relevant (Kelsen 1979: 54–55).
7
I have written an extensive refutation to Dan-Cohen’s article elsewhere (Stevenson 2003:
132–36).
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 303
This is true not only of the general legal command of the legislator, but also of the
individual legal command of the judge”8 (Kelsen 1979: 57).
Near the end of General Theory of Norms, Kelsen returns to this point, explain-
ing why the norm addressed to the legal organ is “primary” and the indirect norm
for the citizenry is “secondary,” rather than the other way around9 (Kelsen 1979:
142–143). Kelsen’s concluding point seems to be that law without a sanction is not
really law, but he addresses this point in his other works, explaining that sanction-
less norms can still induce behavior because adherents want social approval, credi-
bility, and so on. General Theory of Norms also develops a detailed theory of
desuetude for laws that state officials or judges no longer follow or enforce.
To summarize, Kelsen’s discussion of this point became increasingly detailed
through the years as he wrote subsequent books. By the end, he recognized that this
point—that laws are addressed to the judiciary and executive organs—is necessary
for understanding that law is autonomous. This appears to be an under-appreciated
component or feature of Kelsen’s overall system, a point to which he returned repeat-
edly, and a point he seemed to consider inseparable from the rest of his theory.
This Part explores the implications of Kelsen’s addressee concept for understanding
the persistence of technical terms and jargon within laws. It also discusses interpre-
tive rules pertaining to legislative delegations to executive agencies, and for under-
standing the boundaries of executive and judicial power.
Given that the addressee of the laws (or at least primary addressee) is a state organ,
like courts or bureaucrats, then it is unimportant to have laws in language that is
easily understandable to laypersons or the citizenry overall. The plain language
8
Kelsen concludes that objectively observing or violating a command occurs when the behavior
addressed by the law comports with the law’s prescription, regardless of the knowledge of the
actor, while subjectively obeying or violating a law requires knowledge and intent on the part of
the actor concerning compliance.
9
The translator’s Introduction to General Theory of Norms observes the following about this
aspect of Kelsen’s thought in the book:
ATN [?] clarifies things considerably; a legal norm has two addresses, one immediate (the
official) and the other mediate (the person liable to the sanction), and both addressees can
observe or violate the norm; this implies that the effect of the norm on both addressees is
one of commanding. It imposes a legal duty on the mediate addressee, and on the official it
imposes some sort of requirement which is something other than a legal duty but which is
never explained.
Id. at xl.
304 D.D. Stevenson
10
See, eg, Siegel’s biographical summary at http://www.siegelgale.com/team_member/
alan-siegel/.
11
See also www.commongood.org.
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 305
The Plain English Movement has perhaps its most appealing argument when it
comes to jury instructions. The legal system intentionally includes layperson-citizen
jurors in litigation decision-making. There is an easy, intuitive appeal to the idea
that jury instructions about the law need to be in terms the jurors comprehend. Legal
language reformers insist that jurors find the judge’s explanation of the law incom-
prehensible, especially if the judge uses technical legal terms or jargon (likely to
occur if the judge quotes the relevant statute or caselaw itself). Yet even here, recent
empirical studies demonstrate that that the Plain English advocates are mistaken. In
a recent study by Shari Siedman Diamond, Beth Murphy, and Mary R. Rose, in
which they observed and analyzed the deliberations of 50 real juries in actual trials,
it appears the traditional jury instructions were not the problem. “[W]hen commu-
nication breaks down, the breakdown stems from more fundamental sources than
simply opaque legal language.…We conclude that it will take more than a ‘plain
English’ movement to achieve genuine harmony between laypersons and jury
instructions on the law” (Diamond et al. 2012: 1537).
The Plain English movement seems even more misguided in pushing for the
redrafting of statutes and regulations in “user-friendly” English, as this endeavor
seems premised upon an ideological commitment to having citizens read the laws.
A number of sections of the modern Code of Federal Regulations (C.F.R.) contain
repeated use of “when you do this,” and “we will try to do this.”12 It is futile to
rewrite laws in non-legal language merely to make the laws “accessible” to the citi-
zenry, as the citizenry is not the real addressee. This is not to say that we should
favor grandiloquence, anachronisms, or poor grammar. The law serves its purpose
when it is understandable to agency officials, judges, law enforcement officers, and
perhaps (but not necessarily) lawyers.13 The efficient course would be to cast the law
in terms both familiar and facile to this group. Clarity and precision are helpful to
courts and officials as much as for others. Judges and officials live in the modern
era, and overly antiquated language may hinder, rather than facilitate, their tasks.
Cumbersome language consumes time in deciphering and explaining, and can be a
waste of judicial resources, whether in statutes or older court opinions. Even so, the
benchmark should be the readability for a judge (most of whom have law degrees)
or the relevant government official (usually experienced and specialized in
that field).
12
See, eg, 20 C.F.R. §404.1530 (2002) (“In order to get benefits, you must follow treatment pre-
scribed by your physician if this treatment can restore your ability to work”).
13
Maley observes that the grammatical layout of statutes, which are generally one continuous
sentence, was historically motivated by the belief in the legal community that “it is easier to con-
strue a single sentence than a series of sentences, and that there is therefore less potential for
uncertainty” (Maley 1994: 24). While this belief may be mistaken, it has led draftsmen to use
complex patterns of subordinate clauses, making for greater lexical density. Maley notes that even
with modern formatting, such as indentation of subordinate clauses, “the syntactic complexity
-probably more than technical terms -renders legislative texts incomprehensible to all except the
specialist reader.” He notes that drafters prefer repetition of nouns rather than employing pronouns
for the same reason (Maley 1994: 25).
306 D.D. Stevenson
It makes little sense to talk about citizens “interpreting” the ambiguous statutory
language, as a private individual’s personal interpretation of a statutory term would
not be recognized in our courts. Certainly, a legislature would not leave ambiguity
in a statute in order to delegate discretion or power to individual citizens, which
would be result of the citizens having legal rights to make authoritative interpreta-
tion of the law, even for oneself. Kelsen discusses this idea and argues that whatever
discretion that may appear to be left to citizens themselves is not “authentic, because
it is not binding on the state agents responsible for enforcement and punishment14
(Kelsen 1960: 355). Interestingly, Kelsen distinguishes state interpretation of legal
texts from interpretations by the citizenry in stark terms: “The interpretation by a
law-applying organ [of the state] is different from any other interpretation—all other
interpretations are not authentic, that is, they do not create law” (Kelsen 1960: 355).
Jargon or “legalease” is appropriate and efficient where the primary interpreters
or recipients of the communication are familiar with the nomenclature or shorthand
for complex concepts. The “law” directed at the citizenry is not, in fact, the text of
the statute or regulation, but the sanction of the state organ against those who engage
in the delineated behavior. There is obvious utility in technical vocabulary, as every
profession develops its own shorthand expressions, technical terms, acronyms, and
other jargon (Maley 1994: 24–25). One word, such as “domicile,” “Mirandize,”
“bailment,” or “assignee,” can capture and communicate an entire phrase or set of
ideas to one trained in the profession. It does not undermine democracy that a per-
son on the street does not understand “bailments” or know that “consideration” in a
contract does not mean altruism, neighborliness, or contemplation (Tiersma 1999:
106–110). Such terms are for individuals empowered to implement the legal text
with the force of the state. Similarly, legal complexity (volume of laws and provi-
sions, intricacy of legal procedures, and systemic redundancies (checks and bal-
ances) are appropriate despite being the target of perennial complaints from
would-be reformers.15 The systematization and compilation of laws inherent in
14
In the same section, Kelsen argues that an attorney who, in the interest of his client, propounds
to the judge only one of several possible interpretations of the legal norm to be applied in the case,
or a writer who in his commentary extols a specific interpretation among many possible ones as the
only correct one, does not render a function of legal science, but of legal politics.
15
The plight of an average citizen has become an issue in Supreme Court decisions—Citizens
United v. F.E.C., 130 S. Ct 876 (2010), being the prime example. There, the majority based its
holding in part upon the prolixity of campaign regulations, apparently adopting a void-for-verbos-
ity rule:
These entities are subject to separate rules for 33 different types of political speech. The
FEC has adopted 568 pages of regulations, 1278 pages of explanations and justifications for
those regulations, and 1771 advisory opinions since 1975…Prolix laws chill speech for the
same reason that vague laws chill speech: People ‘of common intelligence must necessarily
guess at [the law’s] meaning and differ as to its application.’
Citizens United < 130 S. Ct. at 888–889. Professor Mila Sohoni recently commented that this
“may be the first modern instance of the Supreme Court treating the volume and complexity per se
of a federal regulatory scheme as an unacceptable burden on the exercise of a fundamental right”
(Sohoni 2012: 1600). Similarly, in Sampson v. Buescher, 625 F.3d 1247, 1259 (10th Cir. 2010), the
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 307
modern codification produce law designed for the efficient implementation by the
state-organ recipient, not the citizenry.
In The Concept of Law, H.L.A. Hart included a lengthy attack on Kelsen’s concept
of the law’s addressee (Hart 1961: 35–40). The thrust of his argument is that there
must be some way for citizens to discover or know their legal duties, so that they can
conform their behavior accordingly. Thus, he concludes, the law must primarily
address those whose behavior it seeks to control (Hart 1961: 40). In fact, Hart flips
Kelsen’s nomenclature of “primary” and “secondary” laws. He uses the former to
refer to the citizen-targeted aspect and the latter refer to the instructions to judges
and officials about application and implementation (Hart 1961: 94–97). Hart criti-
cizes Kelsen’s point that the citizen-oriented norm is superfluous and can be missing
entirely from statutory text. He ignores the important fact that most modern statutes
are, in fact, written in the indicative mood using the very form that Kelsen recom-
mended—that is, free from the superfluity that Hart thinks is the “primary” part of
the law.
I have written an extensive answer elsewhere to the question of how the laws
deter citizens, in practice, from the sanctioned behavior (Stevenson 2005: 1535
et seq.); here I will merely summarize the argument. The critical problem with
Hart’s view—which is the prevailing view—is that citizens do not read the law;
most citizens will go through their whole lives without ever reading a single statute.
They see signage announcing speed limits, forbidden access, and so forth, and some
signs actually include a citation to a statute or ordinance. During the era of
Blockbuster video, people would see (and usually fast-forward through) a display of
the F.B.I.’s warnings about copyright violations (pirated video), which included a
quote from a statute. Most of the population is able to conform their behavior to the
requirements of the law reasonably well without ever reading the statutory text
itself. If, as Hart claims, the law must address the citizens if they are to conform
their behavior to it, how does this communication occur when we can easily observe
that almost nobody reads the laws?16 How does a law deter behavior without the
deterred individuals ever reading the laws?
court said, “The average citizen cannot be expected to master on his or her own the many cam-
paign [laws and regulations]. Even if those rules that apply to issue committees may be few, one
would have to sift through them all to determine which apply.” In Doctor’s Hospital of Hyde Park
v. Appeal of Daiwa Special Asset Corp., 337 F.3d 951 (7th Cir. 2003), the court declared, “There
are an enormous number of state laws, and it might be unreasonable to expect a person…to deter-
mine in advance the possible bearing of all of them.”
16
Some may answer that people ask lawyers to read the law for them, and inform them of its con-
tent, but most individuals in society do not consult lawyers before they make decisions—that
luxury is largely reserved for corporations and wealthy individuals. For a recent article recognizing
that those who end up being liable for patent infringement never read patent laws themselves, in a
308 D.D. Stevenson
A variety of possible explanations are available for this phenomenon, but regard-
less of the mechanism, the point is clear that most people conform to the law most
of the time without ever reading it, so it is not necessary to posit that law address the
citizens directly in order to explain the survival of civic society. People often have a
vague notion about the laws pertaining to their activities, and in the presence of
uncertainty about the particulars, they steer clear of the imagined outer limits of
whatever the rules might be (Stevenson 2005: 1584–1585). We are social creatures,
and much of our behavior is merely mimicking the behavior of those around us, so
if even a few people are aware of things that trigger legal sanctions (even without
reading the law), this influences others. Some sanctions, like incarceration, remove
lawbreakers from society, thereby subtracting their example from the pool of influ-
ences on the rest of us. Many laws reflect societal values and morals—most people
would refrain from rape, burglary, and murder even if the law did not sanction it—
these are socially taboo actions, and they can be very risky for the perpetrator
(Stuntz 2000, discussing the complex relationship between popular norms and
criminal statutes). The extensiveness or comprehensiveness of modern codes (statutes
and regulations) means that one individual’s entire life (work, family, and other
activities) will fall outside the ambit of most of laws—only a fraction of the existing
laws in any jurisdiction would be relevant to any given individual. Even lawyers
know only a few laws that pertain to their area of practice, a fraction of the whole
body of laws that govern their jurisdiction. In any case, laws “work” without most
people ever reading the legal texts, so the addressee of the text does not affect
whether, or how, the laws “work” as far as controlling behavior of the citizens.17
Kelsen’s view about the addressee of the law is also illuminating for our understand-
ing of judicial interpretation. When faced with ambiguous provisions or multiple
possible meanings, we should favor the one that fits with the recipient’s common
usage of that language. In the case of statutes, that recipient is the judiciary or an
administrative agency; in the case of agency-promulgated regulations, it is typically
the agency itself. This view runs counter to traditional academic theories of inter-
pretation, which focus almost exclusively on the intent of the author (in the case of
laws, the legislature). Yet it does fit neatly with the most robust interpretive norms
similar vein to the arguments in this paper, see Janis and Holbrook (2012: 72). Janis and Holbrook
argue for better use of “intermediaries” (presumably lawyers) to bridge the communication gap
between the law’s actual audience and those whose conduct will trigger sanctions under the law.
17
Even in the case of so-called “legislative threats,” wherein a regulator or legislator communi-
cates directly to the leaders of a targeted industry that they need to self-regulate to a requisite level
or else face draconian legislation (not yet enacted), the deterrence is not through the legislative text
itself. Rather, the deterrence comes through the orally-transmitted threat of a sanction that contem-
plated legislation will authorize unless the audience preempts this move by voluntarily changing
their behavior (Halfteck 2008).
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 309
decision about institutional competencies that either leads a judge to use textualism
as a second-best rule or intentionalism as a faithful-agent rule; or even a theory that
links an interpretive “approach” to a particular view of the separation of powers or
checks and balances. Both textualism and intentionalism elicit charges of “judicial
activism” from those who take the opposing view, which Kelsen would have pre-
dicted. Ex ante commitments to an interpretive approach, he observes, are inher-
ently political. From an ex post perspective, a judge may exercise her discretion and
then appeal for support to legislative history, dictionary definitions of words, cost-
benefit analysis, stare decisis, or other justifications to deflect criticism and add
credibility and gravitas to the decision. Perhaps some or all of these things indeed
influenced the judge in choosing one alternative over the other—but it was still a
choice nevertheless, and another judge could have chosen the other alternative in
that case and then could have found supporting arguments and rationalizations.
To take Kelsen’s argument a step further than he did, a judge or official who
embraced the concept of being the addressee of the law (rather than the citizenry
being the addressee) could find certain interpretive assumptions to be more consis-
tent with that view than others. If the courts or other government organs are the
addressee of the law, then it seems inconsistent for a judge or official to insist that
the “plain meaning” of the legal text is the one that should control—if, by this, we
mean the common or vernacular meaning of terms, as used by the general popula-
tion. The general population does not read the laws, and has no power to “interpret”
laws in any authentic sense. Rather, it would be more consistent to presume that the
technical or judicial usage of the term is the best—the addressee furnishes the
essential “audience design” of the legal text18 (Bell 1984: 145). Speakers and writers
tailor their communication to how the addressee is likely to understand it (Lotman
and Shukman 1982: 81). When discussing meaning and interpretation, we should be
looking not only at the intent of the legislative author(s), or even at the text itself as
it might be understood by the general culture but as the intended audience would
understand it. Legislators do indeed consider judicial precedent and word usage in
drafting laws, and regulators interact with legislative committees during the drafting
stage of laws that they will have to implement (Bressman and Gluck 2014: 725).
Even though Kelsen eschewed any type of interpretive ideal, his concept of the
law’s addressee suggests at least that it is appropriate for courts and officials to work
within the indigenous linguistic context of those in that position. Instead of asking
what the legislature probably meant by certain words (assuming that collective
semantic intent is even possible), a judge could ask how the judiciary itself typically
uses such words or phrases.
18
Bell surveys several studies in this area, and explains how the primary addressee exerts the most
influence over the crafting of the communication, relatively speaking, while known overhearers
have a relatively small effect on the design of the speech or writing. Bell calls non-addressee
recipients of the communication “auditors,” which would correspond to the role of the citizenry
regarding the law under Kelsen’s theory. I am indebted to Professor Henry E. Smith for some of
these core insights (Smith 2003).
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 311
This brings us to the most robust interpretive norms (as Kelsen would call them)
used by American courts—those requiring (non-absolute) judicial deference to the
legal interpretations of regulatory agencies. These are the Chevron doctrine,19 the
Skidmore doctrine (Skidmore v. Swift & Co., 323 U.S. 134 (1944)) (used when the
court finds that the agency interpretation does not have the force of law), and Auer
deference20 (agency interpretations of the agency’s own promulgated regulations),
each named after the seminal Supreme Court case that made the rule binding on
lower federal courts. The logic undergirding these supremely important doctrines,
or norms in Kelsenian nomenclature, is very close to the idea that the laws have the
government agencies as their addressee. Under Chevron, if a statute is facially
ambiguous and the relevant agency’s interpretation is not far-fetched, the agency’s
interpretation trumps any other. Chevron deference does not apply to agency inter-
pretations of statutes other than their own governing statutes—that is, statutes not
addressed specifically to that agency.21 Chevron essentially recognizes that the
primary addressee of a law is its intended interpreter, which has delegated
authority and responsibility to exercise discretion and make positive law in its field.
Moreover in line with Kelsen’s view, Chevron recognizes that a range of possible
19
The doctrine takes its name from the landmark case Chevron U.S.A., Inc. v. Natural Resources
Defense Council, Inc., 467 U.S. 837 (1984). The decision laid down a two-step rule for courts to
use in deciding whether to defer to an administrative agency’s interpretation:
When a court reviews an agency’s construction of the statute which it administers, it is
confronted with two questions. First, always, is the question whether Congress has directly
spoken to the precise question at issue. If the intent of Congress is clear, that is the end of
the matter; for the court, as well as the agency, must give effect to the unambiguously
expressed intent of Congress. If, however, the court determines Congress has not directly
addressed the precise question at issue, the court does not simply impose its own construc-
tion on the statute, as would be necessary in the absence of an administrative interpretation.
Rather, if the statute is silent or ambiguous with respect to the specific issue, the question
for the court is whether the agency’s answer is based on a permissible construction of the
statute.
Chevron, 467 U.S. at 842. Note that the Supreme Court recently announced in an immigrant
removal case that Chevron Step Two and the “arbitrary and capricious” standard are the same and
yield identical results. See Judulang v. Holder, 132 S. Ct. 476, 484 n.7 (2011).
20
See Auer v. Robbins, 519 U.S. 452 (1997). This is the same as the older rule in Bowles v. Seminole
Rock & Sand Co., 325 U.S. 410 (1945), and courts and writers sometimes call this the Seminole-
Auer Rule (or the Auer-Seminole Rule).
21
H.L.A. Hart’s rejection of Kelsen’s views about the addressees of the law make a large omission
of this type of legislation—delegating tasks to government agencies—that are extraordinarily
common today. Though an individual agency may not receive deference when interpreting a law
not addressed to that agency, the norm of Chevron deference is universal in that the same rule (with
the same contours and exceptions) applies to all agencies. In Mayo Foundation for Medical Educ.
and Research v. United States, 131 S. Ct. 704 (2011), the Supreme Court held that the Chevron
approach should apply uniformly across agencies, rather than having special rules (or varying
levels of scrutiny) for certain agencies like the Internal Revenus Service.
312 D.D. Stevenson
interpretations are inherent in a law and are equally permissible for the intended
addressee (the agency).22
Skidmore deference23 applies in situations where the agency is not making
positive law but nonetheless must implement legislative norms addressed to it.
The analysis is similar to Chevron, and the ultimate outcome is nearly always the
same—the agency typically prevails—but there are some subtle differences.
Skidmore involves judicial inquiry into the circumstances of the agency’s decision,
a host of factors for courts to weigh. Was this decision within the agency’s area of
specialization and expertise? Did the agency study the question and consider alter-
natives, or was it a more spontaneous decision? Was the decision consistent with
prior decisions of the agency in similar cases? What was at stake for the private
party involved in the case? Again, the underlying assumption is that the agency is
the intended addressee of the law, and the judicial inquiry focuses on the reliability
of the agency’s decision-making in this instance.
Similarly, Auer deference rests on an assumption that agencies must promulgate
norms that govern its own future decisions in individual cases—that is, regulations
rather than statutes. Even though the agency is the lawmaker in these instances, it is
also the primary addressee of its own regulations, and courts therefore yield to the
agency’s official interpretation of its own promulgated rules and regulations. This is
a rule of super-deference, at least in its wording or formulation, it is stronger than
Chevron because the agency wins unless it is “plainly erroneous.”24 Most empirical
studies indicate the Supreme Court affirms the agency 90 % of the time when it
invokes Auer.
Significantly (for Kelsenian analysis), Auer deference usually comes up in cases
in which the agency is not a party, but instead has filed an amici brief or has other-
wise sought to intervene in a case between two private parties whose dispute would
22
At the same time, entrenched judicial precedents can trump the agency’s interpretations in certain
cases, according to a recent decision from the Supreme Court. The Court held that the recently
promulgated agency regulation equating an overstatement of unrecovered cost or other basis with
an omission from gross income was not entitled to deference under Chevron based on ambiguity
in the statute. Precedent has already interpreted the statute and there was no longer any different
interpretation, which is consistent with the precedent and available for adoption by the govern-
ment. See U.S. v. Home Concrete & Supply, LLC., 132 S. Ct. 1836 (2012). On the other hand,
long-standing agency interpretations (which the courts have not challenged) receive heightened
deference under Chevron. See Astrue v. Capato ex rel. B.N.C., 132 S. Ct. 2021 (2012), holding that
the Social Security Administration’s (SSA) interpretation of the Social Security Act governing
determination of the status of posthumously conceived children was entitled to Chevron deference;
SSA’s interpretation of the relevant provisions, adhered to without deviation for many decades,
was reasonable, and was therefore entitled to deference.
23
The trigger for applying Skidmore deference, rather than Chevron, is the Mead case’s rule about
whether the relevant legislative norm (the statute) creates a situation where the agency is supposed
to make positive law, or where the agency merely implements the law. Most scholars call this
“Chevron step zero.”
24
Justice Scalia, the author of the majority opinion Auer v. Robbins, worried in his dissent in Mead
that agencies would start promulgating vague rules for the strategic reason of getting Auer super-
deference to whatever interpretation they want to adopt later.
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 313
25
The Supreme Court began applying Auer more often starting in 2007, and it has become an
important doctrine now. The Department of Justice and other agencies are filing a lot more amicus
briefs in cases around the country urging the Court to adopt agency interpretations rather than
those proposed by the parties. See Decker v. Northwest Environmental Defense Center, 133 S. Ct.
1326 (2013); Christopher v. SmithKline Beecham Corp., 132 S. Ct. 2156 (2012); PLIVA, Inc. v.
Mensing, 131 S. Ct. 2567 (2011); Talk America, Inc. v. Michigan Bell Telephone Co., 131 S. Ct.
2254 (2011); Chase Bank USA, N.A. v. McCoy, 131 S. Ct. 871 (2011); Kennedy v. Plan Adm’r for
DuPont Sav. and Inv. Plan, 555 U.S. 285 (2009); Long Island Care at Home, Ltd. v. Coke, 551 U.S.
158 (2007); National Ass’n of Home Builders v. Defenders of Wildlife, 551 U.S. 644 (2007).
314 D.D. Stevenson
This Part applies the concept to the inherent problems with executive subdelega-
tions of state functions to private corporations. Such outsourcing began primarily in
the defense industry, but it has now spread to most areas of civilian governance.
A problem arises when the state actors, who are the primary addressees of the
law, subdelegate their functions to private for-profit firms via public contracts. This
is an increasingly widespread practice—with privatized prisons, privatized parking
meter enforcement, privatized welfare services, privatized foster care systems,
privatized motor vehicle licensing bureaus, and so on. The inherent delegation of
discretion in the statutes, which originally conferred discretion on the officials,
passes imperfectly through the contract with the private party now carrying out the
legal organ’s responsibilities (Metzger 2003). While there may be some supervision
of the contractor by the official, agency costs and monitoring costs necessarily ren-
der such supervision imperfect, meaning the private contractor—not a public ser-
vant—will exercise some of the discretion delegated through the law in implementing
it. Moreover, any ambiguous provisions in the contract itself necessarily create
additional room for the exercise of discretion by the contract worker.
In this situation, a tension can arise between the interpretive norms in the legal
system governing the application of statutes by officials, and the different interpre-
tive norms governing the construction of contracts. Interpreting the terms of a con-
tract is almost completely “intentionalist”-driven; the courts attempt to read each
word as the parties would presumably have understood it. In contrast, when it comes
to statutory interpretation and construction, legislative intent is only one of the array
of interpretive tools courts employ. The statute and a contract are different genres of
legal text, and indeterminacy or imprecision can function differently in each. Courts
are likely to interpret privatization arrangements according to contract principles
(Freeman 2000: 176–83),26 leaving potential for violations or noncompliance with
the legal norms in the sense that Kelsen described.
26
Another significant difference between the operation of contracts and regulations is that agencies
are generally free to change or amend problematic regulations (as long as proper procedures are
followed), while contracts cannot be freely revoked by states (although the federal government can
claim sovereign immunity when it breaches a contract). Freeman notes that “an agency may find
itself, even if only temporarily, bound to a bad bargain and unable to alter it through a simple
interpretive decision or rulemaking process. States may choose to avoid these complications by
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 315
15.5 Conclusion
Kelsen argued convincingly that the written formulations of the law address the
state and its actors, not the citizenry in general nor the segment of the population
whose conduct the law potentially sanctions. This concept has significant implica-
tions for legal reform movements calling for “simple English” in statutes and regu-
lations, for doctrines of judicial interpretation, and for delegations of governmental
power to private parties. Nevertheless, some of these implications run counter to
populist American ideals about democracy and civic responsibility. Kelsen’s view
of the law’s addressee is an important component of his overall system of identify-
ing the law with the state, so his arguments in this regard are an obstacle to accep-
tance of his larger work by American jurists and legal commentators.
Acknowledgments This chapter was occasioned by the “Hans Kelsen in America” conference in
Chicago on June 27–28, 2014. Valparaiso University Law School sponsored the event, with sup-
port from a grant by the Botstiber Institute for Austrian-American Studies. Many thanks to Jeremy
Telman for inviting me to participate, and to the other participants for thoughtful comments
and suggestions. I am deeply indebted to Dr. Henry Smith (currently at Harvard Law School) for
introducing me to both the sociolinguistic concept of addressees and to Hans Kelsen’s work on
legal theory.
codifying contractual terms in state law or promulgating them as regulations.” (Freeman 2000,
183).
316 D.D. Stevenson
References
Alan Siegel, Let’s simplify legal jargon!, TED talk video. http://www.ted.com/talks/alan_siegel_
let_s_simplify_legal_jargon. Accessed on Feb 2010.
Austin, John. 1832. The providence of jurisprudence determined. Amherst: Prometheus Books
2000 ed.
Bartor, Assnat. 2012. Reading biblical law as narrative. Prooftexts 32: 292.
Bell, Allan. 1984. Language as audience design. Language in Society 13: 145.
Bentham, Jeremy. 1999. In ‘Legislator of the world’: Writings on codification, law, and education,
ed. Schofield Philip and Harris Jonathan. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bressman Lisa, Schultz, and R. Gluck Abbe. 2014. Statutory interpretation from the inside—An
empirical study of congressional drafting, delegation, and the canons: Part II. Stanford Law
Review 66: 725–801.
Crump, David. 2002. Against plain English: The case for a functional approach to legal document
preparation. Rutgers Law Journal 33: 713–744.
Dan-Cohen, Meir. 1984. Decision rules and conduct rules: On acoustic separation in criminal law.
Harvard Law Review 97: 625–677.
Diamond, Shari Seidman, Beth Murphy, and Mary R. Rose. 2012. The “Kettleful Of Law” in real
jury deliberations: Successes, failures, and next steps. Northwestern University Law Review
106: 1537–1608.
Freeman, Jody. 2000. The contracting state. Florida State University Law Review 28: 155–183.
Gallacher, Ian. 2013. “When Numbers Get Serious”: A study of plain English usage in briefs filed
before the New York Court of Appeals. Suffolk University Law Review 46: 451501.
Gopen, George. 1987. The state of legal writing: Res Ipsa Loquitur. Michigan Law Review 86:
333–380.
Halfteck, Guy. 2008. Legislative threats. Stanford Law Review 61: 629–710.
Hart, H.L.A. 1961. The concept of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hathaway, George. 1994. The plain English movement in the law. Journal of the Missouri Bar 50:
19–21.
Howard, Philip K. 2010. Four ways to fix a broken legal system. http://www.ted.com/talks/philip_
howard. Accessed on Feb 2010.
Janis, Mark D., and Timothy R. Holbrook. 2012. Patent law’s audience. Minnesota Law Review
97: 72–131.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945. General Theory of Law and State. Trans. A. Wedberg 1945. Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1960. Pure Theory of Saw, Second ed. Trans. M. Knight 1967. Berkeley: University
of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1979. General Theory of Norms. Trans. M. Hartney 1991. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Lotman, Yury M., and Ann Shukman. 1982. The text and the structure of its audience. New Literary
History 14: 81.
Maley, Yon. 1994. Language constructing law. In Language and the law, ed. Gibbons John, 24–25.
London: Routledge Publishing.
Metzger, Gillian E. 2003. Privatization as delegation. Columbia Law Review 103: 1367–1502.
Moore, Sir Thomas. 1516. Utopia. London: Cassell & Co., 1901.
Serafin, Andrew. 1998. Kicking the legalese habit: The SEC’s plain English disclosure proposal.
Loyola University of Chicago Law Journal 29: 681–717.
Smith, Henry E. 2003. The language of property: Form, context, and audience. Stanford Law
Review 55: 1105–1191.
Sohoni, Mila. 2012. The idea of “too much law”. Fordham Law Review 80: 1585–1632.
Solan, Lawrence. 1993. The language of judges. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Somek, Alexander. 2006. Stateless law: Kelsen’s conception and its limits. Oxford Journal of
Legal Studies 26: 753–774.
15 Kelsen’s View of the Addressee of the Law 317
Stevenson, Drury. 2003. To whom is the law addressed? Yale Law and Policy Review 21:
105–167.
Stevenson, Dru. 2005. Toward a new theory of notice and deterrence. Cardozo Law Review. 26:
1535–1594.
Stewart, Iain. 1990. The critical legal science of Hans Kelsen. Journal of Law & Society 17:
273–284.
Stuntz, William J. 2000. Self-defeating crimes. Virginia Law Review 86: 1871–1899.
Tiersma, Peter. 1999. Legal language. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Weinberger, Ota. 1985. Freedom, range for action, and the ontology of norms. Synthese 65:
307–324.
Wilson, A. 1981. The imperative fallacy in Kelsen’s theory. Modern Law Review 44: 270–281.
Chapter 16
Kelsen, Justice, and Constructivism
Joshua W. Felix
Hans Kelsen’s final and posthumously published work, General Theory of Norms,
has been a puzzle for Kelsen scholars. It is an extended treatment of arguments that
Kelsen first presented in Derogation (reprinted in Kelsen 1973: 261–275) and Law
and Logic (reprinted in Kelsen 1973: 228–253): the critique of practical reason and
deontic logic. On the one hand, the work provides a general philosophical treatment
of norms and normative science. These are important and familiar themes from the
pure theory of law. It elaborates much of the metaethical and social scientific frame-
work of normative science. On the other hand, it has generally been received as a
failure and a radical departure from his previous work. For Michael Hartney,
Kelsen’s arguments are fallacious and conflate problems of logic and ontology
(Hartney 1993: 16). For Deryck Beyleveld, Kelsen’s critique of practical reason
results in “normative irrationalism,” altering a phrase of Ota Weinberger (Beyleveld
1993: 104). For Stanley Paulson, Kelsen’s arguments undermine the basis for nor-
mative science (Paulson 1992: 273).
This chapter makes two claims. First, Kelsen’s critique of practical reason and
deontic logic is best understood as a response to constructivism. These arguments
should not be viewed as a radical departure from his previous work, but as an
attempt to defend his skepticism about justice from a constructivist challenge.
Second, these arguments are not fallacious and may be of interest in contemporary
debates about constructivism.
Section 16.2 provides a general overview of Kelsen’s idea of normative science.
It covers the distinction between facts and norms, normative science and sociology,
positivity and validity, psychological and real volition, and objective and subjective
value.
Section 16.3 presents Kelsen’s general case for skepticism about justice. Justice
is a subjective value that originates in the hope for a society in which there is a har-
mony of interests. For Kelsen, this hope is irrational because its end is impossible.
Conflicts of interest are inevitable and intractable. Moreover, the idea of justice is
ideological: it inverts the relation between norms and normative orders.
Section 16.4 introduces constructivism and the challenge it poses for skepticism
about justice. Classical constructivism relies on an analogy between incompossibil-
ity and logical contradiction. Kelsen argues that there is no such analogy.
Section 16.5 introduces John Rawls’ version of constructivism and its relation to
Kelsen. Rawls attempts to circumvent positivist conceptions of objective value by
means of a decision procedure to identify rational criteria for validity.
Section 16.6 assesses the critique of practical reason and deontic logic. Kelsen
sets up a dilemma for practical reason: either it leads to the absurdity that reason and
will are identical, or reason cannot posit norms. This dilemma is supplemented by
two arguments: that validity is not a property and that norm conflict is not a logical
contradiction. The section also considers and responds to the objections of Hartney
and Beyleveld.
Section 16.7 concludes the chapter with a reconsideration of the Kelsen’s view
that validity is the existence of a norm. For Kelsen, the possibility of normative sci-
ence rests on the realist conviction that validity is existence.
Normative science is the science of objective value. However, there are two kinds of
value judgment: factual value judgments and normative value judgments. Factual
value judgments are propositions about facts. Normative value judgments are prop-
ositions about norms. Nevertheless, only norms can be the basis of objective value.
Factual value judgments are about subjective value and normative value judgments
are about objective value (Kelsen 1991: 185). The method of verification for each
kind of value judgment is essentially different. Factual value judgments are verified
when the corresponding fact is the case. Normative value judgments are verified
when the corresponding norm is valid (Kelsen 1991: 180). Positivity is a necessary
condition for the validity (existence) of a norm (Kelsen 1991: 251). It follows that
all valid norms are positive norms, and that normative science is a positive social
science.
There are two kinds of positive social science. Sociology is the science of posi-
tive facts. Normative science is the science of positive norms. However, the positiv-
ity of a fact is different from the positivity of a norm. A fact is positive if it is the
case. A norm is positive if it has been posited (Kelsen 1991: 4). The existence of a
fact is its positivity, whereas the validity (existence) of a norm is a consequence of
its positivity.
16 Kelsen, Justice, and Constructivism 321
Sociology and normative science both explain value in terms of volition. There
are two kinds of volition: psychological volition and real volition. These differ in
their content and mode of address. Psychological volition is an act of will that posits
an interest (Kelsen 1957: 211). Real volition is an act of will that posits a norm
(Kelsen 1991: 27). Psychological volition is an act of will directed to one’s own
behavior, whereas real volition is an act of will directed to the behavior of another
(Kelsen 1991: 31–32). Interests are the objects of factual value judgments. Norms
are the objects of normative value judgments. It follows that subjective value is
reducible to facts about acts of psychological volition, whereas objective value is
reducible to facts about acts of real volition.
Sociological theories of value are interest theories. Interest theories of value hold
that something is valuable because someone takes an interest in it. Therefore, all
value is reducible to facts about acts of psychological volition. Interest theories are
appropriate for subjective value but not objective value. When interest theories are
applied to objective value, they entail the absurdity that norms are interests, or that
norms are posited by psychological volition.
Consider the absurd consequences of interest theories of value in ethics and
jurisprudence. Classical interest theories in ethics are those of Hobbes and Hume.
These theories maintain that the validity of moral norms depends on individual or
general interests (Stevenson 1937: 15–16). The classical interest theory in jurispru-
dence is that of Austin. That theory maintains that the validity of legal norms
depends on the interests of the sovereign or legislating body (Kelsen 1957: 212–
214). If moral and legal validity depend on interests, ethics and jurisprudence are
forms of applied psychology. This is absurd because the ethicist and the legal scien-
tist are concerned with norms. The ethicist is concerned with valid moral norms
(Kelsen 1991: 359). The legal scientist is concerned with valid legal norms (Kelsen
1957: 273). The study of objective value requires normative science.
For Kelsen, justice is an “irrational ideal” (Kelsen 1945: 13). Justice is supposed to
resolve conflicts of interest. But conflicts of interest are inevitable and intractable.
They can only be resolved “by an order that either satisfies one interest at the
expense of the other, or seeks to achieve a compromise between competing inter-
ests” (Kelsen 1945: 13). Moreover, although justice purports to be an objective
value it is in fact a subjective value (Kelsen 1945: 49). It follows that justice is a
topic for sociology.
Accordingly, Kelsen provides a sociological analysis of justice. He claims that
justice as an idea that originates in the hope for a society in which there is a harmony
of interests: “Justice is social happiness” (Kelsen 1957: 2). This hope is irrational
because its object is impossible: it is the hope for a social order in which all interests
are satisfied (Kelsen 1957: 3). This hope can only be made rational by abandoning
the ideal of satisfying interests, and replacing it by the ideal of satisfying needs.
322 J.W. Felix
16.4 Constructivism
Rawls revives constructivism through the notion of a decision procedure that deter-
mines the criteria of validity rather than the analogy between incompossibility and
logical contradiction. The most comprehensive version of this view is presented in
A Theory of Justice (Rawls 1971: 118–136), but it was initially worked out in his
doctoral dissertation and early publications. Important for our purposes, Rawls had
more than a passing familiarity with the work of Kelsen. Early in his career, Rawls
sought to use the pure theory of law as a model for a normative science of ethics
(Reidy 2014: 15–16). However, by the time Rawls finished his doctoral dissertation,
his attitude toward positivism in moral and political theory had soured.1 Rawls’
mature work was developed against the background of his dissatisfaction with posi-
tive social science.
Rawls came to accept the view that positive social science has the wrong account
of the objectivity of value. Sociology presents subjective value as objective value:
1
Rawls’ dissertation references the first edition of the Reine Rechtslehre, General Theory of Law
and State, and The Pure Theory of Law and Analytical Jurisprudence (Rawls 1950: 4). Of note is
that the dissertation predates Rawls’ time at Oxford, where he was in contact with H.L.A. Hart.
324 J.W. Felix
the objectivity of value ultimately depends on our psychology and emotional states.
Normative science presents objective value as a problem of ontology: the objectiv-
ity of value ultimately depends on the validity (existence) of norms. However, for
Rawls,
the objectivity or the subjectivity of moral knowledge turns, not on the question whether
ideal value entities exist or whether moral judgments are caused by emotions… but simply
on the question: does there exist a reasonable method for validating and invalidating given
or proposed moral rules and those decisions made on the basis of them? (Rawls 1951: 177)
Rawls’ solution is to set aside the presumption that validity depends on psychol-
ogy or ontology. This puts out of play the key considerations that entail that justice
is a subjective value and an “irrational ideal” (Kelsen 1945: 13). Rawls’ approach is
to make use of a decision procedure in order to identify rational criteria for validity.
The rational criteria for validity are analogous to rational criteria for inductive infer-
ence (Rawls 1951: 177). Therefore, in contrast with classical constructivism, the
decision procedure models validity in terms of inductive logic rather than deductive
logic.
On this view, the idea of justice is a construction of reason. The elements of con-
struction are ideas about the characteristics of competent judges, the scope of proba-
tive judgment, and the context of impartial adjudication (Rawls 1951: 178–186).
The construction can then be used to “determine the manner in which competing
interests should be adjudicated, and, in instances of conflict, one interest given pref-
erence over another” (Rawls 1951: 177).
act of thought is also an act of real volition (Kelsen 1991: 80–81). But this is absurd,
since reason and will are distinct faculties. On the other hand, if practical reason is
not an act of real volition, then practical reason cannot posit norms.
The critique of deontic logic is necessary to demonstrate that there is no analogy
between validity and truth. For Kelsen, the problem of deontic logic concerns
whether norm conflict is a logical contradiction and whether the rule of inference
from the general to the particular applies to norms (Kelsen 1991: 191).
Kelsen argues that validity is not a property of a norm and that norm conflict is
not a logical contradiction. First, validity is not a property of a norm because valid-
ity is the existence of a norm, and existence is not a property (Kelsen 1991: 383).
Second, norm conflict is not a logical contradiction for reasons presented in Sect.
16.4: there is no analogy between incompossibility and logical contradiction.
Hartney argues that Kelsen’s critique of deontic logic is based on a mistake. The
mistake was to conflate logic and ontology: Kelsen does not distinguish between
norms as imperatives from norms as entities (Hartney 1993: 16). Consequently,
Kelsen came to believe that “the only way of preserving the law-making monopoly
of legal authorities is to deny that norms can be derived from other norms” (Hartney
1993: 15). For Hartney, Kelsen would not have involved himself in the quagmire of
deontic logic had he had a clearer sense of the distinction between logic and
ontology.
But Kelsen had good reason to believe that the problem of deontic logic is rele-
vant to whether norms may be valid for reasons other than having been posited by
competent authorities. Part of the problem of deontic logic is whether validity is a
logical property such that there can be a deontic logic analogous to propositional
logic. More generally, it concerns whether there is an analogy between validity and
truth. As shown in Sect. 16.4, classical constructivism makes much of the analogy
between incompossibility and logical contradiction in order to motivate the position
that validity is a logical property. Likewise, Rawls’ constructivism presents validity
as a logical property.
Moreover, Kelsen does not emphasize the distinction between imperatives and
entities because he rejects the thesis that deontic logic is imperative logic (Kelsen
1991: 150). For Hartney, the difference between facts and norms is a formal one:
facts and norms are expressed by different sentence forms. Facts are expressed in
the form of propositions and norms are expressed in the form of imperatives. On this
view, deontic logic is imperative logic. Therefore, he believes that Kelsen’s failure
to discuss imperatives belies an essential misunderstanding of deontic logic. For
Kelsen, the difference between facts and norms is a modal one: facts and norms can
only be expressed in sentences with different modal operators (Kelsen 1991: 195).
Norms can be expressed by imperatives and sollen-sentences (Kelsen 1991: 149). It
is the modal operator and not the sentence form that counts (Kelsen 1991:155).
In fairness to Hartney, his point is that logic concerns relations between sen-
tences, not relations between entities (Hartney 1993: 18). Hartney is right to empha-
size that Kelsen is inconsistent in his use of terms. Kelsen frequently uses “norm”
to refer to both entities and to sentences. Consider the analogy he frequently draws
between facts and norms. According to Kelsen, norms are no more subject to logical
326 J.W. Felix
relations than facts are because both norms and facts are entities and not sentences
(Kelsen 1991: 17, 181). Nevertheless, Kelsen often compares norms with proposi-
tions, especially when discussing the disanalogy between truth and validity (Kelsen
1991: 163–165, 170–174).
On account of this inconsistency, Kelsen makes two different kinds of arguments
about norms and deontic logic. First, insofar as norms are entities, there can be no
logical relations between norms. It follows that a logic of norms in the strict sense
is not possible. If there is a deontic logic, it cannot be a logic of norms. Second,
insofar as norms are sentences, there are no relations between such sentences analo-
gous to those between propositions. This is the case because validity is not a prop-
erty and, even if it were a property, it would not be the kind of property that would
be the basis of a deontic logic analogous to propositional logic. Hartney finds the
first kind of argument unimpressive and misleading because it conflates logic and
ontology. Hartney thinks the second kind of argument is also ultimately about ontol-
ogy because, for Kelsen, validity is existence. Although the success of the second
kind of argument depends on the definition of validity as existence, it does not con-
flate logic and ontology.
Beyleveld argues that Kelsen’s critique of deontic logic begs the question about
whether validity is a logical property (Beyleveld 1993: 115). For Beyleveld, the
problem of deontic logic is whether validity is a logical property. As he presents it,
Kelsen argues that validity is not a logical property by appeal to the fact of norm
conflict. But this begs the question, since appeal to the fact of norm conflict is to
assume that validity is not a logical relation (Beyleveld 1993: 115).
Like Hartney, Beyleveld thinks there is something problematic with the idea that
validity is existence. For Beyleveld, validity is the binding force of a norm and not
its existence. The problem of deontic logic is whether binding force is a logical rela-
tion between sentences that express norms. Kelsen’s view entails that norms are
binding because they exist (Beyleveld 1993: 113). However if existence is the same
as binding force, appeal to the fact of norm conflict to demonstrate that validity is
not a logical property begs the question.
This criticism conflates Kelsen’s two arguments against deontic logic. The argu-
ment that norm conflict is not a contradiction is distinct from the argument that
validity is not a property. The former argument does not depend on the fact of norm
conflict, but on the definition of norm conflict. Since all norms are valid norms,
norm conflicts can only occur between valid norms. The latter argument holds that
validity is not a logical property because it is the existence of a norm and existence
is not a property.
Beyleveld also argues that Kelsen’s critique of practical reason undermines the
basis of normative science. For Beyleveld, empowering norms must function
through an application of the rule of inference from the general to the particular to
sentences that express norms. Since Kelsen denies that the rule of inference applies
to norms, he must account for empowering norms by making positivity and validity
identical (Beyleveld 1993: 115). But if positivity and validity are identical, there is
no distinction between sociology and normative science.
16 Kelsen, Justice, and Constructivism 327
Custom appears to be a case in which positivity and validity are identical, since
it is a norm that originates in convergent behavior rather than real volition.
Convergent behavior becomes custom by virtue of an empowering norm
(Kelsen 1967: 9).
However, this critique fails to show that the rule of inference for empowering
norms is an exercise of practical reason. Recall that Kelsen recognizes discernment
as a power of reason. He only denies that discernment is a form of practical reason.
The rule of inference can apply to norm propositions: from the fact that an empow-
ering norm is valid, and that convergent behavior is sufficient to be custom, it fol-
lows that custom is valid (Kelsen 1991: 252–253). It can also apply to the “modally
indifferent substrate” (Kelsen 1991: 60–61). The modally indifferent substrate is the
part of a sentence that expresses a norm that is distinct from the modal operator.
There are further questions about Kelsen’s notion of custom, but they are distinct
from Beyleveld’s argument about empowering norms.
Much of what is puzzling about General Theory of Norms turns on the realist con-
viction that validity is existence. As we have seen, both Hartney and Beyleveld find
something suspect with this account of validity, even if they do not successfully
show that it is blatantly false. Likewise, Rawls’ constructivism attempts to circum-
vent this realist view by presenting an alternative conception of validity based on
rational criteria.
Unfortunately, Kelsen does not directly argue for this notion of validity. But it is
worth recalling the first horn of the dilemma about practical reason. For Kelsen,
practical reason is the power of postulation: it is the identification of reason and
will. If such an identification is not absurd, it is only possible insofar as human rea-
son is divine reason. Practical reason is essentially a theological notion (Kelsen
1991: 4–6). This hardly demonstrates that validity cannot be determined by rational
criteria. However, it illustrates what is at stake if this notion of validity is denied.
Briefly, if validity is distinct from existence, objectivity is unhinged from actual-
ity. Rawls’ later formulations of constructivism drive a wedge between validity and
truth: the validity of a conception of justice is a matter of its reasonableness, which
is distinct from its truth (Rawls 2005: 128–129). But for Kelsen, notwithstanding
the disanalogy between validity and truth, to disconnect the validity of a norm from
the truth of a norm proposition is to abandon the scientific enterprise. The need to
defend normative science is what stands behind Kelsen’s conviction that one can no
more derive an ought from an ought than an ought from an is.
Acknowledgements Thanks to George Mazur for an informative discussion and for pointing me
in the direction of Foundations of Democracy. Thanks to Jeremy Telman and Valparaiso University
Law School for organizing Hans Kelsen in America. Finally, thanks to Jessica Wielgus for her
hospitality during my stay in Chicago.
328 J.W. Felix
References
Beyleveld, Deryck. 1993. From the ‘middle way’ to normative irrationalism: Hans Kelsen’s
General Theory of Norms. The Modern Law Review 56: 104–119.
Hartney, Michael. 1993. The death of practical reasoning in Kelsen’s later theory of norms. In
Sociological jurisprudence and legal philosophy: Random thoughts on, ed. K.B. Agrawal and
Rajendra Kumar Raizada, 11–18. Jaipur: University Book House.
Hume, David. 1983. An enquiry concerning the principles of morals. Indianapolis: Hackett
Publishing Company.
Kant, Immanuel. 1996. Practical philosophy. Trans. M. Gregor. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1945. General theory of law and state. Trans. A. Wedberg. Cambridge: Harvard
University Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1955. Foundations of democracy. Ethics 66: 1–101.
Kelsen, Hans. 1957. What is justice? Justice, law, and politics in the mirror of science. Berkeley:
University of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1967. The pure theory of law. Trans. M. Knight. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1973. Essays in legal and moral philosophy. Trans. P. Heath. Boston: D. Reidel
Publishing Company.
Kelsen, Hans. 1991. General theory of norms. Trans. M. Hartney. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Paulson, Stanley. 1992. Kelsen’s legal theory: The final round. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 12:
265–274.
Paulson, Stanley. 1996. Hans Kelsen’s earliest legal theory: Critical constructivism. The Modern
Law Review 59: 797–812.
Rawls, John. 1950. A study in the grounds of ethical knowledge: Considered with reference to
judgments on the moral worth of character. Ph.D. Thesis, Princeton University.
Rawls, John. 1951. Outline of a decision procedure for ethics. The Philosophical Review 60:
177–197.
Rawls, John. 1971. A theory of justice. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Rawls, John. 2005. Political liberalism: Expanded edition. New York: Columbia University Press.
Reidy, David. 2014. From philosophical theology to democratic theory: Early postcards from an
intellectual journey. In A companion to Rawls, ed. Jon Mandle and David Reidy, 9–30.
Chichester: Wiley Blackwell.
Stevenson, C.L. 1937. The emotive meaning of ethical terms. Mind 46: 14–31.
Part V
Conclusions
Chapter 17
In Defense of Modern Times: A Keynote
Address
Clemens Jabloner
17.1 Introduction
Recently, the Hans Kelsen Institute in Vienna published Kelsen’s opus posthumous
Secular Religion—A Polemic against the Misinterpretation of Modern Social
Philosophy, Science and Politics as “New Religion” (Kelsen 2012). The work is the
final chapter in Kelsen’s serial critique (Kelsen 2004) of his former pupil Eric
Voegelin’s New Science of Politics (Voegelin 1987). It is illuminating that previous
versions of Kelsen’s work bore the titles Defense of Modern Times and Religion
without God?1 Both alternatives seem highly significant: Kelsen as a “champion of
modernity” serves quite well as a Leitmotiv—and therefore as the title of my short
address.
Then again, Religion without God—with a question mark—is almost identical to
the title of Ronald Dworkin’s last monograph, Religion without God (Dworkin
2013). The two similar titles offer an occasion for putting these two eminent schol-
ars into conversation with one another. At the same time, it might be of interest to
focus a little on Kelsen’s concept of religion, with a view to his Jewish
background.
1
For the complicated pre-history of this publication see the editorial remarks in Kelsen (2012, 11)
and Di Lucia/ Passerini Glazel (2014, XIX).
C. Jabloner (*)
University of Vienna, 1010 Wien, Austria
e-mail: [email protected]
2
For the following, compare in more detail Jabloner (1998).
3
Cp. the collected essays in Stadler (2004).
4
Cp. the collected essays in Stadler (1997).
17 In Defense of Modern Times 333
Kelsen embarked on his undertaking within the realm of legal science, which always
remained his main concern. On the one hand, he combatted natural law doctrines,
including rational law. On the other hand, he condemned the contamination of legal
science with a false understanding of legal sociology. As is often pointed out, Kelsen
aimed at—and succeeded in—the construction of a normative as well as a positivist
legal theory (see Dreier (1990: 27); Paulson (2006: passim)). In his critique of natu-
ral law, Kelsen not only attacked the phenomena of explicit natural law, but he also
reached out to identify the residua of natural law, especially in the Staatslehre of his
age. It is not surprising that the concept of the “state” itself, as an essence beyond
the law, served as the primary target for Kelsen’s deconstruction (see Dreier (1990:
208; Feichtinger 2010: 369): “Funktionen statt Substanzen”).
It is rather surprising that Kelsen’s critique of ideology found its inspiration not
least in Sigmund Freud, perhaps as the result of their personal interactions (see
Jabloner (2014: 138); Feichtinger (2010: 385)). In his essays Der Staatsbegriff und
die Psychoanalyse and Gott und Staat (Kelsen (1922/23, und 1927)). Kelsen made
an extremely bold attempt as a legal theoretician to apply Freud’s theory of totem-
ism—that is, a tribal community’s collective consumption of a sacrificed animal as
an act of identification—to legal theory. Kelsen recognized that the idea of the state
as person, the “illustrative personification of the legal order constituting the social
community and founding the unity of a diversity of human behaviour” was an
example of a reification. He replaced that idea with the recognition of the state as a
legal function. Kelsen saw parallels with other concepts of substance, such as
“force” in physics or “soul” in psychology, and recognized in such residua the piece
de résistance of metaphysical thinking. According to Kelsen, in the “totem-meal,”
the primal image of any conception of substance comes to light. Undoubtedly,
Kelsen’s deconstruction of the state as a superior and obscure entity is sufficient to
qualify him as a modern thinker. His recourse to Freud’s phylogenetic fable could
today be questioned as an act of “re-mythologizing,”5 but I will leave this open.
In a political sense, Kelsen’s modernity centers on the fact that man-made positive
law could take the place of the instructions derived from religious or metaphysical
worldviews. In a society in which the law is explicitly and centrally set, the positiv-
ization of the law, therefore, also entails the ongoing opportunity to change it. In this
way, the law becomes an instrument to shape society. Still, this displacement of
religious or metaphysical perspectives tells us nothing about who should legislate.
This is where Kelsen’s theory of democracy applies: Kelsen analyzed democracy as
5
For an early critique on Freud’s fable, compare Kroeber (1920), passim.
334 C. Jabloner
a political idea. We are referring here to Kelsen’s famous essay Vom Wesen und Wert
der Demokratie, first published in 1920 and expended in 1929. It is surprising that
the first English translation of this important—and famous—work only dates from
2013 (Kelsen 1929).
As a way of creating law, democracy best realizes the idea of freedom. In order
to function, democracy must, as parliamentarism, accept a compromise with the
division of labor that is a condition of all social and technical progress. Kelsen
showed the degree to which this compromise requires fictions—a concept he used
neutrally—in order to achieve the desirable identities of rulers and ruled.
The element that connects Kelsen’s pure theory of law with his theory of democ-
racy is value relativism (see Dreier (1990: 249); Jestaedt and Lepsius (2006:
XVIII)). The main concern of Kelsen’s legal theory is that the validity of the law
cannot be based on pre-positive values or norms, while the main concern of his
theory of democracy is not to impose limits on the decisions made by the people—
that is, by the majority.6 Such limits are frequently called for with the argument that
it is by no means certain that the majority will recognize what is right. However,
according to Kelsen, such limits on democracy assume insight into absolute values
and are ultimately possible only within the framework of a “metaphysical, and espe-
cially religious and mystical, Weltanschauung” (Kelsen 1929: 225).
For Kelsen, however, democracy is not only a convenient form of producing laws
to optimize individual freedom in mass society. Rather, he is looking for the corre-
sponding conception of man as one functional condition for democracy.
His relevant social-psychological considerations can be found in particular in his
Staatsform und Weltanschauung from 1933. Although he does not mention Freud in
that work, his influence is manifest (Freud 2000, 120 seqq.). Using Freud’s struc-
tural model of the human psyche, Kelsen opposes the democratic to the authoritar-
ian character. The authoritarian subject identifies with his superego, his ego-ideal,
which is represented in the mighty dictator. Consequently, this typus adores the
blind obedience and finds happiness in dictating as well as in obeying: “The identi-
fication with the authority: this is the secret of obedience” (Kelsen 1929: 13). By
contrast, the democratic subject is inclined to find his ego-ideal in equality with the
other (Kelsen 1929, 11). Thus, Kelsen recognizes the democratic character in the
type of person who has a relatively reduced sense of ego—a type of sympathizing,
peace-loving, non-aggressive Epson—a person whose primary aggressive drive is
not so much directed to the outside world but rather inwards, manifesting itself as a
tendency to self-criticism and a heightened sense of guilt and responsibility. We can
say that in Kelsen’s view the democratic-tempered individual and the—well-
functioning—democratically organized state are interdependent because a well-
functioning democracy does not create a favorable terrain for the principle of
authority. Now we understand why Kelsen—from his very beginnings—laid so
much weight on education and Volksbildung (Kelsen 1913).
6
Against the background of the inter-war-period Feichtinger (2010, 373) sees the function of a
Kelsenian purified legal theory as a “guardian of democracy.”
17 In Defense of Modern Times 335
Kelsen saw Voegelin’s attack as a threat to the scientific perception of the world: “If
any criterion distinguishes modern times from the Middle Ages, it is—in Western
Civilization—the existence of objective and independent science” (Kelsen 2012:
preface, 4). Voegelin’s thinking offered Kelsen a number of points of attack and
plenty of space for immanent criticism. For our context, it is essential that Kelsen
fixated primarily on the abuse of the concept of religion, and it is remarkable how
important this—perhaps merely conceptual—question was for him. The transfer of
the concept of religion to “moral-political doctrines,” such as Marxism, was, for
Kelsen, based on a confusion of the intensity of feelings that people can have for
ideas with the “nature of the feelings.” Arguing against Raymond Aron, who
regarded Marxism as a political religion, Kelsen declared Aron‘s argument to be the
product of an erroneous identification of religious and moral systems of belief:
“Such a system is not necessarily religious. Some moral systems have no relation to
any religion. The moral values of a religion are characterized by the belief that they
are established by the will of god or a godlike transcendent being and hence are
336 C. Jabloner
absolute” (Kelsen 2012: 25). The—at first glance affirmative—title Secular Religion
is misleading. Kelsen’s aim was to show the absurdity of this concept.
As I mentioned at the beginning, Kelsen came from a Jewish family and he devel-
oped in an intellectual climate in which assimilated Jews played an important role.
He himself was probably more agnostic than atheist. He did not oppose religions as
such in the sense of subjective beliefs. He also said in the preface to Secular Religion
that his writing is not directed against theologians (Kelsen 2012: preface, 3). He
viewed his own religious association pragmatically, as attested by his two religious
conversions—first to Roman Catholicism, then to the Protestant faith (see Staudacher
(2009), passim). Certainly he remained aware of his Jewish ancestry, and it influ-
enced some of his personal decisions. Kelsen’s very late reflection on his Judaism,
reported by Max Knight, may be semi-apocryphal (Knight 1973).
Furthermore, there is no sense in seeking to detect “Jewish” characteristics in the
pure theory of law. Such an endeavor would be highly ambivalent in itself and,
besides, while Kelsen and many other scholars from his circle did have Jewish fam-
ily backgrounds, many other outstanding minds of the time did not. Alfred Verdross
and Adolf Julius Merkl, two of Kelsen’s earliest companions, came from bourgeois
non-Jewish families.7
It is wrong to say that the pure theory of law—as a general legal theory—has
been inspired by Jewish law or legal thinking. The question of whether the pure
theory of law is compatible with Jewish law would be just as misguided, as Itzhak
Englard impressively demonstrated at the Vienna Symposium on Secular Religion
(Englard 2013, passim). Gustafsson’s recently uttered thesis that there was a school
of “distinctly ‘Jewish Legal Positivism,’” inspired by Hermann Cohen, which
included the Jellineks, Kelsen, Hart and Raz, is also rather embarrassing (Gustafsson
2010: 330).8
Admittedly, in the preface to the 1923 second edition of his Hauptprobleme der
Staatsrechtslehre Kelsen mentioned that he had become aware of the extensive par-
allels between his own work and Cohen’s Ethics of Pure Will, with regard to the
concept of the legal will (Kelsen 1923: XVII). Here Kelsen admitted his neo-
Kantianism, “according to which the epistemic orientation determines its object,
and the epistemic object is generated logically from an origin.” Kelsen also wrote
some time later in a letter to Renato Treves that Cohen’s “théorie de la conaissance”
had a lasting influence on him (Kelsen 1992). But Kelsen does not cite Cohen’s
7
For more details, see Jabloner (1998, 370).
8
Englard (2013, 105) calls Gustafsson’s attempt “absurd.”
17 In Defense of Modern Times 337
work on the philosophy of religion, Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des
Judentums (“Religion of Reason from the Sources of Judaism”), first published
1919 and reissued in 1928, and it is by no means established that he read it at all.
Some possible analogies may be found, but they remain superficial.9
I cannot close this section without reflecting on the fact that Kelsen was indeed
particularly subjected to anti-Semitic attacks, in which the Pure Theory of Law was
reviled as a typical Jewish product. At the forefront of this agitation was the sharp-
tongued and malicious Carl Schmitt, whose anti-Semitism was not just an ingredi-
ent in his work, but was at its center (Gross 2000, passim). Thus Schmitt spoke after
1933 of the “Vienna School of the Jew Kelsen” (Schmidt 1936: 1195). Kelsen’s
central elements—normativism, universalism, pacifism—can only be tools of
Jewish decomposition for Schmitt: “normativity,” because it destroys the original
unity of the “Nomos”; universalism, because “whoever invokes humanity wants to
cheat”10—and pacifism in any case. Schmitt was part of the phalanx of those German
Meisterdenker who dressed up their anti-Semitism as the opposition of soul and
spirit, essence and form; Heidegger was another one—as has become even clearer
today (Wenzel 2014).
There is the temptation to follow this identification of Jewish elements, which
was originally made with anti-Semitic intent, but to re-evaluate it positively, in
accordance with a popular contemporary consensus. Then one would have a “secu-
lar Judaism,” based on strong self-control, the equality of all men and peacefulness
acquired through civilization. I would urge not to give in to this temptation. Indeed,
secular Jews might often embrace such values, but they are not specifically “Jewish.”
Now, the fact that Kelsen was fascinated by religious subjects should not be over-
looked (Dreier 2009: 13; Englard 2013: 106). The concluding sentences of Vom
Wesen und Wert der Demokratie, in which Kelsen recounts the scene of “Jesus
before Pilate” from the Gospel of John, are very well known. According to Kelsen,
this encounter has become “a tragic symbol for relativism and democracy.” Kelsen
ends with the following:
Believers—political believers—may object that precisely this example argues against,
rather than for democracy. This objection must be granted, but only under one condition:
9
Cohen (1928: 66) speaks about the image of God as follows: “…so lehrt dagegen der
Monotheismus, daß Gott schlechterdings kein Gegenstand sei, der nach Anleitung eines Bildes
gedacht werden könnte. Und es ist die Probe des wahren Gottes, daß es kein Bild von ihm geben
kann (spaced by Cohen). Er kann nie durch ein Abbild zur Erkenntnis kommen, sondern einzig und
allein nur als Urbild, als Urgedanke, als Ursein.” Here we are invited to speculate about a certain
analogy to Kelsen”s Basic Norm, which is—in its final version—by no means a norm but is to be
understood as a mandatory assumption for objective normativity, cp. Walter (1992: 56).
10
Schmitt (1932, 55): “Wer Menschheit sagt, will betrügen”.
338 C. Jabloner
that these believers are as certain about their political truth, which they will enforce by
violence if necessary, as the son of god was about his (Kelsen 1929: 103; see the cited
English translation, 104).
Kelsen therefore does not rule out the possibility of faith; rather, he regards it as an
expression of subjective certainty, which can even be realized if the believer does
not at the same time consider his experience to be objectively true—and thus bind-
ing for all. Value-relativism—as particularly elaborated by Horst Dreier—is there-
fore by no means a value-nihilism (Dreier 2013: 18).
Kelsen understood religion as a system of norms, the validity of which is attrib-
uted to the will of God (Kelsen 1963a: 4, 7). I emphasize two aspects of Kelsen’s
view of religion that are not always easy to tell apart. First, if religious norms are
described in a scientific manner—which is the task of theology—this can only be
done under the condition that a “basic norm,” which is to obey God’s command-
ments, is established. Only in this way can the objective “ought” of religious
norms—their “validity”—be achieved.
Second, the later Kelsen’s fundamental principle, “No imperative without an
imperator,” also breaks new ground here. In his General Theory of Norms, Kelsen
made clear that the positivity of the law depends for Kelsen particularly on the fact
that it is based on real acts of will set by certain people. This remains true even “if
the authority’s act of will of which the merely thought norm is the meaning is ficti-
tious.…In general terms: No Ought without a will (even if it is only fictitious)”
(Kelsen 1979: 186 seq.). Because—according to Kelsen—one can think of such a
norm only as the meaning of an act of will that has to be assumed at the same time.
Transferred to a religious system of norms, acts of will have to be assumed and/or
believed in their fictive setting, but the idea of a personal God is essential. For
Kelsen, the conception of a religion without god must inevitably be absurd.
According to Englard’s cautious remark, Kelsen developed here, in a nutshell,
something like “A Pure Theory of God.”11
It should not be neglected to note that Kelsen’s late view on norms brings with it
a series of questions, especially with regard to his naturalistic concept of the “will-
act” and in the light of customary law (Cp. Jabloner 1988: 78, 84). But the point
here is to illuminate the consistency of his thinking.
11
“…man könnte fast sagen, es sei eine reine Gotteslehre” (Englard 2013, 110). Kelsen referred to
himself—perhaps ironically—once even as an “advocatus Dei” (Kelsen 1963b: 711).
17 In Defense of Modern Times 339
Dworkin expresses the firm opinion that “religion is deeper than god,” according
to the first sentence of his lecture, and he explains that a “belief in a god is only one
possible manifestation or consequence of that deeper worldview.” In a sharp contra-
diction to Kelsen, Dworkin says that the “conviction that a god underwrites value…
presupposes a prior commitment to the independent reality of that value” (Dworkin
2013: 1–2). Only consequently does Dworkin presuppose “the objective truth of
two central judgments about values:” “Life’s intrinsic meaning and nature’s intrin-
sic beauty” (Dworkin 2013: 10). But how does one get this security without the
authority of a god? Dworkin argues that there is a need for basic assumptions in
science and mathematics as well, because without the shared assumption that there
is an external world or without accepting the axioms of mathematics, science cannot
certify itself (Dworkin 2013: 17). Dworkin does not aim at verification through
interpersonal agreement but through personal evidence. This is not to be understood
in a merely subjective manner, however, as Dworkin notes “that we cannot have
that conviction without thinking that it is objectively true” (Dworkin 2013: 20).
Now, Dworkin, as a rational thinker, has to draw a line between general religious
worldviews and—for instance—creationist beliefs. For that purpose, Dworkin dif-
ferentiates between two parts of the traditional theistic religions, “a science part and
a value part”—and for him “as a religious atheist,” only the second part matters
(Dworkin 2013: 23). Dworkin then embarks on the fundamental theistic problem:
the image of god, about which he says—and in this point he is in agreement with
Kelsen—that a non-personal god is an “obscure idea” that we no longer need
(Dworkin 2013: 43).
We have to appreciate Ronald Dworkin as a deeply human scholar, who wrote
this rather moving essay at the very end of his life. However, the analogy between
the certainty concerning the real world and the evidence of values does not convince
me. The first may be—in Dworkin’s words—an implicit “assumption” that we
make while we are acting in and speaking about reality. The second seems to me just
an individual experience of evidence, a rather romantic way of “beholding” values
(ein Erlebnis des “Erschauens” von Werten). Furthermore, it does not make a dif-
ference in one’s actual experience whether one believes in reality or not, which is
manifestly not the case with values (A solipsist may argue that, if reality is only an
illusion, then there is no reason not to murder, but this is an expression of a mental
insanity).
Concerning the second argument, the objectivity of values, Kelsen and Dworkin
are indeed just as divided as they are in their respective legal theory. As far as the
interpretation of general legal norms is concerned, legal science could only offer,
according to Kelsen, a framework of possible interpretations; it remains for the
judge to decide among those possibilities. Kelsen called this—not very conve-
niently—an “authentic interpretation” (Kelsen 1960: 346). In Dworkin’s theory, it is
precisely the most important exercise of the judge to find the legally correct inter-
pretation. Therefore, in Kelsen’s view, the famous “hard cases” are outside the
“law’s empire,” but in Dworkin’s view, they are its very heart. Dworkin’s foremost
argument is that the judge cannot think of his opinion as one of many possible
340 C. Jabloner
solutions, but has to be convinced of having found the right solution—the “interpre-
tation aims at truth” (Dworkin 2011: 126).
Here we do not intend to contribute to this basic question of legal interpretation.
Kelsen’s attitude towards interpretation, and its further development in the post-
Kelsenian Viennese school, is a chapter of its own. My concern here is only to point
out that Kelsen and Dworkin consequently followed their respective methods.
However, we perhaps should not neglect the fact that Kelsen and Dworkin are not
addressing the same people. Dworkin has in mind the judge applying the law, while
Kelsen addresses the legal scholar, prohibiting him from selling his opinion as sci-
entific truth. In addition, on the religious level, Kelsen is thinking of the theologian
who reaches out for a scientific description of his (or one’s) faith rather than the
believer himself, who is most certainly Dworkin’s mainspring.
References
Arnold, Eckhard. 2008. Erich Voegelin. In Der Kreis um Hans Kelsen, ed. Robert Walter, Klaus
Zeleny, and Clemens Jabloner, 513–552. Wien: Manz.
Bräuer, Stefan. 2013. Hans Kelsen als Aufklärer –Einsichten und Grenzen. In Secular religion.
Rezeption und Kritik von Hans Kelsens Auseinandersetzung mit religion und Wissenschaft, ed.
Clemens Jabloner, Thomas Olechowski, and Klaus Zeleny, 165–168. Wien: Manz.
Cohen, Hermann. 1928. Religion der Vernunft aus den Quellen des Judentums, 2nd edn, reprint
1995. Wiesbaden: Fourier.
Di Lucia, Paolo, and Passerini Glazel, Lorenzo. 2014. Prefazione all’editione Italiana. Religione
senza un Dio. In Kelsen, Hans. 2014. Religione secolare. Una polemicva contro l’errata inter-
pretation della filosofia sociale, della scienza e della politica modern come “nuove religioni”.
A cura di Paolo di Lucia e Lorenzo Passerini Glazel, IX–XXIII. Milano: Raffaello Cortina
Editore.
Dreier, Horst. 1990. Rechtslehre, Staatssoziologie und Demokratietheorie bei Hans Kelsen, 2nd
ed. Baden-Baden: Nomos.
Dreier, Horst. 2009. Joh 18, Wertrelativismus und Demokratietheorie. In Reflexionen über
Demokratie und Recht, ed. Robert Walter and Klaus Zeleny, 13–31. Wien: Manz.
Dreier, Horst. 2013. “Secular Religion” im Kontext von Kelsens Gesamtwerk. In Secular religion.
Rezeption und Kritik von Hans Kelsens Auseinandersetzung mit religion und Wissenschaft, ed.
Clemens Jabloner, Thomas Olechowski, and Klaus Zeleny, 1–18. Wien: Manz.
Dworkin, Ronald. 2011. Justice for hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA/London: The Belknap Press of
Harvard University Press.
Dworkin, Ronald. 2013. Religion without god. Cambridge/London: Harvard University Press.
Englard, Izhak. 2013. Haben Kelsens Reine Rechtslehre, seine Faszination für Religion und sein
Religionsverständnis einen jüdischen Hintergrund. In Secular religion. Rezeption und Kritik
von Hans Kelsens Auseinandersetzung mit religion und Wissenschaft, ed. Clemens Jabloner,
Thomas Olechowski, and Klaus Zeleny, 101–111. Wien: Manz.
Feichtinger, Johannes. 2010. Wissenschaft als reflexives Projekt. Von Bolzano über Freud zu
Kelsen: Österreichische Wissenschaftsgeschichte 1848–1938. Bielefeld: transcript.
Freud, Sigmund. 2000. Massenpsychologie und Ich-Analyse (1921). In Freud, Sigmund.
Studienausgabe, ed. Alexander Mitscherlich et. al., vol. IX: Fragen der Gesellschaft. Fragen
der Religion. Special edition. Frankfurt: S. Fischer.
Gross, Raphael. 2000. Carl Schmitt und die Juden. Eine deutsche Rechtslehre 2000. Frankfurt/
Main: Suhrkamp.
17 In Defense of Modern Times 341
Schorske, C.E. 1980. Fin de Siècle Vienna. Politics and culture. London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson.
Stadler, Friedrich (ed.). 1997. Wissenschaft als Kultur. Österreichs Beitrag zur Moderne. Wien/
New York: Springer.
Stadler, Friedrich (ed.). 2004. Vertriebene Vernunft. Emigration und Exil österreichischer
Wissenschaft [1988], 2nd ed. Münster: LIT.
Staudacher, Anna L. 2009. Zwischen Emanzipation und Assimilation: Jüdische Juristen im Wien
des Fin-de-Siècle. In Hans Kelsen: Leben—Werk—Wirksamkeit, ed. Robert Walter, Werner
Ogris, and Thomas Olechowski, 41–53. Wien: Manz.
Voegelin, Eric. 1987. The new science of politics. An introduction [1952], 2nd ed. Chicago: The
University of Chicago Press.
Voegelin, Eric. 1997. Der autoritäre Staat. Ein Versuch über das österreichische Staatsproblem
[1936]. Wien/New York: Springer.
Walter, Robert. 1992. Entstehung und Entwicklung des Gedankens der Grundnorm. In
Schwerpunkte der Reinen Rechtslehre, ed. Robert Walter, 47–59. Wien: Manz.
Wenzel, Uwe Justus. 2014. Das Schwarz der Seele. Ein Versuch, Martin Heideggers “Schwarze
Hefte” zu lesen. Neue Zürcher Zeitung, 12. April 2014: 25.
Chapter 18
The Free Exercise Clause and Hans Kelsen’s
Modernist Secularism
18.1 Introduction
Hans Kelsen’s most recent book, Secular Religion (Kelsen 2012) is a passionate
confrontation with leading mid-century thinkers who chose in various ways to
equate intellectual and political movements with religion or at least analogize them
to religion. Kelsen’s abreaction against this characterization marks him as both a
representative and a defender of the high modernism that shaped the social sciences
and humanities while also paving the way for the more pronounced forms of skepti-
cism associated with post-structuralism. The publication of Kelsen’s work is espe-
cially timely for the U.S. legal academy, as numerous U.S. and Canadian scholars,
from a number of perspectives, have similarly grappled with the troublesome but, as
recent U.S. case law indicates, momentous distinction between religious conviction
and other forms of deeply held belief.
Section 18.2 of this Article summarizes Kelsen’s argument in Secular Religion.
First, Kelsen objects to commentators who have characterized modern systems of
scientific1 and political belief as either religious in form or as substitutes for reli-
gion. Second, Kelsen bristles when contemporary commentators claim that indi-
vidual enlightenment and post-enlightenment figures, many of whom are renowned
for their religious skepticism or avowed atheism, structured their thoughts in funda-
mental ways according to religious modes of thinking, incorporating teleology and
eschatology borrowed from Christian theology. Kelsen attacks both modes of
1
I use “scientific” here in the sense of Wissenschaft. The European concept is broader than the
American concept of science. The word encompasses the natural sciences and the social sciences
and even the humanities to the extent that they encompass systematic approaches to knowledge
and information.
D.A.J. Telman (*)
Valparaiso University Law School, Valparaiso, IN 46383, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
analysis and points out how easily the distinction between analogy and identity
melts away.
Section 18.3 briefly addresses Kelsen’s reasons for electing not to publish the
book during his lifetime. Section 18.4 places Secular Religion in the context of the
times in which it was finally published. In the U.S. context, the book is at least as
timely now as it was in the 1960s, as it lands in the midst of a wave of recent publi-
cations and court opinions addressing the legal protections available for the free
exercise of religious belief and religious practices.
In defending modern science against the claim that it is either a religion or a substi-
tute for religion, Kelsen was defending the modernist movement, of which his pure
theory of law is a part.
For Kelsen, both scientific and political beliefs are based in human reason. They
are subject to proof and disproof, and upon disproof, they are discarded or revised.
Religious belief, by contrast, is based on faith and is impervious to demonstration
or counter-demonstration. His polemic is a defense of modern science and modern
politics, which are based not in faith in ultimate, transcendent and revealed truth but
in the human capacity to reason and understand one’s surroundings.
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 345
in religions terms. As Kelsen explains, those Enlightenment figures who were not
outspoken atheists described themselves as deists who rejected Christianity but
retained the concept of a Supreme Being. Their “natural religion” had no theologi-
cal content; it was a moral system (Kelsen 2012: 91). Rousseau distinguished his
“civil religion” from what he termed “true religion” because he considered the latter
to be destructive to the civil spirit. God plays no role in Rousseau’s civic religion; it
is strictly a moral code (Kelsen 2012: 172).
Auguste Comte and Friedrich Engels, embraced the view that the sciences that
they created were forms of anti-religious religion (Kelsen 2012: 159). Comte con-
sciously modeled his society of the future on the Catholic Church, but he did so
because he thought the Church’s organization was efficient, not because he accepted
any part of the Church’s ideology (Kelsen 2012: 162–63). If one thinks of religions
as mainly being systems of thought that provide moral codes for behavior in this
world and hope for a better world to come, one can easily claim that modern
approaches to philosophy, beginning with the Enlightenment association of history
with progress, and political ideologies, ranging from communism to nationalism,
serve the same role for their adherents that religious belief serves for believers.
Kelsen notes the obvious difference: religion defers the hopes for a perfect world
through a separate existence and relies on supernatural intervention to bring that
world about, while modern science and politics believe that human beings can cre-
ate a perfect world here on earth simply through the exercise of our reasoning pow-
ers (Kelsen 2012: 91–128). Kelsen acknowledges chiliastic movements within the
Christian tradition, which, while not eliminating God from the equation, did postu-
late a second earthly paradise (Kelsen 2012: 117). Still, Kelsen insists on an
unbridgeable gap between religious modes of thinking and his understanding of
modern science, which provides us no path from the “is” to the absolute “ought”
(Kelsen 2012: 42–43).
One can easily understand the attraction of the analogy. Modern political move-
ments substitute a “heaven on earth” for the heavenly kingdom. Works such as
Crane Brinton’s A History of Western Morals replace the messiah with a messianic
belief in human progress (Kelsen 2012: 31–32). In the secular religion in which man
is the measure of all things, human lawgivers displace the sovereign Lord, and
morality derived from human reason replaces divine law. And yet, Kelsen finds the
analogy fundamentally misleading in that it ignores the extent to which modern
scientific inquiry, including modern social scientific inquiry and the modern politi-
cal movements that derive from such inquiry, is fundamentally a-religious or even
anti-religious in nature.
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 347
Moreover, the penchant for analogy can lead into intellectual cul de sacs. First,
some scholars characterize a modern thinker as a prophet of a new religion. Next, if
they themselves are invested in a certain religious perspective, they denounce the
modern thinker as a heretic. Finally, they debate which sort of heretic the modern
thinker is. Kelsen cites the example of Fritz Gerlich, who focuses on the Marxist
belief in progress. Gerlach declares communism a “secularized religion of redemp-
tion” and a chiliastic movement, but he concludes that Marxism is a corrupted ver-
sion of the Christian idea (Kelsen 2012: 163). Crane Brinton blames modern natural
science for giving rise to the “heresies of materialism, rationalism, humanism, sci-
entism, naturalism, secularism, evolutionism, positivism and ethical culture”
(Brinton 1959: 275). These heresies are, for Brinton, “great secular religions” asso-
ciated with the likes of Galileo, Newton, Darwin, Locke, Spencer and Marx (Brinton
1959: 277). Voegelin calls both Marx and Nietzsche “speculative Gnostics,” and
calls Marx a Gnostic magician, and Jakob Taubes points to Marx’s dialectics as the
evidence of his Gnosticism (Kelsen 2012: 181, 213). Karl Löwith sees Comte as a
philosophical priest whose scientific age realizes Joachim of Fiore’s vision of a
Kingdom of God on earth, and Voegelin views Comte as in the tradition of Joachim
but also as a “volitional Gnostic” like Marx and Hitler (Kelsen 2012: 148).
It is not surprising that one can identify non-religious thinkers with certain types
of heretical thinkers, but this would only be relevant if they were attempting to con-
tribute to a theological discourse. This manner of characterizing modern social sci-
entists in terms of Christian doctrines does not add anything to our understanding of
their perspectives. Worse, it obscures the fundamentally a-religious or anti-religious
impetus that animates so much of modern social thought and suggests that there is
no escape from religious modes of inquiry.
Kelsen is more suspicious of analogies than most. He cites approvingly Hobbes’s
categorization of metaphor as an abuse of speech in which words are used “in other
sense than that they are ordained for, and thereby deceive others” (Kelsen 2012:
162). Raphael Gross suggests that Kelsen was especially wary of analogies applied
to modes of thought because, throughout his career, Kelsen was dismissed as a
Jewish thinker, and his anti-Semitic adversaries attempted to establish analogies
between Talmudic thought and the pure theory of law (Gross 2013: 113, 119). In
Secular Religion, Kelsen specified the tendency of analogies to exaggerate similari-
ties while downplaying differences and to ignore the ways in which similar termi-
nology can have completely different meanings in two analogized systems of
thought (Gross 2013: 113, 119).
Another reason for Kelsen’s hostility to metaphor might lie in his intellectual
antipathy for Carl Schmitt, whose work on political theology (Schmitt 1922) Kelsen
holds up as an example of the dangers of inappropriate analogical reasoning. Kelsen
accuses Schmitt of confusing analogy and identity in his political theology (Kelsen
2012: 17). In particular, Schmitt equates the omnipotence of God with the omnipo-
tence of the legislature. However, Kelsen points out, God’s omnipotence is unlim-
ited, while the legislature is only omnipotent with respect to its power to promulgate
positive law, a much more modest power (Kelsen 2012: 18).
348 D.A.J. Telman
But Schmitt was by no means alone in mistaking analogue for identity. For
Kelsen, Karl Löwith’s approach to history merges the human-centered philosophy
of history with God-centered theology of history by contending that teleological
philosophies of history that regard history as progressing towards a utopian future
are in fact secularized theologies featuring secularized eschatologies. These con-
cepts are for Kelsen contradictions in terms, as the very essence of secularism is the
elimination of supernatural religious and eschatological elements (Kelsen 2012:
20–21). Thus Kelsen rejects Löwith’s interpretation of Comte’s political philosophy
as eschatological:
But how can Comte’s philosophy be eschatological if he does not and cannot accept the
Christian idea of salvation of the individual soul? The only element that positive philosophy
and the Christian scheme of salvation have in common is the idea of improvement, which
is certainly not a monopoly of the Christian religion (Kelsen 2012: 156).
anticipated a perspective very much like Kelsen’s in defending the extended anal-
ogy in his work between modern political movements and religions. Kelsen cites to
Brinton as acknowledging that, if nationalism is not a theistic religion and that, if
you regard “a theos and a supernatural view of the cosmos an essential mark of a
religion, you must abandon the analogy between religion and nationalism. You will,
however, have thereby abandoned a useful tool for understanding human conduct”
(Kelsen 2012: 269). But Kelsen has a ready response. Brinton cannot decide between
analogy and identity: “He again and again asserts that the Enlightenment and its
offspring are religions” Kelsen has no regrets about abandoning “a highly danger-
ous misinterpretation of the essential elements of modern civilization” (Kelsen
2012: 270).
Make no mistake. Analogies are powerful, and they threaten to rob modern science
of its main intellectual legacy: the liberation of human thought from religious modes
of thinking. Kelsen explains that the attacks on modern social theory as “secular
religions” threaten to re-subordinate science to theology. He cannot specify cause
and effect, but he does note “the work of theologians who welcome this misinterpre-
tation of modern philosophy and science, who want us to go back to religion, to let
theology again rule over science” (Kelsen 2012: 29). Kelsen points to the writings
of Antoine-Gilbert Sertillanges, Reinhold Niebuhr and Arnold Toynbee. Sertillanges
clearly wanted to subordinate science to faith (Kelsen 2012: 43). In Niebuhr and
Toynbee, where one might simply see Cold War denunciations of Communist mis-
readings of history, Kelsen sees similar attempts to subordinate scientific to theo-
logical understandings of history (Kelsen 2012: 44).
Indeed, Kelsen imagines that the wedge created by the idea that modern social
theory and political movements are ersatz religions can open a space for the eradica-
tion of a-religious thought:
If modern social theory is secularized theology and if political ideologies are disguised or
degenerated religion, are we then to think that this secularization, disguise or degeneration
are the fundamental errors of modern civilization, that our social theory and politics are
moving in a wrong direction and should return to their original, but forgotten or wrongly
denied model? As a consequence of this doctrine a desecularization of science and political
ideologies is necessary. Only then will they be able to reach the truth, which, of course, can
only be the truth of God. Thus the emancipation of science and political ideology from
theology and religious authority, to which modern civilization owes its existence, shall be
undone (Kelsen 2012: 43).
Having laid out the fundamental opposition between theological and scientific
modes of inquiry, Kelsen then presents his own readings of the most important rep-
resentatives of modern social thought. In each case, his aim is to demonstrate that
these thinkers consciously sought to and succeeded in eliminating theological
modes of inquiry from scientific methods.
350 D.A.J. Telman
Kelsen begins this part of the book with a brief chapter on Thomas Hobbes. In a
few pages, he refutes Voegelin’s characterization of Hobbes as a Gnostic thinker
(Voegelin 1952: 152). Hobbes cannot be a Gnostic, according to Kelsen, because his
was among the first “attempts to establish a positivistic political and legal theory at
a time when theological speculation and natural-law doctrine were prevailing”
(Kelsen 2012: 85). Voegelin thought that because Hobbes wrote of the “law of
nature” that he was part of that natural law tradition, but Voegelin misread Hobbes.
Hobbes characterizes the state of nature as one in which law is absent. Law only
comes into being with the advent of the state, and the state, as a product of mortal
men, like them, is only a transitory, earthly order (Kelsen 2012: 85–86). On Kelsen’s
reading, Hobbes regarded speculation on eternal legal or cosmological orders as
beyond the scope of his inquiry (Kelsen 2012: 86–87).
The chapter on Hume and Kant is also very short. Apparently, none of Kelsen’s
main interlocutors dared claim Hume as a theological thinker. Although the point
seems unnecessary to Kelsen’s broader argument in Secular Religion, Kelsen’s dis-
cussion of Hume emphasizes the extent of Hume’s rejection of revealed religion,
which Kelsen insists is the “inevitable consequence” of Hume’s empirical skepti-
cism (Kelsen 2012: 131). His brief discussion of Kant stresses that Kant’s transcen-
dental philosophy of epistemology built on Hume’s skeptical empiricism and thus
ruled out any eschatological speculations (Kelsen 2012: 134–135).
Given the patently anti-theological nature of their works, one would think that
Saint-Simon and Proudhon would be unlikely candidates for the title of prophets of
new religions. Nonetheless, Kelsen takes on Etienne Gilson’s treatment of Saint-
Simon’s philosophy as “a new Christianism of science” (Kelsen 2012: 137).
Although Proudhon was an avowed atheist, Karl Löwith characterized him as a
“theologian of progress” and a “religious soul.” Kelsen refutes these views with
numerous quotations from Proudhon evidencing his atheism and his hostility to
religion (Kelsen 2012: 139–40).
Kelsen provides a far more extensive refutation of scholars who have character-
ized the Enlightenment as a religious movement or as an ersatz religion. Ernst
Cassirer errs, in Kelsen’s view, in conflating the Enlightenment fascination with the
problem of evil with theodicy, which is a specifically religious “problem of how
moral evil comes into this world created and governed by an all-good and all-
powerful God” (Kelsen 2012: 94). Enlightenment thinkers regarded evil as a fact in
existence in this world, and it was to be subjected to the same sort of inquiry as any
other fact (Kelsen 2012: 95–96).
In Kelsen’s estimation, Carl Becker’s work on The Heavenly City of the
Eighteenth Century Philosophers (1932) “obliterates the essential difference
between reason and faith” (Kelsen 2012: 97). As a result, he misreads the enlighten-
ment project as one consistent with Christian ideas of service and commitment to
“the humanitarian impulse to set things right” (Kelsen 2012: 98; Becker 1932: 41).
Kelsen objects that Christianity has no monopoly on commitment to service and
humanitarianism, and that moral and political perspectives derived from human rea-
son animated the philosophes (Kelsen 2012: 98). Rather than putting their faith in
some superhuman theological order, the philosophes aspired for humankind,
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 351
through progressive improvements on its past endeavors and the exercise of human
powers, to create the ideal society. For Kelsen, this mode of thinking was as far from
religion as black is from white (Kelsen 2012: 101).
Charles Frankel’s work on the Enlightenment (1948) assumes that the philos-
ophes made metaphysical assumptions because they thought that they could estab-
lish absolute truths. Kelsen points out that the philosophes were empiricists and
believed (mistakenly in Kelsen’s view) that they could arrive at absolute truths with-
out resort to metaphysical claims (Kelsen 2012: 102–03). Crane Brinton similarly
mistakes the philosophes’ penchant for the teleological to be a rough equivalent of
Christian eschatology (Kelsen 2012: 114). But Kelsen regards the philosophes’ per-
spective to be essentially the opposite of eschatology, because it substitutes belief in
progress through human ingenuity for Christian faith in supernatural intervention in
human affairs. Moreover, the Enlightenment telos does not entail any ultimate day
of judgment. There is to be neither reward for good behavior nor retribution for evil.
Rather, the Enlightenment foresaw progress towards a world in which one received
according to one’s needs (Kelsen 2012: 116).
It is somewhat surprising that Kelsen felt the need to devote two entire chapters
to the refutation of claims that Friedrich Nietzsche, who called himself the Antichrist,
was either a Christian or a metaphysician. The extensive treatment was necessary
because major authorities had claimed him as both a Christian and a
metaphysician.
Karl Jaspers argued that Nietzsche’s passionate attacks on Christianity sprang
from his own Christianity (Kelsen 2012: 199). Jaspers located Nietzsche’s
Christianity in his “boundless will to truth,” but Kelsen was no more willing to
acknowledge a Christian monopoly on truth-seeking than on belief in progress
(Kelsen 2012: 200–201). Indeed, although they are distinct in many ways, both
Kelsen and Nietzsche see Christian methods of truth-seeking as antithetical to their
own: “If truth is a value recognized by Christianity, it is not truth in the sense of
science, that is, truth accessible to human reason” (Kelsen 2012: 206). Kelsen also
noted that, if some impulse gave rise to the Nietzschean idea of eternal recurrence,
the impulse would have to be classical, not Christian (Kelsen 2012: 204).
In Kelsen’s view, “Nietzsche’s philosophy clearly, incontestably, passionately
rejects Christian metaphysics” (Kelsen 2012: 222). Kelsen makes this point emphat-
ically in order to refute scholars who have attempted to claim “a close affinity”
between Nietzsche and Kierekgaard (Kelsen 2012: 222–223). But in response to
Heidegger’s treatment of Nietzsche, Kelsen also makes broader claims, rejecting
Heidegger’s suggestion that Nietzsche is a metaphysician (Kelsen 2012: 230).
Kelsen contends that Nietzsche’s relativism is incompatible with any form of meta-
physics (Kelsen 2012: 227). Nietzsche, Kelsen says, could not engage in metaphys-
ics because he has no concept of transcendent truth. Just as one cannot have religion
without God, Kelsen observes that there can be no metaphysics without a concept
of transcendence (Kelsen 2012: 231).
In fairness to Heidegger, as the quotations that Kelsen provides make clear, he
acknowledges that Nietzsche is attempting to combat metaphysics. Heidegger, how-
ever, contends that metaphysics is inescapable and Nietzsche, in attempting to
352 D.A.J. Telman
overcome metaphysics, can only enact and re-inscribe it (Kelsen 2012: 234, n.878).
Kelsen recognizes that Heidegger’s project is not to explicate Nietzsche in his own
terms but to expose the limitations of Nietzsche’s anti-metaphysical project. But
Kelsen contends that Heidegger’s project results in a gross misinterpretation of
Nietzsche (Kelsen 2012: 249).
Kelsen’s explication of modern social science and political theory is clear and con-
sistent throughout. He views modernity as an escape from religious modes of
thought. Modernity replaces a belief in God with a faith in human resourcefulness.
It replaces a hope for the afterlife with an optimism that reason can lead in this
world to solutions to human problems. Modernity need not be anti-religious,
although it often combats the distortions of logic that emanate from religious per-
spectives. Rather, scientific approaches bracket the questions that religion addresses.
Reason lacks the tools to resolve those issues and thus finds reasoned inquiries into
the traditional subject matters of religion to be pointless.
Contemporary writers who identify modernity with or analogize modernity to
religion err in two ways. Some, trapped within their own Christian perspectives, fail
to grasp the extent to which modernity has liberated itself from such perspectives.
Others, more ominously, resist modernity and mischaracterize it in an attempt to
drag social, scientific, and political discourse back into the traditional modes of
thinking from which modernity liberated them.
In Secular Religion, Kelsen goes to war on behalf of his high estimation of the value
of science. He regards the scholars to whom he is responding as posing an actual
danger to the progress of modern science. Given how strongly Kelsen felt about the
subject matter of Secular Religion, it is curious that he decided not to publish the
book during his lifetime.
No writings of Kelsen’s explain his decision not to publish Secular Religion.
Scholars have offered numerous explanations for Kelsen’s decision not to publish
Secular Religion in the 1960s. In defending his book in its concluding chapter,
Kelsen himself offered the simplest explanation for its non-publication—the entire
book was an overreaction to a mere manner of speaking that posed no serious con-
sequences to readers who would not confuse analogies and identities. But Kelsen
insisted that the stakes remained high: he regarded the writers addressed in his book
as one part of a movement aimed “at returning religion to politics, and theology to
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 353
It appears that Kelsen had originally planned the title Religion without God? for the
book that became Secular Religion (Jabloner 2012: XIII). According to Kelsen’s
biographer, Kelsen regretted that title and the narrowness of the definition of reli-
gion that the work entailed. He recognized that some thinkers to whom he was
sympathetic, Julien Huxley and Bertrand Russell, believed in the possibility of reli-
gion without metaphysics or belief in a supreme being (Métall 1969: 91). Kelsen
came to doubt the operative assumption in Secular Religion that religion is impos-
sible without belief in God (Arnold 2013: 38). In defending modern science against
a retreat into theology, Kelsen treated committed atheists who saw social science as
analogous to religion no differently from genuine enemies of modern social science
who derided it as a false religion (Arnold 2013: 38).
As Michael Potacs has pointed out, Raymond Aron was quite clear-eyed about
the ways in which Marxism could be analogized to religion and the ways in which
it was distinct from religion. The analogy was useful to Aron because it helped him
specify the ways in which Marxism, like religion, built up a self-contained and self-
reinforcing system of ideas and thus insulated itself against external critique (Potacs
2013: 98). On the other hand, Aron recognized that Marxism remained anchored in
an empirical reality while religions recognize a transcendental godly realm. Aron
made this difference clear in referring to Marxism as a secular religion (Potacs
2013: 99). This was not enough for Kelsen. For Kelsen, Marxism could be discred-
ited through rational discourse, while religion operated on a separate plane. Still, the
distinction was really a matter of argumentative strategies, and Potacs specultates
that Kelsen came to doubt whether he needed to publish an entire book refuting
people over word choice (Potacs 2013: 99).
his book-length review of Voegelin’s New Science of Politics, although that book,
like Secular Religion, was published after Kelsen’s death (Kelsen 2004).
At least one Voegelin scholar disputes this version of events. Bjørn Thomassen
(2013) cites to a letter that Voegelin wrote to Alfred Verdross in 1956 in which
Voegelin wrote that Kelsen could “publish anything about me that he wishes.”
Voegelin’s only objection was that Kelsen could not expect that Voegelin would
respond to Kelsen’s criticisms (Voegelin 2007: 270). The letter does not really illu-
minate the mystery. Voegelin’s letter comes nearly a decade too early to shed light
on Kelsen’s decision not to publish Secular Religion. Voegelin’s haughty and dis-
missive tone in his letter to Verdross suggests a great deal of resentment towards his
former mentor and actually suggests that Voegelin would be quite annoyed by the
prospect of a publication like Secular Religion.
One refreshing aspect of Secular Religion, written as it was during the chilliest parts
of the Cold War, is Kelsen’s appreciation of Marx’s and Engels’ work. But perhaps
Kelsen, who was already an exile, decided that, given the political climate in the
United States in the 1960s, this was not the time to defend dialectical materialism
(Gross 2013: 121). Voegelin’s warning to Kelsen may have related to Kelsen’s posi-
tive depiction of Marx and Engels. But Kelsen wrote two books criticizing
Bolshevism as a political system and the communist theory of law (Kelsen 1948,
1955).2 In the former, Kelsen set out to show “the paradoxical contradiction which
exists within Bolshevism between anarchism in theory and totalitarianism in prac-
tice and to defend the true idea of democracy against the attempt to obliterate it and
adulterate it by presenting a party dictatorship as the political self-determination of
a free people” (Kelsen 1948: 1–2). One might think that such writings would put
Kelsen’s anti-communist bona fides beyond peradventure. Still, Kelsen might not
have wanted to take the risk.
As in his treatment of other major figures in the history of modern social science,
Kelsen focuses, in his discussion of Marx and Engels, on their anti-metaphysical,
empirical approach to the studies of history of and economics. Kelsen rejects Robert
C. Tucker’s claim that Marxism is a religion because it puts man in the place of God
as a “supreme being.” Marxism is for Kelsen simply a “system of morals” without
any religious character (Kelsen 2012: 179–80). Attempts to read a religious impulse
back into Marx (or Feuerbach) undercuts the fundamentally anti-religious nature of
their thought:
According to these anti-religious thinkers, what man should draw back to himself is not and
cannot be God—whose existence they denied—but all that is best in man and which the
2
I am grateful to George Mazur for calling my attention to these works.
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 355
Christian religion has projected into an imaginary beyond…By drawing back what is best
in man to himself, man abolishes the religious self-alienation, in the same way as by the
proletarian revolution he abolishes his economic self-alienation (Kelsen 2012: 193).
The publishers of Secular Religion had their own reasons for publishing the work
decades after Kelsen had abandoned it (Jabloner 2012: XIV–XV), but the timing of
the publication was serendipitous, as Kelsen’s work constitutes a useful intervention
in an on-going debate about the status of religion in a secular society. Recently, legal
scholars have focused on the question of the special legal status accorded to reli-
gious belief. But their work builds on more fundamental philosophical inquiries into
the nature of religious belief and the status of such belief in a secular society.
Following Jocelyn Maclure and Charles Taylor, I will use the phrase “secular soci-
ety” to connote “a political and legal system whose function is to establish a certain
distance between the state and religion.” (Maclure and Taylor 2011: 2–3). Maclure
and Taylor identify two aims and two modes of secularism. The aims are respect for
the moral equality of individuals and protection of freedom of conscience and of
356 D.A.J. Telman
religion; the modes are the separation of church and state and state neutrality
towards religions (Maclure and Taylor 2011: 20).
The two aims come into conflict when adherents of recognized religions are
accorded certain accommodations or exemptions (Maclure and Taylor 2011: 4).
While some scholars argue that non-religious or non-traditional belief systems are
entitled to exemptions as much as are religious belief systems (Dworkin 2013;
Maclure and Taylor 2011); others argue that no belief systems should be entitled to
such exemptions (Leiter 2013).
Christopher Eisgruber and Lawrence Sager take a somewhat different approach,
focusing not on religious exemptions from generally applicable laws but on a sys-
tem of laws that guarantees the free exercise of religion while retaining its commit-
ment to equal treatment (Eisgruber and Sager 2007). Their principle of Equal
Liberty “insists that no member of the community ought to be devalued on account
of the spiritual foundations of his or her basic commitments” (Eisgruber and Sager
2007:18). On the subject of religious exemptions from generally applicable laws,
Eisgruber and Sager propose that such exemptions be available on religious grounds
where they are also available on other grounds:
Hence the conclusion that the City of Newark had to permit Muslim police officers to wear
beards on grounds of religious necessity, just as it had already permitted other officers to do
so on medical grounds; and hence the conclusion that a high school basketball association
that permitted players to wear eyeglasses was obliged to make a comparable concession to
Orthodox Jews whose religion required that they wear yarmulkes (Eisgruber and Sager
2007: 279–280).
Eisgruber and Sager thus seek to arrive at practical results through a “principled
moderation” (Eisgruber and Sager 2007: 280) that rejects both those who would
strictly separate law and religion and those who would always seek to accommodate
those who claim entitlement to religious exemptions from generally applicable
laws.
Kelsen’s Secular Religion does not directly address the question of religious
exemptions from generally applicable laws. However, like Brian Leiter’s work. it
helps us focus on what may set religious beliefs apart from other belief systems.
Kelsen’s understanding of religion places religious sensibilities at odds with moder-
nity and thus raises interesting challenges for those who would preserve special
exemptions for adherents of religions while also embracing other aspects of the
modern outlook.
A number of recent works by secular scholars have embraced the concept of secular
religion or religion without god. Maclure and Taylor contend that, in countries like
France and Turkey, where secularism arose after “a bitter struggle against a domi-
nant religion,” the temptation is far stronger to make secularism “the equivalent of
religion” in the tradition of Rousseau’s civil religion (Maclure and Taylor 2011: 14).
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 357
Maclure and Taylor’s project is to determine the extent to which, in keeping with the
principle of moral autonomy, a secular society must accommodate religious prac-
tices that might otherwise violate laws of general applicability. For example,
Maclure and Taylor cite with approval a 2004 decision of the Canadian Supreme
Court in which it embraced a justification grounded in moral autonomy for the
accommodation of religious practices (Maclure and Taylor 2011:81–82). However,
the same principle of moral autonomy leads Maclure and Taylor to advocate accom-
modations of all practices, whether religious or not, that derive from “core
commitments.”
The important distinction for them is not between religious and secular core
beliefs but between core commitments and “personal preferences that are not inti-
mately connected to my self-understanding as a moral agent” (Maclure and Taylor
2011: 91). Maclure, and Taylor fuss about mechanisms for preventing excessive
claims of entitlement to special treatment. They would allow a government to refuse
requests for accommodation that: (a) significantly hinder the realization of institu-
tional aims; (b) are excessively costly or burdensome; or (c) impinge on the rights
and freedoms of others (Maclure and Taylor 2011: 100–101). They conclude that
“[t]here do not seem to be any principled reasons to isolate religion and place it in a
class apart from the other conceptions of the world and of the good” (Maclure and
Taylor 2011:105). Thus, religious practices ought to be entitled to no special protec-
tions not accorded to core commitments that derive from secular belief systems.
Ronald Dworkin arrives at a similar solution from a different direction. Rather
than calling for equal treatment of all deeply-held beliefs and practices, whether
religious or secular, Dworkin adopts a broad understanding of religion. While
Kelsen rejected the possibility of a religion without God, Dworkin embraced it,
titling his last book, Religion without God (2013). As Dworkin explains at the out-
set, his view is that “religion is deeper than God” (Dworkin 2013: 1). Dworkin
defines religion as encompassing two views: first, that human life has objective
meaning or importance, with each person carrying a special responsibility to make
her life a successful one; and second, that “the universe as a whole and in all its
parts…is itself sublime: something of intrinsic value and wonder” (Dworkin 2013:
10). Thus Dworkin disagrees with Richard Dawkins, who thought Einstein’s refer-
ences to God were misleading (Dawkins 2006: 8). Einstein may not have believed
in god, but that, in Dworkin’s view would not disqualify him from being a deeply
religious person (Dworkin 2013: 5–6).
Dworkin, like Maclure and Taylor,, applauds the U.S. Supreme Court’s decision
in United States v. Seeger (380 U.S. 163 (1965)) to recognize the right of an atheist
to protection as a conscientious objector (Dworkin 2013: 119–20). But he dislikes
the Court’s willingness to protect any “sincere and meaningful belief which occu-
pies in the life of its possessor a place parallel to that filled by the God of those
admittedly qualifying for the exemption” (Seeger, 380 U.S. at 176). Dworkin
expresses concern that the Supreme Court’s approach would protect a worshipper of
Mammon, and so he would limit protections to beliefs that are “part of and drawn
from a general, sincere, coherent, integrated and comprehensive account of why it
is important for people to live well and what it is to live well” (Dworkin 2013: 122).
358 D.A.J. Telman
Brian Leiter devotes an entire chapter of his Why Tolerate Religion (2013) to the
project of identifying criteria that capture all religions and exclude all non-religions
(Leiter 2013: 31–53). He concludes that all religions: (1) make categorical demands
on their adherents; (2) are insulated, by virtue of being based on faith, from ordinary
standards of evidence and rational justification applicable to both common sense
and science (Leiter 2013: 34); and (3) offer existential consolation to their adherents
(Leiter 2013: 53). Given the way he has defined religion it comes as no surprise that
Leiter concludes that “there is no moral or epistemic consideration that favors spe-
cial legal solicitude toward beliefs that conjoin categorical commands with insula-
tion from evidence…(Leiter 2013: 67). It follows that there is no reason to “tolerate”
deviations from laws of general applicability based on religious belief, nor should
we respect religious belief (Leiter 2013: 90–91), if by “respect” we mean “an atti-
tude of positive appraisal of [a] person either as a person or as engaged in some
particular pursuit” (Leiter 2013: 70).
By contrast, Maclure and Taylor refuse to adopt any definition of religion for
legal purposes. They observe that such definitions tend to lean toward the “three
major monotheisms,” excluding eastern spiritual philosophies, “something that
seems hardly seems justifiable” (Maclure and Taylor 2011: 84). Dworkin goes in the
opposite direction, adopting a definition of religion so broad as to encompass even
the beliefs of some who may not think of themselves as religious or would even
emphatically reject the label.
Dworkin recommends the abandonment of the idea of a special right to religious
freedom. Instead, echoing Maclure and Taylor’s embrace of the moral autonomy
argument, he calls for the recognition of a right to “ethical independence” (Dworkin
2013: 132). Dworkin’s and Maclure and Taylor’s approaches are consistent with
that of the Human Rights Committee in its construction of Article 18 of the
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, which guarantees “freedom of
thought, conscience and religion” (ICCPR 1966: Art. 18.1). The Human Rights
Committee commented that Article 18 “protects theistic, non-theistic and atheistic
beliefs, as well as the right not to profess any religion or belief” (General Comment
22 (1993: 2). The U.S. Supreme Court had some latitude to define conscientious
objection broadly in the Seeger case, in which the Court construed a congressional
enactment, but the U.S. Constitution’s protections of religious freedom pose special
challenges to those who want to erase the distinction between religious and non-
religious convictions.
The U.S. Constitution’s First Amendment states that Congress shall make no law
establishing a state religion, nor may it interfere with any person’s free exercise of
religion (U.S. Const, amend. I). This Amendment has been incorporated through the
Fourteenth Amendment’s Due Process Clause and thus also prohibits state govern-
ments from establishing a religion or infringing upon the free exercise of religion.
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 359
In light of these constitutional provisions, quite a bit turns on whether or not a set
of beliefs is religious in nature. For example, the U.S. Supreme Court recently
exempted religious organizations from the duty to comply with prohibitions on
workplace discrimination so long as the affected employees do “ministerial” work,
and the Court deferred to the defendant congregation’s definition of which employ-
ees can be counted as a minister, so long as the evidence supports that designation
(Hosanna-Tabor Evangelical Lutheran Church & School v. EEOC, 132 S. Ct. 694
(2012)). More recently still, the Court determined that corporations can avail them-
selves of protections of religious liberty under the Religious Freedom Restoration
Act (RFRA) (107 Stat. 1488, 42 U.S.C. § 2000bb, et seq., 1993).
RFRA provides that, where a federal regulation imposes a substantial burden on
religious exercise, that regulation must both serve a compelling government pur-
pose and also constitute the means for achieving that purpose that impose the least
possible restriction on religious exercise (Burwell v. Hobby Lobby, 134 S. Ct. 2751,
2759 (2014)). At issue in Burwell were regulations passed by the U.S. Department
of Health and Human Services intended to implement the Patient Protection and
Affordable Care Act of 2010 (124 Stat 119). These regulations required employers
with 50 or more full-time employees to provide health care coverage for their
employees, including coverage of forms of contraception approved by the Food and
Drug Administration (77 Fed.Reg. 8725–8726 (2012)).
In Burwell, the Court struck down these regulations on the ground that they vio-
lated RFRA. The Court assumed that the government had a compelling interest in
guaranteeing access to the forms of contraception at issue in the case (Burwell, 134
S. Ct. at 2779–2780). It nonetheless found that the regulations violated RFRA
because they were not the least restrictive means available to the government for
achieving its ends (Burwell, 134 S. Ct. at 2781–2782). In so doing, the Court also
ruled that the closely-held plaintiff corporations were “persons” who could avail
themselves of RFRA’s protections of religious freedom. This made sense, according
to the Burwell majority, because protecting the religious freedom of closely-held
corporations like the plaintiffs “protects the religious liberty of the humans who
own and control those companies” (Burwell, 134 S. Ct. at 2768).
RFRA, and the various state RFRAs that have extended it, exempt religious
humans, religious institutions, and now also close corporations held by religious
humans from a wide range of generally applicable laws. In her God vs. the Gavel
(2014), Marci Hamilton has catalogued the consequences of such exemptions.
Hamilton’s book “describes six arenas where religious individuals and institutions
have insisted on the right to avoid the law as they have harmed others: children,
marriage, schools, land use in neighborhoods, prisons and the military, and anti-
discrimination laws” (Hamilton 2014: 36). Her book highlights the many areas in
which the modernist project that Kelsen defends in Secular Religion can be thwarted
by exemptions based on religious belief.
360 D.A.J. Telman
In Religion without God, Dworkin attempts to bridge the gap between the secular
and the religious by means of a definition that most adherents of religion would find
too broad and that some agnostics and atheists would still find ill-suited to describe
their deeply-held commitments. One review of Religion without God concludes that
“the company to which Dworkin belongs or belonged must still converse with more
traditional theists from opposite sides of [a] chasm” (Smith 2014: 1355).
In Secular Religion, Kelsen celebrated determinedly materialist, anti-
metaphysical thinkers, and he energetically opposed any characterization of their
philosophical systems as religious in nature, even if religion is defined as broadly as
Dworkin defines it. That is, the heroes of Kelsen’s narrative are not only without
God.; many of them reject Dworkin’s embrace of objective value, human purpose
and an ordered universe.
Compared with Dworkin and with Kelsen’s various mid-century nemeses
(Voegelin, Löwith, Cassirer, Aron, Brinton), Kelsen defines religion very strictly.
Kelsen seems to have grown so frustrated with the post-war ubiquity of the concept
of ersatz religions that he could no longer tolerate even extended metaphors or anal-
ogies between modern philosophical or political movements and religion. For
Kelsen, a religion must entail a belief in a superhuman being and an end of days in
which either an earthly or an ethereal paradise awaits. Like Leiter, Kelsen associates
religion with a set of beliefs that defy traditional modes of verification.
18.5 Conclusion
Based on Secular Religion, it seems that Kelsen would side with Brian Leiter and
not with Ronald Dworkin or Taylor and Maclure. Kelsen thought that religious
modes of belief are radically different from at least certain non-religious modes of
belief. The Kelsen of the pure theory of law could thus imagine a perfectly coherent
legal system in which religious beliefs are accorded special protections. However,
like Brian Leiter, the Kelsen of Secular Religion seems to think that there are good
reasons for a modern society to reject special protections for religious belief.
Kelsen’s defense of modernity encompasses a rejection of the power of theology in
legal affairs and in other realms of society that, Secular Religion strongly suggests,
are better governed by Enlightenment and post-Enlightenment modes of reasoning
that reject metaphysics, supernaturalism, eschatology and other variants of pre-
modern irrationalism. But Kelsen does not specify those conclusions in the book.
He restricts himself in Secular Religion to a defense of modern science and politics
as projects that define themselves in crucial ways as antithetical to religious modes
of discourse.
18 Free Exercise and Kelsen’s Modernist Secularism 361
Acknowledgments I am indebted to George Mazur for his careful attention to and instructive
comments on multiple drafts of this chapter. I would also like to thank Karen Koelemeyer for her
extraordinary editorial efforts in bringing this chapter and this volume into being. Finally, my work
on this chapter and this volume were made possible with the support and encouragement of the
Hans-Kelsen-Institut in Vienna and through a grant from the Dietrich W. Botstiber Foundation’s
Institute for Austrian-American Studies.
References
Arnold, Eckart. 2013. Bedarf die politische Ordnung einer spirituellen Grundlage? Kelsens Kritik
an Voegelins autoritärer politischer Theologie. In Secular Religion: Rezeption und Kritik von
Hans Kelsens Ausinandersetzung mit Religion und Wissenschaft, ed. Clemens Jabloner et al.,
19–42. Wien: Mainz.
Becker, Carl. 1932. The heavenly city of the eighteenth century philosophers. New Haven: Yale
University Press.
Brinton, Crane. 1959. A history of western morals. New York: Harcourt Brace.
Dawkins, Richard. 2006. The God delusion. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Dworkin, Ronald. 2013. Religion without God. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Eisgruber, Christopher L., and Lawrence G. Sager. 2007. Religious freedom and the constitution.
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Frankel, Charles. 1948. The faith of reason: The idea of progress in the French enlightenment.
New York: Columbia University Press.
Gross, Raphael. 2013. Der Parallelismus als Gefahr: Zur “jüdischen Biographie” von Hans Kelsen.
In Secular Religion: Rezeption und Kritik von Hans Kelsens Ausinandersetzung mit Religion
und Wissenschaft, ed. Clemens Jabloner et al., 113–129. Wien: Mainz.
Hamilton, Marci A. 2014. God vs the gavel: The perils of extreme religious liberty, 2nd ed.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Human Rights Committee, General Comment 22. 1993. U.N. Doc. CCPR/C/21/Rev.1/Add.4.
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights. 1966. 999 U.N.T.S. 171.
Jabloner, Clemens, et al. 2012. Editorial remarks. In Secular religion. A polemic against the mis-
interpretation of modern social philosophy, science and politics as “new religion”, ed. Hans
Kelsen, IX–XV. Wien/New York: Springer.
Kelsen, Hans. 1948. The political theory of Bolsheivism. A critical analysis. Berkeley/Los Angeles:
University of California Press.
Kelsen, Hans. 1955. The Communist theory of law. London: Stevens & Sons.
Kelsen, Hans. 2004. A new science of politics: Hans Kelsen’s reply to Erik Voegelin’s “new science
of politics.” Edited by Eckhart Arnold. Berlin: De Gruyter (Ontos).
Kelsen, Hans. 2012. Secular religion. A polemic against the misinterpretation of modern social
philosophy, science and politics as “new religion”. Wien/New York: Springer.
Leiter, Brian. 2013. Why tolerate religion? Princeton/Oxford: Princeton University Press.
Maclure, Jocelyn and Charles Taylor. 2011. Secularism and Freedom of Conscience. Trans.
J.M. Todd. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Métall, Rudolf Aladár. 1969. Hans Kelsen: Leben und Werk. Vienna: Verlag Franz Deuticke.
Potacs, Michael. 2013. Marxismus als “säkularer” Religion? Kelsen und Aron. In Secular Religion:
Rezeption und Kritik von Hans Kelsens Ausinandersetzung mit Religion und Wissenschaft, ed.
Clemens Jabloner et al., 89–99. Wien: Mainz.
Potz, Richard. 2012. Introductory remarks. In Secular religion. A polemic against the misinterpre-
tation of modern social philosophy, science and politics as “new religion”, ed. Hans Kelsen,
VII–X. Wien/NewYork: Springer.
362 D.A.J. Telman
Schmitt, Carl. 1922. Politische Theologie: Vier Kapitel zur Lehre von der Souveranität. Berlin:
Duncker und Humblot.
Smith, S. 2014. Is God irrelevant? Boston University Law Review, 94: 1339–1355.
Thomassen, Bjørn. 2013. Review of Hans Kelsen. Secular religion. A polemic against the misin-
terpretation of modern social philosophy, science and politics as “new religion”. Plurilogue:
Politics and Philosophy Reviews. Available at http://www.plurilogue.com/2013/01/secular-
religion-polemic-against_28.html.
Voegelin, Eric. 1952. The new science of politics: An introduction. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Voegelin, Eric. 2007. The collected works of Eric Voegelin: Selected correspondence, 1950–1984.
Edited by Thomas Hollweck. Columbia/London: University of Missouri Press.
Index
A C
A posteriori judgment, 266, 282 Capitalism, 188, 195, 353
A priori judgment, 266, 267, 272, 273, 281, Cardozo, Benjamin, 274–278, 280, 283
282 Categories, 8, 12, 25, 165, 166, 172, 200,
Achterberg, Norbert, 224 201, 242, 266, 267, 269, 281,
Addressee, 71, 179, 184, 244, 297–317 283, 284, 289
Alexy, Robert, 24 Chevron, 309, 311–313
Allegheny College, 274, 275, 277, 278, 283 Choice hypothesis, 64
Analytical judgment, 266 Cognition, 12, 23, 48, 59, 60, 69, 119, 121,
Anti-positivism, 116, 335 124–127, 131, 185, 253, 256,
Anti-Semitism, 218–219, 337 258–260, 265–296
Aron, Raymond, 335, 345, 348, 353, 360 Cognitivism, 186
Association of German Scholars of Public Common law, 4, 20, 164, 186, 202, 231–234,
Law, 217, 221, 224 276, 277, 288
Audience, 136, 162, 170, 265, 304, 308, 310 Comte, August, 345–347
Austin, John, 18, 232–234, 298, 321 Conflict of laws, 50, 69–73, 163
Austrian Constitution, 202 Constitutional courts, 70, 175, 201–207, 255
Constitutional review, 201, 202, 204, 206, 207,
209, 210
B Constructivism
Barzun, Jacques, 25 decision procedure, 320, 323–324
Basic Law (German constitution), 222–224 rational procedure, 11, 322
Basic norm (Grundnorm), 6, 21, 24, 180 Contract law
presupposition of, 20, 22, 49 bilateral contract, 277, 278
whether a matter of choice, 24 consideration, 274
Basic rights, 177, 179, 186, 189, 196, 207, mutual intention of the parties, 268, 286
222, 223 unilateral contract, 277, 278
Becker, Carl, 345, 350 Critical legal scholars, 204, 208
Bernstorff, Jochen von, 8–10, 35, 42, 51, 60, Custom, 38, 46, 95, 178, 188, 194,
64, 78, 85–99, 181 221, 327
Beyleveld, Deryck, 319, 320, 326, 327
Bienenfeld, Rudolf, 164, 166, 167, 172
Brinton, Crane, 345–348, 351, 360 D
Brunkhorst, Hauke, 181 Decision maker, 187, 250, 251
Business law, 265–296 Decisionism, 175–183
G J
Gardner, John, 24 Jackson, Robert L. (Justice), 178
Globalization, 194, 195 Jaspers, Karl, 345, 351
Green, Leslie, 19 Jesch, Dietrich, 224
Index 365
Judicial deference, 309, 311, 313 theory of democracy, 136, 225, 333
Justice theory of justice, 11, 168, 206, 236
irrational ideal, 153, 236, 240, 321, time in the United States, 11
322, 324 treatment of war criminals, 93
social happiness, 321 U.S. reception of, 2, 4, 115, 116, 234
Justice, procedural, 185, 186, 191 value relativism, 239, 245, 334, 338
view on religion, 142, 146
views on “crimes against peace”, 86, 91,
K 92, 94
Kadi I and Kadi II cases, 197, 198, 201 views on Nuremberg Tribunal, 10
Kadi, Yassin Abdullah, 201 views on religion, 12
Kant, Immanuel Walgreen Lectures, 135, 231
neo-Kantian theories, 25 work for U.S. government, 10, 101–112
transcendental deduction, 25, 281 Knowledge, constitutive, 269, 283, 291
Kantorowicz, Ernst, 128 Koskenniemi, Martti, 89, 90, 193, 208–210
Kaufmann, Erich, 224
Kellogg-Briand Pact, 92–94, 108, 109, 194
Kelsen, Hans L
basic norm, 6, 7, 17, 19–23, 25, 26, 39, 40, Langdell, C.C., 291
43–48, 181, 182, 185, 192, 270, Law
271, 280, 338 Anglo-American, 10, 189
critique of ideology, 239–243, 333 fragmentation of, 208, 209
defense of science, 12 functional definition of, 182
democracy as the idea of freedom, 150, paradigms of, 208
156, 334 validity of, 38, 39, 47, 68
indeterminacy, 118, 128–130 League of Nations, 86, 87, 89, 90, 103, 108, 194
international judiciary, 85–91 Lefort, Claude, 118, 128–130
international law, 2, 7, 9, 10, 18, 38, 41, 42 Legal evolution, 182, 188
international relation, 1, 78, 85–88, 90, Legal formalism, 4, 182
182, 193, 230 Legal pluralism, 50, 59, 60, 68, 70, 71, 74, 76,
Jewish background, 12, 331 78–81, 192, 193, 208
legal interpretation, 22, 254, 309, 311, 340 moral consequences of, 76
legal monism Legal positivism, 5–6, 18, 107, 116, 119, 120,
and conflict of laws, 50, 69–73 161, 165, 166, 175, 219, 220, 235,
international monism, 9, 64, 66, 67, 69, 239, 243, 249, 250, 252, 253, 260,
70, 72, 73, 75–79 265, 268, 270, 273, 336
moral consequences of, 74–79 Legal realism, 4, 5, 162–166, 201–207, 232,
national monism, 64, 66, 67, 75–78, 81 249, 260
strong monism, 9, 60, 74, 76 Legal sociology, 6, 162, 164–166, 180,
weak monism, 9, 61, 65, 74, 76, 79 234, 333
on Anders Nygren’s Agape and Eros, 155 Leipzig trials, 108, 109
on equality, 135, 153–159, 334 Leiter, Brian, 250–252, 254–256, 258–260,
on justice, 11, 115, 123, 153–159, 356, 358, 360
167–169, 235, 240, 241 Liberal tradition, 137–140
on Niebuhr’s relativism, 146 Liberalism, 120, 136, 137, 183
pure theory of law, 1, 2, 5–7, 9, 23, 26, 31, political, 190, 221
36, 40, 42, 46–48, 50–54, 62, 97, Llewellyn, Karl, 3, 258, 259, 292
102, 116, 120, 149, 161, 166–173, Logic
180, 182, 220, 224, 231, 234–236, contradiction, 320, 322, 323, 325
249, 252, 299–300, 332, 335, 337, inference, 269
344, 347, 360 London Agreement, 91, 92, 94, 95, 107
pure theory of law and democracy, 334 Löwith, Karl, 345, 347, 348, 350, 360
reception in Germany, 225 Luhman, Niklas, 189
366 Index
Pure theory of law, 5–7, 11, 31–36, 38, 39, Synthetic judgment, 266, 267, 272, 282, 285
47, 50–54, 74, 101, 121–123, 153,
161, 162, 165–173, 232, 233, 241,
242, 253–255, 258, 260, 265, 267, T
299–300, 309, 319, 322, 323, Taylor, Charles, 355–358, 360
336, 355 Teleology, 182, 280–288, 292, 343
Theoretical reason, 12, 272, 285–287, 289,
290, 293
R Theory of legal hierarchy, 65
Radbruch, Gustav, 178, 219 Tolerance, 35, 80, 81, 117, 120, 126–128,
Rationalization, cultural, 187 146, 147, 153, 236, 237, 239, 242,
Rawls, John, 11, 320, 323, 324, 327 243, 348
Raz, Joseph, 20, 22–24, 59, 67, 77, 79, Toleration, 140, 145–159, 188, 192
192, 336 Transcendental argument(ation), 25, 26, 40,
Reason, 6, 31, 37–40, 43, 46, 62, 65, 74, 76, 48, 49, 181, 185
78, 96, 108, 119, 120, 125–127, Transcendental illusion, 269, 270, 280,
141, 143–145, 149, 151, 154, 171, 289–292
179, 181, 192, 202, 205, 206, 234, Triepel, Heinrich, 224
236, 240, 243, 244, 265–296, 320,
322, 324–327, 332, 344, 346–348,
350–352, 358 U
Reductionism, 36, 37, 40, 43, 47–49 U.S. Constitution
Reflexive procedure, 181 Establishment Clause, 358–360
Religious Freedom Restoration Free Exercise Clause, 343–360
Act (RFRA), 359 U.S. Department of State, 359
Rule of recognition, 19, 21, 63, 68, 79, UN High Commissioner for
282, 289 Refugees, 209
Rupp, Hans Heinrich, 224 UN Security Council, 98
Uncertainty, 97, 129, 166, 305, 308
United Nations War Crimes, 106, 108
S Unity of law, 7, 9, 39–44, 47, 61, 63, 64,
Sager, Lawrence, 356 66, 74
Schauer, Frederick, 5, 24, 75, 250, 251, 256, Universal Declaration of Human Rights
258–260 (1948), 196, 198
Schmalz-Bruns, Rainer, 196
Schmitt, Carl, 81, 90, 175, 176, 183, 192,
202, 203, 218–220, 224, 335, 337, V
347, 348 Validity
Secularism, 139, 148, 149, 343–360 binding force, 326
Self-reflection, 172 existence, 77, 320, 324–327
Smend, Rudolf, 218, 222, 224 Value
Social contract, 184, 193 factual value judgment, 320, 321
Social science normative value judgment, 320, 321
normative science, 319–321, 323, 324, objective value, 320–323, 338, 360
326, 327 subjective value, 150, 169, 240, 320, 321,
sociology, 224, 238, 244, 320, 323 323, 324
verification, 320, 339 Vienna Declaration (1993), 199
Sociology, 1, 5, 149, 230, 238, 319, 321, 326 Voegelin, Eric
Statutory, 46, 183, 192, 299, 306, 307, anti-positivism, 335
309, 314 critique of Gnosticism, 335, 345, 347
Stevenson, C. L., 321 Volition
Strauss, Leo, 11, 12, 115–131 psychological volition, 321
Super-ego, 166, 172, 334 real volition, 320, 321, 324, 325, 327
368 Index