Time and Memory)
Time and Memory)
Founding Editor
J. T. Fraser
VOLUME XII
Time and Memory
Edited by
Jo Alyson Parker,
Michael Crawford
and
Paul Harris
BRILL
LEIDEN • BOSTON
2006
About this book series The nature of time has haunted humankind through the ages. Some
conception of time has always entered into our ideas about mortality and immortality, and
permanence and change, so that concepts of time are of fundamental importance in the study
of religion, philosophy, literature, history, and mythology. How we experiences time physi-
ologically, psychologically and socially enters into the research of the behavioral sciences, and
time as a factor of structure and change is an essential consideration in the biological and
physical sciences. On one aspect or another, the study of time cuts across all disciplines. The
International Society for the Study of Time has as its goal the interdisciplinary and compara-
tive study of time.
BD638.I72 2004
115—dc22 2006049032
ISSN 0170-9704
ISBN-13: 978-90-04-15427-8
ISBN-10: 90-04-15427-2
© 2006 by Koninklijke Brill NV, Leiden, The Netherlands
Koninklijke Brill NV incorporates the imprints Brill, Hotei Publishers, IDC Publishers,
Martinus Nijhoff Publishers and VSP.
Dedication ...................................................................................................... v
List of Contributors ...................................................................................... xi
Foreword ......................................................................................................... xvii
Michael Crawford, Jo Alyson Parker, Paul Harris
Founder’s Address
Reflections Upon An Evolving Mirror ..................................................... 7
J. T. Fraser
Response: Globalized Humanity, Memory, and Ecology ................ 27
Paul Harris
Preface to Section I
Inscribing and Forgetting ............................................................................. 35
Jo Alyson Parker
Chapter One
The Body as a Medium of Memory ........................................................... 41
Christian Steineck
Response ..................................................................................................... 53
Remy Lestienne
Chapter Two
Body Memories and Doing Gender: Remembering the Past and
Interpreting the Present in Order to Change the Future ................. 55
Karen Davies
Response ..................................................................................................... 70
Linda McKie
viii contents
Chapter Three
Coding of Temporal Order Information in Semantic Memory .......... 73
Elke van der Meer, Frank Kruger, Dirk Strauch,
Lars Kuchinike
Chapter Four
Telling the Time of Memory Loss: Narrative and Dementia ............... 87
Marlene P. Soulsby
Response ..................................................................................................... 98
Alison Phinney
Chapter Five
Georges Perec’s “Time Bombs”: about Lieux .......................................... 101
Marie-Pascale Huglo
Chapter Six
Seeking in Sumatra ........................................................................................ 115
Brian Aldiss
Preface to Section II
Inventing .......................................................................................................... 125
Paul Harris
Chapter Seven
Furnishing a Memory Palace: Renaissance Mnemonic Practice and
the Time of Memory ................................................................................ 129
Mary Schmelzer
Chapter Eight
The Radiance of Truth: Remembrance, Self-Evidence and
Cinema ........................................................................................................ 145
Heike Klippel
contents ix
Chapter Nine
Tones of Memory: Music and Time in the Prose of Yoel Hoffmann
and W. G. Sebald ...................................................................................... 163
Michal Ben-Horin
Response ..................................................................................................... 176
David Burrows
Chapter Ten
Once a Communist, Always a Communist: How the Government
Lost Track of Time in its Pursuit of J. Robert Oppenheimer ......... 179
Katherine A. S. Sibley
Response ..................................................................................................... 197
Dan Leab
Chapter Eleven
Temporality, Intentionality, the Hard Problem of Consciousness
and the Causal Mechanisms of Memory in the Brain: Facets of
One Ontological Enigma? ...................................................................... 199
E. R. Douglas
Chapter Twelve
Jump-starting Timeliness: Trauma, Temporality and the Redressive
Community ............................................................................................... 229
Jeffrey Prager
Chapter Thirteen
Black in Black: Time, Memory, and the African-American
Identity ....................................................................................................... 247
Ann Marie Bush
x contents
Chapter Fourteen
Remembering The Future: On the Return of Memories in the Visual
Field ............................................................................................................. 261
Efrat Biberman
Responses ................................................................................................... 275
Shirley Sharon-Zisser
Robert Belton
Chapter Fifteen
Family Memory, Gratitude And Social Bonds ........................................ 279
Carmen Leccardi
Chapter Sixteen
Time to Meet: Meetings as Sites of Organizational Memory .............. 303
Dawna Ballard and Luis Felipe Gómez
Brian Aldiss is a prolific and diverse writer. His history of science fiction,
Billion Year Spree, broke new ground in science fiction studies, and he has
achieved much acclaim for his extensive publications of science fiction short
stories and novels, including the trilogy the Helliconia novels, Spring, Summer
and Winter. He has won most of the important awards in the SF field. Roger
Corman filmed his novel Frankenstein Unbound and his short Story Supertoys
Last all Summer Long formed the basis of the Kubrick/Spielberg movie A.I.
His writings have become more and more diverse, with his autobiography,
Twinkling of an Eye, his elegy for his wife, When the Feast is Finished, his
utopia, written with Roger Penrose, White Mars, his poetry, plays and now
a possible opera based on his recent novel, Jocasta. He is an actor, a lively
speaker and was made a Doctor of Literature. Last year he was invested in the
O.B.E. (Order of the British Empire) for services to literature.
Robert Belton is the Dean of the Faculty of Creative and Critical Studies
in the University of British Columbia Okanagan. A well-known art historian
and award-winning teacher, Dr. Belton joined the faculty of the Department
of Fine Arts at UBC Okanagan’s predecessor, Okanagan University College,
in 1992. He has published widely in his areas of interest: art theory, criticism
and historiography; and modern and contemporary European and North
American art and architecture. He has also acted as a curator, participated as
a juror, served as an artist and/or technician, and discussed contemporary art
issues in public forums not only in British Columbia but also across Canada
and overseas.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. xi–xvi
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
xii list of contributors
Karen Davies worked at the Swedish National Institute for Working Life
and was director of a national research program on social exclusion in the
labor market. She was also associate professor at the Department of Sociology,
University of Lund, Sweden. Since the 1980’s, she published widely on the
issue of time and gender.
Peace and Change, and Diplomatic History. Her books include the prize-
winning Loans and Legitimacy: The Evolution of Soviet-American Relations,
1919–1933 (1996); The Cold War (1998); and Red Spies in America: Stolen
Secrets and the Dawn of the Cold War (2004). She is book review editor
for Intelligence and National Security as well as Commonwealth Speaker
for the Pennsylvania Humanities Council, and she serves on the U.S. State
Department’s Historical Advisory Committee, the Council of the Society
for Historians of American Foreign Relations, and the Board of Editors of
American Communist History.
As sensate beings afloat on the river of time, the only faculty that we possess
that can endow us with both a sense of permanence and identity is memory.
Memory plants signposts along the banks of where we have been, fixes
markers of our experience of the present, and helps us to chart our course into
the future. Memory links experience with thought, permits reflection and
planning, and helps us to form our very selves. That said, as much as memory
fixes time, memory is also a labile medium of it. A philosopher of time and
memory, Paul Ricoeur is careful to differentiate between the recollection of
directly experienced events (memory) and the retrieval of conveyed facts
(memorization). Both are prone to errors in fidelity and also to manipulation
since they are potentially subject to creative and destructive impulses. Both
require inscription, which also, somewhat perversely, requires forgetting and
inventing. We are constantly recalling and recasting memories and in a real
sense re-inventing our past and ourselves.
Memory takes many forms, from personal recollections to written histories
and narratives. It can reflect an intensely personal dialog, an impersonal
electronic blip, or a collaborative societal project. Memory can be fixed
in architecture, DNA, silicon, or our bodies—it can be dynamic or static,
reliable or ephemeral. Quite apart from serving as a medium to record and
reflect the passage of time, memory also has the power alter our experience of
it. Memory can dilate potent events to huge proportions, and equally, it can
constrict uneventful or inconvenient experiences to the point of vanishing.
Our experience of time is variable because our memory is plastic.
This volume presents selected essays from the 12th triennial conference of
the International Society for the Study of Time. Inscribed memory can take
many forms, so it was appropriate that the conference was housed at Clare
College, Cambridge, an institution that was founded in 1326, and parts
of which have been built and elaborated upon ever since. Along a similar
theme, we are attempting an experiment to build and elaborate upon the
arguments presented in the volume’s essays: we solicited our reviewers to
divest themselves of their anonymity and to provide short responses to the
works that they assessed, and a number of them did so. In this manner we
hope to stimulate further thought and discussion. Following the traditional
xviii michael crawford, jo alyson parker, paul harris
lectures from the Society’s Founder and from the President, the volume is
divided into three sections that reflect themes apparent in the discourse of the
meeting. The first two sections, “Inscribing and Forgetting”, and “Inventing,”
are followed by “Commemoration.” The essays grouped under the title
“Inscribing and Forgetting” explore the mechanisms by which we remember
and forget, and they compel us to consider the importance of memory for our
sense of individual identity. As the essays make clear, memory and temporality
are integrally related, for it is by our present accessing of past memories
that we can move forward into the future. Time can distort and destroy
memory—and consequently a stable sense of self. The section entitled
“Inventing” features essays that address, from very different perspectives, ways
in which new memory practices, concepts and effects constitute inventions
in the history of human memory. Such mnemonic inventions unfold at the
level of individual minds, philosophical ideas, and complex social relations
alike. The processes of inventing memory reviewed here do not involve the
truth or verifiability of specific memories, as the section heading could imply.
Under the moniker of “Commemoration,” we have grouped essays that deal
with a unique and constructed form of memory. Commemoration demands
collaborative inscription and subscription to a version of history that may or
may not reflect reality. Commemoration serves to project past experience
into the future: it is a form or memory that is often imbued with a moral or
pedagogical agenda, and it can often play a profound social role. That said,
as some of the essays take pains to show, when frailties rather than valorized
strengths are recast to perform a commemorative function, interesting things
can happen both to our sense of time as well as to our memories.
This last section, “Commemoration,” is appropriate not only in a temporal
sense, but in a thematic sense as well. The conference program included a
beautiful and very moving memorial concert by Deborah Bradley to our
colleague musicologist and composer Jon Kramer, who died unexpectedly just
prior to the meeting, The volume itself is dedicated to one of its contributors,
Karen Davies, who worked hard to complete her essay before her premature
death in Spring 2006.
Finally, thanks are due to Thomas Weissert for creating a website that
facilitated communication among the coeditors as well as for his patient and
efficient support of our work. Furthermore, we must thank Tara Wessel for
editorial assistance. We acknowledge our great debt to the many reviewers
who helped to ensure the academic rigor of the volume and to Brill Academic
Publishers, which continues to invest in our collaborative project, The Study
of Time.
PRESIDENT’S WELCOMING REMARKS
Remy Lestienne
Summary
The property of memory is strongly entangled with the notion of Time. Consideration
of cosmological, physical, biological, and human memories shows the importance of
collectiveness in its full expression. In humankind, affectivity seems to be of special importance
for the transfer from short term memory to long term memory and the creation of permanent
memory traces. The corresponding neurobiological mechanism in the brain implicates specific
neurobiological networks, in which the hippocampus, the amygdala and the prefrontal cortex
all play a part. This process seems to be largely controlled by neuromodulation networks of
bioamines, in particular dopamine, the correct function of which seems to depend on the
affective input from the subject, although much remain to be ascertained in this domain.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 1–6
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
2 remy lestienne
Alex Thomson will describe the mechanisms that underlie memory in the
human brain. I am sure that she will introduce early in her talk the classical
distinction between short term memory, now more often extended to the
concept of working memory, with their properties of limitation on their
capacity (classically, 5 to 7 items) and lability or erasability, and long term
memories, that are much more permanent and possesses various sub-kinds
such as declarative and procedural memories. One of the key questions,
one of the most intriguing problems posed to neurobiologists, sociologists,
psychiatrists, etc. . . . is the condition of passage from the short term memory
to long term memory. Allow me to focus for a while on this fascinating
problem.
In short, the question may be put in this way: How is it that I remember
perfectly well, in complete detail, the moment of first encounter with the
woman who would later become my wife, when I glanced at her in the
ballroom, with her blond hair bun and her red dress. I have completely
forgotten hundreds of women as attractive as she was at that moment, and
that I have met before or after this first encounter. How is it that I remember
perfectly well the locale, time and hour, and other circumstances in which I
learnt of the murder of President John Kennedy, when so many important
events of the world left only vague traces in my memory?
In opening ways to discuss this matter, I would like to stress two particular
aspects of the conditions of passage from short term to long term memories.
The first one is collectiveness, the opposition between individual, personal,
and so to speak selfish memory, and the more open, shared, collective
memories. The second is affectivity, particularly the role of positive affectivity,
attractiveness, desire, love and tenderness in memorisation.
Let us pause a moment on the question of collectiveness. You know that,
at the level of the material world of physics, there is no possible sense of the
passage of time for an isolated particle, a single atom. A radioactive atom,
for instance, always has the same probability to decay in the next second,
independently of how much time has elapsed since its creation. Let us state
this with a bit of anthropomorphism by saying that a single atom has no
memory. By contrast, a macroscopic sample of radioactive stuff, a large
collection of atoms has a collective memory, in the sense that collectively the
number of decays they suffer testifies to the passage of time.
Cosmological memory of the remote events related to the origin of the
universe is also evidently a kind of collective memory. A local fluctuation of
the ever-encompassing background radiation, in a given narrow direction of
the celestial vault, will tell nothing about the history of the universe. But the
president’s welcoming remarks 3
whole map of such fluctuations has been explored and exploited recently to
learn lessons about the history of the universe.
At the biological level, the genome has been correctly looked at as the
main repository of the history of the evolution of the considered species. In
the animal kingdom, the genome is also the repository of a huge collective
memory of habits, instincts, which dictate the behaviour of each individual
in most circumstances of life.
But this collective aspect of memory acquires specific and even more
essential characters with humankind.
Thanking in passing Mark Aultman for having shared with us the review
of Juan Luis Arsuaga’s book The Neanderthal’s Necklace (2002), I will borrow
from the latter a few remarks that struck me when reading through.
As it is now well known, Neanderthals are not our antecedents but our
cousins. In other words, there was a time on earth, about 40 000 years ago,
when two distinct species, incapable of cross-fertilisation, coexisted. Brain
size, at first sight should have given the advantage to the Neanderthals,
whose brain volume was in average slightly larger than that of Homo sapiens.
Both species seemed equally aware of their mortal condition. However,
the complexity of the Homo neanderthalis brain may have been somewhat
lower than our own. One way of judging this is to compare the traces of the
blood vessels on skulls of specimen of the two species. Such a comparison
displays a higher blood irrigation of the Homo sapiens as compared to Homo
neanderthalis, particularly in the parietal region (Saban, 1995). Arsuaga
argues that there is a correlation between the complexity of primate social
groups and the complexity (rather than the size) of their neocortex.
When a new ice age occurred, Neanderthals died out and Cro-Magnon
flourished. One possible explanation is that, unlike Cro-Magnon, the
pharynx of Neanderthal was of such a structure that he was unable to utter
certain sounds, in particular most vowels, possibly enforcing a simpler social
life and smaller group size relative to those of Cro-Magnon’s. According to
Arsuaga, the Neanderthals never attained high local population densities,
and biological and cultural resources were spread too thinly for their survival.
In short, their collective memory system was too simple, too short-ranged for
survival in the adverse conditions that finally prevailed 40 000 years ago in
Europe. By contrast, modern humans formed larger groups, with population
clusters that were reproductively viable and economically self-sufficient.
I shall borrow a second reflection on the importance of collectiveness in
human memorisation and development from observations of infants that
were reared by animals, as illustrated by the documented cases of the “feral”
4 remy lestienne
or “wild” children. Is it not striking that, despite the fact that the size and
organisation of their brain was similar to that of other adult humans, such
infants deprived of social exchanges in their childhood never reached the
state of a mature brain, capable of reasoning and socialising? An American
researcher, Jaak Panksepp (1998), has devoted his entire life to study the
influence of emotions on psychological development, not without some
condescension from his colleagues.
In a recent review article on “Child Abuse and Neglect and the Brain”, Danya
Glaser (2000) enumerates the effects of child abuse and neglect in the brain:
disregulation of the hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal axis, weakening of the
parasympathetic and catecholamine responses, maybe even a general reduction
of the brain size. She stresses that “neglect and failure of environmental
stimulation during critical periods of brain development may lead to permanent
deficits in cognitive abilities”. These deficits may be due, in part, to the lack of
exercising the property of neuronal plasticity, which may extend well beyond
the critical period of childhood; for example, recent studies on rodent have
shown that neurogenesis continues throughout adult life in the dentate gyrus
of the hippocampus, a very important nervous centre for memorisation.
As everyone would have guessed, the early mother-infant interaction is of
particular importance in this frame. In the brain of the infant who sees the
responsive mother’s face, brain stem dopaminergic fibres are activated, which
trigger high levels of endogenous opiates. The endorphins are bio-chemically
responsible for the pleasurable aspects of social interaction and social affect
and are related to attachment. Dopamine is postulated to mediate the
behavioural facilitatory system, activated by rewarding (or aversive but
surmountable) stimuli. An interesting psychobiological attachment theory
has been expounded by Kraemer (1992), who suggests a central role for
biogenic amines as mediators of secure or insecure attachment. Thus the
importance of the question of the role of bioamines in the “now print” signal
between short term memory and long term recording system.
While many studies have been devoted to the interaction between fear and
stress and the memorisation system (where the amygdala complex seems to
play a central role), very few papers are available on the role of affectiveness,
loving and caring emotions, in memorisation. We know that fear messages
from the amygdala arriving into the nuclei of the brain stem, and CRH
(corticotropin-releasing hormone) from the hypothalamus, released by stress,
stimulate the locus coeruleus and thus noradrenaline secretion in the brain
(LeDoux, 1996). This demonstrates direct links between the noradrenergic
and the cortisol responses to stress.
In pre-clinical studies, stress was also shown to enhance the release
president’s welcoming remarks 5
References
Arnsten, A. F. “Development of the Cerebral Cortex: XIV. Stress Impairs Prefrontal Cortical
Function.” Journal of the American Academy of Child and Adolescent Psychiatry 38, no.
2 (1999): 220–2.
Arsuaga, Juan Luis de, Andy Klatt, and Juan Carlos Sastre. The Neanderthal’s Necklace: In
Search of the First Thinkers. New York: Four Walls Eight Windows, 2002.
Bremner J. D., Scott T. M., Delaney R. C., Southwick S. M., Mason J. W., Johnson D. R., Innis
R. B., McCarthy G., Charney D. S. “Deficits in short-term memory in posttraumatic
stress disorder”. American Journal of Psychiatry 150, no. 7 (1993): 1015–9.
Glaser, D. “Child Abuse and Neglect and the Brain—a Review.” Journal of Child Psychology
and Psychiatry 41, no. 1 (2000): 97–116.
Kraemer, G. W. “A Psychobiological Theory of Attachment.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences
15, no. 3 (1992): 493–511.
LeDoux, J. E. The Emotional Brain, New York: Simon & Schuster, 1996.
Nachmias, M., M. Gunnar, S. Mangelsdorf, R. H. Parritz, and K. Buss. “Behavioral Inhibition
and Stress Reactivity: The Moderating Role of Attachment Security.” Child Development
67, no. 2 (1996): 508–22.
Panksepp, J. Affective Neuroscience: The foundations of Human and Animal Emotions, New
York: Oxford Univ. Press, New York, 1998.
Saban, R. “Image of the human fossil brain: endocranial and meningeal vessels in young and
adult subjects” in: Origins of the Human Brain (Changeux J. P. and Chavaillon J. ed.),
Oxford: Clarendon, Oxford, 1995, pp. 11–39.
Squire, L. R. and Kandel, E. R. Memory: From Mind to Molecules, New York: Sc. Am. Library,
1999.
FOUNDER’S ADDRESS
J. T. Fraser
Summary
This paper suggests that the violent turmoil of our age is a symptom of an identity crisis of
humankind at large, precipitated by globalization. For an understanding of that identity crisis,
the evolutionary origins and uses of intent, memory and identity are sought and interpreted.
This interpretation is then applied to our global laboratory in which many, incompatible
needs demand fulfillment. In that perspective, the identity crisis may be seen as a struggle to
decide upon whose understanding of the past, upon whose collective memories are the plans
for the future of mankind to be based.
The reasons that led to the founding of this Society had nothing to do with
anyone’s interest in the nature of time. They had to do with the puzzlement in
the mind of a man of twenty-one who, in the autumn of 1944, found himself
on a mountainside between two vast armadas. Behind him was the armed
might of Nazi Germany, in front of him the immense masses of the Soviet
Union. He knew that he was watching a struggle between two ideologies,
each of which was convinced that it, and it alone, was destined to fight and
win the final conflict of history. The Soviets had their creed summed up in
their revolutionary anthem: “This is the final conflict / Let each stand in his
place / The international party / Will be the human race. . . .”1 The official
Nazi march said the very same thing, in different words. “This is the final
bugle call to arms / Soon Hitler’s flag will wave o’er every single street. /
Enslavement ends / When soon we set things right.”
Having been aware of both dogmas, I came to wonder whether there does
exist a final conflict in history. Perhaps the buzz bombs the Nazis kept on
sending over London were not the ultimate weapons they were claimed to
1
“The Communist Internationale.” The words are those of Eugene Pottier, a Parisian
transport worker who, in 1871, wrote of “c’est la lutte final.”
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 7–26
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
8 j. t. fraser
be. But, being hungry, cold and miserable, I did not pursue the puzzlement.
All I did was to promise myself that if I ever got out of that hell alive, I
would enroll in Plato’s Academy and report to it about the wisdom of Robin
Goodfellow, “Oh what fools these mortals be!”.2
Nine months after I witnessed the clash of those final conflicts, I stood in
an almost empty St. Peter’s in Rome, in front of Michelangelo’s early Pietà,
a piece of Renaissance marble transfigured by human feelings. I saw two
sculptures in it: a heavenly and an earthly one, joined by the two natures of
the female figure: the mater dolorosa and the amante dolorosa, the grieving
mother and the grieving lover.
The heavenly sculpture showed the Virgin holding the dead body of her
son. In it Michelangelo asserted that the suffering of the Redeemer freed man
from his earthly conflicts and opened up the way to a fulfilled, everlasting
life.
I could not help but observe that the Virgin’s figure was that of a woman
much younger than the man whose dead body she held. I did not then know
that her youth, compared to that of the man, had a veritable literature and
that Michelangelo himself was asked about it.3
In the earthly sculpture, the youth of the female figure was no problem.
She was Michelangelo’s Italian model, real or imagined. She was also Dante’s
Beatrice, murmuring “L’Amor che muove il Sole e altre stelle” I gave the age
difference an interpretation that made its way into my writings. This is from
Time, Conflict, and Human Values.
Just out of the havoc of World War II, I was ready to jettison all received
teachings. I failed to see the Virgin holding the body of Christ. What I did
see was a young woman of exquisite beauty holding the body of her man,
murdered by the powers of law and order. Her face is one of infinite sadness
as the irreversibility of his death permeates her unbelieving mind. Her beauty
suggested to me that she was with child for I believed that women were most
beautiful when they were pregnant. In a melodrama the woman of the statue
would faint. In the Roman Pietà she bears up because she carries the child of
the man whose body she holds.4
2
“Midsummer-Night’s Dream,” iii–ii–115.
3
Those youthful features, explained Michelangelo, were the result of her “never having
entertained the slightest immodest thought which might have troubled her body.” R. S.
Liebert, Michelangelo. New Haven: Yale Universoity Press, 1983, pp. 67–8.
(EB 12–98). An entry to that dialogue may be had through the comments on this Pietà in
Umberto Baldini, The Sculpture of Michelangelo, New York: Rizzoli, 00000, pp. 39–40.
4
J. T. Fraser, Time, Conflict, and Human Values. Chicago: University of Illinois Press,
1999, pp. 151–2. Also in the introduction to Il tempo: una presenza sconosciuta, Milano:
Feltrinelli (1991) p. 7.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 9
Soon after my arrival, the promise I made to myself called me to task. How
was I going to tell people about that awesome stage upon which I was an
insignificant walk-on? War stories were coming out in great profusion and I
thought of contributing to the flood. One day, while browsing in a bookstore
in New York’s Greenwich Village, I came upon a comic book called, “The
5
Matt. xi, 28.
6
“Give me your energetic, your rich / Your privileged yearning to be free / The executives of
your teaming shore / Send these, the achievers to us: / We lift our lamp beside the golden door.”
Poem titled “Invitation to New York Corporations Thinking of Moving Their Headquarters
to Fairfield County.” Author is E. J. Brennan, publisher, Fairfield County Magazine, 1976
[TAC 274].
10 j. t. fraser
Nazis and the Invisible Man.” I did not then know the poetry of T. S. Eliot.
If I had, I would have thought of “Go, go, go, said the bird: human kind /
Cannot bear very much reality.”7 Even without Eliot, I gave up the idea of
writing or even speaking about my war experiences.
Instead, I began to search for a vehicle that could carry “Oh what fools
these mortals be” as well as Beatrice’s planetary theory of love. It had to be
a subject of universal interest, yet one that demanded clarity of thought and
exposition, so as to protect it from the merchants of bogus scholarship and
wooly science.8
My memory obliged. I remembered that one morning in gymnasium
we learned about the mathematical pendulum and how it may be used to
measure time. That evening I saw a movie in which people danced around
a fire. The subtitle said that they danced to help them forget the passage of
time. The next day, all across town, there were crowds, ecstatic with hatred
and love. They marched in ways that looked to me like dancing around the
fire.
Obviously, the pendulum was used to measure something people wanted
to forget. If I could trace a connection between the swings of a pendulum
and the desire to forget whatever it measured, then I could bracket both the
foolishness and the greatness of the species. My theme, then, could serve as
did the images on the shield of Achilles: an illustrated encyclopedia in which
people could see themselves both as heavenly and earthly.
Four years after I sailed by the Statue of Liberty, while finishing my work
for my first degree, I wrote a paper called “A short essay on time.” It won a
national humanities award for science students. This encouraged me to search
the literature of time—which led me to the writings of S. G. F. Brandon, then
professor of comparative religion at the University of Manchester.
He maintained that the human knowledge of time is a powerful tool in the
struggle for life because, with the help of memory, it makes preparations for
future contingencies possible. But, it is also the source of “an abiding sense
of personal insecurity” which inspires people to seek such forms of refuge as
represent their ideals of safety from all they fear and help conserve all they
desire.9
7
T. S. Eliot, “Burnt Norton.” In Four Quartets, New York: Harcourt, Brace & World,
1971, p. 14.
8
In a later view: from Blake’s “idiot questioner.” In: “Milton: Book the Second” Line 12 of
the verses for Plate 42. David V. Erdman, ed. The Complete Poetry and Prose of William Blake,
Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982, p. 142.
9
S. G. F. Brandon, Man and his Destiny in the Great Religions. Manchester: Manchester
University Press, 1962, p. 384. For a summary and continuation of this idea see his essay,
reflections upon an evolving mirror 11
“Time and the Destiny of Man,” in J. T. Fraser. ed. The Voices of Time, 2nd ed. Amherst:
University of Massachusetts Press, 1981, pp. 140–60.
10
J. T. Fraser, ed. The Voices of Time, (1966) 2nd ed. Amherst: University of Massachusetts
Press, p. xvii, 1981.
11
John Donne, “Death be not proud . . .”
12 j. t. fraser
3. ISST
12
J. T. Fraser, ed. The Voices of Time (1966) 2nd ed. Amherst: University of Massachusetts
Press, 1981.
13
1 Corinthians 14: 10–11.
14
New York Academy of Sciences, Annals. V. 138, Art. 2. “Interdisciplinary Perspectives of
Time,” pp. 822–48. Quote is from p. 845.
15
G. J. Whitrow, “Foreword” in J. T. Fraser, F. C. Haber and G. H. Müller, eds. The Study
of Time, Heidelberg, New York: Springer Verlag, 1972, p. v.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 13
My inquiries began to bring books and articles by the drove. The themes
people judged essential for a study of time extended from the iconography
of Renaissance art to information conveyed by the bees’ dance, from
medieval poetry to the entropic measure of human migrations. With the
flow of ideas the problems of any interdisciplinary dialog became evident.
Namely: different disciplines employed different jargons, had different
criteria for testing for truth and maintained different, unstated assumptions
about reality. Also, opinions about which field of knowledge was the most
appropriate one for studying the nature of time, though widely divergent,
were always accompanied by deadly parochialism.
I had the privilege of discussing the problems of interdisciplinary exchanges
with Joseph Needham. He responded by giving me a copy of his Herbert
Spencer lecture “Integrative levels: a revaluation of the idea of progress.”17
“See, Fraser, whether this will help,” he said. It helped immensely.
The idea of integrative or organizational levels extends from Plato and
Aristotle to the Christian Platonists and Aquinas, to Hegel, Marx and
Bertrand Russell. It occurred to me that recognizing in nature a nested
hierarchy of stable integrative levels, distinct in their complexities18 and
languages,19 could accommodate the different epistemologies necessary for
16
Sam Walter Foss, “The House by the Side of the Road,” Hazel Felleman, ed. The Best
Loved Poems of the American People, Garden City: Garden City Publishing, 1936, p. 105.
17
Joseph Needham, (1937) Reprinted in his, Time, the Refreshing River, London: George
Allen and Unwin, 1943, pp. 233–72.
18
“Complexity and its measure,” (constructed with the help of algorithmic information
theory) in J. T. Fraser, Time, Conflict, and Human Values, Chicago, University of Illinois Press,
1999, pp. 235–42.
19
By “languages” is meant a coherent family of signs and symbols necessary to describe the
structures and interpret the functions of the stable integrative levels of nature.
14 j. t. fraser
dealing with the worlds of radiation, particle-waves, solid matter, life, the
human mind and human society. And, for that reason, it could serve as a
framework for an interdisciplinary, integrated study of time.
I did not realize until many years later that the reasons of the remarkable
appropriateness of the nested hierarchical model of nature for integrating the
epistemologies that an interdisciplinary study of time must accommodate,
may be found in the logical structure of Gödel’s incompleteness theorem.20
Indeed, the model could accommodate Brandon’s recognition of the
conflict between (1) the human knowledge of time as a weapon and (2) the
“abiding personal insecurity” of our species, together with the dynamics of
the life- and the physical sciences. It gave rise to the theory of time as a nested
hierarchy of unresolvable, creative conflicts. I will now appeal to that theory
to help us learn about the evolutionary origins and roles of intent, memory
and identity.
The theory employs an operational definition of reality. Specifically, it
extends the biologically based definition of reality, formulated by Jakob
von Uexküll a century ago, to all forms of human knowledge: experiential,
experimental and abstract. What emerges is an understanding of reality as a
relationship between the knower and the known. Applying this understanding
of reality to the diverse material that must enter an interdisciplinary study
of time leads to the conclusion that what, in ordinary use is called “time,”
has a structure, that it comprises a nested hierarchy of qualitatively distinct
temporalities.21
Let me introduce the two major dramatis personae of the theory. They are
evolving causations and evolving temporalities.
First, let me attend to causation and name its evolutionary stages. They are:
chaos, probability, determinism, organic intentionality, noetic intentionality
and collective intentionality. Next, let me visit each separately and identify
the steps in the evolution of temporalities.
The primeval chaos is without any connections among events. It supports
no causation, its world is without any features that may be associated with
time. Absolute chaos or pure becoming is atemporal.
The organizational level of nature above chaos, known through quantum
theory, is that of particle-waves. In that world distinct instants do not yet
exist, only probabilistically distributed likelihoods of instants do. Time is not
yet continuous. That world is prototemporal.
20
“J. T. Fraser, “Mathematics and Time,” KronoScope 3–2 (2003) pp. 153–168.
21
For its mature form, see “Perspectives on Time and Conflict,” ibid., pp. 21–43.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 15
The next step in cosmic evolution was the coming about of the galaxies
that form the astronomical universe of solid matter. Instants in that universe
are well-defined. They are connected through deterministic relations, as
embodied in both Newtonian and Einsteinian physics. That level-specific
time is eotemporality. It is one of pure succession, without preferred
direction. The reason why we cannot find purely deterministic processes is
that, because of the nested hierarchical organization of nature, there can be
no deterministic processes without probabilistic and chaotic components.
Michael Heller, physicist and Catholic theologian, has shown that the
physical world is time orientable, that it allows for two directions of time, but
it need not be so oriented, that it is complete and intelligible without directed
time.22 Heller’s conclusions are consistent with P. C. W. Davies’ assertion that
“The four dimensional space-time of physics makes no provision whatever
for either a ‘present moment’ or a ‘movement’ of time”23 and that, “It is a
remarkable fundamental fact of nature that all known laws of physics are
invariant under time reversal.”24
By the Principle of Parsimony, the hierarchical theory of time maintains
that what physics reveals about time in the physical world is the total truth.
The reason why the laws of physics do not make provisions for a present
and for the flow of time is not because physical science is incomplete in that
respect but because the temporalities of the physical world are incomplete
when compared with what we, as living and thinking beings experience and
think of as time.
For Einstein, according to his friend and biographer Paul A. Schilpp,
“there was something essential about the Now which is just outside the realm
of science.”25
The parochialism of equating “science” entirely with physics, dooms an
understanding of the “now” in terms of natural philosophy. But, if biology is
22
Michael Heller, “The Origins of Time” in J. T. Fraser, N. Lawrence and D. Park, eds. The
Study of Time IV, New York: Springer Verlag, 1981, pp. 90–93.
23
P. C. W. Davies, The Physics of Time Asymmetry, U. Calif. Press, 1974, p. 21. The absence
of time’s flow and that of a present are corollaries. Namely, the flow of time must appeal to
distinctions between future and past, and future and past have meaning only with reference
to a present. If there are no distinctions between future and past, directed time can have no
meaning. David Park even asked, “Should Physicists say that the Past Really Happened?” In
J. T. Fraser, ed. The Study of Time VI. Madison, CT: International Universities Press, 1989.
pp. 125–42.
24
P. C. W. Davies, The Physics of Time Asymmetry, U. Calif. Press, 1974, p. 26.
25
P. A. Schilpp, ed. The Philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (La Salle: Open Court, 1963), pp.
37–8.
16 j. t. fraser
included among the sciences as it must be, then, a scientific, operational basis
of the “now” may be identified. To explain how life gives rise to the “now,” to
intent, to memory and to identity and how the flow of time acquires meaning
through the life process, we have to think ourselves back to the primeval
chaos of pure becoming.
David Layzer gave good reasons in support of the claim that chemical order
was not present at the initial universe but was created by cosmic expansion.26
It is necessary to add that ordering, created by the expansion of the universe,
has been opposed all along by disordering, governed by the Second Law of
Thermodynamics. Also, that ordering and disordering define each other.27
In the physical world ordering and disordering are random, uncoordinated.
In sharp contrast, within the boundaries of an organism, ordering and
disordering—growth and decay—go on simultaneously and are coordinated
from instant to instant. The life process is identically equivalent to securing
that events which must happen simultaneously do so happen, events that
ought not happen simultaneously, do not. When coordination between
growth and decay fails the conflict ceases, the organism dies. For this reason,
the coordinated processes of growth and decay are the constitutive conflicts of
life. They are necessary and sufficient to define the life process. The instant to
instant coordination that maintains the life process, introduces nowness into
the nowless universe of nonliving matter. With nowness it defines conditions
of non-presence. Nowness is, a local phenomenon. This is the reason why, in
the words of Whitrow, the Special Theory of Relativity denies the universal
simultaneity of spatially separated events. Consequently, the simultaneity of
events throughout the universe becomes an indeterminate concept until a
frame of reference (or observer) has been specified.28
In Shakespeare’s As you Like It we learn that “from hour to hour we ripe
and ripe / and then from hour to hour we rot and rot.”29 The Bard had youth
and age in mind. But the life process, as I suggested, is identically equivalent
to simultaneous ripening and rotting. Or, one may speak of simultaneous
26
David Layzer, Cosmogenesis—The Growth of Order in the Universe. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1990, p. 144.
27
On this, see J. T. Fraser, “From Chaos to Conflict,” J. T. Fraser, M. P. Soulsby and
A. Argyros, eds. Time, order, Chaos (The Study of Time IX), Madison: International Universities
Press, 1998, pp. 3–17.
28
G. J. Whitrow, The Natural Philosophy of Time, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1980,
p. 253. See also “Conventionality of Simultaneity,” in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
http://plato,stanford.edu/entrieds/spacetime-comvensimul/.
29
“And so from hour to hour we ripe and ripe/And then from hour to hour we rot and
rot. . . .” ( “As You Like It,” 2–7–26.).
reflections upon an evolving mirror 17
30
J. T. Fraser, “Temporal Levels and Reality Testing,” International Journal of Psycho-
Analysis (1981) v. 62 pp. 3–26.
31
On the Kantian idea of time, see Charles M. Sherover’s The Human Experience of Time,
2nd ed., Evanston, IL, Northwestern University Press, 2000, p. 109 ff.
18 j. t. fraser
32
Ulysses.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 19
33
Walt Whitman, “Songs of Myself,” No. 15 in Complete Poetry and Selected Letters, Emory
Holloway, ed. London: The Nonesuch Press, 1938. p. 39.
20 j. t. fraser
34
Alfred North Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, New York: Macmillan, 1933, p. 41.
35
Samuel P. Huntington, The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order. New
York: Simon and Schuster, 1996.
36
“The past is not a frozen landscape that may be discovered and described once and
for all, but a chart of landmarks and paths which is continuously redrawn in terms of new
aspirations, values and understanding.” In J. T. Fraser, Of Time, Passion, and Knowledge. 2nd
ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990, p. xv. See also Robert Robertson, “The New
Global History: History in a Global Age,” in Scott Lash et al. eds. Time and Value, Oxford:
Blackwell, 1988, pp. 210–27. and J. Prager’s essay, “Collective Memory, Psychology of ” in
N. J. Smelser and Paul B. Baltes eds. International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral
Sciences. Oxford: Pergamon, 2001, pp. 2223–2227.
37
My inquiry has an ancestry in Thomas Ungvàri’s ”Time and the Modern Self,” in J. T.
Fraser, F. C. Haber and G. H. Müller, eds. The Study of Time I” New York: Springer Verlag,
1972, pp. 470–478.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 21
“enacts the cultural history of a people at the same time as it defines its own
contemporary self-consciousness.”38
Specifically, I want to point to some important changes that have
taken place in the ways tragedies depict the uses of the past in the service
of the future. My reasons for selecting tragic drama are these. In tragedies
obligations, memories, hopes and fears are weighed with steady reflection
upon future and past.39 Also, tragedy on the social level has the same role
as death-by-aging has on the organic level. The usefulness of both is to
enable new generations to differ from their ancestors in a manner that is
advantageous not for persons but for the community. The tragic, no less than
death-by-aging, pays for social change with human suffering.
In terms of my definition of collective identity as the mode of applying
collective memory to collective intent, tragic dramas articulate the identities
of the communities in which they are set. I would expect that a tragic drama,
appropriate for globalized humankind, would reflect humankind’s identity-
in-the-making.
I propose to examine three great tragedies by three great dramatists,
associated with three different epochs. Then, compare the ways their
protagonists employ the past in service of their future.
The first one was written in 1602. It is the story of a man who is informed
about the past by a supernatural agent. This makes him confront his destiny.
“The time is out of joint;” he says, “O cursed spite / That ever I was born to
set it right!”40 Yet, that is exactly what he begins to do. The vibrant sensitivity
of this Shakespearean character is recognized in Pasternak’s poem, “Hamlet.”
In it, the Prince of Denmark, an actor acting himself, talks to himself. “I
stand alone. All else is swamped in Pharisaism. To live life to the end is not a
childish task.”41
With that realization, he begins to force the future. He engages a company
of actors to recreate that past and takes action to repair that past through
sacrifice. Hate and love converge to a denouement of “Good night, sweet
prince” echoing in an otherwise empty universe. After a heartbroken farewell
and military salute, the hero is laid to rest.
Hamlet is set in the court of a king. The protagonists are a small group of
38
Claudia Clausius, “Tragedy as Forgotten Memory in Wole Soyinka’s Drama,” paper at
this conference.
39
For a detailed discussion see “The Tragic,” in J. T. Fraser, Time, Conflict, and Human
Values. Chicago: University of Illinois Press, 199, pp. 157–62.
40
Hamlet 1–5–188.
41
“Hamlet” in Boris Pasternak, Doctor Zhivago, New York: Pantheon, 1958, p. 523.
22 j. t. fraser
the privileged. The audience—during its early existence—were those who fit
in the Globe or other small theaters. The conflicts of the plot are between
the finity of human power on the one hand and the infinity of human ideals
on the other hand. I class Hamlet, together with Goethe’s Faust, as tragedies
in the Greco/Western mode of the drama of redemption, leading to a
denouement of mission accomplished.
The second tragedy I have in mind is a painful register of hope lost. It
was written in 1939. Its protagonists wanted to change the world the way
they thought would make it better, but they failed. Now they are trying to
recover their personal identities in the hope of reconciling their enthusiastic
past with an uncaring present. As these efforts also falter, they drift into the
slow death of derelicts. When one of the them jumps to his death from a fire
escape, only a single voice says, “God rest his soul in peace.” All the other
voices celebrate a birthday by singing and shouting in wild cacophony.42 The
central character stares in front of himself, “oblivious to the racket.”43
“The Iceman Cometh” is set in a bar. In it we are watching a collective
identity crisis in a petri dish. The protagonists are men and women, down
and out. The tragic tension is between the memories of the characters and
their assessments of their present. That tension dies in the empty, futureless
life of a flophouse. I class “The Iceman” together with some of Beckett’s plays
as tragedies of impotence. They are dramas of worlds where there is nothing
left either to live or die for. Their moods remind me of those religious views
which, in Brandon’s words, “reject . . . the consciousness of the self . . . as an
illusion of dangerous consequences.”44
During the sixty years after “The Iceman” the world has changed immensely.
The new epoch has no patience for character development. They must be
immediately legible as are the characters of the Audio-Animatronics figures
of Disneyland. The plot must also be simple because the vast, worldwide
audience to which the mass media caters, shares only the most primitive of
human concerns, which are the spilling of blood and of semen.
In a keen and sensitive recognition of the profundity of the human drama,
Paul Harris wrote of “a sense of sweeping change in the nature of being
human, a feeling that we are reaching the end of an epoch in the history of
42
One of them sings the “Carmagnole,” a folk dance, danced around the Guillotine. See
J. T. Fraser, Of Time, Passion, and Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press, (2nd ed.)
1990, pp. 392–3.
43
Selected Plays of Eugene O’Neill, New York: Random House, 1940, p. 758.
44
S. G. F. Brandon, “Time and the Destiny of Man,’ in J. T. Fraser, The Voices of Time,
Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1981, pp. 140–57. Quote from p. 154.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 23
our species.”45 In the same paper, he also wrote that, as a professor of literature,
confronting a hypertext universe, he finds himself “oscillating between a kind
of naïve technophilia and the frustrated rage of a luddite.”
I believe that globalized humanity is confronting a hypertext world that
goes much beyond the boundaries of wired communication. I have been
calling it the anthill threshold. It is an incoherent community whose members
have incompatible scales of values. They could coexist as long as there were
distinct cultural boundaries. But now they live in a cohabitation enforced
by a tight communication network and are all subject to the information
rampage. They have all been thrown off balance by the interpenetration of
financial and military empires where each community, in itself, is a powerless
subject of an uncritical amalgamation of human values.
The consequent tensions are expressed in the conflicts between a
technophilia of unrealistic hopes on the one hand and, on the other hand, a
frustrated rage due to unfulfilled expectations. The crisis gives rise to a form
of tragic drama that is neither in the Greco/Western redemptive category,
nor in the category of impotent fading away. Instead, it is a tragic drama of
globalization-in-process.
A dramatist who wrote such a tragic drama, is a woman. She is known to
carry a trumpet to announce fame, a book in which she records events and a
clepsydra to tell time. She is the muse of communal memory that is, of shared
beliefs about the past. She is the muse of history. Her name is Clio.
Today her trumpet is the worldwide media. Her book is the Internet
with its 420 billion pages of writings. The premiere of her new creation was
performed on the spherical stage of a global theater. Her viewers numbered
a few hundred million people, all of whom were both protagonists and
audiences. At that first performance her clepsydra, calibrated in Gregorian
chronology, showed 9–11–2001.46
In a fine essay, Anne Lévy wrote about “an ongoing American tendency to
create temporal bubbles in which only the stimulating but solvable incidents
rise pell-mell to the status of great meaning, while true predicaments and
45
Paul A. Harris, “www.timeandglobalization.com/narrative” in Time and Society, 9–2/3
(2000) pp. 319–29. The conference was jointly organized by ISST and the French Association
for the Advancement of Science.
46
In the chronology of 7980 years, used by astronomers, the minute the first airplane hit,
was Julian Day 2,452,163.864,583,335. This cycle was devised in the 16th century by the
Dutch philologist and chronologist Josephus Scaliger, to encompass all human history known
in his time.
24 j. t. fraser
tragedies are whisked out of sight.”47 Clio’s latest plot, in which she made
four airplanes stand for humankind, cannot be whisked out of sight. There
are no temporal bubbles left in which anyone can hide. The denouement,
which we have not seen yet, pertains to a decision about the identity and
future of humankind.
The conduct of humans and gods in Greek tragedies set the tone of Greek
cultural identity. The tragedy of Christ, reenacted in the Mass, helped form
the cultural identity of the West. The tragic spectacle of murder in service of
a savage King Ludd, using low-tech to annihilate high-tech, is appropriate in
its form for a globalized humankind. For that reason, it is likely to shape the
identity of the emerging community and likely to remain, at least for a while,
a deed to be “acted o’er / In states unborn and accents yet unknown.”48
The events of 9–11 involve conflicts between the Dionysian and Apollonian
trends innate in history which, Nietzsche maintained, give rise to tragedy.
In a different perspective, they are also conflicts between the biotemporal
and nootemporal assessments of reality. The “global instant everywhere,”
in cahoots with social advances, have lifted the lid off the inner turmoil of
people everywhere, allowing the reptilian brain to act out its desires.
I asked earlier what, for the case of globalized mankind, may serve the
same role as the “unum” did in “e pluribus unum?” When, in 211 B.C. the
armies of Carthage reached Rome, the cry went up in the City: “Hannibal
before the gates!” The cry appropriate for humankind in globalization “Clio
before the gates.”
History is now at all gates, everywhere and all the time.
If, it is indeed the case that memory evolved as an aid to intent and, if one
agrees with the idea that mankind’s identity resides in the manner it employs
its collective memory to serve its future, then, before any realistic plans for
the future may be drafted, it is the past, it is an agreement on history that will
have to be negotiated.
I do not mean agreement on the dates of one or another king. I mean an
agreement about the origin and evolution of man, the origin and evolution
of life, and the origin and evolution of the universe. But views on these issues
differ, depending on whether they are based on critical scientific reasoning,
on revealed religion or on mythology. Consistently, they lead to different
recommendations for future actions. Also, they recognize different and
47
Anne Schulenberger Lévy, “At the Limits of the Utopian Festival.” KronoScope 4–1
(2004) pp. 75–91. Quote from p. 75.
48
“Julius Caesar,” III–I–111.
reflections upon an evolving mirror 25
The evolving mirror I spoke about is the capacity of the human brain to
assess reality in categories of open-ended futures and pasts, referred to a
present. That present is defined locally by life, by the mental processes and
by society.
The sources of this ability of the human brain are unclear and intriguing
enough to have given rise to a question by Walter Russell Brain, later Lord
Brain. He was President of the British College of Physicians and one of the
scientist-scholars who helped place the interdisciplinary study of time and
ISST on the map.50 If memory corresponds to a brain state, he wrote, and
sense impressions to another, and since these coexist, how are they told
apart?51 The formulation of this question surely changed since 1963 but, to
my knowledge, it has not been satisfactorily answered.
To memory and sense impressions listed by Lord Brain I would add a
third family of brain states, namely that which corresponds to intentions,
expectation and hope. Then, I would ask: how are these three categories of
time told apart?
I hope that this question will be considered at this conference, with the
benefit of some useful constraints. For instance, the answer cannot appeal
to an unambiguous physical future, past and present in which biological,
psychological and social processes unfold and to which the individual’s
mental faculties, somehow, adapt.
49
“London.” in The Portable Blake, New York: Viking, 1968, p. 112.
50
Walter Russell Brain, “Time is the Essence . . .” Lancet, May 28, 1966, pp. 00–00.
51
Walter Russell Brain, “Some Reflections on Brain and Mind.” Brain, 86 (1963) p. 392
TPK 252 FN 38 on 485.
26 j. t. fraser
52
Robert Hillyer, Collected Poems, New York, 1961 p. 129.
RESPONSE
GLOBALIZED HUMANITY, MEMORY, AND ECOLOGY
Paul Harris
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 27–32
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
28 paul harris
1
More detailed treatments of this issue are found in the essay “The Time-Compact Globe,”
at the conclusion of Time: The Familiar Stranger (1987), chapter 6, “The Global Laboratory,”
in Time, Conflict, and Human Values (1999), and “Time, Globalization and the Nascent
Identity of Mankind” (2000) (Time and Society Vol. 9(2/3): 293–302. In these texts, the time-
compact globe is defined in terms of “three-cornered struggle between national governments,
transnational groups, and ‘tribal interest cells.’” The latter groups are bound together by
ideological rather than familial or affective ties.
2
“Ten Soundbites for the Next Millenium: Mutations in Time, Mind and Narrative.” In
J. T. Fraser and Marlene Soulsby, Eds. Time: Perspectives at the Millenium. (Westport, CT:
Greenwood Publishers, 2001): 35–48.
globalized humanity, memory and ecology 29
and tribal interest cells, may be evoked by one word: petroleum. From an
ecological standpoint, petroleum is a hydrocarbon fossil fuel found in
very finite reserves under select parts of the earth’s surface. Calculating the
ratio between the amount of time it takes for petroleum to form (millenia)
in relation to the estimated amount of time that globalized humanity—
predominantly the USA—will take to exhaust the remaining supply of
crude oil (about 40 years) is in itself a very pedagogical thought experiment.
From an economic standpoint, petroleum is not a rare resource, but it is an
exceptionally valuable commodity. The politics and economics involved in
transforming petroleum from natural resource into consumable commodity
serve to concentrate wealth into the hands of the few at the expense of the
many. The huge profits controlled by oil companies and those in power in
certain countries fuel a greed that, ecologically or temporally considered, is
short-sighted.
One of J. T. Fraser’s most prescient observations about globalized
humanity is that its evolutionary path is traced on a technological, social
fitness landscape rather than a strictly natural one. In analyzing “the Global
Laboratory,” Fraser points out that while globalization as such is not new,
“what is new to twenty-first century globalization is that the electronic
global present did not come about through evolutionary selection favoring
the continuity of a global community. . . . Rather, it came about through
technological developments sui generis. Humans are now selected for by their
own, self-created environment. We have to learn to live with the global instant
everywhere. Where do we stand in that selection-cum-learning process.”
There are many different implications to this statement important to explore.
From one standpoint, this statement underscores the fact that “mind” in the
global laboratory can no longer be thought of only in terms of human brains.
Mind now operates in a distributed fashion, in communications networks
that connect up different individuals in collective processes. Here, we might
see a potential bridge between a neuroscientific and global learning. How
can this relation be thought in terms of memory?
A compelling way to consider this question is provided by evolutionary
psychologist Merlin Donald. In his book The Origins of the Modern Mind,
Donald outlines a “cognitive ethology of human culture” and develops an
idea of “cognitive architecture.” Cognitive architecture involves the interplay
of individual minds and cultural representational systems; his theory is
marked by “its incorporation of biological and technological factors into
a single evolutionary spectrum.” Donald’s essential contention is that “We
act in cognitive collectivities, in symbiosis with external memory systems.
As we develop new external symbolic configurations and modalities, we
globalized humanity, memory, and ecology 31
3
Merlin Donald, The Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages in the Evolution of Culure
and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1991, p. 382.
32 paul harris
Jo Alyson Parker
If any one faculty of our nature may be called more wonderful than the rest, I do
think it is memory. There seems something more speakingly incomprehensible
in the powers, the failures, the inequalities of memory, than in any other of
our intelligences. The memory is sometimes so retentive, so serviceable, so
obedient—at others, so bewildered and so weak—and at others again, so
tyrannic, so beyond controul!—We are to be sure a miracle every way—but our
powers of recollecting and forgetting, do seem peculiarly past finding out.
—Fanny Price in Jane Austen’s Mansfield Park
If contemporary pop culture is any indicator, the “speakingly incompre-
hensible” nature of memory that prompted Fanny Price’s musings con-
tinues to bemuse us. We are fascinated with “our powers of recollecting and
forgetting.” The 2000 film Memento, for example, features a protagonist,
Leonard, who, due to a head injury, cannot engage in the process of
consolidation whereby short-term memories are converted into long-term
ones. Because no present memories can be inscribed in his long-term memory,
he tattoos brief messages upon himself, literally inscribing upon his body the
information that he needs to direct him toward a future course. The 2003 film
Eternal Sunshine of the Spotless Mind fancifully conceives of a device that can
selectively remove memories, generally of a traumatic nature, from the brain.
When the central character Joel wishes to erase all memories of his ex-lover
Clementine, the device seeks out and destroys not only all memories of her
but also any memories peripherally connected to her, including Joel’s happy
memories of the cartoon character Huckleberry Hound singing “My Darling
Clementine.” Both films prompt us to consider “the powers, the failures, the
inequalities of memory”—their themes resonating for us far beyond the two
hours we spend in a darkened cinema.
It is no wonder that these themes resonate. After all, our sense of individual
identity consists of our carrying past memories into the present to guide us
into the future. As Philips Hilts notes, “Conferring with memory’s ghosts,
consulting its tables of facts, we project the future and what we expect it
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 35–40
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
36 jo alyson parker
to look like. Memory makes us, fore and aft.”1 Memory indeed serves as the
bridge across time—between that self who existed years ago and that self
who exists today.
We are troubled, however, by our awareness of the fluidity of memory—
our awareness that something that we have long forgotten may suddenly rise
to the surface while something that we once knew may sink into the depths,
never to rise again. If we are what we remember and what we remember
can change, then the self becomes an unstable entity. As Shelley Jackson
suggests in her hypertext novel Patchwork Girl, a different set of memories
would entail a different self: “So, within each of you there is at least one other
entirely different you, made up of all you’ve forgotten [. . .] and nothing you
remember [. . .]. More accurately, there are many other you’s, each a different
combination of memories.”2 We have all, no doubt, had the experience of
someone telling a story in which we figure but of which we have no recollection
whatsoever—and, as we hear it, we feels as if the story were about someone
else entirely. Why did this memory inscribe itself upon the storyteller but
not upon us? What difference might it make to the self had the story been
part of our storehouse of memories? In what other unremembered stories do
we play a part? Such questions confound our belief in the self as a continuous
entity persisting across time, and they spark our interest in the mechanisms
of remembering and forgetting.
These mechanisms compel us to consider the very being of memory.
Certainly, contemporary neurobiology has made great strides in charting
the mechanisms of remembering and forgetting within the human brain. We
know, for example, that an injury to the hippocampal region of the brain can
impair our faculty of memory consolidation, as occurred in the case of Henry
M., whose sad history is recounted in Hilts’s Memory’s Ghost. We know, too,
that patients with Alzheimer’s Disease “have an abundance of two abnormal
structures—beta amyloid plaques and neurofibrillary tangles.”3 But is there
any device like that envisioned in Eternal Sunshine, which could extract
a particular memory from the human brain, rather as one might extract a
particular photograph from an album—so that the memory of Huckleberry
1
Philp J. Hilts, Memory’s Ghost: The Strange Tale of Mr. M and the Nature of Memory
(New York: Simon & Shuster), 13.
2
Shelley Jackson, Patchwork Girl by Mary/Shelley & Herself, CD Rom (Watertown, MA:
Eastgate Systems, 1995). The passage come from the following sequence in the text: story /
séance / she goes on.
3
“Alzheimer’s Disease: Unraveling the Mystery,” ADEAR: Alzheimer’s Disease Education
& Referral Center 3 January 2006 <http://www.alzheimers.org/unraveling/06.htm>.
inscribing and forgetting 37
Hound might be removed but the memory of Yogi Bear would not? Although
we may discuss physical processes that facilitate or impair memory, we are
still in the dark about the nature of memories themselves.
What, too, do we make of the physical means whereby we attempt to
preserve memory? The well-known discussion of writing in Plato’s Phaedrus
makes the point that attempts to preserve memory indeed encourage
forgetfulness. Socrates thus deplores writing:
If people learn from them [letters] it will make their souls forgetful through
lack of exercising their memory. They’ll put their trust in the external marks of
writing instead of using their own external capacity for remembering on their
own. You’ve discovered a magic potion not for memory, but for reminding, and
you offer your pupils apparent, not true, wisdom. (275a)4
In a passage famously deconstructed by Jacques Derrida in “Plato’s Pharmacy,”
Socrates distinguishes between the external inscriptions that one might make
on a piece of paper (or papyrus or a computer screen), which he regards as
inducing forgetfulness, and the internal inscriptions on the soul, which he
regards as the stuff of memory:
Can we see another kind of speech that’s a legitimate brother of that one
[writing] and see how it comes into being and how it is from its birth much
better and more powerful than that one? [. . .] That which is written along with
knowledge in the soul of the learner, that’s able to defend itself by itself and
knows to whom it ought to speak and before whom it ought to keep silent.
(276a)5
As Derrida notes in his gloss on the discussion, “writing is essentially bad,
external to memory, productive not of science but of belief, not of truth but
of appearances.”6
According to Plato, the external inscription thwarts rather than preserves
memory—creates, in effect, an inauthentic self. We might come back to
Leonard’s tattoos in Memento; although they enable Leonard to act in the
present so as to influence the future, these inscriptions are merely reminders—
“memories” external to himself, outside the realm of his own knowledge,
creating no bridge between a past self and a present one. We might consider,
too, speculative fictions, such as those by Rudy Rucker or Philip K. Dick, that
4
Plato, The Symposium and The Phaedrus: Plato’s Erotic Dialogues, trans. William S.
Cobb (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1993), 132.
5
Plato, 133.
6
Jacques Derrida, “Plato’s Pharmacy,” Dissemination, trans. Barbara Johnson (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1981), 103.
38 jo alyson parker
7
Derrida, 109.
inscribing and forgetting 39
information-technology sectors, Davies argues for the vital role that narrative
plays in tapping into individual and collective memory. As she shows, these
narratives involve gendered bodies, and, as such, they can have emancipatory
potential. In essence, memories imprinted on the body in the past are narrated
in the present in order to have an impact on the future. Davies’s piece in itself
constitutes “doing gender,” its own narrative suffused with the emancipatory
potential it describes. As respondent Linda McKie points out, “The research
of Davies illustrates how individual and collective memories are dimensions
of social change.”
In the paper that follows, cognitive psychologists Elke van der Meer, Frank
Krüger, Dirk Strauch, and Lars Kuchinike detail the results they obtained
from experiments designed “to analyze whether and how temporal order
information could be coded and accessed in semantic memory.” Proceeding
from the assumption that chronological order was stored in semantic mem-
ory, they combined several complementary research methods: behavioral
studies, pupillary responses, and functional neuroimaging methods. As their
experiments demonstrated, participants processed chronologically ordered
events more rapidly than events in reverse order. These results may encourage
us to consider the increased cognitive effort required as we deal with, say, a
chronologically skewed narrative.
With Marlene Soulsby’s contribution, we shift from inscribing to for-
getting—specifically here to an examination of a situation in which what
had once been inscribed in memory is no longer accessible. Soulsby reviews
both fictional and nonfictional narratives of dementia and concludes with
a discussion of the Time Slips project, whereby facilitators guide groups
of people with memory loss to tell a story based on a picture (a project in
which Soulsby herself has participated). Soulsby notes that people with
memory loss are “trapped in a temporal world of simultaneities,” and the
narratives that they produce are fractured—indicative, it would seem, of
their inability to make a bridge between past, present, and future. Soulsby’s
paper has particular poignancy in a time wherein we are increasingly aware
of the depredations wrought by Alzheimer’s Disease—upon both its victims
and those who care for them. Yet as respondent Alison Phinney points out,
“Positioning narrative as an embodied activity will enrich our ability to
understand the experience of temporality and memory loss in dementia.”
Marie-Pascale Huglo focuses on what we might call a purposeful effort of
memory loss—Georges Perec’s unfinished project Lieux. As Huglo describes,
Perec planned to produce two texts a year on each of twelve Parisian places
related to his past, each of which would then be sealed and not be opened for
a particular span of time. Huglo examines the way in which Lieux highlights
40 jo alyson parker
the relation between time, memory, and place and explains that, for Perec,
memories needed to be inscribed in order to exist. In describing Perec’s
fascinating and tantalizingly incomplete project, Huglo prompts us to consi-
der how its success depended on Perec’s forgetting what he had described
in the past so as to discover it anew in the future; as Huglo points out,
however, the project was beset by tension between Perec’s active memories
and those he had preserved, a tension that Plato might have described as
between the external inscriptions of memory and the internal ones. Stemming
the tide of memory, it appears, may be as difficult as stemming the tide of
memory loss.
We conclude with a narrative, one that evocatively illustrates the way
in which time erodes memory. Brian Aldiss tells the story of two different
sojourns in Sumatra—one he spent in 1945–46 as a young soldier and one
he spent returning to his former haunts in 1978. The term “haunts” may
be taken in its most literal sense, for what Aldiss discovers is that he is a
revenant. Attempting to locate the quarters in which he passed a romantic
interlude, he finds that the certainties of a remembered past are undermined.
Yet the narrative he tells links the past of the young soldier with the present
of the revenant, who will become the storyteller of the future—an elegant
balancing of three different time periods that highlights the layered quality
of memory.
Although Austen’s Fanny Price surmised that “our powers of recollecting
and forgetting do seem peculiarly past finding out together,” the six papers
that follow incisively and at times provocatively explore the mechanisms of
those powers, helping us toward an understand of the “wonderful” faculty of
memory.
CHAPTER ONE
Christian Steineck
Summary
When we attribute human actions and abilities to either the body or the mind, memory seems
to fall neatly within the range of the mind. Still, the act of memorizing often has more to do
with the body than with the mind, a fact strongly emphasized by, and reflected upon, in East
Asian methodologies of cultivation. Furthermore, memories are more often than not evoked
by sensual, corporeal experiences. And finally, the case of a brain-dead patient shows how the
body serves as a subject and object of memories in the absence of all intellectual activities.
An explanation of such phenomena is possible when viewing the mind-body problem in
the light of E. Cassirer’s theory of expression. As an expression, the body is the external reality
that signifies a (non-spatial) ‘internal’ state. If we analyze the correlation of body and mind
accordingly, we may understand that, and how, the body functions as a primary medium of
memory.
Introduction
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 41–52
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
42 christian steineck
the mental is not fully adequate. Analyzing the body and its connection to
memory may help us to clarify the meaning of this proposition and to correct
some misconceptions of the human body.
In the following, I will first illustrate what I mean by talking about the body
as a ‘medium of memory’ and then present my analysis before I come back
to the more general picture. I shall give two examples from divergent fields
of human experience, which may help to illuminate the scope of meaning
involved in the formula ‘the body as a medium of memory’.
Examples
Interpersonal Memories
My first example is taken from the field of modern biomedicine. It concerns
the case of a young man in Japan, who fell into a state of persistent coma after
an attempt at suicide. His condition deteriorated, and he was diagnosed as
clinically ‘brain-dead’ after five days. According to the prevalent interpretation
of that diagnosis, this meant that all parts of his brain had permanently
ceased to function. At that point in time (1994), brain death criteria had
not yet been accepted into Japanese legislation.1 He was therefore treated as
a terminally ill but living patient.
The father of this young man, Yanagida Kunio, is a renowned non-fiction
writer of books about science. He published his observations and reflections
in an article for the widely read monthly magazine Bungei shunjû (Yanagida
1994), and later in a book (Yanagida 1999). Two aspects of his report
concern us here.
The first one is that even after the diagnosis of brain death, cardiovascular
functions in Yanagida’s son invariably stabilize whenever the father or brother
is present. As the attending physician confirms, the patient’s blood pressure
and pulse rate regularly rise to a level closer to normal whenever relatives
come to visit him. This fact, which remains without a medical explanation
in the report, is interpreted by Yanagida and the attending nurses to mean
that the patient perceives the presence of his kin and enjoys being with them
(Yanagida 1994, 144; Yanagida 1999, 184). Such an interpretation runs
1
This situation occurred in 1997. See Lock 2002 for an extensive description of the process
of incorporating brain death criteria into the legal system of Japan, and the US. A printed
version of the Japanese transplant law is available in Kuramochi/Nagashima 2003, 321–335.
the body as a medium of memory 43
relationships) are stored, say, in the hands or in the skin. Rather, the point
is about what is being remembered in ‘personal memories’ and what
may follow from this. As has been remarked by the Japanese bioethicist
M. Morioka (2001), relationships that can last beyond the point of brain
death are typically of a kind that involves close physical contact or coexistence
over an extended period of time. In other words, they involve corporeal as
much as verbal communication, emotional as well as ‘rational’ exchanges.
However, the meaning of these corporeal aspects will be informed by all
other levels on which the persons concerned interact. As words trigger
emotions (which are, in one perspective, physico-physiological states of
the body as a whole) and emotions lead to words again, a history evolves in
which it is obviously impossible to take the ‘mental’ and the ‘physical’ neatly
apart. On the one hand, this may help to understand why phenomena such
as Yanagida’s purported reaction to the presence of his father and brother
could be possible without a mental memory being produced on his part. On
the other hand, it would be overly reductive to interpret it as a mere physical
reaction because the reaction as such is related to, or in fact made possible by,
the full range of meaning that imbues the personal relationship in question.
The second aspect of Yanagida’s report important to our topic is the fact
that in the face of his comatose and, later, brain-dead son Yanagida is incited
to delve into memories of the past. Large parts of his article and even larger
parts of his book consist of reflections that connect memories of his son’s
previous life to observations made in the presence of his comatose,and,
later, brain-dead son. As once again M. Morioka has pointed out, this is a
common reaction of relatives and friends confronted with a brain-dead
body (Morioka 2001, 74–77). In Morioka’s view, it is the combination of an
apparently living body and the absence of those channels of communication
to which we normally pay most attention that provokes such powerful
waves of reminiscence (Morioka 2001, 76). While the warm, breathing, and
pulsating body continues to present the patient as a living person, she lacks
the ability to transmit distinctive thoughts and intentions. Precisely because
of this absence of a limited, actual content, her personality is presented in
totality, in a similar manner as a whole relationship may be summed up in
one single gesture. In this situation, the patient’s body is not a white screen
on which memories are projected. As long as it is perceived as an individual,
living body, it continues to be part of an intercorporeal exchange, to which we
cannot but attach communicative meaning, and, thus, the flow of memories
will be influenced and mediated by the living presence of the brain-dead
body (Morioka 2001, 76).
46 christian steineck
Memorizing virtue
The second example takes us again to Japan, but this time we add some
temporal to the spatial distance. At the beginning of the seventeenth
century, after a period of prolonged internal wars and strife, the Tokugawa
dynasty completed the unification of the country and established a feudal
and bureaucratic system that was to last for 250 years. The Tokugawa
Shogunate fostered a school of Neo-Confucianism that taught a theory of
correspondence between the natural order of the universe and that of society
(see, for example, Ooms 1985). Emphasis was placed on insight into the
principles that governed the cosmic order, and scholars concentrated on
studying the grand systems of philosophers like Zhu Xi or Hayashi Razan
on meditation and speculation to achieve virtue. However, the emphasis on
words also led to a new emphasis on philology, which motivated some scholars
to criticize Neo-Confucianists for their neglect and misrepresentation of the
older Confucian sources (Ogyu 1970, 8, 9). Although these scholars called
themselves the school of “old learning” (kogaku), they established a new
way of thinking. One of the most revolutionary thinkers in this school was
Ogyû Sorai, who was born in 1666 and died in 1728 (see Lidin 1973 for a
biography of this remarkable scholar). He did away with the time honoured
idea of the “heaven” or nature as a source of moral virtue, and separated
the cultural world of man from that of nature as is evident in his saying:
“The Way of the Early Kings is that which the Early Kings created. It is
not the natural Way of Heaven and Earth” (Ogyu 1970, 24).
The way as taught by Confucius, Sorai said, was not to contemplate the
universe and study philosophical systems; it was a way that was meant to
bring peace and harmony to human society by people studying ancient
models of virtue and, even more importantly, by practicing the rituals and
ways of life they established. Sorai saw personal cultivation as the root source
of all virtue, and this, to him, meant cultivation of and with the whole body,
as is evident from the following passages:
the body as a medium of memory 47
To take lightly that which is on the outside and end up attaching importance
to that which is within is contrary to the ancient Way of the Early Kings and
Confucius. (Ogyu 1970, 14)
When bringing peace and contentment to the world, to cultivate one’s
bodily self is the fundamental basis. (Ogyu 1970, 13; translation from Japanese
kanbun [= Sinojapanese style] by the author).
To Sorai, the human body does not possess any innate virtue that will express
itself naturally if one reaches proper insight into one’s nature—a theory held
by Daoists and some East Asian Mahâyâna Buddhists. But it can, and has
to be, employed to realize what has been established as human virtue, most
eminently through the combination of rites and music. In other words, the
body (that is, that which is felt and perceived of oneself ) is a medium that
can be utilized to cultivate virtue, like any natural material may be used to
realize the products of human ingenuity—but this does not mean that the
cultural ends are intrinsic parts of the means: “When cutting wood in order
to build a palace, one must follow the nature of the wood and only thus does
one accomplish it. But how could wood in its nature be a palace?” (Ogyu
1970, 26).2
Applied to the human body, this means that one must take the body’s own
nature, its needs and inbuilt rhythms, into account in order to employ it
for cultural ends, but one cannot expect any virtue to grow ‘naturally’ out of
the body.
The aspect of rites and music most emphasized by Sorai is the embodiment
of harmony—social harmony in the adherence to ritual, and emotional
attunement in the performance of music. According to Sorai, rites and music
can create an environment that enables people to live together in peace and
contentment. The emphasis on music is an old Confucian topos, but it has
specific significance in the light of Sorai’s above quoted saying: as music works
with the body’s own tendency to attune itself to environmental rhythms, it
may work as a medium to communicate a certain ethos—a function of music
effectively employed by modern advertisement and propaganda,but virtually
obliterated in ‘serious’ musical and aesthetical theory with its emphasis on
aesthetic freedom.
There is another aspect to Sorai’s theory which remains largely implicit,
but connects it to our theme of time and memory. It is apparent in his saying
that “Benevolence is the Way of nourishing” (Ogyu 1970, 54). In other
2
The striking similarity (plus the differences) of this passage to Francis Bacon’s famous
saying, “Natura enim non nisi parendo vincitur” (Nature is defeated only by obeying her,
Bacon 1620: 1.3) is worth noticing.
48 christian steineck
3
Speaking from the point of view of Japanese history, the Tokugawa dynasty certainly
managed to end a period of internal war and strife and to impose a stable social order that lasted
for 250 years. However, this order was based on fierce exploitation of the rural population,
which was regularly living in duress and repeatedly ravaged by famines. Confucianists,
with their emphasis on the virtues of frugality and their deep misgivings about trade (as
an ‘unproductive’ profession), advocated anti-commercialist policies which did nothing to
alleviate these conditions. As E. Honjo says in his survey of Tokugawa economics (1965:
32): “The keynote of the agricultural policy followed by the Tokugawa Shogunate during the
300 years of its régime was ’to keep farmers alive but not to allow them to live in comfort.’”
In reality, this meant that bad harvests had a devastating effect on the rural population
Honjo (1965: 105) quotes a saying from Yamagata Bantô as a typical example of Confucian
misgivings about commerce: “Agriculture should be encouraged and commerce discouraged.
Farmers are part and parcel of the state, while artisans and mechants can be dispensed with.
[. . .] Efforts must be made to increase the farming population, while, on the other hand, the
number of merchants should be reduced as far as possible.”
4
Consider Sorai’s argument against discipline (Ogyu/Lidin 1970: 56).
the body as a medium of memory 49
A Theoretical Framework
What we found in our examples was that, within various fields of human
existence, the human body serves as a medium that communicates past
experiences, actions, and emotions into the present. It does so in both a
passive and an active manner. In other words, the body serves as a symbol,
but as a living symbol, one that contributes to the meaning communicated
through it. For this very reason, I have referred to it as a medium, and in our
case, more specifically, as a medium of memory.
Some words on a theory of symbolic functions may be of help in further
clarifying how the human body can fulfil this part. Such a theory has been
developed by Ernst Cassirer in his famous Philosophy of Symbolic Forms
(Cassirer 1964, English translation Cassirer 1953–1996). As Cassirer
explains, there are three fundamental levels of symbolic functioning:
Expression, representation, and pure meaning. Like the different forms of
temporality in J. T. Fraser’s theory of time, they are ordered in a ‘nested
hierarchy’: the higher ones unfold within the lower ones at once remaining
dependent on them and transcending their constrictions. Science, which
is one of the symbolic forms that employ the function of pure meaning, is
coined in language, the classical locus of representation, which itself makes
use of expression. Expression and representation are indispensable for the
functioning of science, but scientific theories are structured according to
laws that transcend the specific constrictures limiting representation and
language.
The symbolic function that is first and foremost at play in our examples
is that of expression. According to Cassirer, expression is the first and most
fundamental of all symbolic functions, in comparison to the more abstract
ones of representation and purely notional meaning. On the level of
expression, we can distinguish between the symbol and its meaning—this
distinction being the arche of symbolicity and, therefore, meaning—but the
perceptual form of the symbol is still closely correlated to what it denotes.
In symbolic representation, there are the possibilities of translation, of using
different signs to refer to the same meaning, of distinguishing denotation
50 christian steineck
5
It should be noted, however, that the communication of a new scientific theory depends
on the fact that even abstract symbols do function as an expression—in this case, the expression
of an attempt to say something scientifically meaningful. If we had to rely on representation
and pure meaning alone, we could never come to understand something we didn’t know in the
first place because we wouldn’t have understood anything before having grasped the theory
as a whole.
the body as a medium of memory 51
References
Bacon, Francis. [1620] 1855. Novum Organon. Oxford University Press. English Translation:
2000. The New Organon. Ed. Lisa Jardine and Michael Silverthorne. Cambridge
University Press. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy.
Bundesärztekammer. 1998. Beirat der Bundesärztekammer (1998): Richtlinien zur Feststellung
des Hirntodes, 3. Fortschreibung 1997 mit Ergänzungen gemäß Transplantationsgesetz
(TPG). Deutsches Ärzteblatt 95 (30): 1861–1868.
Byrne, Paul A., Sean O’Reilly, Paul M. Quay. 1979. Brain Death. An Opposing Viewpoint.
Journal of the American Medical Association 242 (18): 1985–1990.
———. 2000. Brain death: the patient, the physician, and society. Pp. 21–89 in Beyond brain
death : the case against brain based criteria for human death, edited by Michael Potts,
Paul A. Byrne and Richard G. Nilges. Philosophy and medicine 66. Dordrecht et al.:
Kluwer .
Cassirer, Ernst. [1953] 1996. The philosophy of symbolic forms. Translated by Ralf Manheim.
New Haven: Yale University Press.
———. 1964. Philosophie der symbolischen Formen, 3 vols. Reprint of the 2nd edition.
Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft.
Conference of Medical Royal Colleges and their Faculties in the UK. 1995. Criteria for the
diagnosis of brain stem death. Journal of the Royal College of Physicians 29: 381–382.
Descartes, René. 1649. Les Passions de L’Ame. Paris: Le Gras. Quoted from Die Leidenschaften
der Seele. Herausgegeben und übersetzt von Klaus Hammacher. Französisch-deutsch.
Hamburg: Meiner. 1986.
Edelman, Gerald M. and Giulio Tononi. 2002. Gehirn und Geist. Wie aus Materie Bewusstsein
entsteht. München: Beck.
Harvard Medical School Ad Hoc Committee. 1968. A definition of irreversible coma. Report
of the Ad Hoc Committee of the Harvard Medical School to Examine the Definition of
Brain Death. Pp. 287–91 in Bioethics: An Anthology, edited by Helga Kuhse and Peter
Singer. Oxford: Blackwell. 2001. [First published in Journal of the American Medical
Association 205 (6): 85–88].
Heckmann, Josef G., C. J. Lang, M. Pfau, B. Neundorfer. 2003. Electrocerebral silence with
preserved but reduced cortical brain perfusion. European Journal of Emergency Medicine
10 (3): 241–243.
Honjo Eijiro. 1965. Economic Theory and History of Japan in the Tokugawa Period. New York:
Russell and Russell.
Kuramochi, Takeshi and Nagashima Akira. 2003. Zôki ishoku to seimei rinri. Tokyo: Taiyô
shuppan.
Lidin, Olof G. 1973. The Life of Ogyu Sorai, a Tokugawa Confucian Philosopher. Lund:
Studentlitteratur.
52 christian steineck
Lock, Margaret. 2002. Twice Dead: Organ Transplants and the Reinvention of Death (Public
Anthropology). Berkeley: University of California Press.
Nau, Roland, H.W. Prange, J. Klingelhöfer, B. Kukowski, D. Sander, R. Tchorsch, K.
Rittmeyer. 1992. Results of four technical investigations in fifty clinically brain dead
patients. Intensive Care Medicine 18 (2): 82–88.
Morioka Masahiro. 2001. Seimeigaku ni nani ga dekiru ka. Tokyo: Keisô shobô.
National Conference of Commissions of Uniform State Laws. 1980. Uniform Determination
of Death Act: Annual Conference Meeting. [Annual Conference Meeting in its Eighty-
Ninth Year on Kauai, Hawaii, July 26–August 1, 1980]. Chicago (Printed Matter).
Ogyu Sorai. 1970. Distinguishing the Way [Bendô]. Translated by Olof G. Lidin. Tokyo:
Sophia University.
Ooms, Herman. 1985. Tokugawa Ideology: Early Constructs, 1570–1680. Princeton University
Press.
Plessner, Helmuth. 1975. Die Stufen des Organischen und der Mensch. Berlin: De Gruyter.
Yanagida Kunio. 1994. Sakurifaisu: waga musuko nôshi no 11nichi. Bungei shunjû 72: 126–
151.
———. 1999. Sakurifaisu: waga musuko nôshi no 11 nichi. Tokyo: Bungei shunjû.
RESPONSE
Remy Lestienne
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 53–54
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
54 remy lestienne
Karen Davies
Summary
Narrative is one method of tapping individual and collective memory where human experience
is organized into temporally meaningful episodes and where a “point” is often made. In research
projects that I have carried out about working life, “body stories” are often spontaneously
related in making a “point.” These stories exemplify “doing gender”—that is how gendered
relations (that revolve around equality/inequality, domination/subordination, advantage/
disadvantage) are actually created, recreated, contested and changed in everyday life. “Doing
gender” is also linked to “body-reflexive practices”—the idea that the body is not only the
object of symbolic practice and power but also participant. In other words, body-reflexive
practices generate new courses of social conduct. In the second part of this paper, empirical
examples taken from research projects on gender and professionals working in the health care
and information technology (IT) sectors are provided to illustrate these concerns. The last
example shows how a contestation of “doing gender” brings about change. More generally,
one can say that without individual and collective memories, there would be no social change.
Thus memory and the response that it invokes are pivotal in the unfolding of time.
The body as site of interaction of material and symbolic forces is the threshold of
subjectivity; it is not a biological notion, but marks, rather, the non-coincidence
of the subject with his/her consciousness and the non-coincidence of anatomy with
sexuality. Seen in this light, the body, far from being an essentialist notion, is
situated at the intersection of the biological and the symbolic; as such it marks
a metaphysical surface of integrated material and symbolic elements that defy
separation.
—Braidotti, 1991: 282
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 55–69
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
56 karen davies
in order to make a point—the point being that they feel they are unfairly
treated and by extension would like this state of affairs to be changed, or
that they have in fact accomplished change with regard to gender relations
at their workplace. Narrative, then, is not just recalling a (filtered) past; it
can also “form” the world with its emancipatory potential. Thus the “body
stories” told in my research projects were not related simply to reveal the
victim but told in the spirit of paving the way for dialogue and change. It is
interesting to note that according to Hinchman and Hinchman (1997) the
word narrative comes from the Indo-European root “gna,” which means both
“to tell” and “to know.” In feminist terms, narrative provides the opportunity
to tell “another story”—a story that questions the “master narrative.” While
the stories may be examples of “atrocity tales” (see for example, Goode and
Ben-Yehuda, 1994; Jacobsson, 2000) or see women as victim, narrative may
importantly be used as contestation or protest, as examples of different ways
of seeing and knowing.
Doing Gender
1
Research participants in my studies were asked to give accounts of their work situation and
how they experienced work. They were not asked to describe situations that they experienced
as being gender struggles. Their accounts around such issues, however, emerged spontaneously
and were not always phrased by themselves in terms of being a “gender problem.”
58 karen davies
2002; Davies, 2001, 2003) has emerged as an analytical tool in showing how
gendered relations are actually created, recreated, contested and changed
in daily life. The central question is: how are these relations actually done
and accomplished? What are the deeds and who does the doing? Implicit
is that in all interaction “doing gender” can and does happen (even between
people of the same sex). The feminist concern is thus to unveil these
doings—doings that are often so commonplace or taken for granted that
the doers do not recognise the structures or consequences of their doing.
Yet the doings reinforce gendered relations of power and often leave women
in a disadvantaged position. In order to tap the actual doings, research
methodologies linked to ethnomethodology and symbolic interactionism
are required. As Dorothy Smith writes (in the foreword of Fenstermaker and
West, 2002): “In contrast to the abstract nominalization of much sociology,
ethnomethodology, in all its variants, is oriented to discovering how people
produce what we can recognize as just this or just that everyday event,
occasion, setting, act, or person.” While observation of social conduct is one
way of accessing these doings, they are also unveiled in narratives derived
from interviews discussing everyday life. Such methods are often given the
label of micro sociology, implying that we are only capturing interactions on
an individual level. But the interactions on the micro level mirror the wider
social structures that hinder or enable agency. Individual choice and actions
are formed by the wider social structures, but at the same time individual
choice and action form these social structures. As Fenstermaker and West
(2002: 219) say: “We have taken the position repeatedly that the bifurcation
of ‘micro’/‘macro’ reduces to one of ‘little’ versus ‘big,’ or ‘trivial’ versus
‘consequential,’ or ‘unstructured’ versus ‘structured’ and precludes a vision of
the bridges across the divide.”
Doing gender then lets us understand that gender and gender relations
are not a static pre-given but moulded in ongoing actions where at least two
partners need to be present. As an analytical tool, the concept lets us examine
how others (willingly or unwillingly, consciously or unconsciously) do gender
when interacting with us, but equally how we are accomplices (willingly or
unwillingly, consciously or unconsciously) in the doing. However, the active
and continuous form implied in the “ing” of the doing equally signals its
transformative status, indicating that relations can be changed. The doing
can and does change form (for better or worse). Normative gender relations
can be destabilised.
body memories and doing gender 59
Body-Reflexive Practices
going there because he was usually so arrogant and superior. He started by asking
me in an aggressive tone of voice: “How did you revise for this exam?” I felt very
unsure and didn’t know how to answer. “Tell me now how you revised!”
It wasn’t very nice at all. I told him roughly how I’d gone through the books
and then was quiet. He then said: “It was an excellent exam paper. I wish
everybody used your study technique.” Then he said that it was the best paper
that he’d seen in this subject. “I think you should continue your studies and go
in for this subject. You know we have post-graduate studies.”
I left his room overjoyed, smiling. Felt that maybe the university had
something to offer even me. This was something I couldn’t tell my student
buddies or friends since it would be showing off. But I felt really good, felt joy
and strength.
Later the same day I was walking along the corridor outside the department
and behind me was K. He came up behind me, grabbed hold of my bra at
the back, pulled it out and let it snap back. He then laughed in a supercilious
manner and rushed off. I was so shocked, insulted, that I was silent. (Esseveld,
1999: 107, my translation)
The narrative clearly highlights gendered power relations, and the body as
the site of gender struggle is highlighted in the sexual harassment that occurs
in grabbing the student’s bra. While the student’s bodily reactions are not
spelled out as such in words in this narrative, one automatically imagines
(and even feels oneself ) how these undoubtedly change in this female
student’s day, leading up to what probably were muscular tensions, a possible
headache coming on, the body diminishing in size, et cetera. And what
were the consequences afterwards? We can only speculate (as the narrative
does not give us more information): she never set foot in this department
again; she lost interest in further studies; or she contacted an ombudsman
and the professor was accused of sexual harassment and subsequently lost his
position; the incident was so deep-rooted and painful that she devoted her
work career later to working for sexual equality, et cetera. What is certain,
however, is that the bodily knowing (as both a cognitive memory and a
bodily reaction/memory, for example, muscle tension) led to some form of
social action, whether emancipative or not. The body was not only then the
object of symbolic practice and power but also participant.
From this example, it is clear that (an) individual memory is linked to
wider societal structures, that bodily knowing and body-reflexive practices
are involved in the incident, and that agency as well as objectification are part
and parcel of the encounter. Doing gender is accomplished.
body memories and doing gender 61
Empirical Illustrations
2
The research was financed by The Vardal Foundation during 1997–2000 with the author
as the sole investigator. Results are presented in Davies (2001) and Davies (2003).
3
The research was financed by the Swedish Agency for Innovation Systems (VINNOVA)
during 2001–2003 with Chris Mathieu and myself as co-researchers. Results are published in
Davies and Mathieu (2005) and Mathieu (forthcoming).
62 karen davies
4
Of course the higher positions are more likely to be held by men. Consultants (Sw:
överläkare) consisted of 75% men and 25% women in 1995 (Nordgren, 2000: 70). Thirty-
nine % of women doctors were at the junior doctor level in 1998, while the equivalent figure
for men was 25% (Nordgren, 2000: 70).
5
There are of course a variety of other strategies not linked to the body that are not
discussed here.
6
Physician statistics. Swedish Medical Association. (2001).
body memories and doing gender 63
7
The Vasa race (Vasaloppet) is an annual, international, long-distance skiing competition
where the distance to be covered is 90 km.
64 karen davies
a lot of the work here. Here we are, working in an industry where we use the
latest technology, and yet they can’t see the possibilities! They’re so bound by
tradition! (Female IT consultant, early thirties, married, 3 children under 10
years)
This and similar narratives were expressed by women working at one of the
Swedish companies included in our study. In many ways their opinions and
experiences differ from what was expressed by women (and men) at other
Swedish companies who argued that they assumed combining work and
family would not be problematic. “Assumed” is central here. The IT sector
is a young area, and in the majority of the companies we visited, the median
age of the employees was low. Employees, especially women, had not started
families yet. This is not surprising given that well-educated women in Sweden
are postponing the arrival of their first-born until their thirties. Many of the
Swedish companies in our study also displayed a “young, trendy image”—
advocating buzz words such as diversity, opportunity, flexibility, “no old
boy chauvinistic atmosphere here,”8 they obviously wanted to disassociate
themselves from what they saw as the burgeoning flotsam of traditional
organizational life. They communicated a view of the company to the outside
world and to their employees that “anything was possible.” The company
where the women cited above worked did not exactly fall into this category.
It had existed for some time, and, while having always specialized in technical
areas, it was only in recent years that an IT and telecommunication profile
had been mantled. The median age of employees was also higher here and
having families was a common occurrence. It could thus be argued then that
the particular form of “doing gender” that emerges in the above narrative
will apply to women in other companies later when the reality of combining
work/career and children emerges.
The IT consultant’s tale shows us that the women are constructed
significantly in terms of careers. In no interview, with managers (men—or
women for that matter), is it stated, or assumed, that the women lack technical
or other competency. Technical knowledge or competence is not what is at
issue here. What is at issue is that the work requires, it is argued, mobility and
accessibility both in space and time. Having responsibility for children—at
least for women—is assumed to jeopardize this mobility and accessibility. But
the women strongly argue in the interviews that the arguments used against
8
Willim (2002) found that in the young, fast-moving Swedish company Framfab,
traditional and older IT companies, such as Ericsson, were disparagingly called “respirators.”
body memories and doing gender 65
them are somewhat a “sham.” On the one hand, they’re not asked if they
can solve travelling /being-away-from-home “problems” (it is assumed that
they can’t);9 on the other hand they argue that new technology can surely
mitigate logistic headaches (that is, time and space are in a variety of ways
“released” with the new technology). They emphasize again and again in the
interviews that solutions can be found—but that they aren’t given the chance
to show their ingenuity. The result is that they get stuck in what they see as
rather boring and dead-end jobs or work duties. They also point out that the
male bosses don’t realize that they are being discriminatory or narrow in their
thinking. On the contrary, they say that the men argue that they are trying to
take the women’s situation into account in a fair way.
The body enters this particular narrative in two ways. On the one hand, the
women’s bodies are physically and geographically—in the managers’ eyes—
locked in space due to the women’s caring function, and this affects what
jobs it is assumed they can take (even if they are seen as being technically
competent). On the other hand, it is their female bodies as such that signals
diminished capacities. They are reproductive bodies. The men do not have
reproductive bodies and thereby are not constructed as a certain type of
worker, and thus they avoid certain assumptions and questions. Lack of
competency may hinder the men in their careers, but the male body, as such,
does not.
The appropriation and use of space are political acts. The kinds of spaces we
have, don’t have, or are denied access to can empower us or render us powerless.
Spaces can enhance or restrict, nurture or impoverish. (Weisman, 2000: 4)
The example to be presented below is taken from the study examining the
relations between doctors and nurses. Historically medicine and nursing
have been constructed on certain notions of masculinity and femininity
(see, for example, Davies, 1995; Davies, 2001, 2003; Gamarnikow, 1978)
and embraced “doing dominance” and “doing deference.” Doing gender
9
Interestingly the husbands or partners of the women we interviewed in this company did
not work in the IT sector but often had less qualified jobs (for example, carpenter, pre-school
teacher), and it was argued by the women that it would be fairly easy for their husbands to take
a larger share of child-care. Their husbands were not hounded by ‘top-pressure jobs.”
66 karen davies
out its advantages though: “We spend more time discussing the patient
from various angles now, including social aspects and what will happen to
the patient when he/she leaves the hospital—in addition to talking about
various investigations and lab results. We can sit down and discuss more in
peace and quiet.”
The nurses felt that they had won time with this form of round, especially
as they did not accompany the doctors later into the patient (unless it was
felt that there was a special reason to do so). Earlier, time would be wasted
waiting in the corridor for the doctor to get to their patient. Now the doctors
might have to wait if the nurse could not drop everything on the spur of the
moment when it was time to discuss her patients.
As I understood it, it had been the nurses that had pushed for the new
order of things. The nurse manager gave the following reasons for its
implementation:
It’s an attempt to minimise the number of people in the patient’s room. What’s
the point of a whole flock? In part it’s a question of confidentiality—when
you’re standing there in the corridor . . . And then the doctors, they get irritated
when the cleaning trolley arrives or when the food trolley is on its way out.
They, themselves, don’t see that they stand there and take up a lot of space [in
the corridor] during quite a long period of time. When the new electronic case
records system was introduced, it became obvious that the old routine wasn’t
feasible any longer. I tried to argue that sooner or later they need to sit down
somewhere when all the medication and case records are on the computer. We
can’t do a traditional round with a lap-top and everyone trying to peer into it.
You have to be able to sit down at a larger screen.
Nurses frequently emphasized their patient advocacy role in their work
as well as their concern for the patient, and this type of round, one could
say, facilitates this. Improving patient care was an argument used by both
doctors and nurses to justify a new form of round. Surprisingly, establishing
more egalitarian ways of working between the two professions was not taken
up by my respondents. And yet it seemed to me that this was one of the
outcomes and an important one at that. Space was utilized in the traditional
round to ensure medical authority. The culturally determined spatial rules,
admittedly unwritten but none the less widely understood, saw to it that
each person knew his or her place in the hierarchy (including doctors within
the medical hierarchy). Sitting around a table, by contrast, places bodies on
an equal footing and provides the opportunity for real discussion.10 Sitting
10
I am of course aware that spatial arrangements may not be sufficient to engender equal
talk.
68 karen davies
Concluding Remarks
References
Esseveld, Johanna. “Minnesarbete” (Memory work). In Mer än kalla fakta. Kvalitativ forskning
i praktiken (More than Cold Facts. Qualitative Research in Practice), ed. Katarina Sjöberg,
107–127. Lund: Studentlitteratur, 1999.
Fenstermaker, Sarah. The Gender Factory. New York: Plenum, 1985.
Fenstermaker, Sarah and Candace West, eds. Doing Gender, Doing Difference. Inequality,
Power and Institutional Change. New York: Routledge, 2002.
Gamarnikow, Eva. “Sexual division of labour: the case of nursing.” In Feminism and
Materialism. Women and Modes of Production, ed. Annette Kuhn and AnnMarie Wolpe.
London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978.
Gergen, Kenneth. “Self-narration in social life.” In Discourse Theory and Practice, ed. Margaret
Wetherell, Stephanie Taylor and Simeon J. Yates, 247–260. London: Sage Publications,
2001.
Goode, Erich and Nachman Ben-Yehuda. Moral Panics: The Social Construction of Deviance.
Oxford: Blackwell, 1994.
Haug, Frigga. Female Sexualization: A Collective Work of Memory. London: Verso, 1987.
Hinchman, Lewis P. and Sandra K. Hinchman. Memory, Identity, Community. The Idea of
Narrative in the Human Sciences. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1997.
Jacobsson, Katarina. Retoriska strider. Konkurrerande sanningar i dövvärlden. (Rhetorical
Struggles. Competing Truths in the Deaf Community) Lund: Palmkrons förlag, 2000.
Jedlowski, Paolo. “Memory and sociology. Themes and issues.” Time & Society, 10, no. 1
(2001): 29–44.
Mathieu, Chris. “Pushing and Pulling Female Computer Professionals into Technology-plus
Positions.” In Encyclopedia of Gender and Information Technology, ed. Eileen M. Trauth.
Information Science Publishing, 2006.
Nordgren, Margreth. Läkarprofessionens feminisering. Ett köns- och maktperspektiv (The
Feminization of the Medical Profession. A Gender and Power Perspective). Stockholm
Studies in Politics 69, Stockholm University: Department of Political Science, 2000.
Polkinghorne, Donald E. Narrative Knowing and the Human Sciences. Albany: SUNY Press,
1988.
Weisman, Leslie Kanes. “Women’s environmental rights: A manifesto.” In Gender Space
Architecture, ed. Jane Rendell, Barbara Penner and Iain Borden, 1–12. London:
Routledge, 2000.
West, Candace and Don H. Zimmerman. “Doing gender.” In The Social Construction of Gender,
ed. Judith Lorber and Susan A. Farrell, 13–37. Newsbury Park: SAGE publications,
1991. First published in Gender and Society 1, no. 1 (1987): 125–51.
Willim, Robert. Framtid.nu Flyt och friktion i ett snabbt företag. (Future.now Flow and friction
in a fast company). Lund: Symposion, 2002.
RESPONSE
Linda McKie
In this contribution Karen Davies draws upon theory and narratives from
research projects to illuminate and explore “body stories” as these exemplify
“doing gender.” “Doing gender” refers to the varied and interweaving ways
in which gendered relations are created and reinforced, and infuse the
everyday. To that I would add that “doing gender” is reflected in structural
and organizational entities; for example gender segregation in public and
private sector bodies and policies ranging from government to education
and employment. Body-reflexive practices are evident as the body is both an
object of symbolic practice and power as well as a participant in these very
processes. Davies asserts that memories can both chart these experiences and
also prove “pivotal in the unfolding of time.”
The construction of women’s bodies, and bodily experiences, as infused
with their reproductive potential and history, leads to assumptions about
competency. Narratives on working in information technology highlighted
the ways in which “doing gender” is evident in women’s perceptions of their
positioning in dead-end or boring jobs. Ironically, it would seem that women
workers perceive male managers as trying to take women’s caring roles into
account but in ways that result in discriminatory practices.
The potential to shift gendered social relations and challenge discriminatory
practices is developed through Davies’s study of the morning rounds in
several hospital wards. In one, nurses have negotiated across time and space
to ensure that all medical and nursing staff met in a room at a round table.
Nurses initiated discussion of each patient’s case also presenting an appraisal.
While doctors felt it took too much time and created an imbalance in the
usual ward relations (in which doctors led a walk around beds) proposing
that nurses might learn from medical staff, the nurses persisted with the
“round table” arrangement. Nurses secured a more egalitarian way of working.
Professional and gendered hierarchies illuminate the relationship between
professions, organizations and patriarchy. In this example, the challenge by
nurses achieved change and they worked to maintain these changes through
the controlling the interplay of space—the room and the round table—and
time—the appraisal of each patient’s case.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 70–71
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
response 71
Summary
The fundamental aspects of psychological time (duration, temporal order, perspective)
are mediated by memory structures and processes. The present research examined the
coding of temporal order information in semantic memory and its retrieval. To explore this
question a recognition paradigm and a combination of several different research methods
(behavioral, pupillometric, and neuroimaging studies) were used. The temporal orientation
and the distance between events were manipulated. Reaction times, error rates and pupillary
responses demonstrated that the temporal dimension in mental event representations showed
directional and distance properties. In general, these findings supported the theoretical
framework proposed by Barsalou (1999). Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging (fMRI)
data suggested that the processing of temporal-order relations depended on prefrontal brain
regions. These results are discussed with regards to executive functions of the prefrontal
cortex.
Theoretical Background
Time is one of the most central aspects of human life. However, no sense or
sense organ is known by which time can be perceived directly. More than
a century ago, the physicist Mach started with experimental studies on the
sense of time. Based on the results he argued that “time is an abstraction at
which we arrive by means of the changes of things” (Mach, 1886, p. 209).
Ever since, researchers have been trying to disclose the secret of information
processing responsible for the sense of time (cf., Gruber, Wagner, & Block,
2004; Ivry & Spencer, 2004; Kesner, 1998; Lewis & Miall, 2003). However,
psychological time appeared to be extremely complex. No simple theory
could adequately describe the multifaceted pattern of temporal experiences
and behaviors.
At present, cognitive psychologists typically agree that the fundamental
aspects of psychological time—namely, duration, temporal order, and
perspective (cf., Block, 1990)—are mediated by memory structures and
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 73–86
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
74 van der meer, krüger, strauch & kuchinke
processes. This chapter will focus on the aspect of temporal order relations in
semantic memory. Following Tulving (1972, p. 386), semantic memory “is a
mental thesaurus, organized knowledge a person possesses about words and
other verbal symbols, their meanings and referents, about relations among
them, and about rules, formulas, and algorithms for the manipulation of these
symbols, concepts, and relations.” The aim of our experiments was to analyze
whether and how temporal order information could be coded and accessed
in semantic memory. According to Michon (1993), temporal information
cannot be completely separated from the content and the structure of events.
That is, events and sequences of events are assumed to hold an intrinsic
temporal structure. The theoretical framework adopted for representing
highly familiar sequences of real-life events in semantic memory postulates
conceptual entities in the form of scripts (Schank & Abelson, 1977). Scripts
(for example, going to a doctor) have a relatively simple syntax that represents
a succession of events defined by an initial and a final state. Within a script,
individual events are thus primarily defined by their temporal position in the
sequence. Other dimensions can be important as well. As we have argued
elsewhere (van der Meer, Beyer, Heinze, & Badel, 2002) event sequences,
about which we have background knowledge, typically have a causal relation
of some sort. Trabasso, van den Broek, and Suh (1989) differentiated
motivational, physical, psychological, and enabling relations. Nevertheless,
most physicists and philosophers agree that all types of causal relations
have one basic presupposition in common: temporal orientability (Earman,
1995, p. 274). The present chapter will focus on this property of temporal
orientability.
Familiar sequences of real-life events are organized unidirectionally. Thus,
temporal-order relations of our experiences are asymmetric relations. The
order in which two or more real-life events occur obeys multiple constraints
(Grafman, 1995). Some constraints are physical. You cannot drink coffee
from a cup unless it is first poured into the cup. Some constraints are cultural.
In Germany, people generally look left before passing the street. In Great
Britain, however, one has to look right before passing the street without
risk. Some constraints are purely individual. Some people drink hot milk in
the evening before going to bed. Obviously, representing the chronological
order of real-life events in memory and recognizing it later on contributes
to human intelligence by supporting correct anticipations and adaptive
behavior. Therefore, the chronological order of familiar sequences of real-life
events is assumed to be stored in semantic memory. Several findings support
this claim. For example, sentence and text comprehension is impaired if
there is a mismatch between the chronological order and the reported order
coding of temporal order information 75
of events (cf., Ohtsuka & Brewer, 1992; van der Meer et al., 2002). Münte,
Schiltz, and Kutas (1998) measured event-related brain potentials (ERPs) as
participants read “before” and “after” sentences. “Before” sentences elicited,
within 300 ms, greater negativity in the left-anterior part of the brain than
“after” sentences. That is, deviations from chronological order increase
cognitive effort.
On the theoretical front, it has been proposed that our mental
representations of real-life events reflect the dynamic character of our
environment. Dealing with very short-term memory effects, Freyd (1987,
1992) has hypothesized the internal temporal dimension to be like external
time, that is, directional and continuous. Barsalou (1999) made the more
general assumption that representations of events in semantic memory are
not arbitrary and amodal, but are based upon physical experiences. According
to Barsalou (1999), comprehension is the mental simulation of events,
using perceptual symbols from all information modalities available. Because
temporal order relations of our experiences are asymmetric relations, mental
event representations should mirror the preferred temporal orientation of
events in favor of future time.
The aim of this chapter is to discuss how temporal order is coded and
accessed in semantic memory. In particular, we focus on whether the mental
representation of temporal order relations between real-life events has
directional and distance properties. With this in mind, a combination of
research methods—behavioral studies, pupillary responses, and functional
neuroimaging methods—was employed to study the coding of temporal
order information in event knowledge.
1000
950
Reaction Time (in ms)
900
850
800
chronological reverse
Temporal Orientation
Figure 1: Reaction time in milliseconds required to accept related items depending
on temporal orientation.
a faster access (cf., Friedman, 1990; Sirigu et al., 1995). In general, our
findings correspond with this associative view. They support the hypothesis
that the temporal dimension in mental event representations has directional
properties (cf., Barsalou, 1999).
SOA = 200 ms
Ordinal Distance 1 Ordinal Distance 2
M SD E% M SD E%
Metric Distance Small 893 217 12.3 917 219 10.0
Metric Distance Large 890 211 6.9 931 236 9.2
SOA = 1,000 ms
Ordinal Distance 1 Ordinal Distance 2
M SD E% M SD E%
Metric Distance Small 851 197 3.8 928 223 9.2
Metric Distance Large 852 190 7.7 929 298 11.5
117,557, p = 0.71] and metric distance [F < 1], but a significant main effect
of the ordinal distance between probe event and target event [F (1,17) =
10.16, MSE = 4,470, p = .005], with longer RTs for more distant events. All
two-way interactions and the three-way interaction were not significant. In
addition, the analysis of error rates revealed no significant effects.
These data closely match our second hypothesis. Retrieving the rough
position of the two events on the internal temporal dimension provides critical
information on relatedness. Participants primarily accessed knowledge of the
distance of the position of events on the mental temporal dimension. An
SOA of 1,000 ms did not help in speeding up and improving the recognition
of temporally related items compared with an SOA of 200 ms. In accordance
with Fischler and Goodman (1987) and Neely (1991), it is argued that the
SOA interval of 200 ms stands for automatic activation, whereas the longer
SOA interval of 1,000 ms stands for controlled, elaborative processing.
Therefore, the access of ordinal distance information in event knowledge
is assumed to be due to automatic spreading activation mechanisms. In the
recognition task, rough accuracy in relatedness judgement could be derived
from coarse-grained categorical (position) knowledge. However, taking into
account other tasks, for example distance estimation tasks, knowledge of
fine-grained metric type might crucially improve performance. Thus, future
research will have to determine whether the temporal dimension in mental
event representations might contain some event related metric distance
information, too.
Table 2: Means (M), and Standard Deviations (SD) for Pupil Parameters Peak
Dilation (PD, z-score) and Latency to Peak (LP, in Milliseconds) Dependent on
Temporal Orientation of Items
Human and animal learning studies have provided evidence that the prefrontal
cortex is important for temporal sequencing (Kesner, 1998). Moreover,
frontal patients have been reported to experience impairments in event and
action processing at both the schema and the script level. For example, patients
coding of temporal order information 81
right ventrolateral cortex (BA 47), the posterior lateral cortex (BA 6), and
the medial cortex (BA 32) (cf., Table 3, II). These patterns of activation have
been observed under a variety of conditions, suggesting that they are related
to generic semantic retrieval operations, too (Cabeza & Nyberg, 2000).
Contrasting the temporal-order and the non-temporal semantic relations
conditions (cf., Table 3, III) resulted in enhanced activation in the anterior
cingulate cortex (BA 24) for temporal-order relations. This finding fits the
results of several imaging studies that have shown an involvement of the
anterior cingulate cortex (ACC) in conflict monitoring (Botvinick, Braver,
Barch, Carter, & Cohen, 2001). It has been suggested that activation in ACC
during complex cognitive processing reflects, among others, the initiation of
appropriate responses while suppressing inappropriate ones. The cognitive
processes involved in the temporal-order discrimination task might be very
similar to those seen in Stroop studies: For reverse items, the prepotent mental
representation (that is, the chronological orientation of sequences of events)
must be inhibited. Instead, the trial-appropriate mental representation (the
reverse temporal orientation of sequences of events) and the corresponding
response must be initiated. Note, that due to the block design it was not
possible to compare the patterns of activation for chronological and reverse
items directly in this study.
In addition, contrasting the temporal-order and the non-temporal
semantic relations conditions resulted in enhanced activation in prefrontal
cortex (BA 6, 9, 45, 47) for temporal-order relations. Because the temporal-
order condition led to longer RTs and higher error rates than the non-
temporal semantic relations condition, this result pattern was assumed to
reflect the higher task difficulty of temporal-order trials compared to non-
temporal semantic relations trials (Smith & Jonides, 1997). The higher
the task difficulty, the more areas in the brain are activated. This would be
consistent with evidence that temporal information-processing generally
taxes more cognitive resources than processing of other types of information
(Hälbig, von Cramon, Schmid, Gall, & Friederici, 2002).
In consequence, these findings provide evidence for a non-specific
involvement of the prefrontal cortex in executive monitoring functions,
which seems to be closely related to temporal-order memory performance,
too (Shimamura, Janowsky, & Squire, 1990). Future research should examine
this issue in more detail by using a variety of temporal and non-temporal
tasks.
84 van der meer, krüger, strauch & kuchinke
Conclusion
References
2nd ed., ed. J. T. Cacioppo, L. G. Tassinary and G. G. Berntson, 142–162. New York:
Cambridge University Press, 2000.
Block, R. A. “Models of Psychological Time.” In R. Block (Ed.), Cognitive Models of
Psychological Time, ed. R. Block, 1–35. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1990.
Botvinick, M. M., T. S. Braver, D. M. Barch, C. S. Carter and J. D. Cohen. “Conflict monitoring
and cognitive control.” Psychological Review 108 (2001): 624–652.
Cabeza, R. and L. Nyberg. “Imaging cognition II: An empirical review of 275 PET and fMRI
studies.” Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 12:1 (2000): 1–47.
Crozier, S., et al. “Distinct prefrontal activations in processing sequence at the sentence and
script level: An fMRI study.” Neuropsychologia 37 (1999): 1469–1476.
Earman, J. “Recent work on time travel.” In Time’s arrows today, ed. S. F. Savitt, 268–310.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.
Fischler, I. and G. O. Goodman. (1987). “Latency of associative activation in memory.” Journal
of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance 4 (1987): 455–470.
Freyd, J. J. “Dynamic mental representations.” Psychological Review 94 (1987): 427–438.
———. “Dynamic representations guiding adaptive behavior.” In Time, action and cognition,
ed. F. Macar, V. Pouthas, and J. Friedman, 309–323. Dordrecht: Kluwer, 1992.
Friedman, W. J. About Time. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1990.
Gabrieli, J. D. E., R. A. Poldrack and J. E. Desmond. “The role of left prefrontal cortex in
language and memory.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences USA 95 (1998):
906–913.
Grafman, J. (1995). “Similarities and distictions among current models of prefrontal cortical
functions.” In Structure and Functions of the Human Prefrontal Cortex, ed. J. Grafman,
K. J. Holyoak, and F. Boller. Annals of the New York Academy of sciences, Vol. 769 (1995):
337–368.
Gruber, R. P., L. F. Wagner and R. A. Block. “Relationships between subjective time and
information processed (reduction of uncertainty).” In Time and Uncertainty, ed. P. A.
Harris and M. Crawford, 188–203. Leiden, Boston: Brill, 2004.
Hälbig, T. D., D. Y. von Cramon, U. D. Schmid, C. Gall and A. D. Friederici. “Processing of
temporal duration information in working memory after frontodorsal tumour excisions.”
Brain and Cognition 50 (2002): 282–303.
Humphreys, G. W., E. M. E. Forde and M. J. Riddoch. “The planning and execution of
everyday actions.” In The handbook of cognitive neuropsychology, ed. B. Rapp, 565–589.
Ann Arbor, MI: Taylor and Francis, 2001.
Ivry, R. B. and R. M. C. Spencer. “The neural representation of time.” Current Opinion in
Neurobiology 14 (2004): 225–232.
Just, M. J. and P. A. Carpenter. “The intensity of thought: Pupillometric indices of sentence
processing.” Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology. Special Issue: Reading and
language processing 47:2 (1993): 310–339.
Kesner, R. P. “Neural mediation of memory for time: Role of the hippocampus and medial
prefrontal cortex.” Psychonomic Bulletin and Review 5:4 (1998): 585–596.
Krüger, F., A. Nuthmann and E. van der Meer. “Pupillometric indices of temporal order
representation in semantic memory.” Zeitschrift für Psychologie 209 (2001): 402–415.
Kuchinke, L. Zur Dissoziierbarkeit von Exekutiven Funktionen und Zeitfolgemanipulation
mittels fMRI [Dissociation between executive functions and processing of temporal order:
An fMRI study]. Master thesis, Humboldt University at Berlin, 2002 (unpublished).
Lewis, P. A. and R. C. Miall. “Distinct systems for automatic and cognitively controlled
time measurement: Evidence from neuroimaging.” Current Opinion in Neurobiology 13
(2003): 250–255.
Mach, E. Beiträge zur Analyse der Empfindungen (Contributions to the Analysis of Perception).
Jena: Fischer, 1886.
Michon, J. A. “Concerning the time sense: The seven pillars of time psychology.” Psychologica
Belgica 33:2 (1993): 329–345.
86 van der meer, krüger, strauch & kuchinke
Miller, E. K. and J. D. Cohen. “An integrative theory of prefrontal cortex function.” Annual
Reviews of Neuroscience 24 (2001): 167–202.
Münte, T. F., K. Schiltz and M. Kutas. “When temporal terms belie conceptual order.” Nature
395 (1998): 71–73.
Neely, J. H. “Semantic priming effects in visual word recognition: A selective review of current
findings and theories.” In Basic processes in reading: Visual word recognition, ed. D. Besner
and G. Humphreys, 264–336. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum, 1991.
Ohtsuka, K. and W. F. Brewer. “Discourse organization in the comprehension of temporal
order in narrative texts.” Discourse Processes 15 (1992): 317–336.
Partiot, A., J. Grafman, N. Sadato, S. Flitman and K. Wild. (1996). “Brain activation during
script event processing.“ Neuroreport 7 (1996): 761–766.
Schank, R. C. and R. P. Abelson. Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding. Hillsdale, NJ:
Erlbaum, 1977.
Shallice, T. and P. W. Burgess. “Deficits in strategy application following frontal lobe damage
in man.” Brain 114 (1991): 727–741.
Shimamura, A. P., J. S. Janowsky and L. R. Squire. “Memory for the temporal order of events
in patients with frontal lobe lesions and amnestic patients.” Neuropsychologia 28 (1990):
803–813.
Sirigu, A. et al. “Planning and Script Analysis following Prefrontal Lobe Lesions.” In Structure
and Functions of the Human Prefrontal Cortex, ed. J. Grafman, K. J. Holyoak and F.
Boller. Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 769 (1995): 277–288.
Smith, E. E. and J. Jonides. “Working memory: A view from neuroimaging.” Cognitive
Psychology 33 (1997): 5–42.
Strauch, D. Repräsentation zeitlicher Distanzen in typischen Ereignissequenzen [Representation
of temporal distances in highly familiar sequences of events]. PhD Thesis, Humboldt
University at Berlin, 2002 (unpublished).
Trabasso, T., P. W. van den Broek and S. Y. Suh. “Logical necessity and transitivity of causal
relations in stories. Discourse Processes 12 (1989): 1–25.
Tulving, E. “Episodic and semantic memory.” In Organisation of memory, ed. E. Tulving &
W. Donaldson. London: Academic Press, 1972.
van der Meer, E., R. Beyer, B. Heinze and I. Badel. “Temporal Order in Language
Comprehension.” Journal of Experimental Psychology: Learning, Memory, & Cognition
28:4 (2002): 770–779.
van der Meer, E., M. Friedrich, A. Nuthmann, C. Stelzel and L. Kuchinke. “Picture-Word-
Matching: Flexibility in Conceptual Memory and Pupillary Responses.” Psychophysiology
40 (2003): 904–913.
Wood, J. N. and J. Grafman. “Human prefrontal cortex: Processing and representational
perspectives.” Nature Reviews/Neuroscience 4 (2003): 139–147.
Zeelenberg, R., R. M. Shiffrin and R. W. Raijmaker. “Priming in free association tasks as a
function of association directionality.” Memory & Cognition 27 (1999): 956–961.
CHAPTER FOUR
Marlene P. Soulsby
Summary
Narratives of dementia evoke a human experience typically associated with loss—the loss of
self, the loss of a hold on reality, the loss of the past. This paper explores the more complex layers
of self, reality and time that we encounter through the reading of several different narratives:
biographies by Eleanor Cooney and Sue Miller, an autobiography by Thomas DeBaggio, the
novel Man in the Holocene by Max Frisch, and group stories created through the Time Slips
project. These narratives tell the time of realities as they are experienced by those afflicted with
memory loss. They also tell about the frustrations and the possibilities that can emerge when
the experiences of different temporal realities meet. These narratives not only give us insights
into memory loss and the experience of time but also create a complexity of time experiences
through the very process of reading.
With the use of memory, we construct narratives that lift the events and
experiences of life into a meaningful and coherent order. Our narratives give
shape to time and define a continuity of self. For those who are losing the
ability to remember due to Alzheimer’s Disease or other dementias, however,
narrative becomes more difficult if not impossible to construct. The sense of a
continuous self appears to unravel or dissolve, and attempts to communicate
deteriorate. Yet the impulse to tell is a vital way to confirm, or affirm, that the
self still exists in the midst of this experience. It is also a way to connect to the
world outside the self.
Telling the story of memory loss involves telling the time of an experiential
world. In this paper I examine several examples of narratives that attempt
to convey the temporal experience of those whose memory is failing. They
include biographical and autobiographical perspectives, a work of fiction, and
samples of stories created in group settings by people with mild to moderate
dementia. In each case we encounter realities shaped by temporalities that
are not linear or continuous. We enter worlds that are difficult to traverse
because of their temporal structure. The encounter with these realities and
their temporalities takes us on a journey through many layers of the human
story. The attempt to understand, to make connections, or to bridge gaps
between realities is indicative of the human attempt to touch one another.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 87–97
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
88 marlene p. soulsby
asking if there’s a hospital in the next town, telling us she’s going to take a nap,
asking the name of the doctor she saw last time she was here, asking if she’s
having dinner with us, telling us she wishes she knew when she was going to die,
asking if there’s a hospital in the next town, asking if there’s vodka in the house,
searching for her basket. (55)
In The Story of my Father, Sue Miller recounts an episode with her father
when he insisted that he needed to get in touch with “Sue Miller” even
though she was sitting in front of him. Their short exchange reveals that
Miller’s sense of linear, ordered, noetic time confronts a temporality with
no direction, an abiding present of repetition and pure succession that blurs
with the past. Upon reflection, Miller speculates that her father’s memory
of her and the person he saw before him had somehow separated from one
another. There were multiple Sues in his mind based actually on a “deeper
reality”—that Alzheimer’s had changed her too and made her into another
person. For him the memories of his daughter at different times coexisted in
the present (137).
Miller’s biography, however, is clearly a narrative of her own memory—it
is her story of associations and feelings, her attempt to preserve the identity
of her father and in a broader way to make sense of life. The time that she
tells is her time based on her memory. For example, the recollection of a little
girl watching her father work merges with a memory in the more distant past
when she herself was a girl going to her father’s study (53). This blending of
past memories is narrated in the present tense. They exist now, simultaneously,
not linearly, in her mind. They are memory in the Augustinian sense of “the
present time of things past” (11.20, 273). The difference between Sue and
her father is that she is not trapped in a temporal world of simultaneities. She
can pull back and order this experience through narrative.
Writers such as Diana Friel McGowin in her book Living in the Labyrinth
and Morris Friedell in his internet journal record their own progression
of memory loss through a constantly evolving story of past memories and
present reality. These writers juxtapose an awareness of the “present time of
things past” with an awareness of the present of things slowly slipping away.
Thomas DeBaggio in his autobiography, Losing my Mind, employs several
narrative lines to reveal who he is and was. But throughout the text is the
unavoidable realization that “Alzheimer’s works to destroy the present and
the past” (xi). One narrative line traces long-term memories and projects
into the future. It reflects on and analyzes experience. It is characterized by
a noetic arrow of time and the ability to move easily back and forth along
this line, reconstructing a life that changed dramatically with the diagnosis
of Alzheimer’s. Thus in one paragraph he speculates, “I have been thinking
90 marlene p. soulsby
of my obituary all day, wondering what will be written, if anything.” The next
paragraph turns back to the past, “Going to school was important, I was told,
but school made me anxious” (62).
A second narrative line frequently interrupts this account with brief,
often metaphorical statements such as, “Once in a while I hear wind whistling
through my brain” (62), or “I am suspended in time, hanging by a rotting thread
of memory” (59), or “I am being gobbled up in time” (20). The statements are
not logically connected to one another and are set off in the text by italics.
DeBaggio says that this line “intersects the first” with “a mind-clogged,
uncertain present” (xi), a present charged with the immediacy of emotion.
A third line, identified by text indented five spaces from the rest, is not
really narrative. It consists of selections and excerpts from other texts that
provide information about Alzheimer’s Disease, for example: “Due to the
complex changes occurring in their brain, patients with Alzheimer’s may see
or hear things that have no basis in reality” (117). Many of these statements
are taken verbatim from publications of agencies such as the National
Institutes of Aging and Health and The Alzheimer’s Disease Research Center.
These objective and factual items suspend time altogether by objectifying the
personal experience and stepping outside of the narrative.
Thus DeBaggio interweaves three time-lines in his story: one that depicts
the continuum of his life from the past through the present and towards
the future; one that taps into the emotion of the present; and one that is
atemporal in both content and tone. The juxtaposition and interweaving of
these times-lines generates the temporality of the work as a whole; they are
simultaneous aspects of the writer’s increasing memory loss while he is still
able to reflect on the experience and articulate it through language. Eventually,
however, he projects that his self-narrated story will come to an end. As he
says, “Alzheimer’s sends you back to an elemental world before time [. . .] I
sense reality slipping away, and words become slippery sand” (89).
Arthur Frank in his book The Wounded Storyteller writes about the
storyteller who can no longer narrate experience. As memory fails, and with
it the ability to determine sequence and causality, experience becomes more
chaotic. Frank says, “In telling the events of one’s life, events are mediated by
the telling. But in the lived chaos there is no mediation, only immediacy”
(98). Thus, narratives that tell the story of memory loss must deal in some
way with the time of an abiding present. Authors like DeBaggio attempt
to give narrative order to a life that is progressing into greater disorder, like
narrating the edge of an ever-widening hole or wound. Those who are living
the chaos, in the hole so to speak, cannot gain the reflection, distance, or
articulation of language necessary to form narrative; therefore their stories
telling the time of memory loss 91
are told through the voice of someone else, as we have seen in the narratives
of Cooney and Miller.
Works of fiction present another possibility for narrating the experience
of memory loss and giving voice to “lived chaos.” A fictionalized account can
create a world, a self, and a sense of time without stigmatizing the author. I
will give particular attention to one such work, Man in the Holocene by Max
Frisch. This novel records a week in the life of a 74-year-old man with failing
memory, a week of relentless rain and thunderstorms. The only access road
to the remote Alpine village where he lives is blocked; telephones are not
working, and the power fails repeatedly.
One day follows another. Not much seems to happen. Geiser, the prota-
gonist, isolated in his home, “has time to spare” (3). Whatever he does, time
passes. Whether he remembers what occupies his mind from one moment to
the next, time passes.
The narrator sustains this sense of passage through a perspective situated
in the moving now of the present moment. He observes and records whatever
comes to his awareness without making causal or logical connections:
The hot plate is turned off.
Cats always fall on their feet, but in spite of that she is now yowling outside
the front door; perhaps Geiser said: Get out—but after that not a word in the
house.
Outside it is raining.
It is true the gray cobwebs on the ceiling have been there a long time [. . .]. (59)
At times it is difficult to distinguish narrator from protagonist, creating a
uniquely dual perspective as though we were watching from the inside.
Michael Butler points out that this technique enables the reader both to share
in Geiser’s “experience of progressive disorientation and simultaneously to
observe it almost clinically” (574). It also allows for an intimate interweaving
of objective and subjective time. (See also Donahue, Dahms, Probst.) In the
following passage, the narrative tracks the objective, inexorable ticking of the
clock, juxtaposing it to Geiser’s perception that time is standing still:
92 marlene p. soulsby
To keep looking at one’s wristwatch, just in order to convince oneself that time
is passing is absurd. Time has never yet stood still just because a person is bored
and stands at the window not knowing what he is thinking. The last time Geiser
looked at his watch it was six o’clock—or more exactly, three minutes to six.
And now?
The portrait of Elsbeth that he recently took from the wall and put in the
hallway is out of place there. Where should it go? This indicated that, since
last looking at his watch, Geiser has been in the hallway; otherwise the portrait
would not be in his hands, and he is now standing in the bedroom.
...
When Geiser goes back to the window to convince himself, by watching the
slowly gliding raindrops, that time is not standing still—and in the whole of
history it has never done that!—and when he cannot resist looking at this
again, it reads seven minutes past six. (66–67)
The narrator has recorded ten minutes in a text which in its entirety numbers
279 words. It takes a reader much less time to read those words. During this
span, Geiser’s thought leaps from one impression or thought to another,
leaving gaps in the causal chain. Without a memory of the past continuum,
he looks for evidence of change in the external world (the watch as well as the
rain) and uses clues in the present (his position in the hallway, the portrait
in his hands) to reconstruct and fill in a bridge of linked changes between
moments. The contrast between the passage of clock time and Geiser’s inner
experience, as well as between the time that is narrated (ten minutes) and
the time that it takes a reader to read, generates the impression that time
has stopped. We, as readers, know the minutes are ticking away but there is
telling the time of memory loss 93
style characteristic of the rest of the narrative. At first the past merges in the
telling with the flowing present so that it is not immediately apparent that
this is a memory; then the past recollection alternates with present thoughts.
The lived memory, immediate and powerful, is experienced simultaneously
with the confusion of the now. Linear sequential time alternates with the
associative randomness of an abiding present.
In the experience of this memory, Geiser recalls a climbing expedition
up the Matterhorn with his brother Klaus: the triumphant ascent, the
treacherous descent, standing alone against the face of the glacier, unable to
move, waiting for a rope from his brother to save his life. “That remains in
his memory. Klaus was a good brother” (104). The reality and emotional
impact of this long-term memory and the sense of an enduring human
bond between brothers combines with other experiences: the intensifying
frustration of trying to remember the names of his grandchildren and the
inability of figuring out the sequence of events leading to the appearance of
his daughter in his house.
The daughter wants to know what events have led to this moment. She asks
why—“Why the closed shutters, why all these papers on the wall, why his hat
on his head?” (105) He wants to know about now: “Why does she talk to
him as if he were a child?” The questions speak of the painful divide between
two experiential worlds, two temporal realities and the frustrating inability
to bridge the gap. She wants to reconstruct a linear causal timeline in order
to understand what has happened in the past; he wants her to acknowledge
who he is. His identity and his humanity are grounded not only in the ability
of recollection but also in the fleeting experiences of life as they occur, in
the unpredictable human encounters and relationships with others, and in
the triumphs, large and small, that are part of his own unique existence. Yet
without communication, he is essentially alone.
Narratives that tell the story of memory loss typically tell of the
disintegration of time’s arrow and the implications of that disintegration for
the sense of self and community. If the “real self ” is the one who was able
to function in linear time but can no longer do so, then that self ceases to
exist, dissolves, when that temporal world dissolves. Geiser’s story, however,
reminds us that human time encompasses multiple levels of experience, and
the self does not forfeit its reality or its humanity because it is trapped in a
lower temporal order. It just needs a lifeline to enable communication and
connection to someone else.
Other types of stories and story-telling situations direct our attention to
the communal needs of the self and the possibility of making connections
between people living in different time realities. Anne Davis Basting has
devised a story-telling project called Time Slips that reinforces the sense of
telling the time of memory loss 95
self as more than linear time and memory. She explains that “one’s personal
control of memory is just one of several components of identity” and that
persons are defined by “more than their ability to link past, present, and
future” (135). Time is the great “divider.” There are those who can master
linear time and those who cannot; those who know the date and the year
and who can draw numbers on a clock and those who cannot (136). The
difference between the two experiences of time is indeed the difference
between worlds. The Time Slips project avoids the futility of trying to
impose the temporality of one world on another. Instead, it establishes a
“shared present” where people from both temporal worlds can communicate
and interact through creative give and take.
The story telling situation is as follows: groups of people with memory loss
meet with facilitators for an hour or so and tell a story together based on a
picture. The facilitators assist with the process and write down the story as it
unfolds, but are trained not to interfere or to impose their own temporality,
“sense of linear logic,” or idea of what a story should be on the group (136).
Stories, just as human experience itself, can take many shapes and tell of many
worlds. These stories are the product of the combined efforts of all persons in
the group; and time can flow as it will. Basting describes the time of the story-
telling situation: “Staff, volunteers, and storytellers were under the spell of
the present moment and our ability to communicate in it, occasionally in
complete nonsense. For all of us, story-time was a place where fragments of
memory could launch us into new places that we built together rather than
lock us into labels of loss or badges of control” (142).
The stories are inspired by a picture—usually something funny or
provocative that is not so realistic that people fear they have forgotten its
“real” story. The members of the group “tell” the story as it occurs to them
spontaneously or in response to questions posed by the facilitators: for
example, “What should we call her?” or “Where are they?” The narrative
is recorded as it evolves from the group without forcing it to make sense or
to assume a certain direction with a beginning, middle and end. If a person
in the group cannot think of the words but uses sound or gesture—that too
becomes part of the story. The stories, therefore tell the time of the moment
and, in doing so, reflect the temporality of the group’s experience.
I have facilitated several story-telling sessions in a residential health
care facility and in an adult day-care center. Participants were identified by
facility administrators as having mild to moderate dementia. For comparison
purposes, I also collected stories told by elderly without memory loss and by
college students. During the sessions, I worked in the questions: “What is
happening now? What happened before? What might happen after this?”
The stories told by groups with memory loss tell of present experience and
96 marlene p. soulsby
time that is discontinuous. In fact, my questions about the past and the future
were typically followed by silence or disinterest. If there was reference to the
past it might be a trace of remembered experience from a person’s own past:
“ We used to have a light like that.” Or it might be a general impression of the
future: “Somebody could get hurt doing that.” The stories are driven for the
most part by associative leaps, simultaneous threads, ruptures, repetition.
The stories told by elderly without memory loss incorporated more
personal memories from the past and would often include narrative diversions
tangential to the picture. College students were more concerned that the
story had a beginning, middle and end reflective of linear thinking and an
arrow of time. For example, the following sentences establish a definitive
and complex time line: “They’re returning home from a class reunion and
stopped along the way in Las Vegas to get married by an Elvis impersonator.
Because he listened to her, he turned down the wrong road and then lost his
toupee about ten miles ago.“ When telling this story, students paid particular
attention to the plot, and they frequently worked together through several
revisions to get it “just right”—that is, causally logical. A story told by a
group with memory loss about the same picture reveals no such concern with
establishing a thread. Instead it relies on the power of emotion felt now, as
is evident in the repetitive language and the merging together of storyteller
and story:
The car must have broken down.
The man is holding his eyes and saying, “Oh no!”
He’s got his hands full and he’s the driver of the car.
He’s saying, “Oh no,” because the car broke down.
To no avail, he’s saying, “Oh no.”
...
He has a headache.
Which way are we going, “Oh no.”
You can see the dirt and sand.
The narratives that were created as part of Time Slips reflect the time of human
experience without the imposition of narrative order. Arthur Frank might
refer to them as chaos stories told by “wounded storytellers.” Indeed, they
do tell of life as it is experienced, “without sequence or discernable causality”
(97). They often tell of repetition, unrelated succession, and even silence. But
unlike chaos stories, these are not threatening or anxiety-provoking. They
do not tell “how easily any of us could be sucked under” (97). Instead, they
tell that a story may emerge from many “worlds” and that there are ways to
bridge the temporal rifts, thus acknowledging the person, the connection to
community, and the story.
Many of the biographies, autobiographies, diaries, e-journals, fictional
telling the time of memory loss 97
texts and group narratives of memory loss that are available today bring us in
touch with realities that are frightening yet strangely familiar. We fear loss—
the loss of threads that hold the world together and the loss of timelines
that give order to experience; we fear the social and spiritual isolation that
accompanies such loss. Yet the narratives of loss take us on journeys into
depths and times of our own selves. As J. T. Fraser’s hierarchical model of
time illustrates, human beings encompass many levels of temporal experience;
even though we identify the experience of noetic, linear time as the common
measure of our identity and our humanity. For those who dwell in a less
ordered temporality, it is difficult if not impossible to function effectively in
the everyday world, but the self and the humanity of the person are not lost.
These narratives attempt to give a voice to the experiencing self and to tell the
time of that experience. In this way, they not only promote understanding of
an affliction but also help us to recognize and make contact with the many
dimensions of the human story.
References
Augustine of Hippo. The Confessions of St. Augustine. Translated by Rex Warner. New York:
Signet, 1963.
Basting, Anne Davis. “ ‘It’s 1924, and Somewhere in Texas, Two Nuns are Driving a Backwards
Volkswagen’: Storytelling with People with Dementia.” In Aging and the Meaning of Time,
eds. McFadden, Susan H. and Robert C. Atchley, 131–149. New York: Springer, 2001.
Butler, Michael. “Max Frisch’s Man in the Holocene: An Interpretation.” World Literature Today:
A Literary Quarterly of the University of Oklahoma 60:4 (1986 Autumn): 574–580.
Cooney, Eleanor. Death in Slow Motion: My Mother’s Descent into Alzheimer’s. New York:
HarperCollins, 2003.
Dahms, Erna. Zeit und Zeiterlebnis in den Werken Max Frischs. Berlin: de Gruyter, 1976.
DeBaggio, Thomas. Losing My Mind: An Intimate Look at Life with Alzheimer’s. New York:
The Free Press, 2003.
Donahue, Neil H.: “Age, Beauty and Apocalypse: Yasunari Kawabata’s The Sound of the
Mountain and Max Frisch’s Der Mensch erscheint im Holozän.” Arcadia: Zeitschrift
fur Vergleichende Literaturwissenschaft 28:3 (1993): 291–306.
Frank, Arthur W. The Wounded Storyteller: Body, Illness, and Ethics. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1995.
Fraser, J. T. Time the Familiar Stranger. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1987.
Friedell, Morris. “Home Page.” <http://members.aol.com/MorrisFF> (Accessed 12 May 2005).
Frisch, Max. Man in the Holocene. Translated by Geoffrey Skelton. Orlando: Harcourt, 1980.
McGowin, Diana Friel. Living in the Labyrinth: A Personal Journey through the Maze of
Alzheimer’s. New York: Delacorte, 1993.
Miller, Sue. The Story of My Father. New York: Knopf, 2003.
Olney, James. Memory & Narrative: The Weave of Life-Writing. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1998.
Probst, Gerhard. “The Old Man and the Rain: Man in the Holocene.” In Perspectives on Max
Frisch, ed. Gerhard F. Probst and Jay F. Bodine. Lexington: University Press of Kentucky,
1982.
Ricoeur, Paul. Time and Narrative, 3 vols. Translated by Kathleen McLaughlin and David
Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1985.
RESPONSE
Alison Phinney
1
Alison Phinney, “Fluctuating Awareness and the Breakdown of the Illness Narrative in
Dementia.” Dementia: an International Journal of Social Research and Practice 1, no. 4 (2002):
329–44.
2
Dementia Advocacy and Support Network International www.dasninternational.org
(accessed September 30, 2005).
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 98–99
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
response 99
in a moving performance of the national anthem. “My arms to this day, can
just conduct,” he said. I have listened to a man explain how he is “in the old
habit of being a teacher,” watching over the person he has hired to build a
fence in his backyard, offering words of encouragement and guidance for the
work he can no longer do himself.3 These “old habits” of the lived body may
constitute something of a bridge across the “temporal rifts” created out of
memory loss, thus contributing to a sustained sense of self.
To say that we understand our lives through narrative is to say that we are
each in the process of living out a story that runs from our birth to our death,
and we are accountable for providing an intelligible account of the events
and experiences of that life to ourselves and to others.4 Dementia forces us to
recognize that intelligibility resides not only in language but in the habits and
practices of the lived body. Positioning narrative as an embodied activity will
enrich our ability to understand the experience of temporality and memory
loss in dementia.
3
Alison Phinney and Penny Brown, “Embodiment and the dialogical self in dementia”.
Symposium paper, Canadian Association of Gerontology Annual Scientific and Educational
Meeting, Victoria, BC, Canada, (October 2004).
4
Alistair MacIntyre, After Virtue (Notre Dame, IN: University of Notre Dame Press
1981).
CHAPTER FIVE
Marie-Pascale Huglo
Summary
In considering Georges Perec’s unfinished project Lieux, I reveal the relationship between
archives, memory and memory realms. First, I expose the frictions between time and memory
in a project which aimed to collect and to preserve present traces for future use. From there,
I show that even if Lieux is not homogeneous, it clearly refers to a lack of memory related to
Perec’s early childhood. I try to see how such a lack inscribes itself into the project. But Lieux
is not solely autobiographical. It highlights the instability of urban places and can thus be
connected to the disappearance of a memory milieu rooted in tradition and space. Taking
Perec’s Lieux as memory realms, I re-examine the strong opposition between records and
memory that governs the well-known reflections of Pierre Nora on Lieux de mémoire.
1
This paper is part of a research project on the Poetics of archives in contemporary
literature, funded by FQRSC (Fonds québécois de la recherche sur la société et la culture).
2
“Lettre au mathématicien Chakravarti”; “lettre à Maurice Nadeau”; “Lieux, un projet
(confié à Gérard Macé)”; “Les Lieux (notes sur un travail en cours)”; “Entretien avec
Georges Perec et Bernard Queysanne”. Perec mentions Lieux many times in his Entretiens et
conférences.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 101–114
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
102 marie-pascale huglo
3
Perec published five Real places : “Guettées”; “Vues d’Italie”; “La rue Vilin”; “Allées et
venues rue de l’Assomption”; “Stations Mabillon”. Philippe Lejeune posthumously published
a Memory place: “Vilin souvenir”. Andrew Leak translated four “Reals”: “Scene in Italy”;
“Glances at Gaîté”; “Comings and Goings rue de l’Assomption”; “Stances on Mabillon” into
English (AA files, nos 45–46).
4
Perec insisted on the fact that, after he had given up Lieux as a whole, he wanted to develop
each Lieu and to produce different types of publications: films, an Album (photographs and
poems), a radio program(“Georges Perec, Le Paris d’un joueur”, Entretiens et Conférences II,
130). Perec refers to (respectively): Les Lieux d’une fugue (1976); La Clôture (1976); Tentative
de description de choses vues au carrefour Mabillon le 19 mai 1978. He also relates the film
Un homme qui dort (1974) to Lieux (“Entretien avec Georges Perec et Bernard Queysanne”,
Entretiens et conférences I, 161). Of course, Tentative d’épuisement d’un lieu parisien extends
from Lieux as does W ou le souvenir d’enfance (see Philippe Lejeune, “La lettre hébraïque.
Un premier souvenir en sept versions”, La Mémoire et l’oblique, pp. 210–231). In fact, many
publications have to do with Lieux: Je me souviens brings forth collective memories and
transient manifestations. The same goes for La Vie mode d’emploi (Perec began to write it
after he had given up Lieux) and Récits d’Ellis Island. As we can see, Lieux is not a failure. It
is a matrix and figures among Perec numerous unfinished projects, which are part, per se, of
his œuvre.
georges perec’s “time bombs” 103
1. Planning
5
Andrew Leak, “Paris created and destroyed”, 26. The second table, reproduced in Philippe
Lejeune, identified the places by name (La Mémoire et l’oblique, 156).
104 marie-pascale huglo
6
“[It] would be enough to root an existence, to legitimate a memory, to establish a
tradition” (“Vilin souvenirs”, 136 [my translation]).
7
His father died in 1940. A Jew, his mother was sent to Auschwitz in 1943 and never
returned.
8
See Bernard Magné’s comments on the grid pattern:“Quelques pièces pour un blason, ou
les sept gestes de Perec”, 209–211.
9
Rue Vilin is also the metonymical site of Perec’s early childhood which, according to him,
also took place elsewhere in Paris (see “Vilin souvenirs”).
georges perec’s “time bombs” 105
in 1969 on l’Île Saint-Louis: the plan does not allow room for a new “place”;
there is no future opening for it. As Philippe Lejeune extensively shows, l’Île
Saint-Louis is related to S., with whom Perec was involved. The emergence of
Lieux goes along with the end of his relationship with S. Lejeune considers
that Lieux was initiated as a love memorial (La Mémoire et l’oblique, 146).
As far as the plan is concerned, the importance of 1969 and l’Île Saint-Louis
is stressed by the fact that it is there that time stops. Perec’s publications,
however, never put forward that place (and time). They focused instead on
Rue Vilin and early childhood, as if the immediate loss gave way to a more
remote loss that was extremely difficult to deal with. This move “backwards”
goes along with the psychoanalysis that Perec undertook in 1971. As we can
see, it is difficult to make a clear-cut division between Perec’s life and his
project. The cryptic autobiography involved in Lieux is partly responsible for
that, but the fact that Perec left his project uncompleted inevitably confronts
us with a work in progress where writing and “life” go together.10
The scopic impetus that governs Perec’s description of “real” places also
governs his planning. The square encompasses future and past projections
in its grid, which represents a dis-located memory as well as a suspended
future.
2. Recording
10
I chose to analyse Perec’s concrete “apparatus” (the grid, the records) and images (the
time bombs) in order to avoid immediate biographical reduction, and I connected Perec’s
work and life via a textual nexus: the recent publication of Entretiens et conférence enabled
me to establish a number of connections between the Œuvre itself (including films and
photographs), the project (Lieux) and what Perec said about it.
106 marie-pascale huglo
which ticket punchers used to . . . punch (!): nobody paid attention to that,
but after ticket punchers had disappeared, it became, said Perec, a memory.11
Therefore, the unnoticed present is a potential memory on which Perec
capitalized. As Philippe Lejeune puts it, Lieux was a Time-saving Bank.
The relationship between records and memory goes even further than
that. Perec attempted to neutralize his gaze and to produce records instead of
impressions, but since he systematically wrote down written traces scattered in
the streets (announcements, names of shops and films, slogans), the intimate
relationship between (external) traces and (internal) memory comes to the
forefront. To remember and to record are indeed two different operations, but
a strict separation between memory and records does not make sense. Their
intertwining is quite clear in Lieux: Perec remembered what he recorded (or
wrote down), and he recorded what already was a trace (letters or numbers)
or what would become a trace precisely because he had “recorded” it. His
“Reals” have to do both with the written and the visual, they are impressed
(or framed) by various forms of recording. The numerous descriptions and
enumerations that Perec made can be seen as a way to combine visibility and
scriptibility into records that have to do with the “memorizable.”
3. Differing
11
Georges Perec, “Le travail de la mémoire”, Entretiens et Conférences, vol. II, 48. In order
to become a memory that can be shared with others, the punched ticket has to be recorded.
Perec did it in his book Je me souviens (memory no 185), but before that, he did it in his film,
Un homme qui dort (1973) (see note 5). From Un homme qui dort to Je me souviens, a network
is in progress: it discreetly connects patterns which, however (apparently) insignificant, are
related to Perec’s life and places.
108 marie-pascale huglo
if they had been contaminated by what had already been recorded. Perec had
to forget what he had already written in order to be in accordance with each
“portion of time.”
The running of the experiment therefore depended on a simple device
which can be compared, according to Lejeune, to a banking operation. “Reals”
and “Memories” are like currency taken out of circulation, accumulated into
a savings account, and yielding profit over time. Such a comparison, however,
misses something crucial: in order to gain value, current time must change
into memory. An ordinary underground ticket is not of much value, and yet
an obsolete and useless underground ticket is valued as a memory of the past.
Memory of times (things, places) gone by is the value on which Perec bets, a
value that had to be secured because things (as well as memories) change or
disappear with time.
Perec expressed what he had in mind when he spoke of Time Bombs in
1981 at a conference “About description”: “I want to build my own time
Bombs,” he said.12 He explained that time bombs are ordinary objects, such
as a Coca-Cola bottle, that are “very very deeply buried” so that in a million
years, when Martians may discover them, they will be able to know that we
drank Coca-Cola and so on (Entretiens et conférences II, 236). It means that
what is over now, what is enclosed, sealed and buried, shall be disclosed later
as a testimony. To make your own time bombs also means that you produce
memories. Time traces had to be very deeply buried in order to be discovered
afterwards as good as new: the found past would be like a found treasure.
Of course, to plan to undertake this yourself, not in a million years but in
twelve years, also implies an acceleration of history which is, as Nora puts
it, a sign of our times (Les Lieux de mémoire, vol. I, XVII). According to
this, the time Bomb device is a deferred “explosion” of memory, a tentative
redemption of the past: Perec probably expected it to provoke an anamnesis
of what he already anticipated as his previous existence. Anamnesis is, in
fact, related to places themselves. In “La Ville mode d’emploi,” Perec explains
that he had almost completely forgotten that he ran away as a child until
he found himself in situ. Concrete details played the same role as Proust’s
madeleine (Entetiens et conférences II, 28).13 In Lieux, the fact that he noted
12
We can see here than the image of the time bomb was still active and productive after
Perec had given up Lieux.
13
The same goes for a journey he used to do twice a week by train as a child: it came back
later as he was once more on that train (“Entretien Georges Perec/Bernard Pous”, Entretiens
et conférences II, 191).
georges perec’s “time bombs” 109
down the price of the coffee he drank or recorded the slogans of the day into
his “Reals” indicates that he was well aware of the potential memory value of
these ephemeral manifestations. The time bombs enabled him to pin down
both the swift passage of time and its fixation in a lasting trace. Lieux is a
matrix of Perec’s poetics of transience, which is at the core of his sociological
approach of everyday life.
However, there is a dark side to this: what is “very deeply buried”
reminds us that grief is at stake. And what Perec’s scenario does not tell is
the catastrophe, the destruction of our world. It is in this way that the time
bomb device makes sense. We understand, then, that what is “very deeply
buried” is destruction itself, which already took place. Perec’s previous
existence is not ahead of him but behind him, buried on Rue Vilin, which
he did not quite remember, where he did not belong. We can say that Perec
was deeply divided: on the one hand, he was the Parisian astronaut who
built his own time bombs and dreamt of ageing; on the other hand, he was
the Martian who collected the remnants of an estranged world. It produced
unforeseen interferences between active memory (which Perec did not
plan) and preserved memory which had to be captured and frozen into time
capsules. After the first year, Perec found that the sealed envelopes did not
prevent him from remembering, and this greatly annoyed him (“Lieux, un
projet (confié à Gérard Macé)”). In the same way, whereas the astronaut’s eye
managed to catch transient manifestations, the supposedly neutral Martian’s
eye was insecure: Perec was obsessed by what he called his incapacity to look
correctly (“Lieux, un projet (confié à Gérard Macé)”). He was not certain to
observe the right things, he felt deprived of vision, disturbed by the fact that,
after the first record, he noted what had changed rather that what was there.14
The “monstrous” device that he planned was an attempt to bring together
past, present and future, but it somehow suffered from the lack of memory
it intended to replace and from the “interferences” and frictions inherent to
14
In fact, when Perec notices that it is difficult to “look again” at a place that he has already
seen, he is blind to the fact that his attention to changes is at work from the start, from the very
first records. The same goes for the interferences between descriptions and memories. One
good example of such “interferences” is the first record of Rue de la Gaîté (1 December 1969):
“Coming from the new Montparnasse Station, I arrive in rue de la Gaîté by avenue du Maine.
I was intending to stop in a café I’ve known for many years, ‘Aux Armes de Bretagne’ (fried
sausage, pinball machines) but it is closed, not, apparently, for refurbishment; it looks more as
if it has gone bankrupt or been sold (in anticipation of a radical transformation of the quartier
over the next few years: the new expressway will wipe out the whole of rue Vercingétorix).
I fall back instead on ‘Les Mousquetaires’ café, almost opposite, on avenue du Maine (I
came here one day in ’55 or ’56 to look for Jacques and his father who were playing billards).
The billiard tables are still here.” (“Glances at Gaîté”, 44).
110 marie-pascale huglo
the project. In that sense, the intimate destruction that Perec kept “deeply
buried” probably contributed to the weariness he developed over time, but it
also took part in another framing that came out of Lieux.
In order to understand this, it is important to realize that short-lived
manifestations have different implications when it comes to places. Unlike
prices, slogans, pedestrians or cars, places and buildings are supposed to
remain the same, they are supposed to last. When places become evanescent,
memory looses its landmarks; it is indeed dislocated. In this way, the image
of the time bombs reminds us that if such a dislocation goes unnoticed here
and now, it is destructive in the long term because it affects a stability which
memory needs. It is the very faculty of memory that is at stake here. What
Perec accumulated into his envelopes were not only ephemeral signs but also
signs of destruction: his Parisian places did not age; they changed; they were
(and still are) renovated: “out with the old in with the new!” (Andrew Leak,
“Paris created and destroyed,” 28). What he recorded was the demolition of
old buildings. In “Glances at Gaîté,” for example, Perec anticipates the “radical
transformation” of the neighborhood (see note 14). Rue Vilin is particularly
exemplary of that: it began to interest him once he learned that it was doomed
for destruction, as if the planned demolition of that particular street and the
emergence of Lieux went hand-in-hand. Remarkably enough, Perec writes
that the place will blow up [sautera] like a bomb (“Vilin souvenirs,”135).
Along with the fixation of mobile and transient scenes, Lieux attempted to
preserve a trace of vanishing places and to record the visible signs of a double
disappearance: that of Parisian places and buildings and that of memory
rooted in space and transmission.
Conclusion
A close reading of the grid, of the time-bomb and of the records that
Perec imagined and produced enables us to expose the complexity of the
relationship between time and memory in Lieux. If indeed Perec aimed to
“secure” future memories, the various temporal layers of each of the twelve
Parisian places that he intended to archive one by one did not fully meet the
archaeological model which apparently inspired him. He wanted to preserve
the (future) memories of a few Parisian places from alteration and destruction,
but the very organization of the project was haunted and disturbed by “very
deeply buried” memories. The urge to freeze time, to plan, to treasure, and
to protect has to do with a grievous event which occurred in early childhood
but never took place: the loss of Perec’s mother was impossible to localize.
georges perec’s “time bombs” 111
Even the fact that Perec was behind schedule can be read as the repetition
of an endless delay surrounding his mother’s death, a delay that the time-
bomb device reproduced but also attempted to unbury. To archive and to
record the signs of destruction of old Parisian places can thus be understood
as an attempt to give a place to a destruction that was out of place, but it
would be a simplification to see Lieux as a mere product of a traumatic past.
The growing importance of rue Vilin, during the writing of Lieux and after
Perec had abandoned it,15 enables us to see that it was indeed crucial, but the
conflicting forces at work that I pointed out also make it clear that there was
more than one time bomb involved in the project. One of them is closely
related to time and memory: Lieux managed to produce what “exploded”
later as lieux de mémoires (or memory realms) and are related to the loss of
collective memory.
Pierre Nora shows that the multiplication and diversification of archives
is related to the decline of a memory milieu. Along with the disappearance
of a rural society rooted in space and tradition, along with the accelerated
mobility of people and the instability of places, memory loses ground to
more and more sophisticated recording devices. Memory as a milieu used
to give rhythm and continuity to everyday life, and Perec’s project coincides
with the decline of a collective and spontaneous memory. In fact, Lieux failed
to replace that milieu, but it produced Lieux de mémoire, which are kinds of
sacred Islands isolated from the rest, where every single little thing, however
trivial, is supposed to convey meaning (Pierre Nora, Les Lieux de mémoire,
vol. I, XLI). Perec’s records produce a sense of the past and of the common
place. As Nora puts it, the production of lieux de mémoire is an answer to the
acceleration of history (which complicates the disappearance of a past which
is still part of our personal experience) and to a sense of continuity rooted
in space (which, however “mobile” we might be, we basically need). To that
extent, Perec’s attention to Parisian places and to their fast transformation
(destruction) can be seen as part of our post-war cultural and historical
landscape. However, his lieux de mémoire are not produced in spite of
archives and records: they are archives and records. As such, rue Vilin is again
exemplary: it has been almost erased from (the map of ) Paris, it has almost
completely disappeared, but Perec’s photographs and texts transformed it
15
Cf. “La rue Vilin”; La Clôture; W. ou le souvenir d’enfance; Un homme qui dort (the film)
(the last image of this film is an image of Paris and of rue Vilin). In Récits d’Ellis Island (the
film) the photograph of his mother’s house on rue Vilin can be seen among others in the
album that Perec glances through . . .
112 marie-pascale huglo
into a memory realm which can now be part of our memory even if we never
lived or went there.
Perec is sensitive both to the loss of traditional memory (mediated by
the family) and profoundly curious about the creative powers of recording
media. After he had given up Lieux, he chose to concentrate on each place
through different recording media. It enabled him to relate each memory
realm to a form of description: “The experiment stopped in 1975, and has
been taken up and continued by other sorts of descriptions: poetic and
photographic (La Clôture, about rue Vilin), cinematographic (“Les Lieux
d’une fugue,” about Franklin Roosevelt), radiophonic (about Mabillon, in
progress; Georges Perec, “Scene in Italie.” 34). In La Clôture, rue Vilin is
photographed in black and white, silent, deserted and still (“as if,” writes
Pierre Getzler, “the space they show is already dead, as if a neutron bomb had
fallen on the city [. . .]”),16 whereas carrefour and Mabillon is noisy, lively and
colourful. There is no separation, in his memory realms, between media and
memory. The different framings of parisian places involve different types of
memory. The materiality of the various time traces (or records) is not simply
taking the place of a more or less idealized spontaneous memory; it gives
new contour to the “memorizable,” which can be, in turn, internalized and
transformed (that is, memorized). Contrasting with Nora’s longing for a lost
collective form of life, Perec (however nostalgic) shows that different arts of
memories go along with various recording techniques. In fact, techniques
are part of the so called “spontaneous” memory: songs, for example, display
repetititive patterns that enable us to remember them. Furthermore, recorded
images, slogans and old songs that we know by heart are, more often than
not, part of our individual and collective memory. So if records tend indeed
to supplant memory, they also transform and diversify it. The question of
whether we can digest our countless records is left open, but Perec’s “failure”
and what came out of it gives us a hint of the potentiality of records as far as
memory is concerned.
This is perhaps what emerged after Lieux. Perec’s persistent experimenta-
tion with different “sorts of description” brings the relationship between
memory and image to the forefront. Even if the “visual proof ” is most
16
Jean-Charles Depaule & Pierre Getzler, “A City in Words and Numbers”, 124 (my
emphasis). Getzler adds that Georges Perec asked Chistine Lipinska—who photographed rue
Vilin for La Clôture, “to photograph front on” and also asked him to take the façades “where
the openings had been bricked up”. Getzler did not want to to do it this way, so that “he could
imagine the movement of the city” (Ibid., 124 and 119).
georges perec’s “time bombs” 113
References
SEEKING IN SUMATRA
Some late news about time. Well, I’m late with it.
The University of Oxford awarded an Honorary Degree of Doctor of
Science to Professor Ahmed Zewail in 2004. Professor Zewail has divided
up Time—and I quote—“into units so tiny that while we are pronouncing a
single letter, a million billion units have elapsed.” These are femto seconds. I
must try and write a short story about that—as short as possible.
In the 2004 tennis tournaments in Wimbledon, the BBC were using a
new TV camera, the Typhoon. The Typhoon takes 5000 frames per minute.
So one can study exactly the techniques of players.
Both these achievements are awesome. However, I am going to talk about
a larger slice of time—thirty years, no less.
English poetry has always been involved with time. The most famous
example is probably Andrew Marvell’s line “Had we but world enough and
time,” the opening of a poem that goes on to extol whole epochs. Thomas
Hardy uses time for its pathetic qualities, for example in “She to Him”:
“When you shall see me in the toils of time, / My lauded beauties carried off
from me [. . .],” C. Day Lewis, once poet laureate, celebrates the pleasures of
time:
Now the full-throated daffodils,
Those trumpeters of spring,
Call Resurrection from the ground,
And bid the year be king!
What were once the nation’s two favorite poems, in the days when people
enjoyed poetry that rhymed, are time-bound: “The curfew tolls the knell of
parting day,” which begins Thomas Gray’s “Elegy in a Country Churchyard,”
and, at the other end of the day
Awake! For morning in the bowl of night
Hath flung the stone that put the stars to flight.
And lo! the Hunter of the East hath caught
The Sultan’s turret in a noose of light.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 115–121
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
116 brian aldiss o.b.e.
Time must be expressed because it’s in our bones. And our intellects. I have
always expressed it in novel form.
I am no philosopher. I am a story-teller. It happens that I have a true story
embedded in historic time and geography. It takes place in what some would
call “my time,” although I make no proprietorial claims for it.
By the seventies, I had become moderately prosperous, certainly in
comparison with the naive youth from whom I had developed, that youth in
World War II who took the King’s shilling and was posted to the East to serve
his country. By the seventies, my books were published, first in hardcover,
and then, when published in paperback, could be bought in Sydney, Samoa,
Singapore and Sarajevo, as well as San Francisco (if nowhere else . . .).
In 1978, I took a week’s package tour from Singapore to Sumatra.
Sumatra!—Once I had lived there for a year, in my army days. I had never
expected to be able to visit it again; it lay like a dream at the back of my
mind. Off I went. Sumatra is speared by the equator like a sausage on a
skewer. My novel set in Sumatra, A Rude Awakening, had just been published.
I was curious to see how the country had changed in thirty years. And,
although I was happily married, I hoped to revisit the scene of an old love
affair.
I was to discover that history is fossilized time.
In August 1945, the atomic bombs had been dropped on Hiroshima and
Nagasaki, Japan had surrendered, peace was in the offing. If it was end of
an epoch for Japan, so it was—although few of us realized it—for both the
British Empire and the Dutch Empire in the East. Those two great galleons
were sinking fast in the seas of time—and, as it happened, were inextricably
locked together. They and we were victims of history. History is what happens
when you are not looking.
In November of that momentous year, 1945, the 26th Indian Division
arrived by ship in Sumatra. Our mission was three-fold: to return the
occupying Japanese army to their homeland, to release from prison camps
the Dutch and other nationalities imprisoned there, and to reinstate the
Dutch in authority. When we landed, how green the country seemed, how
well-dressed the people, how friendly—all this in contrast to the India we
had left behind.
But time was against us. Sumatra was no longer part of the N.E.I.—the
Netherlands East Indies: it had become, under Soekarno, part of Indonesia,
a sovereign power, and the people longed for freedom—the freedom to go to
hell in a bucket in their own way.
As long as the British Army went about disarming and shipping the Japanese
home, all was well. As soon as we welcomed in the first Dutch contingent,
seeking in sumatra 117
the natives started firing at us. The situation resulted in deadlock. We were
too few in number to be effective. In the end, we gave up and went home.
In 1978—thirty years later—I flew in to Medan airport. When I had
flown out in 1946, the airport had been in the wilds, outside Medan, the
capital. Now it was surrounded by squalid suburbs.
Uncomfortable as the political situation was in 1945 and 46, I was able to
better my position. Medan was enjoyable and semi-functional. There were
restaurants, shops, clubs and two operating cinemas. One cinema was the
Deli, named after the local river, forbidden to troops, one, the Rex, open
to troops and showing old films which had been in storage for a long time.
The Hollywood films of the thirties carried Dutch subtitles and Chinese
side-titles, so that half the screen was covered by writing. The films belonged
in another time-frame, with stars like Wallace Beery and Jean Harlow still
young. They spoke of a distant epoch, but they were something to watch,
fairy tales of the past.
One evening, as we were all marching out after the show, a group of
civilians standing by spoke up and asked, “How was the film this evening?”
It happened that of all those troops, the question was addressed to me as I
passed. I stopped to talk.
So I became acquainted with some friendly Chinese families. The ladies of
one group had been educated at Hong Kong University and spoke excellent
English. I saw some of them most days, I ate with them in the evening, I took
the ladies shopping in my Jeep, and I escorted them to the cinema. I fell in
love with one of those ladies and she with me. She had exquisite manners and
looked exquisite. Was exquisite.
We would sit outside her house at night—those warm starry nights! That
humble, tumbledown town! Just down the street, guitars were playing where
the Ambonese lived. The sateh man would come along with his mobile
wooden kitchen and serve us soup and sateh on sticks. I wished for nothing
better. The agreeable lady would smile at me and dream of distant London.
By 1978, Singapore, like Indonesia, had become an independent country.
But Singapore flourished as an entrepreneurial port, bolstered by the fact
that English was its official language for the diverse nationalities living there.
In Singapore, the sateh were big and fat and sizzling with peanut sauce.
Because I had some artistic talent, I got the job in 1946 of looking after
a theatre—a thatched barn, in effect. I decorated it with a series of screens
depicting local life. Sunsets and dancing girls. We got a band together, held
dances there (local lady friends invited), musical evenings and film shows.
The barn became a social centre, open every evening. I had private quarters
there, with a bed, and two sepoys to do all the hard work for me.
118 brian aldiss o.b.e.
family and I sat and talked about freedom—Merdeka!—and the way times
changed. I said I had lived in an upper room. They were excited. They showed
me upstairs. But hadn’t the stairs run the other way? However, I thought I
recognized the landing, with a window at the end of it. So that had been my
room, there! Still misgivings . . . We entered. Had it indeed been here that,
thirty years earlier, a delectable Chinese lady had crossed the floor, put her
arms about my neck, and kissed me?—The opening shot of an intense love
affair?
Ah, but this room had no balcony. Mine had had one. But balconies in
the tropics tend to fall off like fruit from a twig . They tend to rot like over-
ripe fruit. All the same . . . “Was this your very room?” they asked, eagerly in
chorus, these pleasant people. I had not the heart to disappoint them.
“Yes,” I said. “My very room.”
Never be a time-traveller. To this day I cannot tell if I had managed to
work my way back through the interstices of time to where that saving idyll
had blossomed.
On the day following, I tried to find her house, nearby, where Dinah had
once lived. I walked and walked in the heat, seeking my way through a maze
of streets. Here was a concrete analogy of our life, as we wend our allotted
path through unknown circumstance.
I came at last on a familiar curved stucco wall. Behind the wall, a cinema,
the Deli Cinema!—Unmistakable! Much as it had been, thirty years back.
Despite all other changes, the Deli was still operating. Its posters announced
the same kind of fantasy horror it had screened in the old days: The Night of
the Rivers of Blood, Shark Raiders of the Pacific, Queen of the Python Men.
Some things at least had not changed in thirty years: in particular, a human
desire to be amazed, to fantasize—as I myself was pursuing a fantasy.
Indeed, it seems that human brains are built better equipped for fantasy
than intellect, for Tolkien rather than Aristotle, for imagination rather than
logic. How painful are the years of education for most children, as we school
them from dreamtime into real time, from the world of play to fish-cold
reality.
As far as I know, official histories make no reference to that old British
campaign in Sumatra. One hopes our occupation of Iraq will not be as long
or as fruitless. Certainly I find no mention of the battle where British, Indian
and Japanese troops were united in a fight against the Extremists, as indeed
they did also in neighboring Java.
No trace is left of our brief regime in that tropical island. No memorials
on land, nothing in the history books. The soldiers who were involved have
grown old, and memories fade. One solitary account of our occupation of
seeking in sumatra 121
INVENTING
PREFACE TO SECTION II
INVENTING
Paul Harris
1
Henri Bergson, Creative Evolution (London: MacMillan, 1911), p. 361.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 125–128
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
126 paul harris
of lists—inscription was often used to store records and data that exceeded
the mnemonic capacities of individuals. A stirring evolutionary and historical
account of memory along these lines is presented by Merlin Donald in The
Origins of the Modern Mind. Donald argues that human brains function
within a larger “cognitive architecture,” that encompasses human minds, the
representational systems they develop, and the tools through which such
systems are deployed. He concludes that, “We act in cognitive collectivities,
in symbiosis with external memory systems. As we develop new external
symbolic configurations and modalities, we reconfigure our own mental
architecture in nontrivial ways.”2 In other words, time, mind and memory are
strongly intertwined: emerging mnemonic tools recursively impact the ways
in which we learn and think, which in turn modifies brain development, and
so on in entangled loops.
The essays in this section of Time and Memory investigate different ways
in which inventing has entered into human memory. Mary Schmelzer revisits
the history and practices of the memory palace, one of the most renowned and
fascinating of mnemonic inventions. Rather than emphasizing their power to
help a person store and retrieve information, however, Schmelzer demonstrates
how memory palaces ultimately reveal the temporal contingencies that
intervene in mnemonic practice, seen in “the constructedness, selectivity,
and interpretive status of memory.” She then goes on to explore how
contemporary theoretical views of memory and language shed light on
the dynamics of memory’s selective and preferential predilections. Heike
Klippel’s essay examines how psychological writings on memory in the early
20th century yield productive terms in which to understand new mnemonic
formations emerging in conjunction with the early cinema of the period. The
cinema in fact substantially effected human perceptions and conceptions
of time in many complex ways.3 Klippel resuscitates the work of Bergson
and Freud’s contemporary August Gallinger, who described the quality of
“self-evidence” inherent in the process of remembrance, in which the Ego
experiences itself without differentiating between past and present. Klippel
compares the experience of self-evidence, which entails “the presence of a
past that as such has never been real and a sensual shimmer that owes its
2
Merlin Donald, The Origins of the Modern Mind: Three Stages in the Evolution of Culture
and Cognition (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1991), p. 382.
3
For a thorough treatment of this issue, see Mary Ann Doane, The Emergence of Cinematic
Time: Modernity, Contingency, the Archive (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
2002).
inventing 127
4
Theodor W. Adorno, “Cultural Criticism and Society,” in Prisms, trans. Samuel and
Shierry Weber (Camb. Mass.: MIT Press, 1967), p. 19.
128 paul harris
Mary Schmelzer
Summary
Renaissance memory devices, the treasure house that Erasmus adumbrates in de Copia the
memory palace that Matteo Ricci constructed as a Jesuit missionary in China, the extensive
iconography of Renaissance portraiture or even Ignatian Spiritual Exercises, mark the period’s
keen interest in holding on to memories over time.
Erasmus and Ricci both understand the instability and complexity of memory over time
and their mnemonic devices seek to stabilize memory on one hand, but to free it from stasis
and calcification over time. No strict constructionists they! The path of their desire shifts the
objects in the memory palace or treasure house over time. Some once honored objects are sent
off to the attic to be held onto, but to be used less often and to be sometimes forgotten. Desire
and memory shift over time.
What interests me most about Renaissance construction of memory is the temporal space
in which an item is prepared for the palace, the instant in which a decision is made about the
mnemonic assignment of a place in a memory system. This moment signifies more than a
curious practice born of a need of a specific time. I propose it as a model for the construction
of all memory. The question I pose, “What happens every moment that memory is being
constructed in a liminal temporal space over-determined by conscious and unconscious desire
that is itself constucted by every moment that has preceded it?”
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 129–143
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
130 mary schmelzer
only the possibility of “knowing about” the “The Things of the World,” to use
Michel Foucault’s chapter title from The Order of Things.1
Where Erasmus practiced the mnemonic of the notebook and encouraged
students to construct a figurative treasure house of apt citation to be re-
deployed performatively in discrete circumstances, Matteo Ricci chose the
imaginative construction of a virtual memory palace as a way of domesticating
and managing at least that aspect of individual interiority. These palaces,
in their long history from the Greeks to the late Renaissance, relied on
connecting especially striking objects, with a whole constellation of ideas
that the artifact would embody and recall. For example, blind justice holds
balance scales and figures forth the complexities of the virtue. Moreover,
in a more carefully delineated object every fold of a robe, every ornament,
and every physical attribute could be used as a mnemonic. That way, vast
quantities of information might be stored in a single image.
This object was then placed in an architectural space that could be derived
from something familiar like famous buildings in a city or a real street or
neighborhood; or the area could be an imaginative amalgam of places that
would produce a structure that facilitated the storage of memory images.
Such places were to be quiet, uncrowded, and of appropriate amplitude,
lighting and differentiation. The rooms of a memory palace should not be
especially similar one to the other. Each object was situated relationally
with all the others so that they formed a chain of signification. If a viewer
recognized Justice in one corner of a room, she might more easily recognize
Fortitude in the next chosen space. Often, the architectural spaces held ideas
about a single subject. The rules of navigation might best be remembered
by filling a sailing ship with countless nautical objects. A church might be
furnished with statues, stained glass, and paintings that served as memory
prompts. Elaborate memory constructions might include many buildings,
each assigned to a discrete area of inquiry. Objects in the memory palace
could be moved around as their significance increased or diminished. Some
objects were sent to an attic for storage. Other rooms might be sealed off as
their usefulness became marginalized.
1
Michel Foucault, The Order of Things: An Archeology of the Human Science (New York:
Vintage Books, 1973). Two other works helped me to understand the importance of Erasmiam
rhetorical practice in a world that questioned the availability of truth in the episteme of the
English Renaissance. I recommend them both: Terrance Cave’s The Cornucopian Text (Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1979) as well as Marion Trousdale’s Shakespeare and the Rhetoricians
(London: Scholar’s Press, 1982).
132 mary schmelzer
2
Francis Yates has written the quintessential text on the history and use of memory
practice in The Art of Memory (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1966), 2. More recent
and important explorations of the subject have been done by Mary Carruthers in The Book of
Memory, A Study of Memory in Medieval Culture (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1991), and by William Engel in two valuable works: Mapping Mortality: The Persistence of
Memory and Melancholy in Early Modern England (Amherst: University of Massachusetts
Press, 1995), and Death and Drama in Renaissance England (Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2003).
furnishing a memory palace 133
Places are chosen and marked with the utmost possible variety, as a spacious
house divided into a number of rooms. Everything of note therein is diligently
imprinted on the mind, in order that thought may be able to run through all
parts without let or hindrance. The first task is to secure that there shall be
no difficulty in running through these, for that memory must be firmly fixed
which helps another memory. Then what has been written down [Erasmian
treasuries] or thought of [Riccian palaces], is noted by a sign to remind of it.
The sign may be drawn from a whole ‘thing’, as navigation or warfare, or from
some ’word’; for what is slipping from memory is recovered by the admonition
of a single word. However let us suppose that the sign is drawn from navigation,
as, for instance, and anchor; or from warfare as, for example, a weapon. These
signs are then arranged as follows. The first notion is placed, as it were, in the
forecourt; the second let us say in the atrium; the remainder are placed in order
all around the impluvium, and committed not only to bedrooms and parlours,
but even to statues and the like. This is done when it is required to revise the
memory, one begins from the first place to run through all, demanding what
has been entrusted to them, of which one will be reminded by the image. Thus,
however numerous are the particulars which it is required to remember, all are
linked one to another as in a chorus nor can what follows wander far from what
has gone before to which it is joined, only the preliminary labor of learning
being required.
What I have spoken of as being done in a house can also be done in public
dwellings, or on a long journey or going through a city with or without pictures
(22–23).
Here, it seems to me, Quintillian obscures as much as he enlightens. At the
same time, he uncovers notions about the status of memory that help us
with the project at hand, connecting the temporalized memory construction
of mnemonic practice with contemporary discursive and psychoanalytic
understanding of memory.
Whether one is reading Roman Quintillian or Renaissance Matteo
Ricci, someone who shares my theoretical position will not fail to be
struck with qualities that were, perhaps, of little interest to either of them.
Most importantly, the method uncovers the constructedness, selectivity,
and interpretive status of memory. An architectural space is entered by its
creator who then places a mnemonic object in it, an anchor, in the bow of a
sailing vessel, for example. When that object is returned to, it will serve as a
reminder of what one needs to know to place an anchor properly precisely
because it is properly placed and weighted in the memory image. In addition,
a person could use the sailboat figuratively as a life journey or a ship of state
and understand that anchor from an entirely different position. No two ships
embody the same set of ideas. One ship can be read from many places.
Memory, furthermore, is as selective as it is constructed. Memory palaces
serve functional utility. What is deemed un or less important may be discarded.
134 mary schmelzer
3
John Willis wrote on the significance of forgetting in Mnemonica; sive Ars Reminiscendi
(London, 1618), in English: Mnemonicas or The Art of Memory (London: Leonard Sowersby,
1661). Grant Williams use of Willis in “Introduction: Sites of Forgetting in Early Modern
English Culture,” coauthored With Christopher Ivec , in Forgetting in Early Modern English
Literature and Culture: Lethe’s Legacies, edited by Williams and Ivic (London: Routledge,
2004), provides an inventive model for thinking about the connection between remembering
and forgetting.
furnishing a memory palace 135
memory image for war, for example, he proceeds to examine the stormy
wars in Italy at the time of Ricci’s birth in 1552. He performs mnemonic
technique as he explains it and in so doing produces a rich history of Counter
Reformation Europe and sixteenth century China.4
In 1582, during the Ming dynasty, the Jesuit Matteo Ricci arrived in China
where he was to spend almost thirty years introducing the Christian faith
and Western thought to scholars, rulers, and literati, a highly sophisticated,
albeit alien, society, one in which he thrived. He learned Chinese, but was
limited in the ways he could bring the Gospel message without a Bible in
that language. To overcome that difficulty he conceived of two strategies:
using Chinese ideographs to construct a memory palace in his 1596 draft
of The Treatise on Mnemonic Arts and later working with printer Cheng
Dayue (1606) publishing an Ink Garden with illustrations of Bible passages
accompanied by brief explanations of their content.
Ricci’s use of sense-memory devices is especially apposite for a Jesuit since
Ignatius of Loyola the order’s founder saw the vivid restructuring of memory
as vital to spiritual training. Spence says, “In order that his followers might
live the biblical narrative in all its force, Ignatius instructed them to apply
their five senses to those scriptural passages that they were contemplating”
(15). Here, Ignatius follows the lead of Medieval Dominicans who believed
that if a memory is to be effective, it must be must be firmly imprinted . The
firmest impressions were vividly sensual even to the point of being shocking;
the soul must be moved for memory to be effective (Yates, 65).
Ricci’s desire to move souls colored every decision he made about imbuing
an object with meaning. To serve his purpose he engaged in conscious acts of
restructuring the physical aspect of an object in order that he might redact its
meaning. The first image in Spence’s study, The Warriors (Fig. 1), shows the
Chinese ideograph for war, pronounced wu.
To prepare it for placement in the reception hall of his memory palace, Ricci
divided it into two separate ideographs one for spear, and another that carried
with it a sense of “to stop” or “to prevent.” This second sign is under the left
arm of the overreaching image of the weapon. Ricci then anthropomorphizes
each into warriors, the larger with a spear ready to strike, the smaller grasping
at the spear trying to save himself from falling victim to it. Each is given facial
expression, dress, and myriad qualities that distinguishes each from the other,
as well as suggesting aspects of both warriors. In so doing Ricci encourages
4
Jonathon Spence, The Memory Palace of Matteo Ricci (New York: Penguin Books,
1984).
136 mary schmelzer
his audience to internalize a concept of war that also holds out a possibility
of peace. Spence notes that in this mnemonic, Ricci lights upon a dichotomy
that resonates both Christian and Chinese intellectual and moral positions:
In dividing the ideograph in this fashion Ricci follows—whether wittingly or
not—a tradition among Chinese scholars reaching back almost two millenia, a
tradition that allowed one to see buried inside the word for war, the possibilities,
however frail, for peace (24).
We need to pay attention to the temporal complexity of the construction of
this mnemonic. In linear time Ricci analyzes an image, decides how it can best
serve his needs, divides it into two parts, adorns each part with mnemonically
helpful particulars, carefully places it in his memory palace, decides how it
will be lit and approached, and how it will connect with other objects placed
in close proximity. While it is not possible to say how much time Ricci spent
thinking about this image or the other images no longer available to us, that
time, nonetheless, is more than instantaneous. This memory is constructed
in a measurable time that negotiates the space between two moments: the
time of the event and the time of its encoding into memory.
The second image from what remains of the Memory Treatise might shed
more light on Ricci’s work. This ideograph, yao, (Fig. 2), is elusive. It can
mean something desired, needed or important.
Ricci in his 1605 Fundamental Christian Teachings uses the image to
translate the word “fundamental.” The journey of this ideograph points to the
connection between the meaning of a memory and the desire and discursive
circumstances of the rememberer.
Again Ricci divides the image, this time in half horizontally. The top half
means west and its pronunciation xi calls up the ancient Western Chinese
kingdom, Xixia. The lower half is woman. The image to be stored up then
furnishing a memory palace 137
becomes a woman from the west with an exotic look in the “vivid dress, the
felt boots, the braided hair common to that region” (Spence, 95). Most of
the Eastern Chinese would recognize her as Muslim, a huihui. Ricci knows
that Jews and Christians were designated huihui as well, and connects this
mnemonic of the exotic tribeswoman from the west with fundamental
beliefs of Islam, Judaism, and Christianity. One huihui creates a multiplicity
of potential explorations for the differences between Eastern and Western
spiritual practice. Ricci places this image in the northeast corner of the
reception hall close enough to the two warriors so that their stories can
inform each other where, as Spence says, “She will stay . . . in the quiet light
that suffuses the memory palace for as long as he chooses to leave her” (96).
In the ideographs Ricci gave new sense impact to traditional Chinese
images; the Ink Garden illustrations help with remembering not so much the
stories from the Gospels as the spiritual lessons Ricci wrote to accompany each
picture. The actual depiction in the print matters less than the interpretation.
This memory work itself confirms the disconnection between the memory
of a thing and the thing itself as it filters through the screens of mnemonic
encoding, confirming the distance between an item in a memory palace and
its always absent dimensional reality. So far the images we have looked at
underscore the temporal deferral of meaning in memory. In this next drawing
we see both elements of Derridean differance.
This picture, The Apostle in the Waves, a drawing now in the public domain,
(Fig. 3) is complicated on a number of levels.
The image itself is problematic in a universe embattled over subtle
doctrinal distinctions as was Ricci’s at the time. It claims to depict that story
in Matthew’s Gospel in which Christ walks on water. Ricci would have liked
to have had Cheng Dayue engrave that image, but at the time that Cheng
138 mary schmelzer
agreed to work with Ricci on the project, the Jesuit had lent his copy of
Jeronimo Nadal’s Images of Christ to another missionary, to use as a means of
evangelization. Ricci wrote in 1605:
This book is of even greater use than the Bible in the sense that while we are in
the middle of talking we can also place right in front of their eyes things that
with words alone we would not be able to make clear (Spence, 62).
He used instead an illustration from the eight volume Plantin polyglot Bible
that had just arrived in China. In it Christ is standing firmly on the shore.
This image was actually an illustration of Christ appearing to his disciples
after the Resurrection, with the stigmata of Crucifixion removed from the
extended right arm. The real of the illustration changes signification at the
behest of the desire of the user. Ricci’s accompanying text suited his own
views of what he thought might appeal to the Chinese. The last sentence of
this story in Matthew says, “Truly you are the Son of God.” Ricci focuses on
the story as a means of comprehending the way one lives virtuously:
A man who has strong faith in the Way can walk on the yielding water as if on
solid rock, but if he goes back to doubting, then the water will go back to its
true nature and how can he stay brave? (Ricci in Spence, 60)
The wrong picture did the right work by helping him inculcate a habit of
Christian spirituality to a community whose belief system focused more
on moral practice than belief, the huihui of the cross made amenable to the
fundamental belief of Confucianism, Taoism, and Buddhism.
While Ricci is laboring in China, the intellectual climate in Europe is
changing rapidly and the value of mnemonic technique is waning. In the
early moments of The Anatomy of Melancholy, Robert Burton says, “there
is no end of writing of books” (I, 22) and again, “who can read them? As
already we shall have a vast chaos and confusion of books, we are oppressed
with them . . .” (I, 24).5 This 1620 manuscript marks the end of the wide use
of mnemonic technique, especially the Erasmian program based as it was
on a vast reading program, but I think that much the same case might be
made for the memory palace with its need for ever-expanding buildings to
house exponentially increasing information. The nascent episteme of the
Age of Reason regards memory as immediate and erases, for the most part,
the importance, or even the existence of, a temporal space between a thing
and its inclusion in memory. Intellectual history has little to say about the
5
Robert Burton, The Anatomy of Melancholy, edited by Holbrook Jackson, 3 volumes
(London: Everyman’s Library, 1932).
140 mary schmelzer
memory palace after the early sixteenth century. It itself has been placed in
an attic for historical curiosities.
But I argue that the palace does not completely crumble as history might
conjecture; rather it has migrated to the unconscious. What Renaissance
rhetoricians and teachers did consciously over minutes, hours, sometimes
weeks, happens instantaneously in the unconscious. In psychoanalytic
practice the discursive lapsus of diurnal time provide entrances into its barred
signification. That same bar creates a paradigmatic differance, and renders all
unconscious memory different and deferred from any actual or real moment.
In classic memory work, unconscious processes are invisible, as they often
still are.
We still remember the mnemonics that get us through board examinations,
and use repetition and visual or aural images to help us recall a name or a
phone number. My cell number is mnemonically a picture of a leanish man
who ate for one and worked for seven sick ones. In all it seems to come to
little as a subject for serious analysis, but there is nothing simple about the
simplest memory practice. What I cannot say easily is why I have chanced
upon this set of images to recall the sounds of the numbers. And that matters.
Our unconscious memory work is denser and more elusive than the earlier
practices to which I suggest it bears much correspondence; this is especially
true of the temporal aspect of memory.
Unconscious time bears little relation to the ticking of our watches, but that
is not to say that it is atemporal. The time of memory functions constantly, not
in discrete, linearly designated interstices, but always in its own synchronic
dimension. Another time. By using the insights inherent in classical memory
practice we might uncover some of its staggering complexity.
Jacques Lacan says that the unconscious is constructed like a language; the
lingustic model he has in mind is Ferdinand de Saurrure’s that sees all meaning
as relational. The value of a sign, single word, or even a letter is empty until it
is contextualized for each is arbitrary and unstable on its own:
In the end, the principle it comes down to is the fundamental principle of the
arbitrariness of the sign. It is only through the differences between signs that
it will be possible to give them a function, a value. In language there are only
differences. Even more importantly: a difference generally implies positive
terms between which the difference is set up; but in language there are only
differences without positive terms. . . . language has neither ideas nor sounds that
existed before the linguistic system.6
6
Ferdinand de Saussure, A Course in General Linguistics, edited by Charles Bally and
Albert Sachehlaye in collaboration with Albert Heidinger, translated by Wade Baskin (New
York, McGraw Hill, 1959), 120.
furnishing a memory palace 141
7
It is often difficult to know where to begin with Lacan. Most theorists know of the
mirror stage and have read some seminars. If your interest is clinical I recommend The Four
Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis, edited by Jacques-Alain Miller, translated by Alan
Sheridan (New York: Norton, 1977), as a fecund starting point.
furnishing a memory palace 143
8
The Complete Introductory Lectures (New York: Norton, 1966), 538.
9
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1990, 446.
I would like to thank Frances Chen, a tenth grade student at the Agnes Irwin School, for
her graceful rendering of the Chinese ideographs that appear in this essay.
CHAPTER EIGHT
Heike Klippel
Summary
In the following essay I will discuss a certain characteristic of human memory, namely its
self-evidence, as it has been theorized at the turn of the 20th century. I will then relate this
discussion to the cinema in order to trace a quality of filmic images which can be considered
analogous to the self-evidence of memories so often experienced when we remember. When
speaking of the self-evidence inherent in memory, I refer to the truth of memories as it is
subjectively perceived, regardless of whether they can be proven or not. The concept of
self-evidence describes an experience that itself belongs to and emerges from the non- or
pre-conceptual realm because such a spontaneous insight does not need a reason for how
it came about. A phenomenon considered self-evident may have good reasons, but it also
does without them because what is commonly called “self-evident” are such matters that
are immediately obvious and experiences whose truth appears to be beyond doubt. When
speaking of the self-evidence of cinematic images, I do not want to imply that the content and
intended meaning of films is in itself obvious. Rather, I would like to address an intensity of
subjective film perception as it emerges from the direct relation between the spectator and
what is seen on screen. This relation allows for the cognition of a ‘reality’ which cannot be
logically deduced, but which nonetheless does not necessarily escape objectification. Whether
or not this realization coincides with the communicative intentions of a film is as irrelevant as
is the factuality of experience with regard to the self-evidence of memories.
The attempt to present, by means of language, a phenomenon that itself escapes logical
conceptualization carries certain risks which are mirrored in the form of this essay.
Argumentation and reasoning collide with a subject that attempts to escape these forms
of mastery. The self-evidence of cinematic images as well as of memory images is based
on liveliness and plasticity, and their powers of persuasion are always also a seduction. With-
out rationalizing it away, this moment of seduction shall be taken seriously in the following
essay.
Introduction
The period around 1900 is considered to have been one of cultural upheaval,
during which the headlong progress of technical and media developments
challenged traditional forms of thinking. In particular, the history of film,
starting in 1895, is considered by Hans-Ulrich Gumbrecht as the beginning
of an epistemological shift from conceptual thought to “the description of
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 145–161
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
146 heike klippel
1
Hans-Ulrich Gumbrecht, “Wahrnehmung vs. Erfahrung oder die schnellen Bilder und
ihre Interpretationsresistenz,” Kunstforum 128 (1995): 175.
2
Ibid.
3
Ibid.
4
Ibid.
5
Ibid., 176.
6
August Gallinger (1872–1959) was a medical doctor and philosopher. He represented
a phenomenologically oriented philosophy. His text “Zur Grundlegung einer Lehre von der
Erinnerung [On the Foundation of a Doctrine of Memory]” from 1914 was part of a lively
academic discourse before World War I which dealt with psychological and epistemological
issues and questions. He returned from emigration after 1945, and was a professor of
philosophy in Munich until 1952.
the radiance of truth 147
conceptual thought in the humanities suffered from a deep crisis while the
new technologies of visualization were simultaneously hypostasized in a
way which was to cover up doubts that thus became only more apparent.7
Memory and remembering became of interest as a human capacity the results
of which are, on the one hand, vitally necessary but which, on the other
hand, were often held to be questionable. Moreover, the relative obscurity
of the memory process complicated the investigations: neither neurological
research nor biographical reconstruction could definitively show how, for
instance, learning was achieved or memories were created and recalled.
The aforementioned questions equally relate to the simultaneously
emerging mass media, above all the cinema. The cinematic experience presents
something that seems immediately obvious, sensual-visual “truths”, the status
of which remains unclear: in the cinema, one sees ‘things as they are’—this,
however, is not the same as recognition in the way it has been traditionally
understood. The complex relation between visibility and meaningfulness can,
in the cinema, merge into a self-evident obviousness. Though ‘judgements’
formed in such a manner avoid intellectual reasoning, they cannot simply
be dismissed as being irrational or invalid. They represent mass-medial
transformations of Charcot’s famous dictum that “seeing is believing,” and
they, together with judgments based on memory and remembrance, belong
to the sphere of pre-conceptual cognition.
In the following, I will attempt to unfold the question of self-evidence
inherent in selected theoretical texts concerned with memory dating from
the turn of the century. Finally, these will be related to the medium of cinema
as it presented itself in its beginning.
Self-Evidence in Memory
7
See Comolli’s classic essay in which he shows how the “hype of visibility” prevalent in
the 19th century, and, particularly, the invention of the photographic apparatus testify to the
crisis in the supremacy of the look that had been established since the Renaissance: “At the
very same time that it is thus fascinated and gratified by the multiplicity of scopic instruments
which lay a thousand views beneath its gaze, the human eye loses its immemorial privilege; the
mechanical eye of the photographic machine now sees in its place, and in certain aspects with
more sureness. The photograph stands as at once the triumph and the grave of the eye.” Jean-
Louis Comolli, “Machines of the Visible” [1971/72], Teresa de Lauretis, Stephen Heath, Eds.
The Cinematic Apparatus (New York: St. Martin’s Press 1980), 123.
148 heike klippel
It is generally known that memory does not conserve the past as such, but
rather compares and balances the past with the present, thereby proceeding
selectively. Thus, subjective memories cannot be expected to offer conclusive
evidence: “What matters [. . .] is not what my past actually was, or even
whether I had one; it is only the memories I have now which matter, be
they false or true,”8 writes Henry Price. Memories point to a past the status
of which always remains unclear: the historical context of its origin, that is
the triggering event, mixes inseparably with its further evolution within the
memory system, with the history of its modifications and restructurings;
they are being “usuriert”,9 as Freud says, that is worn out. In the course of this
history we always also find appropriations of “alien materials,” i.e. the telling
of events one had not been present at, so that the question of what has been
truly experienced by oneself cannot anymore conclusively be decided. This
position between validity and untruth, between unreliability and a subjective
sense of conviction turned memory into an exemplary field of inquiry during
this period. The question regarding the factuality of that to which memories
refer is usually of subordinate importance. Accurate reproduction is more
often expected from those memory activities that proceed automatically
or from physical memory. Remembrance, on the other hand, is a special
phenomenon the results of which are questioned in regard to their respective
meanings rather than in regard to their verifiability.10
This is the case, for instance, with Bergson, who proposes a theory of
consciousness emphasizing the qualitative properties of consciousness
with regard to time. Thus, he develops a counter-position to concepts
which attempt to describe human consciousness in spatial terms. What is
characteristic for consciousness, according to Bergson, is duration (durée):
it is essentially memory in which time periods pass into each other, moving
from virtuality into actuality in a process of continuous differentiation. The
present exists not only simultaneously with its own past, which it is constantly
in the process of becoming, but also with the past in general. Consequently,
duration is less determined by a sequence of events than by their simultaneity
and co-existence. Consciousness is to be regarded as a quality, a merging of
8
Henry H. Price, Thinking and Experience (London: Hutchinson 1969), 84.
9
Josef Breuer and Sigmund Freud, “Studien über Hysterie” [1895], Gesammelte Werke I
(Frankfurt/M.: Fischer 1999), 88.
10
“The first [memory], conquered by effort, remains dependent upon our will; the second,
entirely spontaneous, is as capricious in reproducing as it is faithful in preserving.” Henri
Bergson, Matter and Memory [Matière et mémoire, 1896], (Mineola, New York: Dover 2004),
102.
the radiance of truth 149
11
Henri Bergson, Time and Free Will [Sur les données immédiates de la conscience, 1899]
(Mineola, New York: Dover 2001), 161.
150 heike klippel
widely known that very early in his work Freud gave up the assumption that
the memories recounted to him by his patients were based on true events;
instead, he analyzed their complex structures with regard to their inherent
representational dynamics. This analysis involves a meticulous deciphering
of the infinite displacements, condensations and disfigurations of the
memory contents which continually take on new form each time they enter
the realm of consciousness. The ‘truth’ of memories is subject to continuous
negotiations.
A series of mostly shorter texts within Freud’s work thematize memories
which display, in a particularly stark manner, the disparity between the
convincing presentation of a particular memory and its questionable basis
in reality.12 Here, he deals less with neurotic dispositions than with everyday
phenomena in which the particularities of memory work manifest themselves.
In the following, I will offer a discussion of an exemplary treatise dealing
with “screen memories”. The phenomenon of “screen memories,” so vividly
described by Freud, reminds one of film images due to its impressive visuality.
Screen memories frequently date back to early childhood, and they mostly
consist of indifferent or everyday impressions that often do not even refer
to actual events. Usually, they are embellished with hyper-sensory elements
(i.e. strong coloring, intensive perceptions of smell or taste); they seem to
display hallucinatory qualities which, though seemingly exaggerated, make
the respective memory very convincing. Related phenomena are memory
illusions, sometimes referred to as fausse reconnaissance or déjà vu. These, too,
are often impressively vivid, but they relate to occurrences that can be proven
not to have taken place. ‘Screen memories’ owe their name to the fact that
Freud interpreted them as a condensation of memory elements representing
other, usually later, repressed contents which they simultaneously cover up,
or screen. In Screen Memories13 he describes the case of a young man who has
merged two fantasies into one, both of them combining lost opportunities of
the past with potential future developments: these fantasies were condensed
into the memory of a slightly altered childhood scene dating from a much
12
Sigmund Freud, “The Psychical Mechanism of Forgetfulness” [1898], The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 3, Ed. James Strachey
(London Hogarth Press 1962, repr. 1995), 289–297; ”Screen Memories” [1899], ibid.
303–322; ”The Psychology of Everyday Life” [1901], ibid., Vol. 6; ”Fausse Reconnaissance
(Déjà vu) in Psycho-Analytical Treatment” [1914], ibid., Vol. 13, 201–207; ”Remembering,
Replaying and Working Through (Further Recommendations on the Technique of Psycho-
Analysis II” [1914], ibid., Vol. 12.
13
Sigmund Freud, “Screen Memories”, ibid., Vol. 3, 303–322.
the radiance of truth 151
earlier time period that became highly symbolic as a result of this re-
projection. The image of the past thus came to represent desires and hopes
for the future. Freud comments on the example as follows:
There is in general no guarantee of the data produced by our memory. But
I am ready to agree with you that the scene is genuine. If so, you selected it
from innumerable others of a similar or another kind because, on account of
its content (which in itself was indifferent) it was well adapted to represent the
two phantasies, which were important enough to you. Recollection of this kind,
whose value lies in the fact that it represents in the memory impressions and
thoughts of a later date whose content is connected with its own by symbolic
or similar links, may appropriately be called a screen memory.14
Freud’s analysis, explaining the scene to be based on later fantasy formations,
lets the young man eventually doubt his very strong sense of the authenticity
of this memory. Freud responds:
It is very possible that in the course of this process the childhood scene itself
also undergoes changes; I regard it as certain that falsification of memory may
be brought about in this way, too. In your case the childhood scene seems only
to have had some of its lines engraved more deeply: think of the over-emphasis
on the yellow and the exaggerated niceness of the bread. But the raw material
was utilizable.15
What is interesting in this passage is the use of the term “genuine” in
contrast, for instance, to the attribution of “truth”, which would have been
inappropriate. Practically nothing is “true” about the scene described; on the
contrary, it actually lies by pretending to be something else, masking that
which is represented as an innocent childhood experience in order to show
it and, at the same time, render it unrecognizable. “Genuine” only refers to
the authentic core of the memory, a truth that has been whittled down to
mere factuality; in this case, nothing more than the actual existence of the
green meadow, the dandelion, the children’s game. Here it becomes clear
how little authenticity actually matters: it is turned into raw material in
order to create meanings that maintain only superficial relationships with
the manifest memory content. What is problematic is the immanent power
of authenticity which seems to suggest that whatever is authentic cannot be
wrong. This authenticity characterizes the experience of self-evidence and
generates moments that ultimately escape analysis. More impressive than all
the clarifying arguments in this case story are its strong sensual intensities:
14
Ibid. 315f.
15
Ibid. 318.
152 heike klippel
the yellow dandelion, the green meadow, the taste of bread, the innocently
cruel game. Ultimately, it is this plasticity that has such a convincing effect
on the young man, the one who remembers, and it is so strong that it even
conveys itself to the reader of the text. One remembers the “screen memories”
as if they had been one’s own memories.
Although the experience of the self-evidence of memories is addressed
by Bergson and Freud, it is a subordinate topic with regard to their actual
theoretical interests which focus on the presentation of consciousness, on
the one hand, and the effects of the unconscious on the other. Among the
many, now forgotten treatises on memory from around 1900 there is one
text that proves particularly relevant to our discussion. August Gallinger, in
a paper titled “Grundlegung zu einer Lehre von der Erinnerung [Foundation
of a Doctrine of Remembrance]” written in 1914, explicitly aims to show
that the experienced self-evidence of memories is not a construction of the
mind but occurs in an unmediated fashion.16 Using a phenomenologically
oriented method, Gallinger gives a detailed discussion of remembrance as
a “fact of consciousness”. He refers to a number of contemporary writers
working with memory experiments, but above all to authors working in the
fields of psychology and philosophy; he briefly mentions and quotes Bergson,
but not Freud.
One of Gallinger’s major concerns was to describe the act of remembering
as an independent phenomenon and to differentiate it from the individual’s
memory as such. Despite all of the relations between remembrance and
memory, the act of remembering remains, for Gallinger, an independent
process of consciousness. For him, ‘memory’ refers to the reproductive
activities of physical memory: memorizing, learning, and storing; as such,
they are unconscious processes. The act of remembering, in contrast,
is always coupled with an awareness of the past and thus is a form of
experience. In his efforts to present remembrance with its particular qualities
as an independent, mental activity, Gallinger hypostasizes the two forms
of memory already differentiated by Bergson17 and delineates an extreme
profile of remembrance. Thus, he considers historical accuracy to be
wholly irrelevant with regard to remembrance, a thesis which he repeatedly
emphasizes: “What is meant here exclusively, is that something appears to the
16
August Gallinger, Zur Grundlegung einer Lehre von der Erinnerung (Halle a. S.: Max
Niemeyer 1914), 22.
17
This corresponds to the presentation of different forms of memory in Bergson; however,
Gallinger does not explicitly refer to Bergson’s text. Cf. Henri Bergson, The two forms of
memory, Matter and Memory, 86–105.
the radiance of truth 153
18
Gallinger 1914, 22.
19
Ibid. 113. Gallinger is quoting Johannes Volkelt, Die Quellen menschlicher Gewißheit
[The Sources of Human Certainty] (Munich 1906) 9 et seq. remarking: “Jessinghaus (Psychol.
Studien, Volume VII, P. 337 et seq.) also supports this view.” Ibid. 114.
20
Ibid. Gallinger is again quoting Volkelt.
154 heike klippel
21
Ibid., 132.
22
Ibid., 142.
23
Ibid., 143.
24
Ibid., 144.
the radiance of truth 155
25
Ibid., 135. Translator’s note: Gallinger’s use of the term “Anschauung” is based on the
Kantian notion of “Anschauung” which denotes awareness, or direct knowledge, through the
senses, and is translated as ‘intuition’ in English versions of Kant.
156 heike klippel
26
Cf. Helmut H. Diederichs, Anfänge deutscher Filmkritik (Stuttgart: Fischer und
Wiedleroither 1986).
27
Cf. Emilie Altenloh, Zur Soziologie des Kino [On the Sociology of Cinema] ( Jena:
Verlag Eugen Diederichs 1914), 63–92.
28
Ibid., 19.
29
Ibid., 38.
the radiance of truth 157
news. “You come and go whenever you want, you watch the closing sequence
of a melodram, followed by the latest news, two bad jokes and then Act I
and II.”30 Even if one is overcome by emotion, it often remains unclear which
quality of the film exactly this emotion is rooted in: “The final image of
‘The Detective’s Death at the Hospital’ is deeply moving in its versatility,
affecting the audience in an undefinable way.”31 I provide this brief sketch of
the atmosphere surrounding early cinema in order to point to the continuity
of the forms of experience, perception and recognition between that period
and today’s cinema even if it rarely shines through.32 Early film was, on the
one hand, characterized by a certain freedom because the code of narrative
cinema had not yet been established;33 on the other hand, it featured an often
mechanistic repetition of themes and structures—which created, within
early cinema, a tension between aesthetic innovation and stereotype. Though
it has been defamed for its “lack of soul”, for its exuberant materialism, Georg
Lukács ascribes to cinema a tendency towards metaphysics especially because
of its strong sensual presence.
The temporality and flow of the ‘cinema’ are completely pure and unspoilt:
the essence of ‘cinema’ is movement as such, eternal variability, the unresting
succession of things. The different fundamental principles of composition
as applied on stage as well as in the cinema correspond to these different
30
Heinrich Stümcke, “Kinematograph und Theater,” Bühne und Welt, 15 (1912): 89–94.
Cit. op. Jörg Schweinitz, Prolog vor dem Film, (Leipzig: Reclam 1992), 244.
31
-n., “Wovon man spricht,” Der Komet, 1121, (1906), cit. op. Diederichs 1986, 64. The
comment refers to the Gaumont-film La Pègre de Paris (1906) directed by Alice Guy, the
“best film to be released to date”. Ibid.
32
The limited space of this essay does not allow for further consideration of these early
testimonies. However, the contemporary writings on cinema available today are of special
significance for the history of early cinema, as they provide the only testimonies aside from
the films still preserved. Caution and carefulness provided, these materials allow for gaining
an impression of the state of cinema before World War I and, moreover, an understanding of
how much early cinema differed from what we mean by cinema since the establishment of the
narrative code. Writing film history, one necessarily is forced to reconstruct and thus is always
confronted with the danger to obstruct the view onto the particularities of this era. One of
the most important sources in this regard is Emilie Altenlohs investigation from 1914, ibid.
With regard to the presentation of experiential reports on early cinema and their relation to
memory theories see Heike Klippel, Gedächtnis und Kino [Memory and Cinema], (Frankfurt/
M.: Stroemfeld 1997). The most comprehensive, not only historical but also theoretical study
of early cinema remains Heide Schlüpmann’s Unheimlichkeit des Blicks [The Uncanniness of the
Look], (Frankfurt/M.: Stroemfeld 1990). Though it focuses on Germany’s social-historical
context, its conclusions are in large parts relevant for early cinema in general; to date, there is
no comparable study available that would equal its depth.
33
See, for example, Tom Gunning, “An Unseen Energy Swallows Space: The Space in
Early Film and ist Relation to American Avant-Garde Film,” John L. Fell, Film before Griffith,
(Berkeley, Los Angeles: Univ. of California Press 1983), 355–366.
158 heike klippel
34
Georg Lukács, “Gedanken zu einer Ästhetik des Kino,” Frankfurter Zeitung 25 (1913).
Cit. op. Fritz Güttinger, ed., Kein Tag ohne Kino, (Frankfurt/M.: Deutsches Filmmuseum
1984), 11.
35
Ferdinand Avenarius, “Vom Schmerzenskind Kino,” Der Kunstwart 19 (1918): 2. “A
breaking ocean wave presented in images of light belongs to the most beautiful one can see.”
Alfred Baeumler, “Die Wirkungen der Lichtbühne’” März 6 (1912): 339. Both cit. op., Fritz
Güttinger, Der Stummfilm im Zitat der Zeit, (Frankfurt/M.: Deutsches Filmmuseum) 11.
36
Ludwig Volkmann, “Dante im Kino,” Der Kunstwart 15 (1913): 213. Cit. op. ibid.
the radiance of truth 159
37
Altenloh 1914, 89.
38
Ibid., 102.
39
Bela Balázs, “Der sichtbare Mensch” [1924], Schriften zum Film, (Budapest, München,
Berlin: Akadémiai Kiadó, Hanser, Henschelverlag 1982), 130.
40
With regard to the significance of this moment of self-recognition in early cinema,
especially as it relates to female perception, see Schlüpmann 1990, 8–183, especially her
160 heike klippel
Michal Ben-Horin
Summary
This article examines the relationship between music and time in contemporary Hebrew and
German literature that creates poetic memories. A poetic memory in this context refers to a
mode of representing the past that is consciously shaped within literary narratives. I claim
that the transformation of musical-time concepts into literature is crucial for the formation of
alternative temporalities to historical ones.
The article focuses on The Christ of Fish (1991) by Yoel Hoffmann, and The Emigrants
(1992) and Austerlitz (2001) by W. G. Sebald. These prose texts demonstrate new modes
of poetic documentation on one hand, while challenging the very essence of testimony and
commemoration on the other. Therefore, the article also includes a critical discussion on
the problem of representing the past, while dealing with cases that manifest the affinity of
literature with music.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 163–175.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
164 michal ben-horin
1
On the potential of music for documentation see Adorno, Philosophie der neuen Musik
47.
2
For further discussion of these aspects as part of musico-literary study, i.e. the form-
analogies, ‘word music’, as well as ‘verbal music’, see Scher 10–15.
3
A key essay that questioned the very possibility of dealing with these past events within
the literary medium and aroused ambivalent responses from both authors and researches
is: Adorno, “Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft” 7–31. For further critical discussions, see Parry
109–124; Hell 9–36.
4
On the German discourse, see, for example, Brockmann 18–50; Shapira (40–58)
discusses the construction of representations of the past in Israel.
5
Relatively recent attempts to inquire into the role of audible components within
narratives of memory are found in: Morris 368–378; Schmitz 119–142. Yet both authors
stop at this point without analyzing further aspects of the musical system in relation to the
question of representing the past.
tones of memory 165
6
Despite his disagreement with Fraser’s interpretation of certain temporal levels in specific
musical pieces, the crucial point for Kramer (The Time of Music 451) is that art and music do
propose metaphors for all temporal levels of the hierarchical model.
166 michal ben-horin
In his novel The Christ of Fish, Yoel Hoffmann, an Israeli author born in 1937,
describes the worlds of immigrants who came from Europe to Palestine in the
nineteen-thirties. The narrator tells the story of his aunt Magda, interweaving
it with other stories of family members and acquaintances. From a position
that blurs the distinction between children’s and grownups’ perspectives, the
narrator follows the characters in their daily encounters, documents their
foreign languages (German, Hungarian, Rumanian, Yiddish), and listens to
their desires and fears.7 More unconventionally, however, Hoffmann’s novel
also portrays the return of dead figures to the world of the living.
7
Similar to his two previous books, The Book of Joseph (1988) and Bernhard (1989), here
as well Hoffmann’s poetics seeks the limits of language as a representative medium, by using
various techniques of estrangement and by interweaving unique textures of perspectives.
Herzig considers this a possible explanation for the ambivalent reception of Hoffmann’s
tones of memory 167
The novel begins with a short prologue, namely an image of uncle Herbert,
a cembalist, arriving at night and speaking to the narrator. A brief dialogue
follows this visit, as the narrator addresses his father: “But uncle Herbert
is dead. Am I dreaming?” And his dead father answers: “He is alive”.8 By
introducing a ‘dialogue with the dead’, this prologue thus demonstrates a
narrative form that requires an alternative time conception to the historical
one. This conception is poetically shaped due to the intense affinity of
Hoffmann’s text with music; precisely in the ways it borrows and develops
the time structures of music.
The novel’s initial paragraphs recount the death of aunt Magda, the death
of the narrator’s father: “When my father died [. . .] it seemed at first as
though I still had my Father, but my father was a Dead Father” (The Christ of
Fish 2); and the death of the narrator’s mother: “My mother gave birth to me
and died (in this sequence of events there is evidence of perfect order) so my
father searched in the books until he found me a name you can pronounce
backwards, and remained [. . .] alone” (9–10). It transpires, however, that
NATAN, the name given to the narrator (6), embodies within its phonetic
composition a central motif that dominates Hoffmann’s ‘memory poetics’.
Reading the name backwards and forwards generates two identical
semiotic successions. This bi-directional motion suspends the immediate
semantic operations of language (i.e. the denotative value of the Hebrew word
Natan is “gave”), and thus enables other modes of signification.9 The ascribed
meaning of “giving birth” (life), which might be activated in this context,
is neither primary nor exclusive. Instead, a potential mode of ‘returning’
appears that is generated from the reversibility of sound succession. In this
sense, the semiotic configuration manifests an essential interference with
the time concept of daily life, namely nootemporality; one that depends
on ‘absolute time’ and is reflected in the “perfect order” of events as birth
precedes death (10). And indeed, Hoffmann’s novel explores the ability of
‘returning’ not only in terms of space, but also of time:
Many ships set sail from the port of Constantsa. Some came back there again
and again. But no ship ever set sail a second time on its first voyage. How
can ships break the time barrier? The clocks show a different time and the
literature, which evoked in the readers either fascination or extreme antagonism (“Hoffmann’s
Poetics of Perspectives” 115–116). Compare also with Openheimer 26.2.1988.
8
My translation. These lines were not included in the English translation.
9
In his essay on the poetry of Paul Celan, Szondi (“Celan Studien” 362–263) discussed
modes of signification that escape description or representation, by stressing the composition
principle, i.e. the syntax, in favor of the sense, i.e. the semantics.
168 michal ben-horin
wood rots. Maybe one should spin the great wheel on the bridge of the ship
simultaneously forwards and backwards and then, in a flash, what was will be
again, for the first time once more. (61, italics mine)
The figurative solution of the wheel’s simultaneous motion (forwards and
backwards) allegorically reveals the desire to break the tyranny of ‘absolute
time’ within which past events are passé, fixed in ‘history’, and the dead
are forgotten. Yet another answer to the time dilemma is to be found in
the structure of music, namely the concept of multiply-directed time that
simultaneously comprises two opposite motions: backwards and forwards.
This is demonstrated by Hoffmann’s use of specific musical allusions such
as Bach’s suite. Listening to music that embodies the multiply-directed
time structure, Mr. Moskowitz, one of Hoffmann’s characters, becomes
a “resonating body” (128), thus giving voice to those who can no longer
speak:
When Casals played his cello by virtue of such love, he was ninety-six years
old. In the middle of Bach’s C Minor Suite, his dim eyes opened wide and it
was clear he was looking past death at life. Mr. Moskowitz remembered those
notes as though he himself were the cello. His eyes surveyed his inner organs.
He heard the dead breathing. From that day on all the winds that blew were for
Mr. Moskowitz internal winds. (127)
The reversible motion of the gaze which, due to the ‘power of music’, turns
from outside to inside, enables us to “look past death at life,” instead of
looking past life at death. This capability, which is soon formulated in terms
of time, suggests a poetics that seeks to musically ‘resonate’ the past within
the present:
It was a dreadful shock when his hair began to grow inward, into his body. This
was the external sign of the breakdown in the flow of time. His hair returned,
as it were, to that other time that Casals had seen with blind eyes when he
was ninety-six and playing Bach’s Suite in C Minor, almost with no body.
(127–128, italics mine)
The confrontation between the absolute “flow of time” and the “other time
that Casals had seen [. . .] when playing Bach’s suite” (128) demonstrates
the attempt to emancipate oneself from the tyranny of ordinary time. More
precisely, this is the ability of music to divorce the past-present-future
succession from the earlier-simultaneous-later that progresses in fixed
‘absolute time’. Thus, a ‘gestural time’ future, i.e. a musical cadence, can exist
earlier in ‘absolute time’ than a present, just as a past may succeed a future.
The musical time structure that penetrates into Hoffmann’s fictive world
with the allusion of Bach’s suite becomes an integral part of the characters’
experience.
tones of memory 169
The question still remains of how exactly the ‘semiotic’, namely a musical
structure presented in language, could be of value for creating new modes
of representing the past. A preliminary answer is that semiotic expression
allegorically exposes literature’s timeless dimension, namely its ‘unconscious’,11
in that it presents elements that resist immediate semantic construction.
Nevertheless, the phonetic unfolding of these elements within the literary
text, characterized as it is by tonal repetitions and acoustic similarities,
enables other modes of signification. Proposing a psychoanalytical model for
narrative structures, Brooks argued that certain repetitions create a return
in the text, a doubling back, that might manifest either “a return to origins
or a return of the repressed. Repetition through this ambiguity appears
to suspend temporal processes, or rather, to subject it to an indeterminate
shuttling or oscillation that binds different moments together” (Brooks,
“Freud’s Masterplot” 100). Similarly, the semiotic expressions in Hoffmann’s
novel that are based on tonal repetition and similarity, might bind earlier
and later as part of an attempt to convey an impression of ‘eternal present’ in
which nothing can get lost.
Hoffmann’s literature is, indeed, semiotic, requiring the reader to listen,
and demanding from him, as an integral part of the reading process, to
hear its rhythmic and tonal configurations. This happens, for instance,
in the case of the narrator’s name (NATAN), or with various wordplays
based on transcriptions of foreign words, such as emphasizing the phonetic
similarity between the German words “Tante” (aunt) and “Tinte” (ink),
as well as with semiotic flows such as the presentation of foreign verbs
(pasian, srinwan, sprisan, swapan etc.) without translating them—thereby
suspending immediate signification. By undermining determined practices
of signification, Hoffmann shapes poetics of memory that avoid conventional
schemes of commemoration.
Another example of semiotic flow is onomatopoeia, such as the repetitive
morphemic pattern “Tweetweetweet” heard with minor variations over
a whole page by Dr. Staub, “who could tell Bachbirds from Mahlerbirds”
(Christ of Fish 143–144). And he does this with the “ears he had brought
from Braunschweig [that] revolved like saucer antenna” (143). Emphasizing
the acoustic images alongside the audible organs reveals a central meta-poetic
notion: Hoffmann attempts to shape poetics that listens to voices from the
past, such as the voices that were once heard or played in Braunschweig.
11
‘Timelessness’ (Zeitlosigkeit) is one of the features used by Freud (“Das Unbewusste”
146) to define the psychic processes of the unconscious.
tones of memory 171
This is his attempt to talk about lost worlds and absent beings in order to
repeatedly free them from the irreversibility of “passing away”.
12
On this point, see also Eshel’s argument that “Sebald’s ‘time effects’ model a modern
postcatastrophic temporal consciousness, one that reflects the loss of a sense of successiveness,
chronology and coherence” (93).
13
Most research on Sebald’s literature with regard to the problem of representing the
past has focused on his use of photographic images. See, for instance Harris 379–391; Long
117–136. This article, on the contrary, tries to shed light on Sebald’s use of acoustic and
musical images, which are nonetheless presented in his prose.
172 michal ben-horin
References
Adorno, Theodor W. Philosophie der neuen Musik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1975.
———. “Kulturkritik und Gesellschaft.” In Prismen, ed. Rolf Tiedemann, 7–31. Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 1976.
Brockmann, Stephen. Literature and German Reunification. Cambridge: Cambridge Uni-
versity Press, 1999.
Brooks, Peter. “Freud’s Masterplot: A Model for Narrative.” In Reading for the Plot, 90–112.
New York: Vintage, 1985.
Eshel, Amir. “Against the Power of Time: The Poetics of Suspension in W. G. Sebald’s
Austerlitz.” New German Critique 88 (2003): 71–96.
Fraser, J. T. The Voices of Time. Amherst: University of Massachusetts, 1981.
———. “The Art of the Audible ‘Now’”. Music Theory Spectrum 7 (1985): 181–184.
Freud, Sigmund. “Das Unbewusste.” In Studienausgabe. Vol. III: Psychologie des Unbewußten,
121–173. Frankfurt am Main: Fischer, 2000.
Harris, Stefanie. “The Return of the Dead: Memory and Photography in W. G. Sebald’s Die
Ausgewanderten.” The German Quarterly 74 (2001): 379–391.
Hell, Julia. “Eyes Wide Shut: German Post-Holocaust Authorship.” New German Critique 88
(2003): 9–36.
Herzig, Hanna. “Hoffmann’s Poetics of perspectives. (Hebrew)” In First Name: Essays on Jacob
Shabtai, Joshua Kenaz, Yoel Hoffmann, 115–133. Tel Aviv: Hakibbutz Hameuchad,
1994.
Hoffmann, Yoel. The Christ of Fish (Hebrew). Trans. Edward Levenston. New York: New
Directions, 1999 [1991].
Kramer, Jonathan D. The Time of Music: New Meanings, New Temporalities, New Listening
Strategies. New York: Schirmer Books, 1988.
———. “Postmodern Concepts of Musical Time”. Indiana Theory Review 17 (1996): 21–62.
Kristeva, Julia. “Revolution in Poetic Language.” Trans. Margaret Waller. In The Kristeva
Reader, ed. Toril Moi, 89–136. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986.
Long, J. J. “History, Narrative, and Photography in W. G. Sebald’s Die Ausgewanderten.” The
Modern Language Review 98 (2003): 117–136.
Morris, Leslie. “The Sound of Memory.” The German Quarterly 74 (2001): 368–378.
Openheimer, Yochai. “An Author’s Poetry. (Hebrew)” Davar (26.2.1988).
Parry, Ann. “Idioms for the Unrepresentable: Postwar Fiction and the Shoah.” In The Holocaust
and the Text. Speaking the Unspeakable, eds. Andrew Leak and Goerge Paizis, 109–124.
Houndmills: Macmillan Press, 2000.
Scher, Steven P. “Einleitung: Literatur und Musik—Entwicklung und Stand der Forschung.”
In Literatur und Musik: Ein Handbuch zur Theorie und Praxis eines komparatistischen
Grenzgebietes, ed. Steven P. Scher, 9–25. Berlin: Erich Schmidt, 1984.
Schmitz, Helmut. “Soundscapes of the Third Reich. Marcel Beyer’s Flughunde.” In German
Culture and the Uncomfortable Past, eds. H. Schmitz, 119–142. Aldershot: Ashgate,
2001.
Sebald, W. G. The Emigrants (German). Trans. Michael Hulse. London: Harvill Press, 1996
[1992].
———. Austerlitz (German). Trans. Anthea Bell. Toronto: Alfred A. Knopf, 2001.
Shapira, Anita. “The Holocaust: Private Memories, Public Memory.” Jewish Social Studies 4
(1998): 40–58.
Szondi, Peter. “Celan Studien.” In Schriften II, ed. Jean Bollack et al., 321–397. Frankfurt am
Main: Suhrkamp, 1978.
RESPONSE
David Burrows
Ben-Horin shows how both Hoffmann and Sebald play with everyday
expectations for time. In the normal course of things, we expect our lives
to give us a varied succession of events. Each event is followed by a new
one, with each event implying a past and a future proper to it, the whole
possessed of an overall direction of flow. These authors, however, give us a
time shaped in ways that Jonathan Kramer has described for some twentieth-
century music. Some music exists in moments that have no past or future.
Other music stacks and accumulates instances of the same moment repeated
over and over so that time seems frozen. In yet other music independent
discourses are yoked together, their conflicting agendas undermining any
sense of an overall direction. Music has of course always made it its business
to play with time. In fact, any of the arts that take time—film and dance for
example—can use the time they take to play with duration, repetition, and
order of succession, and one effect in all these cases is a pleasureful sense of
mastery over time.
“Ordinary time” is conflated with “absolute time” in Ben-Horin’s essay,
but she no doubt realizes that this ordinary time is quite different from
the “absolute time” described by Newton. Ordinary time is a construction
imposed on happening by nervous systems, conspicuously including the
human ones, in the interest of their self-regulation. In ordinary time,
happening comes with a surround of alternative states, the past and the
future. The brain clings to and fixes occurrence and creates a file, the past,
where hypostatized occurrence can be stored. The past is partnered by a zone
where the disequilibrium of the present is hypothetically resolved: the future
(and the future, where hope flourishes, is conspicuous by its absence from
the texts Ben-Horin reports on). So time as we find it in these writers, and in
music, is a construction superimposed on a construction.
Music shares a liberated approach to time with another area of experience
that stands to one side of everyday experience, dreaming, mentioned in
passing in Ben-Horin’s essay. When we dream we are notoriously out of our
ordinary minds, and this applies inevitably to ordinary time. In fact, the time-
play in both Hoffmann and Sebald, for all their differences, is accompanied
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 176–177.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
response 177
Katherine A. S. Sibley
Summary
The government’s denial of a security clearance to atomic scientist J. Robert Oppenheimer in
1954 has always carried the taint of McCarthyism. Less often recognized is that Oppenheimer’s
hearings were also linked to events eleven years earlier, when the physicist had learned of Soviet
intelligence agents’ interest in his nuclear research. That this episode continued to be central
at the time of his security hearings resulted from officials’ construction of a powerful memory
about him which had become institutionalized, despite agents’ awareness of its flaws.
This narrative of disloyalty persisted in large part owing to the moment in which it first
surfaced in 1943. Although Oppenheimer had by then left the Communist Party, he was
evasive about his awareness of Soviet spying even as the FBI learned of a separate Russian
atomic espionage operation linked with a friend of the physicist. The attempt to develop a case
against Oppenheimer then was only stopped by his importance to the successful development
of the atomic bomb.
The affair never died down completely, and in 1954, it resurfaced with a vengeance in
the wake of debate over the hydrogen bomb, which Oppenheimer had opposed. Though
investigators soon conceded that he had no espionage contacts, he lost his clearance anyway.
His fate suggests the way in which memories are constructed and concretized at a particularly
charged moment, with devastating results.
1
Richard Polenberg, ed., In the Matter of J. Robert Oppenheimer: The Security Clearance
Hearing (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2002), xiv.
2
Dr. J. Robert Oppenheimer: Summary for May 7, 1954. FBI Security File: J. Robert
Oppenheimer, cited in Polenberg, In the Matter of JRO, xv.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 179–196
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
180 katherine a. s. sibley
be ignored in any discussion of the physicist’s treatment; he was all too eager
to conduct an investigation of the scientist, a probe prevented when AEC
head Lewis L. Strauss pointed out that the Wisconsin Republican’s handling
of such a delicate matter would be “most ill-advised and impolitic.”3 Strauss, a
convinced Oppenheimer critic, preferred to handle the matter himself.
Yet, though the political culture of the early to mid 1950s is key in
understanding the fate of Oppenheimer, so too are events eleven years earlier,
and it was the memory of those distant events, as this article will argue,
that was chiefly responsible for the physicist’s fate. In 1943, Oppenheimer
learned of Soviet intelligence efforts to garner information on the bomb
at the Berkeley Radiation Laboratory where he worked, and was less than
forthcoming about them with his Manhattan Project superiors. Though the
physicist kept his leading role as an advisor in nuclear matters throughout
the war and well into the Cold War, this only murkily understood episode
continued to resonate in the collective memory of security officials. By 1954,
when a new presidential administration exposed government advisors to
greater scrutiny, Oppenheimer’s wartime history re-emerged as instrumental
in the intelligence community’s campaign against him. The kind of
“scriptlike plotline” with which officials conveniently lined up past events
in Oppenheimer’s life has been well described by sociologist of memory
Eviatar Zerubavel. Zerubavel writes that such a practice bestows “historical
meaning” on otherwise unconnected episodes, which thus lend themselves
to “inevitably simplistic, one-dimensional visions of the past.”4
This constructed narrative of disloyalty persisted in large part owing to the
moment in which it had first surfaced during World War II. Oppenheimer
had been evasive about what he knew about Soviet intrigue at the same time
that the FBI learned of a separate Russian espionage operation against the
Berkeley Radiation Laboratory linked with California Communist leader
Steve Nelson, who himself claimed a friendship with Oppenheimer.5 This
coincidence was especially searing for officials, making Oppenheimer’s
3
Quoted in Polenberg, In the Matter of JRO, xvii.
4
Eviatar Zerubavel, Time Maps: Collective Memory and the Social Shape of the Past
(Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 2003), 19.
5
See Comintern Apparatus (COMRAP) Report, May 7, 1943, in Steve Nelson file 100–
16847–112, 12, Federal Bureau of Investigation, Washington, D.C.; Recording No. 3, Nelson
and “X”, (Soviet representative Vassili Zubilin), April 10, 1943, attached to D.M. Ladd to
Director, Communist Infiltration at Radiation Laboratory (CINRAD) report, Nelson File
100–16847–201; FBI Report, “Soviet Activities in the United States,” July 25, 1946, 21,
in Clark Clifford Papers, box 15, Harry S. Truman Library, Independence, Mo. (hereafter
HSTL).
once a communist, always a communist 181
evasions more “eventful” than they otherwise might have been, and imparting
them with heightened significance.6 Oppenheimer and Nelson also shared
a personal connection, since the scientist’s wife, Kitty, had been married
to Nelson’s late friend, Joseph Dallet, a casualty of the Spanish Civil War.
Nelson, moreover, visited Oppenheimer on at least five occasions in 1941.
Still, the physicist claimed that “Nelson never approached him directly or
indirectly to obtain information regarding the experimentation . . . at the
Radiation Laboratory, and . . . never . . . contacted him at the University.”7
Despite such concerns, World War II has often appeared to be the golden
age of Soviet-American relations: Lauchlin Currie, an aide to FDR during
the war, declared that “we were all united . . . the atmosphere of suspicion and
caution only arose after I left the government” in 1945.8 Currie’s views may
be less than convincing, owing to his secret role as a Soviet spy;9 yet even a
skeptic of all things Soviet like George F. Kennan was convinced that “in 1943
the Soviet Union was hardly regarded by our top people in our government
as an enemy.”10 Indeed, a “wholly different atmosphere” then prevailed,
as Oppenheimer’s counsel Lloyd K. Garrison contended in 1954: “The
whole attitude toward Russia, toward persons who were sympathetic with
Russia, everything was different from what obtains today.”11 Nevertheless,
inside security agencies like the FBI and military intelligence, a much more
critical outlook prevailed, and the discovery of Soviet espionage in World
War II only confirmed this posture. For these reasons, Oppenheimer’s lack
6
For a fascinating discussion of how past time is divided in our memories into either
intensely “memorable” periods or eminently “forgettable” ones, see Zerubavel, Time Maps,
25–34.
7
Harry M. Kimball, SAC San Francisco to Director, FBI, September 19, 1946, Nelson
file 100–16847–354; July 4, 1946, July 19, 1946, Surveillance log, Steve Nelson, Nelson File
100–16847–394 Volume 5, 67. At his 1954 security hearings, however, Oppenheimer said
he knew that Nelson was “an important Communist.” See U.S. Atomic Energy Commission,
In the Matter of J. Robert Oppenheimer: Transcript of Hearing before Personnel Security Board
and Texts of Principal Documents and Letters (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1971), 195
(hereafter IMJRO). Despite abundant evidence, Nelson consistently denied his espionage
role during his lifetime, enabled by a long-held scholarly reticence on the subject in the post-
McCarthy era. See Steve Nelson, James R. Barrett, and Rob Ruck, Steve Nelson: American
Radical (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1981), 294; author’s note from Maurice
Isserman, January 3, 2005.
8
Quoted in Roger Sandilands, The Life and Political Economy of Lauchlin Currie: New
Dealer, Presidential Adviser, and Development Economist (Durham: Duke University Press,
1990), 149.
9
R. Bruce Craig, Treasonable Doubt: The Harry Dexter White Spy Case (Lawrence, Kan:
The University Press of Kansas, 2004), 96.
10
IMJRO, 98.
11
IMJRO, 358.
182 katherine a. s. sibley
12
Julius Robert Oppenheimer, February 17, 1947, FBI background, attached to Hoover
to Harry Vaughan, February 28, 1947, President’s Secretary File box 167, HSTL; Communist
Infiltration at Radiation Laboratory (CINRAD) Summary Memo #1,100–190625–2017,
March 5, 1946, 8. I am indebted to Gregg Herken for a copy of the CINRAD report.
Oppenheimer’s brother, sister-in-law, and wife were all former Communists, as was former
paramour Jean Tatlock. On monitoring of Kitty Oppenheimer, see FBI Report, November
27, 1945, 39, box 97, Record Group 233, Records of the U.S. House of Representatives,
Special Committee on Un-American Activities (Dies), Exhibits, Evidence, etc. re Committee
Investigations: Communism Subject Files 1930–1945, National Archives, Washington, D.C.
In July 1943, the War Department’s Military Intelligence Division had opened an investigation
on Frank Oppenheimer, in response to his attendance at Communist meetings in 1940 as
well as his brother’s leadership of the Manhattan Project. According to Lt. Col. Pash, who
instigated the probe, Frank Oppenheimer was “reliably reported to be a Communist and
possibly engaged in espionage.” Pash called for an investigation of “Oppenheimer’s associates,
activities, and political sympathies.” But one of his former teachers, G.H. Dieke of Johns
Hopkins, saw Frank as a shy and retiring type, and dismissed his political leanings, only to
say that as a “Hebrew”, Frank Oppenheimer would not have any warm feelings about Nazism.
Boris T. Pash, T. Col, Military Intelligence, Chief, Counter Intelligence Branch, to Major
Geroge B. Dyer, Director, Intelligence Division, headquarters Third Service command,
Baltimore, July 10, 1943, Richard Connolly, Special Agent, CIC, Memo for the Officer in
Charge, July 19, 1943, Washington Post, June 15, 1949, all in Frank Freidman Oppenheimer
File, E2037207, box 51, RG 319 Records of the Army Staff, Records of the Office of the
Assistant Chief of Staff, G-2, Intelligence, Records of the Investigative Records Repository,
Security Classified Intelligence and Investigative Dossiers, 1939–1976 (hereafter IRR),
National Archives, College Park, Md.
13
Memo to Boardman, April 16, 1954, FBI Oppenheimer file 100–17828–1208;
Comintern Apparatus (COMRAP) Summary Report, San Francisco, December 15, 1944,
100–17879, 38–39. I am grateful to John Earl Haynes for a copy of the COMRAP report.
once a communist, always a communist 183
theoretical: he gave $150 monthly donations as late as 1942, and was almost
certainly a member.14
Though the atomic physicist’s party membership could not be proven
during the war, this did not stop Lt. Col. Boris T. Pash, who headed the
Manhattan Project’s investigative arm, from asserting that Oppenheimer
“is not to be fully trusted and that his loyalty to the Nation is divided.”
Given the physicist’s dissembling on the issue of his party membership, the
government’s “considerable doubts” about him are not without foundation.15
They do not, however, justify assertions that Oppenheimer was a spy, as Pash
claimed he was, providing material to persons who “may be furnishing . . .
[it] to the Communist Party for transmission to the USSR.” Though this
security officer urged that the Los Alamos leader be replaced, Manhattan
Project manager General Leslie R. Groves, convinced that the physicist was
essential to the bomb project, was able to foil such attempts to remove him
during the war.16
The FBI, meanwhile, was learning that Oppenheimer’s party connections
were, if anything, increasingly attenuated. In a 1943 conversation recorded
by the Bureau, Steve Nelson informed Radiation Laboratory scientist
Joseph Woodrow Weinberg that while he had talked to Oppenheimer
about the project, he had not pressed him, since “I didn’t want to put him
in an unfriendly position. I didn’t want to put him on the spot, you know.”
Weinberg agreed, noting that Oppenheimer would not think Nelson the
“proper party” for gaining any materials.17 Nelson acknowledged that he
and the party made the physicist “uncomfortable,” even “jittery.” Weinberg
complained that as for himself, Oppenheimer had “deliberately kept” him
from the project, in part because of Weinberg’s politics. Weinberg believed
14
Gregg Herken cites a letter that Haakon Chevalier wrote Oppenheimer much later,
discussing their membership in the same unit of the party from 1938 to 1942. See Chevalier to
Oppenheimer, July 13, 1964, as well as further substantiation in Gordon Griffiths’ unpublished
memoir, Venturing Outside the Ivory Tower: The Political Autobiography of a College Professor,
on deposit at Library of Congress, Washington, DC; both of these may be found also on the
website for Herken’s Brotherhood of the Bomb: www.brotherhoodofthebomb.com.
15
IMJRO, 260, 270; Pash to John Lansdale, September 6, 1943, cited in idem, 273.
16
Pash to Lansdale, June 29, 1943, cited in IMJRO, 822; Oppenheimer was considered a
“calculated risk” owing to his past political associations. The notion of “calculated risk” allowed
for giving clearance to a candidate who otherwise had security issues, but who “is a man of
great attainments and capacity and has rendered outstanding services.” The Hearing Board
felt that such a standard only applied during times of “critical national need.” See IMJRO,
15/1013, 43/1041. Also see Leslie Groves, Now It Can be Told: The Story of the Manhattan
Project (New York: Harper Brothers, 1962), 63.
17
Steve Nelson File, August 20, 1945, 100–16847–NR, 15.
184 katherine a. s. sibley
this was “a strange thing for him to fear. But he’s changed a bit.” Both men
agreed that Oppenheimer was “just not a Marxist” and that while he “would
like to be on the right track,” he was being pushed away by his wife, who was
“influencing him in the wrong direction.” Her ambitions for him, as well as
his own, were leading him away from his old associations.18
Nelson and Weinberg’s association, however, definitely included
espionage. On the night of March 29, 1943, the Communist leader was
overheard at his home securing “some highly confidential data regarding the
nuclear experiments” from Weinberg.19 Informing the party leader that the
separation process for uranium was the Lab’s chief problem at the moment,
Weinberg noted that he was “a little bit scared” to hand over a published
document on the project. Nelson, nevertheless, pressed him for material, but
did not attempt to assuage Weinberg’s fear that his espionage could lead to
him being put under investigation.20 With some trepidation, then, Weinberg
provided Nelson a formula of about 150 to 200 words which concerned the
“calutron”, a separator that would enrich uranium. Most of it the Bureau’s
listeners found unintelligible.21 Soon after this meeting, an FBI tail saw
Nelson passing materials to Soviet vice consul Peter Petrovich Ivanov on the
grounds of nearby Saint Joseph Hospital.22
Ivanov was also working other avenues. He had contacted George C.
Eltenton, a sympathetic chemist at a nearby oil company, and complained to
him that “the Russians . . . needed certain information and . . . for political
reasons there were no authorized channels through which they could
obtain such.”23 Eltenton knew that left-leaning professor of French Haakon
Chevalier was a friend of J. Robert Oppenheimer at Berkeley, and got in
18
Steve Nelson File, August 20, 1945, 100–16847–NR, 4–7, 15. Lansdale agreed with
this; Kitty Oppenheimer’s “strength of will was a powerful influence in keeping him away
from what we would regard as dangerous associations.” See IMJRO, 266.
19
See U.S. House, Committee on Un-American Activities (HUAC), The Shameful Years:
Thirty Years of Soviet Espionage in the United States. (Washington, D.C., 1951), 31; FBI
Report, September 27, 1945, 40. On the surveillance of Nelson, also see D.M. Ladd to the
Director, April 16, 1943, Re: Cinrad, FBI File 100–16847–201; “Communist Infiltration of
Radiation Laboratory, University of California, Berkeley, California,” FBI File 100–16980,
July 7, 1943, 1; FBI Steve Nelson File, 100–2696, June 25, 1945, 28.
20
Steve Nelson File, August 20, 1945, 100–16847–NR, 8–20 passim.
21
Steve Nelson File, August 20, 1945, 100–16847–NR, 18; COMRAP Report May 7,
1943, 100–16847–112, 5; FBI Report, “Soviet Activities in the United States,” 26.
22
CINRAD Summary Memo #1 100–190625–2017, 7; Ladd Memorandum for the
Director, May 5, 1943, 100–16847–104; FBI Report, San Francisco, May 7, 1943, 100–
16847–112.
23
FBI background on Julius Robert Oppenheimer, February 17, 1947, attached to Hoover
to Vaughan, February 28, 1947, President’s Secretary’s Files, box 167, HSTL.
once a communist, always a communist 185
touch with him. Eltenton pressed Chevalier “to find out what was being
done at the radiation laboratory, particularly information regarding the
highly destructive weapon which was being developed.” He told the professor
that since “Russia and the United States were allies, Soviet Russia should be
entitled to any technical data which might be of assistance to that nation.”24
In Chevalier’s later version of the story, the whole suggestion was
“preposterous,” and Oppenheimer would be “horrified” to hear of it. Yet
he nevertheless decided to tell the physicist, whom he considered his “most
intimate and steadfast friend,” owing to his professed concern that Eltenton’s
might be only the first attempt to get more information about the secret
project.25 Chevalier reported that he had informed Oppenheimer at a visit to
the physicist’s home in the winter of 1943, whereupon Oppenheimer flatly
slammed the entreaties as “treason.”26 But Oppenheimer did not alert Army
security to the episode until some six months later—and the story he told
then was largely fabricated. So too, as it turned out, was Chevalier’s portrayal
of events.27
In August 1943, Oppenheimer informed his Army interviewers that
sometime the previous winter he “had learned from three different
employees of the atomic bomb project . . . that they had been solicited to
furnish information, ultimately to be delivered to the USSR.” None of the
men had cooperated, according to Oppenheimer, so he refused to name
24
Quoted in HUAC, Hearings regarding Communist infiltration of the Radiation
Laboratory and Atomic bomb project at the University of California, Berkeley, California,
(Identification of Scientist X), December 22, 1950, 81st Congress, second sess. (Washington,
1951), 3495; also see HUAC, Report on Soviet Espionage Activities in Connection with the
Atom Bomb; Investigation of Un-American Activities in the United States, September 28, 1948,
80th Congress, second sess. (Washington, 1948), 182; John Lansdale, Jr. to J. Edgar Hoover,
August 27, 1943, December 13, 1943, RG 319, 383.4 USSR; FBI Report, November 27,
1945, 39–40; David Holloway, Stalin and the Bomb: The Soviet Union and Atomic Energy,
1939–1956 (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), 103. Eltenton’s argument was also
made by spies like Ted Hall. See Albright, Joseph and Marcia Kunstel. Bombshell: The Secret
Story of America’s Unknown Atomic Spy Conspiracy (New York: Times Books, 1997), 89–90.
25
Haakon Chevalier, Oppenheimer: The Story of a Friendship (New York: George Braziller,
1965) 53–54. Chevalier’s discomfort was not so apparent to Eltenton, however. See, Gregg
Herken, Brotherhood of the Bomb: The Tangled Lives and Loyalties of Robert Oppenheimer,
Ernest Lawrence, and Edward Teller, (New York: Henry Holt and Co. 2002), 92.
26
Chevalier, Oppenheimer, 19.
27
Oppenheimer’s reply to Nichols, March 4, 1954, cited in IMJRO, 14. Despite his
sympathy toward better relations with the Soviet Union, scholars have persuasively dismissed
Oppenheimer’s links with espionage. See, for instance, Allen Weinstein and Alexander
Vassiliev, The Haunted Wood: Soviet Espionage in America—The Stalin Era (New York:
Random House, 1999), 183–185; Herken, Brotherhood, 93. On Oppenheimer’s “passivity”
in taking action on what he did know, see Haynes and Klehr, Venona, 330.
186 katherine a. s. sibley
them. He also refused to name the intermediary who had been assigned by
Eltenton to approach them, declaring this person “innocent.”28 This was, of
course, a cryptic reference to Chevalier. Authorities were alarmed: even if
no espionage had taken place, an official at the Soviet consulate stood ready
“who was said to have had a great deal of experience with microfilm and who
was in a position to transmit the material to Russia.”29 Oppenheimer’s story
led to much fruitless work for intelligence agents, who attempted to find
the three men, spurred on by their knowledge of Nelson’s activities. Eleven
years later, memories of that looming espionage threat remained vivid in the
hearing transcripts.30
In December 1943, after having been repeatedly badgered about it,
Oppenheimer at last revealed to General Groves that his intermediary had
been Chevalier.31 Then, demanding he keep it a secret, Oppenheimer told
Groves that the French professor had contacted not three people, but only
one—his brother, Frank.32 Robert apparently told his convoluted story of
Chevalier’s approach to himself in order to protect his brother, who had been
a member of the Party and was also a Radiation Laboratory scientist. Thanks
to Groves’ discretion, this more accurate story remained largely unexplored
until 1954.
Meanwhile, the FBI, which had been kept off the case by the Manhattan
Project security team during the war, eagerly resumed its investigation of
Oppenheimer in 1946.33 Agents continued to attempt to demonstrate
28
Report on J. R. Oppenheimer, February 5, 1950, Summary Brief on Fuchs, February 6,
1950, FBI Klaus Fuchs file, 65–58805–1202, 3.
29
“Chevalier Conspiracy,” Part II, August 20, 1945, Steve Nelson FBI file, 100–16980,
34–35.
30
IMJRO, 148, 815.
31
“Chevalier Conspiracy,” Part II, Steve Nelson file, August 20, 1945, 100–16980, 36;
Julius Robert Oppenheimer, February 17, 1947, FBI background, attached to Hoover to
Vaughan, February 28, 1947, PSF box 167.
32
CINRAD Summary Memo #1, 100–190625–2017, March 5, 1946, 14–15, IMJRO,
264–265. This story has been most recently and convincingly told in Herken, Brotherhood,
113–114. Oppenheimer may have sworn Groves to secrecy about Frank, but the general told
Colonel Lansdale, who informed the FBI. As Herken relates, Oppenheimer’s reporting on
Chevalier was “comeuppance” for the French professor’s attempt to recruit his brother. See
idem, 120.
33
See Hoover’s request for a wiretap, April 26, 1946, memo to the Attorney General, FBI
Oppenheimer File 100–17828–29, where he justified the request based on Oppenheimer’s
“contact with individuals reported to be Soviet agents.” Also see George M. Langdon Report,
Oppenheimer file, 100–17828–16; San Francisco Office to Washington Director, May 8,
1946, Oppenheimer file, Internal Security 100–17828–33; SAC San Francisco to Director,
May 14, 1946, Internal Security 100–17828–33. The FBI took over the Manhattan District
files on Oppenheimer in the summer of 1946. See IMJRO, 417.
once a communist, always a communist 187
34
Oppenheimer had been an adviser to Bernard Baruch in the latter’s eponymous plan for
internationalizing atomic energy, and contributed to the Acheson-Lilienthal Report for the
control of atomic energy. Julius Robert Oppenheimer, February 17, 1947, FBI background,
attached to Hoover to Vaughan, February 28, 1947, PSF box 167.
35
Hoover to Vaughan, February 28, 1947, PSF box 167; see discussion of Frank
Oppenheimer’s investigation in Herken, Brotherhood of the Bomb, 181.
36
Memo on Oppenheimer, April 16, 1954, 100–17828–1208.
37
W. A. Branigan to A. H. Belmont, April 7, 1954, 100–17828–1055.
38
See FBI memo, April 21, 1947, cited in Jerrold and Leona Schecter, Sacred Secrets: How
Soviet Intelligence Operations Changed American History (Washington, D.C.: Brassey’s, 2002),
Appendix 1, 314.
39
Memo on Oppenheimer attached to Ladd to Director, March 18, 1946, Oppenheimer
file 100–17828–51, 6.
40
Memo on Oppenheimer attached to Ladd to Director, March 18, 1946, 100–17828–51,
6; also see Belmont to Boardman, April 15, 1954, 100–17828–1159; Memo to Boardman,
April 16, 1954, 100–17828–1208.
188 katherine a. s. sibley
secretary, whom the Bureau hoped “on the basis of her religious convictions
and patriotism” might become a source for the Bureau. The secretary would
not be so typecast.41 Even the fact that Oppenheimer admitted to the FBI
after the war that he “‘concocted a completely fabricated story’” about the
three contacts of Chevalier, and that he “failed to recognize the potential
threat to the nation’s security which was present in the incident,” did not
affect him adversely.42
Thus the new surveillance campaign ended in 1947, as AEC chairman
David M. Lilienthal reported the consensus of his advisors that “Dr.
Oppenheimer’s loyalty was an accepted fact.”43 Called to testify in front of
HUAC two years later, while it was investigating wartime espionage at the
Radiation Lab, Oppenheimer was treated with kid gloves—even by Richard
Nixon. Speaking at the same hearings, however, his brother ended up losing
his job when it was revealed he had kept his Communist past a secret.44
The renewed emphasis on Robert Oppenheimer’s danger as a “security
risk” that emerged less than five years later shows the tenacious grip which
memories of his earlier misstatements had on the minds of Washington’s
intelligence community. As Zerubavel observes, “memory often schematizes
history,” applying an overarching narrative to it. This “editing” process, as
he notes, “mentally transform[s] . . . noncontiguous points in time into
seemingly unbroken historical continua.”45 Government officials would once
again proclaim their suspicions of Oppenheimer’s disloyalty despite a clear
understanding that his Communist associations were more than a decade old
by 1954—a mustiness confirmed by the FBI’s having dropped his surveillance
for the previous seven years. Oppenheimer’s lack of support for the hydrogen
bomb no doubt played a significant role in the newly critical scrutiny he
received, but the powerful memory of his past political associations and
obfuscations appear to have been most central in the new charges.
Resistance to Oppenheimer’s continued advisory position had arisen
even before former President Harry S. Truman returned home to Missouri.
In June 1952, Oppenheimer was essentially forced off the GAC when his
term ended, and here his opposition to the H-bomb was key. The FBI was
busily marshalling reports from interviews with critics like physicist Edward
41
Strickland to Ladd, March 26, 1946, 100–17828–24.
42
Report on J. R. Oppenheimer, February 5, 1950, Summary Brief on Fuchs, February 6,
1950, 65–58805–1202, 4–5.
43
“Scientist Upheld Despite FBI File,” New York Times, April 13, 1954, 19.
44
Herken, Brotherhood, 196–97.
45
Zerubavel, Time Maps, 25, 40.
once a communist, always a communist 189
46
Herken, Brotherhood, 249–64 passim.
47
Herken, Brotherhood, 265–67. The scientist had made fun of Strauss at a 1949
Congressional hearing. When Strauss pressed him as to the “dangers” of radioactive isotopes
being used to make bombs, Oppenheimer compared their explosive potential to shovels or
bottles of beer.
48
“President barred data to scientist,” NYT, April 14, 1954, 18.
49
IMJRO, 832–833.
50
See Borden’s letter to Hoover, November 7, 1953, cited in IMJRO, 837–838.
190 katherine a. s. sibley
perceived past transgressions as the synecdoche of his life, despite his heroic
status and his long years of government service. Indeed, the physicist’s very
presence in the government now carried the weight of “historical analogy”;
to Borden, Oppenheimer’s status as a consultant to the AEC was a glaring
example of replicating the errors of the past, when blinkered officials had
allowed Communists into the federal ranks.51
Borden’s letter reached Strauss on November 30, and Eisenhower on
Dec. 2. The president, after speaking to several top officials, decided the
following day to construct a “blank wall” between Oppenheimer and secret
information, suspending his clearance, although not yet informing him
about it.52 Neither Hoover nor Strauss recommended pursuing the matter in
the halls of Congress, to be subjected to the treatment of Senate investigative
pioneers like Democrat Pat McCarran and Republican Joseph McCarthy. At
the same time, however, General Kenneth D. Nichols of the AEC prudently
worried that a separate hearing of the AEC’s personnel security board would
distance other scientists from the Commission, especially since the charges
prominently featured Oppenheimer’s opposition to the hydrogen bomb, an
issue that seemed to suggest that scientific advice was subject to a “political
correctness” standard.53
Then, just as Eisenhower announced the erection of his wall, further
discussions among the AEC, White House, and military officials stirred
up the story of the old Chevalier incident—and the even more effectively
suppressed tale that it was Oppenheimer’s brother Frank, and not
Oppenheimer himself, who had been the French professor’s contact in 1943.
The AEC Chairman decided that a hearing of the personnel security board
would be necessary after all. Borden had not even mentioned the Chevalier
affair. Now, it seemed that the “decade-old approach by Chevalier would
be key to any legal case that might be made against Oppenheimer,” Gregg
Herken notes. An already outraged Eisenhower snarled that “Oppenheimer
is a liar,” as officials quickly seized upon the fact that the physicist’s past
misstatements, rather than his present views on the “Super”, would be
the more compelling hook on which to hang him. Oppenheimer was not
informed of the various charges against him until after he had returned from
a trip to Europe some two weeks later—a trip that ironically included a visit
51
See discussion of these concepts in Zerubavel, Time Maps, 48–53.
52
“Eisenhower Order Barred U.S. Data to Oppenheimer,” NYT, April 14, 1954, 1, 18;
Herken, Brotherhood, 268.
53
Herken, Brotherhood, 269–270.
once a communist, always a communist 191
54
Herken, Brotherhood, 270–74; “AEC Suspends Dr. Oppenheimer,” NYT April 13,
1954, 15. The Eisenhower quote is in A. Branigan to AH Belmont, March 31, 1954, FBI
Oppenheimer File, Internal Security 100–17828–1279. Branigan was quoting Lewis
Strauss, Chairman of the Atomic Energy Commission, via David Teeple, Lewis’ assistant, on
Eisenhower’s view of Oppenheimer.
55
“Dr. Oppenheimer Suspended by A.E.C. in Security Review; Scientist Defends
Record,” NYT, April 13, 1954, 1; “Strauss, Oppenheimer Serve Same Institute,” NYT, April
13, 1954, 21.
56
See IMJRO, 7–20.
57
Herken, Brotherhood, 275.
58
Belmont to Ladd, January 5, 1954, 100–17828–587; W. A. Branigan to A. H. Belmont,
April 7, 1954, 100–17828–1055.
192 katherine a. s. sibley
bull story,” completely at odds with what he had said to the FBI in 1946,
when he had dismissed the earlier tale. He conceded, “I was an idiot.” The
government did not attempt to illuminate the more dramatic reality of the
1943 affair, since it would only make Oppenheimer look like “a hero” who
had tried to protect Frank.59 That particular memory would be blotted out
in favor of a more incriminating scenario, one that placed the scientist in
the “villain” category—and Oppenheimer wasn’t about to name his already
beleaguered brother to thicken the plot.
The board’s three members voted 2–1 on June 1, 1954, to affirm the
suspension and deny the physicist a position as a consultant. Despite its
members’ professed belief in Oppenheimer’s loyalty, the board was troubled
by Oppenheimer’s “continuing conduct and associations.” Harking back to
his record with Chevalier, the majority report noted that the scientist “has
repeatedly exercised an arrogance of his own judgment with respect to the
loyalty and reliability of other citizens to an extent which has frustrated and at
times impeded the working of the system.” Moreover, they pronounced that
“his conduct in the hydrogen bomb program [was] sufficiently disturbing as
to raise a doubt as to whether his participation . . . in a Government program
relating to the national defense, would be clearly consistent with the best
interests of security.”60
Oppenheimer’s supporters strongly disagreed. John J. McCloy, for instance,
pointed out that “We are only secure if we have the best of brains and the best
reach of mind in the field.”61 Well aware, too, of the scientific community’s
distaste for the hearings, the majority on the board pointedly defended
themselves against the charge of “anti-intellectualism.”62 They needed to,
since many scientists were furious that Oppenheimer’s “enthusiasm” (or lack
thereof ) for the H-bomb was used as a criterion in the case. Nichols thus
urged that the AEC drop the issue of the hydrogen weapon as a consideration
in its upcoming hearing of Oppenheimer’s appeal of the security board’s
decision, focusing on the matter of his history and obfuscations instead.63
The AEC then rejected Oppenheimer’s appeal on June 29, with
Strauss joining three other commissioners against him in a 4–1 decision
59
Herken, Brotherhood, 287–88; IMJRO, 137.
60
“Dr. Oppenheimer is Barred from Security Clearance, Though ‘Loyal,’ ‘Discreet,’” NYT,
June 2, 1954, 1, 13.
61
“Counsel Defend Dr. Oppenheimer,” NYT, June 16, 1954, 18.
62
“Scientists Views Stir Panel Worry,” NYT, June 2, 1954, 17.
63
Polenberg, In the Matter of JRO, xxv.
once a communist, always a communist 193
64
IMJRO, 1049.
65
“Oppenheimer Loses Appeal to AEC, 4 to 1,” NYT, June 30, 1954, 1, 9.
66
“AEC Vote Bars Oppenheimer, 4–1,” NYT, June 30, 1954, 9; Zerubavel, Time
Maps, 40.
194 katherine a. s. sibley
that “no information was developed by this method indicating his contacts
with espionage agents or Soviet officials.”67
The lack of results did not stop the FBI from doggedly applying for yet
another wiretap authorization of Oppenheimer from the Justice Department
two months after the hearings had ended; the Department, meanwhile, was
considering the Bureau’s reports for possible action against the scientist. Alas,
sighed Belmont, “Oppenheimer suspects that his telephone conversations
have been monitored,” thus eliminating much chance for interesting
information. Moreover, “the residential nature” of his neighborhood hindered
effective surveillance, and monitoring Oppenheimer on Princeton’s campus
was no easy trick either. At last, he admitted, “the Bureau cannot anticipate
any great results from either the technical or physical surveillance.” The FBI
discontinued surveillance in October 1954.68
While the memory of Oppenheimer’s wartime behavior and even earlier
associations stubbornly persisted for officials well into the Cold War, the
Institute for Advanced Study’s board was happy to keep him as director
until Oppenheimer, by then afflicted with cancer, resigned in 1966. Joseph
McCarthy, ironically, had been disgraced the same month that Oppenheimer’s
hearings took place, and the Cold War had rapidly cooled off. Indeed, the
very year that Oppenheimer lost his security clearance, he was honored
by a group of black businessmen from the Pyramid Club in Philadelphia,
who gave him an achievement award.69 Despite the powerful narrative of
disloyalty the U.S. government created and nurtured about him, therefore,
Oppenheimer would remain a source of inspiration for many Americans
who had constructed different memories of his contributions.
67
FBI Newark to Director, FBI, July 13, 1954, 100–17828–1880; Belmont to Boardman,
August 24, 1954, 100–17828–1974; see also Hoover’s earlier request for a wiretap, April 26,
1946, memo to the Attorney General, 100–17828–29, where he justified the request based
on Oppenheimer’s “contact with individuals reported to be Soviet agents.”
68
Belmont to Boardman, August 24, 1954, 100–17828–1974; Hoover memo, October
15, 1954, Oppenheimer, Internal Security 100–17828–2072.
69
“Club to Honor Dr. Oppenheimer,” NYT, September 15, 1954, 19.
once a communist, always a communist 195
References
Primary Sources
Independence, Missouri
Harry S Truman Library
President’s Secretary’s File
Clark Clifford Papers
Washington, D.C.
Federal Bureau of Investigation Files
Communist Infiltration of Radiation Laboratories (CINRAD)
Klaus Fuchs
Steve Nelson
J. Robert Oppenheimer
National Archives
Record Group 233, Records of the U.S. House of Representatives, Special Committee on
Un-American Activities (Dies), Exhibits, Evidence, etc. re Committee Investigations:
Communism Subject Files 1930–1945.
Record Group 319, Records of the Army Staff. Army Intelligence Project Decimal File,
1941–45.
Record Group 319, Records of the Army Staff. Records of the Office of the Assistant
Chief of Staff, G-2, Intelligence, Records of the Investigative Records Repository,
Security Classified Intelligence and Investigative Dossiers, 1939–1976.
Congressional Hearings
U.S. House. Report on Soviet Espionage Activities in Connection with the Atom Bomb;
Investigation of Un-American Activities in the United States. Eightieth Congress,
second session. Washington, D.C., 1948.
——. Hearings Regarding Communist Infiltration of Radiation Laboratory and Atomic
Bomb Project at the University of California, Berkeley, Calif. (Identification of
Scientist X). Eighty-first Congress, first and sessions. Washington, D.C. 1949–1951.
——. The Shameful Years: Thirty Years of Soviet Espionage in the United States.
Washington, D.C., 1951.
Newspapers
New York Times, 1954.
Books
Albright, Joseph and Marcia Kunstel. Bombshell: The Secret Story of America’s Unknown Atomic
Spy Conspiracy. New York: Times Books, 1997.
Chevalier, Haakon. Oppenheimer: The Story of a Friendship. New York: George Braziller,
1965.
Craig, R. Bruce. Treasonable Doubt: The Harry Dexter White Spy Case. Lawrence: University
Press of Kansas, 2004.
196 katherine a. s. sibley
Groves, Leslie. Now It Can be Told: The Story of the Manhattan Project. New York: Harper
Brothers, 1962.
Haynes, John Earl and Harvey Klehr. Venona: Decoding Soviet Espionage in America. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1999.
Herken, Gregg. Brotherhood of the Bomb: The Tangled Lives and Loyalties of Robert
Oppenheimer, Ernest Lawrence, and Edward Teller. New York: Henry Holt and Co., 2002,
and website: www.brotherhoodofthebomb.com
Holloway, David. Stalin and the Bomb: The Soviet Union and Atomic Energy, 1939–1956.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994
Nelson, Steve, James R. Barrett, and Rob Ruck. Steve Nelson: American Radical. Pittsburgh:
University of Pittsburgh Press, 1981.
Polenberg, Richard, ed. In the Matter of J. Robert Oppenheimer: The Security Clearance
Hearing. Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2002.
Sandilands, Roger. The Life and Political Economy of Lauchlin Currie: New Dealer, Presidential
Adviser, and Development Economist. Durham: Duke University Press, 1990.
Schecter, Jerrold and Leona. Sacred Secrets: How Soviet Intelligence Operations Changed
American History. Washington, D.C.: Brassey’s, 2002.
Sibley, Katherine A. S. Red Spies in America: Stolen Secrets and the Dawn of the Cold War.
Lawrence: University Press of Kansas, 2004.
U.S. Atomic Energy Commission. In the Matter of J. Robert Oppenheimer: Transcript of
Hearing before Personnel Security Board and Texts of Principal Documents and Letters.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1971.
Weinstein, Allen and Alexander Vassiliev. The Haunted Wood: Soviet Espionage in America—
The Stalin Era. New York: Random House, 1999.
Zerubavel, Eviatar. Time Maps: Collective Memory and the Social Shape of the Past. Chicago
and London: University of Chicago Press, 2003.
RESPONSE
Dan Leab
1
James Nuechterlein, “In the Matter (Again) of J. Robert Oppenheimer,” Commentary,
October 2005, 55; Thomas Powers, “An American Tragedy,” The New York Review of Books,
22 September, 2005, 73–79.
2
Thomas Powers, Intelligence Wars: American Secret History From Hitler To Al-Quaeda
(New York: The New York Review of Books, 2002), 62–63; Jerrold and Leona Schecter,
Sacred Secrets: How Soviet Intelligence Operations Changed American History (Washington,
D.C.: Brassey’s Inc., 2002), 205.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 197–198
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
198 dan leab
however one may morally view the destruction wrought on Japan by the use
of nuclear weapons, the response to the reasons for the dropping of the atomic
bombs by such gifted and articulate polemicist scholars as Gar Alperovitz
and Martin Sherwin (which it seems to me had more to do with anti-Cold
War politics) is one with the discussion of Oppenheimer’s later supposedly
tragic situation; as Professor Sibley points out its roots lay in his political
feelings, however complex these may have been. Sherwin and Kai Bird in
their compelling, comprehensive biography of Oppenheimer maintain that
the scientist knew that “the atomic bombs” he had “organized into existence
were going to be used. But he told himself that they were going to be used
in a manner that would not spark a postwar arms race with the Soviets.” She
foregoes that tendentious after-the-fact insight.3
If Professor Sibley fails to address thoroughly any aspect it is that she
did not follow through on the public relations side of the debate over
Oppenheimer, and his relations with Communism and the Soviets. “Oppie”
in the many images of him which appeared in the press and on TV after the
AEC hearings until his death looked ascetic, frail, and worried—pipe in hand
or mouth. He did not present the stern visage of a Lewis Strauss or the rough-
hewn features of a Edward Teller, his prime opponents (neither of whom
even Bachrach could have made attractive) at the time when Oppenheimer
lost his clearance. Perhaps if he had more of their physical attributes his
standing as an icon would have been less likely. In the TV parlance of the day
Oppenheimer was “hot”; they were not.
3
Gar Alperovitz, The Decision to Use the Atomic Bomb and the Architecture of an American
Myth (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1995); Martin Sherwin, A World Destroyed: Hiroshima
and Its Legacies, 3rd ed. (Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2003); Kai Bird and Martin
Sherwin, American Prometheus: The Triumph and Tragedy of J. Robert Oppenheimer (New
York: Alfred A. Knopf, 2005), 314.
CHAPTER ELEVEN
E. R. Douglas
Summary
This essay concerns the intricate and multifaceted metaphysical relationship between memory,
intentionality, physical time, psychological time, causality, and the arrow of time. Specifically,
I argue that they have resisted scientific explication for very similar reasons, and I conclude
that natural philosophy can come to terms with them once several fundamental notions,
including directedness and transience, are clearly articulated and formalized. The implications
are significant for the philosophy of mind, the metaphysics of time, the cognitive sciences,
as well as contemporary cosmology and natural philosophy generally. This work moreover
highlights an important difference in the operative assumptions respectively grounding the
humanities and sciences.
1. Introduction
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 199–222
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
200 e. r. douglas
the clarity of the disparate issues and concepts at hand, but also motivated
by the humanities’ focus on the function of human agency in the pursuit
of natural truth, I claim rational grounds for drawing a synthesis among
the corresponding problem sets. So on the one hand, I attempt to explicate
such diverse terms as, for example, time, intentionality, causality, memory
and directedness—whose commonly understood definitions leave them too
ambiguous and/or obscure for an analytically empirical methodology. On the
other hand, while they prove under inspection to have a common conceptual
thread, its empirical credentials depend for merit on the acceptance of the
phenomenological relationship between the scientist and nature, or the
philosopher and philosopheme, as itself legitimately evidential. While this
step does not require an endorsement of Protagoras’s relativist claim that
man is the measure of all things, we must nonetheless accept that he remains
the measurer of all that we know.1
From the vantage of this interdisciplinary perspective, it becomes in-
creasingly evident that physics, and the scientific Weltanschauung generally, is
coming to a crossroads. While there remain many questions without definitive
answers, science as most generally construed now comprises a patchwork of
models and theories that collectively can speak to almost every conceivable
issue in natural philosophy. Yet, internal inconsistency abounds, and I would
further contend that at least mainstream science has overlooked a very
important aspect of nature. Illustrating for the nonce with a metaphor that
may yet prove more than mere metaphor, science has sketched the design of
the cosmos, but the blueprints reproduced remain monochromatic; whereas
nature in all its wonder remains demonstrably colourful.2 Nonetheless, one
can inscribe all the colours with a single ink—so the metaphor continues—
and though it is disputable whether one can thus entirely characterize their
natures, we should at least attempt such ‘scientific’ descriptions as completely,
accurately and truly as possible.
In particular, I nominate three classes of ‘empirical’ phenomena that
mainstream science has not sufficiently explored: consciousness, causality
1
Many scientists of course do tacitly accept this point, even celebrating science as a
product of a humanist cultural revolution against the medieval metaphysics that preceded it.
Nevertheless, there are no mainstream scientific methodologies that legitimize themselves as
objects of their study. Indubitably, the sophists would not approve.
2
This metaphor of colour may be more than a metaphor. In his argument against
physicalism, the philosopher of mind, Frank Jackson proposes a celebrated thought
experiment: Mary is a woman of the future who knows all there is ‘scientifically’ to know
about colour, but she herself is colorblind, and so limited to a physicalist vocabulary to explain
the phenomena. ( Jackson 1986)
facets of one ontological enigma? 201
and psychological time. With respect to the first, it has been widely objected
that purely physicalist, materialist and even cognitivist accounts can suffice
to explain away (mental) phenomena qua phenomena (and in particular for
our purposes, intentionality, but also notably, qualia or indeed the experience
of colour itself ). To the second, I ask: does causality as we perceive it actually
equate with a statistical correlation between events as stipulated in most
contemporary analytic accounts and, if so, how did the universe come to
be, and what would that even mean? Finally, the third begs whether ‘time’
really reduces accurately and completely in all its forms to a static tableau, in
spite of our manifest experience of temporality as profoundly transient and
directed.
Each of these three problem sets is marked by several possible solutions,
theories or philosophical approaches that one might adopt, some easier,
some ‘harder’ or, indeed, some considerably more ‘colourful’ than others.
The first and ‘easiest’ solution falls under the name of eliminativism in the
philosophy of mind, but it generalizes to all three of the problem domains we
are considering here. This view relegates all mental phenomena to instances of
mechanistic brain chemistry, but we may regard its cousin theories equating
cause with correlation and time with space respectively. The more difficult,
but more colourful—i.e., I contend, more ‘empirical’—approaches involve
wrestling with the underlying hard problems of explicating the emergence
and nature of consciousness and intentionality, temporal transience and
direction, as well as the metaphysics of being, becoming and causality.
Although I discuss some of the ‘colourful’ theories available to explain
the emphasized phenomena endemic to each domain of inquiry, my focus
throughout this essay remains primarily on distinguishing eliminativist
solutions—which at root simply expurgate their respective ontologies of the
problematic phenomena—from those that do not.
The ultimate thesis of this essay asserts that the apparent quandaries
of these three introduced problem sets are really each facets of a single,
underlying enigma, but I make this case through several lemmas or staged
arguments. First, I link these disparate concepts (time, mind, cause) by first
explicating their meanings and then identifying how directionality plays a
central role in the interpretation of all three; this comprises the remainder
of section one. Second, I remonstrate something of a collective bad faith
marked by a tendency in the philosophical and scientific literature to explain
the most difficult aspects of each of the problem sets by smuggling implicit
assumptions from the other two respective problem domains. This discussion
strongly emphasizes the concept of directionality and so also significantly
informs yet a quasi-fourth quandary of import to the natural philosophy of
202 e. r. douglas
time: the meaning, origin and nature of the arrow of time. This last matter
figures prominently in the larger problematic, for, in contrast, none of the
other ‘empirical’ phenomena I endorse (consciousness, apparent causality or
temporal transience) has aggravated especially physical scientists so much.
From here, I contend that while there may not necessarily be clear
a priori grounds to choose one class of explanation over another—i.e.,
‘monochromatic’ universe over ‘colourful’ cosmos—to explain the three (or
four) aforementioned quandaries, insofar as metaphysics motivates arguments
introduced in natural philosophy, the principles invoked for one solution
should be employed consistently across the other two problem domains. In
this way, I maintain an all or nothing approach to eliminativism in natural
philosophy; the cosmic models we endorse are either very colourful or very
monochromatic, there is little room for compromise. However, the stage is
thus set to revisit the issue of whether and how science should attempt to
explain the ‘colourfulness’ of the cosmos, and from this more global, human
perspective, I maintain a considerably stronger case presents itself for the
affirmative on the first question through a kind of logical inter-corroboration
of empirical evidence.
As for ‘how’ science should proceed, both the principle of parsimony and
this weave of logical association between problem domains support theories
able to resolve all the aforementioned difficulties synchronically. Although
I mention a few promising scientific attempts to come to terms with these
issues, a complete review of contemporary research lies beyond this essay’s
scope; notably, I have had to omit due consideration to ideas stemming
from Bohm’s implicate order—I could not do it the justice here it deserves.
Finally, I would conclude this introduction with a small warning: although
rigor is desirable, natural philosophy is neither mathematical nor empirical
per se, and the discourse herein is less an analytical proof than a metaphysical
sketch stencilled with plausibility arguments, all hopefully inducing further
dialectical investigation.3
3
Schulman analogizes speculative philosophy as “scouting” new terrain, leading the way
for the “heavy-tanks” of physics (his discipline) to follow. (1997) While I regard the military
metaphor as a trifle extreme, there is much to be said for philosophy that does not limit its
scope only to what can be proved.
facets of one ontological enigma? 203
4
The term, ‘rhealogical,’ is a neologism I introduce to characterize a class of models of time
that compliments especially Bergson’s use of ‘chronological.’ It avoids many semantic pitfalls
prevalent amongst temporal terminology by addressing the essential property of authentic
change (which I discuss in this essay). The etymology is both the Greek word, rhein, meaning
to flow (as in ‘time flows’), but it also nicely dovetails with the name of the titan-goddess Rhea,
who was sister and wife to Kronos, god of time. For further discussion on the nature and
significance of rhealogical models of time, see Douglas (2006).
204 e. r. douglas
5
Cf. Park (1996; 1972). Similarly, in the only article to address transience in Scientific
American’s most recent issue dedicated to time, Davies summarily dismisses it as an illusion:
‘Nothing in known physics corresponds to the passage of time. Indeed, physicists insist that
time doesn’t flow at all; it merely is.’ (2002)
6
The view I am confuting here is nicely summarized in Oaklander’s conclusion to his
refutation of A-series interpretations of time: ‘What distinguishes greater than among
numbers from later than among events? . . . only the relation itself . . . [which] is a simple and
unanalyzable relation. Thus, there is nothing that we can say about temporal succession that
would distinguish it phenomenologically from other relations that have the same logical
facets of one ontological enigma? 205
the direction of process. However, not wishing to beg the question before
discussing direction, allow me to propose another definition of authentic
change: a single token entity manifesting as two or more inconsistent types. In
the philosophy of mind, a ‘token’ denotes a unique and particular or singular
entity, whereas ‘type’ refers to a mould or form, such as the class of full wine
bottles with ‘Chianti-Rufina-1998’ etched onto them. In the example above,
the token is ‘this bottle of Chianti,’ and the two types separated by time are
‘full’ and ‘empty’ respectively.
While I choose to accept transience as inevitably involving an (onto)-
logical contradiction, there are many who impugn such impossibility as
absurd and, to their credit, not without good cause. In particular, a topic or
object of discourse only makes (scientific) sense if one can characterize its
nature in a formal language, whereas from an inconsistent phrase, anything
and everything can be logically adduced, with all the pragmatic inadequacy
this ‘explosiveness’ entails. Thus, the law of non-contradiction is a first law in
logic that one only perilously transgresses, and I suspect this accounts for a
good part of the reason why analytic philosophy has had such a difficult time
coming to terms with temporal transience (and perhaps love).
However, recent work in ‘paraconsistent logics’ suggests this law is not
inscribed in stone, though I have yet to find any of the developed logics
satisfactory for the characterization of transience.7 Nevertheless, there are
grounds for hope, for the contradictions in question are marked by the
order they are presented: i.e., while a full bottle may become empty, or an
empty bottle might become full—both of which are only expressible in
most logics as ‘bottle is full and empty’ or, equivalently, ‘bottle is empty
and full’—we only wish at most one of these contradictions to be true.
Thus, it may prove possible to control the aforementioned ‘explosiveness’ of
our logic of transience by introducing a non-commutative operator—e.g.,
an ampersand with an arrow—that delimits truth or satisfaction to some,
but not all, inconsistent expressions: e.g., in this instance, ‘Full(Bottle) &▶
Empty(Bottle),’ corresponding to ‘the full bottle becomes an empty bottle,’
could be true, but ‘Empty(Bottle) &▶ Full(Bottle)’ would remain false.
If this digression into formal logic seems a trifle pedantic to some readers,
I would assure them that it is difficult to overestimate its importance here.
properties. Nevertheless, succession is something more than its logical properties and we all
know what more it is although we cannot say . . . There is no further basis for the difference
between temporal and non-temporal relations with the same logical properties, they are just
different.’ (Oaklander 1984: 17)
7
For a good introduction to paraconsistent logics and the problems facing their
construction, see Beall (2004) and Priest (2004).
206 e. r. douglas
Figure 1.
8
Kant identifies both the issue of inconsistency and that of direction or order: “. . . the
concept of motion, as alteration of place, is possible only through and in the representation of
time . . . render[ing] comprehensible . . . a combination of contradictorily opposed predicates
in one and the same object, namely, one after the other. Thus our concept of time explains the
possibility of . . . motion . . .” (Kant 1998: B48–49)
facets of one ontological enigma? 207
Naturally, some of these arrows may reduce to or derive from one another, and
this list is not intended to be complete; our concern here is with directedness,
or its lack, and this becomes yet more transparent in the following thought
experiment. Suppose that after much laudable science, seven independent
asymmetries were discovered to remain: Which direction does time tend?
If each is thought to point in one of two directions, then there would be
7
2 = 128 possible combinations, and in only two would all seven converge.
The moral of the story is that ‘forward’ is trivialized as conventional,
and so most research on the arrow of time only concerns the asymmetric
distributions of properties across space-time; it says nothing about temporal
directedness. (Price 1996; Sklar 1974: 355–60) The only feature of time that
clearly incorporates an intrinsic direction is its perceived flux! Thus, we should
proceed carefully, for much like Augustine’s celebrated dictum about time,
that we only know it when we do not ask too much of it, closer inspection
similarly reveals directedness to be a surprisingly Janus-faced concept.
I have thus far argued inductively that these three categories are sufficient
to account for all physical instances of directedness, and I have conjectured
with some supporting rational that transience and the (directed) arrow
of time mutually entail one another. We may now turn to three further
methodological arguments, each respectively linking our conceptions of
time, causality and intentionality together into a larger logical-conceptual
synthesis. The first shows a general correspondence between models of
generative causality and rhealogical temporality; the second correlates such
causality with intentionality; and the third argues that our ontological
commitments to intentionality and time are strongly interdependent. This
sets the stage for the last section’s conclusions about the natures of memory,
agency, physical reality and time.
Figure 2.
Yet, we wish to explain the origin of the apparent direction and order of
the many causal relationships we commonly experience. Hume grounded
such structural features in temporality as he experienced it, which was
psychological, hence transient and rhealogical. (Hume, 2000) Similarly,
most contemporary theories follow suit, for as Reichenbach observed,
‘Time . . . represents not only an ordered series generated by an asymmetrical
relation, but is also unidirectional. This fact is usually ignored. We often
say simply: the direction from earlier to later events, from cause to effect is
the direction of the progress of time.’ (1958: 138–39) And, indeed, if time
describes a manifold with an engraved direction and includes every physical
event, it follows trivially that the said direction maps onto any subset of those
of events characterized in a causal theory or relationship. Thus, rhealogical
time suffices to account for the directedness of causality.
This state of affairs would all be fine and well, but the problem deepens
considerably when an origin for temporal direction is sought. As discussed
earlier, the physical arrows of time provide no answers, and a suitable
scientific account founded on a chronological conception of time has proven
sufficiently vexing, that several thinkers have rather attempted to derive the
latter’s structure from the ‘natural’ order and direction of causality. (Bunge
1959; Tooley 1997; 1999) Indeed, if we suppose the cosmos is composed of
some set of events arranged as a directed causal lattice, its order and direction
can be homomorphed back onto those events, introducing a directed structure
to time. In this case, two events are said to be ‘simultaneous’ if-and-only-if
they are identical or do not belong to any common causal chain, and an event
is said to ‘precede’ another if-and-only-if it precedes that other causally on
such a chain. Finally, the temporal orientation of an event corresponds to the
direction of causal relations to which the event belongs. Thus, the directedness
of an ontological account of causality suffices for a corresponding structure
of time.
facets of one ontological enigma? 213
O1 and O2, which in turn likely signify other memories or experiences, which
in turn refer to yet other objects, O11 and O21, etc. Ultimately, I postulate such
a chain of signification yields a web of objects, which at certain loci start to
take on the characteristics of physical events, E1 and E2, the putative referents
of memories, M1 and M2. When these events actually occurred—so the
theory goes—they left causal impressions on the brain, affecting brain states,
B1 and B2, though both are also affected by all the elements of the chain of
objects. Per our assumptions above, these are the two physically instantiated
brain states upon which our two respective memories putatively supervene.
There is then a web of relationships—which, in vivo, would be complex to a
degree beyond description—but isolating an absurdly simplified example, I
illustrate below the different kinds of directed relations to consider, namely,
intentional (unbroken lines), causal (dashed) and mixed:
E1 O12
O11
B1 O1
E2 M1
O21
B2 O2
M2
Figure 3.
Above, ‘causally’ related events (E), experienced states (S) and physical
phenomena of some asymmetric class (X) are all respectively simultaneous
at times (t). Such asymmetric ‘arrows’ are the closest contemporary science
comes to explicating causality, but they all fail to account for its apparent
directedness, whatever may be claimed.12 The alternative anchors our
12
Hawking writes, ‘The psychological arrow, our subjective sense of time, the fact that we
remember events in one direction of time but not the other, . . . [and] the electromagnetic
216 e. r. douglas
arrow . . . can be shown to be consequences of the thermodynamic arrow, which says that
entropy is increasing in one direction of time.’ (1993: 3) However, he never does tell how this
is done, as Price notes. (1995, 1989)
13
Freeman maintains psychological time is rooted in future-directed intentionality. (2000)
As Modell writes, ‘The emergence of a goal thrusts the organism’s past into its future.’ (2002:
facets of one ontological enigma? 217
22) Similarly, Peirce writes, ‘One of the most marked features about the law of mind is that
it makes time to have a definite direction of flow from past to future.’ (Øhrstrøm 1995: 133)
For further research that intimates a deep connection between time and mind, see Penrose
(1994), Hameroff (2001).
14
Cf. Schlesinger writes, ‘a spatial world in which time did not exist would be entirely
stripped of capacity to contain the basic ingredients of a viable universe.’ (1980: 18)
15
Cf. Leibniz’s comparison of the mind to a windmill. (1714)
218 e. r. douglas
3. Conclusions
16
This assumes a classical space-time. However, the relativity theories do not appear to
undermine my argument, for they do not address either directionality or transience explicitly.
The key difference is the Lorentz metric, which can be interpreted to mean time adopts an
imaginary value, and the fact that the “proper time” of a world line is determined by velocity
and accelerative forces.
facets of one ontological enigma? 219
Brain
Directed Directed
(Rhealogical) (Generative)
Temporality Causality
Platonic
Truths?
Physical
Mind Universe
Intentionality
Figure 5.
I have considered how these three doubled arrows coalesce and how each
finds resolution in the other. Thus, each individual plausibility thesis con-
tributes to a collective corroboration of the others, and it suggests strong
grounds that the directedness of causality, time and intentionality all share a
common ontological origin. This view has been espoused by others, such as
J. R. Lucas, albeit argued differently, but it has yet to be aggressively pursued.17
This results in great part, because so little is really understood about the brain,
mind and time.
Nevertheless, there are indications that a new philosophical approach may
be gaining momentum to uncover these mysteries. At this point, we are still
in the dark, and the best we can do is ask questions. However, these questions
are now being posed:
Time is the brain’s glue . . . The experience of time is a neurophysiological
construction that is generated actively within our brain, but how this
is accomplished no one really knows . . . the sense of time follows from
intentionality but the links that translate such a neural process into a subject
experience are unknown. (Modell 2002, 34)
Indeed, there is growing recognition that these ‘perennial’ mysteries are
related.
So, where does that leave us in this search? Firstly, I have argued that we
are in fact searching for a single underlying principle. Secondly, this suggests
refining the methodological approaches adopted in disparate domains,
that they better cohere and so support interdisciplinary dialogue. Thirdly,
17
Lucas similarly argues for an ontological integration of time, consciousness, and causality,
though not via directedness. (1999)
220 e. r. douglas
References
Beall, J. C., 2004. Introduction: At the Intersection of Truth and Falsity. In The Law of Non-
Contradiction: New Philosophical Essays, edited by Priest, Graham, Beall, J. C. and
Armour-Garb, Bradley. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Bunge, Mario, 1959, 1979. Causality and Modern Science, 3rd revised edition. New York:
Dover Publications Inc.
Čapek, Milek, 1961. The Philosophical Impact of Contemporary Physics. Princeton; NJ:
Princeton University Press.
Davies, Paul, 2002. That Mysterious Flow. Scientific American (September, 2002).
Douglas, E. R., 2006. Rhealogical & Chronological Time: a Titanic Marriage. Submitted to
Kronoscope.
Fraser, J. T., 1999. Time, Conflict and Human Values. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.
———, 1998. From Chaos to Conflict. In Time, Order, Chaos: The Study of Time IX, edited by
Fraser, J. T., Soulsby, P. and Argyros, A. Madison: International University Press.
———, 1996. Time and the Origin of Life. In Dimensions of Time and Life: The Study of Time
VIII, edited by Fraser, J. T. and Soulsby, M. Madison: International University Press.
———, 1987. Time: the Familiar Stranger. Redmond, WA: Tempus Books.
———, 1975. Of Time, Passion and Knowledge. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Freeman, Walter, 2000. Perception of Time and Causation through Kinaesthesia of Intentional
Action. Journal of Cog. Proc. 1.
Goodman, Nelson, 1977. The Structure of Appearance, 3rd edition. Boston: Dordrecht
Reidel.
Hameroff, Stuart, 2001. Time, Consciousness and Quantum Events in Fundamental Space-
time Geometry. In The Nature of Time: Geometry, Physics and Perception, edited by
Buccheri, R., Saniga, M. and Stuckey, W. Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
Hawking, Stephen, R. Laflamme and G. W. Lyons. The Origin of Time Asymmetry. Phys. Rev.
D 47, 5342–5356 (1993).
Hume, David, 2000. A Treatise of Human Nature. Edited by Norton, D. F. and Norton,
M. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jackson, Frank, 1986. What Mary Didn’t Know. The Journal of Philosophy LXXXIII, 5 (May
1986): 291–95.
Kant, Immanuel, 1998. Critique of Pure Reason. Translated and edited by Guyer, Paul and
Wood, Allen W. Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.
Leibniz, Gottfried, 1714; Monadology. Reprinted in Philosophical Writings: Leibniz, edited
by Dent, J. M., 1995. Everyman’s Library, Rutland VT: Orion Publishing Group.
Lucas, J., 1999. A Century of Time. In The Arguments of Time, edited by Butterfield, Jeremy
and Isham, Chris. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
McTaggart, John, 1908. The Unreality of Time. Mind 17: 457–74.
Modell, A., 2002. Intentionality and the Experience of Time. Kronoscope 2(1):21–39.
Newton-Smith, W. H., 1980. The Structure of Time. New York: Routledge.
Oaklander, Nathan, 1984. Temporal Relations and Temporal Becoming: A Defense of a
Russellian Theory of Time. Lanham, MD: University Press of America.
Øhrstrøm, Peter and Hasle, P., 1995. Temporal Logic: From Ancient Ideas to Artificial Intel-
ligence. Amsterdam: Kluwer Academic Publsihers.
Park, David, 1996. Consciousness and the Individual Event in Scientific Theory. In Dimensions
of Time and Life: The Study of Time VIII, edited by Fraser, J. T. and Soulsby, M. Madison:
International University Press.
———, 1972. The Myth of the Passage of Time. In The Study of Time, edited by Fraser, J. T.,
Haber, F. C. and Müller, G. H. Berlin: Springer Verlag.
Penrose, Roger, 1994. Shadows of the Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Priest, Graham, 2004. What’s So Bad About Contradictions? In The Law of Non-Contradiction:
222 e. r. douglas
COMMEMORATION
PREFACE TO SECTION III
Michael Crawford
1
Ricoeur, Paul. Memory, History, Forgetting. Translated by Kathleen Blamey and David
Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2004. p. 80.
2
Engel, Susan. Context Is Everything: The Nature of Memory. New York: W. H. Freeman,
1999. p. 44.
3
Ricouer p. 80.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 225–228
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
226 michael crawford
lend depth of meaning to the present, and thereby set an agenda to negotiate
hospitable avenues into the future. Perhaps paradoxically, it is a form of
memory that is designed to project from past experience into the future. It
is a re-lived or re-constituted memory that emanates from a fixed starting
point but is resurrected in periodic fashion, usually with hopes for perpetual
delivery (“let us never forget . . .”). Finally, depending upon one’s perspective,
commemorative events can be seen as imperfect vessels for the transmission of
memory. They are politically susceptible to flexibility both with regard to the
way in which the past is represented, as well as with regard to the intentions
articulated for the future. Temporally speaking, past, present, and future are
indeterminate even though the cultural accoutrements of commemorative
ritual are designed to relay the perception of immutable inscription.
Moreover, with the passage of time and generations, commemoration is
removed from the remembrance of direct experience to a recollection of
learned stories. In many cases the re-animation of commemoration stories
creates an empathetic category of synthetic or virtual “remembering.” The
empathetic experience curiously attains an arm’s length distance through
ritual. Indeed perhaps this is what makes commemoration of painful events
endurable. By eliciting an empathetic response, commemoration not only
speaks across time, but also entrains and employs emotion to rekindle the life
of a historical person, group, or event. The entraining nature of ritual within
an emotional context serves a potent cohesive purpose in communal events.
Not incidentally, the public event is rendered intensely personal when license
is granted for us to express emotion, to share thoughts, or to vicariously re-
experience historical sentiments and aspirations.
Commemoration, then, is neither entirely remembering nor forgetting,
and it is situated neither entirely in the past, present, nor future. It is both a
product of, and a strange attractor for, societal mores and behaviours.
Trauma shares attributes with commemoration in several regards. It
is sometimes large enough in scale to be recognized by a community, and
frequently it can only be redressed through formal community action.
Jeffrey Prager argues that traumatic humiliation and injury tends to be re-
lived rather than be remembered by the afflicted. As a consequence, trauma
assumes residence in the past, present, and if untreated, in the future. The
reiterative timelessness imposed by the engendered sense of helplessness
that comes with traumatic injury can best be broken by empowerment in a
forum that restores timeliness. Like commemoration, the distance imposed
by a formal structure of people willing to stand in for, speak to, apologize
for, or forgive past transgressions can help to sever reiterative timelessness
and thereby restore a modicum of normality. The Truth and Reconciliation
commemoration 227
4
Ricouer p. 404.
CHAPTER TWELVE
Jeffrey Prager
Summary
This paper argues counter-intuitively that psychological trauma describes not an event in
the past but a condition of the present. Trauma is a memory illness characterized by the
collapse of timeliness, when remembering prior experiences or events intrude on a present-
day being-ness. The social basis of traumatic remembering is defined: an a posteriori and
critical remembering of those who, either because of their presence (as perpetrators) or
their absence (as protectors) generate suffering. Trauma endures through time when, in the
absence of a reparative community, no capacity is available to allow for closure of past events.
If timelessness—the inability to demarcate past from present—is symptomatic of trauma,
then trauma’s cure requires the jump-starting of timeliness, and timeliness depends on the
existence of a community that colludes in the illusion of an individual’s current day well being.
How to restore to an individual the experience of the world’s timeliness? The paper considers
the conditions necessary for social redress, the restoration of community, and trauma’s cure.
Apology and forgiveness are described both as constitutive features of trauma’s redress and
as dependent upon the creation of a new liminal community (of apologizers and forgivers)
whose members are temporally demarcated from the past.
Trauma Defined
1
A version of this paper was presented to the International Society for the Study of Time,
Time and Memory Conference, Clare College, Cambridge, July 26–29, 2004. Original research
completed while in residence in the Redress in Law, Literature and Social Thought Seminar
of the University of California Humanities Research Institute, Irvine, Winter-Spring, 2003.
Special thanks to Stephen Best, Cheryl Harris and Saidiya Hartman, seminar conveners, as
well as to all members and participants.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 229–245
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
230 jeffrey prager
past; a then folds in upon the now largely without awareness or distinction.
Certain powerfully affect-laden experiences or events from before (that can
include mental disturbances) yield the for-ever collapsing of time and the
experiencing of the past as if it were the present, even when, in other respects,
the demarcation of a then and a now remains clear. Traumatic remembering
can preclude the possibility of a being’s unencumbered movement into the
future, as it can impede the potentiality of a group creatively responding to
a changing world.
Trauma, because of its timelessness, cannot be specified exclusively in
terms of properties of the past. While a prior overwhelming experience
or horrific event—a moment described as inflicting upon the sufferer a
wound (Van der Kolk, et al.)—is a defining condition for trauma, even that
depends on its post-hoc remembering. Nonetheless, contemporary trauma
research and theory tend not to emphasize trauma’s negotiated relation
between subsequent re-visits and prior experience, but give primacy to
the events or experiences of the past, seeing them as driving all subsequent
effects. In this spirit, trauma is described as an experience so overpowering
as to defy representation and symbolization. The result, it is argued, is an
inability to achieve a healthy distancing from the shock (Caruth, 152–3).
The failure of language to soothe and contain, portrayed often as a typical
feature of the precipitating occurrence, here is misconstrued as constitutive
of psychological trauma itself. Similarly, trauma is defined by the symptoms
it yields: photographic-like, veridical reproductions in memory, what have
been characterized as intrusive flashbacks, in which what happened becomes
belatedly recalled (Van der Kolk et al.; Caruth, 5). Among these scientists,
little interest has been shown in discovering the ways in which a present-day
“return to the past”—remembering—and the past itself may significantly
differ. They accept at face value the subjective experience of those who
describe this uncanny return to the past as if no time has elapsed.2
These characterizations of trauma, what Ruth Leys critically describes as
“the science of the literal,” (Leys, 229–297) insist upon the determinativeness
of the past on the present and assert that trauma’s meaning lies intrinsically in
the character and nature of the material event that sets traumatic recall (and
suffering) in motion. The victim becomes condemned to repeat, through
performance, the meaning and significance of the trauma since the experience
defies the capacity for representation or articulation (Leys, 266–7). By the
same logic, the power of the past, that which cannot be represented, has no
hope of mitigation. It is an experience without the possibility of closure. It
2
For an excellent discussion of the relation of trauma to timelessness, see Leys (229–65).
jump-starting timeliness 231
3
See Thoma and Cheshire, for an extensive discussion of Freud’s interest in challenging
traditional understandings of psychological causality when he suggests that retrospective
memory makes the “pure” retrieval of experience impossible. To that end, Freud, from an early
point in his writings, defines trauma in temporal terms, always mixing experience with the re-
working of it through memory. These authors argue that Strachey, Freud’s English translator,
often sought, perhaps unwittingly, to reinstate a more conventional understanding of the
primacy of the material event to psychological thought. Thoma and Cheshire cite Freud’s
original German in a passage from The Scientific Project (p. 410), along with a pre-Standard
Edition Strachey translation of it to read: “as a memory . . . which becomes a trauma only after
the event.” Strachey alters his own translation for later publication in The Standard Edition to
reflect both a consistent terminology for Freud—in this case, the term nachtraglichkeit that
he defines as “deferred action,” but that results in reinstating the primacy of past experience
on psychological understanding. In contrast to a view of deferred action as implying a kind of
latent festering that, some time later, manifests itself, Freud suggests rather that prior (external)
experience effects a person’s inner world when it later becomes re-worked in terms of feelings
of helplessness separate from the experience itself. See, too, Mather and Marsden.
4
To the comparability between individual and collective memory, Freud (1954a, 206)
writes in his “Notes upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis,” i.e., the Rat Man case: “If we do
not wish to go astray in our judgment of their historical reality, we must above all bear in
mind that people’s ‘childhood memories’ are only consolidated at a later period; and that this
involves a complicated process of remodeling, analogous in every way to the process by which
a nation constructs legends about its early history.”
5
While the idea of unconscious memory derives from Freudian thought, it is also worth
232 jeffrey prager
noting that non-Freudians, speaking from within different disciplines and intellectual
tradition, also posit knowledge as contained within individuals, acted upon, without a self-
consciousness of it, that while embodied within the person express his or her embeddedness in
a broader social universe. See, for examples, Pierre Bourdieu on “Bodily Knowledge,” Charles
Taylor, “To Follow a Rule,” Antonio Damasio, Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the
Human Brain, and Daniel Schacter, “Emotional Memories.”
6
Contrast this view, with that of Judith Herman, a clinician and theorist who emphasize
the ways in which traumatic moments determine the present. Herman, responding to those
who focused on a pathological predisposition to traumatic responses rather than to trauma’s
perpetrators, seeks to assert the centrality of the “crime” to trauma, not a “victims” propensity
to become traumatized. Laudable in itself, Herman nonetheless “overcorrects” by isolating
the event itself as the psychological source of trauma. For her, the “cure” is to recapture the
moment in as much detail as possible. She (175) writes, “In the second stage of recovery, the
survivor tells the story of the trauma. She tells it completely, in depth and in detail. This work
of reconstruction actually transforms the traumatic memory, so that it can be integrated into
the survivor’s life story.” Here, therapeutic cure requires a return to the traumatic event, “telling
the story,” to enable its psychological integration. While my emphasis on the environment
that sustains traumatic memory does not preclude an exploration of the past and trauma’s
perpetrators, it does insist that the multiple ways in which a trauma of disillusionment has
been sustained in memory need to be the objects of enquiry, not the detailing of the horror
of any single event or experience. “Telling the story” of trauma risks elision of the multiple
sources of suffering, including the social context in which suffering occurred.
jump-starting timeliness 233
Traumatic harm is understood, as Freud sought to make clear from his early
writings onward, not by a description of the external injury alone but by the
ways it becomes internally processed and remembered. He writes, “Man seems
not to have been endowed, or to have been endowed to only a very small
degree, with an instinctive recognition of the dangers that threaten him from
without . . . The external (real) danger must also have managed to become
internalized if it is to be significant for the ego. It must have been recognized
as related to some situation of helplessness that has been experienced”
(1954c, 168) For Freud “the idea of trauma is not to be conceived so much as
a discrete causal event [but] as part of a process-in-system;” a system comprised
of drives, events, precipitating events, “all playing out in the context of a
continuing struggle between an instinctive apparatus versus a defensive
apparatus” (Smelser, 35). The context of helplessness registers experience as
traumatic and on-going reminders of it keep trauma alive.
Trauma endures through time, it will be argued, when no capacity is
currently available to allow for closure, to enable the understanding of
the past as past, to permit the distinguishing between present-day acts
of remembering from the memory itself. Said differently, the context of
contemporary experience, in its deficiency, keeps alive in memory an earlier
moment of psychic rupture. Trauma is a function of the present failure
of the environment to provide safety and security and wholeness—what
Freud (1954c) adumbrates as “helplessness”—to buffer the person against
the intrusive reminder of a world neither safe, secure nor whole.7 Trauma is
the intrusion of memory, an occurrence that affectively, i.e., with emotion,
describes the failure of members of the community to contain against
disappointment the memorial experience of the person. In this sense,
psychological trauma is both a disease of the contemporary moment as well
as a social one, when an individual’s capacity to engage the world presently
and orient herself autonomously to the future is insufficiently enabled by
the environment. When these conditions prevail, memory intrudes and a
traumatic past dominates.
Thus, psychological trauma describes not a moment occurring in the past,
i.e., the experience of an instant of terror or horror suffered alone by the
7
On the experience of helplessness in infancy, see, especially, D. W. Winnicott, who I
discuss below; also, Martha C. Nussbaum, Upheavals of Thought, The Intelligence of Emotions
esp. “Emotions and Infancy,” pgs. 181–190.
234 jeffrey prager
rememberer. It is not even only the memory of such an instant. Danger may
generate instinctive reactions, whereby involuntarily instinctual responses to
danger link human beings to all animals. But autonomic response, at least
for humans, becomes meaningful belatedly, i.e., traumatically, because it is
re-experienced in memory and it is social-ized. When it manifests, trauma
is never an asocial encounter with the past; in fact, it is replete with an a
posteriori and critical remembering of those who, either because of their
presence (as perpetrators) or their absence (as protectors), generate suffering.
It is always, therefore, an egocentric experience of the profound failure of
particular members of one’s own community to provide and protect. It is
never impersonal and abstract (though it may become defensively understood
impersonally and abstractly, as experience-distant).8
Psychological trauma is characterized, on the one hand, by the memory of
a person or people who profoundly exploit the victim’s vulnerability and, on
the other, by the memory of those who disappoint by failing to offer necessary
protections, who fail to defend against suffering. Firstly, it conjoins the
sufferer with the memory of the perpetrator; i.e., the guilty party responsible
for the breaching of innocence, for the shattering of expectations, and for
the harsh intrusion of ugly reality against whole-some fantasy. Secondly,
trauma indicts in memory the victim’s intimate community—principally
mother, father or other caregivers—who, at the time of such overwhelming
experience, is felt to have failed to protect the victim. The wish, however
irrational, to imagine the world as complete and good, with oneself as safe
and secure within it, has been thwarted.
Disillusionment and harm are inextricably intertwined. When the
perpetrators and the community members who fail to shield the individual are
one and the same, disillusionment, of course, is likely to be more devastating
and the trauma more persistent.9 Physical or sexual abuse by a parent is one
8
For this argument, I am following the lead of others who distinguish between traumatic
memories whose origins are “person-made”, and not a result of natural disasters, like hurricanes
or earthquakes. It is likely that the experience of betrayal by others is a universal one to
trauma; nonetheless, the psychodynamics of abuse, abandonment or loss undoubtedly differ
in appreciable ways from “acts of God.” Especially because of my focus in this paper on the
intersubjective sources both of trauma and its repair, I limit my discussion of trauma to those
that result from intra-human interaction.
9
Think, perhaps, of those children of the perpetrators who have to endure both the love
of their parents and the guilt felt by their transgressions. Here is another difficult traumatic
“processing challenge,” now being explored extensively in terms of the German experience
during World War II. See, for example, Gunter Grass, Crabwalk and W. G. Sebald, On the
Natural History of Destruction.
jump-starting timeliness 235
10
Nicholas Abraham and Maria Torok, in essays included in their The Shell and the Kernel,
Vol. 1, Nicholas Rand (ed.), (Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1994) develop a similar
distinction to the one being drawn here between identity and identification. In “The Illness
of Mourning” (p. 114), Torok distinguishes between introjection (identity) and incorporation
(identification). “Like a commemorative monument,” she writes, “the incorporated object
betokens the place, the date, and the circumstances in which desires were banished from
introjection: they stand like tombs in the life of the ego.” Introjection is a gradual process
of taking-in objects, including their drives and desires, a process that both broadens and
enriches the ego, while incorporation is a secret, all-at-once moment, marking the (traumatic)
instant in which the process of introjection has ceased. “The prohibited object is settled
in the ego in order to compensate for the lost pleasure and the failed introjection.” Torok’s
formulation of incorporation describes, in her words, the origins of traumatic memory, a
description that corresponds to my own. My concept of identification also has an affinity to
Arendt’s description of fraternity, though hers without the backward-in-time dimension that I
emphasize. Fraternity, for Arendt, is a formulation intended to capture the experience of Jews
in the face of persecution. As Schaap (Political Reconciliation p. 3) describes Arendt’s position,
“fraternity becomes a bulwark against a hostile environment as people huddle together for
mutual support against the pressure of persecution. While fraternity often produces genuine
warmth of human relationships, however, it dissolves the ‘interspace’ between persons. In this
situation, what is shared in common is no longer a world perceived from diverse perspectives
but an identity predicated on a common situation.” See, too, Hannah Arendt, Men in Dark
Times, 1968.
jump-starting timeliness 237
dying amongst us, often yields a more sober understanding that the world,
indeed, can (and will) exist without us. But traumatic ruptures promote the
premature destruction of omnipotent dependency. They yield, in memory, an
experience of the community’s failure to indulge the illusion that the world
is there to gratify me. The living of life in the shadow of this failure means
that trauma cannot be placed in the past tense: the fear of its present-day
return, as Winnicott (1974) describes, shapes the person’s relationship to the
future.11
In place of omnipotence, trauma can generate a precocious compliance to
the external world, a premature abandonment of the illusion of omnipotence.
With the loss of a sense of the world’s provision of safety and security, the
individual may attempt to present herself (to herself, and/or to others)
as without dependent needs, as an adult (of whatever age) without a link
to her child-like feelings, as no longer needing a world outside herself to
provide a sense of safety and containment. These are defensive maneuvers
that seek either to preserve a sense of cohesion and capacity in oneself that
the memory is attacking, a “fear of breakdown” (Winnicott 1974) and/
or to protect those loved ones from the anger felt by having been, at that
moment, forsaken. By prematurely destroying the fantasy of omnipotence
that accompanies dependence, trauma interferes with the process, occurring
through the life-course, of the slow weaning from dependence and the
movement toward independence. This life-long enterprise is accomplished
through social relationships in collaboration, a community that only slowly
gives up the collusion with the person that the world is present because of
her making-it-so.
A scar, a permanent reminder that memory has broken through, marks
psychological trauma: a breach in the social “skin” has occurred, a registration
that wholesomeness has been violated (Margalit, 125). The scar constitutes
the record of a past remembered that, while never fully healing, nonetheless,
11
In this instance, Winnicott is describing a traumatic rupture that occurred so early in a
child’s life that “this thing of the past has not happened yet because the patient was not there
for it to happen to. Only in the transference, Winnicott (105) argues, is it possible for the
patient to regain omnipotent control over the fear because “the only way to ‘remember’ in this
case is for the patient to experience this past thing for the first time in the present, that is to say,
in the transference.” But as I argue below, re-remembering trauma in the context of a redressive
community similarly holds the promise that the victim can regain omnipotent control over
memory so that the past can be put in the past tense. A community whose members—the
victims and the guilty—jointly acknowledge the existence of the rupture—to-that-point
only remembered by the victim—serves to restart a process of living in the present for an
unencumbered future.
238 jeffrey prager
over time can ever better blend into the surrounding tissue. Its capacity to be
re-opened, memory revived, as a result of traumatic triggers, however, remains
ever-present; these triggers can instantaneously return the person to his past,
and disrupt, once more, the timeliness of the present en route to the future
(Stolorow)12 Repair, or healing, then, is not about the return to “the scene
of the crime,” a revisiting of the literal or veridical event or events signified
by the scar. It is rather the jump-starting of timeliness, the overcoming of a
pervasive and entrenched psychic commitment to the stoppage of time.
Unlike those who suggest that traumatic relief depends on a person’s
return in memory to his or her unassimilated past in the form of representing
and speaking it in an affect-laden language,13 it is, rather, the restoration of a
community that has disappeared and a re-engagement with an experience of a
providing-world that enables moving-on. Relief derives not monologically by
reclaiming one’s past through its representation, but dialogically by presently
describing to a listener or to a community of listeners who are willing and
capable of understanding both the breach that is now occurring and its
likely origin in prior disillusionment. The signifier, i.e. the memory, while
a reference to the past, cannot be undone by redoing the signified; rather,
its efficacy as an organizing principle for living diminishes when the social
world, by listening, presently reconstitutes itself on behalf of the sufferer. The
experience of “falling on deaf ears” results in the perhaps increasingly strident
insistence that someone pay for the crime or crimes of the past. When there
are no listeners, one begins to shout. Only when the conviction develops that
significant others “know the trouble I’ve seen” (or, obversely, that significant
others are no longer willfully denying either a traumatic past or its enduring
efficacy) does it become possible to appropriate past experiences on behalf
of the future. The burden of holding on to the past, sequestered in private
experience, for the first time, has been lifted. Now, past events are capable
of becoming integrated and mobilized to realize potentiality. But for this to
12
On triggers, see Robert Pynoos.
13
The renewed interest in dissociation, and its relation to trauma, expresses this particular
formulation of the historical origin of trauma. An unassimilated, unrepresented event,
inaccessible to consciousness, remains part of the mind’s latent structure. It manifests itself,
however, in dissociated fugue-like states, co-existing with conscious awareness but inaccessible
to it. In this rendering, trauma’s cure is the integration of dual mental states into one, making
experience that is now dissociated part of one’s conscious awareness. In identifying the problem
of dissociation, it was claimed, post-traumatic stress disorder and its relation to other mental
diseases like Multiple Personality Disorder could be better understood and more effectively
treated. For critical considerations of this prevailing model of treatment, and the history of its
origins, see Allan Young, Ian Hacking, and also, Jeffrey Prager (1998).
jump-starting timeliness 239
Trauma’s Redress
Its timelessness imposes its own demands, and challenges, for the possibility
of trauma’s redress, or repair. How to restore timeliness to a condition
defined by a psychic investment in preserving the past? How to have the
past acknowledged for its continuing efficacy, so as to reclaim from it an
unburdened present?
Trauma requires community for its repair. The scar’s healing-over cannot
be accomplished alone. Since the preservation of memory involves the re-
visiting of the experience of the world’s disillusionment for its failure to
offer protection, the social world presently, is responsible for redress. The
reconstitution of social relationships to enable repair is never a foregone
conclusion; the fabric of trust, security and protection is so exquisitely
delicate, especially when confronting one’s enemies, or substitutes for them,
that its restoration requires an equally fine re-stitching. In the same way that
psychological trauma is a function of a social community that failed, trauma’s
repair requires the social recuperation of omnipotence after its premature
destruction, in the face of those who originally contributed to the failure, or
of those whom all of mistrust and violation has become “entrusted.”
Put differently, the present-day community, invested in the work of
repairing a tear in the social fabric, is the receptacle of possibility where an
adversarial relationship characterized by enmity might become transformed
into one of civic friendship (Schaap, 5). “The commonness of the world,”
Andrew Schaap (2) writes, “is not merely revealed. . . . . but constituted
through politics since each perspective brought to bear on the world comes to
form part of the inter-subjective reality we inhabit. Friendship thrives on the
‘intensified awareness of reality’ that arises from such political inter-action”14
Precisely because the aim of civic friendship, in part, depends upon the jump-
starting of timelessness, this outcome cannot be foreordained: neither the
14
Schaap here is quoting Hannah Arendt on friendship, Men in Dark Times, p. 15.
240 jeffrey prager
according of forgiveness, on the one side, nor apology, on the other, can be
effected independent of an “agonistic process” in which the words and deeds
both of forgiveness and apology can meaningfully, at the end, be uttered
and enacted. The reparation of community cannot be achieved if the process
begins as pre-ordained by a presumption that it will succeed; to fore-ordain
the outcome precludes the possibility of achieving a new horizon of shared
understanding (Schaap, 4). Paradoxically, redress is achievable only when the
shadow of absolute failure constitutes real possibility, when the potential for
an even more permanent alienation between members is not foreclosed.
The community, in order for it to achieve its aim, must be comprised both
of the victim(s) and perpetrator(s) who meaningfully confront one another’s
different perspectives. If the guilty offenders are unavailable (or unwilling)
to present themselves in an effort to reconstitute community (and to restart
omnipotent dependency), others, with authority to do so, must stand in
for them. The redressive community in-formation is comprised, on the one
side, of those disposed to replace a stance of resentment or disbelief with
a disposition toward forgiveness and, on the other side, of those willing to
risk a position of defensive power and authority, non-accountability, now
oriented toward apology.15 Forgiveness, understood as part of this political
engagement, is not an achievement, a fait accompli, but a negotiated process
in which, over time, those who have been harmed develop a voluntary
psychological orientation in which forgiveness becomes possible. The
willingness to forgive the offenders develops not before they are confronted,
encountered, and talked to. Forgiveness is performed in real-time, not simply
granted.16 The stakes, of course, could not be greater but, as Schaap (105)
describes it, “the possibility of setting aside resentment, of comprehending
the other as more than one’s transgressor, must be allowed if there is to be a
place for hope and trust in the politics of a divided society.”
But forgiveness within community, if it is to occur, can only happen
15
Hieronymi (546) writes, “Resentment is best understood as a protest. More specifically,
resentment protests a past action that persists as a present threat . . . a past wrong against you,
standing in your history without apology, atonement, retribution, punishment, restitution,
condemnation, or anything else that might recognize it as a wrong, makes a claim. It says, in
effect, that you can be treated in this way, and that such treatment is acceptable.”
16
One is reminded once again of Winnicott’s formulation of the psychoanalytic encounter
in “Hate in the Countertransference.” Winnicott describes the confrontation between analyst
and analysand that, in the beginning, may mobilize in the analyst hateful countertransferential
feelings toward the analysand. These, in time, are sentiments that may become redeployed in
more loving ways. Yet this redeployment constitutes the achievement of a productive analytic
relationship. There is nothing foreordained in this outcome.
jump-starting timeliness 241
17
Margalit uses the term “thick relations,” as I am here, to describe relations with people
with whom we have a sustained, in-depth, historical relationship. Thick relations evoke
moral questions about the community while thin relations—concerns, say, about the abstract
individual—impose merely ethical considerations. We might think of African-American/
white relationships in the United States, and European/Jewish relations in Europe as examples
of thick relations. Here, the importance, as well as the difficulties, of achieving redress is
more pressing because of the interweaving—both past and presently--of communal histories.
Margalit argues that thick relations impose a standard of moral behavior, more difficult to
realize than an ethical standard concerning, say, the treatment by humans of animals where
thick relations do not obtain. In a similar spirit that stresses the especially complex and urgent
task of repair in a democratic society, see Paul Barry Clarke (118) who writes about “deep
citizenship,” suggesting the inextricable connection between care of the self, care of others,
and care of the world.
242 jeffrey prager
References
Abraham, Nicholas and Maria Torok. The Shell and the Kernel, Vol. 1. University of Chicago
Press, 1994.
Arendt, Hannah. Men in Dark Times. Harcourt, 1968.
Bourdieu, Pierre. Pascalian Meditations. Stanford University Press, 1997.
18
In a recent collection of essays Loss, The Politics of Mourning, D. Eng and D. Kazanjian
(eds.), there is an effort to valorize “melancholic history,” suggesting that its alternative, i.e.
“mourning the past, ” risks the past being forgotten. To insure that prior tragedies not simply
be lost to memory, a melancholic attachment to that history ought to be preserved. Not only
does this constitute a misreading of Freud’s (1954b) “Mourning and Melancholia” and his
definition of mourning, it also romanticizes the illness that was the focus of Freud’s concern.
Melancholia, it must be recalled, incapacitated its victims, denying them the possibility of
engaging the world presently, and resulted in their suffering unrelentingly. Used rather as a
free-floating signifier without attachment to the illness being described, the contributors to
the current volume idealize melancholy’s attributes. See Prager (forthcoming).
244 jeffrey prager
Caruth, Cathy. Trauma: Explorations in Memory. Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995.
Clark, Paul. Deep Citizenship. Pluto Press, 1996.
Damasio, Antonio. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason and the Human Brain. Harper Collins,
1994.
Derrida, Jacques. “On Forgiveness.” In On Cosmopolitanism and Forgiveness. Routledge,
2001.
Eng, David and David Kazanjian, eds. Loss: The Politics of Mourning. University of California
Press, 2002.
Freud, Sigmund. “Notes upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis.” In The Standard Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, X, The Hogarth Press, 1954a [1909].
Freud, Sigmund. “Mourning and Melancholia.” In The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, XIV: 237–260, The Hogarth Press, 1954b
[1917].
Freud, Sigmund. “Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety.” In The Standard Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, XX. 1954c [1926].
Hacking, Ian. “Trauma.” In Rewriting the Soul, Multiple Personality and the Sciences of Memory,
183–97. Princeton University Press, 1995.
Herman, Judith. Trauma and Recovery, The Aftermath of Violence from Domestic Abuse to
Political Terror. Basic Books, 1992.
Hieronymi, Pamela. “Articulating an Uncompromising Forgiveness.” Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research LXII (2001): 529–555.
Grass, Gunter. Crabwalk. Harcourt, 2003.
Leys, Ruth. Trauma: A Genealogy. University of Chicago Press, 2000.
Loewald, Hans. “Perspectives on Memory.” In Papers on Psychoanalysis. Yale University Press,
1980.
Margalit, Avishai. The Ethics of Memory. Harvard University Press, 2002.
Mather, Ronald and Jill Marsden. “Trauma and Temporality, On the Origins of Post-Traumatic
Stress.” Theory and Psychology 14 (2004): 205–219.
Nussbaum, Martha. Upheavals of Thought: The Intelligence of Emotions. Cambridge University
Press, 2001.
Prager, Jeffrey. Presenting the Past, Psychoanalysis and the Sociology of Misremembering.
Harvard University Press, 1998.
———. “Lost Childhood, Lost Generations: The Intergenerational Transmission of Trauma.”
Journal of Human Rights 2 (2003): 173–181.
———. “Melancholic Baby, Unrequited Love as Identity Formation, A Critique.” In Identity
in Question, eds. A. Elliott and P. du Gay, Sage Publications, Forthcoming.
Pynoos, Robert. “Traumatic Stress and Developmental Psychopathology in Children and
Adolescents.” American Psychiatric Press Review of Psychiatry eds. Oldham, Riba,
Tasman. 12 (1993): 205–238.
Schaap, Andrew. Political Reconciliation. Routledge, 2005.
Schacter, Daniel. Searching for Memory, the Brain, the Mind and the Past. Basic Books, 1996.
Sebald, W. G. On the Natural History of Destruction. Random House, 2003.
Smelser, Neil. “Psychological Trauma and Cultural Trauma.” In Cultural Trauma and Collective
Identity, ed. Alexander et al., 31–59. University of California Press, 2004.
Stolorow, Robert. “Trauma and Temporality.” Psychoanalytic Psychology 20 (2003): 158–
161.
Taylor, Charles. Philosophical Arguments. Harvard University Press, 1995.
Thoma, H. and N. Cheshire. “Freud’s Nachtraglichkeit and Strachey’s ‘Deferred Action’:
Trauma, Constructions and the Direction of Causality.” International Review of Psycho-
Analysis 18 (1991): 407–427.
Van der Kolk, B., A. McFarlane and L. Weisath, eds. Traumatic Stress: The Effects of
Overwhelming Experience on Mind, Body and Society. The Guilford Press, 1996.
Winnicott, D. “The Theory of the Parent-Infant Relationship.” In The Maturational Processes
and the Facilitating Environment. International Universities Presses, 1965.
jump-starting timeliness 245
———. “Transitional Objects and Transitional Phenomena.” In Playing and Reality, 1–25.
Tavistock Publications, 1971.
———. “The Fear of Breakdown.” International Review of Psychoanalysis 1 (1974): 103–106.
———. “Hate in the Countertransference.” In Through Pediatrics to Psycho-Analysis, 194–203.
Basic Books, 1975.
Young, Allan. “Our Traumatic Neurosis and its Brain.” Science in Context 14 (2001): 661–
683.
CHAPTER THIRTEEN
Summary
African Americans have two distinctly different past heritages: their African heritage and
their American slave heritage. They must recall and accept both in order to portray an open,
truthful African-American experience and an accurate cultural identity that they can honor.
Painter John Biggers and story-quilter Faith Ringgold, both African-American artists, weave
together contemporary moments of their respective eras with glorious and traumatic cultural
memories of the past to celebrate and pay tribute to the African-American experience and
cultural identity and to allow African Americans to embrace fully and with pride who they
really are. Each artist fashions a unique structure that assembles pieces of the here and there
and the now and then, that restores the flow of linear time from past to present to future, and
that generates a trustworthy and notable portrait of the African-American experience and
African-American cultural identity.
1
See Howard Schuman and Jacqueline Scott, “Generations and Collective Memory,”
American Sociological Review, vol. 54: 359–81, pp. 361–362, 1989, who define collective
memory as recollections of a shared past “that are retained by members of a group, large or
small, that experienced it.”
2
See Michael Fultz. Pride & Prejudice: A History of Black Culture in America,
videorecording, Knowledge Unlimited, 1994, who notes that “African-American identity
comes out of the context of slavery” and who calls that context “traumatic.” See Ron
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 247–259.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
248 ann marie bush
Eyerman, author of Cultural Trauma: Slavery and the Formation of African American Identity,
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001, p. 14, who indicates that “whether or not
they directly experienced slavery or even had ancestors who did, blacks in the United States
were identified with and came to identify themselves through the memory and representation
of slavery.” See Kenneth V. Hardy, an African-American psychologist, who says in The
Psychological Residuals of Slavery, videorecording, Guilford Publications, Inc., 1995, that
“slavery shades all contemporary experiences of African-American people.”
3
See Kenneth V. Hardy, The Psychological Residuals of Slavery, videorecording, producer
Steve Lerner, Guilford Publications, Inc., 1993, who describes the “silencing” of African-
American slaves as forbidding slaves to use their native languages and demanding they use
only English and adopt Anglo names and who says that slaveowners employed “silencing” to
“irradicate all sense of Africanness from the psyches of black people so they could be trained
to think of themselves as slaves.”
black in black 249
his students “to look to their own [southern rural] African-American and
African heritages for inspiration in their work” (Wardlaw 71). The mural,
a form of public art, proved a perfect means for his students and Biggers
himself to “inform an impoverished people of their history and to build their
self-esteem” (Bearden and Henderson 431).
If we look at one of Biggers’ murals, Shotguns, we can find these three
important motifs: the quilt pattern, the shotgun house, and strong, dignified
women. Each of these motifs brings together collective memories of the
African and the southern, rural slave heritages of African Americans and
works to join the past and the present.
Shotguns shows us rows of little houses arranged in a pattern reminiscent
of a quilt, and unquestionably, Biggers may be personally thinking about the
quilts his grandmother and mother made with quilt patterns passed down
from generation to generation of women who themselves or whose relatives
came from Africa and lived as slaves in the southern, rural United States.
However, the pattern is also reflective of Kuba cloth and similar African
textile designs that Biggers may have seen on his visits to Africa or in his
study of African art. Quilts originated in Europe, not Africa, but slaves in the
United States “adopted the craft and many . . . applied a different aesthetic to
their design” (Visona, et al. 503). African weavers of many tribes employed
a textile tradition in which “abstract, figurative, and geometric designs are
used separately and in combination” (Tobin and Dobard 41–42). Quilt
patterns created by slave women were surely those of the African textiles
woven in their homelands and lodged in their minds as memories which they
brought with them from Africa and which, having been passed down from
generation to generation of their families, have become an important part of
the collective memory of all African Americans. The quilt was an important
part of a slave woman’s work. She could make warm covers for her family
out of scraps of material. And although this study does not deal, as does the
study of Jacqueline Tobin and Raymond Dobard, with the quilt as a secret
communication of American slaves traveling on the underground railroad
to freedom, we can agree with Tobin and Dobard’s speculation that designs
found in African-American quilts “have been passed on from one generation
to the next . . . through cultural memories” (8). The quilt patterns that
appear in many of Biggers’ murals, certainly in his Shotguns, bring together
the African-American ancestral heritage of Africans and slaves of the rural,
southern United States through shared memory.
The second motif that runs through Biggers’ Shotguns is the shotgun
house, defined by John Vlach as “a one-room wide, one-story high building
with two or more rooms, oriented perpendicularly to the road with its front
250 ann marie bush
door in the gable end” (qtd. in Thompson 118). After considerable research,
Vlach notes that “the shotgun house derived ultimately from the narrow one-
room unit of the Yoruba . . . in West Africa” and that the design of the house
came to the United States by way of Haiti, a common path of the slave trade
(qtd. in Thompson 119). We can certainly see the similarities among houses
in Africa, slave quarters in the United States, and a 19th-century shotgun
house preserved in New Orleans, Louisiana, and can agree with Vlach that
the shotgun houses of the United States seem traceable to architecture
found in West Africa. Perhaps, slaves in the United States, responsible for
building their own quarters, drew from their cultural memory of houses they
inhabited in Africa when they constructed their living quarters in the United
States, and perhaps, freed slaves remembered the architecture of their living
quarters when they constructed their own homes after their emancipation.
In many parts of the southern, rural United States, African Americans can
still be found living in shotgun houses. This type of dwelling is a part of the
African-American experience of life and surely something that also connects
African Americans to their slave heritage and to their African heritage
through collective memories. Biggers can also make a personal connection
to the shotgun house, having been born in one that was built by his father in
Gastonia, North Carolina (Thompson 121).
The last visual motif we will focus on in Shotguns is the five women who
stand on the porches of the first row of shotgun houses. Each is holding a
small shotgun house and standing next to a pot for washing and for cooking,
and some stand next to a washboard. Their faces resemble African masks
(Visona 524), and their strong, straight bodies stand with dignity, as though
they are guarding the small homes. Surely, Biggers is indicating that women’s
devotion to family and their ordinary domestic work, keeping all clean and
nourished, holds the home together. The woman on the far right stands next
to an open door, through which we can see a bed, which may symbolize
procreation and continuation of the people and their heritage. Through the
doorway next to the woman to the right of center, we see a table with a cup
and bowl, perhaps indications that the woman provides sustenance for her
family and, more broadly, for her race. And on another level, Biggers has
said that women are “wisdom bearers” and that the shotgun houses are their
“temples,” so the women holding the homes are lifting up the people, lifting
up their pride in the lives they lead, the places they live, and the heritage from
which they have come (Kindred Spirits videorecording). Women of dignity
and strength project a significant presence in many of Biggers’ murals and
call to mind the African tradition of looking upon women as stately and
holding them in the highest regard.
black in black 251
murals, nearly all of Biggers’ murals tend to integrate both the traumatic slave
heritage and the rich African heritage of the African American and to project
positive, uplifting, beautiful images of the African American by drawing
elements from their collective memory.
Like Biggers, Faith Ringgold blends her personal life memories as well
as African Americans’ collective memories of their African origins and
American slave heritage into her work. Unlike Biggers, Ringgold, a feminist
and Civil Rights activist, exhibits a more confrontational disposition in her
art and blatantly exposes sexism and racism directed at African Americans.
She does not entirely exclude males in her art, but concentrates on capturing
the strength and success of African-American women, their courage, their
values, and their dreams.
During her career, Ringgold has created paintings, soft sculpture, masks,
and quilts—all leading to her most distinct and unique art form, the story
quilt. The story quilt is mixed-media art comprised of pieces of fabric sewn
together as a quilt on which she paints images and writes original narratives
in her own hand. The stories are imaginary, but based on events, some
historical, and dealing with issues that could actually take place in people’s
lives (Ringgold, We Flew 254). In her memoirs, she says, “My stories may
include real-life experiences that I have had—that I know about or can
imagine happening to me or to other people—but they are almost always
imaginary. None of them can be read literally” (Ringgold, We Flew 254), and
she goes on to explain that:
Most of my stories are about women and all of my narrators are female. These
narrators are fashioned after the women I heard tell stories . . . [when I was
a child and] sat quietly, so as not to be sent off to bed, listening intently to
the often tragic details of the lives of family members and friends told in that
way that black women had in my childhood of expressing themselves. (We
Flew, 257)
By creating narrators akin to those story tellers from her childhood, Ringgold
has, in her own unique way, kept alive the oral tradition of Africans and
African Americans.
If we focus on the woman at the head of the table in Ringgold’s quilt,
Harlem Renaissance Party, we immediately notice that the design of the
woman’s dress and the mask she holds in her right hand reveal an obvious
African influence. Further, these traits of African art appear as well: the
African textile design of squares and triangles; the bright colors; the overall
symmetrical look of the piece, with the narrative running down the sides and
complete squares framing the dinner table; and the polyrhythms evident in
black in black 253
her how she feel ‘bout being descendant from slaves? She come back at him.
‘How you feel descendant from SLAVERS’” (Ringgold, Matisse’s Chapel
135). The white man answers by recounting a story told to him by his father
about his grandfather’s trip from Europe, during which the ocean liner he is
traveling on encounters a ship filled with a cargo of slaves. After ending his
story, the white man says that every time he thinks of the story his father
passed down to him, he cannot seem to rid himself of the smell of the slaves
packed on the ship. And Great-great-grandmother Susie smiles with pride at
the generations of her black family who are seated around her now and who
were born and have died free. The narrative indicates that both whites and
blacks have to live their respective stories as descendants of slave-owners and
descendants of slaves.
Michele Wallace, Ringgold’s daughter, correctly perceives Matisse’s
Chapel as a story quilt “about mourning and death, at the same time that it
is clearly a celebration of a tradition of resistance and a legacy of hope” (24).
Ringgold exposes the trauma of her own family’s historical roots in slavery,
but generations of her family have lived in freedom, so we also see a death
of their bondage. They feel anger and bitterness, but they also feel a sense of
pride in who they are and where they came from. The hope is that they and
all African Americans will draw from their individual and their collective
memories, embrace their African and American slave heritages, and continue
to honor themselves and their collective identity as they live their story.
Concerning the art, we see that Ringgold has provided a unique voice
through her work. She has come a long way from her student days when
she was taught to copy the style of the white, male European masters (Faith
Ringgold videorecording). Just as African Americans, when slaves, blended
some cultural aspects of the dominant white race under which they lived
into their own unique mixed culture of slave and African heritage, Ringgold
has brought together Matisse’s art and the bright colors, patterned designs,
and polyrhythms of African art. The blend shows her own unique voice as
an African-American artist and the noteworthy contribution she has made
with her story quilt to the world of art. The hope is that African Americans
and the world recognize that African Americans have a unique culture and
a distinct voice generated by their shared memories, collected over time,
of their African traditions and slave heritage and that they have made and
continue to make significant contributions to humanity.
In Who’s Afraid of Aunt Jemima, Ringgold has taken the negative stereotype
of Jemima as the very dark, obese, uneducated woman always pictured with
the bandana around her head, always placed in the kitchen, always speaking
black in black 255
with the collective memories of a past slave heritage and an African legacy
common to all African Americans. Biggers’ murals and Ringgold’s story
quilts bring to mind two important periods in American and African-
American history—the 1920s, often referred to as the Harlem Renaissance
or the New Negro Movement, and the 1950s to the 1970s, known for the
rise of the Black Muslims and the Civil Rights, Black Power, and Black Arts
movements. During both those eras, African Americans were focusing on
who they were and how to portray themselves. They were accepting and
rising above the humiliation, brutality, and degradation they had suffered
under the trauma of slavery, they were emphasizing dignity and racial pride,
and they were advocating self-empowerment and self-determinism. During
those eras, African Americans not only re-collected shared memories of their
slave heritage, but they also summoned up collected memories of their more
distant African heritage and used both legacies with their own individual
personal histories to define and portray themselves accurately as a group.
During the Harlem-Renaissance, African-American philosopher Alain
Locke fostered racial pride by urging African Americans artists to study
the richness of African art and culture. Intellectuals like W. E. B. DuBois
and Carter G. Woodson, also associated with the Harlem Renaissance,
“encouraged pride by researching Black history in the United States and in
Africa to refute the allegations that the African race had bred only slaves and
savages incapable of contributing to civilization” (Turner xviii). And according
to Sterling Brown, Harlem-Renaissance artists and writers incorporated into
their works new ideas, among them “Africa as a source for race pride. . .[and]
the treatment of Afro-American masses . . . [and rural black] folk, with more
understanding and less apology” (qtd. in Turner xix–xx).
Harlem Renaissance writers, artists, and intellectuals promoted the idea
of African Americans recalling their collective memory, recognizing their
collective identity, accepting themselves for who they were, and establishing
a strong sense of self-worth that would carry into the future and prove them
esteemed contributors to humanity. John Biggers and Faith Ringgold are
among the artists, writers, and intellectuals of the 1950s through the 1970s
and beyond who have continued what began in the 1920s.
As we have seen, in Starry Crown, Biggers portrays three regal-looking
African women engaged in making a quilt and surrounded by a quilt of
stars, and in Shotguns, he creates a quilt pattern from shotgun houses, a type
of abode resembling American slave quarters, traceable to West African
dwellings, and found even today in the American South. Faith Ringgold, on
the other hand, has not used the quilt as a motif in her works of art, but has
black in black 257
actually created quilts as art pieces. Whether as motif or as work of art, both
have used quilt patterns associated with the patterns found in African textiles
and slave quilts. Biggers has also exposed the rich oral tradition in his murals,
most significantly in Starry Crown, and Ringgold has printed narratives by
hand on her quilts to keep alive the African and the American slave tradition
of telling stories. By depicting women as strong and self-assured, both artists
have identified African Americans as a proud and dignified ethnic group.
These two African-American artists, each in his or her unique way, have
specifically formed a bridge to the past by using the quilt and the oral
tradition so much a part of African-American history and identity. By raising
the collective memory of their people’s African legacy and American-slave
heritage to the conscious level in combination with memories from their
own personal lives, Biggers and Ringgold have spawned a trustworthy and
notable image of the African-American collective identity and have re-
established the flow of linear time from the far-distant past to the present,
which will continue to project into the future.
Figure Sources
John Biggers, Shotguns, oil and acrylic on canvas, 1987. 40 × 56 inches. Photo is by Dallas
Museum of Art and is found in Black Art Ancestral Legacy: The Impulse in African-
American Art by the Dallas Museum of Art, New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc., 1989:
200.
Woollen Textile, Kabyle, Algeria, width 41 inches. Photo is by The British Museum and is
found in African Textiles by John Picton and John Mack, New York: Harper & Row,
Publishers, 1989: 62–63.
Traditional Beembe House, Northern Kongo, Musonda Village. Photo is by Robert Farris
Thompson and is found in Black Art Ancestral Legacy: The Impulse in African-American
Art by the Dallas Museum of Art, New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc., 1989: 119.
Closeup of Traditional Beembe House. Detail of door and decorated façade of a Beembe
House, Musonda village. Photo is by Robert Farris Thompson and is found in Black Art
Ancestral Legacy: The Impulse in African-American Art by the Dallas Museum of Art,
New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc., 1989: 119.
View of Mulberry, painting by Thomas Coram. Oil on Canvas. Owned by the Gibbs Museum
of Art in Charleston, South Carolina. Photo is by Gibbs Museum and is found in A
History of Art in Africa by Monica Blackmun Visona, Robin Poynor, Herbert M. Cole
and Michael D. Harris, New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc., 2001: 502.
Restored 19th-Century Shotgun House. Photo is by John Michael Vlach and is found in A
History of Art in Africa by Monica Blackmun Visona, Robin Poynor, Herbert M. Cole
and Michael D. Harris, New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc., 2001: 502.
John Biggers, Starry Crown, acrylic on canvas, 1987. 59 ½ inches × 47 ½ inches. Photo by the
Dallas Museum of Art and found in Black Art: Ancestral Legacy: The African Impulse in
African-American Art by the Dallas Museum of Art, New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc.,
1989: 190.
Faith Ringgold, The Bitter Nest Part 2: Harlem Renaissance Party, 1988. Acrylic on canvas;
258 ann marie bush
printed tie-dyed and pieced fabric. 94 × 82 inches. Photo is by Gamma One Conversions
and is found in We Flew Over the Bridge: The Memoirs of Faith Ringgold by Faith
Ringgold, New York: Little, Brown and Company, 1995: 112.
Faith Ringgold, The French Collection Part I #6: Matisse’s Chapel, 1991. Acrylic on canvas,
printed and tie-dyed fabric. 74 × 79 ½ inches. Photo is by Gamma One Conversions
and is found in Dancing at the Louvre: Faith Ringgold’s French Collection and Other
Story Quilts, edited by Dan Cameron, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1998:
103.
Faith Ringgold, Who’s Afraid of Aunt Jemima? 1983. Acrylic on canvas, painted and pieced
fabric. 90 × 80 inches. Photo is by Studio Museum in Harlem and is found in Dancing
at the Louvre: Faith Ringgold’s French Collection and Other Story Quilts, edited by Dan
Cameron, Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1998: 81.
References
Beardon, Romare and Harry Henderson. A History of African-American Artists from 1792 to
the Present. New York: Pantheon Books, 1993.
Biggers, John. Ananse: The Web of Life in Africa. Austin, Texas: University of Texas Press,
1962.
Biggers, John and Carroll Simms with John Edward Weems. Black Art in Houston: The Texas
Southern University Experience. College Station, Texas: Texas A & M University Press,
1978.
Cameron, Dan, Ed. Dancing at the Louvre: Faith Ringgold’s French Collection and Other Story
Quilts. Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1998.
———. “Living History: Faith Ringgold’s Rendezvous with the Twentieth Century.” In
Dancing at the Louvre: Faith Ringgold’s French Collection and Other Story Quilts,
5–13. Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1998.
“Conversations with John Biggers.” Web of Life: The Art of John Biggers. On ArtsEdNet: The
Getty’s Art Education Web Site. http://www.getty.edu/artsednet/resources/biggers.
The J. Paul Getty Trust, 2000.
Dallas Museum of Art. Black Art Ancestral Legacy: The African Impulse in African-American
Art. New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc: 1991.
Eyerman, Ron. Cultural Trauma: Slavery and the Formation of African American Identity.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
Faith Ringgold: The Last Story Quilt. Videorecording. Producer Linda Freeman. Editor Alan
McCormick. Writer David Irving. Home Vision, 1991: 28 minutes.
Gates, Henry Louis, Jr. and Nellie Y. McKay, Eds. The Norton Anthology of African-American
Literature. New York: W. W. Norton & Company, 1997.
Hardy, Kenneth V. The Psychological Residuals of Slavery. Videorecording. Producer Steve
Lerner. Guilford Publications, Inc, 1995: 18 minutes.
Kindred Spirits: Contemporary African-American Artists. Videorecording. Editor/Photo-
grapher Christine McConnell. Executive Producer Sylvia Komatsu. North Texas Public
Broadcasting, Inc, 1992: 30 minutes.
Pride & Prejudice: A History of Black Culture in America. Videorecording. Producer
Golden Communications Association. Project Director Jonathan Burack. Knowledge
Unlimited, 1994: 28 minutes.
Ringgold, Faith. “Matisse’s Chapel.” Reprinted in Dancing at the Louvre: Faith Ringgold’s
French Collection and Other Story Quilts, 135–136. Los Angeles: University of California
Press, 1998.
———. We Flew Over the Bridge: The Memoirs of Faith Ringgold. New York: Little, Brown
and Company, 1995.
black in black 259
Schuman, Howard and Jacqueline Scott. “Generations and Collective Memory.” American
Sociological Review, vol. 54: 359–381. 1989.
Theisen, Olive Jensen. The Murals of John Thomas Biggers: American Muralist, African
American Artist. Hampton, Virginia: Hampton University Press, 1996.
Thompson, Robert Farris. “The Song That Named the Land: The Visionary Presence of
African-American Art.” In Black Art: Ancestral Legacy: The African Impulse in African-
American Art, 97–141. Dallas Museum of Art. New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc,
1989.
Tobin, Jacqueline L. and Raymond O. Dobard. Hidden in Plain View: A Secret Story of Quilts
and the Underground Railroad. New York: Anchor Books, 2000.
Turner, Darwin T. Introduction. In Cane, ix–xxv. By Jean Toomer. Reprinted. New York:
Liveright, 1975.
Visona, Monica Blackmun, Robin Poynor, Herbert M. Cole and Michael D. Harris. A History
of Art in Africa. New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc, 2001.
Wallace, Michele. “The French Collection: Momma Jones, Mommy Fay, and Me.” In Dancing
at the Louvre: Faith Ringgold’s French Collection and Other Story Quilts, 14–25. Los
Angeles: University of California Press, 1998.
Wardlaw, Alvia J. “A Spiritual Libation: Promoting an African Heritage in the Black College.”
In Black Art: Ancestral Legacy: The African Impulse in African-American Art, 53–74.
Dallas Museum of Art. New York: Harry N. Abrams, Inc, 1989.
CHAPTER FOURTEEN
Efrat Biberman*
Summary
Memory, it seems, is constituted under a temporal sequence. First, some event occurs. Then
the event is inscribed in our memory, while being represented as a former event. Any stimulus
like a particular smell, sound, word, or a visual image, can trigger the memory of something
that took place some time ago. Following the psychoanalytic discourse of Freud and Lacan, I
would like to suggest another way of thinking about memories in which they function in an
opposite direction, where an act that already took place draws its meaning from the future.
This situation can be fruitful in understanding both works of art and the collective memory
they evoke. I will demonstrate this claim by analyzing a work of art by Dganit Berest, an Israeli
artist, which deals with the murder and the memory of the Israeli Prime Minister, Yitzhak
Rabin.
The late Israeli Prime Minister, Yitzhak Rabin, was assassinated on Saturday
evening, November 4th 1995, as he was walking towards his car after a large
peace demonstration that was intended to increase public support of the
peace process Rabin had been promoting. Three bullets, shot at Rabin’s back
by a right-wing Jewish terrorist, wounded him severely and led to his death
a few minutes later. Rabin’s murder was like no other political event that
had ever occurred in Israel and could be described as a trauma. This event
constituted a turning point which ultimately led to a comprehensive change
of Israeli politics in general and specifically with regard to the peace process
and relations with the Palestinian Authority.
On November 4th, 1996, the date of the first anniversary after Rabin’s
assassination, Deganit Berest, an Israeli artist, published a work of art on the
front cover of a weekly magazine. Berest’s work showed a daily newspaper
dated the day before the assassination over which she had superimposed
a text in which she quoted the surgeon who had examined Rabin’s body,
* I would like to thank the artists Deganit Berest and David Ginton for their willing
cooperation in the writing of this paper.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 261–274
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
262 efrat biberman
described him before realizing who he was. The physician had written:
“An old man, wearing a suit . . . a very old man, his face is as white as snow”.
The inscription was traced by hand onto the editorial section of the
newspaper, which, in addition to several articles and a cartoon, included an
advertisement announcing the demonstration to be held the following day.
This demonstration was the very same demonstration in which Rabin was
assassinated.
In what ways can visual works of art represent or preserve traumatic events
that seem too traumatic to be embodied? In what manners can memories be
evoked and rendered by visual means? The subject of this paper is the ways in
which works of art capture the elusive nature of memories and specify their
unique temporality.
Berest’s work refers to several artworks from the history of art which
visualize political assassinations, and hence address the issue of memory. One
of the most famous paintings that come to mind is Jacques Louis David’s
Death of Marat of 1793, in which David depicts the last minutes of Marat’s
life. Jean-Paul Marat was one of the political leaders of the French revolution
and an associate of Robespierre. He had been stabbed to death by Charlotte
Corday while taking a bath. The dying Marat is holding a petition given to him
by Corday. David depicts Marat as a young suffering man, in a manner that
shows his great sympathy and admiration towards him. Thus, the painting is
obviously a memorial for Marat by David, his friend and admirer.
Death of Marat can be regarded as a narrative painting, describing a
historical event, which began several minutes before the represented scene
occurred. The painting thus pertains to the connection between time and
memory in two ways, as a memorial for a historical event and as a painting
representing a temporal sequence by means of one image. Besides, the painting
directly represents the remembered event and hence can be regarded as a
visual repetition of that event. In this sense, the painting connects memory
and repetition. The act of repeating is a way of remembering in which certain
aspects of the event are stressed. In the case of Marat, David stresses Marat’s
appearance as a martyr, which, according to various interpretations alludes to
other pictorial representations of martyrdom.1
A radically different state of affairs pertains to Berest’s work. This artwork
does not, at first glance at least, seem to repeat any part of the traumatic event
to which it refers. Furthermore, there seems to be no narrative, or explicit
description of the act of assassination, or any evident linear time sequence.
1
Among the interpretations some refer to visualizations of the decent from the cross, while
others suggest allusions to Francisco de Zurbaran’s St. Serapion, of 1628.
264 efrat biberman
Yet, this work, which at first sight seems very enigmatic and puzzling, has a
tremendous effect upon the viewer and clearly deals with memory, time and
temporal ordering. What kind of memory does it evoke? In what way, if any,
does it capture the elusive nature of specific memories and their relation to
time and temporal ordering?
Memory seems to be determined by means of a temporal sequence. First,
some event occurs. Then the event is inscribed in our memory, represented
as an event in the past. Any stimulus, a particular smell, sound or word, can
trigger the memory of something that took place some time ago. The same
is true with regard to images: seeing an old photograph, or encountering a
familiar landscape may awaken a memory from the past.
Do memories necessarily function only in one direction, evoking
something of the past? In this paper, which focuses on the visual arts, I would
like to suggest another way of thinking about memories where they function
in the opposite direction. An act that took place some time ago receives its
meaning at a future point in time. In this sense, the future constructs the
past.2 This temporality could facilitate an understanding of both the works
of art and the memory they evoke. Moreover, reversed time ordering assumes
a kind of temporality which is not necessarily progressive and accumulative
and thus coheres with the visual field. That is, the traditional discourse on
the temporality of visual images has stressed the restricted temporality
of paintings. Reversed time ordering may subvert the fundamental
differentiation between space and time, and hence suggests an alternative
way of thinking about time in relation to visual images.
The theoretical bases for my argument are Freud’s concepts of “screen
memories” and “deferred action” and Lacan’s development of these concepts.
Although Freud used these terms to explain how a trauma functions, I suggest
that a similar concept of temporality may shed light on works of art.
Before addressing the psychoanalytical discourse, I would like to consider
another painting, which refers to Rabin’s assassination. In 2001, the Israeli
artist David Ginton painted a picture called Back of a painting: Date,
Rabin and the Blindram stretcher. The painting depicts the back of a canvas,
showing the oil stains, which permeated from the front of the canvas, the
wooden stretcher, and the folded edges of the cloth. Although the surface
of the painting is hidden, the painting provides the viewer with two hints
about its subject matter: the assassination date of November 4th is written
2
Slavoj Zizek describes that state of affairs in his paper “The Truth Arises from
Misrecognition”. In Lacan and the Subject of Language. Edited by Ellie Ragland-Sullivan and
Mark Bracher. London: Routledge, 1990.
266 efrat biberman
sloppily on the back of the canvas.3 Another hint is the title of the painting,
which alludes to a painting by the nineteenth century American painter
John Frederick Peto. In 1898, Peto, known for his trompe-l’oeil paintings,
painted a picture entitled Lincoln and the Phleger Stretcher, referring to the
assassination of Abraham Lincoln. Like Ginton in 2001, Peto painted the
back of a canvas, with a painted portrait of Lincoln attached to its frame. In
addition to Lincoln, the title of the painting refers to the craftsman Phleger,
who made the stretcher in Peto’s painting. Similarly, Ginton’s title refers to
Blindram, the manufacturer of his stretcher.
At first sight, there is no apparent connection between Berest’s and
Ginton’s artworks, except for the fact that they both allude to the same
historical event. Formally, technically and stylistically, they are completely
different. Yet, despite the different styles and media, both works share some
common features: they both feature a minimum of information and they
both say little explicitly. In both works the allusion to the assassination is
implicit. Both works contain inscriptions, and relate to Rabin’s assassination
by means of an object with the date of the event: the newspaper page that
appeared the day before the event and the painting that was allegedly painted
on that day. As their background, both works use an object treated in a way
that deviates from the way this object is usually used. Specifically, the canvas
is reversed, and the newspaper has writing all over it. Both works convey
something that is enigmatic and minimal. In a way, the act of conveying
meaning is in effect also an act of obscuring meaning: in Ginton’s case, he
shows us something hidden; in Berest’s case, the seemingly casual text uttered
by the physician is presented as a riddle to be deciphered. But in both cases,
the veiling is multiplied. In addition to the act of reversing, Ginton plays
the old trompe-l’oeil trick, letting the viewer suppose he is encountering an
actual reversed painting, that was mistakenly hung backwards. Berest reveals
a fragment of a fairy tale to the beholder. Hence, both Berest and Ginton
pacify the viewer, as if saying to her that “we are hiding something, but it is
actually a joke, or a naïve fairy tale”. Yet, the effect of these two artworks on
the viewer is tremendously shocking. The act of hiding seems more obscure
when we take the historical context of these artworks into account: the
trigger of these works was, no doubt, Rabin’s assassination. Their manifest
content, nevertheless, does not cherish the memory of Rabin but effaces it.
However, is this really the case? What is the function of these multiple layers
of veiling, and what is there to be hidden? Moreover, why is such a traumatic
3
According to Ginton, this inscription also alludes to a sticker, noting the date 4.11.95,
which was distributed after Rabin’s murder and was attached to back of cars.
remembering the future 267
David Ginton, Back of a painting: Date, Rabin and the Blindram stretcher, 2001.
Private collection.
268 efrat biberman
and significant event disguised and thereby denied? In many cases, the act of
interpreting art amounts to deciphering a puzzle presented by the painter.
The interpreter aims to reveal some hidden information that was overlooked
by the spectator at first glance. In Berest’s and Ginton’s respective cases, the
artists themselves seem to be exposing the act of disguising, as if blocking the
possibility of elucidating any meaning.
I would like to argue that this multi-layered hiding cannot be distinguished
from another crucial aspect of these two art works, which is the temporal
order they present. In Death of Marat, the temporality is constructed by
means of the narrative partially represented in the painting, which the viewer
is required to complete. Berest and Ginton unfold temporality in a different
manner. In a personal communication about this work, Berest noted the
following: “The thing that was most important for me was recreating the
moment of “not knowing”, the moment that precedes knowing, which
coexists and yet conflict with the doctor’s retroactive realization. This
impossible moment is allegedly hung in space, happens simultaneously
on the newspaper page in which the advertisement which announces the
demonstration is published, and in the deferred moment of looking at the
corpse without recognizing its identity”. Berest’s work hence simultaneously
presents several complex time sequences in which time goes back and forth:
the newspaper from the day before the event, the announcement of a future
demonstration, the doctor’s testimony that precedes identification. Besides
these temporal sequences, the artwork presents an “impossible moment” of
not knowing, a moment excluded from any historical time duration. That
impossibility is heightened since the newspaper page from the day Rabin
was assassinated represents a day that allegedly did not occur, that is, a day
without any journalistic representation, since newspapers do not appear on
Saturdays in Israel.
Ginton’s work also seems to present a complex temporal sequence. As
in any trompe-l’oeil painting, the viewer, who at first sight believes that she
is encountering an actual object, does not see the painting and its dazzling
effect. She believes that she is standing in front of an actual picture that was
hung wrongly. Only when she becomes aware of the deceit does the viewer see
the painting per se. However, she now sees it apart from its pictorial essence.
But Ginton’s work has its complex time ordering for another reason: In a
way, the work attains its meaning from Peto’s earlier painting dated 1898,
and hence conveys a linear temporality. But Peto’s painting itself deals with
memory. Ginton makes use of Peto’s recollections in order to remember an
event which takes place 130 years later.
remembering the future 269
4
Freud, Sigmund, “Screen memories,” in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological
Works of Sigmund Freud, edited by James Strachey (London: Hogarth Press, 1899), Vol. III,
p. 306.
5
Ibid., p. 307.
270 efrat biberman
6
Jean Laplanche and Jean-Bertrand Pontalis, The Language of Psychoanalysis, translated by
D. Nicholson-Smith (London: Karnac Books, 1988 [1973]), pp. 203–204.
7
Lacan distinguishes between the look as an act of the subject’s eye and the gaze, which is
a lost object that can never be represented. According to Lacan, there is a fundamental split
remembering the future 271
between the eye and the gaze. Lacan, Jacques, The Four Fundamental Concepts of Psychoanalysis:
The Seminar of Jacques Lacan, Book XI, translated by Alan Sheridan (New York and London:
W.W. Norton and Company, 1998), pp. 67–119.
8
Lacan, Jacques, The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book I: Freud’s Papers on technique 1953–
1954. Translated by John Forrester (New York and London: W.W. Norton and Company,
1988), p. 158.
272 efrat biberman
man’s look is fixed on the wolves he remembers nothing of the primal scene.
Only after the analytic session does he relate this gaze to his own look years
earlier as he watched his parents having sexual intercourse. In this sense,
the repressed returns from the future, and not from its position in the past.
Moreover, Lacan notes that “. . . Wiener posits two beings each of whose
temporal dimension moves in the opposite direction from the other. To be
sure, that means nothing, and that is how things, which mean nothing all
of a sudden, signify something, but in a quite different domain. If one of
them sends a message to the other, for example a square, the being going in
the opposite direction will first of all see the square vanishing, before seeing
the square. That is what we see as well. The symptom initially appears to us
as a trace, which will only ever be a trace, one which will continue not to
be understood until the analysis has got quite a long way, and until we have
discovered its meaning”.9
While analyzing the implications of such temporality, Slovoj Zizek
stresses the inverted temporal order suggested by Lacan, which in a way
resembles science fiction stories. He argues that “. . . the Lacanian answer to
the question, from where does the repressed return, is paradoxically: from the
future. Symptoms are meaningless traces; their meaning is not discovered,
excavated from the hidden depth of the past, but constructed retroactively.
The analysis produces the truth, i.e., the signifying frame which gives to the
symptoms their symbolic place and meaning . . . [T]he meaning of these
traces is not given; it changes continually with the transformations of the
signifier’s network. Every historical rupture, every advent of a new master
signifier, changes retroactively the meaning of all tradition, restructures the
narration of the past, makes it readable in another, new way. Thus things
which don’t make any sense suddenly mean something, but in an entirely
other domain”.10
In what sense could this notion of inverted temporality be applied to
Berest’s work? Berest’s work challenges any way of considering time ordering.
The background of the work, which is the page from the newspaper from the
day before the murder, and the words uttered by the physician minutes after
the assassination are both visible, while the traumatic event itself is concealed.
But this cannot exhaust the complex temporality of the artwork, since every
9
Ibid., ibid.
10
Slavoj Zizek, “The Truth Arises from Misrecognition,” in Lacan and the Subject of
Language, edited by Ellie Ragland-Sullivan and Mark Bracher (London: Routledge, 1991),
pp. 188–189.
remembering the future 273
11
One can think in this respect of the newspaper article titles as they appear in the
background of the work. For instance, the headline article on the newspaper page is entitled
“Why was it a success”, another title is “Virtual celebrity”. These titles gain new meaning in
retrospect, besides their original context.
12
Lacan, Jacques, Seminar XIV: The logic of phantasy, translated by Cormac Gallagher
(Unpublished, 1966–1967), p. 116.
274 efrat biberman
In conclusion, the purpose of this paper was to define the unique way
memories and their relation to time and temporal sequence can be embodied
by works of visual art, and to show how this treatment of temporality subverts
the traditional differentiation between spatial and temporal media. However,
one cannot avoid the political implications of the specific subject matter of
Berest’s work. Using Lacan’s terms, Berest’s work sends us a message from a
temporal dimension that moves in the opposite direction from ours. Hence,
her work first appears to us as a vanishing trace the reason for which only
appears later, and at the same time, the work’s elusive temporality allows us
to think of an alternative future, which could have existed but never did. The
work enables us to glimpse this lost future, while the flickering and fleeting
image of this lost future makes reality mean.
RESPONSE
Shirley Sharon-Zisser
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 275–276.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
276 shirley sharon-zisser
form would show [them] dead” (Sonnet # 108 line 14), made possible by the
graphic space common to poetry and painting? In Seminar 14, Lacan shows
that graphic space enables the representation of chains of signifiers just as
much as of objects appearing as an excluded remainder with respect to those
chains. What might be the logic of time and memory with regard to a non-
representable object-hole be in three-dimensional art, a common medium
for monumental commemoration? What form might this logic take in the
spoken arts (such as theater) where vocalized signifiers necessarily appear in
a chain that does not allow phonemes to fall? Such are some of the intriguing
questions opened up by Efrat Biberman’s ground-breaking study.
References
Lacan, Jacques. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan Book 14: The Logic of Phantasy (1966–1967).
Trans. Cormac Gallagher from unedited French Typescripts. (Unpublished).
Shakespeare, William. The Complete Sonnets and Poems. Ed. Collin Burrow. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 2002.
RESPONSE
Robert Belton
1
Efrat Biberman, “You never look at me from the place from which I see you,” Imagendering
11 (2005): http://www.genderforum.uni-koeln.de/imagendering/biberman.html.
2
For example, Iakov Levi and Luigi Previdi, “Killing God: From the Assassination of Moses
to the Murder of Rabin,” Agora 4 (2000): http://www.geocities.com/psychohistory2001/
KillingGod.html.
3
Biberman, paragraph 11.
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 277–278.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
278 robert belton
4
Robert Belton, “Hermeneutic spiral,” Sights of Resistance, online glossary, http://www.
uofcpress.com/Sights/toc_hl.html.
CHAPTER FIFTEEN
Carmen Leccardi
Summary
Memory is not only that exquisitely suggestive and secret dimension, the basis of one’s
identity, with which we are intimately familiar, but it is also a cultural product in the proper
sense, which takes form, becomes structured and changes with time and in social space. Both
remembering and forgetting can be considered social actions in the proper sense, enacted on
the basis of mechanisms of selection which at one and the same time make it possible to mold
a given representation of the past and to transform it into an essential tool of belonging and
of identity. Like memory, also gratitude (as Simmel highlighted) can be considered, from a
sociological point of view, an instrument of cohesion and continuity of social life. The aim
of the paper is to analyze the characteristics and potential of collective memory and gratitude
thus viewed, through the empirical data of research into young people’s attitudes towards
work in southern Italy.
Introduction
Memory is not only that uniquely subjective and secret dimension with
which we are intimately familiar, the very basis of our identity, nor
can it be considered a simple “repository” of the past (Schwartz, 1982;
Schudson, 1989; Jedlowski, 2001; Zerubavel, 2004). The past, in fact, is not
‘reconstructed’ with perfect fidelity from memory, but rather, it is redefined
and restructured on the basis of precise selection mechanisms, in function
with the needs of the present that are always different.1 In particular, if we
look at memory from a sociological point of view, we can affirm that it is a
cultural production in its true sense, that it takes its form, is structured and
changes over social time and space.
Sociological studies of memory, that have flourished particularly over the
past decades in the wake of the pioneering work performed by Halbwachs in
the first half of the Twentieth century, have underscored how remembering,
1
“The past structures the present through its legacy, but it is the present that selects this
legacy, preserving some aspects and forgetting others, and which constantly reformulates our
image of this past by repeatedly recounting the story” ( Jedlowski, 2001: 41).
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 279–302.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
280 carmen leccardi
2
The research was performed in the first half of the Nineties in Calabria: during that
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 281
will try to prove, is the fruit of the conjunction of two different factors. On
the one hand, the family is recognized as a central agency and institution, that
is capable of constructing memory and of guaranteeing its intergenerational
passage. On the other hand, the importance of gratitude (Simmel, 1908/1964),
understood as moral and social feeling at the same time, is expressed by the
young people toward the preceding generations. Analogously to memory,
this appears able to resist the wear of time, reinforcing interpersonal and
group bonds, here specifically the bonds between the parents’ generation and
that of their children.
This chapter is divided into three parts. The first contains an examination
of the salient characteristics of collective memory and of family memory,
which represents one of its branches. The second provides an analysis
of the sociological concept of gratitude, elaborated by Simmel, with the
intention of showing how this sentiment, not unlike collective memory, can
be considered an instrument that serves to bridge cultural discontinuities.
The third and last part is dedicated to the role played by the union of family
memory and gratitude in the formation of the work culture of young people
in Calabria, one of the regions of Southern Italy that is most disadvantaged
from an economic point of view, but characterized by a young population
that is becoming more and more educated and rich in innovative potential
(Fantozzi, 2003).
“We are never alone . . . our most individual memories are closely dependent
on the group in which we live.” Thus French psychologist Paul Fraisse (1957:
168) wrote in the Fifties, referring to the mechanisms of individual memory.
His theoretical reference, explicitly mentioned in the text, is Maurice
Halbwachs. Halbwachs’ work on the social dimension of memory3—
developed in the period between the Twenties and the Forties (Halbwachs,
1925/1976; 1941/1971; 1951/1968)4—had a profound effect on the social
sciences and continues to be an influence even if it is not homogeneously
divided among the different areas involved.5
Halbwachs, a fervent follower of Durkheim’s line of thought, has the
great merit of having delivered the theme of memory from an analytical
approach limited to an individual key—of which Bergson was considered
the most authoritative spokesman at that time—making it a specific subject
of sociological reflection. According to this scholar, in a nutshell, there is
a collective organization of memories or collective memory6 from which
the individual memory draws amply. In his opinion, the latter is to some
extent a kind of derivation of the former.7 In fact, he writes that the act of
remembering would not be conceivable (Halbwachs, 1968: 47) “except on
the condition that one adopts the point of view of one or more currents of
collective thought.”
A characteristic trait of collective memory consists of the fact that it is
a “living history”: its time limits, as opposed to written history, coincide
with those of the existence of the group possessing it. This leads to one of its
fundamental characteristics, that of continuity. To quote Halbwachs (1968:
89), collective memory is “a continuous current of thought, of a continuity
that is by no means artificial, because it conserves nothing from the past except
the parts which still live, or are capable of living, in the conscience of the
group.” It can therefore not exist and express itself without the living support
of a group. It is the members of the group who through their interaction
mold that particular image of the past that is transmitted in the present.
According to this approach, the past is anything but a static dimension.
Rather, it changes according to the creative play of the collective memory (or
the collective memories)8 and thus, in accordance with the requirements of
4
La mémoire collective (1968, or ed. 1951) was published posthumously.
5
As Luisa Passerini (1987) notes, Halbwachs’ work is still relatively unknown to historians,
including those who work on the subject of memory as a historical source.
6
With regard to the relationship between social memory and collective memory
understood respectively as social organization of memories and organization of memories on
the part of a group, see Namer (1987).
7
On this subject, Jedlowski (2002) underscores the role played by “the missing encounter”
between Halbwachs and psychoanalysis (especially as regards the concept of the unconscious)
in the construction of his sociology of memory.
8
The theme of the plurality of collective memories is developed by Halbwachs in La
mémoire collective. To the contrary, in Les cadres sociaux de la mémoire his attention is focused
on three “great” collective memories: the family, the religious and class memory. Implicitly,
these three memories seem to exhaust the field of the social memory. On the two different
approaches of Halbwachs’ thought on the subject of collective memory, see Namer (1987).
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 283
the present.9 “Society,” Halbwachs points out (1976: 279), “represents the
past for itself according to the circumstances and according to the times. . . .”
therefore becomes essential on the basis of this premise to “renounce the idea
that the past is preserved just as it is in individual memories” (Halbwachs,
1976: 279).10 From this point of view, the past is merely a construction, a
collective image elaborated in the present and for the present, “what one has
agreed to call the past,” as Halbwachs writes in La mémoire collective (1968:
131). Once recreated, however, its effects become very real: it molds the
group’s vision of the world, it becomes a driving force of its actions.
The collective frames of memory, the “instruments” of collective memory
(Halbwachs, 1976: XVIII) serve as filters, selecting the aspects of the past
that the group must remember, to keep its own identity alive in the present.
Collective memory thus becomes essential to guarantee the integrity and
survival of the group over time. A community may use the past to guarantee
its stability and at the same time obtain a fundamental anchor of sense for
the present.11
As mentioned above, it is on the frames of collective memory that,
according to Halbwachs, the functioning of individual memory is based.
The nature of these frames appears complex: they are together notions,
representations and norms (Namer, 1987: 58–62; see also Assmann, 1995).
The elements comprising them, as Halbwachs underscores (1976: 28), “may
be considered at the same time as notions, more or less logical and linked
in a more or less logical fashion, which provide motives for reflection, and
as imaginary or concrete representations of events or personalities, located
in time and space.” Collective memory can thus be considered as a notion,
an element of a specific knowledge, of an idea or a constellation of ideas,
and as a representation, here in the sense of image, fantastic configuration,
changing creation. While different, within the picture of collective memory
notion and representation appear superimposed to the point of being hard
to distinguish. But this is not, as we will see, the only conceptual alchemy
featured by collective memory.
9
Gérard Namer (1997: 272), in his afterword to the new French edition of La
mémoire collective (1997) underscores how collective memory can be considered a real true
“reconstruction of the present performed in function of the past.”
10
This “reconstructing” vision of the past differentiates in a clearcut manner Halbwachs
from Proust, for whom the past is not reconstructed but ‘found again.’
11
We are in this case dealing with what Bellah et al. (1985: 153) define as “community of
memory”.
284 carmen leccardi
12
In the experience of time, the bond between the two dimensions is, as we know, crucial:
what we are able to imagine is inseparable from what we are able to remember. As Bachelard
perceived already in the Thirties (1980: 46), one of the essential components of social memory
frames is the “desire for a social future”. Modernity, with its tendency to dissolve continuity,
nevertheless introduces quite a few complications in this scheme. On this subject, see the
reflections of Koselleck (1986) concerning the gap between experiences (of the past) and
expectations (for the future) in the modern age.
13
In a way, the study of collective memory enables us to go beyond the de-traditionalization
thesis, avoiding conceptualizing the contemporary condition as completely opposed to
tradition. See Adam (1996) for a reflection on this strategic issue in sociological analysis.
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 285
or dead, reach us through memory, not only does the image of the past which
they transmit to us live again in our present, but those experiences become
an intrinsic part of our identity. Our identity, thus, also includes numerous
characters borrowed from members of the group (family, political, religious
etc.) we belong to, and who have preceded us in time. According to Shils, this
memory mechanism contributes to keeping the force of tradition alive.
As lived history, collective memory is moreover characterized by a strong
affective element (Namer, 1988), which is the result of close interaction and
subsequent sharing of experiences among members of the group (Alfred
Schutz, 1971, would speak here of the sharing of a “vivid present”). Through
this affective dimension, on the other hand, the normative character of
memory is reinforced.14
By providing an essentially chaotic past experience with a language and at
the same time a structure and a unitary direction characterized by a highly
internal coherence, collective memory diminishes the differences between
those participating in group life and their individual memories, guaranteeing
collective force, cohesion and identity ( Jedlowski, 2002).
Of the three collective memories analyzed by Halbwachs (1925/1976)—
family memory, the memory of religious groups and that of social classes—
our attention will now focus briefly on the first. In fact, it is the memory of
the family group that plays the most important role in the development of
Southern Italian young people’s approach to work: the theme, as mentioned
in the introduction, that has inspired these reflections.
Halbwachs dedicates the fifth chapter of Les cadres sociaux de la mémoire to
the collective memory of the family.15 The main topic of his reflections is the
following: underlying the family group there is a “mutual fund” of memory
through which the “general attitude of the group” is expressed and from
which the family members “obtain their distinctive traits” (Halbwachs, 1976:
151–52). It is as if the thoughts of every member carry a mark of this “mutual
fund,” a cipher that they secretly share with the other members of the group.
It is significant to note that Halbwachs speaks of different “ramifications” of
the same line of thought. It is thanks to this memory that the family group
14
With the pluralization involving collective memories in the modern age, also the sense
which each of them transmit become, on the other hand, relative. This phenomenon is
associated with a weakening of their affective component.
15
On family memory, see Bertaux-Wiame (1988) and Muxel (2002).
286 carmen leccardi
can survive as a unit over time and despite the changes it faces, retain the
feeling of its own uniqueness. This ability to remember provides the family
with, to use the author’s coined expression, its own “traditional armature.”
The story of every family, as seen through the eyes of those belonging to
it, is unrepeatable: every family, Halbwachs writes (1976: 151), “has its own
spirit, its own memories which it alone commemorates, and secrets which
are not revealed except to its members.” These memories, as we have already
had occasion to observe, not only indicate the nature, quality, and strong
and weak points of the group; they also represent a set of rules to follow, an
example and model to emulate. The path followed by the family memory
cannot be ignored, on pain of leaving the group.
Family memory is, on the other hand, the perfect home of tradition. If
one participates in the life of a family, Halbwachs observes (1976: 147), one
finds oneself belonging “to a group in which it is not our personal feelings,
but rules and customs beyond our control, and which existed before us, that
establish our place.” These rules and customs are in the first place nourished
in our everyday life by the dominance of the times and places of the family.
This is one of the reasons, according to the author (1976: 154), why “most
of our thoughts are mixed with family thoughts.” This impossibility of
separating our thoughts from the family’s thoughts, or our memory from
the family’s memory, is indicative of the profound bond that, according to
Halbwachs, ties the individual members to the family group. “When a group
has permeated us with its influence for a long time,” he underscores (1976:
167), “we are so saturated that if we find ourselves alone, we act and think as
if we were still under its pressure.” The pervasiveness of the models proposed
by family memory, the lessons provided by it and in general all its messages,
are in the first place to be retraced to the power of habit and the daily contact
between its members—in a word, “familiarity.”
This nature is, for that matter, reinforced by the specific character of family
relations. “Until one leaves the family,” Halbwachs (1976: 163) reminds us,
“as opposed to other groups whose members may change and sometime
change place with respect to one another, one remains in the same position
as a relative . . .”. New family relations can be added to those preserved in the
group memory: we may in turn be not only children but also parents, but old
relationships cannot be cancelled. Their mark is indelible. From this point of
view, family memory seems to be perfectly uninfluenced by changes: nothing
appears relative or mutable within it. The trait of certainty dominates
everything.
Another striking aspect of this memory is the perfect complementarity of
the two aspects of memory, the collective and the individual. Thus, if every
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 287
16
“Memories, recollections or testimonials attributed to a generation,” Claudine Attias-
288 carmen leccardi
and plans together can then become the basis of a moral obligation: for
instance, for children to honor the family memory by continuing along the
paths which their parents have traced.
When what is remembered by the group is linked, as in the case of the
family, to the spontaneous and daily interaction among members, the basis
of the intimate relationship uniting them, the significance of the “images”
and the “notions” conveyed by memory certainly increases. The particularly
intense light that emanates is, in other words, the fruit of sharing both a
symbolic universe and everyday times, spaces and rhythms. The “practicality”
of knowledge of the social world conveyed by family memory, inseparable
from the everyday dimension in which it is immersed, reinforces this
luminosity.
A last element has to be understood with regard to family memory.
Isabelle Bertaux-Wiame (1988: 25) observes, reflecting on topics associated
with family histories, that an important role is played by the evaluation of
the social path covered by the family group as a whole. The hopes, anxieties
and desires of the present time, that give the reconstruction of the past the
particular image and flavor which only the group members are familiar with,
also has to be understood on the basis of this evaluation. If the path that
has already been covered is valued collectively in positive terms, social pride
penetrates the family memory. The presence of this feeling reinforces the
sense of collective identity, while it also makes other possible paths of memory
fade. Thus, the all-absorbing dimension of family memory is strengthened.
Donfut writes in this regard (1988: 48) “are not comprehensible unless they are related to the
others, as they are sequences of a collective memory which incorporate them in a continuity
in time endowed with significance and full of plans.”
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 289
17
The obligation in archaic societies to give gifts, to receive and return them is, as is known,
at the basis of the reflections of the French sociologist and anthropologist Marcel Mauss,
nephew and colleague of Durkheim (Mauss 1925/1950). Despite the importance of these
reflections for the analysis of social life understood as a system of relationships, for reasons
linked to the economy of work, attention here is concentrated in an exclusive way on the
theoretical proposal of Simmel.
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 291
preliminary way to focus on the centrality of the family in the Calabrese social
context. The social strength of these two dimensions, collective memory and
gratitude, in fact is directly linked to this centrality.
According to Shils (1975) every society has central areas, or society
centers as he defines them, and more peripheral areas. The symbolic orders,
the values, the beliefs and traditions which interest in different ways those
who live in that particular social space are radiated from the former; desires,
interests and collective goals are formed. The existence of those central areas
is of great importance, according to Shils, for the legitimatization of the
social and cultural order. Society centers, while taking on a sacred character,
actually at the same time belong to the sphere of action, structuring social
activities and roles. The symbolic and at the same time organizational aspects
of social life thus find full institutionalization within them.
The existence of these focal points in the symbolic articulation of a
society, capable of establishing the significance of behavior and of specifying
ends and means, becomes very evident when one works on the materials of
memory. Social memory is shaped on the basis of these centers, and clearly
carries their mark. In particular, if one deals with a reality that is still wavering
between tradition and modernity18 as Calabria was at the beginning of the
Nineties, where the process of pluralization of collective memories induced
by modernity is weak, their presence is more easily retraceable within
these materials. In fact, in Calabria there were, and still are, some collective
memories whose voice is socially stronger, and makes more sense not only
for the members of the group which expresses them, but also for society as
a whole. Hegemonic collective memories, we might say, which incorporate
other group memories tend to impose themselves as a social memory
tout-court. Family memory is certainly one of these memories; likewise, in
Calabria, the family may be fully entitled to be considered a “society center”.
Both before and after the “great transformation” of the years after World
War II (Polanyi, 1944), that is, before Calabria was incorporated into vaster
pluralistic systems, integration and social cohesion were in the first place
guaranteed by the family structure. In traditional Calabria, and in particular
in the area around Cosenza, as Pino Arlacchi clearly showed (1980), the
18
In a social reality subject to complex changes, as those brought about by the process of
modernization, not only do aspects of tradition and modernity merge in a heterogeneous
mix but, as Gusfield observes (1967), they also tend to reinforce one another mutually, the
one supporting the other. With regard to the dynamic between tradition and modernity in
Calabria, see in particular Piselli (1981) and Fantozzi (1982).
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 293
19
On the concept of political clientelism see Eisenstadt and Lemarchand (1981). See also
Eisenstadt and Roniger (1984).
20
Arrighi and Piselli (1985: 471) argue that “kinship is now maintained in existence as
a framework of protection, as a last defence against the fluctuations of the market, a sane
instrument of strength of the individual in the local labor market, as a means of climbing the
social ladder to the top; naturally, by means of the exercise or support of political power”. I
reflected at length on the relationship between clientelism and the condition of young people
in the South in Leccardi (1995b).
21
In the second half of the Ninties the PSI disappeared, after probes of corruption.
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 295
Young people appear thus to be well aware of the importance of the family
as a bridge toward the labor market, passing through politics. But, on a level
that may be banal but no less important in terms of everyday life and identity,
they are also aware that their chance to play the role of consumers in a society
in which the manufacturing structure is traditionally weak, is inconceivable
without the economic support of the family. Finally, we must not forget that
the everyday existence of young people in Calabria continues to take place
within the family circle. Even if the generation gap is, of course, a reality here
as well—it concerns above all education, life styles and consumerism—the
majority of young people in Southern as well as in Central and in Northern
Italy still live with their parents.22 And if the grandparents do not share the
house of the grandchildren, they usually live in the same neighborhood
or in the same small town. Even though education has made a significant
contribution to breaking this tight connection—consider for instance the
strong modernizing influence of the principle of residence for the students
at the University of Calabria—nonetheless, attempts to bridge this ‘cultural
gap’ are clearly visible in everyday life.23
The family as a reference point in the life of young people in Calabria is all
the more significant if we consider the social progress which a considerable
number of families in Calabria have made in recent years. From the
grandparents who knew neither how to read nor write and who worked to
survive, to the parents who are generally barely literate, who have had a very
hard life but who have nevertheless enjoyed a better lifestyle, to the sons and
daughters who at least potentially may try to plan their own future, especially
thanks to new levels of education, this transition is decidedly revolutionary
for Calabria.24
Reflecting on the lives of grandparents and parents, two young female
students express themselves this way for example:
My grandmother stayed home, she had to take care of the children, they had
many children my grandparents . . . seven . . . she always stayed home she told
22
The “famiglia lunga” (long family), that is the cohabitation under the same roof even
if the children have already finished their studies, has been a characteristic of Mediterranean
countries during the last few decades (Cavalli and Galland, 1993). In 2000, only 30% of young
Italians of an age between 25 and 29 years old did not live with their parents (Buzzi, Cavalli
and de Lillo, 2002).
23
Thus, on Saturday and Sunday (as well as other holidays) the University of Calabria
campus is almost completely empty. The great majority of students return to their families,
mostly small towns or villages.
24
In the span of a few generations in Southern Italy, we have gone from a situation
characterized by low levels of education in which illiteracy was still widespread to a situation
of education that is much closer to the European model.
296 carmen leccardi
me because my grandfather drove a boat, and with the boat he often had to go
to England (. . .) My mother worked hard for us children. . . she’s a housewife . . .
plus we have the land . . . a vineyard . . . so my mother always stayed home and
worked in the field. . . she watched how things were done and she learned . . . she
found herself forced to work the fields because my father was not around, he
had emigrated to Germany. She told me that when she was my age, there was no
chance of studying, she knows how to sign her name, even how to write some
things. She tells me that she would have liked to study, she always repeats that
I have to continue with my studies, go to the university (Margherita, 19 years
old, high school student, Calopezzati).
My paternal grandfather was a hired hand in the fields for a Count, then he left
and set up his own work. He was a very strong person but at the same time very
sweet . . . that’s what my grandmother says. Now my grandfather is dead. My
grandmother has always been a housewife and worked in the fields along with
my grandfather. She was a very energetic woman because they had six children
and had to maintain them (. . .) With respect to my grandparents, there is a
better tenor of life, the work has changed too. My mother works as a janitor
in a school, my brother and I study and I would like to go into the field of
computers (Anna, 17 years old, high school student, Crosia).
The grandparents and parents tell their sons and daughters these biographical
stories with an abundance of detail, about the efforts made in their precarious
work situations, without certainty for the future, marked by the experience of
emigration.25 The young people consider the transmission of these memories
an obvious thing. In the interviews, they speak without hesitation about hard
or very hard work experiences on the part of their grandfathers and fathers,
about the life as a ‘housewife’26 of their grandmothers and the majority of
their mothers that familiar memory has preserved and transmitted. In their
eyes, the social trajectory that has been covered in a short time span—and
that has allowed them to acquire well-being and education—appears first
and foremost to be the result of their parents’ long litany of denial, their
25
Between 1951 and 1971, for instance, 800.000 people emigrated from Calabria, that is
one inhabitant out of three. See Congi (1988: 21).
26
In the situation of Southern Italy, women’s work has traditionally been socially invisible
(Cornelisen, 1977). Even if, as Amalia Signorelli writes (1983: 71–72) in spite of “the
stereotype according to which they were all housewives, Southern Italian women have always
worked outside the home, except for some brackets of middle-class women . . . However, the
productive capacity of women, in particular the work done outside the home, has been, as we
know, culturally denied, as a sign of dishonor for the man: consequently women, in particular
among farmers, have never had, I will not go as far as to say professional identity, but not even
awareness of themselves as workers”.
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 297
spirit of sacrifice, rather than the result of a social and cultural evolution. The
cultural and social range of this representation emerges for example clearly
from this excerpt of interview:
My maternal grandfather worked in agriculture and devoted to sheep
breeding . . . He tells me often how he lived day to day, how he was forced to
try to get by with a big family . . . my father is ignorant in the sense that he
only went up to second grade in elementary school, then his father died young
and to maintain a big family he had to accept all kinds of work . . . His life was
full of sacrifices and wasn’t a happy life like I am living now: school, home,
fun (. . .). Now my father is a trucker . . . it’s a job with sacrifices because many
times he has to work far from home, and he cannot have even a minute for
stopping because the less time he takes to do his job, the more chance he has
for doing another one when he gets back ( . . ..) Fun things, he hasn’t had very
much, because his life has been on a big truck . . . my father and my mother and
their parents before them made a ton of sacrifices to allow us children to have
a better future . . . their sacrifices haven’t been thrown away . . . they taught us a
lot, how to live in society, how to care for a family, how life is not a walk in the
park . . . they gave us a lot (Roberto, 22 years old, university student, Cosenza).
According to Roberto’s point of view—the same as that of the great majority
of the young people interviewed—it is always the individual who subsumes
the social, and never the other way round. It is a viewpoint ratified by a
cultural model that is by now centuries old. This also gives rise to the tacit
debt of gratitude that binds children to parents: children feel profoundly
grateful with regard to their family members because in the family they see
the first source of the well-being and freedom they enjoy. It is also thanks
to this profound and timeless bond of gratitude that, despite the profound
changes that have affected lifestyles, their relationship is so strong. Young
people have the impression of proceeding along the path that their forefathers
have traced.
In this framework, the reasons why family memory is one of the crucial
centers (if not the center) of social memory in Calabria become clearer.
Through family memory, the past—characterized for older generations
by hard manual labor, by the emigration experience, by the interminable
rosary of sacrifices made to provide oneself and one’s family with a dignified
existence—becomes indelible, is turned into a perennial present.
Thus, family memory provides the younger members with important
resources for the definition of an identity. In the first place, it indicates the
starting point for the path of social ascent whose final stages they are covering.
A guide for the future as much as a lesson from the past, the “living history”
conveyed by family memory becomes, for the young people forced to face
298 carmen leccardi
a vague future, a protective shield both against the unknown and interior
wavering, and against any incidents faced in the struggle for status. Thanks
to its vitality, young people can count on a path whose sense is socially
unchallengeable. Its affective, intimate cipher blunts the feeling of difference
within the family group and increases the latter’s ability to unify different
worlds. It is thanks to the power of family memory that the feeling of the
children’s gratitude can be consolidated, resisting the new uncertainties of the
present. This memory in fact manages to transmit intact the profound sense
of the effort made by the older generations to guarantee the young people
a more acceptable existence. Gratitude and the force of family memory
contribute to reinforcing emotional involvement, while underscoring the
immutability of that which ‘matters in life’. In turn, collective memory
strengthens gratitude and the latter, for its part, increases the former. This
circular development also serves to legitimate a model of work culture for
young people in Calabria.
Preserved from the wear of time due to this twofold influence, archaic
dimensions survive in the orientation of young people, even if with a perfect
change in character associated with the present work culture. In other words,
the memory of difficult work experiences of the preceding generations
preserved in the family memory allows young people to relish their own new
social condition that is free from the obligation of manual labor. They are
in fact passing through the last phase of a path of ascending social mobility
that has proceeded from the agricultural work of their grandparents (and in
part still of their parents) to their new condition as students. The memory
of physically hard labor, above all associated with working the land, thus
becomes a tool for the young people to reject manual labor. The stories of
their grandparents and parents make the effort of work real and show to
their grandchildren and children what should be avoided. More precisely,
that which the new access to non-manual labor guaranteed by education
makes it possible to avoid. The memory of separation from one’s beloved,
the poisoned fruit of the emigration experience, is transformed, in the
increasingly educated present of the sons and daughters, into a refusal to
sever, even temporarily, one’s territorial and affective ties to find work in
other parts of Italy. Thus, after the hardship associated with the emigration
of grandparents and parents, which often lasted many years, the fact of living
and working in the same place appears, to the eyes of young people, to be
an inalienable request. Finally the memory of existential precariousness,
many jobs without any quality and economic security, the everyday “coping”
faced by the grandfathers and fathers (for the latter, also in a relatively recent
period) is changed into the primary importance assigned by young people to
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 299
the stability of the job as compared to its concrete contents.27 The dominant
model of work culture among the grandparents and parents, which may be
summarized in the statement “any job is fine, as long as it permits one to
live and keep one’s family alive” is transformed, in the changing scene of
contemporary Calabria, into their offspring’s dictate “any job is fine, as long
as it is not manual.” Together with the new conditions of the present, the
family memory that is transmitted thus produces a reference framework for
values and norms that is renewed by the young people, but without losing
an ounce of its own strength. In short, the teaching that is imparted by
collective memory manages to remain whole in substance, even if the forms
with which it expresses itself are modified today, falling into line with a social
situation that is increasingly well-off. In this situation—and it could not be
otherwise—even the ways of working have been transformed, in accordance
with new levels of education of the population.
The presence of the feeling of gratitude of the younger members with
regard to those who are not as young, as has been brought to light, appears
in turn doubly linked to the dedication shown by the latter with regard to
the family. This dedication, constantly celebrated in the family memory,
is part of the present and leaves its mark even on the work cultures. The
gratitude that the research has underscored thus seals a real “pact between
generations”, that the transmission of the family memory in turn contributes
to strengthening.
The results of the research suggest that the lesson provided by family
memory has been profoundly absorbed by the dominant model of work
culture among young people in Calabria. The indissoluble bond created by
the obligation of gratitude uniting the sons and daughters to parents whose
“sacrifices” have guaranteed the broadening of the horizon of choices through
access to the educational system seals it, and reinforces its timelessness.
Instruments of cohesion, integrity and social continuity, collective
memory and gratitude remind us that even in the ‘society of acceleration’
(Rosa, 2003) in which we find ourselves, it is illegitimate to postulate the
pure and simple wiping out of the past. Despite the tendency to make “short
time” a privileged point of reference in the relationship with timeframes
27
This aspect tends to gather importance as the so-called ‘contingent work’ (jobs without
guarantees for long-term employment) and the new existential precariousness associated
with it become more diffuse. On this point, see Beck (2000). For young Calabrese people,
this situation is aggravated by the high levels of unemployment: according to a recent study
(Fantozzi, 2003: 9), 45.2% of those between 15 and 34 years old in Calabria are unemployed
(as opposed to 18.4% of the national average for the same age bracket).
300 carmen leccardi
of life, the interviews show how the great majority of the young people are
well aware of the inseparable link between the past, present and the future.
By showing in this way strong sensitivity with respect to processes of social
and historical order that have changed the horizons and daily lives of the
generations in a radical way in an arc of time that is relatively short. No less, the
movement of time in which young people perceive themselves to be inserted
is not resolved simply in a fast passage between different presents. The past
emerges from the interviews as a time full of meaning, in the first place on
the topic of interpersonal and family relationships,28 that place it in direct
conjunction with identity. In short, this prevalent elaboration of the past as a
“lived time” that has been morphed by sentimental ties and emotional bonds,
safeguards the possibility of maintaining a broader temporal horizon despite
the contemporary problem of building a future in the long-term.
References
28
It is possible that the changes that have taken place over during the last decades—calling
into question the stability of traditional love bonds as well as the norms of the family (Beck
and Beck-Gernsheim, 1995; Bauman 2003)—made even family memory more evanescent.
However, in Calabria during the first half of the Nineties a widespread de-structuring of
family norms appeared to still be far off.
family memory, gratitude and social bonds 301
Summary
Meetings are regularly treated as the backdrop of time-sensitive activities, but rarely
considered as an important socio-temporal structure in their own right. Through positioning
organizational activities in a timeframe, their decision making function links members to a
socially constructed past that resides in their collective memory and simultaneously shapes their
present and future. In the present examination, we illustrate our argument drawing examples
from the very meeting of which this paper was a part. As central communication structures
drawn on regularly to effect a variety of goals, meetings are at the heart of organizational
communication and temporality which accounts for their vitality in establishing, debating,
and reflecting a group’s collective memory.
From the afternoon of Sunday July 25th to the morning of Saturday July 31st
2004, members of the International Society for the Study of Time (ISST)
gathered at Clare College in Cambridge, England for the purpose of sharing
research and ideas and developing (and maintaining) collegial ties. The
conference opened on Monday morning with a brilliant and moving Founder’s
Address in which J. T. Fraser took great care to situate this meeting within
the collective memory of the group. This, the twelfth triennial conference,
was the largest such Society meeting in the history of the organization and
represented a critical turning point in the “timing” of previous conference
traditions. At previous gatherings, the membership was small enough so as
to avoid the need for concurrent paper presentation sessions. However, the
growing size of the membership and corresponding number of conference
attendees in Cambridge gave way to concurrent paper sessions for the first
time in the organization’s history. This meeting, centered on the theme of
Time and Memory, offers excellent occasion to consider its very focus.
As central communication structures drawn on regularly to effect a variety
of goals, meetings are at the heart of organizational communication and
temporality which accounts for their vitality in establishing, debating, and
reflecting a group’s collective memory (Gheradi & Strati, 1988). Following
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 303–314.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
304 dawna ballard & felipe gómez
The open council meeting of the ISST on Thursday evening was characterized
by extended sense-making (including retrospective sense-making) about
the appropriate course of action to manage the present change in their
environment (i.e., marked growth in membership) and its impact on past
traditions and routines. Having enacted a vision of the future in which
the number of conference attendees would only continue to increase, an
important agenda item concerned members’ feelings about the success of
306 dawna ballard & felipe gómez
the concurrent session format “tried out” in Cambridge and suggestions for
managing the growing membership vis-à-vis the logistics of paper sessions
at future conference sites. It was not a decision-making activity per se, but
initial input was sought for decisions to be made in the near future. New and
old members alike were present for this sense-making activity.
While the time “of ” meetings, such as their periodicity, referenced earlier
is a relevant aspect of organizational temporality—such as how a triennial
meeting typically has the effect of making interaction more hallowed and
precious than a daily event, contributing to a stronger orientation to the
past and future—it is the time “in” meetings that shapes and is shaped by
members’ collective memory. Time “in” meetings (i.e., interaction time)
shapes the whole organization (McPhee, Corman, & Iverson, 2006). While
this is the case for every activity in an extended meeting like a conference in
Cambridge, the structured nature of decision making directly casts light on
the interconnections among an organization’s past, present, and future as it
places organizational members and their activities in a timeframe (Butler,
1995).
Butler (1995) observes: “We experience time in the present, but only by
relating ourselves to a past and to a future. . . . The present is preceded by a
whole series of events and decisions which become sedimented into some
kind of order codifying our experience. . . . Codes signify (Giddens, 1984: 31;
Clark, 1990: 144) states learned from past action (Cyert and March 1992:
174) and enable communication about those states to actors in the present. . . .
Codes contain the history of an organization, but as March (1988: 13) says,
history is notoriously ambiguous” (pp. 928–929). In terms of the present
discussion, collective memories constitute these codes, but they are not
faithful reproductions of the past: memories are social constructions in the
present (Zerubavel, 2003). For example, meetings are the communicative
events wherein organizational history and knowledge becomes codified and
where the meaning of those codes gets debated. Codes determine what gets
attended to in discussion vis-à-vis the agenda or impromptu contributions—
they are used to define and draw attention to a problem (and to ignore others)
as well as signal that a decision must be made to address it. This decision is
based on members’ retrospective enactment of their environments (Weick,
1979).
The open council meeting illustrates these issues. The organization’s
“attention” codes (Butler, 1995) defined the growing size of the organization
as an issue about which decisions needed to be made. While the issue was
consistently described as “a good problem to have,” it necessitated a decision,
time to meet 307
Schwartzman (1986) describes the various ways in which meetings are so often
maligned both by group members and organizational practitioners as useless,
poorly ran, and ineffective. Instead of refuting these complaints, she suggests
that serious consideration of the ways in which these characterizations are
true can lead scholars to a deeper understanding of what purposes meetings
really do serve for social collectives. Schwartzman considers three images of
meetings that suggest how scholars might reconsider the function meetings
serve for organizational members—meetings as homeostats, rituals, and social
metaphors. Below we apply a socio-temporal perspective to this framework
and consider the implications of these three images for organizational
memory.
Meetings as Homeostats
pride and love that a range of members old and new held for the Society led
to clear resistance to part with the past. Nonetheless, everyone continually
acknowledged that growth is a good problem to have and resigned to the
inevitable change (even if it was not an individually experienced change, but
existed as a new development in the shared history of the group).
Meetings as Rituals
express their feelings about the past, present, and future of the organization.
This occurred not only through discussions of the presentation sessions,
but also through discussions about both the location and theme of future
conferences. Given the inordinately high valuation of the British pound
compared with the currency of many conference attendees, discussions
about the location of future conferences were made through referencing
the shared values and norms found at past conferences. Members told awe-
inspiring stories of the tiny Italian village they traversed during the last
triennial meeting and the wonderful collegiality and familial environment
it inspired as well as the ability to travel with one’s family (the latter owed
in good measure due to a more favorable exchange rate). While the present
conference was also seen as collegial and familial in nature, the importance of
these values for future meetings was underscored in members’ narratives.
Conclusion
expressive means. Stohl (2006) recognizes this tension between the topic
of discussion and the social context in which it takes place. For example,
in order to engage in the sense-making needed to effect instrumental goals,
like strategic planning or establishing a new policy, members often invoke
collective memories (whether real or imagined), such as the founder’s original
vision or recent developments in the group’s history, in order to endorse
particular paths of action. Thus, memories (i.e., social constructions of the
past) serve expressive functions as they are drawn on through members’
discourse to opine, while being used (as “data”) to impact instrumental
functions concerning the group’s present and future directions.
Through positioning organizational activities in a timeframe, the decision
making function of meetings links members to a socially constructed past
that resides in their collective memory and simultaneously shapes their
present and future. In the present examination, we illustrated our argument
drawing examples from the very meeting of which this paper was a part.
Given their pervasiveness in organizational life, meetings afford researchers
regular access to large amounts of data that can be analyzed drawing from a
number of different methods and epistemological perspectives. Depending
on the scope of the data, it can point to important and practicable insights
for organizational scholars, members, and practitioners. For example, in a
single organization, future investigations can yield information that helps
members to better understand their unique decision making dynamics
and assumptions. Across several organizations, relevant analyses might
allow generalizations on topics like the role of contested memories and
shared memories in shaping group development and decision outcomes.
Considering meetings as sites of organizational memory has the potential
to inform a variety of literatures—from group communication and decision
making, to organizational assimilation, to learning, to strategic planning, to
team identity, to name a few. We hope that the issues and arguments raised
here can be assistive in this regard.
References
Ancona, D. and C. Chong. “Entrainment: Pace, cycle and rhythm in organizational behavior.”
In Research in organizational behavior, Volume 18, ed. B. M. Staw & L. L. Cummings,
251–284. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press, 1996.
Ancona, D. G., G. A. Okhuysen and L. A. Perlow. (2001). “Taking time to integrate temporal
research.” Academy of Management Review 26 (2001): 512–529.
Ballard, D. I. and D. R. Seibold. “Communicating and organizing in time: A meso level model
of organizational temporality.” Management Communication Quarterly 16 (2003): 380–
415.
314 dawna ballard & felipe gómez
Jo Alyson Parker, Michael Crawford, Paul Harris (Eds), Time and Memory, pp. 315–321.
© 2006 Koninklijke Brill N.V. Printed in the Netherlands.
316 index