Solutions Manual for
ANDREU MAS-GOLELE MICHAEL D. WHINSTON
LUO) Lael
Chiaki Hara
Ilya Segal
Steve TadelisCHAPTER 1
L.B.1 Since y > z implies y » 2, the transitivity implies that x » 7
Suppose that z x x. Since y x z. the transitivity then implies that y x x,
But this contradicts x > y. Thus we cannot have z > x. Hence x > z.
1.B.2 By the completeness, x > x for every x € X. Hence there is no x © X
such that x x
ippose that x > y and y > z, then x > y yz By (iii) of
Proposition 1.B.1, which was proved in Exercise 1.B.1, we have x > z. Hence >
is transitive. Property (i) is now proved.
As for (ii), since x x x for every x € X, x ~ x for every x € X as well.
‘Thus ~ is reflexive. Suppose that x ~ y andy ~z Then x¥ryye7%yEX
and z x y. By the transitivity, this implies that x x z and z x x. Thus x ~
2. Hence ~ ie transitive. Suppoce x that ~ y. Then x xy andy yx Thus y
x x and x yy. Hence y ~ x. Thus ~ is symmetric Property (ii) is now
proved.
1B.3 Let *¢ X and yc X. Since u(+) represents >, x » y if and only if
u(x) = uly). Since f(-) is strictly increasing, u(x) = uly) if and only if
v(x) = vly). Hence x > y if and only if v(x) = vly). Therefore vi-)
represents y.
1.B.4 Suppose first that x > y. If, furthermore, y x x, then x ~ y and hence
u(x) = uly). If, on the contrary, we do not have y > x, then x > y. Hence
u(x) > u(y). Thus, if x » y, then ule) = uly).
Suppose conversely that u(x) = u(y). If. furthermore, u(x) = u(y), then
ix
y and hence x » y. If, on the contrary, u(x) > uly}, then x > y. and
henee x x y.
uly), then x x y. So ul+) represents >.
1.B.S. First, we shall prove by induction on the number N of the elements of X
that. if there is no indifference between any two different elements of X,
then there exists a utility function. If N = 1, there is nothing to prove:
Just assign any number to the unique element. So let N > 1 and suppose that
the above assertion is true for N - 1. We will show that it is still true for
N. Write X = Gy,
*y-p%y) By the induction hypothesis, x can be
represented by a utility funetion u(-) on the subset (xp.-y_,) - Without
loss of generality we can assume that u(x,) > ulx,) >... > ulxy_,)
Consider the following three cases:
Case 1: For every i < N, x,
>
Case 2: For every 1 < Ny x, > Hy,
Case 3: There exist i < Nand Jj <¢ N such that x, > Hy > x;
Since there is no indifference between two different elements, these three
cases are are exhaustive and mutually exclusive. We shall now show how the
value of ulx,) should be determined, in each of the three cases, for u(-) to
represent ¢ on the whole x.
If Case 1 applies, then take u(xy) to be larger than u(x,). If Case 2
applies. take ulxy) to he smaller than uly). Suppose now that Case 9
applies. Let I= i ¢ (lu... N- Ih x) > xy,)) and J= Ge ..., N= De
Xyu1 > Xj Completeness and the assumption that there is no indifference
implies that 1 u J = G,..., N- 1). The transitivity implies that both I and
dare “intervals,” in the sense that if i ¢ I and {’ <1, then i’ € 1; and if
j€Jand j’ > j, then j © J. Let i* = max I, then i* + 1 = min J. TakeUomy) 10 tie
the open interval (ulxje,,).t(%j_))- Then it is easy to see
that u(-) represents x on the whole X.
‘Suppose next that there may be indifference between some two elements of
x). For each n =
X= &, AN, define %,, = Og, © X q, ~ %,)- There
by the reflexivity of ~ (Proposition LB.1GD), UN.X, = Xs Also, by the
transitivity of ~ (Proposition 1.8.16i)), if X, # X,, then X, 0%, #8 So
in Xe n° Xm
let M be a subset of (1,...,N) such that X
Umen%nn 290 X,, # X, for any me M
‘and any ne M with m#n, Define an relation »* on {X,,: m € M} by letting X,,
Fe he lalla le tal
indifference between two different elements of (X,,: me M). Thus, by the
preceding result, there exists a utility function u®(+) that represents 2*.
Then define us XR by ulx,) = uNX,) if me Mand x, € X,, It is easy to
show that, by the transitivity, u(+) represents >.
LCA If y € Cl(xy,2)), then the WA would imply that y « C((x,y)), Rut
contradicts the equality Cl(x,y)) = Gd. Hence y € C({x,y,2)). Thus
CUx,y,2)) € (20,(2),00,2))
1.€.2 The property in the question are cyuivalent to the following proper")
Wee, B eB, xeByeB, xeBy y eB, x € OB), and y © OB), then
x € C(B’) and y € CIB). We shall thus prove the equivalence between this
property and the’ Weak Axion.
Suppose first that the Weak Axiom is satisfied. Assume that B ¢ 8, B’ ¢
B,x
* y, then there is some B € B such that x € B, y €
B, x € CIB), and y € G(B). Thus x >" y. Suppose that y »* x, then there
8 Re A such that xB, ye Band x © G(B). But the Weak Axiom impliee
that y € C(B), which is a contradiction. Hence if x >* y, then we cannot have
yy" x. Hence x >** y.
Conversely, suppose that x >** y, then x x* y but not y >* x. Hence
there is some B € B such that x ¢ B, y ¢ B, x C(B) and if x € BY and yc BY
for any BY © B, then y € C(B"). In particular, x € C(B) and y € C(B). Thus
xt y,
The equality of the two relation is not guaranteed withont the WA. As
can be seen from the above proof, the WA is not necessary to guarantee that if
x >" y, then x >* y, But the converse need not be true, as shown by the
following example. Define X = (x,y,z), B= ((x,y)(x,y,2)), Clix.) = (x),
and C((x,y,z)) = {y). Then x >* y and y >* x. But neither x >* y nor y >* x,
(b) The relation >* need not be transitive, as shown by the following example
Detine X = (x,y.2h, B= (Oxy) (y.2)), Clay?) = tx) and Cl{y,2)) = ty).
Then x >* y and y >* z. But we do not have x >* z (because neither of the two
sets in B includes (x,z}) and hence we do not have x >* z either.
(c) According to the proof of Proposition 1.D.2, if B includes all three
element subset of X, then »* is transitive. By Proposition 1.B.1(i), »** istransitive. Since >* ts equal to >**, >* 1s also transitive.
‘An alternative proof is as follows: Let x ¢ K, y ¢ K, 2 € X, x ># y, and
y >* z, Then {x.y.z) € B and, by (a). x >** y, and y >"* z, Hence we have
neither y >* x nor z >* y. Since >* rationalizes (B,C(-)), this implies that
y € CUix,y,2)) and z € Clix,y,2)). Since Cl{x,y.2)) # @, CUx,y.2)) = (x).
Thus x >* 2.
LD.1 The simplest example is X = (x,y), B= Ux){y)), CUO) = Ge, Cy)
= (y). Then any rational preference relation of X rationalizes C{-).
L.D.2_ By Exercise 1.B.5, let u(+) be a utility representation of . Since X
its, for any BS X with B+ @ there exists x © B such that u(x) = u(y)
for all y ¢B. Then x ¢ C*(B,>) and hence C¥(B,,) + 0. (A direct proof with
no use of utility representation is possible, but it is essentially the same
as the proof of Exercise 1.B.5.)
1.D.3 Suppose that the Weak Axiom holds. If x € G(X), then x © C(Xx,z)),
which contradicts the equality Gl(s,z)) = {2}. If y € G(X), then y €
CUix,y), which contradicts Cl(x,y)) =
(x). If z € C(X), then z € Clty,z)),
which contradicts C((x,z)) = (y}. Thus (B,C{-)) must violate the Weak Axiom,
L.D.4 Let » rationalize G(-) relative to BR, Let x € G(H, W BL) and y © GCF)
v GB), then x x y bevause By UB, > G(B,) v O(B,). Thus x © O(0(B,) uv
ctp,)).
Let x € O(C(B,) v O(B,)) and y € B, v Bp. then there are four cases:
Case 1. x € CIB), y € By.Case 2. x © OB), y © By,
Case 2 x 6 CB), ¥ ¢ BY.
Case 4. x € CIB,). v € By.
If either Case 1 or 4 is true, then x » y follows directly from
rationalizability, If Case 2 is true, then pick any z € C(B,). Then z > y.
Since x € O(C(B,) u CIB,)), x x z. Hence, by the transitivity, x > y. If
Case 3 is true, then pick any z € C(B,) and do the same argument as for Case
2.
1.D.5 (a) Assign probability 1/6 to each of the six possible preferences,
which are x > y>Z,X>Z>Y,Y>X>2¥>Z>x,Z>x>y, andzry>
(b) If the given stochastic choice function were rationalizable, then the
probability that at least one of x > y, y » z, and z » x holds would be at
most 3 x (1/4) = 3/4. But, in fact, at least one of the three relations ~
always holds, because, if the first two do not hold, then y » x and 2 > y.
Hence the transitivity implics the third. Thus, the given stochastic choice
function is not rationalizahle
(c) The same argument as in (b) can be used to show that a = 1/3. Since
CUx,y = CUiy,2)) = CUZ,x}) = (a 1 - a) is equivalent to Cl{y,x)) =
Czy = OKx.2n
"
(1 ~ @ a), if we apply the same argument as in (h) to y
>) Z> y, and x > 2, then we can establish I - @ = 1/3, that is, « = 2/9,
Thus, in order for the given stochastic choice function is rationalizable, it
is necessary that a € [1/3,2/3]. Moreover, this condition is actually
sufficient: For any « € [1/3,2/3], assign probability a - 1/3 to each of x >
Meé
y>2,y>Z>x, and z > x > y; assign probability 2/3 - @ to each of x > 2 >
yy yx z, and z>y 7x. Then we obtain the given stochastic choice
function.
17CHAPTER 2
2.D.1 Let p, be the price of the consumption good in period 2, measured in
units of the consumption good in period 1. Let x,, x, be the consumption
levels in periods 1 and 2, respectively. Then his lifetime Walrasian budget
2. <
set is equal to (x € RU: x, + ppx, = wh.
2n2 (uh) eR: b= 24, pe ens 28
2.D.3 (a) No. In fact, the budget set consists of the two points, each of
which is the intersection of the budget line and an axis.
() Let xe By, XB, yy and A € [0,1]. Write x" = Ax +1 - alk’. Since
X is convex, x" « X. Moreover, p-x" = Ap-x) + (1 = AVlp-x') = Aw + (1 = Adw
=w. Thus x" B |.
paw
2.D.4 It follows from a direct calculation that consumption level M can be
attained by (6 + (M ~ 85)/s") hours of labor. It follows from the definition
that (24,0) and (16 - (M - 86)/c’, M) are in the budget cet. But their convex
combination of these two consumption vectors with ratio
M - 8s
is not in the budget set: the amount of leisure of this combination equals to
16 (so the labor is eight hours), but the amount of the consumption good is
8 8 8
M >M—Po—ae = Mae = 88
ve HSE vs Hee Ws
22.E.1 The homogeneity can be checked as follows
op, ew
xjlepew) = a
: op, + ap, + OP AP)
ap, aw
Xglepew) = Gaps ay BPS
2 D7 Py Py Py
ep, ow
xglap.aw)
“ap, + ap, + =, OP,
To see if the demand function satisfies Walras’ law, note that
PP, + Pz + Py
pextow) =
Pipaeuaes)
Hence p:x(p,w) = w if and only if @ = 1. Therefore the demand function
satisfies Walras' law if and only if & = 1
2.E.2 Multiply by p,/w both sides of (2.£.4), then we obtain
L
Lge! PpylP¥0/ WG pl.) 8p, P,/x (WI) + PLY (P.WI/W
Hence p_by(p.wep(p.w) + by(p.w) = 0.
By (2.E.6), TE _(ppeglp. w)/ wil x ylp.v)/8N(w/xy(p.¥))
Hence
Lye ¢lP-Wlepy(P.w) = 1.
2.5.3. There are two ways to verify that p:D,x(p,wip = = w.
One way {s to post-multiply (2.E.5) by p, then p-D.x(p.w) p+ w= 0 by
Walrac’ law.
The other way is to pre-multiply (2.F.1) by pT, then p-Dpx(p,wip +
p+D, x(p,w)w = 0, By Proposition 2.E.3, this is equal to p-D,x(p,wp + w
An interpretation is that, when all prices are doubled, in order for the
consumer to stay at the same consumption, it is necessary to increase his
wealth by w.
2-2
°.2.6.4 Dy differentiating the equation x(paw) = axtp,w) with respect to a and
evaluating at a = 1, we obtain wD,,x(p,w) = x(p,w). Hence D,lp,w) ~
(/w)x(p.w). Hence €,,, = (8xylp.w)/ow)lw/x,(p.w)) = 1, This means that an
one-percent increase in wealth will increase the consumption level for all
guods by one percent.
Since (1/w)x(p,w) = x(p,1) by the homogeneity assumption, D.,x(p,w) is a
function of p only. The assumption also implies that the wealth expansion
path, F, = Gx(pyw): w > 0}, is a ray going through x(p,).
2.E.S Since x(p,w) is homogeneous of degree one with respect to w, x(p,aw) =
ex(p,w) for every a > 0. “Thus x,(p,w) = x,(p,lw. Since ax,{p,11/8p, =
Spq(p)/op, = 0 whenever k + & xp(pd) is actually @ Function of pp alone, So
we can write xy(pw) = x/(P_). Since x(p,w) is homogencous of degree zero,
x,(Py) must be homogeneous of degree - 1 (in p,). Hence there exists a, > 0
such that x(pj) = ay/py, By Walras’ law, Typy(cty/p,Jw = wD ya, = w. We must
thus have Syay = 1.
2.E.6 When @ = 1, Walras’ nw and homogeneity hold, Hence the conclusions of
Propositions 2.E.1 ~ 2.E.3 hold.
2.6.7 By Walras’ law,
(w - ppqi/n, = w/p, ~ (p)/p,)ew/p,) = UL - alw/p,.
‘2 2
This demand function is thus homogeneous of degree zero.
2-32.6.8 For the first part, note that
In ¥((p.w) = In yylexptin p,),....exptin p, exp(in w)),
Thus, by the chain rule,
ax, ax,
atin x,(0.00) apie re tin Pi apeh wd
aE 7 pw = eyiprwT 7 See
Similarly,
ax, ax,
(in xylp.w)) = (p.w)-explin w) ay iP wlw
Sat BT pipe * Fel
Since a, = d(in, x,(p,w))/dlln pj), a, = dlln x)(p,w))/alIn pp), and a, =
(in x(p,#))/dlin w), the assertion is established
2.F.1 We proved in Exercise 1.C.2 that Definition 1.C.1 and the property in
the exercise is equivalent. It is easy to see that the latter is equivalent
to the following property: For every Be B and B' ¢ B, if O(D) nD’ ¥ © and D
1 C(B") @, then CIB) n BY c CIB") and Bn C(B') < CIB). If Cl-) is
single-valued, then this property is equivalent to the following one: For
every B ¢ B and B’ € B, if C(B) < BY and Bc C(B’), then C(B) = C(B"). In the
context of Walrastan demand functions, this can be restated as follows: For
any (p,w) and (p',w'), if p-x(p',w') = w and p’-x(p,w) = w’, then x(p,w) =
x(p',w"). But this is the contraposition of the property stated in Definition
2.F.1. Hence Definitions 1.C.1 and 2.F.1 are equivalent,
2.F.2 It is straightforward to check that the Weak Axiom holds. In fact, if
= 9. since p?x! = 8, x2
Js 8 andi + 4, then p’-x’ Is revealed
P
preferred to x!, similarly, siuce p!-x9 = 6, x! is revealed preferred to x%,But, since p°-x" = 8, x° is revealed preferred to x
2.F.9 [First printing errata: Add the sentence "Assume that the weak axiom is
satisfied." in (b) and (c).] Denote the demand for good 2 in year 2 by y.
(a) His behavior violates the weak axiom if
100-120 + 100y = 100-100 + 100-100
and
100-100 + 80-100 100-120 + Soy.
That is, the Weak Axiom is violated if y ¢ [75,0].
(b) The bundle in year 1 is revealed preferred if
100-120 + 100y = 100-100 + 100-100
and
100-100 + 80-100 > 100-120 + 80y,
that is, y < 75.
(c) The bundle in year 2 is revealed preferred if
100-100 + 80-100 = 100-120 + 8oy
ana
100-120 + 100y » 100-100 + 100-100,
that is, y > 80.
(@) For any value of y, we have suffictent information to Justity exactly one
of (a), (b), and (c).
(©) We shall prove that if y < 75, then good 1 is an inferior good. So
suppose that y < 75. Then100-120 + 100y = 100-100 + 100-100
and
100-100 + 80-100 > 100-120 + Boy.
Hence the real wealth decreases from year 1 to 2. Also the relative price of
good | increases, But the demand for good 2, y, deercases because y < 75 <
100. This means that the wealth effect on good 1 must be negative. Hence it
is an inferior good.
(f) We shall prove that if 80 < y < 100, then good 2 is an inferior good. So
suppose that 80 < y < 100. Then
100-100 + 80-100 = 100-120 + Soy
100-120 + 100y > 100-100 + 100-100.
Hence the real wealth increases from year 1 to 2. Also the relative price of
good 2 decreases. But the demand for good 2, y, decreases because y < 100.
This means that the wealth effect on good 2 must be negative. Hence it is an
interior good.
2A (a) IE Lg <1, then (py°%)/lpy'¥q) <1 and hence pox) 1, then (p,-x,1/(p,-%p) > 1 and hence Pyx, > Py'Xy- Thus the
consumer has a revealed preference for x, Over Xo
A. Hence, by taking 2
(©) If py = Ap, and w, = Aw), and x, = x5, then E,
Q
larger or smaller than one. we can make Eq larger or smaller than one. But
this obviously does nol have any revealed preference relationship.2.F.5 We shall first prove the discrete version. By the homogeneity of
degree one with respect to wealth, it is enough to show that
(p’ ~ p)-Ge(p',1) - x(p,1)) 0 for every p and p’.
Since
= x(p) = Soe (et PtP = x(p.10)
1
+ Ode, Seip) > x0,
it is sufficient to show that
(p’ - p)-(x(p',p'+x(p,1)) ~ x(p,1)) = 0,
and
. 1 <
@ ~ Prete, Sze TT) > XIPID) = 0.
For the firet inequality, note that
(p’ = p)-Ge(p',p'+x(p,0) = x(p,1)) = - pexe(p’sp!-aelpt)) + 1
If x(p',p’+x(p,1)) = x(p,1), then the value is equal to zero. If
2(p',p'+x(p,1)) # 2x(p,1), then the weak axiom implies that p-x(p',p’+x(p,1)) >
1, Henee the above value is negative.
‘As for the second inequality,
. . 1
(8 ~ PG, Sestpay) ~ tea)
ero 1 = prextp) - ——t
Pixle. Sepp) > Pl) - Soetegy tt
= 2 (pexlpD + —
6D Boxe TT
52-2 Viploxtp. MM Srsteay)
2-2=0.
The infinitesimal version goes as follows. By differentiating x(p,aw) =
cx(p,w) with respect to a and evaluating at @ = 1, we obtain D..x(p,wiw =
x(pyw). Hence
2-7
éSlp.w) = D,x(p,w) + D, xtpywhe(p,w)™ = Dx(p.w) + (1/wlx(pywhelp, 0)"
thus
Dyxtpaw) = Stpiw) - arm xtpwixtpiw)
By Proposition 2.F.2, S(p,w) is negative semidefinite. Moreover, since
vs Gelp,whetp,w) Ww =~ (vexe(p,w))*, the matrix - (1/wix(p.whx(p,w)! is also
negative semidefinite. Thus D,x(p,w) is negative semidefinite.
2.F.6 Clearly the weak axiom implics that there exists w > 0 such that for
every p, p’, and w’, if p-x(p',w") = w and x(p',w') # x(p,w), then p'-x(p,w) >
Conversely. suppose that such a w > 0 exists and that p:x(p’,w") = w and
x(ptw!) # x(p,w). Let & = w'/w. Then x(p',w') = x(p',ew) = x(a /p',w) by
the homogeneity assumption, and p-xta"'p',w) = w and x(a'p',w) # x(p,w). But
this implies that (a!p')-x(p,w) > w, or, equivalently, p'-x(p,w) > aw = w'.
‘Thue the weak axiom holds.
2.F.7 By Propositions 2.E.2 and 2.E.3,
P-Sip.w) = p-D,x(p.w) * p-D,x(piw)x(pw)" = peDyxlpw) + x(pw)" = 0
By Proposition 2.F.1 and Walras’ law,
Ty -
Sip.wip = Dyx(p.w)p + D,,x(p.wix(p.w)'p = Dpx(p.w)p + Dyx(p.w)w = 0.
2,
pce
2F8 Sq(Pow) = Sopa tah)
Piece Ppaeese=r
- (pw) + aan (we, (pw)
Ep) Op, ¥lewT Bw x
ax, PX, (Pw)
= ey (Pw) + We et pw) KE
ePr xlp.w) ow
EydP.W) + Cp (Pr¥ID, (PW)2.F.9 (a) Since x"ATx = (x"Ax)" = xTAx, a matrix A is negative definite if
and gnly if xT AK + xTalx <0 for every x € K\(U). Since xtax 4 xTATs =
xT(A + AT)x, this is cquivalent to the negative definiteness of A+ AT. Thus
A is negative definite if and only if so is A + al ‘The case of negative
definiteness can be proved similarly.
‘The following examples shows that the determinant condition is not
sient fr the nsec cse. tat A= [4 2, J then Ay = 1
:
- “1
and Ayy = 1 But, [4%
I[ i ] = 1. Hence A is not negative
semidefinite.
(®) Let S(p,w) be a substitution matrix. By Proposition 2.F.3, S(p,wip = 0
and hence syo(p,w) = (- Py/pa)ay,(p.¥)- Also p-S{p,w) = 0 and hence 55,(p,¥)
= p,/pQ)5,,(P.w). Thus s,(p,w) = (pt/ps)s,,(p.v). Thus, for every v =
H
v5)"
©
Now, suppose that S(p,w) ic negative semidefinite ond of rank one. According
a 2 2 ,.2),2
VeSEp.We = 5, (P,WILVT = (2Py/PQ),¥> + (BI/PEIND) <
= e 2.
= 54 (P.wI(¥, > (Y7P2V5)
to (*), the negative semidefiniteness implies that <,,(p,w) = 0. Reing of
rank one implies that 5,,(p,w) * 0. Hence s,(p,w) < 0. Thus s,p{p.w) < 0.
Conversely, let s,,(p,w) < 0, then, by (*), v-S(p,wlv < 0 for every v.
2.F.10 (a) If p = (1,11) and w = 1, then, by a straightforward calculation,
we obtain
2-9Hence Sipiw) is not symmetric. Note that
=r
(pL o =a Shy) *
2
sar - 3V574.
7. =- -
Bagi Be 6,
7
‘Theorem M.D.4(iii), S(p,w) 1s negative semidefinite.
(v) Let p= (tj) and w = 1. Let Sip,w) be the 2 x 2 cubmatrix: of Sip,w)
obtained by deleting the last row and column. By a straightforward
calculation, we obtain
° = 3e
Spam = @ + e*[ 25 ® eral
Thus,
7 7 1 2,
4, 4, ostam] 4 | =a, tel 1] = e+ ere ater > 0.
°
if © > 0 is sufficiently small. Then Stp,w) is not negative semidefinite and
hence the demand function in Exercise 2.E.1 does not satisfy the Weak Axiom.
2.F.IL By Proposition 2.F.3, Sip,w)p = 0 and hence s,,(p.w) =
(- py/pp)sylp,w). Also p-S(p,w) = 0 and hence sp,(p,w) = (- p,/P9}54,(P.¥)-
(We saw this in the answer for Exercise 2.F.9 as well.) Thus s,.(P,w)
Spy(PW)
2.F.12 By applying Proposition 1.D.1 to the Walrasian choice structure. we
know that x(p,w) satisfies the weak axiom In the sense of Definition 1.C.1. By
Exercise 2.F.1, this implies that x(p,w) satisfies the weak axiom in the sense
of Definition 2.F.1.2.F.13 [First printing errata: In the last part of condition (*) of (b), the
inequality p-x > w chould be p'-x > w’. Also, in the last part of (c), the
~
relation x’ € x(p.w) should be x’ ¢ ¥(p,w).
(a) We say that a Walrasian demand correspondence satisfies the weak axiom if
the following condition ic satiefied: For any (p,w) and (p’,w'), if x €
2(b.w), x © x(p'yw'), pix = w', and p>x’ = w, then x" € x(p,w). OF
equivalently, for any (p,w) and (p',w"), if x € x(pyw), x’ © alps), pox’ =
w, and x’ € x(p,w), then psx > w!
(b) If x © x(p,w), x’ € x(p',w’), and p-x’ < w, then x’ € x(p,w) by Walras’
law. ‘Thus p'-x > w'.
(©) If x € x(p,w), x’ € x{p'w'), and p'sx = w', then (p! = p)-(x’ = x) = w=
p-x'. If, furthermore, x’ « x(p,w), then Walras’ law implies that px’ = w.
Hence (p' - p)-(x’ - x) = 0, If, on the contrary. x’ € x(p.w), then the
generalized weak axiom implies that p-x' > w. Hence (p' ~ p)-(x' - x) <0. «
(@) It can be shown in the same way as in the small-type discussion of the
pranf af Proposition 2.F.1 that,
in order to verify the assertion, it is
sufficient to show that the generalized weak axiom holds for all compensated
price changes. So suppose that x € x(p,w), x’ ¢ x(p'.w"), p'-x = w', and p+x’
Sw. Then (p' - p):(x' - x) = w - p-x' = 0. Hence, by the generalized
compensated law of Demand, we must have (p' ~ p):(x' = x) = 0 and x’ € x(p,w).
2.F.14 Let p >> 0, w > 0, and @> 0, Since p-x(p,w) = w and (ap)-x(ap,aw) =
aw, we have ap-x(p.w) = aw and p-x(ap,aw) = w. The weak axiom now impl
au &that x(p,w) = x(ap,aw),
2.F.1S Since ax,(p,w)/ew = 0 for both £ = 1,2, we have sp(p,w) =
ax(p,w)/0p, for both & = 1,2 and k = 1,2. Hence, let Stp,w) be the 2 x 2
submatria of Slp.w) obtained by deleting the last row and column, then S(p,w)
= [ool 2} ri mate te seative seit tense
wy, a ‘ “1 - Pau -ee- Wy, -
r2Lo -1 4 ly te 7 %2
(We saw this iu the answer to Exercise 2.F.10(a).) Hence, by Theorem
cee]
72) - av5/4.
M.D.4liii), v-S(p,w)v <0 for alll v not proportional to p. Since Sip,w) is
not symmetric, Sip.w) is not symmetric either.
2.F.16 (a) The homogeneity can be checked as follows:
X,lop,aw) = apap, = Pp/Py = X{(P.W)s
x,lap.aw) = ~ apy/ap, = - By/P3 ~ Xp(Pw)
x,lap.aw) = aw/ap, = W/py = x3(P,W).
As for Walras’ law,
P,x,lb.09 + Poxplp.w) + PaXa(P.W) = (PP. ~ PyPy + PaW)/Py = W-
(b) Let p = (2,0, w = 1, p’ = (11), and w’ = 2, then x(p.w) =
(2, 1, 1) and x(p'w') = (1, - 1, 2). Thus p'+x(pyw) = 2 = w! and
p-x(p!,w') = 1 = w. Hence the Weak Axiom is violated.
(©) Denote by Dx(p,w) the 2 x 2 submatrix of the Jacobian matrix Dx(p,w)
obtained by deleting the last row and column, then
oe sat
vii.w = ange! 4]
Let Sip.w) be the 2 x 2 submatrix of S(p,w) obtained by deleting the last row
2-12and column, then S(p,w) = Dx(p,w) = wel aa ] because ax,(p,w)/aw =
éxpip,wi/ow = 0. Note that v-Sipwiv = 0 for every ¥ € R°. Now let ve R
3
Note that v = (v - (vg/P3)P) + (v3/P5)P and the third coordinate of v -
(vg/Pq)P is equal to zero. So denote its first two coordinates by v € R°,
‘Then, by Proposition 2.F.3, v-S(p.wiv = ¥-S(p,wiv = 0.
2.F.17 (a) Yes. In fact, xylapow) = aw/Zyap,) = w/SyPy) = x,(p.w)
() Yes, In fact, p-x(p.w) = Dex (p.w) = Dppw/(Spp)) = w.
(©) Suppose that p’-x(p,w) = w’ and p-x(p',w') $ w. The first inequality
implies that (Eypj)w/(Eyp)) + w', that is, w/(fyp,) 3 w'/(Dypp)- The second
inequality implies similarly that (J,p))w'/(Syp)) = w, that is, w'/(Sypi) =
WAQypy). Therefore w/(Eyp)) = w'/(Sypj). Hence x{p,w) = xfp',w'). Thus the
weak axiom holds.
%
(@) By calculation, we obtain
eee
2,
Dyelp,w) = (= w/Typg))} : ala
ieee)
D, (Pw) = (W/T,p,)
= x(p.w).
Hence Sip,w)
It is symmetric, negative semidefinite, but not negative
definite,
23 &CHAPTER 3
3.B.1 (a) Assume that » is strongly monotone and x >> y. Then x ® y and x #
y. Hence x > y. Thus > is monotone.
(b) Assume that x is monotone, x € X, and © > 0. Let e = (1,..41) € RU and
y= x+(cMD)e. Then ly ~ xls © and y » x. Thus » is locally nonsatiated.
3.B.2 Suppose that x >> y. Define € = Min Gx = Yyy oir my ~ yp) > ©, then,
for every 2 € X, if ly - zl < e, then x >> z, By the local nonsatiation,
there exists z* ¢ X such that lly - z*ll < © and z* > y. By x >> 2* and the
weak monotonicity, x > 2*. By Proposition 1.B.1(iii) (which is implied by the
transitivity), x > y. Thus > is monotone
r ) 3.B.3 Following is an example of a convex, locally nonsatiated preference
relation that Ie not monotone in 2. For example, # >> y but J >
0 x3.C.1 Let » be a lexicographic ordering. To prove the completeness, suppose
‘that we do not have x > y. ‘Then "y, > x," :
7 Hence
and “x, # y, or yp > x,"
EAL and ¥9 > x,
either *y, 7 x)" oF Thus y x x.
To prove the transitivity, cuppose that x > y and y x 2. Then x, > yy
and y, = 2. Hence x, & 7). If x, > 2), then x xz. If x, = 2), then x, =
¥, = 2, Thus x, = yp and yp =z. Hence x, = zp, Thus x > 2.
To show that the strong monotonicity, suppose that x = y and y # x. This
, or that x, = y, and x, > yp. In
implies either that x, > y, and x, > y, 7
either case x > y.
To show the strict convexity, suppose that y > x, 2> x, y #2, and ae
(0.1). Without loss of generality. assume that x # y. By the definition of
the lexicographic ordering, we have either "y, > x," or "y, = x, and y, > x)".
On the other hand, since z » x, we have either "z, > x," or "2, = x, and x, =
Cv
Jor” Hence, we have either “ay, + (1 - wz, 7 x," oF “ayy + (L~ az = xy
and ayy + (1 - az, > xy." Thus ay + (1 - az > x.
3.C.2 Take a sequence of pairs (x) y"))"_, such that x" > y" for all n, x" +
x, and y® + y, Then u(x") © uly") for all n, and the continuity of ul-)
implies that u(x) = u(y). Hence x » y. Thus x is continuous.
3.€.2 One way to prave the assertion is to assume that > is monotone and
notice that the proof actually make use only of the closedness of upper and
lower contour sets. Then the proposition is applicable to x, implying that it
has a continuous utility function. ‘Ihus, by Exercise 3.C.2, » 1s continuous.
A more direct proof (without assuming monotonicity or using a utility
function) gocs as follows. Suppose that there exist two sequences (x"} and
32fy") in X such that x" > y" for every n, x" > x €X, y" > ye X, and y> x.
Since (2:
¥ > 2} is open, there exists a positive integer N, such that y > x”
for every n> Ny. Since (2: 2 > x) is open there exists a positive integer N,
such that y" > x for every n> Ny. Conceivably, there are two cases un the
Ly:
sequence (y"):
Case 1: There exists a positive integer N such that y" » y for every n > N,
Case 2: There exists a subsequence (y“) such that y > y* for every n.
If Case 1 applies, then, by Propusitivi 1.B.1(iii), we have y" > x” for every
n> Max (N.N3). This is a contradiction. If Case 2 applies, then there
exists a positive integer m such that k(m) > Ny Since {z: z > yet), is
oven, there exists postive Integer Ny such that gP > 8) top every >
Ngo By x® k(n)
ly xy" and Proposition 1.8.11), x > y
em)
for every n> Ny.
Since (2: z x y""™) is closed, x x ¥ But, since k(m) > Np, this is a
contradiction.
.C.4 We provide two examples. The first one ie cimpler, but the second one
satisfies monotonicity, which the first does not.
Example 1. Let X- R, and define u(+): R, > R by letting u(x) = 0 for * <1,
u(x) = 1 for x > 4, and uli) be any number in [0,1]. Denote by » the
preference relation represented by u(-). We shall now prove that x is not
continuous, In fact, if u(1) > 0, then consider a sequence (x) with x = 1 ~
Wn for every n, Although x" ~ 0 for every n and x" 9 1, we have 1 > 0. If
u(1) <1, then consider a a sequence {x"} with x” = 1 + 1/n for every n.
Although x" ~ 2 for every n and x" 4 1, we have 2 > 1. Note that if u(x) = 0,
then all lower contour sets are closed. If u(1) = 1, then all upper contour
sets are closed.
3-3Example 2, Take X ~ R2 and define a utility function u(-): RZ > R by the
following rule:
Case 1. If x +% = 2 and x # (1,1), then u(x) = Xt XD
Case 2. If mintx,, oh = 1 and x # (1,0), then ulx) = min{x,,X,) +2.
Case a. If x, + x, > 2, mints, x,) <1, and x, > X,, then
u(x) = 3 - O - On, - 0).
Case 6 + x, > 2, minty, x) <1, and x, < x5, then
u(x) = 3 - (1 - xx, - 2.
Case 5. u(i,1) € [2,3].
‘The indifference curves of the preference relation » represented by u(-) are
desi
‘bed in the following picture:
cy
2
1
==
oo
0 1 2 x
Figure 3.0.4
It follows from this construction that u(-) is continuous at every x # (1,1).
‘The preference » is convex and monotone. But, whatever the choice of the
value of u(l,1) is, it cannot be continuous at (1.1). In fact,
(= 1/a, 1 - 1/n) > G1) and (+ 1a, 1+ W/m) > (0) as n> @, and
u(l = a, 1 /n) = 2 - 2/0 9 2
3-4ull + In 1+ Yn) = 1+ in +293.
Henes, if 2 < ullsl)s then (2,0) x 1. ~ W/m, d= a/m) but (141) » (2,015 If
ul) <3, then (1 + In, 1+ 1/n) » (2,1) but (21) > G41). If uC = 3,
‘then all upper contour sets of » are closed: if u(l,1) = 2, then all lower
contour sets of » are closed.
3.C.5 (a) Suppose first that u(+) is homogeneous of degree one and let « = 0,
xen, yent, and x~y. Then ulx) = uly) and hence au(x) = auly). By the
homogeneity, ulax) = ulay). Thus ax ~ ay.
Suppose conversely that » is homothetic. We shall prove that the utility
function constructed in the proof of Proposition 3.C.1 is homogeneous of
degree one. Let x € Ry and «> 0, then ulxle ~ x and ulaxle ~ ax. Since » is
homothetic, au(x)e ~ ax. By the transitivity of ~ (Proposition 1.B.1(ii)),
ulcxrde ~ cu(xde. Thus u(exx) = aulx).
(b) Suppose first that x is represented by a utility function of the form u(x)
4 OOK). Leta eR xe RE, ye RY, and x ~ y, Then ulx) = uly)
and hence u(x) + @ = uly) + a. By the functional form,
Ua) + 6 = (@ + Hy) + Hayy
a) = ulx + ae),
uly) +e = (@ +) + BID) = OLY + 20),
where € = (1,0.....0) € RE. Hence u(x + ae,) = uly + ae,). or x + ae, ~ ¥ +
ae,
‘Suppose conversely that > is quasilinear with respect to the first
commodity. The idea of the proof of this direction is the same as in (a) or
Proposition 3.6.1, in that we reduce comparison of cammadity bundles on a Tine
by fining out indifferent bundles and then assigning utility levels along the
line, But this proof turns out to exhibit more intricacies, partly because it
35depends crucially on the connectedness of RL”), which appears in X = (- @, @)
xR} (Connectedness was mentioned in the first simall-lype discussion i
the proof of Proposition 3.C.1.) The proof will be done in a series of steps,
First, we show that comparison of bundles can be reduced to a line parallel to
ej. Then we show that the quasilinearity of » implies the given functional
form.
Let x be a quasilinear preference and a utility function u(-) represent
x. ‘The existence of such a (+) is guaranteed by Proposition 3.C.1, but, of
course, it need not be of the quasilinear form. For each x € RL, define
1G) = (uGc8) © RE x, © R), then 1G) is a nonempty open interval, by the
continuity and the strong monotonicity of 7 along ey,
Step i For every xe RU andj € RE", if 16K) # 169), then 18) 9 1G)
2
Proof: Suppose that IG) # (7). Without loss of generality, we can assume
that there exists u € I(x) such that u ¢ Ily]. Then either u = sup G7) or
u + infl(G). Suppose that u = euplly). (The other case can be treated
similarly.) Then let xf € R satisfy u = Glxt.x), then, for every y, € R.
Ge.) > (y9). In particular, for every x, © Rand yy © Ry Gtk) >
(y, - +24, 9). By the quasilinearity, this implies that (x,,%) >
yD. Thus GO.8) > G9). Hence 1G0 0 19) = &.
For each x € RE, define E(x) = Je RE! 1) = 1G))-
Step 2: For every x € RL, EGX) is open in RL
Proof: Let Ke RL, x, €R, and u = lx, x) € IG), Let © > 0 satisty
(u- ec, u +e) ¢ 1G). Since ii{+) is continuous, there exists 5 > 0 such that
it Fe WL and ux ~ yu <6, ten 1dlxx) ~ Glxy) < ©. Hence
3-61G) AI > G@- eure alee
L-1,
Thus, by Step 1, 16) =). or Fe EG. tence G eRe! ak - ju <8)
¢ E(x). Thus E(x) is open.
Step 3: For every xe RE, BG ~ a,
Proo;
It is sufficient to show that for every xe RL and ye RE, we
nave FU) = EG). Suppose net, then there exit Se RET and 3 RET auch
that Elo) # E(y), then the complement RL“\E(x) is nonempty. By Step 1,
RENEGH) is equal to the union of those E(3) for which ye RL NEG:. By
Step 2, this implies that RL“\E(E) is open. Hence we have obtained a
pertition (EGO,RE NEGO) of RL, both of whose elements are nonempty aud
‘open. This contradicts the connectedness of RL! Hence Else) = Ely) for
every xe RL and jy RE
By Step 3, I(x) = 1(0) for every xe RL! Thus for every xe RU, there
exists a unique @ € ® such that oe, ~ (0.3). Detine ¢: wl
(0,n) for every x € RL. Define us X > R Uy ula) = x, + Kye:
3K by alte, ~
‘for
every x eX
Step 4: The function u(-) represents x.
Proof: Suppose that x ¢ X, y € X, and x > y. By the quasilinearity, this is
equivalent to (x, - Ys Xpyeees Xp) X (O,Yyyeeu¥,)- By the definition of
66), Chis ix equivalent 0 (x) = yy) Xp
xp) 5 O09
yp Je Again by
Je, Again
ets r
(Oxo XL) x Qa) + ¥, — Hey
Again by the definition of ¢(+), this is equivalent to
OK yooor MIO_ 2 HY gH -orVE) + Hy ~ MDOy-
Hence PX p.04 Xp) = Oy ed_) + Yy ~ Xp that is, ulX) = UG.
3-7‘These properties of u(-) are cardinal, because they are not preserved
under some monotone transformation, such ax Flu(a) = ufal?
3.6.6 (a) For p = 1, we have u(x) = a,x, + a,x,. Thus the indifference
curves are linear.
(b) Since every monotonic transformations of a utility function represents the
same preference, we shall consider
toa = - (a,x? + aagx?)
Gx) = Inulee) = (17plin(eryxf) + a.yx8).
By L’Hopital’s rule,
lim U0)
xd
= lim (a, +a, ax + a
Hin ting, + aime vin + 08)
= (ayInx, + a,Inx,)/(a, + a).
is Seen! .
Since expl(a, + @,Vilse)) = x,'x,°, we have obtained a Cobb-Douglas utility
function
There is an alternative proof to this proposition: Since both the CES and
the Cobb-Douglas utility functions are continuously differentiable and
homothetic, it is sufficient to check the convergence of the marginal rate of
substitution at every point. The marginal rate of substitution at (x,,x))
with respect to the CES utility function is equal to @,xf/a,x5"'. The
marginal rate of substitution at (x,,x,) with respect to the Cobb-Douglas
uullity function is equal to a,x,/a%,, Note that «x2 "'a,x2" » a,x,/2%
as p>. (in tact, «x "lagx8°l ts well defined for every p and is equal 0
@,x,/a,x, when p= 1.) The proof is thus completed.
Strictly speaking, there is a missing point in both proofs: We proved the
convergence of preferences on the strictly positive orthant (x € R: x >> 0),but we did not prove the convergence on the horizontal and vertical axes. In
fact, the convergence on the axes are obtained in such a way that all vectors
there tend to be indifferent. To be more specific, compare, for example, x =
(x,.0) and y = (y;.0) with x, > y, > 0, According to the CES utility
function, x is preferred to y, regardless of the values of p. But, according
to the Cobb-Douglas utility function, x and y are indifferent. Futhermore,
the following is true: If x is in the strictly positive orthant and y is on an
then x is preferred ta y for every p sufficiently close to 0. To see
this, simply note that if x = (x,,0) with x, > 0 and y >> 0, then ax?’ >
and ay? + a,y) > a, +a. The implication of this fact is that, as p > 0,
every vector in the strictly positive orthant becomes preferred to all vectors
on the axes. ‘hat is, unconditional preference towards strictly positive
vectors tends to hold, as it is true for the Cobb-Douglas utility function.
(©) Suppose that x, =x, We want to show that
Bg hile
x pee a,x5)
<0, Since x, = 0 and x, = 0, we have ax? sain? + a ws
Let <0. Since xj #0 and) #0, we have ay? sax? + aps Th
a/Px, = (a,x? + ayx6)”P, On the other hand, since x, = x,.
Pe ugh sax? + ux? = a +
mL te ART + Hy Mey + abe
Hence (a,x + a,x6)/P = (a, + 0,)/Px,. Therefore,
Ven = + aya? & (a, + al”,
a Px, = (axl + aad)? & (a, + a),
Letting p * - e wovobtain Lim (ax? + anxPi!/P = x, because Lim «, "Px,
pre pre
lim (a, + a,)?;
prot 2
3.D.1 To check condition (i),
X,(Ap,AW) = a(AWIZ(Ap,) = aw/p, = x\(P.¥),x2{Ap-AW) = (I~ @(AWIZ(Ap,) = (1 = alW/p, = xp(p.w).
To check condition (ii),
Pyx(b.W) + poxylpow) = paw/p, + poll ~ adwrp,
Condition (iii) is obvious.
3.D.2. To check condition (i),
v(Ap,Aw)
w eane + (1 ~ alin(L ~ @) + Inaw - aindp, ~ (1 - adinap,
= alna + (1 - @)In(1 - @) + Ind + Inw
= ainda - alnp) - (1. - @)ina - (1 = «inp,
= a@lna + (1 - @)in(1 - a) + Inw - alnp, ~ ae inp,
= vip,w).
To check condition (ii),
Ov(p,w)/dw = I/w > 0,
avlpiwl/ap, ~~ a/p, < 0,
avip.wi/ap, = - 1 - ap, < 0
Condition (iv) follows the functional form of v(-).
In order to verify (iii), by property (i), it is sufficient to prove
that, for any v € R and w > 0, the set {p € RL: vip,w) ¥ v} is convex. Since
the logarithmic function is concave, the set
2 2
AippPp) € RL: - adnp) ~ (1 - @llnp, = v)
is convex for every v € K. Since the other terms,
aina + (1 - @in(l - a) + Inw,
do not depend on p, thi implies that the set (pe RE: vipw) # ¥) is convex,
2.0.3. (a) We shall prove that for every pe RL, w= 0, a0, and xe Rt, ifoe(pyw), then ax = x(pyaw). Note first that p-(ax) * aw, that is, ax is
affordable at (p.awl. Let y € Ry and py = aw. Then p-(a™'y) = w. Hence
ula™y) = u(x). Thus, by the homogeneity, uly) = ulax). Hence ax = x(p,aw).
By this result,
V(paw) = ube(p,aw)) = uCare(p,w)) = aulse(pw)) = av(p,w).
Thus the indirect utility function is homogeneous of degree one in w.
Given the above results, we can write x(p,w) = wx(p,1) = wi(p) and v(p,w)
= wv(p,1) = w¥(p). Exercise 2.£.4 showed that the wealth expansion path
(elpwh: w > 0) is a ray going through slp). The wealth elasticity of demand
Egy 5 equal to 1
(b) We first prove that for every p © RE
iy WE 0, and a = 0, wo have x(paw) =
cxc(p,w). In fact, since v(-,+) is homogeneous of degree one in w, V,v(pycw) =
av,vip,w) and V,,v(p,ew) = Vv(p,w). Thus, by Roy’s identity, x(p,aw) =
axc(p,w).
now tet ce WE, x 6 WE, uO = ule), and «= OL Since uC) is strictly
quasiconcave, by the supporting hyperplane theorem (Theorem M.G.3), there
exist pe #L,, pie 6, w > 0, and w' > O euch that # = xlp.w) and x =
x(p’,w'). Then u(x) = v(p,w) and u(x’) = v(p’,w’). Hence v(p,w) = v(p’.w").
Thus, by the homogeneity, vip,aw) = v(p',aw’). But as we saw above, x(p,aw) =
ax and x(p',aw") = ax’. Hence vip,aw) = ulax) and vip’aw") = ulax'). Thus
ulax) = ulax'). Therefore u(x) is homogeneous of degree one.
3.D4 (a) Let ¢, = (1,0,...,0) € RY. We shall prove that for every p € RL.
WER GER, and xe (- 0, 0) x RL, if x = xip,w), then x + ae,
xp, w + a). Note first that, by pj = 1, p-(ax + e,) < aw, that ic, x + a8,
is atfordable at (p, w + an). Let y eR and pry sw +a. ‘Then poly = a)
Bell= w. Hence x zy acy. Thus, by te quasilinearity, x + ae, > y. Hence
.
x + ae, = xlp, w + ad.
Therefore, for every € €(2....L wR, and w © R, x4(p,w) =
JL are
x (p,w'). That is, the Walrasian demand functions for goods 2,
independent of wealth. As for good 1, we have dx(p,w)/aw = 1 for every (p,w).
That is, any additional amount of money is spent on good 1.
(h) Define #(p) = ulx(p,0)). Since x(p,w) ~ x(p,0) + we, and the preference
1
relation can be represented by a utility function of the quasilinear form u(x)
xX, + Ulx,,...%,) (Exercise 3..5), we have
v(p.w) = ulx(p,w))
= x\(Rw) + Be fP,W), 26, (BAW).
(p,.0)
w + x4(P,0) + Ule,(p,0),
w + ulx(p,0)) = w + g(p).
(c) The non-negativity constraint is binding if and only if PpX5(P,0) >w,
Note that x,(p,0) = (n')"“(p,), because p, = 1. Hence the constraint is
binding i
and only if p(n')"(p,) > w. If s0, the Walrasian demand is given
by x(p.w) = (O.w/ps). Thus, as w changes, the consumption level of the first
ood is unchanged and the consumption of the second good changes at rate 1/p)
with w until the non-negativity constraint no longer binds.
3.0.5 (a) Since any monotone transformation of a utility function represents
the same preference relation, we may as well choose
Tio = pute” = ple? + x)
iG) = pute? = ple? + xf).
By the first-order condition of the UMP with ii(-),
3-1
xtpw) = (wtp + ponent poh,where 8 = p/(p - 1) € (- @, 1). Plug this into u(-), then we obtain
vtpand = Wiig + BBV,
(b) To check the homogeneity of the demand function,
xlap.aw) = (aw/(ap,)® + (ap,)° (ap) lap,)°4)
= ea eS yiwrtp? + pS ytp2 haps
(aca? "a Kwtpy + pp)of pg)
= x(p.w)
To check Walras’ law,
38 a1 ae,
prx(p.w) = (w/(py * pa)tpy Py + Py"Pa) = W.
‘The uniqueness is obvious.
To check the homogeneity of the indirect utility function,
vlap, aw)
85
ewra V808 4 528 3/8
3
= aw/(ap,)® + (ap) pai’? = wip? + pa
= vip.w)
To eheck the monotonicity,
avip,wivaw = Vip? + pa) > 0,
= wed Med 4 98/84
av(p.w)/apy = - wee p> + pb) °
‘The continuity follows immediately from the derived functional form.
Tn order to prove the quasiconvexity, by property the homogeneity, it is
sufficient to prove that, for any v ¢ R and w > 0, the set (p € R* vip,w) $
Wis conver, If 8 then the utility function is a Cobb-Douglas one, and
the quasiconcvity was already extabliched in Exercise 3.0.2. So we consider
two cases, 8 € (0.1) and 8 £0. Ih elther ease define stp) = (98 + 38)Y®,
If 8 € (0,1), then sip)” = p® + p is a concave function. Hence {p € R°:
aie
Ftp) = (r(p)8)8 z vy Is convex for every v. Since vlpyw) = w/S lp), this
implies that {p € R%: v(p,w) < v) is convex for every v and w.
3-13If § <0, then fip)® = p> + p8 is a convex function. Hence {p € R:
81-8)
wre) = (rp)? = vids convex for every v. Since vip,w) = w/y(p),
this implies that {p ¢ BR: v(p,w) # v) is convex for every v and w.
(c) For the linear indifference curves, we have
(w/py. 0 i py < py
x(p.w) = 4 (0, w/p,) if P, > Py
{Cw/p A, =A: Ae (0,11) if py = poi
Mipyw) = max(w/p,.w/p,)
For the Leontief preference,
x, (D.W) = (w/tp,+ py):
vip.) = w/(p,* Pp).
As for the limit argument with recpect to p. First consider the case
with p< Land p31. Then d= p/p -1)>-easp>i.
Case. py < Pp.
8
30. This
: wp,
lim pf lwp? + p8) = 11m ——_. = w/p,.
5 b9-@ 1 + (p,/p,)
Since p,/p, > 1, we have (p,/p,
since p/p) <1, we have (p\/pp)® > @, Thus
: we,
tim 8 twu8 + p= 11m ——2— =
a 33-0 (p,/pQ)° +1
Thus the CES Walrasian demands converge to the Walrasian demand of the linear
indifference curves. As for the indirect utility functions, we showed in the
answer to Exercise 2.C.6le) that (p® + p3)/®
> yy for py 4 py Heuce the
CES indirect utilities converge to the indirect utility of the linear
indifference curves.
Case 2. py > Py
Do the same argument as in the Case 1Case 3. py
In this case, (w/(p> + pain" ye)
) = (wp? + prvn(p?
2
(w2p 1). This consumption bundle belongs to the set of the Walrasian
demands of the linear indifference curves when pj =p. As for the indirect
utility functions, we showed in the answer to Exercise 3.C.6(¢) that
5 joys z
(of + py”? » p, for p, = Pp.
Let’s next consider the case p > - @. Note that 5 = p/(p - 1) 91 as p >
1, Su just plug 6 = 1 into the CES Walrasian demand functions and the
indirect utility functions. We then get the Walrasian demand function and the
indirect utility function of the Leontief preference.
(@) From the calculation of the Walrasian demand functions in (a) we get
- 3-1
X(.W)/x2(P,W) = (Py/P.)°
8-2
p/P)
(x (B.WI/x9(P,WII/P/Pp) =
6-2
Ale (W)/xp(eW4dlp,/pp) = (6 = Wp, 49) *-
Thus €,,(p.w) = - (8 - 1) = 1/1 - p). Hence, €,>(p,w) = @ for the linear,
E,2(p.w) = 0 for the Leontief, and €,,(p.w) = 1 for the Cobb-Douglas utility
functions.
WatBe) _
a OOOO eG OME
3.D.6 (a) Define G(x) = utx) Ox, = BY Ory = dy Gx, - d4)%,
with of = aa + @ +9), B= Pa + B+ 7) v= ya+ B+ 7¥). Then a’ +p”
and U(+) represents the same preferences as u(+), because the
function u > ul/asey) is a monotone transformation. Thus we can assume
without loss of generality that a +B + y= 1.
(p) Use another monotone transformation of the glven utility function,
Inu(x) = aln(x, - bj) + Bln(x, ~ by) + vinx, - b,).‘The first-order condition of the UMP yields the demand function
(pw) = (Vysbyi¥) + Cw ~ prbMarp,,A/R,.¥/7,),
where p:b = pjbj + poby + pads. Plug thic demand function to u(-), then we
obtain the indirect utility function
vip,w) = (w - p-d)a/p,)"8/p,Pta7p,)”.
(©) To check the homogeneity of the demand function,
X(APAW) = (bybyybg) + (Aw ~ Ap-EG/AP BAP I/A)
= (by bgrb) + (w - p-bMa/pyB/pay7/Pq) = x(prw).
To check Walras law,
p-x(p,w) = pb + (w - p-b\(p,a/p, + p,B/P, + P52/Dq)
prb + (w - pba + B+ 9)
The uniqueness is obvious.
To check the homogeneity of the indirect utility function,
vapAw) = Aw ~ Ap-b)la/p)*(e/API arp,”
ARDY — p-vya/p JB/pgIta/pq)
= (w = p-b\(a/p,)%(8/p)ta/p5)* = vip,w).
To check the monotonicity,
avipiwi/ow = (a/p,)%(8/p9!ta/y_)" 2 0,
avip,w)/apy ~ vipiw)-(- a/p,) < 0,
ov(p.w)/ap, = vip.w)-(- B/p,) < 0.
1
avip.wi/ap, = vip,wi-(- ¥/pq) < 0.
The continuity follows directly from the given functional form. In order to
prove the quasiconvexity, It Is sufficient to prove that, for any v ¢ R and w
> 0, the set (p © RY vip.w) = ¥) ia convex. Consider
Invip.w) = alna + flnB + giny + In(w ~ p-b) ~ alnp, ~ Blnp, - zinpy.
Since the logarithmic function is concave, the set|
|
\
{p € R°: In(w ~ pb) - ainp, - Binp, - yinp, = v)
is convex for every vc R. Since the other terms, alna + Bin8 + yiny, do not
depend on p, this implies that the set (p € R°: Inv(p,w) = v) is convex.
Hence so is (p € R°: vip.w) = ¥)
3.0.7 (a) Since p!-x°< w! and x! # x°, the weak axiom implies p°-x! > w°,
Thus x! has to be on the bold
e in the following figure.
Figure 3.D.7(a)
In the following tour question, we assume the given preference can be a
differentiable utility function u(-).
(b) If the preference is quasilinear with recpect to the first good, then we
can take a utility function ul-) so that au(x)/ax, = 1 for every x (Exercise
3.C.5(b)), Hence the first-order condition implies 6u(x')/axy = p/p; for
each t = 0,1. Since p9/p° < pip} and ul-) is concave, xp > x3. Thus x! has
to be on the bold line in the following figure.02 4 8 10 5
Figure 3.D.7(b)
(c) If the preference is quasilinear with respect to the second good, then
then we can take a utility function u(-) so that du(xl/éx, = 1 for every x
(Exercise 3.C.5(b)). Hence the first-order condition implies aulx')/axy =
tpt since 50/20 > ohyy? 5
Pi/P) for each t = O,1. Since py/PD > pi/p) aud ul-) is concave, we must have
Oo.
x} pj/Pyy x' has
to be on the right side of the ray that goes through x°, Thns x! has to be on
the bold line in the following figure.Figure 3.D.7(e)
3.D.8 By Proposition 3.D.3(i), vlap,aw) = v(pyw) for all a > 0. By
differentiating this equality with respect to a and evaluating at a = 1, we
obtain Vvip.w)-p + wavip.w)/aw = 0, Thus wavip,wi/aw = - U.v(p.w)-p.
3.E.1 The EMP is equivalent to the following maximization problem:
Max = px sit. u(x) eu and x20.
‘The Kuhn-Tucker condition (Theorem M.K.2) implies that the first-order
conditions are that there exists 4 > 0 and 4 RU such that p = AJu(x*) +p
and y-x* = 0. That is, for some A > 0, p = AVu(x*) and x*-(p - ATu(x*)) = 0.
‘This fs the same as that of the UMP.
3.E.2 To check the homogeneity of the expenditure function,
ep) = et - 0) ap Map) u
T 2
= = aA yy = elp.u).
To check the monotonicity,
3-20ae(p,ul/au = @ 1 - al !p tps > 0,
aelp.ulvap, = alt = a pip ® > 0,
Tey 70.
To check the concavity, it is easy to actually calculate Dee(p.u) and then
ae(piu)vep, = a1 - a)
apply the condition in Exercise 2.F.9 to show that Deto.u) is negative
semidefinite. An alternative way is to only calculate
Tag. gytpt phe
ePetp.ur/epy eal MU - apps < 0.
Then note thal the homogeneity implies that DPetp.up = 0. Hence we can apply
Theorem M.D.A{lii) to conclude that DZe(p,u) is negative semidefinite, The
continuity follows from the functional form.
To check the homogeneity of the Hicksian demand function,
Iw bea
“Ap, “Py
hyQpwu) = ue w= hyip),
Wap, Ws a,
@ - aap, )* Ga - ap, )*
nga = | aap |e = | ap | hae
To check the no excess utility,
ep, 8 = wp,
uo = |e] 4) || at} 9
on (-ae-a(1-a)
- od yet
Trap,
The uniqueness is obvious.
3.E3 Let X ¢ RU and uGR) =u. Define A = (x © RE: prx prk and ule) = vu)
‘Then A #@ by Xe A. Furthermore, A is compact: The closedness follows from
that of (x ¢ RU: ulx) 2 u) and of RL; the boundedness follows from the
inelustan
Ac (x eR: 0 = xy = pri/p, for every F= 1,...1)
3-21Now consider the truncated EMP:
Min p-x st. xe A.
Since p-x is a continuous function and A is a compact set, this problem has a
solution, denoted by x* € A. We shall show that this is also a solution to
the original Emp. Let x ¢ RU and u(x) 2 u. If x € A, then p-x = p-x® because
x* is a solution to the truncated EMP. If x € A, then p-x > p-X and hence p-x
> p-x*. Thus x* is a solution of the original EMP.
3.E.4 Suppose first that x is convex and that x € h(p,u) and x’ € h(p,u).
Then p-x = p+x’ and u(x) = u, u(x’) = u, Let @ € [0,1] and define x” = ax +
(1 = ax’, Then p-x" = ap-x + (1 - a)p-x' = p-x = p:x’ and, by the convexity
Of x. u(x") © uw. Ths x” € n(p.u)
Suppose next that x is strictly convex and that x € n(p,u), x’ € n(p,u),
x # x’, and u(x) 2 ulx') = u. By the argument above, x" = ax + (1 - alx’ with
« € (0,1) satisfies p-x" = p-x = p-x’ and. by the strict convexity af », we
have x" > x’. Since x is continuous, @x" > x’ for any B € (0,1) close enough
to 1. But this implies that p-(8x") < p-x and u(x") > u(x’) 2 u, which
contradicts the fact that x is a colution of the EMP. Hence A(p,u) must be a
singleton.
3.E.5 [First printing errata: The equality h(p,u) = A(p)u should be h(p.u) =
uftp), because u is a etalar and filp) is @ veetor.] We shall first prove
that, for every p >? 0, U= 0, @ = 0, and x = 0, if x = Alp,u), then ax =
Aipyew). In fact, note that ulax) = au(x) = au, that is, ax satisfies the
constraint of the EMP for au. Let y ¢ RL and uly) = au. Then ula” y) = wu,
Hence p-(a'y) = p+x. Thus p+y = p-(ax). Hence ax = h(p.aul. Therefore
3-22h(pju) is homogeneous of degree one in u.
By this result,
e(p.au) = pehlpyau) = p-(eh(pyu)) — a(p-h(p,u)) = ae(p,u)
‘Thue the expenditure function is homogeneous of degree one in u.
ih(p) and
Now define filp) = h(p.l) and e(p) = e(p,1), then hlp,u) =
e(p,u) = uel(p).
3E.6 Define 8 = p/(p = 1), then the expenditure function and the Hicksian
demand function are derived from the first-order conditions of the EMP and
they are as follows:
nips = ug + 98 9G,
3,8 Vs
e(p.u) = ulpy + p3
To check the homogeneity of the expenditure function,
878 _ 81/8,
elapyu) = ullap,)® + (ap,)°) (p> + po? = aetp.n)
‘1 2 1 2
To check the monotonicity,
detp.ul/au = (p> + pb)“ > 0,
de(p,ul/ap, = ups ‘ip? + py)? > 0.
To check the concavity, it is a bit lengthy but casy to actually calculate
ee(p,u) and then apply the condition in Exercise 2.F.9 to show that DZetp.u)
is negative semidefinite, An alternative way is to only calculate
aelp.ul/ape
8-2) 8, SI/S1 , F1.3s , 8y1/8-2 Bl
= us ~ ph (pe + pO* + upl Mwy + pb)? Pave = Dap}
208 5S VE2 8 a
= ull ~ arp ip? + pay Pept - (wt + PO) < o,
by 6 <1. Then note thal the homogeneity implies that DZetpwudp = 0. Hence
we can apply Theorem M.D.A(iil) to conclude that DZe(p,u) is negative
semidefinite. The continuity follows from the functional form.To check the homogeneity of the Hicksian demand function,
Alap.a) = ullap,)® + (ap,)8"°8”8((ap >"! (apy?)
(8(1-8)/8)4(8-1),,3 , ,8)(1-81/8 8-1 8-1
ne ute? + pb) ey Py)
= h(pyu).
To check no excess utility.
utr(pud) = leh + pp IE p/FUe , plF-eyp,
Since (8 - 11/8 = - 1/p, we obtain u(h(p,u))
The uniqueness is obvious.
3.E.7_ In Exercise 3.C.5(b), we showed that every quasilinear preference with
respect to good 1 can he represented by a utility function of the form u(x) =
.0) € RY. We shall prove that for every
x1). Let e, = (10
p> Owith p= 1 ueR we R and xe (=, 0) xR it x = Alpwul, then
x7 0e, = MP, U+ a). Note first that ux + ae,) = u + a, that is, x + ae,
satltes the constraint of the EMP for (pu + al. Let y @ RE and uly) = w+
& Then uly - ae) =u. Hence pely - 90,) = psx. Thus pry = pilx + ae
Hence x + ae, = Alp. u + a).
Therefore, for every £ € (2,...L), ue R, and v’ © R, hylpu) =
‘hj(pwu'). That is, the Hicksiai: demand functions for goods 2,...,L are
independent of utility levels. Thus, if we define A(p) = h(p,0), then h(p,u)
= Rip) + ue).
Since h(p, u + a) = hlp.u) + ae,, we have elp, u + a) = elpyu) + &
1”
Thus, if we define (p)'= e(p,0), then e(p,u) = Sp) + u.
BEB We use the utility function uc) = x95". to prove (3.6.1),
- Lede gylme ma anl
elp(pyw)) = Mt ~ a) Ip tpd Ma - ay! pi IW) = w,
na, alge ole Ia
vinetp.ud) = ata = ay pi *pS MaMa ~ a Ate) Muy » u.
3-24To prove (3.£.3),
& alpre(pyu)) = et - a Hyp) Burlarpy, (1 - 1p)
ea a
an, Gap,
= || eae] [ma] nip.u),
a Ina =a a1, ap, Pf a - wp
hipyv(pyw)) = aU = a! “pS | | = +
1 2
= wla/py, ( ~ @/p)) = x(pw).
3.E.9 First, we shall prove that Proposition 3.D.3 implies Proposition 3.b.z
via (3.E.1). Let p >> 0, p' >> 0, ueR, v' eR, and ae 0.
i) Homogeneity of degree one in p: Let @ > 0. Define w = e(p,u), then u =
vipw) by the second relation of (2.E.11. Hence
elapyu) = elap,v(p,w)) = elap,vlapaw)) = ew = ae(p,u),
where the second equality follows from the homogeneity of v(+.+) and the third
0 from the first relation of (3.E.1).
(ii) Monotonicity: Let u’ > u. Define w = e(p,u) and w’ = e(p,u’), then u =
vip,w) and u' = vip,w'). By the monotonicity of v(-,-) in w, we must have w"
> w, that is, e(p'u) > e(p,u)
Next let p' = p. Define w = e(p,u) and w’ = e(p',u), then, by the second
relation of (3.E.1), u = v(p.w) = v(p',w'). By the monotonicity of v(-,
must have w’ = w, that is, e(p',u) = e(p,u).
(iii) Concavity: Let & € [0,1]. Define w = e(p.u) and w’ = e(p’,u), then n=
vip,w) = v(p',w). Define p" = ap + (1 - ap" and w" = aw + (1 - aw’, Then,
»
by the quasiconvexity of v(+,+), vip"sw") (piu) and any w, if e(p au") = w for
every n, then e(p,u) s w; if e(p"u") = w for every n, then e(p,u) = w.
‘Suppose that e(p",u") = w for every n. Then, by the monotonicity of v(+,-) in
w, and the cecond relation of (3.E.1), we have u" < vip",w) for every a. By
the continuity of v(-,-), us vip,w). By the second relation of (3.E.1) and
the monotonicity of v{-,-) in w, we must have e(p,u) < w. The same argument
can be applied for the case with e(p".u") = w for every n.
Let’s next prove that Proposition 3.E.2 implies Proposition 3.D.3 via
(3.E.1), Let p >> 0, p' >> 0, we R, w ER, and a= 0,
(i) Homogencity: Let @ > 0. Refine 0 = v(p.w). Then, by the first relation
of (3.E.1), e(p,u) = w. Hence
vlap,aw) = v(ap,ae(p,w)) = v(ap.elap.u))
vip.w),
where the second equality follows from the homogeneity of e(+,-) and the third
fram the second relation of (3.E.1). Kw
(ii) Monotonicity: Let w' > w. Define u = v(p,w) and u' = v(p,w'), then.
= w and e(pju’) = w".
et. By the monctonicity of e(-,-) and w' > w, we
must have u’ > u, that is. v(p.w') > v(p.w).
Next, assume that p’ = p. Define u = v(p,w) and u’ = v(p'.w), then
e(p,u) = elp'ju') = w. By the monotonicity of e(-,-) and p’ = p, we must have
ul su, that is, v(pyw) = v(p',w),
(iii) Quasiconvexity: Let a € [0,1]. Define u = v(p,w) and u' = v(p',w').
Then e(p,u) = w and e(p,u') = w’. Without loss of generality, assume that u”
=u. Define p" = ap + (1 - a)p' and w = aw + (I - aw’. Then
elp"u’)
= ae(p.u') + 1 ~ alelp’= ae(p,u) + (1 - ade(p’,u')
saw + (1 - aw = wy
where the first inequality follows from the concavity of e(-,u), the second
from the monotonicity of e(-,+) in u and u' 2 u, We must thus have v(p",w") <
w
(iv) Continuity: It is sufficient to prove the following statement. For any
a
sequence ((p"™,w°)"_, with (p".w") > (p,w) and any u, if vipw") = u for
every n, then v(p,w) 3 u; if v(p",w) > u for every n, then vipw) =u
Suppose that vip",w') = u for every n. Then, by the monotonicity of e(+,-) in
u and the first relation of (3.E.1), we have w" 3 e(p"u) for every n. By the
continuity of e(
++), ws e(pu). We must thus have v(p,w) = u. The same
argument can be applicd for the cace with vip",w") ® u for every n.
‘An alternative, simpler way to show the equivalence on the concavity/
quasiconvexity and the continuity uses what is sometimes called the
epigraph.
For the concavity/quasiconvexity, the concavity of e(+,u) is equivalent
to the convexity of the set {(p,w): e(p.u) = w) and the quasi-convexity of
VG) 1s equivalent ta the convexity of the set (pw): v(pw) = u) for every
But (3.E.1) and the monotonicity imply that v(p,w) = u if and only if
e(p.u) > w. Hence the two sets coincide and the quasiconvexity of v(-) is
equivalent to the concavity of e(+,u).
As for the continuity, the function e(+) is continuous if and only if
both {(p,w,u): elp.u) + w) and ((p,w,w): e(p,u) = w) are closed sets. The
function v(+) is continuous if and only if both {{p,w.u): vip») = u) and
{(p,w,w): v(p.w) Su) are closed sets. But, again by (3.E.1) and the
monotonicity,
3-27{(p.wwuh: etp.u) = w) =
(p.W,w): vip.w) = Ur;
A(p,w,u): efp.u) = wh = Upwyul: vipw) ud.
Hence the continuity of e(+) is equivalent ta that of v(-)
3.6.10 [First printing errata: Proposition 3.f.4 should be Proposition
3.6.3.)
Let's first prove that Proposition 9.D.2 implies Proposition 3.£.3 via the
relations of (2.6.1) and (3.6.4), Let p ¢ RL and ue R.
(1) Homogeneity: Let « > 0. Define w = e(p,u), then u = v(p,w) by the second
relation of (3.E.1). Hence
Alap,u) = xlap,elap,u)) = x(ap,ce(p,u)) = x(p,e(p,u)) = Alpu),
where the first equality fellows from by the first relarfon of (3.E.4), the
Second from the homogeneity of e(-,u), the third from the homogeneity of
x(+.), and the last from by the first relation of (2.£.4)
(ii) No excess utility: Let (p,u) be given and x € h(p,u). Then x €
x(p.e(p,u)) by the first relation of (3.6.4). Thus u(x) = v(p,e(p,u)) = u by
the second relation of (3.E.1).
Convexity/Uniqueness: Obvious
Let's first prove that Proposition 3.F.2 implies Proposition 2.0.2. via
the relations of (3.E.1) and (3.6.4). Let p ¢ RU, and we R.
(i) Homogeneity: Let « > 0 and define w = e(p,u), then vip,w) Hence
xlap,ew) = hlap,viap,aw)) = hlap,v(p.w)) = hip,v(p,w)) = x(p,w),
where the firet equality follows from the second relation of (3.E.4), the
second from the homogeneity of v(-}, the third from the homogeneity of h(+) in
b, aud the last from the first relation of (3.E.4).
(ii) Walras’ law: Let (p,w) be given and x € x(p,w). Then x € hlp,v(p,w)) by
3-28the second relation of (3.6.4), Thus p'x = e(p,v(p,w)) = w by the definition
of the Hicksian demand and the firet relation of (3.E.1)
(iii) Convexity/Uniqueness: Obvious.
3.F.1 Denote by A the intersection of the half spaces that includes K, then
clearly A > K. To show the inverse inclusion, let X ¢ K, then, since K is a
closed convex set, the separating hyperplane theorem (Theorem M.G.2) implies
that there exists a p * 0 and c, such that p-X <¢ < p-x for every x € K.
Then (2 € RU: p-z = c} is a half space that includes K but does nol contain x.
Hence X € A. Thus K > A.
3.2 If K is not a convex set, then there exists x ¢ K and y € K such that
(/2)x + (W/2ly € K, as depicted in the figure below. The intersection of all
the half-spaces containing K (which also means containing x and y) will
contain the point (1/2)x + (1/2)y, since half-spaces are convex and the
intersection of convex sets is convex. Therefore, the point (1/2)x + (1/2)y
cannot be separated from K.
x
(iayx+ (Lay K
y
Figure 3.F.2
3-29As for the second statement, if K is not convex, then there exist x € K,
y €K, and @ ¢ (0,1) such that ax 4 (1 - aly € K. Since every half space that
includes K also cuntains ax + (1 - ay, it cannot be separated from K.
3.G.1 Since the identity v(p,e(p,u)) = u holds for all p, differentiation
with respect to p ylelds
V,v(p.e(p.u)) + (6v{p,e(p,u))/awI¥, (Pu)
By Roy's identity,
(ovlpre(p.u)/owN(- x{p.e(p.u)) + Vpe(p.u)) = 0.
By avip.e(p.u))/ew > 0 and hip,u) = x(pre(p.u)), we obtain hip.u) = VLe(P.u).
3.6.2 From Examples 9.D.1 and 3.E.1, fur the utility function. u(x) =
we obtain
wp,
Pyste = 1a alvp, |
~ aw/pe °
D,xlp.w) = 2
a 0 ~~ awrpy
a a we;
Velpu) = ulp,Za)(py/lt ~ a))® [ ne ep |:
D,elpwu) = Drip,
pel, ) D ple. u) ‘ , e
og | - x - ae ell ~ @/ppp,
= ulp, 20)p, iL = at iad v Hae)
zi ZI el ~ ec)/y = all = a7 a
PiP2 Pe
‘The indirect utility function for u(x) = xh is
vip,w) = (p,Za)%(pg/t1 ~ a) Ww.
(Note here that the indirect utility function obtained in Example 3.U.2 is Yor
the utility function u(x) = alux, + (1 - a@)lnxy.) Thus
U,MPLw) = vipwi= apy ~ (I~ ap)¥viB.w) = vip, w/w.
8 Hence:
h(p,u) = Vgetp,u),
Detp.u) = D,h(p.u), which is negative semidefinite and symmetric,
D,hlpwulp = 0,
D,plpsu) = D,xtp.w) + D,x(e.w)xtp.w)",
xplb.w) ~~ (Bv(p.u)/ap )Aav(p.u)/ow)
3.6.3 (a) Suppose thal a +B + 4 Note that
Inu(x) = aln(x, ~ b,) + Bln(x, ~ b,) + rinlx, ~ v4).
By the first-order condition of the EMP,
Alpwu) = (by byybq) + ulP,/)(Py/8 tp g/2)"(a/P PP 2 9/9)
Plug this into p-h(p.u), then we obtain the expenditure function
elpu) = pod + ulp,/a)"(pp/)(Py/n)”,
eo where p-b = pib, + Pzb, + Pqdy
To check the homogeneity of the expenditure function,
e(apwu) = Ap-b + uApy/al*ap,/ePapy/)™
= Ape + Aulp/o%™p,/Bipy/a" = retp.u).
To check the monotonicity, assume b, © 0, by = 0, and by = 0. Then
delp.ulau = (p,/a)(p,/AIpa/1)* > 0,
aelp,urvap, = 0,
+ prep >
1 + UD Zep BIC 4/7)" arp)) > 0,
by + ulpy/a%v,/BPtPy/"(0/PQ) > 0,
: 2e(p.vl/0p,
Belpiul/apg = by + ulp,/al“(p,/AP(ps/a ap) > 0
To check the concavity. we can show that Dye(p.u) is equal to
331all -a/pt — 08/p,p, 23/02,
ulp/a(p,/8(py/e"| —aB/p,p, BL - B/S By/ppPy &
«9/P,P BY/P2P, -ra- nA,
nd then apply the condition in Exercise 2.F.9 to show that Dee(pu) is
negative semidefinite. An alternative way ic to only calculate the 2 x 2
submatrix obtained from Dee(p.u) by deleting the last row and the last column
and apply the condition in Exercise 2.F.9 to show that it is negative
definite, Then note that the homogeneity implies that De(p,ulp = 0. Hence
we can apply Theorem M.D.Alii) to conclude that DZe(p,u) is negative
semidefinite. The continuity follows from the functional form.
To check the homogeneity of the Hicksian demand function,
Opa) = (bybyby) + lap 70) apy/BIP(Apy/2)a/Ap B/APy3/APg)
= (by barby) + "PF 70)%(p,/8P i g/7)"(a/P18/Py19/Pg)
nip,u)
To check no excess utility, &
UinprU)) ~ ulp,/a)™(Py/P (pga Me’ B/P.)a/py) =
The uniqueness is obvious.
(b) We calculated the derivatives e(p,u)/ap, in (a). If we compare them with
(P,w), then we can immediately see de(p,u)/ap, = hy(p,u).
he
(e) By (b), Dyhtpwul = DZe(pul, In (al, we calculated DBe(p.u). In Exon
3.D.6, we showed
x(p,w) = (by,b,,d5) + (wee -b)(a/p,,B/P2,7/P,)
and hence D,,x(p,w) = (@/p,,8/Py,3/Pq) and
3-32é
2
we 9 0 ap,
2
Pyxtpm = - tw = pro] © Bee 0 | - | Bie | toy bydgl
0 0 a5 ey
Using these results, we can verify the Slutsky equation.
(a) Vee D,hipu) = Dfetp.u) andthe explicit expression of O%tp) in ta
(6) This follows from Sip,u) = D,h(p.u) = Dee(p,u) and (a), in which we showed
that Dietp.u) is negative semidefinite and has rank 2.
3.G.4 (a) Let a> 0 and beR. Defined: RL > R by ilx) = aulx) + b and, for
each & a,
R, oR by a,lx,)
auy(x,) + b/L. Then
U(x) = aL yup(x,) + b= Llauglx,) + b/L) = Lyiiplx,).
‘Thus any linear (to be exact, affine) transformation of a separable utility
function is again separsble.
Next, we prove that if a monotone transformation of a separable utility
function is again separable, then the monotone transformation must be linear
(affine). To do this, let's assume that each ul) is continuous and strongly
monotone, Then, for each & the range u/(R,) is a half-open interval. So let
where by may be + @, Define cy = by - ay > 0, a= Spay b=
and o~ Lycy (If some by is equal to + », then b and c are + @ as
eee
= lab). Suppose that f: [a,b) + K is strongly monotone
and the utility function U(-) defined by U(x) = f(u(x)) is separable. To
simplify the proof, let’s assume that f(-) is differentiable. Define g: [0,c)
am by
atv) = flv + a) ~ flad,
3-33then g(0) = 0, g(-) is differentiable, and
glu(x) ~ uf0)) = fluGed) — flu(o))
tor every x € Ab, Thus, in order to prove that +) 1s Hnear (affine), 1s
sufficient to prove that g(-) is linear. For thi
tis sufficient to show
that the first-order derivatives g'(v) do not depend on the choice of
v € [0.c).
To this end, we shall first prove that if Wwe {0,c,) for each é, then
yyy
Tyely). For this, it is sufficient to prove that
glue) ~ ul0)) = Fygtuglxy) ~ uy(00)
tor every x ¢ Hl tn fat, by the separabltyasrumpio, fer cach &, ere
exists a monotone utility function il) such that ie) = fyi) for every x
RL, Fix an x © RE and, for each t, detine x6 RL by yf = x) and yf = 0 for
any k #2 Since iy’) = fluty’,
Tylreg) + Fyceglhy Od = Flryly) + Ty gpl (ON.
(0) = G(0) = F(u(O)) from both sides and noticing that
o) + tk
~ Uf0) = klufx,
subtracting TE sy
Aagloep) + FigptylO) = upOup) =
14,(0), we obtain
lx, - u,(0)).
‘Summing over &, we obtain
Lyip(x,) - Lj O) = Lyetuylxy)
Since
Lpliplaxy) ~ LpiglO) = GOR) - (0) = ful - FlulOn = glutxd - won,
we have
gtulx) - u(0)) = Sygtu,(x,) ~ ulo)).
We have thus proved that g(D,v)) = Syg(vy)
To prove that the g’(v) do not depend on the choice of v € [0,c), note
first that if vp € [0,cg) for cach & and v = Fyvy e [0,c), then g'(v) = g'(v,)
3-34for each €, This can be established by differentiating both sides of e(Dy¥,)
= Tyslvp) with respect to vy
So let v € [0,c) and v' € [0,c), then, for each ¢, there exist v, €
{0,c4) and v; € [0,¢,) such that v = Jjvy and v’ = Jv Then g'(v) = g'(v,)
and g'(v') = g"(vi). Now, for some ¥, € [0,¢,), consider v, + ¥, € [0,e) and
2
vi +H € (0c). Then
si) = 8 + ¥) = 8G,
gly) = glu, + V2) = g'C¥9).
Thus g'(v,) = g'(v}) and hence gv) = g'(v").
Note that the above proof by means of derivatives is underlain by the
cardinal property of additively separable utility function, which is that,
when moving from one commodity vector to another, if the loss in utility from
some commodity is exactly compensated by the gain in utility from another,
‘then this must be the case for any of its monotone transformations resulting
in another additively separable utility function. (Thi fact is often much
more shortly put into as: utility differences matter.) For example, consider
p05) ~ unl) > 0 and xy =
0<}) + up{x3), the separability
b vere - .
xe RY and x’ € RY such that u(x) — uC)
for every £= 2. Since uyjlx,) + ulx,)
implies that u(x) = u(x’). By the equality g(F,vy) = Tyetvy)
g(uj(x,) - u,(0)) + glug(x,) ~ up(0)) = gluj(x}) - u(0)) + gluy{x5) - uA(0)).
Hence
8(u,0%) ~ uy(0) ~ glug) ~ uO) = glug(xs) - uA(0)) ~ glu(x,) - up{0)).
We have shown that, under the differentiability assumption, if this halds for
every x), x3, x}, and x}, then g(+) must be linear.
1 rt
(b) Define $ = G,...,L) and let T be a subset of S. The commodity vectors
3-35for those in S are represented by 2, = (z,},., € RS! and the like, and the
commodity vectors for tote outside are represented by Zp (ggg € AEM
ad the like, We shall prove that for every 2, ¢ RY, 2t e RET, 2, e aL",
and 23 € RY", (225) (zz,) if and only if (2,25) » (21,25). In fact,
since u(+) represents », (21,25) » (21.25) if and only if
Lyertelee) * Leerte%p) = Letty 2p + Leertel2y?
Likewise, (21,25) x (2},25) if and only if
Teer£ 20+ Baer” eer * Dye
Dut both of these two inequalities are equivalent to
Tyerte'ey) * Epertel@p-
Hence they are equivalent to each other.
(c) Suppose that the wealth level w increases and all prices remain unchanged.
Then the demand for at least one good (say. good £) has to increase by the
Walras’ law. From (3.D.4) we kuow that uj(c(p.w)) = (p/p) )ujbep(p.¥)) for Ne
every k
sL. Since x,(p,w) increased and u,(-) is strictly concave, the
Tight hand side will decrease. Hence, again since u,(-) is strictly concave,
,(P,w) will have to increase. Thus all goods are normal.
(@) The first-order condition of the UMP can be written as
Mpwipy = Walp),
where the Lagrange multiplier (pw) is a differentiable function of (p,w)
This can be easily seen in the proof of the differentiability of Walrasian
demand functions, which is contained in the Appendix.
By differentiating the above first-order condition with respect to py, we
obtain
3-36(BAlp,w)/8p,)Pp + A(p,w) (xq(p.w)(dxylp,w)/ap,)
By differentiating the above first-order condition with respect to p, (k # U,
we obtain
“ (2n(p.w)/2p, Bp ~ UL glp, WI Bxylp.W)/8p,)-
Thos
dlp: x(p,wil/p,,
UZ, p,x(P.w)]/dp,,
2(B.W) + Py 826, (P,WI/EPL) 1 Tyg PplB2/(P.¥)/P,)-
(2lp,w)/ap, IPE + ACP. W)P, (nlp, wap, )Py
= xj(prw) + ——,_*# *& Ep
u" Ce (p,w)) ul ey (p.w))
2
ACPWPY, Pe
= xy.) « + (2X(p,w)/0R, Ey .
UG (p yw) weg (pyw))
Lele enPr
By the first-order condition, Alp, wp), = U'Gx,(p,Ww)) and hence this equals
U(x (ow) x (D,wIU (xy, (D.w)) %
- — (KE + 1) + (anlp,w)/8, 15, ————
UC (pw) Uw" Gx, (PW) U(x (pw)
By Walras’ law, this equals zero. By the strong monotonicity and the strict
Or Gey(p.w)d %
concavity, —K <0 and Ey x4. < 0, By the assumption on
Woy (p.w) Oe (pew))
ke t
- iP WI" Og, (DAW)
ul-), ——.—____ +1 > 0. Hence
a (x,(P,w))
U(x (BW))xylp, wId" Cx, (PW)
+ = neo.
UG, (BW) Ur tx, (R.W)
We must thus have @(p,w/ap, <0. Hence, by (*), axylprwi/ap, > O-
3.6.5 (a) We shall show the following two statements: First, if (x*,2*) is a
solution to
3-37Max, 2) He2) st. pox + az sw,
then there exicte y* cuch that q-y* = z* and (x*,y*) is a solution to
7 5 w&
aX y) MOLY) St pox + (agg)-y < ws
second, if (x*,y*) is a solution to
Maxey 9) UOKY) 8.t. pox + lagg)-y < w,
then (x*,qg"y*) is a solution to
Maxyy 2) Hoo) sit. px + az sw.
Suppose first that (x*,2*) is @ solution to Max,, 9) W(xz) st. pox +
az sw. ‘Then, by the definition of (+), there exists y* such that qg-y* =
2" and u(x*,y*) = U(x*.z"). Let (x,y) satisfy p-x + (agg)-y sw. Then
ulxy) = Goygg*y) < ulxt, ulx.y"),
where the first inequality follows fram the definition of ti(+) and the second
Inequality follows from p-x + alqg-y) = p-x + (agg)-y = w and the definition
of (x*,z*). The first statement is thus established.
AAs for the second one, suppose that (x*.v*) is @ solution to Max, yy te
ulxy) s.t. pex + (aqy)-¥ Sw. For every y, if Ay = doy" then
Prat + (aqg)-y = p-x® + algg-y) S p-x* +-alag-y*) = w.
Hence ula) 3 ubet.y®). Thus ulety*) = Glatgg:y"). Now let (x,2) satiety
P’x + az = w. Then there exists y such that qo-y = z and u(xy) = U(x,z).
Thus p-x + (adg)-y = px + algg-y) s p-x + az sw. Hence
WO%,2) = ulxy) 5 ulxtsy*) = OOxa,-¥").
(b) (c) These are immediate consequences of the fact that the Walrasian demand
functions and the Hicksian demand functions are derived in the standard way,
by taking U(-) to be the (primitive) direct utility function,
3.6.6 (a) By applying Walras’ law, we obtain x, = (w - x,p, - X5P,)/P5.
*%3 1Py ~ %2P2!/Po:
3-38(p) Yes. In fact, for every A > 0,
100 - 5Ap,/Apy + PAPy/Apy + SAW/AP, = 100 - Spi/py * BPa/Py + Su/Pyy
a + PAD, Ap, + 7AP,/AP, + SAW/Ap,
a + Bp,/p; + m,/p, + dw/p,.
(c) By Proposition 3.G.2 and 3.G.3, the Slutsky substitution matrix is
symmetric. Thus
8/pg + (8/P,Na + BP,/P3 * TP2/Py + 6W/P)
= P/Py + (8/P3)(100 - 5p,/P3 + By/P + 3¥/y)-
Hence hy putting p= 1 and rearranging terms, we obtain
(B + a8) + BSD, + 25p, + S°w = (B + 1008) - S8p, + BSp, + Ow.
Since this equality must hold for all p,, p and w, we have
B+ ad = BP + 1005, BS = - 55, 7S = PS.
Hence « = 100, 8 = - 5, and y = - 5. Therefore,
X17 Xp, 7 100 - 5P,/pq + Spp/Pg + Sw/py
Recall also that all diagonal entries of the Slutsky matrix must be
nonpositive. We shall now derive from this fact thal 8 = 0. Let P3 = 1, then
the first diagonal element is equal to
- 5 + 6(100 - St Sp) + ow.
If 8 # 0, then 8” > 0 and hence we can always find (pyspy,W) such that the
above value is positive. We must thus have 4
In conclusion,
X, =X, = 100 - 5P,/P, + SPo/Py-
(a) Since x, ~ x, for all prices, the consumer's indifference curves in the
(x,.x,)-plane must be L-shaped ones, with kinks on the diagonal. (So the
restricted preference is the Leontief one.) They are depicted in the
following figure
3-39Figure 3.G.6(4)
(©) By (a), for a fixed x3, the preference for goods 1 and 2 can be
represented by min(xyx,). Moreover, there is no wealth effect on the demands
for goods 1 and 2. We must thus have
Uber) = minty x5) 4 xy
or a monotone transformation of this.
3.G.7 By the first-order condition of the UMP, there exists A > 0 such that
gtx) = vu(x). Premultiply both sides by x, then Ax+g(x) = x-Vulx). By
Walras’ law, x-g(x) = 1 and hence A = x-Vulx). Thus
= Mute = gta outs
a0) = utd = Sapte Tule)
By Exercise 3.D.8, we have av(p,1)/8w = - p-V,v(p.l). By Proposition
1 . 1
3.6.4, 207) = > aap yaw Up (PH) = Ue re
3.6.8 Differentiate the equality v(p,aw) = v(p,w) + Ina with respect to « and
evaluate at a = 1, then we obtain (v(p,w)/8w)w Hence év(p,1)/8w
By Proposition 3.6.4, x(p,1) =
Viv(p.D).
3-40ec
3.6.9 Let p >> 0 and w > 0. All the functions and derivatives below arc
evaluated at (p.w)
By differentiating Roy's identity with respect to p,, we obtain
(2°v/8p,8p,(av/ew) ~ (8v/ap,)(3°v/ap aw)
axyop, =
ere (avrewy”
Or, in the matrix notation,
Dix = - 5 (0,,vb2y - v.y0,v,y) € a,
YDB — UprD aa
wy)
(Recall that V.v is a column vector of RY, and Div and DV y are row vectors
? ? pw
of Ri (Section M.A).) By differentiating Roy's identity with respect to w, we
obtain
(2? v/ep,awilav/aw) - (av/6p,)(8°v/aw")
axyow = -
( av/aw)
Or, in matrix notation,
1
Dx =- — Hayy - vey) Re.
wv) P Pr
Hence
1 2, 1 ev 1
eae Mut Ge ~ MpPPphgh — Cy MOL pia Dye * Vip Vel gy Day”
i 2
1 2, Pw
~ EWG = IDV # WyYyPDpy) + az YyyDpy)
w
It is noteworthy that we can know directly from Roy's identity and this
equality that the Slutsky matrix S has all the properties stated in
Proposition 3.6.2. To, see this, note first that both V.v(p.w) and V,,v(p.w)
are homogeneous of degree - 1 (in (p,w)) by Theorem M.B.1. Hence x(p,w) is
homogeneous of degree O (where we are regarding Roy's identity as defining
x(p.w) from Yevip.w) and V,,v(p,w)). Thus (2.E.2) follows, as proved in
Proposition 2.E.1. On the other hand, by Exercise 3.D.8, p-x(p.w)
3-41Henee,
2 proved in Propositions 2.E.2 and 2.£.9, this implies (2.6.5) and
(2.£.7). Now, as proved in Exercise 2.F.7, (2.£.2), (2.£.5), and (2.E.7)
together imply that S(p,w)p = 0 and p-S(p,w) = 0.
The matrix S(p,w) is symmetric because Dev, V.vD,¥,,v + ¥,0,¥D,¥, and
V,yD,y are symmetric, ‘The negative semidefiniteness ean be shown in the
following way. Since v(-) is quasiconvex, for every price-wealth pair (q,b),
if Dyyq + Dyvb = 0, then (q.b)-D2y (q,b) = 0 (Theorem M.C.4). But Daya + Hye
= 0 if and only if b = - Diva/V,v. Plug this into (q,b)-D7v(q.b). then
2, 2, 42
a-Diva + 20(0,0,,¥a) + Uy b'
2
2D,0 va (va)
= a-Devq - —B*—p vq + vey —P
» w ’ (vv)
" A 2 (val?
= Tp yarDiva) - 210,7yraND,va) + av —P—
P
Hence the quasiconvexity of v(-) implies that the above expression is
nonnegative for every q. On the other hand,
; --1, -D?vq) ya) + ve
a-Stp.wia (Ma Deva) - 200,¥,,vaD,va + VY
(vv)
(vv)
Thus q-S(p,w)q 0. Therefore S(p,w) is negative semidefinite.
3.G.10 We shall prove that a(p) is a constant function and b(p) is
homogeneous of degree - 1, quasicanvex, and satisfies b(p) = 0 and Uh(p) < 0
for every p >> 0.
We shall first prove that a(p) must be homogeneous of degree zero. Since
v(p,w) is homogeneity of degree zero, we must have a(Ap) + D(ApIAW = a(p) +
biplw for all p > 0, w* 0, and A» 0. If there are p and A for which a(Ap)
a(p), then this constitutes an immediate contradiction with w = 0. Thus
3642,a(p) is homogeneous of degree zero.
Next, we show by contradiction that Valp) + 0 for every p > 0. Since
vip,w) is nonincreasing in p, we must have Va(p) + Vb(plw = 0 tor every p >> 0
aud w 0. If there are p> © aud € for which dalpl/Opp 7 0, then this
constitutes an immediate contradiction with w = 0, Thus alp) < 0 for every p
> 0.
We shall now prove that the only function a(p) that is homogeneous of
degree zero and satisfies Va(p) = 0 for every p > 0 Is a constant function.
In fact, by differentiating both sides of a(Ap) = a(p) with respect to A and
evaluating them at A= 1, we obtain Valplp =
Since p >> 0 and Va(p) = 0,
we must have Va(p)
Hence a(p) must be constant
Given this result, the homogeneity of v(p,w) implies that 0(p) is
homogeneous of degree - 1. Since v(p,w) is quasiconvex, so is a(p) as a
Tunction of p. Finally, since V,v(p,w) = Volplw < 0 and Vvip,w) = O(p), we
myst have U(p) & O aud Wolp) + 0 for every p 7 0.
This result implies that, up to a constant, v(pyw) = b(p)w and hence, if
the underlying utility function is quasiconcave, then it must be homogeneous
of degree one. On the other hand, according to Exercise 3.D.4(b), if the
underlying utility function is quasilinear with respect to good 1, then, for
Pt
w. You will this wander why we have ended up excluding this quasilinear case.
all w and p >> 0 with p, = J, v(p,w) can be written in the form #lPpy
‘The reason is that, when we derived vip,w) = @(p) + w, we assumed that the
consumption set is (- @, «) x RL. Thus x,(p,w) can be negative and, if so,
then dv(p,wl/ap, is positive, which we excluded at the beginning of our
analysis, following Proposition 3.0.3, (Note that, when we established
ov(p,w)/op, + 0 in Proposition 9.D.3, we assumed that the consumption set is
3-43L
Ry) As x,(pw) ie positive for sufficiently large w > 0, the quasilinear
case could be accommodated in our analysis if we assume that the inequality
4v(p.w)/8p, $0 applies only for sufficiently large w > 0. (In this case, we
can show that a(p) is homogeneous of degree zero, and b(p) is homogeneous of
degree - 1, quasiconvex, and satisfies b(p) © 0 and Ub(p) = 0 for every p >>
0.)
3.G.11 Suppose that v(p.w) = a(p) + blp)w. By Roy's identity,
xtp.w) = ~ (1/b(p)Talp) ~ (w7btp)7_ I
p. pv, Alp (PDT, PEP).
Thus the wealth expansion path is linear in the direction of ¥,b(p) and
intercept (- 1/b{p))¥, alp).
3.6.12 Note first that, according to Exercise 9.G.l1, the wealth expansion
path is linear in the direction of V.b(p) and intercept (— 1/b(p))0,a(p)
If the underlying preference is homothetic, then (— 1/b(p))V,a(p) =
Hence a(p) must be a constant function. If the underlying utility function is
homogeneous of degree one in w, then vipyw) must be homogeneous of degree one
in w by Exercise 3.D.3(a). Hence alp) = 0 for every p >> 0.
If the preference it
quasilinear in good 1, then please first go back to
the proviso given at the end of the answer to Exercise 3.G.10. After doing
50, note that, since ihe demand for goods 2,...,L do not depend on w,
10),
( Yo(p)V, lp)
/p,,0,
or (90(p)/0p,)/0(P) = 17p, and 20(p)/9p, = O for every £ > 1. Hence v(p)
bpe + x for some B+ 0, p40, and y eR. Dut, by Exercise 9.6.10, b(p) must
‘be homogeneous of degree - 1, positive, and nonincreasing. Hence p = - 1. 7 =
0, and @ > 0. That is, b(p) = B/p, with @ > 0. If the underlying utilityfunction is in the quasilinear form x, + fit...) then, by Exercise
3.0.4(b), v(p,w) must be written In the form #(p>,.
pL) + w for all p> 0
with p, =. Thus 6 = 1.
G3 For each 1 € {O,h....n), let @, be @ differentiable function defined
on the strictly positive orthant (p< RU: p >> 0). Tat vip.w) = D*_.a\(plw!
be an indirect utility function. Denoting the corresponding Walrasian demand
function by x(p,w). By Roy's identity,
1
xp.) =~ pega Wath)
Hence, for any fixed p, the wealth expansion path is contained the linear
subspace of RE that is spanned by Pag.)
As for the interpretation, recall from Exercise 3.6.11 that, an indirect
utility function in the Gorman form exhibits linear wealth expansion curves.
But the Gorman form is a polynomial of degree one on w and a linear wealth
expansion curve is contained in a linear subspace of dimension two. Hence
‘the above result {mplies that the indirect utility functions that are
polynomials on w is a natural extension of the Gorman form,
3.G.14 Define a, b,c, d, e, and f so that
-10 a b
ec -4 4
=o
Since the substitution matrix is symmetric, we know b = ande ad
By Propositions 2.F.3, p-S(p,w)
Hence p,(- 10) + p,e + P38 = 0. “Thus ¢
=-4anda=c
4. For the second column, p,(- 4) + pp(- 4) + pge = 0.
3-45Hence e = 2 andd =e = 2. Finally, for the third column, we have p,3 + p,2 +
psf ‘Thus f = = 7/6, Hence we have
-10 -4 3
- 4 -4 0 2
3 2-1
The matrix has all the properties of a substitution matrix. which are
symmetry, negative semidefiniteness, S(p,w)p = 0, and p:S(p,w) = 0. (For
negative semidefiniteness, apply the determinant test of Exercise 2.F.10 and
Theorem M.D.4(iii).)
Pw 4pyw
3.6.15 (a) x(p,.p,.W) =
z* zy
PyPo + APY 4D yP2 + Pz
Pou 2 pe 2)
©) MEyP” = || aap eT | | ase, | |
2
P Pat!
(©) eloprpys) = apap ep’ He is then easy to show that Yhetpypyiu) =
A(PyPpst-
(€) vipypp,yw) = 20w/p, + 4¥/p,)". To verity Roy's identity, use
av(p,.p,.wiap,
= tw, + anny Ye we
Ov(ppPpsWl/Opy = (w/py + 4w/py)/?(- 4m/pe),
aut,
wi/aw = (w/p, + aw/p,)/U/p, + 4/n,)
3.G.16 (a) It is easy to check that
8
de(p,ulven, = etp.ullo,, + vB, (Ilypy “D/P,
Since e(p,u) is nondecreasing in p, this must be nonnegative for all (p,u).
But, if a <0 and lpi is sufficiently small, then this becomes negative.
Also, if @, < © and §pll is sufficiently big, then this becomes negative.
3-46Therefore
w @, = 0 and B, = 0 for all k.
It is a little bit manipulation to show that
Toy BB
eQrpu) =a fexplDyaylnp) +> ‘aime, 4,
Ae(p.u) = Aexpl(ityesinp,) + ulTlp, D).
Since e(p,u) is homogeneous of degree one with respect to p, they must be
equal for every (p.u) and A> 0, Take, for example, p
(41) and u = 1
Then
log efpru) = (Sy loza + he
log Xe(p,u) = loga + 1.
They must be equal for every A > 0. Therefore
@ Tete) Tete
Thus
Typ ~ 1s yO By
Hence the expenditure function now takes the simplified form:
@ elp.u) = (expudttie, Os Tyay = 1. a =
This is increasing with respect to u and concave in p.
“
() By equation (3.6.1), w = (exp vip,wittypy ). Hence
@ vipiw) = logw ~ yszloepy-
(c) By differentiating e(p,u) with respect to p, we obtain
Alpwu) = el uN /Pyr.e-sth /Pp )-
Since x(p,w) = h(p,v(p,w)) and e(p,v(p,w)) = w,
(5) 2e(p.W) = wl 7D, PL).
Use equations (3), (4), and (5) and follows the same method as in the answer
3-47to Exercise 3.6.2 to verify Roy's Identity and the Slutsky equation.
3.6.17 [Eirst printing errata: The minus sign at the beginning of the right-
hand side of the indirect utility function should be deleted. That is, it
should be
Vip.w) = (w/p, + bMap,/p + a/b + cllexp(- bp,/p,)
Also, in (b), the minus sign in front of the first term of the right-hand side
of the expenditure function should be deleted. That is, it should be
elp.u) = pauexplbp,/p,) - (/b\lap, + ap,/d + ppc’.
Finally, in (c), the minus sign in front of the first term of the right-hand
side of the Hicksian function should be deleted. That is, it should be
- arb.
(paw) = unexp(op, /p,
(a) Use
Sulp,wi/ap, = - p;'(apy/p, + bw/p, + elexpl- dp//p,)
Ovlpw)/8w = pziexpl- bpy/P,)s
and apply Roy's formula.
(b) According to (3.£.1), we can obtain the expenditure function by colving
w= (e(p.ui/p, + b'Cap,/p, + a/> + cllexpl- bp,/p,).
(©) Apply Proposition 3.G.1 to obtain the given Hicksian demand function for
the first good.
9.6.18 We prove the asst ion. Suppose that there exist £ €
4a
connecting ¢ and k. Define J = (é) u (J € U,
jon by contradi
sL) and k € (1,...,L} such that there ic no chain of substitutes
L): there is a chain of
substitutes connecting & and j). Since £€ J and k € J, both J and its
3-48complement (I,...,.L)\J are nonempty. Moreover, for any j¢ J and any j € J,
an (p.ulvap,, © 0, decause, otherwise, J < 1
Let u: RE 4 R be the underlying utility function, Following the hint, as
in Exerciee 3.6.5, define G: RO > R by
x L
Hilyy,) = Maxtubd: x © RE, Digi ey = ¥y Dye shy >
® x Gin?) + m® be the Hicksian demand function derived from i(-).
Let fiw,
That is, Fla,.a,,u) € RY is the solution to
Ming yp) SUL ' S22
st gay) =u
Define playay) >> 0 by pilayay) = ap, if je J and playa, = a,p, if j
J. We shall prove that
Flayagyu) = (jeg Ry (Play ag)uls Figs? hy (Play.a).0)
Write x* = h(pla,.a,),u). Then iS
xD QjP,x4) & ulx*) =u. Hence the
ea PE jes
constraint of the cost minimization problem is satisfied. Suppose that
(yp¥q) © RE and ly,,y,) & u, then (assuming strong monotonicity) there
1 . a
exists x € RY such that 569%; = Jy» LigsPXj = Yor and ulx) = Gy, ys).
Thus u(x) © u and hence, by the cost minimization of 3", playe,)'x =
pla.a,)-x*, This is equivalent to saying that
2 HD ye Pf) + HEP >
Thus Flay a.0) = Lie jP X4 Lye sP XP
By this equality and the chain rule (M.A.1),
AR aay Wl Ba4y = Lye PD pg y(h (Pa 05).u)/0P,IP,)
= ZyeBcggP Py 2 j Pla ppatghul/opp)
We now derive a contradiction from this equality evaluated at (a,.0,) =
(1). On the one hand, since 8h (pyu)/8p, <0 for every J © J and every k ¢
J, we must have dh,(1,1,u)/da, <0. On the other hand, note that fi(-) is theHicksian demand function of U(+) for two (composite) goods. Since
GFi,(a,05,u)/8a, < 0 by the negative cemidefinitenecs, and
(OF (a .05,4)/0a, Ip, + (OF, (ay.a,4)/00,)P,
we must have ah,(1,1,u)/8a, = 0, We have thus obtained a contradiction.
3.H.1 By Proposition 3.H.1, e(p,u)
Min(p-x: x € V,}. Thus, to complete the
proof, it is sufficient to show that V,
(x: u(x) =u). That is, x € Vy if
and only if Sup (t: x € V,) 2 u.
Clearly, if x € V, then Sup (t: x € V,} =u.
Assume that Sup (t: x ¢ V,) =u. Define u* = Sup (ti x ¢ Vp. If ut
> u, then there exists t € (u.u*l such that x € V,. Since e(+) is
Increasing in utility levels, Vy > V, and hence x € V,. If u* = u, then, for
every ne N, there exists u, € (u - 1/n, u) such that x ¢ V,, that is, px =
‘n
e(p.u,) for all p. Let n+ ©, then u, + u and, by continuity of e(p.u), prx =
e(p.u) for all p. Thus x € V,
3.11.2 We show the contrapositive of the assertion. If a preference is not
convex, then there exists at least one nonconvex upper contour eet. Let u ¢ R
be its corresponding utility level. We can choose a price vector p so that
h(p,u) consists of more than one elements, as the following figure shows.
According to Proposition 3.F.1, e(-) is uot differential at (p,u).
3-50Figure 3.2
3.H.3 By (3.E.1), for each p, take the inverse of e(p,u) with respect to u.
‘3.H.@ The following method {s analogous to that of "Recovering the
Expenditure Function from Demand” for L = 2.
Pick an arbitrary consumption vector x° and assign a utility value u° to
We will now recover the indifference curve (x: u(x) = u°) going through
x°, Assuming strong mono tonicity, this is equivalent to finding a function
(sur: (0, @) 2 (0, a) such that ulx,§(x)) = uo for every x, > 0.
Differentiate
both sides of ulk,,€(%)) = u° with respect to ,, then we obtain
ul, .€(%,))/6x, + (dulX,,€(%,))/6x,)6 6 0.
Hence
auld, .666,)/8%
© Bulky ER N70K | ;
since ope elses aes eG) ESS
Bul ECR N/O% gl /ECE)) 89 (K EK)
3-51or, by replacing %, by x), we obtain
(oy s8(25))
BRT
€lx,) =~
1 Ee
By colving thie differential equation, we obtain the indifference curve yuing
through: 2°.
3.H.S By (3.E.1), we can recover the expenditure function by simply inverting
‘the indirect utility function.
To recover the direct utility function, define u: RI 9 R by lx) =
Min(v(p,w): p+x s w). We shall prove that u(x) is the direct utility function
that generates vip.w). So let x#(p,w) be the demand function and v#(p,w) be
the indirect utility function generated by u(x). It is sufficient to show
that v"(p,w) = v(p,w) for all p >> 0 and w = 0.
Let p >> 0 and w = 0, then p-xt(p,w) = w and hence v*(p,w) = ulx®(p,w)) =
vipyw). It thus remains to show that v*(p,w) = vip,w). Define
1
==> ayia pe
Ths x « at by the monotonicity. Since V,yip.m):p # Vyvipanlw = 0 by the
homogeneity, p:x —
It is thus sufficient to show that ulx) = v(pw). So
let p' >> 0 and w’ 2 0 satisfy p'+x = w’. Then (p' - p):x = w’ - w, or, by
the definition of x, V.v(p,w)-(p' - p) + V,v(p.wiw" - w) = 0. Hence, by the
quasiconvexity of v(p,w), vip',w') = vip,w). Thus u(x) = v(p,w)
3.H.6 Let's first prove that the symmetry condition on S(p,w) is satisfied.
Ry equation (3.H.2), Se(p,ul/dpy = ayelp,ul/py for every &. By
differentiating both sides with respect to p,. we obtain
aPelpiul/OppP, ~ (ay/PNBe(pvul/O,) = (aye /PyP,Je(Pv)-
On the other hand, by differentiating both sides of de(p,ul/ap, = a,e(p,ul/p,,
3-52with respect to pp, we obtain
* = =
2%e(p.ul/On, ay = (a,/p,)(de(D.u)/dp~) = (aya, /P,P,Je(PU
Hence the symmetry condition is satisfied,
We can thus apply the iterative method explained in the small-type
discussion at the end of Section 3.H to derive the expenditure function.
First, we shall prove by induction that, for every &, there exists a function
F(Pyy-PL») such that
Inetp.w) = Sy aptylnDy, + FplPpgyee-Py 2
Suppose first that £ = Since (8e(p,u)8p,)e(p,w) = &,/p,. Hence, by,
integrating both sides with respect to p,, we obtain
Inet(pyu) = aylnp, + £4(Pyee- Pt.
Thus the equality ic verified for ¢
Suppose next that # > 1 and the
equality holds for £ ~
Ry differentiating both sides of
Ine(py) = ep MlOPy, + Fy y(PysssPL yw)
with respect to p,, we obtain
Belp.ul/8p, = Ay {yonesPy ¥)/OPp
Since de(p,ul/8py = ay/Py, this is equivalent to
yg = Fp Pye 0)/APp
Hence, by integrating both sides with respect to py, we know that there exists
FelPyyye-esPLyW) such that
eplnpy = 1440 = FPpgee PLD
By plugging this into
Ine(p.U) = Decpas% AP + Fpy(Pp- PL
we obtain
Inetp.u) = YjeghylOD, + F4lPyyyreenPY:
If £ = L, then this equality becomes Ine(p.u) = Tyo %lnp, + Fu). Or,
3-53equivalently, e(p.u) = (Mp, expf,, (u)
In what follows, for every Increasing function f, (u), we shall find the
utility function that generates the expenditure function e(p,u)
o
«
(hyp, expf,(u). To start, consider the utility function ut(x) = Thx, &
which appeared in Example 3.E.1 for the case of L = 2. Denote its expenditure
function by e*(p,u), then
aaeeanac es
(yay “Typ, Du*.
*(p,ut)
(We considered a similar expenditure function in Exercise 3.G.16. Note that,
these similarities incidentally show that, for every increasing function
«
FW), the expenditure function e(pyu) = (Ip, ‘lexpf,(u) has all the
Properties of expenditure functions in Proposition 3.£.2, because it
4
corresponds one of the monotone transformations of uM(x) = Mx, 4) Let g(u*)
he an monotone transformation and denote by e,(P,u) the expenditure function
of the utility function (geu*)(x). Then
Kg te) = Me, emp, Se tw.
e,(Pu)
By comparing this with e(p.u) = (Mypy Sexpy,(u), we know that (geut)(o) =
ulx) if
muy wy *,
(nye, Dep, dew = trp, Yexpr,(w
This equality is equivalent to ¢"(u) = (Myx, expf,(u). Letting ut = eu)
and solving this with respect to u*, we obtain
*) = 7 inut ~
gu") = F7'Unu® ~ Lyaplne)
Thus
wh) = glutad) = Fy "Unut(xe) - Syaylnay) = FP (Dyaylinxy ~ Ina).
Of course, two possible utility functions are u(x) = Tiyx, © (corresponding to
ee
Fu) = Inu ~ Fyapina,) and ube) = Fyne, (corresponding to f,(u) = u -
3-54&
Taina)
3.H.7 (a) Let p = (...1) Since x(P,L) = (1,...)1) and u(l,...91)
according to Propositions 9.[.1 and 3.G.1, DyelPat) = Alp)
Hence eff
L.
On the other hand, S(a,w) = DZe(a,w) = 0 for every q >> 0 by Exercise
2.F.11d). Hence
elp.u) ~ equ) = Die(q.ulp - 4).
for every q >> 0 and p >> 0. Now take q
thus etpa) = Bhp
» then e(p,l) - L = pr(p - p).
(b) The upper contour set is equal to
(xe Al: pox = TE py for every p >> Ob = xe RE: x
3.1.1 By the came method ae deriving equation (3.1.3), we obtain
Ev(p°,pw) = e(p?,u!) - etptu!)
0 0.0 oO. 0.0 0) cll
= ea - ete! p9.79,--sppul) + aes Se uePpt) = e(phu)
P »:
1 neo 0.00 yl 2 nel ou
Fo Moye orf amy +1 men Soranh he
1 2
cv(p®,p.w) = etp?,n°) - etp!u?)
© 1) — gion? 0°
= e(p°,u°) - e(ps.Pp.P5,
1
P ».
1 00 0.0 2 0,
=F GA PpPa Pg PLU) ary + SO MPpPZPge PL) dP,
ni Po
If there is no wealth effect for either good, then, by the first relation of
(3.E.4),
nip, .P-PS, pPu?) for every p, > %
9
wish 1.) for evry bg > 8Thus EVip®,plw) = ov(p>,
Denote the deadweight loss given in equation (3.1.5) by DW,(t) and that
in equation (3.1.6) by DW,(t). Then
ers tant? at B,
nt) = nip? et. Bw) = (hoe tS 1
DWi(t) = Aipy +t, By w) = (rip) + t, 8. vyep))
Oneal
vrontp? +t, By vhvapy.
‘Thus DW:(0) = 0 and, if ah(p B_ys8!0p, > 0 for every p, > 0, then DWi(t) >
0 for every t > 0. It can be similarly shown that NW; (0) = 0 and, if
AMP B_yU°/6p, > 0 for every p, > 0, then DWg{t) > 0 for every t > 0.
A possible interpretation of this result is that the first-order
derivatives of the deadweight loss at t = 0 may be a bit misleading t
approximation. In fact, their being zero means that, approximately, there is
no deadweight loss. On the other hand,
\ce those derivatives are positive
at every t > 0, DW,(t) = £5 DW3{t) de > 0 and DW, {t) = S5 DWelc) dt > 0.
fact positive. wl
Hence the deadweight losses are i
°
3.13 Write vw vip?w) and u! = viptyw), then uv < a ‘because po . pt and
Cant
pos pl, Thue
0 0, °
elDp Pept) < Aylpy Pope)
for every py > 0. Since good £ is inferior,
8
°
XflPppepelppP>,ul) > xylrpP,elPpP? pu).
By the first relation of (3.£.4), this is equivalent to
oO 0 oo,
hylPpp pe) > hylpyPopu).
Hence, by (3:12), (3.1.4), and p® < pl, we have cv(p%,plw) > EV(e° pw).
3.1.4 We shall give two examples, both of which have two commodities. The
3-56 Nefirst one is simpler, while the second one is more illustrative.
In the first example, we consider a preference with “I.-shaped”
indifference curves such that Ue vectors (1,1), (4,2), and (6,3) are kinks
of indifference curves, Let u(ll) - 1. Note that if one of the two prices
‘equal to zero, then the demand is not a singleton. We thus need to
consider a demand correspondence x(p,w). But this does not essentially change
our argument because we are working on expenditure functions, which is
single-valued by its definition.
1
Let p? = (1), pl = (12,0), p® = (0,2/3), and w= 2. Then x(p®
an, xtpw) > (4,2), xlp.w) > (5,3), and vip2w) > v(ptw) Rut etn =
1/2 and elp®,1) = 2/3. Thus
erty) = 2 - 72 = 3/2,
cvip?,p?.w) =
= 23 = 473,
Hence v(p°,plw) > cvip®,p.w).
It is worthwhile to remark that, although the given preference is neither
smooth, strongly monotone, nor strictly convex, it can be approximated by such
one.
In the second example, we consider a utility function u(x) which is
quasilinear with respect to the first commodity. Let v(p,w) be the
corresponding indirect utility function, Starting from p° =
1,1) and w > 0,
we conser two other price vectors pt = (pha) and 12 = (192) such that 0.<
Ph <1, 0 < py <1, and viplw) = vip".w). Write v? = vip?w) and ub =
vipt,w) = v(p%w). Then EV(p°,p.w) = EV(p°sp?w)
1
He, oven
We shall now show that CV(p°,p!.w < GV(p®\p’.w). BY P|
< Evip®.phw). Also, by the quasilinearity, CV(p%p?w) = EV pp?)
(Exercise 3.1.5). Hence oVip° pw) < CV(p?,p%w.
357It is worthwhile to remark that, although Ev(pplw) = Ev(p?,p2,w), we
can obtain the strict reverse inequality Ev(p®,plw) > EV(p?,p?w), while
preserving CV(p°.p',w) < V(p”.p".w), by decreasing p% only slightly.
3.15 According to Exercice 3.£.7, we can write the expenditure function
e(pu) = &(pp,....P,) + u for py Hence
Ev(p?yplw) = e(p ul) - e(p?,u)
p0
Co.
>= G09.) +
0
e
cv(p?,p yw) = elp'u') - etp'u)
Gos
PE) tw) Bp) +0)
° on 1 0)
povw)). IP Fy6V,(p%sphw,) & 0, hen Dw, ® Delp ul).
(plu), then Sw; = Ew, and v,(p',wi) = uP = v(p°.w,).
2.1.7 (a) Dy applying Walras’ law and the homogencity of degree zero, we can
obtain the demand functions for all three good defined over the whole domain
{(p,w) € R° x R: p >> 0}. Thus we can obtain the whole 3 x 3 Slutsky matrix
as well trom the demand function. The Z x 2 submatrix of the Slutsky matrix
that is obtained by deleting the last row and the last column is equal to
tveg)[ 2 § ]: By the nomogeneity and Walras' law, the 3 x9 Slutsky matrix
is symmetric if and only if this 2 x 2 matrix is symmetric. Moreover, just as
in the proof of Theorem M.D.4{iii), we can show that the x 3 Slutsky matrix
is negative semidefinite (on T,, and hence on the whole R) if and only if the
3-582% 2 matrix is negative semidefinite. Hence. utility maximization implies
that ¢ bs 0, 20, and bg - c7 BO.
(b) First, we verify that the corresponding Hicksian demand functions for the
first two commodities are Independent of utility levels and, as functions of
the prices of the first two commodities alone, they are equal to the given
Walrasian demand functions. let p be any price vector and u, u' be any two
utility levels. By (3.E.4), hy(p,u) = x,(p.e(p,u)) and hy(p.u')
+) do not depend on wealth,
xfprelpn')) for = 12, Since the x4
x,(p,e(p,u)) = x,lp,e(p.u')). Hence: (pu) = ypu). Thus the hyp.) do
not depend on utility level and they are the same as the x;(p,w).
If the prices change following the path (1,1) + (2,1) + (2,2), then the
equivalent variation is
J tpl asuddp! + 5? n?(2,p? uldp?
= ra xp! 1,widp! + g 27(2,p",widp™
= (a + (3/2)b + c) + (d + 2e + (3/2)g)-
If the prices change following the path (1,1) + (1,2) + (2,2), then the
equivalent variation is
J2 rcp wlap™ + FF np! 2,u)ep"
=F Pp wiep? + 2 ipl 2widpt
= (d +e + (3/2)g) + (a + (3/2)b + 20).
‘These two equivalent variations are the same if and only if ¢
(©) As we caw above,
EV, = £2 x'tp'L,widp! = a + (9/2) + 6
L Pup widp™ = doe + Wye d+ e+ WB,
EV,
EV = (a+ (3/2)b + c) + (d + 2e + (3/2)g)
3-59a+ (3/2)b + 304d + (3/22.
Hence EV — (LV, + EV,)
The sum EV, + EV, does not contain the effect on equivalent variation due
to the shift of the graph of the demand function for the second commodity when
p! goes up to 2 (or equivalently, the shift of the graph of the demand
function for the first commodity when p* goes up to 2). Graphically,
Jetting ¢ = € > 0, EV contains the shaded area below but EV, + EV, does not:
a
2
1
o dte d+2e x!
Figure 3.1.7%(¢)
(@) Since (2,1,w) - a + 2b + c, the tax revenue from the first good is equal
to this. Thus DW, = (a + (3/2)b +c) ~ (a + 2b +c) = - b/2,
Since x5(1,2,w) = d+ © + 2g, the tax revenue from the second good is
equal to this. Thus DW, = (d +e + (3/2)g) - (4+ 6 + 26) = — gv2
Since x(2,2,w) = a + 2b + 2c and x,(2,2,w) = d+ 2e + 2g, the tax
revenue from both commodities is
(a+ 2b + 2c) + (d+ Ze + 2g) = a+ 24 404d + 2g.
Thue
DW = (a + (9/2) + 304d + (3/2)g) ~ (a + 2b + 4c +d + 2p).
3-60Hence DW - (DW, + DW,) = - c
(e) Our problem is
Min, DWit,,t,)
tt) PWT!
Bhp + ty Le ty Wty R
Here,
DW(t,t,) = EV(ty sty) . TR(tyty)
Hell + ty 1+ ty, w= etdsLud - Spang + ty, 1+ ty, uty
Set up the Lagrangean by Lty, tps) . DW(ty,to) +R TR(tyst9))- ‘Then the
first-order condition with respect ta ty is aDW(t,,t. ay - STR sty) dtp
= 0. But,
ODWIt,.t,)/dty = Gell + th 1+ ty ul/at, - ht +t, ltt, u)
~ Sica
= pe OA + ty, 14 ty, wlveryyty
by Gell + ty, 14 ty, wi/oty = hell + t,
(ah, (1 + ty 1+ ty, wat, ty
2!
14 ty, wy and
ATR tysty)/aty = hyll + tyy 1+ ty, w+ Tym + ty 1+ ty, wl/atyty.
Hence the first-order condition is written as
Te planglt + ty 1+ ty, wierd + 2d
tani ety Let, w= 0
for both & = 1,2, From this and R= Te hyll + ty 1+ ty
ulty, we obtain
be, + ety, ct, + at,
“= Sper ays cs a) * See sat) + wt ty)"
SOT Faye oe apy aS oe at) + BF By)
(a+ bi + ty) + cll + tye + Cd 4 oft + ty) + all + tity = R
3-613.1.8 (2) Quasilinear utility functions: ulx,.x,,X_) = Glx,x,) + x,
(b) As in Exercise 3.1.7(a), the symmetry implies
© + ap, = by + dypp for all py > 0 and p, > 0.
Thus c, = b, d, = d, = 0. Then the negative semidefiniteness implies that
2
by #0, 6) 40, byes ~ 6,7 50.
(©) Since the Walrasian demand functions and Hicksian demand functions are the
same as we saw in Exercise 9.1.7(b), we can defin
Si! selapyowda + JP?
cv = 5) wilqpy,widg +
py Baarpnia + Je
or, equivalently,
2 ‘1 :
fp) pimp arwida + Jp, mifngwta
(@) By the same calculation as in Exercise 3.1.7(c), we obtain
EV, = 1/2, EV, = 1/2, EV, - 9/2.
In this case, EV # EV, + EV,. In the general case in which the conditions in
(b) hold,
EV, = a, + (3/2)b, + ¢,
v
1g + By t (BAe,
ig = 8, + (3/2Ib, +e + a, + 2b, H9/2Ie,.
Hence EV, + EV, = FV, if and only if b, = ¢, = 0. This condition is
equivalent to saying that any change in the price of one good does not have
any (cross) effect on the demand for the other.
3.19 Let Qe re be the vector of which the é-th component is one and all
the other components are zero, For each t, define p(t) = p + tey Then the
after-rebate income w(t) with tax t satisfies w(t) = w + x,(p(t),w(t))t
3-62Hence p-x(ptt,w(t)) = (ptt) ~ tep)-x(pte)nw(t)) = w(t) ~ xplploawende = w.
Therefore x(p(t),w(t)) ig at most as good as x{p,wl. In order to prove that
xe(p{t,w(t)) is strictly less preferred to x(p,w), it is sufficient to prove
that these two are different, because the demand function is assumed to be
single-valued.
Now suppose that there exists a t > 0 such that x(p(t),w(t)) = x(p,w),
Let u = v(p,w). Then we have A(p(t),u) = Alp,u). In particular, hy(p(t).u) =
hglpiw). Since the Hicksian demand funetion ¢ + hy(p(s),u) is nonincreasing,
this equality implies that hy(p(s),u) = hy(p.u) for every 5 € [0,t], But
dlhg(pls),u)l/ds = dh,(p(s),u)/épy, Evaluating at s = 0, we have ahy(p,ul/6py
= sylPw) = 0. This violates the assumption that sy(p.w) < 0. Hence
Ie(p(t).w(t)) * h(pyw) for every t > 0.
3.1.10 We consider an example of a consumer who face the choices over two
goods and whose preference » and demand function x(p,,P,,W) satisfy the
following condition:
For every p, € Ws2h (p42) = (Ul - py 1+ 2s
for every py ¢ (h2h x(Py.2) = (I= €, + €)/p,)
(1-2, 1+ e)>- 6, 0+ eZ).
By using the figure below, you can convince yourself, perhaps with some
application of the weak axiom, that there actually exists such a preference.
3-63x
2
” \
TAA
Figure 3.1.10
Define p° = (2,1) and p! = (1,2). Then
x(p0,2) = (( = 072, 1+ ©),
x(p2)
GQ-e + ev),
Thus x(p%,
) > x(p',2). However, the area variation measure following the
price-change path p° » (1,1) » p! is
ave vp
1
19% lPLi2V4P, + SPX (LP,.2)dp,
2 2
fy 1 ~ ele, dp, + ST (t+ evep, dn,
2
= = odin pyle y+ [+ edt py
i
0
2eln2 > 0.
Hence the area variation measure ranks p! over p?.
BLM If (p' - p®)-x' > 0, then w > p?-x. The local non-satiation implies
that x° is preferred to x'. Hence the consumer must be worse off at (p!,w).
As for the interpretation in term of the first-order approximation, since
e(p,u) is concave in py
1
cpu) = etpul + vetplul-(p° - ph.
3-64Since Ve(p'.u')-(p? = p') < 0, e(p.u') < eto!
1
1) = w. Thus u? = vi(p°,w) >
Finally, (p! - p°)-x! > 0 if and only if w > pox’, which, in turn, Is
equivalent to pox! - 2° <0. This test is depicted in the picture below:
Figure 3.1.11
3112 Let v? = vip°,w®) and ul = vipliw!). Then we define
EV(?.w°ipwh = e(p°.ut) - etp®.v9) = et®u!) - w°,
wi etpiu®y.
°
ov(p?.wiptw!) = etpiyu’) ~ etp!.u
The “partial information” test can be extended as follows: If pl-x° < w', then
the consumer is better off at (pw). This can be proved in three ways.
The first one is the same revealed-preference argument as in the proof of
Proposition 3.1.1
‘The second way is to use the indirect utility function. Since vip.w) is
quasiconvex, if
tot = p%-v,vin®ws + cx! ~ wravipw®rrow > 0,
then we can conclude that vip4yw!) > vip°,w°). But, by Roy's identity, this
36ssufficient condition is equal to
= (wl = vd-(ort aw rrowrxty2.wd + tt = wiiorto®w°izow)
(30(p9,w)7awi(= plex? + ws wl - w)
(avip?,wrvawnw! ~ pl-x°) > 0,
Hence, if p'+x° < w', then vipw!) > v(p°,w°).
The third way is to use the expenditure function. vip',w!) > vip°,w°) if
and only if e(p!,vip!w')) > etp!vip?w°)}. But e(p!,vip',w')) = w! and
o
e(p!vip°,w)) = pix Hence, if pl-x? < wl, then we can conclude that
viptiwh > v(p,ws.
3.5.1 (First printing errata: The difficulty level should probably be B.] It
follows immediately from the definition that if x(p,w) satisfies the strong
axiom, then it satisfied the weak axiom. Conversely, if x( p,w ) satisfies
the weak axiom (in addition to the homogeneity of degree zero and Walrac’
law), then the Slutsky matrix is negati
semidefinite and, by Exercise
2.F.l, symmetric. Hence x(p,w) is integrable, implying that there exists a
preference relation that generates x( p,w ). Thus x(p,w) satisfies the strong
axiom as well.
BAA If (pw) = (1,11), then x(p,w) = (0,1). The locally cheaper
condition is not satisfied since B, , = {x € Ry: x, + x, = 1) and there is no
1
y such that p-y < w, as depicted in the following figure.
3-660 I
Figure 3.AA.1
x
To check that the demand function is not continuous at (J,1,1), consider the
sequence (p",w") = (1 - I/n, 1, 1 - 1/n). Then (p",w") + (1,11) and x(p",w")
= (1,0), but x(1,1,1) = (0,1), This discontinuous change in demands arises
because the budget set D, , consists of (1,0) for every nm, but By 1) 1 =
pw oe
{x € RO: x, + x, = 1), so that the commodity bundle (0,1) becomes available
suddenly at p = (1D.
3.AA.2. [Eirst printing errata: The upper hemicontinuity of h(p,u) cannot be
guaranteed at p = 0, because the local boundedness condition in the definition
of upper hemlcontinulty need not be satisfied. Hence the clause in the
bracket “even if we replace minimum by infimum and allow p = 0 should be
understood as concerning only with e(p,u).] We shall first prove that A(p,u)
is upper hemicontinuous. Let B be a compact subset of the domain of h(p,u)
(which is, in turn, a subset of {p € RU: p >> 0) x R). Then there exists a
(B,u) € B such that 0 = u for every (pu) € B. Let x € h(p,u), then ulx) = u
= u for every (p,u) € B. For each &, define
3-67By = Maxip-X/p, € R,: (p.u) © RD
and § = (Fy.¥,) © Ry We now show thal, for every (pu) € B and x €
A(p.u), we have J = x. If fact, since uli) = u, pe = px. Since p >> 0 and
Xe RY, py Spex Thus pee Pyxp Divide both side by py, then we obtain
Pit/py ® my and hence Jy * xp We have therefore established the local
boundedness condition of upper hemicont
ity. Next, let Pu), bea
sequence of pairs of price vectors and utility levels, converging to (p.u).
Let (x"), be a sequence in RL, x” © n(p"u") ror every n, and x" +x. It is
sufficient to prove that x € h(p,u). Since u(x") = u" and u(x") » u(x) by the
continuity, we obtain u(x) = u. Heuce x satisfies the constraint of the EMP
at (pyu). To show that it is cost-minimizing, let y © RE and uly) =u. If
uly) > u, then uly) > u" for any sufficiently large n. Hence p"+y = p™-x" for
such n. By taking the limit as n @, we obtain p-y = p:x. Suppose then that
uy)
By the local nonsatiation, there exists a sequence {y"), in RE such
that u(y) > ux) for every n and y" 4 x, Hence there exists a subsequence
k(n), Kin), m
CRE) of (pu), such that uy" = uk), Hence pl
ptm), tn)
By taking the limit ac ns m, we obtain p-y > p-x. Hence x is
cost-minimizing.
We now turn to the continuity of e(p,u). In fact, its continuity at
every p >> 0 can be derived immediately the continuity of A(p,u), as the
latter is well defined nt every p >> 0. Thus the essential part of the
following proof is the case of nonnegative, but not strictly positive,
vectors. We shall establish the continuity with respect to p and that with
Fespect to u separately.
Let u ¢ R be a utility level, p € RL be a price vector, and (p") be a
vesuence of price vectors in converging to p. We need to prove that
3-68e(p"\n) + e(pu). As a preliminary result, let's first prove that if the
sequence (e(p",u)) in R, converges, then it must do so to e(p,u). Let w be
the limit of (e(p"u)}. Let x € Ry and u(x) = u. Then p™-x = e(p".u) for
every n. Taking the limit as n + , we obtain p-x = w. Since this holds for
L
every x ¢ RL with ulx) & u, we have e(pw) 2 w. To prove the reverse
ually elpa # wwe woe the concavity of fp.) in pc A, Take «
kin) k(m)
cubsequence (pK) of (p%) such that (Pp - pirg'™ - p,) 2 0 for all Le
{,....L) and positive integers n and m. That is, for each & € (l,.
reauire the stan ot okt”
L}, we
~ pp along the subsequence to be constant (including
zero). Such a subsequence does actually exist because each p® - p has one of
at most 2" sign patterns. Now, for each ¢ ¢ (1 ait
phim) _ p= 0 for every n; and vp =~ 1 if ph” -
k(n) k(n)
PE” = y+ Ing ~ Pylvy.
y= 0 for every n. Then,
So tet 2? = Ipk'™ - ppl = 0 and define vé € RE by letting vj = ¥, and vy = 0
for every k # &, then
x(n)
pe aps patel,
A n
Now, define 28 — 1 - Sys then
Oe a
pin) 2 atp + Syzpm +)
since pM » p, 2B 9 0 for every £€ (ua.L). Thus 2591. Hence, for
)
every sufficiently large n, 23 > 0 and pM? is a convex combination of 2°,
en Therefore, by the concavity,
ety) = zMe(pu) + Bevel + v4, w.
k(n)
Since e(p",u) w, e(pX"),u) » w. The right-hand side converges to e(p,u).
Therefore w < e(p,u).
We have thus proved our preliminary fact Ubat if the sequence (e(p™,u))
in R, converges, then it must do so to e(p,u). Let's now prove by
3-69contradiction that this implies that e(p"\u) + e(p,u)- So suppose not, then
there are a 8 > 0 and a subsequence ip™)) of (p") such that
letp™)
u) - elp.u| = S
for all n, Since the subsequence ¢etp“"),u)) is bounded, it has a further,
convergent subsequence. On the one hand, the limit can never be e(p.u,
herause tecpkin)
4) ~ e(p,u)| > 8 for alll n. On the other hand, our
preliminary result implies that the limit must be e(p.u). This is 2
contradiction. We must thus have e(p",u) > e(p,u).
Let's now turn to the continuity of e(p,u) with respect to u. Let p € Rt
be a price vector, u € R be a utility level, and {u") be a sequence of utility
levels in R converging tou. We need to prove that e(pu") » e(p,u). Just ae
before, it is sufficient to prove that if the sequence (e(p,u")) in R,
converges, then it must do so to e(p.u). Let w be the limit of {e(p,u™).
Let © > 0, x € RE, u(x) = u, and p-x < e(p,u) + €. By the local nonsatiation,
we can make u(x) > u while preserving p+x < e(p,u) + ¢. Then there exicts a
positive integer N such that u(x) > u" for every n > N. Thus, for such n, p+x
= e(p.u"), Take the limit as n> ©, then p-x = w. Thus (pu) t © > w.
Since this holds for every © > 0, we must have e(p,u) 2 w. To show the
reverse inequality e(p,u) = w, we can assume that u" < u for every n. (The
reason is as follows: If there is a subsequence such that u = u for every n
in the subsequence, then we can apply this ease to subsequence. If there is
no such subsequence, then there is a subsequence such that u" = u for every n
in the subsequence, Hence e(p,u) < e(p,u") for such n. Taking the limit, we
obtain e(p,u) = w.) Now let ¥ ¢ RY and ule) = u. Define B= (x € RL: RE xd,
then B is compsct. This and u" = u implies that the truncated EMP
Min p-x s.t u(x) = u™
3-10has a solution, denoted by x" © B. Then x" © hi(p,u"), that is, x" a solution
ee eens car femmeaesl pa oe siete aleeemer cee
is a convergent subsequence (x*')) of (x), Denote its limit by x. Since
u(-) is continuous, u(x) = u and hence p-x = e(pu). Moreover, p-x“™ =
kin),
etp.u*!™)) and p-x! px. Thus w = p-x and hence w = e(p,u).
Suppose that u(x) is strictly quasiconcave, twice continuously
differentiable and that Ju(x) * 0 for all x. Then we know that hip,u) is a
function and the Lagrange multiplier A of the EMP must be positive. The
first-order condition for the EMP can be considered as a system of L +1
equations and L + 1 unknowns:
p- avu(x) = 0
ux) =u = 0
By the implicit function theorem (Theorem M.E.1), the solution h(p,u) as a
function of the parameters (p.u) of the system is differentiable if the
Jacobian of this system has a nonzero determinant
= Dux = p
vulx™ 0
at (p.x) satisfying the above two equatians. Fut, then, p= AVu(x) and hence
#0
this condition is equivalent to
- Dud = wud |g
fn ,
Puls) °
that is,
2,
pu) vax) | yg,
vutx™ 0
By Theorem M.D.2(i), thie inequality holds if D°u(x) is negative definite on
ty < RL: vulx)-y = 0). This sufficient condition is a stronger differential
version of quasiconcavity, as the latter is equivalent to the condition that
2,
D°u(x) Is negative semidefinite on {y € RU: Vulx)-y = 0).
71CHAPTER 4
4.B.1 By Roy's identity (Proposition 9.6.4) and vj(p.w,) = ai(p) + (pw,
1
x00) = aT en?
1 NG
Bey pA”) ~ Bepy MPP)
fl
Thus ¥y (009) =~ p9,$) for al |. Since the right-hand side i
i
identical for every i, the set of consumers exhibit parallel, straight
expansion paths.
As for the second part, by (3.E.1),
e\(b.u,) = Cu, ~ a,(P))/0(0).
Hence, by letting clp) = 1/b(p) and d,(p) = - a,(p)/olp), we obtain e,(p,u,) =
wha, + ain).
4.B.2 (a) Let pe RU he a price vector and w > 0 be an aggregate wealth.
Consider two consumers, i and j. Consider two wealth distributions
Wy) and (wi,...,wy) such that w; w= 0, w, = 0 for any k # i,
and w; = 0 for any k # j, Since the preferences are homothetic, x(p,0,5,) = 0
for every k. Thus the aggregate demand with (w,,...,W;) is x(p,w,5,) and the
aggregate demand with (w,
W)) 18 x(p,w.s,). Since aggregate demand
depends only on prices and aggregate wealth, we have xlp.w,s,) = (pws 3)
Since p and w were arbitrarily chosen, this means that i and j have the same
demand function. Hence they have the same preference. Since i and j were
arbitrarily chosen, we conclude that all consumers have the same preference.
(b) By analogy to the Gorman form, consider the following form of indirect
utility runctions:
adNote that b(p) and e(p) do not depend on i. By this and Roy's identity
(Proposition 3.6.4),
1
x(p.Wys) =~ V,y,(Pw,)
Pie Wai pw) philPM
¥, s
1 ‘ :
2 pepe Mal) = orp MP) = Bepy Pele)
Thus
= ghee tivated - FE once - BE gees
eer HPAI) = Bey PNP) “ot NP
Thus the aggregate demand depends only on J,w, and Js, (and p).
Tptpwye
4.C.1 By the definition of a directional partial derivative,
D,x(ewhly = lim, ,o(l/elixly + edp, w) ~ x(P)-
Hence
ap-Dyxtp.wép = dp-(lim, g(1/eNixtp + edp, w) ~ xlp.w)))
= lim, ,o(l/eldp- Getp + edp, w) ~ x{p,w))
But the ULD property implies that dp-(x(p + edp, w) - x(p,w)) = 0 for all © >
0. Hence, by taking the limit © > 0, we obtain dp-D.x(p,widp + 0. Thus
D,x(p,w) is negative semidefinite
rl, a
We shall prove the converse by contradiction. Suppose that the Jacobian
D,elp.w) is negative definite for all (p,w) and that there exist p € RY, pie
RY, and w, ¢ R such that x;(p,w,) # x,(p',w,) and
(Pw) - xp.) = 0.
Let A > 1 be sufficiently close to 1 that for every A € [0,A], demand is well
defined at (1 - A)p + Ap’. (If demand ic well defined at strictly positive
price vectors, 1 is determined so that (1 - Alp + Ap’ >> O for every A €
f0.41.) Define pla) = (1 - Alp + Ap’ and
4-2wOD = (Pt = P)-Ge(POI,w) ~ 26;(P.¥7))
‘Then the function w(-) is differentiable. w,(0) = 0, w,(1) = 0, and
Wi) = (p" = p)-Dyx,(pA,wHP" - p).
We consider two cases:
Gase 1: w(A) + 0 for every A € (0,
‘Then
) = 0 and it is a maximum. Thus wi(1) = 0, that is,
(p" ~ p)-D,x(p",wilp" - p) = 0.
This is a contradiction to the negative definiteness.
Case 2: wi(2) > 0 for some A € [0,A].
‘Then, by the mean-value theorem, there exists A* € (0,A) such that w,(A) ~
w)(O) = WANE ~ 0), By wi(0) = 0 and wi(A) > 0, wi(A") > 0. That is,
("= p)-D,x(pOa*),wilp" ~ p) > 0.
This is a contradiction to the negative definiteness. Our proof is thus
completed.
4.0.2 If Dyx\(Paiw) is negative definite on the whole Re for every i, then
‘the sum J;D_x/(P.a;w) is negative definite on the whole RY. since Dox(Pw) =
7.
plying that
TD, ;(0.a,w), De x(p.w) is negative definite on the whole Ri
x(p,w) satisfies the ULD property. To establish the WA, one way is simply to
notice that the ULD property implies the WA, as the latter considers only
compensated price changes.
Another way is to prove the xiven differential sufficient condition.
Let’s assume that w > 0. Define H = (v ¢ RY: v-x(p,w) = 0}, thet is, H is the
‘hyperplane with normal x(p,w) that goes through the origin. Then p ¢ H
because p-x(pyw) = w > 0. Thus, if v € RI and v is not proportional to p,
then there exist v, ¢ RU and v, € RY such that v, €H, v, #0, v, is
3proportional to p, and y= ¥ + ¥p. Since S(pywlvy = 0 and vy:S{p,w) = 0 by
Proposition 2.F.3, we have
veS(p.wlv = (vy, + v,)Slp.wily, + ¥))
vy Siwy, + v-Slpiwlyy + vy-Stp.why, + ¥5"SIp,¥v,
vy Sipwy,.
But here, by v, € H,
JT,
Slpswoy = (Dyxlp.w) + Dyxtprwhetp.w) Wyy= Delp.)
Hence ¥,-S(p.wiy, ~ y-D,x(p.w)y, <0 because v, # 0 and D,xip,w) is negative
definite. Thus the WA holds.
4.C.3 A Giffen good will be a most familiar example. In the figure below,
good 1 Is a Giffen good,
Figure 4.0.3
This example shows that the ULD property is actually not derived from the
utility maximization. It ic a restriction on preferences.
4.0.4 The L-shaped indifference curves imply that for every strictly positiveprice vector, the consumer's demand is always be at the corner of a upper
contour set. Hence no compensated price change will change the demand. Thus
S,(P.w) = 0 for every (p,w,) and D.2;(p,0,) = Dy x(p.w,)x\(p.w,)" Suppose
i
that there exists (p,w,) such that Dy, sa(p.w,) * (7,
(ow). Since
PD, x,(p,w,
; = prllyw xp) =
this implies that. Dy (Pw) and
i
x,(P.w,) are not proportional. Hence there exists av € R2 such that
v'D,, %(P/¥,) < 0 and v-x,(p.w,) > 0, as illustrated in the figure below:
i
(Awyx(p.wi)
P
x
Figure 4.0.4
Thus
ee wiEy = = Ov
WD LxylPw Wy = — wD, aelprwa(pw) Ty = - (Dy
(bw 0
WD) > 0,
which implies that the ULD property is not satisfied. Thus, If it is in fact
satisfied, then we must have D,, x,(p,w;) = (I/w,)x(p,w,) for every (p,w)-
‘Thus the unique wealth expansion path, which is the set of the corners of the
“upper contour sets, is a ray going through the origin. Henee the preference
is homothetic.4.CS Following the hint, we fix w = 1 and write x,(p) = x;(p.1). Consider
1
the indirect demand function g0) = Sorte
i
Wujx). Since x\(p) = x if and
only if g(x) = p, the ULD property of x;(p) is equivalent to the following
property: if x # yy then (g;(3) ~ g,(y))+(x = y) <0. For this latter
property, it is sufficient to show that D?g,0x) is negative definite. We
shall now establish this.
By the chain rule (Appendix M.A),
(0-9
Dg, = O60 anu, ~ vu,000u,007 ~ vu,00x7D7u,00)
Let q = Vu,(x) and C = D’u,(x), then this can be rewritten as
Dgi6o) = (eg) Abx-@)C ~ aa” - ax")
We need to show that v-Da,(xlv < 0 for every v # 0. If v-q = 0, then
v-Dg,(xWv = (x-q) "v-Cv < 0, (This property is equivalent to the negative
definiteness of the bordered Hessian of u,(+) and used to guarantee the
differentiabllity of the dewand function, as explained in the Appendix to
Chapter 3). So cuppoce that v-q * 0. By multiplying a ecalar to v if
necessary, we can assume that viq = xq. Then
v-Dg,(xlv = (x-q)""(vGv ~ veg ~ x-Cv).
By x-q > 0, we need to show that v-Cv - vq - x-Cv < 0. Since C is symmetric,
vite = xeGv = (v ~ (172)x)-Clv ~ (1/2)x) = 1/4 )K-Cx.
Since u,(-) is concave, C is negative semidefinite and the first term in the
above expression is non-positive. Thus,
vety = xeCv 5 ~ (U/Ax-ox.
Hence
veGy = veg = x+Cv S ~ (U/AK-CX ~ ax,
since - °C < 4, the right-hand side is nexative, Hence so Is the left=hand side.
4.C.6 By differentiating both sides of u(x) = Au(x) with respect to A and
taking A = 1, we obtain Vu(x)-x = u(x). Then by differentiating both sides of
this equality with respect to x, we obtain D°ulx)x + u(x) = Yulx). Thus
D7uGdx = 0 and hence of)
4.C.7 Suppose that the distribution of wealth has a differentiable,
nonincreasing density function f(-) over the interval [0,i]. Let ve Rt and v
* 0, then, just as in the proof of Proposition 4.C.4, we have
v-Dxlply = SMor-ste,wnrtwaw a Serb, Zp wn Sp, wi Flwidw.
Here, the first term is negative, unleas v is proportional to p. (This
Property is equivalent to the negative definiteness of the bordered Hessian of
u,(-) and used to guarantee the differentiability of the demand function, as
explained in the Appendix to Chapter 3). As Tor the second term, just as in
the proof of Proposition 4.¢.4,
3 p.w)
dw
Sl Dy Hew ly Hp,whsewdaw = (72) 3 Stwnaw,
By integration by parts and X(p,0) = 0, this is equal to
Aas2yv
ABW) = 720% xt, WI)? F wldw
The first part of this is always nonnegative, and it is positive when v is
Proportional to p. ‘Ihe integral of the second part is nonpositive because
2
Flwidw = 0. Hence v-Dx(plv < 0.
X(p.wi)
dw
F'lw) $0. Thus (i/2)s% 2
To see that there are unimodal density functions for which the
conclusions of this propositions do not hold, recall that
viDx(ply = Sly Stp,wie)flwldw ~ Shlv-D, Mp.wiliv-Xip. wns twraw.
To be specific, let v = (1,0,...,0) € al, then