A Paradox of Budgets: The Postwar Stabilization of American Neoclassical Demand Theory
A Paradox of Budgets: The Postwar Stabilization of American Neoclassical Demand Theory
We would like to thank the many individuals who provided useful comments on this essay
during the 1997 HOPE conference and to give particular thanks to Ross Emmett, Dan Ham-
mond, Steve Medema, Perry Mehrling, and Mary Morgan for their remarks. This essay is an
abridged version of the original conference paper; the longer version is available from the
authors.
other virtues, the Hotelling model had the drawback that the “income”
or “budget” term was not treated as a fixed entity independently of the
equilibrium outcome. This bothered Schultz, but he nonetheless chose to
collaborate with Hotelling to explore various justifications for the novel
treatment of the budget in the utility maximization problem.1 Schultz,
after all, was searching for a theory of interdependent demand curves,
and this seemed a viable formal candidate, even though it was not to be
found in Walras or Pareto. The novel treatment also gave rise to some
additional symmetry (or “integrability”) restrictions that Schultz imme-
diately tested and found to be violated in the agricultural demand func-
tions he estimated. Hotelling and Schultz then discussed the various
auxiliary hypotheses one might use to explain the failure, with
Hotelling focusing on pure theory, while Schultz tended to be con-
cerned with statistical and data problems. During this period Schultz
and Hotelling became aware of the now-standard Slutsky symmetry
conditions. Hotelling acknowledged the Slutsky equation but viewed it
as just another, more “Walrasian,” way to underwrite observed demand
curves. Although the Slutsky approach of maximizing an individual’s
utility function subject to a fixed income constraint had a certain appeal,
Hotelling found it unsatisfactory because it (unlike his own theory) had
only a limited ability to provide welfare theorems and did not guaran-
tee that demand curves sloped downward. When Schultz decided to test
the Slutsky and Hotelling symmetry conditions as rival hypotheses, he
found (much to his dismay) that both conditions appeared to be con-
tradicted by the data.
Here the saga of Hotelling and Schultz essentially draws to a close
with a denouement satisfying to neither of them. Schultz wrote up the
results of his decade-long search for the Walrasian principles underly-
ing demand curves in his 1938 Theory and Measurement of Demand. It
is seldom recognized that the book is essentially a swan song for empir-
ical Walrasian economics: Schultz bravely reported the empirical deba-
cle in detail and then produced a litany of excuses why things had not
1. Here we must signal that this was not simply an appeal to the special case of the Mar-
shallian constant marginal utility of money, nor was it straightforwardly a special case to be
rigidly restricted to some separate sphere of production. These issues are discussed in detail
in Hands and Mirowski 1998. For the present, it suffices to insist that Hotelling and Schultz
were engaged in a process of negotiation over the meaning and significance of the budget
term, which would imply revision of a whole array of other theoretical terms in tandem,
including but not restricted to the measurability of utility, the treatment of money, the signif-
icance of complementarity, the nature of interdependence, and so on.
worked out as hoped. The book ended with a promissory note that was
never redeemed, since Schultz died in a car accident in November
1938, just as the book appeared in print.
The reaction of Hotelling to the empirical disappointments and the
loss of Schultz was no less unexpected and presents more of an explana-
tory challenge to the historian. Initially, Hotelling showed every sign of
wishing to continue to pursue his initial price potential program.2 He
continued to teach a graduate course in mathematical economics at
Columbia, but the war and its own demands intervened. On 15 April
1943 he was formally appointed consultant to the Applied Mathemat-
ics Panel of the National Defense Research Council in recognition of
his work in putting together the Statistical Research Group (SRG) at
Columbia. Until it was dissolved in 1946, the SRG worked on the test-
ing of bombsights, the statistical effectiveness of various bombing
strategies, gun equilibration on ships, compressed flow through noz-
zles, the use of ordinary least squares (OLS) in antiaircraft fire control,
aerodynamic pursuit curves for overhead attacks, and numerous other
projects. This group included Allen Wallis, Milton Friedman, George
Stigler, Leonard Savage, and Abraham Wald.
The evidence suggests that Hotelling had essentially stopped reading
economics by 1940. Requests that Hotelling comment on subsequent
developments were met with reiterations of points he had made in the
1930s. In a letter of recommendation for Tjalling Koopmans’s move to
Yale University in 1955, he managed to avoid citing or discussing any
of his work in economics (Hotelling 1954). His class notes also suggest
that he restricted his lectures almost exclusively to problems tackled in
his 1930s works. It might be thought that with the loss of Schultz, his
2. Indeed, it seems that for Hotelling, the price potential model had become equated with
the very idea of rational action tout court. Evidence for this comes from Hotelling’s undated,
unpublished note titled “On the Nature of Demand and Supply Functions”: “ ‘Rational
Actions’ may be taken to mean a system of demand functions such that a ‘potential’ U exists
with pi = ȶU/ȶqi. Such demand & supply functions may well be taken as central, all others
being treated as more or less casual deviations, often of only temporary importance. But U
may be a function not only of the q’s but of their time — or space — derivatives. . . . Also, each
person’s U may depend upon the consumption of others (emulation; competitive display; but
also less wasteful types of activity, as when in intellectual cooperation a particular subject
occupying the focus of attention of a group may, advantageously to society, be pushed). The
statistical determination of ȶpi /ȶq j, which equals ȶpj /ȶqi for ‘rational action,’ involves a least-
squares solution & ideas of correlation which generalize ordinary calculus of correlation by
replacing individual variables by matrices. These matrices will, moreover, by [sic] symmet-
ric, giving rise to interesting theory.”
the Walrasian approach to price theory and the sole local partisan of
“econometrics.” It is not irrelevant to our story that by 1938 he was the
prime defender of planning in the socialist calculation debate, an early
interpreter of Keynesianism, and a Marxist. His initial impact on the
Chicago scene was to polarize conceptions of formal economics in even
starker terms than one might find elsewhere. In the minds of many at
Chicago, Walrasian mathematical theory became conflated with social-
ism, crude numerical empiricism, and politically naive welfare eco-
nomics. Knight assumed proprietary rights over graduate price theory
during the latter part of the war, but it was Lange who taught John
Hicks’s Value and Capital. As Patinkin (1995, 372) notes, “it was the
socialist Oskar Lange who extolled the beauties of the Paretian opti-
mum achieved by a perfectly competitive market — and Frank Knight
who in effect taught us that the deeper welfare implications of the opti-
mum were indeed quite limited.”
The situation was further disturbed by the unanticipated arrival of
the Cowles Commission in September 1939. The move was arranged
largely by Alfred Cowles and Robert Hutchins, then president of the
University of Chicago; the Economics Department had little say in the
matter. Theodore Yntema of the School of Business was named direc-
tor of research, and the only members of the Economics Department to
be named to the Cowles staff were distinctly junior: Lange, Gregg
Lewis, and Jacob Mosak. In retrospect, it is clear that Cowles was rel-
atively weak just after the move. Some Cowles staff members declined
the move to Chicago, like Wald, who went to Columbia. Yntema was
largely an absentee research director from 1939 to 1942, and by 1942,
half the staff members were involved in war research (Christ 1952, 23).
The situation might have been tailor made for Lange to enter the void
and recast the Chicago department in his own image, but it never came
to pass; he was a visitor at Columbia in 1942 – 43, and by 1945 he
resigned from both the commission and the university to become Pol-
ish ambassador to the United States.
Despite Stigler’s (1988, 148) claim that in 1947 “there was no
Chicago School of Economics” (see also Bronfenbrenner 1962), it is
clear that Knight and his group were successful in advancing their
agenda during the war, and by 1944 they were engaged in open intel-
lectual warfare with the Cowles Commission (Reder 1982, 10; Ham-
mond 1993, 231). Friedman’s role as self-appointed tormentor of Cowles
and acknowledged leader of the Economics Department was para-
3. The most painstaking and perceptive case that Friedman’s demand curve cannot be
found in Marshall is Aldrich 1996. We can do no better than suggest that the reader interested
in the fine technical points of the argument begin there. We also view our argument as con-
sistent with that found in Hirsch and De Marchi 1990: “Looking to Marshall to help is just as
likely to confuse” (36); “it is only with the help of Knight, we suggest, that one can derive a
coherent political economy from Friedman’s writings” (285). What we add to their theses is
the historical context that can explain the genesis of the doctrine and the position it occupied
versus other constructions of orthodox neoclassical price theory.
gest another way to understand these texts. One need not search for
Friedman’s demand curve in Marshall, any more than one needs to find
his philosophy in Karl Popper or John Dewey. Friedman’s demand
curve grows out of Knight, via Schultz and Hotelling. It was the culmi-
nation of a whole sequence of reviews and articles, most notably Fried-
man 1941, Friedman and Wallis 1942, and Friedman 1946, seeking a
way out of the impasse bequeathed him by Schultz’s palpable failure.
These articles are the traces of a mighty struggle with the meaning and
significance of income for neoclassical price theory, and it is no coin-
cidence that the work for which Friedman is most famous, such as the
“permanent income hypothesis” and the mantra that “money matters,”
derives directly from his empirical work on the measurement of pro-
fessional incomes and the estimation of relevant demand functions in
the late 1930s (Friedman and Kuznets 1945).
What are the main precepts of Friedman’s theory of demand, which
became the foundations of the Chicago approach? First and foremost,
he agrees with Knight that the demand function is the primary entity
in price theory. Early on, he adopted the position that to “go behind”
the demand curve to its foundations in laws of utility or “indifference”
is largely a waste of time. It could not further the quest “to obtain exact
knowledge of the quantitative relation of consumer expenditures to
prices and incomes for the purpose of predicting the effect of changes
in economic conditions on the consumption of various commodities”
(Friedman and Wallis 1942, 188). Of course, the analyst should not repu-
diate something like utility altogether, since it “may be a useful expos-
itory device,” but one should not “mistake the scaffolding set up to
facilitate the logical analysis for the skeletal structure of the problem.”
By the time of his Price Theory (1966), he identifies utility as a conve-
nient fiction: “We shall suppose that the individual in making these
decisions acts as if he were pursuing and attempting to maximize a sin-
gle end” (37; emphasis in original). The divergence from Knight comes
in relinquishing all rights to criticize utility as a scientific concept and
instead linking its legitimacy to the uses it serves, namely, as a language
to motivate and discuss observable demand curves. Friedman the sta-
tistician here inverts Knight the “ideal type” philosopher: Good empir-
ical demand curves underwrite dubious quasi psychology rather than
vice versa.
The upshot of all these considerations for Friedman was emphati-
cally not the conclusion that demand theory was in a sorry state but
fixity of income, only to discover that one must not take it too seriously,
at least in Chicago. The next step might have been to double back to the
Hotelling model to reevaluate its attractions and drawbacks, but that
did not happen, primarily because the approach to demand theory now
became confused with tangential issues: prostatist versus antistatist
politics; the intrinsic attractions of mathematical formalism; the extent
of commitment to utilitarian psychology; the correct format for statis-
tical inference; the resonance or dissonance with Keynesian macro-
economics; the significance of imperfect competition for price theory;
and much more. But through all the blooming, buzzing confusion,
Chicago never lost sight of its most immediate rival in demand theory:
the Cowles Commission.
4. Here we must register out disagreement with the very interesting history of our period
by Ingrao and Israel (1990, esp. 284 – 88). Those authors present the history of price theory as
a single unified thread, with a single break in the 1930s– 40s, when mathematically sophisti-
cated authors renounced physical metaphor for the rigors of mathematical formalization.
They conclude that the Sonnenschein-Mantel-Debreu (S-M-D) results are the fruits of that
reorientation in that axiomatization has now definitively revealed the empirical emptiness and
conceptual limitations of the Walrasian program. This essay demonstrates that we would
challenge their theses on a number of counts: (1) Neoclassical theory, even within a single
nation, is not monolithic in its core doctrines but fractured and fragmented. (2) Many of the
main American protagonists in the 1930s and after persisted in taking their cues from physics,
though it tended to be from vintages contemporary with their experience. (3) The S-M-D
results would impact different versions of neoclassicism with differing degrees of damage,
depending on their variant attitudes toward the treatment of the income constraint, the Slut-
sky equation, and the centrality of the law of demand vis-à-vis Walrasian theory. (4) Most
denizens of the Cowles Commission did not find S-M-D very distressing, since they had
already renounced the laws of supply and demand.
Once these lessons are absorbed, it becomes clear that Ingrao and Israel’s narrative is just
an inversion of the more conventional Whig account, written from the constricted vantage
point of one subset of one school of American neoclassicism. To find these confusions in such
otherwise discerning authors reveals why a comprehensive history of demand theory in the
twentieth century is still desperately needed.
ingly over the last few decades, he has been critical of econometric test-
ing in general.
Let me make a confession. Back when I was 20 I could perceive the
great progress that was being made in econometric methods. Even
without foreseeing the onset of the computer age, with its cheapen-
ing of calculations, I expected that the new econometrics would
enable us to narrow down the uncertainties of our economic theories.
We would be able to reject false theories. We would be able to infer
new good theories. My confession is that this expectation has not
worked out. (Samuelson 1992, 243)
This puts the champion of positivist economics in a rather peculiar
position. The person who is often viewed as one of the staunchest advo-
cates of the empirical science of economics does not do, nor does he
have much faith in, the type of econometric work that dominates the
empirical practice of the contemporary mainstream he helped create.
This paradox has implications for Samuelson’s entire career, but we
will focus on his version of demand theory.
The problem for Samuelson was to find a way of formulating the the-
ory of demand that would be consistent with his positivist-operational-
ist methodology while simultaneously avoiding the type of economet-
ric testing associated with Schultz. How could this possibly be done?
How could one steer the ship of economic science between the Scylla
of apriorism and the Charybdis of Schultz’s economic estimates while
honoring the law of demand and accepting only neoclassical givens?
His answer, published in 1938, was to ground demand theory on what
later came to be called the theory of revealed preference. In essence his
answer was to change the place where the empiricism lived in the neo-
classical theory of demand. Instead of having empiricism enter at the
back end — by testing the empirical implications deduced from the
theory — the revealed preference approach would place empiricism
right up front at the beginning of the exercise. If the epistemologically
dubious notion of subjective utility could be replaced with a strictly
behaviorist — thus objective, observational, operational, and meaning-
ful — concept of consumer action, demand theory could be reconsti-
tuted on what Samuelson considered legitimate scientific foundations.
A demand theory based on a behaviorist-inspired notion of human
action (i.e., response) would already be empirical at the start, thus elim-
In this postulate, x is the bundle of goods at price vector p, and x' is the
bundle of goods purchased at the price vector p'. If bundle x' was afford-
able at p but was not selected, then x must have been more expensive at
p', since it was not selected. In the language of the later literature, since
x' was affordable at p but was not chosen, the bundle x was “revealed
preferred” to x'; thus if x' was chosen at p', it must be because x is more
expensive at these prices.
Samuelson was careful in the original article to avoid the word
“preference” or any other term that might imply subjective evaluation
or intentionality. The 1938 article strictly maintains the behaviorist
idiom of “selection” throughout; the theory was, after all, meant to
replace the intentional theory of subjective utility, preference, and
choice. From these three postulates, Samuelson was able to derive what
he considered the main result of the utility-based theory of demand: a
generalized version of the law of demand. According to Samuelson, he
started with the operational-observable condition RP and ended up
with an observable generalized law of demand; not only could eco-
nomics do without the nineteenth-century notion of cardinal utility, but
also now it could do without the concept of ordinal utility or well-
ordered preference. The shroud of utility metaphysics was cast away,
and economics was now indeed “part of the advancing army of sci-
ence” (Samuelson 1983, 10).
The substantive result of ordinal utility theory that did not follow
way. Rather than saying it simply chased out the competition — which
it did, if by “competition” one means the institutionalists, Marxists, and
Austrians — and replaced diversity with a single monolithic homoge-
neous neoclassical strain, we say it transformed itself into a more
robust ensemble. Neoclassical demand theory gained hegemony by
going from patches of monoculture in the interwar period to an inter-
locking competitive ecosystem after World War II. Rather than present-
ing itself as a single, brittle, theoretical strand, neoclassicism offered a
more flexible, and thus resilient skein of three strands. Each subprogram
had the capacity to absorb certain forms of criticism and thus deflect
those criticisms away from the vulnerable areas in other subprograms,
where they might do the most damage. Attack general-equilibrium the-
ory for its lack of empirical relevance, and one is quickly directed
toward Becker, Stigler, and the grand Chicago tradition of applied
microeconomics. Go after Chicago for its loose use of subjective utility
and a priori categories, and one is quickly told how the relevant prefer-
ences are operationally defined and could be revealed by direct observa-
tions of consumers’ choices. Finally, go after revealed preference theory
for emptiness as a tautological definition of consistency in choice, and
one is immediately shown the way through the equivalence results and
right into the heart of the complete Walrasian general-equilibrium model.
Pace Harry Truman, the buck stops nowhere. We think this insight goes
a lot further toward explaining the postwar success of neoclassical eco-
nomics than any of the arguments presented in the standard internalist
or externalist histories.
References
Aldrich, John. 1996. The Course of Marshall’s Theorizing about Demand. HOPE
28:171 – 217.
Bailey, Martin. 1954. The Marshallian Demand Curve. Journal of Political Econ-
omy 62:255 – 61.
Becker, Gary. 1962. Irrational Behavior and Economic Theory. Journal of Political
Economy 70:1 – 13.
Bronfenbrenner, Martin. 1962. Observations on the Chicago School(s). Journal of
Political Economy 70:72 – 75.
Christ, Carl. 1952. History of the Cowles Commission. 1932 – 52. In Economic The-
ory and Measurement: A Twenty Year Research Report, 1932–1952. Chicago:
Cowles Commission.
———. 1994. The Cowles Commission’s Contributions to Econometrics at
Chicago, 1939 – 1955. Journal of Economic Literature 32:30 – 59.
Ingrao, Bruna, and Giorgio Israel. 1990. The Invisible Hand: Economic Theory in
the History of Science. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.
Knight, Frank. 1944. Realism and Relevance in the Theory of Demand. Journal of
Political Economy 52:289 – 318.
Koopmans, Tjalling, ed. 1950. Statistical Inference in Dynamic Economic Models.
Cowles Commission Monograph 10. New York: Wiley.
Lange, Oskar, Francis McIntire, and Theodore Yntema, eds. 1942. Studies in Math-
ematical Economics and Econometrics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Leonard, Robert. 1991. War as a Simple Economic Problem. In Economics and
National Security. Edited by C. Goodwin. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.
———. 1995. From Parlor Games to Social Science: Von Neumann, Morgenstern,
and the Creation of Game Theory, 1928 – 1944. Journal of Economic Literature
33:730 – 61.
Lewin, Shira. 1996. Economics and Psychology. Journal of Economic Literature
34:1293 – 1323.
Marschak, Jacob. 1939a. Personal and Collective Budget Functions. Review of Eco-
nomics and Statistics 21:161 – 70.
———. 1939b. Review of Henry Schultz’s Theory and Measurement of Demand.
Economic Journal 49:486 – 89.
———. 1943. Demand Elasticities Reviewed. Econometrica 11:25 – 34.
———. 1944. Marschak to Robert Redfield, 15 February. Rockefeller Foundation
Archives, Sleepy Hollow, N.Y.
Mirowski, Philip. 1989a. The Measurement without Theory Controversy. Econ-
omies et sociétés 11:65 – 87.
———. 1989b. More Heat than Light. New York: Cambridge University Press.
———. 1989c. The Probabilistic Counter-revolution. Oxford Economic Papers
41:217 – 35.
———. 1990. Problems in the Paternity of Econometrics: Henry Ludwell Moore.
HOPE 22:587 – 609.
———. Forthcoming a. Machine Dreams. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
———. Forthcoming b. RAND/OR. Social Studies of Science.
Morgan, Mary. 1990. The History of Econometric Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Mosak, Jacob. 1938. Interrelations of Production, Price, and Derived Demand.
Journal of Political Economy 46:761 – 84.
Patinkin, Donald. 1995. The Training of an Economist. Banca Nazionale del
Lavoro Quarterly Review 48:359 – 95.
Reder, Melvin. 1982. Chicago Economics: Permanence and Change. Journal of
Economic Literature 20:1 – 38.
Samuelson, Paul. 1938. A Note on the Pure Theory of Consumer’s Behaviour. Eco-
nomica 5:61 – 71.
———. [1948] 1968. Consumption Theory in Terms of Revealed Preference. Eco-
nomica 15:243 – 53. Reprinted in Utility Theory: A Book of Readings. Edited by
A. N. Page. New York: Wiley.