(SUNY Series in Radical Social and Political Theory.) Fisher, Andy - Radical Ecopsychology - Psychology in The Service of life-SUNY Press (2013) PDF
(SUNY Series in Radical Social and Political Theory.) Fisher, Andy - Radical Ecopsychology - Psychology in The Service of life-SUNY Press (2013) PDF
Radical Ecopsychology
Psychology in the Service of Life
ANDY FISHER
Andy Fisher
Published by
State University of New York Press, Albany
No part of this book may be used or reproduced in any manner whatsoever without
written permission. No part of this book may be stored in a retrieval system or
transmitted in any form or by any means including electronic, electrostatic, magnetic
tape, mechanical, photocopying, recording, or otherwise without the prior permission in
writing of the publisher.
BF353.5.N37F57 2012
155.9’1—dc23
2012003051
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Preface xiii
Acknowledgments xxi
PART I. GROUNDWORK
vii
Notes 249
Bibliography 337
Index 377
Ever since the Enlightenment, technological civilization has assumed a clear divide
between the presumably “exterior” world of material nature and the presumably
“interior” world of the mind and emotions. In Europe and North America we
have lived with this division for several long centuries, and it has taken a tremen‑
dous toll—on ourselves, on our relationships, and on the animate earth around
us. Nevertheless, the bifurcation persists: today, for instance, the science of ecology
studies the external realm of earthly interactions, while psychology ponders and
ministers to the internal realm of our mental life.
As its name implies, ecopsychology (or ecological psychology) neatly explodes
this age-old divide between mind and matter, between the psyche “in here” and
nature “out there.” Ecopsychology suggests that the psyche cannot really be under‑
stood as a distinct dimension isolated from the sensuous world that materially
enfolds us, and indeed that earthly nature can no longer be genuinely understood
as a conglomeration of objects and objective processes independent of subjectivity
and sentience.
The book you now hold is the most important work yet written on ecopsy‑
chology from a clinical perspective. As a practicing psychotherapist, Andy Fisher is
well acquainted with the manifold stresses and sadnesses that beset contemporary
persons, and he has come to believe that a genuine comprehension and ameliora‑
tion of these ills cannot proceed without a radical metamorphosis in our under‑
standing of the psyche, and a new recognition of the psyche’s entanglement with
the more-than-human natural world.
Dr. Fisher has read widely and deeply, and he gathers insights from a rich
diversity of sources, greatly expanding our awareness of the manifold springs from
which ecopsychology can drink and draw sustenance. Yet he tests the reflections
of others against his own experience, synthesizing the disparate strands into a
uniquely coherent and compassionate vision. His voice is at once poetic and
precise, and thus implicitly opens the way for a style of speech unencumbered by
obsolete distinctions between subjective and objective modes of discourse.
Among the divergent springs that feed these pages, the most consistent
philosophical source is that of phenomenology—the study of direct experience.
Developed in the first half of the twentieth century, phenomenology sought to
ix
would begin to resuscitate and carry forward the rich work done by some of those
thinkers. Indeed, Andy Fisher makes careful use of such phenomenologists as
Martin Heidegger, J. H. Van Den Berg, and especially the brilliant French phe‑
nomenologist Maurice Merleau-Ponty, as well as a number of their more recent
followers.
Fisher has also learned from hermeneutics, from psychoanalysis and Gestalt
psychotherapy, and from some of our best wilderness writers, as well as from the
unique and prescient reflections of Paul Shepard—the maverick “human ecolo‑
gist” whose audacious writings, so little known, have nevertheless influenced so
many environmental theorists. Yet Fisher brings to these various thinkers a keen
social and political awareness rarely present among those who write on behalf of
the natural world. His own turn toward the animate earth is not at all a turn away
from the social and economic relations that so influence our psychological life;
rather, his work suggests that our widespread social injustices can no longer be
understood without taking into account the unnecessary violence inflicted on the
rest of nature by a society impervious to all that stands in the way of “progress.”
Fisher implies that the many-voiced earth is the ultimate context of our social as
well as our psychological experience. His Radical Ecopsychology calls us toward
active engagement in a transformation of society no less profound than the trans‑
formation of personal life that he invokes, and makes clear that these two projects
cannot genuinely be separated.
Both political and deeply personal, stirring us both ethically and aestheti‑
cally, Andy Fisher’s vision enlivens the young field of ecopsychology. With any
luck, his book will infect the wider (and all-too-complacent) discipline of psy‑
chology, inducing more than a few therapists to throw open the windows of their
consulting room, letting a wild wind rush in to jostle their papers and to join in
the conversation.
—David Abram
xii
The book is divided into two parts, with part one laying the ground for part
two. In part one, “Groundwork,” I introduce the reader to the terrain of ecopsy‑
chology; reflect on the overall ecopsychological project; and situate my own work
within this larger project. The two chapters that comprise this part of the book
are the most heavy-going and academic in tone. The reader who is put off by such
weightiness, or who prefers to go straight to the main event, may therefore wish
to either skip or skim them. I do, however, encourage such readers to consider
circling around to pick these chapters up after having reached the end.
Chapter one, “The Project of Ecopsychology,” begins with a brief discus‑
sion of currently used definitions of ecopsychology, as well as some of its historical
antecedents. The bulk of the chapter consists of a discussion of the four main
tasks that in my view comprise the essential work of ecopsychology. I call these the
psychological task, the philosophical task, the practical task, and the critical task.
The best way to define the project of ecopsychology, I suggest, is to trace the inter‑
relationships among these four historical tasks. Given that all of these tasks rely on
each other, I argue that they ought to be pursued more or less in unison, whether
through a coordination of separate efforts or through an inclusion of all of them
within individual undertakings. For the purposes of demonstrating the interde‑
pendencies among the four tasks, I have opted in this book for the latter strategy.
I address the psychological task by proposing a “naturalistic” psychology—one
that aims to link the claims and limits of human nature to the claims and limits of
the larger natural world. I address the philosophical task by adopting an approach
to theory-building that is grounded in the experiential or phenomenological tra‑
ditions in both philosophy and psychology. I address the practical task by pro‑
viding an experiential framework for undertaking a wide range of practices that
go counter to the life-negating tendencies of our society. I address the critical
task, finally, by locating my project within what I regard as the deeper and more
critical currents within both psychology and ecology, and by demonstrating how
a naturalistic and experiential psychology may be used as a basis for developing a
critical theory of modern society.
In chapter two, “The Problem with Normal,” I reflect on what kind of dis‑
course the terrain of ecopsychology is calling for, that is, on what sort of method is
most adequate for approaching the subject matter of ecopsychology. The problem
with normal, mainstream psychology—including “environmental psychology”—
is that it is committed exactly to those philosophical dualities (inner/outer,
human/nature, subjective/objective) that ecopsychology must overcome. For my
own project I therefore adopt an interpretive or “hermeneutical” method—one
that can work in the difficult space between the “human” and the “natural,” and
that can disclose aspects of the human-nature relationship that normal science
simply cannot. Because I wish to set up ecopsychology as a project that raises rad‑
ical doubts about the course of modern society, I also adopt a rhetorical method.
As an art, rhetoric has historically employed language as a symbolic means to
create specific experiential effects in the psyche or soul, so as to inform, please,
and move the listener. As James Hillman has suggested, this makes a rhetorical
approach particularly appropriate for psychological discourse. For a radical project
such as ecopsychology, moreover, I suggest that an openly rhetorical approach is
imperative. The hermeneutic and rhetorical traditions both recognize the prima‑
rily symbolic or metaphorical nature of reality and make room for discussion that
can both touch us where we live and advance viewpoints that go counter to the
social and cultural status quo. An interpretive and rhetorical discourse, in short,
can speak to the felt reality of our alienated relationship with the life process and
then say something critical that might help move our society forward from that
estranged starting place.
In part two, “Nature and Experience,” my goal is primarily to demonstrate
the feasibility of the project—to show that the leap from a human- to a nature-
centered psychology may draw strength from much that is already agreed on or
familiar within psychological and ecological thought, and that many practical
and critical implications can immediately be drawn. I call this part of the book
“Nature and Experience” because these are my two central terms. Nature refers
to ecology, experience to psychology. We discover the claims of nature precisely
by interpreting our bodily felt experience of them. I thus argue that if we are to
better understand our own nature, as well as our place within the larger natural
order, it is crucial that we work experientially. Learning to do so, moreover, has the
character of a therapeutic and historical task, in that those of us living within the
repressing structures of the modern world tend to lose touch with our own bodily
experience. As a consequence, we become limited in our ability to take guidance
from our own feeling process and vulnerable to ideological manipulation of all
sorts. It is for this reason that I conceive of ecopsychology as a kind of naturalistic
and experiential politics that struggles against the nature-dominating and reifying
aspects of this society as it correspondingly works to relocate the human psyche
within the wider natural world.
In the tradition of the existentialists, I suggest in chapter three, “Begin‑
ning With Experience,” that we need to ground ecopsychological inquiry in lived
experience. The aim of the chapter is thus to provide some introductory con‑
cepts, descriptions, and exercises that will get the reader on speaking terms about
“experience.” More specifically, I want the reader to appreciate that our experi‑
encing is always an organismic or bodily phenomenon, and that it is also always
an interacting with an environment. Once this basic appreciation is gained, it is
a short step into ecopsychology. I additionally introduce the key notion of the
“life process.” Both epidemic human psychopathology and the ecological crisis
can, I suggest, be fruitfully understood in terms of a general violation of the life
process under capitalist social relations. This understanding makes for a helpful
critical strategy for linking psyche and ecology. It also offers a way to conceptually
unify our psychological and ecological crises under the umbrella of our nihilistic
cultural condition, wherein the violation of life is tied to a frustrating absence of
meaning or widespread impoverishment of our experience.
Chapter four, “From Humanistic to Naturalistic Psychology,” is a bridge
between chapter three, which still draws primarily on “humanistic” sources, and
chapter five, which proposes a specifically “naturalistic” approach. The bridge itself
is an inquiry into nature and human nature, wherein I describe what I mean by
these hugely contested terms. Although this seems a foolish exercise, it is nonethe‑
less a necessary one, for the plain reason that so much rides on our understanding
of nature, including how (and if ) we understand ourselves as spiritual beings. I
discuss a number of conceptualizations of nature within three general categories:
the natural world; the essential quality, way, order, or character of a being; and the
life force (desire, spirit, etc.). While it is right to allow for a plurality of interpreta‑
tions within these categories, I also believe that it is fair to argue for better interpre‑
tations—one’s arrived at through a deepening and broadening of one’s experience.
It is only by undertaking hermeneutical inquiries into the meaning of nature (even
if such inquiries have no final endpoint) that we may make persuasive arguments
for just what is being violated and what needs to be recovered. Showing my realist
colors, I assert that the place of humans in the natural order is not some insoluble
puzzle, but is to be found in the given order of our own bodily, world-bound
nature; and that the demands of nature, inside and out, can therefore simply not
be intellectualized, marketplaced, or bulldozed away.
Chapter five, “Naturalistic Psychology: A Sketch,” is my outline of a kind
of psychology that would serve the life process or hold out the human-nature
relationship as an ultimate concern. Naturalistic psychology advocates fidelity to
nature, being in the service of nature, and seeing humans as part of a larger natural
order. I want to develop a psychology that reinterprets our current situation in
ever-more primordial terms, even as it acknowledges the historical and culturally
mediated nature of human reality. At the core of this psychology are three herme‑
neutical (or “sense-making”) principles that I suggest will be helpful, at this early
stage of inquiry, for getting our bearings. The first holds that we are ordered by
nature to participate ever-more widely in the world; the second that our language
is always a “singing” of this world; and the third that all phenomena intertwine
or mirror one another as a common “flesh.” I finish this chapter by illustrating
these principles through an examination of the human life cycle in the context
of a more-than-human world. I discuss the infantile need for loving, responsive
human relations and for exploratory contact with wild nature; the childhood need
for playful immersion in the natural world; and the adolescent need for rites of
passage into a sacred adult cosmos, wherein the natural world is understood not
as a fallen realm to be transcended but as the everyday ground of our limited and
mysterious human existence. Attending to the human life cycle is a key concern
of my approach.
In my sixth and concluding chapter, “Making Sense of Suffering in a Tech‑
nological World,” I emphasize the need to create a psychology that is not just
for those who like the outdoors (or whatever), but which can be used as a basis
for social criticism. This chapter is thus my most concentrated attempt to tie my
psychological efforts into a critical framework. Given my own approach, I take
them. I give my gratitude to them all. Thanks, also, to Joanna Macy for (among
other things) inspiring the dedication to this book.
Friends and family have been universally supportive. For warm, musical,
and thought-provoking friendship, I am particularly thankful to my class (and
canoe) mates Jean-Marc Daigle, Donna Havinga, Joanne Nonnekes, Lionel Nor‑
mand, Adrian Ivakhiv, mark meisner, Ian Attridge, Stephen Horton, David Berger,
Dieter Brock, Julie Palmer, Randee Holmes, Anne Bell, and Connie Russell. The
generous love of my parents, David and Marnie Fisher, is a constant source of
good feeling; as is the presence in my life of sister Lynne, brother Richard, sister-
in-law Shelley, and niece Gwyneth. Closest to heart and home is my wife, Jill
Dunkley, who throughout our time together has graced me with her humor,
patience, emotional support, and gut-felt criticism. I also wish to acknowledge
here my grandfather, George Gilmour, who died some months before I was born,
but whose religious and scholarly spirit has become a welcome force in my life.
Since “coming out” as an ecopsychologist, I have been encouraged-on by
a number of good people. Robert Greenway was the first to suggest that I look
for a publisher and has been a generous supporter of my work. I am honored to
know this wise and spirited man. David Abram’s enthusiasm for the manuscript
really got me going on the book, and a number of his suggestions have helped me
to improve it. He is a wonderful ally and mentor. Joel Kovel took time out of his
own busy writing schedule to carefully read my work and offer some tough and
thoughtful advice. I look forward to carrying-through on many of his suggestions
in future efforts. An encouraging letter from Steven Foster, who also found the
time to read the manuscript, did much to warm my heart. Jed Swift and Laura
Sewall invited me to an ecopsychology workshop in Boulder, Colorado, in the
summer of 2000. It was in preparation for that event that I did much of my
final thinking about the project of ecopsychology itself. The reception that my
views received from the participants at that event emboldened me to put them
into print. Laura, who has since become a collaborator in thinking about ecopsy‑
chology, kindly helped me to hone my vision. My deepest thanks to all these
people.
For making available a copy of her beautiful print, Moon Howl, for the cover
of this book, I am grateful to Martina Field. Thanks, also, to a number of anony‑
mous reviewers, who made a number of helpful comments; and to my editor
at SUNY Press, Michael Rinella, for taking this on. And thanks to my mother,
Marnie Fisher, for her last-minute commentary on the entire book.
Finally, I want to mention the many other-than-human beings, from icicles
to cormorants, who keep me writing. I am especially thankful to the powers of the
Leslie Street Spit, and to my neighborhood crows (for their constant reminders).
For the second edition, I wish to acknowledge my wife Jill Dunkley for her
patience, love, and always helpful feedback. Thank you, also, to Robert Greenway,
for his many thoughtful and encouraging comments.
Around the time that Rachel Carson’s Silent Spring was igniting the modern
environmental movement, the psychoanalyst Harold F. Searles published a book
that received a much quieter reception, a thick volume entitled The Nonhuman
Environment: In Normal Development and in Schizophrenia. His guiding idea was
that, whether we are aware of it or not, the “nonhuman environment”—the trees,
clouds, raccoons, rivers, skyscrapers, and manifold other nonhuman phenomena
that weave together as the larger matrix for the affairs of humans—has great sig-
nificance for human psychological life, a significance we ignore at peril to our
own psychological well-being. In introducing his subject matter, Searles paused to
comment that it “may be likened to a vast continent, as yet largely unexplored and
uncharted.”2 Sensing this large territory before him, he wrote: “During the past
approximately sixty years, the focus of psychiatry’s attention has gradually become
enlarged, from an early preoccupation with intrapsychic [interior] processes . . .
to include interpersonal and broad sociological-anthropological factors. It would
seem then that a natural next phase would consist in our broadening our focus still
further, to include man’s [sic]3 relationship with his nonhuman environment.”4
Four decades later, this next phase in the broadening of psychology’s5 focus—call
it “ecopsychology”—is finally beginning to take shape.
In offering definitions of ecopsychology, most of the people presently devel-
oping this field do indeed say something along the lines of Searles. They talk about
synthesizing ecology and psychology, placing human psychology in an ecological
context, and mending the divisions between mind and nature, humans and earth.
3
Many have simply adopted the position that, as human ecologist Paul Shepard
put it in 1973: “If [the] environmental crisis signifies a crippled state of conscious-
ness as much as it does damaged habitat, then that is perhaps where we should
begin.”6 In the words of one of its most visible representatives, cultural historian
Theodore Roszak, ecopsychology does not want to “stop at the city limits,” as if
“the soul might be saved while the biosphere crumbles,”7 but rather illuminate the
innate emotional bonds between “person and planet.” Such characterizations are
appropriately in harmony with the root meanings of “ecopsychology.” Psychology
is the logos—the study, order, meaning, or speech—of the psyche or soul. “Eco”
derives from the Greek oikos which means “home.” Ecopsychology, then, would
approach the psyche in relation to its earthly or natural home, its native abode,
and explore “the basic shifts in our patterns of identity and relationship that occur
when we include our connection to the web of life around us as essential to human
well-being.”8
Ecologists study nature, while psychologists study human nature. Assuming
these natures overlap, psychology already has obvious potential links to ecology.
Indeed, before ecopsychology even became a word a small number of psycholo-
gists and ecologists were already crossing the boundaries. Any thorough reading
of the works of depth psychologist Carl Jung, for example, will demonstrate that
ecopsychologists are by no means starting from scratch. Among many other note-
worthy remarks, Jung wrote that as:
scientific understanding has grown, so our world has become dehumanized. Man
feels himself isolated in the cosmos, because he is no longer involved in nature
and has lost his emotional “unconscious identity” with natural phenomena. These
have slowly lost their symbolic implications. . . . No voices now speak to man from
stones, plants, and animals, nor does he speak to them believing they can hear. His
contact with nature has gone, and with it has gone the profound emotional energy
that this symbolic connection supplied.9
keeping themselves based primarily in the contexts of their own traditions, with
which they are most familiar.
Broad definitions of ecopsychology, such as I have just introduced, are easy enough
to come by. Many people are still left wondering, however, just what ecopsy-
chology is or what exactly an ecopsychologist does. I think there are two main
reasons for this. First of all, the combining of psychology and ecology opens up
such a vast terrain that it can seem limitless at times. Psychotherapy with “nature,”
contemplative practice, wilderness practice, vision quests, earth poetics, ecolog-
ical restoration, ecological design, building sustainable communities, shamanic
counseling, Jungian dream analysis, deep ecology, environmental education: all
have been associated with ecopsychology. How can a field that includes so much
be considered a field at all? The second reason why ecopsychology is hard to define
is because there is actually not a lot of strictly ecopsychological work that one can
define it by. The literature of ecopsychology is still small, and much of it consists of
explorations directed “toward” an ecopsychology rather than attempts to actually
build one. The challenge I want to take up in this section, then, is that of getting
a handle on a field that seems to have so much possibility yet so little actuality.
I suggest, to begin, that ecopsychology is best thought of as a project, in the
sense of a large, multifaceted undertaking. This makes room for a great number
of perspectives and interests and rules out the idea that ecopsychology will ever
resemble a traditional discipline. I suggest, next, that ecopsychology be consid-
ered a historical undertaking—which is to say that it has arisen in response to
specific historical conditions. More exactly, I believe there are four general tasks
that ecopsychologists are in fact engaged in, each of which aims at resolving a cor-
responding historical need. I call these the psychological task, the philosophical
task, the practical task, and the critical task. These tasks identify the common
burdens that befall ecopsychologists, regardless of our particular orientations or
vocabularies, for they derive from a historical moment we all share. Nature and
history demand that we undertake these tasks. Hence, our work as ecopsycholo-
gists is to feel this demand in our bodies and to be true or faithful to it in our
own particular ways. When the examples of ecopsychological work that do exist
are organized into these four tasks, the overall project comes into view. Thus, I
propose that it is these four tasks—or, more precisely, the interrelations among
them—that define ecopsychology. In other words, the four tasks weave together to
form the whole endeavor that I am calling the project of ecopsychology.
In what follows I walk through the four tasks in turn, describing the his-
torical situations from which they arise and offering brief examples of ecopsy-
chological works that are addressed to each of them. The section concludes with
a discussion of some of the interrelations among the four tasks, so that my defi-
nition of ecopsychology as an intricately woven general project can be further
elaborated. I wish to say, finally, that my goal with this exercise is not to nail
down ecopsychology for good, so that it can never move again. Certainly, there are
other formulations of the tasks and other examples that could be given. My goal,
rather, is to provide a scheme that can bring into better focus what we are doing
as ecopsychologists, or at least provide a basis for some good discussion, while
nonetheless leaving lots of room to maneuver.
The archetypal role of nature—the mineral, plant, and animal world found most
complete in wilderness—is in the development of the individual human personality,
for it embodies the poetic expression of ways of being and relating to others. Urban
civilization creates the illusion of a shortcut to individual maturity by attempting to
omit the eight to ten years of immersion in nonhuman nature. Maturity so achieved
is spurious because the individual, though he may be precociously articulate and
sensitive to subtle human interplay, is without a grounding in the given structure that
is nature. . . . Indeed, the real bitterness of modern social relations has its roots in that
vacuum where a beautiful and awesome otherness should have been encountered.
Westerners, suggests Shepard, “may now be the possessors of the world’s flim-
siest identity structure.” “The West is a vast testimonial to childhood botched
to serve its own purposes, where history, masquerading as myth, authorizes men
of action and men of thought to alter the world to match their regressive moods
of omnipotence and insecurity.” In short, we are “childish adults” who keep our
society going only at the private cost of “massive therapy, escapism, intoxicants,
narcotics, fits of destructive rage, enormous grief, subordination to hierarchies, . . .
and, perhaps worst of all, a readiness to strike back at a natural world we dimly
perceive as having failed us.”22
The Philosophical Task: To Place Psyche (Soul, Anima, Mind) Back into
the (Natural) World
Psychology without ecology is lonely and vice versa. The salmon is not merely
a projection, a symbol of some inner process, it is rather the embodiment of
the soul that nourishes us all
—Tom Jay,23
commenting on the view of Northwest Coast Indians, 1986
is none other than the Earth.”39 Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy was itself gradually
revealing the earth as the original field for all human experience, the ultimate
source of, or necessary ground for, all psychological life. He called perception a
“mutual embrace” or conversation between body and world, such that the sensible
world solicits our bodily responses and our bodies in turn interrogate the sen-
sible.40 Claiming, as did Merleau-Ponty, that we can have no experience, percep-
tion, or self-knowledge without a world in which to bodily interact, to touch and
be touched by, Abram argues that the earth—the soil, wind, birds, insects—is the
given world that our sensory life opens on to, anticipates, and is fed by. Turning
to Abram’s evocative words themselves:
The human mind is not some otherworldly essence that comes to house itself
inside our physiology. Rather it is instilled and provoked by the sensorial field itself,
induced by the tensions and participations between the human body and the ani-
mate earth. The invisible shapes of smells, rhythms of cricketsong, and the move-
ment of shadows all, in a sense, provide the subtle body of our thoughts. . . .
By acknowledging such links between the inner, psychological world and the
perceptual terrain that surrounds us, we begin to turn inside-out, loosening the
psyche from its confinement within a strictly human sphere, freeing sentience to
return to the visible world that contains us. Intelligence is no longer ours alone but
is a property of the earth; we are in it, of it, immersed in its depths. And indeed each
terrain, each ecology, seems to have its own particular intelligence, its own unique
vernacular of soil and leaf and sky.
Each place its own mind, its own psyche. Oak, madrone, Douglas fir, red-tailed
hawk, serpentine in the sandstone, a certain scale to the topography, drenching rains
in the winter, fog off-shore in the summer, salmon surging in the streams—all these
together make up a particular state of mind, a place-specific intelligence shared by
all the humans that dwell therein, but also by the coyotes yapping in those valleys,
by the bobcats and the ferns and the spiders, by all beings who live and make their
way in that zone. Each place its own psyche. Each sky its own blue.41
Of course I am in mourning for the land and water and my fellow beings. If
this were not felt, I would be so defended and so in denial, so anesthetized,
I would be insane. Yet this condition of mourning and grieving going on
in my soul, this level of continuous sadness is a reflection of what is going
on in the world and becomes internalized and called “depression,” a state
altogether in me—my serotonin levels, my personal history, my problem. And
the United States) is the “vision quest,” in which a solo quester typically spends a
number of days fasting in the wilderness in order to seek guidance and spiritual
renewal through openly encountering the forces of nature (a practice that, while
being recollective, also has a therapeutic dimension).
What I propose, then, is that ecopsychological practice can presently be
grouped into these two general areas, even if there may at times be considerable
overlap between them; and that what characterizes the practice is both a psycho-
logical intention or emphasis and an alignment with the historical goal of building
a society in which human and nonhuman nature can flourish together.
Although therapeutic and recollective practices are not mutually exclusive,
I wish to offer some further examples below that relate primarily to the former.
I have chosen this focus not because I think that the one area of practice is more
important than the other (far from it), but simply because this seems the right
place to talk about therapeutic practices and because the theme of recollection will
appear throughout much of the second part of this book.
The work of the ecological, peace, and social justice activist Joanna Macy
and her colleagues probably offers the most extensive answer to the need for thera-
peutic practices. Macy offers an illustrative story. “Once, when I told a psycho-
therapist of my outrage over the destruction of old-growth forests, she informed
me that the bulldozers represented my libido and that my distress sprang from fear
of my own sexuality.”45 Macy’s experience, she says, is not untypical; therapists
often interpret feelings of despair “as manifestations of some private neurosis.” In
her own work, she has therefore made a point of validating, as healthy and real,
what she calls our “pain for the world”: “the distress we feel in connection with the
larger whole of which we are a part.” Refusing both dualism and individualism,
she says that we suffer for old-growth forests and for other people in pain because
we and these others are so interdependent. The immeasurable losses we are expe-
riencing—including the loss of the biosphere as a viable habitat for countless life
forms—comprise “the pivotal psychological reality of our time.” Our emotional
responses are appropriately complex: fear, dread, or terror before the forces pres-
ently threatening life on earth; anger and rage at having to live under such threat;
guilt for being “implicated in this catastrophe”; and, above all, sorrow—a “sadness
beyond telling” that arises from confronting “so vast and final a loss as this.”46
Macy says that she has yet to meet anyone “immune” from this pain for
the world. Yet, precisely because this suffering is so collective and great we face
an additional difficulty: the tendency to deny or repress this pain. The notion of
“psychic numbing”—coined by psychologist Robert J. Lifton to describe the lack
of feeling capacity among Hiroshima survivors—is often used to make sense of
this denial. Immersed in an emotionally overwhelming reality, we anaesthetize
ourselves and blot out or dissociate the unwanted truth. As therapist-activist Elissa
Melamed wrote: “We may know intellectually that we are in desperate straights,
but emotionally we are unconnected to this knowledge. An aura of unreality
hangs over the whole thing. . . . We are dealing with a vast psychological problem,
a planetary clinical picture of flattened affect, if you will, yet psychology offers
little in the way of assistance.”47 Although it is understandable that we cut our-
selves off from our painful feelings, people like Melamed and Macy point out that
by doing so we deprive ourselves of the energy and direction our emotions might
lend us toward taking creative political action. By staying numb, we stay stuck.
Against this emotional background, some ecopsychologists are now
exploring how the ecology movement may in fact be “organizing, educating, and
agitating with little regard for the fragile psychological complexities of the public
whose hearts and minds it [seeks] to win.”48 Roszak, for example, goes right to
the point: “Environmentalists are among the most psychologically illiterate people
you will ever meet. They work from a narrow range of motivations: the statis-
tics of impending disaster, the coercive emotional force of fear and guilt. . . they
overlook the unreason, the perversity, the sick desire that lie at the core of the
psyche. Their strategy is shock and shame.”49 In this light, many environmental
groups may actually be exploiting our emotional condition—our fear, guilt, and so
forth. Macy herself says that the grim information held up by activists “by itself can
increase resistance, deepening the sense of apathy and powerlessness.”50 Amongst
its goals, ecopsychology thus “seeks to acquaint the environmental movement with
a subtler, more sensitive psychological approach to the public it seeks to win over
to its cause.”51 Educator Mitchell Thomashow similarly claims that environmen-
talists have a responsibility “to provide support for the anxiety that accompanies
the perception of cultural upheaval and wounded ecosystems.” They must learn to
facilitate the inner changes in the public that will help bring about the policy and
behavioral changes they desire. “In this way, the environmental profession becomes
a healing profession.”52
Macy comments that “unless you have some roots in a spiritual practice that
holds life sacred and encourages joyful communion with all your fellow beings,
facing the enormous challenges ahead becomes nearly impossible.”53 The role of
psychological and spiritual practice in ecopsychology is currently being devel-
oped in a number of ways. Organizations such as the Center for Psychology and
Social Change (with its Institute of Ecopsychology, Psychotherapy and Health)
in Cambridge, Massachusetts, and the Shavano Institute in Boulder, Colorado,
for instance, hold workshops where health professionals, activists, and others
are introduced to ecopsychological theory and a range of psychological and
spiritual practices to assist them in their work and lives. Macy and others have
also responded to the need for healing on a more collective level by developing
community workshops aimed at facilitating the so-called inner work of social
change. One of the purposes of these workshops is to help participants overcome
the oppressive taboos against expressing their pain for the world. As Sarah Conn
notes, to become responsible for the current state of the world one must regain
the ability to “feel and to engage rather than to become numbed and dulled.”54
The workshops typically take place over a number of days, and proceed through
three typical stages which spontaneously flow one into the other. The first stage
involves using exercises to evoke the dreadful social and ecological realities of our
times. People are supported to feel their pain for the world in a group setting and
to cathartically express formerly blocked emotions. This expressive process sets
the ground for the second stage, in which participants come to realize that just
as there is pain in being interconnected with others, so too is there synergy and
power. The “collective nature of our pain for the world is recognized as evidence
of our interexistence, revealing the larger transpersonal matrix of our lives.”55
The third and final stage is called “empowerment,” in which participants experi-
ence their personal power, broaden their vision of what is possible, and acquire
skills for social change work. Because of the intense sharing of emotion and
transpersonal sense of this work, it carries a distinctly spiritual charge.
The basic principles of despair and empowerment work have also been
focused by Macy and others into another, more exclusively ecopsychological or
deep ecological practice called “The Council of All Beings.”56 This Council is a
ritual meant to help people “think like a mountain” (as Aldo Leopold phrased it).
Through exercises aimed both at freeing up painful emotions over our society’s
destructive relation to the natural world and at deepening a sense of identity or
connection with other-than-human beings, participants are supported to become
more “ecologically conscious” and are allowed to “express their awareness of the
ecological trouble we are in, and to deepen their motivation to act.”57
They would reconceive nature along less narcissistic lines, as a sacred realm of
intrinsic worth and as a world full of vital “others” for the articulation of the
human psyche. (This, to say the least, changes everything.) This challenging of
anthropocentrism is an example of the critical work of ecopsychology: to engage
in ecopsychologically based criticism. Such criticism is called for because the
world ultimately envisioned by ecopsychology is simply not the world of today.
As I conceive it, the critical task consists (at least initially) of bringing
together the sorts of social and cultural criticism found among the more radical
voices within both ecological and psychological circles. I believe it is fair to say,
however, that most of the criticism currently encountered within ecopsychology
is of the “cultural” variety (such as the critique of anthropocentrism) rather than
the “social.” Indeed, the more socially critical elements of the radical ecology
movement have yet to really make an appearance in ecopsychology. Ecopsycholo-
gists have made little use, moreover, of the socially radical views found within
the literature of psychology, many of which are critical of the “psy” practices (psy-
chiatry, psychology, psychotherapy, etc.) themselves. Of the four tasks or histor-
ical demands I have identified, I therefore suggest that the demand for criticism
has so far received the least satisfying response from ecopsychologists. Hence my
emphasis in what follows is on the vital need for ecopsychologists to become
more thoroughly engaged in social analysis. Because my treatment of this task
will involve detailing the points I have just introduced, the discussion here will be
lengthier than each of the previous three.
Roughly speaking, mainstream environmentalists aim for reforms “within
the system,” while the radicals want to reconstruct or change the system itself.
On the whole, radical ecologists argue that without challenging the cultural back-
grounds (beliefs, values, attitudes) and social arrangements (institutions, mate-
rial conditions) that have historically sanctioned ecological degradation, nothing
much will change. Among radical ecologists themselves, however, there is much
disagreement about the best way to go, as is indicated by the numerous dif-
ferent schools or movements to which they variously belong, and by the vigorous
debates that often occur between them.61 Of these schools, it is “deep ecology”
and “ecofeminism” that have had the greatest influence on ecopsychology, prima-
rily the former. Indeed, some say that ecopsychology is simply an outgrowth or
instance of deep ecology. The result of this situation, however, is that the tension
between deep ecology and the rest of the radical ecology movement has effectively
carried over into ecopsychology. Plainly put, ecopsychology is currently vulnerable
to the same criticism that is often made against the deep ecology movement itself:
that its social and political thought lacks depth. To understand this point, we first
need to take a look at deep ecology itself.
As with ecopsychology, deep ecology defies easy definition. I would briefly
characterize it, however, as a movement to bring our personal lives and our culture
into alignment with an ecological view of reality. It is usually defined by a broad
themselves have a social context—a context that the deep ecology movement has
to a large extent ignored. For example, while deep ecology supporters wish to sup-
port a revolution in worldviews (from Newtonian-Cartesian to holistic-ecolog-
ical), they tend not to consider how our worldview is itself anchored in particular
social structures and everyday relations within a racist, sexist, classist society. At
times they therefore give the impression that worldviews change merely through
revolutions in thought or through the introduction of a new science.68 Such criti-
cism will not of course apply to all of those who think of their work as being
deeply ecological. It is worth taking note, however, when one of the defenders of
deep ecology, Kirkpatrick Sale, defines it by the fact that it thinks primarily “in
biotic rather than social terms.”69 For it is precisely over this point that the other
areas of radical ecology have taken deep ecology to task.
Much of the criticism of deep ecology has come from ecofeminism.
Ecofeminists bring attention to the historical fact that under patriarchal rule the
repressing and exploiting of women has gone hand-in-hand with the repressing
and exploiting of the natural world. The domination of nature, say ecofeminists,
cannot be satisfactorily understood unless viewed as a feminist issue, so close is the
connection between the man-centered or “androcentric” exploitation of nature
(regarded as feminine) and of women (regarded as natural).70 Many ecofeminists
suggest that as a movement deep ecology is insufficiently sensitive to the com-
plex ways in which naturism (domination of nature), sexism, racism, and classism
interlock, and to the strategically central role that gender analysis could play in
dismantling all of them.71 In reference to Fox, for example, Ariel Salleh charges
that the attraction to transpersonal psychology “hangs on the self-actualizing logic
of middle-class individualism,” and betrays comfortable doses of “illusion and
self-indulgence.”72 (The kind of psychology advanced by many ecofeminists, by
contrast, is a version of the feminist “self-in-relation” model—one in which the
self is defined by its concrete and caring relations to particular others, human
and otherwise, and by an openness to a plurality of other voices.73) It is exactly
deep ecology’s preoccupation with psychological and metaphysical themes, and
the relative weakness of its social analysis that concerns her. Although the ecofemi-
nist literature is widely held to be an important source for the development of
ecopsychology (ecofeminism anthologies appear on all the ecopsychology bibliog-
raphies), the more demanding political claims made by ecofeminists such as Salleh
have simply not been taken up by ecopsychologists.74
The relative lack of social radicalism in ecopsychology is also indicated by its
near complete neglect, so far as I am aware, of the social ecology and ecosocialist
literatures. Broadly stated, social ecology is an anarchist movement based on the
notion that social conflict is of a piece with our ecological troubles, that is, that
oppressive social relations and the domination of the natural world share a single
hierarchical mind-set; while ecosocialism goes beyond the classical Marxist anal-
ysis to emphasize how the contradiction between expanding economic production
and finite ecological limits (i.e., between the forces/relations of production and
the conditions of production) will also play a role in the transition toward a post-
capitalist society.75 The one notable person to contribute views to ecopsychology
in this social area is the environmental justice activist Carl Anthony.76 One of
Anthony’s main points is that the so-called ecological self has to date not been
a “multicultural self,” and that deep ecology’s embrace of diversity and interde-
pendence has not in practice extended to an embrace of human diversity and
interdependence. “An ecopsychology that has no place for people of color, that
doesn’t set out to correct the distortions of racism,” he says, “is an oxymoron.”
Deep ecology, he says, tends to construe the ecological crisis in terms of a “white”
identity, neglecting the experiences and history of people of color, including the
estrangement of blacks from the land under slavery. He also speaks of “the sense
of loss suffered by many people living in the city, who are traumatized by the fact
that they don’t have a functional relationship to nature.” Suggesting a possible
area for ecopsychological investigation, he notes, finally, that the “environmental
justice movement . . . needs a greater understanding of the psychological dimen-
sions of environmental racism.”77
Whether any given ecopsychologist aligns him- or herself with environ-
mental justice, ecofeminism, or some other socially critical brand of radical
ecology is not my main concern. My intention in these paragraphs has simply
been to identify (in an admittedly limited way) a general area of radicalism that is
at present not well-enough occupied by ecopsychologists.
The other general area relatively unoccupied by ecopsychologists is that
of socially radical psychology. Psychological knowledge, insofar as it exposes the
unlovely shadow side of a society, is dangerous knowledge.78 As psychology
unmasks, it has the potential to threaten—a fact well known by those, such as
feminist psychiatrist Judith Herman, who have fought to disclose the widespread
occurrence, and devastating effects, of domestic abuse and political terror. As
witnesses to the psychic injuries wrought by our society, psychotherapists are
uniquely positioned to be social critics. Indeed, there is a sort of latent affinity
between social radicals and psychotherapists in that they both have an interest in
identifying our self-deceptions and mystifications, in piercing our illusions and
making better contact with reality. From a psychological angle, I therefore believe
that what Joel Kovel has said about psychoanalysis also needs to be said about
ecopsychology: that it “necessarily has to adopt a deeply critical attitude toward
society” and that it “cannot be itself unless it is linkable—at least in principle—to
a radical political attitude.”79
The number of radical thinkers in psychology is relatively small, these
including, in my reading, Herman, Kovel, David Ingleby, Russell Jacoby,
Christopher Lasch, Peter Breggin, Philip Cushman, and Isaac Prilelltensky.
What these radicals lack in numbers they nonetheless make up for in polem-
ical bite. They accuse the psychological mainstream of being an instrument of
Part of the psychological task, first of all, is to utterly dispel the illusion that
we are somehow exempt from membership in the natural world and to overcome
the delusion that we could ever be sane while alienated from our own earthiness,
from the bodily ground we share with the twigs and mice. In this respect, the
psychological task clearly feeds the critical task, in that it provides a good base
from which to criticize our earth-punishing society. The philosophical task, next,
feeds the other three tasks by supplying the conceptual-linguistic or ontological
environment in which to articulate and unfold them. The practical task, in turn,
feeds the psychological and philosophical tasks by providing a body of experi-
ence from which to then build psychological and philosophical theory. It also
feeds the critical task, in that ecopsychological practices not only provide support
for radical actions, but also show us what kind of shape our psyche’s are in; by
showing us the emotional and spiritual toll exacted by the modern world, they
provide material for indicting modern society. The critical task, finally, feeds all the
other tasks by making room for them. While it is ecopsychology’s goal to foster a
sense of connection with nature, including our own, the major structures of our
society generally function by rubbing out that connection (a claim I will expand
on later). The critical work of ecopsychology thus makes room for the other tasks
in the sense that it demonstrates the very need for an ecopsychology. The critical
task also feeds the philosophical task, in that our dualistic thought has emerged
within a particular historical and social context. In order to ultimately overcome
dualism we must become different people, must overcome the mode of existence
in which our dualistic thought is rooted, and for this our repressing and frag-
menting society must itself fundamentally change. Lastly, the critical task feeds
the practical task as well, in that it offers up ecopsychological critiques that may
then provide further ground for social action.
The project of ecopsychology, as I have just described it, is a big one. It will
take a great number of committed people, working together, to keep it rolling.
Some will want to concentrate on or go deep with one particular task. Others, like
me, will want to keep all four on the go, working from a sense for the project as
a whole. Indeed, my intention in this book is to promote the project of ecopsy-
chology by illustrating it with an approach of my own.
Naturalistic
We need to see ourselves as part of a larger order that can make claims on us.
—Charles Taylor99
The discourse of the ecology movement focuses on the claims and limits of the
natural world. Stan Rowe, for example, writes: “we belong to the encompassing
world and sooner or later it claims us.”100 Much psychological discourse also
addresses the claims and limits of nature, as when Konrad Stettbacher says that:
“Child neglect runs counter to all the dictates of Nature.”101 Not only external
nature, the biotic community, but our own human nature makes demands on
us and sets limits. The work of ecopsychology, naturalistically conceived, is to
relate or unify these claims and limits. Naturalistic psychology advocates fidelity
to nature, being in service of nature, and seeing the human as part of a larger
natural order. The ecological and psychological crises of our time may then both
be traced to the violation of nature. The destruction of rain forests and the neglect
or abuse of children are equally transgressions of the natural world, for children
are nature too. Ecopsychology, in this sense, is the ecology movement not only
psychologized, but expanded to include the domination of human nature. When
we include human nature within ecological discourse—is it not odd that it is usu-
ally left out?102—that discourse necessarily turns psychological.
Despite the dangers of doing so, I thus propose that nature be adopted as
a radical concept. In this, I fortunately have an ally in Kovel, who in his own
writings has attempted to “rescue the notion of human nature . . . for radical
discourse.”103 Only something that has a nature can be violated; thus, as we
recognize violation so do we recognize nature. Precisely how we are to under-
stand this nature remains for me to elaborate in the chapters to come. I have
said, however, that the society that violates nonhuman nature is the same society
that violates human nature. A naturalistic psychology that keeps both of these
abuses in sight will not abandon human society for the wilderness, nor will it
deny the deep need we all have to be initiated into mature, personal relations
with the natural world. As critical thinkers such as Kovel tell us, modernity’s
infamous domination of nature faces in two directions: in one it diminishes the
earth (ecological crisis), in the other it diminishes the human (social and psycho-
logical crisis). A naturalistic approach carried through to its proper conclusions
will therefore itself face in these two directions—as did John Rodman when
he made the following remarks: “I strongly suspect that the same basic princi-
ples are manifested in quite diverse forms—e.g. in damming a wild river and
repressing an animal instinct (whether human or nonhuman), in clear-cutting
a forest and bombing a city, in Dachau and a university research laboratory, in
Experiential
The only “drive” or instinct of which one can usefully speak, in human
behavior, is the drive to interact with the environment itself
—Gordon Wheeler,
commenting on the view of Kurt Goldstein105
traditionally dealt with them as external events. If, however, we give our relation-
ship to nature psychological status, then we may study the inner sense of our
interactions with, and participation in, the natural world. Part of my strategy
toward this end is to build up in the reader an experiential sense for the interac-
tive or dialogical nature of reality. For having a sense for how all phenomena
mirror each other, intertwine, and arise only in contact with one another, radically
undoes our more usual dualistic, isolated-in-the-head, feel for the world.
Perhaps what is most radical about an experiential approach is that it gives
authority to our experience, all the more so as we learn to listen to and focus it.
As discussed above, social movements do not always attend well to what people
are experiencing, and it is not uncommon to hear of activist organizations that are
themselves oppressively run. An experiential approach to politics makes the open
sharing of experience and the active supporting of personal healing central to its
agenda. At a time when many of us are struggling just to make it through the day,
such an approach may have much to contribute to resolving the kind of prob-
lems identified above. Experiential approaches avoid being dogmatic about what
people must or ought to do. They do, however, maintain that our bodily experi-
ence of the world implies certain social changes, and encourage us to take actions
that move in the direction of those changes.108 This is not to say that experiential
politics takes no guidance from social theories, as these are certainly important for
helping us to interpret our situations. It concentrates as much, though, on taking
life-forwarding steps that emerge from making honest contact with presently felt
reality. Experiential approaches take advantage of the creativity of the life process,
of the arising of new meanings and possibilities with the unfolding of experience
itself. To the extent that it adopts this kind of approach, ecopsychology may avoid
fitting itself into ready-made forms, and seek new ones instead. (The despair and
empowerment work of Macy and her colleagues is an excellent example of how a
radical new form of practice may develop through paying attention to what our
experience is calling for.) Most generally, by acknowledging the uniqueness or
particularity of people’s life situations, an experiential approach allows for a high
degree of flexibility and a wide variety of options. It may, then, help us to live
radical lives in whatever ways make sense from within the context of our own life
experience and interests.
Discursive Problems
There are few experiences quite so cruel as, when after having made a well-
argued, even elegant and moving case to someone, you lean back expecting
the warm sparkle of shared insight and understanding, only to encounter the
flat opaqueness of complete and utter incomprehension.
—John Livingston1
We predict the weather and try to control inflation because we are not the weather
and not inflation. . . . the dominant discourse about the future of our society is com-
posed of the vocables of prognoses, projections, extrapolations, scenarios, models,
programs, simulations, and incentives. It is as though we have taken ourselves out
of reality and have left only objectified and disavowed versions of ourselves in the
universe we are trying to understand and shape. We vacate our first-person place
and presence in the world just when we mean to take responsibility for its destiny.3
Nowhere are the inadequacies of modern discourse more apparent than in what
Owen Barfield once called “the virtual breakdown of communication between the
devotees of technocracy on one side and the habitual lovers of nature and life on
the other.”4
It is a source of some dismay for ecological advocates that the things they
are moved to talk about often find no home within the official views of reality
that dominate our public language. Robert Socolow, for example, writes: “conser-
vationists have separate languages for talking to one another, to politicians, and
29
to their avowed opponents. Except when they talk to one another (and perhaps
not even then) they refrain all too often from articulating what really matters to
them.”5 John Rodman similarly writes of his impression that when legal and moral
philosophers use “logical gymnastics” to advocate for the “rights” of natural enti-
ties—whether laboratory animals or trees—“they sound as if they want to say
something less reasonable, less moralistic, more expressive of their total sensibility,
but are afraid of seeming subjective, sentimental, or something that’s not quite
respectable.”6 Putting his finger on this dilemma, Neil Evernden notes that: “not
everyone feels compelled to defend a mountain. But those who do . . . find it
an awkward compulsion, for they must reconcile the conflicting tasks of being
faithful to their subject and maintaining their credibility.”7 Because ecopsycholo-
gists share the basic concerns of the ecology movement, they are to a large extent
in the same boat: they are burdened with the task of finding a language capable
of honestly illuminating their ecologically and psychologically informed accounts
of what truly and finally matters, while at the same time being respectable or
legitimate before a public audience.
And so we must talk about discourse. A discourse (as I use the term in
this chapter) is a way of making sense with words; as such, it is from the start
an interpretation of the world. When our interpretations are just too far off
the norm, however, our audiences—as John Livingston says regarding wildlife
ethics—“literally do not know what we are talking about.”8 The danger is that the
reality we care for and feel compelled to talk about may be so poorly recognized
by others that it is simply “leaving the realm of discussibility.”9 In this respect,
historian Michel Foucault claimed that an era’s reigning discursive practices act to
police which beliefs, values, and attitudes get to be included within a society and
which get excluded, setting the boundaries on what is understandable or accept-
able. In a related vein, the communist Antonio Gramsci believed that changing
the structure of society is no longer a matter of military revolution but of rhe-
torical struggle. He spoke of the need for “new popular beliefs, that is to say a
new common sense and with it a new culture and a new philosophy which will
be rooted in the popular consciousness with the same solidity and imperative
quality as traditional beliefs.”10 Insofar as ecopsychology seeks to help reverse,
at the level of psyche, one of the cardinal features of modernity—the domina-
tion of nature11—it may be thought of as an effort to move beyond the modern
era. And like other holders of nonmainstream perspectives, ecopsychologists want
their radical notions to one day be part of the common sense which governs our
everyday existing.12
The purpose of this chapter is to offer a reflection on the discursive possi-
bilities—and pitfalls—open to ecopsychology in pursuing this end. I am framing
the discussion as “the problem with normal” in order to highlight, first of all,
that normal psychological discourse is incapable of making good sense of the ter-
rain of ecopsychology because of the dualism entrenched into it. Quite simply, in
contesting the strict division between inner, subjective, human reality and outer,
objective, natural reality, ecopsychology implicitly puts the whole research tradi-
tion that is based on this division into question. Whereas conventional modern
science holds that the best way to disclose the natural world is to eliminate any
personal or subjective relations with it, ecopsychology seeks a nature that is known
precisely through enhancing this relationship. There are, of course, certain kinds of
truth that only a scientific method can reveal, and there are many varieties of sci-
ence. However, because ecopsychologists wish to grant the natural world its own
subjectivity, agency, or personhood, they, of all people, need to protest the rigidly
scientific viewpoint that denies nature these properties, and must embrace other,
less divisive and more qualitative methods of inquiry. While the supremacy of the
modern scientific method is increasingly questioned among qualitative researchers
in the human disciplines, Norman Denzin and Yvonna Lincoln note that the
challenges are still many: such “researchers are called journalists, or soft scientists.
Their work is termed unscientific, or only exploratory, or entirely personal and
full of bias.”13 These are the same barbs that will undoubtedly be used against
ecopsychology (and which, incidentally, have already been tossed at some of my
own work by a peer-reviewer). I believe that foregrounding this issue will better
allow ecopsychology to deal with such criticism and make the case for privileging
a “not-so-normal”14 discourse. More specifically, I suggest that ecopsychology
needs to wrestle with finding interpretive, experiential, or “hermeneutic” forms
of discourse which, being demanded by the subject matter itself, have their own
validity and necessity.
A second bit of trouble facing ecopsychology is the privilege normally
granted to our technocratic and economic discourses. As Tom Athanasiou notes,
it is doubtful whether “greening” is even possible so long as “economics is taken as
the sole source of sound judgment and virtue,” and while economists themselves
grope “even to locate the ecological crisis on their charts.”15 Within such a climate,
how can ecopsychology win an audience for its own discourse? How can it gain
any recognition for its own radical set of priorities and ultimate concerns? My
suggestion on this matter is that ecopsychology adopt an openly rhetorical style of
speaking. As I discuss below, there is a strong affinity between the hermeneutical
and rhetorical modes, and both are well-suited for navigating through psycho-
logical terrain. I propose, in short, that a hermeneutical and rhetorical method is
well-suited for the purpose of establishing a radical ecopsychological discourse.
The subject matter of ecopsychology is neither the human nor the natural, but
the lived experience of interrelationship between the two, whether the “nature”
in question be human or nonhuman. In their quest for scientific respectability,
however, modern psychologists have thoroughly adopted an objectivist outlook,
which to a large extent excludes this subject matter from consideration. Natural
scientific empiricism and rationalism continue to exercise a “dual hegemony” over
academic psychology, providing the bulk of its taken-for-granted background
assumptions.17 In other words, mainstream psychology is organized around the
very dualism that ecopsychology would overcome. Rationalists, such as cognitive
psychologists, focus on such things as the internal processing of “information,”
while empiricists, such as behavioural psychologists, focus on data gathered from
the external world (e.g., human behavior). Within this mainstream, questions con-
cerning “the environment” are dealt with by the existing field of “environmental
psychology,” a field from which ecopsychologists generally distinguish their own
efforts.18 In what follows, I suggest that—precisely because of its continuity with
a dualistic research tradition—environmental psychology is simply not capable of
disclosing those meanings that concern the more radical field of ecopsychology.
Ecopsychology tends to attract the more experientially oriented and less main-
stream psychologies, while environmental psychology tends to hold that scientific
line.19 The challenge for ecopsychology is thus to give up psychology’s attachment
to the various forms of objectivism, and, accordingly, to find a mode of discourse
that can walk in the challenging space between the human and the natural.
The goal of environmental psychology is to use traditional scientific methods
to study the impact of certain environmental factors—atmospheric conditions,
pollution, stress, noise, urbanization, crowding, and so forth—on individual
human well-being. The research in this field is dominated by the behavioral and
cognitive traditions, neither of which has much of a presence in ecopsychology.
Although I do not intend to discuss in any great detail the kind of findings pro-
duced by these two approaches, I will venture here to say that ecopsychology
reaches beyond them to a more qualitative or poetic consideration of the inter-
weaving of humanity and nature, one that reveals aspects of the world and modes
of experience that are not visible to the modern scientific persona. One leading
pair of cognitive researchers, Rachel and Stephen Kaplan, who clearly bring much
sensitivity to their work, admit in this regard that “it is hard to justify the role that
nature plays in rational terms.” Their findings are largely limited, then, to how
nature can provide a “restorative environment” that supports humans in recov-
ering from “mental fatigue,” and so in regaining the ability to effectively “manage
information.”20
In addition to making for narrow findings, the scientific worldview adopted
by environmental psychology quite simply preserves the human/nature split. As
David Kidner remarks, “scientific and technological ‘objectivity’ serve to stabilize
a style of personality functioning in which the relation of humanity to the natural
restricted way that makes it amenable to prediction and control. Indeed, it espe-
cially behooves ecopsychologists to criticize the idea that modern natural science
gives us the only solid way to know reality.26 But what of human nature? To reduce
people, as is common in psychiatry, to genetic, biochemical, or neurophysiological
explanation, is surely to see humans in an equally restricted way. The science of
psychiatry, to pursue this authoritative field, has grown particularly “hard” since
the 1980s, when—spurred on by the development of psychiatric medications—it
was overtaken “with a fervor for biological explanation.”27 The experiential cri-
tique of biological psychiatry begins with the assertion that human existence is a
totality, simultaneously psychic and somatic, and so is prior, and irreducible, to
either of these two aspects.28 No physiological condition is ever just a “natural”
phenomenon, but is lived. Lived, moreover, within a political, economic, and
sociocultural field. Whatever is the “organic” contribution to, say, schizophrenia
(and there is no unanimity of opinion on this),29 to attend mostly to manipulating
the physicochemical structure of schizophrenic people is to refuse to give their
hellish existence a hearing, to listen to the meaningful voice—the logos—of their
suffering souls.30 The medical strategy that would bring schizophrenia “under the
sway of medical technics,” says Kovel, and so reduce this horrific “collapse of
being” to a biochemical abnormality in the brain, has
obvious cultural power, since it combines in one conception the mystique of the
machine and the managerial ethos. In its system the doctor-expert is the manager
of the soul, regarded now as a mechanism like any other, capable of tuning up or
overhauling. . . . The notion also has a political power, . . . disease is something going
on within a person; it is to be looked for in the malfunctioning of the ‘parts’ of his
personality and not in the entire relationship between the self and the world; and it
is to be remedied by individual or particularistic action. . . . It should not [, however,]
be thought that social problems are beyond the scope of the medical model. Quite
the contrary: it exists to gobble them up and medicalize them.31
I have cited this passage to indicate how the modern project of splitting off and
mastering nature has made its way into the psychiatric establishment, as it has
with academic psychology more generally. By keeping madness primarily on the
far (nature) side of the human/nature divide, in the realm of broken machinery, it
helps obscure the role that social disintegration, poverty, family stress, child abuse,
sexism, racism, class discrimination, dehumanizing institutions, ecological col-
lapse, and other stressing social factors also play in the genesis of suffering32 (even
if these are not entirely ignored by psychiatrists33 and even if medical knowledge
and psychiatric medication are indeed sometimes called for).34 More generally,
however, my intention in this paragraph has been to highlight the need to develop
better conceptions not only of nonhuman nature, but of human nature too.
walk between the human and the natural, and so escape the trouble discussed
above, only as we learn to describe how we experience them together: the move
away from dualism is the move toward experience.
Overcoming Alienation. J. H. van den Berg once called child psychology the
“result of a state of emergency,” its “scientifically-phrased understanding” being
“the smallest compensation for the lost natural understanding between old and
young.”41 Anthropologist Stanley Diamond likewise commented that his own
discipline has grown popular precisely because civilization has exacted such an
acute loss in our understanding of ourselves as human beings. Yet, anthropology is
in the main a “narrow discipline with mechanical techniques and trivial goals” that
represses its own urgent and central question, namely, “what part of our humanity
have we lost and how and in what form we may regain it.”42 I take these blunt
statements from van den Berg and Diamond as suggesting that our scientific “olo-
gies” not only restrict our vision, but largely define our estrangements. As the scope
of our historical alienation widens, and as the losses are felt, disciplines or fields
such as child psychology and anthropology—and now ecopsychology—are born.
The ecophilosopher George Sessions has traced ecopsychology’s beginnings
to Jean-Jacques Rousseau, one of the first Europeans to articulate the “psycho-
logical importance of relating to wild Nature.”43 Van den Berg claimed, though,
that the “sense of nature” Rousseau would have us believe was “a valuable matter
which people for some inexplicable reason had never seen before” was in fact “the
discovery of a loss.”44 Does it not seem fitting to suggest that the “vast conti-
nent” to be mapped by ecopsychologists is, in truth, a terrain born of alienation?
Richard Nelson writes: “Probably no society has been so deeply alienated from
the community of nature, has viewed the natural world from a greater distance of
mind, has lapsed into a murkier comprehension of its connection with the sus-
taining environment.”45 I imagine van den Berg and Diamond, then, cautioning
ecopsychologists not to forget the “state of emergency” that has initiated our own
field; to beware the danger of attempting “to find in science a substitute for lost
orientation.”46 As ecopsychologists, we need to keep our own broad and urgent
questions of alienation, of loss and recovery, before us.47
This is where hermeneutics comes in; for a hermeneutical inquiry is one
that studies something strange, unfamiliar, or alien that must be made compre-
hensible, familiar, or near through a process of interpretation.48 One of the key
figures in hermeneutics, Hans-Georg Gadamer, described it as letting “what is
alienated by the character of the written word or by the character of being distan-
tiated by cultural or historical distances speak again.”49 And alienation takes place
“when we have withdrawn ourselves and are no longer open to the immediate
claim of that which grasps us.”50 To hear Gadamer’s words with the idea that
it is nature’s claims that have been made distant is, I suggest, to reveal ecopsy-
chology as a hermeneutical form of inquiry. It seeks to listen to or interpret the
voice of nature in a way that normal science simply cannot. What Gadamer tells
us—that estrangement is overcome “only through a dialogical encounter with
what is at once alien to us, makes a claim upon us, and has an affinity with what
Risking Being Changed. A basic tenet of hermeneutics is that all experience takes
place within an implicitly sensed context or “horizon” of background under-
standing, which for the most part remains obscure or concealed. Most of what
we understand was never given to us in the form of an explicit belief system or
theory, but is simply embodied in shared daily activities or cultural practices we
have meshed ourselves into. We do not teach children, for instance, how far to
stand from other people; instead, they catch on to our subtle distance-standing
practices by imitating adults, with little awareness that they are doing so.60 In
like fashion, we also pick up or come to grasp specific points of view and ways of
conceiving things—all of which adds up to a pervasively felt “preunderstanding”
that “forestructures” our perception of the world. Thus, no matter how clear and
distinct our knowledge, it will always trail off into an unclear background sense
whose origins will forever remain mostly in the dark.
There can therefore be no presuppositionless understanding, no coming
to some topic without any biases or tacit expectations.61 Otherwise, we could
not make any contact with our subject matter to begin with; it could not even
show up as something interesting or worthy of study. The process of interpreta-
tion, accordingly, must proceed from whatever understanding we already have;
it has no absolute beginning or end, but takes place within the so-called herme-
neutic circle. In reading this chapter, for instance, you, the reader, are grasping the
meaning of my words under the condition of whatever prior understanding of
things you bring to them. Certain passages, if quite unfamiliar to you or foreign to
your background, may be opaque; while others will be more readily gathered. In
any event, if after finishing this chapter you read it again, my words will inevitably
make more sense. This is because the first reading will have granted you a feel for
the chapter-as-a-whole, however tentative, which will then act as a new horizon
within which to continue puzzling out its various details. You will, in short, be
interpreting what I am saying by cycling back and forth between the various pieces
or particulars of the chapter and the chapter considered more globally; by reading
the ending into the beginning, and vice versa. This interpretive dialectic, in which
“a partial understanding is used to understand still further,”62 and in which one’s
felt sense of the “text” is explicated by shuffling between parts and whole, is the
hermeneutic circle.
Notice that in the process just described the reader’s own horizon of
understanding must somehow meet the implicit horizon of the text, such that
there is what Gadamer called a “fusion of horizons.”63 In other words, as we make
genuine contact with something novel or alien, our own horizons are broadened
and enriched. What is more, the alien context provides a contrasting ground
against which buried prejudices hidden within our own preunderstanding are
made more visible. A central tenet of hermeneutics is therefore that we gain self-
understanding only through our interaction with others. Gadamer was insistent,
however, that we not merely explicate our own prejudices, but be willing to risk
them. Readers of this chapter who are committed to a traditional scientific view,
for example, might become more aware of their own prescientific assumptions
and perhaps willing to examine and/or modify some of them. Or they might
disagree with what I have said, but still find that this helps them sense, clarify, or
advance their own understanding of things. This kind of hermeneutics asks, then,
that we risk, as one anthropological title puts it, Being Changed by our encounter
with the other.64 The kind of reality we discover depends on the kind of people
Both really invent their own language to communicate their own vision; there is no
given mode of discourse, no recognized literary genre, no established philosophical
option, which is wholly adequate. Their fusions of the language of myth and of sci-
ence are not confusions but conscious and deliberate undertakings. Because they are
writing out of their unique and overwhelming experiences—Freud out of the discovery,
“I am Oedipus,” precipitated by his father’s death; Jung out of his six-year-long
deliberately chosen “confrontation with the unconscious”—they could not borrow
another’s language to render them. To them their own speech was alive, pregnant,
avowedly metaphorical.73
with an atmosphere and an impelling force that can be felt; where points, even if
surrounded by ignorance, nonetheless get made and are able to dialogically elicit
fruitful responses from the reader.
may be: “our thought itself—philosophical, scientific, and artistic—is born and
shaped in the process of interaction and struggle with others’ thought, and this
cannot but be reflected in the forms that verbally express our thought as well.”95
The poetic-rhetorical, in short, is the “single inevitable dimension of language.”96
Before anything else, we are every one of us poet-rhetoricians—symbolic and dia-
logical beings.
What, then, is the relationship between rhetoric and hermeneutics? The
fields of rhetoric and hermeneutics can both be said to work in the symbolic or
metaphorical mode, as speaking and interpreting are both acts of symbolization
or metaphor use. The difference lies in their emphases, the former on the com-
municative arts, the latter on the event of understanding or meaning creation.
Given that both communication and understanding are involved in any sort of
inquiry, however, it is safe to say that these two fields have a close relation. Says
Gadamer, “Convincing and persuading, without being able to prove—these are
obviously as much the aim and measure of understanding and interpretation as
they are the aim and measure of the art of oration and persuasion.” We would not
be seeking to persuade others unless shared understanding were at issue, and there
would be no hermeneutical task unless, in the pursuit of better understanding, we
were engaged in dialogue. Hence, “rhetorical and hermeneutical aspects of human
linguisticality completely interpenetrate each other.”97
In this book, I am myself attempting to maintain a balance between rhe-
torical and hermeneutical goals by speaking “deictically.” “The word deictic comes
from Greek deiknynai, which means to show, to point out, to bring to light, to
set before one, and then also to explain and teach. Speakers of deictic discourse
never finally warrant the validity of what they tell but point away from them-
selves to what finally matters; they speak essentially as witnesses.”98 The chal-
lenge for a deictical speaker is to make an ultimate concern tangible to others, to
articulate a world that has this concern at its centre. As Borgmann says, modern
scientific laws are unable to elucidate “the crucial and remarkable features of the
modern world” and so by themselves cannot provide us with the orientation we
so need. Scientists begin their explanatory work only after some subject matter
has emerged as worthy of investigation; they cannot explain the emergence of this
significance itself. For significance resides in-the-world, not in decontextualized or
“de-worlded” data.99 Deictic discourses, then, are experiential; they play the role of
offering the orientation, the larger context of meaning, that is missing from our
more narrow scientific or “apo-deictic” discourses.100 Of course, blank opposition
to all scientific investigation is an untenable position, for there are certain kinds
of regularity within the natural world that only the scientific mode can detect.
Indeed, we would be much the poorer without such undertakings as attachment
theory and conservation biology. The experiential critique, in general, insists only
that scientific knowledge be placed within the context of, and so take its sense or
bearing from, our whole lived existence.101 Erazim Kohák writes in this vein that
there is “something wrong when we use medicine to deaden our sensitivity, when
we . . . blind ourselves with the very lights we devised to help us see.”102 Providing
a sensitive vision of what truly matters, and which may bring some sense to our
science, is, by contrast, precisely the task of deictical rhetoric.
In place of our more usual technical rhetoric, then, deictical rhetoric is
disclosive. It requires of us not scientific exactitude, but a sharpness of another
sort: for symbolizing and appealing to experience, for bringing to light what is
going on. It throws us back onto our shaky selves, onto our interpretive abilities.
Part of the therapeutic work of ecopsychology is exactly to resensitize ourselves
to what we might perceive without the aid of science or other forms of explana-
tion, by consulting our experience. As Joanna Macy suggests: “Our capacity to
reach each other stems less from our command of statistics than from our exis-
tential confrontation with the dangers of our time. . . . In all such conversation,
we need to believe . . . that there is that in the other person that can hear us at
the level of these deep concerns. To the extent that we can address the human
being—somewhere there inside—we become effective communicators.”103 Or as
Wendell Berry writes: “It is not necessary to have recourse to statistics to see that
the human estate is declining with the estate of nature.”104
I am calling my own work deictical because it is part of a larger effort to
establish or open up the human-nature relationship (as a relationship) as a domain
of concern, to make it discussible. Borgmann says that to get out of the modern
era we must let “the things that are beyond the control of modernity . . . speak in
their own right.”105 This statement could well serve as a motto for my own natu-
ralistic approach. In pointing toward wilderness as the most obvious realm that
stands in its own right outside the rule of modern technology, however, Borgmann
is typical of writers who effectively locate wild nature in the woods, not in the
body, and so avoid confronting more psychological themes. I wish, rather, to dem-
onstrate that not only field and forest, but our own bodily nature lies essentially
outside the control of modernity, is wild; and to reject mainstream psychology’s
alliance with the prevailing technological-economic order, allying my psychology
instead with the order of primordial nature, inside and out.
The way I am doing this is by building an approach: a set of concepts and
working principles by which the human-nature relationship may be understood and
practical actions encouraged. My intention is not so much to announce a system as
to disclose a matter of deep concern. Inasmuch as we are all poetic-rhetorical beings,
and that I want to address the reader at the level of our essential humanity, I would
like to use a poetic-rhetorical language in my efforts. Indeed, Borgmann asserts
that “poetical speech is the purest kind of deictical discourse since it is the most
adequate medium of ultimate significance.”106 His is not an uncommon sentiment.
Great poetry is language at its most hermeneutical, for truth “is always in poetic
form; not literal but symbolic.”107 Ecopsychology, in particular, must embrace the
poetic principle exactly because a gross imbalance toward the rational principle has
“Returning to Experience”1
To illustrate what he means by this, Livingston invites the reader to take a moment
to “look at the cock pigeon strutting on the eavestrough [sic]. . . . See the bird;
really see him, and feel the urgency and the perfection and the beauty of his hot
being. . . . Know that you and he pulse as one, and that you always did.”5 For the
vast majority of modern folk, however, I suggest that such an exercise, to borrow
one of Livingston’s own phrases, is going exactly nowhere. It’s just not that easy.
Most of us simply do not have the capacity to feel what Livingston is attempting
to evoke in us. And the reason we do not is contained in the very notion of
“recovery.” To recover a sense of unity with all life is to also recover from the
trauma of having been so utterly divorced from it. I thus contend that what Liv-
ingston’s work essentially invites is the development of a more concretely detailed
understanding of the nature of this trauma and of the specific processes necessary
for some sort of genuine recovery.
We might, in similar fashion, call Evernden’s project “listening for a new
story.” Evernden describes humans as “natural aliens” in that as a species we are
born into the natural world problematically, as a kind of niche-less exotic that
must always mediate a relationship to nature through culture, must adopt some
story about how we fit into the scheme of things. Because our current story dic-
tates that we ravage the planet like some global locust, his hope lies with the
possibility of choosing a new cultural self-interpretation, one in which we might
recognize the natural world as a community of fellow subjects rather than a col-
lection of meaningless objects to be humanly exploited. In order to facilitate the
arrival of a new story, Evernden counsels a surrender of common sense, a let-
ting go of existing categories, so that we may recover a sense of wonder, experi-
ence the world afresh, and so hear the notes of a new song, should one be in the
offing. As with Livingston, however, I believe there is more to consider here than
Evernden allows. While I certainly agree that the place of humans in the natural
world is a troublesome question, it is also important to recognize that our current
state of extreme alienation is “achieved only by outrageous violence perpetrated
by human beings on human beings.”6 Indeed, our current story is so thoroughly
geared against the life process that stepping away from it will require a great deal
of social struggle and healing along the way.
What is common to these two projects is their orientation toward some
kind of experiential renewal. Both prescribe a suspension of the belief system of
our culture in order to allow for a more direct contact with wild others and so
for a more authentic self-understanding and cultural script to emerge. What they
both lack, moreover, is any kind of practical or detailed insight as to just what
this might involve. It is perhaps unfair to expect of these two thinkers something
that neither professes to offer. However, without an understanding of the violence
inherent in our present manner of existing and of the nitty-gritty of recovery
work, that is, without taking a closer look at what is presently going on with our
experiencing, the kind of renewal they propose can only remain an idea. It is this
“closer look” that I want to start undertaking in the next four chapters. Need
it be said, my intention in doing so is to honour the efforts of Livingston and
Evernden—for we most respect other people’s work when we try to pick up some
of its strands and weave them a little further. My work has effectively become a
response to theirs, a conversation with theirs. I like to frame it as such, in any case,
as a strategy for bringing some focus to my own critical and recollective project.
The purpose of this section is to lay down some concepts, introduce some notions,
that will get us on better speaking terms about “experience.” It is an endless topic.
In what follows, I have therefore restricted myself to four subject areas, all of
which will figure prominently in the remaining chapters: the primacy of experi-
ence or felt meaning in human existence; the embodied nature of our experiencing;
the power of a relational or interactive framework (so different from the individu-
alistic and dualistic framework of our Western tradition) to open up satisfying
new avenues of understanding; and the suffering we experience when our human
nature is violated. Each of these, in turn, have an important connection to the
life process, which for this chapter is my bridge into ecopsychology. The section
roughly progresses in order through these four areas, building on earlier terms as
it goes, and always aiming to bring along the reader’s own experience.
Beginning with experience is what existentialists do. Not just those French
ones who feel that human existence is absurd and nauseating but, more broadly,9
anyone who feels that, as Wilhem Dilthey put it: “Life cannot be brought before
the bar of reason.” To get close to the things that matter we have no recourse but
to our bodily experience. The philosopher and psychotherapist Eugene Gendlin
writes:
Within experiencing lie the mysteries of all that we are. For the sake of our
experiential sense of what we observe, we react as we do. From out of it we create
what we create. And, because of its puzzles, and for the desperation of some of
its puzzles, we overthrow good sense, obviousness, and reality, if need be.10
for more than thirty years.”18 A quarter of a century later what is still apparently
missing is not the scientific data, but the existential sensitivity, the felt orienta-
tion.19 A story from my own life may help to make this point.
When I was a child I had a compelling love affair with all things rocky: bedrock
outcroppings, cliffs, mountains, sandy beaches, stones. I would sit for great lengths of
time among limestone boulders on the shores of the Bruce Peninsula, just sensing their
timeless presence, their heavy being. As a student geologist later in life, I undertook a
research project on what is known as the “Kingston limestone,” a lovely rock with a
warm glow. From a local quarry I obtained a section of rock core and then diamond-
sawed it into cylinders two inches in diameter and five inches tall. These were placed
one at a time between the plattons of a servo control compression testing machine,
and then slowly squeezed to the breaking point, so as to measure their strength. As I
watched that rock crumble, I felt a voice inside me scream; yet the mood of the labora-
tory overrode it. It was not until some time later that I let myself feel the shame for
what I had done.
Ecopsychology, as I discuss throughout, is fundamentally a response to vio-
lence (for to violate something is precisely to insult its nature). From this view, the
goal of the ecopsychologist is to work toward the recovery of our ability to perceive
and answer back to this violence, and to engage in nonviolent modes of relating.
The story I just told was meant, in this respect, to illustrate the principle that vio-
lence “cannot be seen through the sights of positivism.”20 (“The objects weep, but
the researcher sees no tears.”)21 Despite my repeated criticisms, I mean no disre-
spect to modern scientists. In a scientific age, we are all more or less naive positiv-
ists. What is so transgressive about smashing rock samples, anyway? What matters
to me is that in order to participate in the rock-breaking incident I had to deflect
my own felt recognition of violence. The promise of an experiential approach for
ecopsychology is that it may give such feelings a place, accord them their proper
truth and weight. While a psychology based on the model of externalized nature
aims to produce positive knowledge, a psychology based on relationships has no
choice but to be experiential. For the “data” of relationships are the feelings, reali-
ties, or meanings born of interaction. That is, an interactional perspective resig-
nifies experience; it brings—to use the familiar terms—objectivity to the subject
and subjectivity to the object. Thus, to study the human-nature relationship is to
pursue the essence of experience itself. While, conversely, to revivify our experi-
ence is to find nature at its heart.
Any explication of the process of experiencing will reflect the degree of the
author’s own awareness and understanding, and is best be read in that light. I
think it is helpful, for instance, to say that Cartesian dualism truly describes only
self-estranged, disembodied, narcissistic experience; and that with a deepening
of experience, mind, body, and world increasingly unify. My tutors in the deep-
ening of my own experience have been humanistic psychologists, existential-
phenomenological and hermeneutic thinkers, and Gautama the Buddha. In what
follows, my aim is to introduce some general concepts that come from the tradi-
tions of these teachers (leaving Buddhism mostly for the next chapter), so that we
may get an initial sense of what is meant by the notion of “experiencing.”
An experiential approach is one that takes “experience” as its root metaphor
or main guide. The basic scheme I use for describing the process of experiencing
comes from Gendlin. In its simplest formulation, experiencing is the interaction
between feelings and symbols. To understand this better we need to say more about
“feelings,” “symbols,” and the nature of their interaction. Before doing that, how-
ever, I must make two notes about word usage. First, experiencing carries a double
meaning, referring both to the flow of feelings which interacts with symbols and
to this process of interaction itself. Given the internal relationship between feel-
ings and symbols, however, this ambiguity is fitting, and in my experience causes
no confusion. Second, although generally referred to as a noun—as experience—
the phenomenon of experiencing is a process, and so needs to be heard as a verb—
as in What are you experiencing?
Any piece of experiencing, then, whatever it might be, will always have two
basic aspects or orders. The symbol is the direct form of the experience. It is some
figure of awareness: a thought, a behavior, a sight or sound, an emotion (which, as
I clarify below, is not the same as a feeling), an image, a rite, an event, some words.
The feeling is the ongoing, concrete, underlying “inward sentience” or bodily sen-
sitivity that accompanies and interacts with these symbols: the felt background
that lends meaning or sense to the figure. Because they comprise the sense we
bodily-have in relation to any content we may be experiencing, feelings are also
called felt meaning. As Gendlin says, without having a “feel” for a concept it is only
some verbal noise, lacking in meaning; it is in the dimension of feeling that the
meaning of the concept is experienced. Note that felt meaning is explicitly known
only when given some symbolic form that houses and so completes the meaning.
From the reverse direction, note also that felt meaning is “called forth” when we
interact with something whose symbolic character arouses in us a feeling. Symbols
and feelings are thus mutually formative or determining: the traffic between them
moves in both directions. The difference between feelings and symbols is most
noticeable, perhaps, when we have a feeling but can find no words to express it.
We must then stay with the feeling and wait for the right word-symbols to come.
Or we may say something, but not mean it. Here, we have some word-symbols,
but they are hollow because lacking in feeling—which we must then sense if we
are to speak more authentically. It is, then, the interaction between these two basic
orders that makes up experiencing. While not all of these terms may be clear at
this stage, I do want the reader to eventually develop a good feel for them, to get
a solid experiential sense for what these word-symbols mean. The descriptions and
examples I offer in this section, along with a couple of exercises, are intended to
help with that process. For now, I wish to make a number of points only toward
some initial clarification.
“Feeling is the very state . . . in which our being human hovers.”24 This
remark of Heidegger’s makes my first point. An experiential approach does not
advocate swimming around in emotions and eschewing all intellection. It instead
acknowledges that there is a felt or experiential dimension to everything; that
the world is intelligible only on account of the feeling tone that pervades, usu-
ally unnoticed, all our thinking, speaking, and doing (including our emoting).
Thinking does not therefore escape feeling, but is rather “the process of succes-
sively ‘selecting’ symbols for present felt meaning, finding that the symbols ‘call
forth’ more meaning than one anticipated, then ‘selecting’ more symbols from
some of this excess.”25 Feelings are our bodily grasping of all that is nonfocal at the
moment; they are our sensing, all at once, the many background meanings that are
in play or relevant to us in any given situation. Feelings are thus more diffuse or
fuzzy than emotions, less distinct or clear, because they contain all of these mean-
ings as a prereflective mass. It is, however, exactly because feeling is a constant and
pervasive factor in human existence that Heidegger called it the “basic mode” of
human being. When asked what I am experiencing, or how I am, or what I mean,
I turn to my feelings. They are the primary way I know, and may hermeneutically
inquire into, my own being-in-the-world. (A brief aside: while the question always
looms about the relationship between Heidegger’s thought and his unsavory poli-
tics, I have chosen to selectively employ his thinking throughout this book.)26
My second point of clarification is that the term symbol is meant here in a
wide sense. We are used to thinking of symbols as a special class of entities, such as
those we find in churches or dreams. By saying in the previous chapter, however,
that all of reality is symbolic I was using the word symbol in a wider-than-normal
sense. Symbol is a compound of two Greek words, “sum-ballein,” which may be
translated as “to draw or throw together.” In other words, a symbol gathers, brings
together, or calls forth a confluence of meanings that are felt when we interact
with it. The richest symbols are those with great disclosive power. It is the case,
though, that anything we meaningfully encounter may be thought of as a symbol.
In other words, whatever we experience—a dinner party, a bird in the forest,
a fantasy, a summer breeze—symbolizes that experience immediately.27 We may
then find further ways to symbolize the experience, to bring out some more of its
hidden meaning—perhaps by doing a dance about the breeze. Or we may find no
more symbols for the experience at all. Much “nature experience” is like this; we
feel much meaning in our contact with a landscape, but are at a loss for words to
describe it. The experience is ineffable, but the landscape symbolized it right on
the spot. Similarly, ordinary sense perception involves what Gendlin calls “recog-
nition feelings.” I see something familiar, say a table, and understand what it is
without having to think about it as such. Or as you gesture at me I pick up your
meaning; not through some intellectual analogy, but directly, because I am myself
a gesturing body that resonates to your actions, feels their meaning. All learning
is to an extent like this, wherein we “get” some meaning. (This comes out in the
word comprehend, the Latin prehendere meaning “seize” or “take hold.”) Learning
a new word, for example, is a matter of grasping how it is used, “much as one
imitates a gesture.”28 All of which is to say that the world we experience is always
already symbolically meaningful to us, most of the time.
My third point, finally, concerns the figure/ground structure of experi-
encing. Cézanne tells a story about wanting to paint a still life he found described
in a book. The setting includes bread rolls that appear to “crown” the napkins on
which they are sitting. Cézanne remarks, though, that it is impossible to paint
“crowned.” He must faithfully paint only the tangible details of the napkins and
rolls, and then wait for the intangible “crowned” quality to shine through the dabs
of paint.29 This illustrates the principle that, as Merleau-Ponty put it: “Meaning
is invisible.”30 The visible is “pregnant” with the invisible; while the invisible is
the “secret counterpart” of the visible, is its “inner framework”—or as we said in
chapter one, its soul. The meaning we experience is not itself tangible, but must
be symbolically mediated. The symbol is the line in the drawing, the voice in the
singing, the image in the dreaming. The sense these have, by contrast, “is always a
production of absent things.”31 In other words, what is tangibly present is always
pervaded by what is absent, by an intangible atmosphere we implicitly feel. (Intui-
tions come exactly from having a sense for this felt absence.) Or in our earlier
terms, the meaning of the figure, our interpretation of it, is itself mediated by
the felt ground. This figure/ground (theme/horizon, explicit/implicit, focus/field)
relationship is the basic structure of experience. I stress the importance of this
relation especially because, as I discuss next, the body is itself a kind of ground.
Only human beings have come to a point where they no longer know why
they exist . . . they have forgotten the secret knowledge of their bodies, their
senses, their dreams.
—John (Fire) Lame Deer32
also be a retrieval of our embodiment. This comes as no surprise, for the somato-
phobia of the Western tradition is a matter of historical record and present-day
experience. My own first deliberate efforts to become more inwardly aware of my
body were like trying to force a large balloon under the surface of a lake. Toward
the end of this section I will discuss some of the social factors that motivates us
to take such fearful flight from our bodies, so that we might better understand
this most central of issues for ecopsychology. For the discussion here, however, my
focus is principally on a positive reappraisal of the being of the body, specifically
on how it orders (organizes, commands) our experience, and on the intimate, felt
relationship that exists between body and world.
Historical prejudices against the body are by now well-known. Nietzsche
wrote of how Western thinkers before him “despised the body: they left it out
of the account: more, they treated it as an enemy.”34 Plato dumped the body for
suprasensuous Ideas. Later, the erotic body was seen as the Devil itself, the very
site of corruption. During the witch trials, the witch “had her sensualism burned
out of her.”35 The body, in general, was resented and feared because it linked us to
a fallen, beastly nature; imprisoned us in flesh. The Cartesian mechanizing of the
body and disembodying of the soul can in retrospect be understood as an attempt
to resolve this terrible dilemma. Today, the dominant model of the body is still
a scientific one: a physiological system with no significant relations to the world;
a material container for the mind (the latter of which can potentially be made
immortal, some claim, by being “downloaded” into machines);36 a corpse even.37
The history of our abandonment of the body has perhaps reached its extreme
in the appearance of what Robert Romanyshyn describes, in a frankly upsetting
essay, as two complementary bodies: that of the astronaut, the “masculine spirit
taking leave of a despoiled earth,” and that of the anorexic, “the dying, starving
body, the discarded feminine, left behind.”38
From out of this disturbing history our task is to reclaim a body that walks
on, and is nourished by, the living earth. Given that we are making of this a
psychological exercise, it makes sense to begin with Freud. The part of our per-
sonality that corresponds to nature Freud called the “id” (better translated from
the German “es” as “it”). Of the id, he wrote: “we call it a chaos, a cauldron full of
seething excitations. . . . It is filled with energy reaching it from the instincts, but it
has no organization, produces no collective will, but only a striving to bring about
the satisfaction of instinctual needs.”39 Freud thus feared that unless we repress
our instinctual id-body it will, as Alan Watts wryly put it, “turn out to be a wild
animal rutting and snarling in the squalor of its own excrement.”40 Civilization
may be a mess, but without it what “would then remain would be a state of nature,
and that would be far harder to bear.”41 Freud’s opinion is consistent with a long
tradition that equates our nature with irrational tendencies that must be either
controlled or broken.42 Indeed, by the time of the Age of Reason it was our very
animality that was considered to be at the root of madness; the insane person was
robbed of humanity and thereby returned to a chaotic, autistic, animal state, the
“zero degree of his own nature.”43
A model of nature that identifies it with madness obviously makes a poor,
if not ironic, starting place for ecopsychology. Indeed, a great deal turns on this
point. For if our nature is chaotic then our experience has no intrinsic order. The
id, said Freud, is asocial.44 The part of us that deals with reality, the ego, is thus
wholly a product of whatever order a society imposes on top of, or molds out of,
our unruly id-nature. The assumption here, that the precivil body has no organiza-
tion of its own, that rational order must be pressed on it, is however a bias that not
all accept.45 Specifically, I believe that a better interpretation of human nature—
one more phenomenologically true—is to be found within the general camp of
humanistic psychology. What Freud did not recognize, humanistic psychologists
say, is the ongoing creativity of the human organism, its inherent wisdom, its
holistic knowing, its self-organization. This organism, then, is not to be confused
with the literal, material body of natural science, nor the Freudian body of chaotic
drives, but understood as an intelligent body which has a precisely attuned inten-
tional relationship with the “external” world, as we experience it from within.
That the body is self-organizing is obvious in the experience of hunger. For
hunger is the physical implying of feeding; it is a feeling that points to, intends,
calls for, or means eating. Eating, in turn, symbolizes and resolves the hunger.
Similarly, when feeling dull-headed in a stuffy room our bodies are telling us to go
outside for some air. Such cases of meaningful somatic direction, although quite
simple, are no different in principle from instances of more complex living. In
general, that is, our bodies are always sensing our whole life-situation and urging
us toward the next action that will, as Gendlin phrases it, carry our lives forward.
Every feeling is a holistic implying, a steering of our lives in some direction, a stir-
ring of the life force toward the unfolding of our existence, often in unpredictable
ways. The body is thus more truly a finely ordered living responsiveness, always
seeking some sort of symbolic completion for its needs or intentions, whether
the “hunger” be physical, social, emotional, developmental, intellectual, sexual,
spiritual, aesthetic, or whatever.
Gendlin has developed an experiential practice called “focusing” which
works with this natural ordering or demanding of the body, and illustrates it well.
(I should add, however, that it is only one possible mode of experiencing or felt
interacting—an inward directed conversation with “ourselves” that Gendlin calls
“self-responding.”) In the process of “focusing,” we turn our attention to our
bodies in order to get a single, diffuse feel for the whole mass of meanings that
are implicitly functioning in relation to some situation in our lives, the ground
of our experience. By attending to this feeling, by listening for the direction that
is coming from our bodies, we may then come to live more awarely. As Gendlin
says: “Your body enacts your situations and constitutes them largely before you
can think how. When your attention joins this living, you can pursue many more
possibilities and choices than when you merely drive your body as if it were a
machine like the car.”46 I invite you, the reader, to now let me lead you through
an exercise in such “joining” with your own bodily living.47
In one sense, there is nothing special about focusing. It is simply a more delib-
erate way of letting our bodies guide us than is our normal custom. On the other hand,
most people are so unused to working in this way that it can be difficult, strange, or
even scary at first. To learn focusing, therefore, people generally need to have someone
teach it to them over a number of get togethers. (It is the more rare, bodily attuned
person who catches on straightaway, already being a “natural” focuser.) With these
comments in mind, the point of the following exercise is not so much to teach you to
focus, but only to give you a rudimentary sense of what it involves. I suggest you under-
take it only if, after having read through the instructions, it feels right to do so. If you
do not feel comfortable about doing the exercise, however, you might choose to notice
what that feeling is like.
The first part of the exercise is only to explicitly experience a “felt sense” or
feeling. Focusing works best if you are relaxed and undistracted, yet not so relaxed that
you cannot sense your physical body. Begin by bringing your attention into the center of
your body, to the zone that includes your throat, chest, stomach, and abdomen, Just pay
attention, in a curious way, to whatever you notice there: your breathing, some tense
spots, a warm sensation, whatever. A felt sense is a murky, unclear, subtle feeling about
some aspect of your life that forms in this sensitive zone of your body. It is physically
felt, but is also more than just a sensation, being meaningful in some way. You may in
fact already have a felt sense about something going on in your life: some quarrel with a
friend, event you are planning, issue you are concerned about. Or, as is not uncommon,
you may not feel much at all.
As a way to now deliberately engender a specific felt sense, pick two people in
your life, one of whom you get along with well, the other not so well. With your atten-
tion still in your body, imagine that the second person enters the room—and notice any
felt difference this makes. You might now feel some “butterflies” in your belly or tension
in your throat. Whatever your response, stay with the implicitly complex, globally felt
quality this person calls forth in your body: this is your experiencing of the person, your
feeling of what she or he means to you. Now imagine this person leaving; notice again
whether this brings any change in your body; and then bring the other person into the
room. How does this person feel to you? You may sense some easing of tension; some
warm, happy feelings perhaps. Again, the exercise is only to notice your experience—
what you feel in this interaction.
Once you have a hold on a felt sense, the process of focusing involves “sitting”
with this feeling. When making direct reference to a felt sense we are sensing much
more than what we already consciously know: those innumerable facets of background
meaning we have yet to put into words or move into some other kind of symbolization.
For either of the two people you chose to get a sense of, then, you might inquire into this
deeper knowing. Open ended questions are best. What is this feeling all about? What
is so terrible/wonderful about this person? What does this feeling need from me? What
action would help it? The important thing is that you direct these questions toward,
and let any answers come from, the bodily felt sense, not your head. You may suddenly
realize who the person reminds you of, or what you appreciate about her or him, or
what you need to say to her or him. Such moments of awareness are signaled by a felt
shift in the body, a relaxing or resolving of the feeling, which signals a disclosure of
meaning, a moment of forward living. These shifts are the body’s way of saying “Yes,
that feels right’’ to whatever came. You may not have experienced such a shift here—
which because I am talking to you from this page and not in person is even more likely
than is usually the case. You may, however, be able to recall a time when some insight
just “came” to you that felt right—which is the same thing.
Following this excursion into the felt body, I wish to touch on several points
that the practice of focusing brings out.
First of all, many people are surprised to discover on learning to focus that
their feelings are so intricate, that they mean something, that their bodies are
ordered to spontaneously carry their lives forward (as just described in the above
exercise). Focusing is a deliberate way of “dipping down” into that bodily felt place
whence life-forwarding steps of change may come, where our organismic wisdom
resides. Even without being a “focuser,” however, most people can recall being in
some situation that “just didn’t feel right,” or by contrast that “just felt right.” This
feeling of rightness is an important touchstone for anyone who works experien-
tially. As Gendlin notes: “Every bad feeling is potential energy toward a more right
way of being if you give it space to move toward its rightness. The very existence
of bad feelings within you is evidence that your body knows what is wrong and
what is right.”48 Hence: “The life process in us has its own direction and this is not
relative.”49 In other words, the life process has a certain autonomy.
We cannot impose whatever meaning we like on our experience, some story
we want to have as our own, for then we could be just whatever we choose. This is
why being authentic, being what we are, is not simply a matter of nonconformity,
but also of bringing ourselves before our experience and pursuing only those
possibilities that arise from this felt starting place, the ones that are genuinely
“ours.” Similarly, we do not become free of our life difficulties by wishing them
away, but often must complete very precise, sensitive, and difficult experiential
steps that satisfy what our bodies are calling for. The felt sense, in other words,
adjudicates our responses to it. Feelings cannot be fooled or bypassed; they shift
only when rightly symbolized. When an expression is on the tip of our tongue,
our felt sense will keep rejecting the phrases we “try on” until the right words at
last appear and bring us that wonderful sigh of relief or outflow of energy. This
example also shows that our bodies understand language. While language use is
in important respects different from a behavior such as eating, it is also the same
inasmuch as they both carry life forward. Thus, the conversation or book that is
boring or senseless is the one that does nothing for our lives. By contrast, when
such as meeting the eyes of a raccoon. It does not follow, however, that language
is not implicit in these experiences. For no matter the situation, we simply could
not understand the world as we do without all those background meanings that
have been formed in words. I have come to make sense of the world through a
history with language that leads all the way up to that wild encounter with the
raccoon. On the other hand, our experience is also thicker, more “intricate,” than
any words, concepts, theories, or existing forms; these do not, in other words,
wholly encompass our experience.59 With the raccoon, I am drawn into a unique
event of contact. The meaning disclosed in that moment is not only a matter of
prior social learning, but also of how available I am to the claim of the raccoon’s
otherness. The raccoon, too, is a symbol or form capable of stirring up feelings in
me—as am I for her or him.
I am dwelling on the topic of language because it is so crucial for ecopsy-
chology. Without an extralinguistic space within our experiencing, without an
opening beyond our previous symbolizations, the meanings we find in relation
to nature can never be other than what our existing language-forms already say.
When a person like John Livingston remarks that his feelings “cannot be force-
fitted into convenient categories of common . . . experience,”60 he is communi-
cating that he feels something more or other than what these existing categories
mean, even if a better language has yet to arrive. The latter may well come, how-
ever, if we are able to locate what Merleau-Ponty referred to as that “primordial
silence” or “mute presence” which exists “beneath the chatter of words”61—the
Gendlin-ian bodily felt sense from which original intentions and creative expres-
sions arise. Conversely, to “tell people that any saying must inevitably fail, that it
cannot help but fall into the old dead forms, is just another mode of silencing that
[which] in them . . . needs to speak.”62
A final point that the practice of focusing demonstrates is the unity of
body and world. “In the body,” says Hans Jonas, “the knot of being is tied which
dualism does not unravel but cut[s].”63 The body is the site of intersection of
inside and outside, self and world; it belongs to both realms and mediates their
relations. As I noted above, the felt sense has “a life of its own.” It is precisely
via our bodies’ implicit dialogue with the world, gathered in the felt sense, that
we feel the quality of our relationships with others, orient ourselves, and take
the actions we do. We sense our situations, say a social function, as a global
flavor, texture, energy, or mood. This felt sense is our tacit bodily grasp of what
is going on, what is relevant, what might happen, and so on. Most of the time
we just have our feelings “in-action” as they implicitly govern our lives, without
paying much attention to them. If I walk into a room and my stomach lurches,
however, I must consult my bodily felt sense if I am ever to discover what I am
so scared about and what course of action might be the right one. Without
doing so, I will just cringe in the corner, unaware of what the situation really
means to me.
Whether I focus this feeling or not, it is not just an inner event, but a pre-
reflective sensing of my whole “outer” situation as I feel it from the “inside.” The
felt sense is thus a bodily knowing of how I am in-the-world that is prior to any
cleavage between inside and out (which are only metaphors for zones of aware-
ness or aspects of reality).64 In the language of Gestalt therapy, our “feelings are
not isolated impulses but structured evidence of reality, namely of the interaction
of the organism/environment field, for which there is no other direct evidence
except feeling.”65 Recall from chapter one that it is of our cultural pathology to
interiorize experience. The idea of an “organism/environment field” is meant to
suggest instead the intimacy or inseparability of the body-world relation—as in
the inhaling and exhaling of air. Our bodily felt intentions (as Merleau-Ponty
wrote) are the threads that connect us to the world. Assigning intentionality to the
body itself thus incarnates and enworlds the mind, so that it is no longer tucked
away up in the skull.66 Hence, body and world are originally together, and are only
isolated—turned into cadaver and object—in an act of reflective abstraction. As
we live them, in short, what differentiates body and world “is not a frontier, but
a contact surface.”67
The unfolding of our lives is not just the flowering of some inner potential—as if
the only role of the outer world were to water our seed—but a process of interact-
ing with others in which we seek the best fit we can between our bodily intentions,
needs, or desires and what our environments have to offer. As Medard Boss
remarks, we are “at any given time nothing but in and as this or that perceiving,
instinctual, impulsive, emotional, imaginative, dreaming, thinking, acting, will-
ing, or wishing relationship toward the things which [we] encounter.”69 In my
relationships with others I invent and discover the meanings by which I both
grow and adjust to the world in which I find myself. Aside from this interacting,
there is no “me.” Contact, then, denotes the activity of ex-change, transaction,
meeting, fusion-across-difference, transmission, encounter, or engagement with
the world—without which no life or experiencing would be possible.
Contact is the opposite of in-difference. It is our being changed by inter-
acting with that which is different. The word “contact” therefore applies princi-
pally to those events in which we come in touch with the world and acquire a new
meaning—when the ground of our existence is altered (if only a little). We may be
affected by others on an implicit level, but only when we symbolize how we have
been touched—perhaps by realizing years later how somebody cared for us, and
how much that meant to us—do we make explicit contact with this touch. Reality
is most fully given or revealed under ongoing conditions of good, organismically
satisfying contact; while we suffer a diminished and decaying reality under condi-
tions of weakened or distorted contact. Contact is itself one of the great mysteries
of the universe, as the variety of metaphors used to describe it suggests. In what
follows, I discuss a number of these metaphors, each of which has its own merits
and limitations.
The first metaphor is that of dialogue (conversation, verbal interaction). This
metaphor acknowledges the power of language (even if, primordially considered,
not all language need be verbal); it indicates the very real importance of having an
expressive “voice” for the making of contact. It also suggests the back-and-forth or
dialectical motion wherein we feel our impact on one another as we are “played”
by the subject matter of our dialogue. Dialogue does not, however, consist only of
words bumping into each other. Good contact insists that my words be truthful.
For example, when I recently told my wife, Jill, that “our marriage bond feels a bit
wobbly of late,” it named something we had both been sensing and opened up an
exchange of feelings which then deepened our bond. My bodily felt sense implied
some sort of contact, the saying of some words that belonged to the situation we
shared, that would restructure or carry forward our lives together. Where life lacks
contactful communication such as this it becomes overly routine, dull, and thin.
The second metaphor for contact is that of touching. Indeed, tactility inheres
in the very word con-tact: touching together, touch-touching. We talk of “being
touched” by someone or “getting in touch” with some part of ourselves. A pure,
disembodied consciousness could never experience anything because it is not
capable of touching and being touched, has no flesh. Contacting always occurs at
a boundary, in this metaphor the skin surface. Our skin, as Gestaltists observe, is
less a part of ourselves than it is an “organ” of the relationship between organism
and environment, delimiting (containing and protecting) the former and joining
it to the latter.70 It binds the organism both from and to the environment. Touch
is the paradigm for contact because it is a “close” sense, as opposed to “distant”
ones such as seeing or hearing, which more easily become bodiless or remote. In
the act of being touched we are vulnerable. As a metaphor for contact, touching
thus suggests the danger or peril that resides in the middle of ex-per-ience.71 Every
contacting is to some extent a risk, for it involves being changed and its outcome
is never quite certain. We are, accordingly, always balancing the need to grow and
change with the need to resist the intentions of others and maintain or conserve
our existing ground. In a hostile or unnourishing situation, the latter need takes
precedence; whereas in a friendly and giving one it is the former. I discuss this
topic below, so will only note here a major psychological issue of our time: that
for many people today the peril of contact feels too great, the fear of touching one
another too large, for them to take “the reasonable risks which are part and parcel
of growing and living.”72
Eating metaphors, next, pervade discussions of experience. Hunger, appetite,
tasting, chewing, swallowing, vomiting, digesting, assimilating, eliminating—all
apply to how we relate to the “material” or “food” of our experience. We speak of
“soul food” and “toxic” experiences. The cyclical nature of hunger/eating makes it
a good model for the whole organismic rhythm of experiencing, as will come out
in the discussion of the final metaphor below, that is, a cycle or wave. Here I want
to focus on how the eating metaphor is a particularly apt one for ecopsychology—
for it connects experience to food: to plants and animals. As Paul Shepard remarks:
“Being human has always meant perceiving ourselves in a circle of animals. The
crucial event in this encounter has been ingestion. We have attended passionately
to this consuming force until the idea of assimilation has permeated the nature
of experience itself.”73 Gordon Wheeler criticizes the food metaphor—at least as
it was developed by the founder of Gestalt therapy, Fritz Perls—arguing that it
turns others into mere objects of oral aggression.74 I think it better, however, to
recognize that if we are to live, we have no choice but to eat others. As Perls himself
noted, it “is as impossible to feed off oneself psychologically as it is to feed off one-
self physically.”75 The real issue, then, is what kind of attitude we take toward our
food. A Cheyenne Indian saying—“let us all be meat, to nourish one another, that
we may grow”76—indicates how, rather than seeing the world only in its object-
being, it is possible to see the animals and plants we put on our table as kin, and to
therefore adopt a fiercely moral, celebratory, and nonviolent attitude toward our
food.77 With factory farms, supermarkets, and fast food, there is of course little of
this left, and it becomes progressively harder to sense that eating might be a form
of nature communion.
A last group of metaphors—a cycle, wave, or behavioral sequence—
characterizes the whole process by which an experience begins in a feeling, excit-
edly builds toward symbolic completion or resolution, and dissolves back into the
ground of our ongoing experiencing. In addition to hunger, the sexual cycle is
often used as a model for this, illustrating as it does how an experience moves from
an awareness of felt need through the orderly stages of rising excitement, taking
action to satisfy or extinguish the need (orgasm), and integrating and withdrawing
from the experience. Each such experiential cycle, passing through a sequence
of phases or behaviors in self-organizing waves, forms an experiential whole or
gestalt, which is the basic unit of experience. Depending on the experience, these
cycles can last anywhere from a brief instant to the whole of one’s life (one’s life-
gestalt). The movement through waves of experience—and through waves within
waves—is the rhythm of life itself. Every cycle of experience is a step of living. I
therefore want to describe the different phases of these cycles in some detail, as we
move through them in complete or undistorted experiences.
Mobilization Satisfaction/Assimiliation
Awareness Withdrawal
Feeling
this phase is how the primary orientation of our lives is outward, toward the world.
The “ex” of the words we use to describe our living marks this point: ex-perience,
ex-istence, ex-pression, e-motion (ex-movere). In Boss’s words, we body-forth our
existence. We bodily reach toward the contacts or relationships that will complete
our felt meanings (prefigurations, anticipations, expectations, purposes, aims,
desires, needs, intentions) and thus carry our lives forward. I live through my
body, not as an object inside of which I am stuck, but as a power for inhabiting
and disclosing a world, for engaging in the “forward-looking, problem-solving,
meaning-making activity”80 of working out the best resolution possible between
my needs, urges, dreams, hopes, and so on, and the actual conditions of my life,
with all of its contingencies, limitations, and dangers. Action-taking, moreover,
is necessarily aggressive, in the sense that it requires the taking of initiative. As
its etymology suggests, aggression is simply the “stepping toward” whatever is
needed or else in the way of our lives (whether frustrating or threatening). In its
nonmalignant form, aggression is thus not an evil but an essential aspect of any
vital existence. Without it we would never engage the world or get on in life; we
would lack any assertiveness, inquisitiveness, critical ability, self-confidence, or
creativity.81 (Pathological aggression, as I discuss below, derives from the frustration
of this intrinsic aggression, which then turns hateful and violent.82) It is the action
phase, finally, that most involves our free will. In it we make choices about what
kind of contact we will actually pursue and how we might get there.
Final contact, to use a biological metaphor, is the exchanging of material
across an osmotic membrane. To make good contact we must relax our boundaries
enough to allow something new “in” (eat the food) but not so much as to lose our
integrity.83 Thus do we surrender into an orgasm, dissolve into our grief, acquire
a skill, learn something, flow into an expressive movement, recognize ourselves in
another, receive some message, let some reality come home. In final contact our
experience takes meaningful form, our need is met, our question answered, our
tension released. This is the phase where we feel a shift in or restructuring of our
ground, where our experience comes to a symbolic point, where we are changed.
We may experience an “aha!” when a gestalt coheres vividly, but most contact
occurs more subtly, in everyday ways.
The postcontact phase of the cycle is satisfaction-assimilation, wherein we
enjoy an “afterglow” and “digest” the meaning of our experience. The meaning-
fulness of an event is a matter of whether and in what respects it carries our lives
forward or satisfies our bodily demands.84 (Hence, Perls’s simple formula that “the
meaning of life is that it is to be lived.”85) It is exactly this understanding that
overcomes the Freudian dualism between natural organismic force and human
meaning. For the organism itself seeks meaning, and it is our own most impor-
tant business in life to identify with this organism and find completion for its
intentions (overcoming dualism, recall, means giving mind back to nature). Every
completed gestalt is a finished meaning, which is then integrated into our ongoing
The psychotherapist Carl Rogers said that one of the qualities of mature persons
is that they are willing to be a process.86 Gestaltists similarly say that what we call
the ‘self ’ is simply the experiential cycle in motion, the contact process itself (the
functioning of the boundary in the organism/environment field). Or as Gendlin
puts it: “We are our felt experiencing.” We only know ourselves (are ourselves) in
our movements in and out of interaction with the world. I want to close, then,
with an exercise in noticing just this.
As with the previous exercise, the most important thing in this one is simply to
notice what you are experiencing (even if it is only your resisting of my suggestions).
The purpose of the exercise is for you to “try on” my description of the cycle of experi-
ence by attending to how you are experiencing this chapter. Recall the phases of this
cycle: feeling, awareness, mobilization, action, final contact, satisfaction/assimilation,
withdrawal. Now pay attention to what you are sensing in your body, and ask yourself
what you are aware of. Is this chapter holding your interest (is it appetizing) or is there
something else you need or want to be doing? How actively or energetically are you
engaging it? Do you drift off? What sort of contact are you making with it? Do you
feel touched in any way? Does it seem relevant or meaningful to you? Do you feel any
satisfaction? Do you pause to chew on and digest some piece of what I am saying? What
do you find objectionable, that is, what do you not want to take in? Do you withdraw
from the text when you have had enough? In short: How is this chapter interacting with
your living? What kind of experience are you having?
“Psychopathology” refers to the suffering (pathos) of the soul, and to the kind
of voice (logos) we allow it. That suffering is part of the human condition is
contained in the First Noble Truth of Buddhism, and is an obvious enough fact
to anyone who reflects on the matter. Suffering, in other words, seems intrinsic
to experiencing itself. To be experienced, it is said, is to have suffered through; to
have had the vessel of one’s self repeatedly broken and reformed over countless
experiences. To change is to suffer a change. Gadamer, for instance, says that every
“experience worthy of the name thwarts an expectation,”88 is some kind of nega-
tion. Otherwise we just remain the same old person we already are, with our same
old understanding of things. I believe, however, that he is partly wrong in this—
and for telling reasons. He is right inasmuch as he has identified those experiences
that force us to relinquish the security of our former beliefs or ways, disturb the
sedimented meanings to which we have grown attached, or touch us with some
painful truth. We will never grow or learn unless we are open to such experiences.
But he is wrong not to further identify in what way experiences also fulfill our
expectations. Our interactions do not just displace old meanings, but may also
satisfy prefigured ones. Here, again, a lack of appreciation of the organismic nature
of experiencing has lead to a misconception. In Gadamer’s view, for an event to
count as a genuine experience we must not expect it, we must be surprised and
disillusioned by it.89 What I have been suggesting in this chapter instead is that
our bodily felt needs are precisely the expectations or intentions that reach toward
the world to be specified and completed, so that our lives may both continue and
unfold. A child finding all kinds of new things in a pond is hardly a convincing
image of suffering. The theme I pursue under this heading, in fact, is that of how
much unnecessary suffering is engendered exactly from the violent disregard of our
inherent expectations (which are wrongfully thwarted) and in the struggle to get
these life needs met.
The line I wish to develop is as follows. I am persuaded (by the Buddha
and my own experience) that suffering is indigenous to an Egoic mode of exist-
ence (the capital E differentiating a pathological sense of Ego from a basic sense
of ego, the latter simply being the agent of the organism). As I discuss in the next
chapter, the Ego isolates itself from the ground of being, attempts to exist for
itself outside the flux of life, to become a permanent island in the swirling ocean
of nature—and suffers from the impossibility of the project. While the tendency
toward this suffering mode is given in the human situation, the attitude a society
adopts toward it is not. A society, that is, can develop ways to understand, find
meaning in, minimize, and move through suffering; or—at the other end of the
spectrum—it can choose to mystify, institutionalize, exacerbate, and exploit it.
I put our own society in the latter camp. (The emergence of a “socially engaged”
Buddhism indicates a recognition of this social factor.) In the account I offer
below, then, I discuss our suffering specifically as it originates in social antagonism
toward the life process. According to the view of this chapter, that is, pathology
is generated in the hurtful conflict between the demands of our own nature and
those of the life-denying and life-threatening social forces we encounter in the
world—as well as in the subsequent chronic interrupting of our own life processes
that we ourselves perform as a means of survival.90 Ego grows, in fact, precisely in
response to hostile conditions, as a defensive structure that aims “to obtain love by
way of mastery in an unloving world.”91 While this may not yet be an adequate
account of the deeper spiritual nature of our suffering, it is nonetheless congruent
with one. For any route out of suffering will surely point the way back into life.
And any ecopsychology must surely do the same.
I have chosen five features of psychopathology specifically for how they
illustrate the relationship between suffering and the life process. Given the grossly
pathological state of our normalcy,92 I presume that readers will to at least some
extent recognize themselves in my discussion of them. My aim is to introduce
an interpretation of psychopathological phenomena that will serve the needs of
the rest of the book (even if it is by no means a complete account of these phe-
nomena). I need say that although the material to be covered here is not pleasant,
I do not want an immobilizing heaviness to descend on the discussion. Please bear
in mind, then, that I am venturing into these challenging places only because we
are already in them, and because we find more satisfying life options only to the
extent that we are willing to recognize this.
their children in a misguided attempt to gratify their own unmet, and so now
“frozen,” childhood needs. We are also widely hurt via social oppression—the sys-
tematic mistreatment of particular groups or communities. Racism, classism, and
sexism are the most recognized of these institutionalized abuses, although people
are discriminated against on an astonishing variety of bases. While it would be
possible to elaborate ad nauseum the manifold ways in which we hurt one another
in this society, my aim at this stage is only to introduce the idea of these violations
and to make mention that they themselves can all be understood as instances of
“naturism”: the global mistreatment of nature by our society.96
Good contacting occurs at an optimal experiential “distance.” Hurtful
contacts, by contrast, are either “too close” (dangerous, invasive) or “too distant”
(neglectful, absent). In other words, in situations antagonistic to our living, our
boundaries are either overwhelmed through direct intrusion or become unbear-
ably tense through starvation (or both).97 In such a setting, to openly express (or
even know) our needs or make life-forwarding contact with others becomes dif-
ficult, anxiety-filled, or unsafe. The creative adjustments we are then motivated to
adopt take the form of coping strategies that both distort our contact with others
and block our own life urges. A person, for example, may develop very subtle and
ingenious ways to manipulate others as a way to maintain some sense of control
in an otherwise chaotic or ungiving situation. Or a person who has learned to fear
open, face-to-face love, may adjust by becoming a fetishist who contacts others
via, say, their shoes, thereby preserving an experience of intimacy. Despite that
they are our best efforts at living, these kinds of creative strategies are nonetheless
all interruptions of our full experiencing, such that much of our common experi-
ence is incomplete, distorted, or deficient in satisfaction.
In order to further demonstrate this last point, I want to consider the gen-
eral creative adjustment known as desensitization. All self-interruptions can be
located somewhere along the experiential cycle (for our living consists precisely
of this cycle). Desensitization occurs at the beginning. It is the manipulating of
ourselves (e.g., tightening the surficial muscles of our bodies) in such a way that
we lose bodily feeling and blot out our perception of a hurtful world. When, for
instance, we feel unloved as a child or that our caregivers are rejecting our needs,
our bodies become a source of terrible pain and anxiety. We then adjust exactly
by renouncing these needs and fleeing our bodies—abandoning reality in order
to survive. Such desensitization reaches the point of “depersonalization” when it
penetrates to our very sense of self, and “derealization” when our felt disconnec-
tion from the world or divorce from reality becomes severe—two linked dissocia-
tive phenomena routinely experienced by trauma survivors.98 Desensitization is,
however, only one of many possible ways to habitually interrupt our experience,
as will become clear in my further discussions.
Self-interrupting creative adjustments have one further aspect worth noting.
When met with abuse or neglect children simply cannot understand it because it
so contradicts their inborn expectation that they will be lovingly welcomed, held,
comforted, and attended to; it betrays an ancient pact that their caregivers will
nurture their growth. That is why it is so painful. The child, however, has to
make sense somehow. Why am I being punished and prevented from crying and
screaming? At an early age, the reality that our caregivers might not love us is too
painful and incomprehensible to let in. The meaning that children almost invari-
ably make out of their abuse is therefore that they must be bad, inadequate, wrong,
useless, unimportant, and so on for others to be so mistreating them. Their crea-
tive adjustment is to blame themselves. That children do this again and again
shows that we will do almost anything to preserve our relationships with others,
so central is our need for them. (Victims, in general, often identify with and find
ways to love those who perpetrate violence against them.) We create whatever
meanings we need in order to carry on.
Summarizing this unhappy discussion, R. D. Laing once said that only
by “the most outrageous violation of ourselves have we achieved our capacity to
live in relative adjustment to a civilization driven to its own destruction.”99 The
squashing of our own vitality, the distorting of our contact with the world, and the
adopting of a pained meaning system are our general solutions for adjusting to a
soul-punishing environment, to the “chronic low grade emergency”100 of modern
life. These are the strategies, said Laing, by which we destroy our experience.
Fear-Laden Rigidity: The Frozen Ground. The vision of a vital existence within an
experiential framework is that of persons who move flexibly and awarely from
experience to experience, making satisfying contact with the world, responding
openly and creatively to new life situations. Their figure-ground relationship is
elastic and reversible, such that they experience their lives hermeneutically: as a
forward moving dialectic between symbols and felt meaning, forever changing
their understanding of things as they continually enrich the basis of their experi-
encing. In a pathogenic environment, however, this original mode of experiencing
must be sacrificed because it is too dangerous a way to live. If our world is not a
place in which our trust and faith can flourish, then the need for security and con-
trol wins out over the need for open contact and growth. Our adjustments then
include finding patterns of living that seem to work best, all things considered,
and sticking to them for the relative safety or comfort they provide. We stop being
a process and instead “take refuge in stasis,”101 insist on a familiar world, cling to
the status quo. The fear is that to change or step out of our habitual patterns will
only stir up distress we would rather not feel or else make matters worse. From a
ground of hurtful experience we imagine that the same injuries we experienced
in the past will be repeated in the future (even if we sense these only as a gen-
eral dread or aversion), and interpret the world in this unchanging light. Thus
does Konrad Stettbacher call suffering “the fear-laden, painful anticipation of the
past”102 and do Gestaltists call neurosis a “fixation on the unchanging past.”103
To the extent that we live in these fear-based patterns, our lives become
rigid, each pattern corresponding to a frozen ground or unchanging horizon
of experiencing. In those areas of our lives where we are so-patterned we are
not really experiencing because we are just repeating the same old stereotyped
routines based on past experiences. Our feelings do not change because we have
made them unavailable for interaction, bound them off in a background that is
not modified, because not contacted, by present situations. That is, our inac-
cessible feelings are not actively functioning in a life process; all we have instead
are the symbolic patterns we keep enacting. When our experiencing is rigidly
symbolized or “structure-bound” in this way we do not freshly interpret our situa-
tions, but keep having the same old automatic meanings—the same old thoughts,
emotions, reactions, behaviors, and so on—over and over again. As Gendlin
says, we perceive only a “bare outline” of the present. Famously, for example, we
react to people just as we did to our parents, seeing only authority figures rather
than unique persons, and remaining in patterns of submission, anger, panic, or
whatever our particular obsolete responses may be. As this also shows, each such
pattern contains within itself the “unfinished business” that led us to adopt it in
the first place.
Psychopathology, then, tends toward a constricted, unfree, contact-impov-
erished existence. In pathology, the symbolic moment of experiencing dominates,
that is, our lives become feelingless and formulaic—the form or shape of our
existence becomes fixed. (To repeat, a feelingless life is not necessarily one lacking
in strong emotion. What is frozen, rather, is the underlying, subtle, bodily felt
sentience needed to understand and shift—rather than stay stuck in—these emo-
tions.) Any life will involve making contact with the world in routine, day-to-
day ways, wherein we ride our already-acquired structures or habits. The more
severe our pathology, however, the more do these routines become all. When our
very survival seems at stake, making contact with that which is novel or different
(i.e., contact in the principle sense) becomes rare or alarming. We are resistant to
change because who we are, our interpretation of the world, is fearfully “locked
in” on a feeling level to which we have little conscious access.
Because pathology involves a restricted ground of available feeling and a
limited contact style it also involves a loss of self. The self exists to the extent that
we respond to and maintain our own process of felt interaction with the world.
Where our lives are frozen this process of experiencing is missing—and thus so are
we. We feel alien to ourselves, disorganized, out of it; the center does not hold.104
Some degree of depersonalization or soul loss is therefore a component of all suf-
fering. In “psychosis” the functioning of feeling is so distant and interaction so
curtailed that the contents of experience are overwhelmingly alien: hallucinated
voices, foreign invasions, and so on. Psychic disturbance, then, is a narrowing of
our manner of experiencing, a constricting of our openness. In depression, for
example, our sense of temporality shrinks to a meaningless present: the past does
not nourish, the future does not invite. Our spatial world, meanwhile, narrows
down to the chair we are sitting in and the wall we are staring at. Our contact is
constricted and distorted in such a way that the world may reveal itself as only
so many disapproving faces, critical voices, and other confirmations of our own
worthlessness.
Alienation From and Conflict With Our Organismic Self. One of the main con-
sequences of adjusting to environments that are at odds with our nature is that
we come to live according to certain meanings—beliefs, concepts, rules, moral
injunctions—that replace our own organismic, implicitly felt meanings. Rather
than our bodily felt intentions we follow “introjected” social conventions. As Carl
Rogers understood this, the “experiencing organism senses one meaning in experi-
ence, but the conscious self clings rigidly to another, since that is the way it has
found love and acceptance from others.”105 The feeling of being unloved, as I
noted above, is unbearably anxiety-provoking, leaving us all alone in the cosmic
void. We thus agree to obey or adopt meanings opposed to our organismic self—
what Rogers called “conditions of worth”—as a way to minimize any threatening
difference between ourselves and others and so to secure some measure of love and
social belonging. Men, for example, are often alienated from their experience at
such an early age that they are guided almost wholly by introjected beliefs about
masculinity, duty, responsibility, and so on. Or as Alice Miller notes: “The more
successfully a person was denied access to his or her feelings in childhood, the
larger the arsenal of intellectual weapons and supply of moral prostheses has to be,
because morality and a sense of duty are not sources of strength or fruitful soil for
affection. Blood does not flow in artificial limbs.”106 The result of such bloodless
living is that “consciously we are moving one way, while organismically we are
moving in another.”107
What characterizes the process of introjection, in general, is the taking “in”
of experiences or meanings without having yet made adequate contact with them.
We take on another’s values, ideas, or modes of being without going through the
sequence of chewing on these, assimilating those aspects that feel organismically
right (in that moment), and then spitting out the rest.108 This happens in abusive
situations when our boundaries are violated and the abuser gets right “inside” us.
So long as the traumatic experience is unfinished we are then haunted by the inter-
nalized presence of the abusive other. The meanings we adopt in abuse are thus
imposed, forced in; they do not come from a life-forwarding process, but an over-
whelming one. As Perls et al. write of childhood introjection: “Whatever the child
gets from his loving parents he assimilates, for it is fitting and appropriate to his
own needs as he grows. It is the hateful parents who have to be introjected, taken
down whole, although they are contrary to the needs of the organism. Accompa-
nying this is the starving of the child’s proper needs and his repressing of rebellion
and disgust.”109
As this last line indicates, alienation from our organismic self also means
being in active conflict with it. The part of the personality most opposed to organ-
ismic life is what Freud called the “superego” and what is popularly called the
“inner critic.” It is generated in a complex way, from our introjected “bad par-
ents,” from negative beliefs about ourselves we have inferred from our environ-
ment, and from aggression (hatred) we have repressed or disowned. It takes the
form of a hostile and critical voice that haunts us, squashes us, comes at us (and
yet which is “ours”), usually operating outside of explicit awareness. It is con-
stantly telling us how we are screwing things up, how we are bad, and what we
should be doing. Under the influence of the superego, we go to war with ourselves,
diverting our energy away from the process of growing, bending it back so as to
“jail” our rejected bodily impulses. Our own genuine needing or wanting then
becomes a source of anxiety, as we squeeze ourselves against our own spontaneous
bodily urges out of the terror that to really express ourselves or make any demands
on the world will lead only to further rejection and loss of love. We live not for
ourselves, but for the pseudolove of others; and then become increasingly guilty
both under the admonitions of our superegos and out of indebtedness to our own
unlived existence. The words of Ellen West, one of existential psychiatry’s most
famous cases, and who was later to commit suicide, portray vividly the nature of
these dynamic inner conflicts: “I feel myself, quite passively, the stage on which
two hostile forces are mangling each other.”110
The price we pay for alienating ourselves from the life of our own bodies is
great. First of all, we lose the vitality, spontaneity, and creativity that comes only
from being in touch with our organismic being. Our actions become repetitive,
feelingless, unconnected to organismic need. Like Ellen West’s, our lives become—
as Perls called it—a “self-torture game,” in which alien introjects battle it out
with now-alien organismic hungers (Freud’s id). We become unsure of ourselves,
confused about what we need or want, because we are without inner guidance.
Unable to make discriminations based on anything other than what we have been
socially programmed to believe or what other people tell us, we chase after one
thing, then another. Fighting against our bodies rather than letting them organize
our experience, our gestalt formation is weakened. Few of our interactions actually
satisfy our needs, and so we come to trail a growing bag of unfinished experiences
behind us, especially those involving the grief and anger our superegos chide us
against expressing. Lacking appetite, direction, bodily satisfaction, self-esteem,
outgoing energy, and a willingness or ability to express forbidden emotion, we
become prone to depression.
What replaces a bodily based existence is a verbal, intellectual, fantasy-
based one. In a hostile environment, divided against ourselves rather than directed
toward the world, we retreat into an inflated inner life. Dreams and fantasies
become the primary safe realm and are maximized accordingly.111 Our frustrated
or unwelcomed intentions are gratified or entertained only in fantasy—those of
Shame, Isolation, and the Loss of Sociality. An interactive framework puts a radical
stress on our inherent togetherness, interdependence, or sociality. Merleau-Ponty
called the subject a “project of the world” as a way to make this point (while also
granting to subjects their own unique perspectives on and intentions toward this
world). This also means, however, as I have been discussing above, that psycho-
pathology is not just an individual matter, but involves disturbances in the whole
social field.115 As J. H. van den Berg noted, psychopathology is at bottom the
“science of loneliness.”116 Only a being who essentially belongs with others can
suffer from isolation. When hurt by others, our basic social sense is damaged. Our
trust in relationships, our faith in the nature of things, and our belief in the safety
and goodness of the world—all are weakened.117 In what follows, what I want to
discuss, in particular, is how all chronic interruptions or absences of contact are
isolating, and how the emotion that goes with this feeling of aloneness is shame.118
Shame is the experience of having some part (or the whole) of ourselves,
some need or urge, some action or movement of ours toward contact with others,
disapproved of, ridiculed, refused, unsupported, violated, or unacknowledged by
our environment. Our natural desires are bad. We are exposed as “dirty,” defec-
tive, unworthy, despicable, not enough, not part of the human family or of this
earth. The feeling of shame is about as awful as anything we are likely to experi-
ence. When feeling shame we avoid eye contact, hang our heads, shrink. Other,
less obvious signs that we are experiencing or trying to relieve our shame include
and fearing that they may not measure up to the male stereotype. Many men will
sacrifice their inner lives, even go to war and die, rather than face their shame
(so shameful is it to be ashamed). Females are shamed, in turn, by a society
that pervasively devalues their very femaleness. Noteworthy here are the soci-
etal introjects concerning women’s bodies and their perceived imperfections—
for which they must (apply) “makeup,” and so feed a multibillion dollar a year
cosmetic industry.125 Only in a society that has made it shameful to be “fat,”
moreover, does anorexia and bulimia become epidemic. Gender patterns, finally,
are further enforced by the oppression of gay, lesbian, bisexual, and transgen-
dered people, groups with whom it has historically been made shameful to in any
way be identified.
The Repressed Unconscious: Frustration of the Life Process. Ernest Becker writes that
psychopathology “is always fundamentally a problem of organisms which are crip-
pled, cramped, or blocked in their experience.”126 From my perspective, the most
essential feature of pathology is that it involves a frustrating of the life process.
Repression is the chronic nonliving, blocking, or reversing of our world-bound
energies or intentions; the contracting of ourselves against our own internally
directed expansion into the world; the nonrealizing or stopping of certain kinds
of implied relationships or contacts with others—such that we do not body-forth
our lives. As Boss notes, “relationships which are not openly admitted do not flow
through the bodily realm of existence in their movement toward the perceived
things. They come forth and remain within the sphere of the body, so that there
is a ‘jam’ instead of vibration.”127 We learn to deliberately intercept our bodily
intentions until this becomes habitual, falling out of explicit awareness. Our urges
then persist only in a cramped or dammed-up form—as bodily blocked sexuality,
anger, grief, fear, terror, love, joy, and so forth—which color our perception as
they relentlessly push in the background toward some final contact and closure.128
They are felt only as a ground of pain, as an aura of frustration, agitation, dissatis-
faction, fear, lack, incompleteness, and so on, which permeates our world.
What I am introducing here is an experiential theory of the repressed uncon-
scious. Gendlin writes simply that “the unconscious consists of the body’s stopped
processes, the muscular and physiological blockage.”129 What is unconscious are
the world-relations that are interrupted, unexpressed, not mirrored, unconsum-
mated, or concealed between us; yet which, as I just suggested, are present in
a jammed manner, as our implicit and unfocused bodily sensing of them. The
unconscious is thus a relational or interactive phenomenon.
“The unconscious” . . . is all those parts of experience that remained inchoate and
unarticulated, parts for which we never developed a full voice, for want of that
receptive intersubjective field that is requisite . . . for the full development/articu-
lation of the self. . . . experience that is felt but cannot be shared, represented,
articulated, echoed, [symbolized,] and thus integrated into the whole social field
thus tends to become stunted and arrested at best, if it doesn’t disappear from felt
reality altogether.130
bodily existence; it is our unaware sensing of the blocked and background living
that wants to come forth. In other words, when the unconscious is understood in
the mode of a remote repository full of discrete mental contents (ideas, images,
emotions), we come to think of mental phenomena as belonging in some dis-
embodied head-space. Understood rather in the mode of our world-entangled
bodies, psychological life becomes intensely somatic. What is unconscious to us
are our body’s relations to the world that we are not explicitly taking up and acting
on—living as we are, instead, in our narrow and automatic patterns.136
An experiential approach further criticizes the traditional model of the
unconscious for reifying experience by focusing on isolated contents rather than
seeing these as aspects of a felt process.137 When some content of experience—an
emotion, idea, memory, dream image—passes out of focal awareness (for what-
ever reason) it does not stay all neatly formed as it is. It does not get filed away as
a discrete entity, but instead melts back into the flow of our bodily experiencing,
goes into solution, as it were, to become “part” of the complex and holistic felt
ground of our ongoing interacting with the world. Contents may of course be
reformed (as in a memory) when some relevant situation or supportive context
draws them out, for they are still implicit in our experience. But the unconscious,
experientially conceived, does not strictly consist of such contents. Merleau-Ponty
thus called it “a retrospective illusion” to assume that what we become aware of
in a moment of insight exists ahead of time as unconscious psychic material.138
The practice of focusing, for example, does not involve unearthing buried con-
tents, but rather allows some unfinished feeling to be symbolized—in that very
moment—into consciousness. I want to associate the unconscious, then, not pri-
marily with images (as do Jungians), but rather with the life process, in which
images play the crucial role of life-forwarding symbols. Even the most dreadful
dream contents come to us as an invitation to some further living—for which our
bodily felt sense is always the touchstone.
merely repressed.”161 What Horkheimer and other critical theorists described was
a social order whose essential trajectory is precisely to become increasingly incom-
patible with or repressing of nature.162 The lone phone operator in a fluorescent-lit
cubicle whose performance is being monitored by computer is hardly unfolding
her or his existence as nature intended. Horkheimer observed that when we domi-
nate nature we inevitably get pulled into the arena of violence as we ourselves
are converted into instruments and resources (this is not to posit a homogenous
humanity lacking in social distinction, but to assert that no one escapes some kind
of mistreatment163). I call this vicious dialectic “the double violation of nature”
in order to emphasize this rebounding or mirroring effect. As Kovel describes it:
Our society is an immense machine constructed to extract wealth from the earth
through unlimited economic penetration. Its raw materials extend to nature (viewed
as “resources”), other societies, culture, and critically, the selves of individual
persons.164
Hence:
The great menace of capitalism, the one to which the entire ecology movement is
responsive, is that all of nature itself will come under the sway of the commodity and
be violated. . . . as the forest becomes a field which becomes a lawn which becomes
Astroturf, so is the human organism converted into a zone of commodification. . . .
In the emergence of the narcissistic character as the central figure of late capitalism,
we see this movement appear in the self.165
Because the capitalist order insists on economic growth, and because profits are
made by taking it out of the earth, (human) nature must be exploited on a per-
petually escalating scale. Trade agreements (GATT, NAFTA, etc.) are simply the
latest developments in this history of economic expansion, in which “ecological
rapine and human slavery are both means of lowering prices on merciless global
markets.”166 The workings of capital, that is, violate the nature of things in general.
And as Kovel here suggests, this process now shows up in humans as the universal-
izing of pathological narcissism.
The permeation of our culture by narcissistic features167 signals one of
the central psychological outcomes (and engines) of our historical mode of
relating to nature. While narcissism is usually discussed in terms of grandiosity
and self-absorption, I want to emphasize that at the core of the classic narcissist
is an utterly shame-bound person whose early needs were severely violated and
who consequently has only an abysmal sense of self. Narcissists are wounded
to such an extent that they have almost no sense of their own insides, their
own bodily felt living. They identify instead with grand self-images that act in
fantasy to compensate for their terrible sense of inadequacy. They spend their
entire lives propping up these images and insisting brittlely that others be their
loving mirrors. The cult of celebrity—in which we adore and identify with
images of the rich, the powerful, and the beautiful, found in those glossy maga-
zines at the supermarket checkout—likewise betrays a pervasive sense of worth-
lessness in our society. On the whole, however, this condition is not a problem
for the running of a capitalist society, for feelingless, hungry narcissists are in
many ways perfectly adapted, if not tailor-made, for it.168 Having had their
own nature violated, and lacking much grasp of their inner motivations, nar-
cissists consume endlessly in a quest for lost selfhood, and, seeking self-esteem
Finally, I need note that we are not committed to a violent economic system
without reason. Environmentalists have long been frustrated by how easily “fear
for the economy” displaces “fear for the ecology.”172 I believe this fear is key. We
are born into a social world in which our need for personal viability or security
gets “met” by being twisted down along narrow economic pathways which then
become difficult to leave, for both emotional and structural reasons. We are just
too existentially vulnerable for it to be otherwise, at least for most of us. These
pathways, however, fail to bring us the release from fear we desire. For it is the
very pattern of relationships within the system of capital that generates our deep
and desperate insecurity in the first place. Thus, the whole historical dialectic
of double violating nature is essentially a compulsive and doomed search for an
ever-more-elusive sense of security, in which the repression and degradation of
human and nonhuman nature has become a strange and viciously spiraling end in
itself.173 To understand all this better I suggest we need a concrete mapping of the
connections between the form of our society, the nature of our experience, and
our relation to more-than-human reality. Chapters four through six are exercises
toward this end.
not-quite-right affair, a strategy that betrays our nihilistic times. For as Romand
Coles suggests, value is not some quanta, but “emerges like breath exhaled under
water from encounters between self and other.”178
Perhaps the connection I am exploring here is most simply made in
R. D. Laing’s oft-cited line that: “If our experience is destroyed our behaviour
will be destructive.”179 Nihilism is a frustrating cultural condition; it engenders
rage and (self-)destruction (i.e., an-nihil-ation). The more our living and feel-
ings are blocked, the more we are estranged from our own bodily-felt nature, the
more does the aggression within the life force press up against this repression;
hence “adjustment in our time involves an element of resentment and suppressed
fury.”180 As many have noted, violence often originates in repressed aggression
combined with an inner sense of shame or impotence. That is, acts of rageful vio-
lence can be seen, in part, as desperate attempts to assert one’s existence or person-
hood, so as to defend oneself against the painful feeling that one is a nothing or a
nobody. There is, furthermore, no shortage of literature describing much of the
male-driven mistreatment of the earth as an act of blind hostility, in which nature,
denuded of meaning to the status of brute matter, becomes the target for guilt-
free or morally sanctioned acts of violence. Barry Lopez, for example, writes that
the historical slaughter of wolves in North America is rooted in “theriophobia,” a
fear of the beast (within). All that has become violent, irrational, insatiable, and
disinhibited within humans is disowned from awareness and then projected onto
animals who do not themselves “rape, murder, and pillage.” This projection, notes
Lopez, has stuck particularly well to wolves, who when targeted for annihilation
are therefore asked to pay the price (as are all dogs who get kicked) for the distor-
tion and repression of life among men.181
Konrad Stettbacher calls our feelings “the guardians of life.” Rinzler like-
wise remarks that “the only safety and protection we can ever know is in our pro-
found connectedness with our sensory selves, as part of the living earth, warning
us of our danger.”182 As Audre Lorde has noted, however: “Within structures
defined by profit, by linear power, by institutional de-humanization, our feel-
ings were not meant to survive.”183 And as Heidegger suggested, this means that
our time is “no longer able to experience its own destitution.”184 One final way
to view the domination of nature, then, is simply as a “cruelty sanctioned by
tradition,”185 wherein we do not feel the impact of our violent actions. The
narcissist is just unable to recognize the self or personhood of others, and thus to
value and care for life.186
In “beginning with experience” in this chapter I have also begun my efforts
to demonstrate the centrality of the human-nature relationship in all psycholog-
ical, social, and ecological matters. In my view, thinkers who wish to oppose the
destructive aspects of our society need to acknowledge the primary authority of
self-organizing nature—so that they may both more adequately gather the essen-
tial nature of our crises and, just as importantly, find this nature in their own
91
ecopsychology (e.g., its organismic focus and its interactive view of reality), while
leaving behind some of those that are blinding or false. Ecological thinkers have
brought much criticism down on humanism, calling it, among other things, an
“ideological fixation” on humans.7 When it comes to humanistic psychology, how-
ever, I would rather put it in dialogue with radical ecology in order to create
something that benefits from and filters out weaknesses in both of them. The
basic image of human nature that unites the humanistic psychologies is that of
a continual state of becoming, emerging, or unfolding.8 We are most human,
in other words, when perpetually transcending or growing beyond our current
mode of being. The problem from an ecological perspective is that this process
is largely disarticulated or disembedded from the natural world, and so lacks any
restraint or necessary commitment to an earthly place. Humanists often proclaim
our unlimited potential, sometimes even fantasizing of planetary omnipotence.9
To put it plainly, then, the ecologizing of humanistic psychology will require a
certain amount of deflation. Hans Peter Duerr writes, in this regard, that to be
able to “speak” with nonhuman entities “a person needs what the [Native Ameri-
cans] call ‘reverence.’ Humans must become unimportant before the other things
of nature.”10
I have already voiced my concerns about the natural scientific disclosure of
nature. The exercise in this chapter is thus to begin inquiring into the meaning
of nature in more psychological, primordial, and openly dialogical terms. I do so
by defining nature under three headings, namely, the natural world, the essential
qualities or character of some phenomenon, and the life force. This will then set
the stage for me to outline a naturalistic or nature-centered psychology in the
chapter to follow. In sum, I would note that the word “human” comes from the
Latin humus, meaning soil or earth. The naturalistic psychology I propose in the
chapters ahead attempts to stay attuned to what is indeed distinctive about being
human, while nonetheless keeping us grounded in the earth of which we consist.
Many of the proposed solutions to the current ecological crisis are taken in by
traditional interpretations, ignore questions of hermeneutics, and so overlook
the underlying fantasies and prejudices that condition . . . our perception of
the natural world—and thereby also our interaction with the environment.
—Graham Parkes11
Hermeneutic inquiry arises out of some sort of alienation from meaning. Our
nihilistic era, however, suffers from a general loss of meaning across the board,
a condition both born and perpetuating of violence. My own interpretive and
rhetorical strategy is to counter this nihilism by taking nature as my theme, for it
is in this direction that I feel the sources of meaning are to be found or rediscov-
ered, and our violence is to be understood. To do this, however, is to walk into
tricky territory, so ideologically misused is the notion of nature (e.g., capitalism is
natural) and so blunt a tool is it for justifying any kind of status quo (“that’s just
human nature”). The muddying of the whole idea of nature—to the point where
nature is said not to exist at all—is nonetheless exactly the point. The notion of
nature has been ideologically perverted precisely because it is so powerful, so very
much at the heart of it all, so decisive in how we understand and behave in the
world. Stronger still, it is because our society so poorly acknowledges and under-
stands the nature of things that we continue to grossly mistreat them, as I began
to argue in the previous chapter. Rather than give up on or renounce the concept
of nature as irremediably or unavoidably a product only of human discourse, I
therefore say that ecopsychologists need to make deliberate efforts to reclaim and
defend this “nature” against reactionary, conservative, or naive usage.12
We can all agree, I presume, that nature is a matter of interpretation. My
general ontological outlook—which I call plural realism13—is that there are innu-
merable ways of disclosing or interpreting reality. This position does not naively
suggest, however, that all perspectives are equally valid; it does not rule out criti-
cism and debate. What it does do is seek a “middle way” between the extremes.
Most notably, it is neither objectivism nor relativism. That different interpreta-
tions are possible, that many truths can coexist, refutes objectivism. That better
interpretations are possible, that our experience can always adjudicate the truth or
falsity of an assertion, or lead us into more satisfying contact with reality, refutes
relativism. Hence, to think of truth in plural terms is not say that anything goes. In
other words, as a plural realist I hold that many different interpretations of a phe-
nomenon are possible, but also that these will not all be equal in their truthfulness
or openness to the phenomenon in question (as Simone Weil writes: “Every being
cries out to be read differently”).14 How we understand nature, then, depends on
the quality of our relation to it, our mode of existence, the ground of interpreta-
tion, the historical and personal prejudices we bring to it. One way I see naturalistic
psychology is therefore as a dialogue concerning different symbolizations of nature,
in which the participants must be willing to be changed, to work experientially,
in order to better hear and more faithfully respond to the phenomena of nature.
While, for example, I have learned a great deal about nature from Buddhism, the
practice of Buddhism is still largely human-centered.15 As Gary Snyder remarks,
there is little in the traditions of any of the major world religions, including Bud-
dhism, that addresses the question: “Well, what do you say to Magpie? What do
you say to Rattlesnake when you meet him?”16 Although different approaches or
schemes reveal nature in their own ways, my faith is that our comprehension will
benefit from an open dialogue among them—so long, that is, as we take our con-
cepts experientially, making an effort to practically embody them or see what felt
differences they make, rather than just bandying them about in the air.
The knife of separation is cruel. I not only remember in a factual sense but
I can feel to this day the anguished frustration, the knowledge that I could
never—not ever—be more than a boy on the grass, excluded from [the world
of toads and frogs and newts] wholly and eternally.
—John Livingston20
This first category is what we simply call the natural world, sometimes including
ourselves in it, sometimes not. How are we to understand this ambiguity?
step back from being (or as Heidegger would say, that being itself withdraw from
us). Humans are able to feel awe and wonder because as creatures of distance we can
differentiate and contact the world in its sheer and inexhaustible otherness, grasp
it in its unfathomable mystery. Under the best conditions, we are creatures of right
or optimal distance: the distance where we make meaningful contact,31 where good
gestalts are formed.32 The crisis in our current relationship with nature is not, then,
one of distance per se, but of overdistance. Joel Kovel is accordingly critical of deep
ecology supporters who seek to abolish any sense of difference between humans and
nature, for this ironically “deprives humans of what is in fact our peculiar nature.
The dialectic, to be both part of and [experientially] separate from nature, is in fact
human nature.”33 The step back from being opens up an experiential gap—the
moment of separation—which is our human lot to negotiate, with all the beautiful
and tragic possibilities it entails. Shepard claims, in this regard, that it is “an atti-
tude of accepted separateness . . . which characterizes both the great naturalists and
primal peoples.”34 As Nelson reports, offering one example of this, for Koyukon
Indians “humans and animals are clearly and qualitatively separated.” Despite that
the “natural and human communities originated together in the Distant Time and
have never become completely separate,” there is still a “narrow gap . . . between the
worlds of humanity and nature.”35
In the human-nature relation, then, one sense of “human” is that of a
community of human beings bounded by shared language, myth, custom, and so
on, as it collectively interacts with nonhuman others. As Sean Kane observes, in
archaic human societies this boundary is often physically marked by, for example,
the edge of the forest or the surface of the sea, where worlds meet and exchanges
take place.36 I leave it for Kane and others to detail what such primal life at
the edge of mystery is like. What I would emphasize is that kinship with the
rest of nature has traditionally been won by admitting of boundaries and then
dialoguing with the nonhuman presences on the other side of them, through
ritual, dream, myth, nonordinary states of consciousness, skillful everyday inter-
action, and so forth. This involves the working out of covenants, and the main-
tenance of a complex balance between the worlds, governed by taboos and rules
of exchange that guard against overexploitation. As Barry Lopez notes, “our rela-
tionships with animals were once contractual—principled agreements, founded
in a spirit of reciprocity, mythic in persuasiveness. Among hunting peoples in
general they consisted of mutual obligations and courtesies.”37 More generally
still, in such conversation humans relate not to some homogeneous or undif-
ferentiated Nature but to particular beings, to elk or beaver people, even as these
others themselves interrelate as an ecological whole. Experienced as kin, such
persons are approached with respect and confidence, for they are not seen as
adversaries.38 For us, on the other hand, the disappearance of this kind of intense
and respectful interaction has turned a narrow gap into a spiritual chasm, into
which we are now forever falling.
Nature and Spirit. Cultural narratives around the globe signal the gap between
humans and nature in their stories of a human fall from grace, of a departure from
purity or harmonious unity, or of an introduction of separation and self-conscious
struggle between humans and the rest of nature.39 Our original sin, the mark of
shame on all humanity,40 comes from this essential sense of isolation or of being
cut off from the world of nature. Nature for us is that which we have lost; and we
experience this separation as a sense of lack, deficiency, or incompleteness on our
part. Hence the basic shame inherent in the human condition. In asking about
the human/nature relation we thus come to the “problem of man”; or as I prefer to
say; the question of nature raises the question of spirit. I use the word spirit, in this
instance, to refer to a mode of experience that tends in the direction of reunion
with nature or that works to overcome splits between realms of being.41 With the
exception of our own largely despiritualized society, spiritual practice has been a
prime, if not all-encompassing, concern throughout the record of human exist-
ence. I do not hesitate therefore to call the spiritual an essential form of experience
for humans. Or as Kovel puts it: “human beings are configured spiritually.”42 A
being who was already at one with nature would have no need of spiritual lessons
(or of “nature”). On account of how we stand in relation to the rest of nature,
then, it is of our own human nature to be spiritual.
The spiritual urge is so strong in us humans because in our incompleteness
we are bound to ask about the meaning of life and the ground of our existence. But
what is this ground? As a network of relationships the natural world is not a thing
at all, but a constant flux of interweaving processes, lacking in any permanence or
ultimate solidity. In standing apart from nature, this nonsolidity, groundlessness,
or “emptiness” to reality is revealed to humans as such—which makes us anxious.
In the face of the so-called void, the separated self or Ego then seeks security
through creating the illusion that it is an immortal substance exempt from the
law of change or impermanence.43 As an illusory structure, however, the Ego is
haunted by the void—by a sense of lack, emptiness, insecurity, or tenuousness;
by the agitated prospect of its own annihilation. As the word suggests, what we
ultimately a-void with our fearful and rigid life-patterns is the void. The fear of our
future death derives in fact from this implicit dread or more basic anxiety of being
suspended over the abyss at every present moment.
As David Loy has suggested, drawing on Buddhist and existential psychology,
“the most fundamental dualism of all” is that between the separated or isolated self
and the no-thing-ness or void that perpetually threatens its existence.44 From this
view, we see that the Ego is caught in an endless struggle between the desire to
exist for itself as a separate being and the desire to not exist, to be fused back into
the whole, so as to extinguish the pain of separation. The story of a schizophrenic
man who spends much of his time bowing illustrates this dynamic. Asked why he
bows, the man says he is balancing his emotions; when feeling isolated and lonely
he leans forward to be close to others, whereupon he immediately feels afraid and
straightens back up, pulling away from contact—only to once again feel lonely and
to commence another bow.45 What this man describes is an oscillation between
those two well-known poles of life that I call our “twin terrors.”46 One terror is
that of being all alone in the cosmos, wherein the void looms large to the extent
of our Egoic isolation. The other is that of the death of our Egos, or of being
engulfed or overwhelmed by others—what has been called “annihilation panic.”
While few today actually contemplate the void, the twin terrors are the stuff of
everyday interpersonal relations. They are seen, in particular, in the lives of trauma
survivors, which often swing dramatically between states of intense attachment and
terrified withdrawal.47 It takes little effort, however, to see such dynamics in almost
anybody’s life: the anxious isolate (fearful of intimacy), the needy “codependent”
(fearful of independence), the addict (fused with her or his “drug”), and so on.
We may also experience the void whenever our lives are in transition or limbo—
when we switch careers, get divorced, lose a loved one, develop an illness, or leave
home for the first time—when we can no longer hold onto our old identities and
relationships and must instead confront a distressing gap in the continuity of our
existence.48 While I can only demonstrate it in this limited way, my point here is
that the spiritual conditions of human existence, based in our distanced relation to
nature, while they may be a-voided, can never be escaped.
One of the nature-violating hallmarks of our own society, then, is that it does
not adequately attend to the spiritual region of existence. Significantly, our repressed
fear of the void, our hidden ontological insecurity, then gets translated into (among
other things) a fear of nature: a million tentacles, creepy-crawlies, microorganisms,
or hidden beasts—alien and fearsome others—threatening our vulnerable and pre-
carious Egos. Indeed, Horkheimer wrote that the “history of Western civilization
could be written in terms of the growth of the [E]go,”49 its rational functions being
employed to dominate and control nature (whether id or wilderness) in an endless
and self-defeating search for security. As Kovel notes: “Egoic experience gravitates
toward paranoia, and does so precisely because of the splitting and domination
conjugated into it. . . . The concrete effects . . . are the repression of the body and
the inevitable return of the repressed. Ecologically, nature turns into wilderness
which must be ‘tamed,’ that is, paved, converted into Disneyworlds or simple raw
materials. . . . Ego is thus the specific antagonist of any emancipatory project. It
is what an ecologically sensitive practice must overcome.”50 In short, because the
Egoic mode is so antagonistic to and split from nature, ecopsychology is called
toward a spiritual mode, one that would overcome Ego.
To finish this discussion I wish to speak briefly about three aspects of spir-
itual life that will be relevant to discussions ahead. First, as Loy suggests, the anti-
dote for fear of the void is to become the void. In other words, spiritual practice is
the dissolving of Ego and the realizing of ourselves in relation to others. I imagine
all “nature lovers” know the experience of at least temporarily releasing their Egos
outward, so as to spontaneously flow with birds, trees, wind, sky, water, rock,
moss, flowers, insects—in which they feel a relative loss of self-density, noticeable
for its peacefulness, spaciousness, vividness, or at least its freedom from a more
confined Egoic mode of existence. Sartre’s world, by contrast, is imbued with
the dread and unreality of existential isolation. Thus, while there are many ways
of being spiritual, all of which involve discipline and work, it is not difficult to
gather that the more we identify with the greater rhythms of life, the more com-
munity, common ground or kinship we sense, the less anxious we will be, because
less attached to our own individual atom. Second, spiritual life confronts death.
The question of nature brings the topic of our death aversion, our impoverished
comprehension of the interplay between birth and death in the larger stream of
life, right to the fore. As Gary Snyder teaches, to “acknowledge that each of us at
the table will eventually be part of the meal,” rather than being a source of disgust
with self, humanity, and life, can be a way into the sacred, celebratory, and sac-
ramental side of existence. The fact that life unavoidably involves death-dealing
can be taken, that is, as a spiritual challenge: as an invitation to understand “the
play of the real world, with all its suffering,” to realize that all “of nature is a gift-
exchange, a pot-luck banquet” at which we ourselves are both gift and guest.51
Third, spiritual life is the development of our capacity to love. As Fromm wrote:
“The awareness of human separation, without reunion by love—is the source of
shame. It is at the same time the source of guilt and anxiety. The deepest need of
man, then, is to overcome his separateness, to leave the prison of his aloneness.”52
To be loved is to have our being affirmed, to feel connected to and embraced by
others; love is thus the source of our ontological security, of feeling grounded
in our own being.53 To love others is to identify their interests with our own,
while nonetheless maintaining our distance from them, so that they (and we) may
unfold their own particular natures, or be.
Nature as Mysterious Birth, Genesis, Growth, Unfolding. “Nature” comes from the
Latin word natura, which means birth. Hence the widespread (though apparently
not universal) association of nature with “mother” and the feminine; and its rela-
tion to such words as natal and pregnant. (The Latin for mother—mater—is in
turn the source for such words as matter and matrix.) The Greek word is physis or
phusis, which similarly means the process of genesis, growing, a-rising, e-merging,
opening up, unfolding—as in the blossoming of a flower.54 Such words make
the link between nature and life. Note also how nature in its primordial sense
is a process, is a verb. Nature as a noun, as physical matter, is thus (as Heidegger
observed) nature in a “restricted sense.” The natural world is fundamentally,
therefore, a field of arising-and-passing phenomena or appearances, a myriad of
unfolding-and-dying interactional events.
How are we to grasp this primordial sense of nature? We might begin by
noticing the countless cyclic phenomena in the world, such as breathing, the
rising and setting of the sun, the turning of the seasons, or the life cycle of a
plant, animal, river, or mountain. The character of the bear, in particular, has
through much of human cultural experience been a “mentor in birthing and dying
in the endless cycle of becoming,” a “master of renewal and the wheel of the
seasons”55—as she rotates across the northern sky in the constellation of the Great
Bear or goes “underground” to den for the winter, emerging once again in the
spring (perhaps with the new life of cubs). Indeed, the verb to hear means to
bring forth or give birth. We may also return here to much of what I discussed in
the previous chapter. All complete experiences are an arising from out of the felt
ground and a passing away back into it, a forming and dissolving of a gestalt, a
contacting and a withdrawing. Our human experiencing, as I took pains to say,
is but a cyclic process within the vaster natural world. “The naturalist,” says John
Livingston, “sees a wild animal as one among uncountable ephemeral corporeal
emergences, one minor miracle to remind us of the ineffable whole.”56 So might
we see ourselves.57
All phenomena arise from out of a larger field or ground, as plants perhaps
teach best. They all, therefore, have a hidden dimension: they are mysterious. The
natural world, as a play of appearances in which the things that are disclosed to
us are rooted in what still remains closed, is intrinsically mysterious. Think about
the origin of things. Dream images are given, emotions just come up. We may say
something and then ask ourselves Where did that come from? Symbols, in other
words, emerge spontaneously into the space our existence helps to hold open; they
float to the surface, according to an order of things that is beyond our reckoning.
The much talked about “Dreamtime” of Australian aborigines, while difficult for
us to understand conceptually, is apparently something like a time out of time that
lies within evident reality; it refers to a perpetual emerging of the world from out
of a mysterious depth or earthly dreaming.58 To speak of mystery is to say that the
world contains invisible grounds, unseen forces. In fact, the early Greek thinker,
Heraclitus, claimed that nature itself “loves to hide.” Or as Kane writes, the minds
or intentions of the ecological complexities of nature “prefer to be kept hidden.”59
Archaic myths, he says, do not explain the why of it all, but are rather stories
about the links or relationships among things, the general patterns of the natural
world (as in, to use a minor example, “red sky at night, sailor’s delight”). More to
the point, myth-telling peoples have injunctions against attempting to eliminate
mystery, against bringing everything out into the open, for such acts encourage a
destructive or meddling hubris.
It is the business of Ego, however, to break “itself off from the mystery.”60
The rise of the Ego through Western history has accordingly been paralleled by a
shift in the way the natural world has displayed itself to us, becoming increasingly
distant, hard, literal, mute, static, passive: unmysterious. While, for example,
modern people perceive the world as a kind of picture that stands in front of them
and recedes away from view,61 the experience of Medieval people was more like that
of being in the picture, as is indicated by the (to us, odd looking) absence of linear
perspective in their art. Although it is hard to imagine, people felt themselves mys-
teriously immersed with other beings and with their language “in something like
a clear lake of . . . ‘meaning.’”62 Today’s scientific project of total unconcealment is
an offense against the things of nature (including ourselves) because it attacks the
mystery that is essential to them and only invokes them to further withdraw from
us, thereby taking us all that much more out of the picture.63 The idea of nature
as otherness, then, implies an opacity, polydimensionality, or wildness that asks
to be respected. Barry Lopez writes of wolves, for instance, that: “No one—not
biologists, not Eskimos, not backwoods hunters, not naturalist writers—knows
why wolves do what they do.”64
Nature as Any (Personified) “Other.” Although the historical Buddha spoke a lan-
guage known as Pali, the word used for nature within Buddhist thought is most
often the Sanskrit term dharma (spelled dhamma in Pali). Dharma is a multifac-
eted word denoting an all-pervasive reality. What I would draw out here is that
among its usages the term signifies any phenomenon: any kind of being that arises,
stays awhile, and passes away. Hence, we may speak of “a” dharma, or “a” nature,
to refer to whatever is borne by the mind,65 that is, to whatever appears in our
awareness as some “other.” Buddhism adopts, then, what is called a phenomeno-
logical ontology, the view that whatever we experience (phenomena) has some
manner of reality. In our own time the predominant understanding of nature,
of the real, is that of matter. The many nonmaterial phenomena that stubbornly
persist in our experience are then given a derivative or secondary status, degraded
to epi-phenomena. Hence, for a recollective project such as this I suggest that
a phenomenological ontology is imperative. We might do our best to adopt a
kind of mythological consciousness, wherein “anything of existential significance
or displaying affective power is important and hence real. For example, dreams
are considered real events, and the emotional impact of dreams about deceased
persons accounts for the absence of a strict separation between the living and the
dead. . . . The world is not measured by consistency but by existential import.”66
We need also admit that: “In a multiple world I too am multiple. Otherness is
inside and out, a part of myself and a part of the outside world.”67
What this all means is a loosening up of our grip on the real. To say that
nature is “other” means that we exist both in and as our felt relations to whatever
symbolic otherness we encounter, in whatever realms or modes of experience
we may be open to—whether private or public, ordinary or nonordinary. Thus,
any so-called spirit-being—whether a critical superego, bear-spirit, angel, bad
introject, malevolent possession, dream figure, ancestor, transpersonal guide,
or hallucinated sound—may be taken simply as a hidden presence or spectral
force in our lives, one that visits us, helps us, possesses us, haunts us: claims us
somehow.68 Eugene Gendlin writes that the bodily felt sense “comes between the
conscious person and the deep universal reaches of human nature where we are
no longer ourselves.”69 The otherness that Jung attributes to the unconscious may
also be read, then, as the autonomy that Gendlin attributes to the body (in its rela-
tion to the world). This autonomy of the body-unconscious leads, moreover, to
a paradox that is well known to anyone who does inner work: that our experience
is not exactly “ours.”70 “Like the fox in the forest which is not mine just because
I see it, so the fox in the dream is not mine just because I dream it.”71 In inner
work, we are asked to “own” our experience, feel our feelings, while nonetheless
dis-identifying from what we experience, creating an aware or detached distance
from it, imagining it as another person. Doing so opens up the needed space to
then converse with it, make contact with it, and—paradoxically—achieve greater
closeness or intimacy with it. In the practice of focusing, for example, we often
symbolize a feeling by allowing an inner image to emerge from it, whether this
image be a block of ice, a scared little boy, or a prowling wolf. We then enter into
a relationship with this imagined and personified other—as it is still felt in our
bodies—getting to know it, seeing what it wants, getting close to it, working out
conflicts with it, and so on.72
One of the additional things focusing demonstrates, then, is that the per-
sonification of otherness is indigenous to the psyche.73 We do recognize the living
quality of nonhuman beings, their inwardness, whether these others be an inner
image, a cat, or an old pair of hiking boots. It is a great irony that so many psy-
chologists have described personification as “primitive” or childish animism; for
no good therapist (it seems to me) can ignore it. This shows how easily one of the
most obvious and significant tendencies of the psyche can be pushed aside by an
objectivist view. We may love others, and feel loved by them, only if we under-
stand them as persons.74 As I discussed in chapter one, moreover, there are efforts
afoot to revive an animistic sense of things, which has always been the common
sense among indigenous peoples. A traditional Hopi belief, for instance, is report-
edly that “humans emerged into the world as corn does,” and so, conversely, that
corn ought to be treated as newborn persons.75 If this seems too outlandish an
idea, we may simply recall that one of the goals of hermeneutics is to grant others
their own voices and intentions.
In a well-known reflection on a path through a field he walked as a boy,
Heidegger wrote that “the message of the Fieldpath speaks only as long as there
are human beings who, born in its air, are able to hear it. . . . The danger threatens
that men of today remain hard of hearing to its language.”76 Following Heidegger,
we may understand or imagine the natural world as a communicative and personi-
fied body, even if we have trouble hearing its speech. In my own experiences of
conversing with nonhuman others, the moment of contact arrives like a window
opening: I feel a sudden resonance, where a message unmistakably comes through,
as when a Raven flew onto a nearby branch of a hemlock to tell me who is boss
and whose world I should be paying attention to. Such experiences need no justi-
fication beyond themselves—for meaning is transmitted in them, and I feel a clear
change in my existence, in the way I sense things following them. The more I am
able to attune myself to the natural world the more I discover that it is correspond-
ingly attuned to me. Like being in a great big dream, relevant messages are being
spoken everywhere, telling me things I need to hear, and to which I need respond.
I offer this modest testimonial only to suggest both the very ordinariness of such
earthly communication and its utter mystery.77
As a final note, I wish to clarify how I will hereafter use the term natural world.
Although I call any “other” a natural event, I still wish to employ the “natural
world” as a shorthand for that realm of wild and diverse processes found most
fully, though not exclusively, in relatively unhumanized places, where a richer
community of beings is present. To make this relative distinction I will therefore at
times refer to the “wider” or “larger” natural world. At other times, however, I will
use “natural world” and “nature” without qualification, unbothered by the ambi-
guity. What matters most, from my perspective, is the quality of our experiencing
among the various realms of otherness, a point I hope to make evident enough
regardless of terminological difficulties.78
I have already spoken of certain qualities of the natural world, such as its inherent
mystery. Given that all phenomena interrelate to comprise a single whole, people
everywhere have intuited that there is a general way to this mysterious world of
changing appearances. Big words like Phusis, Tao, Being, Great Mystery, Logos,
Dharma, God, and so on get used for it. This sense of nature will come out further
below when I discuss the next category of nature, a general organizing force in the
world. We may quickly get a feel for it, however, simply by pointing to the prin-
ciple of karma, some version of which is recognized across cultures. Karma means
action. Roughly speaking,80 to harm others is to harm or bring down misfortune
and suffering on oneself. Good karma, on the other hand, bears the fruit of good
luck, grace, or release from suffering. Buddhists, Christians, and primal peoples
(among others) all say something like this, although the last group is more likely
to talk about proper or nonviolating actions in relation to nonhuman persons
as well, or at least to do so in more local detail. Plainly put: “The natural world
responds to us in a universal language. If we’re behaving badly, the world will tell
us.”81 That is its nature.
Moving from the character of the natural world, to that of particular entities
within that world, nature here refers to the essential qualities, calling, virtues,
excellences, or life of a being. Dharma means “that which bears its own nature. . . .
The blazing of the sun is its characteristic.”82 All dharmas are said to sustain one
another by keeping to their own unique modes of being. In its primordial sense,
phusis denotes the unfolding of entities as a whole whereby they can emerge “of
their own accord from out of themselves—coming forth uncompelled from con-
cealment.”83 That is, the essential nature of an entity is the way it organizes itself,
implies its own further living, even if it is externally compelled to deviate from this
nature. James Hillman remarks that each animal has its own kind of self-display,
and that “the animal’s urge to self-revelation is reason enough for its creation. . . .
the animal continually reminds that the play of creation is revelation.”84 All beings
also have their own characteristic liveliness. The things we experience as being most
alive are those that self-emerge most intensely, with the greatest energy, motion,
brilliance, or power (this idea coming from the Greek word for life, zoe, which is
a characteristic of, or equivalent term for, phusis).85 What we normally regard as a
living being, say a squirrel, is simply a self-emergence that stands out for the capti-
vating or striking way in which it exhibits itself—in contrast, say, to the less lively
sidewalk on which it hops.
What the essential nature of some entity may be is obviously debatable or
subject to different interpretations. I would only repeat here my commitment
to the notion that we can know the nature of things more or less authentically.
Indeed, another meaning of dharma is that which it is “right” for something to
be.86 We will not always agree on what makes for the nature of a little brown bat
or a silver maple, but there will be better or worse readings of these, depending on
the conditions of our relations to them. In the stories of indigenous peoples, ani-
mals and other nonhuman beings are often portrayed with distinct personalities
that convey their essential characters. Such narratives vary from place to place, but
the attempt to understand and respect the nature of local beings does not. In any
case, what I would hope we can agree on is that different beings must have their
own natures because we draw on them metaphorically to understand ourselves
(e.g., “I am a rock”) and because they have lessons to teach us—a topic I consider
at some length in the next chapter, and so leave aside for the time being.
What, next, are we to make of human nature? I suggest we can deviate from,
or be ignorant of, our essential nature, but that it will ultimately call us back or be
rediscovered as we deepen our experience. I showed this in the previous chapter
when I discussed the inherent life-forwarding orderliness of our bodily nature,
and under the heading above when I talked about our spiritual nature. What
follows is a discussion of three aspects of human nature that builds on or adds to
these earlier discussions.
multifaceted I feel this idea to be. I will not go over what I have already said about
hermeneutics. What I do want to get at, however, is a sense for how it is of our
nature to understand, or to grasp the meaning of things; to create symbols or
metaphors from out of our dwelling in or experiencing of the human/nature gap;
to sing, dance, and play in the mystery; to care for being, the process of living;
and to celebrate and converse with the cosmos, helping to keep all the world in
shape or in balance. There is no positive way to prove all this, for the truth of our
hermeneutic nature lies in our felt sensing of it, in our experience of “rightness” as
we come home to it or feel it near.87 As with so much of what I discuss here, these
are among the most obvious of things to most indigenous societies.
As hermeneutic beings we are poets by nature. In order to best make this
point I need to back up and note that this is so only because the natural world as
a whole is poetic. The early Greek word for poetry, poiesis, refers to the bringing
forth, making, or creative revealing of beings from out of the hidden or earthy
depths of reality. As a continually changing emergence of the myriad forms of
being, physis, primordial nature, is a mode of poiesis; it is poetic in its sheer beauty,
suchness, or presencing—radiating forth, just now, in the swaying of these branches
or the graceful breaking of this wave. “Physis is indeed,” said Heidegger, “poiesis
in the highest sense.”88 Prior to any human speaking, notes Sean Kane, “a world
of poetry . . . already fully exists, in the darting red streak of a sapsucker or in the
rainclouds gathering ominously over Hecate Strait.”89 This is a crucial message for
ecopsychology, as previous psychologies have so far “refused to see that the animal
kingdom is first of all an aesthetic ostentation, a fantasy on show, of colors and
songs, of gaits and flights, and that this aesthetic display is a primordial instinctual
force laid down in the plasma.”90 Hillman rightly says that psychologists have
instead degraded animals to mere symbols for our own “lower” instincts, denying
to them their own self-displaying natures. According to Owen Barfield, the hall-
mark of poetry is movement, the unfurling of meaning or stretching out toward
life.91 Thus, the cloud “poetizes” because it goes “beyond itself to what is no longer
itself.”92 We recognize poetry, moreover, by the experiencing of aesthetic pleasure,
which, as etymology suggests, is a “breathing in” of the beauty of the cosmos.93
If nature is essentially poetic, and if we too are nature, then humans have a
place in nature’s creativity, in its motions, in its birthing of new forms. As Robert
Avens notes: “Physis, in her psychic aspect, is . . . the ultimate source of thought,
language, poetry.”94 If nature were not ordered poetically, then metaphor-ing—the
carrying forward of meaning and life—would not be possible.95 Human nature
is the felt process of completing needs, meanings, or intentions as they “phusi-
cally” arise in the interplay between body and world, creatively giving them some
symbolic form.96 Thus, the artist who is “pregnant with things needing form”97
describes all of us. We must agree with Freud, then, when he said that “a human
being in the spirit of all times [is] an artist.”98 Or as Paul Goodman put it, the self
is the “artist of life”; it plays the “role of finding and making the meanings we live
Basic Goodness: Our Original Nature. The Buddhist teacher Chogyam Trungpa
wrote that every “human being has a basic nature of goodness which is undi-
luted and unconfused.” Thus, when “we hear a beautiful sound, we are hearing
our own basic goodness.”127 This so-called original nature may not be obvious
to all, especially today, but it is nonetheless discoverable. Buddhist practice is
exactly about awakening to this our “true” nature. Beneath “all the busyness of
thought,” writes the Buddhist teacher Jack Kornfield, there lies “a sweet, healing
silence, an inherent peacefulness in each of us, a goodness of heart, strength, and
Everything, including us, has . . . life force in it. We’re the same as everything
else. Only our form changes, because everything has to reveal itself in a
different form so that this wonderful creation can be.
—Jeannette Armstrong134
This final category is the aspect of nature having to do with force or power. When
we talk about nature, we normally mean the first two categories, namely, “the
natural world” and “the nature of things.” Nature conservation documents are not
known to talk about the life force. In discussing it, therefore, ecopsychology may
bring in a sense of nature normally overlooked, one that is especially experiential.
Many different terms are used for it, and as always there are no final interpreta-
tions. We can be sure, though, about the category itself.
I take Abram’s remarks about our bad karma very seriously. As I discussed in
chapter three, the life force wants to move events in certain directions; we know
the way of this life force by the feeling of rightness; and it is by following this way
that we are lead to health. These broad principles certainly apply to the situation
outlined by Abram, as being in right relation to the world involves listening to
what is called for in our interactions with others. The life force can also be felt,
however, in practices that are less directly or concretely involved with the goings-
on in the wilderness; where this force is channeled within or limited to a space that
is more narrowly focused on human interactions and interests. For the purposes
of illustrating the very presence of this spirit force I wish to discuss my own general
experience with some of these practices, all the while recognizing the very real
ecopsychological need to expand the focus of them.
In all four of the experiential trainings I have undertaken, a similar optimal
attitude is required, namely: being aware of or concentrating on what one is expe-
riencing; finding the right distance from this experience; and keeping a curious,
allowing, welcoming, kind, and caring state of mind toward it.147 It is this atti-
tude that frees up the life force. Each of these practices, moreover, takes place
under particular conditions that affect how the life force is experienced. In Vipas-
sana meditation, for example, one adopts a posture that includes closed eyes, a
straight back, and a relaxed body.148 With an equanimous attitude one then moves
one’s awareness throughout one’s body, observing whatever sensations are arising
(whether pleasant, unpleasant, or in-between), and making efforts not to develop
cravings for, or aversions to, any of them. The openness or yielding provided by
this nonreactive and aware attitude allows the life force to then go to work on
burning up old negativities in the mind, releasing energy that is locked up behind
rigidities and compulsions, untangling knots in one’s body, and gradually dis-
solving one’s Egoic solidity and illusions of separateness. Because I go through
this kind of subtle process on a daily basis, the autonomous reality of the life force
is simply incontestable to me. This is the same autonomy I mentioned in the
previous chapter, albeit in a different context, when I discussed how our bodies
urge us in a prolife direction. As my teacher says, the job of the meditator is not
to fix anything, but rather to “leave it to dharma.” The word dharma directly
translates as “the bearer.” Dharma is the life force that sustains or supports us,
carries us forward, gives us strength, bears us onward, liberates us. As a meditator,
one gradually comes to feel borne along by this force, like being buoyed up by
that wonderful oceanic sound made by grasshoppers and crickets in late summer.
Said Heidegger, those who are existentially daring, who hold themselves face-
on into the abyss, are “sustained by that on which they expend themselves”149 (a
notion found in all sorts of spiritual traditions). By meditatively going into one’s
suffering one is supported by nature in going through that suffering, in widening
out a ground of inner peacefulness and strength, or opening up a clear and loving
space within which a continual stream of new phenomena may then enter, arise,
or show themselves.
Although Vipassana meditation is a way of getting to know the life force
by means of an exploration of the interaction of mind and matter within one’s
own body, Buddhist practice is not confined to the meditation hall. The idea is
to take what one learns there out into the world, where the task of life becomes
to meditatively work toward the happiness of all beings. Historically, this has
not always converted into an active pursuit of reciprocal relations with the nat-
ural world, which is why an eco-Buddhism is now emerging along with ecopsy-
chology. My point, however, is that I believe the life force, the Dharma, the
Great Mystery, all to be the same, even if some traditions or practices feel this
spirit force within a relatively restricted field of otherness. What is more, the
fact that the responsive and respectful attitude one adopts within these various
experiential practices seems to be roughly the same suggests that this attitude,
the one that serves the life force, that allows things to heal and flourish, is the
one that is called for by nature, whatever the sphere of otherness happens to
be. Even the more narrowly focused experiential practices, then, teach an atti-
tude that I think readily translates into a more-than-human realm: a posture of
patient listening to the voices one finds both inside and out, of aligning oneself
with what needs to happen or will do no/least harm, and of opening oneself to
the claims of others.150
An Erotic Force: Desire. In the formation of our selves, a residual reality is created
outside ourselves, a reality we have lost, feel as a lack, and so desire.151 This reality
is “nature,” which, as Joel Kovel notes, is “the generic object of desire.”152 Charles
Bergman writes: “We are drawn to nature, impelled by some desire, like body
moving to body. And if, for Western culture now, in the late twentieth century,
desire is experienced primarily as an absence, . . . even a wound, it must be that
the longing for nature is more intense, more poignant, more cut with a sense of
its own inevitable impossibilities, than ever before.”153 The life force, as desire,
thus has a basis in separation itself, is “a pull or polarization between things that
have been separated.”154 Such an understanding of desire puts it on a spiritual
or ontological footing. As against a purely biological conception of desire, Kovel
thus calls it “the roiling of indwelling nature striving toward spirit.” Spirituality
is then “the desire for being,” for a melting of Ego and an opening of the self
toward all reality (Jung’s “thirst for wholeness”). We do not normally think about
desire in such spiritual terms, for the very reason that our natural desires have
become so repressed and problematic in our despiritualized society. Indeed, the
“sphere of the political economy as a whole . . . may be seen as a gigantic and self-
contradictory negation of desire.” That is, “the extreme degree of binding imposed
by the culture necessary for the accumulation of capital has alienated desire itself,
has twisted it about, and made it spectral and monstrous.”155
We need to make a distinction, therefore, between what Kornfield calls
skillful and unskillful desire. The former “is directed by love, vitality, compassion,
creativity, and wisdom” and includes “desire for the well-being of others, the desire
of awakening, the creative desires that express the positive aspects of passion and
beauty.”156 Pathological desires, on the other hand, include those of “addiction,
greed, blind ambition, or unending inner hunger.” These find no true satisfaction,
do not tend toward spirit, but only multiply or carve themselves deeper with each
round of desiring; they do not aim to care for, but rather to possess, control, or
suck dry the other. Significantly, however, underneath our unskillful desire we will
always find “a deep spiritual longing for beauty, for abundance and completeness.”
This “underneath” is the felt place where we touch down into the true needs of the
soul which underlie all of our surficial and painful desires. What the experience
of desire tells us, then, is both that felt-separation from nature is definitive of our
psychology and that the less our desiring is supported the more will it lead us into
trouble or manifest itself as an ever-deepening longing. Longing is exactly “the
heightening of appetite confronted with a distant object, in order to overcome
distance or other obstacles.”157 Our society’s desperate search for spiritual under-
standing—for which the popular psychology or New Age section of any bookstore
may stand—speaks to just how great this longing has become.
We are led, finally, to the notion of Eros, which reveals itself precisely as
our bodily desires. David Levin refers to Eros as “an immortal aspect of Physis:
the sheer energy and ecstasy of Being.”158 Freud called it the love instinct, its
aim being “to establish ever greater unities and to preserve them thus—in short,
to bind together”159 or reunite what has been separated. For Gestaltists, Eros
is the excitement of vividly felt creative living, transpiring right at the contact
boundary between organism and environment. Our bodily intentions all imply
some desired relationship, and so are essentially erotic160—the erotic life is life
itself. (Hence the connection between Eros and Psyche in Greek myth.) Terry
Tempest Williams calls the erotic life a “making love to the world that I think
comes very naturally.” Both she and Audre Lorde distinguish the erotic from the
pornographic by the absence of feeling in the latter, by a “denial of the power of
the erotic.”161 Hence, even our daily “intercourse” becomes pornographic when
it lacks “engagement of the soul.” It is also true to say that the nonerotic life does
not play, for “play is the erotic mode of activity,” the essential way of being of a
satisfied humanity, freely delighting or finding pleasure in life.162 (Indeed, every
animal is a “mode of play,” says Hillman.) As the child analyst D. W. Winnicott
has it: the “natural thing is playing.”163
That one sense of nature is that of an erotic force means that when we
repress our desires we negate our own essence, alienate ourselves from our natural
powers, and deny our “deep hunger for communion” any satisfying food. Hence,
Norman O. Brown’s remark that “mankind, in all its restless striving and progress,
has no idea of what it really wants. . . . mankind, unconscious of its real desires
and therefore unable to obtain satisfaction, is hostile to life and ready to destroy
itself.”164 As Freud demonstrated, however, desire is “immortal.” When repressed
it does not disappear but returns via neurotic symptoms. (“Drive out the natural
and back it comes straightaway,” observes Gaston Bachelard.165) Thus, while we
may well use different terms to interpret the phenomenon of desire, as a transhis-
torical force it cannot be interpreted away.
Freedom and the Life Force. If the life force organizes or directs the shape of events,
or courses through all beings in the way they body themselves forth and interact
with one another, then what role does human agency or freedom play in relation
to this mysterious force? The short answer is that our freedom lies in our being
able to choose whether or not we “obey” the demands of the life force. We pay
the price of suffering, however, if we decide against it; for there is no opting out
of nature. As Percy Shelley said, freedom is “sweet bondage.”166 From the per-
spective of the previous chapter, we are most free when we work to realize those
creative possibilities, in whatever situation we may find ourselves, that satisfyingly
answers what our bodies are asking for; that is, when we are able to maintain an
open, contactful, and responsive relation to the world. We are least free, on the
other hand, when our lives are rigidly set in unconscious habit-patterns. On this
view, the image of humans presented by deterministic philosophies (i.e., those
which deny freedom) is in fact a pathological one. To be totally determined is
to have no free room in which to act, is to have no “breathing space.” Citing
Kierkegaard’s line that the “self of the determinist cannot breathe,” Levin writes:
“Breathing beings will suffocate unless they have space to breathe; a space, as it
were, of possibility. Breathing beings will also suffocate unless they have time to
breathe: a time that is not so pressing that it becomes impossible to breathe.”167
Anyone who knows what it is like to feel anxious or pressured—states in which
it is hard to breathe—knows how claustrophobic our lived space can become and
how tightly a dreaded future can squeeze in on us, such that we lose our ability
to creatively and freely respond to the present moment.168 Our deliberateness or
agency, by contrast, depends on our maintaining a free and open realm in which
to act or relate to others, on keeping a clear temporal and spatial distance between
ourselves and the other-phenomena of our lifeworld. One of the tasks of experi-
ential psychotherapy is to open up this existential clearing, to differentiate and
back off the underdistanced otherness that presses in on us, or operates covertly
in our background, so that we may then become more aware of it and enter into
a freer or more caring relationship to it. For all of us, the more open this clearing
becomes, the more are we able to use our freedom in making good contact with
others, and so serving the life force of nature.
Although I have taken a relatively large block of text to stake out some terms
for discussing nature, the goal of this interpretive exercise was not to promote
Buddhism or humanistic psychology or Koyukon understanding or Heideggerian
thought, but only to employ these to begin revealing a naturalistic landscape. I
have been especially concerned to show that, as Snyder put it, “When humans
know themselves, the rest of nature is right there.”169 I trust that I have established
at least a minimum starting place, then, to pursue the outlines of a naturalistic
psychology.
If we truly experience needs that are in the long run incapable of satisfaction
within the framework of a system dedicated to paving the world with
asphalt, then it is no merely utopian exercise to loosen up the imagination
so as to envisage an alternative world in which such needs might find
satisfaction.
—John Rodman1
Throughout this book I am aiming to build up a sense for the centrality of the
human-nature relationship in human existence, thereby disclosing this relation-
ship as an ultimate concern. What I propose for this chapter is to pencil-in the
main contours of a kind of psychology that would be of assistance to this concern.
The discussion is divided into three sections: “Naturalism” introduces the general
spirit of this psychology; “Life as a Hermeneutic, Sense-Making Journey” its
general principles; and “Nature and the Human Life Cycle” its general content.
Naturalism
tender sense of human limitation is no longer rewarded. Yet we suffer for the want
of that vanished world, a deep grief we learn to misconstrue.”8 In view of our
society’s consistent denial and narcissistic hatred of limits,9 I am thus advancing
a naturalistic approach that focuses precisely on such limits, and so aims to send
up some sparks around what I believe is terribly at stake in our historical times.
Important to this undertaking is the convergence from manifold quarters
on the notion of releasing ourselves to or serving something that is not strictly us.
Fritz Perls, to begin, called the ego the servant of the organism (thus reversing the
usual Freudian view).10 Here, the lower-case “ego” refers only to that free agency
which, as an aspect of the organism, deliberately sets the boundaries and performs
the actions that will satisfy the needs of the organism (and which, whether as
ego or Ego, is the individual sense of “human” in the human-nature relation-
ship). “Serving soul,” writes Hillman, “implies letting it rule; it leads, we follow.”11
Ellen Chen likewise calls Taoism a religion that serves life by following “the way”
of nature.12 For Heidegger, we are servants of being or agents of possible world-
disclosures. The Buddha, for his part, did not actually call his followers Buddhists,
but dharma servants (or wayfarers). Knowing that, in his own words, one “lives
unhappily who has nothing to venerate and obey,” he committed himself to living
“under the Dharma, honouring and respecting that.”13 Certainly the idea of
serving God is familiar to all. From the German word Gut, the original meaning of
“God” is “the Good One.” Peter Mathiessen suggests that in this sense it is close
to the Native American “Great Spirit” or “Great Mystery.”14 Says one primer on
Native American spirituality, the “greatest of all lessons of the medicine wheel” is
that the essence of our humanity is “to be found in service to others.”15 Or as the
Koyukon Indians believe: “the proper role of humankind is to serve a dominant
nature.”16 These are among the oldest, or at least the most basic, of intuitions
about the essential business of humanity. Naturalistic psychology, accordingly,
calls for a humbling of the self, an admitting that we emerge from and are
beholden to serve a natural world much deeper and greater than our individual or
personal selves.17 A narcissistic culture, however, takes the reverse view, insisting
that the world of nature serve it. When I look out on the dense buildings and
roadways covering the earth and imagine instead living in a culture that genuinely
serves nature, that would rather praise than pave, my grief rushes up inside me.
The truth of the need to serve nature, I suggest, is in the tears.18
What, indeed, does a naturalistic approach have to say about culture?
It certainly disagrees with the view that as cultural beings we have transcended
nature or left the apes behind. But it does not go on from there to make “culture”
some sort of enemy we need to get away from if we are ever to become more
natural. Both of these positions only reinforce the human/nature dualism. An inter-
active view of nature and culture sees them, rather, as internally related moments
within a unified and processual reality. From the Latin cultura, “culture” referred in
its earliest uses to the tending of natural growth.19 In this sense culture is essentially
a verb, a cultivating, a kind of techne or artful attending to the life process.20 When
we conceive of culture as “an historically transmitted pattern of meanings embodied
in symbols,”21 such symbol systems may therefore be looked at in terms of how they
serve the natural world and complete our own bodily nature. As Mary Midgley puts
it: “What we build into our cultures has to satisfy our natural pattern of motives.”22
Note, moreover, that an interactive model reframes the old nature/nurture debate.
The issue is not whether traits are innate or whether they are acquired (or some
aggregate of the two), as if these were wholly distinct options, but how cultural pat-
terns reorganize or affect our nature and how our nature always anticipates certain
kinds of culturing. What matters, in other words (and to repeat a by now familiar
line), is the reciprocity or dialogue between body and world, in which person and
environment do not begin as independent entities making their separate contribu-
tions (as psychologists have historically conceived of them), but as poles within a
single interactive process of being-in-the- world or meaning creation.23
Naturalism, then, does not mean turning away from culture but being all
the more demanding of it. Erazim Kohák writes that “culture is not the contradic-
tion of nature but rather the task of humans within it.” It follows, furthermore,
that the relationship between nature and culture is asymmetric. Our bodies are
prior to any one culture, even as they anticipate a culture. As the grounding or
governing moment of human existence, our own bodily nature thus “reserves the
right to judge culture, and resist and revise it.”24 We often mistake the plasticity
of human culture for the plasticity of human nature, entranced by the spectacle
and variability of the former, while neglectful of the constraints and claims of the
latter. Knowing this, we may examine our culture for just how willing it is to adjust
itself to nature’s demands. “A healthy culture,” says Wendell Berry, “is a communal
order of memory, insight, value, work, conviviality, reverence, aspiration. It reveals
the human necessities and the human limits. It clarifies our inescapable bonds to
the earth and to each other. It ensures that the necessary restraints are observed,
that the necessary work is done, and that it is done well.”25 Snyder also remarks
that it “has always been part of basic human experience to live in a culture of wil-
derness.”26 It is a simple fact that our culture is mostly geared to meet the needs
of the political economic body, rather than the given needs of the body of nature.
Naturalistic psychology, accordingly, cannot avoid criticizing this culture; and to
this I turn more thematically in the final chapter.
us from both below and outside of human history. I would like the idea that we
are hermeneutic creatures to embrace both of these worlds—the historical and the
natural—as one. So far, however, most hermeneutic thinkers have emphasized only
that we belong to history. As Marjorie Grene remarks, “the stress on historicity
seems to entail ignoring nature.”28 More strongly, Shepard writes that “the idea of
history is itself a western invention whose central theme is the rejection of habitat.
It formulates experience outside of nature and tends to reduce place to a stage upon
which the human drama is enacted.”29 Not Wind and Crow, but history now
teaches us our lessons. In arguing against biological reductionism, Heidegger spoke
rather oddly of “our appalling and scarcely conceivable kinship with the beasts.”30
The mistake he made was to assume that affirming our kinship with other ani-
mals plunges us immediately into biologism. To the contrary, Grene argues, against
Heidegger, that not to acknowledge our animality itself “constitutes an ontological
omission,” that is, it misses an essential aspect of our being.31 My own project is
exactly to articulate human existence within the process of life: to ground our his-
torical meaning-making, or to formulate our experience, entirely inside the body of
nature. This section aims to add some further weight to this undertaking.
In referring to life as a “hermeneutic sense-making journey,” I am invoking
the presence of the wing-footed Greek god Hermes, the go-between the divine and
mortal spheres, deliverer and interpreter of messages from the gods to humans.32
For all his mythological richness, however, my sense of the hermeneutic mode of
existence comes less from the actual character of Hermes than from what herme-
neutics has made in his name.33 I start with the bias that all humans have an
inherent desire to understand deeply. The same assumption is made by saying that
a “thirst for experience is a part of all life,” or that human existence “is innately
disposed to an extremely broad experience.”34 Meaning may be invisible, yet it is
what we live for. Humans are beings who are simply unable to live in a cosmos that
does not—somehow—make sense. Clifford Geertz notes that chaos is a condition
in which events are uninterpretable; where our intellect is baffled, our suffering
unbearable, or our moral problems defiant of insight.35 Chaos is intolerable; it
nakedly reveals the void while offering no bearings. Thus, the more chaotic and
insecure our world gets, the more must we devise symbolic means to keep our
balance and ward off our nausea. The Cartesian search for absolute foundations,
for instance, betrays an anxious existence whose sense-making is directed toward
gaining control over or stabilizing a fluid and threatening reality, toward stilling
the flux. Many delusions, if not all of them, are ironically based on this need
to make sense, where our anxieties will not permit us a less distorted grasp of
reality. The less existentially unified we are, the less tolerant we are of ambiguity
or of contrary views, and the more insistent we are that our concepts be final,
our world be unchanging. In short, then, it is by questioning into the process of
sense-making that I wish to help find a way through to a more ontologically secure
and so less violent mode of understanding—one that is experientially rich and in
which nature, of course, figures prominently.
Only the support of the familiar and common understanding makes possible
the venture into the alien . . . and thus the broadening and enrichment of
our own experience of the world.
—Hans-Georg Gadamer37
The title for this principle comes from Shepard, who writes that psychological
maturity “celebrates a central analogy of self and world in ever-widening spheres
of meaning and participation, not an ever-growing domination over nature,
escape into abstraction, or existentialist funk.”38 The principle is that we are
innately moved to differentiate and enter into progressively more encompassing
realms of otherness, to dialectically widen out the ground of our being or the
spheres of our understanding, thus developing an ever-growing horizon of
awareness. It refers to the opening out of a life process, the moving into deeper
and wider contact with the world, the building up of a sense of common ground
or of belonging with others (“the widening and deepening of love”),39 in the
process of which we ourselves emerge, step by step, as the unique persons we are
called to be. That human psychological development or individuation progresses
as a relational project, as a process of bonding with and then separating from
others, is well-recognized.40 The ecopsychological maneuver is simply to assert
that this process wishes to continue beyond the human realm, that our humanity
is incomplete until we have established our kinship or social relations with
the larger natural world and so satisfied our longing to feel at home in or at
peace with the cosmos as a whole. As Abram writes, the human body is a “form
destined to the world . . . a sort of open circuit that completes itself only in
things, in others, in the encompassing earth.”41
person progresses “from one womb to yet another,” each of these analogous to the
former, yet experienced on a new or higher plane. The child thus moves through
a series of developmental matrices that begin with the mother’s actual womb and
then extends outward to the mother herself; to the interior of the dwelling-hut;
to the village camp; to the children’s playground; and finally to the surrounding
forest. Each transition to a new realm of otherness is the crossing of a critical junc-
ture, a leap into the unknown. Thus when the mother for the first time brings her
child out of the hut to greet the camp (both of which are spherical in shape), the
“infant learns that there is a plurality of warm bodies, similar in warmth (which
is comforting) but dissimilar in smells and rhythmic movements and sounds. If
it is disconcerted enough to cry in protest, its mother immediately takes it back
[to the hut] and puts it to her breast. Thus an initial model of predictability and
security is reinforced.”49
Note how the mother’s caring actions help the child to navigate the latter’s
relation to the void. We are best supported to grow or phusically emerge as a dif-
ferentiated being when we remain grounded in that sense of wholeness that comes
from being lovingly connected to others.50 To stand apart as an autonomous self
is otherwise to risk a terrifying aloneness. A good developmental process, then, is
one that “emphasizes relationships to others, so that intensified separateness does
not maroon but establishes the self as ever more unique and yet more fully bonded
to nonselves by chains of interaction, kinship, dependence, cooperation, and com-
pliance.”51 Against our modern prejudice, Tim Ingold argues that hunter-gatherers
generally do enjoy a kind of individualism, but unlike our own, theirs is “grounded
in the social totality.”52 As he describes it, the un-folding of a life is at the same time
an en-folding of others into one’s own being—thus confirming Winnicott’s observ
ation that the assimilation of good others as a caring and affirming inner presence
is essential to the capacity to enjoy or tolerate solitude.53 In our own shaming
society, we face the problem of the “mass” person or weak individual who lacks the
inner security to break out of his or her conformity or confluence with the crowd.
As individuals, we fear living—emerging as a differentiated self—because we lack
the ontological security to do so, because it puts us too close to the void. We then
also fear dying—the dedifferentiating of ourselves—because we have not yet lived.
Existentialists typically look down on this fearful “herd” mentality, counseling us
to courageously stand out from a meaningless nature, and so face the abyss. What
they generally don’t do, however, is trace the origins of our mass fear (as well as our
grandiose, shame-based, limit-denying fantasies) to a loss of loving relations. They
thus turn our sense of isolation into an essential fact of existence rather than a cre
ation of our despiritualized and denatured historical condition.
Bearing these thoughts in mind, I also wish to conceive of this journey as
a spiritual project. Under good conditions, it is the evolution of desire as the life
force presses us on toward spirit, or the dissolution of Ego as we make good contact
with others.54 Using the notion of “the primitive” not pejoratively but as a way to
evaluate civilized society, Stanley Diamond writes that “the primitive self cannot
be reduced to an [E]go but is the result of a hierarchy of experiences, incorporated
into an increasingly spiritualized being as maturation proceeds from birth through
the multiple rebirths symbolized in the crisis rites, to ancestry of others.”55 Good
conditions, as I define them, are those that do not lead to a reification or halting
of experience, but rather allow for ongoing growth at the contact boundary, this
being a zone of experience that is balanced between the twin terrors of isolation and
fusion. Such conditions generally allow our desires to change their nature as the self
is gradually transformed from an early state of near-total dependency on the service
of others to one in which the wish to ourselves serve others is increasingly realized.
In other words, the equilibrium won through the meeting of a need or completion
of an experience is immediately disturbed by the further stirring of the life force, as
it urges the self ever-more deeply into the world. “Here desire takes on the shape of
Eros, or love, and unifies the self with object in ever-widening totalities.”56 Under
bad conditions, on the other hand, our desires do not only remain a spur to further
growth and challenge, but also become overfrustrated. The world then becomes a
dangerous place from which we must protect ourselves and toward which we harbor
some measure of hatred, our fears now fixing others into threatening aliens.57 In this
case, the experiential field cannot differentiate but, tragically, must split.
As a final point under this principle, I wish to stress that the spiritualization
of the self is also its sociation, the widening of its social horizons, as the discus-
sion above has already suggested. To be sociated is to derive our identity from
our embeddedness within a society. “Living through participation in the life of
others, the inner self becomes a congregation of the Other.”58 Parents are only one
form of otherness in this journey, even if we get stuck on them in this society. To
the growing child, parents play the role of nature, the source of being, but do so
only as one phase or occasion in the larger human-nature dialectic that is human
nature. As Kovel notes, viewing parents in this manner places our (albeit crucial)
interactions with them within a spiritual framework and opens the possibility for
a psychology that looks beyond (human) familial relations.59 More specifically, the
work of ecopsychology is to develop a psychology that embeds humans within a
more-than-human society. The anthropocentrism that has so far prevented psy-
chologists from doing so is an enormously blinding prejudice, which because
it ignores our need to differentiate and relate to nonhuman others, contributes
to that state in which the natural world remains a largely homogeneous and so
threateningly alien presence.60 In traditional societies where humans are but a
minor presence in the landscape, not attending to social relations with the natural
world is unthinkable. For the Mbuti, for instance, social life is permeated by one’s
relations to the forest. All Mbuti, young and old, “talk, shout, whisper, and sing
to the forest . . . , addressing it as mother or father or both [depending on how
they feel at the moment], referring to its goodness and ability to ‘cure’ or ‘make
good.’”61 For the Koyukon, similarly, “the environment is like a second society in
which people live, governed by elaborate rules of behavior and etiquette. . . . The
surroundings are aware, sensate, personified. They feel. They can be offended.”62
Nelson tells a story of being with an elder who at one point begins speaking in
earnest to a bird. “For how many thousand generations, I wondered, have people
spoken and prayed to natural beings around them, as a customary part of daily
life? At any other time in human history, this event would be as ordinary as talking
to another person.”63 Going to the heart of the matter, he remarks that the failure
of this kind of “understanding in our own culture is where the depth and poign-
ancy of our own loss lies. Losing the recognition of spirituality in nature may be
the most important transformation of the human mind in all of human history.”64
That “nature is a social place”65 is especially evident in the words spoken by
a Navajo elder, Old Torlino, just before telling part of the creation story:
Recall that the emotion of shame is associated with our very social sense. I do not
read the shame expressed here as neurotic, but as the humbling of a self before
the whole society of nature, an admitting of the fallibility of one’s humanity, of
one’s capacity to do harm or show disrespect, at a spiritually significant moment.
If, moreover, Old Torlino is able to feel some shame before the natural world,
then we may speculate that in a violent society such as ours the discovery of a
tremendous well of shame, including that related to our mistreatment of other-
than-human beings, is an event waiting to happen for most of us. As Turnbull
suggests, to be truly dedicated to Spirit is also to be dedicated to Society or to the
greater social Self.67 If nature is itself a social place, then the ecological crisis is
both a spiritual crisis and a pathological disturbance in this largest of social fields.
The landscape and the language are the same. For we ourselves are landscape
and are land.
—Conrad Aiken68
from the perceptual interplay between the body and the world, then this lan-
guage ‘belongs’ to the animate landscape as much a it ‘belongs’ to ourselves.”72
Heidegger is remembered for saying that language is the “house of being.” He
did not, however, call this house a human prison. Language, he said, borrowing
from the poetry of Hölderlin, is “the flower of the mouth. In language the earth
blossoms toward the bloom of the sky.”73 Language is in this case a phenomenon
of nature: it has sensuous, earthy roots, yet also the clarity and lightness of the sky.
Hence, Merleau-Ponty’s line that “in a sense . . . language is everything, since it
is the voice of no one, since it is the very voice of the things, the waves, and the
forests.”74
What I have said so far is not the whole story, for words do not just come to
us via some direct pipe from the natural world. Rather, there is a circular relation
between the two. Merleau-Ponty held that “the body is, so to speak, predestined to
model itself on the natural aspects of the world. But as an active body of gestures,
of expression, and finally of language, it turns back on the world to signify it.”75
Language, in this view, originates as a kind of gesture that draws its meaning from
our contact with the world, but our perception of this world is itself structured by
the language already sedimented into it. That is to say, our linguistic symbols not
only make the world intelligible but in doing so also change the world, bringing it
forth in a way that favors a particular view or interpretation. The Merleau-Pontian
interpretation I want to forward here is that language, on the one hand, and the
phenomenal world, on the other, form two open systems which mirror and feed
one another; that the world knows itself as it is reflected in language, and language
knows itself only as it is reflected in the actual world.
Much current thought about language traces back to the structuralist Fer-
dinand de Saussure, who observed that language systems are not composed of
independent linguistic elements but rather form organic totalities, with internal
relations among their parts.
In English, for instance, the sounded word “red” draws its precise meaning from
its situation in a network of like-sounding terms, including, for instance, “read,”
“rod,” “reed,” and “raid,” and in a whole complex of color terms, such as “orange,”
“yellow,” “purple,” “brown”; as well as from its participation in a still wider nexus
of related terms like “blood,” “rose,” “sunset,” “fire,” “blush,” “angry,” “hot,” each
of which holds significance only in relation to a constellation of still other words,
expanding thus outward to every term within the language. By describing any par-
ticular language as a system of differences, Saussure indicated that meaning is found
not in the words themselves but in the intervals, the contrasts, the participations
between the terms.76
left unmoored, unaffiliated with place and the sentient beings there.” Language,
cut off from the wider natural world, goes its own delirious way. Or as Marcel
Detienne writes: “As soon as mankind ceases to ‘reverberate’ to the world, the
sickness penetrates language,” which becomes “the victim of illusions produced
by words.”102 Because our speaking is so disjunctive with the earth’s own voices,
Martin suggests that we have in a very real sense become less-than-human.103
The task, then, is to reopen the circuit between language and the larger
world in order to permit into our language a vital return flow of meaning. In
this, we again need acknowledge a crucial asymmetry: the living world outside of
human language, the world of creeks and porcupines and leaves, even if revealed
through language, is the given, primary reality, the ultimate social context to
which our speaking must in good health remain faithful. As with much else of
significance to ecopsychology, models of such faithfulness are best found among
indigenous persons. Speaking of the Okanagan, for example, Jeannette Armstrong
writes that “the land taught us our language. The way we survived is to speak the
language that the land offered us as its teachings.”104 Sean Kane refers to the myth-
telling of archaic peoples as a poetic “dialogue with nature,” “an affectionate coun-
terpoint to the earth’s voices.” A myth, he says, “is the power of a place speaking,”
conveying events as much from the perspective of the spirit world as the human.
Such oral myths, moreover, are typically complex in the middle, but with “no pro-
nounced beginning or end.” This openness at the edges, then, deliberately allows
for an influx of meaning from the surrounding wilderness.105 We of the modern
world are not myth-tellers, at least not of the oral sort described by Kane. We are,
however, still people who, being of the natural order, are claimed by nature to use
our language in its service. As Merleau-Ponty taught, the “call to language . . .
originates from beyond language in an unspoken, or silence, that appropriates us
or demands . . . a singing expression.”106 Language is not a closed system of verbal
forms, but a mode of poetizing, of allowing for the disclosure of new meanings,
new forms, in our dwelling on or listening to the earth.107 Authentic speech, that
is, is a response to our felt sense of what in the world needs to be said, to the
“unspoken aspects of the world that seek expression.” As before, I suggest that the
demand for such speech gives us our embodied starting place.
The body . . . offers to him who inhabits it and senses it the wherewithal
to sense everything that resembles himself on the outside. . . . If it touches
[things] and sees them, this is only because, being of their family, itself
visible and tangible, it uses its own being as a means to participate in theirs,
because each exists as an archetype for the other, because the body belongs to
the order of things as the world is universal flesh.
—Maurice Merleau-Ponty108
The flesh is not matter, is not mind, is not substance. To designate it, we should
need the old term “element,” in the sense it was used to speak of water, air, earth,
and fire, that is, in the sense of a general thing.110
As the element of being itself, flesh is a medium more primary than mind and
matter, which are differentiations within the flesh. In this case, language, too, is a
kind of flesh; one that is “less heavy,” or “more transparent,” than other kinds.111
As we saw above, language and the perceived world, although different, are not
discontinuous. Rather, they resemble one another and are meaningful exactly in
the way they reflect one another as different sorts of flesh.112 Our bodies, moreover,
are made of the same flesh as the world and the world shares in the flesh of our
bodies.113 Just as we speak of a shared or common humanity, so may we thus speak
more broadly of a common flesh. I consider this Merleau-Ponty’s way of saying that
“we too are nature,” of conceptualizing our embeddedness in, or continuity with,
the wider natural world.114 Something in us vibrates to the cry of wolves, to the
play of bears; we are not some purely inward, acosmic stuff, but rather of the same
flesh as bird song and snow. A deeply buried preunderstanding of our oneness
in flesh is exactly what permits us to touch or understand one another. In other
words, the nature or style of flesh is such that contact is possible. It “has a porous
quality that allows, even requires, a coming and going through it; by definition,
flesh ‘breathes’ or seeps, as well as containing or separating.”115 Given that the
flesh is a single elemental fabric, each instance of contact is, furthermore, a case of
flesh touching itself, of its folding back on or differentiating and mirroring itself. A
calloused hand is thus flesh knowing itself as skin contacts (touches and is touched
by) the rough surfaces of ropes and ladders, a delicate one as skin contacts the
smoothness of pen and paper. To gather in this way the commonness or generalness
of flesh has a decentering or transpersonalizing effect on the self, for all perceiving
becomes not the activity of individuals, but of the world itself.
While Merleau-Ponty’s formulation of the flesh may be an original con-
tribution to Western philosophy, his ideas by no means stand alone. The poet
Rainer Maria Rilke, for instance, wrote that we “are set down in life as in the
element to which we best correspond” and, moreover, that “when we hold still
we are scarcely to be distinguished from all that surrounds us.”116 It is this theme
of a correspondence between ourselves and others that I wish to pursue. At the
heart of this philosophy is the idea that like can only touch like; that we can con-
tact the world only when able to sense in ourselves something that resembles or
resonates with it.117 Bruno Snell held, for example, that “man could never have
come to experience a rock anthropomorphically if he had not also experienced
himself ‘petromorphically.’ ”118 “Things,” in other words, “have an internal equiva-
lent in me.”119 Bringing this principle into an ecological context, Shepard writes:
“Wild species are true Others, the components of wilderness, and at the same
time are the external correlates of our inmost selves.”120 The visible world, in
other words, provides the tangible symbols to call forth or connect us with the
intangible aspects of our own being. “We are selves composed of sleeping figures,”
says Shepard, “each a secret that can be awakened in acts of correspondence.”121
Other animals have always been used for human self-understanding, from totem
animals to everyday metaphors (e.g., sloth, weasel), where some aspect of the ani-
mal’s nature corresponds to or matches some quality in ourselves. The “otherness
of stones and stars,” meanwhile, “are models for thinking our humbleness in the
universe, and they are the key to the strangeness of ourselves.”122
Having introduced the principle of “one flesh,” I wish to use it in what
remains of this discussion to revisit a number of psychological notions, and so
show further what a nondualistic and naturalistic psychology might look like. All
of the interactive concepts I introduced in chapter three still apply. Here, I am
only adding to that discussion.
Projection, first, is normally spoken of in negative tones. It is taken to mean
the act of attributing some psychological content from inside ourselves to the out-
side world, such that we misperceive things. We anthropomorphize or personify
our pets, think everyone is out to get us, or otherwise fill the world with fancy
imaginings that exist only in our heads. No doubt our perception of others is often
faulty. But the usual understanding of projection suffers both from a persistent
dualism and from a limited and dismal view of imagination. Most important,
our being is never located “inside” ourselves to begin with, but (as I have dis-
cussed at length) is always in-the-world, as a field phenomenon. Thus, how we
imagine the world is not just a solipsistic act but is based on what sort of style of
relating we have so far established with others, on how we are currently knotted
into the world’s flesh. We do not pollute things with our subjectivity; rather, they
show up somehow in the light of our worldly existence. Medard Boss observed,
in this regard, that “when the phenomena of my world confront me they reveal,
of their great store of meanings, only those to which my perception—in the state
of my existence at that time—is open.”123 We may note, then, that projection
certainly does have something to do with how we are attuned to the world, but
this attunement is a function of the ground of our existence, not some mech-
anism inside us. In this view, imagination is not simply a discrete mental faculty
for making things up.124 It refers instead to how all of our perception involves
more than what is just immediately given to our senses, for we always participate
in what we experience, imagining events in the context of the experiential back-
ground or felt biases we bring to them, the clearing our existence holds open. A
snake may appear frightening to us, for example, because ours is the kind of exist-
ence wherein we imagine such animals biting us. We make sense of the world,
that is, in a way that corresponds to the condition of our own existence, seeing in
the world (projecting) that which resonates to the possibilities we can imagine
from within the context of our own experiential history. Stated still otherwise: the
visible surface of reality is the symbolic clue to its invisible depths, and it is only
through imagining these depths that we reach into the hidden flesh of the world
and so make contact with others at all.125
What, then, of projection in a negative sense? Consider the case I men-
tioned in chapter three, in which the person who slaughters wolves was said to
repress all that is violent, irrational, insatiable, and disinhibited in himself and
then to project these qualities onto wolves. I suggest that the real issue here is
not projection per se, but the quality of this projection and the poverty of con-
tact that obtains under a repressed condition. For even if his own “beastliness”
is repressed—or, rather, precisely because of this—the wolf-hater’s existence is
implicitly attuned to the “beast”-like qualities in others. Wolves get singled out
because their nature actually does correspond, if only trivially (i.e., because they are
wild and predatory), to those qualities negated by the hunter. The wolves, that is,
serve as the slimmest symbolic cue for calling forth the blocked and ugly meanings
in the background of the hunter’s life. The bias created by these off-base meanings
then reveal the wolves in a relatively distorted or untruthful way. Where there is
little contact with others, as here with the wolves, the imaginative component of
our experience might therefore better be called fantasy. As Stephen Levine notes,
imagination “is the means by which we reach out and connect with otherness,”
whereas fantasy “ignores actuality in creating images of pleasure or pain.”126 The
way to dissolve fantasy projections is thus not to eliminate projection, but to
make better contact with the world, thereby converting “fantasy” into “imagina-
tion” and owning our repressed feelings. The idea within a hermeneutic frame-
work, to repeat, is that we can perceive others more faithfully only by more openly
approaching them, letting them “talk back” to us, and so revising the imagina-
tive biases by which we (necessarily) perceive them.127 This amounts, in turn, to
thickening up the sense of fleshy connection between us, recognizing ourselves in
them, feeling our own flesh caught up with theirs. Indeed, Lopez remarks that we
have broken our ancient contracts with other animals in two main ways: through
a failure of everyday contact and through a related failure of imagination.128
In a similar vein, the environmental researcher Tom Fleischner has called natural
animals come into our dreams as guides, helpers, and saviors. . . . they teach us
about something, but they are not part of us. The bear dream that one man had
corresponds with his own earthy, shaggy nature, and therefore he can feel an affinity.
But that bear is not his own shaggy nature. That reduces the bear to just a piece of
himself and insults the bear—it interprets the bear away. The presence of the bear in
the dream corresponds to qualities of the human soul, but is not reducible to it.137
my night existence, I feel that I am being visited, not that I am merely projecting
myself.139 It is this fleshy reciprocation between ourselves and the otherness we
experience, so well-exemplified in dreams, that is at the paradoxical or ambiguous
heart of all experience: that our experience is ours, yet not ours; that in order to
make contact with it we must identify with it, yet dis-identify from it; and that we
are as one with the otherness we experience, yet different.
Finally, I return to the notion of kinship. I have left this notion for last
because, as we have seen, a philosophy of the flesh suggests that kinship exists
between all sorts of realms of reality, where there exists some common ground
or likeness between them but where they necessarily maintain their distance and
difference. In fact, in every moment of contact or act of correspondence we experi-
ence some commonality, sense the other as like unto ourselves. What is familiar
is family. Following Merleau-Ponty, perception is “the mode of relatedness that
separates us from ourselves and thereby brings us into contact with the things that
teach us about themselves and ourselves.”140 For ecopsychologists, it is vital to
note, in this respect, that prior to domestic times “animals served as delicate signs
of the way the world goes, as elaborate metaphors and symbols, as spiritual beings,
and as themselves.”141 As Gary Snyder asks:
What do we learn from Wren, and Hummingbird, and Pine Pollen, and how? Learn
what? Specifics: how to spend a life facing the current [salmon]; or what it is to
perpetually die young; or how to be huge and calm and eat anything (Bear). But also
that we are many selves looking at each other, through the same eye.142
we are in our own particular ways attuned to the world. In general, however, the
“highest order of maturity” is achieved, suggests Searles, when one is able to relate
to, find likeness in, what on the surface seems “most unlike oneself.”148
The general effect I have been after under this heading is the realization that
all things correspond to (reflect, echo, mirror, metaphor, resemble) one another
and only because of this have sense for us. This realization is common in the
worlds of indigenous peoples, where the likenesses or analogies among things are a
source of constant learning, where all things are potential symbolic mirrors—as
is endlessly worked out in such instruments as the medicine wheels used by some
Native North Americans.149 The world experienced by primary peoples is often
described as one with fluid boundaries, such that no absolute lines can be drawn
among human, animal, and spirit realms; a world of metamorphoses, shape-
shiftings, transformations. Joseph Epes Brown writes of the Lakota world that “the
correspondence between levels of reality are as if one were the reflection of the
other; they flow into each other in a manner that expresses a total, integrated
environment.”150 A naturalistic psychology would explore these correspondences
or resonances, would be a project of learning to recognize ourselves in what was
formerly alien, of shifting ourselves along the kinship continuum or deepening
our perception of the unity of the world’s flesh. It would also emphasize that
hyperdifferentiation or splitting is a possibility given in the very differential structure
of the flesh, and that when we harden our boundaries, and so attenuate our sense of
kinship with others, we suffer a spiritual loss.
Beneath the veneer of civilization, in the trite phrase of humanism, lies not
the barbarian and the animal, but the human in us who knows what is
right and necessary for becoming fully human: birth in gentle surroundings,
a rich nonhuman environment, juvenile tasks with simple tools, the
discipline of natural history, play at being animals, the expressive arts of
receiving food as a spiritual gift rather than as a product, the cultivation
of metaphorical significance of natural phenomena of all kinds, clan
membership and small group life, and the profound claims and liberation of
ritual initiation and subsequent stages of adult mentorship.
—Paul Shepard151
high levels of stress and trauma, war and strife, social alienation, and ecological
dysfunction are therefore the consequence of our having strayed from a general
form of social life that is more in tune with the claims of wild nature and better
suited to fulfilling our own generic expectations or needs.154 Such ideas have
greatly influenced my own, and it is to them that I wish to devote this section.
Whether Shepard got all the details right seems to me beside the point. What is
appealing is the vision of an unfolding of human life into ecologically mature
adulthood, in which caregivers, mentors, and other-than-human beings provide
good symbolic nutrition for completing the gestalts that the child’s maturing body
are organizing at any given time, thus revealing to him “the meaning of his own
impulses, by providing them with an aim.”155 It is a vision in which our inherent
world-relations find the specific kind of responses from others that will satisfy
them, thereby lighting up the way to self-knowledge and to a sense of cosmic-at-
homeness. I do not believe humans to be strangers on this earth. All along in this
chapter I have in fact been working on the assumption that we all desire to be
nurtured into loving relations with the cosmos, and that the achievement of same
is a very real possibility. In what follows, therefore, my aim is to briefly consider
some of the specifics.
Because this is an exercise in matters transhistorical, I must make some addi-
tional precautionary remarks. First, I think the idea of an inherent psychogenesis
that includes other-than-human beings gains strength once we recognize a number
of unfair prejudices working against it. Most obviously, developmental psycholo-
gists have effectively shut out the world of butterflies, ponds, and porcupines—a
condition little changed since Searles first remarked on it forty years ago.156 It has
thus not occurred to researchers, furthermore, to ask about the possible ongoing
harm of being restricted to domestic, human-dominated settings—as opposed to
the more wild, multispecific sorts that have been the norm for all humans up until
only recent times (considered on the scale of the deep past of our species). One
important exception is the psychologist Gene Myers, who claims that the essence
of our humanity lies not in our discontinuity from the rest of nature, as is normally
assumed, but in our ability to sense our commonality with it all. Seen from this
reverse perspective, maturity is the outcome not of transcending our animality or
participation in nature, but of realizing it ever more fully.157 Indeed, to see life as
a quest for meaning and belonging on the largest of social scales is, as Edith Cobb
said, to reorient psychology toward our “total relations with ‘outerness,’ with
nature itself.”158 And then there is the prejudice that to posit a need for “nature” is
romantic or nostalgic, the deluded product of an infantile longing for lost origins
that never were. As I have discussed above, and will elaborate further below, my
response to this charge is that our experience suggests otherwise. Finally, consider
a comment made by the chief engineer for the Three Gorges hydroelectric scheme
on the Yangtze River in China: “If we return to nature we cannot develop.”159 He
meant economic development, of course. Yet “development” is a metaphor whose
original meaning was biological, that is, natural. Insofar as it is prejudiced against
nature, “economic development” is thus an oxymoron.160 Indeed, I suggest that
the engineer gets it exactly backward; for it is only by “returning to nature” that
we can truly develop.161
That our bodily nature is self-organizing supports the kind of suggestion
made by Shepard that we carry a preknowledge of what will be right for us as
we extend ourselves out into the world, even if the particulars of this knowl-
edge may be open to interpretive debate. My aim below, in this regard, is to put
some relatively sure detail to the three principles I discussed above (ever-widening
spheres; singing the world; one flesh). The more these principles are illustrated,
and so reciprocally fleshed out, the more will they make sense, and the more will a
certain scheme of human life become apparent. As with any other cyclic phenom-
enon, a human life is not without inherent organization. If nothing else, finally,
I would stress that our psychological development is not only a process of going
through our maturational sequences, but also of signifying the world—of coming
to understand ourselves in relation to a more-than-human universe. This makes
the topic of “nature and the human life cycle” of potential relevance to anyone
who thinks about this relation. In what follows, I walk through the life cycle,
focusing on the nature of infancy, childhood, and the adolescent transition into
adulthood. This is another huge topic in its own right. I ask the reader, therefore,
to bear in mind that my intention is not to offer an exhaustive treatise, but only
an evocative sketch.162
Loving Mirrors for the Infant. That we are fleshy mirrors for one another is never
more evident than in infancy. For it is through those intense and decisive inter
actions with her or his caregivers that the baby’s self takes shape. Infant and care-
giver are caught up in each other’s being in such a way that simply undercuts any
dualistic view of reality. The voices of caregivers awaken the infant’s first smile;
their faces reflect and give form to her or his first feelings.163 Parent and infant
famously exist in a state of mysterious synchrony, of mutual experiencing, where
there is a “feeling mainline” between them.164 Whereas early infants were once
thought to be nonrelational or passive, a more recent view is that they are percep-
tually discriminating and interactive right from the start.165 While newborns may
not be reflectively aware of their difference from others, they nonetheless do live
in their interactions, searching for nurturance from a source outside themselves.166
The caregivers’ mirroring responses, nurturing acts, and energetic adjustments,
moreover, symbolize for infants the latter’s preverbal experiencing, thereby car-
rying it forward. Infants make sense of their own experience, that is, primarily
through their caregivers, as this is something that they are at birth not yet able
to do for themselves via their own self-responses (at least that is what it seems).
Indeed, these exchanges are part of the process whereby infants begin to satisfy
their inborn desire to discover the world’s meaning—what has been called their
“cosmological urge.” Even the child’s play with her or his own body is what Erik
Erikson called “autocosmic play.”167 This urge is evident also in those moments
where infants interact with their nonhuman surroundings, as when, for instance,
they interrupt their feeding in order to curiously gaze at something interesting, say
a cat, that has caught their attention. Feeding, we may therefore note, is “capable
of being usurped by a deeper hunger, namely the search for a comprehensible
world.”168
All these interactions are far from arbitrary, however. For as Gendlin writes:
“Much more arrives at birth than a blank tablet. . . . The human infant implies
the breast and the mother. . . . Infants come with good mothering already implicit,
interpersonal communication already ongoing, the complexity of syntax already
in place. They need not first be made from perceptions.”169 There is what Jean
Liedloff calls a “continuum” between caregiver and child. Even if the baby refuses
the breast, as sometimes happens, the baby-breast relation is still a general inter-
action-pattern of our species, and the fluid in the mother’s breast still implies the
infant in turn. When infants contribute their poetic babble to the dialogue at a
social gathering, moreover, and cry in protest when taken away, it is hard not to
recognize their “innate desire to be included in shared activity, to be acknowl-
edged as a participant in the linguistic community.”170 Infant and caregiving
environment are, then, a single field of mutually anticipated world-relations. As
Goodman notes, the infant is a helpless being only when seen in isolation from
the total social context that her or his existence implies. Regarded as part of the
whole prefigured caregiving field, the child is not helpless at all.171 Of significance
to ecopsychology is the distinct possibility that the relational field implied by the
infant’s body also includes a richness of other-than-human beings. Although the
most important relational matrix for the infant is no doubt human, Shepard sug-
gests that the nonhuman setting for that nexus is thus also highly significant. He
speaks of:
a surround of living plants, rich in texture, smell, and motion. The unfiltered,
unpolluted air, the flicker of wild birds, real sunshine and rain, mud to be tasted and
tree bark to grasp, the sounds of wind and water, the voices of animals and insects
and humans—all these are not vague and pleasant amenities for the infant, but the
stuff out of which its . . . grounding [in the matrix of the earth], even while in its
mother’s arms, has begun. . . . it is a world bathed in nonhuman forms, a myriad of
figures, evoking an intense sense of the differences and similarities, the beckoning
challenge of a lifetime.172
outdoors in order to introduce them to blue jays, squirrels, and such,174 and to let
them get into all those earthy things close at hand.
Reflecting on a lifetime of experience, Harold Searles wrote: “I am con-
vinced . . . that lovingness is the basic stuff of human personality, and that it is with
a wholehearted openness to loving relatedness that the newborn infant responds to
the outside world.”175 Jean Liedloff likewise notes: “The feeling appropriate to an
infant in arms is his feeling of rightness, or essential goodness. . . . All babies are
good, but can know it themselves only by reflection, by the way they are treated.
There is no other viable way for a human to feel about himself; all other kinds of
feeling are unusable as a foundation for well-being.”176 I cannot imagine an infant
who does not need to be loved simply because she or he is. For such is the foun-
dation for loving relations toward both ourselves and others. The world-relations
called for at this time are thus those reliable, responsive, and adaptive ones that will
hold a safe space for infants and preserve their core feelings of continuity, trust,
and innocence. No two babies are exactly alike; we enter the world with different
genes, past karmas, destinies, personalities, or whatever. It is for this reason that I
also emphasize the general need to have our specific needs lovingly recognized and
adapted to by our caregivers. As Mary Ainsworth has documented, empathic and
responsive caregiving177 has a “buffering” effect even on infants born with consti-
tutional difficulties.178 Among most primal peoples, a continuous maintenance
of closeness, and attendance to the infant’s particular needs, reportedly results in
children who are securely attached to their caregivers (i.e., who have a sure emo-
tional tie with them) and so who cheerfully and freely explore the transitional
space away from them.179 Much study on attachment and separation by Western
researchers also supports the idea that genuine independence is won only by having
our early dependency needs well-met, despite the still frequently held belief that
doing so only “spoils” children (especially males) or actually prevents them from
becoming independent.180 For the anxiously attached infant, who was perhaps
forced to “grow up,” life will predictably be marred by insecurities of all kinds,
and much of life may be spent seeking little more than proof that one exists.181 I
stress this point because so many serious psychological disturbances surface in the
wake of abuses occurring at this vulnerable stage in life. The so-called borderline
personality disorder, for example, which involves chaotic or crisis-filled interper-
sonal relations and a severe fear of abandonment, is often traced by clinicians to
poor attachment experiences in infancy, including situations in which the young
child was punished for taking steps toward autonomy182 (as well as to situations
of early sexual and physical abuse).183 Borderline personalities are also prevalent
among men who batter their female partners—a significant finding given the cur-
rent crisis of domestic violence.184 In contrast to the traumatized infant, then, it is
the well-loved baby who is generally able to spontaneously move on to the further
stages of childhood with a relative absence of unfinished infantile business.
A Childhood Immersion in the “Natural World.” Naturalists Gary Paul Nabhan and
Stephen Trimble are not shy about claiming that “children need wild places” (nor
is child psychiatrist Robert Coles, who comments in the introduction to their book
that all “young people ache for nature”).185 The view worked out by these and other
authors is that in childhood the innate urge toward meaning creation and social
belonging takes the matrix of the earth as its locus. In a much-celebrated study
on “the ecology of imagination in childhood,” Edith Cobb wrote that “there is a
special period, the little understood, prepubertal, halcyon, middle age of childhood,
approximately from five or six to eleven or twelve—between the strivings of animal
infancy and the storms of adolescence—when the natural world is experienced in
some highly evocative way, producing in the child a sense of profound continuity
with natural processes.”186 Cobb was convinced that what children want most is
“to make a world in which to find a place to discover a self,” and that their natural
surroundings is the terrain in which to do it. Having graduated or separated from
the earlier field of infant relations, children’s emerging gestalt-making powers now
direct them toward an aesthetic encounter with nature, for a joyful and wonder-
filled revelation of creeks, groundhogs, and tadpoles. This period is a time that calls
for imaginative play and wonder, for total absorption in and free exploration of the
world. “The child learns that all life tells something and that all sound, from the
frog calling to the sea surf, issues from a being kindred and significant to himself,
telling some tale, giving some clue, mimicking some rhythm that he should know.
There is no end to what is to be learned.”187 Just as we bond to caregivers in infancy,
so do we—in this new phase of symbiotic immersion in the green world—need to
become bonded to the earth. The “child must have a residential opportunity to soak
in a place, and . . . the adolescent and adult must be able to return to that place to
ponder the visible substrate of his own personality.”188
Because the childhood need for nature is poorly recognized by most psy-
chologists, I wish to make a couple of methodological remarks. First, I mentioned
above that one of the main ways we discover needs is by tracing back along lines of
suffering. The other is by paying attention to the fresh promptings of the life force:
to where our bodily energy is genuinely pointing, to what is becoming newly
figural in our awareness, to what tastes like nutritious or satisfying food. Within
an experiential framework, especially, wherever there is spontaneous interest in
the world, there we recognize an organismic need. For me, then, it is enough that
(given supportive conditions) children are in general highly curious about and
attracted to the world outdoors. They are themselves clearly saying what they need
next in order to build up their existence, widen their self-boundaries, add fur-
ther experiences to their life-gestalt, or discover-and-invent their “own increasing
reality.”189 As Myers notes, in this regard, “the animal emerges for the infant and
young child as a truly subjective other whose immediate presence is compelling
. . . . cultural practices do not just create out of whole cloth (or fail to create)
In hunting and gathering societies play is the main activity of children throughout
their waking hours, in contrast to other types of societies in which chores and
schooling occupy large amounts of children’s time after the age of six. Also, for
hunting and gathering societies, the period of middle childhood—ages six to twelve
appear to be optimally discrepant social others . . . , offering just the right amount of
similarity and difference from human pattern and other animal patterns to optimally
engage the child. . . . animals are symbolic for the child . . . in the sense of confirming
the child’s own uniquely human self and representing and furthering the living,
feeling self in a more vivid form than can other kinds of carriers of meaning.203
That is, children innately anticipate the kind of symbolic nutrition offered by
animals. By this period the ground has been prepared for them to undertake the
metaphorical leaps in self-understanding, and the widening of their social cir-
cles, that animals offer to them. In this way, their lives are carried forward into
new realms of existing. “Each kind of animal gives concrete representation to an
ephemeral and intangible element of the human self such as assertion, intimi-
dation, affection, doubt, determination, kindness, anger, hope, irritation,
yearning, wisdom, cunning, anticipation, fear, and initiative. Only when these
feelings are discovered outside the self and then performed can such intense but
elusive ‘things’ be made one’s own.”204 In enacting other animals, moreover, chil-
dren not only feel closer to them, but clarify for themselves just how they are not
like animals. As Myers suggests, this has the effect of preserving the animal’s other-
ness, of establishing a kinship based on shared qualities rather than pure identity.
In such play the “vital natures of animals are encountered—and become our best
defense against the conspiracy that animals are only machines or artifacts, and
therefore against the lie that we ourselves are made of cogs, wheels, and wires.”205
In developing a connection with other animals, finally, children expand their own
existential fields of care, not only to include these animals, but also the local ter-
rains and larger ecologies to which they belong. (As Myers notes, the dilemma
today is that to assist children in recognizing animals as genuine “social others,”
while also introducing them to a world that routinely violates animals, is to set
them up for a good deal of grief. Hence: “If society were to really grasp what is
at stake in child development, we might well reduce exploitation of animals to a
minimum dictated by a stricter sense of necessity.”206)
What is perhaps most generally missing in our own Western childhoods is
a culture of wilderness, wherein stories, rituals, everyday language, and day-to-day
activities are all richly embedded in a more-than-human world. Trimble notes, for
example, that:
Pueblo Indian children learn about connections to the earth through virtually every
experience in their culture. Beginning at about three years of age, Pueblo boys
dance in their village plazas as animals, transforming themselves into the spirits of
antelope and deer. They wear gray fox skins, deer-hoof and tortoise-shell rattles,
parrot feathers, antler and horn headdresses, and skunk-fur gaiters. A little later, the
girls may dance as parrots or buffalo mothers. The words of the songs, the symbols
painted on costumes, and the choreographed gestures all connect the dancers with
the earth: corn, clouds, the sun, rain, lightning, thunder, rainbows, evergreen trees.
Life, growth, harvest.207
Despite my own joyful childhood experiences along the forest trail, I can little
imagine what a difference in my perceptual universe it would have made to have
been a member of such a culture as the Pueblo’s—nor what it might have meant
for the next phase of the life cycle.
Adolescent Initiation into a Sacred Adult Cosmos. One of the main tasks of a natural-
istic approach is to identify those natural claims that are not being acknowledged
or met by our society and to highlight the trouble this is creating. Our general
misreading of the nature of adolescence provides a strong case in point. Having
studied the human life cycle in a variety of cultural settings, Turnbull writes of
adolescence that he “cannot think of a single culture . . . that handles this crucial
stage of life more abysmally than we do.”208 While it is normal for us to view ado-
lescence as a troublesome period that youth and their parents have to just survive
somehow (or even as a kind of “mental illness”—sometimes officially209), other
societies recognize it as a stage of great significance for both social and cosmic
renewal, in which elders are called on to provide the cultural assistance necessary
for youth to undergo a powerful symbolic rebirth into adulthood. As Turnbull
thus notes: “Most of the adolescent behavior that is so puzzling to adults would
be comprehensible if only they searched for the proper symbolic key.”210 In ado-
lescence the carefree days of childhood wane as our maturing bodies ready us for
the challenge of confronting our society and forming an adult identity, becoming
part of our society in a new way. Our bodies naturally acquires sexual significance;
we become highly sensitive to how others see us; and our minds search for a way
to understand a cosmos that now bears down on us mightily. Struggling under the
multiple burdens of physiological revolution, identity crisis, and spiritual awak-
ening, it is not surprising that adolescents have developed a reputation for being
difficult. I refuse to believe, however, that adolescents are “crazy” by nature; I
argue instead (as do others) that the tragic mess our society makes of this stage
of life demonstrates just how impoverished is its understanding of the cultural
demands that our human nature makes on it.
A “humanistic” assumption of this book is that people are always making
the best creative adjustments they can between their organismic needs and the
situations in which they find themselves. We may well ask, then, about the general
needs of adolescents; the kind of cultural conditions that are required to optimally
meet them; and the creative adjustments that youth make when these conditions
are lacking. This is essentially what Erikson did in his classic and still-valuable
studies on youth. The following passage from Identity: Youth and Crisis sets the
stage for much of what I want to discuss.
appears to offer them roles and ideals worthy of their fidelity. This fidelity, which
Erikson describes as the naturally emerging power (or “vital virtue”) of youth, can
come to fruition or complete itself only if there is a “true community” available to
house it—one to which the adolescent may genuinely be loyal or “true.” Adoles-
cents are “desperately seeking for a satisfactory sense of belonging,” for a “defined
personality within a social reality.”212 When, however, their elders fail to provide
satisfying means to incorporate youth into the social whole, it is of the wisdom
of their rebellious bodies to refuse that society, even if they themselves don’t quite
understand what they are doing.
Much of the adolescent activity that disturbs adults may thus be seen as
forms of creative adjustment to an unsatisfactory situation. Gangs and cliques, for
example, are “pseudo-societies” or “micro-societies”213 that youths substitute for
adult society, creating for themselves a community to which they can indeed be
true. Gangs, said Erikson, are a “defense against a sense of identity confusion,”214
as these offer a more satisfying identity for youth than is possible through mem-
bership in a corrupt or unwelcoming society-at-large. Even a “negative identity”
is preferable to a bankrupt one, and even deviancy can be a form of loyalty to one’s
own nature.215 Some adolescents adjust by withdrawing inwardly, while others
become manifestly disturbed, disintegrating under their psychospiritual load.
As Erikson argued, if we do not understand the need for (giving and receiving)
fidelity, we will instead confirm the youth “by every act of the correctional or
therapeutic authorities as a future criminal or a lifelong patient.”216 That is, rather
than recognizing the intertwined needs of youth and society, our adult society
effectively punishes and shames adolescents for how it has failed them. Instead of
listening to the feedback offered by adolescents through their distress-filled activi-
ties, and taking responsibility for that distress, our elders call for more police and
discipline. Punk rock and grunge music are adolescent ways of singing the world,
are a kind of voice of nature. Adolescents, in other words, are natural mirrors for
a society, even if our own society generally refuses to see itself in them, and even
if our society is itself a broken mirror for reciprocally showing to adolescents their
own “true” selves. Looking for a world to believe in, noble values to uphold, and
cosmic meanings to embrace, the last thing adolescents “need” is wrong-headed
social judgment.
In the general unfolding of adolescent life, two regions of existence that are
highly figural, and so much in need of societal recognition, are the sexual and spir-
itual.217 I thus want to consider these two in turn (even if they are tightly linked).
First, the sexual. Sexual maturation spontaneously turns adolescents into a new
kind of being, and so creates a discontinuity in their existence, makes them unfa-
miliar to themselves, at least to some degree. The bodily changes occurring at this
time bring their ontological insecurity to a new apex and make them extremely
self-conscious for that reason.218 The pursuit of social acceptance by adolescents
thus includes the desire for an identity in which their sexual being is actively
with which novices listen to mythological traditions and take part in ceremonial
life, or the avidness they show in pursuit of the significance hidden within the
myths they are being introduced to. What also led Eliade to call rites of passage
“an existential experience that is basic in the human condition” was his recogni-
tion that even when initiatory patterns “lose their ritual reality,” as they did in
the West during the middle ages, they nonetheless persist in the mode of literary
motifs in eagerly consumed stories.228
It is not my intention to offer much detail on the topic of adolescent initia-
tion rites, as there is much existing literature that already does so.229 I will only stress
a number of points important for my purposes. The first is that such initiation is
crucial for the sociation of the individual. Initiates in primal societies go through
a process of separation from their families, of ritual death or descent, only through
which process are they reborn as members of the wider community, their social place
consolidated and recognized in a ceremony that usually follows on their return. The
form of rites vary widely from culture to culture, of course. What is common, how-
ever, is that they reveal to initiates “the sacredness of life and of the world,” as it is
conveyed to them, for example, in origin myths. On a vision quest the initiate may be
visited by a tutelary spirit or discover new planes of existence through ecstatic experi-
ences. As Eliade notes, indigenous peoples generally believe that to live is to share in
the sacrality of the cosmos. It is only through this ritual second birth into the spiritual
realm, therefore, that the initiate attains full social standing as a human being.
One of the valuable contributions made by Shepard to this topic was his
insight into the important role played by the earlier stages of the life cycle in
readying the adolescent to comprehend this sacred dimension of ultimate mean-
ings. Hence, the adolescent:
will not put his delight in the sky and the earth behind him as a childish and irrel-
evant thing. He will graduate not out of that world but into its significance. So,
with the end of childhood, he begins a life-long study, a reciprocity with the natural
world in which its depths are as endless as his own creative thought. He will not
study it in order to transform its liveliness into mere objects that represent his ego,
but as a poem, numinous and analogical, of human society.230
Each stage of life lays down the preunderstanding for grasping the next. In this
case, myths “and spiritual and cosmological concepts are communicated by allu-
sion to a [now] familiar natural world.”231 The result is a form of spirituality that
is tied to or grounded in a more-than-human place, one that initiates have already
learned to love and feel themselves a part of.232
It is at this stage of life, moreover, that we are ordered to gather the meta-
phorical nature of reality as such; to achieve a symbolic level of perception. The
adolescent passage is thus also “a transition in the imaginative faculty from a literal
to a figurative place, from familiar temporal reality to the dreamtime.”233
For myself, I am most able to experience the world in an explicitly symbolic way
when I am lucid dreaming, in which I am aware that I am dreaming while still in
a dream state. In the days following such dreams the taste of lucidity permeates
my waking life, such that my existence becomes more spacious and filled with a
kind of luminous glow. Every being I encounter is potentially rich in meaning, has
some important message, some secret link to my own life. I thus imagine a mature,
earth-based spiritual life as one in which one feels enveloped in a mysterious-yet-
familiar world; where time and space easily slip out of their Cartesian dimensions;
where a million little resonances keep one paying attention; and in which new
revelations continually reform one’s sense of the possible. As many seekers today
still understand, a symbolic perception of the world lifts one out of one’s Ego
into a larger cosmic drama in which nothing, including oneself, has that substan-
tial reality of the literal viewpoint. To undergo a symbolic death and rebirth, for
example, takes the sting out of one’s literal death. As Eliade notes, it even gives it
a positive value, for one realizes that death is merely the end of a mode of being,
a stage in the transformation of all things. And as Erikson observed, “healthy
children will not fear life if their elders have integrity enough not to fear death.”235
Not initiation into a sacred adult cosmos, but all sorts of perversions of it
are what we in the modern era generally live out. For us, it is senseless hazings
and literal descents rather than elaborately symbolic ordeals ritually completed.
“In many tribal cultures,” writes the men’s work leader Michael Meade, “it was
said that if boys were not initiated into manhood, if they were not shaped by the
skills and love of elders, then they would destroy the culture.”236 Good initiation
rites are designed to creatively resolve the tension between youth and society in
a way that is meaningful and of benefit to all. In their absence, social pathology
blooms—a notion well-captured in the suggestion that overcrowded prisons are
“houses of failed initiation.”237 Writes Meade:
process of initiation presses to break through. The most important reason to study
rites of passage may be to see in the events erupting in the streets and at the borders
and crossroads of our post-historic era the archaic energies of life renewing itself.238
At the heart of much of our modern trouble, that is, the life force is still pushing
toward the completion of the initatory gestalt. “Instead of ritual descent and emo-
tional resurrection,” however, it is often the case that “complete death occurs;
actual corpses pile up.”239 We may speculate with great seriousness, then, about
the tremendous potential value of finding our way back to or reappropriating rites
consciously enacted.
The human life cycle does not of course end at the beginning of adult-
hood. I have concentrated on the earlier stages of life both because of their forma-
tive significance and on account of the space restrictions of this chapter. In brief,
however, we may note that adults themselves need to be needed, gaining their
satisfaction through guiding the next generation and undertaking projects that
are of service to others. Under good conditions adults ripen with age, continuing
to learn lessons from a world still experienced as a constantly novel presence. They
may then arrive at old age not as crippled and unwise adolescents, but as “memory
banks, keepers of the lore and genealogy, healers, accumulators of useful social
lessons (especially childrearing and the resolution of disagreement)” and tutors in
ceremonial matters.240 In their own way, by their proximity to death (and so to
the spirit world), the old may also revitalize society, especially through their special
connection to the young. A satisfying life, then, sees our basic desires met. “As the
needs of adults in their prime to initiate and carry through their projects become
fulfilled and age begins to reduce physical powers, desires are for seeing one’s
loved ones succeed, for peace, for less variety in experiences, to feel that things are
moving through the cycle of life with less help from oneself, and ultimately, with
no help, as the last of life’s succession of desires is fulfilled and is replaced by none
but the wish to rest, to know no more, to cease.”241 As Nietzsche said: “all that is
ripe . . . wants to die.”242
In complicated times it is all the more helpful to have simple ideas. Like other
ecological thinkers, my interest lies quite simply with the flourishing of all life—
with a condition we might call happiness. The Buddhists say “may all beings be
happy,” which I hear as “may all beings thrive according to their own natures.” In
the previous three chapters I presented an interpretation of our own world-bound
nature and of what the satisfactory unfolding of a human life generally entails. I
also worked from the assumption, definitive of Buddhism, that if we are to find
real happiness we have to know something about the basis of our suffering. Today,
moreover (unlike in the Buddha’s time), this means making sense of our suffering
in a technological world. For this final chapter, then, I wish to more focally con-
sider this general task to which my naturalistic and experiential approach points.
I begin in the present section by examining the idea that currently rules over
our society’s thinking about what will make us happy, namely, technological
progress. Norman O. Brown remarks that what humankind “is doing seems to be
making itself more unhappy and calling that unhappiness progress.”2 Indeed, if
the idea of technological progress is backward, as many argue, then I must make
it the main butt of my own critical thought. The very process—technological
155
progress—that is meant to enhance our lives will be seen in fact to betray “an
impatience and even disdain for life, a contempt and defiance of our bodily, that
is mortal, earthly existence.”3
Not only the Buddha, but the likes of Aristotle, Francis Bacon, Marx,
Freud, and the advertising industry all agree that the goal of life is happiness. This
only makes sense, for we all want a good life, want to feel satisfied.4 Indeed, one of
Freud’s central findings was that the “whole world may be against it, but still man
holds fast to the deep-rooted, passionate striving for a positive fulfillment of hap-
piness.”5 Where these various sources differ is over the route toward this happiness,
and on the prospect of getting there. These days, it is primarily the advertisers who
get listened to, for it is generally assumed that our happiness has something to do
with technologically delivered commodity wealth, that “the good life is the goods
life.”6 We need to note at this point, therefore, the close connection between eco-
nomic and technological principles. A technologized reality, in other words, is an
economized reality. To use Marxist terms, technological progress is of the essence
of the capitalist mode of production,7 is of a piece with its development. Associ-
ated with technology, then, is the steady concentration of wealth in the hands
of the ruling class, the (in my terms) double violation of nature, the perpetual
expansion and intensification of the capitalist marketplace, and in general, the
relentless imposition of capitalist social relations. What I say about technology in
this chapter thus carries on from my remarks at the end of chapter three on the
economization of reality. Given that the promise of technological progress enjoys
so much economic power and such a strong hold on the popular imagination, it
will serve us, next, to consider the history of this promise.
In his book Progress Without People, David Noble8 traces this history to an
ideological transformation that occurred among monks in ninth-century Europe.
It was at this time, observes Noble, that the “useful arts”—cloth-making, agri-
culture, weaponry and fortification, animal husbandry, mathematics, sculpture,
and so on—were drawn into the Christian mythology of redemption. These arts,
previously kept well out of the realm of religion and transcendence, suddenly
took on a new significance, now being regarded as a vehicle for the salvation of
“man” (women being excluded from the project of redemption), that is, for the
restoration of his lost perfection and prelapsarian powers. What was to become
modern technology thus had a religious and a masculine meaning right from the
start, emerging as both a historical and salvationary force in the same stroke. It
was not until the scientific revolution, however, that the “religion of technology”
was brought “from the margins of Western history to centre stage, where it has
remained.”9 Francis Bacon, in particular, gave bold definition to the masculine
millennial project of modern technology. Human suffering, he said, was a need-
less scandal. Through the elevation and improvement of the “mechanical arts,”
directed toward the torture, inquisition, and subjugation of a female nature, it
would be possible, he argued, to relieve “the inconveniences of man’s estate”10 and
to finally erase man’s sins by returning to him his divinelike powers. This religious
theme was then carried into the industrial revolution of the nineteenth century,
in which engineers were viewed as the “priests” of a new epoch, and in which
the project begun in the ninth century was given its new name under industrial
capital: “technology.” At this time, worker opposition arose in Britain to the way
that machines were being used by capitalists in creating a system of social domina-
tion that involved deskilling, wage slavery, and the destruction of communities.
It was then, suggests Noble, that “middle-class apologists and optimistic econo-
mists” invented the idea of inevitable technological progress (as well as that of the
virtue of competition) as a way to induce paralysis in this “Luddite” opposition
to technology, and to prevent its recurrence. “Society” was similarly “discovered”
as an entity that existed apart from the people who comprised it, having its own
autonomous, “natural” laws, operating on the “hard logic of the market and the
machine.” In short, social progress and technological progress were equated and
the system of capital promoted as an automatic process for delivering human hap-
piness, “so long as people allowed it to follow its natural course.”11
Of particular note is Noble’s argument that the doctrine of technological
progress derives its ideological strength from its abstract and future-oriented
character, that is, from the manner in which it deflects attention away from the
concrete and present moment. In other words, a high-altitude narrative about
progress is used to explain away obvious human, social, and ecological losses as
necessary costs along the way to a better future—those who suffer are enjoined
simply to “look for future deliverance.” Felt experience thus becomes largely irrel-
evant as the present tense is progressively replaced by fatalism and futurism, and as
fantasies about technological development replace our contact with actual reality.
This makes for a “proudly irrational framework,” wherein we are told that we can’t
stand in the way of progress, even if it kills us, so sacrosanct and inevitable is it.
In today’s secular society, technophiles now use an openly religious vocabu-
lary. “We are as gods,” some of them say, speaking (especially in magazines such
as Wired) of the powers made available to them by the “new” technologies. “In
space exploration, they are joining the angels; in artificial reproduction they are
regaining Adam’s male-only procreative powers; in artificial intelligence, they
are overcoming the curse and the mortal bondage of the body; in genetic engi-
neering, they are becoming once again God’s partner in creation; in cyberspace
they are recovering their rightful dominion over the universe, omniscient and
omnipresent.”12 Technosalvationism, in sum, is the “shared delusion” of our age.
In contrast to the optimism of today’s techno-boosters, it is helpful to con-
sider the pessimism of Freud, who said that between happiness and unhappiness,
the latter “is much less difficult to experience.”13 According to Freud, the three
sources of human suffering are “the superior powers of nature” (“She destroys
us—coldly, cruelly, relentlessly, as it seems to us”),14 “the feebleness of our own
bodies,” and conflicts within human society.15 Given this situation, he believed
the best thing a person can do is become “a member of the human commu-
nity, and, with the help of a technique guided by science, [go] over to the attack
against nature, subjecting her to the human will”—even if humans shall “never
completely master nature,” including our bodies. Social problems, too (the third
source of suffering), may be traced to “a piece of unconquerable nature,” namely,
our own hostile human nature which causes us to battle one another. We must
therefore include ourselves in the attack on nature; that is, “every civilization must
be built up on the coercion and renunciation of instinct.”16 Hence, the “principle
task of civilization, its actual raison d’être, is to defend us against nature,”17 both
outside and in. With such views, Freud hopelessly dichotomized nature and cul-
ture, making our own organismic intentions the forces against which we must
defend ourselves, and aligning himself with the idea of progress. Having made a
necessity out of dissatisfaction, he concluded that the “programme of becoming
happy . . . cannot be fulfilled.” Rather, in exchange for the “security” offered by
civilization, we pay the price of “a loss of happiness through the heightening of
the sense of guilt.”18 What is admirable about Freud is his blunt acknowledgment
that the technological domination of nature, even if necessary, brings no joy. In
this respect, his vision is more honest than that of the optimists, for he did at least
witness what was later to be called the “revolt of nature.”
The revolt of nature is an aspect of what, in chapter three, I called the
double violation of nature, and is a simple though compelling notion for refuting
the promise of technological happiness. It was first named as such by Max
Horkheimer, who saw civilization as a project of putting down or managing a
nature increasingly in revolt, a revolt that is reaching “its peak in this era.”19 It
is an easy enough notion to grasp. We experience the revolt of our own nature
as our body’s painful rebellion against repressing social and cultural conditions.
I spoke in the previous chapter about the revolt of adolescent nature, and in the
discussion above about the revolt of Luddites. Examples are endless. Much of
the experience of depression that is widespread within Western culture can, for
instance, also be read as a revolt of nature, our bodies saying “no” to the crushing
demands and abuses of modern life. The revolt of nonhuman nature, on the other
hand, manifests as mutating bacteria, mudslides, droughts, and the ecological
crisis in general.20 “As more of nature is domesticated and controlled, it becomes
more compressed and dangerous. In the [atom] bomb, all the former wildness is
concentrated . . ., pushed to an explosive end in the very heart of minerals them-
selves.”21 As William Leiss writes: “A vicious circle results, imprisoning science
and technology in a fateful dialectic of increasing mastery and increasing con-
flict. The attractive promises of mastery over nature—social peace and material
abundance for all—remain unfulfilled.”22 Any open recognition of the revolt of
nature would spell disaster for the existing social order, as this would amount to
an admission that technological progress is not the path to a heavenly future it is
promised to be, but an ideology for safeguarding a vicious status-quo. The revolt
of nature must therefore be mystified, as is done in at least two general ways.
The first is by manipulating or taking advantage of it. As Horkheimer
argued, the “prevailing forces of civilization” use the revolt of nature “as a means
to perpetuate the very conditions by which it is stirred up and against which it is
directed.”23 The corporate world, in particular, has learned with a vengeance how
to manipulate the revolt of nature. To take an obvious example, it profits from the
alienation and interpersonal distance engendered by capitalist social relations by
selling us the telephones we need in order to “reach out and touch somebody.”
Phones and other such commodities then “become necessary, a sign of progress, a
proof of prestige for those who ‘own’ them.”24 Or the pharmaceutical companies
sell us the antidepressants that gets us back to work. Peter Breggin says of psychia-
try’s appropriation of suffering: “The mental health professions, led by psychiatry,
have rushed into the void left by the default of the family, the schools, the society,
and the government. . . . By diagnosing, drugging, and hospitalizing children,
psychiatry enforces the worst attitudes toward children in our culture today and
exonerates those adult institutions that need reform.”25 As for the ecological crisis,
the cooption of the environmental movement by the corporate sphere—recently
dubbed “greenwashing”—immediately comes to mind. “Corporate environmen-
talism” is mostly a public relations exercise that portrays large corporations, such
as car companies, as friends of “the environment” and that tends to redefine social-
ecological problems in purely technical terms.26 In an article that seeks to debunk
the notion of “green capitalism,” furthermore, Joel Kovel notes: “So seamless is
capital’s current moment of triumph, and so absent any appreciation that there
might be alternatives to it, that the thought of whether its stewardship of the earth
will necessarily bring about ecological catastrophe . . . scarcely enters anybody’s
consciousness.”27 Whenever “jobs” are pitted against “the environment,” finally,
the chance is missed to see the link between the revolt of human nature and that
of nonhuman nature.
A second way the revolt of nature is controlled is by means of what has
been called “mental health” oppression,28 which is a blanket social force for the
repression of it. An important ecopsychological point is that psychoanalysis was
born only when the revolt of nature within the individual could no longer be
ignored. Freud claimed that history itself has the character of an ever-increasing
neurosis.29 As civilization advances, our desires are frustrated more and more,
not only by external pressures, but by our own internalized social authority,
the superego. The result is massive psychic derangement. What Kovel calls “the
mental health industry” is, then, the bureaucracy that has evolved for managing
this crippled desire.30 “Mental health” oppression refers to all the ways we are
made afraid of seeming or actually becoming “crazy” and so entering this “mental
health” system. To behave contrary to the rigidly prescribed patterns that keep the
a lie.37 This sets the stage for the third section, in which I take up that ever-pressing
question, What is to be done? Borrowing from Borgmann and others, I suggest
that what a naturalistic and experiential approach leads to, broadly speaking, are
practices that work with the life force in deliberately countering the pattern of
technology. I want it to be very clear that such counterpractice does not involve
getting rid of technology, but rather overcoming its current resourcist ontology
and putting it back where it belongs: in the artful service of life. I also want to
reemphasize my belief that it is the practical work of ecopsychology that will form
the most fruitful basis for its theorizing. The most constructive theory will emerge,
in other words, as we change ourselves in practice and as we develop concrete
interventions capable of opening up new insights and avenues of understanding.
To counter modern technology means refusing to live for an abstract future, and so
recovering our lives in the concrete present. To make contact with present reality,
however, is also to confront the painful feelings that are masked or numbed-out
by our technological mode of living. In the final section, which concludes this
book, I therefore address what I feel is an important aspect of this work: learning
to collectively bear, find meaning in, and move through the suffering we inevitably
uncover in the course of counterpractice.
Although we can no doubt develop a psychology that identifies our need for
contact with wildlife, for rites of passage, and so on, the recognition of needs by
psychologists has never been a guarantee that they will be met. For our society is
not structured to care for life, to attend carefully to relationships and honor the
growth or sacred unfolding of things. To be “successful” in today’s society, one
does not serve nature but rather the expansion of capital.39 It is for this reason
that ecopsychology will lack the necessary teeth to have much influence unless
it is accompanied by critical thought or social analysis. Drawing on the concepts
and traditions of my own naturalistic and experiential approach, I am here taking
technology as the theme of my criticism. My basic critical strategy is a familiar
one, namely, to frankly expose the suffering that is veiled by a reigning ideology
and to generate in the reader some antipathy for this situation.40 More exactly, I
am aiming toward a sort of critical theory that takes a nonanthropocentric vision
of happiness as its starting point (sketched out in the previous two chapters) and
rejects the ideology of technological progress (something that Marx, for one, did
not do). The initial challenge, however, is to find a pattern in our experience of
technology that can then be countered in practice.
As a way to enter into this challenge, I begin with Fredric Jameson’s remark
that we are:
at the moment of a radical eclipse of Nature itself: Heidegger’s ‘field path’ is after
all irredeemably and irrevocably destroyed by late capital, by the green revolution,
by neocolonialism and the megapopolis [sic], which runs its superhighways over
the older fields and vacant lots, and turns Heidegger’s ‘house of being’ into condo-
miniums, if not the most miserable unheated, rat infested tenement buildings. The
other of our society is in that sense no longer Nature at all.41
Jameson struggles to name what is now the “other” of our society, but claims
that it may vaguely be conceived as the global network of power and control
that comprises the world economic and social system of late capitalism—as it is
embodied in technology. In his words, “technology may well serve as an adequate
shorthand to designate that enormous properly human and anti-natural power
of dead human labour stored up in our machinery, . . . which turns back on and
against us in unrecognizable forms and seems to constitute the massive dystopian
horizon of our collective as well as individual praxis.” The problem presented here
by Jameson is that we are underdistanced from the forces of technology and capital,
and so that we lack free ground on which to get our critical footings.42 Drawing
on the work of Heidegger, Borgmann, and others, however, I suggest below that
there is a specific pattern within the dynamics of technology, the discernment of
which does help provide some of the necessary distance to win a degree of libera-
tion from it. What I stress, then, is the vast difference between, on the one hand,
a life patterned to the needs of human and nonhuman nature, to the rhythms of
the life cycle, the land, the passage of the seasons, and, on the other hand, a life
patterned to the needs of a technological society, to the rhythms of the market and
machine. Because technology patterns or structures our lives it is no mere neutral
set of instruments, as some like to claim. Rather, it determines—to the extent that
we agree to live it—the sense, form, and telos of our existence. To recognize a pat-
tern in technology is therefore to start making sense of it, seeing through it, and
being more aware of the great disjunction between the promise of technological
progress and the reality of our lived experience.
The Pattern of Technology. The former premier of Quebec, Robert Bourassa, said
that “Quebec is a vast hydroelectric plant in the bud, and every day millions of
potential kilowatt-hours flow downhill and out to sea. What a waste.”43 Heidegger
claimed that the essence of our late modern epoch lies exactly in this technological
mode of understanding. “Nature becomes a gigantic gasoline station, an energy
source for modern technology and industry.”44 Or: “the earth now reveals itself
as a coal mining district, the soil as a mineral deposit.”45 In other words, nature
has for us become what Heidegger called a “standing reserve,” in which all beings
Brian Stableford . . . promises that the “battery chickens” of the future, “whether
they are being used to produce eggs or meat,” will look very different from the
birds of the moment. In fact the accompanying illustrations shows them looking
like—well, hunks of flesh. This is because thanks to biotechnology, we might design
chickens without the unnecessary heads, wings, and tails.46
of a human life involves making more and more of the world familiar and mean-
ingful, the machinery of devices is designed precisely to be unfamiliar. To the
extent that it is hidden, this machinery is simply not experienced, and to the extent
that it takes over our living relationships, it therefore makes the satisfaction of our
cosmological urge an impossibility. The pattern of replacing vital relations with
machinery, that is, frustrates our world-making needs and so desiccates our reality.
What remains of our lives, according to Borgmann, are the two principle
activities that correspond to a reality now split between machinery and commodi-
ties: labor and leisure. Labor—a degraded form of “work”—consists of the con-
struction, maintenance, and operation of the machinery, while leisure consists of
the consumption or uptake of the commodities produced by it, wherein the real
happiness is meant to be had. The pattern of technology, then, refers to the progres-
sive replacement and/or substitution of our world-relations by, in labor, slim rela-
tions with an ever-more hidden and unfamiliar machinery and, in leisure, shallow
relations with ever-more pervasive commodities—the overall effect of which is to
dissolve the meaningful fabric of our lives. As notes Borgmann, “our once profound
and manifold engagement with the world is reduced to narrow points of contact
in labor and consumption.”59 I do not suggest that this pattern is the only way to
understand our society, as there are many aspects of our social arrangements that it
does not especially bring out.60 What is fruitful about it, however, is that it helps
tie together both technological and economic themes.61 Our increasingly thin and
meaningless laboring at the machinery and equally thin and meaningless consump-
tion of commodities do not make us happy, for they do not offer us the kind of deep
and wide contact with others that our bodies inherently demand. They are, however,
the essential activities of a capitalist society, for they do create profits.
as a human being.”63 I believe this point goes very far, extending into many areas
of social and cultural life that I will not pursue here (including the deskilling,64
alienating, and unemploying of the labor-force, and the general overburdening of
women with emotional duties that compensate for the dehumanizing effects of
capitalist relations). What I want to suggest is that within an economized reality
we are relieved of life exactly so that weakened or less satisfying versions of it can
then be sold back to us for profit.65 Take, for instance, the supermarket. It is a
general human need to be skillfully engaged in the gathering/hunting, preparing,
and presenting of food.66 When this need is well-met, a meal is more likely to be
a “ritual of gathering and remembrance, a communion in which the offering and
the eating of food bonds us together into a community and installs us within the
circle of life and its seasons.”67 A frozen dinner from the supermarket can be eaten
after only six minutes in the microwave oven. Yet the consuming of such a disbur-
dening and inconsequential commodity (perhaps in front of the TV set) hardly
elicits our thanks; nor does it call forth a sense of our sacred membership within
the community of all earthly beings, some of whose bodies we eat.
This returns us to that central feature of capitalist reality: commodity fet-
ishism. The aspect of commodity fetishism that is important to consider here is that
it involves an active mystification of our needing.68 It is as if all our needs were such
that they could be satisfied only by commodities; as if every felt intention pointed
to a bottle of Pepsi or a jet ski. Unsure about our genuine needs, we interpret them
according to what is both available and promoted to us for the meeting of them. As
William Leiss suggests, in order to maintain this state of affairs, the economic order
must [. . .] then guard against our becoming aware of needs lying outside the field
of commodity consumption: “Filtered through layers of commodities, the natural
and human environment is progressively simplified, more smoothly ordered; the
abrasive particles which might disrupt the flow of everyday normal experience—
which might stir modes of feeling not dependent on the acquisition of [goods]—
are trapped and removed.”69 Thus, for example, the tourist machinery serves up
the natural world in commodity form, as scenery viewed through the windows of
a tour bus, accompanied by postcards, travel guides, mass-made mementos, and
so on. With such a thin experience, something like ecological consciousness is
not likely to arise. Likewise, people must be convinced that the meeting of their
nonmaterial needs—as for love, security, privacy, freedom, and so forth—are all
bound to the purchase of commodities.70 Our freedom, for instance, is supposedly
realized when we are in a position to choose among a wide range of commodities.
The Lotto 6/49 television ad asks us to “Imagine the Freedom” and then right away
feeds us images of people recreating with the expensive toys they have bought with
their lottery winnings. Finally, it is not only that our “needs” must be met by com-
modities, but also that they must expand so as to keep up with the expansion in
the production of commodities themselves.71 One way this is done is through the
breaking down of existing needs into ever-more finely disconnected and numerous
part-needs. Our lives then become an endless series of point to point correspond-
ences between increasingly discrete needs and commodities. Thus do we purchase
a plethora of bathroom products to meet a vast array of grooming needs—all of
which have become components of our need for interpersonal respect, which has
itself become a kind of “scarce resource that can only be appropriated through a
fortunate selection and combination of the newest items in the marketplace.”72
Judged on the basis of our clothes, possessions, and the way we “sell” ourselves to
one another, even we become just “another commodity offered up for consump-
tion on the open market.”73
Note that a dominant general mode of contact in our society is now con-
sumption. The universal, unburdened consumption of commodities is in fact the
fulfillment of the promise of technology.74 Some portion of the goods and services
we purchase do of course offer real satisfactions.75 The smell of an old cotton
sleeping bag reminds me of just how much joy and contentment I truly have
experienced. I reserve the term consumption, therefore, for the process of using “up
an isolated entity without preparation, resonance, and consequence.”76 It is a style
of interaction which, to greater or lesser extents, has the character of an addiction,
wherein any stirring of felt need or bodily tension leads straight away to the intake
or enactment of the “drug” to which we are fixated. Consumption, accordingly,
is a mode of experience that amounts mostly to tension relief, and not to any
restructuring of the ground of our existence or carrying forward of our lives. It
follows the same basic pattern of fleeting satisfaction over and over again. When
we consume we do not unfold or expand our lives or deepen our understanding of
the cosmos. To the extent that a commodity is disposable, moreover, we may well
wonder about the depth of contact, or life-transforming meaning, it could ever
offer to us. Knowing all this, it is all the more appalling to recall the words of the
retailing analyst Victor Leblow, spoken following the Second World War:
Here is a naked admission that the ethical duty to consume was dictated not by
any primary interest in happiness, in the demands of nature, but by the need to
maintain the capitalist way of being at a certain phase in its historical develop-
ment. Indeed, the truth of the matter is closer still to the lines suggested by Kovel.
relentless spiritual impulse. Rather than witness this impulse, the corporate world
invests in the delusions and cravings born of its frustration. In order to better get
at this point, I wish to briefly look at four spiritually based delusional tendencies
within our society, as identified by David Loy. The spiritual task, as considered
here, is to find a way to resolve the anxiety of separation, wherein we feel the
cosmic gap as a dread of annihilation and as a feeling that there is something
wrong with us, that we are not real, that we are not enough, that we are lacking.
One delusory route toward “being somebody,” or overcoming our spiritual lack,
is the quest for fame. When reality becomes equated with the glamorous world
of celebrity, sold to us through every pore of the mass media, “to be unknown is
literally to be nothing.”84 We fantasize, therefore, that fame will bring us the ado-
ration and recognition we need to overcome our shame and unreality (remember
the song: Fame!). A second delusory attempt at resolution is romantic love. In this
case, we see our love partners only in the light of how they might fill in our own
lack, might complete us, save us, make us whole, take us off to paradise.85 Such
fantasies make for hefty sales of pulp romance novels, soap operas, and pop music,
but certainly not for the attainment of spirit. The third trend identified by Loy is
what he calls the money complex. Here, we desire money as a means to happiness,
and then make the acquisition of money a religious end in itself, even while doing
so may make us miserable. Finally, the very idea of technological progress also bears
a strong spiritual undercurrent, as I discussed in the opening section. The techno-
logical enterprise, says Loy, is “our effort to create the ultimate security, by trans-
forming the entire world into our own ground.”86 In this event, the whole earth
will testify to our reality. The idea of progress is the projection of a “lack-free time
somewhere in the future” when the technological task has finally been completed,
when we are saved. As Diamond has suggested, the idea of progress simply does
not arise within “primitive” culture, for it was born precisely of the disequilibrium
within the civilized world. For primal peoples progress “is a reality of personal
growth, of progress through society, not of society.”87 Only a chronically nonsat-
isfied people are driven to fantasize about future fulfillment. And only a death-
denying people are obsessed with using their technology for building immortality
projects such as banking towers. The idea of progress is thus founded less on the
aim of going to somewhere than on fleeing from “our own lack-shadow.” As an
effort to take over the world, in fact, technology “is a meaning-system without any
ultimate meaning, because lacking any vision of cloture [sic] between humankind
and cosmos.”88 It is poor food, in other words, for our cosmological hungers.
more on this point, feeling that I have already made it in a number of places.
Given the centrality of the nature-culture interaction to my arguments, however,
I wish to add a few more brief thoughts.
First of all, much of our shared symbolic life consists of the outpourings of
what Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno called the “culture industry.” Mass cul-
ture—what we would today call the whole sphere of entertainment, news, adver-
tising, tourism, electronic reality, and “information” in general—was in their view
a mechanically produced stream of commodious amusements, unabashedly calcu-
lated to be consumed rather than to offer any sort of “meaningful explanation of
life.”90 Kovel has also taken up this criticism, drawing particular attention to the
ideological function of mass culture: “It would be a grave mistake to think that the
aim of the culture industry is to produce objects of real utility, enlightenment, or
gratification. Rather, its concrete goals are to mystify, to titillate, and to frustrate;
to take from people the organs of their own cultural resistance and to keep them
hungry, restless, and confused, frantic in search of leisure, greedy for new com-
modities, and incapable of understanding much less changing their world.”91 I
am not inclined to make my criticisms as strongly as does Kovel, having had some
fine experiences in movie theaters and other such venues. I assume, furthermore,
that the reader is well aware that a great deal of what is produced by the culture
industry is rubbish. It is, though, the very obviousness of the superficiality of the
bulk of mass culture that concerns me. As Horkheimer and Adorno note: “The
triumph of advertising in the culture industry is that consumers feel compelled to
buy and use its products even though they see through them.”92
Daniel Boorstin calls advertising the characteristic rhetoric of technology.93
Odd as it may seem, advertising is thus the definitive voice of our epoch, for in it
“the promise of technology is presented both purely and concretely and hence most
attractively.”94 Thus, advertisements that say “Drink Lots of Pepsi—Get Lots of
Stuff ” now tell us what we stand for. As with the consumption ethic, the advertising
industry arose at a historical time when a surplus of commodities threatened to slow
down the forward march of capital. Advertising, then, is a rhetoric of consumption
which relies for its persuasive power on our dissatisfied and insecure condition,
taking advantage of our unskillful desires. As Jean Liedloff observes: “Advertising
has learned to capitalize on the longings of the [love] deprived public by holding
out promises which seem to say, ‘If you had this you would feel right again.’ ”95
As a dominant form of symbolization, then, advertising is not much interested in
our healing and growth—as is an authentic culture—but in selling us the goods
any way it can. Again, many people seem to know all this. Yet we are not generally
inclined to ask what an authentically life-serving culture might look like, nor to
question the economizing of our reality. Consider, for instance, a television adver-
tisement for a sport utility vehicle in which an earnest voice-over announces that it
will “save your soul.” Perhaps more than any other I have seen, this ad shows both
how utterly vacuous is the promise of technology and how deep is our yearning.
“social, economic and technological milieu almost wholly removed from the intri-
cate web of nature.” What he does not adequately consider, though, is whether
we would be happy.102
For all the hyperstimulation it provides, the quality of reality within a tech-
nological society suffers from a definite sameness. As the wild world is increasingly
squeezed to the margins, it is replaced by a monotonous landscape of subdivisions,
shopping malls, and electronic games. “The loss of wild others,” writes Shepard,
“leaves nothing but our own image to explain ourselves by—hence empty psychic
space.”103 In a naturalistic sense, then, our experiential options are actually quite
minimal.104 We have in a sense been deworlded, not by being plucked by a scientist
from out of our living context, but through the destruction of it. Thus we may ask:
What is left of that nonhuman world or relational field our bodies imply or antici-
pate, and which we need in order to make earthly sense of ourselves?105 What is now
available to be symbolically called on in the making of ourselves? What sort of self-
understanding do we form in interaction with the flesh of our own devices? (Recall
the discussion in the previous chapter regarding the predominance of the machine
metaphor.) In short, given that we exist not inside our skulls, but both in and as our
world-relations, does not the denuding and violating of the natural world denude
and violate our own minds? I submit that there is just nowhere in the great chain
of decision making within a technological society where these kinds of questions
get asked, where the deleterious experiential effects of replacing wild others with
machines and commodities is properly considered—precisely because the pattern
of technology itself sets the terms of the discourse. A large number of ecologically
minded people have, however, thought long and worried hard about just these mat-
ters. Naturalist E. O. Wilson, for instance, writes that “on Earth no less than in
space, lawn grass, potted plants, caged parakeets, puppies, and rubber snakes are
not enough.”106 Insect ecologist Robert Michael Pyle likewise uses the phrase “the
extinction of experience” to describe the loss of personal contact with wildlife that
follows on the extirpation of local habitats.107 Reminding us of the principle of “one
flesh,” Shepard writes, finally, that “our children, growing up with an inadequate
otherness from which to rebound the elements of self, are in danger of becoming
less than human.”108 Having largely destroyed a beautiful and mysterious world, we
are less able to know our own corresponding beauty and mystery, all reality decaying
to the mundane level of a video arcade. In the spirit of these witnesses, I suggest
that most people in a technological society suffer from a form of “violent lack”109 or
experiential starvation; and that it is for ecopsychologists to highlight this condition.
My naturalistic argument, as always, is that our transhistorical environ-
mental needs cannot be bypassed without generating trouble. Historian William
Irwin Thompson argues, by contrast, that “those who were good at living with
trees are on the way out, and those who are good at living with video display
terminals and silicon tubes will be selected for. So cultures are actually selecting
for a new post-natural environment.”110 In this view, there is no problem here,
for nature is nothing but “the horizon of culture.” Again, I believe this is a bad
interpretation of nature. As our world is technologized and denuded of wild
others, we do not “evolve”; rather, we suffer and then creatively adjust. As Shepard
argues, our transhistorical urges are met in “perverted forms in modern society:
our profound love of animals twisted into pets, zoos, decorations, and entertain-
ment; our search for poetic wholeness subverted by the model of the machine
instead of the body; the moment of pubertal idealism shunted into nationalism or
otherworldly religion instead of ecosophical cosmology.”111 We settle for partial,
secondary, or substitutive gratifications—we do the best we can, even when our
best still has much pain and destructiveness in it. I believe that studying many
of our contemporary behaviors as creative adjustments to an antinatural world
would go a long way, therefore, toward discerning the transhistorical needs that
are being thwarted by our society. John Livingston comments, for example, that
the intensity of the house plant business expresses “a deep and primal need” for
contact with other forms of life. “The geranium on the tenement windowsill is
both an offering to the mysterious tidal pull of some distant biological memory,
and a heartbreaking cry for help.”112 Indeed, the promise of studying such creative
adjustments is that we might better hear this cry.
Some argue, nonetheless, that we are not experientially deprived at all. They
say, for example, that the “computerized sensory immersion”113 of virtual reality
can in fact be richer, more thrilling, than the unsimulated reality of the natural
world. Video games are widely available virtual realities of today, while something
like Star Trek’s holo-deck is the promise for tomorrow. Other kinds of artificial
realities also offer experiences otherwise unavailable. At the West Edmonton Mall,
for example, we can (on any day of the year) rent a rubber tube and take a ride
on simulated rapids; towel off; and then go for a walk down an artificial version
of Bourbon Street, New Orleans.114 If our “wildest,” most fantastic dreams can be
virtually or artificially realized, if we can “improve” on reality, then why not do it?
So go the arguments. Borgmann makes an important point when he observes that
such arguments rely on dualistic biases. Hence, “‘experience’ no longer denotes a
decisive encounter with reality but a certain subjective state engendered by what-
ever objective reality.”115 What we experience is an inner event, the result of so
much sensory stimulation acting on our brains. The reality of the “outer” world,
in other words, is a matter of some indifference.116 Against this view, I posit the
alternative one that “the real is progressively given in contact.”117 Reality organismi-
cally unfolds and is built up through our interactions with the world’s otherness.
I said earlier that whatever we experience has some manner of reality. The term
reality is used here, then, in a relative sense—as a designator of the strength or
weakness of our contact with the world. To be more “in touch” with reality is to
make better contact with, or to be dis-illusioned about, the situations in which we
find ourselves. What is most “real,” in this view, are the felt meanings we gather, or
gestalts we form, in active, embodied, and concrete dialogue with the larger world
of which we are a part.118 The strongest, most satisfying reality, in short, is gener-
ally found-and-made in ever-widening spheres of meaning and participation,119
and not simply in consumptive relations with a commodious, artificial, smoothed-
over reality. To the virtual reality company whose motto reads “Reality isn’t enough
anymore,”120 I therefore respond that there isn’t enough Reality anymore.
One can only insert oneself into [the social world] by taking one’s place in the
future-oriented productive juggernaut. But this now seems without any sense;
the relation to the earth as raw material is therefore experienced as empty
and alienating, but the recovery of a valid relation to the earth is the hardest
thing once lost; and there is no relation to the absolute where we are caught
in the web of meanings which have gone dead for us.
—Charles Taylor121
Focal Practice: Disciplined Engagement136 What first of all characterizes all coun-
terpractice, as I am using the term, is that it both takes the form of a regular dis-
cipline and helps bring our lives into focus, providing them with a center. These
are its baseline features. Through such practice, we rediscover a world outside
of labor and consumption, where deeper satisfactions or more life-giving mean-
ings may be experienced. There are no prerequisites for such practice other than
that it be life-forwarding for the person involved. My daily meditation practice,
Anyone can have [a] sense of moral and spiritual engagement with a place. One of
the deep sources of that is to choose a place and focus on it in some way or another.
It doesn’t matter if it’s your backyard in the city, or Central Park, or a farm field. It’s
to find a place in which you can feel deeply engaged, and then go back to it over a
long period of time. . . . I think there’s something very very important about that
engagement.141
Ten minutes by bike from my house142 there is a piece of land known as the Leslie
Street Spit. Built of construction rubble, it was originally intended to form an outer
harbor for the city of Toronto. While the planners were trying to decide what to
do with the landform, plants started to take root in the soil dumped on it from the
construction of a subway line. Now it is a park, rich with flowers, coyotes, musk-
rats, terns, cottonwoods, and other plants and animals, surrounded by a powerful
body of water than meets a beautiful sky. It is also the destination for regular visits
by my friends and me. I mention this place because, with rebar and slag jutting out
all over the place, it is no pristine wilderness. Yet with every visit, it offers its gifts.
On a recent trip, my wife and I looked up from studying a flower to find ourselves
in the middle of a flock of ring-billed gulls feasting on June bugs that filled the air
close to the ground. We felt right inside a feeding event, as if standing upside down
on the surface of a lake watching a school of fish eat minnows. It was an exciting,
funny, graceful, awful experience, whose meanings are still reverberating within
me. And it is just the kind of nontechnologized encounter that is easily available to
anyone who would make of such trips a counterpractice.
Counterpractice also entails a commitment to understanding others not as
mere objects, resources, and consumers, but as ensouled persons with something
to say. This, to be sure, is not the easiest of practices in a deanimated world. The
great long-term significance of making such an ontological shift, however (one
which I again feel will require much healing along the way), is that people “do
not exploit a nature that speaks to them.”143 Abram suggests, in this respect, that
we assume there is “some manner of spontaneity and sentience,” some mode of
aliveness, in all we encounter. He then recommends the practice of not speaking
disrespectfully to or about anything.144 Ursula LeGuin also writes: “Perhaps it is
only when the otherness, the difference, the space between us (in which both cru-
elty and love occur) is perceived as holy ground, as the sacred place, that we can
‘come into animal presence.’ ”145 Practices that are dedicated to place are so impor-
tant because they involve this kind of sacrilizing process, wherein through skillful
dialogue with a specific locale it is allowed to disclose itself in its deeper meanings.
Coming Back to Life147 The ecology movement works to defend and restore life
on earth. The promise of ecopsychology is to assert that humans themselves par-
ticipate in this life, and to encourage the work that brings us back to it. My own
strategy is to criticize our society on the basis of its antagonism to the life process,
and then to argue for a kind of politics that explicitly makes what Dorothy Din-
nerstein has called “a deep turn toward life.”148 Whatever actions I am involved
in, I want them to be healing and satisfying, for those are the kind that the life
process calls for, that are meaningful; I want to act in ways that are at the same
time a defense and restoration of human life. As I reviewed in chapter one, there
is a growing recognition that when activists try to mobilize people on the basis
of fear, guilt, and shame, they may well be adding to an immobilizing despair,
apathy, and denial. What follows, then, are my own thoughts on what a difference
it makes to our practice when our political acts are grounded in a dedication to, or
appreciation for, our nature and our experience.
I have already suggested that a pivotal issue for ecopsychology is the weak-
ened state of our humanity. As the biosphere crumbles, so do we. The dreadful
possibility is that we are sliding into a state in which most people are too dis-
tressed, are not in any kind of shape, to ever turn their attention to the better-
ment of society. Christopher Lasch refers to the emergence of a “minimal self,” a
self that “contracts to a defensive core,” that retreats from any kind of emotional
commitment to long-term causes, its main task being day-to-day survival. “The
hope that political action will gradually humanize industrial society has given way
to a determination to survive the general wreckage or, more modestly, to hold
one’s own life together in the face of mounting pressures.”149 I heard an author
of a book about the unhealthy speediness of our society say that: “If we can’t save
society, at least we can save ourselves.” For the beleaguered self, the need to work
for social change simply does not become figural, for the conditions are not right
for the organism to feel this as its most pressing need. The “permanent emergency
of the individual” — “unable to think beyond itself ” — “blocks the permanent
and social solution.”150
As a result of the disintegration of the self, politics in our times has largely
been replaced by therapeutics—a development much bemoaned by many radi-
cals. As Jacoby suggests, “the depletion of political concepts in favor of psycho-
logical and subjective ones is a by-product of the scramble for the remains of
human experience.”151 Recall that the workings of capital require that the personal
sphere become inflated, that we become ever-more needy. This is partly why the
field of psychology looms so large in our age, and why social issues tend to get
reduced to psychological ones. Within the circles of humanistic psychotherapy,
for example, it is often assumed that personal transformation will somehow “mag-
ically extend” to the rest of society. As Isaac Prilleltensky notes, in their groups
“humanists nurture each other and foster the belief that a better world is inevitably
coming, without intervening in the real world.”152 Social activism becomes a kind
of group therapy session. As much as anything else, what is perhaps revealed by
the culture of personal growth is simply a “growing despair of changing society,
even understanding it.”153
A first step toward addressing this matter is to recognize that it is not only
a moral issue, but a political issue in itself. What “needs to be criticized and con-
demned,” writes Lasch, “is the devastation of personal life, not the retreat into pri-
vatism. . . . The trouble with the consciousness movement is not that it addresses
trivial or unreal issues but that it provides self-defeating solutions” (because it
does not address itself to the social structures that brutalize personal life in the
first place).154 If people are preoccupied with their own growth or survival, I think
it is only fair to say that this reflects how very little our society is itself occupied
with their growth and survival.155 In my view, the best way to encourage indi-
viduals back toward society is therefore to be all the more attentive or sensitive to
their personal experience. In this, I am agreeing with a large number of thinkers
who argue that social movement toward greater freedom and happiness will occur
only if the “subjective conditions” are suitably prepared.156 To concentrate on pre-
paring these conditions is not the same as flattening out the psyche-society dialect
in the psychologistic manner I just discussed. It is rather to give the personal
sphere its due.157 Roger Gottlieb writes that “the flaws of both communism and
advanced capitalism can be overcome only if ordinary people achieve sufficient
power and self-knowledge to shape social life in terms of the wisdom of their own
experience and the demands of their own true needs.”158 This requires, in turn,
that they develop (1) an understanding of how their lives have been deformed
by their society, and (2) the capacity to act on that understanding, including the
inner ability to make judgments independent of authorities and experts. (These
two tasks clearly act in concert, for we take up a critical theory of society only to
the extent that we are capable of bearing what it is trying to show us; and such
a theory itself arises from or is complemented by our independent judgments
or symbolizations of our own experience.) My discussion of the pattern of tech-
nology was addressed to the first of these tasks. A technological society, like any
other, organizes our experience in a way that is consistent with or that corresponds
to it. As many have noted, competitive, commodity-hungry, individualists are by
their very essence not drawn to radical politics or cooperative action. To work
from and toward a different understanding of ourselves, one that is both truer to
our nature and incompatible with the order of technological society, is therefore a
way to gradually turn ourselves out of this society and to energize ourselves toward
the transformation of it. The challenge, as Paul Goodman expressed it, is “to live
in present society as if it were a natural society.”159 Developing the ability and sup-
port to do so is the topic for the rest of this section.
Among the many efforts that people are making to better our society and
its relationship with the natural world, the role I see for ecopsychology is to create
the contexts that will help people recover their own nature and experience. This
means, furthermore, being respectful of the position from which each person
might begin such a recovery. If the life process be our concern, then I believe all
people are entitled to keep themselves above what I call the healing threshold.160
Below this critical threshold our lives spiral downward, we fall through the cracks
and self-destruct, we lack the support (both inner and outer) to get on top of our
pain and find our bearings. Above this threshold, our lives move forward, we gain
strength, we enjoy the necessary support to learn, grow, and expand the spheres
of our social concern—as we are naturally ordered to do. I am myself dedicated
to creating a society in which all people are generally able to remain above this
healing threshold (such a society being as far as I allow my utopian thinking go).
The Buddhist Ken Jones takes a similar position: “The unequal burdens of [kar-
maic] conditioning are compassionately recognized as well as the sacred individual
freedom to relinquish them. Spiritual egalitarianism therefore honours individual
differences and the importance of each person being able to develop their poten-
tial in their own unique way and at the pace proper to them.”161 My own vision is
that of a society in which each person is supported in unfolding her or his life in
the direction that her or his specific existence implies, whether it be to heal from
childhood trauma, lead a movement to end poverty, or guide adolescents through
their initiation rites. While I have no wish to add to the long list of elaborate
political programs that never make it off the page of the text, I do want to mention
two general areas of practice, already underway, that are indeed designed to help
build a life-oriented society. The first includes the work of all those communities
or forums that offer support for the beleaguered self. The second includes all those
efforts that are contributing to the development of a culture that is responsible to
the human life cycle.
Efforts to support the beleaguered self include the community workshops
and other initiatives I discussed in chapter one which attempt to provide emo-
tional and spiritual ground for activists and concerned citizens. Because my own
experience in this area is primarily with a peer self-help psychotherapy group
(Re-evaluation Counseling) and with the worldwide “focusing” community,
I will base my discussion primarily on them. What is crucial about these two
c ommunities—and others like them—is that they provide contexts within which
we can re-emerge as human beings and turn our attention toward the larger world.
I can think of three important ways that they do this.
The first is that they offer training in recovering our ability to work from
our own bodily experience, to hear our own inner voice. If the violence of the
modern world alienates us from this voice, then reconnecting with it is a coun-
terpractice of historical significance. Overcoming dualism is no easy thing, no
mere philosophical exercise, but a practical task that asks us to give ourselves
over to the worldly demands of our bodies and to go through the often painful
and scary process of thawing out our own flesh. We generally prefer to stimulate
ourselves—to get excitement into our deadened bodies through bungee jumping
and watching horror movies—rather than to resensitize ourselves. To the extent
that we can do the latter, however, the benefits are tremendous, for (among other
gains) we reclaim a centre for ourselves. Nothing compares to being able to speak
our own truth, to having confidence in our saying because of the sureness of our
feeling. There is an astonishing difference between going through life on the basis
of stuck patterns, old ideas, introjected beliefs, habitual reactions, other people’s
opinions, superego warnings, expert advice, and archaic fantasies versus being
aware of what we are bodily sensing in any given situation and listening for the
needs, insights, fresh symbols, creative resolutions, and dialogical responses that
flow from this source of organismic guidance. The goal of the focusing community
is to make a space for all those bodies who are interested in working in this latter
way, on the assumption that a society full of people capable of doing so will bear
very little resemblance to the society of today. Meeting regularly with a “focusing
partner” is one of the main forms of practice that comes out of this commu-
nity. The person who introduced this popular self-help practice, Eugene Gendlin,
writes: “The political context I am concerned about is the individual’s own self-
guidance by an inner source. Without this we cannot hope for any better political
forms than we have now and have had throughout history.”162 In helping people
to revitalize the concrete, experiential side of life, the focusing community is in its
own way thus endeavoring to generate a populace of more capable social agents.163
The second way these efforts contribute to the making of a life-oriented
society is that they locate social change work within the life process, making it
part of the good life. The commitment is to develop, in Joanna Macy’s words,
“practical methods for embarking on social action, and sustaining and enjoying it,
so that it is no longer seen as a daunting, demanding exercise in self-sacrifice. . . .
so that our work for the world runs like an ever-refreshing stream through our
lives.”164 In other words, the intention is to create conditions under which we can
both discover what particular social action will be meaningful for us and acquire
the emotional support to then do it. In this case, our organismic energy flows
into the action because it meets a genuine need to engage the world on a matter
their being and as the original domain for spiritual initiation. Amongst all the
noise of technological adolescence, vision quests and other wilderness rites are
counterpractices capable of bringing a transformative focus to the lives of many
a confused youth. As Foster notes, such rites, which includes guidance from a
council of caring elders, provide “an invaluable opportunity to make a difference
in how at-risk youth see their future.”173 This kind of rite work, furthermore, is
not just for adolescents. In his The Four Shields: The Initiatory Seasons of Human
Nature, Foster (with Little) lays out an entire psychological model based on the
seasons and other metaphors drawn largely from the natural world, and in which
all the stages of life are incorporated. I myself undertook a wilderness quest at the
time of my marriage, and the vision and understanding I gained on it remain a
continual source of guidance and strength as I paddle my way forward in life. Rite
work, in fact, explicitly involves all three of my naturalistic principles. It supports
people in finding their place in both human and more-than-human society (i.e.,
in widening their spheres of belonging and responsibility); in perceiving a world
beyond the boundaries of strictly human reality, and so in beginning to sing (or
even “creatively mythologize”)174 this wider world; and in learning to see their
own lives symbolically mirrored and bound up in the flesh of all living things.
All manner of rite work—an annual wilderness fast, for example, to refresh one’s
vision and maintain one’s connection with the psyche of nature—can thus form a
strong basis for counterpractice.
quite mysterious. Despite my emphasis on the losses of the modern era, in order
to be humble servants of nature we do not need to be all sorted out nor living in
profound relation to Wolf and Eagle; we only need to be present. To come back to
life is to realize that it is a process, one that involves taking countless steps that we
can never quite predict, but which are most surely taken when grounded in con-
tact with presently felt reality. Regardless of one’s starting situation, to serve nature
is to sense what the life force is asking for, what wants to unfold, move, happen, or
come next. Today, moreover, perhaps more than at any other time, I believe that
to be a servant of nature is to learn the essentially human art of bearing pain and
suffering—as I discuss next.
Life, as we find it, is too hard for us; it brings too many pains,
disappointments and impossible tasks. In order to bear it we cannot
dispense with palliative measures. . . . There are perhaps three such
measures: powerful distractions, which cause us to make light of our misery;
substitutive satisfactions, which diminish it; and intoxicating substances,
which make us insensitive to it.
—Sigmund Freud176
Rather than putting down the revolt of nature, I have said that we need to join
it—need to join with the life force in rebelling against the repressive and exploita-
tive aspects of modern society. Revolts are messy, though; and to join this one is
to feel the pain and suffering that the pattern of technology both generates and
acts to hide. Indeed, in the discussions above I have depicted the domination of
nature as an entirely backward solution to the problem of pain and suffering. In
the environmentalist’s thinking about what it will take to reverse the ecological
crisis, I suggest that this is a terribly overlooked factor. In this section I thus want
to discuss the age-old truth that we can know ourselves, know our humanity, only
if willing to consciously learn from our suffering. But how to bear it? The healing
that goes on in a psychotherapist’s office involves contacting those painful feelings
we have previously been unable to bear, but which in a more supportive context
can now be awarely experienced and completed. The same principle applies in all
healing work: that the ground for the work—inner, interpersonal, physical, moral,
conceptual, spiritual, ecological—must be strong enough so that we can maintain
a sufficient distance from our unpleasant feelings to both tolerate and move through
them. For the most part, our society lacks such contexts; it offers cotton candy and
pills instead. It is thus no wonder that we have become so apathetic, for apathy
(a-pathos) is precisely an insensibility to suffering. I suggest, in short, that we are
just not going to be able to get it together, or do the radical work, unless we enjoy
better self-knowledge—and that this implies creating the loving conditions under
which we can feel, and so discover the meaning of, our pain and suffering. In the
previous section I discussed some of the forums and communities that presently
offer these kinds of conditions. What I concentrate on here is the specific need
to make the bearing of pain and suffering a central principle of ecopsychological
work. Gary Coates suggests that we view our historical suffering as an invitation to
undertake a kind of rite of passage, through which we might renew our culture.178
All such rites, however, involve preparation. As Venerable Myokyo-ni writes, the
first step toward wholeness takes place “in the training yard, learning to bear with
oneself, to bear emotional onslaughts, becoming gentle and stronger, acquiring
not Bull-strength but bearing strength.”179
Life strives toward happiness; suffering is a message that we’re going the
wrong way or that some painful state of affairs needs our attention. Our suffering,
then, is a kind of life compass and teacher. Even the most vital people move
their lives forward by responding to the tension of those bodily felt desires that
urge them to take some action, make some sense. In a way, then, we are always
making sense out of suffering. Inasmuch as we do not, our tensions inevitably
grow. Hence, a society that knows little about suffering, that does much to avoid
it, will know little about life (and so little about happiness). Consider, on this
note, the biopsychiatrist Donald Goodwin’s remark that “anxiety has no more
survival value than a tension headache. Its elimination would be a blessing.”180 I
understand anxiety as our feeling for the void. It thus both motivates the spiritual
search and emerges strongly in people who have been traumatized and isolated.
I understand tension headaches, furthermore, as symptomatic of repressed emo-
tion, such as grief and anger. To argue for the “elimination” of these is therefore
to grossly ignore their potential meaning. It is also to adopt that self-defeating
approach for disburdening ourselves of suffering—itself rooted in anxiety—which
I call “the strategy of violence.”
The strategy of violence is to deal with the problem of pain and suffering
by trying to annihilate what are perceived as the sources of distress. Richard
Slotkin suggests that a dominant myth in the United States is that of “regenera-
tion through violence.” Originating with Puritan colonists, this myth holds that
a new society is to be made through exorcising or attacking dark (corrupt, bad,
threatening) forces, whether these be located in nature, Native Americans, Satan,
or North Vietnamese. It, too, is a defective myth, however, in that it leads not to
any kind of satisfaction, but only to a spiral of increasing violence and increasing
guiltanxiety.181 All death, no rebirth. This myth, then, is part of the cultural back-
ground of a society that has become a kind of killing machine. My concern here is
with how we turn this killing attitude toward ourselves, using drugs, for example,
as “a weapon against the void.”182 Ours is a society that for the most part attempts
to annihilate pain, to self-destructively go to war with it (whether the target be a
recipient of our “projections” or our own bodies), rather than to recover the life
that is locked up inside it. Why might this be so? Having started this chapter with
a simple idea (happiness), I wish to also finish it with one: that we choose the
strategy of violence only when we lack the contexts necessary to bear our pain and
suffering, and so to stay above the healing threshold. When the pain of life is too
great to bear, we use our aggression against it. All repression, for example, is a life-
diminishing act of aggression against our natural selves. Drugs and alcohol desen-
sitize or temporarily soothe us. And so on. The strategy of violence does not satisfy
us precisely because it is not a positive search for fulfillment but a last-ditch quest
for release from pain. The “fateful question” for our times is thus not, as Freud
held, whether the instinct for life can win out over the instinct for death (the latter
of which is an erroneous construction183), but whether or not we will choose to
find collective ways to bear our pain and suffering, to strengthen ourselves, so that
we can then stop negating life and instead get back to it. In the hope that we will,
and in the face of all the evidence that we won’t, I offer the following remarks.
To stay above the healing threshold we need a context for containing our pain
that is larger or stronger than the pain itself (recall, for example, the contexts neces-
sary to do the oppression-work within the RC community). Given the enormity
of our pain, I suggest that our society needs very strong frameworks indeed. The
strongest contexts, moreover, will in some sense always be spiritual. The recovery
movement involves much spiritual practice (e.g., twelve-step programs) exactly
because this puts people’s pain into a more tolerable context. As the Gestaltist
James Kepner also comments, the “reality of trauma and abuse, with its horror,
hideousness, and inexplicable quality, simply cannot be held and made sense of
within the individual person.” Thus, “most survivors find some compelling need
to develop a transcendent spiritual or philosophical framework.”184 This comes
as no surprise, as religious symbols have traditionally helped people understand
the cosmos in a way that makes their pain endurable. “As a religious problem,”
says Clifford Geertz, “the problem of suffering is, paradoxically, not how to avoid
suffering but how to suffer, how to make of physical pain, personal loss, worldly
defeat, or the helpless contemplation of others’ agony something bearable, sup-
portable—something, as we say, sufferable.”185 Our technologized and economized
society does not encourage the creation of such cultural frameworks for bearing
pain and suffering—only for avoiding and trying to kill it. This seems to me a fatal
state of affairs. It is not my place to prescribe specific spiritual practices. I think it
fair to say, though, that we are today called by nature, by the voice of our own pain,
by the cry of the earth, to reoccupy the spiritual-ecological dimension of existence.
I have already mentioned efforts by people like Joanna Macy to promote
spiritual practice and understanding within the ecology, peace, and social justice
movements.186 The Green Party activist Ken Jones does not mince words: “only
some spiritual kind of conviction and training have the strength to bring about
the necessary radical shift.”187 Or as Ram Dass has said, such training is necessary
if we are to “keep our hearts open in hell.”188 Among the various dimension that
make up my own practice, the most powerfully healing and strengthening have
been those tied to a routine of Buddhist meditation and study. I have come to be
less resentful of my pain, realizing that the work of life is exactly to learn from this
suffering: to see how it attunes me to the pain of others; to develop the capacity
to disidentify from it and so “breathe it through”; and to make out of it whatever
small piece of work is mine to do in this lifetime.189 I do not doubt, then, that
the spread of such practice would be of great benefit to all—as would many other
kinds of such practice. Whether our society undergoes a positive spiritual shift,
whether it gets on top of its pain and violence, is obviously a matter that goes well
beyond whatever interventions ecopsychologists might make. What I do want to
stress, however, as a central theme of my own, is that the spiritual condition of our
time is largely defined by the shame and isolation of the terrified Ego. The Cath-
olic author Michael Higgens, in commenting on the hellishness of the twentieth
century, characterizes hell precisely as a state of isolation (and so heaven as a state
of communion).190 I thus believe that the most basic requirement of a strength-
ening spiritual practice for our times is that it include a supportive response to this
widespread condition of shame and isolation.
Shame is perhaps the hardest emotion to bear. When workaholics stop
working, for example, they often feel engulfed by a sense of worthlessness, and so
dive once again into further work. The more we matter-of-factly acknowledge the
feeling of shame, however, and so give up the shameful feeling of having to run
from it, the more compassionate will we become as a society. This is because shame
is the emotion of rejection and isolation; to respectfully listen to shame is to hear a
cry for love and community, for acknowledgment of both the goodness and full-
ness of our nature. Tuning into this cry—to those common feelings of inadequacy,
inferiority, badness, unlovability, fear of abandonment, and so on—could thus be
an ecopsychological undertaking of great historical significance, going right to
the emotional core of our society. Our historical economic development, writes
Kovel, “was won through the destruction of community. . . . From its basis and
origin in the differentiated unity of primitive society, subjectivity has undergone
a ‘progressive’ atomization and conflictual intensification with the intrusion, first
of the state, then of the capitalist market, into the organic relationship between
self, others, and nature. This results in the isolated, deeply problematic subject of
today.”191 Hence: “A more or less universal separateness characterizes being under
capital.”192 As so many people have realized, overcoming this loss of sociality is a
matter of rebuilding community.193 What is also called for, though, is acknowl-
edgment of the terrible feelings of shame, hate, grief, and so on that the history
of desociation has engendered. Whatever form our practice takes, I simply believe
it needs to make room for the bearing of these feelings. The practice needed to
transform this society, then, may look less like sitting on a meditation cushion and
more like holding hands.
And what of the natural world? Bearing pain is always a matter of placing
it in a larger context so that it both loses its overwhelming power and is given the
space it needs to move. Several years ago I entered into some emotionally stormy
waters. After one particularly sleepness night spent with my demons, and feeling
all tight with my pain, I made my way to the kitchen for a mug of tea. I was sitting
there alone when a cardinal began to whistle outside the window. “The cardinal
still sings,” I whispered . . . and then started to cry. The thick beauty of that song,
the cool, pungent early morning air, and the crystallizing words that arrived on
my lips, all combined to lift me out of my Ego—out into the enduring life stream
beyond my own narrow existence—so that I was finally able to let the healing tears
roll down my face. I am sharing this story for two points it illustrates. The first
is that the more isolated we are the more pain we feel, that is, the more personal,
cramped, and unbearable it becomes.194 The second is that making healing con-
nections with nonhuman others can involve the simplest of acts. Plainly put, any
practice that helps reembed us within the society of nature, or expand the field of
our care, cannot but help us bear our pain and suffering.
I vividly recall an Ojibway elder who, while talking before a group of
people, said that he lacked the courage on his own to get up in front of a crowd.
His strength came from his relationship with the spirit of Bear. If, indeed, it is
our nature to seek empowerment from other animals, what more appropriate
animal to lend us strength and help “bear” our pain than the bear? (Although
there is apparently no etymological link between the verb “to bear” and the lum-
bering animal we call a “bear,” the phonetic link is a fruitful one. Indeed, Hillman
notes that such phonetic resemblances may “indicate profound connections.”195)
Shepard writes that our fascination and fear of bears suggests an “urge to be reu-
nited with something lost and treasured, seen in the animal that most resembles
us. It is almost as though in him we can see how great is our loss of contact with
ourselves. Perhaps the bear can still serve as a pilot and messenger.”196 More gen-
erally speaking, I would note, if only suggestively, that if we are to consciously
experience our historical suffering as a kind of rite of passage, we had best make it
a prayer to the whole natural world.
Contrary to modern myth, the technological domination of nature does
not relieve but ultimately exacerbates our suffering. Just what combination of
contexts might provide the support for this wounded society to now bear its pain
and suffering, for people to give up the fantasy of technological salvation and so
come back to earth, is not something that can be predicted. Despite all my tenta-
tive commentary, my aim in this section was primarily to raise this topic, to stir
up some areas of thought, and not to give any answers. I have attempted in this
book to illustrate an approach that puts its faith in the process of feeling our way
forward, not in coming up with the master solution. It is the natural governance
of this process that is my greatest source of hope.
Last night I was in the pub talking with local environmentalists about
their depression and despair. They also talked about their sense for the beauty
and wonder of life, and their uncertainty about how to communicate that to
the public, how to speak from their passion. As the discussion unfolded into the
night it became clear to me that the work of ecopsychology is to help us “come
out” as human beings. To come out is to say: “Yes, this is what I am; no apolo-
gies.” A human being is a servant of nature, a plain member in the community
of all life. For us today, however, to stand up and say this with an open heart is
to make ourselves vulnerable; is to risk ridicule. We can nonetheless be confident
in our vulnerability. As a psychotherapist I know that all people need to love and
be loved, that they all suffer in some way or other, and that they are all basically
good. As an ecopsychologist, I can now say with equal confidence that all people
need to experience themselves as a part of the natural world, need to understand
their own naturalness. The more we can, as ecopsychologists, build our alternative
vision of humans and nature, the bolder we will become in encouraging others to
speak out for a society that is consistent with this vision. Indeed, the promise of
ecopsychology is to be a force for the therapeutic, recollective, and critical work
that will help to make such a society a reality.
A good hockey player plays where the puck is. A great hockey
player plays where the puck is going to be.
—Wayne Gretzky
I wrote Radical Ecopsychology in the late 1990s, a time when ecopsychology was
still riding the wave of excitement generated by the Ecopsychology primer released
in 1995.1 While I shared in this excitement I also felt that ecopsychology faced
specific conceptual, methodological, and political challenges that made its suc-
cess as a field far from assured. My goal with Radical Ecopsychology was therefore
to make a contribution that would help both to define the radical character of
ecopsychology and to set it on some firm intellectual footings. I was concerned
with how ecopsychology might develop, not wanting to see it absorbed into the
mainstream or stalled for lack of scholarly follow-through. In this new chapter,
then, I reflect on how ecopsychology has actually developed in the last ten years
and offer my thoughts on how I see the project today.2 In many ways it is better
positioned to get on its feet now than it was a decade ago. This is partly due to
efforts made by various people to keep the field alive and partly due to historical
trends that make ecopsychology increasingly attractive and viable. My concern
nonetheless remains unchanged: to keep the possibility open for an ecopsychology
skillfully at home with its own radicalness.
If all thinkers have one main thought, mine is that ecopsychology is an
inherently radical project. Everything I have written since Radical Ecopsychology
continues to sing this song.3 One of the questions I get asked about my work,
however, is whether using the word radical is such a good idea, given that it can be
associated with extremist politics. My usual response is to say that being a radical
simply means regarding our collective problems as deeper or more thoroughgoing
than the mainstream view appreciates or is willing to recognize. To be a radical
ecologist is to hold that the ecological crisis has deep cultural, social, economic,
political, historical, philosophical—and psychological—roots. My argument is
197
merely that ecopsychology has this radical nature, that it sprang from and essen-
tially belongs to the radical ecology movement. Indeed, to practice ecopsychology
is consistently to stumble onto its disruptive philosophical and critical implica-
tions. For example, ecopsychology is about relating or integrating psyche and
nature, yet the conceptual dualisms of inside/outside, mind/body, subject/object,
immediately stop us in our tracks. Hence, the philosophical task I discussed in
chapter 1. If I were writing the book today, I would actually enlarge the philo-
sophical task to make it more radical still, for the dualism between psyche and
society also falls once the psyche is turned inside out (as I discussed under the
heading of the critical task). An ecopsychology that faces the psychological dimen-
sion of the ecological crisis head-on will not pretend that the psyche—as an inter-
relational phenomenon—can be disentwined from either nature or society, and
hence psychology from either ecology or politics (or thus from political ecology).
Such an ecopsychology quickly winds up in territory radically different from that
of normal psychology. But for me this is the only way that psychology with an
ecological ontology or nondualistic view of reality can make sense. In short, I call
ecopsychology radical because it is radical.
I have suggested that ecopsychology is best thought of as a psychological
politics aimed at creating the subjective conditions for an ecological society.4 (If
it is not playing this role then what exactly is it doing?) Another reason to keep
ecopsychology radical is that we are otherwise unlikely to get an accurate under-
standing of our existing society and so of the radical work necessary to transition to
an ecological one. With the Great Recession still reverberating around the globe, it
is becoming ever clearer that ours is what James O’Connor calls a “specifically capi-
talist” society, one that remakes the world in the image of capital, subjecting every
nook and cranny of reality to the logic of profit, capital accumulation, and com-
modification; a society, furthermore, that sets in motion “a self-perpetuating spiral
of ecological and human destruction”5 as it wastefully converts public or common
wealth into private riches. I remain convinced, then, that an ecological society
must be a postcapitalist one and hence that ecopsychology must incorporate the
discourse of ecosocialism. The challenge nonetheless remains: how to win an
audience or avoid being a marginal movement when using terms such as socialism.
I think there is a way forward with this challenge. As I discussed in
chapter 2, it is a matter of rhetoric, of persuasive speech. The question, then, is
how ecopsychology can stay radical (as I think it must if it is not to contradict
its own first principles), while also appealing to or moving a mainstream audi-
ence, both academic and popular. First of all, I do believe that strong scholarship
is necessary. Ecopsychology is often dismissed as a flaky or lightweight field, its
radical message thereby lost. I find this sad and ironic because in its questioning
of so much that is taken for granted in the modern world ecopsychology actually
calls for scholarship of the most demanding and creative kind. Without a founda-
tion of such radical scholarship we have nothing to stand on, don’t really have a
field, and therefore cannot hope to persuade others to our cause. If, for example,
mainstream psychologists don’t see the relevance of political economic questions
then we need to carefully demonstrate how psychology is already saturated with
political economic meanings, and how these relate to ecological issues. I imagine
a text for an academic audience entitled Invitation to Ecopsychology precisely as a
way to initiate scholarly dialogue at this level.
Beyond the need for strong scholarship, I think there are several other
points to consider. Being a radical ecologist has always involved a certain paradox:
that to get a seat at the table of respectability one generally has to stifle one’s
true feelings and viewpoints.6 I believe, however, that this paradox is weakening
because historical events are making the radical view appear more and more sen-
sible. The modern world has reached a point in history in which the false promises
and grossly exploitative nature of the capitalist system are steadily being recog-
nized. Richard Heinberg’s popular book The End of Growth, which essentially
announces the grinding down of capitalism, would not have appeared even a few
years ago. Fred Magdoff and John Bellamy Foster’s guide What Every Environ-
mentalist Needs to Know about Capitalism likewise seems of this moment. As I
write this, the Occupy Wall Street protest is in its third week. Climate change
and peak oil loom darkly over the future. And because of all of this, the need and
desire for alternative social arrangements are growing louder, the Transition, local
food, and new peasant movements being three widespread responses. I think the
possibility thus exists for a well-crafted radical ecopsychology to speak to a large
audience if it can line its praxis up with the grain of history, discerning the kind of
social changes implied by current times rather than proposing something entirely
discontinuous with them.7 Despite that ecosocialism might for some people pro-
voke fearsome images of the communist horde, when it is looked at openly with a
mind to our present needs it does in fact have many attractive elements and give
numerous clues to the nature of an ecological society, as I attempt to demonstrate
in discussions below.
What may help to make the image of a postcapitalist ecological society even
more attractive is if the case for it can be made with some psychological skillful-
ness and sensitivity. Ecopsychologists are lovers of life, whether life is expressed as
nature or as psyche (two terms that increasingly merge in the mind of the ecopsy-
chologist). If we can speak against the life-negating aspects of capitalist society
and in favor of a life-serving one, using a rhetoric that is not alarmist or militant
but rather attuned to the struggles, anxieties, and longings of modern existence,
then the radical view may indeed take root. Ecopsychology is a response to the
profound ecological and psychological illiteracy that accompanies the modern
alienation from nature.8 Ecopsychology radically conceived adds the idea that
this alienation also involves political illiteracy. One of the remarkable features
of modern society is how thoroughly the capitalist system shapes our lives and
yet how poorly this system is generally understood. To my mind, part of the art
vexed issue of where and how . . . conservation psychology situates itself with respect
to ecopsychology and its myriad forms. . . . There are many psychologists working
in the environmental arena who have serious reservations about a seeming psycho-
logical and conservation initiative and movement (i.e., ecopsychology) which draws
from, in part, very mixed popular culture, new age, anti-psychiatry, and analytic and
psychoanalytic roots, and often spiritual emphasis and application. . . . [M]uch of
this enterprise is incongruent with, if not inimical to, the research- and evidence-
based practice of applied psychology, environmental management and planning,
and conservation sciences. . . . [T]here are clear costs with respect to who will join
a collaborative research venture and field [i.e., conservation psychology] which does
not clearly situate itself with respect to ecopsychology.19
Reser’s remarks cut two ways. On the one hand, he recognizes the significance of
the topics raised by ecopsychology but shares the scientific mainstream’s reserva-
tions about granting the field the status of psychology. On the other hand, he
laments the narrow mindset and academic politics within psychology that have
prevented it from taking up these same topics:
These comments—which suggest the uphill battle ecopsychology faces within the
academy, especially because environmental psychology itself had to win respect-
ability as a scientific discipline21—were made by Reser in reference to the period
leading up to his 1995 article. Reser does believe, however, that there is some
degree of openness today within psychology to the ecopsychological viewpoint
due to a gradual recognition of its merit and to the increasing gravity of the eco-
logical crisis.22
Two psychologists who are indeed open to ecopsychology are Susan Koger
and Deborah Winter.23 In their text The Psychology of Environmental Problems they
suggest that although “ecopsychology is often ignored by mainstream psycholo-
gists and even treated with contempt by some,” this can be attributed to the fact
that ecopsychologists tend not to be scientists but rather “clinicians, therapists,
and philosophers” who look at “aspects of human experience that are difficult to
measure.”24 Koger and Winter are nonetheless hopeful that scientific research on
the ecological self “may empirically validate some of the claims of ecopsychologists,
and thus put it in more direct view” of conservation psychologists. Given this posi-
tion, they make a point of disagreeing with my idea that ecopsychology needs
to “give up psychology’s attachment to various forms of objectivism.” While
acknowledging that quantitative methods have their limits and drawbacks, they
“believe that the psychology of environmental problems will progress as measuring
tools are developed for what was previously believed to be unmeasurable.”
As mainstream psychologists who are generous in their treatment of eco-
psychology, Koger and Winter present an instructive case. To me their approach
demonstrates that a meaningful gap still exists between what even sympathetic
members of the mainstream can make of ecopsychology and the kind of vision
of ecopsychology I offer in this book. In evaluating ecopsychology, the starting
point for Koger and Winter is quantitative empiricism, which means that ecopsy-
chology has to prove itself to conventional science if it wants into the clubhouse.
This is exactly the bias I have wished to challenge.
(As a point of clarification, however, I am not an all-out foe of empirical
science, as I state at several places in this book.25 When I urge a move away from
objectivism I am using that term to refer to the philosophical position that there
is some singular, ahistorical, unbiased framework by which objective truth can
be determined and knowledge claims assessed.26 In fact, Koger and Winter make
statements indicating they themselves do not hold this view.27 Radicals tend not to
oppose empiricism in its entirety but rather the objectivist ideological restriction
of truth to the arena of conventional empirical research alone. My own discussions
in this respect have been directed at raising the hermeneutic question, so that the
history of and ontological prejudices within modern empiricism may be evaluated
in relation to the ecopsychological project,28 and so that the various meanings of
interest to ecopsychology but obscured by mainstream science may be revealed.)
Koger and Winter clearly care about ecopsychology and wish to help validate
its claims. I am not convinced, though, that the form of scholarship they propose
is the most suited to do this. Missing from their account is any real acknowledg-
ment of the serious debate over psychology’s image of itself as a science29 and of
what Thomas Teo calls “psychology’s hermeneutic deficit,” its relative blindness
to or disinterest in its own entrenched biases and unquestioned modes of inter-
pretation.30 Most obviously at work here is the quantification bias, which feeds a
drive to convert the unmeasurable to the measurable. As an exercise in returning
soul, depth, and spirit to the world—qualities that indeed resist measurement—
ecopsychology must champion approaches that are adequate to these phenomena
while simultaneously protesting the modern “disqualifying” of the universe which
contributes to the destruction of human and earthly worlds.31 While Koger and
Winter do make room for experiential data (and include in their discussion of
ecopsychology a moving testimonial from Terry Tempest Williams and a lovely
poem by Mary Oliver), this allowance is not pursued with much force, being over-
shadowed by their commitment to conventional psychology and by the minor
presence in their text of hermeneutical and critical approaches.32 Finally, what
from my perspective is most absent from Koger and Winter’s discussion is a rec-
ognition that the very notion of ecopsychology actually constitutes a challenge to
psychology not just to apply itself to solving “environmental problems” but, more
radically, to transform itself in the face of them.33
What might this transformation involve? In my reading, Reser and Koger
and Winter are essentially saying something like: “We think ecopsychology is
important but let’s make sure to keep it psychology.” By contrast, consider the
words of one of ecopsychology’s earliest voices, Robert Greenway: “I have argued
for many, many years that ecopsychology is not just another psychology. But most
of the people interested in ecopsychology are either therapists or psychologists.
not a method of simple confession but rather of allowing oneself to be drawn into
the work of the research through one’s wounds or complexes, through a kind of
love for or “erotic tie” to the work, and then engaging in imaginal dialogues that
give a voice to that in the world which has been lost, forgotten, or marginalized.
According to Romanyshyn, working with dreams illustrates this approach best,
as dreams are always asking the dreamer to release their ego’s hold on the status
quo.39 Just so, research with soul in mind requires of the researcher that they
release their narcissistic attachment to what they want the research to be about
and to allow the soul of the work to dictate the outcome instead. In this way, says
Romanyshyn, the research sinks into the depths of the divide between subject
and object, resulting in a deepened sense of objectivity arrived at through deep
engagement in subjective dynamics.
I could give other examples of research approaches that deliberately incor-
porate the researcher’s subjectivity, and which, like Romanyshyn’s method, have
potential value for ecopsychology.40 My point in this discussion, however, has
been that overcoming dualism means legitimating such methods and, further,
arguing for their necessity if new realities are to be disclosed, as this requires, cor-
respondingly, new forms of subjectivity in the research process. As I discuss next,
such approaches also place the research and researcher explicitly back within the
life process.
Making Room for Life and Natural Wisdom through Lived Experience. This is a
topic I covered at length throughout this book, so I will here just quickly gather
some important points. I argue that an experiential approach is crucial because it
is through our experience that we contact and interpret the claims of nature. The
marginalization and mystification of subjective experience in modern times, and
the rise of an “academic-corporate-government elite”41 who tell us how to think and
live, is then central to our alienation from nature. Learning to work skillfully with
bodily felt experience is in this light both a therapeutic and a political act. If we
find in our bodily experience not so much the workings of a machine but rather a
source of wisdom and guidance that comes from the force or spirit of life, a crea-
tive force that calls for healing, growth, liberation, and resistance to oppression,
then can our scholarship make room for this natural moment we find within our
experience? Appreciating that the body senses and carries knowledge about the
situations in which we find ourselves, can we allow new ideas or theories to be not
just the achievement of a disembodied mind but a development of the whole
organism/environment field, a formulation of what the world is asking for? To
be sure, I think research can be seen as an act of living, as a process that dips into
the experiential knowledge that is right there in our bodies—by virtue of the fact
that these bodies are themselves both intelligent and inside the world or of it.42 If
we pursue our intellectual, moral, and aesthetic hungers, our bodily felt interests,
and make a place in our experience for the otherness, the responsiveness, of life
psychologists that they make themselves vulnerable. This includes being willing to
disrupt disciplinary boundaries, “allowing debates and research in disciplines such
as anthropology, education, performance studies, cultural studies, art, religion,
sociology, and philosophy to enrich theorizing about the practice and research
of psychology.” Finally, Watkins and Shulman highlight the devastating effects
of colonialism and globalization on human-place relations, insisting that libera-
tion psychologies “also be eco-liberation psychologies that attend to the mutual
interdependence of the natural and built environments, animals, and humans.”
In many respects, I think Watkins and Shulman have presented the psy-
chology of the future, given the radical nature of our times. Lest it be said, though,
that such cultural and community-oriented approaches deny the sovereignty or
dignity of the individual, I think what they propose actually achieves the opposite.
As I noted in chapter 4, anthropologists such as Tim Ingold observe that a sense of
individuality and autonomy may be strengthened by rich communal ties, whereas
it is the lonely, isolated individual of our own culture, suffering from a gnawing
emptiness and crippling doubts about their worth, who is prone to the defense of
mass conformity.48
Overcoming the Historical Displacement of the Aesthetic and Moral by the Cognitive
and Instrumental: Decolonizing the Lifeworld. Just as ecopsychologists are often
attracted to marginal modes of psychology, so do they tend to value modes or
regions of experience that have been pushed to the edges of psychological dis-
course: the sensuous, intuitive, emotional, spiritual, oneiric, mythological, ritu-
alistic, poetic, and so on.52 While the displacement of these modes is generally
attributed to the rise of the modern age, I want to introduce the idea here that
the culprit is not just some stationary worldview (scientific, rational, industrial,
etc.) that defines the age but rather a specific dynamic that steadily increases this
displacement, namely, the historical development of capitalism. This dynamic has
been examined in exhaustive detail by the critical theorist Jürgen Habermas, whose
account of the colonization of the modern lifeworld by the capitalist political
economic system provides a highly persuasive interpretation both for validating
ecopsychology’s desire to recall marginalized regions of existence and for arguing
in favor of a radical politicization of psychology.53 For Habermas, the lifeworld is
the everyday world of cultural meanings and traditions, ethical attitudes, artistic
expressions, stories, social relations with nature, and so on. The system is that net-
work of money and power which parasitically draws the life out of the lifeworld,
relentlessly invading non-marketized regions of our lives and rechanneling them to
efficiently meet the needs of this system (an obvious example being the commodi-
fication of the Christmas celebration). Through this historical process, the three
main value spheres or orders of life—aesthetic-expressive, moral-practical, and
cognitive-instrumental—get split apart, with a cognitive-instrumental approach
to the subjective, social, and natural worlds coming more and more to dominate,
and with the aesthetic-expressive and moral-practical approaches to these worlds
increasingly diminished and degraded (so that now “greed is good”). As David
Kidner notes, for example, when art is no longer integrated into the lifeworld and
“becomes split off from nature in this way, it loses the ethical force which derives
from its capacity to express the order of nature, leaving a moral vacuum that
allows it to be quickly assimilated to economic relations,” thus trivializing the role
of art.54 According to Habermas, finally, a world ruled by cognitive-instrumental
rationality in service of the system gives rise to a number of social pathologies,
including a loss of shared meaning, a deepening sense of alienation and demorali-
zation, a spread of social disintegration and instability, and a growth in personal
suffering or psychopathology.55
Habermas’s critical theory invites a particular framing of radical politics,
wherein the realms of subjective and artistic experience, morality and practical
action, and science and reason are integrated, which simultaneously requires a
de-colonizing of the lifeworld or reclaiming of everyday life from the intrusions
of the system. The implications of such a politics for ecopsychology are, I think,
enormous. For if ecopsychology is to participate in the decolonization of the life-
world in its efforts to integrate psyche and nature then it is fair to point out how
psychology (as all science)56 has itself been colonized by the system and adopted
the dissociated cognitive-instrumental mentality used historically in the domina-
tion of (human) nature. The kind of psychology that would undo the dissociation
of aesthetics, morality, and science would have to operate much differently that
the psychology of our day, conceiving of itself more as a cultural and political
project and—as in the case of Watkins and Shulman’s liberation psychology—
adopting methods that include the full range of being human as opposed to that
portion allowed within value-neutral psychology. When one recognizes how
the trivializing of art, degrading of morality, and dehumanizing of science have
been good for none of these three,57 the idea of integrating them becomes highly
attractive. Indeed, as very challenging as it may seem, this way leads to a possible
rapprochement between empiricism and its critics,58 for an empiricism that
included aesthetic and moral-political elements would be a form of science that
achieves distance from nature not just to manipulate it but rather simultaneously
to find more mature and beautiful ways of being in intimate relation with the
more-than-human.59 A hermeneutically sensitized empiricism will to my mind
always be needed for answering questions about relatively impersonal dimensions
of reality. But in a more integrated lifeworld it would no longer be for empiricism
alone to validate all truth claims. We could even argue that empirical findings
would themselves need to be validated subjectively, aesthetically, practically, or
ethically. On this note, it must be said that although conservation psychology does
lead with an ethic of care, such an ethic is not intrinsic to psychology when it is
still conceived as a scientific discipline. By contrast, for all approaches that adopt
an ecological, dialogical, or interrelational view of reality (e.g., hermeneutics,
feminist psychology, Indigenous methods, Buddhism, and, as I discuss below,
dialectics), ethics are not added-on but inhere in the very fabric of how the world
of all, the subject matter of dialectics is change and interaction. Reality is viewed as
a process, with transformations occurring as various contradictions and comple-
mentarities in the world play themselves out (for better or worse) or as different
systems or moments of reality interact over the course of natural and human his-
tory (which are brought together in dialectical thought).65 The dialectical view
also corresponds to a radical political attitude that, seeing change as being in the
nature of things, actively pursues those social changes that would resolve specific
contradictions or injustices present in the world—in contrast to the conserva-
tive political attitude embodied in “the various forms of non-dialectical thinking
[which] can always be identified as so many strategies for containing, repressing,
or naturalizing contradictions as such.”66 (Thus, for example, orthodox eco-
nomics contains a status quo politics because it theorizes the economy in terms
of a static equilibrium, thereby hiding the grave contradictions that generate the
crisis-prone dynamics within the capitalist system, and making it unable ever to
explain or anticipate such events as the Great Depression or Great Recession).67
Among other possibilities, these ideas—about the thoroughly processual and
political nature of our reality—give us a way to think about ecopsychology itself,
viewing the transformation in psychology that it stands for as a politically radical
creative emergence at a particular moment in history as psychology dialectically
returns to nature.
The second feature of dialectics is that it is based on a philosophy of internal
relations.68 Here is where the ecological character of dialectics is perhaps most
evident, as this philosophy perceives reality entirely in terms of interrelationships
and looks for interconnections where they are usually not seen. This is moreover
an aspect of dialectics that makes it difficult to grasp, for when things are viewed
as relations rather than as self-contained entities they can never be identical with
themselves, all phenomena being present or implied in one another in some
fashion (recall Merleau-Ponty’s ontology of the flesh and Gendlin’s philosophy
of experiencing, both of which have this dialectical quality).69 At the same time,
because opposites internally relate they are seen as having a certain identity (e.g.,
causes are effects—organisms, for example, are both causes and effects of their
environments).70 The radical implications of this philosophy are many, but one
important topic we may return to is that of the subject/object dualism. As dis-
cussed above, subject and object form a differentiated unity. But what socialists
stress is not so much developing subjectivity alone as changing the objective social
conditions in which our subjectivity lives, transforming ourselves by transforming
the world, understanding the world by changing it and thereby ourselves. I will
have more to say about this angle in discussions ahead, but if ecopsychology is
indeed committed to overcoming dualism then I suggest it must include thinking
of this sort, wherein the development of the object side of the subject-object
interrelation or dialectic is also considered.
Within the scholarly world, fields do not effectively exist unless they have a journal.
It was thus a good day when the Ecopsychology journal came into being in 2009.
The editor Thomas Joseph Doherty, being mindful of the “decade-long . . . ‘cold
war’ between ecopsychology and mainstream psychology and related fields like
environmental studies,”81 envisioned the journal as a forum for bridging these var-
ious camps and so ending the standoff between them. To get the bridge building
going, he distinguished between what he called first-generation and second-
generation ecopsychology, making it the mission of the journal to lay the founda-
tions for the latter. According to Doherty, first-generation ecopsychology can be
characterized as: countercultural (offering an alternative to mainstream Western
culture); holistic (connecting the needs of person and planet); ecocentric (having
earth-based values and commitments to the tradition of deep ecology); experien-
tial and nature-based (stressing firsthand sensuous participation in nature); and
romantic in its worldview (“valuing psychological depth, passion, intuition, the
soul, and the stereotypically feminine [i.e., versus rational, scientific, competi-
tive, and stereotypic male attributes of the enlightenment and modernism]”).82
within the research situation. As she writes: “The history of science shows that
research directed by maximally liberatory social interests and values tends to be
better equipped to identify partial claims and distorting assumptions” present
within science.97 Foster, Clark, and York argue in this respect that, ironically,
social science is on the whole hamstrung in its ability to be critical of society
because “both its analysis and what is deemed acceptable/unacceptable tends to
be filtered through the dominant institutions and structures. . . . Getting ahead
in the academy . . . all too often involves self-censorship, a narrow focus on the
relatively inconsequential, and leaving the big stuff—in terms of social change—
off the table.” In the specific matter of the ecological crisis, “the more pressing
the environmental problem has become and the more urgent the call for eco-
logical revolution has been articulated, the more quiescent social scientists seem
to have become on the topic, searching for a kind of remediation of the problem,
in which real change will not be required.”98 In this light, my hope for the journal
is that it may indeed support “real change” by encouraging scholars to resist the
academic politics and class interests that immobilize social scientists,99 and also
by holding out an image of the overall project of ecopsychology, including its
relationship with the radical ecology movement, that could lend the journal a
unifying political drive. In recognizing that the conversation about what counts
as ecopsychology has not been settled, and in creating a space with the journal to
carry out this conversation, I believe that Doherty is doing ecopsychology a great
service. Much will depend on how that conversation goes.
While only a single effort, I believe this project could act as a seed for a larger
ecopsychological art politics, a form of cultural therapy inviting awareness of and
recommitment to the commons. I wish to compare it, in any event, to some other
forms of ecotherapy that take a less critical attitude. George Burns’s “nature-guided
therapy” is a pragmatic approach to therapy that uses sensory outdoor experiences
to increase pleasure and foster a general sense of wellness, helping clients to “reach
their desired therapeutic goals in the quickest and most effective manner.”113 In
other words, sensory stimuli from the environment are among the therapist’s tools
in an otherwise conventional therapeutic practice. While there is much to appre-
ciate about Burns’s approach, I do not think it leads us to an ecological society or
to critical ecological consciousness (or, given its use of dualistic scientific language,
to an ecological understanding of reality). In short, I find minimal ecopsychology
in it, as I use the term, because it goes only a small distance toward the roots.
As another example, the British mental health charity Mind published a report
calling “for a new green agenda for mental health, following the growing evidence
in support of an accessible, cost-effective and natural addition to existing treat-
ment options—ecotherapy.”114 The projects covered in the report are universally
inspiring, including the use of “care farms” where people experiencing psycholog-
ical distress work periodically for a farmer who is then paid for providing a health
service. What is missing from the report, however, is any query along the lines
presented by Kidner about the political economic background or origins of peo-
ple’s distress now being treated at the care farm (why, for instance, is there a rising
epidemic of depression in advanced capitalist nations, while it is virtually absent
among modern-day hunter-gatherers?).115 Indeed, ecotherapy is presented as a
way of saving the health care system money by reducing prescription drug costs.
While the ecotherapeutic approaches presented by Burns and Mind are clearly an
improvement on office-bound and pharmacologically driven treatments, I believe
that ecopsychological critical theory asks us to go farther.
Consider, as a second example of how a critical perspective sheds light on
ecotherapy, the psychologist Bruce Alexander’s dislocation theory of addiction.
A leading researcher on the psychology of addiction, Alexander found that the
riddle of addiction is solved only by viewing it historically and anthropologically.
In brief, he demonstrates that wherever free-market capitalism goes, addiction
follows in its wake. Alexander’s explanation for this relation—echoing Haber-
mas’s theory of the colonization of the lifeworld—is that capitalism and psycho-
social disintegration are synonymous. “‘Psychosocial integration’ is a profound
interdependence between individual and society that normally grows and
develops throughout each person’s lifespan. Psychosocial integration reconciles
people’s vital needs for social belonging with their equally vital needs for indi-
vidual autonomy and achievement.”116 It refers to an integrated lifeworld with
traditions that hold people in place. By contrast, psychosocial disintegration or
historical dislocation refers to the process of alienation built into the system of
capital: “[T]raditional sources of psychosocial integration in every type of society
came to be identified as ‘market distortions’ that had to be eliminated. [Thus,]
the ideal form of free-market society would inevitably create universal disloca-
tion.” Defining addiction broadly to include not only drugs and alcohol, but
also gambling, work, power seeking, religious or political zeal, Internet surfing,
video game playing, pornography viewing, “love,” food, shopping, and so on,
Alexander characterizes it by a devotion to narrow, distress-based lifestyles that
substitute for psychosocial integration. Thus: “Free-market society can no more
be addiction-free than it can be free of intense competition, income disparity,
environmental destruction, unequal access to life-saving medical care, or dis-
honest business practices.” Drawing on Alexander and other sources, Lorraine
Fish similarly defines addiction as a “cultural disorder brought about by mas-
sive societal upheaval and geographical dislocation, resulting in a culturally
dysfunctional relationship with self, community, and the natural world.”117
Given that addiction is best viewed as a social pathology, Alexander suggests
that addressing addiction means “reorganizing the practices of addiction profes-
sionals within a larger social project.” The question here is whether ecotherapy
practices for healing addiction, such as outdoor behavioral healthcare programs
for youth, are actually organizing themselves for such a necessary social project.
I think Chellis Glendinning’s account of heroin addiction and recovery in the
New Mexico village of Chimayó is instructive in thinking about this. Glendin-
ning describes a community-focused approach that uses indigenous land-based
traditions in successfully coming to grips with the severe state of dislocation,
caused by a brutal history of capitalism and colonialism, underlying Chimayó’s
horrific heroin problem. Highlighting the importance of addressing addiction
at the level of cultural ownership and community empowerment, Glendinning
notes that “healing is one and the same as the work of decolonization.”118
What I hope these few brief examples illustrate is the need to include
political education and processes in the practice of ecopsychology, given that the
social and cultural roots of ecological and psychological crisis run deep. I am
not proposing, however, that the practice of ecopsychology aim simply at moti-
vating people to engage in existing forms of political or environmental activism
(a strategy more characteristic of environmental and conservation psychology).
Ecopsychology is to my mind still a psychological politics, working on the level
of subjectivity, and so needs to develop novel forms of social intervention that are
themselves ecopsychological, incorporating the poetics, healing, earth celebration,
ritual, care for the human lifecycle, rites of passage, embodiment, ecospirituality,
and so on that it is known for. The challenge is to shape these interventions so
that they are deliberate efforts at decolonization, at psychosocial integration, at
building an ecological society.
From Integral Ecology, by Sean Esbjorn-Hargens, PhD, and Michael Zimmerman, PhD,
©2009 by Sean Esbjorn-Hargens and Michael Zimmerman. Reprinted by arrangement with
Shambhala Publications Inc., Boston, MA. www.shambhala.com.
increasing levels of development or evolution in each of the four quadrants. For humans
in the UL quadrant, for example, this covers a spectrum of consciousness from the most
infantile to the most spiritually attained, with the UR quadrant indicating the corre-
sponding rise in complexity of behavior and anatomy. In the lower quadrants, the arrows
refer to cultural and social evolution, human and otherwise. Nature appears in this dia-
gram in three senses. “NATURE” is depicted as the entire diagram, that is, all levels of
development in all quadrants of reality (All Quadrants, All Levels = AQAL); “Nature”
as the right side of the diagram, which is to say, the empirical, sensory world studied
by science; and “nature” as those relatively low levels of development located closest
to the center of the diagram, for instance, the sensory body as opposed to the rational
mind, or the biosphere as opposed to the noosphere (the sphere of mind, language,
technology, etc.). Despite that these four quadrants can be differentiated, the diagram
is meant to indicate that any phenomenon includes all four of them, with correspond-
ences or correlations across all the quadrants. Thus, there is no separating our con-
sciousness (UL) from our behavior (UR) and from the culture (LL) and society (LR) in
which we live.
There are many uses to which this diagram can be put, but I will highlight
two arenas in which I think ecopsychology and Integralism are fruitfully in accord
(even if disagreements can also be found in these places). First, it shows that the
scientific materialism of the modern age has ignored or eliminated the interior,
lefthand (L-H) side of the Kosmos, reducing reality to the exterior, righthand
(R-H) side (the cosmos). The first chapter in Integral Ecology is entitled “The
Return of Interiority,” which suggests how Integralism seeks to be a corrective to
the modern exteriority bias. This return involves legitimizing methods other than
R-H scientific ones,121 bringing subjectivity on its own terms into our analyses of
the world, including the level or depth of psychological development reflected in
various actions or worldviews. According to Wilber:
[T]he real problem is not exterior. The real problem is interior. The real problem is
how to get people to internally transform from egocentric to sociocentric to world-
centric consciousness, which is the only stance that can grasp the global dimen-
sions of the problem in the first place, and thus the only stance that can freely, even
eagerly, embrace global solutions. . . . [A]bout these interior transformations, and
all the intricate psychological changes necessary in order to effect them, the Eco
camps have virtually nothing to say. . . . [T]heir understanding of interior dynamics
and development is incredibly anemic; thus they are contributing little to the real
changes that have to occur in order to “save Gaia.”122
Wilber criticizes the “Eco camp” for adopting R-H web-of-life or systems theoretical
approaches to nature on the assumption that this alone will transform conscious-
ness, rather than the difficult work of interior development. I agree with this criti-
cism to some extent, which is why in this book I introduced phenomenology,
hermeneutics, and other L-H approaches. However, I also aimed to demonstrate
that what defines ecopsychology is precisely the view that the ecological crisis has a
subjective or interior dimension and that psychospiritual work is a necessary con-
dition for building an ecological society. In ecopsychological circles, practices for
interior development are pervasive. It is Joanna Macy’s genius to see that we cannot
face the devastating realities of our times without the strengthening provided by
spiritual commitment. The transpersonal ecopsychologist John Davis even incor-
porates Wilber’s work.123 I think, then, that we can all get on the same page and
agree that the theme of interiority is crucial in these and many other respects,
including: recognizing the unavoidability of subjectivity in research and so making
the argument for interior development or soul education among researchers,124 as
well as for remaining humble about our inevitable blind spots; challenging the aca-
demic world’s typical discomfort with spirituality and putting back on the scholarly
table the notion that our essential work as human beings is to grow in spirit; and
returning to the world the depth or meaning that people hunger for (Wilber is a
“pan-interiorist,” seeing some manner of interiority or depth in all reality, while
Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman suggest that “any ecological system is a com-
plex eco-social system whose members not only exhibit behaviors but also possess
interiors that comprise overlapping horizons of culture”).125
it was not always as free of romantic ideas as I would now like, and I am keen to
engage the topic further. I will consider the two aspects of Eco-Romanticism—
historical and psychological—in turn.
Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman define the historical form of Eco-
Romanticism by its “contemptuous attitude toward modernity, the depiction of
civilization as a fall from pristine and noble origins, and the failure to consider the
dark side of tribal and premodern sociocultural conditions.”130 Eco-romantics,
they say, complain about the disasters of modernity while ignoring its dignity and
praise the dignity of premodernity while ignoring its disasters. The antiromantic
view is instead that we must look to the future, transcending there our current
problems, rather than deluding ourselves that there is something better behind
us. In chapter 2 I questioned this orientation, arguing for neither full speed
back nor full speed forward but rather for recollecting essential aspects of our
humanity that have been lost over the course of history while also appreciating
the virtues of modernity as we move beyond it.131 I furthermore highlighted in
chapter 6 a number of spiritual delusions that include not only (past-oriented)
romanticism but also certain (future-oriented) ideas about progress. In Wilber’s
own words, the thwarting of our vertical potentials for spiritual realization results
in their being projected into the dimension of time in “utterly futile schemes”
such as scientific progress or political utopianism seeking future salvation.132
I would now add to this discussion that a danger of antiromanticism is seeing in
Eco-Romanticism only delusion, rather than discerning the truth in it as well. As
David Kidner argues regarding such “frauds” as Grey Owl (né Archie Belaney) and
Chief Seattle’s speech: “Simply to dismiss Euro-American fantasies about native
cultures as ‘fraudulent’ . . . is to miss the significance of this phenomenon. The
underlying problem is that certain types of experience cannot easily find authentic
expression within industrial society, and are fundamentally incompatible with
current economic structures.”133 Following Kidner, we could say that within
Eco-Romanticism can be found a longing for unavailable this-worldly relations
that native or indigenous cultures signify. The challenge is to give an account of
history that validates the truth in these yearnings while also keeping it free of spir-
itual delusion, making sense of our alienation while not fooling ourselves about
past harmony.134
Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman offer the slogan that “things are getting
worse, are getting better, and are perfect.”135 This is their way to acknowledge
the disaster of modernity while cautioning against forgetting its dignity (as well
as the spiritual or absolute perspective that “things are Always Already perfect”).
In a related way, Wilber does acknowledge that regression is necessary when there
has been a dissociation or repression, so that what has been split off or denied
can then be reintegrated at a higher level; his concern is only when the prescrip-
tion is for regression alone.136 He and the Integral Ecology authors would then
presumably agree that the modern epidemic of depression, to use this example,
spiritual states. Magical and mythical mindsets, says Wilber, are not the same as
transpersonal or even rational ones.
Although he tends to lump together groups in a way that is not always
fair,144 Wilber’s remarks are worth heeding, and do point to the importance of
interior development and vertical analysis (assessing the level of psychological
development that a given position reflects). The danger of such antiromanticism,
however, is that its focus on the vertical dimension can lead to neglect or misrep-
resentation of the horizontal, the dimension of this-worldly embrace or descent
to earth that concerns ecopsychologists. The human psyche emerged from this
earthly world and remains tied to it.145 The delusion that we can break this
tie—that we can forget our kinship, our intimate relations, with plants, animals,
and soil, that we can dissociate ourselves from bodily and ecological rhythms,
imposing a mechanical order of time instead, that we can do all these life-denying
things without consequence to the integrity of both our minds and the rest of
earthly creation—this is the serious problem ecopsychology addresses. Ecopsy-
chology affirms our deep human love for the land and its creatures, our erotic
attraction for wild and sensuous things, our innate desire to know the stars and
planets, the birds and mammals. (The pull ecotherapists feel to abandon office-
bound therapy, with its devotion to the posture of sitting,146 to go outside and
dance with the wind, comes from this place.) Although Integralists are aware of
the interrelationship between the vertical and horizontal, I cannot find in their
writings where they give it much demonstration, where the kind of earthly inter-
relations I just discussed are explored. For example, in Wilber’s book Integral
Psychology—which contains a large number of charts of vertical development as
mapped by a variety of theorists—he writes: “Much of development—at least half
of it—involves various types of non-hierarchical, heterarchical [i.e., horizontal]
processes of competence articulation and application. These nonhierarchical
processes, of course, are not indicated on the charts, which focus on migratory
development; but their profound importance should not on that account be for-
gotten.”147 To provide a reminder, perhaps Wilber should rename his diagram
AQALAR—All Quadrants, All Levels, All Relations.148
In their discussion on psychological development and ecology, Esbjörn-
Hargens and Zimmerman likewise tend primarily to vertical matters, which
again makes it difficult to sense the dimension of horizontal differentiation and
depth, the profoundness of our fleshy interexistence with the earth (the term flesh
designating for Merleau-Ponty “an encompassing lateral investment”),149 or the
urgency to sing the land. On the one hand, they choose to discuss theorists such
as Stephen Kellert and Peter Kahn, Jr., whose research can be used to disprove the
Eco-Romantics (by showing that children are egocentric and anthropocentric)
and to chart such things as the development of values about nature and animals
(Kellert) and moral reasoning about the environment (Kahn, Jr.).150 On the other
hand, they knock theorists such as Paul Shepard for being romantic (applauding
him nonetheless for his use of developmental psychology). I think, though, that
Shepard’s lasting contribution will not be his primitivism, but rather his strong
antidote to otherworldliness and his evocation of the lateral dimension of earthly
relations while still offering a model of psychological and spiritual development.
Indeed, many of the ideas that Shepard pursued—including attachment to place
and play at being animals—have also been taken up by researchers such as Louise
Chawla and Gene Myers. Chawla is given no mention in Integral Ecology and
Myers is named but his findings are not. I think the omission of researchers of
this sort is important to note for two reasons. First of all, to integrate the vertical
and the horizontal is not just to show how a new level of vertical development
lends us a higher and different view of the world but to show how the vertical and
horizontal internally relate.151 When Chawla discusses the incorporation of the
natural world by children as a secure emotional base152 and Myers details the
emergence of the child self through fleshy interaction with other animals, they
are doing this. In both of their cases, second of all, they have had to challenge
anthropocentric/antiromantic prejudices in psychology that are employed in
denying human-nature continuity and the necessity for childhood experiences
of nature.153 Just as we need to beware the risks of Eco-Romanticism, then, it is
equally important to beware the risks of antiromanticism.
Integral Psychology is based on the idea that there are multiple, semi-inde-
pendent lines of vertical development (moral, cognitive, spiritual, etc.). In making a
move toward ecopsychology, Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman offer the thought
“that many currently established lines of development could, in principle, be trans-
lated to or situated within an ecological context.”154 I would tweak this, however,
to say not “many” but all lines of development. For do we not need to ecologize the
entire spectrum of consciousness in all its levels and dimensions? Is not anything less
still to leave some aspects of the human psyche floating in Searles’s “homogeneous
matrix of nothingness,” disarticulated or disembedded from our earth-home? Bill
Plotkin’s Wheel of Life model, presented in his book Nature and the Human Soul,
includes eight stages of interior development, from infancy to sagehood, from ego-
centrism to “cosmoscentrism,” in which the matrix of the natural world, revealed
differently at each stage, is indeed never absent. It is thus an attempt to weave the
vertical and horizontal together through the entire spectrum of ecological con-
sciousness: it is an example of ecopsychology.155 As an example, next, of ecolo-
gizing one particular line of development, consider educator David Sobel’s work on
Piaget’s theory of cognitive development. Sobel recognized that the middle child-
hood period when the child has an insatiable hunger for being outdoors corresponds
exactly to Piaget’s stage of concrete operations. What Sobel realized, then (in a way
that resonates with Shepard’s emphasis on nature in human cognition), is that the
life of the child calls at this time for intense interactions with the concrete earth that
literally inform the child’s mind.156 While I think Sobel’s work is very important,
when thinking about Piaget it is also necessary to be mindful of his antiromantic
biases. As Graham Harvey notes in his review of cultures with animistic world-
views: “According to Piaget, children are alleged to be animistic until they develop
more advanced, rational and correct understandings of the world around them. . . .
[To the contrary,] far from being a childish (if understandable) error, animism is
more developed—deliberately, thoughtfully and experientially—in elders than in
infants.”157 For Harvey, the term animism refers to an ethic of learning “how to
behave appropriately toward persons, not all of whom are human,” wherein one
becomes “increasingly animist” over a lifetime, carefully developing the skill and
cultural knowhow to increase the world’s personhood: to make persons of others,
revealing them as such, thereby making more of a person of oneself. In her study
of imaginal dialogues, Mary Watkins similarly observed Piaget’s prejudice against
imagination and animism. Her goal was to demonstrate “the development of the
imaginal other from an extension of the ego, a passive recipient of the imaginer’s
intention, to an autonomous and animate agency in its own right.” In other words,
she suggested the idea of a line of development in which the “imaginal other is
gradually released from our egocentrism to an autonomy from which he or she
creates us as much as we create him or her.”158 I have found no mention of an
imaginal/animism line of development in Integral Psychology or Ecology (though
Wilber does include shamanism). Animism is rather defined in Piagetian terms,
and associated with the earliest, tribal stage of human evolution. The danger here
is that the antiromantic perspective can be used to add to the cultural weight sub-
merging lines of development important to ecopsychology. There is a pervasive
fear in Western culture of getting furry and feathered, of losing human bounda-
ries;159 one wonders about the role of this fear in some antiromantic rhetoric. In
any event, I would caution once more against allowing antiromantic prejudices to
shut the mind we need to keep open in developing ecopsychology.
an infant differentiates itself from its own body it then becomes able to be
aware of, relate to, and control that body). Recall Searles’s idea that the mark of
increasing maturity is the ability to relate to, and thus find within oneself, what is
most seemingly unlike oneself. Recalling, as well, the principle of ever-widening
spheres of meaning and participation (chapter 5), Wilber says that every step of
development is “a new going within to a deeper and wider beyond.”164 The rub,
however, is that all of this describes an optimal or ideal developmental process. If
as a culture we actually embraced and interiorized the earth in our development,
widening out our biospheric existence through ever-deepening earthly relations
within the context of an integrated lifeworld, then we would have no need for
ecopsychology. Wilber himself seems aware of this in his comments about the
disastrous modern Ego:
I would add, as well, that this cutting off process is, in Wilber’s terms, a four
quadrant affair, expressing not merely individual psychology but social and cul-
tural conditions shared in our historical period. My point is that under current
historical conditions the biosphere is in the noosphere in only the thinnest of
senses, the more-than-human world being disclosed in the shallowest of ways. I
discussed this topic in this book in terms of the deanimating of the world as
the psyche withdraws into the highly problematic interior of the modern self,
its own deanimated soul being a sign of absent, broken, frustrated, or unrealized
world-relations. (The need to reverse this process is why I repeatedly stressed our
worldly nature.) It is precisely to this condition of withdrawal that ecopsychology
is a response, being an effort to get the biosphere into the noosphere thickly, to
perceive the earth deeply.
Wilber holds that the more interiority an entity has, “the more networks
of communion it is involved in, and thus the greater its responsibilities in com-
munion,” the “greater the burden of inclusion.”166 Wilber’s comments notwith-
standing, neither he nor Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman appear to pursue this
theme nearly to the extent that Wilber’s own ideas about our burdens of inclusion
and communal responsibility demand. That Wilber’s spectrum of consciousness
model must be ecologized tells us that it is not on its own an ecopsychology.
Where is the embrace of the land? Where is the inclusion of plants and animals?
In Searles’s study on “the nonhuman environment”—in which he posited that dif-
ferentiating and entering into intimate relatedness with this environment is vital to
the human psyche—he found the strongest examples of cultures engaged in such
which leads to what I believe are certain misreadings, as in their criticism that
David Abram is making a “crime” out of alphabetic literacy in his account of
the historical withdrawal of psyche from the more-than-human surround. What
I think he is actually doing is highlighting the immense power of language (for
both dignity and disaster) and identifying the need to counterbalance the detach-
ment that literacy engenders with modes of local or place-based engagement that
reanimate the world and tie us back to the land—that keep earth in mind.173
To round this discussion out, finally, I would note that the political challenge of
dialectically linking global environmental actions with place-based and locally
strategized social and ecological struggles (thereby avoiding “globalocentrism”)174
is increasingly being identified. A radical ecopsychology in step with this trend
will not see the biosphere’s containment in the noosphere only as a simple fact of
human existence but also as a potential whose realization or relational enactment
currently requires that a political process be in place.
Perhaps what Integralists most overlook is the fact that the capitalist system itself
develops, that it has its own historical dynamic based on increasingly violating natural
limits in order to maintain its perpetual expansion. Wilber, however, defines the cur-
rent level of social evolution not as capitalism but as industrialism,181 which avoids
the reality of this capitalist dynamic. Wilber is not alone in defining the social system
this way, as industrial production is common to both capitalist and socialist nations.
A closer investigation, however, reveals that the former Soviet Union and other such
socialist experiments are more accurately described as forms of state capitalism, never
having escaped involvement in or the logic of the world capitalist system.182 Thus,
when Wilber suggests that the next step in social evolution will involve limiting
industry,183 he is missing the fact that industrial society is essentially capitalist society
and that it tolerates no limitation. To limit and go beyond industrialism it is thus
necessary to go beyond capitalism—to some form of ecological socialism (or what-
ever we may call it), not to the informational society that Wilber anticipates next.184
In a related vein, Wilber gives much discussion to the dissociation of
art, morals, and science as identified by Habermas (who, recall, used the terms
aesthetic-expressive, moral-practical, and cognitive-instrumental for these three value
spheres). The quadrants of Wilber’s AQAL diagram in fact match these categories,
which he calls the Big Three (art/self/consciousness = UL; morals/culture/values =
LL; and science/nature = UR and LR). Wilber argues that the ecological crisis will
not be resolved until a new society evolves that integrates the Big Three.185 What
he leaves out of his discussion, however, is Habermas’s theory of the colonization of
the lifeworld, which identifies the agent of their dissociation as the capitalist polit-
ical economic system—this system stabilizing itself through its crises by steadily
diminishing the aesthetic-expressive and moral-practical orders and by imposing
an instrumental-commodifying logic in their stead. For Wilber, the dissociation
of the Big Three is the result of an evolutionary differentiation that “went too far,”
traceable largely to the influence of the machine mentality of industrialization.186
But because the colonization of the lifeword was underway right at the transition
from feudalism Wilber’s explanation is not nearly sufficient, hiding as it does the
inherently disintegrative or dissociative nature of capitalism. If Wilber’s Integral
Psychology had included critical psychology (which faces the horizontal world of
material relations) then perhaps he would have seen that capitalism unavoidably
creates conditions that thwart interior development and that disintegrate or dis-
sociate consciousness—the very opposite of what he aims for. As the psychiatrist
Marlene Steinberg writes: “It is no exaggeration to say that just as hysteria was the
dominant psychiatric illness in Freud’s time, and depression reigned in the twen-
tieth century, dissociation is the illness of today.”187 For me, this suggests a specific
internal relationship between our social system (LR) and our consciousness (UL)
not identified by Integralists. It also suggests that if we are interested in the develop-
ment of consciousness and in the integration of art, morals, and science, then it is
to a postcapitalist ecological society that we must look.
The question is: What does the process of social change entail? What does it
look like? Wilber seems to have two (perhaps complementary) views. One is that
the “Left-Hand path, not merely the Right-Hand path, must take the lead.”188
The “coming transformation,” says Wilber,
is being built, as all past transformations have been, in the hearts and minds of
those individuals who themselves evolve to centauric planetary vision. For these
individuals create a “cognitive potential” in the forms of new worldviews (in this
case, centauric-planetary) that in turn feed back into the ongoing mainstream of
social institutions, until the previously “marginalized” worldview becomes anchored
in institutional forms which then catapult a collective consciousness to a new and
higher order. The revolution, as always, will come from within and be embedded
in the without.189
Notice that Wilber introduces the idea of a techno-economic base but equates this
with technology, so that it is not clear what the economy side of his term means.
This is a move he frequently makes, speaking in terms of the forces of production
rather than also the social relations of production, the combination of these two
making for the mode of production (capitalism, feudalism, etc.). This is again a
serious omission, as it leaves out of the picture the entire history of class conflict
and changes in social organization and power. (It furthermore gives an overly
simple view of social evolution, rather than a more complex one that includes
political dynamics.)191 The view of social change that emerges, then, is of either
allowing the new level of technology (e.g., digital-informational) to come in and
create the conditions for a new level of consciousness or else developing a new level
of consciousness at the individual level that transforms worldviews and makes its
way into society. Wilber also proposes an integral politics that integrates liberalism
with spirituality, combining exterior development with interior development.192
It is difficult to find critical social terms in his writings, though, and so to envi-
sion from them a more radical dialectic between social and psychological change.
Integral writings, I may also have erred in places. Despite these qualifications, I
hope to have demonstrated an attempt at what Integralists themselves promote:
finding the value and partial truth in another’s positions, while developing posi-
tions that have even greater inclusiveness and holistic capacity.
Challenges Ahead
is the journalist Michael Pollan. Offering a sort of case for revitalizing the life-
world, Pollan has convincingly highlighted the ecological and human health
disasters that have resulted from industrial food production and food/nutrition
science and has argued for a recollection of the aesthetic and cultural dimensions
of food instead.199 Despite Pollan’s often astute observations about capitalism,
however, he refrains from linking these to a critique of the capitalist system as a
whole.200 The task, then, is to align with the Pollans of this world who are willing
to apply their rhetorical skills in popular ecopsychological writings that offer a
language of both critique and possibility in touch with the mood of the historical
moment.201
As I have been discussing throughout this chapter, I think the main
challenge for ecopsychology is to integrate not only psyche and nature but also
society, in theory and in practice. To help visualize this task, I have plotted
several fields (though many others are possible) relevant to it on the triangular
figure below.
PSYCHE
En
vir
on
log y
me
ho eor
nta cops
y
syc Th
l/C ych
E
al P cial
on olo
itic So
ser
Cr hist
vat gy
dd
ion
Bu
Psy
ho c
log
y
The figure shows that none of these fields integrates all three terms, as
each is primarily involved in connecting two of them (e.g., both ecosocialism
and ecological anthropology link society and nature). With respect to building an
ecological society, each would benefit from inclusion of more of the third term at
the opposite corner of the triangle as it is found in the adjacent fields. Thus, ecoso-
cialism could use greater psychological depth, whether from a Buddhist theory of
society or from an ecopsychological understanding of nature. For ecopsychology,
meanwhile, the need is to integrate more of the social term, whether via ecosocialist
or Buddhist social theories, critical psychology, or ecological anthropology. The
power of this triple integration is that it steers us to places we might not otherwise
go. For example, ecosocialism identifies labor as the main site of the human-nature
relationship, the locus for a society’s metabolic exchange with the larger natural
world. This makes the development of concrete or nonalienated labor a potential
arena of ecopsychological practice. I think that by reflecting in like fashion on
how these three terms might go together we will see the practical steps we need to
take in building a new society, one that incorporates the important truths of all
the fields on the triangle.
In finding an image that shows the integration of psyche, nature, and
society, I like to use ecological anthropologist Philippe Descola’s notion of a
“society of nature,” which serves to overcome the dualism between society and
nature.202 Recall that when more-than-human beings are granted personhood,
agency, power, or interior depth of their own, then the natural world may be
regarded as a psychological and social field. Anthropologists such as Descola and
Ingold describe cultures in which this is a living reality and so in which people,
say, visit the forest to maintain relations with the beings there as one might with
a human friend. Psychosocial integration in this case includes integration with
the society of nature. As Ingold notes, however, such an observation “plays havoc
with the established Western dichotomies between animals and society, or nature
and humanity. The distinction between the human and the nonhuman no longer
marks the outer limits of the social world, as against that of nature, but rather
maps a domain within it whose boundary is both permeable and easily crossed.”203
Another anthropologist, Edvard Hviding, similarly writes: “Since the separation
of society from nature is so much a part of our own ontological constructs as
westerners and intellectuals, it may be difficult to grasp that the social and the sub-
jective may need to be extended [i.e., granted or recognized—AF] well into what
might initially be seen as the natural and the objective.”204 Adopting Descola’s
term, we may accordingly replace the triangle above with the following circle.
Society of Nature
Human
Society
This figure shows how human and more-than-human reality may be per-
ceived as a single field of subjective social relations. Notably, Descola remarks
Despite that Western society is not a society of nature in Descola’s sense, we may
nonetheless observe the same correspondence between our relationship with
nonhuman nature and our interhuman relationships. It is no coincidence, for
example, that the natural world is regarded as a stockpile of resources while the
employees of capitalist business are seen as a pool of “human resources.” One
way to think about psyche-nature-society, then, is in terms of a general style of
relating that cuts across the human/nature boundary and discloses both humans
and other-than-humans in a similar light. It follows, moreover, that if we are to
treat the larger natural world with more care then the quality of care must corre-
spondingly enter further into our human social and political relations. I think this
gives us an important clue about the nature of an ecological society.
I am not proposing that the anthropological studies of Descola and others
be used as an exact template for reforming modern Western culture. I am sug-
gesting, though, that the idea of a society of nature be realized in our own, more
familiar terms. We may still work with the notion that our human society is
embedded in a larger more-than-human social and psychological field, and that
our being-in-the-world is deepened and made more responsible as we enter into
open and caring relations with other forms of life. There are many possible ways
to understand this on ground close to home. For example, a study conducted in
Ann Arbor, Michigan, found that people with an attachment to specific urban
natural areas protested against proposed changes to them, and experienced grief
when changes did occur or were threatened. Such stories are all too common. In
remarking on this study, though, David Kidner offers that the “emotional rela-
tion to place, in a sense, was not merely an element of self, but reached beyond
self to become a stabilizing force within the ecosystem, suggesting a potentially
more integrated self-place system.”206 In other words, attachment theory can be
expanded to the scale of eco-social systems and human emotion can be seen as
an element in the ecological dynamics of a place. Consider, as well, Ariel Salleh’s
remark that “[e]cofeminists go beyond dualistic structures by recognizing that
ecology and society form a relational web where everything flows bio-energetically
in/out of everything else.”207 This too gives us a clue about the nature of an eco-
logical society.
I think the best guidance toward an ecological society—crucial for the inte-
gration of psyche, nature, and society—is found in ecosocialism. Not only do the
ecosocialists provide a clear-eyed analysis of the psychological, social, and eco-
logical destructiveness inherent to capitalism, they also offer helpful principles
for an alternative society in which mature, ecological selves could develop and
the integrity of the earth could be maintained. Moreover, in identifying how all
social movements are in one way or another struggling against capitalism, ecoso-
cialism presents itself as a way to invite unity and dialogue among diverse move-
ments, North and South. Salleh’s ecofeminism, for example, is socialist, though
she criticizes ecosocialists who maintain Marx’s bias of giving primacy to pro-
duction rather than reproduction.208 Unfortunately, ecosocialism is up against a
fierce anticommunism, especially in the United States, and a history of repressive
totalitarian states that have used Marx for ideological purposes, causing terrible
suffering. An initial challenge is thus to address the fear of socialism directly by
charting the history of the uses and misuses of Marxism and of its ongoing dia-
lectical development into the current ecological form, and also by showing the
attractiveness of many of its elements as we face the daunting task of reconfiguring
our social world to make it more psychosocially and ecologically integrative. The
current economic crisis, and the glaring failure of the orthodox establishment to
predict or understand it, has generated a resurgence of interest in Marx. This is
fitting, for “the main contours of world economy today can be practically read
off the theoretical lines found in Marx’s classic text,” Capital.209 As the American
dream fades, moreover, with its individualistic vision of fame and material wealth
having turned sour in the movement against the One Percenters, perhaps the
dread of all-things-Marx will also start to fade. For ecopsychology, I think the goal
needs to be to help this process along by finding the psychologically and ecologi-
cally valuable features of ecosocialism and to work these into our own terms, as
well as to lend ecosocialism itself a greater understanding of the vital role ecopsy-
chology could play—by fostering necessary subjective conditions—in attempting
this social transition. What follows is a brief sketch toward this goal, recognizing
that there is much more to say and think about.210
important, in fact, to give the recent trends toward concrete labor and com-
munity greater coherence and further direction, for the current conversa-
tion about localism tends to shy away from the direct critique of capital
and the idea of community building on its own lacks a radical political
vision. With respect to ecopsychology, these recent trends are also notably
in keeping with the goal of overcoming alienation from nature. The oppor-
tunity, then, is to integrate the discourses on alienation from ecopsychology
and ecosocialism in order to create a stronger and deeper discourse than
either presents on its own.
• “It is impossible,” says the ecosocialist Michael Löwy, “to conceive of the
construction of a new society without the majority of people attaining a
high level of socialist and ecological consciousness as a result of their strug-
gles, their self-education and their social experience.”218 An ecological
society will indeed demand more not less of our humanity, more realization
of our potential versus the hollowing out and stunting of human life under
conditions of alienated commodity production and consumption. Marx
imagined communism as a social form that produced “fully developed
human beings.”219 What socialism has historically lacked, however, is an
appreciation of what is required in order to produce the subjective or inte-
rior conditions necessary to support the transition to a postcapitalist society.
There is here again a happy convergence with the historical moment, for we
are collectively called to mature or develop spiritually in order to meet the
current crisis. Adjusting to new ecological and social realities will take all
our creativity, compassion, wisdom, and generosity. A worldcentric identity
is indeed needed to cooperate in the ways now demanded of us, seeing the
needs of others as important as our own, while an ecocentric identity is
needed to care for creation, seeing the needs of the land as the same as our
own. In other words, we might say (keeping in mind the discussions above
about vertical and horizontal development): ecopsychology is needed. Spir-
itual discipline also counters the disastrous capitalist pedagogy—embodied
in the advertising industry and culture of consumption—of flight from pain
or discomfort, this preventing us from skillfully inquiring into our suffering
and so developing the insight, courage, equanimity, and other spiritual
strengths so needed in our times.220 If for reasons of ecological rationality
we must recover the commons and release our attachment to hyperindi-
vidualism and private property, then who among us can do so with grace?
I always think in this context of the work of Joanna Macy and Ken Jones,
both engaged Buddhists with ecological commitments who stress the direct
interrelationship between spiritual growth and social change. As an activist,
Jones calls for the building of a “radical culture of awakening” that would
bring spiritual insight to the work of social reconstruction. Ecopsychology
and ecosocialism would do well to join him.
From the ecological angle, now, consider the following two points.
has close links with deep ecology and, as I discussed in chapter 1, is there-
fore prone to such culturalism (neglecting the internal relationship between
culture and society). Where a materialist philosophy is perhaps most helpful
to ecopsychology, however, is with respect to understanding the history of
the human-nature relationship. Whereas it is common to present this as
a history of ideas, an ecosocialist history links these ideas to actual mate-
rial conditions. To make this point, I wish to quote James O’Connor at
some length on the origin of dualistic ideas in the modern period: “It is
now possible to connect the revolution in the idea of nature with the revo-
lution in sociomaterial practices of capitalist everyday life. These dualistic
notions or separations or fragmentations were caused by, and helped to
cause, real material and social changes. . . . [Capitalism started with] the
breakup or enclosure of common lands and common property, the seizure
of the commons by the well-to-do, and New World slavery, hence the real
separation of nature or land and human beings. . . . The creation of a labor
market separated human beings from one another, increasingly atomizing
society. Then, in the capitalist factories, there occurred the separation of
mind labor from manual labor, and mind workers from manual workers,
and both from emotion or affect, which was now expected to be produced
by women in the domestic sphere.”228 I do not think this is the whole story
but I think it is an important part of it (and it connects with the ideas of
Carl Anthony, whom I discussed in chapter 1, on the history of alienation
from nature among people of color). I think such material analysis should
be included in any satisfactory history of the psyche-nature relationship.
• Although Marx was hardly an ecocentric thinker, his materialism did
attune him to ecological issues, most notably regarding the health of soil in
England: “In early societies, the produce of nature was often recycled back
to the land, fertilizing it. But the concentration of land ownership, which
involved the depopulation of rural areas, and the increasing division between
town and country, changed this process. Food and fiber were shipped from
the countryside to distant markets. In this, the nutrients of the soil were
transferred from the country to the city where they accumulated as waste
and contributed to the pollution of cities, rather than being returned to
the soil. This caused a rupture in the nutrient cycle.”229 Marx used the idea
of “social metabolism” for the “complex interchange of matter and energy
between human beings and nature,” with each mode of production having
its own characteristic form of metabolism that then defines a particular
society-nature relationship, as in the example just given about the rift in
the soil nutrient cycle. The site of this metabolism is labor, being defined
by Marx as the process “by which man, through his own actions, mediates,
regulates, and controls the metabolism between himself and nature.”230 In
wage labor under capitalism, however, this metabolic relationship becomes
alien to laborers as they become alienated from nature, from the cycles of
matter and energy they are involved in. Now, the reason I am drawing atten-
tion to the topic of labor is because Marx demonstrated how pivotal it is
to the relationship between humans and nature—the psychology of which
is the subject of ecopsychology. It follows, furthermore, that overcoming
the alienation between capitalist society and the larger natural world will
require a different mode of production. As I mentioned above, this makes
the development of nonalienated labor—in which workers are connected
with their own bodily nature and creative powers, their society, the prod-
ucts of their labor, and the rhythms and cycles of the larger natural world
in which they are actively working—an arena that ecopsychology would
do well to pursue. (I think, as well, that Robert Greenway’s frequent plea
for the inclusion of “real” ecology in ecopsychology may find a positive
response here, for it is in such nature-connected labor that scientific ecology
takes on practical meaning.)
As Joel Kovel and others observe, there can be no exact blueprint for the transi-
tion to a postcapitalist ecological society; our transformational praxis can only be
prefigurative.231 A final challenge for ecopsychology is to consider how its own
activity might be prefigural or ground-preparing in this respect. I discussed above
the need to design our practice with a radical understanding of our historical
ecopsychological situation in mind. I wish to finish this chapter with one more
simple thought. We live in dark times, and in dark times there are always pos-
sibilities for renewal as the darkness calls out our humanity. In Iraq, a group of
Sunni and Shiite poets founded Freedom Space as a forum for supposed enemies
to come together to sing poems to one another. At one event, some of the poets
were killed by al Qaeda militants who believe that poetry is heresy. Despite the
risks, the Sunnis and Shiites persisted and at the next Freedom Space event sol-
diers from the local militia volunteered to guard the poets for free because the
organizers had no money. As one of the poets, Yanar, said, “We cannot give them
anything other than the spiritual feeling of the poetry. But they say they have
received a symbolic salary.” As for the participants who shared the magic of poetry
together, Yanar said: “People are desperate for this kind of positive connection.
What we see in every face, regardless of denomination, is absolute love and aspira-
tion for freedom.”232 The territory of ecopsychology is large; there are many places
to go and many ways to walk there. But perhaps it is something like the spirit of
Freedom Space that is most important. We may have to think of ecopsychology as
a psychology for dark times; we may have to put some portion of our lives aside as
a gift to others in bringing our world back to life.
Preface
Chapter 1
39. David Abram, “Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth,” p. 105. Hwa Yol
Jung had also made this connection in his 1972 article, “The Ecological Crisis: A Philo-
sophical Perspective, East and West.”
40. Merleau-Ponty writes, for example: “As I contemplate the blue of the sky I
am not [dualistically] set over against it as an acosmic subject . . ., I abandon myself to it
and plunge into this mystery, it ‘thinks itself within me’ [i.e., as I lend my senses to it], I
am the sky itself as it is drawn together and unified, and as it begins to exist for itself; my
consciousness is saturated with this limitless blue” (Phenomenology, p. 214). He also calls
perception “a coition, so to speak, of our body with things” (p. 320).
41. Abram, The Spell, p. 262.
42. James Hillman, “Aesthetics and Politics,” p. 39.
43. See, respectively, Sarah Conn, “When the Earth Hurts, Who Responds?” and
Elan Shapiro, “Restoring Habitats, Communities, and Souls.” Another way of looking
at this situation is to recognize that once the psyche is turned inside out, reality becomes
psychological through and through (see note 37 above). If we are in the psyche, if all of our
engagement with reality involves the soul in some way, then it is possible to consider any
number of practices “psychological,” let alone “ecopsychological.”
44. The distinction I am making here—between ecopsychology in support of
activism and ecopsychology as activism—can be a fine one. In her article “Personal Trans-
formation and Social Change: Conversations with Ecopsychologists in Action,” Mary
Gomes talks with two people (Renee Soule and Amy Fox) who are “extensively engaged in
both ecopsychology and environmental politics.” In my reading, the emphasis in the article
is on “bringing psychological sensitivity to the environmental movement” (p. 218), and
not on reframing this movement as a form of ecopsychological practice in itself. Soule, for
example, talks about how “ecopsychology can make an important contribution to activism”
(p. 226, my emphasis). By bringing attention to its psychospiritual dimension, ecopsy-
chologists may indeed play a role in changing the nature of activism. But the activism will
still be activism. That said, I do want to leave space in this account for those who undertake
ecological social action precisely as an effort at healing, or as an extension of their personal
practice. As the green-Buddhist activist Ken Jones writes: “the distinction between personal
Buddhist practice and social activism can be false; there is only one practice to be done”
(The Social Face of Buddhism, p. 19). Indeed, the wise among us have always taught that
everyday life is the primary theater of psychological and spiritual practice.
45. Joanna Macy, “Working Through Environmental Despair,” p. 244. See, also,
Anita Burrows, “Crying for the Manatees.”
46. Joanna Macy, Despair and Personal Power in the Nuclear Age, pp. 2, 3.
47. Melissa Melamed, “Reclaiming the Power to Act,” p. 9.
48. Roszak, “Where Psyche,” p. 2.
49. This quotation is a composite from Theodore Roszak, “The Greening of Psy-
chology” (Gestalt Journal), p. 16 and The Voice of the Earth, p. 38
50. Macy, Despair, p. xiii.
debate. Roszak, I should also note, does give some mention the ecofeminism-deep ecology
debate in his The Voice of the Earth. I have, of course, not been able to outline all the
features of this debate, seeking primarily to indicate only that there is a debate. Deep
ecology theorists have made numerous responses to their critics. See The Trumpeter 12:3
(1995); Warwick Fox, “The Deep Ecology-Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels”; and
Zimmerman, Contesting.
75. Social ecology’s main theorist is Murray Bookchin, although he is by no means
its authoritative voice. His main work is The Ecology of Freedom, while Remaking Society is a
more accessible introduction. While ecofeminism and social ecology share a focus on social
and historical issues, they have differing philosophies and agendas. On this see Val Plum-
wood, “Ecosocial Feminism as a General Theory of Oppression.” On Ecosocialism, finally,
see James O’Connor’s “Socialism and Ecology” and Natural Causes, as well as Kovel’s forth-
coming The Enemy of Nature.
76. I should note that there are a number of ecopsychologists besides Anthony (e.g.,
Allen Kanner, Mary Gomes, Jeanine Canty) who advocate for more of a multicultural
perspective within ecopsychology. As far as I am aware, however, they have yet to publish
any statements on the matter. I should also mention René Soule, who coauthored an article
with Anthony (“A Multicultural Approach to Ecopsychology”).
77. Anthony, “Ecopsychology,” p. 264. “Environmental injustice. . . refers to the
fact that poor communities are disproportionately harmed by industrial toxic pollution and
that corporations and government—intentionally or unintentionally—build their worst
toxic sites and store their most hazardous chemicals in and around these low-income neigh-
borhoods. It also refers to the well-documented fact that local governments have excluded
minority communities from environmental planning and that toxic sites have destroyed
many traditional minority communities” (Ruth Rosen, “Who Gets Polluted?).
78. “. . . the kind of knowledge and insight that upsets institutions and threatens
to overturn sovereign regimes of truth” (Joe Kincheloe and Peter McLaren, “Rethinking
Critical Theory and Qualitative Research,” p. 138).
79. Joel Kovel, “The American Mental Health Industry,” p. 89.
80. Russell Jacoby, Social Amnesia, p. 125.
81. Norman O. Brown, Life Against Death, p. xvii.
82. Joel Kovel, “Therapy in Late Capitalism,” in The Radical Spirit, p. 121.
83. Kovel, “Therapy,” in The Radical, p. 119.
84. Dreyer Kruger, The Changing Reality of Modern Man, p. xiv. In addition to
those cited here, my main sources for these views include David Ingleby (ed.), Critical
Psychiatry; David Levin (ed.), Pathologies of the Modern Self; Joel Kovel, The Age of Desire;
Issac Prilelltensky, The Morals and Politics of Psychology; Christopher Lasch, The Culture of
Narcissism; and articles by Philip Cushman and Edward Sampson.
85. Tom Athanasiou, Divided Planet, p. 52. See also Brian Tokar, Earth for Sale.
86. As Kovel says, “psyche refers not to an isolatable thing but to a historically
dynamic relation between a person and a social totality. . . . And if this is so, then the
consequences for psychology are drastic, for it finds itself without the confident location
of an object for its discourse” (“Mind and State in Ancient Greece,” in The Radical Spirit,
p. 224). Kovel also has an interest in ecological politics, which makes his combination of
social and psychological theory particularly helpful to ecopsychology. See, for example,
“The Marriage of Radical Ecologies,” p. 406.
87. See, for example, his “Things and Words.”
88. I am referring here to Fox’s Toward a Transpersonal Ecology. In his “The Deep
Ecology-Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels,” he defends deep ecology against criticisms
made by ecofeminists and social ecologists, but his discussion there is not psychologically
focused.
89. See, for example, the contributions in the journal ReVision (20.4, 1998), which
are dedicated to the theme of “Ecopsychology and Social Transformation.” In her “A Psy-
chological Impact Report for the Environmental Movement,” for instance, Melissa Nelson
writes of how our “polluted thinking” creates a form of consciousness “that manifests in
destructive beliefs and behaviours such as anthropocentrism, racism, sexism, nationalism,
classism, greed, and aggressiveness” (p. 38).
90. Allen Kanner and Mary Gomes, “The All-Consuming Self,” p. 83.
91. In his Regarding Nature, Andrew McLaughlin makes this same point in relation
to the ecology movement in general.
92. Roszak, “Where Psyche,” p. 15. Roszak is suggesting that if we could say with
the “full weight of professional psychological authority” that humans are emotionally
bonded to the earth, then this might “achieve the same legal and policy-making force that
now attaches to physical hazards like toxic waste.”
93. Sarah Conn, “When the Earth Hurts, Who Responds?,” p. 162.
94. See, for example, Irene Harvey, “Schizophrenia and Metaphysics: Analyzing the
DSM-III.”
95. Joel Kovel, “A Critique of DSM-III,” p. 135.
96. Conn does not view “the need to consume” as an individual issue, for example,
but as “as a serious signal of our culture’s disconnection from the Earth.” She would there-
fore revise the DSM to include this larger context. My point, by contrast, is to suggest
that ecopsychology keep its distance from establishment psychology altogether; that it stay
radical, rather than reformist.
97. A point I first made in my, “Toward a More Radical Ecopsychology.”
98. Roszak, The Voice, p. 55. Roszak refers, moreover, mostly to the “antipsychiatry”
movement of the sixties and seventies, in which psychiatrists such as R. D. Laing contended
that the so-called mentally ill were expressing a sensible response to social conditions that
were themselves mad. I have in mind, rather, the more sociologically and philosophically
informed works of the critics listed above, that is, Kovel et al.
99. Charles Taylor, quoted in Raymond Rogers, Nature and the Crisis of Modernity,
p. 166.
100. Stan Rowe, Home Place, p. 5.
101. Konrad Stettbacher, Making Sense of Suffering, p. 42.
102. The well-known ecologists Anne and Paul Ehrlich, for example, have written
a book called Healing the Planet, in which there are headings about pollution, the ozone
layer, and so on—but none about healing humans. The danger that industrial society poses
to human physical health have, of course, always been a focus of modern environmentalism.
The environmental justice movement, which emerged in the mid-1980s, does include
humans within its definition of “the environment,” but focuses mostly on social rather than
psychological issues (see Giovanna Di Chiro, “Nature as Community: The Convergence of
Environment and Social Justice”).
103. Joel Kovel, “Rejoinder to Kenneth J. Gergen,” p. 407. Kovel asks, as I do: “if we
are completely malleable [i.e., without a nature], then what can be postulated as the source
of the drive toward freedom and the resistance to oppression?” (“On the Notion of Human
Nature,” p. 371).
104. John Rodman, “The Liberation of Nature?,” pp. 89–90.
105. Gordon Wheeler, Gestalt Reconsidered, p. 34.
106. John Dewey, Experience and Nature, p. x.
107. John Welwood, “Meditation and the Unconscious: A New Perspective,” p. 8.
108. See Eugene Gendlin, “A Philosophical Critique of the Concept of Narcissism.”
Gendlin uses the Women’s Movement as an example of how everyday experience can imply
social change, that is, how women’s experience of social reality contests that reality because
it oppresses them as women (pp. 296–297). Just so, in an ecodestructive society our eve-
ryday experience implies social change toward a more ecological one.
Chapter Two
respectively. Ecopsychology, as should be evident by the end of this chapter, stands opposed
to these two as well.
12. In his chapter on “Common Sense as a Cultural System,” anthropologist Clif-
ford Geertz writes: “As a frame for thought, and a species of it, common sense is as total-
izing as any other: no religion is more dogmatic, no science more ambitious, no philosophy
more general.” As a cultural system, however, rather than some immediately given native
wisdom: “It can be questioned, disputed, affirmed, developed, formalized, contemplated,
even taught, and it can vary dramatically from one people to the next” (Local Knowledge,
pp. 76, 84).
13. Norman Denzin and Yvonna Lincoln, “Introduction: Entering the Field of
Qualitative Research,” p. 4.
14. A phrase I prefer over “abnormal,” even if the latter makes for smoother English.
15. Tom Athanasiou, Divided Planet, pp. 44, 197.
16. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 24.
17. Martin Packer and Richard Addison, “Introduction,” to Entering the Circle,
p. 13. I am using the term “objectivism” here in a broad sense, as the position which insists
that there must be some ahistorical, definitive framework that can serve as a foundation for
all knowledge claims (see Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism).
18. See David Canter and Kenneth Craig, “Environmental Psychology”; Daniel
Stokols and Irwin Altman, eds., Handbook of Environmental Psychology; and Russell Veitch
and Daniel Arkkelin, Environmental Psychology.
19. Although David Seamon has made a call for a more phenomenological orien-
tation to environmental psychology (“The Phenomenological Contribution to Environ-
mental Psychology”), he did so precisely because the latter is so objectivistic in outlook.
20. Rachel and Stephen Kaplan, The Experience of Nature, pp. 1, 196.
21. David Kidner, “Why Psychology Is Mute About the Environmental Crisis,”
pp. 368, 370.
22. Kaplans, The Experience, pp. ix, 198.
23. I do not mean to demonize mainstream environmentalism. The radical critique
does not make the concerns and efforts of the mainstream irrelevant, but rather points to
the ways in which this mainstream, by itself, still supports the status quo.
24. Russell Veitch and Daniel Arkkelin, Environmental Psychology, p. 425.
25. Paul Stern, “Psychological Dimensions of Global Environmental Change,”
p. 295.
26. Ecopsychologists, of course, are not the only ones involved in such criticism,
for the positivist conception of an “objective” nature (one unaffected by historical or social
prejudice, human meaning or value, ideological distortion, and so on) is increasingly in
disrepute. As historian Elizabeth Bird states: “Every aspect of scientific theory and practice
expresses socio-political interests, cultural themes and metaphors, personal interactions,
and professional negotiations for the power to name the world” (“The Social Construc-
tion of Nature,” p. 256). For more specific treatments of this topic, see Donna Haraways
Primate Visions, in which, taking primatology as her vehicle, she examines how “themes of
race, sexuality, gender, nation, family, and class have been written into the body of nature
in western life sciences since the eighteenth century”; or Donald Worster’s The Economy of
Nature, in which he traces the history of social metaphors embedded in the shifting theories
of scientific ecology. In addition, a significant number of natural scientists (e.g., feminist
scientists) have themselves put traditional natural science into question. See, for example,
Evelyn Fox Keller, Reflections on Gender and Science.
27. Arthur Kleinman, Rethinking Psychiatry, p. 1.
28. As discussed at length in Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology. A valuable,
Heideggerian treatment of this topic is also given by Medard Boss in his Existential Founda-
tions of Medicine and Psychology.
29. In a recent article (“The Myth of the Organicity of Mental Disorders”), Victor
D. Sanua argues that after a hundred years of research into the brains, biochemistry, and
genes of schizophrenics, no case can be made for an organic basis to schizophrenic suf-
fering. Psychiatry leaves in its wake one discarded theory after another, each announced
in its day with the claim that the “cause” of schizophrenia had finally been found. He
asks: “Why do biopsychiatrists continue to attribute mental disorders to organic factors,
while ignoring completely social factors which offer a more parsimonious explanation for
the development of mental disorders?” (p. 61). As Judith Herman writes, “many or even
most psychiatric patients are survivors of childhood abuse” (Trauma and Recovery, p. 122).
Arthur Kleinman similarly comments that the genetic theory of schizophrenia “is now
in complete disarray. Inheritance has not been proven. . . . There is still, after more than
30 years of intense biological investigation, no clear-cut understanding of the biology of
schizophrenia. . . . This does not deter psychiatrists and those who write the advertisements
for drug companies from asserting without any hesitation that schizophrenia is a biologi-
cally based disorder. This belief is the central tenet of professional orthodoxy” (Rethinking
Psychiatry, p. 188, n. 1 for chapt. 3). While schizophrenia will always be a possibility within
the vulnerable terms of the human condition, less “developed” countries reportedly have
relatively low rates of it, with some small preliterate societies being almost entirely free of
it. On the other hand, rates are globally highest in North America and some European
societies (Kleinman, Rethinking, pp. 34–35). It has therefore been suggested that not only
biology, but political economy plays an important role among the conditions that con-
tribute to schizophrenia. The condition of the Western economy and “the development of
capitalist modes of wage-labor in non-Western societies appear to lead to greater numbers
of individuals manifesting schizophrenia and fewer of them improving” (Richard Warner
quoted in Kleinman, Rethinking, p. 36).
30. The outspoken psychiatrist Peter Breggin calls schizophrenia not a disease but
a psychospiritual crisis. Repeating a point made familiar by the antipsychiatry tradition,
he argues that schizophrenic speech appears to have no meaning only when it is taken
literally rather than metaphorically or poetically. He refers to one schizophrenic patient,
Brugo, who was shown on the television program 60Minutes speaking about such things
as being Adam and Eve’s kin, being a Homo-erectus man, and about not yet being extinct.
While the intention of the program was to demonstrate the nonsensibility of schizophrenic
communication, Breggin heard Brugo symbolically discoursing about his “desperate need
for personal value and dignity, his identification with religion and humanity, and perhaps
his awareness of primitive [sic] impulses stirring inside himself, as well as his fear of personal
extinction” (Breggin, Toxic, p. 23).
There is a large body of literature arguing for the meaningfulness of schizophrenic expe-
rience, and protesting the medical model. James Glass, for example, writes that schizo-
phrenics’ delusional systems—obsessed as they are by themes of power, domination,
enslavement, violence, and transformation—mirror the mentality of political programs
and leaders that themselves paranoically divide the world into powerful and weak, seek
to dominate others, and so on. “By being in the world,” says Glass, “the schizophrenic
conveys messages about social power; yet in its haste to banish the mad, society blunts their
implicit criticisms and its symbolic meaning” (“Schizophrenia and Rationality,” p. 431).
David Levin, furthermore, says that in the speech of schizophrenia “there is always a painful
truth about us, about family, society, world, which needs to be recognized.” In particular,
Levin suggests that the voice of schizophrenia is the most extreme manifestation of the pain
inherent in modern dualism, wherein the inner self is isolated from the external world, cut
off, lonely, empty, fearful of engulfment, and so on (“Clinical Stories: A Modern Self in
the Fury of Being”). See also Peter Breggin and Mark Stern, eds., Psychosocial Approaches to
Deeply Disturbed Persons.
31. Joel Kovel, “The American Mental Health Industry,” p. 86. Eugene Gendlin’s
remarks are also relevant here: “I think that all our efforts to define schizophrenia—to clas-
sify it as a disease entity—will fail. Schizophrenia is something that isn’t. Interaction isn’t.
Being alive toward other people isn’t. Certainly there must be all sorts of chemical imbal-
ances and organismic reactions as a result of this. If we can find chemical means to alleviate
these, the individual may be more able to become reconnected. I doubt, however, that there
can be a chemical or any other kind of cure without interaction. I think the not being, the
cutoffness of interaction constitutes what we call schizophrenia” (“Schizophrenia: Problems
and Methods of Psychotherapy,” pp. 183–184).
32. See Sanua, “The Myth,” p. 59.
33. The latest version of the American Psychiatric Association’s Diagnostic and Sta-
tistical Manual of Mental Disorders (DSM-IV) includes “psychosocial and environmental
problems” among its diagnostic axes. These problems nonetheless still have a minor pres-
ence in the manual, and their inclusion in no way makes the DSM a work of social com-
mentary. Nor does the mention of these problems do much to change the predominantly
medical ethos within the mental health setting.
34. Despite my concerns about biopsychiatry, I am not an outright opponent of
psychobiological research, some of which has shed very helpful light on the physiological
aspects of trauma (see, for example, Bessel van der Kolk, et al., Traumatic Stress). Nor do I
think that it is always a bad idea to use psychiatric medication, especially for persons who
have been traumatized and who are unable to “regulate” their overwhelming emotional
reactions in other than self-destructive ways, or persons who have no other good options
for reducing their suffering to the point where they can actually engage in a healing process
or manage their lives. What I do object to is the reduction of human suffering to a purely
medical condition and human nature to biomechanics. It goes without saying that there
would be less need for medication if the experience of trauma were not so common and
if we had more humane and understanding environments in which to see our emotional
and spiritual crises through. Kovel cites a case—Soteria House—where a “drug-free, non-
medical treatment environment worked better for acute psychosis and was far cheaper
to boot.” Yet, it “was perceived as a threat to the medical-pharmaceutical-insurance-
government power structure, and was eliminated” (“Schizophrenic Being and Techno-
cratic Society,” pp. 345–347). See Loren Mosher, “Soteria: a Therapeutic Community for
Psychotic Persons.”
35. I am taking some of my cues here from Joel Kovel, “On the Notion of Human
Nature: A Contribution Toward a Philosophical Anthropology” and “Things and Words.”
36. As discussed in his writings on Freud in The Conflict of Interpretations and in
Freud and Philosophy. The quote is from Kovel, “Things,” p. 23.
37. Georgia O’Keeffe, quoted in Mical Goldfarb, “Making the Unknown Known,”
p. 180.
38. Hans-Georg Gadamer, “The Problem of Historical Consciousness,” p. 86.
39. Richard Rorty, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, pp. 360, 373. John Dewey
quoted on p. 379. On this point, see also John Caputo, Radical Hermeneutics, chapter
eight.
40. Richard Palmer, Hermeneutics, p. 215.
41. J. H. van den Berg, The Changing Nature of Man, pp. 95, 96. Italics mine.
“Natural understanding” is a phrase used to denote everyday, pretheoretical understanding.
42. Stanley Diamond, In Search of the Primitive, p. 122.
43. George Sessions, “Paul Shepard: Ecological Elder,” p. 86.
44. Van den Berg, The Changing, p. 234.
45. Richard Nelson, “Searching for the Lost Arrow,” p. 203.
46. Hans-Georg Gadamer, quoted in Bernstein, Beyond, p. 148.
47. It is this point, once again, that differentiates ecopsychology from environ-
mental psychology.
48. By contrast Hans Peter Duerr suggests that normal scientists “mount the defence
against what is strange” (Dreamtime, p. 126).
49. Hans-Georg Gadamer, “Practical Philosophy as a Model of the Human
Sciences,” p. 83.
50. Hans-Georg Gadamer, “The Universality of the Hermeneutical Problem,” in
Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 5.
51. As related by Bernstein, Beyond, pp. 128–129.
52. Borgmann, Crossing, p. 51.
53. Rorty, Philosophy, p. 300. Rorty is here drawing on the views of Donald
Davidson.
54. Kovel, “On the Notion,” pp. 378–380. See also “Freud’s Ontology—Agency
and Desire.”
55. Gadamer ultimately avoids this charge, for he claims that language always refers
back to lived experience, of which language is the articulation. The criticism here, however,
is that his view of experience has little body. On this, see Jerald Wallulis, “Carrying For-
ward: Gadamer and Gendlin on History, Language, and the Body.”
56. Eugene Gendlin, “Human Nature and Concepts,” p. 5. I added the word
“human” to indicate the possibility of nonhuman language and culture.
57. Eugene Gendlin, “A Philosophical Critique of Narcissism,” p. 293.
58. David Abram, “Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth,” p. 112.
59. Hermeneutics and phenomenology have a close relationship. While herme-
neutics may not always be associated with phenomenology, Heidegger claimed in Being and
Time that phenomenology is necessarily hermeneutical, working as it does to interpret or
uncover phenomena. This “hermeneutic phenomenology” is distinguished from Edmund
Husserl’s “transcendental” phenomenology, the latter of which is conceived as an attempt
to describe the pure structures of transcendental consciousness. While Merleau-Ponty held
that his own work sprang most directly from the later Husserl, his writings are nonetheless
best located in the tradition of hermeneutic phenomenology. Even Husserl’s work can in
retrospect be read as a hermeneutical undertaking.
60. My discussion here is drawing on Hubert Dreyfus, Being-in-the-World,
pp. 16–23, and Martin Heidegger, Being and Time, p. 191. Dreyfus notes that there is
no reason to believe that there are any theories, principles, or rules behind the “pervasive
responses, discriminations, motor skills, and so forth” that make up our cultural practices.
“Indeed, if one tried to state the rules for distance-standing, one would require further
rules, such as standing closer if there is a noise in the background, or further away if the
person has the flu, and the application of these rules would require further rules, and so on,
always leading us back to further, everyday, taken-for-granted practices.”
61. Such biases are in fact necessary for any inquiry to proceed, for they provide the
initial organization or orientation for any kind of sense-making whatsoever. As Gadamer
wrote: “Prejudices are biases of our openness to the world. They are simply conditions
whereby we experience something—whereby what we encounter says something to us”
(“The Universality,” in Philosophical, p. 9). He was, accordingly, critical of the Enlighten-
ment “prejudice against prejudices.”
62. Palmer, Hermeneutics, p. 25.
63. Gadamer has been criticized for his notion of a “fusion of horizons” because it does
not adequately account for the problematic aspects of dialogue or communication. Critics such
as Jürgen Habermas rightly say that in describing fusion as a simple process in which preexisting
traditions are mutually enriched, Gadamer does not sufficiently consider how communication
is ideologically distorted and disrupted or how traditions can oppress people and limit their view
of reality. For us, dialogue does not take place in some ideal community of equal participants but
in a world riven with class interests and exploitative relations. While I believe there is merit in
these criticisms, I also believe that the notion of a “fusion of horizons” does describe the everyday
process by which meaning is transmitted and our biases are revealed. In other words, I think it
is fair to use the term for the phenomenon it truly does describe, even if a critical hermeneutics
must go beyond the model of a simple fusing of horizons (i.e., dialogue under ideal circum-
stances) to also engage in the critique of ideology.
64. David Young and Jean-Guy Goulet, eds., Being Changed.
65. Richard Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism, p. 141.
66. This point is made repeatedly in a recent issue of Man and World, 30 (1997),
which is dedicated entirely to the topic of hermeneutics and natural science. Human/
social scientists are increasingly adopting explicitly interpretive or qualitative approaches,
although academic psychologists in particular have been slow to make the move. On the
reluctance of the psychological mainstream to incorporate a hermeneutic perspective, see
Kenneth Gergen, “Emerging Challenges for Theory and Psychology;” Stanley Messer et
al., Hermeneutics and Psychological Theory; and Martin Packer and Richard Addison, eds.,
Entering the Circle: Hermeneutic Investigation in Psychology.
67. This is not to say, however, that there are not many scientists aware of herme-
neutical issues.
68. Gadamer, “The Problem,” p. 133.
69. Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, p. 96.
70. Baleen, quoted in Joel Kovel, History and Spirit, pp. 58–59.
71. Allen D. Kanner, “The Voice of the Earth: A Review,” p. 170.
72. Robert Greenway, “The Wilderness Effect and Ecopsychology,” p. 123. See also
“Psychoecology as a Search for Language.”
73. Christine Downing, “Poetically Dwells Man on this Earth,” pp. 316–317.
Emphases mine.
74. Peter Mathiessen, The Nine-Headed Dragon River, pp. ix–x. Charles Bergman,
furthermore, echoes a common sentiment when he says: “increasingly we are coming to
know nature through what is no longer available to us” (“The Curious Peach,” p. 282).
75. Richard Nelson, The Island Within, p. 280.
76. Rogers, Nature, p. 152. Indeed, Rogers argues that a sense of loss is “the cen-
tral battleground over which this divisiveness [between the radicals and the mainstream]
struggles.”
77. Erazim Kohák writes that “discourse seeks to communicate by evoking an expe-
rience shared” (The Embers and the Stars, 64). As I noted at the start of this chapter, how-
ever, the possibilities for communication become slim when one’s experience is not shared
by others (at least not on the surface). By focusing on what I presume is a common experi-
ence—loss—I am thus hoping indeed to evoke an “experience shared.”
78. In his book Radical Hermeneutics, John Caputo does a good job of laying out
what is at issue here. Caputo adopts Søren Kierkegaard’s distinction between two basic
orientations toward life: “recollection” and “repetition.” Recollection is backward looking;
it tries to regain something lost or forgotten, seeks to recover from a fall. Repetition,
meanwhile, is forward looking; it is based on the idea that we come to know ourselves—
repeatedly come back to ourselves—only by courageously pushing ahead through our dif-
ficulties, not by trying to recover some former innocence. The knock against recollection
is that it “begins at the end instead of at the beginning, with the loss instead of the task”
(p.14). As Caputo describes it: “The love of repetition is happy, an earnest and exhilarating
struggle, while the love of recollection is a nostalgic melancholy longing for a lost paradise,
a dreamy wistfulness” (p. 15). I think, however, that this contrast is unfairly put. Repetition
appears in such a positive light only because recollection is cast so negatively. This is the
kind of binary strategy that Caputo is himself so adamant that we deconstruct (recollection
is repetition’s negated “other”). I would instead adopt an orientation that incorporates both
motions, and that sees either motion on its own as problematic. A recollection that only
looks backward, that spends all its time dwelling on losses and fantasizing about an idyllic
past, is indeed an avoidance of present society, as well as a recipe for perpetual discontent.
A repetition that lacks a recollective moment, however, is no less of a problem. For it misses
utterly the genuine experience of loss; becomes insensitive to the deep “pain for home” (the
etymological meaning of “nostalgia”) that many people do in fact feel. At a time when our
society is so obviously estranged from its “earth-home” (oikos), when such great numbers
of people have been dislocated, when so much is disappearing, and when “soul loss” is such
a common complaint, I just see no merit in dismissing all talk of loss as weak-willed or
deluded chatter. I would ask the reader, then, not to confuse my use of the term recollection
with Caputo’s. For one thing, I am not trying to recall a golden era but rather our own
human nature and our grounding in the more-than-human earth. I focus on both loss and
task. I frame ecopsychology as a response to history, not a running away from it. Repeti-
tion, says Caputo, “is a living response which speaks against, protests, disavows the weight
of tradition which has become leaden and lifeless” (p. 91). So would I describe the critical
work of ecopsychology. It is in fact precisely through a process of recollection that I see
ecopsychology helping us to find the strength and creativity to move forward. (Despite my
disagreements with Caputo, there is much in his book that I would support, including his
proposal for “an ethics of otherness, an ethics aimed at giving what is other as big a break
as possible” (p. 260).)
As for the charge that to concentrate on our modern losses is to neglect or be
ungrateful for what has in fact been gained, I will simply say that this is not necessarily the
case. As should be apparent in this book, I am very much in support of the modern ideal
of authenticity, as well as the modern goal of universal freedom and solidarity. In short, I
seek to counter modernity only in its negative aspects; I want to get beyond modernity, not
to duplicate precisely some premodern state of affairs. If I focus on the experience of loss it
is only because I feel there is much important work to be done by doing so.
79. David Abram, The Spell of the Sensuous, p. 196.
80. On the relationship between theory and practice within an experiential frame-
work, see Eugene Gendlin, “The Role of Knowledge in Practice.”
81. The work of philosopher Eugene Gendlin has been crucial to me in validating
such an approach.
82. Erazim Kohák, The Embers and the Stars, p. 55. Emphasis removed.
83. Paul Campbell, “Poetic-Rhetorical, Philosophical, and Scientific Discourse,” p. 2.
84. Aristotle himself dedicated an entire book of his Rhetoric to the topic of indi-
vidual and group psychology.
85. Hillman, Revisioning, pp. xvi, 213. The mind, says Hillman, has a poetic basis;
it seeks meaning, not facts. Hence, to become less literal is to become more psychological—
a point lost on those scientific psychologists who seek literal, objective accounts of psycho-
logical life.
86. It is worth noting, in this vein, that the traditional goal of rhetoric is to advance
a persuasive case for how to deal with a collectively held problem that defies easy, single-
discipline solution. “Rhetoric exists. . . because a world of certainty is not the world of
human affairs. It exists because the world of human affairs is a world where there must
be an alternative to certain [apodeictic] knowledge on the one hand and pure chance
and whimsy on the other. The alternative is informed opinion.” Rhetoric guides decision
making, “where no method is inherent in the total subject-matter of decision” (Donald
Bryant, “Rhetoric: Its Function and Its Scope,” p. 39).
87. Borgmann, Technology, p. 240.
88. I am borrowing here from Charles Taylor, who, in the same spirit as Borgmann,
has written that: “As our public traditions of family, ecology, even polis are undermined or
swept away, we need new languages of personal resonance to make crucial human goods
alive for us again” (Sources of the Self, p. 513).
89. Owen Barfield, “The Meaning of the Word ‘Literal,’” p. 57. Emphasis mine.
90. Barfield, Poetic, p. 63. Emphasis removed.
91. Ralph Waldo Emerson, quoted in Barfield, Poetic, p. 179. Heidegger likewise
wrote: “Poetry proper is never merely a higher mode of everyday language. It is rather
the reverse: everyday language is a forgotten and therefore used-up poem, from which
there hardly resounds a call any longer” (quoted in Charles Taylor, “Heidegger, Language,
Ecology,” p. 269, n. 32). Or as Paul Ricoeur says: “Every metaphor is a poem in miniature”
(quoted in Véronique Fóti, “Alterity and the Dynamics of Metaphor,” p. 307).
92. There is therefore no sharp line between literal and figurative speech, but only
different degrees of metaphorical “twist” that may still be felt in a word or phrase. The point
of this paragraph—that the metaphoric-poetic mode is primary—has been well established
by many others. In addition to the works by Burke, Barfield, Romanyshyn, and Campbell
cited in this section, see Eugene Gendlin’s numerous writings on metaphor and experi-
ence; Merleau-Ponty’s writings on speech/language in Phenomenology of Perception (as well
as Jerry Gill’s study, Merleau-Ponty and Metaphor); Heidegger’s Poetry, Language, Thought;
and, for psychological perspectives, James Hillman’s Re-Visioning Psychology; Ronald Valle
and Rolf von Eckartsberg, ed.’s The Metaphors of Consciousness; and David Leary, ed.’s Met-
aphors in the History of Psychology.
93. Edmund Burke, quoted in Campbell, “Poetic-Rhetorical,” p. 3.
94. Paul Campbell, Rhetoric-Ritual, p. 21. The word rhetoric traces back to a pre-
historic Indo-European base, wer-, which means “speak, say,” and which also gives us word
and verb.
95. Mikhail Bakhtin, Speech Genres and Other Late Essays, p. 92, emphasis removed.
The modern scientific and philosophical dream, by contrast, was to discover the literal
foundations of reality without having to resort to using figurative, rhetorical language in
order to persuade one’s audience toward the truth. Thus, in 1667 Thomas Sprat wrote of
the Royal Society of London that it had “endeavored to separate the knowledge of Nature
from the colours of Rhetorick, the devices of Fancy, [and] the delightful deceit of Fables”
(David Leary, “Psyche’s Muse,” p. 8).
96. Campbell, “Poetic-Rhetorical,” p. 5.
97. Hans-Georg Gadamer, “On the Scope and Function of Hermeneutical Reflec-
tion,” in Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 24. See also “The Hermeneutics of Suspicion,”
in which Gadamer notes that there is a “deep inner convergence with rhetoric and
hermeneutics.”
98. Borgmann, Technology, p. 178.
99. “World” refers here to the everyday context or interrelational whole in which
we gather the meaning of things according to our practical, concernful involvement with
them. To the extent that natural scientists attempt to rub out any such involvement, their
methods “deworld” nature—disclose it in only its thinnest, decontextualized, meaning-
shrunken dimensions. On this, see Dreyfus, Being, chapter eleven.
100. Aristotle made a distinction between epi-deictic and apo-deictic discourses, both
of which seek to demonstrate something, the latter by means of scientific proof, the former
by means of displaying or showing forth some phenomenon. I believe that Borgmann
uses the simple term deictic in place of Aristotle’s epideictic. Relating these two forms of
discourse in his own way, Gadamer wrote that the “hermeneutical experience . . . is the
matrix out of which arises the questions that it then directs to science” (“On the Scope,” in
Philosophical, p. 40).
101. As Medard Boss argues in Existential Foundations of Medicine and Psychology, for
example, all medical interventions should in principle take their bearings from the existence
of the person, from the meaning of a medical condition within the world of the patient. Even
to fix a broken leg, for example, is more than just treating bone matter. For the meaning of
the break is that one can no longer play with one’s friends, go to work, walk to the store, go
on a canoe trip. The break is essentially an injury to one’s existence, which shrinks as a conse-
quence. Hence, the real significance of medical treatment is that it restores one’s freedom to
engage the world, returns one to one’s former life. Why else fix the bone? A broken bone may,
however, further symbolize to a person that she or he is “breakable,” a loser, a victim, or some
other disturbing existential meaning, in which case applying plaster to the bone will of itself
not be an adequately human response. All the more so is the sufficiency of purely medical
treatment a question in the case of psychic suffering, as I discussed above.
102. Kohák, The Embers, p. xii.
103. Joanna Macy, Despair and Personal Power in the Nuclear Age, p. 146.
104. Wendell Berry, The Unsettling of America, p. 107. I do not wish to give the
impression that statistics have no place in ecopsychological (or any other) inquiry, but do
offer Gadamer’s caution that “what is established by statistics seems to be a language of
facts, but which questions these facts answer and which facts would begin to speak if other
questions were asked are hermeneutical questions. Only a hermeneutical inquiry would
legitimate the meaning of these facts” (“The Universality,” in Philosophical, p. 11).
Chapter Three
1. With a nod to Neil Evernden, who used this phrase as the title for the third
chapter of his The Natural Alien.
2. Stanley Diamond, In Search of the Primitive, p. 119.
3. John Livingston, The Fallacy of Wildlife Conservation, p. 100. A conclusion
shared, incidentally, by David Abram in The Spell of the Sensuous, p. 268.
4. Evernden, The Natural, p. 33.
5. Livingston, The Fallacy, p. 115.
6. R. D.Laing, The Politics of Experience, p. 12.
7. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, p. 346.
8. David Levin, “Psychopathology in the Epoch of Nihilism,” p. 33.
9. As a popular movement in mid-twentieth-century Europe, existentialism
became associated (especially under the influence of Jean-Paul Sartre) with the idea that
existence precedes essence, that is, that our nature is purely what we choose it to be through
our free actions. I oppose that idea, so do not want my use of the term existentialism to
be limited to it. I am using the term more broadly, to indicate an emphasis both on the
primacy of experience and on a confrontation with the ultimate concerns in life (death,
freedom, meaning, suffering, the human place in nature, etc.). In this sense, Buddhism,
for example, is a kind of existentialism. My specific goal is to develop a kind of “ecological
existentialism,” wherein the ultimate concerns of life are worked out in the context of our
membership within the community of all life. As a Buddhist-ecologist, Gary Snyder seems
to me an example of someone practicing this kind of existentialism.
10. Eugene Gendlin, Experiencing and the Creation of Meaning, p. 15.
11. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 166.
12. Mikhail Bakhtin made a similar existentialist point: “Contemporary man feels
sure of himself, feels well off and clear-headed, [only] where he is essentially and funda-
mentally not present. . . . The course from a premise to a conclusion is traversed flawlessly
and irreproachably, for [he himself does] not exist on that course. . . . But he feels unsure
of himself, feels destitute and deficient in understanding, where he has to do with himself ’
(Toward a Philosophy of the Act, pp. 20–21). Middle sentence is out of original order.
13. Gendlin, Experiencing, pp. 15–16.
14. See David Levin, “Psychopathology in the Epoch of Nihilism,” p. 29.
15. Theodore Roszak, “Where Psyche Meets Gaia,” p. 15.
16. Theodore Roszak, The Voice of the Earth, pp. 94–95. Emphasis mine. Roszak
also comments: “If any part of an animist sensibility is to be reclaimed, the project will have
to integrate with modern science. Nothing else will qualify as an honest intellectual effort.”
My discussions in part one, especially concerning Hillman’s and Abram’s work, should suf-
fice to indicate my utter disagreement with Roszak on this point.
17. Max Horkheimer, The Eclipse of Reason, p. 3. “Reason” here refers to instru-
mental reason—not to be confused with critical, practical, spiritual, or other kinds of
reason. Even Issac Newton cautioned that “Reasoning without experience is very slippery”
(quoted in Carolyn Merchant, The Death of Nature, p. 284).
18. Paul Shepard, The Tender Carnivore and the Sacred Game, p. xii.
19. Hence, even Shepard’s statement is misleading, for scientific data may of itself
only assist, and not guide, a redirection of society. On the folly in presuming that it may,
see Neil Evernden, The Social Creation of Nature. On the dangers of defending nature by
speaking in ecological abstractions (e.g., complexity, diversity, integrity, etc.), rather than
by offering testimonials and appeals based on lived experience, see Albert Borgmann, Tech-
nology and the Character of Contemporary Life, pp. 186–187.
20. Laing, The Politics, p. 51.
21. Hans Peter Duerr, Dreamtime, p. 115.
22. The discussion under this heading and the next draws particularly heavily on
the work of Eugene Gendlin. Indeed, I use many of his phrases throughout. I wish, then,
to indicate here my colossal indebtedness to Gendlin.
23. Eugene Gendlin, “A Theory of Personality Change,” p. 129.
24. Martin Heidegger, quoted in David Levin, The Listening Self, p. 219.
25. Gendlin, Experiencing, p. 162.
26. In the early 1930s, Heidegger believed that Nazism was a necessary violence for
halting the decline into nihilism and for reversing the devastation of the Earth wrought
by modernity. The danger of using Heidegger’s thought is that it includes hierarchical and
authoritarian views that can still conceivably be used to justify fascist causes. My position
on the Heidegger question is essentially that of Thomas Sheehan’s: “If Heidegger himself
felt free, even for awhile, to put not just his person but also the major categories of his
philosophical thought at the service of Nazi foreign and domestic policy, then one would
do well to ask whether those categories are really as free of economic, social, and political
interests as most Heideggerians contend. The point is not to condemn a man for his past
but to learn something about oneself in the present, not to dismiss Heidegger’s philo-
sophical work out of hand but likewise not to join the Perpetual Adoration Societies that
currently thrive among the Heideggerian faithful in Europe and America. The task, for
those who care to take something from Heidegger, is to learn how to read him critically,
both his life and his works, not to swallow his philosophy whole but to sift it for what is still
of value and what is not.” (“Reading a Life: Heidegger and Hard Times,” p. 92). Although
I am still in the process of learning to read Heidegger critically, I believe that the elements
of his thought I have drawn on bear no necessary connection to fascism. The task of saving
what is profound and essentially human in Heidegger’s thought, while rejecting what is
dangerous and inhuman, is one that I plan to take up more fully in future works.
27. See Gendlin, Experiencing, p. 125, n. 17 and p. 134.
28. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, p. 403.
29. As recounted in Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, pp. 197–198. See also Jerry
Gill, Merleau-Ponty and Metaphor, pp. 29, 121.
30. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and the Invisible, p. 215.
31. Neil Bolton, “The Lived World: Imagination and the Development of Experi-
ence,” p. 9.
32. John (Fire) Lame Deer and Richard Erdoes, Lame Deer, p. 162.
33. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “The Concept of Nature I,” p. 70.
34. Friedrich Nietzsche, The Will to Power, p. 131.
35. Duerr, Dreamtime, p. 57.
36. See David Noble, The Religion of Technology.
37. The “corpse is the body abandoned and invented for the space of explanation”
(Robert Romanyshyn, “The Human Body as Historical Matter and Cultural Symptom,”
p. 165).
38. Romanyshyn, “The Human,” p. 173.
39. Sigmund Freud, New Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis, p. 106. Emphasis
mine.
40. Alan Watts, Psychotherapy East and West, p. 168.
41. Sigmund Freud, “The Future of an Illusion,” p. 194.
42. On violent practices designed to break children of unwanted natural tendencies
see Alice Miller, For Your Own Good.
43. Michel Foucault, Madness and Civilization, pp. 73–74.
44. “The core of our being. . . is formed by the obscure id, which has no direct rela-
tions with the external world” (Sigmund Freud, An Outline of Psychoanalysis, p. 108).
45. See Eugene Gendlin, “A Philosophical Critique of the Concept of Narcissism:
The Significance of the Awareness Movement.”
46. Eugene Gendlin, Focusing-Oriented Psychotherapy, p. 304. Emphasis mine.
47. This exercise is the briefest of introductions to focusing. Gendlin has presented
focusing in a variety of forms: popularly in Focusing; psychotherapeutically in “A Theory
of Personality Change” and Focusing-Oriented Psychotherapy; and philosophically in Experi-
encing and the Creation of Meaning.
48. Eugene Gendlin, Focusing, p. 76. Emphasis removed.
49. Gendlin, Focusing, p. 76. Emphasis mine.
50. Susan Griffin, A Chorus of Stones, p. 330.
51. See Gendlin, “A Philosophical Critique.”
52. Eugene Gendlin, “The Wider Role of Bodily Sense in Thought and Language,”
p. 194.
53. I am using this term in the strong sense (as discussed by Richard Bernstein in
Beyond Objectivism and Relativism), that is, in reference to the position that because all
truths are relative to a particular (social, cultural, theoretical, geographical, personal, . . .)
context, there are no grounds for judging one view better than another. I agree that truths
are relative, but argue in this paragraph that the life process gives us our ground.
54. See Carol Bigwood, Earth Muse, p. 46.
55. Martin Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s Ontology, p. 101.
56. “The dead end of postmodernism,” says Gendlin, “arises when one discounts
the role of experience because it is never pure, never without conceptual forms and distinc-
tions already implicit in it, and then discount those because they are never purely logical,
but always involve experience” (“How Philosophy Cannot Appeal to Experience, and How
It Can,” p. 6).
57. Eugene Gendlin, “Neurosis and Human Nature in the Experiential Method of
Thought and Therapy,” p. 140.
58. Eugene Gendlin, “Experiential Phenomenology,” p. 292.
59. This is perhaps the central point of Gendlin’s whole philosophy of language.
60. Livingston, The Fallacy, p. 59.
61. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, p. 184.
62. Eugene Gendlin, “Reply to Wallulis,” in David Levin, ed., Language Beyond
Postmodernism, p. 287. I have modified this sentence to clarify its meaning.
63. Hans Jonas, The Phenomenon of Life, p. 25.
64. This is an argument made by Martin Heidegger in Being and Time, where he
suggests, for example, that any effort to “prove” the existence of the “external world” “pre-
supposes a subject which is proximally worldless or unsure of its world, and which must,
at bottom, first assure itself of a world” (p. 250). See also Eugene Gendlin, “Befindlichkeit:
Heidegger and the Philosophy of Psychology.”
65. Frederick Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, p. 332.
66. The words mind and mean both mean intend, sharing as they do the common
Indo-European base, “men.” Given that meaning and intentionality are both bodily based,
then so is the mind. Simply put: “psychological events are body events” (Eugene Gendlin,
“A Small, Still Voice,” p. 59).
67. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, p. 271.
to happen, it must therefore be a painful contradiction of some earlier form, rather than a
satisfying lending of good form to a genuine bodily need. Gadamer’s philosophy of experi-
ence thus does contain a pessimistic element, even as he openly denies it.
90. As Joel Kovel notes: “Neurosis is living proof of the tension between the human
subject and the objective social order; it only comes into existence so far as these are incon-
gruent” (“Therapy in Late Capitalism,” in The Radical Spirit, p. 123).
91. Morris Berman, The Reenchantment of the World, p. 164.
92. In Civilization and Its Discontents Freud speculated that all of civilized society
might be neurotic. In 1955 Erich Fromm coined the phrase “the pathology of normalcy,”
arguing, indeed, that “the fact that millions of people share the same forms of mental
pathology does not make these people sane” (The Sane Society, p. 23). Abraham Maslow
later spoke of “the psychopathology of the average.”
93. To be clear, I use the term problem broadly: to include any tension between
body and world that calls for some action and resolution, not just those technically or
formally defined ones.
94. The theory of creative adjustment, as developed by Paul Goodman, is presented
in part two of Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy.
95. Konrad Stettbacher, Making Sense of Suffering, p. 33.
96. On understanding social oppression as nature domination, Kovel writes that
“the major forms of social domination, of class, of race and of gender, are each mediated
through the domination of nature-as-body. In class domination, the oppressed body of the
slave/serf/worker is repressed and converted into a machine for the aggrandizement of the
master; in racial domination, sensuousness is lost by the master, who splits off bad [shame-
bound] parts of the self and invests them in the body of the oppressed; while in patriarchy,
female parts of the self are degraded, repressed and conquered in the body of the woman”
(“The Marriage,” pp. 412–413).
97. Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, p. 260.
98. As discussed in the context of Gestalt therapy by Kepner, Body, p. 98.
99. Laing, The Politics, p. 64.
100. Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, pp. 264–265.
101. Stettbacher, Making Sense, p. 15.
102. Stettbacher, Making Sense, p. 26.
103. Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, p. 375.
104. On this see Gendlin, “A Theory,” p. 142.
105. Carl Rogers, “Ellen West—And Loneliness,” p. 165.
106. Miller, For Your Own, p. 85.
107. Carl Rogers, “A Therapist’s View of the Good Life,” p. 195.
108. This is not to say that introjection is not an aspect of contact making. In learning
a new field of study, for example, we must take in much material and only gradually come
to develop our own views in relation to it. What is contrary to the organism is to never
bodily evaluate that which has been swallowed. See Gordon Wheeler, Gestalt Reconsidered.
109. Perls et al. Gestalt Therapy, p. 190.
urban alienation, trickle-down economics, combat service in the trenches of the gender
wars, the threat of extinction, linear thinking, the mind/body split, technological progress,
and the mechanical worldview” (My Name Is Chellis and I’m in Recovery from Western
Civilization, p. ix).
146. Perls et al. Gestalt, p. 333.
147. Joel Kovel, “Things and Words,” p. 49. Hence, “the unconscious must be pri-
marily grasped as the indwelling, subjective record” of the “uneasy” relationship between
human society and nature. Next quotation, p. 48.
148. See Joel Kovel, “Mind and State in Ancient Greece,” in The Radical Spirit,
p. 220.
149. See Kovel, History. This is not to ignore the existence of a considerable body
of psychoanalytic social criticism. For an anthology dedicated to juxtaposing socialist with
psychoanalytic theories and practices, for example, see Barry Richards, ed., Capitalism and
Infancy.
150. Toronto Star, June 21, 1995, p. C2.
151. Kovel, “The Marriage,” p. 411. As Kovel notes elsewhere, “capitalism is not so
much a species of economy as it is a kind of society which deifies the economic in order to
produce capital” (“On the Ontology of Capital,” p. 2).
152. Wendell Berry, The Unsettling of America, p. 138. “. . ., to put these [material,
social, spiritual] sources under the control of corporations and specialized professionals,
and to sell them to us at the highest profit.”
153. How much this is the case is suggested in Roger Gottlieb’s discussion of
the nuclear family: “The male-dominated nuclear family is a highly mobile unit for an
economy which needs to shift its labor force to changing areas of investment. The nuclear
family also tends to create people who think of themselves primarily as individuals rather
than as members of communities or classes. This self-understanding makes political organ-
izing and mass radical movements extremely difficult. Having women do the household
and emotional labor necessary to ‘reproduce’ male laborers and raise new ones cheapens the
reproduction of workers—and thus the cost of labor for capitalists. Women’s inferior social
status also allows capitalists to pay them less and treat them worse than men. Addition-
ally, the atomized nuclear family is necessarily a high-consumption family, providing an
ever-growing market for consumer goods. Finally, the power that men enjoy over women
makes up in a psychic sense for the powerlessness they experience on the job. After a day
of demanding and at times degrading paid labor, a man may exercise power at home while
he is catered to by his wife. At the same time, the authoritarian, nonegalitarian relation-
ships within the home perfectly prepare children for a public world defined by hierarchy,
competition, and unequal power” (Marxism, pp. 137–138).
154. Joel Kovel, The Age of Desire, p. 113.
155. Some factories are now openly “managed by stress.” That is, the pace of produc-
tion is continually speeded up “to find out where the weaknesses and soft spots are, so that
new designs and procedures can be implemented to increase the pace and performance.”
The consequence is reportedly a historically high level of mental and physical pathology
among workers (including chronic fatigue) as they are progressively transformed into high
velocity machinery (chapter twelve of Jeremy Rifkin, The End of Work). As David Noble
also writes: “In the wake of five decades of information revolution, people are now working
longer hours, under worsening conditions, with greater anxiety and stress, less skills, less
security, less power, less benefits, and less pay. Information technology has clearly been
developed and used during these years to deskill, discipline, and displace human labour in
a global speed-up of unprecedented proportions” (Progress Without People, p. xi).
156. Raymond Rogers, The Oceans are Emptying, p. 9.
157. Raymond Rogers, Nature and the Crisis of Modernity, p. 1.
158. Rogers, Nature, p. 160. Because the ecological crisis predates capitalism the
latter cannot entirely be blamed for the former. To the extent that the system of capital
defines our society, however, it is the current antagonist. On this, see Joel Kovel’s forth-
coming The Enemy of Nature.
159. Rogers, Nature, p. 12. Winona LaDuke offers an indigenous person’s perspec-
tive on this topic in her “From Resistance to Regeneration.”
160. Vandana Shiva, “The Impoverishment of the Environment: Women and Chil-
dren Last,” in Maria Mies and Vandana Shiva, Ecofeminism, p. 75.
161. Horkheimer, The Eclipse, p. 94. Emphasis mine.
162. For discussions of the work of other critical theorists on this topic see Henry
Blanke, “Domination and Utopia: Marcuse’s Discourse on Nature, Psyche, and Culture”
and Robyn Eckersley, “The Failed Promise of Critical Theory.”
163. As William Leiss clarifies, the “notion of a common domination of the human
race over external nature is nonsensical” (The Domination of Nature, p. 122). Rather, the
artificial separation of human society and the natural world masks the way in which ruling
groups dominate other social groups, who are put to work in exploiting nonhuman nature.
The domination of nature, as a “species project,” has thus historically arisen as an ideology
for concealing social contradiction.
164. Kovel, History, p. 205.
165. Kovel, The Age, p. 125. Middle sentence is from p. 172. Kovel is currently pre-
paring a manuscript entitled The Enemy of Nature.
166. Tom Athanasiou, The Ecology of Rich and Poor, p. 171. See, also, James
O’Connor, “Socialism and Ecology.” These points are basic aspects of Marx’s theories of
exploitation and capitalist development.
167. See Christopher Lasch, The Culture of Narcissism and Joel Kovel, “Narcissism
and the Family,” in The Radical Spirit.
168. “For all his inner suffering, the narcissist has many traits that make for success
in bureaucratic institutions, which put a premium on the manipulation of interpersonal
relations, discourage the formation of deep personal attachments, and at the same time
provide the narcissist with the approval he needs in order to validate his self-esteem” (Lasch,
The Culture, p. 91).
169. John Rodman, “The Liberation of Nature?,” pp. 114–115. Emphasis mine.
170. Livingston, The Fallacy, p. 116.
Chapter Four
Rollo May are probably the most committed to such a division, saying that humans,
“cast on this barren crust of earth aeons ago,” have to willfully make their own meaning
in an intrinsically meaningless and indifferent world. However, one of my favorite
humanistic authors, Eugene Gendlin, has a strong interest in what ethology can teach
us about the continuity between human and nonhuman nature, and emphasizes our
kinship with plants. There is much in Gestalt therapy, furthermore, that opens toward
the natural world, and Fritz Perls speculated that awareness is a property of the entire
universe (making him a quasi-animist). My comments, then, are aimed at humanism as
its main authors have presented it over the years and also at the fact that, quite simply,
humanistic psychology could by no means as yet be called an ecopsychology. For over-
views of humanistic psychology, see Frederick Wertz, ed., The Humanistic Movement:
Recovering the Person in Psychology; and Joseph Royce and Leendert Mos, Humanistic
Psychology: Concepts and Criticisms. I should also say that although I am throughout
this book blending hermeneutic and humanistic psychological sources, there are notable
differences in their general outlooks, as Louis Sass has discussed in his “Humanism,
Hermeneutics, and the Concept of the Human Subject.” Granted Sass’s distinction,
humanistic psychology and hermeneutics are both “humanistic” in the sense of being
human-centred, which is the general point I am after. I might thus have more broadly
called this chapter “From Humanism to Naturalism.”
4. Amedeo Giorgi, “Whither Humanistic Psychology?,” pp. 312, 318.
5. Erich Fromm, quoted in David Kidner, “Why Psychology Is Mute About the
Ecological Crisis,” p. 366.
6. Noteworthy here is William Cahalan’s effort to ecologize his Gestalt therapy
practice (see “Ecological Groundedness in Gestalt Therapy”); as well as the efforts of those
with articles in a special issue of the The Gestalt Journal on ecopsychology (18.1, 1995). See
also The Humanistic Psychologist’s special issue on ecopsychology (26.1–3, 1998).
7. See, most notably, David Ehrenfeld, The Arrogance of Humanism.
8. Roy DeCarvalho, Founders of Humanistic Psychology, p. 82.
9. David Levin, commenting on the failures of humanism, in “Clinical Stories: A
Modern Self in the Fury of Being,” p. 487.
10. Hans Peter Duerr, Dreamtime, p. 110.
11. Graham Parkes, “Human/Nature in Nietzsche and Taoism,” p. 356.
12. On these general themes, see Joel Kovel, “On the Notion of Human Nature: A
Contribution Toward a Philosophical Anthropology.”
13. Plural realism is Hubert Dreyfus’s term for the stance of Heidegger’s later
thinking. I am, however, additionally qualifying the term along my own lines. Says Dreyfus:
“For a plural realist there is no point of view from which one can ask and answer the meta-
physical question concerning the one true nature of ultimate reality. . . . for Heidegger
different understandings of being reveal different sorts of entities, and since no one way
of revealing is exclusively true, accepting one does not commit us to rejecting the others”
(Being-in-the-World, pp. 262–263). In Being and Time, the early Heidegger had already said
that “an entity can show itself from itself in many ways, depending in each case on the kind
of access we have to it” (p. 51). He also did not dispute that what is represented by modern
natural science “is indeed nature itself,” but was adamant that this “objective” nature is
“only one way in which nature exhibits itself ” (“Science and Reflection,” in The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, p. 174).
14. Simone Weil, quoted in Ken Jones, The Social Face of Buddhism, p. 315.
15. This is not the place to discuss the relative ecological merits of Buddhism. On
these topics, see Ian Harris, “How Environmentalist is Buddhism?” and “Buddhist Envi-
ronmental Ethics and Detraditionalization: The Case of EcoBuddhism;” Alan Badiner,
Dharma Gaia: A Harvest of Essays in Buddhism and Ecology; Martine Batchelor and Kerry
Brown, Buddhism and Ecology; and D. T. Suzuki, “Nature in Zen Buddhism.”
16. Gary Snyder, A Place in Space, p. 187.
17. These three categories correspond to those discussed by Raymond Williams in
his Keywords.
18. See Sean Kane, Wisdom of the Mythtellers.
19. This is my own version of James Wright’s suggestion that while it is impor-
tant for Euroamericans to draw on Euroamerican traditions, the work of eco-spiritual
renewal must still rely to some extent on indigenous knowledges. In his own wilder-
ness quest work, Wright has chosen to perform a “literary archeology” of European
mythology in order to retrieve the skeletons of rites that he feels are hidden in the
old myths. He admits, nonetheless, that without “direct experience of some of [the]
North American ways, . . . the work of reanimating the old European forms would be
virtually impossible” (The Bones of Metamorphosis, p. 19). Caught between using ritual
forms native to North America or reimagined forms indigenous to old Europe, Wright
counsels that “we must do some of each”—while insisting that as an archetypal pattern,
found across cultures, “the core vision quest experience does not belong to any one
people.” I assume that it is clear to the reader that I claim no authoritative knowledge
of indigenous ways—that I am using such general notions as can roughly be grasped
not as a guide to those ways, but primarily as a means to come back to and show up
my own theme of loss and longing. I am aware, moreover, that disharmonious relations
with the natural world, warfare, starvation, and questionable gender arrangements are
not unheard of amongst primal peoples. These things do not of themselves, however,
erase the general relevance of indigenous teachings for undertaking the recollective task
at hand.
20. John Livingston, The Fallacy of Wildlife Conservation, p. 101.
21. Richard Nelson, The Island Within, pp. 245, 249.
22. Robert Avens, “Heidegger and Archetypal Psychology,” p. 185.
23. Martin Dillon, “Merleau-Ponty and the Reversibility Thesis,” p. 368.
24. I developed the idea of a kinship continuum from Dillon, “Merleau-Ponty,”
p. 378; as well as from Joel Kovel, “Human Nature, Freedom, and Spirit,” in The Radical
Spirit, pp. 300–301; and the writings of Paul Shepard.
25. Douglas Kirsner, The Schizoid World of Jean-Paul Sartre and R.D. Laing, p. 68.
In Sartre’s novel, Nausea, even the protagonist’s own hand is a source of disgust.
26. In truth, Sartre’s world is conceivable, but never quite achievable, as a person
with no common ground with others could never make contact with them. Similarly, nir-
vana is a temporary state only, so could never be regarded as a day-to-day form of life.
27. Gary Snyder, The Practice of the Wild, p. 8.
28. A point I take from M. C. Dillon, “Erotic Desire,” p. 158.
29. Joel Kovel, History and Spirit, p. 152.
30. Joel Kovel, “On the Notion of Human Nature,” p. 375.
31. Contacting, recall, occurs across a boundary zone of “me and not-me.” We
are never identical with that which we contact, no matter how much we may be identi-
fied with it. Even when in such “nondual” states of awareness as meditation or absorp-
tion in a task, we are still in contact with the world. As the Zen author D. T. Suzuki
writes: “The mountains do not vanish; they stand before me” (“Nature and Zen Bud-
dhism,” p. 241).
32. The idea of some “optimal distance” is present, in one form or another, in all
experiential practices of which I am familiar. T. J. Scheff discusses the relation between “aes-
thetic distance” and “optimal distance” in his Catharsis in Healing, Ritual, and Drama. The
notion of finding the “right distance” from a felt sense is a central feature of the practice of
focusing. The Buddhist idea of a “middle path” also suggests an optimal balance between
the extremes of sensual indulgence and asceticism, or a zone of experiencing in which one
can face one’s suffering while not being overwhelmed by it. Merleau-Ponty, finally, writes
that: “For each object, as for each picture in an art gallery, there is an optimum distance
from which it requires to be seen, a direction viewed from which it vouchsafes most of
itself: at a shorter or greater distance we have merely a perception blurred through excess or
deficiency” (Phenomenology of Perception, p. 302).
33. Joel Kovel, “The Marriage of Radical Ecologies, p. 411.
34. Paul Shepard, The Others, p. 5. Emphasis mine.
35. Richard Nelson, Make Prayers to the Raven, pp. 20, 33, 76.
36. Kane, The Wisdom, p. 105.
37. Barry Lopez, “Renegotiating the Contracts,” p. 14.
38. Calvin Martin, In the Spirit of the Earth, p. 19.
39. For a poetic and touching consideration of this, see chapter eleven of Ursula
LeGuin, Buffalo Gals; And Other Animal Presences. See also Colin Turnbull, The Human
Cycle, pp. 51–52, 183–184.
40. Gordon Wheeler, “Self and Shame: A New Paradigm for Psychotherapy,” p. 49.
41. “For us, being is discontinuous—and yet this discontinuity is experienced as
loss, and life is spent trying to overcome it. It comes naturally to us, then, to sense nonbeing
along with being, and to try to rejoin the two, that is, to be spiritually. For nonbeing [the
gap] is the space between the discontinuities.” (Joel Kovel, History and Spirit, p. 81).
42. Kovel, History, p. 83.
43. Egoic “being is self-experience in which the rationalistic, all knowing ‘I’ crowds
out every other self-phenomenon. In the egoic topology of the self, ontological space is
occluded by the I-centre” (Kovel, “Human,” p. 299). My presentation here on the Ego and
the void is of necessity a great simplification of a complex topic. The three articles by David
Loy in the bibliography offers some further discussion.
44. David Loy, “Avoiding the Void: The Lack of Self in Psychotherapy and Bud-
dhism,” p. 172.
45. Bertram Karon and Leighton Whitaker, “Psychotherapy and the Fear of Under-
standing Schizophrenia,” pp. 39–40.
46. This is a variation on Gary Yontef ’s “twin dangers” (Awareness, Dialogue, and
Process, p. 463). See, also, Irvin Yalom, Existential Psychotherapy, pp. 143–147.
47. Judith Herman, Trauma and Recovery, p. 93. For a discussion of this dynamic
in the lives of physically and emotionally abusive men, see Donald Dutton, The Abusive
Personality: Violence and Control in Intimate Relationships.
48. See William Bridges, Transitions.
49. Max Horkheimer, The Eclipse of Reason, pp. 105, 106.
50. Kovel, “Human Nature,” in The Radical, p. 300.
51. Passages taken from Snyder, The Practice, p. 19, and from Gary Snyder quoted
in Paul Shepard, “A Post-Historic Primitivism,” p. 82.
52. Erich Fromm, The Art of Loving, p. 8. Emphasis removed.
53. See M. C. Dillon, “Toward a Phenomenology of Love and Sexuality: An Inquiry
into the Limits of the Humans Situation as They Condition Loving.”
54. Martin Heidegger, Introduction to Metaphysics, p. 14.
55. Paul Shepard and Barry Sanders, Sacred Paw, pp. xix, 57.
56. John Livingston, Rogue Primate, p. 104.
57. “The gap between nature and ourselves is healed by attempting to sway as
humans within the rhythms of nature, swinging to and fro with the coming-to-be and
passing-away inherent in all life” (Carol Bigwood, Earth Muse, p. 197).
58. David Abram, The Spell of the Sensuous, p. 169.
59. Kane, The Wisdom, p. 40.
60. Jacob Boehme, quoted in Norman O. Brown, Life Against Death, p. 130.
61. On this see Martin Heidegger, “The Age of the World Picture,” in The Question
Concerning Technology and other Essays; and Robert Romanyshysn, “The Despotic Eye: An
Illustration of Metabletic Phenomenology and Its Implications.”
62. Owen Barfield, Saving The Appearances, p. 95.
63. Cf. Heidegger’s comments: “Color shines and wants only to shine. When we
analyze it in rational terms by measuring its wavelengths, it is gone. It shows itself only
when it remains undisclosed and unexplained. Earth thus shatters every attempt to pen-
etrate into it. It causes every merely calculating importunity upon it to turn into a destruc-
tion. . . . The earth appears openly cleared as itself only when it is perceived and preserved
as that which is by nature undisclosable, that which shrinks from every disclosure and
constantly keeps itself closed up” (“The Origin of the Work of Art,” in Poetry, Language,
Thought, p. 47).
64. Barry Lopez, Of Wolves and Men, p. 4.
65. S. N. Tandon, “Dharma—Its Definition and Universal Application,” p. 11.
66. Lawrence Hatab, Myth and Philosophy, p. 35. This is not to equate the outlooks
of Buddhists, western phenomenologists, and various mythological peoples, all of whom
will of course have their own specific understandings of things, even as they share an expe-
riential approach.
67. Shepard, The Others, p. 326. James Hillman similarly remarks that: “Multiple
personality is humanity in its natural condition. In other cultures these multiple person-
alities have names, locations, energies, functions, voices, angel and animal forms” (Arche-
typal Psychology: A Brief Account, p. 51. See also Revisioning Psychology, p. 203). Indeed, in
indigenous societies, and up until about the seventeenth century in our own culture, “the
otherness of the self has been axiomatic” (Michael Holquist in the Introduction to M. M.
Bakhtin, Art and Answerability, p. xxvi).
68. On some such varieties of private otherness, see Roger Levin, “Multiple Person-
ality, Transpersonal Guides, and Malevolent Possessions: Discriminating Kinds of Alterity
in a Psychotherapy Case by Means of Bodily Felt Sensing.”
69. Eugene Gendlin, “The Client s Client: The Edge of Awareness,” p. 81. The felt
sense is thus the source of all our inwardly arising symbols, the place where we discover the
aims or intentions, the needs or claims, of the soul itself (the soul being the personification
of the unconscious). In what could serve as a description of the felt sense, Hillman alludes
to soul as “an inner place or deeper person or ongoing presence” below our normal con-
sciousness (Revisioning, p. xvi).
70. James Hillman calls this the “personal/impersonal paradox of the soul” (Revi-
sioning, p. 105; see also pp. 31, 46–51). I would also call it the identity/dis-identity paradox.
71. Hillman, “The Animal,” p. 320.
72. The best descriptions of this process are contained in the work of Ann Weiser
Cornell, including The Focusing Student’s Manual and The Power of Focusing. Gendlin, fur-
thermore, emphasizes the importance of thanking whatever comes to us in focusing, loving
and appreciating our dreams; in short, of developing a respectful personal relationship with
all “inner” contents. See also Hillman, Re-Visioning, pp. 31, 139.
73. James Hillman devotes the first chapter of Re-Visioning to this point.
74. See Hillman, Revisioning and Robert Sardello, Love and the Soul.
75. Shagbark Hickory, “Environmental Etiquette/Environmental Practice: Amer-
ican Indian Challenges to Mainstream Environmental Ethics,” p. 121. As Nelson also
notes: “weather is the most fully personified element in the Koyukon physical world. The
interchange between people and these conscious entities is fairly elaborate and intense”
(Make Prayers, p. 40).
76. Martin Heidegger, “The Fieldpath,” p. 456.
77. There is, in fact, a great deal of literature on such communication. See, for
example, Stephen Foster and Meredith Little, The Roaring of the Sacred River; Stephanie
Kaza, The Attentive Heart: Conversations with Trees; and the last two chapters of John Liv-
ingston, The Fallacy of Wildlife Conservation.
78. I can, for example, generally distinguish among the kind of experiences I have in
downtown Toronto; on a canoe trip in Algonquin Park; and in those even-less-humanized
places where there are no trails, designated campsites, or line-ups at portages. This does not
mean, however, than I do not have wild encounters in downtown Toronto, nor that I am
always optimally attuned or open to the big outdoors when I am in them.
79. John Livingston, Rogue Primate, p. 104.
80. Even the most cursory glance at the Buddhist doctrine of karma is enough to
realize that to comprehend it in any depth requires much practice and insight.
81. Richard Nelson, Interview. “Life-Ways of the Hunter,” p. 84. Sean Kane simi-
larly writes: “In dealing with nature or any of her people, the one thing you can be really
sure of is that beings are intelligent and therefore easily insulted, and that acts have con-
sequences. For life in a playground of intelligent roving energies, that is perhaps the best
advice. What goes around comes around” (The Wisdom, p. 240).
82. Tandon, “Dharma,” p. 12. These ideas are discussed well in a Taoist context by
Roger Ames, “Taoism and the Nature of Nature.”
83. Bruce Foltz, Inhabiting the Earth, p. 125. Emphasis mine.
84. James Hillman, “The Animal Kingdom in the Human Dream,” pp. 314,
325–326.
85. Martin Heidegger, “What Are Poets For?,” in Poetry, Language, Thought, p. 101.
Heidegger quotes Nietzsche: “How can anything dead ‘be’”? See also Foltz, Inhabiting,
pp. 132–134, from which I am taking most of this discussion. As Foltz observes, Zoe is
itself from the Greek root ‘Za-,’ which means a strengthening or intensification.
86. Tandon, “Dharma,” p. 10.
87. As John Caputo notes, everything in a “hermeneutic interpretation. . . comes
down to its ability to provoke in us the ultimate hermeneutic response: ‘That is what we
are looking for. That puts into words what we have all along understood about ourselves’”
(Radical Hermeneutics, p. 81).
88. Martin Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology,” in The Question
Concerning Technology, And Other Essays, p. 10.
89. Kane, The Wisdom, p. 234.
90. Hillman, “The Animal,” p. 324. Hillman’s comments are inspired by the biolo-
gist Adolf Portmann.
91. Owen Barfield, Poetic Diction, p. 180. Bernard Berenson similarly wrote that
what he perceived in art was the appearance of living motion, even in works of stone (as
discussed in Edith Cobb, “The Ecology of Imagination in Childhood,” p. 131).
92. Martin Heidegger, quoted in Eugene Gendlin, “Dwelling,” p. 139. As this line
suggests, Heidegger regarded written poetry or “poesy” as only one of many possible modes
of poetizing or bringing forth.
93. James Hillman, “Aesthetics and Politics,” p. 76.
94. Richard Avens, “Heidegger and Archetypal Psychology,” p. 199. Emphasis mine.
95. See Eugene Gendlin, “Nonlogical Moves and Nature Metaphors” and
“Dwelling.”
96. Whatever sense we make, it is always from a bodily feeling, is always phys-ical.
Thus, says Avens, physis “as logos (physio-logy) is also the soul (psycho-logy)” (“Heidegger,”
p. 198). Vincent Vycinas observes, in this respect, that: “Logos, as cut off from physis and
standing by itself or for itself, becomes the perverted logos, logic. Physis, on the other hand,
when thought of separately from logos, becomes perverted physis, matter” (Earth and Gods,
p. 196). David Abram makes a similar point when he notes that when reflective reason fails
to acknowledge or loses conscious awareness of its “rootedness in . . . bodily, participatory
modes of experience” it becomes “dysfunctional” (The Spell of the Sensuous, p. 303). On the
original unity of physis and logos, see Martin Heidegger, An Introduction to Metaphysics, pp.
115–196.
97. Paul Klee, quoted in Mica Goldfarb, “Making the Unknown Known: Art as the
Speech of the Body,” p. 188. J. Macmurray likewise wrote: “The artist is not abnormal, but
simply the normal human individual. Not of course the average human being, after educa-
tion and the constraints of social and physical necessity have succeeded in suppressing and
stunting his natural capacity” (Quoted in Neil Bolton, “The Live World: Imagination and
the Development of Experience,” p. 14).
98. Sigmund Freud, quoted in Norman Brown, Life Against Death, p. 67.
99. Frederick Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, pp. 235, 321, 323. The psychoanalyst D.
W. Winnicott claimed that creativity “belongs to being alive.” Hence, the person who lives
creatively feels that “life is worth living.” An uncreative and conformist mode of existence,
by contrast, “is a sick basis for life” (Playing and Reality, pp. 65, 67).
100. See Carl Bigwood, Earth Muse for lengthy discussions of this theme.
101. George Steiner, Heidegger, p. 132.
102. Martin Heidegger, “. . . Poetically Man Dwells . . . .,” in Poetry, Language,
Thought, p. 216.
103. Martin Heidegger, “Building Dwelling Thinking,” in Poetry, Language, Thought,
p. 149. We can tell when our dwelling has become unpoetic exactly “because it is in essence
poetic” (Heidegger, “. . . Poetically,” in Poetry, p. 228).
104. Martin, In the Spirit, pp. 10, 15. Otherwise put, indigenous societies judge
“ecstatic communication with the earth to be humanity’s greatest prerogative and calling”
(p. 133).
105. See Shagbark Hickory, “Environmental,” pp. 114–115; and Jeanette Arm-
strong, “Keepers of the Earth.”
106. Bigwood, Earth, p. 206. John Livingston has suggested that the best word he
can find to describe bird song is “celebratory” (“The Dilemma of the Deep Ecologist,”
p. 68). I do not doubt, then, that others creatures also revel in creation. I would suggest,
though, that it is the special business of humans to create cosmologies.
107. The story is told by the Haudenosaunee statesman Leon Shenandoah, quoted
in Chellis Glendinning, My Name Is Chellis and I’m in Recovery from Western Civilization,
pp. 211–212. As Joseph Bruchac observes, in Native American traditions “Animals are rec-
ognized not only as spiritual beings but, in some ways, as being wiser than humans. A bear
never forgets that it is a bear, yet human beings often forget what a human must do. . . .
This potential for confusion was true for Native people long before the coming of Euro-
peans (though Europeans have raised the art of spiritual confusion to a new level!) That
is why the traditional teachings remain so important. They remind human beings how to
take care” (“Understanding the Great Mystery,” p. 101).
108. See Kovel, “On the Notion.” For an example of weak denial, see chapter two of
Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures.
109. See Eugene Gendlin, “Neurosis and Human Nature in the Experiential Method
of Thought and Therapy.”
110. Eugene Gendlin, “Human Nature and Concepts,” p. 4.
111. For arguments by a phenomenologist who claims that it “cannot seriously be
doubted today that there is a given biological nature,” a “transhistorical order not reducible
to social conditioning,” see David Levin, The Listening Self and “Visions of Narcissism.”
Eugene Gendlin also argues that the “dreadful error” of many modern thinkers has been
“to think of humans as mere creations of culture, created out of nothingness, disclosed in
the midst of an abyss” (“Reply to Hatab,” in David Levin, ed., Language Beyond Postmod-
ernism, p. 247). “From Descartes to Heidegger. . . there are only cultural humans: there is
no human” (“The Small Steps of the Therapy Process,” p. 209). More, he says that because
the “conviction that there is no human nature” leads to a nonrecognition of our shared
humanity it also leads to bloodshed based on the notion that one group of people’s culture
is superior to another’s (see “Reply to Hatab”).
112. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, p. 254. Emphasis mine. I do not want to make
Merleau-Ponty say what he did not intend. While he clearly felt that we are born already
organizing our experience according to an ancient dialogue between body and world, he
did not go as far as I do in positing a transhistorical human nature.
113. Frederick Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, p. 440.
114. Eugene Gendlin, Focusing-Oriented Psychotherapy, p. 281.
115. Eugene Gendlin, “A Phenomenology of Emotions: Anger,” p. 373. Emphasis
mine.
116. Eugene Gendlin, “A Philosophical Critique of the Concept of Narcissism: The
Significance of the Awareness Movement,” p. 264.
117. See Gion Condrau and Medard Boss, “Existential Analysis”; Medard Boss, Exis-
tential Foundations of Medicine and Psychology; and Christine Downing, “Poetically Dwells
Man on This Earth,” p. 315.
118. Joel Kovel, “Things and Words,” p. 53.
119. See Kovel, “Things.” As Kovel offers: “Secure and coherent intimate human
relations . . . have been established as a transhistorical human need—that is, a necessary
condition for the development of real human power, as against infantile impotence” (“Nar-
cissism and the Family”). See, also, Alice Miller, The Drama of the Gifted Child.
120. The quote continues: “An analogous argument would be that because some
societies do not define fruit and leafy vegetables as edible they are not required in the
diet. Unless one could show that scurvy, rickets, and other diseases of poor nutrition were
absent, the argument about cultural variation in diet would not be credible. Because of
this lapse, the cultural-specific position of the arbitrariness of emotional expression should
probably not be given much weight” (Thomas Scheff, “Toward Integration in the Social
Psychology of Emotions,” p. 339). Noteworthy, also, is the claim of Harvey Jackins that
in counseling people from every corner of the world, he has discovered that they all appear
to have been wounded in the same general ways and to have the same need to express the
same repressed emotions (which seem to be of a cross-cultural nature). Jackins is the Inter-
national Reference Person for a form of peer-counseling practiced in over eighty countries.
(See Harvey Jackins, How “Re-evaluation Counseling” Began, p. 14; and The List.) Mary
Hendricks similarly writes that the process of focusing “seems to get at a variable more
fundamental than cultural differences” (“Focusing Oriented/Experiential Psychotherapy”).
Finally, Shepard offers that most anthropologists have been “hell-bent on the study of cul-
tural differences,” while evincing little interest at all in “species characteristics” (The Only
World We’ve Got, p. xii).
121. Victor Frankl, Man’s Search for Meaning. Of course, the need for meaning cuts
across all the rest, which only goes to show that there are our needs can be articulated in
various ways.
122. I emphasize some developmental needs in the following passage from Judith
Herman: “In [a] climate of profoundly disrupted relationships the child faces a formidable
developmental task. She must find a way to form primary attachments to caregivers who are
either dangerous or, from her perspective, negligent. She must develop a way to develop a
sense of basic trust and safety with caretakers who are untrustworthy and unsafe. She must
develop a sense of self in relation to others who are helpless, uncaring, or cruel. She must
develop a capacity for bodily self-regulation in an environment in which her body is at the
disposal of others’ needs, as well as a capacity for self-soothing in an environment without
solace. She must develop the capacity for initiative in an environment which demands that
she bring her will into complete conformity with that of her abuser. And ultimately she
must develop a capacity for intimacy out of an environment where all intimate relationships
are corrupt, and an identity out of an environment which defines her as a whore and a slave.
. . . Though she perceives herself as abandoned to a power without mercy, she must find a
way to preserve hope and meaning. The alternative is utter despair, something no child can
bear” (Trauma, p. 101).
123. The same can be said, inversely, for the process of affirming the common joys we
experience, such as the universal delight at a baby’s smile.
124. See Judy Steed, Our Little Secret.
125. Paul Shepard, Coming Home to the Pleistocene, p. 134.
126. See Jean Liedloff, The Continuum Concept.
127. Chogyam Trungpa, Shambhala, pp. 9 and 10. I have taken liberties with the
ordering of the quotations.
128. Jack Kornfield, A Path with Heart, p. 50.
129. It may be objected that humanistic psychology and Buddhism have differing
views of our basic goodness. Whereas numerous humanists suggest that we are simply
born good, Buddhists suggest that we are reborn carrying patterns of bad karma from
previous lifetimes. Despite this difference, what is common to humanism and Buddhists
is the belief that we free ourselves from suffering and make better contact with our basic
nature primarily through our own efforts. Although humanists generally trace our suf-
fering to hurtful experiences, they do not advocate victimhood, but rather the taking of
responsibility for our wounds, for becoming more accountable for our behaviors, and for
developing the awareness to personally grow. Buddhists similarly advocate that we take
responsibility for all our past karmas, for our reactions in the present, and for the work of
becoming more enlightened or attained. In other words, for both Buddhism and humanism
our basic goodness is something that can be relied on, that is assumed as an ultimate truth,
and yet which is not realized without our taking responsibility for this realization.
130. The idea of innate human goodness has not gone uncriticized (see, for example,
F. C. Thorne, “Critique of Recent Developments in Personality Counselling Therapy”).
Critics say, for example, that the presence of so much antisocial or oppressive behavior in
the world makes the idea of innate goodness untenable; or they say that humanists set up
a false duality between a good human nature and a bad human society, the latter of which
is regarded as the sole source of our trouble. Because it is not the purpose of this book to
defend humanistic psychology or Buddhism against its critics, I do not intend to pursue
these debates at any length. I would like to assert, however, that pointing to our bad karma
does not by itself refute the idea of basic goodness. Indeed, Buddhists emphasize precisely
that the world is full of greed, hatred, and delusion, while still maintaining that we and
the world are basically good—a goodness that can be gradually realized or understood
with practice. While wholeness and goodness define our original condition, we live in
forgetfulness or ignorance of this fact. How this might have become so is the topic for
numerous cultural narratives, as I discussed above. Regardless of how we might under-
stand this “fall” into ignorance and violence, what seems most significant to me is that the
process of awakening to our essential nature or unity, of spontaneously reclaiming it in
the course of healing and growing, is well-documented and widely experienced by all sorts
of practitioners, including humanists and Buddhists. Goodness and badness in this case
are not dualistically opposed but are related via our condition of ignorance, forgetfulness,
woundedness, and so on.
131. Gary Snyder writes: “There is nothing in human nature. . . which intrinsically
requires that a culture be contradictory, repressive and productive of violent and frustrated
personalities. . . . One can prove it for himself by taking a good look at his own nature
through meditation. . . . To make ‘human nature’ suspect is also to make Nature—the
wilderness—the enemy” (Earth Household, pp. 91, 115).
132. Richard Nelson. “Life-Ways of the Hunter,” p. 96.
133. Russell Jacoby, Social Amnesia, p. 31; Kovel, “Human Nature,” in The Radical,
p. 303.
134. Jeanette Armstrong, interviewed on the Canadian Broadcasting Corporation
radio program, “From Naked Ape to Superspecies.”
135. See Peter Mathiessen, “Native Earth” and Joseph Bruchac, “Understanding the
Great Mystery.”
136. Heidegger, An Introduction, pp. 125, 134.
137. John (Fire) Lame Deer and Richard Erdoes, Lame Deer, p. 120.
138. Joel Kovel, “The Marxist View of Man and Psychoanalysis,” in The Radical
Spirit, p. 169.
139. Nelson, “Life-Ways,” p. 92.
140. Nelson, Make Prayers, pp. 138, 225.
141. Martin, In the Spirit, p. 8.
142. Matthiessen, “Native,” p. 22. Mathiessen continues: “Nature itself is ‘the Great
Mystery,’ the ‘religion before religion’. . . Respect for nature is respect for oneself,. . . since
man and nature, though not the same thing, are not different.” Joseph Epes Brown writes:
“Throughout virtually all indigenous American Indian traditions, a pervasive theme has
been that all forms and forces of all orders of the immediately experienced natural environ-
ment may communicate to human beings the totality of that which is to be known of the
sacred mysteries of creation, and thus of the sacred essence of beings and being” (The Spir-
itual Legacy of the American Indian, p. 26). See also Barre Toelken, “Seeing with a Native’s
Eye: How Many Sheep Will It Hold?,” p. 14.
143. Stan Rowe, Home Place, p. 75.
144. Mathiessen, “Native,” p. 7.
145. “For the Navajo . . . almost everything is related to health . . . one needs not
only medicine, the Navajo would say, but one needs to reestablish his relationship with the
rhythm of nature. It is the ritual as well as the medicine which gets one back ‘in shape’”
(Toelken, “Seeing,” pp. 14–15).
146. Abram, The Spell, p. 22.
147. These four are Re-evaluation Counseling, Vipassana meditation, Gestalt
therapy, and focusing.
148. Vipassana simply means “insight” or “wisdom.” Vipassana meditation is based
on the original discourses of the Buddha, being associated with the earliest, or Theravaden,
stream of Buddhism. For a discussion of how crucial the condition of one’s posture is for
the experience of sitting meditation, see Will Johnson, The Posture of Mediation.
149. Martin Heidegger, “What Is Metaphysics?,” in Basic Writings, p. 108. My
emphasis.
150. In The Attentive Heart: Conversations with Trees, for example, Stephanie Kaza
describes how she draws on her Zen Buddhist training to listen to trees. It was encouraged,
furthermore, in my own training for an extended wilderness quest (on which topic, see
Stephen Foster and Meredith Little, The Roaring of the Sacred River).
151. A topic extensively treated by Kovel in History.
152. Kovel, “On the Notion,” p. 389. “Desire wants fusion with the ground of its being
and the undoing of the distinction between humanity and nature” (Kovel, History, p. 144).
153. Charles Bergman, ‘“The Curious Peach:’ Nature and the Language of Desire,”
p. 282.
154. Kovel, History, pp. 124, 159.
155. Kovel, The Age, pp. 72, 83. “There is no intrinsic need . . . for desire to be problem-
atic unless the society in which it emerges is self-estranged and estranged from nature” (p. 72).
156. Kornfield, A Path, p. 88.
Chapter Five
24. Lionel Trilling, quoted in Paul Shepard, Coming Home to the Pleistocene, p. 38.
Noting that an authentic culture takes nature as its “guide in the task of cultivation,”
Kohák remarks: “If, in the course of the last three centuries, we have become increasingly
marauders on the face of the earth rather than dwellers therein, it is not because we have
become more distinctively human, more distinctively cultured, but rather because we have
become less so” (The Embers, p. 91).
25. Wendell Berry, The Unsettling of America, p. 43.
26. Gary Snyder, The Practice of the Wild, p. 7.
27. Grene, “The Paradoxes,” p. 28.
28. Grene, “The Paradoxes,” p. 29. Note that I am here addressing the problem of
finding a discourse that lies “between the human and the natural,” for (as Grene observes)
human science is said to correspond to the historical, natural science to the nonhistorical.
History (humans) and nonhistory (nature) thus share no common ground.
29. Paul Shepard, quoted in David Abram, The Spell of the Sensuous, p. 181. Emphasis
mine. See, also, “A Post-Historic Primitivism,” pp. 40–47; and Nature, pp. 54–58, 144.
30. Martin Heidegger, “Letter on Humanism,” in Basic Writings, p. 206.
31. For all his talk of earth and sky, Heidegger was thus ultimately unable “to place
man within an organized nature.” “Only if we can place ourselves . . . within nature,” says
Grene, “only then can we save the concept of historicity from the self-destruction to which
it seems so readily susceptible” (“The Paradoxes,” p. 29).
32. Hermes is a complex character—guide of souls, inventor, trickster, bringer of
both luck and misfortune, thief, source of wild versus domestic order, god of fertility.
Walter Otto called the world of Hermes a “basic image of living reality,” a complete form
of existence, where one journeys after the full sweep of human experience while keeping a
good-humored spiritual detachment about it all. See Karl Kerényi, Hermes: Guide of Souls
and Kane, The Wisdom.
33. Kerényi notes the connection between hermeneutics and Hermes: “Hermes is
hermeneus (‘interpreter’), a linguistic mediator, and this not merely on verbal grounds. By
nature he is the begetter and bringer of something light-like, a clarifier, God of ex-position
and inter-pretation . . . which seeks and in his spirit . . . is led forward to the deepest mys-
tery” (Hermes, p. 88). Despite that Hermes figures in my thinking, I am reluctant to wholly
embrace him as a symbol for my psychology, for two reasons. The first is that I wish to work
in broad principles, rather than in the details of Hermes’s world. The second is that I am
mindful of the fact that within indigenous traditions the messengers of the divine are not in
human but animal form. The bear, for example, “has for thousands of years been the master
of souls, bodies, and minds in transition,” guarding the underworld and bringing “to the
people a message of good ecology and good relations between them and the sacred powers
that govern the world” (Paul Shepard and Barry Sanders, The Sacred Paw, pp. xv, xviii, 72).
Likewise, in “the Haida mythworld, the messengers are the loon and pie-billed grebe, birds
of good omen” (Kane, The Wisdom, p. 110). What I am going for in this section, then, is
simply a view of human existence that is inspired by hermeneutic thought, and in which
messages or gifts are welcomed from all sorts of others.
34. Claudio Naranjo, The Techniques of Gestalt Therapy, p. 5; Medard Boss, Existen-
tial Foundations of Medicine and Psychology, p. 282.
35. Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, p. 100. Geertz is also drawing on
Susan Langer.
36. Paul Ricoeur, “Existence and Hermeneutics,” in The Conflict of Interpretations,
p. 17; Hans-Georg Gadamer, “The Problem of Historical Consciousness,” p. 87.
37. Hans-Georg Gadamer, “The Universality of the Hermeneutical Problem,” in
Philosophical Hermeneutics, p. 15.
38. Shepard, Nature, p. 14.
39. Medard Boss, Meaning and Content of Sexual Perversions, p. 37.
40. This is the particular terrain of an area of psychoanalysis known as “object rela-
tions.” See, for example, Margaret Mahler et al., The Psychological Birth of the Human
Infant; D. W. Winnicott, The Maturational Processes and the Facilitating Environment and
Playing and Reality; and Jay Greenberg and Stephen Mitchell, Object Relations in Psycho-
analytic Theory. This principle comes out clearly, as well, in Erik Erikson’s work on psycho-
social development, in which he assumes that “the human personality in principle develops
according to steps predetermined in the growing person’s readiness to be driven toward, to
be aware of, and to interact with, a widening social radius” (Childhood and Society, p. 270).
Finally, the principle of ever-widening spheres also comes out of the field of “attachment
theory,” first formulated by the psychiatrist John Bowlby. See, for example, Bowlby’s A
Secure Base; Mary Ainsworth, Patterns of Attachment; and Michel B. Sperling and William
H. Berman, Attachment in Adults.
41. David Abram, The Spell of the Sensuous, p. 62.
42. Nancy Chodorow, “Gender, Relation, and Difference in Psychoanalytic Per-
spective,” p. 11. Emphasis removed. I am partly drawing on Chodorow in the rest of this
paragraph as well.
43. Winnicott thus speaks of the seeming paradox that there can be a “separation
that is not a separation but a form of union” (Playing, p. 98)—in other words: kinship.
44. Frederick Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, p. 270.
45. Harold Searles, The Nonhuman Environment, p. 30.
46. For Chodorow, it is especially important to see this in boys, who in the absence
of parenting by men must establish their male identity by splitting away and overasserting
their difference from women (mother).
47. Edith Cobb, The Ecology of Imagination in Childhood, p. 70.
48. Joel Kovel, History and Spirit, p. 85. “Splitting . . . is the basic property of domi-
nation, whether of class, sex, race or, more generally, of nature itself. . . . Differentiation . . .
represents what we [ideally] strive for: it is the outcome of human nature in the direction
of ecological interrelatedness and the essential unity of all beings” (Joel Kovel, “Human
Nature, Freedom and Spirit,” in The Radical Spirit, p. 292).
49. Colin Turnbull, The Human Cycle, p. 36. Emphasis mine. The detailed discus-
sions in Turnbull’s entire book admirably bring out much of what I am attempting to say
in this section.
50. I should note that humans are not the only species to experience anxiety before
the void or to go through a developmental process of attachment and separation, both of
which are highly noticeable among primates generally. As Hans Jonas suggests, the various
forms of life are more or less precarious depending on how mediated their relationship is
to the world, how much of a gap they sense. “Imaging and speaking man,” however, has
achieved the most extreme degree of such mediacy (The Phenomenon of Life, pp. 183–187).
51. Shepard, Coming, p. 45.
52. Tim Ingold, The Appropriation of Nature, p. 223. For the hunter-gatherer,
“there is no contradiction, no conflict of purpose, between the expression of individuality
and his generalized commitment to others. Since the world of others is enfolded within his
own person, these are one and the same” (p. 240).
53. D. W. Winnicott, “The Capacity to Be Alone,” in The Maturational Processes
and the Facilitating Environment.
54. I am adapting here from Kovel, History, p. 181.
55. Stanley Diamond, In Search of the Primitive, p. 170. Emphasis mine.
56. Joel Kovel, The Age of Desire, p. 74. My discussion here on desire is in general
inspired by Kovel.
57. In actuality, we typically experience life as a relative mix of goodness and bad-
ness, which leads to a complexly compartmentalized inner life.
58. Kovel, The Age, p. 255. The notion of “sociation” comes from Kovel.
59. See Kovel’s excellent discussion in History, pp. 81–82.
60. As Kovel writes: “The more alienated a society or person, the more horrific the
Otherness” (History).
61. Turnbull, The Human, p. 30. Hence: “With the Mbuti we see the concept of
the family as a constantly expanding universe, beginning with the nuclear family and ulti-
mately embracing the whole forest, the entire extent of their experience at any moment”
(p. 59).
62. Nelson, Make Prayers, pp. 14, 226, 238. Reports such as Nelson’s and Turnbull’s
are ubiquitous. Musicologist Marina Roseman, for example, observes that the Temiar, a
rain-forest people of the Malay peninsula, do not alienate “flowers, trees, or cicadas as
inherently different and distant,” but “stress an essential similarity.” They “receive inspira-
tion and constant regeneration from interaction with the essences of mountains, rivers,
fruits, and creatures of the tropical rain forest. . . . The jungle is a social place” (quoted in
Shepard, Coming, p. 42).
63. Richard Nelson, The Island Within, p. 276.
64. Richard Nelson, “Life-Ways of the Hunter,” p. 88.
65. This idea forms part of the nucleus of Ray Rogers’s thesis in Nature and the
Crisis of Modernity.
66. Old Torlino, quoted in Abram, The Spell, p. 70.
67. Turnbull, The Human, p. 149.
68. Conrad Aiken, quoted in Edith Cobb, “The Ecology of Imagination in
Childhood,” p. 129.
69. The middle chapters of Abram’s The Spell of the Sensuous—namely, “The Flesh
of Language,” “Animism and the Alphabet,” and “In the Landscape of Language”—are all
dedicated to this topic. I will be making reference to others besides Abram in due course,
especially Merleau-Ponty, but see also Kohák, “The Gift of the Word” in The Embers,
pp. 47–66.
70. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p 187.
71. Merleau-Ponty, quoted in Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 215.
72. Abram, The Spell, p. 82. Hence Merleau-Ponty’s remark that “language has us. . .
it is not we who have language. . . . it is being that speaks within us and not we who speak
of being” (The Visible and the Invisible, p. 194). By “being,” Merleau-Ponty here means the
world in its nonthematic, inexplicit, or horizonal character.
73. Martin Heidegger, On the Way to Language, pp. 98–99.
74. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, p. 155. In making this point, Merleau-Ponty is bor-
rowing from Valéry.
75. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, “An Unpublished Text by Maurice Merleau-Ponty: A
Prospectus of His Work,” in The Primacy of Perception, p. 7.
76. Abram, The Spell, p. 83.
77. In addition to Abram’s work, my other main source, Dillon’s Merleau-Ponty’s
Ontology, offers much discussion that helps elaborate this principle beyond what I am able
to do here.
78. Abram, The Spell, p. 84. Emphasis mine. See also Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s,
p. 218.
79. Abram, The Spell, pp. 80, 84.
80. “Alone of all expressive processes, speech is able to settle into a sediment and
constitute an acquisition for use in human relations” (Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology,
p. 190). Words thus also have a transparent quality, going right to the things they disclose
while keeping themselves nonfigural, just as we see with our eyes while having no thematic
awareness of them (unless something gets in them, we develop cataracts, or whatever).
81. This unique disclosive ability of words is suggested, says Abram, in the Old
English word “spell,” which came to mean not only correctly arranging the letters of the
name for some entity but in so doing to also “effect a magic” or cast a “spell” over that
entity, that is, to summon it forth in some way (The Spell, pp. 89, 133).
82. Paul Ricoeur, “The Metaphorical Process as Cognition, Imagination, and
Feeling,” pp. 150–151.
83. See Christopher Norris, Deconstruction, and Robert Mugerauer, Interpreting
Environments.
84. Dillon, “Merleau-Ponty and Postmodernity,” p. xxiii. As Dillon suggests, by
contrast: “sedimented language, the store of knowledge wrested from the perceived world,
does not screen us from the world; rather it provides the means of articulating the world
and adding to that store” (Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 201).
85. Eugene Gendlin, “Nonlogical Moves and Nature Metaphors.” Derrida’s strategy
is to show that language is metaphorical and so that it can never re-present some original
or objective reality, as the modern tradition has sought to do; he wants to show that there
is no such reality, but rather constant slippage. Gendlin argues, however, that in knocking
the representational model, Derrida is at the same time holding onto it, that is, he retains a
dated theory of metaphor. He thus does not go far enough in his criticism, or pose any alter-
natives. That is, Derrida misses the creative, originating power of language-use, wherein
we sense more than our existing concepts and distinctions; “misses the texture of life and
usage” that word-use opens up; misses, finally, the way that metaphors call forth bodily felt
meanings, bring experiential effects, as part of an ongoing life process, rather than simply
mis-represent some original reality that is nowhere to be found.
86. Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 187.
87. Walter Ong has criticized Derrida and other “textualists” precisely on this point.
Ong says that textualist regard the text as a closed system because they view it in historical
isolation, instead of tracing it to its verbal source in primary orality. See Orality and Literacy,
pp. 168–169. In other words, they take the text as primary when it is in fact secondary.
88. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, pp. 429–430. “The only pre-existent Logos is
the world itself ’ (p. xx). I think it is odd that Barfield should have to argue that “if language
is ‘meaningful,’ then nature herself must also be meaningful.” How could it be otherwise?
As Barfield notes: “The denial of any . . . inner being to the processes of nature leads inevi-
tably to the denial of it to man himself ’ (“The Rediscovery of Meaning,” pp. 12, 15).
89. Merleau-Ponty, quoted in Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 201. Note that although
this statement may serve as a response to Derrida, it was written a number of years before
Derrida’s major works appeared, by which time Merleau-Ponty had already died. See also
M. C. Dillon, “Merleau-Ponty and Postmodernity.”
90. See Ricoeur, “The Metaphorical,” p. 142.
91. Hence Merleau-Ponty’s comment: “There really is inspiration and expiration of
Being” (“Eye and Mind,” in The Primacy of Perception, p. 167). See, also, Abram’s chapter
on “The Forgetting and Remembering of Air,” in The Spell.
92. I do not doubt the critical value of Derrida’s efforts to disrupt received habits
of thought. As Joel Kovel comments, however, whatever liberation Derrida promises is
largely undone by his flight into the cage of text. “There is nothing to be said within lan-
guage—yet nothing but language: surely one of the bleakest perspectives ever advanced on
the human condition.” (History, p. 281, n. 48). On intellectual retreatism, see also Dillon,
“Merleau-Ponty and Postmodernity,” pp. xxii–xxiii.
93. “More than any other single invention,” writes Ong, “writing has transformed
human consciousness” (Orality and Literacy, p. 78). Ong is careful to note, however, that
the shift from orality to literacy is not the only historical force that has brought about
changes in “psyche and culture.” “Developments in food production, in trade, in political
organization, in religious institutions, in technological skills, in educational practices, in
means of transportation, in family organization, and in other areas of human life all play
their own distinctive roles. But most of these developments, and indeed very likely every
one of them, have themselves been affected, often at great depth, by the shift from orality
to literacy and beyond, as many of them have in turn affected this shift” (p. 175).
94. As Abram observes, the letters of our alphabet can in fact still be traced to earlier
pictorial signs. In the early Semitic aleph-beth, for example, the first letter, Aleph, is also the
ancient Hebrew word for ox. This letter is (from our perspective) an upside-down version
of our own letter A, with two ox horns pointing upward (The Spell, p. 101).
95. Abram, The Spell, p. 254. Emphasis removed.
96. Abram, The Spell, p. 273.
97. Personal communication, November 2000.
98. See M. C, Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 256, n. 61.
99. See Kurt Danzinger, “Generative Metaphor and the History of Psychological
Discourse,” pp. 348–352. On psychology’s general adoption of the modern world’s eco-
nomic-technological character, David Leary comments that throughout the field one finds
a “cult of efficiency,” a preoccupation with productivity, a language dense with techno-
logical analogues (calling our senses, for example, “signal detection devices”), and many
other features of an engineering vision (“Psyche’s Muse,” pp. 51–52, n. 53). Currently, the
clearest example in psychology of using machine metaphors is cognitive psychology’s adop-
tion of the computer as an image to describe the human mind.
100. Paul Shepard, The Tender Carnivore and the Sacred Game, p. 231. Roughly
speaking, totemism is the practice in which a society perceives itself homologously to cer-
tain totemic beings who act as symbols for organizing the whole community.
101. Leary, “Psyche’s Muse.”
102. Marcel Detienne, quoted in Calvin Martin, In the Spirit of the Earth, p. 2.
103. Martin, In the Spirit, pp. 94, 107. Martin did not actually use the phrase “less-
than-human,” but rather “we are not now true humans.” I used “less-than-human,” how-
ever, because it indicates what becomes of us when we cleave ourselves off from what is
“more-than-human.”
104. Jeannette Armstrong, “Keepers of the Land,” p. 323. As Armstrong also notes:
“The Okanagan word for ‘our place on the land’ and ‘our language’ is the same.”
105. Kane, The Wisdom, pp. 14, 79, 166. Like Abram, Kane offers that our own
language has become domesticated, “no longer wild in the sense of resonating with the cries
of forest animals” (p. 235).
106. Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 235. See also p. 195.
107. See Eugene Gendlin, “Dwelling.” Gendlin also notes: “If words were only dis-
cursive forms [i.e., lacking in an experiential dimension], then they could not say some-
thing new, nor something that does not follow from their established patterns. Then what
words newly say has to be considered only a contradiction or a rupture” (“How Philosophy
Cannot Appeal to Experience, and How It Can,” p. 36).
108. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, pp. 135, 137.
109. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, p. 267. Merleau-Ponty noted to himself that his
philosophy “must be presented without any compromise with humanism, nor naturalism
[natural science], nor finally with theology” (p. 274). In other words, he was convinced
that philosophy could not proceed so long as it retained the traditional cleavages among
humans, nature, and God. Jerry Gill, in fact, calls Merleau-Ponty’s outlook a “naturalistic
theism,” indicating the latter’s belief that God is not above the world but is the world, in the
sense of a nonthematic logos (Merleau-Ponty and Metaphor). Merleau-Ponty’s philosophy of
the flesh was presented in a limited number of places, primarily The Visible and the Invisible
(specifically, chapter four, “The Intertwining—The Chiasm,” and among his “Working
Notes”); and the article “Eye and Mind.” For a brief explication see M. C. Dillon, “Mer-
leau-Ponty and the Reversibility Thesis.”
110. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, p. 139. Thus flesh denotes the commingling or
intertwining of subjective and objective reality, for example, I experience my body’s inten-
tionality, I aim at the world with my hands and feet, yet only because I can see these parts
of my body as objects am I able coordinate my subjective actions.
111. Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, p. 153.
112. Merleau-Ponty himself said that language “is founded on the phenomenon of
the mirror . . . or the echo, . . . on the magical action of like upon like” (quoted in Dillon,
Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 206).
113. “Where are we to put the limit between the body and the world, since the world
is flesh?” (Merleau-Ponty, The Visible, p. 138; see also p. 248). Ecological thinking places
phenomena in con-text, within the larger text-ure, fabric, or weave, of life. The ultimate
“text,” then, is the flesh of the world.
114. Indeed, Merleau-Ponty also noted to himself to: “Do a psychoanalysis of nature:
it is the flesh, the mother” (The Visible, p. 267).
115. Gill, Merleau-Ponty, p. 60. Recall my discussion of the contact boundary in
chapter three. In the terms used here, we would say that our flesh faces both inward and
outward at this boundary.
116. Quoted in David Strong, Crazy Mountains, p. 155.
117. Thus did Heidegger say that “perceiving is responding (resonating)” (quoted in
Avens, “Heidegger,” p. 197). Experiential psychotherapists understand this well, for they
are always sensing into their own bodies in order to sense what might correspondingly be
going on for their clients.
118. Owen Barfield, “The Meaning of the Word ‘Literal,’” p. 56. As the Roman phi-
losopher Plotinus put it: “All knowing comes by likeness” (quoted in Hillman, Revisioning,
p. 99).
119. Merleau-Ponty, “Eye and Mind,” in The Primacy of Perception, p. 164. Emphasis
mine. “We understand the thing as we understand a new kind of behaviour, not, that is,
through any kind of intellectual operation of subsumption, but by taking up on our own
account the mode of existence which the observable signs adumbrate before us” (Phenom-
enology, p. 319; emphasis mine).
120. Shepard, “Wilderness,” in Traces, p. 221.
121. Paul Shepard, “The Ark of the Mind,” p. 59.
122. Paul Shepard, Thinking Animals, p. 191. As many have commented, we experi-
ence the world as a unified whole only because of the way that things resemble or imply one
another, and so hang together in our perception of them (see, for example, Isaiah Berlen’s
comments in David Leary, “Psyche’s Muse,” p. 29, n. 12). Trees are like flowers, flowers
are like us, and we are like stones and stars (and this sentence is like a Gary Snyder poem,
in No Nature, p. 287). Everything overlaps, mirrors, bleeds into, stretches away from, or
“metaphors,” everything else.
123. Boss, Existential, p. 76. Recall that self and world form a single unit, both being
disclosed within the same clearing of being or horizon of understanding. Thus for scientists
to experience the world as a dead place, they must actually deaden themselves—must adopt
a mood or mode of attunement that is “calm, cool, and collected.” In studying vision,
Descartes, for example, chose to take “the eye of a newly dead man” (quoted in Robert
Romanyshyn, “The Despotic Eye: An Illustration of Metabletic Phenomenology and Its
Implications,” p. 93; see also van den Berg, Things, pp. 20–21).
124. Indeed, according to a philosophy of flesh no such independence of mental
functions is even possible, for all aspects or regions of existence continuously play into or
mirror one another. What we perceive, for example, cannot be cleanly separated from how
we are moving our bodies, what emotions or desires we are feeling, what we are thinking,
or what kind of language we have acquired. All of these are intertwined aspects of a single
bodily existing.
125. Please note how this discussion ties into much of what I talked about in chapter
two concerning the impossibility of achieving an unbiased knowledge of reality. On the
necessary of projection for the making of contact see also Abram, The Spell, pp. 58, 275–
276, n. 3; and Gordon Wheeler, Gestalt Reconsidered. Quite simply, if others are so dif-
ferent from ourselves that we can’t imagine what it is like to be them or what they are
experiencing, then we can’t make any contact. This is also why psychotherapists are often
people who have been much wounded themselves, for this helps them to see, understand,
and make contact with other people’s wounds. On the imaginative component within
all experience, see Neil Bolton, “The Lived World: Imagination and the Development of
Experience.”
126. Stephen Levine, Poiesis, pp. 33, 41.
127. In the usual understanding of projection, by contrast, the idea that we misper-
ceive the wolves can only mean that there exists some correct or objective, perhaps scientifi-
cally determined, perception of wolves.
128. Barry Lopez, “Renegotiating the Contracts.” Parabola 8.2 (1983), p. 16.
129. Personal communication, August, 2000; and “Revitalizing Natural History,” p.
87.
130. George Santayana, quoted in Kenneth Burke, A Rhetoric of Motives, p. 82.
Emphasis mine. In concluding the controversial anthology, Uncommon Ground, William
Cronon writes: “Nature is a mirror onto which we project our own ideas and values; but is
also a material reality that sets limits . . . on the possibilities of human ingenuity and story-
telling. . . . The nonhuman world is real and autonomous, a place worthy of our respect and
care, but the paradox of our human lives is that we can never know that world at first hand.
Instead, we see it through the lens of our own conceptions and simulations, which never
map onto the real world in a perfect one-to-one correspondence” (p. 458). While I am in
support of recognizing both the otherness of the natural world and the role of projection in
our understanding of it, I believe that Cronon’s conception of projection is dualistic, for it
makes “the real world” inaccessible. As a plural realist I suggest, rather, that we do contact
reality, even if we can do this in better or worse ways. Reality, in short, is not some objec-
tive, material realm we distortedly perceive through our various lenses, but the meanings
we gather in our fleshy commerce with others.
131. Robert Romanyshyn, “Unconsciousness: Reflection and the Primacy of Percep-
tion,” p. 158.
132. Theodore Roszak, The Voice of the Earth, pp. 303, 320.
133. Gion Condrau and Medard Boss, “Existential Analysis,” p. 503.
134. Medard Boss, Existential, p. 261. See also Medard Boss, The Analysis of Dreams.
135. André de Koning, “Reflections on the Heart,” p. 142.
136. James Hillman, “The Animal Kingdom in the Human Dream,” p. 321.
137. James Hillman, “Animal Presence,” pp. 126–127. Elsewhere, Hillman has
pleaded that we not view dream animals as mere symbols of our instincts or dangerous
subjective forces inside us, but in “motifs of learning from the animal, amazed by its beauty,
touched by its pain, reconciliation with it, being borne, helped, saved by the animal” (“The
Animal Kingdom in the Human Dream,” p. 329). In The Dream and the Underworld,
he also notes that dream animals do not merely represent instincts because “they are not
images of animals, but images as animals” (p. 150). Medard Boss makes similar remarks in
The Analysis of Dreams (e.g., pp. 105–107), even if his theoretical framework differs in other
respects from Hillmans.
138. Erving and Miriam Polster, Gestalt Therapy Integrated, pp. 266–268. As Gen-
dlin, Jungians, and other also emphasize, it is important to establish a reciprocal relation
with dreams, to treat them lovingly and respectfully, to welcome them, pay attention to
them, thank them. In this way, the dreams themselves come to offer more to the dreamer.
139. I thus agree with the distinction made by Gary Snyder: “Animals come into
myth or dream not as projections, but as a way to speak to the human mind. In one sense,
you can say that’s a projection, but the fact is we couldn’t have animals in our dreams if
there weren’t real animals. There is some kind of information that is exchanged there”
(“Hanging Out with Raven,” p. 140).
140. Dillon, “Merleau-Ponty and Postmodernity,” p. xxiii. Emphasis mine. We are
“separated from ourselves” in that we exist only in our interactions with others; and that in
order to contact the other we must reach across a distance, finding ourselves both here in
our bodies and over there, absorbed in another who correspondingly mirrors or informs us
of who we are or what we can be. Thus it is only in being separated from myself that I may
come back to myself changed—the other creates the distance I need in order to see myself.
141. Shepard, The Others, p. 281.
142. Gary Snyder, A Place in Space, p. 187.
143. “Many features of the bear—especially the many races of the brown bear—place
it in correspondence to humanity. Its size, appearance, mobility, dexterity, omnivorousness,
reproduction, annual cycle, length of life, social behavior, and intelligence have an eerie
relation to our own. These characteristics are the source of enduring speculative analogy
and psychological tension. . . . The bear is the only familiar omnivore whose size approxi-
mates our own. . . . It has an expressive face, binocular vision, vocal and gestural responses,
sitting and bipedal stances, almost no tail, and fine dexterity. . . . And yet the bear is vividly
other—huge, furry, long-muzzled, long clawed, quadrupedal—in these things nothing like
a man” (Shepard, “The Ark,” p. 58).
144. Shepard and Sanders, The Sacred, p. 59. Gary Snyder also includes a version of
this story in The Practice of the Wild.
145. Paul Shepard, “The Unreturning Arrow,” p. 211. Emphasis removed. Although
I have not pursued it here, this idea suggests an affinity between the notions of flesh and
that of the life force. Anita Barrows has, in this vein, called for a type of developmental
psychology that would emphasize “the wordless stratum of the child’s being, which is . . . a
life-force made manifest, a porous, permeable, sensitive essence intertwined with all other
such essences, affecting and affected by them with its every breath” (“The Ecopsychology
of Child Development,” p. 110).
146. Shepard, The Sacred, p. 72. By “species” I mean to suggest more than just the
plant and animal world.
147. Shepard, Thinking, p. 72. See, also, “Phyto-resonance of the True Self,” in Traces
of an Omnivore.
148. Harold Searles, quoted in Shepard, Nature, p. 14.
149. For a “wheel” teaching which combines Native American and old European
sources, and which is intended as a contribution to the ecopsychology literature, see Steven
Foster, with Meredith Little, The Four Shields.
150. Joseph Epes Brown, “The Bison and the Moth: Lakota Correspondences,”
p. 13.
151. Paul Shepard, “Nature and Madness,” p. 39.
152. Shepard, Nature, p. 128.
153. Paul Shepard, “On Animal Friends,” p. 279.
154. Shepard, Coming Home, p. 5.
155. Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology, pp. 184–185. The following sentence also bor-
rows from Merleau-Ponty.
156. See Searles’s remarks from chapter one. Anita Barrows recently noted that “from
the earliest moments of life the infant has an awareness not only of human touch, but of the
touch of the breeze on her skin, variations in light and color, temperature, texture, sound.
No one who has spent time watching an infant could fail to notice this; yet the theorists on
whose work our current understanding (and therapies) have been based fail to account for
its importance—indeed, even for its presence” (“The Ecopsychology,” p. 103).
157. Gene Myers, Children and Animals, p. 143. This is the same point made above
by Searles. Shepard also writes: “We do not graduate from animality but . . . into and
through it” (Thinking, p. 3).
158. Cobb, “The Ecology,” p. 131.
159. Wang Jiazhu, quoted in “The Three Gorges: The Case for Development,”
p. 51.
160. A point made by Wolfgang Sachs: “Through the trick of a biological metaphor,
a simple economic activity turns into a natural and evolutionary process, as though hidden
qualities would be progressively developed to their final state. The metaphor thus says that
the real destiny of natural goods is to be found in their economic utilization” (quoted in
Livingston, Rogue, p. 61).
161. One of Shepard’s central arguments, in fact, is that Western history has the
character of a “continuing dedevelopment” (my emphasis). He speculates, that is, that “the
history of Western man has been a progressive peeling back of the psyche,” with “mutila-
tions of personal maturity” being “the vehicle of cultural progress and environmental deci-
mation” (Nature, p. 16). It is not insignificant, then, when Maria Mies reports of male sex
tourists found in Thailand who “demand that the . . . [prostitute] bath and feed them like
a baby, and oil and powder their buttocks” (Maria Mies and Vandana Shiva, Ecofeminism,
p. 136).
162. In his The Human Cycle, Colin Turnbull contrasts his own experiences through
the various stages of the life cycle to those of the different peoples he has studied around
the world as an anthropologist. It was a very moving read for me, and certainly comple-
ments well the discussion here. Needless to say, virtually all of Paul Shepard’s writings may
be sought out for further treatment of the present topic.
163. In his article “The Child’s Relations with Others” (in The Primacy of Perception),
Merleau-Ponty argued, however, that our usual Cartesian view of persons—as self-con-
tained, solitary, rational, and externally related individuals—makes this kind of infantile
experiencing a logical impossibility. Descartes began with the experience of dualistically
split, isolated, intellectual adults, whereas infants exist in an original being-together with
the world and only gradually come to differentiate and enter into relations with others. As
Paul Nonnekes puts it, the infant is involved in “a pulsation of growth that is neither an
inside nor an outside, but an intertwining” (“The Intertwining Wildness of Flesh-Child
Becoming,” p. 20). For a good discussion of how developmental theorists often start not
with the child but with the rational adult word, which is then used as a yardstick against
which “the child is judged to be more or less competent,” see Chris Jenks, “Introduction:
Constituting the Child.” Jenks says that much developmental “theory moves to envelop the
child within its own projections,” such that the child is “abandoned in theory,” or “reim-
ported as an afterthought.” See, also, David Levin, The Listening Self (pp. 150–166) for a
general discussion of mirroring and infancy.
164. The rise and fall of the speech of parents, for example, has been observed to
correspond to rises and falls in the trunk movements and gesturings of their infants. At
times the boundaries between caregiver and infant may become indefinite, where there
exists only an “interpresenced participation in the flesh” (Nonnekes, “The Intertwining,”
p. 22), a blurring of identities in a nondual and synergistic feeling space. See Zachariah
Boukydis, “A Theory of Empathic Relations Between Parents and Infants: Insight from a
Client-Centred/Experiential Perspective.”
165. As discussed, for instance, in Levin, The Listening, p. 152.
166. Dillon, Merleau-Ponty’s, p. 167.
188. Paul Shepard, “Place in American Culture,” p. 32. Emphasis mine. Shepard
believed that: “every child under ten has three ecological needs: architecturally complex
play space shared with companions; a cumulative and increasingly diverse experience of
non-human forms, animate and inanimate, whose taxonomic names and generic relations
he must learn; and occasional and progressively more strenuous exertions into the wild
world where he may, in a limited way, confront the nonhuman” (The Tender, p. 267).
189. Perls et al, Gestalt, p. 270.
190. Myers, Children, pp. 15, 64. Emphasis mine.
191. Shepard, Thinking, p. 59.
192. Myers, Children, p. 5.
193. Myers, Children, p. 16.
194. Myers, Children, pp. 41–42. This again shows a split between the symbolic and
experiential in our society.
195. Myers, Children, p. 170. Myers suggests, in fact, that the child who is “provided
with a human social environment but deprived of nonhuman others,” will be unable to
develop “her or his full humanity.”
196. Jenks writes that for Piaget play “is merely diverting fun or fantasy, it deflects
the child from his true logical purpose within the system of rationality; the criteria of
play need not equate with the rigorous factual demands of reality” (“Introduction,” p.
22). Compare these remarks to those of a Gestaltist, Laura Perls: “A small child, before
becoming socialized, lives on the [contact] boundary: looks at everything, touches every-
thing, gets into everything. He discovers the world, expands his awareness and means of
coping at his own pace: playfully serious or seriously playing, he makes an ongoing creative
adjustment to his own potential” (“Comments on the New Directions,” p. 223; emphasis
mine). On the significance of play in childhood, see also David Levin, The Body’s Recollec-
tion of Being, p. 238–240.
197. Eaton et al., The Paleolithic, pp. 211–212. I have spliced some words into this
quote from elsewhere on the same page.
198. As is thoroughly discussed in Turnbull, The Human; and Shepard, Coming,
p. 59.
199. Martin, In the Spirit, p. 9.
200. Myers, Children, p. 141.
201. Shepard, The Others, p. 282.
202. Shepard, Thinking, p. 121.
203. Myers, Children, p. 10. Emphasis mine. Adding another dimension to this,
Shepard notes: “Fantasies of animals wearing clothes and building houses, what may seem
a too-close similarity between them and [children], creates an excess of common ground,
stored for late adolescence when disjunction almost swamps the ego” (The Others, p. 88).
204. Shepard, The Others, p. 83. Myers mentions a child (Billy) who after a turtle
was introduced to his classroom imagines that he is himself in the water and that a shark
is nearby. Playing the turtle, he pulls his arms in tight to his sides, and only when the
coast is clear extends them back out. “For Billy, the turtle symbolizes not only safety and
coherence but the whole affective experience of surviving an imagined life-threatening situ-
ation. Notably, Billy’s symbolization took the embodied form first of a tightly closed-off
protective posture and them of an expansive, mobile, and agentic one—conveying quali-
ties that would be hard to represent verbally” (Children, p. 57). Qualities such as agency
(animals have their own purposes, confirming the child’s own); coherence (animals are not
contradictory or ambiguous, as are adults; they do not lie, they are whole); affectivity (all
animals convey feelings in their voices, motions, and manner); and continuity (the child
experiences the continuity of her or his own self through the maintenance of her relations
with animal others) are thereby made available to the child in her or his interaction with
animals.
205. Shepard, “The Ark,” p. 55.
206. Myers, Children, p. 171.
207. Stephen Trimble in Nabhan and Trimble, The Geography, pp. 170–171.
208. Turnbull, The Human, p. 81. “The consequences of our folly are to be seen all
around us in the violence, neurosis, and loneliness of our youth, our adults, and our aged,
some of whom never even approach the fullness and richness of life that could have been
theirs had their adolescence been handled with more wisdom, understanding, and gentle
respect.”
209. Peter Breggin writes: “Adolescence, with its struggle to form identity in the
face of unleashed passions, easily gets called ‘mental illness.’ Whether adolescents become
mentally ill often depends mostly on the love, patience, and tolerance of the adults who
surround them” (Toxic Psychiatry, p. 33). Whereas critics like Breggin trace the onset of
schizophrenia and other “mental illnesses” among adolescents to the acute psychospiritual
and social demands of this stage of life, the biopsychiatric establishment generally does not
make such a link, sticking to its biochemical and genetic explanations. See, also, Medard
Boss, Existential, pp. 235–236.
210. Turnbull, The Human, p. 122.
211. Erik Erikson, Identity: Youth and Crisis, p. 258. Emphasis mine. Adolescence,
says Erikson, is a time for, “the mutual confirmation of individual and community, in
the sense that society recognizes the young individual as a bearer of fresh energy and that
the individual so confirmed recognizes society as a living process which inspires loyalty
as it receives it, maintains allegiance as it attracts it, honors confidence as it demands it”
(p. 241).
212. Erik Erikson, Identity and the Life Cycle, p. 95.
213. Carleton Coon, The Hunting Peoples, p. 392.
214. Erikson, Identity and the Life, p. 97.
215. Says Erikson: the adolescent “would rather act shamelessly in the eyes of his
elders, out of free choice, than be forced into activities which would be shameful in his own
eyes or in those of his peers” (Identity: Youth, p. 130).
216. Erikson, Identity: Youth, p. 254.
217. “Sexual and spiritual awareness as modes of experience are just as valid as phys-
ical and intellectual awareness; and like those other modes of apprehension they can be
turned in any direction, inward or outward, restricted to the individual self or encour-
aged to expand and encompass the infinitely greater social self ’ (Turnbull, The Human,
pp. 122–123).
218. M. C. Dillon, “Toward a Phenomenology of Love and Sexuality: An Inquiry
into the Limits of the Humans Situation as They Condition Loving,” p. 344.
219. Turnbull, The Human, p. 82.
220. Eaton et al., The Paleolithic, p. 215. “For the growing child among the !Kung,
as opposed to among ourselves,” for example, “sex becomes less taboo, less frightening, and
less unknown” (p. 221). Mbuti children also spend much time in imitation of “how the
wide diversity of territorial, kinship, age, and sex roles are played” (Turnbull, The Human,
p. 45).
221. Mircea Eliade, Rites and Symbols of Initiation: The Mysteries of Birth and Rebirth,
pp. 1, 39.
222. Among tribal societies males and females generally undergo different forms of
initiation. Both involve a period of severance or isolation from the community and a cer-
emonial return. The female rites, however, tend to center on initiation into the sacrality of
womanhood, or of the female mode of being, and generally follow the first menstruation.
Male rites are generally more elaborate, involving various trials or ordeals, and focusing
on mythology, cosmology, and the like. Among those who are today reviving initiatory
practices in our own society, the female/male distinction is often maintained, although rites
such as vision quests are being offered to both males and females, without distinction. For
a broad treatment, see Louise Mahdi et al., ed., Betwixt and Between: Patterns of Masculine
and Feminine Initiation.
223. See Toni Nelson, “Violence Against Women.”
224. See David Gilmore, Manhood in the Making. Gilmore is careful to point out
that these violent rituals do have a social function. If, for example, a society requires for
its continuance that men take great risks in hunting and warfare, then it makes a sort of
sense to convert boys into “fearless” men through painful initiation tests. Be that as it
may, the need in our own society to question traditional ideals of masculinity—a need
first brought home by the women’s movement—puts any violent form of male initia-
tion into question. Rituals and socialization processes that shame males into disowning
essential aspects of their humanity—including their vulnerable emotions and relational
needs—are not only violent to men, but contribute to the creation of men who are then
violent with women.
225. Geertz, The Interpretation, p. 125.
226. Shepard, Nature, p. 66.
227. Eliade, Rites, p. 130.
228. Thus when initiatory rites declined in the middle ages they were replaced by
literature containing initiatory motifs, as in the heroic tales of Arthur or Percival. Fairy
tales were later to dramatically express initiatory scenarios that “answers a deep need in the
human being.” In our own time, finally, best sellers continue to be full of mythological
figures.
229. In addition to Eliade’s work, see: Mahdi et al., ed., Betwixt; the works of Stephen
Foster and Meredith Little; Joseph Epes Brown, ed., The Sacred Pipe: Black Elk’s Account of
the Seven Rites of the Oglala Sioux; Victor Turner, The Ritual Process; Arnold van Gennep,
The Rites of Passage; and James Wright, The Bones of Metamorphosis. The classic account of
attaining a vision for one’s people is told in John Neihardt’s Black Elk Speaks.
230. Shepard, Nature, p. 10.
231. Shepard, Coming, p. 44.
232. Thus for Shepard, “the frame-work of nature as metaphorical foundation for
cosmic-at-homeness is as native to the human organism in its adolescent years as any nutri-
tive element in the diet” (Nature, p. 71).
233. Shepard, “Place,” p. 90.
234. Shepard, The Others, p. 89.
235. Erikson, Childhood, p. 269.
236. Michael Meade, Men and the Waters of Life, p. 19.
237. Mahdi et al., ed., Betwixt, p. xi. In introducing Arnold van Gennep’s The
Rites of Passage, Solon Kimball writes that the “situation in psychology is a very curious
one. Except in psychoanalysis, there is no indication of knowledge of or interest in rites
of passage, or in events of this type, in the individual’s life. . . . The critical problems
of becoming male or female, of relations within the family, and of passing into old age
are directly related to the devices which the society offers the individual to help him
achieve the new adjustment. Somehow we seem to have forgotten this. . . . It seems . . .
likely that one dimension of mental illness may arise because an increasing number of
individuals are forced to accomplish their transitions alone and with private symbols”
(pp. xiv, xviii).
238. Meade, “Foreword,” to Eliade, Rites, p. xx.
239. Meade, “Foreword,” p. xxi.
240. Shepard, Coming, p. 46.
241. Leidloff, The Continuum, p. 149.
242. Friedrich Nietzsche, quoted in Norman O. Brown, Life Against Death, p. 107.
Chapter Six
7. Fredric Jameson notes, in this regard, that the capitalist mode of production
has engendered three stages of revolution in technology: steam-driven motors; electric and
combustion motors; and electronic and nuclear-powered apparatuses. These revolutions
correspond to three “fundamental movements in capitalism, each one marking a dialectical
expansion over the previous stage”: market capitalism, monopoly capitalism, and multina-
tional capitalism (“Postmodernism, or The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism,” p. 78). See,
also, Andrew Freenberg’s “The Critical Theory of Technology,” in which he argues that
capitalism is in itself a technical system; that technology has an essentially social character.
8. I draw heavily on Noble in what follows, both because he provides a compre-
hensive narrative and because he uses some recent scholarship which revises the usual view
of Luddites as irrational opponents of technology.
9. Noble, Progress, p. 139.
10. Francis Bacon, quoted in William Leiss, The Limits of Satisfaction, p. 37.
11. Noble, Progress, p. 12. Noble is himself drawing here on Geoffrey Bernstein.
12. Noble, Progress, p. 142. See, also, Nobles The Religion of Technology.
13. Sigmund Freud, Civilization and Its Discontents, p. 24.
14. Sigmund Freud, “The Future of an Illusion,” p. 194.
15. Freud, Civilization, p. 33. Next quote, p, 24.
16. Freud, “The Future,” p. 185. Civilization “presupposes precisely the non-satis-
faction . . . of powerful instincts” (Freud, Civilization, p. 44).
17. Freud, “The Future,” p. 194.
18. Freud, Civilization, pp. 30, 81.
19. Max Horkheimer, Eclipse of Reason, pp. 94 and 162. See also Herbert Mar-
cuse, Counterrevolution and Revolt, chapter two. On the use of the notion of the revolt of
nature by the early critical theorists in general, see Robyn Eckersley, “The Failed Promise
of Critical Theory”; and Henry Blanke, “Domination and Utopia: Marcuse’s Discourse on
Nature, Psyche, and Culture.”
20. Although Horkheimer was originally referring only to the revolt of human
nature, William Leiss writes: “If it is the case that the natural environment cannot tol-
erate the present level of irrational technological applications without suffering breakdowns
in the mechanisms that govern its cycles of self-renewal, then we would be justified in
speaking of a revolt of external nature which accompanies the rebellion of human nature”
(The Domination of Nature, p. 164).
21. Paul Shepard, The Others, p. 265.
22. Leiss, The Domination, p. 194.
23. Horkheimer, The Eclipse, p. 94.
24. Stanley Diamond, In Search of the Primitive, p. 44.
25. Peter Breggin, Toxic Psychiatry, p. 275.
26. See Brian Tokar, Earth for Sale; and Tom Athanasiou, Divided Planet, p. 242.
As an example of the power of public relations, Athanasiou notes: “When a scandal-ridden
company called Nuclear Engineering, Inc. changes its name to U.S. Ecology, wins the
contract to build a hotly contested radioactive waste dump, and distributes slick brochures
explaining the dump’s displacement of a threatened desert tortoise as ‘A New Home for
Endangered Friends,’ it is obviously the logic of appearances that sets the terms” of our age
(p. 232).
27. Joel Kovel, “The Justifiers,” p. 1.
28. This term comes from the theoretical work of the Re-evaluation Counselling
Communities. See their booklet “What’s Wrong with the ‘Mental Health’ System: And
What Can Be Done About It.”
29. Brown, Life, p. 15. See Freud, Civilization, p. 80.
30. Joel Kovel, The Age of Desire, p. 174. A “line of self-alienation must be drawn,
above which is ‘normal capitalist restlessness’ and below which is neurosis and frank psy-
chosis. The mental-health professionals have been stationed to patrol this boundary no less
than their brethren police exist to hold the line against objective criminality” (p. 122).
31. Hence, the repression of the revolt of nature is enforced by our fear of social
censure, of being unloved, of facing the void. Our existential insecurity, in other words,
keeps us from questioning our own violation.
32. See Phyllis Bronstein, “Promoting Healthy Emotional Development in Chil-
dren.” As Bronstein notes, some psychologists even support this rule, claiming that mature
people have learned to inhibit their strong emotions. My next sentence draws from the
work of N. Henley, cited by Bronstein.
33. It is not uncommon even for psychotherapists to be afraid of emotional
catharsis. In this case, they are unable to discern those instances when a catharsis is in
fact a movement toward healing (see “What’s Wrong”). In The Stormy Search for the Self,
Christina and Stan Grof discuss how a great deal of spiritual experience is also diagnosed as
“mental illness.”
34. Rogers, Solving, p. 86.
35. As Peter Breggin observes: “After passionate people get psychiatrically labeled,
they become especially vulnerable to defeat and disaster. Psychiatrists commonly force
treatment on them, then claim that they must be ‘mentally ill,’ because they resent and
resist being diagnosed and treated” (Toxic Psychiatry, pp. 33–34).
36. Noble, Progress, p. 21.
37. Joel Kovel does not mince his words on this point: “a colossal burden of neu-
rotic misery in the population . . . continually and palpably betrays the capitalist ideology,
which maintains that commodity civilization promotes human happiness” (“Therapy in
Late Capitalism,” in The Radical Spirit, p. 136).
38. Jules Henry, quoted in David Levin, “Clinical Stories: A Modern Self in the
Fury of Being,” p. 480.
39. See Rogers, Solving, p. 20.
40. This has much in common, for example, with earlier leftist strategies for raising
class consciousness. In his Marxist days, for instance, the psychoanalyst Wilhelm Reich
argued that to awaken this consciousness “we must begin with the assumption that no
social order that requires the frustration of instinct can lead to human happiness. There-
fore, a fundamental dissatisfaction will always be present, at least in latent form. Radical
politics must kindle this latent dissatisfaction into revolutionary class consciousness. . . .
Only people fully in touch with their own needs and interests can be counted on to resist
both capitalist exploitation and communist domination” (the words are Roger Gottlieb’s,
in Marxism, pp. 126–127). Whether the kind of strategy I and others propose has an
advantages over Reich’s, or any greater likelihood of success, remains to be seen.
41. Jameson, “Postmodernism,” p. 77.
42. Jameson writes: “distance in general (including ‘critical distance’ in particular)
has very precisely been abolished in the new space of postmodernism. . . . the prodigious
new expansion of multilateral capital ends up penetrating and colonizing those very pre-
capitalist enclaves (Nature and the Unconscious) which offered extraterritorial and Archi-
median footholds for critical effectivity. . . . we all, in one way or another, dimly feel that
not only punctual and local countercultural forms of cultural resistance and guerrilla war-
fare, but also even overtly political interventions like those of The Clash, are all somehow
secretly disarmed and reabsorbed by a system of which they themselves might well be
considered a part, since they can achieve no distance form it” (“Postmodernism,” p. 87).
On the difficulties of being caught, as a member of our society, within the very meanings
we oppose, see also Charles Taylor, “Interpretation and the Sciences of Man,” p. 72.
43. Robert Bourassa, quoted in Carol Bigwood, Earth Muse, p. 224.
44. Martin Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, p. 50.
45. Martin Heidegger, “The Question Concerning Technology,” in The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, p. 14.
46. Bill McKibben, The End of Nature, p. 165. “Eventually, all plants might’
become unnecessary,’ replaced by artificial leaves that would ‘waste’ none of the sunlight
they receive on luxuries such as roots but instead use ‘all the energy they trap to make things
for us to use.’.”
47. Paul Shepard, Nature and Madness, p. 38.
48. Carol Bigwood, Earth Muse, pp. 149, 170. Emphasis mine.
49. Hence, “nature takes orders from man and works under his authority” (quoted
in Carolyn Merchant, The Death of Nature, p. 171).
50. Martin Heidegger, “The Word of Nietzsche: ‘God Is Dead,’” in The Question
Concerning Technology and Other Essays, p. 100.
51. See George Steiner, Heidegger, p. 132.
52. Martin Heidegger, quoted in Bruce Foltz, “On Heidegger and the Interpreta-
tion of the Ecological Crisis,” p. 334.
53. Noble, Progress, p. 4.
54. The commodity is what the device provides, what function it serves, what it is
there for, or what gets consumed. Thus television sets provide news and entertainment, cars
provide transportation, and so on.
55. Albert Borgmann, Technology and the Character of Contemporary Life, p. 192.
56. Albert Borgmann, Crossing the Postmodern Divide, p. 137.
57. This is an example used by Borgmann, but which I am presenting in my
own way.
75. I don’t know of anybody who argues for an outright elimination of market
exchanges.
76. Borgmann, Technology, p. 51. See, also, Strong, Crazy, p. 94.
77. Alan Durning, “Are We Happy Yet?,” p. 69.
78. Kovel, The Age, p. 82. Kovel also notes how in a capitalist society the “child
loses her/his functionality in the household and becomes a pure consumer. . . . With this
the child-mind in everyone becomes celebrated, as indeed it should be by the managers of
society, who are clever enough to sense in the infantile mental organization a possible way
out of the crisis instigated by the glut of commodities” (pp. 121–122).
79. Kovel, The Age, pp. 58–59.
80. Leiss, “The Imperialism.” p. 31.
81. Leiss, “The Imperialism.” p. 32.
82. As David Loy remarks, our economic system “feeds on and is fed by a sense of
lack” (“Trying to Become Real: A Buddhist Critique of Some Secular Heresies,” p. 419.
Kovel also observes: “For the purposes of advanced capital . . . it is increasingly imperative
that the commodity lead not to satiety but to restless reconsumption” (The Age, p. 82).
83. Joel Kovel, “On the Ontology of Capital,” from The Enemy of Nature, p. 4 of
my version. As Kovel adds: “Ego and capital grow together.”
84. Loy, “Trying,” p. 408. This is, of course, something the media themselves under-
stand very well. The quest for media fame was personified by the actor Nicole Kidman in
the movie To Die For.
85. This is certainly not to rule out the possibility of love, per se. It is rather to
identify a form of obsessive and fantasy-based love, originating in eleventh-century Europe,
which is “effectively a religious experience, in which the deity worshipped is the beloved.
Hence, to lose one’s love is to lose one’s life; is to lose the entire world” (Morris Berman,
Coming to Our Senses, p. 207).
86. Loy, “Trying,” p. 420.
87. Diamond, In Search, p. 40.
88. Loy, “Trying,” p. 421.
89. This view is exhaustively presented in Jules Henry’s classic Culture Against Man.
90. Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, The Dialectic of Enlightenment, p. 147.
Sigmund Kvaløy similarly speaks of the “Disney Land effect,” in reference to cultural diver-
sions that bear not at all on the central or pressing issues of life (“Ecophilosophy and Eco-
politics: Thinking and Acting in Response to the Threats of Ecocatastrophe,” p. 19).
91. Kovel, The Age, p. 184.
92. Horkheimer and Adorno, The Dialectic, p. 167.
93. Borgmann, Technology, pp. 52, 130.
94. Borgmann, Technology, p. 55.
95. Jean Liedloff, The Continuum Concept, p. 113. Liedloff traces our deprivation
most forcefully to a relative poverty of physically close, “in-arms” contact in infancy.
96. Borgmann, Technology, p. 142.
97. Using 1990 data, Jerry Mander says that “the main activity of life for Ameri-
cans, aside from work or sleep, has become watching television” (In the Absence, p. 76). A
research project conducted in 1985 found that: “Eighty percent of leisure is passive con-
sumption; being passive, it is essentially solitary. Television comprises sixty percent of it”
(Borgmann, Crossing, p. 44). I don’t know how accurate these numbers are for today, but
the statistics don’t ultimately matter for the points I am making. See, also Mander’s Four
Arguments for the Elimination of Television.
98. Fredric Jameson, “Postmodernism, or The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism,”
p. 79. Indeed, despite the great amount of time spent in front of the television, it appar-
ently brings little satisfaction to its viewers. In reference to a study performed on leisure,
Borgmann notes: “It appears that people enjoy least what they indulge in most. Generally
they find activities without personal interaction unsatisfying. And television in particular
is thought to have little intrinsic benefit. . . . Commodious privacy [such as TV watching]
remains both strong and unloved” (Crossing, p. 45). See, also, David Strong’s discussion in
Crazy, pp. 87–91.
99. Berry, The Unsettling, p. 130.
100. Thus does the “protective capsule . . . becomes a household of the living dead”
(Berry, The Unsettling, p. 119).
101. Martin Lewis, quoted in Raymond Rogers, Nature and the Crisis of Modernity,
p. 145, 151, 156. Emphasis in first quote mine.
102. Richard Nelson writes, in this respect, that the main source of satisfaction
among Koyukon Indians lies in their “providing a livelihood from nature.” The pleasure
of living close to wild nature is, in fact, “probably the most pervasive theme in their exist-
ence.” A decoupled human being, then, would not even have the possibility of saying, as
did old Chief Henry: “I have had a good life. I have camped many times beneath spruce
trees, roasting grouse over my campfire. So there is no reason to pray that I might live on
much longer” (Make Prayers to the Raven, p. 46).
103. Paul Shepard, “On Animal Friends,” p. 294.
104. An argument made by John Livingston in The Fallacy of Wildlife Conservation
(pp. 92–94); and Sigmund Kavaløy, in “Ecophilosophy and Ecopolitics: Thinking and
Acting in Response to the Threats of Ecocatastrophe.”
105. On this Mary Midgley writes: “The impression of desertion or abandonment
which Existentialists have is due, I am sure, not to the removal of God, but to [the] con-
temptuous dismissal of almost the whole biosphere—plants, animals, and children. Life
shrinks to a few urban rooms; no wonder it becomes absurd” (Beast and Man, p. 18).
106. E. O. Wilson, Biophilia, p. 118.
107. As discussed in Gary Paul Nabhan and Sara St. Antoine, “The Loss of Floral
and Faunal Story: The Extinction of Experience.” “Any conditions which reduce such inti-
mate experience, Pyle claims, creates a cycle of disaffection, apathy, and irresponsibility
toward natural habitats” (p. 239).
108. Paul Shepard, Thinking Animals, p. 251–252. Following Shepard, I suggest that
it is cause for grave concern when a survey reports that 50 percent of “high school students
polled said that they would prefer to be taught by a machine, and gave as their reason that
they wished to be left alone” (cited in Morris Berman, “The Cybernetic Dream of the
Twenty-First Century,” p. 35). Human social relations, it seems, are becoming too much of
a burden. It doesn’t help either when the author of a book called How to Teach Your Child
to Be Gifted, Charles Ling, claims that “Computers are smarter than humans and they are
the best tutors at home. . . . If kids can start working on them, they can soon form those
thinking patterns like a computer” (quoted in Nicholas Keung, “Can you actually make
your child smarter?,” p. BE3).
109. Terrence Real, I Don’t Want to Talk About It, p. 107.
110. William Irwin Thompson. Interview, “Mind Jazz,” p. 14.
111. Shepard, Nature, p. 129.
112. John Livingston, The Fallacy of Wildlife Conservation, p. 94.
113. This is the phrase used by Jason Lanier, the very person who coined the term
“virtual reality” (quoted in Noble, The Religion, p. 158).
114. See the discussion in Mander, In the Absence, pp. 150–152.
115. Borgmann, “Artificial,” pp. 195–197.
116. Witness a remark made by Thompson: “I don’t feel threatened by technology
because I know being a city kid, most of my mystical experiences in my life have come
from things like watching Fantasia, when I was five, listening to Tchaikovsky on the radio
when I was seven” (“Mind,” p. 13). If all that matters is having mystical experiences for
ourselves (by which it is not clear what Thompson means), then what of our relationships
and responsibilities to others, including wild, nonhuman others?
117. Frederick Perls et al., Gestalt Therapy, p. 231. Emphasis mine.
118. Plural realism, recall, opposes any wholesale relativizing of reality. If I were to
adopt a purely relativistic position, the argument I am making here would fall apart.
119. It was in this vein that Harold Searles wrote that a “fruitful effect of the mature
human being’s sense of relatedness with his nonhuman environment . . . is the enhance-
ment, the sharpening, the deepening, the strengthening, of the individual’s experiencing his
own existence, and the existence of the world around him, as being real’ (The Nonhuman
Environment, p. 135.) Stanley Diamond also writes that the primitive’s direct “engage-
ment with nature and natural physiological functions” engenders a “sense of reality [that]
is heightened to the point where it sometimes seems to ‘Blaze’” (In Search of the Primitive,
p. 170). The weakest reality or poorest contact, conversely, is what we have in mind when
we speak of being in a derealized condition, wherein we feel cut off from a world whose
immediate presence is only vaguely felt. I think of the example of a person who is driving
at high speed toward a wall, but who experiences the situation flatly or unemotionally. She
or he sees the oncoming wall, but does not sense the immediacy of the danger.
120. Michael Zimmerman, Contesting Earth’s Future, p. 371.
121. Charles Taylor, “Interpretation and the Sciences of Man,” p. 73.
122. Borgmann, Technology, p. 208.
123. See “Part Three, The Reform of Technology,” in Borgmann, Technology; as well
as the growing literature on radical/alternative technology.
124. Noble, Progress, pp. 72, 112. This is a theme given much concrete detail by
Noble.
125. Martin Heidegger, Discourse on Thinking, p. 54.
126. A point repeatedly made by Shepard.
127. Rodman, “The Liberation,” p. 113.
128. Joseph Campbell, Creative Mythology, p. 6. For the sake of readability I have
deleted Campbell’s alphabetized “enumeration” of these four cosmic realms, while leaving
out the usual ellipses.
129. Loy, “Trying,” p. 419. Economic/technological progress is not, however, the
only myth we could name. I discuss below, for example, a myth that Richard Slotkin has
called “regeneration through violence.”
130. Robert Bringhurst, “Myths Create a World of Meaning,” p. C1.
131. According to Heidegger, it is only the great, epoch-making thinkers and poets
who are capable of revealing those new cultural understandings that change the course of
history. Gendlin has criticized this view by saying that Heidegger did not understand how
every person’s experiencing implicitly exceeds or speaks back to her or his culture. Heidegger
was thus unable to “further examine the role of individual humans in the coming of new
history” (“Thinking Beyond Patterns,” p. 32). As I discuss below, then, this is a process in
which I believe that all people can be actively engaged. On the possibility of singing new
myths, see the Epilogue to Sean Kane, Wisdom of the Mythtellers.
132. William Irwin Thompson, quoted in Coates, “Future,” p. 75.
133. Russell Jacoby, Social Amnesia, p. 64. Jacoby uses his own flood image: “Today
the process of reification is a storm tide; and the human subject is locked in the basement.
The frantic search for authenticity, experience, emotions, is the pounding on the ceiling as
the water rises” (p. 18).
134. Robyn Eckersley, “The Failed Promise of Critical theory,” p. 71. Today, Noble
likewise laments the fortunes of “an ever-weaker labour movement” (Progress, p. 47).
135. James Masterson, The Search for the Real Self, p. vii.
136. Although “focal practice” is Borgmann’s term, I should note that I am not fol-
lowing him in all respects; I am concentrating on the “focusing” effect of such practice.
137. Gary Snyder, “Buddhism and the Coming Revolution,” in Earth Household, p. 91.
138. Borgmann, Technology, p. 245.
139. I am taking cues here from Borgmann, Technology, p. 214.
140. Paul Shepard, Coming Home to the Pleistocene, p. 173.
141. Richard Nelson. “Exploring the Near at Hand,” p. 41.
142. I have moved out of Toronto since writing these words, but decided to leave
them in the present tense.
143. Hans Peter Duerr, Dreamtime, p. 92. Thus any genuine wildlife conservation
practice will protect natural entities not just in their biodiversity (or whatever), but in their
being.
144. Personal communication. The quote in the previous sentence is from David
Abram, “To Speak as a (Human) Animal: A Reply to Ted Toadvine.”
145. Ursula LeGuin, Buffalo Gals; And Other Animal Presences, p. 12. “Coming into
Animal Presence” is a poem by Denise Levertov (p. 13).
146. See, for example, Cisco Lassiter, “Relocation and Illness: The Plight of the
Navajo.”
147. This is the title of a recent book by Joanna Macy and Molly Young Brown,
which updates Macy s earlier work, Despair and Personal Power in the Nuclear Age. I chose
it for the heading here because it fits my own theme, as well as to acknowledge the kind of
work that Macy and others are doing.
148. Dorothy Dinnerstein, “Survival on Earth: The Meaning of Feminism,” p. 198.
149. Lasch, The Minimal, p. 16.
150. Jacoby, Social, p. 101.
151. Jacoby, Social, p. 116. “Society ineluctably coerces everyone to attend to the
remaining fragments of self and subjectivity” (p. 15).
152. Issac Prilleltensky, The Morals and Politics of Psychology, p. 82.
153. Christopher Lasch, The Culture of Narcissism, p. 29.
154. Lasch, The Culture, p. 64.
155. Another factor here is that within the pattern of technology we become less and
less engaged in general. Political engagement dwindles, in particular, as the governmental
and corporate machinery takes over. See Borgmann, Technology, pp. 107–109.
156. This point has been made by people ranging from one of the earliest revision-
ists of Marx’s ideas, Rosa Luxemburg; through the critical theorists; and on to one of my
own favorite authors, Joel Kovel (see the last chapter of The Age of Desire). The same idea
underlies critical education, all sorts of consciousness-raising, and so on. The Buddhist Ken
Jones puts the matter very strongly: “Buddhism implies that unless there is some significant
personal and individual change in the way we feel and think about ourselves and about
others we shall try to go on evolving societies which express and reinforce the futile struggle
of each of us to escape from our root fear into varieties of acquisitiveness and aggressive
belongingness identity” (The Social Face of Buddhism, p. 123).
157. I thus disagree with Murray Bookchin when he remarks that “nearly all ecolog-
ical problems are social problems” (Remaking Society, p. 24). For I believe he is committing
the reductive fallacy of “sociologism,” in which psyche is not abstracted from society, but
society from psyche.
158. Roger Gottlieb, Marxism, p. 78. “The task of the genuine revolutionary is there-
fore to help generate capacities for self-organization and self-expression on the part of the
mass of people in society, to foster many independent self-acting, self-conscious centers of
power and awareness” (103). The discussion which follows also draws on Gottlieb.
159. Paul Goodman, Nature Heals, p. xxii. By a “natural society” I believe Goodman
meant one that attends to human nature and experience. Goodman considered himself
a “sociotherapist,” that is, he applied the principles of Gestalt therapy on a social level so
as “to remedy institutions that hinder experience from occurring.” Much of Goodman’s
work in education, for example, argued against curricula that did not meet student ‘“need,
desire, curiosity, or [imagination].’ All else was parroting and conditioning, either promptly
forgotten after the examination, or worse, introjected as part of self-control and conforming
to authority.” Insofar as students were interested and excited and growing, the curriculum
was a good one. Thus Goodman did not believe in manifestos or received truths, but in the
ability of people to create their own solutions through experimenting with their social situ-
ations and following their own experience as to what felt most satisfying or life-enhancing.
He felt, moreover, that there must be some artistry to solving social problems, for our social
life is grounded in the same human nature as is all art. Quotations are from Paul Stoehr, in
his “Paul Goodman and the Political Dimensions of Gestalt Therapy.”
160. I might have call this the “growth threshold,” but given the hurt state of our
society I think “healing threshold” is more appropriate. All healing, moreover, is itself a
process of growth.
161. Ken Jones, The Social Face of Buddhism, p. 200.
162. Eugene Gendlin, Experiential Psychotherapy, p. 308. Emphasis removed.
163. I have not taken the space here to elaborate Gendlin’s entire political position,
which is essentially based on introducing focusing skills widely enough to create a society
of people capable of making the kinds of microchanges in their immediate contexts that
will add up to structural change on the larger scale. I refer the reader to Focusing, “The Poli-
tics of Giving Therapy Away,” “A Philosophical Critique of the Concept of Narcissism,”
“Process Ethics and the Political Question,” and “Experiential Psychotherapy.” Gendlin
is aware that “individual development does not usually change the social structure.” He
therefore suggests that “We need a whole new branch of social science to study the more
rare conditions under which social change moves from the articulation of experience to
structural change” (“How Philosophy Cannot Appeal to Experience, and How It Can,”
p. 35).
164. Joanna Macy in the preface to Katrina Shields, In the Tiger’s Mouth, p. xi. James
Hillman likewise speaks of “a psychological activism” that works from aesthetic responses.
“The motivation must come from below the superego, from the id of desire” (“Aesthetics
and Politics,” pp. 38, 76).
165. See Thomas Scheff, “Reevaluation Counseling: Social Implications”; Virginia
Coover et al., Resource Manual for a Living Revolution, part four; Cherie Brown and George
Mazza, “Anti-Racism, Healing, and Community Activism;” and Janet Foner, “Surviving
the ‘Mental Health’ System with Co-Counseling.”
166. Philip Lichtenberg, “Shame and the Making of a Social System,” p. 284. In The
Mermaid and the Menotaur, Dorothy Dinnerstein speaks of the “rigid forms of symbiosis,
of fixed psychological complementarity, which have so far dominated the relationships
between men and women.” Men and women are both complicit, in other words, in main-
taining mutually oppressive sexual arrangements.
167. Audre Lorde, “Poetry Is Not a Luxury,’ pp. 126–127.
168. Anne Bell, “Critical Environmental Education/Ecological Critical Education,” p. 5.
169. Constance Russell et al., “Navigating the Waters of Canadian Environmental
Education,” p. 6.
170. Mike Weilbacher, cited in Bell, “Critical,” p. 6.
however, from annihilation, which is “is a defensive response to pain, bodily invasion or danger.”
Annihilation is a “cold” response because it does not satisfy a “hot” appetite, but simply aims to
eliminate pain and danger (Perls et al., Gestalt, p. 341). Freud put forward his “fateful question”
in the last paragraph of Civilization and Its Discontents. See, also, Paul Goodman’s “Critique of
Freud’s Thanatos,” in Perls et al., Gestalt, pp. 349–352.
184. James Kepner, Healing Tasks, p. 101.
185. Clifford Geertz, The Interpretation of Cultures, p. 104.
186. See, also, Joanna Macy, “Buddhist Resources for Moving Through Nuclear
Death” and World as Lover, World as Self.
187. Jones, The Social, p. 123.
188. Ram Dass, “Compassion: The Delicate Balance,” p. 235.
189. Buddhist practice teaches one how to identify less with one’s painful Ego
dramas, and to concentrate instead on being of service, which is much more satisfying.
It also teaches that all feelings pass. Even the biggest experiences of grief or rage just flow
right through us if we let them be—a crucial ability to possess in a time such as ours, with
its great losses and frustrations. Buddhism teaches, finally, how to stay equanimous in the
face of all experience, how to maintain that spontaneous, caring, selfless, and optimally
distanced attitude that is called for by nature (dharma).
190. Michael Higgins, speaking on the Canadian Broadcasting Corporation radio
programme “This Morning,” August 8, 1999. Higgins thus feels that Sartre’s “hell is other
people” is an entirely wrong sentiment.
191. Joel Kovel, “Schizophrenic Being and Technocratic Society,” p. 346. I have
reversed the sequence of the text around the ellipses.
192. Kovel, “On the Ontology,” p. 5. Stated still otherwise, the “movement of
capitalist society is toward dedifferentiation,” which is marked by, among other things,
“an increasing number of desociated characters of one kind or another” (Kovel, The Age,
pp. 248–249. Second emphasis mine).
193. See, for example, Ken Norwood and Kathleen Smith, Rebuilding Community in
America.
194. According to J. H. van den Berg, medical records indicate that there “has
been an increased sensitivity to pain since the beginning of the nineteenth century,” and
attributes this to our increasing loss of contact with others (Divided Existence and Complex
Society, pp. 215–228).
195. James Hillman, “The Animal Kingdom in the Human Dream,” p. 326. Hillman
himself gives credit for this insight to Paul Kugler.
196. Paul Shepard and Barry Sanders, Sacred Paw, p. xii.
Chapter 7
published in the journal Ecological Psychology. These “ecological” approaches are not, how-
ever, defined especially by an interest in the broad psychology of the human-nature rela-
tionships or in addressing the environmental/ecological crisis. They frequently ignore the
natural world altogether. The psychologist Urie Bronfenbrenner, for example, developed
an “ecological systems theory” which places child development in a series of nested systems
which extend out to the child’s sociocultural context but in which a natural system is not
clearly identified. This is not to say that any of these “ecological” approaches are irrelevant
for ecopsychology. The psychologist Louise Chawla, for example, drew on Gibson’s eco-
logical psychology in her article on how children learn to love the natural world (“Learning
to Love the Natural World Enough to Protect It”). But for the purposes of this chapter I am
focusing on the immediate exercise of differentiating ecopsychology from environmental
and conservation psychology.
14. See, for example, the “Promoting Environmentalism” special issue of Journal of
Social Issues and Susan M. Koger and Deborah Du Nann Winter’s The Psychology of Envi-
ronmental Problems, 3rd ed. Research articles in this vein have titles such as “Moderating
Effects of Social Value Orientation on Determinants of Proenvironmental Behavior Inten-
tion” (Tommy Gärling et al.) or “The Application of Persuasion Theory to the Develop-
ment of Effective Proenvironmental Public Service Announcements” (Renee Bator and
Robert Cialdini).
15. Robert B. Bechtel and Arza Churchman, eds., Handbook of Environmental Psy-
chology. The chapter authors are Robert Sommer, Daniel Stokols and Maria Montero, and
Robert B. Bechtel, respectively. Notably, this section does not have a chapter entitled “On
to an Ecological Society!” For another introductory text, see Robert Gifford’s Environ-
mental Psychology: Principles and Practice, 4th ed.
16. Carol D. Saunders, “The Emerging Field of Conservation Psychology,” p. 138.
17. Susan Clayton and Gene Myers, Conservation Psychology, p. 11.
18. Joseph P. Reser, “Wither Environmental Psychology? The Transpersonal Ecops-
ychology Crossroads,” p. 252.
19. Joseph Reser, “Thinking Through ‘Conservation Psychology,’” pp. 170–171.
20. Joseph Reser, “Joseph Reser: The Ecopsychology Interview,” p. 61.
21. In a related vein, the environmental psychologist Robert Gifford notes that the
emerging discipline of sustainability science has made little room for psychology because
the latter is not considered a hard enough science. Indeed, during a discussion about a large
interdisciplinary grant proposal related to climate change he observed a leading natural sci-
entist state that it “should not include any input from ‘fluff,’ by which he apparently meant
the social sciences” (Robert Gifford, “Psychology’s Essential Role in Alleviating the Impacts
of Climate Change,” p. 273). If scientific psychology is considered fluff, then we can only
assume that ecopsychology would be regarded as “ultra–fluff.”
22. Reser, “Joseph Reser,” pp. 61–62.
23. Koger and Winter believe that “ecopsychology will continue to flourish”
because: “it speaks to deeply felt experiences that people have in relationship to the natural
word;” it “offers therapeutic insights into wilderness experiences;” it “makes an important
importance of foregrounding the interpretive and critical elements, but I am happy to use
empirical findings when appropriate, especially if they are hermeneutically-sensitized (see
my “What Is Ecopsychology? A Radical View”).
33. In fairness to Koger and Winter, their book does risk going outside the lines of
typical mainstream psychology, especially their second chapter on “The Nature of Western
Thought” (which, interestingly, was cut from the second edition of their book but returned
to the third because of reader protest). In insisting on the inclusion of ecopsychology in
their survey of approaches to “environmental problems,” they are in a weak sense acknowl-
edging the challenge that ecopsychology poses to psychology. In the end, I would place
their book in a gray zone between a pure mainstream approach and an ecologically radical
one. Despite my concerns, there is no doubt the book makes a significant contribution to
bringing ecopsychology to mainstream attention.
34. Robert Greenway, “Robert Greenway: The Ecopsychology Interview,” p. 51.
Greenway advocates the inclusion of more “real” ecology in ecopsychology, though he also
qualified this: “as long as ecology mean[s] almost a Buddhist kind of systems study, which
for some ecologists it does.” While I do believe there is an important place for scientific
ecology in ecopsychology, my own preferred meaning for ecology is the radical ecology
movement (which incorporates scientific ecology in various ways), this sense of the term
being true in my mind to ecopsychology’s origins.
35. On the idea of “crossing,” see Eugene Gendlin, “Crossing and Dipping.”
36. See, for example, Paul Sears’s 1964 article “Ecology—A Subversive Subject” and
Paul Shepard’s 1969 piece “Ecology and Man—A Viewpoint.” I give this topic lengthier
treatment in my “What Is Ecopsychology? A Radical View.”
37. John Clark, “Introduction” to “Political Ecology,” p. 343.
38. “. . .as if the soul might be saved while the biosphere crumbles” (Theodore
Roszak, The Voice of the Earth, p.19).
39. Romanyshyn is not the first to suggest the significance of dream experience
for scholarly inquiry. In ecopsycholgoical circles, see, for example, Craig Chalquist, Ter-
rapsychology, in which he describes imaginal methods for reengaging the soul of place. For
a philosophical perspective, see Jan Zwicky, “Dream Logic and the Politics of Interpreta-
tion,” in which she argues that an inclusion of the logos of dreaming into philosophy, as
against the current cultural marginalization of dream process, would lead philosophy to an
expanded conception of itself as a discipline and to greater integrity of thought.
40. Goethean science, for instance, may also be worth pursuing by ecopsychology.
Roughly two hundred years ago, Goethe introduced a way of science that involves not
the use of instruments but prolonged emphatic encounter with natural phenomena. This
“delicate empiricism,” as he called it, requires extended practice in developing one’s powers
of perception and understanding so that one may see more deeply and clearly into the
world through direct experience (David Seamon, “Goethe, Nature, and Phenomenology”).
Precisely because it overcomes the subject/object duality—the researcher being immersed
in the phenomena of nature and the latter awakening the former’s powers of recognition—
such science requires that the practitioner attain a “post-rational” level of psychological
development, that is, one that transcends the modes of reason employed in mainstream sci-
entific consciousness (Esbjörn-Hargens, Sean, and Michael Zimmerman, Integral Ecology,
p. 250). Indeed, according to Frederick Amrine, for Goethe the “ultimate goal of science
should be the transformation of the scientist” (quoted in Ecotherapy News Fall 2011, p. 4).
41. Wendell Berry, Sex, Economy, Freedom, and Community, p. xii.
42. One example of a method of theory-production that does work skillfully with
experience, from “something that you know very thickly from years of experience,” is
Eugene Gendlin’s “Thinking at the Edge” practice. See his “Introduction to ‘Thinking the
Edge.’”
43. See, for example, Mary Watkins’s “From Individualism to the Interdependent
Self ” and her “Creating Restorative Ecotherapeutic Practices.”
44. I am drawing my terms here from Albert Bormann’s Crossing the Postmodern
Divide.
45. On this, see Philip Cushman, “Why the Self is Empty: Toward an Histori-
cally Situated Psychology,” Edward Sampson, “The Debate on Individualism: Indigenous
Psychologies of the Individual and Their Role in Personal and Societal Functioning,” and
David Kidner, Nature and Psyche, pp. 48–51. In environmental psychologist Robert Gif-
ford’s article “Psychology’s Essential Role in Alleviating the impacts of Climate Change,”
he repeatedly states that the individual is both the unit of analysis in psychology and the
target for behavioral change.
46. On this, see, for example, David Kidner’s Nature and Psyche.
47. Mary Watkins and Helene Shulman, Toward Psychologies of Liberation, p. 13.
Other quotations in this paragraph are from pp. 1, 15, 26, 270, 271, 221.
48. See also Stanley Diamond’s discussion on individualism in In Search of the Prim-
itive, pp. 159–168.
49. Charles Spinosa, Fernado Flores, and Hubert Dreyfus, Disclosing New Worlds,
p. 168.
50. Adrian Ivakhiv’s book Claiming Sacred Ground is a good example, in this
respect, of scholarship aimed at making sense of New Age earthen spirituality.
51. Nor should we assume that mainstream approaches are themselves free from
irrationality, even if this is less visible under conventional conditions.
52. See, for example, Kidner, Nature, p. 56.
53. I can unfortunately provide here only the barest outline of Habermas’s theory of
the colonization of the lifeworld by the system. The critical psychologist Todd Sloan’s Dam-
aged Life contains a good presentation of this theory, which I am relying on throughout this
discussion.
54. Kidner, Nature, p. 130.
55. Needless to say, it is hard to imagine a human society burdened with these
pathologies entering into balanced relations with the more-than-human.
56. Richard Lewontin and Richard Levins speak, in this regard, of the “dual nature
of science. On the one hand it is the generic development of human knowledge over the
millenia, but on the other it is the increasingly commodified specific product of a capitalist
knowledge industry. The result is a peculiarly uneven development, with increasing sophis-
tication at the level of the laboratory and research project, along with a growing irration-
ality of the scientific enterprise as a whole” (Biology Under the Influence, p. 9).
57. Consider, for example, Thomas Fleischner’s comments on the historical devel-
opment of natural history: “What had made natural history vibrant was the integration of
science, art, and philosophy—a unified approach to understanding and expressing Nature’s
ways. Literary natural history lost scientific grounding, while scientific natural history
drifted away from an honest acknowledgment of its subject’s impact on human emotion.
As literary naturalists became more flowery, the scientific natural historians seemingly sped
to distance themselves from anything resembling literary grace, and instead emphasized
more dry and analytical descriptions of natural processes (“Revitalizing Natural History,”
p. 86).
58. Thus, not only would we be able to speak, as does Romanyshyn, of a “poetics
of research, as opposed to an empirics of research” (The Wounded Researcher, p. 342), we
would also be able to make a place for other forms of empiricism, such as the “delicate
empiricism” of Goethean science (see note 40 above). It is noteworthy in this respect that
Goethe’s science was often dismissed in its day as mere “subjective artistic descriptions”
(Seamon, “Goethe,” p. 1). In an integrated lifeworld there would likely also be more room
for phenomenology (of which Goethean science is an instance), which since Husserl has
been characterized as a radical empiricism both because it works strictly from lived experi-
ence and because it refuses to posit a duality between person and world.
59. On this, see David Abram’s comments in “D. Abram Interviewed by Derrick
Jensen.”
60. Harvey, “The Nature,” pp. 37, 34.
61. John Bellamy Foster, Brett Clark, and Richard York, The Ecological Rift, p. 340.
62. John Bellamy Foster, “The Dialectics of Nature and Marxist Ecology,” p.76.
63. This is because socialism understands our capitalist society better than any
other tradition and because Marx’s materialist conception of history and his notion of
the “metabolic” relationship between human society and the rest of nature, especially as
these have been taken up by ecological socialists, offer a unique critical perspective on the
society/nature relationship.
64. For more complete treatments, see Bertell Ollman, Dance of the Dialectic;
Bertell Ollman and Tony Smith, eds., Dialectics for the New Century; and Richard Levins
and Richard Lewontin, The Dialectical Biologist.
65. William Blake’s “Without Contraries is no progression” expresses this principle.
66. Fredric Jameson, “Persistencies of the Dialectic: Three Sites,” p. 120.
67. See Chris Harman, Zombie Capitalism.
68. See, especially, Ollman, Dance.
69. On the dialectical nature of Gendlin’s philosophy, see David Levin, “Phenom-
enology in America.”
70. Levins and Lewontin, The Dialectical.
71. Joel Kovel, “Dialectic as Praxis,” p. 238. Emphasis added.
88. See chapter 16 in Foster, Clark, and York, The Ecological. These authors further-
more speak of “the common fallacy that by not consuming but rather saving income one
can somehow protect the environment. Yet in a properly functioning capitalist economy
savings are redirected into investment or new capital formation designed to expand the
scale of the entire economy. And it is such expansion that is the chief enemy of the environ-
ment” (p. 382). See, also, David Uzzell and Nora Räthzel, “Transforming Environmental
Psychology” and O’Connor, Natural, p. 206.
89. It is for this reason, again, that I think ecopsychology must stress ecology as
much as psychology—so that these two broad fields may inform and alter each other and
together metamorphose into a new field and political movement.
90. Doherty, “Editorial: A Peer Reviewed,” p. 3.
91. The Bruntland report, in which the idea of sustainable development was intro-
duced, is quite clear on this point: “In the past we have been concerned about the impact
of economic growth on the environment; we are now forced to concern ourselves with
the impact of ecological stress on our economic prospects” (cited in Neil Evernden, The
Natural Alien, p. 152). A truly ecological approach, by contrast, would embrace the prin-
ciple that: “Ecological arguments are never socially neutral any more than socio-political
arguments are ecologically neutral” (Harvey, “The Nature,” p. 25). See, also, David Uzzell
and Nora Räthzel, “Transforming Environmental Psychology.”
92. Teo, “Philosophical,” p. 44.
93. George Monbiot displays an admirable honesty when he declares that no one in
the environmental movement “has a convincing account of how humanity can get out of
this mess” (“None of Our Fixes Can Hope to Save Us,” p. 20).
94. David Uzzell and Nora Räthzel, “Transforming Environmental Psychology.”
95. See our conversation on this in Andy Fisher, “Andy Fisher: The Ecopsychology
Interview,” pp. 172–173.
96. Recall from the preface that my using of the term radical ecopsychology was
a strategy to invite recognition of ecopsychology’s inherent radicalness, not to propose
a particular radical version of ecopsychology. For clarity’s sake, I now prefer the phrase
ecopsychology radically conceived. I do realize that not everyone agrees with my views about
ecopsychology, and I do not presume to speak for the field as a whole. In this sense, the
term radical ecopsychology perhaps still holds this tension.
97. Cited in Foster, Clark, and York, The Ecological, p. 305. I am relying on Foster
et al. in my discussion of Harding’s theory.
98. Foster, Clark, and York, The Ecological, pp. 20, 22, 19.
99. Not a “victim of society” but “Free should the scholar be—free and brave”
(Ralph Waldo Emerson, “The American Scholar”).
100. Reser, “Joseph Reser,” p. 62; Koger and Winter, The Psychology, pp. 308–309.
101. http://graduate.lclark.edu/departments/counseling_psychology/ecopsy-
chology/, November 25, 2011.
102. Linda Buzzell and Craig Chalquist, “Psyche and Nature in a Circle of Healing,”
p. 18.
103. In addition to Louv’s Last Child, see research summaries in Clayton and Myers’s
Conservation and Koger and Winter’s The Psychology.
104. Buzzell and Chalquist, “Psyche,” p. 20.
105. John Scull, “Tailoring Nature Therapy to the Client,” p. 148. Scull uses the
“nature connecting” approach developed by Michael Cohen (see Cohen’s Reconnecting with
Nature).
106. See my “Ecopsychology as Radical Praxis.”
107. Clayton, Susan, and Susan Opotow, “Introduction: Identity and the Natural
Environment,” p. 7.
108. In their Introduction, Buzzell and Chalquist define ecopsychology as “the study
of the psychological processes that tie us to the world or separate us from it” (“Psyche,”
p. 17), but do not discuss it much beyond that. Some authors in the Ecotherapy primer also
provide brief discussions of ecopsychology. These discussions do not, however, add up to the
comprehensive characterization of ecopsychology that I think is needed in order to consider
the topic of ecopsychological praxis. It seems to me, furthermore, that many of the authors
in the Ecotherapy primer (e.g., Bill McKibben) are not actually applying a particular idea of
ecopsychology but are rather simply presenting a viewpoint or practice they have developed.
109. Mary Watkins is inspirational here, having consistently urged psychologists to
dis-identify from aspects of their training and practice out of synch with the suffering and
collective needs of this historical moment: “At some junctures, we will need to learn new
skills appropriate to our evolving understanding of what ails us. We may find ourselves
outside of the role definitions to which we are accustomed as we honestly respond to the
suffering that we witness” (“Creating Restorative Ecotherapeutic Practices,” p. 235).
110. http://graduate.lclark.edu/departments/counseling_psychology/ecopsy-
chology/philosophy/, November 25, 2011.
111. Martin Seligman, cited in David Kidner, “Depression and the Natural World,”
p. 133.
112. Mary Gomes, “Altars of Extinction,” p. 248.
113. George Burns, Nature-Guided Therapy, p. xv. See, also, Burns’s chapter in the
Ecotherapy primer.
114. Mind, Ecotherapy: The Green Agenda for Mental Health, p. 1.
115. Stephen Illardi, The Depression Cure.
116. Bruce Alexander, The Globalization of Addiction, p. 58. Other quotations in this
paragraph are from pp. 61, 64, 4.
117. Lorraine Fish, Nature, Culture, and Abnormal Appetites, p. 130.
118. Chellis Glendinning, Chivas, p. 216.
119. See, most notably, Wilber’s lengthy footnote in Sex, Ecology, Spirituality, starting
on p. 696.
120. Such an appraisal “is legitimate, but we leave it to others to undertake” (Esb-
jörn-Hargens and Zimmerman, Integral Ecology, p. 552).
121. Despite all the problems with postmodernism, Wilber sees it as a positive “return”
of “investigation of the Left-Hand dimensions, including multicultural interpretation and
I think the working out of a dialectic of history that integrates Wilber’s and other’s spiritual
conceptions with the material-political conceptions of Marxists and others is an important
exercise for ecopsychology. The fact that a realistic history of the psyche-nature relationship
can only be pursued in this manner again indicates the inherent radicalness of ecopsychology.
135. Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman, Integral, p. 307.
136. Wilber, Sex, pp. 111, 691.
137. Wilber views history in terms of a “dialectic of progress”: “As consciousness evolves
and unfolds, each new stage solves or defuses certain problems of the previous stage, but then
adds new and recalcitrant—and sometimes more complex and more difficult—problems of
its own. Precisely because evolution in all domains (human and otherwise) operates by a
process of differentiation and integration, then each new and more complex level necessarily
faces problems not present in its predecessors. Dogs get cancer; atoms don’t. . . .So evolution
inherently means that new potentials and new wonders are introduced with each stage, but
they are invariably accompanied by new horrors, new fears, new problems, new disasters”
(Ken Wilber, The Eye of Spirit, p. 66). I would say that Wilber’s view of history itself needs to
be transcended and included in a more complex one. Jameson argues in this respect that the
dialectic, insofar as this refers to “problems of causality and historical narrative and explana-
tion[,]. . .wishes ceaselessly to interrogate and undermine [existing] narrative and historical
ideologies, by allowing us to see and grasp historical change in a new and more complex way”
(“Persistencies,” pp. 120, 127). It is noteworthy, as well, that while Wilber borrowed the term
“dialectic of progress” from Habermas, Habermas has himself “quietly dropped” most of his
theory of social evolution (James Gordon Finlayson, Habermas, p. 73).
138. K.P. Moseley, “In Defense of the Primitive.”
139. According to Wilber the “central idea” of the foraging epoch of human evolu-
tion is that “Spirit is interwoven with earthbody. Foraging cultures the world over sing this
profound truth. The very earth is our blood and bones and marrow, and we are all sons and
daughters of that earth—in which, and through which, Spirit freely flows” (Wilber, A Brief,
p. 490). To say the least, it is hard to see how this idea has been integrated into subsequent
stages, certainly within Western civilization.
140. Stanley Diamond, In Search of the Primitive, p. 129. Other quotations in this
paragraph are from pp. 174–175, 174, xvi.
141. Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman, Integral, p. 230.
142. Richard Lee, “Demystifying Primitive Communism.”
143. I cannot explore here in any depth the debate about what these virtues might be
exactly, but do note the following remarks by the anthropologist Hugh Brody: “Egalitari-
anism, respect for the elderly, loving regard for children, diligent respect for the land, plants
and animals on which they depend—these are the ‘virtues,’ too often missing in the ‘devel-
oped’ world, that cause visitors to hunter-gatherer societies to experience deep admiration.
To describe these things, and seek to understand them, is not romanticism but the most
relevant kind of realism” (The Other Side of Eden, p. 147). While Esbjörn-Hargens and
Zimmerman caution against ignoring the dark side of “ancient tribal cultures and other
premodern cultures” such as destructive superstitions, tribal warfare, and human sacrifice,
175. Wilber’s Sex proposed a holonic ecology but did not address the profoundly
anti-ecological nature of capitalist society. (“Holon” is a term Wilber borrows from Arthur
Koestler. The basic unit of reality, holons are wholes made up of parts that are themselves
parts of larger wholes. For Wilber, the Kosmos is holons all the way up and down.) In
Integral Ecology, Esbjörn-Hargens and Zimmerman likewise make little critical comment
on capitalism; use language that bypasses the very notion of society (e.g., referring to the
quadrants of the AQAL diagram as: self [UL], culture [LL], and nature [UR and LR],
with society buried under nature); make little mention of critical or Marxist methods; and
in their list of recommended books (“The Integral Ecology Bookshelf ”) do not include
any works of critical social theory, the closest being Paul Hawken, Amory Lovins, and
L. Hunter Lovins’s book, Natural Capitalism.
176. Wilber, A Theory, p. 94.
177. David Harvey, The Enigma of Capital, p. 239.
178. Bert Parlee and Ken Wilber, “Like it or Not, You’re a Capitalist. But Are You a
Conscious One?”
179. Wilber argues for the dignity of capitalism, noting how it has transcended
the cruelties of feudalism, but does not go nearly far enough in thinking about the
essential cruelties of capitalism. Marxists do not deny the advances that capitalism
made over feudalism, but they nonetheless argue for the need to advance beyond
capitalism to socialism. Regarding the dignity of capitalism, David Harvey writes
that “the positive side to the capitalist revolution was that it dispossessed arbitrary
feudal institutions (such as the monarchy and the Church) and their powers, liber-
ated creative energies, opened up new spaces and knitted the world closer together
through exchange relations, opened up society to strong currents of technological and
organisational change, overcame a world based on superstition and ignorance and
replaced it with an enlightened science with the potential to liberate all of humanity
from material want and need. . . .It was for socialism and communism to build upon
the progressive aspects of capitalist development. These progressive aspects included
movements for land reform, the rise of democratic forms of government (always sul-
lied by the role of money power), freedom of information (always contingent but
nevertheless vital) and. . .of expression, and the creation of rights civil and legal” (The
Enigma of Capital, p. 249).
For Wilber’s views on Marxism, see Sex, pp. 199–201. Although he agrees with the
need for “equitable material-economic distribution in the physiosphere,” Wilber believes the
flaw of Marxism was that it “reduced the noosphere to the physiosphere [i.e., to the material
plane], such an egregious reduction that it took evolution less than a mere century to begin to
erase that mistake in earnest.” For Wilber, in other words, Marxism is a mistake safely behind
us. While I agree with him that Marxist revolutions have typically been marked by irrational
mythologizing due to the reduction that he notes, what his view most overlooks is the fact
that Marxism provides the best understanding of the capitalist system available, and that this
understanding is coming to bear more than ever in our own times. As I discuss below, it also
does not recognize that actually-existing socialist states have never freed themselves from the
capitalist world system and are better characterized as forms of state capitalism: the failure of
Marxism has in practice largely been the failure of capitalism.
180. See Foster, Clark, and York, The Ecological and Joel Kovel, A Really Inconvenient
Truth.
181. See the detailed version of the AQAL diagram in Wilber, Sex, as well as p. 427.
182. Regarding the former Soviet Union, Harman writes: “In undertaking the task of
accumulation, the bureaucracy substituted itself for a capitalist class that no longer existed.
But the methods it used were essentially those of capitalist industrialization elsewhere in
the world. ‘Collectivization’—in reality the state takeover of the land—increased the pro-
portion of agricultural output available for industrial accumulation while driving a very
high proportion of the peasantry from the land, just as enclosures had for England’s early
capitalists” (Zombie, p. 158; see also p. 118 and elsewhere in this illuminating book).
183. Wilber, A Brief, p. 103.
184. Using Wilber’s own terms, we could say that he aims to translate capitalism by
changing its surface structure rather to transform it by changing its deep structure (Wilber,
Sex, p. 68).
185. Wilber, A Brief History, pp. 420, 512.
186. Wilber, Sex, p. 427.
187. Marlene Steinberg, The Stranger in the Mirror, p. xvii.
188. Wilber, Sex, p. 148.
189. Wilber, Sex, p. 202. Centaur is Wilber’s term for a level of development in
which mind and body are integrated.
190. Ken Wilber, A Theory of Everything, pp. 130–131.
191. Eleanor Burke Leacock and Christine Ward Gailey, “Primitive Communism
and Its Transformations,” p. 100.
192. See Wilber, The Eye, p. xvii and A Theory, pp. 83–89.
193. Parlee and Wilber, “Like it or Not.”
194. Foster, Clark, and York, The Ecological, p. 55.
195. Marx identified three categories of conditions of production: “natural condi-
tions” (land), “personal conditions” (labor power) and “communal general conditions”
(physical and social infrastructure, human-made space, etc.). As O’Connor notes, the
conditions of production may be reframed as the conditions of life, and various social
movements can then be seen a struggles united against capital in preserving, defending,
and enhancing the “conditions of life and life itself ” (Natural, pp. 144–145, 316). Ecopsy-
chology would clearly fit into this scheme.
196. I have drawn for this exercise on Harvey, “The Nature” and O’Connor, Natural
Causes.
197. Wilber, A Brief History, p. 391.
198. “There may be no effective long-term capitalist solutions (apart from reversion
to fictitious capital manipulations) to the crisis of capitalism. At some point quantitative
changes lead to qualitative shifts and we need to take seriously the idea that we may be
at exactly such an inflexion point in the history of capitalism. Questioning the future of
capitalism itself as an adequate social system ought, therefore, to be in the forefront of cur-
rent debate” (Harvey, The Enigma, p. 217).
199. See, especially, In Defense of Food and The Omnivore’s Dilemma.
200. During a public forum in which Pollan interviewed Jack Sinclair, the executive
vice president of grocery merchandise for Walmart, “he described an epiphany he had in
Garden City, Kansas, while writing about the feedlot and slaughter businesses there. He
visited a local Walmart late one night and noticed a kind of cheap meat, tenderized by
injected saline solution and other artificial preservatives, that he’d never seen in his own
area. ‘And there were the people I’d seen working at the slaughterhouse—this was the meat
they could afford to buy. So I saw this whole non-virtuous cycle of low wages and low
prices.’” Here is an example of how Pollan can put his finger right on the exploitative and
competitive logic of capitalist social relationships but then not take the next step and bring
the entire capitalist system into critical view.
201. The idea of these two languages comes from Giroux, et al., “The Need.”
202. Philippe Descola, “Societies of Nature and the Nature of Society.” “[B]etween a
structuralist nature that is good to think and a Marxist nature that is good to exploit there
is perhaps room for a nature that is merely good to socialize” (p. 112).
203. Ingold, The Perception, p. 76.
204. Edvard Hviding, “Nature, Culture, Magic, Science,” p. 179.
205. Findings of G. A. Haudricourt, reported by Descola in “Societies,” p. 112.
206. Kidner, “Fraud,” p. 394. The study was by Robert Ryan.
207. Ariel Salleh and Meira Hansen, “On Production and Reproduction, Identity
and Non-Identity in Ecofeminist Theory.”
208. Ariel Salleh, “Global Alternatives and the Meta-Industrial Class.”
209. “. . .the same thing can’t be said of Adam Smith’s The Wealth of Nations, which
has great symbolic worth but little practical value for neoliberalism” (O’Connor, Natural,
p. 1).
210. Ecosocialist texts can be difficult to approach, as they use the complex and
sometimes obscure language of Marxists. Joel Kovel’s The Enemy of Nature remains for
me the best introduction, though for the uninitiated it is not always easy to follow. Foster,
Clark, and York’s The Ecological Rift is more accessible, but weaker on the actual nature of
the ecosocialist transition (and very repetitive in places). James O’Connor’s Natural Causes
is another important work, O’Connor being one of the main developers of ecosocialism.
Finally, Harvey’s “The Nature of Environment” is a brief but rewarding journey through
this territory. See also Terry Eagleton’s Why Marx Was Right for a useful debunking of many
misconceptions about Marx.
211. Roszak, The Voice, p. 321.
212. O’Connor, Natural, p. 328.
213. Kovel, The Enemy, pp. 215, 228. The Conscious Capitalist commitment to
spiritual development within a wholly quantitative economic and social system is thus
contradictory.
214. Heinberg, The End.
Abram, David. “Merleau-Ponty and the Voice of the Earth.” Environmental Ethics 10
(1986): 101–120.
_____. “The Mechanical and the Organic: On the Impact of Metaphor in Science.” In
Scientists on Gaia, ed. Stephen H. Schneider and Penelope J. Boston. Cambridge:
MIT Press, 1991.
_____. The Spell of the Sensuous: Perception and Language in a More-than-Human World.
New York: Pantheon, 1996.
_____. “D. Abram Interviewed by Derrick Jensen.” Retrieved from http://www.wildethics.
org/essays/interview_derrick_jensen.html, 2000.
_____. “To Speak as a (Human) Animal: A Reply to Ted Toadvine.” In Interrogating Ethics,
ed. James Hatley. Northwestern University Press, forthcoming.
Ainsworth, Mary D. Salter. “Attachment as Related to Mother-Infant Interaction.”
In Advances in the Study of Behavior, vol. 9, ed. Jay Rosenblatt et al. New York:
Academic Press, 1979.
_____, et al. Patterns of Attachment: A Psychological Study of the Strange Situation. Hillsdale,
N.J.: Erlbaum, 1978.
Alderman, Harold. “The Dreamer and the World.” Soundings 60 (1977): 331–346.
Alexander, Bruce. The Globalisation of Addiction: A Study in the Poverty of Spirit. Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 2008.
American Psychiatric Association. Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders,
4th ed. Washington, D.C.: American Psychiatric Association, 1994.
Anthony, Carl. “Ecopsychology and the Deconstruction of Whiteness.” In Ecopsychology:
Restoring the Earth, Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and
Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
_____, and Renée Soule. “A Multicultural Approach to Ecopsychology.” The Humanistic
Psychologist 26.1–3 (1998), 155–161.
Armstrong, Jeannette. Interviewed by Derrick Jensen. In Listening to the Land, ed. Derrick
Jensen. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
_____ “Keepers of the Earth.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth, Healing the Mind, ed.
Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra
Club, 1995.
337
Athanasiou, Tom. Divided Planet: The Ecology of Rich and Poor. Boston: Little, Brown,
1996.
Avens, Robert S. “Heidegger and Archetypal Psychology.” International Philosophical
Quarterly 22 (1982): 183–202.
Ayto, John. Bloomsbury Dictionary of Word Origins. London: Bloomsbury, 1990.
Badiner, Alan Hunt, ed. Dharma Gaia: A Harvest of Essays in Buddhism and Ecology.
Berkeley, Calif.: Parallax, 1990.
Bakhtin, M. M. Speech Genres and Other Late Essays. Austin: University of Texas Press,
1986.
_____. Toward a Philosophy of the Act. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1993.
Barfield, Owen. “The Meaning of the Word ‘Literal.’” In Metaphor and Symbol, ed. L. C.
Knights and Basil Cottle. London: Butterworth Scientific, 1960.
_____. Poetic Diction: A Study in Meaning, 3rd ed. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan
University Press, 1973.
_____. “The Rediscovery of Meaning.” In The Rediscovery of Meaning and Other Essays.
Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan University Press, 1977.
_____. Saving the Appearances: A Study in Idolatry, 2nd ed. Middletown, Conn.: Wesleyan
University Press, 1988.
Barrows, Anita. “The Ecopsychology of Child Development.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring
the Earth, Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen
D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
_____. “Crying for the Manatees: Youth and Our Endangered World.” ReVision 20.4
(1998): 9–17.
Barton, Anthony. “Humanistic Contributions to the Field of Psychotherapy: Appreciating
the Human and Liberating the Therapist.” In The Humanistic Movement: Recovering
the Person in Psychology, ed. Frederick J. Wertz. Lake Worth, Fla.: Gardner, 1994.
Batchelor, Martine, and Kerry Brown, eds. Buddhism and Ecology. London: Cassell, 1992.
Bateson, Gregory. Steps to an Ecology of Mind. New York: Ballantine, 1972.
_____. Mind and Nature: A Necessary Unity. Toronto: Bantam, 1979.
Bator, Renee, and Robert Cialdini. “The Application of Persuasion Theory to the
Development of Effective Proenvironmental Public Service Announcements.”
Journal of Social Issues 56.3 (2000): 527–542.
Becker, Ernest. Angel in Armor: A Post-Freudian Perspective on the Nature of Man. New York:
George Braziller, 1969.
Bell, Anne. “Critical Environmental Education/ Ecological Critical Education.”
Unpublished paper, 1995.
Benton, Ted. “Biology and Social Theory in the Environmental Debate.” In Social Theory
and the Global Environment, ed. Michael Redclift and Ted Benton. New York:
Routledge, 1994.
Bergman, Charles. “‘The Curious Peach’: Nature and the Language of Desire.” In Green
Culture: Environmental Rhetoric in Contemporary America, ed. Carl G Herndl and
Stuart C. Brown. Madison, Wis.: University of Wisconsin Press, 1996.
_____. “The Nature of Reality and the Reality of Nature.” In Reinventing Nature?: Responses
to Postmodern Deconstruction, ed. Michael Soulé and Michael Lease. Washington,
D.C.: Island, 1995.
Boss, Medard. Meaning and Content of Sexual Perversions: A Daseinsanalytic Approach to
the Psychopathology of the Phenomenon of Love. New York: Grune & Stratton, 1949.
_____. The Analysis of Dreams. London: Rider, 1957.
_____. “Anxiety, Guilt and Psychotherapeutic Liberation.” Review of Existential Psychology
and Psychiatry 2 (1962): 173–202.
_____. Psychoanalysis and Daseinsanalysis. New York: Basic Books, 1963.
_____. “Dreaming and the Dreamed in the Daseinsanalytical Way of Seeing.” Soundings
60.3 (1977): 235–263.
_____. Existential Foundations of Medicine and Psychology. New York: Jason Aronson, 1979.
Boukydis, C. F. Zachariah. “A Theory of Empathic Relations Between Parents and Infants:
Insight from a Client-Centred/Experiential Perspective.” The Focusing Folio
4 (1985): 3–28.
_____. “Focusing-Oriented Parent-Infant Play and Psychotherapy.” Funding Request.
Infant Development Centre, Women and Infants Hospital, St. Providence, R.I.,
1999.
Boukydis, Kathleen M. “Changes: Peer-Counseling Supportive Communities as a Model
of Community Mental Health.” In Teaching Psychological Skills: Models for Giving
Therapy Away, ed. D. Larson. Monterey, Calif.: Brooks/Cole, 1984.
Bowlby, John. A Secure Base: Parent-Child, Attachment and Healthy Human Development.
Basic Books, 1988.
Bradford, George. “Toward a Deep Social Ecology.” In Environmental Philosophy: From
Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. Michael E. Zimmerman. Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1993.
Breggin, Peter R. Toxic Psychiatry. New York: St. Martin’s, 1991.
_____. “Psychotherapy in Emotional Crises Without Resort to Psychiatric Medication.”
The Humanistic Psychologist 25.2 (1997): 2–14.
_____, and E. Mark Stern, eds. Psychosocial Approaches to Deeply Disturbed Persons.
New York: Hawthorn, 1996.
Bridges, William. Transitions: Making Sense of Life’s Changes. Reading, Mass.: Perseus
Books, 1980.
Briere, John. Child Abuse Trauma. Newbury Park: Sage, 1992.
_____. Therapy for Adults Molested as Children. New York: Springer, 1996.
Bringhurst, Robert. “Myth Creates a World of Meaning.” Globe and Mail May 7, 1988:
C1, C18.
Brody, Hugh. The Other Side of Eden: Hunters, Farmers and the Shaping of the World.
Vancouver/Toronto: Douglas & McIntyre, 2000.
Bronstein, Phyllis. “Promoting Healthy Emotional Development in Children.” Journal of
Primary Prevention 5.2 (1984): 92–110.
Chalquist, Craig. Terrapsychology: Reengaging the Soul of Place. New Orleans: Spring
Journal, 2007.
Chawla, Louise. (1992). “Childhood Place Attachments.” In Place Attachment, ed. Irwin
Altman and Setha M. Low. New York: Plenum. 1992.
_____. In the First Country of Places: Nature, Poetry, and Childhood Memory. Albany: State
University of New York Press, 1994.
_____. “Spots of Time: Manifold Ways of Being in Nature in Childhood.
In Children and Nature: Psychological, Sociocultural, and Evolutionary Investigations,
ed. Peter H. Kahn, Jr., and Stephen R. Kellert. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2002.
_____. “Learning to Love the Natural World Enough to Protect It.” Barn 2 (2006), 57–78.
Chen, Ellen. The Tao Te Ching: A New Translation with Commentary. New York: Paragon
House, 1989.
Cheney, Jim. “Eco-Feminism and Deep Ecology.” Environmental Ethics 9 (1987): 115–145.
_____. “Postmodern Environmental Ethics: Ethics as Bioregional Narrative.” Environmental
Ethics 11 (1989): 117–134.
Chodorow, Nancy. “Gender, Relation, and Difference in Psychoanalytic Perspective.”
In The Future of Difference, ed. Hester Eisenstein and Alice Jardine. New Brunswick:
Rutgers, 1980.
_____. Feminism and Psychoanalytic Theory. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1989.
Clark, John. “Introduction” to “Part 4 Political Ecology.” In Environmental Philosophy:
From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. Michael Zimmerman, J. Baird
Callicott, George Sessions, Karen J. Warren, and John Clark. Upper Saddle River.
N.J.: Prentice Hall, 2001.
Clarkson, Petruska. Gestalt Counselling in Action. London: Sage, 1989.
Clayton, Susan, and Gene Myers. Conservation Psychology: Understanding and Promoting
Human Care for Nature. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009.
Clayton, Susan, and Susan Opotow. “Introduction: Identity and the Natural Environment.”
In Identity and the Natural Environment: The Psychological Significance of Nature, ed.
Susan Clayton and Susan Opotow. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2003.
Coates, Gary. “Future Images, Present Possibilities: Revisioning Nature, Self, and Society.”
In Resettling America, ed. Gary Coates. Andover, Mass.: Brick House, 1981.
Cobb, Edith. “The Ecology of Imagination in Childhood.” In The Subversive Science, ed.
Paul Shepard and Daniel McKinley. Boston: Houghlan Mifflin, 1969.
_____. The Ecology of Imagination In Childhood. New York: Columbia University Press,
1977.
Cohen, Michael J. Reconnecting with Nature. Friday Harbor, WA.: ProjectNatureConnect,
1995.
Coles, Romand. “Ecotones and Environmental Ethics: Adorno and Lopez.” In In the Nature
of Things, ed. Jane Bennett and William Chaloupka. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1993.
Condrau, Gion, and Medard Boss. “Existential Analysis.” Modern Perspectives in World
Psychiatry, ed. John G. Howells. New York: Brunner/Mazel, 1971.
Conn, Sarah. “Protest and Thrive: The Relationship Between Social Responsibility and
Personal Empowerment.” Cambridge, Mass.: Center for Psychology and Social
Change, 1990. Also published in New England Journal of Social Policy 6.1 (1990),
163–177.
_____. “When the Earth Hurts, Who Responds?” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth,
Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San
Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
Connolly, William. “Voices from the Whirlwind.” In In the Nature of Things, ed. Jane
Bennett and William Chaloupka. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993.
Coon, Carleton. The Hunting Peoples. New York: Nick Lyons, 1971.
Cooper, Marilyn M. “Environmental Rhetoric in the Age of Hegemonic Politics: Earth
First! and the Nature Conservancy.” In Green Culture: Environmental Rhetoric
in Contemporary America, ed. Carl G. Herndl, and Stuart C. Brown. Madison:
University of Wisconsin Press, 1996.
Coovers, Virginia, et al. Resource Manual for a Living Revolution. Philadelphia: New Society,
1977.
Cornell, Ann Weiser. The Focusing Student’s Manual, 3rd ed. Berkeley, Cal.: Focusing
Resources, 1994. Available from Focusing Resources, 2625 Alcatraz Ave., #202,
Berkeley, CA 94705, U.S.A.
_____. The Power of Focusing. Oakland, Calif.: New Harbinger, 1996.
Cronon, William, ed. Uncommon Ground: Rethinking the Human Place in Nature.
New York: W. W. Norton, 1996.
Cushman, Philip. “Why the Self Is Empty: Toward a Historically Situated Psychology.”
American Psychologist 45.5 (1990): 599–611.
_____. “Ideology Obscured: Political Uses of the Self in Daniel Stern’s Infant.” American
Psychologist 46.3 (1991): 206–219.
Davidson, Larry. “Philosophical Foundations of Humanistic Psychology.” In The
Humanistic Movement: Recovering the Person in Psychology, ed. Frederick J. Wertz.
Lake Worth, Fla. Gardner, 1994.
Davis-Berman, Jennifer, and Dene Berman. Wilderness Therapy: Foundations, Theory &
Research. Dubuque, Iowa: Kendal/Hunt, 1994.
Davis, John. “The Transpersonal Dimension of Ecopsychology: Nature, Nonduality, and
Spiritual Practice.” The Humanistic Psychologist 26 (1998): 69–100.
De Koning, Andre. “Reflections on the Heart.” In The Changing Reality of Modern Man:
Essays in Honour of Jan Hendrik van den Berg, ed. Dreyer Kruger. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press, 1985.
Decarvalho, Roy. Founders of Humanistic Psychology. New York: Praeger, 1991.
Denzin, Norman K., and Yvonna S. Lincoln. “Introduction: Entering the Field of
Qualitative Research.” In Handbook of Qualitative Research, ed. Norman K. Denzin
and Yvonna S. Lincoln. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage, 1994.
Descola, Philippe, and Gísli Pálsson. “Introduction.” In Nature and Society: Anthropological
Perspectives, ed. Philippe Descola & Gísli Pálsson. London: Routledge, 1996.
Draper, Patricia. “Social and Economic Constraints on Child Life among the !Kung.’
In Kalahari Hunter-Gatherers, ed. Richard Lee and Irene DeVore. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976.
Dreyfus, Hubert L. “Holism and Hermeneutics.” Review of Metaphysics 34 (1980): 3–23.
_____. “Beyond Hermeneutics: Interpretation in Late Heidegger and Recent Foucault.”
In Hermeneutics: Questions and Prospects, ed. Gary Shapiro and Alan Sica. Amherst:
University of Massachusetts Press, 1984.
_____. Being-in-the-World: A Commentary on Heidegger’s Being and Time, Division
I. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1991.
_____, and Charles Spinosa. “Highway Bridges and Feasts: Heidegger and Borgmann on
How to Affirm Technology.” Man and World 30.159–177 (1997).
Duerr, Hans Peter. Dreamtime: Concerning the Boundary Between Wilderness and
Civilization. New York: Basil Blackwell, 1985.
Durning, Alan Thein. “Are We Happy Yet?” In Ecopsychology, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary
E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
Dutton, Donald G. The Abusive Personality: Violence and Control in Intimate Relationships.
New York: Guilford, 1998.
Eagleton, Terry. Why Marx Was Right. New Haven: Yale University Press, 2011.
Eaton, Boyd, Marjorie Shostak, and Melvin Konner. The Paleolithic Prescription: A Program
of Diet and Exercise and a Design for Living. New York: Harper & Row, 1988.
Eckersley, Robyn. “The Failed Promise of Critical Theory.” In Ecology, ed. Carolyn
Merchant. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1994.
Ehrenfeld, David. The Arrogance of Humanism. New York: Oxford, 1978.
Ehrlich, Anne, and Paul Ehrlich. Healing the Planet: Strategies for Resolving the Environmental
Crisis. Reading, Mass.: Addison-Wesley, 1991.
Eliade, Mircea. Rites and Symbols of Initiation: The Mysteries of Birth and Rebirth. Wood-
stock, Conn.: Spring, 1995.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo. “The American Scholar.” Phi Beta Kappa oration, delivered
at Cambridge, Massachusetts, on August 31, 1837. Retrieved from www.
aboutemerson.com/amscholar.htm, November 24, 2011.
Erikson, Erik. Childhood and Society, rev. and enlarged ed. New York: W. W. Norton, 1963.
_____. Identity: Youth and Crisis. New York: W. W. Norton, 1968.
_____. Identity and the Life Cycle. New York: W. W. Norton, 1980.
Esbjörn-Hargens, Sean, and Michael Zimmerman. Integral Ecology: Uniting Multiple
Perspectives on the Natural World. Boston: Integral Books, 2009.
Escobar, Arturo. “Culture Sits in Places: Reflections on Globalism and Subaltern Strategies
of Localization.” Political Geography 20 (2001): 139–174.
Evernden, Neil. “The Environmentalists’ Dilemma.” In The Paradox of Environmentalism,
ed. Neil Evernden. Downsview: York University, 1984.
_____. “Ecology in Conservation and Conversation.” In After Earth Day: Continuing the
Conservation Effort, ed. Max Oelschlaeger. Denton, Tex.: University of North Texas
Press, 1992.
_____. The Social Creation of Nature. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992.
_____. The Natural Alien: Humankind and Environment, 2nd ed. Toronto: University of
Toronto Press, 1993.
_____. Interviewed by Derrick Jensen. In Listening to the Land: Conversations About Nature,
Culture, and Eros, ed. Derrick Jensen. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
Finlayson, James Gordon. Habermas: A Very Short Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 2005.
Fischer, William F. “On the Phenomenological Approach to Psychopathology.” Journal of
Phenomenological Psychology 17.1 (1986): 65–76.
Fish, Lorraine. Nature, Culture, and Abnormal Appetites. VDM Verlag, 2009.
Fisher, Andy. “Toward a More Radical Ecopsychology.” Alternatives 22.3 (1996): 20–26.
_____. “To Praise Again: Phenomenology and the Project of Ecopsychology.” Spring 76
(2006): 153–174.
_____. “Ecopsychology as Radical Praxis. In Ecotherapy: Healing with Nature in Mind, ed.
Linda Buzzell and Craig Chalquist. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 2009.
_____. “Andy Fisher: The Ecopsychology Interview.” Ecopsychology 3.3 (2011): 167–173.
_____. “What is Ecopsychology? A Radical View.” In Ecopsychology: Science, Totems, and
the Technological Species, ed. Peter Kahn and Patricia Hasbach. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press, forthcoming 2012.
Fleischner, Thomas L. “Revitalizing Natural History.” Wild Earth (Summer 1999): 81–89.
Flynn, Bernard Charles. “Descartes and the Ontology of Subjectivity.” Man and World
16 (1983): 3–23.
Fodor, Iris E. “A Woman and Her Body: The Cycles of Pride and Shame.” In The Voice
of Shame: Silence and Connection in Psychotherapy, ed. Robert G. Lee and Gordon
Wheeler. San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1996.
Foltz, Bruce V. “On Heidegger and the Interpretation of the Environmental Crisis.”
Environmental Ethics 6 (1984): 323–338.
_____. Inhabiting the Earth: Heidegger, Environmental Ethics, and the Metaphysics of Nature.
Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1995.
Foner, Janet. “Surviving the ‘Mental Health’ System with Co-Counseling.” In Psychosocial
Approaches to Deeply Disturbed Persons, ed. Peter R. Breggin and E. Mark Stern.
New York: Haworth, 1996.
Foster, John Bellamy, Brett Clark, and Richard York. The Ecological Rift: Capitalism’s War
on the Earth. New York: Monthly Review Press, 2010.
Foster, John Bellamy. “The Dialectics of Nature and Marxist Ecology.” In Dialectics for the
New Century, ed. Bertell Ollman and Tony Smith. Basingstroke and New York:
Palgrave Macmillan, 2008.
Foster, Mary LeCron. “Body Process in the Evolution of Language.” In Giving the Body
Its Due, ed. Maxine Sheets-Johnstone. Albany: State University of New York Press,
1992.
Foster, Steven, and Meredith Little. The Book of the Vision Quest: Personal Transformation in
the Wilderness. Revised and Expanded ed. New York: Prentice Hall, 1988.
_____. The Roaring of the Sacred River: The Wilderness Quest for Vision and Self-Healing.
New York: Prentice Hall, 1989.
_____. Wilderness Vision Questing and the Four Shields of Human Nature. Moscow, Id.:
University of Idaho Wilderness Research Center, 1996.
Foster, Steven, with Meredith Little. The Four Shields: The Initiatory Seasons of Human
Nature. P.O. Box 55, Big Pine, Calif., 93513: Lost Borders Press, 1998.
Foti, Véronique. “Alterity and the Dynamics of Metaphor.” In Language Beyond
Postmodernism: Saying and Thinking in Gendlin’s Philosophy, ed. David Micheal
Levin. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1997.
Foucault, Michel. Madness and Civilization: A History of Insanity in the Age of Reason.
New York: Random House, 1965.
Four Worlds International Institute for Human and Community Development. The Sacred
Tree: Reflections on Native American Spirituality. Twin Lakes, Wis.: Lotus Light,
1985.
Fox, Dennis, Isaac Prilleltensky, and Stephanie Austin. Critical Psychology: An Introduction,
2nd ed. London: Sage, 2009.
Fox, Warwick. “The Deep Ecology-Ecofeminism Debate and Its Parallels.” Environmental
Ethics 11.1 (1989): 5–25.
_____. Toward a Transpersonal Ecology. Boston: Shambhala, 1990.
Frankl, Victor. Man’s Search for Meaning. New York: Pocket Books, 1963.
Freenberg, Andrew. “The Critical Theory of Technology.” Capitalism Nature Socialism
1:2 (1990), 17–31.
Freud, Sigmund. An Outline of Psychoanalysis. New York: Norton, 1949.
_____. The Ego and the Id. New York: Norton, 1960.
_____. Civilization and Its Discontents. New York: Norton, 1961.
_____. Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis. Harmondsworth, England: Pelican, 1973.
_____. “Beyond the Pleasure Principle.” In On Metapsychology. London: Penguin, 1991.
_____. New Introductory Lectures on Psychoanalysis. London: Penguin, 1991.
_____. “The Future of an Illusion.” In Civilization, Society and Religion. London: Penguin,
1991.
Fromm, Erich. The Sane Society. New York: Fawcett World Library, 1955.
_____. The Art of Loving. New York: Bantam, 1956.
Gadamer, Hans-Georg. Philosophical Hermeneutics. Berkeley, Calif.: University of
California Press, 1976.
_____. “Practical Philosophy as a Model of the Human Sciences.” Research in Phenomenology
9 (1979): 74–85.
_____. “The Hermeneutics of Suspicion.” In Hermeneutics: Questions and Prospects, ed.
Gary Shapiro and Alan Sica. Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1984.
_____. “The Problem of Historical Consciousness.” In Interpretive Social Science: A Second
Look, ed. Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan. Berkeley, Calif.: University of
California Press, 1987.
_____. Truth and Method. Second Revised ed. New York: Crossroads, 1989.
_____. “The Politics of Giving Therapy Away: Listening and Focusing.” In Teaching
Psychological Skills: Models for Giving Therapy Away, ed. D. Larson. Monterey,
Calif.: Brooks/Cole, 1984.
_____, with Doralee Grindler, and Mary McGuire. “Imagery, Body, and Space in
Focusing.” In Imagination and Healing, ed. Anees A. Sheikh. Farmingdale, N.Y.:
Baywood, 1984.
_____. “Nonlogical Moves and Nature Metaphors.” In Analecta Husserliana, ed. A-T
Tymieniecka. Boston: D. Reidel, 1985. Vol. XIX.
_____. Experiential Psychotherapy (Draft). Chicago: The Focusing Institute, 1986.
_____. Let Your Body Interpret Your Dreams. Wilmette, Ill.: Chiron, 1986.
_____. “Process Ethics and the Political Question.” In Analecta Husserliana, ed. A-T.
Tymieniecka. Boston: D. Reidel Publishing Company, 1986. Vol. XX.
_____. “A Philosophical Critique of the Concept of Narcissism: The Significance of the
Awareness Movement.” In Pathologies of the Modern Self: Postmodern Studies on
Narcissism, Schizophrenia, and Depression, ed. David Michael Levin. New York:
New York University Press, 1987.
_____. “Dwelling.” In The Horizons of Continental Philosophy, ed. Hugh J. Silverman, et al.
Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic, 1988.
_____. “Schizophrenia: Problems and Methods of Psychotherapy.” Review of Existential
Psychology and Psychiatry 20.1–3 (1990): 181–191.
_____. “The Small Steps of the Therapy Process: How They Come and How to Help
Them Come.” In Client-Centred and Experiential Psychotherapy in the Nineties,
ed. G. Lietaer, J. Rombants and R. Van Balen. Leuven/Louvain, Belgium: Leuven
University Press, 1990.
_____. “On Emotion in Therapy.” In Emotion, Psychotherapy and Change, ed. J. D. Safran
and L. S. Greenberg. New York: Guilford, 1991.
_____. “Meaning Prior to the Separation of the Five Senses.” In Current Issues in Linguistic
Meaning, 73: Current Advances in Semantic Theory, ed. Max Stamenov. Amsterdam/
Philadelphia: John Benjamins, 1992.
_____. “The Primacy of the Body, Not the Primacy of Perception.” Man and World 00
(1992): 341–353.
_____. “The Wider Role of Bodily Sense in Thought and Language.” In Giving the Body Its
Due, ed. Maxine Sheets-Johnstone. Albany: SUNY Press, 1992.
_____. “Thinking Beyond Patterns.” In The Presence of Feeling in Thought, ed. B. den
Ouden and M. Moen. New York: Peter Lang, 1992.
_____ “Human Nature and Concepts.” In Psychological Aspects of Modernity, ed. Jerome
Braun. Westport, Conn.: Praeger, 1993.
_____. “Celebrations and Problems of Humanistic Psychology.” In The Humanistic
Movement: Recovering the Person in Psychology, ed. Frederick J. Wertz. Lake Worth,
Fla.: Gardner, 1994.
______. “Crossing and Dipping: Some Terms for Approaching the Interface between
Natural Understanding and Logical Formulation.” From the world wide web site:
www.focusing.org. Also in Mind and Machines 5.4 (1995): 547–560.
_____. Focusing-Oriented Psychotherapy. New York: Guilford, 1996.
_____. “Philosophy—Beyond Post-Modernism.” New York: The Focusing Institute, 1996.
From the world wide web site: www.focusing.org.
_____. A Process Model. New York: The Focusing Institute, 1997.
_____. “How Philosophy Cannot Appeal to Experience, and How It Can.” In Language
Beyond Postmodernism: Saying and Thinking in Gendlin’s Philosophy, ed. David
Michael Levin. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1997.
Gendlin, Eugene, T. “Introduction to ‘Thinking at the Edge.’” The Folio 19 (2004): 1–8.
Gergen, Kenneth J. “Emerging Challenges for Theory and Psychology.” Theory and
Psychology 1.1 (1991): 13–35.
Gifford, Robert. Environmental Psychology: Principles and Practice, 4th ed. Colville, Wash.:
Optimal Books, 2007.
_____. “Psychology’s Essential Role in Alleviating the Impacts of Climate Change.”
Canadian Psychology 49.4 (2008): 273–280.
Gill, Jerry H. Merleau-Ponty and Metaphor. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press,
1991.
Gilligan, Carol. In a Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1982.
Gilmore, David D. Manhood in the Making: Cultural Concepts of Masculinity. New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1990.
Giorgi, Amedeo. “Whither Humanistic Psychology?” In The Humanistic Movement:
Recovering the Person in Psychology, ed. Frederick J. Wertz. Lake Worth, Fla.:
Gardner Press, 1994.
Giroux, Henry A. Theory and Resistance in Education: Toward a Pedagogy for the Opposition,
rev. and expanded ed. Westport, Conn.: Bergin & Garvey, 2001.
Giroux, Henry, et al. “The Need for Cultural Studies: Resisting Intellectuals and
Oppositional Public Spheres.” Dalhousie Review 64.2 (1984): 472–486. Retrieved
from http://theory:eserver.org/need.html, August 12, 2003.
Glendinning, Chellis. My Name Is Chellis and I’m in Recovery from Western Civilization.
Boston: Shambhala, 1994.
_____. “Yours Truly From Indian Country.” Yoga Journal January/February (1995): 79–85.
_____. Chiva: A Village Takes on the Global Heroin Trade. Gabriola Island, B.C: New
Society, 2005.
Goldfarb, Mica “Making the Unknown Known: Art as the Speech of the Body.” In Giving
the Body Its Due, ed. Maxine Sheets-Johnstone. Albany: State University of New
York Press, 1992.
Gomes, Mary E. “Personal Transformation and Social Change: Conversations with
Ecopsychologists in Action.” The Humanistic Psychologist 26. 1–3 (1998), 217–241.
_____. “Altars of Extinction.” In Ecotherapy: Healing with Nature in Mind, ed. Linda
Buzzell and Craig Chalquist. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books, 2009.
Gomes, Mary E., and Allen D. Kanner. “The Rape of the Well-Maidens: Feminist
Psychology and the Environmental Crisis.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth,
Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San
Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
Goodman, Paul. New Reformation. New York: Random House, 1970.
_____. Nature Heals. New York: Free Life Editions, 1977.
Gottlieb, Roger S. Marxism 1844–1990: Origins, Betrayal, Rebirth. New York: Routledge,
1992.
Grange, Joseph. “Being, Feeling, and Environment.” Environmental Ethics 7 (1985):
351–364.
Greenaway, Twilight. “Is Walmart Allergic to Pollan?” Grist, Oct 6, 2011. Retrieved from
http://www.grist.org/food/2011-10-06-walmart-allergic-to-pollan, December 7, 2011.
Greenberg, Jay, and Stephen Mitchell. Object Relations in Psychoanalytic Theory. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1983.
Greenway, Robert. “Notes in Search of an Ecopsychology,” Unpublished paper presented
at the first Esalen Institute Ecopsychology Conference. Big Sur, California, July,
1993.
_____. “Psychoecology as a Search for Language.” Unpublished draft, 1994.
_____. “The Wilderness Effect and Ecopsychology.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth,
Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner.
San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
_____. “Robert Greenway: The Ecopsychology Interview.” Ecopsychology 1.1 (2009): 47–52.
Grene, Marjorie. “The Paradoxes of Historicity.” Review of Metaphysics 32 (1978): 15–36.
Griffin, Susan. A Chorus of Stones. New York: Doubleday, 1992.
Grof, Christina, and Stanislav Grof. The Stormy Search for the Self. Los Angeles: Jeremy
P. Tarcher, 1990.
Grof, Stanislav. The Adventure of Self-Discovery: Dimensions of Consciousness and New
Perspectives in Psychotherapy and Inner Exploration. Albany: SUNY Press, 1985.
Haraway, Donna J. Primate Visions: Gender, Race, and Nature in the World of Modern
Science. New York: Routledge, 1989.
Harman, Chris. Zombie Capitalism: Global Crisis and the Relevance of Marx. Chicago:
Haymarket, 2010.
Harris, Ian. “How Environmentalist Is Buddhism?” Religion 21 (1991): 101–114.
_____. “Buddhist Environmental Ethics and Detraditionalization: The Case of
EcoBuddhism.” Religion 25 (1995): 199–211.
Harvey, David. “The Nature of Environment: Dialectics of Social and Environmental
Change.” In Real Problems, False Solutions, Socialist Register 1993, ed. Ralph
Milband and Leo Panitch. London: Merlin Press, 1993.
_____. The Enigma of Capital: And the Crises of Capitalism. London: Profile Books, 2010.
Harvey, Graham. Animism: Respecting the Living World. New York: Columbia University
Press, 2006.
Harvey, Irene E. “Schizophrenia and Metaphysics: Analyzing the DSM-III.” In Pathologies
of the Modern Self: Postmodern Studies on Narcissism, Schizophrenia, and Depression,
ed. David Michael Levin. New York: New York University Press, 1987.
Hatab, Lawrence J. Myth and Philosophy. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1990.
Hauser, Gerard A., and Donald P. Cushman. “McKeon’s Philosophy of Communication:
The Architectonic and Interdisciplinary Arts.” Philosophy & Rhetoric 6.4 (1973):
211–234.
Heelan, Patrick A. “Why a Hermeneutical Philosophy of the Natural Sciences?” Man and
World 30 (1997): 271–298.
Heidegger, Martin. An Introduction to Metaphysics. New Haven: Yale University Press,
1959.
_____. Being and Time. New York: Harper & Row, 1962.
_____. Discourse on Thinking. New York: Harper & Row, 1966.
_____. On the Way to Language. New York: Harper & Row, 1971.
_____. Poetry, Language, Thought. New York: Harper & Row, 1971.
_____. Basic Writings. New York: Harper & Row, 1977.
_____. The Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays. New York: Harper & Row,
1977.
_____. “The Fieldpath.” Journal of Chinese Philosophy 13 (1986): 455–458.
Heinberg, Richard. The End of Growth: Adapting to Our New Economic Reality. Gabriola
Island, B.C.: New Society, 2011.
Held, David. Introduction to Critical Theory. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1980.
Hendricks, M. Excerpts from “Focusing Oriented/Experiential Psychotherapy.” In
Humanistic Psychotherapies: Handbook of Research and Practice, ed. D. Cain and
J. Seeman. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological Association, 2001.
Henry, Jules. Culture Against Man. New York: Vintage, 1963.
Herman, Judith. Trauma and Recovery. New York: Basic Books, 1997.
Herndl, Carl G., and Stuart C. Brown, eds. Green Culture: Environmental Rhetoric in
Contemporary America. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1996.
Hillman, James. The Dream and the Underworld. New York: Harper & Row, 1979.
_____. “Anima Mundi: The Return of the Soul to the World.” Spring (1982): 71–93.
_____. “Let the Creatures Be: An Interview with James Hillman.” Parabola 8.2 (1983):
49–53.
_____. “The Animal Kingdom in the Human Dream.” In Eranos Jabruch, ed. Rudolf
Ritsema. Frankfurt a/M: Insel Verlag, 1983. Vol. 51.
_____. “Going Bugs.” Spring (1988): 40–72.
_____. Re-Visioning Psychology. New York: Harper Perennial, 1992.
_____. “Animal Presence.” (Interview by Jonathon White.) In Talking on the Water, ed.
Jonathon White. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1994.
_____. “Notes on Opportunism.” In Puer Papers, ed. James Hillman. Dallas: Spring,
1994.
_____. “A Psyche the Size of the Earth.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth, Healing the
Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco:
Sierra Club, 1995.
_____. “Aesthetics and Politics.” Tikkun 11.6 (1996): 38–40, 75–76.
_____, and Michael Ventura. We’ve Had a Hundred Years of Psychotherapy and the World’s
Getting Worse. New York: HarperCollins, 1992.
Hood, Robert. “Recovering Green Identity: Paul Shepard’s Archeology of Self.” In The
Company of Others: Essays in Celebration of Paul Shepard, ed. Max Oelschlaeger.
Durago, Colo.: Kivakí, 1995.
Horkheimer, Max. Eclipse of Reason. New York: Continuum, 1947.
_____, and Theodor W. Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment. New York: Herder and
Herder, 1972.
Hull, Fritz. Earth and Spirit: The Spiritual Dimension of the Ecological Crisis. New York:
Continuum, 1993.
Hviding, Edvard. “Nature, Culture, Magic, Science: On Meta-Languages for Comparison
in Cultural Ecology.” In Nature and Society: Anthropological Perspectives, ed. Philippe
Descola & Gísli Pálsson. London: Routledge, 1996.
Hynes, Mary Ellen. “Walking in a World of Wounds: The Work of Donna Meadows.”
CenterPiece (1994): 10–11, 15.
Ilardi, Stephen S. The Depression Cure. Cambrdige, Mass.: DaCapo Press, 2009.
Ingleby, David. “Understanding ‘Mental Illness.’” In Critical Psychiatry, ed. David Ingleby.
New York: Pantheon, 1980.
Ingold, Tim. The Appropriation of Nature: Essays on Human Ecology and Social Relations.
Iowa City: University of Iowa Press, 1987.
_____. The Perception of the Environment: Essays on Livelihood, Dwelling and Skill. London:
Routledge, 2000.
_____. Being Alive: Essays on Movement, Knowledge and Description. London: Routledge,
2011.
Ingram, Catherine. In the Footsteps of Gandhi: Conversations with Spiritual Social Activists.
Berkeley, Calif.: Parallax, 1990.
Ivakhiv, Adrian. Claiming Sacred Ground: Pilgrims and Politics at Glastonbury and Sedona.
Bloomington & Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 2001.
Jackins, Harvey. How “Re-evaluation Counseling” Began. Seattle: Rational Island, 1994.
_____. The List: Everything I Know About Re-Evaluation Counselling (and the World) Until
Now, 2nd ed. Seattle: Rational Island, 1997.
Jacoby, Russell. Social Amnesia: A Critique of Conformist Psychology from Adler to Laing.
Boston: Beacon, 1975.
Jaffe, Aniela. “Symbolism in the Visual Arts.” In Man and His Symbols, ed. Carl Jung.
New York: Dell, 1964.
Jameson, Fredric. “Postmodernism, or The Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism.” New Left
Review 146 (1984): 53–92.
_____. “Persistencies of the Dialectic.” In Dialectics for the New Century, ed. Bertell Ollman
and Tony Smith. Basingstroke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008.
Jenks, Chris. “Introduction: Constituting the Child.” In The Sociology of Childhood:
Essential Readings, ed. Chris Jenks. London: Batsford Academic and Educational
Ltd., 1982.
Johnson, Will. The Posture of Meditation. Boston: Shambhala, 1996.
Jonas, Hans. The Phenomenon of Life. New York: Delta, 1966.
Jones, Ken. The New Social Face of Buddhism. Wisdom Publications, 2003.
_____. The Social Face of Buddhism: An Approach to Political and Social Activism. London:
Wisdom, 1989.
Jung, C. G. “Approaching the Unconscious.” In Man and His Symbols, ed. C.G. Jung.
New York: Dell, 1964.
Jung, C. G. Memories, Dreams, Reflections. New York: Vintage, 1965.
_____. The Portable Jung, ed. Joseph Campbell. New York: Penguin, 1971.
_____. C. G. Jung: Letters, ed. G. Adler. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1973
(Vol. 1.), 1975 (Vol. 2).
Jung, Hwa Yol. “The Ecological Crisis: A Philosophical Perspective, East and West.”
Bucknell Review 20.3 (1972): 25–44.
Kahn, Jr., Peter H. The Human Relationship with Nature: Development and Culture.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1999.
Kahn, Jr., Peter H., and Patricia Hasbach, eds. Ecopsychology: Science, Totems, and the
Technological Species. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, forthcoming 2012.
Kahn, Jr., Peter H., and Stephen R. Kellert, eds. Children and Nature: Psychological,
Sociocultural and Evolutionary Investigations. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 2002.
Kane, Sean. Wisdom of the Mythtellers. Peterborough: Broadview Press, 1994.
Kanner, Allen D. “The Voice of the Earth: A Review.” The Trumpeter 9.4 (1992): 169–170.
_____. “Mount Rushmore Syndrome: When Narcissism Rules the Earth.” The Humanistic
Psychologist 26.1–3 (1998), 101–122.
Kanner, Allen D., and Mary E. Gomes. “The All-Consuming Self.” In Ecopsychology:
Restoring the Earth, Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and
Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
Kaplan, Rachel, and Stephen Kaplan. The Experience of Nature. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1989.
Karon, Bertram P., and Leighton C. Whitaker. “Psychotherapy and the Fear of
Understanding Schizophrenia.” In Psychosocial Approaches to Deeply Disturbed
Persons, ed. Peter R. Breggin and E. Mark Stern. New York: Haworth, 1996.
Kasser, Tim, and Allen Kanner. “Where Is the Psychology of Consumer Culture?” In
Psychology and Consumer Culture: The Struggle for a Good Life in a Materialistic World,
ed. Tim Kasser and Allen Kanner. Washington, D.C.: American Psychological
Association, 2003.
Kaza, Stephanie. The Attentive Heart: Conversations with Trees. New York: Fawcett
Columbine, 1993.
Kearney, Richard. Poetics of Modernity: Toward a Hermeneutic Imagination. New Jersey:
Humanities, 1995.
Keller, Evelyn Fox. Reflections on Gender and Science. New Haven: Yale University Press,
1985.
Kepner, James I. Body Process: Working with the Body in Psychotherapy. San Francisco: Jossey-
Bass, 1993.
_____. Healing Tasks: Psychotherapy with Adult Survivors of Childhood Abuse. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass, 1995.
Kerényi, Karl. Hermes: Guide of Souls. Dallas: Spring, 1976.
Keung, Nicholas. “Can you actually make your child smarter?” The Toronto Star June 13,
1999: BE3.
Kheel, Marti. “Ecofeminism and Deep Ecology: Reflections on Identity and Difference.”
In Reweaving the World: The Emergence of Ecofeminism, ed. Irene Diamond and
Gloria Feman Orenstein. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1990.
Kidner, David W. “Why Psychology Is Mute About the Ecological Crisis.” Environmental
Ethics 16 (1994): 359–378.
_____. Nature and Psyche: Radical Environmentalism and the Politics of Subjectivity. Albany:
State University of New York Press, 2001.
_____. “Fraud, Fantasy, and Fiction in Environmental Writing.” Environmental Ethics 27
(2005): 391–410.
_____. “Depression and the Natural World: Towards a Critical Ecology of Psychological
Distress.” International Journal of Critical Psychology 19 (2007): 123–146.
Kincheloe, Joe L., and Peter L. McLaren. “Rethinking Critical Theory and Qualitative
Research.” In Handbook of Qualitative Research, ed. Norman K. Denzin and Yvonna
S. Lincoln. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage, 1994.
King, Ynestra. “The Ecology of Feminism and the Feminism of Ecology.” In Healing the
Wounds: The Promise of Ecofeminism, ed. Judith Plant. Toronto: Between the Lines,
1989.
_____. “Healing the Wounds: Feminism, Ecology, and the Nature/Culture Dualism.”
In Reweaving the World: The Emergence of Ecofeminism, ed. Irene Diamond and
Gloria Feman Orenstein. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1990.
Kirsner, Douglas. The Schizoid World of Jean-Paul Sartre and R. D. Laing. Atlantic
Highlands, N.J.: Humanities, 1977.
Kleese, Deborah A. “Toward an Ecological Epistemology for Psychology.” The Trumpeter
6.4 (1989): 137–143.
Kleinman, Arthur. Rethinking Psychiatry: From Cultural Category to Personal Experience.
New York: Free Press, 1988.
Kline, Stephen, and William Leiss. “Advertising, Needs, and ‘Commodity Fetishism.’”
Canadian Journal of Political and Social Theory 2.1 (1978): 5–30.
Kockelmans, Joseph J. “On the Hermeneutical Nature of Modern Natural Science.” Man
and World 30 (1997): 299–313.
Koenig, Thomas R. “Ricoeur’s Interpretation of the Relation between Phenomenological
Philosophy and Psychoanalysis.” Journal of Phenomenological Psychology 13.2
(1982), 115–142.
Koger, Susan M., and Deborah Du Nann Winter. The Psychology of Environmental Problems,
3rd ed. New York: Psychology Press, 2010.
Kögler, Hans Herbert. The Power of Dialogue: Critical Hermeneutics after Gadamer and
Foucault. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1999.
Kohák, Erazim. The Embers and the Stars. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1984.
Konner, Melvin J. “Maternal Care, Infant Behavior and Development Among the !Kung.”
In Kalahari Hunter-Gatherers, ed. Richard B. Lee and Irene DeVore. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1976.
Kornfield, Jack. A Path With Heart: A Guide Through the Perils and Promises of Spiritual Life.
New York: Bantam, 1993.
Kovel, Joel. “Things and Words: Metapsychology and the Historical Point of View.”
Psychoanalysis and Contemporary Thought 1.1 (1978): 21–88.
_____. “The American Mental Health Industry.” In Critical Psychiatry, ed. David Ingleby.
New York: Pantheon, 1980.
_____. The Age of Desire: Case Histories of a Radical Psychoanalyst. New York: Pantheon,
1981.
_____. White Racism: A Psychohistory. New York: Columbia University Press, 1984.
_____. “Schizophrenic Being and Technological Society.” In Pathologies of the Modern Self:
Postmodern Studies in Narcissism, Schizophrenia, and Depression, ed. David Michael
Levin. New York: New York University Press, 1987.
_____. “Freud’s Ontology—Agency and Desire: Commentary on Hubert L. Dreyfus and
Jerome Wakefield.” In Hermeneutics and Psychological Theory: Interpretive Perspectives
on Personality, Psychotherapy, and Psychopathology, ed. Stanley B. Messer, Louis
A. Sass and Robert L. Woolfolk. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1988.
_____. “On the Notion of Human Nature: A Contribution Toward a Philosophical
Anthropology” and “Rejoinder to Kenneth J. Gergen.” In Hermeneutics and
Psychological Theory: Interpretive Perspectives on Personality, Psychotherapy, and
Psychopathology, ed. Stanley B. Messer, Louis A. Sass and Robert L. Woolfolk.
New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1988.
_____. The Radical Spirit: Essays on Psychoanalysis and Society. London: Free Association,
1988.
_____. “A Critique of DSM-III.” Research in Law, Deviance and Social Control 9 (1988):
127–146.
_____. History and Spirit. Boston: Beacon, 1991.
_____. “Anticommunism and the Denial of the Primitive.” In Civilization in Crisis:
Anthropological Perspectives, ed. Christine Ward Gailey. Gainesville: University Press
of Florida, 1992.
Lee, Richard B., and Irene DeVore, eds. Kalahari Hunter-Gatherers. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press, 1976.
Lee, Robert G. “Shame and the Gestalt Model.” In The Voice of Shame: Silence and
Connection in Psychotherapy, ed. Robert G. Lee and Gordon Wheeler. San Francisco:
Jossey-Bass, 1996.
LeGuin, Ursula K. Buffalo Gals; And Other Animal Presences. New York: ROC (Penguin),
1987.
Leiss, William. The Domination of Nature. Boston: Beacon, 1974.
_____. “The Imperialism of Human Needs.” The North American Review 259 (1974):
27–34.
_____. The Limits to Satisfaction: An Essay on the Problem of Needs and Commodities.
Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1976.
Leopold, Aldo. A Sand County Almanac; And Sketches Here and There. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1949.
Leslie Gray, “Shamanic Counseling and Ecopsychology.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring
the Earth, Healing the Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen
D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
Levin, David Michael. “Sanity and Myth in Affective Space: A Discussion of Merleau-
Ponty.” The Philosophical Forum 14.2 (1982–83): 157–189.
_____. “Eros and Psyche: A Reading of Merleau-Ponty.” Review of Existential Psychology
and Psychiatry 18.1–3 (1982–83): 219–239.
_____. “Logos and Psyche: A Hermeneutics of Breathing.” Research in Phenomenology 14
(1984): 121–147.
_____. The Body’s Recollection of Being: Phenomenological Psychology and the Deconstruction
of Nihilism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1985.
_____. “Clinical Stories: A Modern Self in the Fury of Being.” In Pathologies of the Modern
Self: Postmodern Studies on Narcissism, Schizophrenia, and Depression, ed. David
Michael Levin. New York: New York University Press, 1987.
_____. “Introduction.” In Pathologies of the Modern Self: Postmodern Studies on Narcissism,
Schizophrenia, and Depression, ed. Dvaid Michael Levin. New York: New York
University Press, 1987.
_____. “Psychopathology in the Epoch of Nihilism.” In Pathologies of the Modern Self:
Postmodern Studies on Narcissism, Schizophrenia, and Depression, ed. David Michael
Levin. New York: New York University Press, 1987.
_____. The Opening of Vision: Nihilism and the Postmodern Condition. New York:
Routledge, 1988.
_____. The Listening Self: Personal Growth, Social Change and the Closure of Metaphysics.
London: Routledge, 1989.
_____. “Phenomenology in America.” Chicago: Unpublished Manuscript, 1991.
Published as “Phenomenology in America,” Philosophy and Social Criticism 17.2
(1991): 103–119.
Lowe, Walter James. “On Using Heidegger.” Soundings 60.3 (1977): 264–284.
Lowen, Alexander. Bioenergetics. New York: Penguin, 1975.
_____. Narcissism: Denial of the True Self. New York: Macmillan, 1985.
Löwy, Michael. “Contribution to the Debate on Climate Change.” Documents of
the FI: World Congresses: 16th World Congress – 2010, Climate Change
(www.internationalviewpoint.org).
_____. Interview by Foad Rad. “Resistance is the Only Way”: Michael Löwy Speaks on
Climate Change.” International Viewpoint Online Magazine: IV404 – Sept 2008
(www.internationalviewpoint.org).
Loy, David. “The Nonduality of Life and Death: A Buddhist View of Repression.”
Philosophy East and West 40.2 (1990): 151–174.
_____. “Trying to Become Real: A Buddhist Critique of Some Secular Heresies.”
International Philosophical Quarterly 32.4 (1992): 403–425.
_____. “Avoiding the Void: The Lack of Self in Psychotherapy and Buddhism.” Journal of
Transpersonal Psychology 24.2 (1992): 151–179.
_____. The Great Awakening: A Buddhist Social Theory. Boston: Wisdom, 2003.
Macy, Joanna Rogers. Despair and Personal Power in the Nuclear Age. Philadelphia:
New Society, 1983.
_____. “Buddhist Resources for Moving Through Nuclear Death.” In Heal or Die:
Psychotherapists Confront Nuclear Annihilation, ed. Keneth Porter, Deborah Rinzler
and Paul Olsen. New York: Psychohistory, 1987.
_____. World as Lover, World as Self. Berkeley, Cal.: Parallax, 1991.
_____, and Molly Young Brown. Coming Back to Life. Gabriola Island, B.C.: New Society,
1998.
Madison, Gary Brent. Hermeneutics of Postmodernity. Bloomington: Indiana University
Press, 1988.
Magdoff, Fred, and John Bellamy Foster. What Every Environmentalist Needs to Know about
Capitalism. New York: Monthly Review Pres, 2011.
Mahdi, Louise Carus, Steven Foster, and Meredith Little, eds. Betwixt and Between: Patterns
of Masculine and Feminine Initiation. La Salle, Ill.: Open Court, 1987.
Mahler, Margaret, Fred Pine, and Anni Bergmann. The Psychological Birth of the Human
Infant. New York: Basic Books, 1975.
Mander, Jerry. Four Arguments for the Elimination of Television. New York: William Morrow,
1978.
_____. In the Absence of the Sacred: The Failure of Technology and the Survival of the Indian
Nations. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1991.
Mann, Charles. “How Many Is Too Many?” The Atlantic Monthly (February 1993): 47–50,
52–53, 56, 59, 62–64, 66–67.
Marcuse, Herbert. Counterrevolution and Revolt. Boston: Beacon, 1972.
_____. “Ecology and Revolution.” In Ecology, ed. Carolyn Merchant. Atlantic Highlands,
N.J.: Humanities, 1994.
Martin, Calvin Luther. In the Spirit of the Earth: Rethinking History and Time. Baltimore:
The Johns Hopkins University Press, 1992.
_____. The Way of the Human Being. New Haven and London: Yale University Pres, 1999.
Masterson, James. The Search for the Real Self: Unmasking the Personality Disorders of Our
Age. New York: The Free Press, 1988.
Matthiessen, Peter. “Native Earth.” Parabola 6 (1981): 6–17.
_____. Nine-Headed Dragon River. Boston: Shambhala, 1985.
May, Rollo. Power and Innocence: A Search for the Sources of Violence. New York: Dell, 1972.
_____. “The Roots of Our Being.” Storytelling (1991): 16–19.
Mayeroff, Milton. On Caring. New York: Harper & Row, 1971.
McGuire, Kathleen. Building Supportive Community: Mutual Self-Help Through Peer-
Counselling. Cambridge, Mass.: Center for Supportive Community, 1981. Available
from Focusing Northwest, 3440 Onyx Street, Eugene, OR 97405, U.S.A.
_____. The Experiential Dimension in Psychotherapy. Eugene, Oreg.: Unpublished Working
Draft, 1984.
McKenzie-Mohr, Doug, and William Smith. Fostering Sustainable Behavior: An
Introduction to Community-Based Social Marketing. Gabriola Island, B.C.: New
Society, 1999.
McKeon, Richard. “Philosophy of Communication and the Arts.” In Perspectives in
Education, Religion and the Arts, ed. Howard E. Kiefer and Milton K. Munitz.
Albany: SUNY Press, 1970.
_____. “The Uses of Rhetoric in a Technological Age: Architectonic Productive Arts.”
In The Prospect of Rhetoric, ed. Lloyd F. Bitzer and Edwin Black. Englewood Cliffs,
N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1971.
McKibben, Bill. The End of Nature. New York: Random House, 1989.
McLaughlin, Andrew. Regarding Nature: Industrialism and Deep Ecology. Albany: SUNY
Press, 1993.
Meade, Michael. Men and the Water of Life: Initiation and the Tempering of Men. New York:
HarperCollins, 1993.
_____. “Foreword” to Mircea Eliade, Rites and Symbols of Initiation: The Mysteries of Birth
and Rebirth. Woodstock, Conn.: Spring, 1995.
Medin, Douglas, Sandra Waxman, Jennie Woodring, and Karen Washinawatok. “Human-
Centeredness is Not a Universal Feature of Young Children’s Reasoning: Culture
and Experience Matter when Reasoning about Biological Entities.” Cognitive
Development 25 (2010): 197–207.
Meeker, Joseph. “Talking with Paul.” In The Company of Others: Essays in Celebration of
Paul Shepard, ed. Max Oelschlaeger. Durango, Colo.: Kivakí, 1995.
Melamed, Melissa. “Reclaiming the Power to Act.” Therapy Now (1984).
Merchant, Carolyn. The Death of Nature: Women, Ecology and the Scientific Revolution.
San Francisco: Harper & Row, 1980.
_____. Radical Ecology: The Search for a Livable World. New York: Routledge, 1992.
Nabhan, Gary Paul, and Stephen Trimble. The Geography of Childhood: Why Children Need
Wild Places. Boston: Beacon, 1994.
Naess, Arne. “The Shallow and the Deep, Long-Range Ecology Movement. A Summary.”
Inquiry 16 (1973): 95–100.
_____. “Identification as a Source of Deep Ecological Attitudes.” In Deep Ecology, ed.
Michael Tobias. San Diego: Avant, 1985.
_____. “Self Realization: An Ecological Approach to Being in the World.” In Thinking
Like a Mountain: Towards a Council of All Beings, ed. John Seed, et al. Philadelphia:
New Society, 1988.
Nanamoli (Bhikkhu). The Life of the Buddha. Kandy, Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication
Society, 1992.
Naranjo, Claudio. The Techniques of Gestalt Therapy. Highland, N.Y.: Gestalt Journal Press, 1980.
Natanson, Maurice. “The Limits of Rhetoric.” In Philosophy, Rhetoric and Argumentation,
ed. Maurice Natanson and Henry W. Johnstone. University Park, Penn.:
Pennsylvania State University Press, 1965.
_____. “Rhetoric and Philosophical Argumentation.” In Philosophy, Rhetoric and
Argumentation, ed. Maurice Natanson and Henry W. Johnstone. University Park,
Penn.: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1965.
Neihardt, John G. Black Elk Speaks. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1979.
Nelson, Richard K. Make Prayers to the Raven: A Koyukon View of the Northern Forest.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1983.
_____. The Island Within. Vancouver: Douglas & McIntyre, 1989.
_____.“Exploring the Near at Hand: An Interview with Richard Nelson.” Parabola 16.2
(1991): 35–43.
_____. “Searching for the Lost Arrow: Physical and Spiritual Ecology in the Hunter’s
World.” In The Biophilia Hypothesis, ed. Stephen Kellert and E. O. Wilson.
Washington, D.C.: Island, 1993
_____. “Life-Ways of the Hunter.” (Interview by Jonathon White.) In Talk on the Water:
Conversations About Nature and Creativity, ed. Jonathon White. San Francisco:
Sierra Club, 1994.
Nelson, Toni. “Violence Against Women.” World Watch (July/August, 1996): 33–38.
Nhat Hanh, Thich. Interbeing: Fourteen Guidelines for Engaged Buddhism. Rev. ed. Berkeley:
Parallax, 1993.
_____. “Love in Action.” In The Soul of Nature, ed. Michael Tobias. New York: Continuum,
1994.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. The Will to Power. New York: Random House, 1967.
Noble, David F. Progress Without People: New Technology, Unemployment, and the Message of
Resistance. Toronto: Between the Lines, 1995.
_____. The Religion of Technology: The Divinity of Man and the Spirit of Invention. NewYork:
Alfred A. Knopf, 1998.
Nonnekes, Paul. “The Intertwining Wildness of Flesh-Child Becoming.” Undercurrents 2
(1990): 20–27.
Norris, Christopher. Deconstruction: Theory and Practice. Revised ed. London: Routledge,
1991.
Norwood, Ken, and Kathleen Smith. Rebuilding Community in America: Housing for
Ecological Living, Personal Power, and the New Extended Family. Berkeley, Calif.:
Shared Living Resource Center (2375 Shattuck Ave., Berkeley, CA, 94704, U.S.A.),
1995.
Nyantiloka. Buddhist Dictionary: Manual of Buddhist Terms and Doctrines. Kandy,
Sri Lanka: Buddhist Publication Society, 1980.
O’Connor, James. “Socialism and Ecology.” In Ecology, ed. Carolyn Merchant. Atlantic
Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1994.
_____. Natural Causes: Essays in Ecological Marxism. New York: Guilford, 1998.
Oelschlaeger, Max. The Idea of Wilderness. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1991.
Ollman, Bertell, and Tony Smith, eds. Dialectics for the New Century. Basingstroke and
New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008.
Ollman, Bertell. Social and Sexual Revolution. Montreal: Black Rose, 1978.
_____. Dance of the Dialectic: Steps in Marx’s Method. Urbana: University of Illinois Press,
2003.
Ong, Walter J. Orality and Literacy: The Technologizing of the Word. London: Routledge,
1982.
Onions, T. C., ed. The Oxford Dictionary of English Etymology. London: Oxford University
Press, 1966.
Packer, Martin J. “Hermeneutic Inquiry in the Study of Human Conduct.” American
Psychologist 40.10 (1985): 1081–1093.
Packer, Martin J., and Richard B. Addison. “Introduction.” In Entering the Circle:
Hermeneutic Investigation in Psychology, ed. Martin J. Packer and Richard
B. Addison. Albany: State University of New York Press, 1989.
Palmer, Richard E. Hermeneutics. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1969.
_____. “On the Transcendability of Hermeneutics (A Response to Dreyfus).”
In Hermeneutics: Questions and Prospects, ed. Gary Shapiro and Alan Sica. Amherst:
University of Massachusetts Press, 1984.
Panikkar, R. Myth, Faith and Hermeneutics. New York: Paulist, 1979.
“Promoting Environmentalism.” Special Issue of Journal of Social Issues 56.3 (2000).
Parkes, Graham. “Human/Nature in Nietzsche and Taoism.” In Nature in Asian
Traditions of Thought, ed. J. Baird Callicott and Roger T. Ames. Albany: SUNY
Press, 1989.
Parlee, Bert, and ken Wilber. “Like it or Not, You’re A Capitalist. But Are You a Conscious
One?” Retrieved from http://integrallife.com/node/60699, December 14, 2011.
Perls, Frederick. Gestalt Therapy Verbatim. New York: Bantam, 1969.
_____. The Gestalt Approach and Eye Witness to Therapy. Palo Alto, Calif.: Science and
Behavior, 1973.
_____. Ego, Hunger and Aggression. Highland, N.Y.: Gestalt Journal Press, 1992.
_____, Ralph F. Hefferline, and Paul Goodman. Gestalt Therapy. New York: Dell, 1951.
Perls, Laura. “Comments on the New Directions.” In The Growing Edge of Gestalt Therapy,
ed. E. Smith. New York: Brunner/Mazel, 1976.
_____. Living at the Boundary. Highland, N.Y.: Gestalt Journal Press, 1992.
Plotkin, Bill. Nature and the Human Soul. Novato, CA: New World Library, 2008.
Plumwood, Val. “Ecosocial Feminism as a General Theory of Oppression.” In Ecology, ed.
Carolyn Merchant. Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities, 1994.
Pollan, Michael. The Omnivore’s Dilemma: A Natural History of Four Meals. New York:
Penguin, 2006.
_____. In Defense of Food: An Eater’s Manifesto. New York: Penguin, 2008.
Polster, Erving, and Miriam Polster. Gestalt Therapy Integrated. New York: Vintage, 1973.
Prilleltensky, Isaac. The Morals and Politics of Psychology: Psychological Discourse and the
Status Quo. Albany: SUNY Press, 1994.
Rabinow, Paul, and William M. Sullivan. “The Interpretive Turn: A Second Look.”
In Interpretive Social Science: A Second Look, ed. Paul Rabinow and William
M. Sullivan. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California Press, 1987.
Ram Dass. “Compassion: The Delicate Balance.” In Paths Beyond Ego: The Transpersonal
Vision, ed. Roger Walsh and Frances Vaughan. Los Angeles: Jeremy P. Tarcher, 1993.
Rapaport, Amos. “Australian Aborigines and the Definition of Place.” In Environmental
Design: Research and Practice. Proceedings of the EDRA 3/AR 8 Conference, University
of California at Los Angeles, ed. William J. Mitchell, 1972.
Rappaport, Roy. Ecology, Meaning, and Religion. Richmond, Calif.: North Atlantic Books,
1979.
Real, Terrence. I Don’t Want to Talk About It: Overcoming the Secret Legacy of Male Depression.
New York: Scribner, 1997.
Reser, Joseph P. “Wither Environmental Psychology? The Transpersonal Ecopsychology
Crossroads.” The Journal of Environmental Psychology 15 (1995): 235–257.
_____. “Thinking through ‘Conservation Psychology’: Prospects and Challenges.” Human
Ecology Review 10 (2003): 167–174.
Reser, Joseph. “Joseph Reser: The Ecopsychology Interview.” Ecopsychology 1.2 (2009):
57–63.
Rice, L. N., and L. S Greenberg. “Humanistic Approaches to Psychotherapy.” In History
of Psychotherapy: A Century of Change, ed. D. Freedheim. Washington, D.C.:
American Psychological Association, 1992.
Richards, Barry, ed. Capitalism and Infancy: Essays on Psychoanalysis and Politics. Atlantic
Highlands, N.J.: Humanities, 1984.
Richardson, William J. “Heidegger’s Critique of Science.” The New Scholasticism 42.4
(1968): 511–536.
Ricoeur, Paul. Freud and Philosophy: An Essay on Interpretation. New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1970.
_____.“The Model of the Text: Meaningful Action Considered as Text.” Social Research
38.3 (1971): 529–562.
_____. The Conflict of Interpretations. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1974.
Rorty, Richard. Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1979.
Rosen, Kim. Saved by a Poem: The Transformative Power of Words. Carlsbad, Cal.: Hay
House, 2009.
Rosen, Ruth. “Who Gets Polluted?: The Movement for Environmental Justice.” Dissent
(Spring 1994): 223–230.
Rosenfield, Lawrence W. “An Autopsy of the Rhetorical Tradition.” In The Prospect of
Rhetoric, ed. Lloyd F. Bitzer and Edwin Black. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-
Hall, 1971.
Ross, Rupert. Returning to the Teachings: Exploring Aboriginal Justice. Toronto: Penguin,
2006.
Roszak, Theodore. The Voice of the Earth: An Exploration of Ecopsychology. New York:
Simon & Schuster, 1992.
_____. “The Greening of Psychology.” The Ecopsychology Newsletter 1 (1994): 1.
_____. “The Greening of Psychology: Exploring the Ecological Unconscious.” The Gestalt
Journal 18.1 (1995): 9–46.
_____. “Where Psyche Meets Gaia.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth, Healing the
Mind, ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco:
Sierra Club, 1995.
_____. The Voice of the Earth: An Exploration of Ecopsychology, 2nd ed. Grand Rapids,
MI: Phanes Press, 2001.
Rothberg, Donald. “Buddhist Responses to Violence and War: Resources for Socially
Engaged Spirituality.” Journal of Humanistic Psychology 32.4 (1992): 41–75.
Rowe, Stan. Home Place. Edmonton: NeWest, 1990.
_____. “The Mechanical and the Organic: Virtual Reality and Nature.” Trumpeter 14.3
(1997): 154–158.
Royce, Joseph, and Leendert Mos. Humanistic Psychology: Concepts and Criticisms.
New York: Plenum, 1981.
Russell, Constance L., Anne C. Bell, and Leesa K. Fawcett. “Navigating the Waters of
Canadian Environmental Education.” In Progressive Educations in Canada, ed. Tara
Goldstein and David Selby. Toronto, Second Story, 1999. Pagination from draft
manuscript.
Salleh, Ariel, and Meira Hansen, “On Production and Reproduction, Identity and Non-
Identity in Ecofeminist Theory.” Organization and Development 12 (1992):
207–218.
_____. “The Ecofeminism/Deep Ecology Debate: A Reply to Patriarchal Reason.”
Environmental Ethics 14 (1992): 195–216.
_____. “Class, Race, and Gender Discourse in the Ecofeminism/Deep Ecology Debate.”
Environmental Ethics 15 (1993): 225–244.
_____. Ecofeminism as Politics: Nature, Marx, and the Postmodern. London:
Zed, 1997.
_____. “Global Alternatives and the Meta-Industrial Class.” In New Socialisms: Futures
Beyond Globalization, ed. Robert Albritton, Shannon Bell, John R. Bell, and
Richard Westra. London: Routledge, 2004.
Sampson, Edward E. “Cognitive Psychology as Ideology.” American Psychologist 36.7
(1981): 730–743.
_____. “The Debate on Individualism: Indigenous Psychologies of the Individual and
Their Role in Personal and Societal Functioning.” American Psychologist 43.1
(1988): 15–22.
_____. “The Challenge of Social Change for Psychology.” American Psychologist 44.6
(1989): 914–921.
San Roque, Craig. “On Tjukurrpa, Painting Up, and Building Thought.” Social Analysis
50.2 (2006): 148–172.
Sanua, Victor D. “The Myth of Organicity of Mental Disorders.” The Humanistic
Psychologist 24 (1996): 55–78.
Sardello, Robert. Love and the Soul: Creating a Future for Earth. New York: HarperCollins,
1995.
Sass, Louis A. “Humanism, Hermeneutics, and the Concept of the Human Subject.”
In Hermeneutics and Psychological Theory: Interpretive Perspectives on Personality,
Psychotherapy, and Psychopathology, ed. Stanley B. Messer, Louis A. Sass and Robert
L. Woolfolk. New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press, 1988.
Saunders, Carol D. “The Emerging Field of Conservation Psychology.” Human Ecology
Review 10.2 (2003): 137–149.
Scheff, T. J. “Reevaluation Counseling: Social Implications.” Journal of Humanistic
Psychology 12.1 (1972): 58–71.
_____. Catharsis in Healing, Ritual, and Drama. Berkeley, Calif.: University of California
Press, 1979.
_____. “Toward Integration in the Social Psychology of Emotions.” Annual Review of
Sociology 9 (1983): 333–354.
Scott, Susan S. Healing with Nature. New York: Helios, 2003.
Scull, John. “Ecopsychology: Where Does It Fit in 2009?” The Trumpeter 24.3 (2008),
68–85.
_____. “Tailoring Nature Therapy to the Client.” In Ecotherapy: Healing with Nature in
Mind, ed. Linda Buzzell and Craig Chalquist. San Francisco: Sierra Club Books,
2009.
Seamon, David. “The Phenomenological Contribution to Environmental Psychology.”
Journal of Environmental Psychology 2 (1982): 119–140.
_____, and Robert Mugerauer, eds. Dwelling, Place and Environment: Towards a
Phenomenology of Person and World. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff, 1985.
_____. “Goethe, Nature, and Phenomenology.” In Goethe’s Way of Science:
A Phenomenology of Nature, ed. David Seamon and Arthur Zajonc. Albany, NY:
SUNY Press, 1998.
_____. “Nature and Madness.” In Ecopsychology: Restoring the Earth, Healing the Mind,
ed. Theodore Roszak, Mary E. Gomes, and Allen D. Kanner. San Francisco: Sierra
Club, 1995.
_____. Interviewed by Derrick Jensen. In Listening to the Land: Conversations About Nature,
Culture, and Eros, ed. Derrick Jensen. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1995.
_____. “Virtual Hunting Reality in the Forests of Simulacra.” In Reinventing Nature?:
Responses to Postmodern Deconstruction, ed. Michael E. Soulé and Gary Lease.
Washington, D.C.: Island, 1995.
_____. The Only World We’ve Got. San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1996.
_____. The Others: How Animals Made Us Human. Washington, D.C.: Island, 1996.
_____. Traces of an Omnivore. Washington, D.C.: Island, 1996.
_____. Coming Home to the Pleistocene. Washington, D.C.: Island, 1998.
_____, and Barry Sanders. The Sacred Paw: The Bear in Nature, Myth, and Literature.
New York: Viking, 1985.
Shields, Katrina. In the Tiger’s Mouth: An Empowerment Guide for Social Action. Philadelphia:
New Society, 1994.
Shiva, Vandana. Earth Democracy: Justice, Sustainability, and Peace. Cambridge, Mass.:
South End, 2005.
Simms, Eva-Maria. “The Infant’s Experience of the World: Stern, Merleau-Ponty and the
Phenomenology of the Preverbal Self.” Humanistic Psychologist 21 (1993): 26–40.
_____. “Phenomenology of Child Development and the Postmodern Self: Continuing the
Dialogue with Johnson.” The Humanistic Psychologist 22 (1994): 228–235.
Sloan, Tod. Damaged Life: The Crisis of the Modern Psyche. London: Routledge, 1996.
Slotkin, Richard. “Dreams and Genocide: The American Myth of Regeneration Through
Violence.” Journal of Popular Culture 5.1 (1971): 38–59.
Slovic, Scott. “Epistemology and Politics in American Nature Writing: Embedded Rhetoric
and Discrete Rhetoric.” In Green Culture: Environmental Rhetoric in Contemporary
America, ed. Carl G. Herndl and Stuart C. Brown. Madison: University of
Wisconsin Press, 1996.
Smith, Laurence D. “Metaphors of Knowledge and Behavior in the Behaviorist Tradition.”
In Metaphors in the History of Psychology, ed. David E. Leary. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1990.
Snyder, Gary. Earth Household. New York: New Directions, 1957.
_____. Turtle Island. New York: New Directions, 1974.
_____. The Real Work: Interviews & Talks, 1964–1979. New York: New Directions, 1980.
_____. Interviewed by Catherine Ingram. In In the Footsteps of Gandhi: Conversations with
Spiritual Activists, ed. Catherine Ingram. Berkeley, Calif.: Parallax, 1990.
_____. The Practice of the Wild. San Francisco: North Point, 1990.
_____. No Nature. New York: Pantheon, 1992.
_____. “Hanging Out With Raven.” (Interviewed by Jonathon White.) In Talking
on the Water: Conversations About Nature and Creativity, ed. Jonathon White.
San Francisco: Sierra Club, 1994.
_____. A Place in Space: Ethics, Aesthetics, and Watersheds. Washington, D.C.: Counterpoint,
1995.
_____. Back on Fire. Berkeley: Counterpoint, 2007.
Sobel, David. Children’s Special Places. Detroit: Wayne State University Press, 2002.
_____. Beyond Ecophobia: Reclaiming the Heart in Nature Education. Great Barrington,
MA: The Orion Society and The Myrin Institute, 2004.
Sperling, Micheal B, and William H. Berman, eds. Attachment in Adults: Clinical and
Developmental Perspectives. New York: Guilford, 1994.
Spiegelberg, Herbert. The Phenomenological Movement, 3rd ed. The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff, 1984.
Spinosa, Charles, Fernando Flores, and Hubert L. Dreyfus. Disclosing New Worlds.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1997.
Steed, Judy. Our Little Secret: Confronting Child Sexual Abuse in Canada. Toronto: Vintage,
1995.
Steinberg, Marlene, and Maxine Schnall. The Stranger in the Mirror: Dissociation—The
Hidden Epidemic. New York: Quill, 2001.
Steiner, George. Heidegger. London: Fontana, 1978.
Stern, Paul C. “Psychological Dimensions of Global Environmental Change.” Annual
Review of Psychology 43 (1992): 269–302.
Stettbacher, J. Konrad. Making Sense of Suffering. New York: Meridian, 1990.
Stewart, David, and Algis Mickunus. Exploring Phenomenology. 2nd ed. Athens: Ohio
University Press, 1990.
Stoehr, Taylor. “Paul Goodman and the Political Dimensions of Gestalt Therapy.” The
Gestalt Journal 16.1 (1993): 55–90.
Stokols, Daniel, and Irwin Altman, eds. Handbook of Environmental Psychology. Malabar,
Fla.: Krieger, 1991.
Storr, Anthony. “Man’s Relationship with the Natural World.” The North American Review
259 (1974): 18–26.
Strong, David. “Wilderness’ Call for Openness.” Trumpeter 9.1 (1992): 10–14.
_____. Crazy Mountains: Learning from Wilderness to Weigh Technology. Albany: SUNY
Press, 1995.
Suzuki, D. T. “The Role of Nature in Zen Buddhism.” In Zen Buddhism: Selected
Writings of D. T. Suzuki, ed. William Barrett. Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday
Anchor, 1956.
Tandon, S. N. “Dharma—Its Definition and Universal Application.” In Dharma—Its True
Nature. An International Seminar (May 6–7, 1995), Dhamma Giri, Igatpuri, India:
Vipassana Research Institute, 1995.
Tanuro, Daniel. “Report on Climate Change.” Documents of the FI: International
Committee Reports, Draft for World Congress Discussion, 2009. Retrieved from
www.internationalviewpoint.org, August 29, 2011.
Taylor, Charles. “Understanding in Human Science.” Review of Metaphysics 34 (1980):
25–38.
_____. Human Agency and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985.
_____. “Interpretation and the Sciences of Man.” In Interpretive Social Science: A Second
Look, ed. Paul Rabinow and William M. Sullivan. Berkeley, Calif.: University of
California Press, 1987.
_____. “The Moral Topography of the Self.” In Hermeneutics and Psychological Theory:
Interpretive Perspectives on Personality, Psychotherapy, and Psychopathology, ed.
Stanley B. Messer, Louis A. Sass and Robert L. Woolfolk. New Brunswick: Rutgers
University Press, 1988.
_____. Sources of the Self: The Making of the Modern Identity. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press, 1989.
_____. The Malaise of Modernity. Concord, Ont.: House of Anansi, 1991.
_____. “Heidegger, Language, and Ecology.” In Heidegger: A Critical Reader, ed. Hubert
L. Dreyfus and Harrison Hall. Cambridge, Mass.: Blackwell, 1992.
Teo, Thomas. “Philosophical Concerns in Critical Psychology.” In Critical psychology:
An introduction, 2nd ed., ed. Dennis Fox, Isaac Prilleltensky, and Stephanie Austin.
Los Angeles: Sage (2009).
The Humanistic Psychologist 26.1–3 (1998). Special issue on Humanistic Psychology and
Ecopsychology.
“The School of Lost Borders.” Pamphlet. P.O. Box 55, Big Pine, Calif., 93513, U.S.A.
“The Three Gorges: The Case for Development.” Time (April 19, 1991): 51.
The Trumpeter 12:3 (1995). Issue on “Culture, Bioregionalism, Economics & the Deep
Ecology Movement.”
Thévenaz, Pierre. What Is Phenomenology? And Other Essays. Chicago: Quadrangle, 1962.
Thomas, Keith. Man and the Natural World. London: Penguin, 1983.
Thomashow, Mitchell. Ecological Identity: Becoming a Reflective Environmentalist.
Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1995.
Thomson, William Irwin. “Mind Jazz.” (Interviewed by David Cayley, et al.) Journal of
Wild Culture 2.4 (1990): 10–18.
Thorne, F. C. “Critique of Recent Developments in Personality Counselling Therapy.”
Journal of Clinical Psychology 13 (1957): 234–244.
Thornton, James. “The State of Environmentalists: A Report to the Nathan Cummings
Foundation and the Natural Resources Defence Council.” 1993.
Tokar, Brian. Earth for Sale: Reclaiming Ecology in the Age of Corporate Greenwash. Boston:
South End, 1997.
Trungpa, Chogyam. Shambhala: The Sacred Path of the Warrior. New York: Bantam, 1984.
Turnbull, Colin M. The Human Cycle. New York: Simon and Schuster, 1983.
Turner, Victor. The Ritual Process: Structure and Anti-Structure. Hawthorne, N.Y.: Aldine
de Gruyter, 1995.
Uzzell, David, and Nora Räthzel. “Transforming Environmental Psychology.” Journal of
Environmental Psychology 29 (2009): 340–350.
Valle, Ronald S., and Rolf von Eckartsberg, eds. The Metaphors of Consciousness. New York:
Plenum, 1981.
Van den Berg, J. H. The Changing Nature of Man. New York: Plenum, 1961.
_____. Things: Four Metabletic Reflections. Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1970.
_____. “What Is Psychotherapy.” Humanitas 7.3 (1971): 321–370.
_____. A Different Existence: Principles of Phenomenological Psychology. Pittsburgh:
Duquesne University Press, 1972.
Van der Kolk, Bessel A., Alexander C. McFarlane, and Lars Weisaeth, eds. Traumatic Stress:
The Effects of Overwhelming Experience on Mind, Body, and Society. New York:
Guilford, 1996.
Van Gennep, Arnold. The Rites of Passage. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1960.
Veitch, Russell, and Daniel Arkkelin. Environmental Psychology: An Interdisciplinary
Perspective. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice Hall, 1995.
Von Franz, Marie-Louise. “The Process of Individuation.” In Man and His Symbols, ed.
C. G. Jung. New York: Dell, 1964.
Vycinas, Vincent. Earth and Gods: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Martin Heidegger.
The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, 1961.
“What’s Wrong with the ‘Mental Health’ System: And What Can Be Done About It.”
A Draft Policy Prepared for the Re-evaluation Counseling Communities. P.O.
Box 2081, Main Office Station, Seattle, Wash., 98111, U.S.A.: Rational Island
Publishers, 1991.
Wallace, Karl R. “The Fundamentals of Rhetoric.” In The Prospect of Rhetoric, ed. Lloyd
F. Bitzer and Edwin Black. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1971.
Wallulis, Jerald. “Carrying Forward: Gadamer and Gendlin on History, Language, and the
Body.” In Language Beyond Postmodernism: Saying and Thinking in Gendlin’s Philosophy,
ed. David Micheal Levin. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press, 1997.
Warren, Karen J. “The Power and Promise of Ecological Feminism.” In Environmental
Philosophy: From Animal Rights to Radical Ecology, ed. Michael E. Zimmerman.
Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 1993.
Watkins, Mary, and Helene Shulman. Toward Psychologies of Liberation: Critical Theory
and Practice in Psychology and the Human Sciences. New York: Palgrave Macmillan,
2008.
Watkins, Mary. “From Individualism to the Interdependent Self.” Psychological Perspectives
27 (1992): 52–69.
_____. Invisible Guests: The Development of Imaginal Dialogues. Woodstock, CT: Spring
Publications, 2000.
_____. “Creating Restorative Ecotherapeutic Practices.” In Ecotherapy: Healing with
Nature in Mind, ed. Linda Buzzell and Craig Chalquist. San Francisco: Sierra Club
Books, 2009.
Watts, Alan. Psychotherapy East and West. New York: Vintage, 1961.
Webster’s Unabridged Dictionary of the English Language. New York: Portland House, 1989.
Weekley, Ernest. An Etymology Dictionary of Modern English. London: John Murray, 1921.
Welwood, John. “Meditation and the Unconscious: A New Perspective.” The Journal of
Transpersonal Psychology 9.1 (1977): 1–26.
Wertz, Frederick J., ed. The Humanistic Movement: Recovering the Person in Psychology. Lake
Worth, Fla.: Gardner Press, 1994.
Wheeler, Gordon. Gestalt Reconsidered: A New Approach to Contact and Resistance.
New York: Gardner Press, 1991.
_____. “Self and Shame: A New Paradigm for Psychotherapy.” In The Voice of Shame:
Silence and Connection in Psychotherapy, ed. Robert G. Lee and Gordon Wheeler.
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1996.
_____, and Daniel Jones. “Finding Our Sons: A Male-Male Gestalt.” In The Voice of Shame:
Silence and Connection in Psychotherapy, ed. Robert G. Lee and Gordon Wheeler.
San Francisco: Jossey-Bass, 1996.
White, Emily. “Greening the Blues.” The Ecologist (October, 2005): 56–60.
Wilber, Ken. Integral Psychology. Boston: Shambhala, 2000.
_____. Sex, Ecology, Spirituality: The Spirit of Evolution, 2nd ed. Boston: Shambhala,
2000.
_____. The Eye of Spirit: An Integral Vision for a World Gone Slightly Mad. Boston:
Shambhala, 2001.
_____. A Theory of Everything: An Integral Vision for Business, Politics, Science, and
Spirituality. Boston: Shambhala, 2001.
_____. A Brief History of Everything, 2nd ed. Boston: Shambhala, 2007.
Williams, Raymond. “Ideas of Nature.” In Ecology, The Shaping Enquiry, ed. Jonathan
Benthall. London: Longman, 1972.
_____. Keywords. London: Fontana Press, 1983.
Williams, Terry Tempest. Interviewed by Derrick Jensen. In Listening to the Land:
Conversations About Nature, Culture, and Eros, ed. Derrick Jensen. San Francisco:
Sierra Club, 1995.
Wilson, E. O. Biophilia. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1984.
Winner, Langdon. “Living in Electronic Space.” In Lifeworld and Technology, ed. Timothy
Casey and Lester Embree. Washington, D.C.: The Center for Advanced Research
in Phenomenology and University Press of America, 1989.
Winnicott, D. W. Playing and Reality. London: Routledge, 1971.
_____. The Maturational Processes and the Facilitating Environment. London: Karnac, 1990.
Woodburn, James. “Egalitarian Societies.” Man 17 (1981): 431–451.
Worster, Donald. Nature’s Economy: A History of Ecological Ideas. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1977.
_____. “The Ecology of Order and Chaos.” Environmental History Review 14.1–2 (1990):
1–18.
_____. “Seeing beyond Culture.” The Journal of American History 76.4 (1990): 1142–47.
_____. “Nature and the Disorder of History.” In Reinventing Nature?: Responses to
Postmodern Deconstruction, ed. Michael E. Soulé and Gary Lease. Washington,
D.C.: Island, 1995.
A Bateson, Gregory, 5
Abram, David, 10–12, 38, 42, 112, 122, Bear, 100, 113, 137, 138, 188–189, 192,
127–128, 130–131, 179, 235, 284n.96, 299n.143, 317n.175
2941n.81, 296n.94, 332n.173 Becker, Ernest, 80, 271n.84
Adolescence, 147–153; initiation rites, Bell, Anne, 186
150–153, 186–187; sexuality and, 149–150; Benton, Ted, 289n.4
symbolic level of perception in, 151–152 Berenson, Bernard, 283n.91
Adorno, Theodor, 170, 177, 319n.6 Bergman, Charles, 114, 263n.74
Adulthood, 153 Beringer, Almut, 321n.31
Advertising Industry, 21–22, 156, 170 Bernstein, Richard, 270n.53, 321n.32
Aeschylus, 188 Berry, Wendell, 46, 84, 91, 120, 171
Aggression, 69, 317–318n.183 Bigwood, Carol, 163, 281n.57
Aiken, Conrad, 126 Bird, Elizabeth, 258n.26
Ainsworth, Mary, 143 Black Elk, 94
Alexander, Bruce, 222–223 Body: beyond the control of modernity, 46;
Alien, Alienation, 21, 24, 37, 39–40, 52, divorce from, 58–59, 73; jammed-up life
76–78, 95, 114, 127, 159, 171, 199, 211, in, 80, 136–137; and language, 62–64; is
223, 228, 234, 241, 244–245, 247–248, meaning seeking, 63, 69, 144; prejudices
293nn. 60, 62, 308n.30, 325n.78, against, 58–59; reclamation of, 59–65;
328n.134. See also Loss orders experience, 38, 60, 62, 107–108;
Anima Mundi. See Soul of the world unity of, and world, 64, 69. See also Inten-
Animism, 5, 10, 102, 104, 112, 179, 233–234 tion, bodily
Anthony, Carl, 16, 19–20, 247 Bookchin, Murray, 201n.75, 261n.157
Aristotle, 43, 156, 266n.100 Borderline personality disorder, 143
Arkkelin, Daniel, 33 Borgmann, Albert, 29, 37, 42–47, 160, 161,
Armstrong, Jeannette, 78, 110, 132, 306n.4 162, 174, 178; device paradigm, 163–165,
Athanasiou, Tom, xv, 31, 307–308n.26 170–171, 257n.11, 267n.112
Attachment theory, 143, 242, 292n.40 Boss, Medard, 65, 69, 80, 108, 134, 136, 137,
Avens, Robert, 105 165, 266n.101
Bourassa, Robert, 162
Bradford, George, 254n.66
Breggin, Peter, 20, 159, 259–260n.30,
B 304n.209
Bachelard, Gaston, 115 Bringhurst, Robert, 176
Bacon, Francis, 156, 163 Brody, Hugh, 329n.143
Bakhtin, Mikhail, 44, 78, 268n.12 Bronfenbrenner, Urie, 320n.13
Baleen, Eskimo shaman, 40 Brown, Joseph Epes, 139, 288n.142
Barfield, Owen, 29, 44, 105, 295n.88 Brown, Norman O., 115, 155
Barrows, Anita, 290n.18, 300n.145 Bruchac, Joseph, 284–285n.107
Barthes, Roland, 129 Bryant, Donald, 265n.86
377
Buddha, Buddhism, 56, 71, 93, 97, 101, 109, to human life cycle, 185–187; supportive of
113, 119, 155, 156, 191, 267–268n.9, beleaguered self, 14–16, 182–185
286–287n.129, 287n.130, 336n.220 Cosmological urge, 122, 142, 164–165,
Burke, Kenneth, 44 306n.232
Burns, George, 222 Creative adjustment, 72, 148–149, 173, 176;
Buzzell, Linda, 201, 219–220, 327n.108 and destruction of experience, 74, 88
Cronon, William, 298–299n.130
Culture, 107, 119–120, 147, 148, 169–171, 172,
290n.19, 291n.24; culture industry, 170
C Cushman, Philip, 20
Campbell, Joseph, 175–176, 317n.174
Campbell, Paul, 43
Canty, Jeanine, 255n.76
Capitalism: confronting, is difficult/avoided, D
200, 212, 219, 235–238, 243, 319n.10, Davis, John, 226
334–335n.198; conscious capitalism, 235, Death (anxiety/denial), 99, 124, 152, 153, 169,
238, 335n.213; historical development of, 258n.102, 317–318n.183
210, 236; hostile to (human) nature/life, Decolonization. See Colonization
xix, 84–87, 157, 159–160, 161, 162, 198, Deep ecology, 17–20, 110, 246–247, 331n.161
222–223; industrialism and, 236–237; Denzin, Norman, 31
fosters and exploits suffering, 165–170; and Derrida, Jacques, 127, 129–130, 294–295n.85,
technology, 156, 306n.4, 310n.61 295n.87, 295n.92
Caputo, John, 263–264n.78, 283n.87 Descartes, René, 56, 59, 121, 244n.123,
Cartesianism. See Descartes, René 301n.163
Center for Psychology and Social Descola, Philippe, 241–242
Change, 15 Desensitization, 73
Cézanne, 58 Detienne, Marcel, 132
Chalquist, Craig, 201, 219–220, 322n.39, Development, economic versus biological,
327n.108 140–141
Chawla, Louise, 231, 320n.13, 321n.28 Dewey, John, 26, 36, 273n.112
Chen, Ellen, 119 Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental
Cheney, Jim, 254n.73 Disorders, criticism of, 22, 260n.33
Childhood, 144–147 Dialectics, 212–214
Clark, Brett, 212, 217, 219 Diamond, Stanley, 36, 51, 125, 229, 330n.143
Clayton, Susan, 202, 220 Differentiation, 123, 133, 139, 292n.48
Coates, Gary, 189 Dillon, M.C., 127, 128–129, 130, 294n.84
Cobb, Edith, 140, 144 Dilthey, William, 53
Coles, Romand, 87 Dinnerstein, Dorothy, 180
Colonization, 210–212, 223, 229 Discourse: inadequacies of modern normal,
Commodity fetishism, 84, 166–167 29–31, 32–33, 290n.7; creating an
Concern, ultimate, 45–47, 86 ecological, xiv, 30–31, 35, 40–42, 263n.77;
Condrau, Gion, 136 deictic, 43–44, 45–47; hermeneutical,
Conn, Sarah, 15, 22, 256n.96 36–42; mixed, of Freud, 35; rhetorical,
Consciousness, ecological, 18, 22 43–47, 265nn. 86, 94
Conservation Psychology, 200–201, 201–205, Distance: optimal, 73, 96, 102, 226n.32;
211, 214, 218 humans as creatures of, 94–96, 123, 162,
Contact, 65–70, 125, 133, 135, 138, 271n.83, 309n.42
280n.31; fear of, 66–67, 75 Doherty, Thomas Joseph, 201, 215–219
Council of All Beings, 16, 253n.57 Downing, Christine, 40
Counterpractice, 161, 174–188; brings life into Dreams, 82, 96, 136, 137–138, 152, 299n.
focus, 177–180; as engagement with reality, 137–139
178; life-oriented politics, 180; responsible Dreyfus, Hubert, 209, 262n.60, 278–279n.13
Dualism, problem of, xiv, 9–10, 24, 30–31, 32, Erikson, Erik, 8, 142, 148–149, 152,
35, 54, 56, 58, 64–65, 69, 78, 79, 81–82, 292n.40
94, 120, 127, 134, 136, 141, 173, 183, 198, Esbjörn-Hargens, Sean, 201, 224–239,
205, 206, 213, 250n.24, 251n.29, 260n.30, 328n.124, 329–330n.143, 332n.173,
273n.112, 291n.28. See also Splitting. 333n.175
Duerr, Hans Peter, 92 Evernden, Neil, 30, 51–53, 87, 321n.31
Ever-widening spheres, principle of, 122–126,
136, 141, 171, 174, 187, 233. See also
Experience, world-directedness of
E Existentialism, 53, 97, 212n.101, 213n.9,
Eating, 67, 142, 166 312n.105
Eaton, Boyd, 145, 150 Experience: bodily ground of, 38, 58–65;
Ecofeminism, 17, 19, 88–89 cycle of, 67–70; consumption as mode of,
Ecopsychology: anthropology and, 234, 240; 167; deprivation of 171–174; destruction
conservative tendencies within, 22–23; of, 73–74, 83, 176–177, 180–181; figure/
critical sense of, xiii–xiv, 16–17, 161; ground structure of, 58; gestalt as basic
definitions of, 3–4, 6, 7, 13, 23–24, 25, unit of, 67; interaction between feelings
33, 112, 180, 187, 198, 199, 205, 233, and symbols, 56–58, 75; marginalizing/
319n.8; experientially conceived, xvii, 26, forgetting of, 54, 129–130; primacy of,
42, 54–55, 174; as a hermeneutical form 53–55; returning to, 51–55, 183; source
of inquiry, 37–38; journal, 201, 215–219; for ecopsychological theory, 41–42, 161,
and language, 127, 131; naturalisti- 207–208; thicker than exiting forms, 64;
cally conceived, 24–25, 46, 91–92, 93, world-directedness of 69, 80
117–120, 147, 172; as a psychologically/
experientially base ecological politics, xv,
xvii, 13, 26–27, 174–188; as a radical
project, xiv; second-generation versus F
first, 201, 215–217; need for social and Fantasy, maximized in hostile environments,
political analysis within, 17, 21–23, 24, 77–78. See also Imagination
83, 110, 114, 147, 161, 217–219; and Fernandez, James, 146
spirituality, 98; therapeutic-recollective Fish, Lorraine, 223
sense of, xiii–xiv, 13, 52, 94, 110, 118, Fleischner, Tom, 135–136, 324n.57
131, 263–264n.78; as a transformation Flesh, 66, 230; definition, 132–134.
of psychology, 204–215 See also One flesh, principle of
Ecopsychology Institute, 22 Flores, Fernando, 209
Ecosocialism, 19, 198, 199, 200, 240–241, Focusing, 60–62, 64, 82, 102,
243–248 182–185
Ecotherapy, 201 Food. See Eating
Ego, 71–72, 97–98, 100, 114, 119, 123, 124, Foster, John Bellamy, 199, 212, 217,
152, 168–169, 280–281n.43, 290n.10 219
Ehrlich, Anne and Paul, 257n.102 Foster, Stephen, 186–187
Eliade, Mircea, 150–151, 152 Foucault, Michel, 30, 63
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 44 Fox, Amy, 252n.44
Environmental education, 185–186 Fox, Warwick, 18, 19, 21,
Environmental justice, 19–20, 201n.77, 254n.65
257n.102 Frankl, Viktor, 108
Environmental movement: mainstream Freedom, 69, 115–116, 166
(reform) versus radical, 17, 41, 217–218, Freud, Sigmund, 20, 35, 40–41, 54, 59, 83,
258n.23, 263n.76; psychology of, 15, 105, 114, 115, 156, 157–158, 159, 187,
253n.52 188, 190, 273n.121, 274n.136, 289n.166,
Environmental psychology, 32–33, 200–201, 317–318n.183
201–205 Fromm, Erich, 91, 99
H I
Habermas, Jürgen, 210–211, 236, 262n.63, Id, 59, 77
329n.137 Imagination, 134–136; versus fantasy, 135–136.
Happiness, 155–156, 160, 161, 189, 306n.4 See also Reality
Haraway, Donna, 258–259n.26 Indigenous peoples, relationship to ecopsy-
Harding, Sandra, 218 chology, 5, 94, 105, 125–126, 132, 139,
Harman, Chris, 334n.182 143, 151, 169, 228–229, 234, 279n.19,
Harvey, David, 212, 214, 235, 319n.4, 284n.104
326n.91, 333n.179 Individual, Individualism, 7, 9, 14, 18, 19,
Harvey, Graham, 232, 331n.157 21, 32, 33, 34, 53, 78–79, 124, 160,
Healing threshold, 182, 190 176, 180–183, 200, 208–209, 215, 221,
Heidegger, Martin, 11, 57, 88, 102, 105–106, 237, 238, 243, 244, 257n.11, 275n.153,
119, 121, 128, 162–164, 262n.59, 301n.163, 323n.45, 323n.48
265n.91, 270n.64, 278–279n.13, 281n.63, Infancy, 141–143
L
J Labor, an arena for ecopsychology, 240–241,
Jackins, Harvey, 286n.120 247–248
Jacoby, Russell, 20, 177, 181 LaDuke, Winona, 180
Jaffé, Aniela, 196 Laing, R.D., 74, 87–88, 256n.98
Jameson, Fredric, 161–162, 309n.42, 329n.137 Lame Deer, John (Fire), 58, 111
Jay, Tom, 9 Language: derives from and “sings” the (natural)
Jenks, Chris, 301n.163, 303n.196 world, 44, 126–132; as a kind of flesh, 133;
Jonas, Hans, 64, 293n.50 and the life process, 62–64, 66, 129–130;
Jones, Ken, 182, 190, 245, 252n.44, 315n.156 and oral peoples, 130–131; against post-
Jung, Carl, 4, 10, 40–41, 102, 114 modern view of, 63–64, 127, 129–131;
returning, to the natural world, 131–132,
235
Lasch, Christopher, 20, 118, 180, 181
K Lauderdale paradox, 238
Kahn, Jr., Peter, 230 Leary, David, 131, 296n.99
Kane, Sean, 96, 100, 105, 132, 283n.81 Leblow, Victor, 167
Kanner, Allen, 22, 40, 200, 255n.76, 290n.9 LeGuin, Ursula, 179
Kaplan, Rachel and Stephen, 32, 33 Leiss, William, 158, 168, 276n.163, 307n.20;
Karma, 103, 112 on commodity fetishism, 166
Kasser, Tim, 200 Levin, David, 38, 53, 87, 114, 115, 246,
Kaza, Stephanie, 288n.150 260n.30, 285n.111
Kellert, Stephen, 230 Levine, Stephen, 135
Kepner, James, 190, 271n.83 Lewis, Martin, 171
Kerényi, Karl, 291n.33 Lewontin, Richard, 215, 323–324n.56
Kidner, David, 7, 32, 210–211, 221, 228, 242 Levins, Richard, 215, 323–324n.56
Kierkegaard, Søren, 115, 263n.78 Leopold, Aldo, 4–5, 16
Kimball, Solon, 306n.237 Liedloff, Jean, 142, 143, 155, 170
King, Ynestra, 89 Life process, 51–52, 81; all meaning grounded
Kinship, 95, 96, 99, 111, 121, 123, 138–139, in, 63; non-relativity of, 62; and human
147, 186, 292n.43, 303n.203; as a psychology, 70–72, 75, 76, 80–82, 83, 153;
continuum, 95 social antagonism toward, xvii, 71–72, 84,
Kleinman, Arthur, 259n.29 88; an ultimate concern, 86
Koger, Susan, 203–204, 219, 320–321n.23, Lifton, Robert J., 14
321n.27, 322n.33 Limits, 24–25, 92, 118–119, 120, 122, 124,
Kohák, Erazim, 43, 45, 118, 120, 263n.77, 153, 163, 168, 290n.9
291n.24 Lincoln, Yvonna, 31
Kornfield, Jack, 109, 114, 274n.144 Little, Meredith, 186–187
Kovel, Joel, 20, 21, 22, 25, 34, 38, 83, 85, Livingston, John, 29, 30, 522–53, 64, 86, 94,
96, 97, 98, 114, 125, 159, 165, 167, 170, 100, 103, 173, 284n.106
191, 214, 248, 255–256n.86, 257n.103, Lopez, Barry, 88, 96, 101, 135
Lorde, Audre, xv, 88, 115, 185 Myers, Gene, 140, 144–145, 146, 147, 202,
Loss, a defining experience for ecopsychology, 231
14, 20, 36–37, 41–42, 47, 49, 83, 114, 119, Myokyo-ni, Venerable, 189
126, 136–137, 172, 187, 191, 192, 280n.41 Myth, Mythology, 96, 101, 132, 151, 175–176,
Louv, Richard, 216, 220 187; Christian, 156–157; creative,
Love, 99; romantic, 169 317n.174; of progress, 175–176; of regen-
Löwy, Michael, 245 eration through violence, 189
Loy, David, 97, 168, 176
Luddism, 157, 160
N
Nabhan, Gary Paul, 144
M Naess, Arne, 17, 254n.65, 254n.73
Macmurray, J., 284n.97 Narcissism, relation to ecological crisis, 85–86,
Macy, Joanna, 14–16, 42, 46, 183, 190, 226, 88, 119, 124, 290n.9
245 Naturalism, 24–25, 118
Magdoff, Fred, 199 Naturalistic psychology. See Ecopsychology,
Mahler, Margaret, 123 naturalistically conceived
Martin, Calvin, 46, 106, 111, 131–132, 146 Nature: as birth, 99–101; claims/demands of,
Martín-Baró, Ignacio, 221 24–25, 26; as desire, 113–115, 125; calls for
Marx, Karl, Marxism, 20, 83, 84, 156, a respectful attitude, 113; as dharma, 101,
161, 212, 243, 244, 247–248, 319n.9, 103–104; domination of, 25, 30, 84–85,
333–334n.179, 334n.195, 336n.231 87–89, 98, 123; in economic theory, 168; as
Masterson, James, 177 Eros, 114–115, 125; as essential quality or
Mathiessen, Peter, 41, 112, 119, 288n.142 order, 103–110; human, 34–35, 60, 94–116
May, Rollo, 278n.3 passim, 125, 155, 158, 168, 284–285n.107,
Mbuti people, 123–125 285n.111, 287n.131, 289n.166; humans as
McKibben, Bill, 162 servants of, 119, 161, 163, 187–188, 193; as
McLaughlin, Andrew, 256n.91 matter of interpretation, 93–94, 168,
Meade, Michael, 152 172–173; as life force or sacred power,
Meaning, 35, 45, 92, 108, 121, 139, 165, 169; 110–116; mysteriousness of, 100–101;
grounded in life not just language, 38, 60, natural scientific disclosure of, 31–34, 45, 92,
62–64, 69, 127, 129–130, 132, 271n.84; as 163, 203–204, 211, 218–219, 258–259n.26,
felt or experienced, 56–58; invisibility of, 58 266nn. 99, 100, 104, 278–279n.13,
Meditation, 112–113, 177–178, 288n.148 298n.123, 323–324n.56; as the natural
Melamed, Elissa, 14 world, 94–103; as otherness, 95, 101–103;
“Mental health” oppression, 159–160 as phusis or physis, 99, 124, 163, 283–284n.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 11–12, 31, 38, 58, 64, 96; poetry of, 105, 284nn. 97, 99, 103;
78, 82, 107, 127, 128–130, 132, 133–134, as resource 162–163; as a radical concept,
138, 213, 230, 251n.37, 252n.40, 262n.59, 25, 93; revolt of, 158–160, 188, 307n.20;
294nn. 72, 80, 296n.109, 297nn. 112–114, second, 110, 175; as a social place, 122,
301n.163 125–126, 132, 138, 146, 147, 303n.195;
Metaphor, 44, 265n.92 and spirit, 96–99; transhistorical, 107–109,
Midgely, Mary, 120, 312n.105 140, 173, 174, 175, 285nn. 111, 119
Mies, Maria, 301n.161 Naturism, 73
Miller, Alice, 76 Navajo people, 288n.145
Mind (charity), 222 Needs, discovery of, 107–109, 144, 150–151,
Monbiot, George, 326n.93 310n.72
Muir, John, 18 Nelson, Richard, 37, 41, 94, 96, 111, 282n.75,
Mumford, Lewis, 321n.31 312n.102
Rodman, John, 25, 30, 86, 117, 175 Shiva, Vandana, 84, 246
Rogers, Carl, 70, 76 Shulman, Helene, 208–209, 221
Rogers, Ray, 41, 49, 84, 160, 171 Singing the world, principle of, 126–132, 141,
Romanticism, eco-, 227–232. See also 149, 187
Nostalgia, charge of Sloan, Todd, 323n.53
Romanyshyn, Robert, 59, 136, 206–207, Slotkin, Richard, 189
324n.58 Smith, Adam, 244
Rorty, Richard, 36, 37–38 Snell, Bruno, 134
Roseman, Marina, 293n.62 Snyder, Gary, 17, 46, 93, 99, 116, 117, 120,
Roszak, Theodore, 4, 15, 22, 54, 136, 224, 243, 138, 186, 254n.73, 267–268n.9, 287n.131,
256n.98, 268n.16, 318–319n.2 299n.139, 332n.172
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 37 Sobel, David, 231
Rowe, Stan, 24, 111 Social ecology, 19
Russell, Constance, 185–186 Sociation, 125, 151, 191, 318n.192
Society of nature, 241–243, 335n.202.
See also Nature, as a social place
Socolow, Robert, 29
S Soul of the world, 10, 206
Sachs, Wolfgang, 301n.160 Soule, Renée, 252n.44, 255n.76
Salleh, Ariel, 19, 242, 243 Spinosa, Charles, 209
Sanders, Barry, 138 Spirituality, 97–99, 114, 124–125, 126,
Santayana, George, 136 149–153, 168–169, 190–191
Sanua, Victor, 259n.29 Splitting, 9, 123, 125, 139, 145, 292n.48
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 95, 99, 267n.9, 280n.26 Steiner, George, 10
Sass, Louis, 224 Stettbacher, Konrad, 24, 88
Saunders, Carol, 202 Storr, Anthony, 7
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 128 Suffering, 70–82, 188–192; bearing, as a
Scheff, Thomas, 108, 285n.120 central ecopsychological principle, 189;
Schizophrenia, 34, 97, 259–260nn. 29–31 capitalist exploitation of, 160, 165–169,
School of lost Borders, 186 245, 336n.220; conflict with organismic
Science. See Nature, natural scientific disclosure of self, 76–78; domination of nature as
Seamon, David, 258n.19 (backward) solution for, 156–157, 158,
Searles, Harold F., 3, 7–8, 16, 123, 139, 143, 160, 188, 192; fearful narrowing of experi-
231, 233 ence, 74–76; Freudian view of, 157–158;
Seligman, Martin, 221 given in the human situation, 71; as a life
Sendivogius, 10 compass, 115, 155, 189; generated in social
Sessions, George, 17, 37 antagonism toward life, 71, 72–73; points
Shame, 78–80, 85, 97, 99, 124, 126, 150, us to our nature, 108–109; involves the
160, 168, 169, 185, 191, 273n.120; in the whole social field, 78–79, 112, 126; and the
creation of gender, 79–80, 305n.224 pattern of technology, 162–165; veiled by
Shavano Institute, 15 ideology, 161
Sheehan, Thomas, 268–269n.26 Superego, 77, 79, 159
Shellenberger, Michael, 217 Suzuki, D.T., 280n.31
Shelley, Percy, 115 Symbol, 56–58
Shenandoah, Leon, 284n.107
Shepard, Paul, 3, 4, 54, 67, 96, 109, 118–119,
121, 134, 138, 163, 172, 173, 178, 192,
230–231, 271n.77, 286n.120; theory of T
normative psychogenesis, 8–9, 139–140, Taoism, 119
141, 142, 145, 146, 151, 301n.161, Taylor, Charles, 24, 174, 265n.88
303n.188 Techne, 106, 120, 163
V Y
Van den Berg, J. H., 36, 37, 78 York, Richard, 212, 217, 219
Veitch, Russell, 33
Violence, xiv, 25, 55, 81, 84–85, 88, 92–93,
150, 163, 168, 172; domestic, 143,
251–305n.224; strategy of, 189–190 Z
Vision questing, 13 Zimmerman, Michael, 201, 224–239, 254n.73,
Void, the, 97–98, 121, 124, 189, 293n.50, 328n.124, 329–330n.143, 332n.173,
308n.31; and the twin terrors, 98, 125 333n.175
Vycinas, Vincent, 284n.96 Zwicky, Jan, 322n.39
Personal in its style yet radical in its vision, Radical Ecopsychology, Second
Edition offers an original introduction to ecopsychology—an emerging field
that ties the human mind to the natural world. In order for ecopsychology
to be a force for social change, Andy Fisher insists it must become a more
comprehensive and critical undertaking. Drawing masterfully from humanistic
psychology, hermeneutics, phenomenology, radical ecology, nature writing, and
critical theory, he develops a compelling account of how the human psyche
still belongs to nature. This daring and innovative book proposes a psychology
that will serve all life, providing a solid base not only for ecopsychological
practice, but also for a critical theory of modern society. In this second edition,
Fisher includes a new preface, a new section looking back at the development
of the field since the book’s initial publication a decade ago, and a look at the
challenges that lie ahead.
State University of
New York Press
www.sunypress.edu