John of St. Thomas and Suárez: 1. Baroque Theology
John of St. Thomas and Suárez: 1. Baroque Theology
115-136
JOSÉ PEREIRA*
1. Baroque Theology1
The Baroque age, extending from the Renaissance to the Enlightenment, was
one of the most productive in the history of Catholic thought. It was an age with a
passion for system and synthesis. Theologians never seemed to weary of
contemplating the architectonic symmetry of the Catholic doctrinal structure, of
meditating, with an almost mystical intensity, on the elegant logic of the religion of
* Department of Theology, Fordham University, Rose Hill Campus, 441 East Fordham Road,
Bronx, N.Y. 10458, USA
1 Our quotations from John of St. Thomas and Suárez are taken from the following:
1. JOANNIS A SANCTO THOMA, O. P. Cursus Philosophicus Thomisticus [henceforward CPT
], Beato Reiser O.S.B, Marietti, Taurino/Turin 1930-1937. 3 vol. Vol. 1, Ars Logica. Vol. 2,
Naturalis Philosophiae, partes I et III. Vol. 3, Naturalis philosophiae, pars IV.
2. JOANNIS A SANCTO THOMA, O. P. Cursus theologici [henceforth CT ], In Primam Partem
Divi Thomae commentarii, Solesmes Benedictines, Desclée, Paris, vol. 1, 1931; vol. 2,
1934.
3. R. P. FRANCISCI SUÁREZ E SOCIETATE JESU. Opera Omnia, Ludovicus Vives, Paris 1856,
vols. 1-26). Vol. 1, De Deo Uno et Trino. Tractatus Tertius. De Sanctissimo Trinitatis
Mysterio. Vols. 25-26, Disputationes Metaphysicae [henceforth DM ], quoted as follows:
DM : disputation : section : number. All the translations are mine.
Since the 1960s, Suarezian studies have been less prolific than previously, when they were
dominated by the great figures of Pedro Descoqs (from the 1920’s) and José Hellin (from
the 1940’s). Some idea of how extensive these studies were can be gauged from the Nota
Bibliografica of A. GN E M M I ’s Il fondamento metafisico. Analisi de strutture sulle
“Disputationes Metaphysicae” di F. Suárez, Vita e Pensiero, Milano 1969, pp. 337-351.
However, from the late sixties, Suarezian studies have still been continued by an impressive
roster of scholars, like José Aleu Benitez, Timothy J. Cronin, Jean-François Courtine,
Douglas P. Davis, John P. Doyle, Eleuterio Elorduy, Jorge J. E. Gracia, David M. Knight,
John D. Kronen, Carlos Noreña, Jeremiah Reedy, T. D. Sullivan, John L. Treloar and
Norman J. Wells. Many of these names appear in the special issue on Francisco Suárez
edited by Jorge Gracia for the American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly, Summer 1991,
which augurs a revival of Suárez studies.
115
note e commenti
the Logos. Systems were constructed from the writings of Scholastic theologians of
earlier times who are not known to have been system builders, or the systematic
possibilities of whose thought had not been further developed in medieval days.
Among these systems were Aegidianism, Anselmianism, Baconianism, Bernardism,
and Henricism. But the major Baroque theological schools were developments of the
three preeminent architectonic systems that had arisen in the age of classical
Scholasticism: Bonaventurianism, Thomism, and Scotism, Thomism being the most
influential, repeatedly recommended by the popes, like Urban V (Laudabilis Deus),
Pius V (Mirabilis Deus, 1567), Sixtus V (Triumphantis Jerusalem, 1588) and Paul V
(Splendidissimi, 1607). And the Thomist system was championed not only by the
Dominican order to which Thomas belonged, and by his fervent admirers like the
Discalced Carmelites, but by other orders too, like the Benedictines, Cistercians,
Mercedarians, Minorites; as well as by the seculars.
The Dominicans, of course, had long been dedicated to Thomism, and had
thinkers of surpassing genius. Among the 15th century Thomists were Cajetan
(Thomas de Vio, 1468-1534), reputed founder of classical Thomism; Franciscus
Sylvester Ferrariensis (1474-1528), elaborator of Aquinas’s polemics; Francisco de
Vitoria (c.1492-1546), initiator of international law; and Domingo de Soto (1494-
1560), creator of a variety of Thomism different from, and less succesful than,
Cajetan’s. The 16th century produced a race of Dominican giants like Melchior Cano
(1509-1560), inaugurator of Baroque Scholasticism, with its balance of positive and
speculative theology; Bartolomé de Medina (1528-1581), propounder of the ethical
theory of Probabilism; Domingo Bañez (1528-1604), protagonist of the theory of
physical predetermination; and the Doctor Profundus John of St. Thomas (João de
São Tomás/Ponçote/Poinsot, 1589-1644), the consummator of classical Thomist
systematics — the organization of a system embodied in the 24 Theses approved by
the Sacred Congregation of Studies in 1914. Classical Thomism was the normative
form of the system from the 16th century to the early 20th, but was challenged in the
mid-20th by newer modes of Thomism, which can be identified as the historical and
the transcendental.
While the Baroque Dominicans produced the consummate classical Thomist,
the Baroque Carmelites were responsible for the consummate classical Thomist opus,
in three divisions. First, a systematization of Thomist philosophy, the C u r s u s
Complutensis (1624-1625); second, a systematization of Thomist dogmatic theology,
in twelve volumes, the Cursus Theologicus Salmanticensis (1624-1712); and third, a
systematization of Thomist moral theology, in seven volumes, the Cursus Theologiae
Moralis (1665-1709). The principal theologians of this undertaking were Antonio de
la Madre de Dios (1583-1637), Domingo de Santa Teresa (1604-1659), and Juan de
la Anunciación (1633-1701), the latter, the Spanish John, almost equal in speculative
profundity to our Portuguese John. The productivity of these Baroque thinkers was
prodigious, never equalled before or since. As John of St. Thomas’s younger
contemporary, the great Portuguese orator António Vieira (1608-1697) said about
them, they seemed to write libraries rather than books, «que mais parece escreveram
livrarias, que livros»2.
2 A. VIEIRA, Desvelos de Xavier acordado. Sermão primeiro. Anjo, in Padre G. ALVES, Padre
António Vieira. Sermões , Lello & Irmão, Porto 1959. Tom. 13, p. 170.
116
José Pereira
117
note e commenti
118
José Pereira
of Suárez becomes the only Scholastic system where the founder himself organized
the elements of its philosophical and theological aspects and integrated them into a
u n i t y. The founders of the other major Scholastic systems, Bonaventurianism,
Thomism and Scotism were able to elaborate only their theologies. They did not
articulate their philosophies as autonomous units; that task was brilliantly achieved
by their later followers.
It has become customary to call the great Thomists of the Renaissance and
Baroque periods “commentators”. It is demanded of them that they be faithful
interpreters of the mens Divi Thomae. But they deserve to be considered philosophers
in their own right, no differently from any modern philosopher. John of St. Thomas
himself is one of the great Thomists remarkable for their originality, for he was «the
first semiotician to systematize the foundations of a doctrine of signs»6, concerned
with the communication between man and God, man and man, and man and nature.
These Thomists may be considered commentators in the sense that Aquinas himself
is a commentator, for, among a total of sixty of his writings devoted to theology and
p h i l o s o p h y, forty are commentaries and only twenty independent works. The
“commentators” can also be thought of as Thomists in the sense that Aquinas is an
Aristotelian. They commented on Aquinas just as Aquinas commented on Aristotle,
but no one today would identify Aquinas merely as an Aristotelian commentator.
«It is not however necessary that the things which are distinct according to the
intellect be so in reality, because the intellect does not apprehend things
according to the manner of things, but according to its own manner»7.
«is made through inadequate concepts of the same thing. For though the same
thing is conceived by either of the two concepts, by neither is all that is in the
6 J. D EELY, Semiotic in the Thought of Jacques Maritain, «Recherches Sémiotiques», 6
(1986), no. 2, p. 112. For a more detailed characterization of this originality see the author’s
Tractatus de Signis. The Semiotic of John Poinsot, University of California, Berkeley 1985,
Editorial Afterword, especially pp. 491-514.
7 AQUINAS, Summa theologiae, pars 1, q. 50, art. 2: «Non est autem necessarium quod ea quae
distinguuntur secundum intellectum sint distincta in rebus; quia intellectus non apprehendit
res secundum modum rerum, sed secundum modum suum».
119
note e commenti
thing conceived exactly, nor is its entire essence and its objective significance
exhausted, which (process) is often realized through conceiving that thing
through a relationship to various other things, or according to their manner —
and so such a distinction always has a basis in reality, but is formally said to
come about through inadequate concepts of the same thing. In this way we
distinguish justice from mercy in God, because we do not conceive the supreme
simplicity of God’s power as it is in itself and according to all its strength, but
we divide it by concepts in relation to various effects, of which that eminent
power is the origin; or else by an analogy to various powers which we discover
to be distinct in men, and which are found in a most eminent way in God’s
supremely simple power»8.
Entities, as exist outside the mind, are by themselves singular; they are not
universals reified or singularized. But, as John of St. Thomas points out, «the express
opinion of St. Thomas, in innumerable places, is that quantified matter is the first
principle of individuation»10.
What then is one to say about the fact that whatever is posited in reality is
singular? John responds:
«by this very fact, that it is posited in reality, it is not posited bare and
unconnected from every circumstance and state of incommunicability, but is
posited in combination with that state — and in this way it is turned into a
singular and individual entity, not by reason of its entity absolutely considered,
but as circumstantiated and incommunicable. Therefore it is one thing [to say]
that a nature posited in reality is singular, and another [to ask] by virtue of what
principle and basis it is singular and this particular thing. And although nature
by itself is indifferent to a plurality of individuals by a negative indifference [in
that it prescinds from, but does not exclude, individuals], nonetheless, this
indifference needs to be removed not by an essential principle, but by one
modificative of the essence. This is because the indifference referred to is only
8 SUÁREZ, DM 7: 1: 5. Vol. 25, p. 251.
9 Ibidem, 5: 6: 1. Vol. 25, p. 180: «omnem substantiam singularem, neque alio indigere
individuationis principio praeter suam entitatem, vel praeter principia intrinseca quibus eius
entitas constat».
10 JOHN OF ST THOMAS , CPT, Naturalis Philosophiae, pars 3, q. 9, art. 3. Vol. 2, p. 781:
«Expressa Divi Thomae sententia est innumeris locis materia quantitate signata esse
primum principium individuationis».
120
José Pereira
of such a kind that the nature has to be modified and materialized by singularity
and individuation, and not further constituted in its essence»11.
«in that individual entity it is possible to distinguish the common nature from
the singular entity, and for this particular individual to add, over and above the
species, something conceptually distinct, which according to a metaphysical
consideration has the significance of an individual differentia. But the opinion
nevertheless adds... that the individual differentia does not, in the individual
substance itself, have any special principle, or basis, which in reality is distinct
from its entity. Therefore the opinion affirms that each entity, in this sense, is by
itself this principle of individuation»12.
121
note e commenti
122
José Pereira
The third note is imperfect precision. Just as what makes all beings similar to
one another is being, what differentiates them is also being, for «the notion of being
is transcendent, and intimately enclosed in all the particular and determinate types of
beings» («rationem entis esse transcendentem et intime inclusam in omnibus propriis
et determinatis rationibus entium» 16). The same concept of being, c o n f u s e d l y
considered “as such”, is what unites them; the same concept, more expressly focused
as “God”, “creature”, “substance”, “accident”, is what differentiates them. «The
contraction of the concept of being to its particular modes», notes Suárez
«is not to be understood in the manner of a composition, but only in the manner
of a more express conception (per modum expressioris conceptionis) of any
particular being contained under being, in such a way that either concept,
whether that of “being” or of “substance”, is simple and irresoluble into two
concepts, differing only in that one is more determined than the other»17.
Some of John of St. Thomas’s sentences, taken out of context, sound as though
they could have been written by Suárez himself:
«And these very modes contracting being, in so far as they signify entity, are
the concept of “being”; in so far as they signify the expression of modification
(expressionem modificationis), are diverse»18.
The fourth note is the inequality of essential dependence, for the notion of being
is attributed unequally according to a set order: primarily to some categories of itself
(like substances, or God), and to others (like accidents or the creature), through
essential dependence on the former. For
123
note e commenti
Classical Thomist being, as described by John of St. Thomas21, differs from the
Suarezian primarily on the second note, unity. While Suarezian being may be
described as simpliciter (licet imperfecte) unum et secundum quid diversum, Thomist
being is simpliciter diversum et secundum quid unum. As John of St. Thomas
(speaking of a concept which in Suarezianism is termed the transcendental univocal)
puts it, the idea that
«this concept, which is one, imperfect and inadequate, so prescinds from its
inferiors that it remains in potency with regard to them and is contractible by
the addition of a differential concept — is deduced from the fact that it would
thus be univocal. For “animal” is univocal to all its species, because it is
conceived as actually one in such a way that it possesses the dividing
differences only in potency and is divided by their addition. Therefore the
analogical concept, which lacks that kind of unity, but has a unity only in a
certain sense, must not include the diversity of its inferiors only in potency; for
in this way it would remain simply one in actuality, which is what being
univocal means, and it would be multiple and diverse only in potentiality. In
order that the concept not remain simply one, it must actually include diversity,
even though it not actually explicate the diversity»22.
John of St. Thomas compares such a concept to that of a heap of sand seen from
a distance, which, he claims, actually represents all the particular grains of sand that
compose it, but not each grain explicitly. Here we also hit upon a basic difference in
conceiving univocity. The Thomist univocal is a concept that has a simple unity. The
Suarezian univocal is more complex: it is a simple unity, but applied to its inferiors
20 I b i d e m,
D M 28: 3: 17. Vol. 26, p. 19: «ipsum ens quantumvis abstracte et confuse
conceptum, ex vi sua postulat hunc ordinem, ut primo ac per se, et quasi complete competat
Deo, et per illam descendat ad reliqua, quibus non insit nisi cum habitudine et dependentia a
Deo; ergo in hoc deficit a ratione univoci, nam univocum ex se ita est indifferens, ut
aequaliter, et sine ullo ordine vel habitudine unius ad alterum, ad inferiora descendat; ergo
ens respectu Dei et creaturarum merito inter analoga comptatur».
21 Following the epoch-making treatise of CAJETAN , De nominum analogia (1498).
22 JOHN OF ST. T HOMAS, CPT, Ars Logica, pars 2, q. 13, art. 5. Vol. 1, p. 493: «ita praescindens
ab inferioribus, quod maneat in potentia ad illa et sit contrahibilis per additionem conceptus
differentialis, ex eo deducitur, quia sic esset conceptus univocus. Nam animal ideo est
univocum ad omnes species, quia concipitur ita unum in actu, quod differentias dividentes
solum habet in potentia et per earum additionem dividitur. Ergo analogum, quod talem
unitatem non habet, sed secundum quid, non debet solum in potentia includere diversitatem
inferiorum; sic enim in actu simpliciter maneret unum, quod est esse univocum, et solum in
potentia multiplex et diversum. Ut ergo non maneat simpliciter unum, actu debet includere
diversitatem, licet actu non explicet illam».
124
José Pereira
«precisely signify singular things [...] it must be conceded that this name
“man”, with equal priority signifies all particular men. It does not follow
therefore that this name “man” is equivocal, because though it signifies many
particulars with equal priority, nonetheless it signifies them by a single
ascription, and in signifying them subordinates them to one concept and not to
many, because of which that concept is univocally predicated of them»23.
125
note e commenti
knowledge of Him. But we cannot know what analogy is unless we already have
prior knowledge of what the relationship is of God’s essence to His existence.
But what does Aquinas himself say about analogy? Gilson tells us that
«His texts on the notion of analogy are relatively few, and in each case they are
so restrained that we cannot but wonder why the notion has taken on such an
importance in the eyes of his commentators»24.
«Principio igitur supponendum est (id quod est certum apud omnes) ens creatum,
quatenus tale est, essentialiter includere dependentiam a primo et increato ente.
Quia haec est prima ratio distinguens ens creatum ab increato [...]»26.
126
José Pereira
From the concept “being by essence” are derived, a priori, all the predicates
characteristic of God: infinity, unicity, immutability, imitability in effects — the latter
predicate being the a priori reason for the possibility itself of “being by
participation.” From the latter concept, in turn, are derived, a priori, all the predicates
that characterize the creature, which are: contingence, dependence in conservation
and activity, finiteness, potentiality by itself and in combination with act, the
multiplication of beings into species and into individuals within each species,
univocal similarities of genus and species, and the analogical similarities between
substances and accidents, and also between the Creator and creature. In this way the
absolute simplicity and unity of “being by essence” is the a priori reason for the
infinite variety and multiplicity of “being by participation”. The concept of “being by
essence” is thus the unifying principle of Suarezianism; it defines the basis of what,
to Suárez’s mind, constitutes the simple and comprehensive structure behind the
various modes of Scholasticism.
Classical Thomism accepts these postulates but (as we noted) judges its own
principles to be philosophically more profound. The most basic of these principles, in
its most abstract form, can be stated thus: a category or being which does not include
limitation in its concept acquires that limitation by the adjection of a really distinct
category or being. One mode of this adjection is what is known as “reception”. Thus
actuality, or act, of itself signifies only perfection and does not connote limitation; to
be limited, it has to be received into a really distinct potency, one that signifies such a
limitation, as having a capacity for only a certain measure of perfection and no more,
«sicut liquor in vase ad eius mensuram se accomodat»28 as John of St. Thomas has
it. Another mode of the adjection is what, as we have seen, he calls
“circumstantiation”, which individuates nature by quantified matter.
The unlimitedness of act (or existence) and its limitation by reception into a
really distinct potency (or essence) is classical Thomism’s foundational tenet 29.
When unlimited by reception into this potency, act is Pure Act and is God Himself.
All His predicates, like infinity and others, derive a priori from this fundamental
illimitation. When limited by reception into that potency, act is impure or mixed, and
constitutes the creature: this limitation is the a priori reason for the predicates of the
creature alluded to above.
From Suárez’s standpoint, this postulate reifies concepts and can be critiqued
thus: is the act or existence that is limited by reception a concept in the mind or a
reality independent of the mind? If it is a concept, it cannot, unless reified, be
received into anything really distinct; if, as a concept, it needs to be limited, it merely
requires an added conceptual modifier. If, on the other hand, this act or existence is
an extramental reality, is it illimitable or limitable? If it is illimitable, then nothing,
created beings, either in actuality or in power, so that if He were to wish to produce them,
He could not establish them outside His dominion».
28 JOHN OF ST. T HOMAS, CT, disp. 7, artic. unicus, n. 2. Vol. 1, p. 547: «as the liquor in the
vase accomodates itself to its measure».
29 This is the second of the famous 24 Theses of classical Thomism, approved by the Sacred
Congregation of Studies on 27 July 1914: «Actus, utpote perfectio, non limitatur, nisi per
potentiam, quae est capacitas perfectionis. Proinde in quo ordine actus est purus, in eodem
non nisi illimitatus et unicus existit; ubi vero finitus et multiplex, in veram incidit cum
potentia compositionem».
127
note e commenti
by definition, can limit it, for illimitation will be intrinsic to its nature. Reception into
something else does not change the nature of the received thing; a lion does not
become a mouse if “received” into a pot. If this act or existence is limitable, it is
already by that fact limited, since it lacks the perfection of illimitability or infinity.
Undeterred by such arguments, our ever faithful Thomist argues that just as
reception implies finitude, irreception implies infinity:
«because if existence be not received (non sit recepta) into any nature or form
from which it is distinguished, it does not have limitation by reason of a
receiving subject, since it lacks that subject... therefore if existence is incapable
of being received (irreceptibilis), it needs to be infinite in every way [...] But an
existence that is not received (irrecepta)is given in God [...] because He is Pure
Act in every manner of being, devoid of all potentiality and materiality.
Therefore such a form is in every way infinite»30.
It needs to be noted here that John, surreptitiously, jumps from an existence that
“is not received”, irrecepta, to one that “cannot be received”, irreceptibilis. For an
existence that is not received can either be limited, unlimited, or illimitable. If it is
already limited, the Thomist principle of limitation will be superfluous, and of course
not serve to prove God’s infinity. If the existence is unlimited, but capable of
limitation by reception, the Thomist principle will be acceptable, but will apply only
to the creature, not to God, whose existence is not only not limited or received, but
also not capable of being limited or received. For John to show that the unlimited
existence is God’s, he will have to show that it is not only i rre c e p t a but also
irreceptibilis. He nowhere proves this, however, but only assumes it to be the case,
and so evidently begs the question. A further objection to John’s position is presented
by Vazquez, one of the many great Baroque Jesuits, who is of the same mind as
Suárez on this point. Vazquez objects that essence is not distinct from existence, so if
essence is not received into anything, neither is existence31. Suárez adds that
«in order that a being be finite, it is enough that it be received from another
being in such and such a measure of perfection, although properly speaking it
may not be received into any passive potency. And similarly the created essence
can be limited by its intrinsic differentia, although it may not be related to
existence in the manner of a receptive potency»32.
Here Suárez clearly describes the two principles of limitation, which are termed
the “objective” and the “subjective”. In objective limitation, an entity is limited
30 JOHN OF ST. THOMAS, CT disp. 7, artic. unicus, n. 3. Vol. 1, pp. 547-548: «quia existentia si
non sit recepta in aliqua natura vel forma a qua distinguatur, non habet limitari ratione
subiecti recipientis, quia caret illo [...] ergo si [existentia] est irreceptibilis, debet esse ex
omni parte infinita [...] Sed in Deo datur existentia irrecepta [...] quia est actus purus in toto
genere entis, omni potentialitate et materialitate carens. Ergo talis forma est ex omni parte
infinita».
31 G. VAZQUEZ, Commentaria et disputationes in Primam Partem Sancti Thomae, in q. 7, disp.
25, c. 2.
32 SUÁREZ, DM 30: 2: 19. Vol 26, p. 70.
128
José Pereira
because, as a caused object, it receives a determinate perfection and no other from its
cause; in subjective limitation, an entity, unlimited in its essence, is limited by being
received into a subject that has a capacity for only so much perfection and no more.
John’s reply to Vazquez and Suárez is significant, for he evidently concedes that the
basic tenet of classical Thomism is debatable — a strange admission on the part of
the system’s major architect:
«To that which Father Vazquez adds, I deny that existence is not distinguished
from created essence, as has sufficiently been proved above. However, since
this has to do with the opinion of some, and since the infinity of God must not
be proved dependently upon any opinion, I add that in the opinion that does not
distinguish existence from actual essence, the argument of St. Thomas still
holds. Because though existence is entitatively the same as subsistent nature,
still, the operation of proceeding from another being through production is
dependently realized by the action of that other, and hence accidently applies to
the produced thing — so the latter is received objectively [as a caused object]
and participatively, although not subjectively [in a subject]. However, when
Being itself is subsistent in such a manner that, neither in its entity nor in the
operation of its procession from or production by another, does it possess being
that is received, or one that accidentally pertains to it subjectively or objectively
— such a being lacks all limitation, because in no way is it received, not even
objectively. All this is clear from a sign: as such a being will not have in itself
any received operation or accident. Indeed if it will not depend objectively on
another for its production, neither will it depend on it for any perfection or
operation. Hence by this very fact that a form is existence itself, it is optimally
proved to be infinite, because it is not received, either subjectively or
objectively — though according to St. Thomas it cannot be maintained that
something be received objectively, without it being distinct in essence and
received subjectively too»33.
129
note e commenti
«because existence by essence [or what is existent by virtue of its essence] does
not have anything which can limit it. But participated being can be limited
either by the will of the one who gives so much perfection and no more, or by
the capacity of the recipient, whether that capacity be understood in the manner
of a passive potency, or only in the manner of an objective potency, or of non-
contradiction. However, in the primal being, which is existent of itself, no
principle or rationale of limitation can be understood, because just as it has no
cause of its existence, in the same way there can be no limitation in it, either on
part of the giver, or from any other principle»34.
It would therefore seem to follow that, since, as Suárez contends, the entire
system of metaphysics can be deduced from the two postulates of God’s entitative
independence and the creature’s entitative dependence, principles which are beyond
debate and admitted as such by the Thomists also, and since the specifically Thomist
principle of the limitation of act by potency or of existence by essence is debatable,
that principle is superfluous for basing a solid metaphysics and can conceivably be
abandoned.
6. Concord of The Two Doctors: on the Divine Nature and the Trinity
Be that as it may, on another, related, topic, the two Doctors, the Uncommon
and the Profound, are unequivocally in agreement — on what constitutes the essence
and nature of God, in so far as it can be expressed through imperfect human
concepts. It is usual to find Scholastics, especially Thomists, saying that it is
“increate entity” ( entitas incre a t a) or “subsistent being itself” ( ipsum esse
subsistens). Suárez agrees, but goes on to affirm that in a more precise sense the
essence or nature of God is subsistent intellection itself ( ipsamet intellectio
subsistens), which he characterizes as «veluti ultimum essentiale constitutivum
divinae naturae»35, the ultimate essential constituent, so to speak, of the nature of the
deity.
The Thomist position is thus stated by Aquinas:
«God’s essence is therefore His existence. Now Moses was taught this sublime
truth by the Lord [...] when the Lord showed him that His proper name is “Who
Is.” Now any name is intended to signify the nature or essence of something.
Hence it remains that the divine existence itself is God’s essence or nature»36.
130
José Pereira
«[God] has the intellectual life by essence and not by participation. To have by
essence is nothing else but to have the intellectual life itself in the manner of
pure and ultimate actuality without any efficiency or causality. And this is
nothing else but that the divine essence is intellectual, not in the manner of
intellectual principle or basis, but as subsistent intellection itself. But the
intellection and knowledge of God are most formally the same: therefore actual
knowledge by essence is so to speak the ultimate essential constitutive form of
the divine nature. And so, conceiving as we do any intellectual nature in a
twofold manner, either because it has an intrinsic relationship to intellection, or
because it is intellection itself, we conceive of created intellectual nature in the
former manner.... But the divine nature is intellectual in the latter manner,
because this mode is characteristic of God, that is to say, because He is the most
pure and abstract [i.e. abstracted from matter] intellection itself. Therefore, in
this way, God’s knowledge most formally constitutes and as it were specifies
His essence»37.
This new definition of the divine nature aids Suárez in resolving a problem of
crucial importance in Trinitarian theology, one which Eastern Orthodox and many
Latin theologians maintain is insoluble 38. According to this theology the divine
nature, by virtue of its unlimited fecundity, needs to communicate itself, since bonum
est diffusivum sui. Such a communication cannot necessarily be to anything ad extra,
since, with respect to all that is not God, the divine being is entirely unnecessitated or
free. Necessity for God exists only within the latitude of His deity. The
communication thus can only be ad intra. Communication entails multiplicity, for
there has to be at least one communicator and one to whom something is
communicated. But communication in God cannot multiply the deity itself, which is
a single omniperfect absolute. The communication can thus only be relational, as
multiple relations do not impair the unity of an absolute. There are in fact three such
(subsistent) relations in the deity, the Persons of the Trinity; one communicator and
two communicated relations. Since these communications are those of an
intelligential being, and as such a being has intellect and will, with the latter
consequent on the former, two communications can be postulated, those of the
37 S UÁREZ, DM 30: 15: 15. Vol. 26, p. 174: «[Deus] habet illam vitam intellectualem per
essentiam, et non per participationem; habere autem per essentiam, non est aliud quam
habere ipsam intellectualem [vitam] per modum puri et ultimi actus absque ulla effectione
vel causalitate. At hoc non est aliud quam quod divina essentia sit intellectualis, non per
modum principii aut radicis intellectualis, sed ut ipsamet intellectio subsistens; sed
intellectio et scientia Dei idem formalissime sunt; ergo actualis scientia per essentiam est
veluti ultimum essentiale constitutivum divinae naturae. Itaque, cum dupliciter concipiatur a
nobis quod aliqua natura sit intellectualis, scilicet, quia habet intrinsecam habitudinem ad
intelligere, vel quia est ipsum intelligere, priori modo concipimus naturam creatam esse
intellectualem [...] Divina vero natura est intellectualis posteriori modo, quia est proprius
eius, scilicet, quia est ipsum intelligere purissimum et abstractissimum. Sic igitur scire Dei
formalissime constituit et quasi specificat eius essentiam».
38 JOHN DAMASCENE, De fide orthodoxa, I: 8, PG 94: 824A: «We have learnt through faith that
there is a difference between begetting and proceeding, but faith tells us nothing about the
nature of that difference». See also ADAM OF ST. V ICTOR, Sequentia XI de S. Trinitate, PL
196: 1459: «Quid sit gigni, quid processus, me nescire sum professus».
131
note e commenti
intellect and the will. The former communication expresses itself in the logos,
concept, or word, and the latter in love.
Scholastic theology calls the process whereby a communication in God is
realized a “procession”, and declares that the procession of the intellect is the origin
of the second Person, the Son, Logos or Word; and that the procession of the will is
the origin of the third Person, the Holy Spirit or Love. The entire divine nature is
communicated to both Son and Holy Spirit, the communicator of the first procession
being the Father, and of the second the Father conjointly with the Son. Since they
share the same divine nature as the Father, both Son and Holy Spirit proceed from
Him in total similitude. What then differentiates the Son from the Holy Spirit? Why
is only the second Person and not the third called a Son: a son being defined as a
living being proceeding substantially from another living being in its similitude? This
is the problem that Eastern Orthodox theologians declare is a mystery.
Suárez replies that that while both the Son and the Holy Spirit do in fact
proceed from the Father in the similitude of nature, the intent or formal terminus of
the procession of the Son is to communicate the divine nature as nature, and since the
divine nature is subsistent intellection, the Son, who is that intellection in its
relational or hypostatic mode, is recipient of the similitude to the Father in a formal
sense. But the intent or formal terminus of the procession of the Holy Spirit is to
communicate, not the divine nature as such, but the divine love of the Father and the
Son; hence the Holy Spirit does not by intent proceed in similitude of nature, and is
therefore not a Son. Still, since love is identical with nature in God, the divine nature
is communicated to the Spirit through its identity with divine love. As Suárez himself
states it, the Word alone is produced
«ex vi intellectionis paternae, ut sic, et non Spiritus Sanctus. Nam inde imprimis
i n f e ro, communicari Verbo ex vi processionis suae divinam essentiam, ut
primario constitutam in esse talis essentiae et naturae, Spiritui Sancto autem
non ita communicari ex vi processionis, sed quatenus per identitatem in amore
includitur»39.
John entirely agrees with this view. He further clarifies a problem not examined
by Suárez: how God’s essence or nature can be described as both ipsum esse
subsistens (or essentia increata)and ipsum intelligere subsistens. In reply, John
distinguishes between a transcendent essence and a specific one; both exactly
characterize a being, but the latter more precisely than the former. Thus the specific
essence of man is “rational animality”, which distinguishes him from any other
being; but his transcendent essence, which describes him no less exactly, is “created
being”, though the latter notion is applicable to all other creaturely things also. A
similar distinction can be applied to God: ens increatum is His transcendent essence
and intellectio subsistens His quasi-specific one. In John’s words:
39 SUÁREZ ,De Sanctissimo Trinitatis Mysterio, lib. 11, c. 5, n. 16. Vol. 1, p. 789: «[the Word
alone is produced] by power of the Paternal [=of the Father] intellection as such, and not the
Holy Spirit. Hence I infer from this, firstly, that the divine essence, by virtue of the
procession itself, is communicated to the Word as primarily constituted in the being of such
an essence or nature; but that to the Holy Spirit it is not communicated in this way by virtue
of the procession, but only in so far as it is included through identity in love».
132
José Pereira
What then constitutes divine nature as such? John (who is no master stylist)
answers with a verbose syllogism. Its main lineaments are as follows:
«Major: that has to be the formal constitutive of divine nature, which is the
primary and intrinsic principle of a proper operation and which is primarily
applicable to God [...]
Minor: but the operation proper to God is intellection (intelligere) [...] and it is
primary, because the operation of the will presupposes intellection itself, since it
is regulated and guided by it [...]
C o n c l u s i o n: therefore it is necessary that the divine nature be formally
constituted by [...] intellection (intellectualitatem) [...]»41.
The major is the definition of nature itself, applied to God. The minor is clear,
because the divine intellect is «supremely spiritual and removed from potentiality
and imperfection, and is the first [operation], because the operation of the will
presupposes intellection, since it is regulated and directed by the latter»42.
Like Suárez, John maintains that the Son formally proceeds as intellection,
«because He proceeds as the similitude of the object known by the intelligence and
existing in the same nature, since in God intelligence and being are one and the
same»43. As formally proceeding in the Father’s similitude, He can be properly
identified as the Son. As for the Holy Spirit, He
«formally proceeds as love who is identified with the divine nature, and yet
does not proceed as a Son, nor by generation, because, formally speaking, He
40 JOHN OF ST.THOMAS, CT, disp. 16, art. 2, n. 9. Vol. 2, p. 338: «Quia esse a se seu substantia
a se, ut dicit rationem actus puri, invenitur in omni attributo et Persona et in omni eo quod
divinum est, non minus quam ens creatum, seu ens ab alio, in omni eo quod creatum est;
ergo non potest iste conceptus entis a se discernere in Deo id quod natura est, ab eo quod
attributum est vel Persona vel operatio: sed solum discernit id quod divinum est in genere,
ab eo quod est creatum: et ita distinguit inter transcendens et transcendens, scilicet inter ens
creatum ut sic et ens increatum ut sic, non inter naturam divinam, ut natura, et proprietates».
41 Ibidem, CT disp. 16, art. 2, n. 19. Vol. 2, p. 341: «illud debet esse formale constitutivum
naturae divinae, quod est per se principium operationis et per se primo conveniens Deo [...]
sed propria operatio divina est intelligere [...] ergo oportet quod natura divina constituetur
formaliter per [...] intellectualitatem [...]».
42 Ibidem, «maxime spiritualis et segregata a potentialitate et imperfectione; et est prima, quia
operatio voluntatis supponit ipsum intelligere, siquidem ab eo regulatur et dirigitur».
43 Ibidem, disp. 16, art. 2, n. 14. Vol. 2, p. 339.
133
note e commenti
If the reasoning of Suárez and John of St. Thomas on this point is correct, then
it demonstrates both the harmony of Scholastic philosophy with theology, and the
falsity of the dichotomy between the God of the philosophers and the God of
Christianity. For, as Suárez declares, in the opening lines of his great work, the
Disputationes Metaphysicae:
7. Conclusion
In sum, it may be observed that in reacting to Suarezianism and to its critique of
the classical Thomist system, John of St. Thomas is sometimes unyielding, and at
other times accomodating and even concordant. In these cases he either retains or
qualifies the classical Thomist tenets, and also either employs the reified Thomist
language or the non-reified Suarezian one. He is unyielding when he retains Thomist
ideas and language — as when he propounds the Thomist concept of being, the real
distinction between essence and existence, and the limitation of act by its reception
into a really distinct potency. He is accomodating when he retains Thomist ideas but
expresses them in Suarezian language, as in the matter of the contraction of being to
its particulars or inferiors, and in that of the individuation of nature by quantified
matter. He is concordant when he adopts both Suarezian ideas and language, as in the
characterization of the divine nature as subsistent intellection rather than as
subsistent being; as well as in the partial abandonment of the commentarial method
of literary expression for one that is more organic and distinctive of each individual
author.
John of St. Thomas’s agreement or disagreement with Suárez can thus be
subsumed under the following five headings, which will be discussed summarily in
turn:
1. Supplantation of the commentarial method by the author’s own
2. The unity of being and its contraction to its particulars
44 Ibidem, p. 340: «formaliter procedit ut amor qui identificatur cum natura divina, et tamen
non procedit ut Filius, nec per generationem, quia procedit solum secundum
communicationem impulsus et amoris formaliter, identice autem accepit communicationem
naturae».
45 S UÁR E Z , D M, proemium. Vol. 25, p. 1: «Although divine and supernatural theology
depends upon the divine light and on the principles revealed by God, since in fact it is
completed by human discourse and reasoning, it is also aided by the truths known to the
light of nature; and it employs them as ministers and (as it were) intruments to develop its
discourses and to clarify the divine truths themselves».
134
José Pereira
135
note e commenti
(who are said to be individuated by their species), but only to material beings, when
it sounds tautologous (that beings having matter are individuated by matter). Still,
every being thus individuated has two aspects: absolute or common nature, which
does not include the note of individuality in its essence, and the individuating
principle itself, the quantified matter, which circumstantiates the absolute nature and
renders it incommunicable. In the reifying Thomist mannner, the nature and the
quantified matter are really distinct; for Suárez they are two conceptually distinct
integrants of an individual reality that in this regard is indivisible. John accepts the
quantified matter principle without reserve, but describes it in non-reifying Suarezian
terms.
Fifth, and last, the nature of God as subsistent intellection, whereby God is
defined not by the broadest and most indeterminate of perfections, being, or esse
(ipsum esse subsistens), but by the intensest and sublimest of them, sapient
consciousness or intellectio (ipsamet intellectio subsistens). This idea, advanced by
Suárez, is unreservedly adopted by John of St. Thomas, who harmonizes the two
definitions, when he declares that ipsum esse subsistens characterizes the divine
nature broadly and transcendentally, and ipsamet intellectio subsistens more narrowly
and as it were specifically. (The latter definition explains why the first divine
procession, that of the Son, is generation, and not the second procession, that of the
Holy Spirit.) In describing God more through the notion of intellect than through that
of being our two Scholastics anticipate some modern thinkers, for whom God’s
essence is “pure understanding” 46; these thinkers reflect modern philosophy’s
tendency to affirm the primacy of thought over being and to start with knowledge
and terminate with being. It must not be forgotten that Suárez and John of St.
Thomas were the contemporaries of the founder of modern philosophy, Descartes
(1596-1650), the Jesuit being 48 years his senior and the Dominican seven. In
contrast to modern philosophy, the Scholastic starts with being and terminates with
knowledge. Accordingly, for the two Doctors, the Uncommon and the Profound,
God’s intellection is not, so to speak, a cognitive nebulosity ungrounded in the primal
reality of being, but is the very consummation of God’s basic essence as subsistent
being; it is, in the words of Suárez, the ultimum essentiale constitutivum divinae
naturae.
46 «For Lonergan the metaphysical essence of God is not ipsum esse subsistens, as Aquinas
says, but rather “pure understanding”, not being but mind». J.M. DE TORRE, Transcendental
Thomism and the Encyclical Veritatis Spendor, «Fellowship of Catholic Scholars
Newsletter», April 1995, p. 24.
136