(New Directions in The Philosophy of Science) Susann Wagenknecht (Auth.) - A Social Epistemology of Research Groups-Palgrave Macmillan UK (2016)
(New Directions in The Philosophy of Science) Susann Wagenknecht (Auth.) - A Social Epistemology of Research Groups-Palgrave Macmillan UK (2016)
A SOCIAL EPISTEMOLOGY
OF RESEARCH GROUPS
Susann Wagenknecht
New Directions in the Philosophy of Science
Series Editor
Steven French
Department of Philosophy
University of Leeds
Leeds
UK
The philosophy of science is going through exciting times. New and
productive relationships are being sought with the history of science.
Illuminating and innovative comparisons are being developed between the
philosophy of science and the philosophy of art. The role of mathematics
in science is being opened up to renewed scrutiny in the light of original
case studies. The philosophies of particular sciences are both drawing on
and feeding into new work in metaphysics and the relationships between
science, metaphysics and the philosophy of science in general are being
re-examined and reconfigured. The intention behind this new series from
Palgrave-Macmillan is to offer a new, dedicated, publishing forum for the
kind of exciting new work in the philosophy of science that embraces
novel directions and fresh perspectives. To this end, our aim is to publish
books that address issues in the philosophy of science in the light of these
new developments, including those that attempt to initiate a dialogue
between various perspectives, offer constructive and insightful critiques,
or bring new areas of science under philosophical scrutiny.
The members of the editorial board of this series are: Otavio Bueno,
Philosophy, University of Miami (USA); Anjan Chakravartty, University
of Notre Dame (USA); Hasok Chang, History and Philosophy of Science,
Cambridge (UK); Steven French, Philosophy, University of Leeds (UK);
Series Editor; Roman Frigg, Philosophy, LSE (UK); James Ladyman,
Philosophy, University of Bristol (UK); Michela Massimi, Science and
Technology Studies, UCL (UK); Sandra Mitchell, History and Philoso-
phy of Science, University of Pittsburgh (USA); Stathis Psillos, Philosophy
and History of Science, University of Athens (Greece). Forthcoming titles
include: Sorin Bangu, Mathematics in Science: A Philosophical Perspective;
Gabriele Contessa, Scientific Models and Representation; Michael Shaffer,
Counterfactuals and Scientific Realism. Initial proposals (of no more than
1000 words) can be sent to Steven French at [email protected]
A Social
Epistemology of
Research Groups
Collaboration in Scientific Practice
Susann Wagenknecht
University of Siegen
Siegen
Germany
v
vi Acknowledgments
1 Introduction 1
1.1 An Epistemology of Research Groups 3
1.2 Empirical Insights for Philosophy 5
1.3 Scientists as Reflective Practitioners 7
1.4 Chapter Overview 11
References 14
2 Research Groups 19
2.1 The Phenomenon 20
2.2 Individualism or Collectivism? 24
2.3 Excourse: Interdisciplinary Research Groups 27
2.4 Conclusion 30
References 30
3 Method 35
3.1 Engaging Empirical Insights in Philosophy 36
3.2 A Qualitative Case Study 41
3.3 Interviewing Scientists 46
3.4 Structuring Empirical Insights 49
vii
viii Contents
6 Division of Labor 91
6.1 Philosophical Perspectives 92
6.2 Complementary Collaboration 96
6.3 Parallel Collaboration 100
6.4 Comparison 104
6.5 Conclusion 105
References 107
is actually practiced. There are several ways to acquire such insight, one
of which I exemplify when I mobilize first-hand qualitative data for
philosophical reflection.
1
As a field of philosophical inquiry, social epistemology is, as much of the philosophy of science
is, rooted in the tradition of analytic philosophy. To inquire about the “social epistemology” of
science means to inquire about the possibilities of well-founded belief and the (scientific) knowledge
that scientists, individually and collectively, possess. Social epistemology, as a branch of general
epistemology, is a relatively young field of philosophical inquiry. The programmatic beginnings
of social epistemology as a field can be traced to the work of Fuller (1988), Longino (1990),
Goldman (1999) and, for example, (Schmitt, 1994). Some social epistemologists have begun to
engage with comprehensive, empirically detailed case studies (see, e.g., Bergin, 2002; Rehg & Staley,
2008; Staley, 2007). Despite the field’s interest in the social dimensions of knowledge, however,
philosophers in the field of social epistemology typically do not refer to social-scientific studies of
science or social-scientific empirical methods.
2
The expression “Big Science” was coined by Weinberg (1961).
4 1 Introduction
In most disciplines, those who do not trust cannot know; those who do not
trust cannot have the best evidence for their beliefs. In an important sense,
then, trust is often epistemologically even more basic than empirical data
or logical arguments: the data and the argument are available only through
trust. (Hardwig, 1991, p. 693f.)
well, since the logical and evidential justification for those claims is
too comprehensive to be understood in deep detail by a single scientist
(Hardwig, 1991, p. 696). When he first formulated these claims, Hardwig
was bluntly challenging the ideal of the autonomous, individual knower
that was (and in many respects, still is) underlying epistemology (cf.
Fricker, 2006b). Against this ideal, Hardwig’s work calls for a new way
of thinking about knowledge and scientific knowledge, a philosophical
angle that is broader than an individualist focus:
3
For a thorough epistemological analysis of Quine’s position see Haack (2009, ch. 6).
1.3 Scientists as Reflective Practitioners 7
This book builds upon naturalist traditions, but it also departs from the
way in which a majority of philosophers of science and epistemologists
formulate naturalized accounts of science and (scientific) knowledge
creation. While it is common for naturalized philosophy to rely upon
interpretations of empirical data provided by research outside philosophy,
that is, research in natural sciences, this book presents first-hand empirical
data, gathered by qualitative, social-scientific methods. The research pro-
cess that underlies this book, hence, has little to do with the methods that
the natural sciences pursue. It is rather an open-ended, iterative process
of interpretation—“hermeneutic” rather than “naturalized” (Schickore,
2011).
Although the crossroads between the methods of the philosophy of
science and history have been explored eagerly, combinations of philo-
sophical inquiry and social-scientific methods have been far less popular—
a rift between philosophy of science and social studies of science that
reaches back to the “Science Wars” (Wagenknecht, Nersessian, & Ander-
sen, 2015). Nonetheless, philosophers of science have begun to make
use of social-scientific methods. So-called “experimental philosophers”
are using quantitative methods such as standardized interviews to learn
about the frequency of people’s intuitions (Griffiths & Stotz, 2008; Knobe
& Nichols, 2008; Machery & O’Neill, 2014). Other philosophers have
pioneered qualitative empirical inquiries within philosophy of science
(Calvert & Fujimura, 2011; Kastenhofer, 2013; Riesch, 2010; Toon, 2012).
Leonelli (2007, 2010), for example, has studied scientific practice in
the life sciences with the help of ethnographic methods. Nersessian
and collaborators (2003, 2006, 2010, 2011, 2015) have made use of
a mix of qualitative methods to explore laboratory collaboration and
scientific modeling in fields such as bio-informatics. It is this strand of
philosophical inquiry—an inquiry into scientific practice grounded in
first-hand empirical data—that I seek to continue in this book.
interviews with them, bringing out what they think about their work, how
they think it should be done, and how they reflect upon the experiences of
the collaboration that they have been involved in. In this book I approach
scientists as reflective practitioners, who have something to say about
their work when interviewed. They are able to offer accounts of scientific
knowledge creation that reflect their education and their experiences. One
premise of this book, a premise concerning its empirical method, is that
philosophers should take these “native” expert accounts seriously, even
though they may lack the terminology, the subtlety and the argumentative
structure of philosophical reasoning.
As reflective practitioners, scientists continuously reflect upon their
work and measure it against the standards of scientific practice. To
practice experimental science involves manual activity as much as it
involves cognitive activity. Scientists reason; reasoning is part of their
work. Therefore, I conceive of scientists as cognizant actors—actors who
form beliefs in the light of what they know, observe and infer. These beliefs
concern the epistemic significance of experimental results, but they also
concern, for example, the trustworthiness of collaborators who produced
these experimental results.
Addressing scientists as subjects who form beliefs and reflectively seek
to justify them, I analyze empirical insights in terms of knowledge as
justified belief, the predominant albeit not uncontested paradigm in epis-
temology (Haack, 2009; Ichikawa & Steup, 2013). Within this paradigm,
knowledge is understood as attributable to an epistemic subject or a
“cognizer” (cf. Longino, 2002, p. 77ff.).4 Conventionally, the paradigm
of an epistemic subject is the individual human being, a paradigm which
allows us to conceive of knowledge as individually held justified belief.
Though a widespread notion in epistemology, the understanding of
knowledge as individually held belief has been criticized by social and
feminist epistemologists (see, e.g., Bechtel, 2008; Gilbert, 2004; Nelson,
1990), and I reflect upon some of their critiques in Chap. 9.
4
An alternative to knowledge as justified true belief is reliabilism, which understands knowledge
as reliable belief (Goldman, 2011). Note that a reliabilist position remains within the paradigm of
knowledge as belief. For a more fundamental critique of knowledge as belief see, e.g., Vendler (1972),
Craig (1990), Welbourne (2001), and Kusch (2002).
1.3 Scientists as Reflective Practitioners 9
5
The notion of knowledge-how, and particularly its relation to the notion of knowledge-that,
i.e., propositional knowledge, is debated. Arguably, not all knowledge-how can be reduced to
knowledge-that (Fantl, 2012; Ryle, 1971). This seems to be the case even in scientific practice where
knowledge-how serves the aim of producing scientific knowledge-that. More important, however,
is the relation between knowledge-how and articulation. Both knowledge-that and knowledge-how
can be imagined to remain unarticulated in a given context. But insofar as knowledge-how pertains
to incorporated knowledge, it stands to reason that it poses a particular challenge for exhaustive
1.4 Chapter Overview 11
References
Andersen, H., & Wagenknecht, S. (2013). Epistemic dependence in interdisci-
plinary groups. Synthese, 190(11), 1881–1898.
Ankeny, R., Chang, H., Boumans, M., & Boon, M. (2011). Introduction:
Philosophy of science in practice. European Journal for Philosophy of Science,
1(3), 303–307.
Bechtel, W. (2008). Mental mechanisms: Philosophical perspectives on cognitive
neuroscience. New York: Routledge.
Bergin, L. A. (2002). Testimony, epistemic difference, and privilege: How
feminist epistemology can improve our understanding of the communication
of knowledge. Social Epistemology, 16 (3), 197–213.
Callebaut, W. (Ed.). (1993). Taking the naturalistic turn: Or how real philosophy
of science is done. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Calvert, J., & Fujimura, J. H. (2011). Calculating life? Duelling discourses in
interdisciplinary systems biology. Studies In History and Philosophy of Biological
and Biomedical Sciences, 42(2), 155–163.
Cheon, H. (2014). In what sense is scientific knowledge collective knowledge?
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44(4), 407–423.
Cohen, S. (1986). Knowledge and context. The Journal of Philosophy, 83(10),
574–583.
Collins, H. (2013). Three dimensions of expertise. Phenomenology and the
Cognitive Sciences, 12(2), 253–273.
Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2007). Rethinking expertise. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Craig, E. (1990). Knowledge and the state of nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
de Ridder, J. (2014). Epistemic dependence and collective scientific knowledge.
Synthese, 191(1), 37–53.
Fantl, J. (2012). Knowledge how. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia
of philosophy (Winter 2012 ed.). Retrieved from http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/win2012/entries/knowledge-how/
Fricker, E. (2006b). Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa
(Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 225–250). Oxford: Clarendon.
Fuller, S. (1988). Social epistemology. Bloomington: Indiana Unversity Press.
Giere, R. N. (1985). Philosophy of science naturalized. Philosophy of Science,
52(3), 331–356.
Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
References 15
1
Scientometric studies have produced a large body of data testifying to the increase in multi-
authored publications (Balog, 1979/1980; Beaver & Rosen, 1978, 1979a,b; Braun, Gomez, Mendez,
& Schubert, 1992; Cronin, 2005; Cronin, Shaw, & Barre, 2004; Meadows, 1974; Meadows &
O’Connor, 1971; Moody, 2004; Wagner & Leydesdorff, 2005). For an overview of the literature
see Subramanyam (1983) and Katz and Martin (1997). Note that the number of colleagues thanked
in acknowledgments has also increased (Cronin, 2005; Cronin et al., 2004).
22 2 Research Groups
size of research groups can change quickly when funding runs out or
new research opportunities open up (Etzkowitz, 1992, p. 36). Yet, for a
group to function, it should be small enough so that its members can
develop ongoing face-to-face relationships. A group is too small when
it cannot ensure enough varied interaction among group members. A
group is too large when its members’ activities cannot be “kept on track,”
when their activities cannot be sufficiently coordinated, especially when
junior scientists cannot be sufficiently supervised and trained and when
they may produce significant results that senior group members miss out
on(Etzkowitz, 1992, p. 38). The less routine the work, the smaller a group
has to be to ensure an accurate exchange of information among its various
members (Hagstrom, 1974a, p. 756).
Research groups can be coordinated in different ways. A great variety
of factors shape research group leadership, such as the degree of interdis-
ciplinarity involved, work ethos and employment culture, but also group
leaders’ professional experience, their academic biography and personality.
While some groups centralize leadership, other groups will distribute its
responsibilities among its members (Cohen, Kruse, & Anbar, 1982). A
crucial responsibility of group leadership is to manage the scientific focus
of group members’ research activities. Here, group leaders focus on an
ambivalent choice, as Hackett observes: “tighter focus may intensify com-
petition, while looser focus may dissipate energy and relinquish fruitful
synergies” (Hackett, 2005, p. 818). While some competition among group
members may increase their initiative, too much competition constrains
collaboration among group members and may prove detrimental to the
group’s research performance.2 Furthermore, group leadership needs to
balance continuity in research focus against “the continual, incremental
freshening of a group’s membership and capabilities that expands the
boundaries of its sphere of inquiry” (Hackett, 2005, p. 794), continuously
adapting to the ways in which scientific fields evolve.
Research group members, as Hackett observes, typically “work face-to-
face, sharing work space, materials, technologies, objectives, hypotheses
2
For competition among members of a research group see Edge and Mulkay (1976); Hagstrom
(1974b), and for the complicated mediation between collaboration and competition in research
groups see Traweek (1988, p. 88); Poulsen (2001).
2.1 The Phenomenon 23
3
For an overview see Frodeman, Klein, Mitcham, and Holbrook (2010); Huutoniemi, Klein, Bruun,
and Hukkinen (2010); Klein (1996, 2010); Weingart and Stehr (2000).
2.3 Excourse: Interdisciplinary Research Groups 29
2.4 Conclusion
In contemporary natural science, scientific knowledge is created col-
laboratively in research groups. Therefore, any attempt to understand
comprehensively the social dimension of scientific knowledge creation has
to account for the epistemic role of research groups. While philosophy has
long focused on notions of community to account for epistemologically
significant matters of social structure, more recent research in philosophy
and social epistemology of science has begun to analyze research groups,
choosing either a collectivist or an individualist approach. I pursue an
individualist approach to research group collaboration, a decision reso-
nant with the book’s empirical grounding in qualitative data obtained
from observation and individual interviewing. Furthermore, I pursue a
comparative angle, investigating the differences and similarities of mono-
and interdisciplinary group collaboration. The following Chap. 3 will
detail the empirical method and the comparative case study that underlie
this book.
References
Abbott, A. (2001). Chaos of disciplines. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Andersen, H. (2010). Joint acceptance and scientific change: A case study.
Episteme, 7 (3), 248–265.
Andersen, H., & Wagenknecht, S. (2013). Epistemic dependence in interdisci-
plinary groups. Synthese, 190(11), 1881–1898.
Balog, C. (1979/1980). Multiple authorship and author collaboration in agri-
cultural research publications. Journal of Research Communication Studies, 2,
159–169.
Beaver, D. d., & Rosen, R. (1978). Studies in scientific collaboration: Part I – the
professional origins of scientific co-authorship. Scientometrics, 1(1), 64–84.
Beaver, D. d., & Rosen, R. (1979a). Studies in scientific collaboration: Part III –
professionalization and the natural history of modern scientific co-authorship.
Scientometrics, 1(3), 231–245.
Beaver, D. d., & Rosen, R. (1979b). Studies in scientific collaboration: Part II
– scientific co-authorship, research productivity and visibility in the French
scientific elite, 1799–1830. Scientometrics, 1(2), 133–149.
References 31
Bechtel, W. (1986). Integrating scientific disciplines: Case studies from the life
sciences. Dordrecht: Springer.
Bouvier, A. (2004). Individual beliefs and collective beliefs in sciences and
philosophy: The plural subject and the polyphonic subject accounts: Case
studies. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(3), 382–407.
Braun, T., Gomez, I., Mendez, A., & Schubert, A. (1992). International co-
authorship patterns in physics and its subfields. Scientometrics, 24(2), 181–
200.
Campbell, D. T. (1969). Ethnocentrism of disciplines and the fish-scale model of
omniscience. In M. Sherif & C. W. Sherif (Eds.), Interdisciplinary relationships
in the social sciences (pp. 328–348). New Jersey: Aldine Transaction.
Cheon, H. (2014). In what sense is scientific knowledge collective knowledge?
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44(4), 407–423.
Clarke, B. L. (1964). Multiple authorship trends in scientific papers. Science,
143(3608), 822–824.
Cohen, B. P., Kruse, R. J., & Anbar, M. (1982). The social structure of scientific
research teams. The Pacific Sociological Review, 25(2), 205–232.
Cronin, B. (2005). The hand of science: Academic writing and its rewards. Lanham:
Scarecrow Press.
Cronin, B., Shaw, D., & Barre, K. L. (2004). Visible, less visible, and
invisible work: Patterns of collaboration in 20th century chemistry. Jour-
nal of the American Society for Information Science and Technology, 55(2),
160–168.
Darden, L., & Maull, N. (1977). Interfield theories. Philosophy of Science, 44(1),
43–64.
Edge, D., & Mulkay, M. J. (1976). Astronomy transformed: The emergence of radio
astronomy in Britain. New York: Wiley.
Etzkowitz, H. (1992). Individual investigators and their research group. Minerva,
30(1), 28–50.
Fagan, M. B. (2011). Is there collective scientific knowledge? Arguments from
explanation. The Philosophical Quarterly, 61(243), 247–269.
Frodeman, R., Klein, J. T., Mitcham, C., & Holbrook, J. B. (Eds.). (2010). The
Oxford handbook of interdisciplinarity. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Frost-Arnold, K. (2014). The cognitive attitude of rational trust. Synthese, 191,
1957–1974.
Gilbert, M. (1987). Modelling collective belief. Synthese, 73(1), 185–204.
Gillespie, D. F., & Birmbaum, P. H. (1980). Status concordance, coordination,
and success in interdisciplinary research terms. Human Relations, 33(1), 41–
56.
32 2 Research Groups
1
Compare with reflection in qualitative social scientific method as in George and Bennett (2005)
and Gerring (2007).
3.1 Engaging Empirical Insights in Philosophy 39
2
For general references on qualitative research methods as developed in the social sciences see Strauss
and Corbin (1990) and Denzin and Lincoln (1994).
42 3 Method
to describe me, a “fly on the wall.” Yet when I began to shadow single
group members my role changed. While observing their lab work or
joining lunch breaks with the scientists studied, I had many extended,
informal conversations about their research groups and their collaborative
networks, about the place that their research groups claim for themselves
within the university organization, and national and international peer
communities. When scientists revealed their curiosity about philosophy
of science, I explained what they seemed to be interested in. I avoided
philosophical jargon in the same way that they avoided biochemical or
geological terms when explaining their work to me. I did not pretend to
share their educational background and their research interests. Despite
my physical presence in the scientists’ labs, meeting rooms and canteens,
and given that I had received no academic training in natural science, I
remained an outside visitor. The professional slack between us helped to
establish myself as a trustworthy outsider, opening a space for conversa-
tions about scientific practice that took a few steps back, “abstracting”
from the “concrete” everyday of research practice and speaking about the
socio-epistemic challenges of collaborative research.
Philosophers of science have found different ways in which to relate
to the scientists whose work and whose manner of working they are
interested in studying. At one end of the spectrum, there are philosophers
whose research interests substantially overlap with those of the scien-
tists observed and interviewed. Borrowing a term which Hasok Chang
has coined, one could call these philosophical studies “complementary
science” (Chang, 2004, p. 238ff.). Reflecting upon her participant obser-
vation, Sabina Leonelli describes herself as being “[…] closely allied with
the scientific goals pursued by the scientists I was studying” (Leonelli,
2007, p. 88). In fact, she calls herself a collaborator rather than observer
(Leonelli, 2007, p. 89). Moving closer to the other end of the spec-
trum, there are philosophers whose research interests are dissimilar to
the scientific interests of the researchers studied, for example, Nancy
Nersessian’s work on scientific cognition. The research questions guiding
her are largely disconnected from the questions pursued by the researchers
studied. This does not imply that her work would be of no concern to
practicing scientists. Nersessian has reasons to believe that her cognitive
studies can contribute to academic training (Nersessian, 1995, p. 211).
46 3 Method
The interview […] is a place where views may clash, deceive, seduce,
enchant. It is as much about seeing a world—mine, yours, ours, theirs—as
about hearing accounts, opinions, arguments, reasons, declarations: words
with views into different worlds. (Schostak, 2006, p. 1)
3
Yet, in contrast to, e.g., Hasu and Miettinen (2006) and Ellis and Berger (2003), my dialogical
approach carries no “interventionist” motivation. The concept of co-construction should not lead
the reader to believe that I have transcended the form of traditional interviewing—I certainly
have not. I have restrained myself to asking questions, elaborating on these questions and offering
reformulations. In single instances I have explained in simple terms how some philosophers would
think about the issue in question. I have not, however, confronted interviewees with an elaborate
description of my tentative, theoretically informed perspective.
3.4 Structuring Empirical Insights 49
niche for reflections that otherwise might not occur. Both interviewer and
interviewee contribute to the interview, but they do so in very different
ways. Neither during nor after the interview can interview partners be
equal peers. Both of them are observers. During the interview, they
observe one another and interpret facial expression, gesture, tone of voice,
and implicit and explicit messages. But whereas the interviewer-analyst is
primarily listening during the actual interview, the interviewee remains
silent during the analysis process. The interpretation that is pivotal for a
philosophical study is the one made by the interviewing philosopher, and
in the end he or she comes to represent the co-constructed interview.4
Interviewing has been a pleasant experience. Most of my questions
were met with goodwill. The challenge for interviewing with philo-
sophical intentions lies, however, before the actual occasion. Preparing
good questions is a time-consuming task. Useful questions have to be
both meaningful to the interviewee and meaningful with regard to the
philosophical issues at hand. In my experience, asking practicing scientists
to take up philosophical theorizing does not yield results of the quality
desired. Interviewing is a co-construction, but its grounds have to be
carefully prepared by the investigator.
4
The issue of representation has been dealt with comprehensively in anthropology, see, e.g., Denzin
(1994, p. 503). Interviewing philosophers represent the people who are participating in their study
and they should deal with this burden carefully, see Fine, Weis, Weseen, and Wong (2000).
50 3 Method
my data, that is, some of the field notes that I took during group meetings
and shadowing phases, and all interview transcripts.
Coding is a method of analysis that treats empirical data as text and
involves an analysis process in the course of which the data text is
segmented and reorganized. Being a term adapted from grounded theory,
‘codes’ are “[…] conceptual labels placed on discrete happenings, events,
and other instances of phenomena” (Strauss & Corbin, 1990, p. 61; see
also Alexa & Zuell, 2000, p. 306). To code means to index text passages
with descriptive or analytic categories that relate, if vaguely at first, to the
research interest. Indexing text passages allows the researcher to familiarize
him or herself with small data fragments. By breaking up a body of
text into manageable segments, describing those segments, unfolding the
information they convey, comparing and relating them, the researcher
reorganizes the data with regard to the research focus and is able to
interpret them as a response to the research questions (cf. Coffey &
Atkinson, 1996).
The formulation of codes can be guided by the intention to describe
data from the bottom-up, that is, with the conceptual resources inherent
in them, or by the intention to relate them to theory, that is, to the
repertoire of abstract concepts offered by the discourse in which a piece of
research is to be embedded. An example of a strongly theory-guided code
in my analysis would be “testimony.” Labeling different text passages with
this code, however, did not help me substantially in organizing my data
material, because the label “testimony” did not correspond very well with
the data that I had. I realized that the acts of informational exchange that I
was looking for were embedded in socio-epistemic relationships that were
better described as “dependence relations.” Therefore, I started to code
for “dependence” instead. This led me to distinguish two different forms
of epistemic dependence (see Chap. 7). An example of a code that was, at
least in the beginning, rather unconnected to my theoretical framework
would be “frustration.” While shadowing a PhD student, frustration
was a recurrent theme in his conversations with me. Clearly, this was
related to the high pressure to succeed, his anxiety about failure and his
understanding that he had been given a high-risk project as his dissertation
topic. His frustration, however, was also related to his work conditions. He
perceived his research group to be only a “little interactive,” a perception
3.4 Structuring Empirical Insights 51
5
For a critique of thematic analysis, questioning the representational status of themes, see Gomm
(2004, p. 196).
52 3 Method
References
Alexa, M., & Zuell, C. (2000). Text analysis software: Commonalities, differ-
ences and limitations: The results of a review. Quality and Quantity, 34(3),
299–321.
Attride-Stirling, J. (2001). Thematic networks: An analytic tool for qualitative
research. Qualitative Research, 1(3), 385–405.
Bogner, A., & Menz, W. (2009). The theory-generating expert interview: Epis-
temological interest, forms of knowledge, interaction. In A. Bogner, B. Littig,
& W. Menz (Eds.), Interviewing experts (pp. 43–80). New York: Palgrave
Macmillan.
54 3 Method
The strength of our group is that we’re experts in particular fields and
all come together with our own expertise and we try not to step on
each others’ toes.
Adam, interview, group1
The first group that I have studied empirically through observation and
interviewing is the planetary science group, which is a small but long-
standing interdisciplinary collaboration among senior researchers and
their graduate and post-graduate students. The group examines extra-
terrestrial surface processes and combines expertise from geology, physics,
chemistry and microbiology. Having searched for interdisciplinary col-
laborations at Danish universities online, I contacted the group in 2010
and soon began to observe their weekly meetings on Tuesday mornings.
Later I shadowed individual group members, following them through
their professional days. When I had familiarized myself with the group, I
set out to interview the five scientists that formed the group’s core at the
time of my investigation.
This chapter portrays the planetary science group and illustrates at the
same time how I familiarized myself with it, providing examples of the
empirical data I obtained. Section 4.1 describes the group meetings where
my observations began. As it turned out, these are crucial for the group’s
functioning and continually interweave individual research interests into
a collaborative experimental practice. Section 4.2 abstracts from my
situated observations and describes the group more systematically. Finally,
Sect. 4.3 draws on two of the interviews I conducted to provide a more
nuanced portrayal of the group from the personal perspective of its
group members. The interviews are not only deeply personal accounts
of sentiment and experience—they also touch upon a range of issues that
are crucial to discussions of scientific practice in social epistemology. The
interviews, thus, provide a first glimpse of what it means to wrestle with
epistemological problems, problems of epistemic dependence and trust in
professional practice.
This chapter, as well as the following Chap. 5, provides the background
against which the data that I refer to in empirically informed arguments in
later parts of the book gain significance. With its main focus on qualitative
empirical data and the way in which I have gathered them, these two
chapters may be an unusual read for many philosophers. Regarding
content, but also regarding tone and style, these chapters do not abide by
the conventions of writing that dominate analytic philosophy of science
and social epistemology. Once I have laid out the empirical foundations
upon which my reasoning rests, however, later parts of the book return to
a way of writing closer to the conventions of analytic philosophy.
Shortly before nine Laurits opens the door to a small meeting room. He
leaves his keys in the lock and takes a seat. Laurits always takes the seat
right next to the door; he is in fact the only person that always sits in the
same chair. He has brought with him a pile of documents, which he spreads
out in front of him. […]
Shortly after nine two senior physicists, Adam and Rasmus, the group’s
technician and three doctoral students arrive. One of them, Lucas, is
attending the meeting for the first time. He has just started his four-year
dissertation project in microbiology. His supervisor, Victor, cannot attend
the meeting, because he has conflicting teaching duties. Another of his PhD
students, however, is present today and she now introduces the new PhD to
the group. They all shake hands. Christoffer, the group’s chemist, arrives.
Since there is no seat at the table left, he chooses an armchair in the corner
of the room.
62 4 The Planetary Science Group
The first point on Laurits’s agenda deals with a “shaking device” that he
wants to have installed within a bigger instrument. Nikolaj, the technician,
has apparently contacted a number of companies to find out where they
could buy such a device and how much they would have to spend on it.
Shaking tables that move horizontally are commercially available. Nikolaj
would have to modify these so that vertical moves are also possible. Laurits
thinks that such a modification would be a good solution, whereas Adam
disagrees. He questions the resilience of horizontally shaking devices with
regard to vertical movements. Adam is in charge of the instrument and
his opinion is crucial. Therefore, they do not settle the issue for the time
being. Nikolaj is asked to develop a different idea for building a shaking
device in cooperation with the companies from whom they might purchase
the device. On this occasion, Laurits also asks Nikolaj about the price of a
cooling plate that they have agreed to order. […]
Laurits asks Christoffer about the results of an experiment that he has
finished recently. They aren’t good, but Rasmus insists that some time
ago they produced reasonable results with a very similar experiment: “It
was little, but significant.” Christoffer agrees, Adam doesn’t. They try to
remember the exact details of the experimental set-up they used in the
earlier experiments. “Anyway,” says Adam, “we could put it on the list.”
By suggesting to ‘put it on the list,’ Adam proposes to repeat the original
experiment. They all agree that it would be worthwhile to perform this kind
of experiment in a number of variations, again at a later date. And Rasmus
mentions in this context that he just ordered some more experimental
materials for another experiment that they planned to carry out soon as
well.
During the remaining time they talk about a potpourri of minor issues
that are mostly brought up by Laurits. An application has to be finished.
Why not include a colleague from another department with whom they
used to cooperate? Instruments have to be built; tests have to be run. How
are the lab students doing? The Xrd-detector in the chemistry department
has been seriously damaged during the rebuilding and will thus not be
available for some time. They can, however, use an instrument in another
department. Their homepage has to be revised and a PhD defense has to
be organized. Maybe one of the censors could deliver a talk? “And,” Laurits
checks with a quick look at today’s agenda what still needs to be discussed,
“there is this project meeting in Norway. Someone should go there.” “Yeah,”
Adam replies, “someone should go there. I’ve looked into the program.
4.2 Group Characterization 63
When Lucas and Adam descend to the basement where the group’s
large simulation facility is installed, I join them. I know that in the
meantime Laurits will return to his office and write up today’s minutes.
At the bottom, he will list open to-dos, on which he will follow up at the
beginning of next week’s meeting.
that emerged around the wind tunnel morphed into a research group.
Since the wind tunnel facility and the experiments conducted with
it became more and more complex, Adam joined the group to take
responsibility for the day-to-day operation and the technical development
of the facility.
What the divergence in accounts of the group’s foundation shows is
how different group members approach the group and their interdisci-
plinary collaboration with other group members from the point of view
of their personal, disciplinary research interests. Despite this difference in
perspective, however, the planetary science group succeeds time and again
in interweaving individual research interests in a shared experimental
practice.
I could work alone down in the [simulation facility] in the lab doing my
physics things and still collaborate internationally with people. That would
work, but I think we would miss out on a lot of, we would miss out on a lot
of research and there are a lot of new avenues that have started up purely
because we are a bunch of experts all talking together.
Like Laurits, Adam underlines the important role that regular meetings
play and how they provide a forum for discussing recent findings, deciding
on the next experimental steps and agreeing on the outline of the
argument which is to constitute their next jointly authored paper. These
meetings also provide an opportunity to discuss different viewpoints
so that group members understand each other’s distinct disciplinary
perspectives and can explain to one another how they would interpret
the measurements that they have obtained. The back and forth between
explaining and understanding is an interactive process that has the func-
tion of bringing “[…] all up to speed, [so that] we’re all sort of knowing
the same sort of thing.” Such a common understanding forms the basis
of collaborative experimentation.
To underline the role of such a common understanding, let me refer to
an episode in the interview where Adam describes an incident of severe
disagreement with a collaborator outside the group’s core. While it is
usually not a problem to agree on a jointly authored paper, a couple of
years ago members of the planetary science group were in disagreement
with an outside collaborator, who refused to accept the conclusion which
the group had reached on the basis of various measurements, some of
which he had taken. As a consequence, he asked to “take his name off the
paper” and the remaining authors had to find a colleague with a matching
field of expertise who could step in. “[I]t’s sad when that happens,” Adam
tells me, “but it’s kind of rare. It doesn’t happen a lot—not to us anyway.
And it doesn’t happen in-house.” This is because “[…] if we disagree with
the conclusions of it, then we would – we do some more measurements
until we, we’re sure.”
70 4 The Planetary Science Group
help, at least that’s what I’ve used all of it for.” Help from scholars with
a different area of expertise is essential, she underlines, because planetary
science as a research field necessarily involves a scientific perspective that
spans across the many narrow specialized niches covered by individual
scientists. Therefore, two particular kinds of knowledge are to be acquired
in interdisciplinary research. On the one hand, Laura, contrary to Laurits,
points out that group members learn from each other about each other’s
fields, particularly with respect to aspects specifically relevant to particular
experiments such as, for example, the choice of materials and instruments.
This knowledge is highly context dependent. On the other hand, group
members learn “what [they] can use each other for,” that is, to gain an
understanding about “the field of expertise [they] each have.”
Laura has been involved in interdisciplinary science not only at the
planetary science group, but also as a participant in a larger international
research project. Planetary science is an interdisciplinary field and charac-
terized, as she tells me, by “[…] the fact that the areas of interest are very
separate.” Although they “overlap” in their common interest in planetary
surfaces as an empirical phenomenon, scholars in the field and members of
the planetary science group in particular “[…] don’t do the same things,
we haven’t been trained to do the same things, we haven’t been taught
to think in the same ways and that can actually be quite a hindrance
sometimes.” As an example, she tells me about the difficulties faced by
scientists from the international research project in which she participated
when they talked about atmospheric particles:
[…] One of the things I found problematic, for example in the [interna-
tional project], we had of course both geologists, physicists, atmospheric
chemists, just talking about for example particles in the atmosphere, getting,
just getting around the fact of what, what do we call the different particles.
Are they sand? Are they dust? Is it silicates? I think we spent three months
coming up with a definition of what size particles are what, because it
turned out that everybody had their own system of size determination of
particles. […] So sands and grains and dust was defined in three or four
different ways, just within the about 50 or 100 scientists that were on [the
international project].
72 4 The Planetary Science Group
Interestingly, Laura has made these observations not within the plane-
tary science group but in an international project whose participants had
not worked closely together before. This, along with other remarks that
she made, suggests that the planetary science group has successfully gone
through a phase of interdisciplinary familiarizing. All group members have
developed a common “general understanding” of planetary surfaces and
this understanding must have been established, Laura tells me, before she
joined the group more than four years ago. Yet, when I ask her whether the
group shares not only a common understanding but also a joint vision, it is
one of the few moments where she hesitates and then answers that “[…]
there is definitely a shared vision of wanting to understand [planets],”
an “overall sense of direction,” but that she cannot specify this sense any
further:
[…] every person in the [planets] group probably has their own, will have
their own interest in [planets] in some respect—ahm, whether you can say
that there is a more narrow perspective for the […] group combined, I don’t,
off the top of my head, I don’t really know.
have, the better opportunity you have of having a group that has a wider
knowledge base.” At a different point in the interview, however, she also
mentions that the core employees of a group, as in fact any senior scientist,
can be described as a knowledge base in themselves. As she explains to
me, as a post-doctoral researcher, you are “[…] seen as a knowledge base
in yourself,” that is, “[y]ou have your own area, start developing the area
where you become the expert.” As she is becoming a post-doc herself, she
sees herself confronted with the challenge of developing and consolidating
the kind of expertise she has to have autonomously— in herself —in order
to respond to the knowledge needs of her interdisciplinary collaborators.
To conclude this chapter, let me point out that the concerns for
professional autonomy in the interviews I have led with Laura and Adam
are present in the interviews with other members of the planetary science
group as well. Like other group members, Laura and Adam seek to
build and retain a distinct disciplinary identity alongside interdisciplinary
collaboration, thereby cultivating a sense of autonomy in the midst of
thoroughgoing collaborative dependence. The next chapter begins to
elucidate how these concerns play out in a molecular biology laboratory,
a mono-disciplinary research group.
5
The Molecular Biology Laboratory
They all came to my lab, because they sort of respect what we do and
what we can do for them.
Johan, group leader, interview, group2
The meeting room is slowly filling, around 20 people present, less than usual
during semester times. People appreciate the opportunity to chat before the
meeting starts. Some of them haven’t seen each other for a while, because
they were on holiday or have been visiting other laboratories. I overhear a
PhD student asking another: “Hey, what about the results you had? I’d like
to know.”
Shortly after nine o’clock, Johan appears, takes his seat, welcomes every-
body, and without much ado begins talking about a funding proposal he is
busy writing and for which he will need input from various group members
during the coming days. Then, in his rather abrupt manner, he announces
“lab matters” and quickly walks through a range of topics. He mentions two
new PhD students who will join their lab and a visitor who will arrive in late
autumn. Then he talks about their plan to move offices and lab space to an
adjacent building. The moving date is approaching. Johan says it is essential
that they “keep the coziness we have here, but to be at the same time closer to
the rest of the department.” He goes on to talk about a planned outdoor trip,
the yearly lab excursion in early October. He takes a look at the handwritten
notes he has jotted on the sheet of paper lying in front of him on the table.
The next point on his agenda concerns their lab equipment. There is a
problem with repairing an important instrument. Repairing this broken
instrument “has been a nightmare.” Other instruments that could serve as
a substitute have been moved around the lab building in the course of the
ongoing reconstruction process, so they are difficult to access. “In urgent
cases we can use the one in biophysics,” Johan says, “but currently we’re
using that one more than they are.” Then they talk about other instruments,
and discuss which ones they might want to purchase in the near future.
When it is time for individual research presentations, it turns out that it
is unclear whose turn it is to present today. Since no one has prepared a slide
show, and no one is volunteering to improvise ad hoc, Johan turns to a newly
started post-doctoral researcher. It’s only her first week in the laboratory, and
she reports that she has started working on a protein together with a PhD
student, trying to purify the protein and separate it from other compounds.
Unfortunately, the concentration of a substance in a dilution they use for
purification was too high, “so that we couldn’t observe any activity.” Johan
comments on this encouragingly: “We should definitely have an eye on
this.” Then he begins questioning a student who has just returned from a
lab at an American university. It turns out, the student reports, that specific
78 5 The Molecular Biology Laboratory
experiments that they have been trying to conduct in Johan’s lab earlier this
year (alas, unsuccessfully) had “worked over there.” They shortly discuss
possible differences in the experimental set-up. Johan closes this episode
with an optimistic remark, then asks: “Any other research summaries?” No.
But suddenly a spontaneous conversation among four people in the room
arises, involving the discussion of recent positive results that one of them
has been able to obtain in purifying a protein. As usual, I observe, their
discussion is a back and forth between a person whose experimental results
are discussed and her commentators whose questions typically follow a
distinctive pattern, trying to establish whether particular experimental
options have been tried and with what success.
Finally Johan, as always, asks: “Anything else?” They quickly talk about
planned trips to synchrotrons, experimental facilities in which the structure
of purified proteins can be tested. The booking of autumn time slots for a
beamline in a particular synchrotron is opening soon. Who is going there in
person? Who else should go, and whose samples can they take with them?
Then the meeting is over, and a half a dozen students are waiting to get hold
of Johan.
These field notes, as cursory as they are, are a first illustration of the
character of the molecular biology laboratory as a research group, its
hierarchical structure, the trial-and-error character of its research, research
that is highly specialized and focused on a handful of experimental
techniques.
they needed a longer conversation, they should book time via the online
calendar system.
Johan himself does not perform laboratory work anymore. Over the
last decade, his laboratory has grown constantly and he has gradually
withdrawn himself from the work bench. With respect to the day-to-day
supervision of undergraduates and graduate students in the laboratory, he
delegates substantial parts of his supervisory role to the more experienced
post-docs and senior researchers in his group, who are overseeing groups
of three to four graduate students and undergraduates. These subgroups
collaborate closely on a cluster of related, that is, structurally similar,
proteins. Each subgroup holds a meeting once a week, often with Johan
present, to take stock of their experimental progress and coordinate their
efforts for the coming days.
As a group leader, Johan likes to emphasize the common theme around
which all members of the laboratory work, namely the structural determi-
nation of a family of complex proteins that perform specific cell functions.
Yet, there is no one shared research object. Typically, every group member
pursues his or her distinct, individual project, which usually consists of
an attempt to determine the molecular structure of a particular protein
by crystallographic methods. From the molecular structure, then, conclu-
sions may be drawn concerning the protein’s molecular functions.
In general, all proteins are subjected to the same biochemical proce-
dures. First, cells containing the protein are selected or manufactured and
vast cell colonies are grown. Then, in various steps, the protein is isolated.
This isolation process is called “purification.” When a sufficiently large
and pure sample of the protein is obtained, it is subjected to conditions
that ideally induce its crystallization. In crystallized form, the protein can
be analyzed with the help of laser beams in a high tech facility called a
synchrotron. Some group members travel to synchrotrons all over Europe,
up to three or four times a year. In synchrotrons, laser light will be directed
at the crystal. When hitting the crystal, the light is scattered in different
directions. If one can detect patterns in the way the crystal diffracts the
laser light, one can model the structure of the protein.
Unfortunately, although all the proteins studied in Johan’s lab belong
to one family and thus resemble each other in both their structure
and function, different proteins are very particular in their biochemical
5.2 Group Characterization 81
features. The dilution that works for one protein may or may not work
for another. Thus, the purification and crystallization of proteins is to a
large extent a time-consuming (and often frustrating) process of trial and
error. Knorr-Cetina hence describes the dominant experimental approach
in molecular biology as “blind variation” (Knorr-Cetina, 1999, p. 79ff.).
Every minuscule step in the purification of a protein can be performed
with a number of different chemicals, at different temperatures, at dif-
ferent times and with varying speed and length. A thorough literature
review can give ideas, but will hardly provide the researcher with a
successful “recipe” right away. Personal experience and informal access to
the practical experience of other group members is vital. The questions
are: What would be worth trying? What worked for others and is likely
to work in the case at hand? The scientific insights generated by research
in this area must, to a large degree, be described as knowledge concerning
the technical manipulation of biological objects such as cells, cell parts
and single molecular structures (Leonelli, 2009).
All scientists in the laboratory have an education in molecular biology
or pursue a degree in this field. This implies that most group members
have either roughly the same experimental skills and expertise or seek
to acquire them. Yet, the fact that the molecular biology laboratory
is a mono-disciplinary team should not veil the diversity of academic
biographies. All scientists working in this group can be regarded as molec-
ular biologists, but there is variation in expertise. Some PhD students
have a background in programs other than molecular biology, such as
medicinal chemistry or even theoretical chemistry, and some of them
have chosen to take courses in neighboring fields such as bioinformatics.
The variation in expertise continues at higher levels of seniority, although
differences in individual specialization tend to be more subtle here.
Post-doctoral researchers may, for example, specialize in proteins with a
particular molecular function that have to be cultivated in particular cell
environments.
It is essential for members of the laboratory to learn from one another,
acquiring tacit knowledge while working side by side at the bench in
the laboratory space they share. More than half of the group members
are students and PhD students who, under the immediate supervision
of a post-doctoral fellow, carry out large fractions of the experimental
82 5 The Molecular Biology Laboratory
labor. Not only students but all lab members have a permanent interest in
acquiring and improving the skill to master new experimental techniques.
Technological innovation in the field of molecular biology moves fast, so
that experienced as well as young researchers face the challenge of keeping
up with the state of the art in experimental techniques. Students start by
learning generic experimental routines; later on they proceed to complex,
highly technology-vested procedures.
Only through learning-by-doing in the laboratory can junior scientists
achieve the professional autonomy of an experienced researcher. To
achieve and maintain this autonomy is the learning goal of all group
members. Yet, laboratory practice is necessarily collaborative as it is
practically impossible for any one person to handle all experimental
procedures required in the pursuit of a specific project alone. These
procedures are extremely time-consuming and knowledge-intensive. For
the laboratory to run smoothly, group members need to help each other
with the planning, set-up and monitoring of their experiments, thereby
offering advice and counsel to one another.
But while scientific practice in the laboratory is highly collaborative,
it also features competition, both among group members as well as
between the group as a whole and other research groups elsewhere. First,
it is not unusual for several groups in one research community to work
on the same protein independently. The crystallographic determination
of protein structures is often perceived as a “race” in which scientists
compete with one another. While the discovery of a new protein structure
allows for a publication in the highest ranking journals, the confirmation
of a discovered structure receives substantially less attention. Therefore,
information about ongoing research given on university websites is often
outdated or intentionally vague. Research meetings are confidential and
unpublished information or material samples are only exchanged within
the laboratory or with collaborating groups whose research is complemen-
tary, not competing.1
1
For an empirical study on the balance between collaboration and competition in the Danish life
sciences see Poulsen (2001).
5.2 Group Characterization 83
Johan has been group leader for many years, a period during which he
has accomplished significant scientific success and during which his lab
has significantly grown in terms of lab members, research volume and
in terms of the breadth of experimental techniques that lab members
apply in their research. Given this development, Johan describes himself as
retaining his “own sort of deep expert knowledge” within crystallography,
a set of experimental techniques that has remained at the center of the lab’s
research activity over the years; yet he acknowledges that the members of
his lab “[…] do a lot that I’m sort of less expert knowledgeable about,
but where for example the technicians, and most of the post-docs also,
are very knowledgeable.”
When asked about his leadership and the kind of work relations he
entertains with group members, he describes his role as group leader in
terms of “mentorship,” trying “to convince them of the good ideas” and
“discourage them from what you see as a bad idea.” When I want to know
more about “bad” ideas, he explains:
Yeah, [a bad idea] could be something where cost–benefit is really not good,
where you end up spending a lot of time and effort on something that in
the end doesn’t answer the question you want. Or starting a project that
isn’t sort of ripe, I mean in the sense that we end up spending a lot of time
on things we are not experts on. […] These are the kind of discussions as
a group leader one needs to take. Also, in terms of for example which kind
of equipment we use, and will invest in, which kind of new methods we
use. I think it’s important from time to time that we try and do new things.
5.3 Interview Voices 85
[…] but we can’t change our lab too much all the time. It has to have a
balance, like, between conservative stability and innovation.
[…] so once a new idea or opportunity pops up, yeah well then one would
think well who can actually incorporate that. Either as a new project or
into [an existing] project, and then talk to these, go down the hallway,
or set up a small meeting with three people. Should we do this […] and
normally they are interested. Other times, if no one really takes the ball
and says well that’s not really—sometimes, one needs to be a little more
insisting. Because I mean everyone wants to sort of get along and produce
something but sometimes you need to invest also in trying something new,
that’s an important role where sometimes one needs to be a bit more sort of
an authority, saying: we gotta do this, right. So, that, finding that balance
is important I think. At the same time being an authority, at the same time
allowing the independence.
I see it as a very important thing that what I do is to set out people for careers
in the future. Not only should I publish good papers, but we should also
publish really—no, no, sorry [laughing] produce or send out really good
people. And you get to realize also among the more senior scientists, they
actually also rate each other like that: are they good people, those people
coming from those labs?
Since many people pass through the laboratory, coming from and
moving on to other research institutions, Johan tells me, “[…] you need
as a group leader to really have a good eye on to be sure that procedures
and the science is really maintaining its high level.” If done right, “[…]
you have this fluent mass of people with a lot of expertise that all the
time maintains in the lab.” Given the constant arrival of new and the
departure of old group members, Johan is, apart from lab technicians and
administrative staff, “[…] the only one really continuing all the time –
I’m the memory, so to say, of the laboratory.” Yet overseeing the group’s
research has become challenging because of its growth, a development that
forces Johan to delegate to others his day-to-day supervision and hands-
on laboratory work. In order to manage a laboratory of this size, Johan has
“[…] set it up more formally, that we have groups and these individual
project groups meet with me and others, and I really encourage them to
meet of course anyways, whether I’m there or not.”
[…] she cares a lot about my PhD which is extremely nice and she is always
kind of telling me that this is, “put this in your thesis” and so forth. In her
mind, when she started, was the thing that in your PhD thesis should be
only and exclusively your results. But what I experience here is that if you
collaborate, of course you state who, that it’s someone else’s, but you can
make a, make a coherent story with results from other people. And for a
while that was unclear, that was trying to do something, everything that I
did should have a coherent kind of storyline. And it was difficult kind of
not to double, then, work. So, […] we had some inefficiencies, and yeah,
we had to figure out kind of on the job. There was not really, the template
was not really there.
After some time, however, Martin and Nanna were able to agree upon
a modus operandi, a routine of synchronized, parallel experimentation
that has proven to be most “efficient.” As Martin explains, he and Nanna
88 5 The Molecular Biology Laboratory
“[…] do simultaneous things and then if any of us have success, start from
there and then split again.” In this manner, they explore experimental
alternatives at each of the steps that it takes to purify a protein for
crystallization. If one of them has obtained good results with a particular
badge—e.g. a particular chemical dilution—at a particular experimental
step, they share the successful badge between themselves and, again, take
it from there and purse parallel experimental tracks. Their shared goal is to
determine the structure of their orphan protein as quickly as possible—as
Martin emphasizes, “you want to publish, you want to get to the end.” For
the amount of time that Martin has at his disposal, this is an ambitious
goal, and he relies not only on close collaboration with Nanna, but also
on intense supervision and substantial help:
In the Danish system […] you have only three years of PhD. I don’t think
you have time for actual whole projects, stumbling on every step, doing all
the steps and having problems at all these steps to learn the techniques –
and be able to publish. […] So, […] generally speaking, you never know all
the techniques. So, whatever you do, you learn some techniques.
The question always is why do we use 50 molar, 100 molar, like you don’t
know if 78 would be better. You just don’t have the time to test every small
detail. You have to go with, just things that work and just copy that. And
then, on top of that, you put what you understand is happening, what you
know generally about science.
References 89
References
Felt, U., Sigl, L., & Wöhrer, V. (2010). Multiple ways of being together alone:
A comparative analysis of collective and individual dimensions of academic
research in two epistemic fields (Preprint). Department of Social Studies of
Science, University of Vienna. Retrieved from http://sciencestudies.univie.
ac.at/fileadmin/user_upload/dep_sciencestudies/pdf_files/Preprints/Felt_
Sigl_Woehrer_Together_Alone_preprint_Apr2010.pdf
90 5 The Molecular Biology Laboratory
Research groups divide the kind of labor that it takes to create scientific
knowledge among their members—cognitive labor, but also the manual
labor of experimental practice and the social effort that it takes for
a group member to interact. But how do groups divide labor? And
hence, what does an epistemological approach to the division of labor
in groups need to take into account? To answer these two questions,
I begin by revisiting social epistemology’s existing discussion about the
division of labor in science, a discussion primarily focused on scientific
peer communities (Sect. 6.1). Thereafter, I examine the division of labor
in the two research groups I have studied, the planetary science group
(Sect. 6.2) and the molecular biology laboratory (Sect. 6.3), providing a
comparison in Sect. 6.4. Based on these two cases, I will argue in Sect. 6.5
that an account of the division of labor in research groups has to differ
from existing community-focused accounts in four crucial respects in
which there is a need to: (i) focus on within-group differences in expertise;
(ii) consider both processes of differentiation and convergence; (iii) shift
attention from competition to collaboration; and (iv) consider scientific
knowledge in-the-making long before formal peer reviewing takes effect.
New motives for the study of the division of labor at the group level
and its epistemic relevance for scientific knowledge creation have recently
come from accounts of research group collaboration. Yet, this strand of
literature is not concerned with the division of epistemic labor per se
but rather foregrounds the question as to whether collaboratively created
scientific knowledge should be considered “collective knowledge” (see,
e.g., Andersen, 2010; de Ridder, 2014; Matthiesen, 2006; Rolin, 2010;
Wray, 2001). Much of this literature developed out of the concept of
a “joint,” that is, irreducibly collective “group belief,” which Margaret
Gilbert proposed (Gilbert, 1989) and which highlights the moral aspects
of group collaboration, for example, elaborating upon the webs of com-
mitments and dependencies that can bind group members to one another.
I will discuss this literature in more detail in Chap. 9.
Many group-focused perspectives upon research collaboration display
a growing interest in the nitty-gritty of group collaboration, an interest
that is often pursued by means of case study. Let me briefly provide
two examples to illustrate the bandwidth of the empirical phenomena
that this literature has sought to deal with so far. Hanne Andersen
develops her account of joint acceptance with reference to a histori-
cal case study on research on induced radioactivity that resulted from
clusters of interdisciplinary collaboration in the 1930s (Andersen, 2010).
In contrast, when Kent Staley and William Rehg study a case of con-
temporary high-energy physics, they study research collaboration on a
much larger scale, involving the institutionally coordinated efforts of
hundreds of scientists (Rehg & Staley, 2008). Both Andersen as well as
Rehg and Staley, however, are ultimately less interested in the division
of epistemic labor among collaborators than in characterizing the kind
of consensus that collaborating scientists reach when they co-author
publications.
Against the backdrop of this literature, in this chapter I empirically
examine different patterns of division of labor in the two research groups
I have studied. Investigating the nitty-gritty of group collaboration will
show how far the existing notion of a division of epistemic labor, a
notion that has by and large been elaborated in reference to scientific
communities, can help articulating aspects of a social epistemology of
research groups.
96 6 Division of Labor
After the meeting, they all gather in the lab opposite Laurits’s office.
With Nikolaj’s advice, Lucas takes two quartz flasks cautiously out of an
oven. The flasks are still very hot, and they transport them down to the
basement laboratory where they plan to vacuum pump them. Adam and
Nikolaj prepare the vacuum pumping and explain the process to Nikolaj.
Christoffer is also present. They talk loosely. Christoffer wants to know:
“Why did we actually never tumble in water?” Adam agrees: “That would
be very interesting. We could do that at some point. We should put it on
the list.”
Then, the vacuum pump is switched on. You can see the flask vibrating
lightly. Lucas takes pictures. They discuss the best way to switch off the
pump and disconnect it from the flask. The latter task will be taken care
of by the glass-blower who has just come over from his workplace in the
chemistry department and is now preparing for the task. Adam slowly
switches off the pump while the glass-blower carefully seals the flask just
above the base of its neck. Then they disconnect the pump and Christoffer
labels the two flasks. Nikolaj measures them. Lucas tells me: “After so many
days of work I’m so happy that we finally have the samples ready.” (field
note, group meeting, group1)
His schedule leaves Alex a little more than half an hour to help Sylvia with
her “lipidization,” a specific experimental step in the purification procedure.
She has performed the step before, but she cannot remember the details of
it. After a look at her protocol, Alex discovers a mistake in the protocol
which she has formulated on the basis of Magnus’s directions. But since
she uses the dilutions Alex had prepared earlier for his experiments, not her
own, it doesn’t matter. She is lucky.
As a student, Sylvia was educated in theoretical chemistry and she is
not yet familiar with a number of standard procedures required for the
purification of proteins. Alex and Sylvia talk repeatedly about Magnus’s
protocol and how exactly she needs to perform certain procedures listed
there—e.g., that the sample should always be kept on ice, Sylvia! But how
do you handle the things in between the lines that differ from lab to lab and
from person to person? Alex: “So you have to ask different people, but not
too many different people. I think Magnus and I are semi-consistent.”
Alex is telling Sylvia what to get and what to do: ice, buffer, defrost the
protein. He does some calculations for her to get the right dilutions in the
right amounts. They do a dry run of lipidization in which he is showing
Sylvia each step. When she performs them herself on her protein sample,
he corrects her. Suddenly something is going wrong. There are too many
bubbles in the dilution with her protein. Their movements become hasty
as they try to fix the problem. Alex is proposing a number of options to
correct the failure, but she will anyway, as Alex explains quickly, “(a) have
too little sample for a good crystallization, because she will be losing some of
her protein by removing these bubbles; or (b), if you get crystals, they will
not be reproducible, because you deviated from the protocol too much.”
102 6 Division of Labor
Sylvia looks distressed. They try to remove the bubbles. “Once you are off
the protocol, it’s really shaky,” Alex comments. (Alex, field note, group2)
As this field note shows, the division of labor in the molecular biology
laboratory is not only a means of efficiently achieving experimental goals.
It is also a means of hands-on learning. The purification of a selected
protein has been assigned to Sylvia not because she would possess the
necessary expertise to carry out the necessary experimental procedures—
rather, it has been delegated to her to provide an occasion for hands-on
learning. To purify “her” protein, Sylvia has to learn how to do it,
and to do so she relies on Magnus’s supervision as well as on Alex’s
help. Delegation, help and learning are key elements in the mode of
collaboration that the molecular biology laboratory has adopted, and I
will discuss each of them in the following.
Delegation is the primary means of coordinating research activity in
the laboratory. What underlies delegation is the authority of scientific
expertise, and therefore research tasks are typically delegated by senior
lab members, that is, a lab leader or a subgroup leader, to less senior
lab members. The lab leader, for example, assigns students to specific
research projects and delegates their day-to-day supervision to the post-
docs who take on the role of subgroup leaders, who coordinate the work
of the junior students. In so doing, it is their responsibility to hold up
scientific standards and guarantee the quality of all experimental steps
performed. They do that by being present at the lab bench and making
themselves available for consultation during most of the day. They also
do that by enforcing a protocol, from which supervised junior scientists
are not supposed to deviate without their consent. Yet, despite the
hierarchical structure that underlies it, delegation in the molecular biology
laboratory is typically phrased as suggestion or advice, and embedded in
a participatory work culture.
Besides delegation, the molecular biology laboratory features many
other instances of division of labor which neither involve a gradient in
expertise nor authority. Often, labor is split up between group members
in a benevolent tit for tat—group members help each other. Help is vital
for the functioning of the laboratory, because experimental procedures are
complex and stretch over long hours.
6.3 Parallel Collaboration 103
past few years, Johan has stopped learning to master new experimental
routines (although he continues to learn about them). Instead, he focuses
upon theoretical research perspectives and strategic management, an
important part of which is the assessment and distribution of risk, that
is, the possibility of experimental failure. This kind of specialization that
“[…] involves the differentiation of theoretical activities on the one hand,
and experimental activities on the other,” and is tied to within-group
hierarchy, has been called “vertical” specialization (Laudel, 2001, p. 764).
6.4 Comparison
At this point, it is instructive to compare the planetary science group and
the molecular biology laboratory. The two groups clearly show distinct
patterns in the division of labor among their members, a difference that
is shaped by their research, the demands of experimental practice and also
by the kind of expertise that different members bring to the group.
While the planetary science group is dominated by senior researchers
who cooperate in an egalitarian way, the molecular biology laboratory
features a distinct hierarchy between junior and senior scientists. While
the planetary science group endorses a loose, rather exploratory and
continuous mode of experimentation, the experiments carried out in the
molecular biology laboratory are established procedures which serve a
clear end. Therefore, planning and framing discussions, such as occurs
in the planetary science group, are not necessary for the molecular
biology laboratory, where the trajectory research activity is structured by
generic experimental procedures—the purification and crystallization of
proteins—in rather foreseeable ways.
While members of the molecular biology laboratory work on a series of
resembling, yet distinct, research goals, members of the planetary science
group pursue research goals that they, given their respective disciplinary
backgrounds, differentially share. Since large parts of the research carried
out in the planetary science group are perceived as a joint endeavor in
which all involved scientists have their stake, the planetary science group
displayed fewer instances of mutual support that might be described as
genuine help.
6.5 Conclusion 105
6.5 Conclusion
My empirical investigation of research groups shows that community-
focused approaches to the division of epistemic labor, such as Kitcher’s,
do not sit well with research group collaboration. Rather, distinct group-
focused approaches are needed because the division of labor at the group
level raises epistemological issues that community-focused approaches
typically sideline. To conclude this chapter, let me outline four episte-
mological aspects that group-focused approaches need to account for.
106 6 Division of Labor
References
Andersen, H. (2010). Joint acceptance and scientific change: A case study.
Episteme, 7 (3), 248–265.
D’Agostino, F. (2005). Kuhn’s risk-spreading argument and the organization of
science communities. Episteme, 1(3), 201–209.
D’Agostino, F. (2009). From the organization to the division of cognitive labor.
Politics, Philosophy & Economics, 8(1), 101–129.
de Langhe, R. (2010). The division of labour in science: the tradeoff between
specialisation and diversity. Journal of Economic Methodology, 17 (1), 37–51.
108 6 Division of Labor
individual relies upon somebody else because he or she has good reason
to believe this other person to be in an epistemically superior position.
Such a relation between individuals’ beliefs has to be mediated, either
through verbal communication or the exchange of material objects such as
data charts, written reports and material probes. When a belief is verbally
communicated from one individual to another by way of assertion, and
when, thus, epistemic dependence is a matter of reliance upon others’
say-so, then epistemic dependence is akin to reliance upon testimony.
Therefore, in this chapter I draw not only on epistemology’s accounts
of epistemic dependence but also, in parts, on accounts of testimony as a
source of justified belief and knowledge.
Examining inter-individual epistemic dependence as an issue of col-
laborative scientific practice, I analyze epistemic dependence as a relation
between one scientist’s believing and another scientist’s beliefs and/or, as
I will elaborate, the product of his or her labor. Three remarks are in
order here. First, when I speak of individual believing or individually held
beliefs, I imply that beliefs can qualify as knowledge if they are “well-
founded,” that is, justified, in terms of the standards that apply in the
context of scientific practice. What, hence, underlies my understanding
is a contextualist notion of knowledge as justified (true) belief.1 Second,
when I understand knowing as believing, I leave issues of tacit knowledge
largely aside. This is not to say that tacit knowledge would be peripheral
to scientific practice. Rather, knowledge that cannot be easily explicated
and communicated does not sit well with the epistemological approaches
discussed here. Third, when I focus on epistemic dependence in collabora-
1
It lies beyond the scope of this book to defend epistemic contextualism (Rysiew, 2016), but as will
become apparent in this chapter and in Chap. 9, a contextualist understanding of what it means to
justify a belief as knowledge allows us to accommodate the fact that second-order reasons may justify
a collaborating scientist’s individual knowing—but does not constitute the kind of justification that
it takes to formulate a scientific knowledge claim. Without such a contextualist understanding, one
would either have to deny individual scientists the possibility to know qua trust or to allow for
scientific knowledge to be justified upon the basis of testimony. Both options are unattractive. To
deny scientists to know qua trust overly limits their epistemic agency and casts collaborative scientific
practice as inferior guesswork. To allow for scientific knowledge to be justified in terms of testimony
does not resonate with the conventions of scientific method and scientific authorship.
7.1 Theoretical Groundwork 111
tive scientific practice, I also sideline all those instances in which scientists
depend upon one another for other than epistemic purposes.2
Drawing on the empirical data I have gathered, I ground my analysis
of epistemic dependence on observations of actual scientific practice in
research groups. From a practice-minded point of view, philosophical
accounts of epistemic dependence need to take into consideration that
the relations of epistemic dependence between collaborating scientists can
vastly vary. No one size fits all. In order to get a grip on the configurations
of epistemic dependence in scientific practice, a subtle and differentiated
terminology is needed. As I will argue, crucial to configurations of epis-
temic dependence in collaborative scientific practice is whether, to what
extent and in which way the dependent person has the possibility to make
use of relevant scientific expertise. For this reason, I propose to distinguish
between translucent dependence (which is supported by the dependent
person’s experimental expertise) and opaque dependence (which is not).
As I will point out, this distinction does not exhaust the phenomenon
of epistemic dependence. Nevertheless, it provides two cornerstones in
relation to which a variety of instances of epistemic dependence can be
understood.
To unfold this distinction, the chapter proceeds as follows. Sect. 7.1
reviews some of the work on epistemic dependence that has been under-
taken by epistemologists so far. Section 7.2, then, harkens back to my
comparative case study and the division of labor in research groups,
which, as I argue, reinforces or creates the epistemic asymmetries in which
epistemic dependence is rooted. Thereafter, Sect. 7.3 elaborates on my
distinction between opaque and translucent epistemic dependence.
2
For a broader, social-scientific account of dependence in science see Whitley (1984, p. 87ff.).
112 7 Epistemic Dependence
3
Goldberg (2011) shows that epistemic dependence extends beyond two-person relationships. In
fact, he argues, in the formulation of well-founded beliefs a person depends not only on eyewitnesses
and experts from whom he might adopt knowledge, but he also depends on his larger epistemic
community. This aspect is important, but for the purpose of investigating collaboration in scientific
groups, I limit my analysis to immediate person-to-person relationships.
7.1 Theoretical Groundwork 113
4
Latour’s observation that scientific practice involves sequences of material “inscriptions” comes
to mind (Latour, 1999). The material dimension of science has been explored paradigmatically by
Rheinberger (1997), and philosophers have developed an increasing interest in the concrete artifacts
of scientific practice as well (Bechtel & Abrahamsen, 2012; Carusi, 2012; Knuuttila, 2011). For
the cognitive value of concrete artifacts more generally, see the literature on distributed cognition
(Hutchins, 1995, 2001; Nersessian et al., 2003).
114 7 Epistemic Dependence
have good reasons for holding this belief. A good reason for holding the
belief that p is to have sufficient observational and/or inferential evidence
that p obtains. I will also call evidence of this kind “immediate” evidence.
What, however, if an individual, for whom it would be important to know
whether or not p is the case, cannot have sufficient observational and/or
inferential evidence, neither for believing that p nor for believing that
not-p? Does that mean that this individual has no possibility whatsoever
of acquiring a well-founded belief as to p? No, Hardwig argues, and he
introduces what I call second-order reasons for having the belief that p.
Translating Hardwig’s argument into my terminology, first-order reasons
for p are reasons that spring from having observational and/or inferential
evidence for p. If first-order reasons cannot be had, then it is rational for an
individual A to rely upon another individual B affirming that p—provided
A has good reasons to believe that B has sufficient evidence for p (Hardwig,
1985, p. 336). Such good reasons to believe that p when B is saying so (or
the products of his labor are indicating it) are second-order reasons, which
are reasons concerning B’s intellectual authority, that is, his qualities as
an eyewitness, his honesty and expertise (Hardwig, 1985, p. 337, 339; see
also Hardwig, 1991, p. 700). As I will elaborate in Chap. 8, second-order
reasons concern the trustworthiness of B as a scientific collaborator.
Following Hardwig, I maintain that second-order reasons concerning
a collaborator’s scientific trustworthiness can justify a scientist’s belief
that p—even though second-order reasons provide neither inferential nor
observational support for the proposition that p. Note also that second-
order reasons do not directly concern the question as to whether or
not that p actually obtains. Second-order reasons concern somebody’s
trustworthiness, and as such they are not identical to reasons which would
justify the assumption that somebody’s testimony would always be reliable
(or, that his or her labor would always be error free).
Summarizing, Hardwig characterizes instances of epistemic depen-
dence as situations in which a dependent collaborator A, in her believing
that p, resorts to second-order reasons relating to the trustworthiness of
B (who, in turn, possesses immediate evidence for p). In the scenario of
epistemic dependence that Hardwig presents, the primary question for A
to answer is not whether p is right or wrong. Rather, the crucial question
for A is how she can reasonably rely on B. Is she warranted to rely upon
116 7 Epistemic Dependence
5
The expression “epistemic opacity” has been used by philosophers of science in different contexts
before. Soler (2011) uses the expression to highlight the fact that tacit components of scientific
practice cannot be explicated and thus remain “opaque.” Lenhard (2006), in turn, uses “opacity”
as a synonym for the limited comprehensibility of mathematically complex simulation models, and
incomprehensibility is also what I denote by the expression.
7.3 Opaque and Translucent Dependence 119
6
Strategies for establishing second-order reasons for the reliance upon a collaborator are analyzed in
Goldman (2001) and Sperber et al. (2010).
120 7 Epistemic Dependence
Q: Mhm. Do you think that the things you have in your papers, in principle
you could do them on your own? Or you could only do them with others?
Laurits: Ahm, if I think back I would say that, that ahm, in many of our
publications Moessbauer spectroscopy has been used as a useful method.
I started with that before Rasmus [physicist in group1] came here. With
the Moessbauer laboratory in Physics. And I started to publish things ahm
with one of the persons from there, so I knew or I never had, it hasn’t been
necessary for me to do Moessbauer spectroscopy myself. And it’s a field
where you need a lot of experience to be sure of what you interpret out of
the spectra you see. So, I would not be able to get the same interpretation
out of that if, if I didn’t have an expert like Rasmus. So that, this wouldn’t
be a good way doing publications, try to do this as an amateur yourself. So
you need to collaborate with people that know more about different fields.
And when it comes to sand transport, I would say that Oliver [geologist
associated to group1] has used all his life on that and he of course has a
basic knowledge there that I don’t have. So if we come to experience and
publications in that field, I would never do it without him. (Laurits, senior
geologist, group1)
can assess the experimental evidence that B provides for this claim. Also,
A is in a position to question B about the details of his claim that p,
so that B is forced to argue for his claim that p. Moreover, A has more
possibilities to assess B’s qualities as an experimenter in general. Therefore,
A’s dependence runs not as deep as in instances of opaque dependence.
Still, I want to emphasize the fact that translucent dependence is a relevant
and epistemically significant form of epistemic dependence in scientific
practice.
De Ridder has suggested a distinction between “cognitively necessary
epistemic dependence” and “practically necessary epistemic dependence”
(de Ridder, 2014, p. 46). This distinction is similar, albeit not identical, to
mine, and I will refrain from endorsing it for two reasons. First, laboratory
skills are a fundamental component of scientific expertise so that it is
fair to say that expertise clearly involves more than cognition. Thus,
an opaque epistemic dependence relation, rooted in an asymmetry in
expertise, may concern more than just cognitive asymmetries. Second,
the circumstances of “practically necessary” dependence have significant
cognitive consequences: if you cannot run an experiment yourself due to a
lack of time, infrastructure or labor, you cannot acquire first-hand reasons
concerning the experimental evidence produced. Therefore, I believe a
distinction between “cognitively necessary” and “practically necessary”
dependence to be potentially misleading.
What is more, I also believe it inadequate to rephrase the conceptual
distinction that I draw between opaque and translucent as “insurmount-
able” and “surmountable” epistemic dependence. Opaque dependence is
not insurmountable; it simply needs considerable time and effort to do
so. In addition, to label translucent dependence as surmountable may
imply that translucent epistemic dependence should be overcome. It is
not my intention, however, to make such a claim. Translucent epistemic
dependence is a valuable instrument in the efficient organization of
research collaboration—and as such it is not surmountable. It has to
be acknowledged that the creation of knowledge in scientific practice is
shaped, and rightly so, by the uneven distribution of various resources,
which are not restricted to scientific expertise. Clearly, experimental
expertise is important, but the experience required to, for example, set
124 7 Epistemic Dependence
Q: OK, so what would be an example for a signal that tells you this person
is maybe not competent? Not competent enough?
Adam: Ah, if they are missing, if they are missing fundamental ahm lines of
argument, if they are confusing cause and effect for example, that would be
bad. And if they are vague on something which is really quite important—
and if and if I explain something, something that is quite basic, and they
still don’t, still don’t get it.
Q: But I can imagine that this works out nicely with another physicist, but
if you are talking to another let’s say biologist, can you then be so sure?…
Adam: Yeah, I think mainly the arguments are the same in that in that they
should be able to explain their thing to me in a way that I understand it. And
in the way they explain it, you can tell, normally, whether they understand
it themselves. (Adam, senior physicist, group1)
Despite the fact that Adam does not possess the same expertise as his
interlocutors, he can make an informed scientific judgment about them
and the things they have to say by means of referred expertise, mobilizing
professional experience gathered in the field he has been trained in. If he
was to rely on the things they have to say for his personal knowing, he
would thus not be dependent upon them in a completely opaque way.
What this discussion shows is that, as concepts, opaque and translucent
epistemic dependence provide useful handles on the diversity of depen-
dence relations in collaborative scientific practice. But as a dichotomous
distinction, they tell us only one half of the story. In practice, there is
a large gray zone between opacity and translucency. Within this gray
zone, there are clearly instances of more and less expertise. A third-year
student is not yet an expert, but will usually possess more expertise than a
first-year student. I will refrain, however, from speaking of a continuum
between epistemic opacity on the one hand and translucency, or even
epistemic transparency, on the other. A rationale for computing the
128 7 Epistemic Dependence
7.4 Conclusion
To conclude, let me summarize what forms of epistemic dependence are
observable in the two research groups I have studied. In the planetary
science group, members from different fields of expertise contribute
to the joint pursuit of research questions. For this reason, relations of
opaque epistemic dependence are frequent. Epistemic opacity can be
handled, because scientists in the group have come to know each other’s
professional qualities during a decade of close collaboration. Furthermore,
they have acquired interactional expertise that helps them to bridge their
own and foreign fields of expertise. Interactional and referred expertise
can render dependence relations less opaque.
The situation is clearly different in the molecular biology laboratory
with its comparatively high fluctuation rate. Here, relations of epistemic
dependence have a different character. Post-docs and senior scientists,
who delegate work to doctoral students and students, will usually be
epistemically dependent in a translucent form. Students, in turn, may be
opaquely dependent on more senior researchers, but since they perceive
themselves as experts-to-be, the epistemic opacity they are confronted
with may be regarded as transient. As they learn to master experimental
techniques more and more independently, they gain gradually more and
more expertise. Therefore, the epistemic dependence that students are
involved in is mostly a gray-zone dependence—not opaque anymore, but
not yet translucent either.
To conclude, I hope to have shown in this chapter how the distinction
between opaque and translucent epistemic dependence helps to charac-
terize the empirical variety of research group collaboration in scientific
practice, articulating thereby how, while epistemic dependence pervades
collaborative scientific practice, not all dependence runs equally deep.
References 129
References
Audi, R. (1983). Foundationalism, epistemic dependence, and defeasability.
Synthese, 55(1), 119–139.
Bechtel, W., & Abrahamsen, A. (2012). Diagramming phenomena for mechanis-
tic explanation. In N. Miyake, D. Peebles, & R. P. Cooper (Eds.), Proceedings
of the 34th annual conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 102–107).
Carusi, A. (2012). Making the visual visible in philosophy of science. Spontaneous
Generations, 6 (1), 106–114.
Collins, H., & Evans, R. (2007). Rethinking expertise. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
de Ridder, J. (2014). Epistemic dependence and collective scientific knowledge.
Synthese, 191(1), 37–53.
Fricker, E. (2006). Second-hand knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenlogical
Research, 73(3), 592–618.
Goddiksen, M. (2014). Clarifying interactional and contributory expertise.
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 47, 111–117.
Goldberg, S. C. (2011). The division of epistemic labor. Episteme, 8(1), 112–125.
Goldman, A. I. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and
Phenomenlogical Research, 63(1), 85–110.
Gorman, M. (2002). Levels of expertise and trading zones: A framework for
multidisciplinary collaboration. Social Studies of Science, 32(5–6), 933–938.
Hardwig, J. (1985). Epistemic dependence. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(7), 335–
349.
Hardwig, J. (1988). Evidence, testimony, and the problem of individualism - a
response to Schmitt. Social Epistemology, 2(4), 309–321.
Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy,
88(12), 693–708.
Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Hutchins, E. (2001). Distributed cognition. In N. J. Smelser & P. B. Baltes (Eds.),
International encyclopedia of the social & behavioral sciences (pp. 2068–2072).
Oxford: Elsevier.
Knuuttila, T. (2011). Modelling and representing: An artefactual approach to
model-based representation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 42(2),
262–271.
Latour, B. (1999). Circulating reference: Sampling soil in the Amazon forest. In
Pandora’s hope: Essays on the reality of science study (pp. 24–79). Cambridge:
Harvard University Press.
130 7 Epistemic Dependence
Laudel, G. (2001). Collaboration, creativity and rewards: why and how scientists
collaborate. International Journal of Technology Management, 22(7), 762–781.
Lenhard, J. (2006). Surprised by nanowire: Simulation, control, and understand-
ing. Philosophy of Science, 73(5), 605–616.
Leonelli, S. (2010). Packaging data for re-use: Databases in model organism
biology. In P. Howlett & M. S. Morgan (Eds.), How well do facts travel? The
dissemination of reliable knowledge (pp. 325–348). Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Nersessian, N. J., Kurz-Milcke, E., Newstetter, W. C., & Davies, J. (2003).
Research laboratories as evolving distributed cognitive systems. In R. Alter-
mann & D. Kirsh (Eds.), Proceedings of the twenty-fifth annual conference
of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 857–862). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum
Associates.
Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthesizing
proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Rysiew, P. (2016). Epistemic contextualism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stan-
ford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2016 ed.). http://plato.stanford.edu/
archives/spr2016/entries/contextualism-epistemology/.
Soler, L. (2011). Tacit aspects of experimental practices: analytical tools and
epistemological consequences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 1(1),
393–433.
Sperber, D., Clément, F., Heintz, C., Mascaro, O., Mercier, H., Origgi, G., et al.
(2010). Epistemic vigilance. Mind and Language, 25(4), 359–393.
Whitley, R. (1984). The intellectual and social organization of the sciences. Oxford:
Clarendon.
8
Epistemic Trust
trust can enable A, who does the trusting, to acquire the knowledge
that p by relying upon a trusted person B (see, e.g., Fricker, 2002;
Goldberg, 2011; Hardwig, 1991; Kappel, 2014; McCraw, 2015). Precisely
under which conditions, A is warranted to place epistemic trust in B
is debated. It is, however, generally assumed that for an adult A to
place epistemic trust in a person B it is necessary for A to regard
B as being “epistemically well-placed” with respect to the belief in
question (McCraw, 2015), a condition I have described with reference
to Hardwig (1985, 1991) as B’s possession of intellectual authority in
Chap. 7.
Epistemic trust, too, can be construed as a three-part relation between
a trusting person A, a trusted person B and a something (C), the care
of which A entrusts B with. Here, C is the justification for the belief
that p, a justification for which A relies upon B. Note, however, that
B cares for C only indirectly. A’s justification for the belief that p need
not be B’s primary concern. Rather, what B is supposed to care about
is his intellectual authority concerning the observations, measurements,
arguments or advice he passes on to A. If B testifies that p to A, conveying
his testimony as a piece of (scientific) knowledge, then B should have
a justification for the belief that p that conforms with those (scientific)
standards of justification that apply. Yet, as I have elaborated in Chap. 7,
B’s justification will not be identical to A’s justification for that p—but B’s
justification will be “folded into” A’s justification because A relies upon
B’s intellectual authority.
While today’s debate about epistemic trust is, generally, benign to the
idea that trust can indeed result in justified believing, Hardwig began
to work upon trust at a time when epistemologists were rather skeptical
about its epistemic potential. This may explain why he construes trust in
strict analogy to evidence gained from observation, inference or memory.
Like such evidence, he argues, trust in a person B provides a “reason” for
A’s adopting the belief that p in reference to B’s maintaining that p. In
Chap. 7 I have characterized reasons of this kind as second-order reasons.
Since these reasons do not pertain to “immediate”—i.e., observational or
inferential—evidence for the belief that p, Hardwig characterizes trust as
“blind” (Hardwig, 1991, p. 693).
134 8 Epistemic Trust
However, that Hardwig calls trust blind must not lead to the con-
ception that trust attitudes were de-coupled from empirical evidence
concerning the trustworthiness of the person trusted. In fact, Hardwig
instructively distinguishes two facets of trustworthiness that enables us
to specify how and in which sense it can be empirically evidenced.
According to him, the trustworthiness of a person concerns both moral
and epistemic character. While moral character concerns dedication and
honesty, epistemic character concerns skillfulness and expertise (Hardwig,
1991, p. 700). A trustworthy person, hence, is one who is sincere and
makes as few mistakes as possible.
The belief (that p) whose justification is at stake in epistemic trust
relations can take many forms in collaborative scientific practice. As
elaborated in Chap. 7, it can be a belief based on a collaborator’s testimony,
asserting that “the measurement is x.” Or, it can be a belief based on
what a collaborator’s labor implicitly conveys. By, for example, making
a chemical compound available to a colleague, a scientist implies that this
compound has been prepared correctly. But a prerequisite to work with
these contributions is to form beliefs about collaborators’ contributions
and their trustworthiness.
Epistemic trust relations involve trust attitudes (A’s trusting B), the
epistemic status of which is debated among social epistemologists. Should
one conceive of attitudes of epistemic trust as beliefs and, if so, do the
standards of justification that apply to knowledge apply to them? Hardwig
seems to be inclined to argue that trust attitudes can, indeed, be “known”
when he argues that the trustworthiness of a collaborator is something
that a scientist can rationally rely upon (Hardwig, 1991, p. 699; see also,
e.g., Fricker, 2006, p. 232). Other authors have taken a different, if
not opposing, stance. In rejecting Hardwig’s account of trust, Klemens
Kappel, for example, characterizes trust as a non-inferential disposition,
a “feeling of confidence about someone or something” (Kappel, 2014,
p. 2017). Such a feeling cannot and need not be evidentially justified.
As a non-inferential disposition, thus, trust cannot be “known”; and
Kappel accordingly claims that collaborating scientists need not, in fact
cannot and “do not know, and are not justified in believing, that other
agents are trustworthy within their specialised domains” (Kappel, 2014,
8.1 Theoretical Groundwork 135
Q: What do you look for if you work with someone? For example, if it’s a
new person. What do you look for to decide whether you really would like
to collaborate with that person or it’s maybe a bit risky?
Laurits: Ah, that’s something you find out when you start to collaborate.
You can never know it in advance. So, it comes out of the collaboration, I
would say. (Laurits, senior scientist, group1)
Q: What would signal to you that this person is maybe not good to
collaborate with? What would be a signal of ahm…ah, maybe rather look
for someone else?
8.2 The Tentative Character of Epistemic Trust 137
Laurits: That’s the same when you start up with a new student that you
want to have as a PhD student. You see what has the person done so far,
and then you start with the collaboration. And it develops from that. And
from that you get your opinion on the person. So, that you know if this is
someone you would like to, ah, to have as a collaborator in the group in the
future or not. (Laurits, senior scientist, group1)
Now [in the group] I can have access to the [major experimental facility] and
there is no way that I can run the [major experimental facility]. So, I would
need Adam or Nikolaj or both to join to work with me on that, and for that
of course I have to trust their expertise. So, if he tells me that the wind speed
is ten meters a second, then—because he measures it—I have to believe that.
Otherwise if, if I would doubt that, I could not collaborate with him. And
that’s a general problem or a challenge in that astrobiology field, because
you need to collaborate with people from a different discipline. And ah well
you know from your own research that you have, you have been through
many years of training and I would be, yeah, of course I can question your
expertise, but if you if we want to work together, I have to consider you
138 8 Epistemic Trust
Q: […] When you work together with others who have a different expertise
than you have, ahm to what extent do you at all try to check what they are
doing? Find out whether what they are saying is actually …
Adam: No, we believe them, trust them.
Q: You just take it?
Adam: But then again, well, you don’t as a scientist, you shouldn’t. You
should, you should—you should ask a question, you know, I don’t under-
stand this, explain this to me. And then they’ll explain it and then if that
sounds logical and reasonable, then you’ll accept it obviously. But if it
sounds really crazy and weird to you, then you don’t accept it. And this is
why sometimes you get into long discussion type arguments […]. (Adam,
senior scientist, group1)
8.2 The Tentative Character of Epistemic Trust 139
There are various ways for scientists to address the fact that the
trustworthiness of collaborators can never be completely evidenced while
maintaining a vigilant yet cooperative attitude toward their collaborators.
As I will argue, scientists can fine-tune expectations of trust towards
collaborators, they can resort to impersonal trust or find ways to reduce
the trust relations necessary through hierarchical co-authorship. Referring
to fragments of the interviews I have conducted, I will elaborate on these
strategies in the following sections. In doing so, I build upon the work
of epistemologists such as Sperber and collaborators (2010) and Alvin
Goldman (2001) who have discussed a number of ways in which epistemic
trustworthiness can be empirically established. I refer to their work in the
following whenever appropriate and show how it applies to collaboration
in scientific practice.
from different disciplines in order to “get the gist.” Second, and a little
later, he speaks about explaining a question himself to find out whether
potential collaborators qualify as trustworthy enough:
Adam: [: : :] I guess from, just from a conversation, I guess, you can tell
whether somebody is technically competent by the way they talk about, ah
you know, talk about things.
Q: OK, so what would be an example for a signal that tells you this person
is maybe not competent? Not competent enough?
Adam: Ah, if they are missing if they are missing fundamental lines of
argument, if they are confusing cause and effect for example, that would be
bad. And if they are vague on something which is really quite important,
and if, and if I explain something, something that is quite basic, and they
still don’t, still don’t get it. (Adam, senior scientist, group1)
Q: […] Why do you think you can accept Rasmus’s expertise? What is your,
I mean you must have some criteria for …
Victor: I consider him an expert in that field.
Q: Umm. What makes him an expert?
Victor: Yeah, the fact that he has published in the field, that he has, well,
he is recognized among colleagues. That’s my validation criteria.
Q: That’s the reputation part. Does it play also a role that you, you work
together with Rasmus in this group? Is this …
Victor: Yeah, of course I have confidence that he is a good person to …that
I can rely on.
Q: So, it would make a difference for you if it’s someone from within the
group or someone you barely know that has also a good reputation?
Victor: No, not necessarily.
Q: Ok, ok.
Victor: And then the other thing is, you know when you, one thing is the
work that you do here, but as soon as you submit a paper for publication,
you get a review on that and if—people are usually quite picky. In particular,
when it comes to multidisciplinary studies. So, ah if, if, you will get
criticized if things don’t stand. (Victor, senior scientist, group1)
trust the first author for his or her judgment of others’ contributions and
the way in which he or she integrates them into a coherent whole.
As interview data suggests, hierarchical co-authorship is the form of
authorship that members of the planetary science group typically engage
in. One or two first authors, “usually the driving force in the experiments”
(Adam, senior scientist, group1), are accountable for creating a publishable
text that is acceptable to all co-authors. Under their supervision, the
paper to be written is split up into sections for which responsibility
is distributed among co-authors. Each co-author is assigned particular
sections, sub-sections or single important paragraphs. A co-author then
either writes pieces of text him or herself or provides the first author with
the information necessary to compose the respective section:
[S]omebody writes the main part and then also comes with some ideas how
the rest should look like and then he will send it to the different co-authors
and they add and criticize and make adjustments, additions and so on. So,
it’s a collective type of work, but there is one person who has to come up
with the major input. (Victor, senior scientist, group1)
As a first author you start by typing up what you know and what you want
in there and when you get to parts where you don’t know, where you’re
unsure, you don’t know how to conclude this, then you send what you have
to other people and say: Hey, we’d like to talk something about this or that,
and you ask them questions to this problem. So what do you think? Do you
have an opinion on this? What should we write, what should we say? What
do you think? Ahm, and they’ll come with suggestions, and you’ll use that.
(Laura, post-doc, group1)
Normally scientific papers are, can be split up quite easily into—in that
you have ah you describe the experiment, so that’s a section or different
sections with a different experimental techniques. And then the results,
there are different results from the different, different techniques. (Adam,
senior scientist, group1)
people of your you know ideas, of your logic, of how you do things, to really,
that they understand how you work and how you see things, so.
Q: But on the other hand, on the other hand, you said like some minutes
ago that you have this sort of paranoia, that you want to repeat things all
the time.
Alex: Yes, that’s true, it goes hand in hand a little bit, I mean the paranoia
comes from the point that you wanna make sure that maybe other people
are on the same page as you are as well and that you, that the science itself is
like trustful in itself right, you wanna ask this question and have this kind of,
build up this trust, also with a certain I would say good sense of paranoia. You
shouldn’t be you know too paranoid but you should, you should always try
to have a balance like between believing everything and follow it blindly and,
and having this kind of paranoia there, of also, sometimes just to see: can I
actually trust all the people?(Alex, PhD student, group2)
Even though of course it’s always, there is always some level of uncertainty
[…], and that’s both other people’s results and also a little bit on your results,
you always have to double-check yourself. But generally it is believed that
the person easiest to fool is yourself. So, as I see it, you should also doubt
your results. (Martin, PhD student, group2)
The uncertainty mentioned here has its source in the fact that experimen-
tal routines are complex and laborious. Mistakes are easily made. In fact,
Martin mentions that he “burnt” himself twice when he was relying on
experimental compounds that other group members had prepared, as it
turned out, wrongly. In both cases, he had to repeat the laboratory work
of several weeks.
In comparison to the planetary science group, epistemic trust in the
molecular biology laboratory reaches more pervasively into the fabric of
group relations. Because basic experimental procedures are often carried
out collaboratively, trust is needed early on in collaborative research
150 8 Epistemic Trust
8.7 Conclusion
Epistemic trust is a necessity when epistemic labor is divided. Scientists
have to trust their colleagues if they want to collaborate with them.
And as much as trust comes with the risk of being let down, so does
scientific collaboration put the trusting scientist in a position to probe
the trustworthiness of his or her collaborators. Scientists find various
ways to address the epistemic challenges associated with the necessity of
trusting in collaborative scientific practice. First of all, they seek to increase
trust and fine-tune their expectations of it toward collaborators through
dialoging practices, eliciting explanations and probing understanding.
Second, they supplement personal trust with impersonal trust. Third, they
reduce the personal trust relations necessary through hierarchical modes
of collaboration.
Nevertheless, epistemic trust in scientific practice remains tentative.
The assumption of a collaborator’s trustworthiness is a provisional
hypothesis that is to be consolidated in iterative cycles of ongoing
collaboration. In fact, my interview data support the notion that trust
among collaborating scientists is accompanied by epistemic vigilance. In
analogy to Chang’s “epistemic iteration” in experimental science (Chang,
2004), moments of socio-epistemic iteration are key to understanding
and managing the uncertainties of collaborative scientific practice. The
rationale that underlies this iteration is that if trust is misplaced, it will
show soon enough—in experimental failure, in inconsistent results, in
critical referee reports.
In the midst of scientific practice, whether or not to trust is not a ques-
tion that vexes collaborating scientists. Rather, for scientists, the pressing
question that they confront continuously is how to make a research
collaboration a scientific success—that is, how to meet the demands
References 151
References
Adler, J. E. (1994). Testimony, trust, knowing. The Journal of Philosophy, 91(5),
264–275.
Andersen, H. (2014). Co-author responsibility. EMBO Reports, 15(9), 914–918.
Angere, S. (2008). Coherence as a heuristic. Mind, 117 (456), 1–26.
Baier, A. (1986). Trust and antitrust. Ethics, 96 (2), 231–260.
Burge, T. (1993). Content preservation. Philosophical Review, 102(4), 457–488.
Chang, H. (2004). Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Chang, H. (2011). The philosophical grammar of scientific practice. International
Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 25(3), 205–221.
Coady, C. A. J. (1992). Testimony: A philosophical study. Oxford: Clarendon.
Fricker, E. (2002). Trusting others in the sciences: A priori or empirical warrant?
Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 33(2), 373-383.
Fricker, E. (2006). Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa
(Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 225–250). Oxford: Clarendon.
Frost-Arnold, K. (2014). The cognitive attitude of rational trust. Synthese, 191,
1957–1974.
Goldberg, S. C. (2010). Relying on others: An essay in epistemology. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Goldberg, S. C. (2011). The division of epistemic labor. Episteme, 8(1), 112–125.
Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Goldman, A. I. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and
Phenomenlogical Research, 63(1), 85–110.
Haack, S. (2004). Coherence, consistency, cogency, congruity, cohesiveness &
co.: Remain calm! Don’t go overboard! New Literary History, 35(2), 167–183.
152 8 Epistemic Trust
For the two research groups studied, Chaps. 6, 7 and 8 have described
how research efforts are divided among group members, how such divi-
sion of labor creates relations of epistemic dependence and how such
dependence relations are facilitated by trust. It was shown that it takes
more than an individual effort to create scientific knowledge. Now, given
that knowledge creation in much of today’s natural sciences is the result
of collaborative effort, philosophers need to explore whether or not
scientific knowledge amounts to genuinely collective knowledge. And in
fact, during recent years, diverse accounts of collective knowledge have
been debated controversially (see, e.g., Andersen, 2010; Cheon, 2014; de
Ridder, 2014; Fagan, 2011; Gilbert, 2000; Miller, 2015; Rolin, 2010; Wray,
2001).
In this chapter, I will focus on two exemplary accounts of collective
knowledge (Sect. 9.1). I will discuss, on the grounds that previous chapters
have laid, how far they apply to the previously observed scientific practice
of collaborative knowledge creation (Sects. 9.2 and 9.3), a discussion on
the basis of which I will formulate my own account of collective scientific
knowledge.
groups of individuals can have the belief that p insofar as all or most
of their individual members have the belief that p. In other words,
summative collective beliefs are reducible to individual beliefs. Non-
summative beliefs, in contrast, are irreducibly collective beliefs. For these
non-summative collective beliefs, Gilbert argues, it is neither a necessary
nor a sufficient condition that all or most (or, in fact, any) group members
individually hold the collective belief.
The observation that underlies Gilbert’s non-summative collective
belief is that there are cases in which individuals adopt beliefs only as a
group. She argues that it can be plausible (and, for that matter, warranted)
for two different groups with identical individual members to have
conflicting group beliefs. She presents the example of a library committee
and a food committee at a residential college which are identical in terms
of membership. She argues that it is plausible for the two committees to
differ in their group beliefs. All group members might individually have
the opinion that college food is too high in carbohydrate; yet, while the
food committee comes to adopt the group belief that college members are
consuming too much starch, the library committee as a group need not
hold this belief (Gilbert, 1989, p. 273; for an elaboration of this example
see Schmitt, 1994, p. 261). These examples suggest that what is decisive
for group belief are institutional constraints under which a group is forced
to act collectively.
According to Gilbert, for a group to hold the non-summative, irre-
ducibly collective belief that p, individual members must jointly express
their individual willingness to let a proposition p stand as the belief of
their collective—a condition that she describes as “joint commitment” of
all group members (Gilbert, 1994, p. 245; Gilbert, 2000, p. 40). A joint
commitment, then, constitutes a “plural subject” which holds the propo-
sition in question as a collective belief.1 Two or more individuals form a
plural subject holding a collective belief if, and only if, they are jointly
committed to holding this belief “as a body” (Gilbert, 1994, p. 244).
1
The concept of a belief-holding plural subject has been met with reservation by social epistemolo-
gists. Therefore, collective belief is rephrased as a form of “collective acceptance” of a proposition. It
is argued that to speak of collective acceptance does not necessitate a plural subject capable of holding
mental states (cf. Schmitt, 1994, p. 262; see also Giere 2007; Hakli 2007; Matthiesen 2006; Wray
2001).
9.2 Non-summative Belief and Joint Commitment 157
The question that I will discuss in the remainder of this section is how
far, and with what analytic benefit, the JC account can be applied to
the observed cases of collaborative knowledge creation. This discussion
will be rather critical, and I will argue that to conceive of collaborative
knowledge creation on Gilbert’s terms creates a misleading image of
scientific practice.
Gilbert’s notion of group belief and its reformulation as collective
knowledge have done much to challenge epistemic individualism, reviving
social epistemology’s debate about the collective character of science. The
conceptual appeal of her group belief is the “slack” that this notion cuts
between individual and collective believing. Group beliefs, she argues,
need not be reducible to individual beliefs. This notion of group beliefs
seems to explain the socio-epistemic phenomena of scientific knowledge
158 9 Collaboration and Collective Knowledge
Observations of the first type (i) should make it plausible that the
JC account explains, in fact, a phenomenon of empirically observable
practice. Observations of the second type (ii) should make it plausible that
the JC account is compliant with actual scientific practice, that it aligns
with the normative notions that are ingrained in scientific practice. Thus,
while (i) reflects a concern for the explanatory value of JC, (ii) reflects a
concern for its empirical applicability (see also Fagan, 2011).
Regarding (i), the data I have been able to gather do not testify to
empirical phenomena that would be particularly well explained through
JC. According to the JC account, a phenomenon that calls for joint
commitment as an explanation would be a collectively held belief that
need not be identical with those beliefs held individually by single
members of the collective in question. Such a phenomenon, if it is a
feature of scientific practice, should be especially observable in the case of
interdisciplinary research, that is, research where individual scientists with
different research backgrounds, perspectives and interests collaborate.
However, in my fieldwork and my interviewing, I have not found evidence
of such a phenomenon.
Instead, what the scientists I observed conveyed to me was an ethos of
individual judgment and conviction—if you are not personally convinced
of something, you should not commit yourself to it. Collaborative scientific
practices should mobilize, not sideline, individual judgment so as to
forestall the premature dissemination of badly corroborated knowledge
claims. As Laura, junior physicist in the planetary science group, observes
about collaborative authoring: “[As a contributing author] I might not be
able to refer exactly to the details, but I’ve checked it through and there
is nothing I am majorly unhappy about”—implying that if she or other
authors were unhappy about a piece of research, she should bring it up
with the first author who should “try to address their concerns and make
sure that the article is written in such a way that people agree” (Laura,
interview, group1).
9.2 Non-summative Belief and Joint Commitment 161
places upon their professional performance. But that is not what the
joint commitment account, which emphasizes precisely the difference of
collective belief and individual believing, is saying. Supporters of the JC
account may furthermore point out that especially younger researchers
are usually confined in their professional freedom and embedded in
hierarchical relations. Yet Gilbert’s notion of joint commitment does
not capture hierarchical decision processes either. In hierarchical research
groups, where senior scientists lead junior scientists, it stands to reason
that the beliefs of senior scientists influence the individually held views
that the junior scientists are endorsing (or are supposed to endorse). This,
again, is not what a JC account is saying.
So despite the fruitful debate that Gilbert’s group belief and the JC
account of collective knowledge have spurred, their usefulness for an
epistemological analysis of collaborative knowledge creation in scientific
practice is not apparent. My empirical data provide no evidence suggest-
ing that the JC account resonates with collaborative scientific practice,
and that its application would generate explanatory benefits. Worse, in
Gilbert’s formulation, the JC account undercuts the practices of dialoging
and explanatory responsiveness, blackening the processes that underlie,
as my case study shows, the creation of scientific knowledge. As it fails
to account for these processes, Gilbert’s collective belief, rephrased as
collective scientific knowledge, risks promoting forms of collaborative
scientific knowledge creation that rely on intransparent and truncated
collective deliberation and judgment (as, e.g., in Beatty, 2006; see also
Beatty & Moore, 2010).
Given that the JC account of collective knowledge does not apply well
to the practices of research collaboration I have studied, I will turn to
the epistemic dependence (ED) account of collective knowledge in the
following section. As I will show, there is, in fact, a robust sense in which
the collaborative practices I have studied yield collective knowledge.
I want to highlight two issues with this argument, one analytic and one
concerning its relevance for the analysis of scientific practice. First, even
when teamwork is a mere “practical necessity” and evidence is “made
accessible,” an individual scientist cannot have scientific justification
entirely non-testimonially. In contrast to de Ridder, I maintain that even
for a scientist with the necessary expertise, mere access to stored evidence
is not sufficient to be certain enough about the way in which a piece
of evidence is based on experimental inquiry. If a scientist has not eye-
witnessed the experiment, she cannot be sure that the experiment has been
performed correctly and its results reported truthfully. An unexpected
result may catch her eye and raise skepticism, but an expected yet inferior
result, accompanied by proper documentation, may not. Hence, if she has
not eye-witnessed the experiments, even the scientist with the necessary
expertise will have to rely upon the trustworthiness of her collaborator—
that is, in justifying her belief in the scientific quality of the evidence in
question, the scientist will have to rely upon second-order reasons. She
alone cannot provide a scientific justification based on the experimental
evidence provided by a collaborator. Therefore, contrary to de Ridder, I
argue that collective knowledge does apply here.
Second, even when evidence could be had non-testimonially, my empir-
ical observations suggest that, in actual practice, scientists often choose to
9.3 Irreducibly Collective Justification 167
I mean for sure one is controlling each other as well within a group. I think
that’s also important, because there is always and is always gonna be people
doing mistakes, if they are made just by chance or if it was really willing to
do the mistake, it’s always gonna happen, because there is so much pressure,
right. So, it’s important that you also internally have kind of a control
system. However, this is more I would say on a base like random control
and so on, yeah. And generally I mean it’s not a big issue I would say within
the group, because you know the experimental set-up, you follow them in
group meetings and so on, so you know what they’re doing. (Alex, interview,
group2)
Collaborators, as Alex sees it, do control one another. But they do not
do so all the time since, he continues, “you gonna easily figure out if
they’re constructing data” (Alex, interview, group2). Much more difficult
to detect than fraud and plain failure are experimental results that could
168 9 Collaboration and Collective Knowledge
have been better, for example, more precise or comprehensive, that maybe
could have yielded serendipitous insights—if experimental routines had
been handled with more skill, care or patience:
[…] at the end of the day you have to convince other people that what you
have done in your experiments is right, it’s – you know, that the experiments
have been done correctly and so on, and there is no sloppiness in there and
so on. (Alex, interview, group2)
Even adequately stored data need not show “sloppiness.” And even
scientists with the necessary expertise often choose to remain epistemically
dependent upon their collaborators, not fulfilling the reflective require-
ment of scientific justification.
A robust notion of collective scientific knowledge should reflect these
realities of scientific practice—the shortness of material resources and
time, the pervasiveness of dependence and trust. Collective scientific
knowledge should account for a broad range of de facto situations.
It should not put too much emphasis on the available, yet unrealized
possibility of epistemic independence. Therefore I suggest an account
of collective scientific dependence, ED**, that is not limited to opaque
epistemic dependence but encompasses cases of translucent epistemic
dependence as well:
One may object to the scope of the ED** account, arguing that
according to it most collaboratively created scientific knowledge should
be considered collective—a conclusion that many social epistemologists
are uneasy about. De Ridder, for example, anticipates the objection that
his ED account would “overgeneralize,” an objection he defends himself
against by emphasizing how limited the conditions for collective scientific
knowledge are if mutual cognitively necessary epistemic dependence is
required (de Ridder, 2014, p. 51).
9.4 Conclusion 169
9.4 Conclusion
In this chapter, I have considered the question as to whether, and in
which sense, collaboratively created scientific knowledge can be con-
sidered irreducibly collective. I have based my consideration upon the
empirical insights into the two research groups I have studied. On the
basis of these insights, I have argued that the joint commitment approach
to collective knowledge does not apply well to collaboratively created
scientific knowledge. Instead, I have suggested pursuing the epistemic
dependence approach to collective scientific knowledge. I have argued that
scientific knowledge is collective when mutual epistemic dependence pre-
vents individual scientists from providing a scientific justification for the
piece of knowledge in question. In formulating this notion of collective
scientific knowledge, I have built upon the work of de Ridder (2014).
170 9 Collaboration and Collective Knowledge
References
Andersen, H. (2010). Joint acceptance and scientific change: A case study.
Episteme, 7 (3), 248–265.
Beatty, J., & Moore, A. (2010). Should we aim for consensus? Episteme, 7 (3),
198–214.
Beatty, J. (2006). Masking disagreement among experts. Episteme, 3(1-2), 52–67.
Bouvier, A. (2004). Individual beliefs and collective beliefs in sciences and
philosophy: The plural subject and the polyphonic subject accounts: Case
studies. Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 34(3), 382–407.
Bouvier, A. (2010). Passive consensus and active commitment in the sciences.
Episteme, 7 (3), 185–97.
Cheon, H. (2014). In what sense is scientific knowledge collective knowledge?
Philosophy of the Social Sciences, 44(4), 407–423.
de Ridder, J. (2014). Epistemic dependence and collective scientific knowledge.
Synthese, 191(1), 37–53.
Fagan, M. B. (2011). Is there collective scientific knowledge? Arguments from
explanation. The Philosophical Quarterly, 61(243), 247–269.
Fagan, M. B. (2012). Collective scientific knowledge. Philosophy Compass, 7 (12),
821–831.
Fricker, E. (2006). Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa
(Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 225–250). Oxford: Clarendon.
Giere, R. N. (2007). Distributed cognition without distributed knowledge.
Social Epistemology, 21(3), 313–320.
Gilbert, M. (1989). On social facts. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Gilbert, M. (1994). Remarks on collective belief. In F. F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializ-
ing epistemology: The social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 235–256). Lanham:
Rowman and Littlefield.
References 171
References
Foley, R. (1994). Egoism in epistemology. In F. F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing epis-
temology: The social dimensions of knowledge (pp. 53–73). Lanham: Rowman
and Littlefield.
Fricker, E. (2006). Testimony and epistemic autonomy. In J. Lackey & E. Sosa
(Eds.), The epistemology of testimony (pp. 225–250). Oxford: Clarendon.
Grasswick, H. E. (2004). Individuals-in-communities: The search for a feminist
model of epistemic subjects. Hypatia, 19(3), 85–120.
Hardwig, J. (1985). Epistemic dependence. The Journal of Philosophy, 82(7), 335–
349.
Hardwig, J. (1991). The role of trust in knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy,
88(12), 693–708.
Kusch, M. (2002). Knowledge by agreement: The programme of communitarian
epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Nelson, L. H. (1995). A feminist naturalized philosophy of science. Synthese,
104(3), 399–421.
Rouse, J. (2002). How scientific practices matter. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
178 10 Concluding Remarks
C E
Callebaut, W., 6, 14 Edge, D., 22, 31
Calvert, J., 7, 14, 41, 54 Ellis, C., 48, 54
Campbell, D. T., 29, 31 Etzkowitz, H., 21, 22, 31
Caneva, K. L., 36, 54 Evans, R., 10, 14, 117, 126, 127, 129
Carusi, A., 113, 129
Chang, H., 2, 14, 38, 45, 54, 140, 150,
151 F
Charmaz, K., 51, 54 Fagan, M. B., 24, 31, 40, 55, 153, 158,
Cheon, H., 4, 14, 24, 31, 153, 170 160, 161, 170
Clarke, B. L., 21, 31 Fantl, J., 10, 14
Clarke, V., 51, 54 Felt, U., 83, 89
Clément, F., 119, 130, 139–142, 147, Fine, M., 49, 55
152 Flyvbjerg, B., 42, 55
Coady, C. A. J., 135, 151 Foley, R., 175, 177
Coffey, A., 50, 54 Fontana, A., 47, 55
Cohen, B. P., 22, 31 Frey, J. H., 47, 55
Cohen, S., 9, 14 Fricker, E., 5, 14, 117, 129, 133–135,
Collins, H., 10, 14, 117, 126, 127, 129 151, 169, 170, 174, 175, 177
Corbin, J., 41, 50, 57 Frodeman, R., 28, 31
Crabtree, B. F., 52, 54 Frost-Arnold, K., 24, 31, 135, 151
Craig, E., 8, 14 Fujimura, J. H., 7, 14, 41, 54
Cronin, B., 21, 31 Fuller, S., 3, 14
Czarniawska, B., 44, 54
G
D Gauker, C., 94, 108
D’Agostino, F., 92, 94, 107 George, A., 38, 55
Darden, L., 28, 31 Gerring, J., 38, 42, 55
Daston, L., 28, 33 Giere, R. N., 6, 14, 39, 55, 94, 108,
Davies, J., 7, 16, 41, 56, 113, 130 156, 170
de Langhe, R., 92, 107 Gigerenzer, G., 28, 33
de Ridder, J., 4, 14, 95, 107, 123, 129, Gilbert, M., 4, 8, 15, 25, 31, 95, 108,
153–155, 162–166, 168–170 153–159, 170, 171
Denzin, N. K., 41, 49, 54 Gillespie, D. F., 29, 31
Author Index 181
I M
Ichikawa, J. J., 8, 15 Machery, E., 7, 16
Israel-Jost, V., 2, 17, 177, 178 MacIntyre, A., 29, 32
182 Author Index
T Z
Thagard, P., 24, 33, 39, 57 Zuckerman, H., 20, 21, 34, 47, 57
Tollefsen, D., 157, 171 Zuell, C., 50, 53
Toomela, A., 23, 33 Zwart, S., 2, 17, 177, 178
Subject Index