Laudan 1977 Progress and Its Problems
Laudan 1977 Progress and Its Problems
Larry Laudan
ISBN: 0520037219
To Rachel, Heather & Kevin—
fellow pilgrims
Contents
Preface ix
Prologue 1
Part One: A Model of Scientific Progress
1. THE ROLE OF EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS 11
The Nature of Scientific Problems—Empirical Problems—Types of
Empirical Problems—The Status of Unsolved Problems—The Na-
ture of Solved Problems—The Special Role of Anomalous Problems
—Converting Anomalies to Solved Problems—The Weighting of
Empirical Problems—Theory Complexes and Scientific Problems
2. CONCEPTUAL PROBLEMS 45
The Nature of Conceptual Problems—The Sources of Conceptual
Problems—The Relative Weighting of Conceptual Problems—Sum-
mary and Overview
ix
xX PREFACE
June, 1976
Prologue
We must explain why science—
our surest example of sound knowledge—
progresses as it does, and wefirst must find out how,
in fact, it does progress. T. S. KUHN (1970), p. 20
1
2 PROLOGUE
about the nature of scientific knowledge still remain of broad,
general interest: Does science progress? Are our ideas about
nature really worthy of credence? Are some beliefs about the
world more rational than others? Issues such as these go well
beyond the boundsofspecialized disciplinary monopolies. They
do so in large part because most people in the West draw the
bulk of their beliefs about nature, and even about themselves,
from the corpus of science. Without Newton, Darwin, Freud,
and Marx (to mention only the more obvious), our picture of the
world would be vastly different from what it is. If science is a
rationally well-founded system of inquiry, then it is only right
and proper that we should emulate its methods, accept its
conclusions, and adopt its presuppositions. If, however, science
is predominately irrational, then there is no reason to take its
knowledge claims any more (or less) seriously than we take
those of the seer, the religious prophet, the guru, or the local
fortuneteller.
For a long time, many have taken the rationality and
progressiveness of science as an obvious fact or a foregone
conclusion, and somereaders will probably still think it bizarre
to believe that there is any important problem to be solved here.
Although this confident attitude has been almost inescapable
given the cultural biases in favor of science in modern culture,
there have been a number of recent developments which bring
it into serious question:
1. Philosophers of science, whose primary aim is to define
what rationality is, have generally found that their models of
rationality find few, if any, exemplifications in the actual
process of scientific activity.’ If we accept the claim made on
behalf of these models to the effect that they define rationality
itself, then we seem forced to view virtually all science as
irrational.
2. Attempts to show that the methodsof science guaranteeit
is true, probable, progressive, or highly confirmed knowledge—
attempts which have an almost continuous ancestry from
Aristotle to our own time—have generally failed,? raising a
distinct presumption that scientific theories are neither true,
nor probable, nor progressive, nor highly confirmed.
3
PROLOGUE
A Modelof Scientific
Progress
The activity of understanding
Is, essentially, the same as
that of all problem solving. K. POPPER (1972), p. 166
Chapter One
The Role of Empirical Problems
Problem formulation in science
is to be understood by looking
at the continuity of the whole
stream of scientific endeavor. H. SIMON (1966), p. 37
il
12 ROLE OF EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS
Thesis 1: The first and essential acid test for any theory is
whether it provides acceptable answers to interesting
questions: whether, in other words, it provides satis-
factory solutions to important problems.
Empirica] Problems
There are two very different kinds of problems which
scientific theories are designed to solve. For now, I want to
focus on the first, more familiar and archetypal, sense of the
concept, which I shall call an empirical problem. Empirical
problemsare easierto illustrate than to define. We observe that
heavy bodies fall toward the earth with amazing regularity. To
ask how and why theyso fall is to pose such a problem. We
observe that alcohol left standing in a glass soon disappears. To
seek an explanation for that phenomenon is, again, to raise an
empirical problem. We may observe that the offspring of plants
and animals bear striking resemblances to their parents. To
inquire into the mechanism of trait transmission is also to raise
rm
ROLE OF EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS
1S
an empirical problem. More generally, anything about the
natural world which strikes us as odd, or otherwise in need
of
explanation, constitutes an empirical problem.
In calling such inquiry situations “empirical” problems, [ do
not mean to suggest they are directly given by the world as
veridical bits of unambiguous data. Both historical examples
and recent philosophical analysis have made it clear that the
world is always perceived through the “‘lenses’” of some
conceptual network or other and that such networks and the
languages in which they are embedded may, for all we know,
provide an ineliminable ‘tint’ to what we perceive. More to the
point, problems of all sorts (including empirical ones) arise
within a certain context of inquiry and are partly defined by
that context. Our theoretical presuppositions about the natural
order tell us what to expect and what seems peculiar or
“problematic” or questionable (in the literal sense of that term).
Situations which pose problems within one inquiry context will
not necessarily do so within others. Hence, whether something
is regarded as an empirical problem will depend, in part, on the
theories we possess.
Why, then, call them ‘empirical’ problems at all? I do so
because, even granting that they arise only in certain contexts
of theoretical inquiry, even granting that their formulation will
be influenced by our theoretical commitments, it is nonetheless
the case that we treat empirical problems as if they were
problems about the world. If we ask, “How fast do bodies fall
near the earth?”’, we are assumingthere are objects akin to our
conceptions of body and earth which move towards one another
according to some regular rule. That assumption, of course, is
a theory-laden one, but we nonethelessassert it to be about the
physical world. Empirical problems are thus first order prob-
lems; they are substantive questions about the objects which
constitute the domain of any given science. Unlike other, higher
order problems (to be discussed in chapter two), we judge the
adequacy of solutions to empirical problems by studying the
objects in the domain.
We have already noted that there is an apparent functional
similarity between talk of problems and problem solving and the
more familiar rhetoric about facts and the explanation of facts.
16 ROLE OF EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS
i a
ROLE OF EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS 43
The Duhemian points out that logic does not permit the
assertion of the falsity of any element, 7;, of the complex just
because the complex itself has been falsified.
Within the problem-solving model, however, we make no
assignments of truth or falsity; there is nothing in the structure
of deductive logic which precludesthe localization of properties
such as problem-solving effectiveness. When we say that a is an
anomaly for a theory 7,, we are not saying that a falsifies T, (to
claim that would open oneself to Duhemian objections); rather,
we are saying that a is the sort of problem which a theory such
as T, ought to be able to solve (albeit in conjunction with other
theories), but which it has failed as yet to solve. That, of course,
does not prove that T, is false; but it does clearly raise doubts
about the problem-solving effectiveness of 7, (and, for that
matter, about every other T; in the complex that failed to solve
the empirical problem a).
A similar sort of analysis applies to the apparent ambiguities
of confirmation. When westress those ambiguities, it is because
we are not clear how mucha successful confirmation of a theory
complex ought to increase our confidence in the truth (or the
likelihood) of its component elements. But if we shift from talk
about truth or probability to talk about problem solving, this
ambiguity dissolves as well, for there is a mirror image here of
the principle (A,) defined above for anomalies; namely (A,),
Whenever any theory complex, C, adequately solves
an empirical problem, b, then b counts as a solved
problem for each nonanalytic element, 7,, T,,...,
T, of C.
As principles (A,) and (A,) make clear, I am proposing we
turn the usual response to these Duhemian ambiguities on its
head. Where previous writers on this issue have tended to
imagine that the solution to the Duhemian ambiguity consists in
trying to find some way, contra Duhem’s analysis, for localizing
blame or credit, I want to try the opposite approach by
suggesting that a way out of the Duhemian conundrum may
emerge if, far from /ocalizing blameor credit in one place, we
simply spread it evenly among the members of the complex
(using a rational variant of the guilt-by-association doctrine).
44 ROLE OF EMPIRICAL PROBLEMS
45
46 CONCEPTUAL PROBLEMS
een
CONCEPTUAL PROBLEMS $3
that, on the model outlined here, (1) progress can occur without
an expansion of the domain of solved empirical problems, and
is even conceivable when the domain of such problems con-
tracts; and (2) a theory change may conceivably be non-progres-
sive or regressive, even when the index of solved empirical
problems increases, specifically, if the change leads to more
acute anomalies or conceptual problems confronting the new
theory than those exhibited by the predecessor theory.
Although an outline of a theory of cognitive progress is now
emerging, there is still one crucial dimension missing. In ali the
talk about problem solving, there has been some confusion
about what kinds of things solve problems. I have been using
the term “theory” to designate those complexes whose problem-
solving capacities must be appraised; in order to clarify the
types of problems in science, I have had to postpone a discus-
sion about what kinds of things can solve problems. We must
examine that side of the problem-solving equation before the
rough-hewn model of progress outlined here can be refined into
a valuable tool of analysis.
Chapter Three
From Theories to
Research Traditions
The intellectualfunction of
an established conceptual
Scheme is to determine the
patterns of theory, the mean
-
ingful questions, the legitima
te
interpretations... 5. TOULMI
N (1970), p. 40
De
72 FROM THEORIES TO RESEARCH TRADIT
IONS
“evolutionary theory”’ for instance, does not refer
to any single
theory but to an entire family of doctrines, histori
cally and
conceptually related, all of which work
from the assumption
that organic species have common lines of descent.
Similarly,
the term “atomic theory” generally refers
to a large set of
doctrines, all of which are predicated
on the assumption that
matter is discontinuous. A particularly vivid
instance of one
theory which includes a wide variety of specifi
c instantiations is
offered by recent ‘quantum theory.” Since
1930, that term has
included (among other things) quantum
field theories, group
theories, so-called S-matrix theories,
and renormalized field
theories—between any two of which there are
huge conceptual
divergences.
The differences between the two types of
theories outlined
above are vast: not only are there contrasts
of generality and
specificity between them, but the modes
of appraisal and
evaluation appropriate to each are radically
different. It will be
the central claim of this chapter that until
we become mindful
of the cognitive and evaluational differences
between these two
types of theories, it will be impossible to
have a theory of
scientific progress which is historically sound
or philosophically
adequate.
But it is not only fidelity to scientific practi
ce and usage
which requiresus to take these larger theore
tical units seriously.
Muchof the research done by historians and
philosophers of
science in the last decade suggests that these
more general units
of analysis exhibit many of the epistemic
features which,
although most characteristic of science,
elude the analyst who
limits his range to theories in the narrower
sense. Specifically,
it has been suggested by Kuhn and Lakat
os that the more
general theories, rather than the more specifi
c ones, are the
Primary tool for understanding and
appraising scientific
progress.
I share this conviction in principle, but
find that the accounts
hitherto given of what these larger theori
es are, and how they
evolve, are not fully satisfactory. Becau
se the bulk of this
chapter will be devoted to outlining a new
account of the more
global theories (which I shall be calling resear
ch traditions), it is
appropriate that I should indicate what
I find chiefly wanting in
FROM THEORIES TO RESEARCH TRADITIONS 73
is not (or ought not be) to judge that tradition false. Nor, in
rejecting a research tradition as momentarily unsuccessful, are
we necessarily relegating it to permanent oblivion; to the
contrary, we can explicitly stipulate conditions which, if
satisfied, would revive and recussitate it. Thus, when wereject
a research tradition, we are merely making a tentative decision
not to utilize it for the moment becausethere is an alternative to
it which has proven to be a more successful problem solver.
Just as the fortunes of a research tradition are linked closely
to the problem-solving effectiveness of its constituent theories,
so too is the determination of the adequacy of a specific
theory inextricably bound up with an assessment of the
problem-solving effectiveness of the entire set of theories
spawned by the research tradition of which that theory is a
part.?> If a theory is closely linked to an unsuccessful research
tradition, then—whatever the problem-solving merits of that
particular theory—it is likely to be regarded as highly suspect.
For instance, Count Rumford’s theories of heat conduction and
convection were far superior to any alternative theories of
thermalflow in fluids available in the period from 1800 to 1815.
Nonetheless, few scientists took Rumford’s theories seriously
because (as they saw it) the research tradition in which
Rumford worked (deriving from Boerhaave) had been discred-
ited by the emergence of rival research traditions in chemistry
(especially Joseph Black’s), which suggested that heat was a
substance rather than, as Rumford imagined, the random
motion of particles. Rumford’s specific theories only became
fashionable in the 1840s and 1850s because by that time the
balance between various research traditions had shifted suffic-
iently that many scientists were more prepared to consider
seriously specific theories (like Rumford’s) which grew out of a
kinetic research tradition.
Contrariwise, a theory, even an inadequate one, will have
some strong argumentsin its favorif it is linked with a research
tradition that is otherwise highly successful. Thus, theories of
mechanistic physiology in the late seventeenth century (such as
those of Borelli and Pitcairn) were highly regarded in many
circles where the mechanistic research tradition was flourishing
84 FROM THEORIES TO RESEARCH TRADITIONS
re
108 FROM THEORIES TO RESEARCH TRADITIONS
1
T°"
Anomalies Revisited
Chapter one contained the paradoxical claim that the refut-
ing instances of a theory are not necessarily anomalous
problems, along with a promissory note to clarify that claim
once the machinery was available to do so. The evaluational
methods outlined here allow us to return to this issue. I said
before that a problem was only anomalous (i.e., cognitively
threatening) for some theory, 7, if that problem was unsolved
by T but solved by one of its competitors. Clearly, some re-
futing instances will satisfy this definition, but many will not.
It is often the case that some prediction of a theory fails to
square with the data, but no other available theory can solve
the data either. In the latter situation, why should the data not
count as a threatening anomaly for T?
In brief, the answer is this: Whenever a theory encounters a
refuting instance, it is possible to modify the interpretative rules
associated with the theory so as to disarm the ‘‘refuting” data.
If, for instance, we have a theory, 7, that ‘all planets move in
ellipses’ and then discover a satellite of the sun, S, which
FROM THEORIES TO RESEARCH TRADITIONS 119
121
EEE
122 PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION
ol
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION 123
'
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION 125
a
127
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION
am suggesting is that we apparently do not have any way of
is
knowing for sure (or even with some confidence) that science
truth. Such
true, or probable, or that it is getting closer to the
know
aims ate utopian, in the literal sense that we can never
being achieved . To set them up as goals for
whether they are
inquiry may be noble and edifying to those who
scientific
can
delight in the frustration of aspiring to that which they
very helpful
never (know themselves to) attain; but they are not
if our object is to explain how scientific theories are (or should
be) evaluated.’
The workability of the problem-solving model is its greatest
virtue. In principle, we can determine whether a given theory
can
does or does not solve a particular problem. In principle, we
determine whether our theories now solve more importa nt
problems than they did a generati on or a century ago. If we
in
have had to weaken our notions of rationality and progress
weare at least now in a position to be
order to achieve this end,
sive—a
able to decide whether science is rational and progres
denied to us if we retain the classical
crucial necessity
connections between progress, rationality, and truth.
How precisely do we go about making this decision? Inevi-
the
tably, it involves the assessment of specific cases drawn from
rational and
history of science; whether science as a whole is
set of
progressive depends, of course, upon whether the
traditio ns: has
individual choices of theories and research
exhibited progress and rationality. Thus, we may ask whether
on
the reaction of the scientific community to Einstein’s paper
a progress ive modifica tion in the
the photoelectric effect led to
the
theories of physics. At another level, we may ask whether
Newtoni an research traditio n over the
overall triumph of the
ian research traditio ns in the eightee nth
Cartesian and Leibniz
ive. In answeri ng such question s, we must
century was progress
scten-
attend very carefully to the parameters of contemporary
and controve rsy, for it is precisel y therein that the
tific debate
l and
historian can find out what the acknowledged empirica
it is there that he can get a
conceptual problems were;
of those
reasonably clear sense of the weight or importance
case (and not
problems. By a subtle analysis of the actual
the histori an—or
4 so-called rational reconstruction of it),
128 PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION
the contemporary scientist—can usually determine the degree
to which competing research traditions, or competing theories
within the same research tradition, were progressive
in their
modifications.
Whatis crucial here is that we must cast our nets of apprais
al
sufficiently widely that we include al/ the cognitively
relevant
factors which were actually present in the historical
situation.
We must not assume a priori, as some historians
of science
have, that the only important parameters were experim
ental or
other obviously “‘scientific’’ ones. Because theories
and research
traditions have to be accommodated within a broader
network
of beliefs and preconceptions, any accurate apprais
al of an
episode must attend carefully to the philosophical,
theological
and other intellectual currents which were brought
to bear on
the case at hand. The fact that a twentieth-century
scientist
might not recognize the cogency of an objection to
a theory on
philosophical or religious grounds manifestly does
not mean
that an understanding of the rationality of earlier science
can be
acquired by ignoring such factors. If a culture at a
particular
time has a strongly entrenched set of religious or
philosophical
doctrines which thinkers in that culture believe to
be crucial to
an understanding of nature, then it is pertectly rational
to
appraise new scientific theories or research traditions
in light of
their ability to be accommodated within that prior
system of
beliefs and presuppositions.
There are doubtless those who would argue that such
an
approach sorelativizes our standards of rationality that
it will
justify any set of beliefs. If such a criticism were true,
then there
would be grave problems with the notion of rational
ity being
defended here. But that is far from the case. To
suggest that
“anything goes,” that any combination of beliefs would
emerge
as rational and progressive on this model, is profoun
dly to
misunderstand the high standards of rational behavio
r which it
requires. Nor does the model involve the complete
surrender of
our standards of rationality to the exigencies of
earlier times
and places.
This point is worth discussing at some length, for
it bears
crucially on many of the central dilemmas in the histori
ography
and sociology of science. Many philosophers have
sought to set
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION 129
|
130 PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION
theories utilizing evaluative measures which we know were not
operative (not even in an approximative form) in the case
at hand?
But the historian is confronted by the other horn of the
dilemma. If he simply takes at face value every actual appraisal
by past scientists of the rationality of a belief, he will never be in
any position to judge whether such appraisals were, even by the
appropriate standardsof the time, well-founded. Obviously, the
fact that some historical agent says, “theory A is better than
theory B,’’ does not necessarily makeit so. If the historian is to
i explain why certain theories triumphed and others perished,
then he must (unless he takes the view that theory choice is
always irrational) be able to show that some theories—by the
best available rational standards of the time—were superior to
others.
Hence, the central problem seems to be this: how can we,
with the philosophers, continue to talk normatively about the
rationality (and irrationality) of theory choices in the past, while
at the same time avoid the grafting of anachronistic criteria of
rationality onto those episodes?
The model I have outlined resolves part of that difficulty by
exploiting the insights of our own time about the general nature
of rationality, while making allowances for the fact that many of
the specific parameters which constitute rationality are time-
and culture-dependent. It transcends the particularities of the
past by insisting that for all times and for all cultures, provided
those cultures have a tradition of critical discussion (without
which no culture can lay claim to rationality), rationality consists
in accepting those research traditions which are most effective
problem solvers. It insists that for scientists in any culture to
espouse a research tradition or a theory which is less adequate
than other ones available within that culture is to behave
irrationally. In these important respects, the model argues that
there are certain very general characteristics of a theory of
rationality which are trans-temporal and trans-cultural, which
are as applicable to pre-Socratic thought, or the developmentof
ideas in the Middle Ages, as they are to the more recent
history of science. On the other hand, the model also insists that
what is specifically rational in the past is partly a function of
_
{31
ON
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTI
of things which count as
time and place and context. The kinds
the sorts of objections that are
empirical problems,
of intelligibility,
recognized as conceptual problems, the criteria
the importance or
the standards for experimental control,
of the methodo-
weight assigned to problems, are all a function
unity of thinkers.
logical-normative beliefs of a particular comm
advantage of
The model under discussion here possesses the
ical norms of a
allowing us to integrate the specific histor
more gener al, time- independent fea-
previous epoch and the
tures of rational decision making.*
nal choice is to
Toignore the time-specific parameters of ratio
geous position of
put the historian or philosopher in the outra
achievements in the
indicting as irrational some of the major
irrational when he
history of ideas. Aristotle was not being
science of physics
claimed, in the fourth century B.c., that the
by, metaphysics—
should be subordinate to, and legitimated
and places, might well
even if that same doctrine, at other times
nas or Robert
be characterized as irrational. Thomas Aqui
d or preju diced when they
Grosseteste were not merely stupi
must be compa tible with
espoused the belief that science
religious beliefs.
disagree with
We in the twentieth century may vehemently
them obscu ranti st and harmf ul to the
such views, thinking
ve we are
development of science. And in so disagreeing, I belie
that theories and
right. One of the things that time has shown is
s) flourish best
research traditions sometimes (though not alway
ogical and meta-
when they are not subordinated to the theol
ific community.
physical doctrines dominant outside the scient
we have come to
But it is with the advantage of hindsight that
ience of the last
that conclusion. In the absence of the exper
d to assu me that it
three centuries, it would be palpably absur
theol ogy and metap hysics
wasirrational to imagine that science,
view that scien ce is quast-
could be mutually supportive. The
is itself a resea rch tradit ion, one
independent of such disciplines
is a kind of resea rch tradi tion that
of relatively recent origin. It
e of progress.
has, in its way, generated a considerable degre
ratio nal in the twent ieth century to
That is why it may be
that a belief is ratio nal in the prese nt age,
accept it. But the fact
matte r, does not neces saril y entail that it
or in any age for that
ee
132 PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION
was rational at other times and places. Quite the reverse is more
often the case.
It should be clear by now that, in arguing that the cultural
exigencies and pressures exerted on science must be taken into
account, I am neither abandoning the possibility of rational
appraisal nor am | insisting that nonscientific factors are
present in every case of scientific choice. I am simply suggesting
that we need a broadened notion of rationality which will show
how the “‘intrusion’’ of seemingly ‘‘nonscientific’’ factors into
scientific decision making is, or can be, an entirely rational
process. Far from viewing the introduction of philosophical,
religious and moral issues into science as the triumph of
prejudice, superstition and irrationality, this model claims that
the presence of such elements may be entirely rational; further,
that the suppression of such elements mayitself be irrational
and prejudicial.
Of course, whether it is rational to use theological, moral, or
philosophical arguments for (or against) a new scientific theory
or research tradition is a contingent matter which depends on
how rational and progressive are the research traditions which
provide such arguments. To argue against modern theories of
chemical combustion on the grounds that such theories are
incompatible with the myth of Vulcan is patently absurd, for
the Greek myths have scarcely established themselves as a body
of rational and progressive dogma. To argue against Marxist
economics on the grounds that it is contrary to Christian
morality is, again, to use a singularly non-progressive tradition
as a tool for criticizing a relatively progressive ‘‘scientific’’
tradition. The rationality or irrationality of any episode where
“nonscientific,’’ but intellectual, factors play a role must be
assessed on a case-by-case basis. But the guiding principles here
should be these: (1) in the case of competing scientific research
traditions, if one of those traditions is compatible with the most
progressive ‘‘worldview” available, and the other is not, then
there are strong grounds for preferring the former; (2) if both
traditions can be legitimated with reference to the same world-
view, then the rational decision between them may be made on
entirely ‘“‘scientific’” grounds; (3) if neither tradition is com-
patible with a progressive worldview, their proponents should
Se
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION 133
Scientific Revolutions
For well over a century, it has been commonplace to focus on
“scientific revolutions” as one of the core concepts for historical
narration and exegesis. Within the last two decades, the idea of
a revolution has become canonized in Thomas Kuhn's classic
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Although far from his
intent (since Kuhn was primarily concerned to draw attention to
non-revolutionary, “normal science’’), his book has led many
scientists, philosophers and historians alike to compartment-
alize the evolution of science into widely separated periods of
revolutionary activity, and to imagine that the scientific revolu-
tion (with its attendant “change of paradigm’’) is the basic
category for discussing the evolution of science.
Although scientific revolutions are undoubtedly important
historical phenomena, they possess neither the importance nor
the cognitive character often associated with them. They have
assumed this privileged position largely because their structure
has been mis-described in ways that make them seem radically
unlike science in its usual state; the exaggeration of the
difference between ‘‘normal”’ and “revolutionary science” in its
turn has led some writers to lay heavier stress on ‘‘periods of
revolutionary activity’ than they probably deserve.
Consider, for instance, Kuhn’s account of scientific revolu-
tions, For him, a revolution is marked by the emergence of a
new theoretical ‘‘paradigm’’ which, in a short span of time,
discredits the older paradigm and draws the virtually unani-
mous adherence of every member of the relevant scientific
community. Revolutions, on his view, are preceded by short
periods of frenetic theoretical activity during which many
alternative viewpoints vie for the allegiance of the scientific
community. Elements of the previous paradigm which were
previously sacrosanct suddenly become objects of lively debate
and heated controversy. A wide range of alternative viewpoints
is explored until eventually (usually in less than a generation)
eh
134 PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION
i
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION 137
": i
oe]
negative, provided that the theories which solve the problem are
not inconsistent with those relatively low-level theoretical as-
sumptions required to state the problem.'* Throughout the late
seventeenth century, for example, numerous conflicting theories
of light (including those of Descartes, Hobbes, Hooke, Barrow,
Newton, and Huygens) addressed themselves to the problem of
reflection. The various optical theories were all regarded as
solving the problem of reflection, because that problem could
be characterized in a way which was independent of any of the
theories which sought to solveit.
I do not mean to suggest, of course, that a/l the problems
which a theory or research tradition attempts to solve can be
characterized independently of the theory (or theories) which
solves them. The determination of the “independence”’ of any
specific problem must depend upon the particularities of the
case. It is my impression, however, that there are far more
problems common to competing research traditions than there
are problems unique to a single one. These shared problems
provide a basis for a rational appraisal of the relative problem-
solving effectiveness of competing research traditions.
I must stress again that this argument does not presuppose
that empirical problems can be stated in some purely observa-
tional, nontheoretical language. To speak of (for instance) light
being refracted through a prism makes a numberof theoretical
assumptions (among them, that light moves, that something
happens to light while it is ‘inside’ a prism, etc.). It is not the
atheoretical nature of empirical problems which is being alleged
here. Rather, the weaker claim being madeis this: with respect
to any two research traditions (or theories} in any field of
science, these are some joint problems which can be formulated
so as to presuppose nothing which is syntactically dependent
upon the specific research traditions being compared. Thus,
when eighteenth-century Newtonians and Cartesians spoke
|
about the probiem offree fall, they were identifying the same
problem—for all the profound differences between their re-
spective research traditions. When these same natural philos-
ophers discussed the problem whyall the planets moved in the
same direction about the sun, they were also in complete
agreement about the nature and meaning of the problem
(although they did quarrel about its relative importance as a
problem). When early nineteenth-century geologists debated the
explanation of stratification, they could all—whether uniformi-
| tarian or catastrophist, whether Neptunist or Vulcanist,
' whether Huttonian or Wernerian, whether God-fearing or God-
| denying, whether French, English or German—agree that one
problem for any geological theory was that of explaining how
i such uniform and distinct layers had been formed.
Kuhn has been misled by his discovery that some empirical
problems are not jointly shared between different traditions or
paradigms (which is certainly true) into believing that no
problems are identical. The generalized thesis of problem
incommensurability is as perverse as the limited thesis of partial
non-overlap is profound.
ee
reg
Non-Cumulative Progress
Ever since the appearance of Condorcet’s Sketch Towards a
History of the Progress of the Human Mind, many philosophers
and historians of science have developed, at least in outline
form, theories of cognitive progress. From Whewell, Peirce, and
Duhem through Collingwood, Popper, Reichenbach, Lakatos,
Stegmiiller, and Kuhn, the search for adequate models of
cognitive progress has been, if not commonplace, at least not
rare. For al! their differences, these models of progress—save
Kuhn’s'*—share one common feature: a conviction that it is
only possible to speak of progress if knowledge is acquired
through purely cumulative theories. By ‘‘purely cumulative
theories,’ 1 mean those theories which may add to the store of
solved problems, but which never fail to solve al/ the problems
succesfully solved by their predecessors. Put slightly differently,
these thinkers argue that a necessary condition for one theory,
T,, to represent progress over another, 7,, is that 7, must solve
all the solved problems of 7,. Although this cumulative
conception of progress is usually associated with Popper and
Lakatos, it was probably most succinctly formulated by Colling-
wood when hewrote:
If thought in its first phase, after solving the initial problems of that phase, is
then through solving these, brought up against others which defeat it; and if
the second solves these further problems without losing its hold on the solution
of the first, so that there is gain without any corresponding loss, then there is
progress. And there can be progress on no other terms. [f there is any loss, the
problem of setting loss against gain is insoluble. '°
i
PROGRESS AND REVOLUTION 149
Both Kuhn and Lakatos are committed to the view that there
are two radically different types of science, corresponding
roughly to the ‘‘early’’ and “‘advanced’’ stages of scientific
activity. Although called by different names (for Lakatos,
“immature” and ‘‘mature” science; for Kuhn, ‘‘pre-”” and
“post-paradigm” science),?? and defined differently, both
writers are committed to the view that the various sciences, at
various times, undergo the transition from infancy to majority
and that when they do, the rules of the scientific game change
substantially. For Kuhn, the transition occurs when one
paradigm establishes monopoly over the field and when ‘‘nor-
mal science’ first ensues. For Lakatos, a science reaches
maturity when scientists in that field consistently ignore both
anomalous problems and outside intellectual and social influ-
ences, and focus almost entirely on the mathematical articula-
tion of research programmes. Thus, what chiefly characterizes
a mature science, for both Kuhn and Lakatos, is the emergence
of paradigms(or research programmes) which are autonomous,
and thereby independent from outside criticism. This transition
is more than a nominal one; Kuhn and Lakatosalike insist that
mature science is more progressive, more genuinely scientific
than its immature counterpart.
There are several troubling aspects to the concept of a mature
science (at least as developed by Kuhn and Lakatos). The
suggestion that every (or even that any) science undergoes a
ql
or
Applications
Chapter Five
History and Philosophy of Science
Philosophy of science without history
of science is empty; history of science
without philosophy of science is
blind. 1. LaKaTos (1971), p. 91
argument of this type does not solve that core problem; to the
contrary, it accentuates its importance by revealing its
universality.
I shall propose one possible way out of the paradox. Let us
begin by returning to the distinction between HOS, and HOS,,.
Within HOS,, there is, I shall claim, a subclass of cases of
theory-acceptance and theory-rejection about which most scien-
tifically educated persons have strong (and similar) normative
intuitions. This class would probably include within it many
(perhaps even all) of the following: (1) it was rational to accept
Newtonian mechanics and to reject Aristotelian mechanics by,
say, 1800; (2) it was rational for physicians to reject homeopathy
and to accept the tradition of pharmacological medicine by, say,
1900; (3) it was rational by 1890 to reject the view that heat was
a fluid; (4) it was irrational after 1920 to believe that the
chemical atom had no parts; (5) it was irrational to believe after
1750 that light moved infinitely fast; (6); it was rational to
accept the general theory of relativity after 1925; (7) it was
irrational after 1830 to accept the biblical chronology as literal
account ofearth history.
The precise dates here are not important, nor yet is any single
item on the list. What I shall maintain, however, is that there is
a widely held set of normative judgments similar to the ones
above. This set, constitutes what I shall call our preferred
pre-analytic intuitions about scientific rationality (or ‘“‘PI,”’ for
short). (This set is a very small subset of all our beliefs about
HOS,.) Our convictions about the rationality or irrationality of
such episodes are clearer and more firmly rooted than any of
our overt and explicit theories about rationality in the abstract.
Particularly decisive here are those theories and research
traditions which have been the most global and the most
influential, i.e., those which have for long epochs provided the
motivation and presuppositions for a wide range of detailed
theorizing. Any model of rationality which led to the conclusion
that the acceptance of most of these doctrines were ill-founded
would have few claims on our loyalty."° As a result, our
intuitions about such cases can function as decisive touchstones
for appraising and evaluating different normative models of
rationality, since we maysay thatit is a necessary condition of
HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE 161
DN
162 HISTORY AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE
171
172
HISTORY OF IDEAS
historians see intellectual history as an anach
ronistic excre-
scence on the scholarly and ideological
integrity of their field,
Because the bulk of this chapter (and
in certain respects the
entire essay) is an effort to stress the
importance of the history
of ideas—at least of a certain type
of history of ideas—it is
probably wise to begin by surveying
some of the reasons for its
present disrepute.
There are several, frequently cited
complaints directed against
intellectual history:
1. that it is “elitist’: not because most
people do not think,
but rather because we only have histor
ical records about the
“thoughts” of a tiny fraction of
the petsons in any society
(namely, those who were both literate
and fairly prolific).
2. that it assumes ideas have
an independent reality. it is, so
the critics stress, “people who have
ideas.” People live in
societies with certain economic, politi
cal and social character-
istics which condition or even cause
their ideas. Intellectual
history, to the extent that it abstr
acts ideas from their broader
social surroundings, distorts the
historical record.
3. that ideas are a far less potent
source of change than the
underlying socio-economic "realities":
on this view ideas (in
form of “ideologies’’) merely mirro
r the material condition of
the society and serve only as token
s for the class conflict
between the warring factions. To focus
on the evolution of ideas
is to misplace the genuine causes of
historical change.
4. that the history of ideas, becau
se it is “impressionistic ”’
and not readily quantifiable, is
out of Step with the move
towards “‘scientific”’ history.
I shall postpone any direct comm
ent on these well-known
quibbles with intellectual history.
It was important to state
them early, however, in order
to underscore the differences
between these standard criticisms
of the history of ideas and
those reservations which I shal]
be voicing. All the above are
objections in principle to any type
of intellectual history; they
seek to cast doubts on any effort
to study the evolution of ideas
(except within a broader socio-econ
omic context). My own
reservations, which I shall discuss
at length, are qualms about
the assumptions currently underlying
certain types of intellec-
tual history. In brief, I shall argue
that much intellectual
history, as currently practiced,
is too discipline-oriented in its
ee
HISTORY OF IDEAS 173
has solved it; for we only know what the problem is by arguing
back from the solution.’"! On such an analysis,
we could never
say that a thinker failed to solve a problem because the
only
criterion Collingwood allows for attributing a proble
m to a
thinker is that he has solved it. Such a Panglos
ian view of
intellectual activity—entailing as it does that the only
problems
we ever attempt to solve are those which we actuall
y solve—
makes it impossible for the historian either to criticiz
e the past
or to explain its vicissitudes (at least in so far as the
latter
depend upon thefailure of certain intellectual systems
to solve
the problems which they address). Collingwood
failed to
" recognize that the historian can often find strong
evidential
grounds forattributing a problem to a thinker, even
when that
thinker fails to solve the problem which he has set
for himself.
ee
180
HISTORY OF IDEAs
Enlightenment historians of idea
s have long agreed that the
shadows of Bacon and Newton
loom very large over eighteenth.
century thought. Countless
books and articles have been
devoted to tracing out the infl
uence of their ideas in France,
Britain, and Germany during
the period. Yet if one asks why
Bacon and Newton were so muc
h more influent ial than, Say,
Hobbes or Boyle or Malebranc
he, one finds that answers
neither frequently offered nor, are
when offered, cogently formu-
lated. The fact of the domina
nce of Newton and Bacon
eighteenth-century thought has in
been documented ad nauseam;
we have yet to make it a reasoned, or an
explained, fact.
With individuals, as tmauch
as with broader movements
intellectual , most
history remains exegetical and
nonexpla
natory. It is
now well known, for inst
ance, that Newton and Leib
heav ily influenced by Cartesian niz were
philosophy in their formative
years. Yet both, for differen
t reasons, came to repudiat
Cartesian conceptions in thei e
r philosophical maturity. The
chronology ofthis process has
been well documented for som
time. Yet if one asks for a conv e
incing explanation of Newton’s
or of Leibniz’s change of min
d, contemporary scholarship
scarcely taken us beyond the has
sketchy explanations offered
Leibniz and Newton themselves. by
The pervasive explanatory pauc
ity of intellectual history, as
illustrated by these few exam
ples, is presumably more than
accidental. There must be,
one is inclined to conjecture,
something about the current
methods and presuppositions
the history of ideas which acco of
unts for jts explanatory bank-
tuptcy. There are at least two
areas where I am inclined to
locate the difficulties: in the
basic units of analysis hitherto
utilized by historians of ideas;
and in the difficulties that atte
any effort to explain the beli nd
efs of human agents. I shall
with these in turn. deal
en
HISTORY OF IDEAS 181
he
182 HISTORY OF IDEAS
ee
HISTORY OF IDEAS 185
Da
186
HISTORY OF IDEAS
not rational in his appraisal of beliefs in this field.
By contrast,
(1) is the problem case, for how do we discover
laws or principles
of type 1?
The question cannot be avoided or postponed,
for a plausible
answer to it is a necessary prerequisite to any histor
y (as opposed
to a chronology) of ideas. The general laws sought will
belong, of
course, to the theory of rational belief; forit is only
such theories
that can provide general principles of the type repres
ented by
statement (1). The applicability of such
theories of rational
belief, in turn, crucially depends on what we
pack into our
characterization of the believer’s “situation type.””
As I pointed
i out in Part One, most theories of ration
al belief fail to be
of much use to the historian because they deal
with a very
impoverished rangeof situation types.
On an inductivist theory of rationality, for examp
le, the only
situation types discussed would be those in which
a belief was
assigned very high (or a very low) probability on
the strength of
the known empirical evidence. But, as we have
seen, this is of
little aid to either the historian of science or
the general
intellectual historian, because virtually no actual
historical cases
of belief exemplify the strict conditions demanded
by inductivist
models. In deductivist theories of rationality, on the
other hand,
the only allowable situation types would be
those in which
relations of entailment obtained between the
belief to be ex-
plained and other beliefs of the agent. While
such cases do
certainly occur in the history of thought (and
to this extent
deductivist models of rationality have more to offer
the intellec-
tual historian than inductivist ones), they
still constitute only a
tiny proportionof the belief situations which he
seeks to explain.
A variant of the deductivist model often invok
ed by intellec-
tual historians is Collingwood’s theory of presup
position. The
idea hereis to get at those core concepts which
lie behind, asit
were, the explicit beliefs to which a thinker
subscribes. The
problem is that presuppositional analysis (at least
in its Colling-
woodian form) is, at its core, purely deductivist.
It can explain
those beliefs of a historical figure which follow
strictly from his
alleged presuppositions; but it can explain neithe
r the presuppo-
Sitions themselves nor any beliefs which fail
to be deductive
consequences of those presuppositions. Still worse,
presupposi-
tional history offers no machineryfor discussing
why historical
HISTORY OF IDEAS 187
188
HISTORY OF IDEAS
Such principles, when conjoine
d with the progress orrationa]-
ity profiles of each of the
available research traditions, wil|
allow one to explain many deve
lopments within the history of
thought which have thus far elud
ed explanation. Such, at any
rate, is the claim being made for
the problem-solving model.
It might be held that, in orde
r to give historical explanations
of the kind Proposed here,
we have no need for rational
normative appraisals whatever ,
. It could be said thatit is not
historian’s task to determine the
whether some belief was rational
only to show that some thinker ,
thought it to be so. Suppose, for
instance, we wish to explain why New
ton advocate d action-at-a-
distance forces to explain grav
itation. Is it not enough mere
recite Newton’s stated reasons ly to
for introducing the concept,
adding perhaps that he regarded
these as sufficient reasons for
using the concept? On this anal
ysis, there is no place for the
historian to ask the normative
question whether, by the then
appropriate canons ofscientific
belief, Newton was right in
judging action-at-a-distance
to be well conceived.
To locate the flaw in this approach
, we mayconsider a second,
parallel example. Suppose we
wish to explain why a certain
“special creationist” believes ther
e was a universal deluge during
the time of Noah. Suppose, furt
her, that we can show that his
only reason forthis belief is that
it accords with Scriptures and
since he takes Scriptural conc
ordance as a sign of truth, thin
his belief is well-founded. Conf ks
ronted with such an “explana
tion,”” we would feel that the -
historian’s job was only half
completed, for we now want
to know why this creationist
subscribed to such a peculiar
theory of truth. Our curiosity
only whetted, not Satisfied, by is
being told that someone accepted
a belief for which there were
only ‘‘bad”’ reasons, not “good’’
ones.
By contrast, if we can show that
a thinker accepted a certain
belief which was really the best
available in the Situation, then
we feel that our explanatory task
is over. Implicit in this way of
looking at the matter is the assu
mption that when a thinker does
what it is rational to do, we
need inquire no further into
causes of his the
action;whereas, when he does wha
irrational—evenif he believes t is in fact
it to be rational—we require som
e
|
HISTORY OF IDEAS 189
192
HISTORY OF IDEAS
and as rational as the sciences, Progress,
as we said in Part One,
is a matter of degree; two systems
of thought can each be
progressive, while one may show a highe
r rate of progress than
another.
If there is any truth at all in the (posit
ivistic) claim about the
differences between the Sciences
and the nonsciences, and |
suspect there is sometruth in it,
it will be found, not in the
exclusive exhibition of Progress by the scie
nces, but rather in the
higherrate of progress exhibited by them
. But even this claim is
still a matter of vague intuition, and
will remain so until
historians of nonscientific ideas begin
re-writing history with a
view toward appraising the relative progr
ess and rationality of
competing researchtraditions in the human
ities.
There is one final aspect of the human
ities-sciences contrast
which requires comment. It is frequ
ently alleged that the
adoption of doctrines in the nonscience
s can only be a subjective
matter of taste and fashion. If one
becomes an empiricist, or
ideali st, or a trinitarian, or a socialist,
the decision (so itis
claimed) is entirely arbitrary. None
of the positions can be
“proven”’ true or false, and there are alway
s arguments pro and
con. As a piece of descriptive socia
l psychology, there is
doubtless much to be said for this
view. Many persons do
indeed see (and make) the choice betw
een competing ideologies
as an intrinsically nonrational affair. But
there is no reason in
principle why this need be the case. The
choice between atheism
and theism, between phenomenalism and reali
sm, betw
een
intuitionism and formalism, between
capitalism and socialism
(to cite only a few examples) could be
made by appraising the
relative progressiveness (and thereby
the relative rationality) of
these competing research traditions.
lf we could show (as |
suspe ct we can forall the pairs cited above
) that, at the moment,
one tradition has been a more progressiv
e problem solver than
its competitors, then we would havel
egitimate, rational grou nds
for preferring it. If and onlyif the comp
eting traditions emerged
from the analysis with equally progressiv
e evaluations would we
then be entitled to argue that the choic
e between them was
necessarily arbitrary and conventional.
The presumption that
the acceptance or rejection of ideologies
can never in principle be
rationally justified (a presumption at
the core of sociology of
knowledge) is, on this analysis, entirely
unfounded.
',
HISTORY OF IDEAS 193
|
195
HISTORY OF IDEAS
,
RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE 197
ee
RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE 201
aE
204 RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOG
Y OF KNOWLEDGE
help is an analysis of z's own intellectual
orientation. Z, and
like-minded types, are attempting to expla
= amcor nee,weedSitSORE, aye lage ate.
i
206 RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
are going to look askance on those episodes in the history
of
thought where (to use the language of Part One)
conceptual
problemsplay a majorrole in determining which theorie
s will be
acceptedorrejected. If a theory in the past has been
objected to
on the grounds ofits incompatibility with a certain
metaphysica]
or epistemological or theologicalbelief structure,
proponents of
this limited, empirical model of rationality will see
the episode as
intrinsically irrational, as one in which certain
ill-founded
prejudices were allowed to controvert the rationa
l judgments of
the agents in question. This, in turn, will lead
to the conclusion
that social factors must have had something to
do with the
outcome of the decision, for the rational canons
of preference
were seemingly ignored.
What vitiates this approach to history, of course,
is the
existence of other models of rational belief which
would makeit
perfectly reasonable, under certain circumstance
s, for factors of
a philosophical or theological kind to enter into
the rational
appraisalof a particular theory. Viewed through
the perspective
of such models, developments which might previously
have been
regarded as prejudiced, obscurantist and irrational
acquire a
rationallegitimacy, which obviates the need to look
to the social
milieu for an explanation of whatis going on. The
moral should
be clear: before we classify an episode as aration
al, before we
begin the search for social causes to explain the ‘‘deviat
ions”’
from the rational norm, we must be quite sure that
our notion of
rationality is an adequate one. To my knowledge,
few if any
sociologists have seen the force of this point, and their
work is
the worse for their failure to seeit. Unfortunatel
y, the error is
doubly confounded; in addition to their failure to recogn
ize that
there may be a broad spectrum of theories of rationa
lity, they
have also generally chosen to subscribe to that
model of
rationality which is the most limited ofall.
To see just how pervasive this error is, it may be useful
to look
at a few prominent examples. In his influential
Structure of
Scientific Revolutions, Thomas Kuhn considers
several of the
better-known “empiricist” models of scientific rationa
lity which
philosophers have espoused. He finds both the confir
mational
and the falsificational models inadequate, but goes
on from
there to enunciate his own model ofscientific rationa
lity. In its
RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE 207
a
208 RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
,
EDGE 209
RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWL
ble theory of
been written (and that, by using the best availa
must simpl y bide his time;
rationality), the cognitive sociologist
the aratio nality assum ption which
to do otherwise is to abrogate
sociol ogical though t. (Some thing
is at the heart of contemporary
ized by Mannh eim,' ® but his latter-
akin to this point was recogn
could do socio-
day disciples have tended to assume that one
blissfu l ignor ance of the ration al history of
logical history in
ideas!)
assumption has
We thus see that accepting the arationality
n ofpossible belief
three important consequences: (1) the domai
to those in which
situations for sociological analysis is restricted
incompatible
agents accept beliefs or weight problems in ways
t; (2) the sociologist
with what rational appraisals would sugges
of rationality
of knowledge must be able to show that the theory
what cases might
to which he subscribes (in order to determine
(3) the historical
be sociological) is the best available one;
episode he
sociologist of knowledge must show, for any given
ble of being expla ined in terms
wishes to explain, thatit is incapa
of rational, intellectual history.
socially ex-
In distinguishing between the rational and the
do not mean to sugges t that there is
plicable as I have, [
ration ality or nothi ng ration al about social
nothing social about
the revers e is the case. The flouri shing of
structures. Quite
inevitably upon
rational patterns of choice and belief depends
e of certai n social struct ures and social norms.
the pre-existenc
choice would be
(To take an extreme example, rational theory
ively suppressed
impossible in a society whose institutions effect
y, the efficient
the open discussion of alternative theories.) Equall
the system oftrial
functioning of most social institutions (e.g.,
such instit utions can,
by jury) presupposes that the agents within
more often than not, makerational decisions.
and “‘so-
But this continuous interpenetration of “rational”
to invoke the
cial” factors should not hinder our capacity
John Stuart Mill pointe d out more
arationality assumption. As
offeri ng any explan ation of some event or
than a century ago, in
to comple teness . To give a “full”
belief, we must not aspire
situat ion, S, would presu mably requir e a
explanation of any
have happened in
complete enumeration ofall the events which
are links in the
the universe prior to S, since all those events
210 RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
causal chain culminating in §. Rather than aspiring to such full
explanations, Mill argued that when we explain anysituation, S,
we should select from among the antecedents of S, those
particular circumstances, c, which seem to be most crucial
and
relevant to the occurrence of S. If we take Mill’s analysis
seriously (and a failure to do so would result in explanatory
anarchy) it provides grounds for avoiding that muddle-headed
eclecticism which argues thatintellectual and social factors can
never be usefully distinguished.
Following Mill’s lead, we can grant that certain social factors
may well be preconditions for rational belief and yet still
legitimately exclude those social factors from an explanation
of
a certain belief, provided we can show that the most crucial
and
relevant antecedent to the acceptance of the belief was a well-
founded reasoning process on the part of the believing agent. In
thus arguing (as the arationality assumption suggests) for the
priority of rational over social explanations for a belief—where
both are available—one is not implying that rational decision
making has no social dimensions; rather oneis stressing
that, in
those cases where agents have sound reasons for their beliefs,
those reasons are the most appropriate items to invoke in an
explanation of the beliefs which those reasons watrant.
’
heart is like a pump,” we know perfectly well that such a
statement must have been madeafter the invention of pumps,
and presumably after some detailed anatomical investigations
investigations of the circulatory system. It is simply not a
statement which a Greek of the third century B.c., nor a
Polynesian of the eighteenth century Could have made. At the
other extreme, certain beliefs (e.g., “2 + 2 = 4’’) tell us very
little indeed about either the time or the place where they first
emerged.
We might call beliefs which do carry their history with them,
contextual, for they do provide important clues as to the cultural
context which generated them. Other beliefs we might cail
non-contextual,'® Clearly, these two extremes are ideal cases; for
the working historian, almost every case will be a matter of
greater or lesser contextuality. (Even in the extreme case of
beliefs such as ‘‘2 + 2 = 4,” we can derive reliable conclusions
about certain intellectual characteristics of the cultures in which
such beliefs could arise.)
What is important here is not the distinction itself, but rather
what cognitive sociologists of knowledge seek to do with it.
Mannheim, for example, argues that a belief which is contextual
(in the sense just sketched above) is a belief which is “historically
and socially determined.’’ Given a sufficiently foose sense of
‘determination,’ this argument is doubtless sound, indeed
vacuously so. But Mannheim’s next step is to argue that any
contextual belief—that is, any belief which can be definitely
located in history—is thereby open to sociological analysis. If we
can pin a belief down to ‘‘a particular historical setting,” then
we have, Mannheim claims, presumptive evidence ‘‘of an ‘infil-
tration of the social position’ of the investigator into the results
of his study.’’?°
This argument is entirely specious, precisely because in
making it, Mannheim (like others who follow him) trades on an
equivocation between the ‘‘historical” and the “‘social.”’ If, for
instance, we encounter a statement such as “electricity is caused
by a fluid whose particles mutually repel one another,’’ anyone
familiar with the history of the physical sciences can readily date
it approximately and make somereliable conjectures about the
intellectual context in which the statement first arose. Similarly,
212 RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
———
a ee
Conclusion
Through much of this chapter, I have been highly critical of
much work, both theoretical and applied, in the sociology of
222 RATIONALITY AND SOCIOLOGY OF KNOWLEDGE
1
Of the many questions which this excursion has left unanswered,
at least two require further discussion:
1. even if we grant that the aim of science is problem solving,
and if we grant further that science has been effective at
such problem solving, we are entitled to ask whether an
inquiry system like science—with the techniques it has at
at its disposal—is the most effective possible mechanism
for the solution of problems:
2. we are also entitled to ask whether the investigation of
intellectual problems of the type science studies can be
justified, given the other compelling demands on our
limited mental, physical, and financial resources.
Definitive answers to these questions are not readily within
reach, but one can at least sketch in what directions we need to
move to answer them.
Muchhas beenwritten of the methods of science, yet with the
notable exception of pragmatists like Peirce and certain recent
“systems analysts,’’ no one has seriously investigated whether
the methods utilized by science are the most conducive to
generating solutions to problems. The preoccupationof classical
philosophers of science has been with showing that the methods
of science are efficient instruments for producing truth, high
probability, or ever closer approximations to the truth. In this
enterprise, they have failed dismally. What we now need to ask
223
924 EPILOGUE
Prologue
1. Rudolf Carnap, for instance, readily concedes his system of inductive
logic and his confirmation theory to be totally inadequate for dealing with the
more important episodes in the history of science: ‘‘For instance, we cannot
expect to apply inductive logic to Einstein’s general theory of relativity, to find
a numerical] value for the degree of confirmation of this theory. . . . The same
holds for the other steps in the revolutionary transformation of modern physics
. an application of inductive logic in these cases is out of the question”
(my italics; [1962], p. 243). Most other proponents of inductive theories of
rationality have madesimilar disclaimers about their models.
2. Carnap, again, finds himself being forced to the view that the degree of
confirmation (Carnap’s basic measurefor rational acceptability) of all universal
scientific theories is zero, which is precisely the confirmation they would haveif
they had never been confirmed at all! Carnap, in a classic piece of understate-
ment, agrees that this “result may seem surprising; it seems not in accord with
woe
the fact that scientists often say of a law that it is ‘well-confirmed’ .. .”:
([bid., p. 571.)
3. Whether these episodes are genuinely irrational or whether they only seem
to be is an issue to which I shali return in chapter seven.
4. See especially Kuhn (1962), and Feyerabend (1975).
S. For a detailed discussion of Kuhn's views on this question, see below,
pp. 148ff.
6. Cf. Lakatos (1968b), where he struggles valiantly to make the Popperian
theory of rationality germane, and to fit his own interesting ideas into a
Popperian context (where they do not really belong).
7. Although Hintikka has avoided some of the difficulties which Carnap
encountered, he, like Carnap, retains the view that degrees of confirmation are
generally language dependent. This failing is as troublesome and as counter-
intuitive as any of Carnap’s earlier results.
227
he
228 NOTES TO PAGES 11-21
Chapter1
1. The two apparent exceptions to this claim are Kuhn and Popper, who
both insist that their models of science are based on a problem solving
approach to scientific growth. Unfortunately, such overtures to problems are
only rhetorical. Popper never convincingly shows how the logic of problem
solving relates to any of the technical elements of his philosophy of science
(such as “‘falsifiability’’ or “‘empirica) content’’); Kuhn, for his part, denies that
“the ability to solve problemsis either the unique or an unequivocal basis for
paradigm [i.e., theory] choice’? (Kuhn [1962], p. 168). Both thus take away
with one hand whatthey give with the other.
2. This is not to claim, of course, that philosophers of science have ignored
the fact that science is empirical. But, as we shall see below, there are vast
differences between “explaining empirical data” and “solving empirical prob-
lems.’ Philosophers of science have said too much about the former and
virtually nothing about thelatter.
3. Cf. Oresme (1968), p. 244. ( I am grateful to Dr. A. G. Molland of the
E. R. Institute for this reference.) A fascinating account of some of the ‘‘non-
factual’ phenomena which have been treated as empirical problems by
, scientists is in Martin (1880).
! 4. There are other important technical differences between empirical prob-
lems and facts (such as that a theory always explains an infinite number of
factual propositions but only solves a finite number of problems) which will be
discussed later.
5. My category of unsolved empirical problems corresponds approximately
to Kuhn's notion of ‘“‘puzzle."’ It is important to stress that Kuhn's puzzle
solving view of science embraces nothing other than this class of unsolved
problems.
6. It should be emphasized that this conception of an anomaly is signifi-
cantly different from the conventional one. (See the next sections for a full
discussion of the details.)
7. Once solved by any theory, however, they generally remain as problems
which subsequent theories are expected to solve (at least until they can
convincingly be shown to be pseudo-problems).
8. A propos the problem of Brownian motion, John Conybeare—a contem-
porary of Brown’s—wrote: “I don’t believe a word on't . . . [Biot] states it to be
possible that solid bodies may be compared of [sic] systems of moving
moiecules, representing in small what the planetary systems do in large. I
would only add one supposition more; that these molecules are inhabited, and
have philosophers among their population who . . . believe they have developed
the system of the universe.” This quotation is taken from Mary Jo Nye’s
excellent history of the reception of Brownian motion (1972), pp. 21-22. For
further discussions of this episode, see Brush (1968).
9. See Vartanian (1957).
10. It is worth pointing out that Lakatos’ theory of ‘‘research programmes”
(for ail its stress on competition between theories) cannot explain cases such as
aS
NOTES TO PAGES 24-47
229
these because materialistic biology did not predic
t the polyp in advance of its
discovery, and thus (on his view) can take no credit for
being able to explain it.
(lL. See chapterfour below, especially pp.
125-27.
: 12. Cf. especially Duhem (1954), Neura
th (1935), and Quine (1953)
.
; 13. Especially Kuhn and Lakatos.
: 14. Popper has comecloseto grasping this
point, (b'), with his requirement
: that any acceptable new theory must be
able to explain everyt
hing which its
i predecessors and competitors can. Unfortunatel
y, however, Popper goes too
far, because in his adherence to (a),
he makes any loss in explanatory conten
i a fatal blow to any theory which exhibi t
ts it. By contrast, I am claiming that
: loss of explanatory content by virtue of a non-re the
futing anomaly counts against
a theory, but not necessarily decisively. For
a fuller criticism of Popper’s (and
Lakatos’) cumulative theory of science, see
below, pp. 147-50 and Laudan (1976b).
i 15. It is important to stress the converse
of this point: if a problem has not
been previously solved by any predecessor
of a theory, then it simply constitutes
an unsolved, not an anomalous, problem
for that theory (with the proviso that
at some fater point the problem may cease
to be a problemaltogether; in which
; case, of course, it would no longer be
anomalous).
16. Indeed, it would probably not be far
wrong to identify the histori cal
emergenceofa science from a proto-scientific state
as that point at whichall its
problems cease to be of the same weight.
17. Home (1972-73) shows convincingly
that Franklin’s treatment of the
Leyden jar effectively diverted attention
away from what had previously been
regardedas the central problems of electri
cal theory. (Cf. especially ibid., pp-
150-51.)
18. Cf. especially Kuhn (1962),
19. See Duhem (1954) and L. Laudan (1965S)
.
20. Many of these claims have been disput
ed by Griinbaum; see especially
(1960), (1969), and (1973).
21. The only way in which some T, which
was a member of the compl ex C
can remove a from among its class of anomalous
instances is by the develop-
ment of an alternative complex C’,
including T,, which can turn the anom-
alous a into a solved problem.
22. And in showing when it is rational to
preserve the entire complex and
ignore the anomaly.
Chapter 2
1. Fora criticism of Kuhn's views on this matter
, see below pp. 150-51, 73-75.
2. Karl Popper, for instance, has often
insisted that the use of metaphysical
or theological beliefs to criticize scientific theori
es is only of “sociologica l”
interest and is in no way germane to the
understanding of rational! evaluation.
In one of his most recent essays, for exampl
e, Popper writes: “the historical and
sociological fact that the theories of both
Copernicus and Darwin clashed with
religion is completely irrelevant for the
rational evaluation of the scientific
theories proposed by them” ({1975], p. 88).
Ina slightly different vein, Philip
he
230 NOTES TO PAGES 47.59
Chapter3
1. Cf. especially Shapere’s excellent critique (1964), and Masterman (1970).
The ambiguity of Kuhn’s analysis has been multiplied as a result of Kuhn’s
later retractions of many of the basic ideasof the first edition of his Structure
of
Scientific Revolutions (1962). Unable to follow the logic of his later changes of
mind, I have been forced to characterize Kuhn’s views in their original form.
2. For a criticism of Kuhn’s theory of “mature” science, see below pp.
150-51.
3. It should be stressed that Kuhn’s notion of “anomaly” is the traditional
one (anomaly=refuting instance) rather than the one I have sketched above,
pp. 26ff.
4. “If any and every failure to fit {the facts] were ground for theory rejection,
all theories ought to be rejectedat all times” (Kuhn [1962], p. 145).
5. As Kuhn originally put it: ‘there are losses as well as gains in scientific
revolutions” ([1962], p. 66). Kuhn, however, is not altogether consistent on
this issue (see below p. 237 n. 18).
6. Shapere (1964).
7. See especially Feyerabend (1970c).
8. Cf. the post-script to the secondedition of Kuhn’s (1962).
232 NOTES TO PAGES 76-83
how can Lakatos identify research programmes in their infancy, since that
identification depends upon specification of the contents of the hard core? (Cf.
note 18 above.)
31. For an illuminating analysis of the manner in which the core assump-
tions of a research tradition can undergo radical transformation, see Brown's
study (1969) of theories of the electric current in the early nineteenth century.
32. As Hull has cogently argued “no degree of similarity between earlier and
later stages” in the developmentof an historical ‘‘object’’ such as a research
tradition is necessary in order for it “to remain the same entity” ([1975},
p. 256).
33. Despite Lakatos’ contempt for the method of trial and error, his only
explanation for the emergence of the core of a research tradition is that it
results from ‘‘a long, preliminary process of trial and error’’ ({1970], p. 133n).
34. Indeed, if Forman (1971) is right, the abandonment of strict determin-
ism in modern quantum mechanics was prompted by the irreconcilability of
classical physics with the general world-view.
35. (1961), p. 191.
36. Schofield (1970).
37. See above, pp. 66-69.
38. Myanalysis here owes muchto discussions with Adolf Griinbaum.
39. I find it very difficult to pin down precisely what Kuhn’s views on this
issue actually are. Consider, for instance, the following remark: ‘Though the
historian can always find men—Priestley for instance—who were unreasonable
to resist [a new paradigm] for as long as they did, he will not find a point at
which resistance becomesillogical or unscientific.”” (Kuhn [1962], p. 158). The
first half of the passage suggests that there are criteria for determining
whether the acceptanceor rejection of a paradigm is rational; whereas thefinal
clause denies that there is any point at which that acceptance becomesrational
(assuming, as I think weare entitled to, that Kuhn is here using ‘‘unreason-
able,” “‘illogical,”’ and ‘unscientific’ as approximate synonyms). Butif there is
no point at which the acceptance (or rejection) of paradigm becomes reason-
able, how could we decide—as Kuhn has—that Priestley was ‘‘unreasonable”’
in rejecting Lavoisier’s paradigm?
40. Like Feyerabend, Kuhn recognizes that there is a context of pursuit and
denies that there are usually any rational grounds for pursuing a new theory
which has not yet been well confirmed: ‘‘the man who embraces a new
paradigm at an early stage must often do so in defiance of the evidence
provided by problem-solving [success] . . . A decision of that kind can only be
madeon faith’ (Kuhn [1962], p. 157; myitalics).
41. In a famous paper published in 1813, the Swedish chemist Berzelius
discussed many of the anomalies for Daltonian atomism. However, precisely
because ‘“‘it would be rash to conclude that we [atomists] shall not be able
hereafter to explain these apparent anomalies in a satisfactory manner”’
({1813], p. 450), Berzelius did not urge non-pursuit of the atomic theory even
though, within the context of acceptance, ‘‘the hypothesis of atoms can neither
be adopted nor considered as true” (Ibid.) Cf. also Berzelius (1815).
NOTES TO PAGES 114-127 235
42. See, for instance, A. Griinbaum (1973), pp. 715-25, 837-39; 1. Lakatos
(1970); E. Zahar (1973), especially 100ff.; K. Schaffner (1974), especially
78-79; and J. Leplin (1975), A thorough historical analysis of the evolution of
the notion of adhocness would probably show that the idea originated at a time
when scientists and philosophers believed: (1) that the constituent parts of a
theory could be tested in isolation; and (2) that only directly observable entities
could be legitimately postulated within a theory. Most philosophers and
scientists have now abandoned both (1) and (2), yet continueto believe that the
requirement of independent testability is still legitimate. Whether the con-
tinued demand for the latter makes any sense given the repudiation of the
simple-minded philosophy of science which originally motivated it is an open
question. [Grtinbaum’s 1976b appearedtoo late for meto discuss it here. —Au.]
43. See the writings of Lakatos and Griinbaum cited above, as well as the
relevant sections of Karl Popper (1959) and (1963).
44. Cf. Griinbaum (1973), p. 718. (Although this useful clarification is due
to Griinbaum, it does not represent his own approach to the problem.)
45. Cf. above pp. 40-44.
46. A fuller treatment of this problem is in L. Laudan (1976b).
47. Such a context—and comparison—dependent sense of ad hoc is dis-
cussed sympathetically in Griinbaum (1973).
48. Utilizing the machinery outlined above, pp. 66-69.
49. Zahar, for instance, speaks of a theory being ad hoc ‘“‘if it is obtained
from its predecessor through a modification of the auxiliary hypotheses which
does not accord with the spirit of the heuristic of the [research] programme”
({1973], p. 101; myitalics). On anotheroccasion, he suggests that a theory is ad
hocin this sense if it “destroys the organic unity of the whole nexus” (Ibid., p.
10S). Zahar may have clear criteria for these processes, but he never unpacks
what it would mean to be out of ‘accord’ with ‘‘the spirit of a programme’s
heuristic’ or to destroy its ‘‘organic unity.”” Schaffner is slightly more specific,
suggesting that theories can encounter “‘trans-empirical” difficulties such as
“complexity’’ or “theoretical discord’’; but until these notions are further
developed one cannot be sure whether Schaffner has in mind the samesort of
analysis for which I have argued here.
Chapter 4
1. For a discussion of some of the weaknesses in classical theories of
self-correction and truth-approximation, see L. Laudan (1973a). A devastating
critique of Popper's theory of verisimilitude is Griinbaum (1976c).
2. Maxwell has attempted to defend the view thatit is rational to seek a goal
(such as truth) ‘“‘even though we have no rational assurance whatsoever that the
aim will meet with success” ({1972], p. 151). It is just such an argument as this
which lies behind beliefs in immortality, the philosopher's stone and El
Dorado. It argues that quixotic quests are always rational until we can prove
them to be otherwise. Surely the burden of proof is precisely reversed; hunting
236 NOTES TO PAGES 129-146
the snark does not become rational just because we have not yet proved its
nonexistence!
3. Scheffler (1967), pp. 9-10.
4. Evidently in fear and trembling lest the incorporation of these evolving
standards into a model of rationality might deprive it of its supra-temporal
(“third-world”) status, they have deliberately repudiated the use of such
notions, taking refuge, rather,in what they imagine to be non-‘‘time-depen-
dent propertfies}"” (Zahar [1973], p. 242n.; see also Lakatos [1970], p. 137)
such as “‘mathematical coherence.’’ Leaving aside the dubious contention that
conceptions of mathematical coherence themselves have not evolved, one
wonders what point there is in maintaining that all the significant meta-level
characterizations of science have been static since the garden of Eden.
5S. This model thus allows us to have best of both worlds; we can
acknowledge that specific standards of rationality have evolved, without
surrendering our capacity to make normative judgments about the past. It is
not uncommon to find in the sociological literature a distinction (similar to the
one I have sketched) between rationality within a given context of belief and
what is frequently called ‘‘transcendent rationality” (See, for instance, Winch
{1964} and Lukes {1967].) What has not been suggested before, so far as I can
determine, is that there is a third, hybrid sense of rationality which allows us to
make transcendent judgments about the rationality of beliefs without ignoring
the crucial particularities of context.
6. “It is precisely the abandonment of critical discourse that marks the
transition to a science. . . [thereafter] critical discourse recurs only at moments
of crisis when the bases of the field are again in jeopardy” (Kuhn [1970], pp.
6-7).
7, Truesdell (1968), the well-known historian of eighteenth-century mechan-
ics, does his best to play down manyof these issues, particularly those which
are not mathematical in character. Costabel (1973) and Aiton (1972) give much
more sensitive accounts of some of the philosophical issues at stake in the
mechanicsof the Enlightenment.
8. Concerning ontology, cf. especially McGuire and Heimann (1971) and
Schofield (1970). On methodology, L. Laudan (1973b) and (1976). See also
above, pp. 57-61.
9. Cf. Kuhn (1962), p. 10.
10. Kuhn’s cynical view is that scientific revolutions are regarded as progres-
sive because the “‘victors’”’ write the history and they would hardly view their
own successes as anything but progressive. (Cf. especially his [1962], pp. 159ff.)
Here, as elsewhere, Kuhn slides too readily between political and cognitive
characterizations of science.
11. See below, pp. 147-50.
12. There are excellent summary discussions of the difficulties of the implicit
definition theory of meaning in Suppe (1974), pp. 199ff, and in Shapere (1966).
13. Kuhn (1970), p. 266.
14. If the theoretical assumptions are inconsistent with the theory under
analysis, then the problem will become a “pseudo-problem.”’
15. In making these determinations, we would have to restrict ourselves, of
NOTES TO PAGES 146-149 237
course, to those problems and anomalies capable of being expressed within the
framework of the research tradition under scrutiny and would have to ignore
rival and (by hypothesis) incommensurable research traditions. The possibility
of assessing these variables does depend upon translations being possible
between the theories that constitute a research tradition.
16. My approach to the problem of incommensurability resembles that of
Kordig (1971), insofar as we both argue that there are methodologicalcriteria
for theory comparison, even when substantive translation between different
theories is inappropriate. Kordig and I differ drastically, however, about what
these methodological criteria should be. Following Margenau, Kordigstresses a
comparison of theories with respect to their empirical confirmation, their
“extensibility,”’ their ‘‘multiple connection,” their simplicity and their ‘“‘causal-
ity”; unfortunately, most of these remain entirely intuitive notions in Kordig’s
discussion, and it is to be hoped that he will refine them into the sensitive
instruments of analysis needed for the comparative appraisal of theories.
17. The cogency of this argument does not rest on the acceptance of the
model outlined in this essay. Any model of rationality which offers a method of
determining an appraisal measure of scientific theories without inter-theoretic
translation can avoid the difficulties of incommensurability.
18. Here, as elsewhere, Kuhn is ambivalent. On the one hand, he stresses
the non-cumulative character of science by insisting that there are always
problem losses as well as gains in every case of paradigm replacement. (See
above, p. 231 n. 5.) Yet, on the other hand, he claims that: ‘‘A scientific
community will seldom or never embrace a new theory unless it solves all or
almost all the quantitative, numerical puzzles that have been treated by its
predecessor" ({1970}, p. 20).
19. Collingwood (1956), p. 329; my italics. Elsewhere, Collingwood reiter-
ates this claim: ‘Progress in science would consist in the supersession of one
theory by another which served both to explain all that the first theory
explained, and also to explain . . . ‘phenomena’ which the first ought to have
explained but could not. . . . Philosophy progresses in so far as one stageofits
developmentsolves the problems which defeatedit in the last, without losing its
hold on the solutions already achieved” ([1956], p. 332).
20. Popper (1963). As he puts it elsewhere: ‘“A new theory, however
revolutionary, must always be able to explain fully the success of its predeces-
sor. In all those cases in which its predecessor was successful, it must yield
results at least as good . . .”” ({1975]}, p. 83).
21. Cf. Lakatos (1970), p. 118.
22. Post (1971), p. 229. Cf. also Koertge (1973). Phenomenological theories
of progress, every bit as much as positivistic and idealistic ones, are committed
to the cumulativity postulate. For a detailed example, see Harris (1970),
especially pp. 352-69.
23. Cf. especially Kuhn (1962), p. 169.
24. This was pointed out, amongothers, by Berzelius (1815).
25. Home’s study (1972-73) makes it quite clear that Franklin realized this
failure of his theory, but did not regardit as sufficient grounds for rejecting it.
One might add that Franklin’s theory also failed to give any solution at al! for
238 NOTES TO PAGES 150-159
the fact—widely observed and explained before his time—that there was
generally a correlation between the density of a substance and its capacity to
act as an electrical conductor.
26. We can illustrate what is involved by an example. Suppose that our
scientific aim is to understand the embryology of birds. We have one theory,
T,, which offers a detailed account of the embryological developmentof eagles
and egrets. We have another, 7,, which explains the embryological develop-
ments of ali birds smaller than eagles, including egrets, but does not work for
eagies. In such a circumstance, we would certainly view T, as preferable to
(i.e., a progressive improvement on) T,, even if T, was not able to solve the
problem about embryonic development for eagles. Such a plausible judgment
would be disallowed on almost all the standard (cumulative) theories of
scientific progress. (For a fuller treatment of these issues, cf. L. Laudan
[1976b].)
27. For the relevant discussions see Lakatos (1970), pp. 137, 175-77, and
Kuhn (1962), pp. 11ff. and (1968).
28. Lakatos—at best—has shown how a programme could conceivably be
progressive, while ignoring many anomalies; but that is a far cry from the
stronger claim—required by his theory of mature science—that such anomaly-
ignoring programmesare ipso facto more progressive than programmes which
pay serious attention to their anomalies.
29. Given Lakatos’ (Kuhnian induced) aversion to anomalies, he would
probably have regarded this very feature of the dichotomy as a bonus. For those
of us who do not share his views on the irrelevance of anomalies and criticism,
however, such untestability must countas a serious liability.
30. It is worth pondering what motivates the search for a distinction between
immature and mature science. My guess is that the quest harkens back to the
old inductivist-positivist conviciton that “proper’’ science only began with
Galileo, Newton, and the other classic heroes of the seventeenth century.
Although eschewing inductivism, both Kuhn and Lakatos propose a demarca-
tion criterion between mature and immature science which resurrects the
inductivists’ search for a definite point in time at which science became
genuinely ‘‘scientific.” (For a lengthy illustration of a historian’s efforts to
write about the history of science by utilizing such a demarcation criterion, see
Gillispie’s whiggish [1960].)
Chapter 5
1. Agassi (1963).
2. Griinbaum (1963).
3. For a guide to muchofthis literature, see Suppe (1974).
4. With the exception of Lakatos who is committed to this thesis. (See
below, p. 165.)
5. Giere (1973).
6. Ibid., p. 292.
NOTES TO PAGES 159-169 239
7. Ibid., p. 293.
8. Ibid.
9. Ibid., p. 290.
10. Most philosophers of science ultimately do fall back on such a class of
“privileged intuitions’ about specific episodes as the final arbiter. Popper, for
instance, writes: “‘It is only from the consequences of mydefinition of empirical
science, and from the methodological decisions which depend upon this
definition, that the scientist will be able to see how far it conforms to his
intuitive idea of the goal of his endeavors’ (my italics; Popper [1959],
p. 55).
11. For a detailed exploration of those issues, see McMullin’s valuable
discussion (1970).
12. Cf. Lakatos’ claims that: (1) “All methodologies . . . can be criticised by
criticising the rational historical recontructions to which they lead" ({1971],
p. 109); (2) “A rationality theory. . . is to be rejectedif it is inconsistent with an
accepted ‘basic value judgment’ of the scientific élite’ ({1971], p. 110); (3)
“|. . better rational reconstructions . . . can always reconstruct more of actual
great science as rational” ({1971], p. 117); and, more explicitly, (4) ‘‘Thus
progress in the theory of rationality is marked... by the reconstruction of a
growing bulk of value-impregnated history as rational” ({1971}, p. 118).
13. Although Lakatostries to avoid this dilemma (saying that no theory of
rationality ‘“‘can or should explain ail history of science as rational” [1971], p.
118), it follows inevitably from his method of ranking theories of rationality
that the best such theory is that which ‘‘rationalizes” the largest part of the
history of science.
14. The bulk of this section is concerned with the role of norms in the history
of scientific ideas. The other main branch of the subject, the social history of
science, likewise utilizes normsof rationality, but in different ways than the
history of ideas. These issues are discussed below, pp. 184ff, 201 ff.
15. Agassi (1963).
16. For a candid voicing of such anxieties, see Cohen (1974).
17. The “ahistoricity” of these philosophers is pointed out by McMillin
(1970), Machamer (1973), McEvoy (1975), and Beckman (1971).
18. Although implicit in much of his work, this doctrine is most explicitly
formulated in Lakatos (1971). The method of rational reconstruction began
initially as philosophical technique for shedding light on the nature of rational
deliberation and decision making. In its original conception, it involved
postulating contrived and artificial cases of choice, which were deliberately
simplified in order to get a handle on the case; these over simplified cases were
then to be rendered more applicable to the actual situation by the gradual
addition of complicating factors.
19. Ibid., p. 91.
20. [bid., p. 106.
21. Similarly, Tornebohm claims, in his ‘‘rational reconstruction’ of seven-
teenth century astronomy, that “historical accidents [sic] which affected the
growth of this knowledge are not of interest . . . 1 will therefore take the
240 NOTES TO PAGES 169-176
Chapter 6
1. See especially the discussion of conceptual problems in chapter two.
2. Kuhn (1968), p. 8&1.
3. Ibid.
4. Kuhn’s beliefs about disciplinary autonomy are widely shared among
historians, of both the ‘‘old” inductivist and the ‘“‘new” socially oriented
school. For references to some of the relevant literature, see below, pp.
213-17.
5. Hodge’s study of the evolution of Lamarck’s ideas (1970-71) exhibits
vividly how important it is to attend to the problems a scientist is trying to
resolve. Hodge points out that a widespread misconstrual of Lamarck’s
problem situation has fed many historians to misinterpret the whole thrust of
his theoretical research. (For a similar analysis of Chambers’ work, cf. Hodge
[1972).)
6. Cf. especially Gilson (1951) and Popkin (1960).
amet, thalll
i
242 NOTES TO PAGES 179-201
Chapter 7
1. Although the bulk of this chapter will focus specifically on the sociology of
knowledge, most of its conclusions also apply, mutatis mutandis, to the
psycho-history of ideas.
2. For instance, unless a scientist believes in subatomic particles, he is
hardlylikely to join a laboratory doing research on the structure of the nucleus!
3. See, for instance, Scheler who asserts that ‘‘the sociological character of
all knowledge, all forms of thought, intuition and cognition is unquestion-
able” (Quoted in Merton [1949], p. 231).
4. A propos these two extremes, it is more than a little ironic that
Mannheim, who chastizes the “‘older’’ intellectual historians for making the a
priori assumption ‘‘that changes in ideas were to be understood on thelevel of
ideas’ ((1936], p. 268), is himself committed—in what can only be described
as an equally a priori fashion—to the view that virtually a// changes in ideas are
“boundup with social existence”’ (Ibid., p. 278).
5. Mannheim grappled with this problem (unsuccessfully) through most of
his career. On the one side, he wanted to insist that sociology had shown the
social origins of virtually all systems of belief, including sociology itself: “Once
we have familiarized ourselves with the conception that the ideologies of our
opponents are, after all, just the function of their position in the world, we
cannot refrain from concluding that our own ideas, too, are functions of a social
position” ({1952], p. 145). On the other hand, as Mannheim gradually
realized that such a view would vitiate the claims of sociology to possess
NOTES TO PAGES 201-209 243
objective validity (and perhaps under pressure from the arguments of Alfred
Weber), he began to argue that the thinkers—such as himself—were often
immune from social influences and he developed the notion of ‘‘the relatively
socially unattached intelligentsia’ (Ibid., pp. 252ff.). But if the intelligentsia
can transcend social determination, and if the history of ideas is mainly
concerned with the intelligentsia, what scope—even on Mannheim’s account—
is left to cognitive sociology?
6. Grtinwald (1934), p. 229.
7. For an articulation of this distinction, see especially Mannheim (1936),
chapterfive.
8. It may be, of course, that the acceptance of beliefs y and z is a function of
social factors, in which case we might say that the acceptance of x (rationally
dictated by y and z) is indirectly the result of the social situation. But this does
not controvert the claim that the most direct and most fundamental explana-
tion for the acceptance of x by some thinkeris that it follows rationally from
y and z,
9. Merton (1949), pp. 516, 558. For Mannheim’s formulation of this
assumption, cf. (1936), p. 267.
10. It is as true today as it was when Mannheim pointed it out in 1931, that
“the most important task of the sociology of knowledge . . . is to demonstrate its
[explanatory] capacity in actual research in the historico-social realm’ (Ibid.,
p. 306).
11. For a discussion of some of these conceptual problems see below pp.
217ff.
12. A point similar to this was made by Imre Lakatos when he wrote,
“internal history [of science] is primary, external history [of science] only
secondary, since the important problems of external history are defined by
internal history” ([1971], p. 105). What handicaps Lakatos’ analysis is a failure
to recognize the difference between cognitive and non-cognitive attempts to
deal with the history of science. Although we are entitled to say that the
“important problems” of cognitive sociology are, as it were, defined by the
rationa! history of science, it is manifestly untrue to believe that the ‘important
problems” of non-cognitive sociology are, to any significant degree, defined by
the so-called internal (or rational) history of science.
13. See, for instance, Kuhn’s remark quoted above p. 234 n. 40.
14. Richter (1973), p. 81; myitalics.
15. Ibid., p. 6.
16. Barber (1962).
17. Barber, for instance, speaks of Kelvin’s ‘‘blindness’’ in opposing
Maxwell’s theory of light because the latter was not sufficiently mechanistic
(Ibid., p. 540). One may, with the advantage of hindsight, quibble with
Kelvin’s search for mechanical models; but in the historical circumstance there
was nothing blind or irrational about Kelvin’s initial reaction to Maxwell's
work.
18. Mannheim effectively concedes this point in (1952), pp. 181f.
244 NOTES TO PAGES 211-216
SS
cient Ramwenmtasturthants [Wedeal
246 NOTES TO PAGE 221
247
:
248 BIBLIOGRAPHY
es
BIBLIOGRAPHY
251
Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 8, edited by R. Buck
and R.
Cohen, pp. 91ff, 1971.
Lakatos, I., and Zahar, E. “Why did Copernicus’ Research Program
Super-
cede Ptolemy's?” In The Copernican Achievement, edited by
R. Westman,
pp. 354ff. Berkeley, 1975.
Laudan, L. “Griinbaum on the ‘Duhemian Argument’.” Philosoph
y of Science
32 (1965): 295ff. (Reprinted in S. Harding, ed. Can Theories Be
Refuted?
Dordrecht, 1976.)
- “Thomas Reid and the Newtonian Turn of British Methodolo
gical
Thought.” In The Methodological Heritage of Newton, edited by
Butts and
Davis, pp. 103ff. Toronto, 1970.
. “C. S. Peirce and the Trivialization of the Self-Corrective Thesis.””
In
Foundations of Scientific Method in the 19th Century, edited
by R. Giere
and R. Westfall, pp. 275ff. Bloomington, 1973a.
- “G. L. Le Sage: a Case Study in the Interaction of Physics
and
Philosophy.” In Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science-IV
, edited
by P. Suppeset. al., pp. 429ff. Amsterdam, 1973b.
- “The Methodological Foundations of Mach’s Opposition to Atomism.”
In Space and Time, Matter and Motion, edited by P. Machamer
and R.
Turnbull, pp. 390ff. Columbus, 1976.
- “Two Dogmasof Methodology.” Philosophy of Science 43 (1976b).
- “The Sources of Modern Methodology.” In Logic, Methodology and
Philosophy of Science-V, edited by R. Butts and J. Hintikka, Dordrecht
,
1977.
Laudan, R. “Ideas and Institutions: the Case of the Geological
Society of
London.” Isis, forthcoming.
Leplin, J. “The Concept of an Ad Hoc Hypothesis.” Stud.
Hist. Phil. Sci. 5
(1975): 309-45.
Lukes, S. “Some Problems about Rationality.” Archives
Européenes de
Sociologie 8 (1967): 247ff.
McEvoy, J. “‘A ‘Revolutionary’ Philosophy of Science.” Philosoph
y of Science
42 (1975): 49ff.
McEvoy, J., and McGuire, J. “God and Nature: Priestley’s Way
of Rational
Dissent.” Hist. Stud. Phys. Sci. 5 (1975).
McGuire, J. “Atoms and the ‘Analogy of Nature’.”” Stud. Hist.
Phil. Sci. 1
(1970): 3¢f.
McGuire, J. E., and Heimann, P. “Newtonian Forces and Lockean
Powers.”
Hist. Stud. in Phys. Sci 3 (1971): 233¢€.
Machamer, P. “Feyerabend and Galileo.” Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci.
4 (1973): 1ff.
McKie, D., and Partington, J. ‘Historical Studies on the Phlogiston Theory,
LIV.” Annals of Science 2 (1937): 361ff; 3 (1938): 1ff and 337ff;
4 (1939):
113ff.
McMullin, E. “The History and Philosophy of Science: a Taxonomy
.” In
Historical and Philosophical Perspectives of Science, edited
by R. Stuewer,
p. 12ff. Minneapolis, 1970.
ants Lele Sen St Ahantn catoloy A LattatieadNitin o£ta
252 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Agassi, 156, 164, 168, 238, 239 Cantor, 230, 231, 233, 244
Aiton, 236 Carnap, 4, 47, 227
Ampeére, 84, 105 Carnot, 23, 90, 91, 92, 94
Aquinas, 97, 131 Chambers, 240
Aristotle, 1, 2, 25, 36, 51, 55, 58, 97, Charleton, 217
112, 131, 134, 160, 214 Clapeyron, 94
Arschloch, 245 Clarke, 63
Clasius, 23, 95
Bacon, 26, 59, 180, 185, 207, 224 Cohen, 239
Barber, 207-208, 243 Collingwood, 47, 121, 147-150, 177, 178,
Barrow, 144 183, 186, 237, 241
Beckman, 239 Comte, 231
Ben-David, 219, 245 Condorcet, 147
Bergson, 241 Conybeare, 228
Berkeley, 46, 135 Copernicus, 21, 46, 47, 55, 110, 112, 141,
Bernard, 58 218, 229, 230, 232
Bernoulli, 25, 99, 104, 135 Costabel, 236
Berzelius, 31, 234, 237 Cotes, 62, 231
Biot, 105, 228 Cramer, 21
Black, 83 Culotta, 231
Boerhaave, 83 Cuvier, 148, 149
Bohr, 71, 169, 182, 232
Boltzmann, 84 Dalton, 113, 117, 149, 234
Borelli, 83 Darwin, 2, 34, 46, 63, 75, 78, 97, 101,
Boring, 102, 103 117, 136, 137, 138, 141, 207, 218, 229,
Boscovich, 104, 135 231
Boyle, 41, 85, 180, 218, 219 Democritus, 182
Brewster, 19 Descartes, 25, 29, 34, 36, 47, 52, 58, 75,
Brongniart, 19 79, 80, 81, 85, 87, 88, 89, 91, 95, 97, 99,
Brooke, 230, 231 101, 103, 104, 105, 117, 127, 139, 144,
Brown, R., 19, 228 166, 176, 180, 218, 233, 240
Brown, T., 214-217, 233, 234, 244, 245 Dilthey, 183
Brush, 228 Duhem, 27, 40-44, 119, 147, 182, 229,
Buchdahl, 62, 230, 231 230, 231
Buffon, 231 Dujardin, 19
Butts, 230 Durkheim, 212, 213, 214, 244
255
256 INDEX
Faraday, 49, 50, 87, 99, 181, 230 Kant, 62, 135, 179
Feuerbach, 105 Kelvin, see Thomson
Feyerabend, 3, 4, 47, 66, 74, 110, 113, Kepler, 29, 35
141, 143, 148, 156, 168, 182, 227, 231, Knight, 231
234 Koertge, 232, 237
Fischer, 171 Kordig, 237
FitzGerald, 117 Koyré, 58, 59, 230
Forman, 214-217, 234, 244, 245 Kramers, 71
Foucalt, 241 Kuhn, 1, 3, 4, 37, 47, 66, 72-78, 96, 99,
Fourier, 105 100, 109, 110, 113, 133-136, 138, L4t~
Frank, 230 143, 145, 147, 148, 150, #51, 156, 171,
Franklin, 34, 90, 149, 229, 237 174, 175, 206, 207, 215-216, 227, 228-
Frege, 100 234, 236, 237, 238, 240, 243, 244, 245
Freud, 2, 46, 71, 78, 97
Lakatos, 4, 26, 47, 66, 72, 76-77, 78, 91,
Galen, 214, 218 95, 97, 99, 100, 113-115, 118, 129,
Galileo, 24, 25, 29, 33, 55, 58, 94, 112, 147-151, 155, 156, 163, 168-170, 191,
164, 218, 238 227, 228, 229, 232-240, 242, 243
Ghiselin, 231 Lamarck, 141, 218, 240
Giere, 158, 159, 238 Lambert, 60, 135
Gillispie, 238 La Mettrie, 21
Giison, 176, 240 Laudan, L. 229, 230, 231, 233, 235, 236,
Gorsseteste, 131 238, 242
Griinbaum, 26, 77, 114-115, 156, 229, Laudan, R., 231
232, 233, 234, 235, 238 Lavoisier, 24, 94, 234
Griinwald, 201, 243 Leibniz, 46, 61, 63, 64, 88, 89, 104, 27,
_
Quine, 27, 141, 182, 229 Zahar, 115, 118, 232, 235, 236
hoy 47987