Aichelburg - Einstein's Influence
Aichelburg - Einstein's Influence
Albert Einstein
His Influence on Physics, Philosophy and Politics
With Contributions by
Peter G. Bergmann, Hiroshi Ezawa, Walther Gerlach,
Banesh Hoffmann, Gerald Holton, BernulfKanitschneider,
Arthur I. Miller, Andre Mercier, Roger Penrose,
Nathan Rosen, Dennis W. Sciama,Joseph Weber,
Carl-Friedrich von Weizsacker,John A. Wheeler and
Wolfgang Yourgrau
DOI 10.1007/978-3-322-91080-6
v
Introduction
General relativity has led to completely new answers to the old problem
of the structure of the universe. The progress of relativistic cosmology, which
started with Einstein's "Kosmologischen Betrachtungen zur Allgemeinen
Relativitatstheorie", was hindered for several decades by the lack of ap-
propriate observational material. The discovery of the Hubble law in the
twenties led to the idea of an expanding universe which had its origin several
billion years ago in a big bang. It was only the discovery of the cosmic back-
ground radiation by Penzias and Wilson in 1965, however, which gave a
further and probably decisive hint to the reality of the hot and dense initial
phase of the universe. Dennis Sciama shows in his short introduction to
relativistic cosmology how the experimental data slowly led to a more
quantitative and exact history of the cosmic revolution.
It was already in 1920 that Einstein concluded from the field equations
of general relativiry that gravitational waves should exist, which propagate
with the velocity of light. At that time it seemed out of the question to
detect these waves experimentally. All known mechanisms for the generation
and discovery of gravitational waves led to effects which were too small to
be measured. Therefore the scientific community was very sceptical when
Joseph Weber began in 1950 first with theoretical considerations and later
with practical attempts to improve gravitational wave antennas. The decisive
improvement of the sensitiviry of these antennas, which is due to him, has
encouraged other scientists. Currently there are about twenty groups working
on the development and improvement of gravitational wave antennas. Weber
surveys the present state of the art in his paper and shows that quantitative
results may be expected within the next years.
An important source of gravitational waves is the gravitational collapse
of stars. Depending on the mass of a star this collapse can lead either to a
white dwarf, a neutron star or a black hole. While white dwarfs have been
known to astronomy for a long time, the discovery of neutron stars came
only in 1967. A research group at the University of Cambridge found periodic
radio signals at that time, which were emitted by stars. Theoretical con-
siderations showed that neutron stars were the only possible source of this
radiation. Thus the second of the three possible final states of the gravita-
tional collapse of a star had been found. The open and outstanding problem
was now to discover a third possible form, black holes. At first it was not
certain whether these singularities of space-time would actually be formed in
the collapse of realistic stars. Theoretical considerations by Stephen Hawking
and Roger Penrose showed however, that the complete annihilation of matter
in gravitational collapse can be expected not only in improbable idealized
cases, but as a general feature of the gravitational collapse of massive objects.
This result initiated the development of methods for the search for black
holes. The paper by Roger Penrose shows that several astronomical objects
are known today which are likely to contain black holes. It is unfortunate
that Einstein could not live to see this confirmation of the most daring con-
Introduction VII
***
Introduction IX
Peter G. Bergmann
Professor of Physics at Syracuse University, USA; born in Berlin, he emigrated to the
USA and became in 1936 assistant to Einstein at the Institute of Advanced Study in
Princeton; numerous articles on special and general relativity; first attempts to quantize
the gravitational field; author of the book "The Riddle of Gravitation"; President of the
International Society on General Relativity and Gravitation.
Hiroshi Ezawa
Professor of Physics at Gakusuin University, Japan; research on quantum field theory
and quantum statistics; author of the book "Who has seen the Atom?"
Walther Gerlach
Professor (Emeritus) for Physics, University of Munich, Bundesrepublik Deutschland;
essential contributions to experimental quantum theory (Stern-Gerlach experiment for
directional quantization); publications on radiation, spectroscopy, magnetism and history
of science.
Banesh Hoffmann
Professor for Mathematics, Queens College, New York, USA; co-worker of Einstein and
member of the Institute for Advanced Study; publications and research on relativity in
particular on the motion of matter in a gravitational field, quantum theory, applications
of tensor analysis to electrical engineering; author of a biography of Albert Einstein.
Gerald Holton
Professor of Physics and History of Science at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology,
USA; research in history of science and philosophy of science; author of "Thematic origins
of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein" and "The Scientific Imagination: Case Studies".
Contributing Authors XI
Bernulf Kanitscheider
Professor for Philosophy of Science at the University of GieBen, Bundesrepublik Deutsch-
land; studies on the concept of geometry and its meaning for physics; author of "Geo-
chronometrie und Wirklichkeit" and "Vom absoluten Raum zur dynamischen Geo-
metrie".
Arthur I. Miller
Assoc. Professor for Physics at Lovell University, USA; interdisciplinary research in the
history of 19th century science.
Andre Mercier
Professor (Emeritus) for Theoretical Physics, also Philosophy at the University of Bern,
Switzerland; research and numerous publications on mathematical methods of theo-
retical physics, theories on the origin of the earth, the concept of time, theory of knowl-
edge; author of the book "Analytical and Canonical Formalism in Physics" and others;
former Secretary-General of the International Society on General Relativity and Gravita-
tion.
Roger Penrose
F.R.S., Rouse Ball Professor for Mathematics, University of Oxford, England; formulated,
together with S. Hawking the first theorems on the existence of space-time singularities
in general relativity; research on black hole physics, techniques of differential topology
in relativity.
Nathan Rosen
Professor of Physics at the Israel Institute of Technology, Israel; colleague of Einstein's
at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton; research in relativity and unified field
theory, quantum theory, thermal diffusion, fundamental particle theory, gravitation and
cosmology.
Dennis W. Sciama
Fellow of All Souls College, Oxford, England; research in astrophysics, cosmology and
general relativity; author of several books e.g. "Modern Cosmology".
Joseph Weber
Professor of Physics at the University of Maryland, USA; he developed the first detectors
for gravitational waves; publications and research on relativity, microwave spectroscopy,
irreversibility; au thor of "General Relativity and Gravitational Waves".
XII Contributing Authors
John A. Wheeler
Professor in Physics at the University of Texas, Austin, USA; he worked many years in
Princeton and was in friendly contact with Einstein; during the Second World War Advicer
on atomic energy projects, co-worker on the Manhattan Project; creator of "Geometro-
dynamics" where matter is described as topological properties of space-time; decorated
with the Einstein Medal and several other awards; author of the books "Geometro-
dynamics", "Einstein's Vision", "Gravitation" and others.
Wolfgang Yourgrau
Professor of Physics at the University of Denver, USA; studied in Berlin with Schrodinger,
Einstein and v. Laue; research on quantum theory and the theory of measurement;
editor of "Foundations of Physics".
XIII
Contents
Peter G. Bergmann
Dennis W. Sciama
Cosmology . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .. 17
Joseph Weber
Gravitational Radiation 25
Roger Penrose
John A. Wheeler
Nathan Rosen
Hiroshi Ezawa
Arthur I. Miller
Gerald Holton
Bernulf Kanitscheider
Banesh Hoffmann
Andre Mercier
Walther Gerlach
John A. Wheeler
Wolfgang Yourgrau
The classical conceptions of space and time were sha?ed by Galilei and
Newton and represent an essential modification of the ideas of the Middle
Ages. The classical concept of space is that of the three-dimensional Eucli-
dean manifold to which the concepts of the straight line and the plane are
basic. I t is assumed that all points in Euclidean space are in principle equi-
valent, and this assumption includes the transition from the geocentric
model of the Middle Ages to the model of the universe in which earth, our
solar system, and even our galaxy are by no means a privileged center of the
universe but only objects of which one is convinced that there exist numerous
of a similar kind which are dispersed everywhere.
Likewise, time represents a one-dimensional manifold wherein no point
(= instant) stand out among the others. Specifically, an instant of the crea-
tion of the universe is ruled out.
A system of reference is a combination of space and time, in which the
concepts of rest and motion of material objects are well defined. A special
kind of systems of reference are inertial systems to which the principle of
inertia applies: a body isolated from all interactions with other physical
objects stays in its condition of rest or uniform motion. It is a physical
hypothesis to postulate such inertial systems, for all assumptions concern-
ing physical space and physical time are not postulates of pure mathematics
or geometry - they allow many other models - but those of physics, or
more generally, of natural science.
2 Peter G. Bergmann
P. Ehrenfest gave a survey of the ~ituation at that time (1912) in his inaugural address
in Leyden: "Zur Krise der Lichtiither-Hypothese" ("On the Crisis of the Light-ether
Hypotheses").
The Development of the Theory of Relativity 3
von
Die Grundhypothesen der '904-Arbeit sorgen daltir,
daB auch bei allen anderen Atherwinrlexperimenten
Prof. Dr. P. Ehrenfest immer wieder die Wirkung des Atherwindes vor dem
Experimentator verborgen bleibt.
Sie sehen: die '904-Arbeit von Loren tz zeigt
tinen ma,gllchen Auswe-g aus der Krise, in die die
Atlwrhypothese geraten war.
Aber niehl alle Physiker glaubten sich mit dieser
Lasung der Krist' zufrieden geben zu kannen.
Wir komm('n damit an die beiden Standpunkte
heran, die Einstein im Jahre 1905 und Ritz im
] ahre 1908 publizierten. Leider mussen wir uns ver..
sagen im Rahmen dieser Rede, eine Besprechung
dieser Standpunkte zu versurhen. Wir begnugen uns,
j ene Ztige in ihnen hervorzuheben, die ihre Stellung
Berlin
innerhalb der Atherkrise markieren.
Verlag von Julius Springer
Das negative Ergebnis aller Atherwind-Experi-
19I3
mente £Uhrt beide Autore!l zur Uberzpugung, daB es
uberhaupt keinen Ather gibt. Der Raum
zwischen den K6rpern sei leer. Die Elektronen der
Karper werfen einander durch diesen leeren Raum hin~
durch die eleklromagnetischen Impulse und das Licht
zu. Kurz. beide Autoren betonen. daB im Gegensatz
zur Athertheorie von Lorentz ihre Theorien wieder
an die Emissionstheorie von Newton anknupfen.
Fig, 1
Ether theory and relativity were compared in an elegant paper by P. Ehrenfest in 1912.
4 Peter G. Bergmann
would be the case if in systems of reference moving against the universe with
the speed v, all scales and all fixed objects were shortened at the rate of
VI - V2 /C 2 without changing their dimensions vertically to the directions of
motion. In other words, an inertial system of "absolute rest" should exist,
but all other inertial systems could not be distinguished from this privileged
system due to deformation of the measuring instruments which were also in
motion. There would be an apparent equivalence of all inertial systems not
corresponding, however, to the geometric-dynamic reality.
The young Albert Einstein was dissatisfied with this situation. In ac-
cordance with most other theoreticians he assumed that by means of obser-
vation no inertial system could be distinguished from all others and assumed
in addition (such as Poincare, whose works in this field were probably un-
known to Einstein) that the equivalence was of a basic nature and searched
for the physical consequences. In 1905 he published his paper "Zur Elektro-
dynamik bewegter Karper" ("On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies") in
which he postulated for the first time that two events taking place simultane-
ously in one inertial system, but at different places, neednot happen simul-
taneously in another inertial system. The reason for the "relativity of simul-
taneity" is that simultaneity can only be defined through the exchange of
signals and no signals can travel with a speed higher than c.
Thus it follows from the relativity of simultaneity that time intervals
depend on the inertial system in which they are measured and that spatial
relations are also modified. The new formula for two events connected by a
vector parallel to, the relative motion of two inertial systems is the Lorentz
transformation (as named by Einstein):
(2)
S'= 1 (S-vT).
jl-v 2 /c 2
As regards light signals, if the two events are the emission and the reception
of a light signal, the relation S = cT or S = - cT (depending whether the
signal moves in the direction v or in the opposite direction) implies the identi-
cal relation between S' and T'. Thus the speed of light is the same in both
systems of inertia and is independent of the direction of transmission.
Obviously, equations (1) and (2) cannot be "correct" despite the fact
that both systems are without logical contradiction within themselves. The
properties of "real" time and "real" space must be determined by means of
observations and experiments. All experiments which were conducted in the
second half of the 19th century in order to determine these questions ap-
proached the border of the experimentally feasible. As, for instance, the speed
of the earth around the sun is 30 km/sec, the ratio ofthis speed to the speed
The Development of the Theory of Relativity 5
of light is 1: 10,000 or 10- 4 . Since the square of these relations enters into
the Michelson-Morley experiment, the minimum accuracy of the experiment
must bei 10-8 or one part in a hundred million. This is one reason why parti-
cularly this experiment was repeated again and again and with ever more
refined methods of measurement. (See diagram on Ether-drift Experiments.)
Today the special theory of relativity based on equations (2) can be
tested by completely different methods. All particle accelerators which are
used today are based in their fundamental designs on the laws of special
relativity. They could not function if the old equations (1) represented
physical reality. The reason is that for the accelerated particles, electrons or
protons, the ratio vic is not extremely small as is the case with the speed of
earth, but is close to one, i. e. these particles nearly reach the speed of light.
One may conclude that the special theory of relativity gives rise to
a substantial revision of the concepts of space and time, which fuses space
and time even more intimately than classical physics did. However, special
relativity employs a number of principles of former conceptions. The most
essential is that among all imaginable systems of reference there is still one
privileged class, viz. inertial systems. to which the first of the three New-
tonian laws applies: in the absence of external forces a material body remains
unaccelerated. In Minkowski's space-time continuum the inertial systems
playa similar role as the cartesian co-ordinates do in Euclidean geometry.
Kennedy Thorndike
X Michelson X
@Miller
xMichelson
Morley XMorley
XJoos XMU-Grup
Miller
til
"E
c 10
XCedarholm et.a!.
XCialdea
X Is sak et.a!.
Fig. 2
The upper limit for the velocity of the earth with respect to the ether was measured
repeatedly between 1880 and 1970. Only the measurement by Miller, indicated by ® ,
lead to a positive result for the ether drift. This result was explained later by temperature
gradients in the laboratory (Diagramm by R. Mansouri)
6 Peter G. Bergmann
The general theory of relativity goes beyond the special one substanti-
ally. Whereas special relativity had its origin in the problems of electro-
magnetism and the transmission of electromagnetic waves, general relativity
is concerned with the field of gravitation. It is fundamental to gravitation
that the force exerted on a material body is proportional to its mass. In other
words, all material objects undergo the same acceleration under the influence
of a gravitational field. No other real field (of force) has this quality with the
exception of the so-called fields of inertia.
Fields of inertia or forces of inertia are accelerations with respect to
non-inertial systems of reference. Centrifugal forces or Coriolis forces are
typical forces of inertia. The normal explanation for the independence of
accelerations from the properties of affected bodies is that these are kine-
matic and not dynamic effects which disappear at the transition into an
inertial system.
Certainly there exist no systems of reference in which true gravitational
forces disapperar everywhere, i. e., in an extended space-time area. As far as
this is concerned fields of gravitation are different from fields of inertia.
There are, however, systems of reference, in which gravitational forces
disappear locally. In this respect Jules Verne was wrong when he had his
space travelers sense gravitation inside a projectile although their shell was on
a ballistic orbit. (The only force-free point he accepted between earth and
moon was one at which the gravitational forces of the two world bodies
cancelled.) Verne should have foreseen that his travelers around the world
were unable to sense gravitation because their shell was accelerated in the
same way as they themselves. In our time every astronaut and cosmonaut
attests this.
However, if one tries to extend such a free-falling system of reference,
one will not be successful in regions, the range of which is about the same as
the distance from the earth. One can observe the existence of a gravitational
field in such regions by means of tidal effects even if floating in space and
surrounded by impenetrable clouds so that one cannot practise optical
astronomy. Even then one cannot measure the gravitational field-strength
(local effects are not sufficient to determine an inertial system but only a
free falling system) but only its gradient, i.e., its spacetime change.
A number of alternative formulations of these properties of gravitation
exist. One formulation distinguishes between the inertial mass of a body,
relating the applied force and the resulting acceleration of a body on the one
hand, and its gravitational mass on the other, i.e. the strength by which it
attracts other bodies or is attracted. This formulation states that these two
kinds of mass are universally the same for all bodies. The equality of gravita-
tional and inertial mass has been examined again and again due to its univer-
sal importance and with an ever increasing degree of exactness. The most
The Development of the Theory of Relativity 7
recent determination was given by R. Dicke and confirms the validity of this
law with an accuracy of 10- 12 . It ranks among the most exact quantitative
confirmations of a law of nature carried out up to now.
Another formulation states that although the existence of a field of
gravitation can be determined through observation of the field gradient, it
is impossible to separate the relative contributions of the gravitational field
and the possible field of inertia. This formulation comes to the conclusion
that uniquely defined inertial systems (in which the field of intertia di-
sappears) exist only in the absence of gravitational fields. It is more difficult
to convert this definition into an exact experimental procedure than the first
one; however, it comes closer to the conceptual root of general relativity.
Both formulations describe a property of the field of gravity which is con-
sidered correct at present. It is called the principle of equivalence which was
well known to Newton but was not fused with the formulation of mechanics.
Newtonian physics prefers inertial systems as the privileged systems of
reference par excellence.
Already in his first paper Einstein indicated some possibilities for test-
ing general relativity experimentally. A consequence of the theory is that a
light ray is deflected from its straight course in a strong gravitational field.
This prediction was confirmed experimentally shortly after the First World
War. The results of the expedition conducted by Eddington made Einstein
a famous public figure although the accuracy of the experimental measure-
ment was only about 30 %. This accuracy was not improved on during the
following decades.
It was only around 1960 that improved methods of radar technology,
satellites, and atomic clocks opened up a new era of experimental accuracy
in the confirmations of general relativity.
j'oJectory of photon
Fig. 3
The geometry of space in the vincinity of the sun is represented here by a warped surface,
embedded into an Euclidean space. A light ray passing close to the sun is deflected and
delayed by the curvature of space.
10 Peter G. Bergmann
Red shift and time dilatation. A light ray rising in a gravitational field
loses energy and its frequency decreases. At first one tried to measure this
red shift by investigating the spectral lines of the sun and of white dwarfs.
But it was only the Mossbauer-Effect which brought the breakthrough in
1965: Pound and Snider were able to measure the red shift of spectral lines
in the earth's gravitational field. A relative frequency shift AlJ/lJ = 10- 15 was
confirmed with an experimental accuracy of roughly 1 %.
The red shift of spectral lines is closely connected with another pre-
diction of general relativity. It states that clocks are slow in the vicinity of
heavy masses such as the earth. The development of atomic clocks with an
accuracy of 10- 14 made a measurement of this effect feasible (Table 1).
Light deflection. The development of large scale radio-interferometers
led to improved measurement of light deflection. The observation of radio
waves emi tted by quasars or satellites has increased the limit of accuracy to
about 1 %.
Perihelion advance. One of the most important predictions of general
relativity is the advance of the point of a planet's orbit closest to the sun
(perihel). It was known even before general relativity that the planet mercury
shows a perihelion advance which cannot be explained by pertubations of its
orbit due to other planets.
Improved measurements of this effect were possible during recent
years. The exact positions of various planets were determined by reflecting
radar beams from planetary surfaces. With this technique the perihelion
advance of mercury was determined with an accuracy of better than 1 % and
agreement between theory and experiment was obtained.
The Shapiro experiment. In 1965 a new test of general relativity was
suggested by I. I. Shapiro. A radar beam emitted from the earth is reflected
by Venus. The echo is received on earth and the round-trip travel time is
measured. According to general relativity there is a time delay larger than
that predicted by Newtonian theory. There are two reasons for this time
2,95
2,75 -
( 29)
2,55
u Eddington Freund-
-0
0
U
2,35
Dyson
Davidson
lich /
Kluber
(51) Weighted Mean
!l>
2,15 \ Braun
III of Data
f(7) \
-
c
.c
1,95 --------f~8J __
III
..Cl
1,75
(71) " Bei Sbroeck
E -Campbell
.....J
Trumpler 'Einstein'S prediction
1,55
1
(11)
1,35
Fig. 4
The deflection of light was measured between 1919 and 1952 with an accuracy of about
20 % (Diagramms 4-7 adapted from a paper by J. P. Richard).
30279
Fig. 5
Earth The arrangement of radio antennas used for the
+ measurement of light deflection.
12 Peter G. Bergmann
1,1 t- -
r
I,D
t-- - - - c-- - - ,r - - -=± - - - -f-- --
0,9
0,8
I-
t- Seielstad
---v--'
I
Sramek Sramek Shapiro et al Sramek,
-
Hill Fomalon
0,7 I- -
Fig. 6
The results of radio-interferometer measurements of light deflection.
Experiment
Theory
1,1 o
0,9
f
Shapiro ,M6 ~7, M9
i
v
et al Others Anderson Sh~piro Anderson
(1974) (69-74) (1973) (1974) (1974) (1978)
Light Bending Time Deloy
Fig 7
Measurements of the delay of radio waves (Shapiro experiment). M and V denote Mariner
and Viking experiments resp ..
The Development of the Theory of Relativity 13
delay. Firstly, clocks are slow in the vicinity of the sun, so that the velocity
of light is decreased there. Furthermore, the path of the radar beam follows
the warped space in the vicinity of the sun and is delayed thereby.
Improvements of radar technology have made possible measurements of
this effect with an accuracy of about 0.15 %. Thus all classical tests of relati-
vity are confirmed today - after decades of uncertainty - with an accuracy
of about 1 %.
Cosmology
Dennis W. Sciama
Introduction
The second idea was by no means obvious, and this was to exploit the
non-Euclidean geometry of his theory by constructing a model in which
space at anyone time is finite but unbounded - the three-dimensional an-
alogue of the surface of a sphere. The topology of space as well as its geometry
was thus brought into the discussion.
The next major step was taken in 1922 by a Russian meteorologist
Alexander Friedmann [3]. He showed that by not insisting that the universe
be static one could construct a whole family of homogeneous and isotropic
models, with or without the cosmological term. These models would contain
systematic motions of expansion or contraction, and because of the symme-
try assumptions the relative velocity of recession or approach of two regions
would be simply proportional to the distance between the two regions con-
cerned (except at very large distances where extra relativistic effects would
come in e.g. because relative velocities approaching that of light would be
achieved). These non-static models of the universe were established two
years before the astronomers made the decisive observational discovery
that the spiral nebula in Andromeda lies outside the Milky Way system.
This was the first step in the discovery of the observational universe, and this
is the question which we must next discuss.
Many spiral nebulae had been observed already in the last century,
and a controversy developed amongst astronomers as to whether these
nebulae were members .of the Milky Way system or were extremal systems
or Milky Ways in their own right. By 1917 the velocities of several of these
nebulae along the line of sight had been measured by means of the Doppler
effect, and it was known that most of the nebulae were receding from the
sun and at much higher velocities than was usual for individual stars, meas-
ured in hundreds of kilometres per second rather than in tens. In 1924 Ed-
win Hubble [4] took his first decisive step when he showed definitely that
the spiral nebula in Andromeda lies outside the Milky Way. He and other
astronomers then set up a major programme of measuring the distances and
motions of the nebulae, or galaxies as they came to be called. He developed
the picture of the universe more or less as we have it today, with galaxies
occurring in groups and clusters of various sizes, our own Milky Way, for
example, belonging to the Local Group of ab'out 20 galaxies. On a large
scale, if one averages over, say, hundreds of galaxies, there appeared to be
no marked deviations from homogeneity and isotropy.
We begin to have formed here, then a possible picture of the whole
universe in which the ultimate building brick is perhaps a cluster of gal-
axies. But Hubble's most decisive contribution came with his discovery
of the systematic expansion of this system of galaxies. In 1929 he pro-
Cosmology 19
pounded for the first time the famous Hubble [5] law, that the velocity
of recession of a galaxy is proportional to its distance from us. This was
7 years after Friedmann's discovery of the uniform non-static models of
general relativity. The observational astronomers had at last caught up
with the theorists!
In the ensuing years both observation and theory were systematised,
and by the mid-thirties they came into a definite form which can be re-
garded as the ending of an epoch. In 1936 Hubble [6] published his book:
The Realm of the Nebulae, and in the same year H. P. Robertson [7] and
A. G. Walker [8] gave a systematic discussion of all the homogeneous and
isotropic models of general relativity. Those models without a cosmolog-
ical term in the field equations all began with a singular moment of infini-
te density a finite time ago. Some of them then expanded for ever, while
others eventually re-contracted into another singularity of infinite density.
The distinction between these two cases arises from the total amount of
matter and radiation in the universe, through the gravitational effect of
this material. The dividing-line between the two cases is given by a model
which just expands for ever but in which the rate of expansion tends to zero
as time goes on. This intermediate model was particularly recommended by
Einstein himself and by W. de Sitter [9] in a joint paper written in 1932,
and is now always referred to as the Einstein-de Sitter model. To this day,
we do not know whether the universe will in fact expand for ever.
(km/s)
10 4
Fig. 1
The Hubble law: The recession
velocity of Galaxies is proportional
to their distances from the earth.
(The conversion of apparent lu-
minosities into distances is based on
the value H = 1.6 . 10- 18 s -1 for the
Hubble constant.)
10 25
v(km)
Fig. 2
Penzias and Wilson in front of
the microwave antenna used for
their discovery of the cosmic
black body radiation. In 1978
they were awarded with the
Nobel prize for physics.
heavier elements out of lighter ones, and so perhaps accounting for the
distribution of elements we see today in the Milky Way. By 1965 this ar-
gument had been forgotten, mainly owing to the success of the alternative
theory in which the heavier elements are built out of the light ones in
supernova explosions.
This situation was rather ironic since the motivation behind this super-
nova picture was the steady-state theory with its abolition of the hot dense
phase of the universe. This theory has itself been made extremely implau-
sible by the discovery of the 3 K background. The point is that in the uni-
verse as it exists today any excess radiation could not be thermalised on the
time scale available. We need a denser universe for such thermalisation
to be possible. If we calculate the last possible moment during the evolution
of the universe at which the radiation could have been thermalised we find
that it is only 300 years after the big bang, when the universe was lOIS
times denser than it is today. Thus when we measure the spectrum of the
background to be thermal we are in effect observing directly the result of
processes which occurred in a universe at least 101~ times denser than the
present universe. Clearly the steady-state theory is ruled out by this argu-
ment.
22 Dennis W. Sciama
A second irony is that the supernova theory remains the most convinc-
ing explanation for the origin of the heavy elements, but not for the lightest,
namely helium and deuterium. It is now fairly certain that most of the
helium we observe today was made by nuclear reactions about 100 seconds
after the hot big bang when the temperature was 109 K. It is less certain,
but fairly likely, that most of the present deuterium was also made then.
This would be of particular interest because of observed abundance of
deuterium can, in the simplest form of the theory, be made in the early
universe only if its mean density is so low that the universe would be destined
to expand forever. However, this conclusion can be avoided by suitably com-
plicating the theory.
The final feature of the 3 K background which we want to mention is
its isotropy. Observations have shown that the temperature does not vary
with the direction of observation [16] (except for a small effect attributed
to the motion of the Earth through the background) by as much as 1 part in
3.000. This is by far the most accurate measurement ever made in cosmology,
and it tells us many things. Here we would mention only two. The first
is that on a large scale the universe must be highly homogeneous and iso-
tropic. Otherwise there would be gravitational effects on the background as
it propagates to us which would show up in an anisotropy of the tempera-
ture distribution. Thus the assumption of the homogeneity and isotropy
of the universe, which were originally introduced mainly to enable exact
solutions of Einstein's field equations to be obtained, now turn out to be
good representations of reality. Why the universe should be so symmetrical
remains a mystery.
The second consequence of the isotropy of the background is that we
can use it in conjunction with the Hawking-Penrose [17] singularity theorems
to show that according to classical (that is, non-quantum) general relativity,
the big bang origin of the universe really was singular. This means that
actually the theory itself has broken down at this early stage. We thus
reach a crisis for general relativity, but one determined not externally,
but by the theory itself. How this crisis will be resolved is unknown. The
least radical solution would be that in transcribing general relativity to make
it conform with quantum theory the singularity would be eliminated.
However, more radical measures may have to be taken. Since we do not yet
know how to quantise general relativity the matter remains unsettled.
Clearly the early universe presents us with a physical laboratory so extreme
that even the greatest theory of space time and gravitation so far devised
is not not able to cope with it. I am sure that Einstein in this centenary
year would have wanted this fact emphasised rather than the triumphs of
his great theory.
Cosmology 23
References
Gravitational Radiation~:-
] oseph Weber
Introduction
* Research supported in part by NASA Grant II NSG 7196-S 1 and in part by National
Science Foundation Grant PHY 77-14818
26 Joseph Weber
Figure 1
Triangle made of light rays in Euclidean (gravitation free) Space.
Figure 2
Triangle made of light rays in space curved by the gravitational
field of the sun.
Gravitational Radiation 27
A U A U
0;
u
0
0..
'"
E
0
VI
a
{j A (j A
1:-
Q)
E
0
'"
01
'0
'"
A (j A U
01
c
0
.c
u
~
0
c.
'" E
E '"
i-=~
Direction of propagation
(change of geometry at different places but same time)
Figure 3
Regions of space alternating from convex to concave in path
of gravitational wave.
28 Joseph Weber
Figure 4
University of Maryland kilohertz frequency gravitational radiation antenna.
30 Joseph Weber
Some years ago an antenna for gravitational ra- array Is a new set of windows for studying the
diation was proposed. 1 This consists of an elas- universe.
tic body which may become deformed by the dy- Search for gravitational radiation In the vicinity
namic derivatives of the gravitational potentials, of 1660 Hz. - A frequency In the vicinity of 1660
and its normal modes excited. Such an antenna Hz was selected because the dimensions are con-
measures, precisely, the Fourier transform of venient for a modest effort and because this fre-
certain components of the Riemann curvature ten- quency is swept through during emission in a
sor, averaged over Its volume. The theory has supernova collapse. It was expected that once
been developed rigorously, starting with Ein- the technology was refined, detectors could be
stein's field equations to deduce' equations of designed for search for radiation from sources
motion. Neither the linear approximation nor the with radio or optical emiSSion, such as the pul-
energy-flux relations are needed to describe sars. A knowledge of the expected frequency and
these experiments, but their use enables discus- Q of a source enormously increases the probabil-
sion in terms of more familiar quantities. All Ity of successful search.
aspects of the antenna response and slgnal-to- However, occasional signals were seen at 1660
noise ratio can be written In terms of the curva- Hz and small numbers of coincidences were ob-
ture tensor. The theory was verified experiment- served on detectors" • separated by a few kilo-
ally by developin~ a hl~h-frequency source' and meters. To explore these phenomena further,
producing and detecting dynamic gravitational larger detectors were developed. One of these II
fields In the laboratory. now operating at Argonne National Laboratory.
Several programs of research are being car- My definition of a coincidence is that the recti-
ried out. One employs laboratory masses In the fied outputs of two or more detectors cross a
frequency range 1-2 kHz.' Another Is concerned given threshold in the positive direction within a
with expected gravitational radiation from the specified time interval. For the present experi-
pulsars. 5 Some designs for such antennas sug- ments the time Interval was 0.44 sec. The mag-
gest a pulsar detection range approaching 1000 nitudes of the outputs at a coincident crossing en-
pc. A third class of antennas employs the quad- able computation of the probability that the coin-
rupole modes of the earth, 1 the moon, and plan- cidence was accidental. Observation of a number
ets' for the range 1 cycle/h to 1 cycle/min. This of coincidences with low probability of occurring
J._~~~-L~~~~ '.~~~~~~~-L
COINCIDENCE TIME MARK J -ARGONNE DETECTOR ___ __:.... _-,-_' __ -L~- .' L I' //
Figure 5
Gravitational Radiation 31
Search has been carried out using the antennas already described.
Since the expected signals are rare, and large local disturbances may occa-
sionally occur, it is necessary to search for coincidences of output for an-
tennas at two locations. Such investigations have been carried out. The
Maryland group. observed significant numbers of signals. A number of
other research groups found nothing. A group in Tokyo and a group in
Munich and Rome found smaller numbers of signals. These observations
are very controversial.
With improved sensitivity, it is hoped that there will be successful
detection of radiation from sources as far away as the Virgo cluster of
galaxies, by observatories throughout the world.
For very low frequencies, the earth and moon may be employed as
elastic solid antennas. The earth may have oscillations excited at a fre-
quency of one cycle every fifty-four minutes, and higher overtone frequen-
cies. The moon may have oscillations excited at a frequency of one cycle
every twenty minutes, and higher overtones. Einstein's general relativity
theory predicts that only certain overtones will be excited by gravitational
radiation. The Maryland group observed the surface acceleration of the
earth for a number of years, and also observed the surface acceleration of
the moon making use of equipment emplaced by the Apollo 17 astronauts.
These observations have thus far produced no evidence that either earth
or moon is excited by gravitational waves.
33
Black Holes
Roger Penrose
About 6,000 light years away, in the constellation of Cygnus the Swan,
lies the blue supergiant star HDE 226868. Its mass exceeds that of our
sun by a factor of about thirty, and its radius by a factor of nearly twenty-
five. This in itself is nothing especially unusual. Many other stars of a simi-
lar nature are known. But once every five and one-half days, HDE 226868
circles in orbit about an invisible companion. It is this mysterious compan-
ion which concerns us here - with a mass one-half that of HDE 226868
but utterly tiny, its radius apparently being only about fifty kilometres.
The companion of HDE 226868 is now believed by many astronomers to be
a black hole - a bizarre consequence of the physical laws embodied in
Einstein's theory of general relativity. The identification of the companion
of HDE 226868 as a black hole is not yet quite certain, but looks highly
probable at the present time.
There are other objects in the heavens which some astronomers claim
are likely also to be black holes and it may be that a final definitive judge-
ment on the existence of black holes could lie, instead, with one of these.
It is thought that black holes might lie at the centres of galaxies or of globu-
lar clusters of stars. There is quite good evidence for the existence of a vast
black hole perhaps 100,000,000 km in diameter, at the centre of M 87, a
galaxy ejecting a huge jet of luminous gas.
But however it comes, such a discovery would be aT: event of the utmost
importance to present-day physical theory. For theory predicts that black
holes should exist and should occur sometimes as the end-point of stellar
evolution. If black holes were not eventually found to exist then this would
point to some drastic revision necessary in the theory. On the other hand
their existence will also pose fundamental problems for theory and I shall
attempt to elucidate some of these later in this chapter.
attraction. At one time a material body was there. But the body collapsed
inwards under its own gravitational pull. The more the body concentrated
itself towards the centre the stronger became its gravitational field and the
less was the body able to stop itself from yet further collapse. At a certain
stage a point of no return was reached, and the body passed within its
'absolute event horizon'. I shall say more of this later, but for our present
purposes, it is the absolute event horizon which acts as the boundary surface
of the black hole. This surface is not material. It is merely a demarcation
line drawn in space separating an interior from an exterior region. The inte-
rior region - into which the body has fallen - is defined by the fact that no
matter, light, or signal of any kind can escape from it, while the exterior
region is where it is still possible for signals or material particles to escape
to the outside world. The matter while collapsed to form the black hole
has fallen deep inside to attain incredible densities, apparently even to be
crushed out of existence by reaching what is known as a 'space-time singu-
larity' - a place where physical laws, as presently understood, must cease
to apply.
One very puzzling question concerning black holes is the following:
how can a black hole exert gravitational attraction on other bodies when
its content is completely shielded from the outside world by the absolute
event horizon? How is it possible for the gravitational field of a collapsed
body to escape, when no information or signals can? The solution to the
problem is as follows: the gravitational field does not "escape" but corre-
sponds with that of the body before the collapse. When the body in the
centre is crushed in the course of a collapse, the outer gravitational field
cannot simply be cut off. In such a case a signal coming from the black
hole would be necessary in order to "give notice" to the gravitational field,
as to when the body disappears. The outer field indicates in no way at all
what is taking place in the interior. After the collapse of the body it is
more accurate to imagine the black hole as a stable configuration of the
gravitational field itself. The field makes no further use of the body that
produced it!
Since the black hole acts as a centre of attraction it can draw new
material towards it - which once inside can never escape. The material
thus swallowed contributes to the effective mass of the black hole. And
as its mass increases the black hole grows in size, its linear dimensions
being proportional to its mass. Its attractive power likewise increases, so
the alarming picture presents itself of an ever-increasing celestial vacuum
cleaner- a maelstrom in space which sweeps up all in its path. But things
are not quite so bad as this. We are saved by the very minuteness of black
holes - a fact which results from the smallness of the gravitational con-
stant.
Black Holes 35
Rotation
,
.
Cygnus X... (block hoi.)
, ....
' ....... I'
Rotation
Sun, drawn to
'am. Kal.- 0
Fig. 1
The gravitational field of the black hole distorts the supergiant star out
spherical shape and drags material from it.
To see this , let us return to our picture of HDE 226868 (Fig. 1). Ac-
cepting the most recent figures for the dimensions involved, we have a black
hole of some thirty miles in radius - in mutual orbit about a giant star
whose radius is over 300,000 times larger. Despite its small size, the gravita-
tional influence of the black hole is sufficient to distort the large star consid.-
erably out of spherical shape. It becomes rather like an egg whose small
end is somewhat pointed in the direction of the black hole. A certain amount
of material is dragged from this point and slowly falls inward to the black
hole. It does not fall straight in, however. The black hole behaves much like
a point mass. Most of the material dragged from the large star will remain
circulating about the black hole for a long time. Only gradually, as frictional
effects begin to play their part, will the material begin to spiral inwards.
Again we must bear in mind the small size of the hole. (Imagine having to
drain a normal-sized bath through a plughole a ten-thousandth of an inch
across - or a bath the size of Loch Lomond through a normal-sized plug-
hole!) The material can be only very slowly funnelled into the black hole.
And as it gets funnelled in it gets compressed and very hot - so hot that the
material must be expected to radiate light of very short wavelength, X-rays,
in fact. Such X-rays are actually observed coming from the vicinity of
HOE 226868 . And the source of these X-rays (referred to as Cygnus X-1)
appears , on the basis of detailed observations, to be in orbit about the visible
component HDE 226868 . The observed signals seem to be perfectly con-
sistent with the black-hole picture I have presented . However we should
remain cautious about drawing premature conclusions, as it is still conceiv-
able that some alternative explanation of the observations may eventually
36 Roger Penrose
Stellar Evolution
Many stars have masses considerably more than 1.5 times that of the sun.
What is going to happen to them?
The answer depends on just how heavy the star is. Consider a star of
twice the mass of the sun. Like the sun it will also expand to an enormous
size and then recontract, but being more massive than Chandrasekhar's
limit for a white dwarf it will be unable to settle down to final equilibrium
in the white dwa rf state. To picture what happens it will be useful to consi-
der the giant phase of a star more fully. As soon as the central density of the
star reaches that of a white dwarf, the outer layers of the star expand, and
they go on expanding as more and more of the central material gets com-
pressed into a white dwarf state. So the giant star develops a growing white
dwarf core. In the case of the sun, all the material that remains in the star
will eventually become part of this white dwarf. But if the star is too massive,
there comes a point at which the core effectively exceeds Chandrasekhar's
limit, whereupon it promptly collapses. In the process of collapse there is a
tremendous release of energy. much of which is in the form of neutrinos
which are absorbed (so it is believed) in the outer regions of the star, heating
the envelope to an enormous temperature. A cataclysmic explosion ensues -
a supernova explosion which blows off a considerable proportion of the
mass of the star. But especially interesting is the collapsed remnant of the
star left behind at the centre of the rapidly expanding cloud of ejected gases.
This core is much too compressed to form a white dwarf and it can only find
equilibrium as a neutron star.
A neutron star is tiny even by comparison with a white dwarf. A neu-
tron star rna \' be only I () kilometres in radius or only about one seven-hun-
dredth the radius of a white dwarf. The density of a neutron star could be
more than a hundred million times the already extraordinary density of a
white dwarf
A rna tehbox full of neutron star material would now weigh as much as
an asteroid a mile or so in diameter. The star's density would be comparable
with the density of the proton or neutron itself - in fact a neutron star
could in some ways be regarded as an over-sized atomic nucleus, the only
essential difference being that it is bound together by gravitation rather than
by nuclear forces. Individual awms have ceased to exist as such. The nuclei
are touching and form one continuous mass. What has happened is that the
stupendous gravitational forces have squeezed the electrons into the only
space available to them that already occupied by the protons, reversing
the usual reaction so that the star is now composed mainly of neutrons and
it is the Pauli Exclusion Principle acting on these neutrons that supplies the
effective forces preventing further collapse. This picture of a neutron star
was predicted theoretically by the Soviet physicist Lev Landau in 1932 and
the Swiss physicist F. Zwicky in 1934 and studied in detail by J. Robert
Oppenheimer, Robert Serber and George M. Volkoff in 1938 and 1939. For
years many astronomers doubted whether neutron stars could actually exist.
38 Roger Penrose
::::.::::
';f~~\W~
e"
Neutron
White Neutron Star
Dwarf Star
Sun
2501
t
0 100:1
~
0 700: 1 0+
{(~W:
,'"""
.
3.1 \
r-\
J
\'::',:,:,:: Bla~k
Hole
Red White
Giant ....... Dwarf
;~}1t~~(~:.
Fig. 2
The neutron star illustrated has the same mass as the sun but has a diameter 700 times
smaller than the earth.
Larger black holes are also possible, the radius of the hole being proportional
to the mass. For example, Cygnus X-I appears to be about 10 to 15 times
more massive than the sun, so its radius (assuming little rotation) is about
30 to 50 km.
The reason I emphasise the slight nature of this further contraction,
perhaps only 3 : 1, is that faced with the unsettling nature of the black holes,
people have naturally asked whether our physical theories are tenable under
these extreme conditions. But these theories seem to have worked well in de-
scribing a very large range of stars of enormously different sizes and densi-
ties. In any case, the conditions under which a black hole is formed are not
so extreme as all that- not necessarily more extreme than the situation
of a neutron star. For example, the densities involved as the collapsing star
crosses the absolute event horizon are not vastly different from those inside
a neutron star. The larger the collapsing mass, the less would be this density
- less in inverse proportion to the square of the mass. It has often been con-
sidered by astronomers that collections of mass of up to 100 million suns or
more might be involved in gravitational collapse in galactic centres and per-
haps the centre of M 87 is an example for such an object. The density at the
time such a huge mass crosses the event horizon might then be only about
that of water. So the local conditions need not be excessive when a black
hole is formed and there seems no reason to suppose that the black hole
condition might render general relativity somehow inapplicable. But also
other theories of gravitation (namely the Brans-Dicke-J ordan scalar-tensor
theory), lead to a black hole picture nearly identical to that arising in Ein-
40 Roger Penrose
light must himself be crossing the horizon by falling inwards into the hole.
To him the speed of the light hovering on the horizon is indeed the same
constant value, in the outward direction. It would be natural for a reader
who is not familiar with general relativity theory to find such a situation
confusing. This is partly because so far we have been using a purely spatial
description rather than a space-time one - and for many purposes a space-
time picture is more illuminating than a spatial one. Strictly speaking, a
space-time picture needs to be drawn in four dimensions, but an overall
description of the space-time situation can be obtained by suppressing one
of the spatial co-ordinates in the space-time diagram and substituting a
time co-ordinate. This gives an instantaneous picture of what is going on
at all times, and obviates the need for many sequential 'snapshots' of a
developing situation.
Consider a light flash emitted in all directions from a given point in
ordinary space (Fig. 3). The wave front of the flash would be a sphere
centred on the emitting point and growing larger each moment at the speed
of light. A purely spatial representation of the flash would be a sequence
of spheres (Fig. 3) each sphere larger than the preceding one, marking
(01 ''. t,
( )
I , Space
, I
I I
I
Spot.
Fig. 3
,, (a) propagation of light from
,
"- X in space at times t I
", and t2'
(b) propagation of light in
(bl space-time to give a 'ligh t
cone',
42 Roger Penrose
the position of the light flash's spherical wave front at a given moment in
time. A space-time representation of the light flash, however, would be a
cone whose vertex represents the time and place at which the light flash
is emitted, the cone itself describing the history of the light flash.
By the same token the history of a star's collapse down to a black hole
can best be depicted in a space-time representation (Fig. 4). The locations
of the light cones at various points in space-time show how light signals pro-
pagate in the gravitational field. At some points the light cones are drawn
as being tipped over, but this is not something that would be noticed by a
local observer. Such an observer would follow a path in space-time that pro-
ceeds into the interior of the light cone; his speed can never be greater than
the locally measured speed of light, and only inside the light cone is this
criterion met. But the tipping of the light cones does affect what an observer
at large distances can see. Fig.4 shows that material particles and light
signals which originate inside the event horizon are inevitably driven further
inwards. For a particle or signal to cross the event horizon from the inside
to the outside it would have to violate the condition mentioned above; it
would have to exceed the local light speed, which would be inconsistent
with relativity.
By taking a horizontal section through the space-time picture we get a
spatial representation of the situation as in Fig. 5. Perhaps the main advan-
tage of a spatial representation, apart from its greater familiarity, is that
one need not dispense with the third spatial dimension when it is important
not to do so. The light cones can be depicted as points (the origin of a light
flash) surrounded by sphere-like surfaces (the location of the light flash a
moment later) - except that when the light cone is tipped over, these sur-
faces do not actually surround the point of origin. In this later case it would
be necessary to exceed the local light speed in order to 'stay in the same
place'. A serious drawback with such spatial pictures, therefore, is that it
becomes hard to interpret situations of this kind. If a space-time description
is used, then it becomes easier to accept that i:he local physics is the same
whether or not the light cones are depicted as tipped over, the 'tipping'
being merely an aspect of the local description.
Although nothing can ever get out of a black hole, things can fall in.
Indeed, it is quite possible that stellar astronauts traversing the depths of
space in ages to come will run precisely this risk. Not that they will be
likely to encounter a black hole by accident - the smallness of black holes
compared with the vastness of the universe will see to that. Indeed, they
would have to seek out a black hole deliberately if they wished to expe-
rience this 'ultimate trip'. And what will happen to a hapless astronaut
who falls into a black hole? What, indeed is the fate of the original body
which collapsed to produce the black hole? Assuming that the exact spheri-
cal symmetry is maintained right down to the centre, the answer provided
by general relativity is an alarming one. According to the theory, the curva-
Black Holes 43
, «q9
~
~
~ ~
~ ~
~
~
~ ~
Empty space Empty SPQce
Fig. 4
TIme
Space-time representation
~pace ~
Collapsing
maUer ~ of collapse of a spherically
SpQce symmetrical body to form
a black hole, showing
propagation of light inside
~ and outside the event
------------ horizon.
'.
"
®
®
®
/' """0
Event Honzon
- , ,,
.... ®
I x
p 0 \
®
I
\
\
,, 0
)(
•
Singularity /
I
I
® ®
--- ""
"- ...... ./
Fig. 5
Light propagation inside and outside a non-rotating black hole.
44 Roger Penrose
ments could in principle be built to withstand such high tidal forces - all
that would be necessary would be to make them tiny enough.
Suppose our astronaut carries such a tiny, rugged instrument as he flies
towards a black hole of one solar mass. Long before he reaches the event
horizon he would be destroyed by the tidal forces, but his instrument can
survive intact as it crosses the event horizon, where it experiences tidal
forces at least thirty times those at the surface of the neutron star. As the
instrument falls in towards the centre, the mounting tidal forces will rise
rapidly, ripping to pieces in turn the material of the instrument, the mole-
cules of which this material is composed, the atoms which constitute these
molecules, the atomic nuclei, and finally the fundamental particles which a
moment ago had been the building-blocks of these nuclei. And the entire
process would not last more than a few thousandths of a second!
So anything falling into a black hole, whether it be a space ship, a hy-
drogen molecule, an electron, radio-waves or a beam of light can never
emerge again. So far as our universe is concerned it disappears completely
and forever into nothing. But how can this be? Is it not a basic law of
nature that matter or energy can never be completely destroyed but only
converted from one form into another? The question is a perfectly respect-
able one, but it can be shown by rigorous argument, based on general relativ-
ity, that there must be a region inside a black hole, a region of infinite
curvature, called a space-time singularity at which the known laws of physics
break down. So there is no known conservation law that can be relied on at
the centre of the black hole. Eventually, perhaps, laws of nature may be
formulated which govern the behaviour of space-time singularities, but no
such laws are known at present. General relativity, like virtually all viable
physical theories, is reversible in time. So corresponding to any solution of
the questions in which time runs one way, there must be another in which
the time-sense is reversed. This leads us to expect that the above situation
could - in principle .- exist in a time-reversed form. Initially there would be
the space-time singularity. Then matter would appear: elementary particles,
light. Only later would these particles collect together into atoms, molecules
or stars. In fact, a picture of this kind has been considered for many years as
a model of the creation of the universe.
The initial big bang of the cosmological models is, like the centre of a
black hole, also a space-time singularity, where the curvature of space-time
becomes infinite. But now, rather than being destroyed, matter is created
at the singularity. The cosmological big bang is not precisely the time-reverse
of a black hole, however, since the singularity is all-embracing, unlike the
relatively localised singularity inside the black hole. The basic difference is
one of size, and we may indeed envisage more localised 'little bangs', called
white holes, which are more precisely the time-reverses of black holes.
A number of theoreticians have considered such white holes seriously in
connection, in particular, with models for quasars. However, I must say that
46 Roger Penrose
I personally regard the possibility of the existence of white holes with consid-
erable unease - and disbelief! The reason is basically this. As soon as a black
hole is formed there is (within classical physics) no means of destroying it. It
is created violently, but then settles down and sits around forever - or until
the universe re-collapses at the end of time. Now a white hole - the time
reverse of a black hole - would have had to have been there since the begin-
ning of time - tamely and invisibly biding its time before making its presence
known to us. Then, when its moment arrives, it explodes into ordinary matter.
But this moment is of its 'own' choosing, governed, apparently, by no def-
inite law. As yet, there is no clearly understood and definitive theoretical
argument against white holes. But nevertheless, certain arguments can be
given to show that their presence would be totally at variance with certain
very desirable thermodynamic principles. In my opinion, we do not have to
take them seriously as actual objects in the universe. However, we are still
stuck with the big bang and that perhaps seems untidy. But here there
appears to be no way out.
But let us now return from these questions and pursue the argument
concerning black holes. Quite apart from the doubts I have already raised
about the validity of the general theory of relativity, there are other questions
that need to be settled before one can fully accept the theoretical concept of
the black hole as a realistic description of something that actually occurs in
nature. In the first place, can we be sure that enough is known about the
behaviour of matter under the extreme conditions required to form a black
hole for the predictions to carry conviction? What role does the assumption
of exact spherical sy~metry play in the discussion? Let us consider these
questions in turn.
As I have already pointed out, the densities involved in the formation
of a black hole need not be excessive. The same applies to space-time curva-
tures. Especially where black holes with a mass equal to several million solar
masses are concerned, an astronaut passing through the absolute event hori-
zon would notice nothing. He would have no means of telling that an irre-
trievable situation had developed, because the exact location of the horizon
is not something that can be discerned by local measurement. After this
he would have but a few hours to enjoy the experience of life inside a black
hole before the tidal effects mounted to infinity.
Asymmetrical Collapse
are slight, we should have every reason to expect that near the central point
these asymmetries would be enormously magnified. Might not the different
portions of the collapsing body miss one another? Perhaps they could re-
emerge after a close encounter and bounce out again. It is fortunate that,
owing to some general theorems that have been proved over the past several
years, a remarkably complete picture of asymmetrical collapse has emerged.
Considering the picture in a little detail, suppose that a massive star or
a collection of bodies collapses and that deviations from the spherical sym-
metry are at first comparatively small. We can establish that a point of no
return has been passed if a certain criterion is satisfied. Imagine that a flash
of light is emitted at some instant at some point in space. The flash of light
will follow the light cone centred on the point according to our space-time
representation (Fig. 6). The light rays start out from the point by diverging
in all directions. When they pass through matter or through a gravitational
field, the matter or the field has a focusing effect on the rays. If enough
matter or a sufficiently strong gravitational field is encountered, the amount
that the rays diverge can be reduced to such an extent that this divergence
is actually reversed, that is, the rays start to converge. The required criterion
Singularity
,Tim~
Fig. 6
IL;:ace The birth of a black hole.
Space
48 Roger Penrose
for a point of no return is that every light ray from the space time point
encounter enough matter or gravitation for the light cone to be reconverged.
It is not hard to show from simple order-of-magnitude estimates that, for
sufficiently large collections of mass, the criterion can indeed be satisfied
before densities or curvatures became excessive, and without any assump-
tion of symmetry. Once this criterion has been satisfied, then according
to a precise theorem in general relativity put forward by Stephen Hawking
and myself, it follows that there must be a space time singularity somewhere.
The theorem does not say that this singularity is necessarily of the same
character as that encountered in the centre of a spherically symmetrical
black hole, but it is hard to avoid the inference that tidal effects which ap-
proach infinity will occur, producing a region of space-time where infinitely
strong gravitational forces literally squeeze matter and photons out of
existence.
Physicists are unhappy with a theory that predicts the evolution of such
a truly physical singular state. In the past whenever a singularity was en-
countered in a theory, it was generally a warning that the theory in its pres-
ent form was breaking down and new theoretical tools were needed. In the
case of black holes we theoreticians are again being presented with a situa-
tion of this kind, but one more serious than before, because here the singu-
larity refers to the very structure of space and time.
There are two distinct possibilities at this stage. It may be that the
resulting singularity is such that signals can escape from it which can be
observed at large distances. Such a singularity is called 'naked'. The possi-
bility of naked singularities is alarming because the physical effects of
near-infinite space time curvatures are quite unknown. If these effects can
influence the outside world, then an essential uncertainty is introduced
into present physical theory.
On the other hand it is possible that the singularities resulting from
gravitational collapse are always hidden from view, as was the case in the
spherically symmetrical situation considered above. This is the hypothesis
of 'Cosmic Censorship', according to which naked singularities are for-
bidden, each singularity being necessarily clothed by an absolute event
horizon. There is perhaps some slight theoretical evidence in favour of
Cosmic Censorship, but it is only rather slight. However, it would be in-
accurate to think of the big bang as a violation of Cosmic Censorship. We
are concerned here only with singularities which arise in the collapse of per-
fectly reasonable non-singular matter. I would certainly tend to believe
that in situations which do not differ too much initially from that of spheri-
cal symmetry, the Cosmic Censorship principle is valid. In more extreme
cases the question is much more open. My own opinion has come round to
the view that Cosmic Censorship is likely always to be valid (in situations of
classical relativity).
Black Holes 49
Let us now consider the situation inside the black hole, and the general
relativistic implication of the existence of a space-time singularity. Since a
'singularity' means a region of breakdown of physical theory, we have the
curious situation that, here, general relativity is predicting its own downfall!
But perhaps we should not be too surprised at this; after all we are treating
general relativity only in its capacity as a classical theory. When the curva-
ture of space time becomes enormous, quantum effects must eventually
playa dominant role. When the radius of space-time curvature becomes as
small, as say, (10- 15 ) m (roughly the radius of an elementary particle) then
the theory of particle physics as understood at present, must break down.
If the radius of space-time curvature ever becomes as small as (10- 35 ) m
(and the implications of what we have said so far are that it will be that
small somewhere inside a black hole - unless theory breaks down before
this), then we cannot avoid having to apply quantum mechanics to the
structure of space-time itself. At present there is no satisfactory theory for
doing this. And if Cosmic Censorship holds true, the absolute event horizon
would prevent the effects of quantum physics in the centres of black holes
having any influence on the outside world.
But one of the most important theoretical developments of the past
several years has shown that our previous considerations do not hold com-
pletely true. With very tiny black holes, whose Schwarzschild radius is approxi-
mately 10- 15 m (the radius of an elementary particle) quantum effects be-
come important, which lead to a destruction of the black hole in a big explo-
sion. This is the discovery by Stephen Hawking, following some results of
Jacob Bekenstein, that if quantum effects are taken into account, a black
hole should continually radiate a certain amount of energy. For any of the
holes that could be expected to arise in astrophysical processes, such as in
Stellar collapse, this effect is utterly minute and does not affect the previous
classical discussion. But it is just conceivable that very tiny holes (of, say,
the diameter of an elementary particle) might have been produced in a
highly chaotic big bang. For such holes the radiation would be very large
and would increase in intensity as the hole loses its mass-energy in radia-
tion. The final explosion of such a mini hole could be detectable here on
earth. However, the observational evidence is such as to indicate that mini-
holes, if they exist at all, must be very infrequent indeed (and there are also
some theoretical arguments against them). Nevertheless, the theoretical
implications of Hawking's result are very considerable, as they suggest
hitherto unsuspected interrelations between general relativity, thermodynam-
ics and quantum field theory.
51
Wheeler: Then I'm sure you'll rejOICe in the theorems of today that a
sufficiently massive collection of cold matter has no escape from
gravitational collapse.
Einstein: Of course it is much simpler to stay away from all special assump-
tions about the relation between density and pressure. That is why
in my 1939 paper [3] I considered a collection of well separated
point masses in orbit about their mutual center of gravitation.
One discovers that the cluster of mutually gravitating particles is
unstable.
Wheeler: Stimulating that was to us all as a beginning. The future will surely
see that work continued from the initial stages of instability to the
final stages of collapse. But did you never feel an urgency about
an extension of these ideas to real stars and an astrophysical search
for real black holes?
Einstein: Yes, that is an interesting point. But, no, for me that was an un-
important question of detail. One has only to apply the general
relativity theory itself to come to some somewhat reliable conclu-
sions about collapse.
Wheeler: How do you feel about Kerr's exact solution for the geometry
around a rotating black hole, consequences of Kerr's and Schild's
early mathematical investigations of algebraically special solutions
of your gravitational field equation?
Einstein: That is really beautiful! I would never have dared to hope for an
exact and simple solution of a problem so difficult.
Wheeler: And how do you react to the work of Carter [4,5] and others?
Einstein: How wonderful it is that they can show that the geometry around
a collapsing object, no matter how contorted and asymmetric and
violently fluctuating it is, in the end always tends smoothly to an
absolutely standard final state depending only on the mass and
electric charge and angular momentum of the black hole. Of course,
that is outside. But, after all, the critical place is inside. That's
where the predicted singularity is. That's where the problem is.
It is impossible to believe a prediction that is a singularity.
Wheeler: I and my colleagues have to confess that we have made only a bare
beginning at studying the approach to singularity both in cosmolo-
gy and in black hole physics.
Einstein: To understand that approach is really important.
Wheeler: Our Soviet colleagues propose fascinating physical insights as to
what goes on in the final stages of collapse, but not convincing
mathematical methodology. Colleagues in the West have the
mathematical methodology but so far it has not sufficed to pro-
vide the insight that we all want.
Einstein: This is an old story in physics. We know in the end everything
comes together in a new and better and larger unity.
The Black Hole: An Imaginary Conversation with Albert Einstein 53
Wheeler: Gamow says that you called it "the greatest blunder of my life" [6).
The 1929 observation of Hubble [7) revealed that you need not
have added an artificial "cosmological term" to your standard
1915 general relativity theory to secure a reasonable account of
cosmology. Also it was Friedmann [8), not you, who in 1922 first
worked out that even today standard and simple cosmology
from your field equation. I and many colleagues want to ask
you how this came about. Was it because [9] you had taken
very seriously in your younger days the idea of Spinoza that the
universe endures from everlasting to everlasting [1O]? Did any
contrary conclusion seem to you philosophically unreasonable? In
your autobiographical notes [11] you speak of the influence of
Spinoza on your outlook. It has been said that "Spinoza rejected
the idea of an external Creator suddenly and apparently capri-
ciously creating the world at one particular time rather than
another and creating it out of nothing." [10] Do you feel that
Spinoza indeed so powerfully influenced what you did and did not
do in the field of cosmology?
Einstein: That is very hard to say. Even today we do not know the right
way to think about these questions.
Wheeler: Do you envisage a "before" before the big bang and an "after"
after the big crunch?
Einstein: One can hold many views on these questions and they all deserve
consideration.
Wheeler: This is an exciting time in astrophysics. Some colleagues are in-
clined to believe that the universe contains less than a tenth of
the mass energy that would be required to curve it up into closure.
Others, following the lead of other evidence, find indications that
the amount of mass energy may be close to what you predicted.
What is your view on the question whether the universe is closed?
Einstein: "[We] may present the following arguments against the concep-
tion of a space-infinite, and for the conception of a space-bounded,
universe: (1) From the standpoint of the theory of relativity, the
condition for a closed surface is very much simpler than the cor-
responding boundary condition at infinity of the quasi-Euclidean
structure of the universe. (2) The idea that Mach expressed, that
inertia depends upon the mutual action of bodies, is contained,
to a first approximation, in the equations of the theory of rela-
tivity; ... But this idea of Mach's corresponds only to a finite
universe, bounded in space, and not to a quasi-Euclidean infinite
universe." [12] "In my opinion the general theory of relativity
can only solve this problem [of inertia] satisfactorily if it regards
the world as spatially self-enclosed." [13]
54 John A. Wheeler
Wheeler: I don't have to tell you that there is still a non-negligible body
of our colleagues who think that an asymptotically flat universe
is more natural than a closed universe.
Einstein: But that view takes the geometry of faraway space out of physics
and makes it pan of theology, to be discovered by reading Euclid's
bible. It puts us back to the days before Riemann, days when
space was still for physicists, "a rigid homogeneous something,
susceptible of no change or conditions. Only the genius of Rie-
mann, solitary and uncomprehended, had already won its way
by the middle of the last century to a new conception of space,
in which space was deprived of its rigidity, and in which its power
to take part in physical events was recognized as possible. " [14]
Wheeler: Space, a new participant in dynamics - that's what you gave us
in your equations! Elie Canan recognized that your geometro-
dynamics requires initial value data just as does any other dynam-
ics [15, 16]. How did you react to his investigations?
Einstein: Yes, Cartan saw into the mathematics deeper than anyone. Yes,
I recognized the importance of his work. Yes, I told Helen Dukas,
"Don't file Cartan's papers away as you do other papers; keep
them out separate so I can study them." Canan understood
things more clearly than anyone.
Still there are two sides to the initial value problem. One is their
consequences. They we know in a general way how to calculate.
The other is their origin. We still have not the faintest idea of
what considerations fix the initial conditions. Your Peebles at
Princeton and his colleagues [17] have studied the initial condi-
tions for cosmology more fully than anyone. They show that
things in the beginning were not quite so arbitrary as one might
have thought. They also find indications that the density is of
the same order as what the general theory predicts. That result
seems to me a natural one.
Wheeler: Do you then feel that gravitational collapse of the universe is
similar in principle to gravitational collapse of a star to a black
hole?
Einstein: To think of both processes as equally inescapable is reasonable.
I confess it was a surprise to me about the big bang. But once
we have to accept that, it seems to me only consistent that we
should also accept gravitational collapse, both for stars and for
the universe. Yes, that is quite contrary to the idea that Spinoza
taught that the universe goes on forever. You mentioned his argu-
ment against an original creation. How could nothingness, depriv-
ed of all possibility of knowing time, know when to give birth
to the universe? How are we to answer this objection today?
The Black Hole: An Imaginary Conversation with Albert Einstein 55
References
[1] Weber, R. L., "A Random Walk in Science", (Institute of Physics, London) 1973
p. 14. I.B. Cohen -+ S. Gouldsmit -+ N. Bohr.
[2] Einstein, A, As quoted in B. Hoffmann, "Albert Einstein: Creator and Rebel",
(Viking, New York) 1972. p. 24.
[3] Einstein, A, "On a stationary system with spherical symmetry consisting of many
gravitating masses", Ann. Math. (USA) 40, 922-936 (1939).
[4] Carter, B., "An axisymmetric black hole has only two degrees of freedom", Phys.
Rev. Lett. 26,331 333. (1970).
[5] Carter, B., "Properties of the Kerr metric", in "Black Holes", Proceedings of 1972
sessions of Ecole d'ete de physique theorique, C. De Witt and B. S. De Witt, eds.,
(Gordon and Breach, New York) 1973.
[6] Gamow, G., "My World Line" (Viking Press, New York) 1970.
[7] Hubble, E. P., "A relation between distance and radial velocity among extragalactic
nebulae." Proc. Nat. Acad. Sci. U.S. 15, 169-173 (1929).
[8] Friedmann. A, "Uber die Kriimmung des Raumes." Z. Phys. 10, 377-386.
[9] The importance of Spinoza's philosophy for Einstein's outlook was kindly emphas-
ized to me by Hans Kung at Tiibingen 12 June 1978.
56 John A. Wheeler
[10] Wolf, A., "Spinoza", "Encyclopedia Britanica", Chicago, 1956, Vo!' 21, p. 235.
[11] Schilpp, P. A., ed. "Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist", (Library of Living Phil-
osophers, Evanston, Ill.) 1949.
[12] Einstein, A., "The Meaning of Relativity", 3rd edition, (Princeton University Press,
Princeton, N.].) 1950. pp. 107-108.
[13] Einstein, A., "Essays in Science", (Philosophical Library, New York) 1934. Trans-
lated from "Mein Weltbild", (Querido Verlag, Amsterdam) 1933. p. 55.
[14] ibid. p. 68.
[15] Cartan, E., "Sur les equations de la gravitation de Einstein", ]. Math. Pures App!. 1,
141-203 (1922).
[16] Cartan, E., "La theorie des groupes et les recherches recentes de geometrie differen-
tielle", "Conference Proceedings International Congress of Mathematicians", To-
ronto, (1924) L'Enseign. math. t. 24, 1-18 (1925).
[17] Davis, M., E. J. Groth und P. J. E. Peebles, "Study of galaxy correlations: Evidence
for the gravitational instability picture in a dense universe", Astrphys. ]. 212:
Ll07-Ll11 (1977).
[18] Einstein, A., "Essays in Science", (Philosophical Library, New York) 1934. Trans-
lated from "Mein Weltbild", (querido Verlag, Amsterdam) 1933. p. 114.
57
Introduction
In 1935 there appeared a paper with the above title (Einstein, Podolsky
and Rosen 1935) in The Physical Review. This paper was the outgrowth of a
number of discussions held by Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky and myself
at the Institute for Advanced Study in Princeton. The purpose of the discus-
sions was to help us understand the concepts and principles of quantum
mechanics, and what we thought we understood troubled us. For the con-
clusion we reached in these discussions was that the answer to the above
question is, "No'.
The paper aroused considerable controversy among physicists at the
time. Now, more than forty years later, discussion is still going on. It seems
therefore appropriate on the occasion of the centennial of the birth of Albert
Einstein to go back to this paper and re-examine it from the perspective of
the present time.
The next section presents a detailed review of the above paper (to be
referred to hereafter simply as "the paper") together with some critical
remarks. This is followed by a section presenting a contrasting point of view,
that of Bohr, and then a section of discussion.
II The Paper
In attempting to judge the success of a physical theory, we may ask ourselves two
questions: (1) "Is the theory correct?" and (2) "Is the description given by the theory
complete?" It is only in the case in which positive answers may be given to both of these
questions, that the concepts of the theory may be said to be satisfactory. The correctness
of the theory is judged by the degree of agreement between the conclusions of the theory
and human experience. This experience, which alone enables us to make inferences about
reality, in physics takes the form of experiment and measurement. It is the second ques-
tion that we wish to consider here, as applied to quantum mechanics.
Nowadays one sometimes hears it said that all that one wants of a theory
is that it should be correct, i. e., that it should enable one to carry out calcula-
tions so as to obtain numbers that agree with the results of experiments, and
that it is not necessary for the theory to provide us with any picture of the
reality. However, it seems to me that most physicists want such a picture,
and for them the second question, that of completeness, is important.
Whatever the meaning assigned to the term complete, the following requirement
for a complete theory seems to be a necessary one: every element of the physical reality
must have a counterpart in the physical theory. We shall call this the condition of com-
pleteness. The second question is thus easily answered, as soon as we are able to decide
what are the elements of the physical reality.
where a is a number, then the observable A has with certainty the value a
whenever the particle is in the state given by '1/1.
In accordance with our criterion of reality, for a particle in the state given by t/J
for which Eq. (1) holds, there is an element of physical reality corresponding to the
physical quantity A.
Thus, in the state given by Eq. (2), the momentum has certainly the value Po. It
thus has meaning to say that the momentum of the particle in the state given by Eq. (2)
is real.
On the other hand, if one considers the particle coordinate, for which
the operator q is that of multiplication by x, Eq. (1) does not hold in this
case, and one cannot say that the coordinate has a particular value. In accord-
ance with quantum mechanics one can talk only about probabilities of
various values, and in the case of the state given by Eq. (2), it is shown that
all values of the coordinate are equally probable.
A definite value of the coordinate, for a particle in the state given by Eq. (2), is
thus not predictable, but may be obtained only by a direct measurement. Such a measure-
ment however disturbs the particle and thus alters its state. After the coordinate is
determined, the particle will no longer be in the state given by Eq. (2). The usual conclu-
sion from this in quantum mechanics is that when the momentum of a particle is known,
its coordinate has no physical reality.
More generally, it is shown in quantum mechanics that, if the operators correspond-
ing to two physical quantities, say A and B, do not commute, that is, if AB f. BA, then
the precise knowledge of one of them precludes such a knowledge of the other. Further-
more, any attempt to determine the latter experimentally will alter the state of the
system in such a way as to destroy the knowledge of the first.
From this follows that either (1) the quantum-mechanical description of reality
given by the wave functions is not complete or (2) when the operators corresponding to
two physical quantities do not commute the two quantities cannot have simultaneous
reality. For if both of them had simultaneous reality - and thus definite values - these
values would enter into the complete description, according to the condition of com-
pleteness. If then the wave function provided such a complete description of reality, it
60 Nathan Rosen
would contain these values; these would then be predictable. This not being the case,
we are left with the alternatives stated.
In quantum mechanics it is usually assumed that we wave function does contain a
complete description of the physical reality of the system in the state to which it cor-
responds. At first sight this assumption is entirely reasonable, for the information obtain-
able from a wave function seems to correspond exactly to what can be measured without
altering the state of the system. We shall show, however, that this assumption, together
with the criterion of reality given above, leads to a contradiction.
For this purpose the paper considers the case of two systems I and II,
which interact from the time t = 0 to t = T, after which there is no longer
any interaction between them. From the states of the systems for t < 0 one
can calculate with the help of the Schrodinger equation the wave function t/J
of the combined system I + II at a time t > T. This does not enable one to
calculate the states of the individual systems after the interaction. That can
be done only with the help of further measurements by a process known as
the reduction of the wave packet, as follows:
Let A be some physical quantity pertaining to system I with eigen-
functions Un (Xl) and corresponding eigenvalues an, where Xl stands for the
variables describing this system. (It is tacitly assumed that there is no degener-
acy.) Then t/J can be expanded in a series of the orthogonal functions Un (Xl),
00
where X2 stands for the variables describing system II and t/Jn (x 2) are merely
the coefficients of the expansion. If the quantity A is measured and is found
to have the value ak, it is concluded that I is left in the state given by the
wave function Uk (Xl) and II in the state given by t/Jk (X2)' Thus the wave
packet given by the infinite series (3) is reduced to a single term t/Jk (X2) Uk (Xl)'
This is the process of the reduction of the wave packet.
Some additional remarks are appropriate at this point. The assumption
that the measurement results in the reduction of the wave packet is some-
times referred to as the projection postulate. The validity of this assumption
depends on the nature of the measurement process. Suppose that we carry
out on a system a measurement of a physical quantity A and obtain the
value a (which must be one of its eigenvalues, according to quantum mechan-
ics). It may be that we are dealing here with a reproducible measurement,
i. e., such that an immediate repetition of the measurement is certain to give
the same result as before. In that case we can conclude that, after the first
measurement, the system is left in a state given by t/J satisfying Eq. (1) (in
order to account for the certainty of obtaining a by another measurement).
The change from the original state of the system to that given by the eigen-
function t/J represents a reduction of the wave packet. On the other hand,
one may have a measurement that is not reproducible, in which case one
Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality 61
cannot draw this conclusion. (We can think of such a measurement as one
which leaves the physical quantity with a value different from that given by
the measurement.)
One can raise the question: is it always possible to choose a repro-
ducible measurement in order to determine the value of a given observable?
For our purpose, in view of the discussion below, it is enough to consider
measurements of the position and momentum of a particle. In these cases
it seems clear that reproducible measurements are possible, in principle.
In the paper it is tacitly assumed that the measurements are repro-
ducible and hence the reductions of the wave packets take place. For the
state given by Eq. (3) this means that, if the measurement of A gives the
value ak, then system I is left in the state with the wave function Uk(XI)'
Since nothing was done to system II, the coefficient 1/!k(X2) is unaltered
(except possibly for a normalization factor arising from probability consider-
ations).
If, instead of A, we had taken another quantity B having eigenfunctions
Us (Xl) and eigenvalues bs , we should have obtained, instead of Eq. (3), the
expansIOn
00
(4)
with new coefficients ¢S(X2)' If B is now measured and found to have the
value b r , one concludes that system I is left in the state given by Ur(XI) and
II in that given by ¢r (X2)'
We see therefore that, as a consequence of two different measurements performed
upon the first system, the second system may be left in states with two different wave
functions. On the other hand, since at the time of measurement the two systems no
longer interact, no real change can take place in the second system in consequence of
anything that may be done to the first system. This is, of course, merely a statement of
what is meant by the absence of an interaction between the two systems. Thus, it is
possible to assign two different wave functions (in our example IPk and if>r) to the same
reality (the second system after the interaction with the first).
Now it may happen that the two wave functions of system II, 1/lk and
¢r, are eigenfunctions of noncommuting operators corresponding to some
physical quantities P and Q, respectively, as can be seen from the following
example:
Suppose that the two systems are two particles and that
00
(5)
- 00
62 Nathan Rosen
(7)
-00
with
l/Ip(X2) = e(2nilh) (XO-X2)P. (8)
This however is the eigenfunction of
P = (bl2ni) a/ax2, (9)
corresponding to the eigenvalue - p of the momentum of particle II.
Now let B be the coordinate of particle I, with eigenfunctions
VX(XI)=O(XI-X), (10)
corresponding to the eigenvalue x, where 0 (Xl - X) is the Dirac delta-func-
tion. Then Eq. (4) becomes
00
(11)
-00
where
00
(12)
-00
case, if one measures the component of the spin of I in any direction, the
corresponding component of II must be equal to the measured value, but of
opposite sign. Hence, by measuring the spin of I in the x or the y direction,
one can determine the spin of II in the x or y direction. However, according
to quantum mechanics, the spins in these directions do not commute. Hence
one has a situation analogous to that in the previous example.
Returning now to the general case contemplated in Eqs. (3) and (4), we assume
that Wk and rfJr are indeed eigenfunctions of some noncommuting operators P and Q,
corresponding to the eigenvalue Pk and qr, respectively. Thus, by measuring either A
or B we are in a position to predict with certainty, and without in any way disturbing
the second system, either the value of the quantity P (that is Pk) or the value of the
quantity Q (that IS qrl. In accordance with our criterion of reality, in the first case we
must consider the quantity P as being an element of reality, in the second case the quan-
tity Q is an element of reality. But, as we have seen, both wave functions Wk and rfJr
belong to the same reality.
Previously we proved that either (1) the quantum-mechanical description of reality
given by the wave function is not complete or (2) when the operators corresponding to
two physical quantities do not commute the two quantities cannot have simultaneous
reality. Starting then with the assumption that the wave function does give a complete
description of the physical reality, we arrived at the conclusion that two physical quan-
tities, with noncommuting operators, can have simultaneous reality. Thus the negation
of (1) leads to the negation of the only other alternative (2). We are thus forced to
conclude that the quantum-mechanical description of physical reality given by wave
functions is not complete.
One could object to this conclusion on the grounds that our criterion of reality is
not sufficiently restrictive. Indeed, one would not arrive at our conclusion if one insisted
that two or more physical quantities can be regarded as simultaneous elements of reality
only when they can be simultaneously measured or predicted. On this point of view, since
either one of the other, but not both simultaneously, of the quantities P and Q can be
predicted, they are not simultaneously real. This makes the reality of P and Q depend
upon the process of measurement carried out on the first system, which does not disturb
the second system in any way. No reasonable definition of reality could be expected to
permit this.
While we have thus shown that the wave function does not provide a complete
description of the physical reality, we left open the question of whether or not such a
description exists. We believe, however, that such a theory is possible.
lies in the fact that Bohr presented the "orthodox" Copenhagen interpreta-
tion of quantum mechanics, which he, more than anyone else, had developed
and which is accepted today by most of the workers in this field. The juxta-
position of the ideas of the two articles should help to understand the differ-
ences in the Weltanschauung of these two great scientists, Einstein and Bohr.
Bohr disagreed strongly with the paper and, in particular, with the
criterion of reality. According to him, the conclusion indicates the "inade-
quacy of the customary viewpoint of natural philosophy for a rational
account of physical phenomena of the type with which we are concerned in
quantum mechanics", and the criterion of reality contains an essential
ambiguity when applied to the problems under discussion.
Let us look briefly at that part of Bohr's work dealing directly with the
paper. He begins by considering the simple case of a particle passing through
a slit in a diaphragm. On the one hand, one can choose an experimental
arrangement in which the diaphragm is rigidly attached to the support so
that the slit is at a fixed position. On the other hand, one can choose an
experimental arrangement in which the diaphragm moves freely and it is
possible to determine the transfer of momentum from the particle to the
diaphragm. In the first case the slit defines the position of the particle just
after it has passed through, but there is an uncontrollable transfer of momen-
tum between particle and diaphragm so that one is ignorant of the particle's
momentum. In the second case, if one knew the particle's momentum pre-
viously, one knows its momentum after it has passed through, but its posi-
tion is unkown since one does not know the position of the slit on the (mov-
ing) diaphragm at the moment the particle passes through. The two experi-
mental arrangements, which can be thought of as suitable for predicting the
position or the momentum of the particle which has just passed through the
slit, are mutually exclusive and allow the use of complementary classical
concepts (e.g., a coordinate or a momentum) which are mutually exclusive
according to Bohr's complementarity principle.
Bohr's purpose in discussing this situation is to emphasize that one is
not dealing with an incomplete description in which one is ignorant of cer-
tain quantities, but rather that in each experimental arrangement one is
faced with the impossibility of defining certain quantities in an unambiguous
way.
Bohr then considers the problem of the two particles discussed in the
paper. According to him the situation is not very different from that of the
single particle above. In principle, one can imagine that the two particles go
through two slits in a diaphragm with an experimental arrangement for deter-
mining the momentum transferred from the particles to the diaphragm. The
distance between the slits gives x 2 - X I just after they have passed through.
Knowing the momenta of the particles before they reach the slits, one can
determine their total momentum PI + P2 after passing through. On the basis
of the commutation relations between operators corresponding to conjugate
Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality 65
variables one sees that these two operators commute, so that we can have a
state of the combined system I + II which is an eigenstate of both of them.
If we now have an additional experimental arrangement for measuring x I,
then we can determine x 2; if we have one for measuring PI, we can deter-
mine P2' This is the situation in the paper.
However, Bohr interprets this situation differently. The measurement
process used to determine x 2 prevents one from determining P2 and vice
versa. According to Bohr, the criterion of physical reality used in the paper
contains an ambiguity as regards the meaning of the expression, "without
in any way disturbing a system". In the case considered there is no mechani-
cal disturbance of system II during the last critical stage of the measuring
procedure (when one measures either XI or PI)' But there is "an influence
on the very conditions which define the possible types of predictions regard-
ing the future behavior of the system. Since these conditions constitute an
inherent element of the description of any phenomenon to which the term
'physical reality' can be properly attached, we see that the argumentation of
the mentioned authors does not justify their conclusion that quantum-
mechanical description is essentially incomplete". On the contrary, as he sees
it, this description "may be characterized as a rational utilization of all possi-
bilities of unambiguous interpretation of measurements compatible with the
finite and uncontrollable interaction between the objects and the measuring
instruments in the field of quantum theory". Therefore, according to Bohr,
the quantum-mechanical description of physical reality is complete.
IV Discussion
have some sort of non-local interaction between the systems, i. e., an inter-
action at a distance, which causes one system to be influenced by a measure-
ment carried out on the other. Most physicists would find this idea rather
unattractive.
Let us now turn to the last paragraph of the paper. What are the prospects
of finding a satisfactory theory that will give a complete description of re-
ality? One must not be overly optimistic. It appears that such a theory will
not be obtained by some simple modification of quantum mechanics, such
as the addition of hidden variables. If someday quantum mechanics is re-
placed by another theory, this is likely to involve revolutionary changes in
concepts and principles - perhaps even changes in our concepts of space and
time. In that case it may even turn out that the question posed by the paper
- is the description of physical reality complete? - no longer has a mean-
ing, or that it has to be given a different interpretation. The consequences of
a revolution in physics are hard to foresee.
References
As early as in 1901, when the reality of atoms was still in the dark, Ein-
stein started his research career with an attempt to determine the strengths
of interatomic forces from the available data of surface tension. His first
paper (1901) and the second (1902) were on this problem 3 ,4.
If one takes, as Einstein did already in such early days, the atomic
constitution of matter for granted, one must proceed to apply the prin-
ciples of mechanics to the atoms themselves. But, the number of atoms in
ordinary piece of matter is presumably so great that it requires statistical
methods. "At present, however, the mechanics is not yet in the position,"
says Einstein in his third paper in 1902, Kinetic Theory of Thermal Equilib-
rium and ... , "to offer sufficient foundation for the general heat theory,
for it has not yet been achieved to derive the thermal equilibrium and the
second law of thermodynamics from the equation of motion and probability
theory. "s
The method of statistical mechanics was not entirely new. Over the last
quarter of the 19 th century, Ludwig Boltzmann in Wien and James Clark
Maxwell in Edinburgh had developed the method almost fully for the case
of gases. In their kinetic theory of gases, the heat was supposed to be the
energy of molecules in chaotic flights with occasional mutual collisions,
and thermodynamic quantities of a gas were supposed to be given by the sum
or the average of corresponding mechanical quantities of the tremendous
number of molecules in the gas. Besides, the second law of thermodynamics,
which says roughly that the heat flows from the place of the higher temper-
ature to that of the lower temperature, or that the gases undergo diffusion,
was interpreted as the tendency of change into the more probable state. It
was argued by Boltzmann in fact that the change in the reverse direction
has such a small probability in general that it would never occur in the life-
time of the universe.
Einstein could not be satisfied with this state of affairs because the
theory was limited to gases only.
even beyond the realm of (classical) mechanics in which it was fostered, and
indeed it would serve as a heuristic means in the quest into the quantum
world.
That "an arbitrary physical system can be represented as a mechanical
system" was the point of departure of Einstein and indeed of the atomic
theory. It means that the state of a system is determined at any instant
of time by a point in the 2n-dimensional "phase space" spanned by the coor-
dinates q 1, ... , q n and the momenta PI' ... , Pn. The energy of the system
is a function H (p 1, ... , q n) of these variables.
6 L. Boltzmann, Wien. Ber. 63, p. 397 (1871). See also "Vorlesungen iiber Gastheorie",
J. A. Barth, Leipzig, 1895-98, Teill-lII.
72 Hiroshi Ezawa
Now, Einstein brings out a basic assumption which is made even in the
statistical mechanics of today: "We assume that, except for the energy or its
functions, there are no such functions of the state variables p, q, ... only, that
do not change with time." Then, it follows that the density distribution
of the representative points in the phase space must be a function of the to-
tal energy only. If all the system in the ensemble have the same energy, then
the density distribution of the points in the phase space is uniform over the
energy shell. Boltzmann in his gas theory stated this proposition as ergodic
hypothesis (1884,1887).
Now, the distribution of the subsystems in their phase space is obtained
if one integrates the joint distribution over all the possible phases of the
other subsystems, that is, the heat bath. Einstein finally arrives at a constant,
~, that determines so-to-say the equilibrium of the system and the heat
bath. The value of ~ is then shown to have the properties of the temperature:
First, it is always positive. Second, if there are different systems in thermal
equilibrium with one and the same heat bath, they share the same value of ~.
Taking, then, the ideal gas as one of those systems, 1/~ can be identified with
2/3 times the average of the kinetic energy of a gas molecule, which is
known from the equipartition theorem to equal 3/2 RT divided by the num-
ber NA of molecules in a mole. Thus, one gets ~ = l/kT with k = RINA .
Actually, this last determination of k was done by Einstein in his 1904 paper
to which we shall come later.
In contrast to the canonical ensemble of systems in thermal equilibrium
with a heat bath, the ensemble of isolated systems having a common energy
is called microcanonical. Remarkably, Einstein's treatment shows that the
two descriptions, microcanonical and canonical, are equivalent statistically,
if one is interested in a physical quantity of a relatively small subsystem.
7 A. Einstein, "Theorie der Grundlagen der Thermodynamik", Ann. d. Physik, (4), Ii,
p.170(1903).
Einstein's Contribution to Statistical Mechanics 73
because, for the microcanonical ensemble, the equal volumes on the energy
shell are equally probable. Boltzmann defined a number similar to Wand
called it the number of Komplexions 8 . In general, the number of Komple-
8 L. Boltzmann, "Uber die Beziehung zwischen dem zweiten Hauptsatz der mechani-
schen Wiirmetheorie und der Wahrscheinlichkeitsrechnung respektive den Siitzen iiber
Wiirmegleichgewicht". Wien. Ber. 76, p. 373 (1977).
74 Hiroshi Ezawa
S = k log(WIL N ), (3)
where an additive constant is immaterial for the (classical) entropy. These
relations between the entropy and the number of Komplexions or the prob-
ability were first discovered by Boltzmann in the gas theory context (1877),
and are called the Boltzmann principle.
Now, Einstein says: "We have to assume that the more probable distri-
bution of the states will always follow the less probable one." From this
assumption, there follows the desired entropy theorem, namely the increase
in the entropy. Einstein gave another proof in the third paper (1904) of his
series 9 , this time using (1) as the bridge to the probability.
In 1911, Paul Hertz criticized the proof sayinglo: "If one assumes, as
Einstein did, that the more probable distribution follows the less probable,
he is introducing an assumption which has no evidence and needs to be pro-
ven." We all know that here is the core of the problem of the second law
of thermodynamics. "I take this criticism to be completely right"ll replied
Einstein in Remarks on P. Hertz's Paper (1911). As a matter of fact, he had
already realized that the changes in the reverse direction, the less probable
following the more probable, could take place in the fluctuation phenome-
na.
3. Fluctuation Formula
9 A. Einstein, "Zur allgemeinen molekularen Theorie der Wiirme", Ann. d. Physik, (4),
14, p. 354 (1904).
10 P. Hertz, "Ober die mechanischen Grundlagen der Thermodynamik", Ann. d. Physik
33, p. 225 u. S. 537 (1910).
11 A. Einstein, "Bemerkungen zu den P. Hertz'schen Arbeiten: Mechanische Grundlagen
der Thermodynamik", Ann. d. Physik, 34, p. 175 (1911).
Einstein's Contribution to Statistical Mechanics 75
(4)
Brownian motion, though at the time of writing the paper Einstein could
not be sure about the identification because "the informations available
to me ... was so inaccurate."
Einstein asserted, this motion, if ever observed, would tell us two
things. One is that "the classical thermodynamics cannot be taken as exactly
valid already in microscopically discernible space." The other is that "an
exact determination of the true sizes of atoms becomes possible."
regarded the molecular motion to obey the same laws as those valid for the
perceptible bodies, it is now necessary to assume for the oscillating ions
that the manifold of states that they can take is smaller than that for the
bodies within our experiences." This was the beginning of the quantum
statistical mechanics. Einstein was led to this conclusion by the following
path of thoughts.
It was from the end of the 19 th century that the spectrum of black
body radiation had been a central issue of physicists. In 1900, Planck 20
discovered his radiation formula which, with an appropriate choice of the
contained parameter h, now called Planck's constant, fits very well with
the measured energy density of the black body radiation. He could even
derive the formula on the assumption that the radiation of frequency v
was emitted or absorbed in a lump, or energy quantum of hv, although
his continuous efforts to understand the mechanism of the discontinuous
changes were never successful.
Einstein could not accept Planck's derivation of his formula. Even
as late as in 1911, after Planck's report in the Solvay Conference, Einstein
expressed his opinion that Planck's probability calculation was a shock to
him. Let us see how Planck derived his formula in his 1900 paper.
which would be the same as the corresponding probability for the ideal gas
if E/hv were the number of gas particles.
Einstein saw supporting evidences for this particle analogy of radiation
in the Stokes law of photoluminescence, the photoelectric effect and the
ionization of gases. Thus, he suggested as a heuristic point of view the "As-
sumption that the energy of light is distributed discontinuously in the space .
... When the light propagates from a point, its energy will not be continuous-
ly distributed over an ever increasing volume of space, instead it consists
invariably of a finite number of energy quanta which can move without
disintegrating and can be absorbed or generated as a whole." This is the light
quantum hypothesis.
Such a view might seem refutable at once by the ample evidences of the
wave theory of light. So Einstein remarked "that the optical observations are
related to the values averaged in time, and not to the values at a moment",
and therefore "it is ... conceivable that the theory employing continuous
functions over a space leads to contradictions with experiences, if one
applies it to the phenomena of generation and transformation of light."
21 A. Einstein, "Ober einen die Erzeugung und Verwandlung des Lichts betreffenden
heuristischen Gesichtspunkt", Ann. d. Physik, (4), 17, p. 132 (1905).
22 A. Einstein, "Zur Theorie der Lichterzeugung und Lichtabsorption", Ann. d. Physik,
(4),20, p. 199 (1906).
80 Hiroshi Ezawa
to examine the entropy of the resonators, finding that his formula (1) gives
the entropy in accord with Planck's number of Komplexions if:
Einstein has thus found three assumptions that underlies Planck's theory of
radiation. He showed that Planck's formula follows from these assumptions
in an impressively simple way.
Logically, one may question if both assumptions [ 1] and [3] are needed.
To Einstein, who saw "disturbing dualism" in particle and field concepts in
classical physics 23 , it was probably most natural to assume that, on the fun-
damental level, what is true with radiation should also be true with mechani-
cal objects and vice versa.
(a) The solids of carbon, boron and silicon have specific heats significantly
smaller than 3 R.
(b) There is no indication of the added contribution to the specific heat
from the electrons, which according to Drude's analysis of optical
dispersion should exist in solids and should be capable of oscillations
with ultraviolet eigenfrequencies.
25 T. S. Kuhn, ibid.
26 quoted in detail by T. S. Kuhn, ibid.
82 Hiroshi Ezawa
incompatible. "28 This finding, however, did not help him to revise the deri-
vation of the Planck formula.
Einstein's interests gradually shifted to relativity and gravitation.
28 A. Einstein, "Ober die Entwicklung unserer Anschauung iiber das Wesen und die
Konstitution der Strahlung", Physikalische Zeitschrift, 10, p. 817 (1909).
29 N. Bohr, "On the Constitution of Atoms and Molecules", Phil. Mag.21, p.l (1913).
30 A. Einstein, "Strahlungsemission und -absorption nach der Quantentheorie" Deutsche
Physikalische Gesellschaft, Verhandlungen, 18, p. 318 (1916).
31 A. Einstein, "Quantentheorie der Strahlung", Physikalische Zeitschrift, 18, p. 121.
32 S. Bosse, "Planck's Gesetz und Lichtquantenhypothese", Zeitschrift fiir Physik 26,
p. 178 (1924).
84 Hiroshi Ezawa
possible in each cell. Bose showed that the Planck formula corresponds to
the 'most probable' distribution.
Many people were perplexed by the counting (8), Einstein himself,
Ehrenfest and Schrodinger among them.
Ehrenfest and others were concerned that in Bose's theory the quanta
were not treated as statistically independent from each other. But, Einstein
could show that Bose's formula (8) was equivalent to Planck's (6). This
implied that Planck's assumption of equal probability for his Komplexions
was not compatible, as Einstein had long suspected, with the assumption
of statistical independence of light quanta; there must be "a mutual in-
fluence ... which, for the moment, is completely puzzling."
That a material particle has a wave aspect was in accord with the hypo-
thesis Louis de Broglie 35 put forward in the thesis he defended on November
29, 1924, just before Einstein completed the part II of his paper (received
in December 1924). In Einstein's words in his 1925 paper: "Mr. L. de Broglie
has shown in his very remarkable paper how a (scalar) wave field can be
associated with a material particle or a system of material particles." Further
in the footnote attached to this sentence: "In this thesis, there is also a very
remarkable geometrical interpretation of the Bohr-Sommerfeld's quantiza-
tion rule. "32 Note the 'very remarkable' used twice. Indeed, it was Einstein
who called attention of many people to de Broglie's work; the paper itself
was published with his encouragement. 36
Schrodinger pointed out at the end of 1925 that a deeper understand-
ing of Einstein's new theory would be obtained if one associated each energy
state Es of a single molecule with a degree of freedom of the whole system
and said that the 5 th degree of freedom had, like a harmonic oscillator, the
energy ns Es in place of saying that ns molecules were in the state Es. His
point was that in this picture, the indistinguishability of Bose-Einstein
'particles' becomes obvious within the ordinary, well established statistics.
"The real meaning of Einstein's gas theory is", wrote Schrodinger 37 , "that
the gas is to be understood as such a system with linear eigen-oscillations as
a volume of radiation or a solid body." Not more than one month later, the
1't communication of Schrodinger's series of papers38, 'Quantization as an
Eigenvalue Problem', was received for publication in Annalen der Physik.
Einstein's influence went so far as to help conceive the wave mechanics.
35 L. de Broglie, "Recherches sur la Theorie des Quantes", Theses, Paris 1924 und Ann.
d. Physik (10),3, p. 22 (1925).
36 W. Heitier, "Erwin Schrodinger", Biographical Memoirs of Fellows of the Royal
Society 1961 (Va. 7), The Royal Society, Burlington House, London.
37 E. Schrodinger, "Zur Einstein'schen Gastheorie", Phys. Zeitschrift, 27, p.101 (1926).
38 E. Schrodinger, "Quantisierung als Eigenwertproblem", Ann. d. Physik (4), 79,
p. 361,p.489;80,p.437;81,p. 109(1926).
39 F. London, "On the Bose-Einstein Condensation", Phys. Rev., 54, p. 947 (1938).
86 Hiroshi Ezawa
7. Concluding Remarks
40 Gibbs' book was translated into German in 1905: J. w. Gibbs, "Elementare Grund-
lagen der statistischen Mechanik", translated by E. Zermelo, J. A. Barth, Leipzig
1905.
Einstein's Contribution to Statistical Mechanics 87
41 See the remark made by Born in the International Conference on Statistical Me-
chanics in 1949. Supp!. Nuovo Cimento vol. VI, Series IX, 1949, p. 296.
42 See M. Born, ref. 2, in particular Einstein's letter to Born quoted therein.
89
I gratefully acknowledge support for this research from the National Science F ounda-
tion
This essay is based upon my paper "The physics of Einstein's relativity paper of
1905 and the electromagnetic world picture of 1905," American Journal of Physics,
45,1040-1048 (1977)
2 For an in-depth discussion of this research effort see A.I. Miller, "A Study of Henri
Poincare's 'Sur la dynamique de l'electron,' " Archive for History of Exact Sciences,
10, Nos. 3-5, 207 328 (1973)
90 Arthur I. Miller
~ ~
'iJ·E=47rp (1)
~ ~
'iJ·B =0 (2)
~ Maxwell-Lorentz
~ ~ 1 aB Equations
'iJXE=---
c at (3)
~
~ ~ 1 aE 47r ~
'iJXB=--+-pv
c at C
(4)
Lorentz force
(5)
equation
--+
'iJ X E
--+
=-
aB
--+
c1 at (8)
Yr = Y (11)
Zr = z (12)
v (13)
tL = t -'2 x
c '
where x, y, z and t are the spatial and temporal coordinates in S; X r , Yr ,
Zr are the spatial coordinates in an inertial reference system Sr moving
with velocity v relative to S and along their common x-axes; and tL is the
"local time" coordinate 6 which is a nonphysical, i. e. mathematical time
coordinate - the real physical time in Sand Sr is the Galilean time t. Lo-
rentz discovered that if the Maxwell-Lorentz Equations (6) to (9) are trans-
formed to Sr using the set of modified Galilean transformations, and appro-
priate transformation equations for the electromagnetic field quantities
are used, viz.,
--+
--+
Er = E +
--+
cv X --+B (14)
--+
--+
Br =B
--+
-cv X --+E, (15)
(18)
(19)
6 Ibid, P 49.
92 Arthur I. Miller
7 Ibid., p. 85.
8 See Ref. 4 for further discussion of the ad hocness of Lorentz's contraction hypothe-
SIS.
9 Poincare's criticisms of Lorentz's electromagnetic theory during the years 1895 -1904
are discussed in Part 5 of Ref. 2.
10 W. Wien, ,.Ober die Moglichkeit einer elektromagnetischen Begriindung der Mecha-
nik," Recueil de travaux offerts par les auteurs a H. A. Lorentz (Nijhoff, The Hague,
1900), pp. 96-107.
11 H. A. Lorentz, "Theorie simplifiee des phenomenes electriques et optiques dans des
corps en mouvement," Versl. Kon. Akad. Wetensch. Amsterdam, 7, 507 (1899); re-
printed in Collected Papers, Vol. 5, 139-155.
On the History of the Special Relativity Theory 93
m
L
= m c2
0 v2
l' 2 vic _ 10 (1 + vic )]
v2 g \ 1 - vic (20)
] --
(2
m
T -
- mo C 33 .1 11 + V 22 ) log
2 v '- \ c /
(11 -+ ViC)
vic
- 2 vic Jl (21)
2
where mo = 8~ is the electron's electrostatic (i.e. rest) mass, and r is the
7r rc
electron's radius. The transverse mass agreed with Kaufmann's data. The
goal of the electromagnetic world-picture appeared to have been reached.
To be sure, Abraham's theory of the electron could not explain the
results of the high precision second-order ether-drift experiments of Lord
Rayleigh in 1902 13 and D.B. Brace l4 in 1904 which sought unsuccessfully
to detect double refraction in moving isotropic bodies. Nevertheless, Abra-
ham believed that in time his theory of the electron could be slightly altered
to explain optical experiments as well.
In 1904, Lorentz, prompted by the criticisms of Poincare and the
appearance of new data accurate to second order in vic (i.e. in addition
to the data of Michelson and Morley, the data of Rayleigh and Brace and
of Trouton and Noble) IS, extended the application of his electromagnetic
theory to a theory of the electron; Lorentz's now famous paper of 1904 is
entitled "Electromagnetic phenomena in a system moving with any velo-
12 M. Abraham, "Dynamik des Elektrons." Nachr. Ges. Wiss. Gottingen, 20-41 (1902);
"Prinzipien der Dynamik des Elektrons," Annalen der Physik, 10, 105-179 (1903).
See Part 3 of Ref. 2 for further discussion of Abraham's theory of the electron.
13 Lord Rayleigh, "Does Motion through the Aether cause Double Refraction?," Phil.
Mag .. 4, 678-683 (1902)
14 D. B. Brace, "On Double Refraction in Matter moving through the Aether," Phil.
Mag., 7.317- 329 (1904)
15 Trouton and Noble attempted unsuccessfully to measure the turning couple of a
condenser which was suspended from a thread at a fixed point on the earth. See
F. T. Trouton and H. R. Noble, 'The Mechanical Forces Acting on a Charged Electric
Condenser Moving through Space," Phil. Trans. Roy. Soc. London A, 202, 165-181
(1903)
94 Arthur I. Miller
city smaller than that of light. "16 Lorentz's electron is deformable, under-
going a Lorentz contraction when in motion (an hypothesis that Abraham
assiduously avoided). Lorentz claimed that his theory could explain the
negative results of ether-drift experiments accurate to all orders in vic.
Lorentz's predictions for the electron's longitudinal (mL> and transverse
(mT) masses are:
4 (22)
mL =-
. 3
(23)
2
where mo = __e_2 is the electron's electrostatic (i. e. rest) mass, and r is
81Trc
the electron's radius. Furthermore, Lorentz claimed that his prediction
for the electron's transverse mass also agreed with Kaufmann's data, within
the experimental error.
But Henri Poincare, at the Congress of Arts and Science in St. Louis
Missouri in 1904, praised Lorentz's new theory of the electron.'7 He empha-
sized that now the Lorentz contraction hypothesis, originally cooked up for
the purpose of explaining one experiment, was no longer ad hoc since it
could now explain several second-order experiments and was folded into the
new theory of the electron as one of several "complementary hypotheses. "18
Poincare referred to Lorentz's new generalized theorem of corresponding
states embodied in his 1904 paper as the "principle of relativity" which
asserts that "the laws of physical phenomena must be the same for a station-
ary observer as for an observer carried along in a uniform motion of trans-
lation."19 Poincare also realized that further work was required on Lorentz's
theory of the electron.
ledger, Lorentz's theory was heavy with hypotheses, including the new
spacetime transformations and the Lorentz contraction; but they seemed
necessary in order to explain the experimental data - especially the meas-
ured value for. the velocity of light. The principle of relativity of Lorentz
and Poincare has the aura of having been induced from the experimental
data, in particular that of Michelson and Morley. Also, it was perceived
that some (presumably minor) elaborations remained to complete the
theory - for example, Newton's second law could only be deduced ap-
proximately from the Lorentz force law because terms in the expansion
of the electron's self-fields containing derivatives of the electron's acceler-
ation had to be dropped. 23
Mechanics appeared to be becoming a branch of electromagnetism that
was consistent with a principle of relativity. The stage was set. A great new
era in science was emerging and the main actors to play their parts were
known - or were they?
It is indeed an irony that less than a month after the brief version of
Poincare's "On the Dynamics of the Electron" appeared in the Comptes
Rendus, there arrived at the editorial office of the Annalen der Physik a
manuscript to be considered for publication in its Volume 17 by the author
of two previous papers in that volume - Albert Einstein. The paper is en-
titled "On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies. "24
To further set the stage for our discussion of Einstein's paper I shall
review briefly what we know of his pre-1905 knowledge of electrodynamics.
From a variety of mutually confirming sources we know that Einstein
while a student at the ETH in Zurich from 1896 to 1900 had studied Lo-
rentz's seminal paper of 1892 on electromagnetic theory and his treatise on
electrodynamics of 1895; and furthermore, that Einstein had seen neither
Lorentz's paper of 1904 nor Poincare's "On the Dynamics of the Elec-
tron. "25 One can also substantiate that Einstein before 1905 had studied
Abraham's theory of the electron and Abraham's criticisms of 1904 on
Lorentz's new theory of the electron. 26 Einstein said later in his "Autobio-
graphical Notes" of 1946 that he had perceived the instability of Lorentz's
electron as a "fundamental crisis, "27 yet he had in 1900 already discerned
an even greater crisis; namely, that accepting Planck's radiation law as valid
vitiated the possibility of either an electromagnetic or mechanical world-
picture. 28
Let us now turn to Einstein's relativity paper and compare his approach
to the electrodynamics and optics of moving bodies with that of the ether
theorists.
The relativity paper is structured thus: an untitled introductory section,
a Part I entitled "Kinematical Part," and a Part II entitled "Electrodynam-
ical Part." Each part is subdivided into five sections. The order of the subject
matter is thus the opposite of papers written by proponents of the electro-
magnetic world-picture, who emphasized the dynamics of the electron, i.e.
they deduced the electron's kinematics from its dynamics.
It is on the first page of the introductory section, a section that is
perhaps the most familiar, that Einstein sets the theme in the opening sen-
tence: 29 "It is known that Maxwell's electrodynamics - as usually under-
stood at the present time - when applied to moving bodies, leads to asym-
metries which do not appear to be inherent in the phenomena." It can be
established that Einstein is referring here to the Maxwell-Lorentz theory,
i.e. Lorentz's electromagnetic theory, and not to Maxwell's original formu-
lation. 30 Einstein is not asserting that there are errors in the formulation
of the Maxwell-Lorentz theory, rather that it is misinterpreted; further-
more, the misinterpretation "leads to asymmetries which do not appear to
be inherent in the phenomena." As an example of an asymmetry Einstein in
his well-known first paragraph discusses, as a gedanken experiment, the cur-
rent that arises in a conducting loop that is in inertial motion relative to a
constant magnetic field. Although the magnitude and direction of the in-
duced current depends only upon the relative velocity of conductor and
magnet, the Maxwell-Lorentz theory, Einstein explains, "as understood at
26 See A. L Miller, "On Einstein, Light Quanta, Radiation and Relativity in 1905,"
American Joumal of Physics, 44, 912-923 (1976).
27 A. Einstein, "Autobiographical Notes," in P. A. Schilpp (ed.), Albert Ei1stein: Philos-
opher-5cientist (The Library of Living Philosophers, Evanston, 1949), p. 37.
28 Ibid., pp. 52-53.
29 Ref. 24, p. 37.
30 E.g Einstein in his essay "Relativitatsprinzip und die aus demselben gezogenen
Folgerungen," Jahrbuch der Radioaktivitat und Elektronik, 4, 411-462 (1907)
refers to the set of Eqs. (1) to (4) as the "Maxwell-Lorentz equations" (p. 427),
and discusses only "H. A. Lorentz's electrodynamics of moving bodies" (p. 412).
98 Arthur I. Miller
the present time ... draws a sharp distinction' '31 between the cases of
magnet in motion and conductor at rest and vice versa.
Did others feel there was an asymmetry in the contemporaneous anal-
ysis of the case of magnet and conductor? After all Einstein began the rela-
tivity paper with the phrase "It is known ... ". However the works of Max-
well, Hertz, Lorentz and Poincare reveal no discussion of asymmetries in
electromagnetic induction.
Einstein then begins the next paragraph, which is breathtaking in
scope: 32 "Examples of this sort, together with the unsuccessful attempts
to discover any motion of the earth relatively to the "light medium," suggest
that the phenomena of electrodynamics as well as of mechanics possess no
properties corresponding to the idea of absolute rest." Einstein's linking
of the experiment of magnet and conductor to an apparently unrelated
set of experiments - the ether drift experiments (left unnamed) - is one
of the master strokes to be found in the relativity paper. For Einstein
realized the importance of the fact that the theoretical interpretation of the
case of magnet and conductor discussed in the first paragraph, depends upon
the laws of mechanics and electromagnetism. However, according to New-
ton's mechanics there are no preferred inertial reference systems; further-
more, the Newtonian principle of relativity obtains for such systems.
Einstein continues: 33 "They suggest rather that, as has already been
shown to the first order of small quantities, the same laws of electrodynam-
ics and optics will be valid for all frames of reference for which the equa-
tions of mechanics hold good."
Thus, since the ether drift experiments, both electrodynamical and
optical, were unsuccessful - especially important to Einstein are the ones
accurate to first order in vic - and since the Lorentz theory unifies both
electricity and optics, then to first order in vic the laws of mechanics and
electromagnetism should be the same in every inertial reference system.
Then, Einstein boldly widens the Newtonian principle, of relativity to em-
brace both mechanics and electromagnetism: 34 "We will raise this conjec-
ture (the purport of which will hereafter be called the "Principle of Rela-
tivity") to the status of a postulate .... "
35 Loc. cit.
36 According to Lorentz's theory the physical coordinate transformation is the Galilean
transformation - for example the local time coordinate in Eq. (13) is a further mathe-
matical scale transformation on the Galilean time, i. e. the absolute time. But since
the ether-fixed reference system S never moves, the inverse transformation has no
physical meaning. See note 56 below for further discussion.
37 Ref. 24, p. 38.
38 Ibid., p. 41.
39 See Ref 2, note 62 on p. 233.
40 For further discussion of Poincare's philosophy of science and its influence on the
direction of his scientific researches, see Ref. 2 and A. I. Miller, "Poincare and Ein-
stein: A Comparative Study," to be published in Volume XXXI of the Boston Stu-
dies in t he Philosophy of Science.
100 Arthur I. Miller
decide the issue for him.41 Only a few, old, quite well established and seem-
ingly well understood experiments would be needed. To Einstein the
first-order experiments concerning stellar aberration and Fizeau's measure-
ments of the velocity of light in moving water "were enough" (as Einstein
once said himself).42 They had in fact been explained systematically by
Lorentz in his treatise of 1895, using the hypothesis of an unphysical local
time coordinate. Einstein later wrote that before 1905 it had occurred to
him that perhaps one should define as time what Lorentz in the treatise
of 1895 had considered merely an auxiliary mathematical hypothesis. 43
But the mathematics would come later, for Einstein did not think in such
terms; rather, there was the predominantly visual component to his thought
from which arose some of his ideas on the nature of light that would lead
to the special relativity theory.44 In particular there was the gedanken ex-
periment of magnet and conductor, and the gedanken experiment from
the Aarau period of 1895 wherein Einstein considered what it would be like
to run alongside of a light wave and then catch up with a point on it. Ein-
stein wrote of the Aarau experiment in his "Autobiographical Notes" of
1946 that it "was intuitively clear"45 that everything should occur for the
moving observer as it did for an observer at rest relative to the earth. He
continues: "For how, otherwise, should the moving observer be able to
determine that he is in a state of fast uniform motion?"46 Einstein consid-
ered this as a paradox containing, as he wrote in 1946, with hindsight,
"the germ of the special relativity theory. "47 But first says Einstein in the
"Autobiographical Notes" he had to realize that the "absolute character
of time, viz., of simultaneity unrecognizedly was anchored in the uncon-
scious." "The type of critical reasoning," Einstein continues, necessary for
this discovery he found in the philosophical works of Hume and Mach. 48 In
fact, by 1905 Einstein may very well have realized that this gedanken
experiment contained in principle every optical ether-drift experiment
that could be performed. Thus, Einstein was working on the same problem
that was of concern to Lorentz and Poincare; namely, why does the veloc-
in ether theories. There, knowledge of the true length of a body was appar-
ently forever denied because one could not determine the earth's velocity
relative to the ether. Einstein then explains that the coordinates of a material
point in motion are functions of time and thus we must understand what
we mean by "time."53
Einstein goes on to argue that simultaneity is not an absolute concept;
rather, there should be a distinction between local and distant simultaneity.
Einstein is careful not to let sensations decide the issue as did the mecha-
nists, the ether theorists, and philosopher-scientists such as Mach and Poin-
care ;54 rather, an in principle operational definition is necessary to define
distant simultaneity and time. Einstein obtains a definition of clock syn-
chronization, and hence time for clocks at relative rest in any inertial refe-
rence system, by means of an in-principle-operational procedure in which is
embodied the homogeneity and isotropy of space for the propagation of
light. It is a two-way two-clock light exchange experiment. Consider two
clocks at relative rest and at positions A and B in an inertial reference sys-
tem. Light is emitted from the clock at A at time tA , received at the clock
at B at time tB where it is reflected back to A arriving at time tA'. Einstein
is led to the definition of the time tB as one-half the sum of the times tA
and tA', i.e.
tA + tA'
tB = 2 (24)
53 Ibid., p. 39.
54 See, for example, my essay "Poincare and Einstein ... " in Ref. 40.
55 For further comparisons of the styles in Einstein's relativity paper and Newton's
Principia, see Holton's "On the Origins ... " in Ref. 25, esp. pp. 170-171.
On the History of the Special Relativity Theory 103
I
x - vt
(25)
X = ( v2 ) 1/2
1--
c2
y' =y (26)
,
z =z (27)
v
t -- X
, c2
t =, 2)112 ' (28)
( 1- ~
(2 ,
where the primed (unprimed) space and time coordinates are measured rela-
tive to the inertial reference system k (K).s6 Einstein interprets them as relat-
ing between two inertial reference systems the readings on clocks and meas-
uring rods. (Unknown to Einstein a mathematically equivalent set of these
equations had appeared in Lorentz's paper of 1904 and had been dubbed
by Poincare in 1905 the Lorentz transformations. s7 )
In Section 4 entitled "Physical Meaning of the Equations Obtained
in Respect to Moving Rigid Bodies and Moving Clocks" Einstein deduces
the apparent contraction of bodies in inertial motion as measured by an
observer in another inertial reference system, and the equation for time
dilation. To Lorentz and Poincare the length contraction was a separate
hypothesis. Furthermore, in their theory the contraction hypothesis had
no clear physical meaning due to the lack of operational methods to deter-
mine changes of length - for example, congruence methods fail because
all bodies contract and experiments using light signals were considered as
equivalent to a Michelson-Morley experiment. In addition, there exist
in the ether theory true lengths and velocities relative to the ether that
are not experimentally detectable. The phenomenon of time dilation had
no operational meaning at all in the ether theories where time was an ab-
solute quantity.58
59 See Part 6.5 of Ref. 2 for a discussion of Poincare's analysis of the Lorentz group.
60 Einstein, in 1905, may very well have used the designation Maxwell-Hertz equations
to emphasize his desire not to speculate on the constitution of matter. Hertz's
electrodynamics did not have an atomistic basis; rather, it was an electrodynamics
for matter in bulk. Furthermore Einstein used Hertz's nomenclature for the electric
and magnetic quantities, referring to them as "electric and magnetic forces" (Ref. 24,
p. 52) and giving to them in-principle operational definitions (Ref. 24, p. 54).
61 Ref.24,p.55.
On the History of the Special Relativity Theory 105
ered most perplexing and elaborated upon by all the great electrodynamic-
ists; namely, the determination of the seat of the electromotive force in a
unipolar induction machine.
In Sections 7 and 8 Einstein uses the results of Section 6 and the
new kinematics to solve certain problems concerning radiation in free
space. Invoking the invariance of the phase of a plane wave Einstein, in
Section 7 entitled "Theory of Doppler's Principle and of Aberration,"
solves exactly two problems for which no exact solution could be obtained
in ether-based theories - the optical Doppler effect and stellar aberration.
In Lorentz's theory not only did unknown velocities prevent a complete
solution to these problems, but in addition, even first order observations of
stellar aberration, a phenomenon dependent only upon the relative velocity
of earth and star, required two different dynamical explanations depending
upon whether the effect was observed in a geocentric system or in an ether-
based system. Thus, Einstein has removed yet another asymmetry "not in-
herent in the phenomena."
Einstein begins Section 8 entitled "Transformation of the Energy
of Light Rays. Theory of the Pressure of Radiation Exerted on Perfect
Reflectors," by proving that the ratio of the energy to frequency of a
"light complex", i.e. a light pulse, is invariant. 62 Einstein asserts that this
result is "remarkable."63 Remarkable indeed! For Einstein with a flair for
the understatement, customarily found only in literary works of high distinc-
tion, chose not to refer the reader to the principal result in his first publica-
tion in Volume 17 of the Annalen der Physik. 64 There, Einstein had demon-
strated that light obeying Wien's law of radiation can be described as an en-
semble of independent particles or pulses whose ratio of energy to frequency
is a universal constant ~ namely Planck's constant. Einstein continues in
Section 8 by solving exactly the two old problems of the reflection of light
from a moving perfectly reflecting mirror, and the pressure of light on the
moving mirror. His matter-of-fact solution, in two short paragraphs, belies
the importance of these problems to the physics of 1905, for they were
considered central to the thermodynamics of radiation. In fact, these pro-
blems could be solved exactly in Lorentz's ether-based theory of electro-
magnetism as Abraham had demonstrated in 1904; however, Abraham's
long path winds torturously through the forty odd pages of his then well-
known paper.6S Furthermore, although the Einstein and Abraham solutions
are mathematically equivalent, they are not observationally equivalent due
to the presence of unknown velocities relative to the ether in Abraham's
work.
In Section 9 entitled "Transformation of the Maxwell-Hertz Equa-
tions when Convection-Currents are Taken into Account" and 10 Einstein
analyzes the so-called Maxwell-Hertz equations for the case including sources.
The sources are point electrons with a totally mechanical mass. The
Maxwell-Hertz equations that Einstein discusses here are mathematically
equivalent to Eqs. (1) to (4); due to the relativity of simultaneity, the
symbols have a different interpretation. Since he is analyzing the motion
of an electron, Einstein is obliged here to finally write that "these equa-
tions are the electromagnetic basis of the Lorentzian electrodynamics
and optics of moving bodies. "66
Einstein, in Section 10 entitled "Dynamics of the Slowly Accelerated
Electron," takes Newton's second law in its familiar mathematical form as
axiomatic in the instantaneous rest system of an electron in an external
electromagnetic field. Then, by transforming to a laboratory inertial refer-
ence system, Einstein deduces the electron's longitudinal (md and trans-
verse (mT) masses. Einstein's results are:
(29)
(30)
65 M. Abraham, "Zur Theorie der Strahlung und des Strahlungsdruckes," Annalen der
Physik, 14, 236-287 (1904). See Ref. 26 for a discussion of Abraham's paper.
66 Ref. 24, p. 60.
67 M. Planck, "Das Prinzip der Relativitat und die Grundgleichungen der Mechanik,"
Verh. d. p. Ges., 4,136-141 (1906). Until 1911 Einstein's results in the relativity
paper were considered by most physicists as a generalization of Lorentz's theory
of the electron; hence, there was referred to a "Lorentz-Einstein" theory.
On the History of the Special Relativity Theory 107
70 Ref. 51,p.484.
71 In Part V of Ref. 30 entitled "Relativityprinciple and Gravitation." Einstein gener-
alized the principle of relativity to include accelerating reference systems, and pro-
posed what became known as the principle of equivalence.
109
2 Writing to Solovine
In all of Einstein's own writings, one message stands out and is returned
to repeatedly: a model of scientific thinking, and indeed of thinking in gene-
ral. The model forms the core of the first pages of his Autobiographical
Notes,2 which I have analyzed elsewhere. 3 But Einstein's most concise and
graphic rendition of his model is to be found in a letter he wrote to his
friend Maurice Solovine in 1952. I have always thought that for sheer
virtuosity of expression and ability to summarize complex and profound
thoughts, this letter is unique in Einstein's correspondence. It is there-
fore well suited for re-examining his credo, for elaborating on his brief
explanations by reference to others of his publications on the same sub-
ject, and therefore for pulling together many of his methodological ideas
scattered throughout his writings.
2 Einstein wrote the essay in 1946 as the opening article for the book Albert Einstein:
Philosopher-Scientist (Paul A. Schilpp, editor); see Principal References at end of
this essay.
3 G. Holton, "What, Precisely, is 'Thinking'? Einstein's Answer," in A. P. French (ed.),
Centennial volume of the International Commission on Physics Education (in press).
Einstein's Model for Constructing a Scientific Theory 111
Solovine was one of Einstein's oldest friends; they had met in Bern
in 1902, and had kept up a correspondence after Solovine had moved away.
Writing on 25 April 1952, Solovine confesses that he has trouble under-
standing a point made in one of Einstein's essays which Solovine has just
been translating for publication in France. "Would you be so kind," Solo-
vine asks, "as to explain precisely a passage ... which is not quite clear.
You write: The justification (truth content) of the system rests in the
proof of usefulness of the resulting theorems on the basis of sense experien-
ces, where the relations of the latter to the former can only be comprehended
intuitively .... " Solovine indicates his puzzlement and raises questions.
In his reply of 7 May 1952, Einstein starts in his characteristically
relaxed, unpompous manner: "Dear Solo! In your letter you give me a
spanking on the behind ... , but," he continues, "you have thoroughly
misunderstood me with respect to the epistemological matter. Probably
I expressed myself badly." There follows a memorable explanation of the
respective roles of sense experience, intuition, and logic in the functioning
of the imagination. As we shall see, and as one would expect, Einstein
places the emphasis on the sequence of steps in doing science, in making
a discovery or formulating a theory, rather than reformulating the results
later on to make them acceptable to publishers of scientific journals or phil-
osophers interested in the justification of proposed theories.
It will also be noted that while the context of Solovine's question and
Einstein's reply make it clear that Einstein is talking about a model for
thinking in science, nowhere in what follows does he use the word science;
and what fragmentary examples he gives (e.g., relation between the concept
"dog" and the corresponding experiences) are not drawn from scientific
theory. This is entirely in line with his typical refusal to tolerate unnatural
:;lnd unnecessary boundaries. For he said repeatedly that one is dealing here
with a continuum: "Scientific thought is a development of prescientific
thought" (Ideas and Opmions, p. 276); "all this applies as much, and in the
same manner, to the thinking in daily life as to the more consciously and
systematically constructed thinking in the sciences" (Ideas and Opinions
[I.O.], p. 23 ; see also 1.0., p. 324). This point of view was perhaps best caught
in his statement that the "whole of science is nothing more than a refine-
ment of everyday thinking" (1.0., p. 290). Just for that reason, however, the
critical physicist should not restrict his examination of concepts to his own
field of expertise, but should consider "critically a much more difficult
problem, the problem of analyzing the nature of everyday thinking" (ibid.).
Perhaps for this reason Einstein had placed the question "What, precisely, is
'thinking'?" near the beginning of his Autobiographical Notes - and then,
during that discussion, referred only rarely to science.
112 Gerald Holton
Figure 1
process, and Einstein enters on its discussion by laying out the stage where
the process must both begin and end:
"1. The E (experiences) are given to us."
This refers to the horizontal line shown at the bottom of the figure,
marked E and labeled "Multiplicity [or variety] of immediate (sense) expe-
riences." As usual, these come first in his account, just as he had put the
"reception of sense impressions" as the first item after asking "What is
thinking?" in the Autobiographical Notes. And it will have to come in at the
end also, when we return to the level of sense experience to see if our
theory can handle as large a part of the totality of the facts of experience
as possible - which is, after all, the final test of a theory.
The thin line marked E is rather deceptive. One might better visualize
it as an infinite plane on which the separate and diverse sense experiences
or observations that clamor for our attention are laid out, like so many
separate points. It does indeed represent the "totality of empirical fact"
(1.0., p. 271) or "totality of sense experiences" (Schilpp, pp. 11, 12, and
often elsewhere). In themselves the points on this plane are bewildering,
a universe of elements, a veritable "labyrinth of sense impressions" (1.0.,
p. 291) of which, moreover, we never can be completely sure that they
are not "the result of an illusion or hallucination" (ibid.). In fact, the ulti-
mate aim of science can be defined in this manner: "Science is the attempt
to make the chaotic diversity of our sense-experience correspond to a logi-
Einstein's Model for Constructing a Scientific Theory 113
cally uniform [unified 1system of thought" (1.0., p. 323). The chaotic diver-
sity of "facts" is mastered by erecting a structure of thought on it that
points to relations and order: "In this system, single experiences must be
correlated with the theoretic structure in such a way that the resulting
coordination is unique and convincing" (ibid.).
An aside: Nobody had to point out to Einstein that sense experiences
or "observations" are virtually never pure and unvarnished. Even the father
of positivism, Auguste Comte, had written (Positive Philosophy, 1829) that
without a theory of some sort by which to link phenomena to some prin-
ciples "it would not only be impossible to combine the isolated observa-
tions and draw any useful conclusions, we would not even be able to re-
member them, and, for the most part, the fact would not be noticed by
our eyes." Indeed, sometimes Einstein speaks of "experience" or "facts"
in a way very different from what Ernst Mach took to be "elements";
among facts, Einstein in various writings included the impossibility of
perpetual motion machines, inertial motion, the constancy of light velocity,
and the equality of gravitational and inertial mass (1.0., pp. 307, 309; cf.
letter to Besso, quoted in Holton, Thematic Origins, p. 229). Nevertheless,
in their most primitive form the E in Fig. 1 can be thought of as simple
. .
sensory ImpreSSIOns.
structive efforts based on known facts. The longer and more despairingly I
tried, the more I came to the conviction that only the discovery of a univer-
sal formal principle could lead us to assured results" (Schilpp, p. 53).4
4 The schema in the letter to Solovine applies to fashioning Principle Theories. That
does not mean Einstein never fashioned Constructive Theories. An example is, in
fact, the photon theory, including the explanation of the photoelectric effect, which
he had published earlier in 1905. But precisely because he did not view the introduc-
tion of the quantum as anything more fundamental than a "heuristic point of view"
to deal with the problem at hand, he could never bring himself to regard quantum
physics as more than a transient analysis. Only in Theories of Principle, he thought,
are the postulated axioms far enough above the plane of experience, and far enough
from ad hoc reasoning, to yield a creative scheme that can handle the totality of
the facts of experience On Einstein's view concerning Principle Theories versus
Constructive Theories, which he discussed from 1919 on, see 1.0., pp. 228, 302-303,
318-319, and Holton, Thematic Origins. pp. 230,252,316 and 348.
116 Gerald Holton
To the same end, Einstein also reminded his readers frequently (e.g.,
1.0., p. 298) of the fatal error that had been made for so long in thinking
that the basis of Euclidean geometry was logically necessary; this error was
caused by forgetting the empirical base and hence the limited experiential
context within which all concepts are fashioned. A similar illusion was the
great obstacle to formulating the Special Relativity Theory (1.0., pp. 298-
299), namely that there exists a universal time applicable to all events in
space as a whole, a concept of time long held to be an a priori given, neces-
sary conception, seemingly independent from our sense experience. This
error was caused by forgetting that the r.otion of time itself arises initially
in our everyday experience by watching sequences of events happening at
one locality, rather than in all of space.
Deprived of any certainty that our concepts have a necessary connec-
tion with the corresponding experiences, we begin to see the precariousness
of the business of theory construction. But we can do no better. We create
new concepts, perhaps suggested at first only tentatively, and gather them
together with old concepts whose usefulness has been tested in previous
struggles, knowing that neither one nor the other is sacred and unchangeable,
neither induced nor in any other way securely abstracted from the plane of
experiences below. It may be that this discontinuity is symbolized by the
small gap in the drawing between the horizontal line E and the arc rising from
that region to A above.
There is a second logical discontinuity which also enters to make it
a "mistake to permit theoretical description to be directly dependent upon
acts of empirical assertions" (Schilpp, p. 674). This concerns the relation
of concepts to one another when they are used together to make a system
of axioms - for example, some postulated laws of nature ("propositions
expressing a relationship among primary concepts" 1.0., p. 293). Not only
each individual concept, but the whole "system of concepts is a creation
of man" (Schilpp, p. 13), achieved in a "free play," the justification for
which lies only in the pragmatic success of the scheme being built up to
give ultimately a "measure of survey over the experience of the senses
which we are able to achieve with its aid" (Schilpp, p. 7).
The two-fold discontinuity, then, is a good part of the reason why
Einstein repeats, again and again, sentences like this one from 1918: "There
is no logical path to these elementary laws; only intuition, supported by
being sympathetically in touch with experience [Einfiihlung in die Erfah-
rungj" (1.0., p. 226). The repeated insistence was in good part in opposition
to the then current form of positivism, which, for example, saw the goal
of scientific work to be the economic statement of relations among obser-
vables. To this day, Einstein's formulation causes hostility from some
philosophical quarters, which insist on exaggerating this particular element
in Einstein's total schema. (On the other hand, it should also be said that
Einstein's Model for Constructing a Scientific Theory 117
5 However, Mach, with W Ostwald, is scolded by Einstein (Schilpp, p.49) for his
"positivistic philosophical attitude" which misled them into opposing atomic theory.
They were victims of "philosophical prejudice," chiefly "the faith that facts by
themselves can and should yield scientific knowledge without free conceptual con-
struction. "
118 Gerald Holton
of his later essays. Therefore, one might elaborate the diagram in Fig. 1 by
drawing thin, vertical lines between E and A, to indicate that such connec-
tions are made whenever we choose the convention or "meaning" assigned
to a term that is part of the scientific (or any) vocabulary.
The other constraint on our choice of concepts - even though they
"have a purely fictious character," being the "free inventions of the human
intellect, which cannot be justified either by the nature of that intellect or
in another fashion a priori" (1.0., p. 272) - lies in Einstein's call for fruga-
lity and simplicity. After all, the aim of any good theoretical system is "the
greatest possible sparsity of the logically independent elements (basic con-
cepts and axioms)" (Schilpp, p. 13). Any redundancy or elaboration must
be avoided, for "it is the grand object of all theory to make these irreducible
elements as simple and as few in number as possible" (1.0., p. 273). For
example, it was, in his view, "an unsatisfactory feature of classical mechanics
that in its fundamental laws the same mass appears in two different roles,
namely as inertial mass in the laws of motion, and as gravitational mass in
the law of gravitation" (1.0., p. 308). The equivalence of these two inter-
pretations of mass signaled to him a truth which needed to be stated as a
basic axiom (in General Relativity Theory), rather than saddling the theory
with a proliferation which did not seem to be inherent in the phenomena.
In good part as a result of Einstein's own work and example, physical
scientists have indeed succeeded in showing, during this century, that only
a very small number of postulated fundamental laws, employing a sur-
prisingly small number of fundamental concepts, are needed to encompass
("explain") at least in principle an ever-growing infinity of separate facts of
experience. This does not mean at all that everything is explained, or even in
principle already explainable; but still, it is a "wonder," and a motivation
for further work. This success also has some curious consequences, to which
we shall return later.
One corrolary of this method of hypothesizing is that during the period
of constructing a theory the innovator must give his proposed "jump" to the
axioms a chance to prove itself. Hence in this early and usually private stage
of theorizing the researcher has to grant himself a freedom, the right of "sus-
pension of disbelief," a moratorium on premature attempts at falsification
(i. e., on attempts to discredit the hypothesized postulate by disproving it). 6
6 For a discussion of the concept of "suspension of disbelief," see Holton, The Scien-
tific Imagination: Case Studies (New York and Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. 1978), pp.71-72. Even the "dean" of logical positivists of his day, Hans
Reichenbach, might have agreed, for he said "The physicist who is looking for new
discoveries must not be too critical; in the initial stages he is dependent on guess-
ing, and he will find his way only if he is carried along by a certain faith which
serves as a directive for his guesses," etc. (Schilpp, p. 292). But he went on to deny
that such mechanisms can or should be of interest to "the philosopher of science."
Einstein's Model for Constructing a Scientific Theory 119
7 Stud. Hist. Phil. Sci. 8 (I 977), pp. 49-60. See also P. Mittlestaedt, "Conventionalism
in Special Relativity." Foundations of Physics. 7 (1977), pp. 573-583.
120 Gerald Holton
Some who have criticized Einstein's remarks as giving too much weight
to intuition and other logically speculative concepts have tended to overlook
the definite role which Einstein did give to the logical phase of the scientific
imagination. If he argues for recognizing the necessary inspirational compo-
nent in the formation of fundamental hypotheses at the level of A, he also
goes on to say "the structure of the system is the work of reason" (1.0.,
p. 272). This part of the scientist's work, where inference follows inference,
requires "much intense, hard thinking," (1.0., p. 282) but at least is a task
that one can learn in principle "at school" (1.0., p. 221). It is only the earlier
step, that of establishing the principles in the first place from which deduc-
tion can proceed, for which "there is no method capable of being learned
and systematically applied .... the scientist has to worm these general prin-
ciples out of nature" (ibid.).
What then can one expect to be the proper relation between the 5
and the E in an adequate theory, at least one of the more ambitious kind
that was of interest to Einstein, a theory whose object is the "totality
8 W. Heisenberg, Physics and Beyond (New York: Harper and Row, 1971), p. 63.
122 Gerald Holton
What can this other ground be? What can make a theory more appealing
or less so, other than the criterion of "external validation"? The answer
is given by Einstein's second criterion for subjecting a theory to a critique.
He called it the criterion of "inner perfection," and it concerns itself with
choosing the superstructure in the EjASE scheme, namely, the j, A, and
S. One must remember that there is no guarantee in a given case that the
elements of a theory are unique. It often happens that two quite diffe-
rent theories, with different J. A, and S, arise out of concern with the same
material of experience, and moreover give equally good correspondence
between their sets of S and the relevant sense experiences. The most famous
case is of course that of Ptolemaic theory and the theory of Copernicus in
the 16th Century. While different with respect to their basic axioms, both
theories arose out of the need to account for the same regularities and ir-
regularities in E, in the observed motion of celestial bodies, and the predic-
tions derivable from both theories had about the same degree of correspon-
dence with the observables.
Einstein's second criterion was frankly stated in his Autobiographical
Notes. "The second point of view is not concerned with the relation to
the material of observation but with the premises of the theory itself,
with what may briefly but vaguely be characterized as the 'naturalness'
or 'logical simplicity' of the premises (of the basic concepts and of the
relations between these which are taken as a basis)" (Schilpp, p. 23).
This of course is not an entirely new idea; Einstein acknowledges
that it "has played an important role in the selection and evaluations of
theories since time immemorial." But in practice, the requirement of natu-
ralness or logical simplicity, or "unity and parsimony" (1.0., p. 23) has
never been easy to follow. Einstein is warning here to stay clear of theories
that are patched up by ad hoc assumptions introduced just to make the de-
ductions correspond better to the facts of experience as they continue to
come in. "For it is often, perhaps even always, possible to adhere to a
general theoretical foundation by securing the adaptation of the theory
to the facts by means of artificial additional assumptions" (Schilpp, pp. 21-
23). Early in his career, Einstein had considered Lorentz's theory of the
electron as just such a patchwork in the sense that it avoided factual discon-
firmation only by introducing assumptions specially chosen for this very
purpose (introduction of length contraction to explain absence of predicted
effect in the ether-drift experiment). This practice could be represented by
124 Gerald Holton
A1
JC~s,- ,
*
S' SOl
, I
I
E * E1
t
E2
E----~---±--------+_
* E1 *E2 E3
Schema C1 Schema C2
Figure 2
sensory reports made available by cloud chambers, counters, and the like.
To believe that this program is right "is logically possible without contra-
diction; but it is so very contrary to my scientific instinct that I cannot
forego the search for a more complete conception" (1.0., p. 318; and also
often similarly, e.g., 1.0., p. 316; letters to Max Born, discussion with
Niels Bohr, etc.). This search for a more complete conception, he knew,
might be doomed. "In the end the choice will be made [by the profession
as a whole 1 according to which kind of description yields the formulation
of the simplest foundation, logically speaking." But until the evidence is
irresistible, he considered it his right to abstain from "the view that events
in nature are analogous to a game of chance. It is open to every man to
choose the direction of his striving" (1.0., pp. 334-335).
Einstein's use of the colorful words "instinct," "striving," "intuition"
or "wonder" was not intended as a calculated provocation of some scien-
tists or philosophers, but is has had this effect nevertheless. To make matters
worse, he referred to yet another process of importance in the growth of
theories, known to every practicing scientist but difficult to define. For
even though he acknowledged that these two criteria of "external valida-
tion" and "internal perfection" defied precise description, he held that
among the "augurs," those who deal deeply with physical theory, there
nevertheless exists at any given time agreement in judging the degree of
external validation and inner perfection (cf. Schilpp, pp.23-25). Once
more, the absence of an air-tight definition did not preclude him from
putting his bet on the usefulness of a concept, in this case that of consensus
in groups within the scientific community.
ideas, and so to see how they can serve to handle other problems of theory
construction and the scientific imagination. As in science itself, our belief in
a scheme increases if we find that it is not merely ad hoc for covering the
area within which it was specifically proposed but is successful beyond it.
There are specifically two problems that Einstein's schema can help us with:
how scientific theories grow and give way to other theories, and how to
understand better the controversies involving fundamentally different
theories that claim to deal with the same experimental facts.
We noted that the schema in Fig. 1 is not a static one, but is a process
which makes a cycle from E via j, A, 5, back to E. But a theory can hardly
be created and tested by going through the cycle once. Even the theories
by which we orient ourselves in our day-to-day life, and a fortiori the estab-
lished theories of science which we honor and use as tools that have come
down to us from earlier workers and controversies, are all the results of
cycles of progressive adaptation, making them more acceptable by using
the feedback from one cycle to modify the next. Moreover, this process
of modification and growth will continue as new phenomena are found that
enlarge the original area of application. Physics is constantly "in a state of
evolution .... Evolution is proceeding in the direction of increasing simpli-
city of the logical basis" (1.0., p. 322).
The need to go through many cycles (C 1 -+ C2 -+ C3 ••• ) of the EjA5E
process is forced on us, if by nothing else, by our human limitations. Neither
thought by itself nor sensory experience by itself leads to reliable human
knowledge. For concepts can be subjected to analysis which gives us cer-
tainty of the kind "by which we are so much impressed in mathematics;
but this certainty is purchased at the price of emptiness of content" (1.0.
pp. 276-277). On the other hand, sense experience cannot be related to the
concepts, as we have seen, except by adopting essentially arbitrary defini-
tions (conventions), and hence they cannot claim certainty either. The best
we can therefore do is to let whatever trustworthiness there is in our theory
construction come out of the interplay of thought and sense experience
through many cycles, carried out over time. Theories therefore have to be
"thoroughly elaborated" (1.0., p. 282) and have to evolve - first in the mind
of the innovator before publication and then in the community of scientists
through discussion or controversy.
For example, in going through the first cycle of the schema, the 5 of
the theory at that stage (SI, S~, S~' ... ) may show an incomplete correlation
with the "facts" in the E plane. Einstein gives an example which, he says,
is one of the considerations which "kept me busy from 1907 to 1911": in
his early attempts to generalize relativity theory, "the acceleration of a
Einstein's Model for Constructing a Scientific Theory 127
falling body was not independent of its horizontal velocity or the internal
energy of the system," contrary to the "old experimental fact" (1.0., p. 287).
A discrepancy of this sort forces one to rethink the A, modifying the original
axiom system At to become a somewhat different one,A 2 •
We recall that Einstein warned that such modification should be made
not in a merely ad hoc. burte-force way, but for example by recasting the
axiom system into a more generalized form that permits more deductions
S2, S;, S;' ... that can be correlated with the E, and if possible from fewer
independent concepts. Thus Einstein was able to go from the first principle
of restricted relativity theory, that all natural laws must be so conditioned
that they are covariant with respect to Lorentz's transformations, to the
first principle of general relativity theory, that natural laws are to be for-
mulated in such a way that their form is identical for coordinate systems
of any kind of states of motion. (1.0., pp. 329~330). In this way Einstein
removed his dissatisfactions with the special nature of the original relativity
theory, namely that it referred only to systems in uniform motion to which
no absolute significance could be attached. The introduction of the principle
of equivalence removed the contradiction between the predicted acceleration
of a falling body and the observed one, as well as removing an unneccessary
duplication (two meanings of mass, as referred to above).
Fig. 3 represents schematically the progress from the early state of
a theory to a later state, from C1 to C2 and from C2 to C3 • Here C3 could
stand for the next step which Einstein saw needed after his success in fash-
ioning general relativity theory; for he felt that "the theory could not rest
permanently satisfied with this success .... The idea that there exist two
structures of space independent of each other, the metric-gravitational and
the electromagnetic, was intolerable to the theoretical spirit" (1.0., p. 285).
Hence, Einstein's persistent attempt to fashion a field theory that corres-
ponds to a "unified structure of space" (ibid.). Again and again, the word
"unity" beckons as Einstein's final goal ~ "seeking, as far as possible, logical
unity in the world picture, i.e., paucity in logical elements" (1.0., p. 293);
"thus the story goes on until we have arrived at a system of the greatest
conceivable unity, and of the greatest poverty of concepts of the logical
foundations, which is still compatible with the observations made by our
senses" (1.0., p. 294).
, s'2"
E-----+-----4----~~----~
E, E4
t
Schema C,
Figure 3
128 Gerald Holton
5
5" I I I I
I I I I I
E E t t I t
El E2 E3 E4 E5 *
Figure 4 Figure 5
10 The commo nly agreed-upon structure of writing scientific papers for publication,
which makes it seem that the gathering of data and induction from them formed
the beginning of scientific work, has prompted P. B. Medawar to call the scien-
tific paper a "fraud" and a "travesty of the nature of scientific thought." P. B.
Medawar, "Is the Scientific Paper a Fraud?," The Listener (1963), pp. 377-378.
130 Gerald Holton
That is, they give us, to use Einstein's phrase, an "overview" by which the
multiplicity of immediate sense experiences of the most diverse kinds are
brought into a unified and therefore understandable scheme.
The next stage in the historic progress of science occurs when a unifi-
cation of two or more theory systems is forged, as when Galileo joined
terrestrial and celestial physics, or when Maxwell produced a synthesis
of electricity, magnetism and optics. Before unification or synthesis, each
of the theory systems has its own system of concepts, and while they might
be closer to experience than the concepts after unification, they lack unity
among their different fundamental postulates within which they are em-
bedded (cf. 1.0., p. 302). In terms of our graphic shorthand, what happens
is symbolized by Fig. 6. On the left side, the separate axiom systems for the
fields of electricity, magnetism,. and optics dominate the respective systems
that sit, like separate pyramids, upon their corresponding territories on the
E plane. After Maxwell's synthesis, the separate axiom systems become
merely special cases of a more general one, incorporating Maxwell's equa-
tions. The separations between the three areas on the plane of phenomena
disappear, the sets of facts previously connected become part of one larger
set, and their theoretical description has thereby been simplified (cf., 1.0.,
p.223).
The same symbolization would be appropriate for many of the great
advances of science, for example, the work of P. A. M. Dirac in the late
1920s by which large areas of both physics and chemistry were brought
under the control of quantum mechanics. In our time, the current attempts
to unify the basic forces of nature is another chapter in this drive to en-
compass eventually the totality of E, all points on the E plane, in terms
of the fewest possible independent axiom systems. It was of course Einstein's
Figure 6
Einstein's Model for Constructing a Scientific Theory 131
hope through field theory to establish a unified foundation for the whole
of physics (cf., 1.0., pp. 328-329). Einstein put this aim very clearly: "From
the very beginning there has always been present the attempt to find a
unifying theoretical basis for all these single sciences, consisting of a mini-
mum of concepts and fundamental relationships, from which all the con-
cepts and relationships of the single disciplines might be derived by [aJ
logical process. This is what we mean by the search for a foundation of
the whole of physics. The confident belief that this ultimate goal might be
reached is the chief source of the passionate devotion which has always
animated the researcher" (1.0., p. 324). It may well be that the ability to
carry in mind the entities and relations symbolized in the right-hand portion
of Fig. 6 is what it means to "have a Weltbild," to have a mental picture of
the physical universe.
We now must come back to deal with an important point which was
left open. The problem can be put as follows: Since the leap from E to A
at the beginning of the schema in Fig. 1 is logically discontinuous and
represents the "free play" of imagination, and since from such a leap can
result an infinite number of A - virtually all of which will turn out to
be useless for the construction of the theory system - how can one ever
expect to be successful in this process except by chance? The answer must
be that the license implied in the J process is the freedom to make a leap,
not the freedom to make any leap at random. Something must guide or
channel J if only because the premises later must pass such tests as those
of naturalness and simplicity in order to meet Einstein's second criterion
for a good theory.
The chief guide is a constraint that shapes the work of every scientist
engaged in a major work on novel ground: the constraint provided by
explicit or, more usually, implicit preferences, preconceptions, presuppo-
sitions. Einstein himself recognized and commented on this repeatedly:
"If the researcher went about his work without any preconceived opinion,
how should he be able at all to select out those facts from the immense
abundance of the most complex experience, and just those which are simple
enough to permit lawful connections to become evident?"l1 By way of
example, he discussed the dilemma that, in formulating the laws of mecha-
nics, one has to follow either the "natural tendency of mechanics to as-
sume .. , material points," which necessarily leads to the presupposition of
81.... .---r--,
8;
82 -+ ~---+,..---i
E
Figure 7
The EJASE schema as now completed lends itself very well to repre-
sent the situation that arises when two different theories claim to handle
about the same experiential material. Thus Einstein often stressed that
his relativistic mechanics, at least in the early years, overlapped with Newto-
nian mechanics with respect to the range of testable experience, even though
the theories corresponded to "two essentially different principles" (1.0.,
p.273).
In analyzing controversies between rival explanations drawn from the
same ground of available experience - most recently the controversy bet-
ween Millikan and Ehrenhaft on the existence of the unitary charge of
electricity 12 - it has been evident to me that the difference of choices of the-
mata by the rivals explains a good deal of the details of their theories and of
the course of the controversy. In very abbreviated form, Fig. 8 will help to
make this point. On the left appears Al as the axiom system reached by
the first of two innovators. His themata are symbolized by eI' The sy-
stem of propositions gives rise to deductions S I, S~, S~, S~', as shown.
To most of these, there correspond observations (E I , E 2 , E 3 ) which can
be correlated with the deductions. As is usual, some deductions (st) re-
main, at least for the time being, without such "verifications," although
work may be in progress on just such a problem at that point.
The second innovator is represented by the system on the right side
of the figure. His axiom system A2 was reached through preliminary no-
tions passing through the constraint indicated by e2, his own set of the-
mata. The system A 2 as a whole is not so utterly different from A I on
the left side that there is not some overlap between the deductions made
Figure 8
by the two innovators. Thus the deductions 52' 5; of the second person
refer to the same phenomena Eland E 2 , at least as far as can be deter-
mined at the time, as do 51 and 5~ . In addition, however, A2 allows deduc-
tion 5; for which there is no equivalent in the first system and which claims
to be correlated with ("borne out by") E4 .
Something like this is how a scientific dispute can continue for some
time. Al or A2 or both may, in the course of the debate, be progressively
modified, with corresponding changes in 51 and 52' Eventually, one or
the other of the two systems wins out, and this happens usually in one of
two ways. The two theory systems, separately, may come to a point of
development where there is no essential difference in the number and
types of phenomena (experimental evidences) which they can handle.
That is, perhaps by some ad hoc adjustment of A 2 , it too "can account
for" E 3 . If this situation persists for some time, a choice is made between
the two systems on the basis of the "appeal" of the fundamental presuppo-
sitions. This comes down to having the preponderance of the scientific
community making a choice on the basis of preferring the system of the-
mata 8 1 or 8 2 , Thus, in the early period when Einstein's relativity theory
could not be clearly distinguished from Lorentz's or Abraham's by any
significant differences in their testable predictions, Max Planck was driven
to exclaim in a scientific meeting, when pressed to confess why he believed
in Einstein's postulate system rather than its rivals: "I find it more conge-
nial" ["Mir ist das ... eigentlich sympatischer"J. 13
An alternative scenario is for one of the two systems to produce more
verifiable predictions of observable events than the other, and fewer (or no)
uncomfortable disconfirmations. Almost never is the situation so clean that
the inability of one theory system to handle a specific experiment produces
right away a decision in its disfavor. What is much more likely is that during
the period when attempts are made to account for apparent difficulties, the
balance of opinion swings toward one of the systems in favor of the other,
and the latter slowly fades from view without necessarily ever being "dis-
proved."
***
The model implied in Einstein's schema can be shown to be useful
in further, fruitful extensions, helping us to understand additional details of
the working of the scientific imagination. That is a task for another occasion.
By having gathered together Einstein's own expressed views, and having tried
to correlate them with the schema he himself proposed, we have found a
consistent prescription for one way the human mind may puzzle out the
order behind the appearances, and for communicating that perception to
others in a convincing manner.
Despite this grand ambition we must not think that Einstein in this
field, any more than in his science, attempted to impose an absolutistic
point of view. He was all too aware of the tentative state of understanding
in the field of scientific methodology. The spirit in which he proposed his
ideas is well conveyed in a passage in his Autobiographical Notes, imme-
diately after he has begun to give his answer to the question "What, preci-
sely, is 'thinking'?":
"With what right .~. the reader will ask - does this man operate so
carelessly and primitively with ideas in such a problematic realm without
making even the least effort to prove anything? My defense: all our thinking
is of this nature of a free play with concepts; the justification for this play
lies in the measure I Ubersicht lover the experience of the senses which we
are able to achieve with its aid" (Schilpp, p. 7).
As limited human beings confronting the seemingly endless, interlock-
ing puzzles of the universe, we can nevertheless hope to play - as in New-
ton's metaphor, with pebbles at the shore of a vast ocean. If we do it well,
that play can yield the most highly desirable kind of knowledge: a survey
(overview, Ubersicht) of the world of nature that grants us the perception of
order guiding the phenomena in their infinite, individual variety, and in their
inexhaustible interactions with one another.
Acknowledgement
I wish to express my indebtedness to Miss Helen Dukas and the Estate of Albert
Einstein for help and for permissions to cite from the publications of Einstein. I am
happy to acknowledge research support by grants from the National Science Founda-
tion and the National Endowment for Humanities.
136 Gerald Holton
Principal References
Albert Einstein, Ideas and Opinions, new translations and revisions by Sonja Barg-
mann (New York: Crown Publishers, Inc., 1954, and, with somewhat different pagina-
tion, New York: Dell Publishing Co., 1954). These essays are based on Mein Weltbild,
a collection of Einstein's essays, edited by Carl Seelig, and other sources.
Among the essays specifically cited in this article are the following (all in Crown edi-
tion): "Remarks on Bertrand Russell's Theory of Knowledge," 1944 (pp. 18-24)
"A Mathematician's Mind," 1945 (Letter to J. S. Hadamard) (pp. 25-26)
"Principles of Theoretical Physics," 1914 (pp. 220-223)
"Principles of Research," 1918 (better: "Motive of Research") (pp. 224-227)
"What is the Theory of Relativity?," 1919 (pp. 227-232)
"Geometry and Experience," 1921 (pp. 232-246)
"On the Method of Theoretical Physics," 1933 (Herbert Spencer Lecture) (pp. 270-276)
"The Problem of Space, Ether, and the Field in Physics," 1930-1934 (pp. 276-285)
"Physics and Reality," 1936 (pp. 290-323)
"The Fundaments of Theoretical Physics," 1940 (pp. 323-33 5)
"On the Generalized Theory of Gravitation," 1950 (pp. 341-356)
Paul Schilpp, editor, Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist (Evanston, Illinois:
The Library of Living Philosophers, 1949). This book includes (pp. 3-94) Einstein's
"Autobiographical Notes," a number of excellent essays on Einstein's work by scientists
and philosophers, and (pp. 665-688) a set of supplementary comments by Einstein. The
"Autobiographical Notes" are scheduled to be published in 1979 as a separate book,
under the editorship of P. A. Schilpp and Otto Nathan.
Albert Einstein and Leopold Infeld, The Evolution of Physics (New York: Simon
and Schuster, 1938).
Albert Einstein, Lettres aMaurice Solovine (Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 1956).
Philipp Frank, Einstein, His Life and Times (New York: A. A. Knopf, 1947).
Banesh Hoffmann, Albert Einstein, Creator and Rebel, with the collaboration
of Helen Dukas (New York: The Viking Press, 1972).
Gerald Holton, The Scientific Imagination: Case Studies (New York and Cam-
bridge: Cambridge University Press, 1978), chapters 1-3.
Gerald Holton, Thematic Origins of Scientific Thought: Kepler to Einstein (Cam-
bridge: Harvard University Press, 1973), chapters 5-10.
137
I.
of the search for invisible, but, according to the Platonic axiom, real mecha-
nisms which save the phenomena. From a logical point of view it is always
justified, when a theory fails, to doubt its methodological basis. The doubt
concerning the Aristotelian principle to use in astronomy representational
theories that can be interpreted realistically, led to Ptolemai's phenomenalistic
approach, i. e., to a theory which used the empirical material for prognosis
in an instrumentalistic way, but could not produce true explanations of the
actual movements of the celestial bodies 3 • This methodology was changed
by Copernicus. He took up Aristarch's and Seleukos' bold conjecture that
the queer paths of the planets are accidental features due to the terrestrial
human perspective. They can be understood causally, if one can make up
one's mind to accept unobservable processes, namely, the three forms of
the earth's motion.
This controversy is even more clearly reflected in the two methodologi-
cal positions in the history of atomism. Democrites tried to formulate his
epistemological idea that the visible world can be explained through ac-
cretion of a small number of transempirical objects. The spatial arrange-
ment and the kind of connection between the micro-objects were to re-
produce the known structures on the level of perception. The development
of the atom-hypothesis shows clearly that the mechanism of the connection
of the elementary constituents, as well as the linkage of the atomic complexes
with the level of phenomena were so poorly defined that its methodology
could not be trusted. The evidence became more convincing, however, when
Berzelius discovered the electrical nature of the chemical binding forces and
Dalton confirmed the connection with the (chemical) phenomenological level
through the law of multiple proportions. But even then, only indirect hints
at the invisible microscopic level resulted therefrom; they can only be referred
to as derived but not as direct evidence. 4 Therefore the opponents of the
atom-hypothesis - grounding their arguments on a positivistic epistemology -
could easily make a case for treating the atoms as useful fictitious concepts
having only the syntactical auxiliary function (as mentioned earlier) to link
certain sense data but do not have any (referential)meaning.
How strong the influence of the empiricist methodology was at that
time can be inferred from the fact that even Planck doubted initially the
reliability of the atomic hypothesis. He changed his mind only when he had
to make use of the probabilistic assumption of the molecular kinetic theory
in the derivation of his radiation law. 5 Only a few scientists were able to
evade the influence of the Mach-Kirchhoff descriptivism which emphasized
II.
10 S. G. Brush: A History of Random Processes I. Arch. Hist. Exact Sci. 5 (1969), p. 35.
idem: Mach and Atomism Synthese 18, 213 (1968), p. 208.
11 M. Planck: Zur Theorie des Gesetzes der Energieverteilung im Normalspektrum, in:
Dokumente der Naturwissenschaft, ed. by A. Hermann, vol. 12, Stuttgart, 1969,
p.25-33.
12 Cf. B. Kanitscheider: Die Philosophie der modernen Physik, Section II: Sprache und
Erkenntnis, Darmstadt, 1979.
142 Bernulf Kanitscheider
13 Ober einen die Erzeugung und Verwandlung des Lichtes betreffenden heuristischen
Gesichtspunkt, Ann. Phys. 17 (1905), p. 132-148.
14 Cf. Dokumente der Naturwissenschaft, ed. by A. Hermann, vol. 7, Stuttgart, 1965,
p.13.
15 Jon Dorling: Einstein's Introduction of Photons. Argument by Analogy or Deduction
from the Phenomena, Brit. J. Phil. Sci. 22 (1971), p. 1-8.
16 A. Einstein: Autobiographical Notes, I. c.
Einstein's Treatment of Theoretical Concepts 143
matter is the site of the charges only, and the field is between the charged
matter. Einstein considered it unsatisfactory, however, that both the concept
of material points and of continuous fields were used as primitive terms
even within electromagnetism:
"If one views this phase of the development of theory critically, one is
struck by the dualism which lies in the fact that the material point in
Newton's sense and the field as continuum are used as elementary concepts
side by side. Kinetic energy and field-energy appear as essentially different
things. This appears all the more unsatisfactory inasmuch as, according to
Maxwell's theory, the magnetic field of a moving electric charge represents
inertia. Why not then total inertia? Then only field-energy would be left,
and the particle would be merely an area of special density of field-energy.
In that case one could hope to deduce the concept of the mass-point
together with the equations of the motion of the particles from the field
equations - the disturbing dualism would have been removed."17
This ontological dualism cannot be avoided within the framework of
a linear theory based on the principle of superposition. Thus his metaphysical
search for unification is likely to be one of the sources of Einstein's pref-
erence for non-linear theories in which not only the properties of the basic
elements but also their interaction can be described.
In order to arrive at the light quantum-hypothesis Einstein 18 used
three theoretical laws: the statistical law WI = (vlvo)n [which gives the
probability to find n particles contained in a volume Vo in the smaller
volume v], Wien's law p (v) = <xv 3 e- hvlkT [the limit of Planck's law for large
values of vlT] and the Boltzmann relation between entropy and probability
S = k ·log W [here statistical assumptions enter, e. g. in the collision term]. A
number of logical steps lead from these theoretical elements to an expression
for the probability W 2 = (vlvo)Elhv of finding the total energy of radiation
at any moment in a partial volume v. From the structural analogy of the
expressions WI and W 2 he concludes the (semantic referential) identity of
the exponents: E = n h v. I n the key sentence of his paper Einstein still uses
the fictionalistic interpretation of the light quanta: "Monochromatic radiation
of low density ... acts from the point of view of thermodynamics, as if it
consisted of mutually independent energy quanta of the size h v." 19 He then
explains some effects which were previously not understood (the dependence
of the energy of the electrons emitted in the photo-electric effect on the wave-
length, Stokes' rule for fluorescence, the release of secondary cathode rays
with unchanged velocity), and thereby strengthens his belief in the auto-
nomous existence of light quanta.
It becomes even more apparent that photons were new theoretical
entities sui generis which were to be given their own position within physical
ontology when Einstein studied the question of statistical fluctuations in a
radiation field. 20 It turned out that the restrictive interpretation of the
photon concept advocated by Planck 21 was untenable. Planck intended to
use the photon concept only for processes of emission and absorption and
considered it to be a stop-gap which had to be used for epistemic reasons
such as the far-reaching ignorance of the interaction between matter and
the radiation field. It turned out to be necessary, however, to accept the
permanent existence of photons and the universal occurrence of radiation
in multiples of h v. Otherwise one cannot ullderstand the fluctuation equation
for the energy (e 2 )112 dv = (h v + c 3 pl8 7r v2 ) 7rV d v, which Einstein derived for
a mirror which can rotate freely within a radiation field cavity. This result is
remarkable in two respects: it shows that fluctuations consist, on the one
hand, of one component following from the classical wave theory of light;
i. e. fluctuations of the radiation pressure exist because wave packets inter-
fere with one another. On the other hand, there is an extra term which is
due to the reflection of light quanta, and only the combination of both
effects leads to the correct average energy! kT of the mirror. "This way of
looking at the problem showed in a drastic and direct way that a type of
immediate reality has to be ascribed to Planck's quanta, that radiation must,
therefore, possess a kind of molecular structure in energy, which of course
contradicts Maxwell's theory. "22 The fluctuation equation is remarkable in
still another respect. It contains the first hint to the phenomenon of duality
which was later the starting point for many interpretations of quantum
theory, since neither the elements of the particle theory nor of the wave
theory can be eliminated from the fluctuation expression.
It is often stated that Einstein's early work was influenced by the
philosophy of science prevailing at that time towards phenomenalism,
operationalism, or positivism, while his later work, starting with general
relativity, was dominated by critical realism, a sense of objectivity, and
the necessity of speculation. The examples given above from Einstein's
early work lead to the impression that no such break in his methodology
exists. The alleged change in Einstein's epistemological position was often
noted and considered to be negative, possibly seen in connection with the
failure of the field theoretic program which Einstein worked on in his later
years. In this negative way the change of position was interpreted mainly by
Bridgman:
''That in his conviction of the possibility of getting away from any
special co-ordinate system, in his conviction of the fruitfulness of so doing,
and in his treatment of the event as something primitive and unanalyzed, he
has carried into general relativity theory precisely that uncritical, pre-
Einsteinian point of view which he has so convincingly shown us, in his
special theory, conceals the possibility of disaster. "23
In the same way it is still seen by many theoreticians:
"The founder of the 'dualistic' interpretation was Albert Einstein,
more accurately the younger Einstein, who did not speculate as he did in
his later years, but analyzed the empirical data with great acuteness and
derived unassailable conclusions therefrom. "24 Is the assertion of a method-
ological break really correct?
It is true that an operationalistic language is used in the first five
paragraphs of the paper "On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies", i. e.,
in the so-called kinematical part of his fundamental paper on special rel-
ativity. In the short introduction Einstein makes some statements, however,
on his heuristic principles from which a completely different epistemological
position becomes apparent. He is irritated mainly by the asymmetries of
Maxwell's theory, which seem to have no counterpart in experience, and
are present when the theory is applied to moving systems. The theory deals
with the interaction between a magnet and a conductor in a different way,
depending whether the conductor or the magnet is moving with respect to
absolute space (represented by the ether), although the relative state of
motion is the same. It is true that Einstein also mentions an experiment
- the unsuccessful attempts to measure the motion of the earth relative to
the ether 25 - in support of the conjecture that an absolute system of ref-
erence is singled out neither by mechanics nor by electrodynamics. The
decisive step is taken, however, when Einstein raises the conjecture that the
fundamental laws of mechanics and electrodynamics have the same form in
all systems of reference which are moving uniformly with respect to one
another, to the state of a principle. From this principle and the postulate
(1) The co-ordinates of two inertial systems are related by Galilei trans-
formations.
(2) The laws of nature are independent of the choice of the inertial system.
(3) The velocity of light has the same constant value in every inertial
system.
III.
reference and may refer to objects of a completely different type than those
given by the set of test instances (empirical evidence). This agrees with the
fundamental postulate of hypothetical realism mentioned in the first section.
A classical example for this are the statements about our past in which the
reference object is inaccessible for nomological reasons (the world in which
we live contains no causal loops). A glaciological hypothesis, for instance,
contains the statement that the last alpine glacial period took place about
9,000 years ago. The statement contained in this hypothesis refers to an
object which no longer exists (the high level of glaciers at that time),
but can be checked by a finite set of observations concerning glacial
polishing and moraine deposits. A causal connection has to be assumed,
of course, between the traces we find from the past and the past events
themselves. In our example this is the dynamics of the creation or moraines,
but this can be tested in the present time because we can observe directly
from presently advancing glaciers the displacement of rock as well as the
process of glacial polishing.
Even beyond the realm of statements concerning the past it has turned
out to be meaningful to distinguish clearly between the relation of reference
and the relation of evidence. In this respect Einstein's theory of gravitation
was epoch-making. In its cosmological applications it contains statements
about large trans-empirical space-time regions but can be tested only in a
few local places. The very success of such a theory makes apparent how
decisively the positivistic command is violated to include only sense data
into the reference class of scientific terms. No excessive use of the surplus
meaning must be made, however. A mathematical formalism can develop
a certain internal life for which not all consequences can be interpreted as
really existing. This is certainly the case with the infinitely many worlds
which come up in the sequence of the analytic extension of the Reissner-
Nordstn6m and the Kerr metric 48 It is no simple task to find the limits be-
tween the surplus meaning and the runaway ontology of a formalism. Non-
empirical criteria of a philosophical nature will be essential in solving this task.
Apart from this difficulty it is not surprising that Einstein's epistemological po-
sition turned towards the hypothetical realism (which had corresponded to his
scientific practice from the beginning) when he constructed his general
relativity which contains a great wealth of theoretical concepts (metric,
affinities, curvature expressions).49 The factual necessity which led to an
increased use of epistemologically abstract objects in the construction of
general relativity has certainly influenced Einstein's metatheoretical reflec-
tions as can be seen in his statement concerning Mach (1922):
50 A. Einstein: Theory of the affine field, Nature 112 (1923), p. 448-449. Cf. also his
contribution to "Theorie de la relativite". Soc. fran~. phil Bull. 22 (1923), p. 111 ff.
51 A. Einstein: Bermerkungen zu Bertrand Russels Erkenntnis-Theorie, in: P. A. Schilpp
(ed.): The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell, La Salle (Ill.), 1971, p. 29l.
52 F. P. Ramsay: Foundations of Mathematics, 2nd edition, London, 1978, p. 233-
241.
53 W. Craig: Replacement of Auxiliary Expressions, Phil. Rev. 65 (1956), p. 38-55.
54 C. G. Hempel: The Theoretician's Dilemma, Minnesota Stud. Phil. Sci., vol. II,
Minneapolis, 1958, p. 37-98; G. Maxwell: The Ontological Status of Theoretical
Entities, Minnesota Stud. Phil. Sci., vol. III, Minneapolis, 1962, p. 3-27;].]. C.
Smart: Between Science and Philosophy, New York, 1968, p. 145. (We follow here
Smart's line of thought.)
Einstein's Treatment of Theoretical Concepts 155
guage as F' (K] , K 2' ... , Kn) where Ki is a class of m-tuples for which
the m-valued predicate <Pi is true. The Ramsay-procedure consists in replacing
F'(K],K 2 , ... ,Kn ) by3X!,3X2 ... 3Xn F'(X!,X 2 •.• X n ) where the
constants K! ... Kn have been eliminated with the help of bound variables.
In a Ramsay-sentence of this type belonging to T, one does not use, for
example, the predicate <PK = "is an electron" or Kk = "the class of electrons",
but only the expression "there is an Xk such that ... ". Thereby V T is
eliminated and a theory about electrons (for instance Dirac's theory) is
replaced by a theory about an abstractly denoted class of objects such that
the relations between the concrete elements and those between the abstract
classes are isomorphic. If the theory formulated in a realistic way originally
makes statements about the existence of electrons, the fact remains neverthe-
less, that the Ramsay-reformulation of the form " ... 3 Kk ... (3X) X E Kk"
contains the same ontological burden. Thus the Ramsay-reformulation can
be interpreted either in an instrumentalist way or with an existential claim
in the same way as the original theory: "The device of the Ramsay sentence
cuts no metaphysical ice one way or the other. "55
A similar ontological indifference applies to the Craig theorem which
replaces a theory T by another T' which contains no part of the vocabulary
of T but only deals with linguistic statements of T. Quite apart from the prac-
tical difficulty which arises from the fact that the empirical equivalence of T
and T' applies only if T' contains infinitely many axioms, there is the funda-
mental counter-argument that both methods of elimination can be applied
only to already existing theories. Only when theories containing theoretical
terms and references to unobservable entities have been created, can they
be converted with the help of one of the logical procedures into a phenom-
enological prediction machinery. Even if this procedure were practical in
all highly developed theories such as the theories of relativity, no questions
could be raised concerning the success of the corresponding replacement
theories T'. Nobody could answer the question why a certain black-box
connection T' of data is successful, since the phenomenalist must not use the
obvious answer of a realist who would argue that the success of the theory
is based on the fact that the objects referred to by T do exist.
Luckily Einstein did not have to follow all these detours aiming at the
elimination of theories and arrived in a rather direct way at the epistem-
ological conviction that no metaphysical harm is done by assigning a realist
interpretation to theoretical terms. 56
A final objection has to be considered: it was just this epistemological
position which led Einstein in his later years, despite all his efforts, into a
scientific back alley. His objections to quantum mechanics, which later con-
cerned the completeness rather than the consistency of the theory, are
clearly connected with his criterion for reality formulated most distinctly in
his paper with Podolsky and Rosen. 57 Since quantum mechanics can be
interpreted only as a statistical theory concerning ensembles rather than a
complete theory of single events, and since he did not consider the introduc-
tion of hidden parameters, only the program of a unified field theory re-
mained, which cannot be realized according to the opinions of almost all
present theoreticians. Was Einstein's epistemological approach including its
ontological claim which he upheld until his death, a misleading guiding
principle? Unfortunately he did not witness the turn in the interpretation
of quantum mechanics which took place in the middle of the sixties. Philos-
ophers 58 and physicists 59 showed that quantum mechanics can be imbedded
in a realistic philosophy of science without any change in its formal struc-
ture and without any loss in its predictive power, but also without a change
in its fundamental probabilistic character. These ideas start from an objective
understanding of probability which guarantees that the revolution brought
about by quantum theory was a nomological revolution rather than an
epistemological one. The idealistic turn in the epistemology of quantum
mechanics which had been emphasized by the Copenhagen interpretation
and the orthodox interpretation of quantum mechanics and which had
been rejected by Einstein, is thus not connected with the statements con-
tained in the theory in an essential way.
In numerous analyses of Einstein's philosophy of science it has been
noted that his ideas were never sufficiently homogeneous and logically
coherent to be abbreviated with a well defined "ism". This applies even for
his explicitly trans-phenomenological period as shown by statements which
go beyond the semantic realism defined in the first section:
"Our experience hitherto justifies us in believing that nature is the
realization of the simplest conceivable mathematical ideas. I am convinced
that we can discover by means of purely mathematical constructions the
concepts and the laws connecting them with each other, which furnish the
key to the understanding of natural phenomena. Experience may suggest the
appropriate mathematical concepts, but they most certainly cannot be
deduced from it. Experience remains, of course, the sole criterion of the
physical utility of a mathematical construction. But the creative principle
laws of our universe are logical necessities. Even if Einstein's highest scientific
aim remains inaccessible for epistemological reasons, the reduction of con-
tingency, the growth of nomological structures and the attempt to go as far
as possible back in the hierarchy of explanations remain a fruitful research
program.
At the moment the understanding for this high aim of scientific
knowledge is not present everywhere. There are many pragmatic constraints
like technical usefulness, economic use for the interests of society, or other
means of utilizations which are demanded from the results of science. The
purely cognitive aim to understand why nature is structured in such a
nomological way as we find it, is considered to be an esoteric epistemological
luxury not connected with the interests of human life. Einstein's epistemo-
logical position shows in retrospect that the highest intellectual accomplish-
ments are not achieved under conditions suffering from these pragmatic
restrictions and cognitive amputations. The pragmatic aims of technical
usefulness can be accomplished by science successfully only if they are not
used as motives in the search for the fundamental laws of nature.
159
Imagine that several centuries from now there will be people who
are interested in phases of the history of man long since past, and let us
ask ourselves which single name in our century will have the best chance
of being known to them. Certainly, we contemporaries have been most
shaken by the political events. But our political crises and those responsible
for them will one day be overshadowed by the crises, and if we are lucky,
their solutions, which are yet to come. If solutions are to be found, perhaps
our radical politicians will appear too inhuman to the people of the future,
our humane politicians not radical enough; perhaps of all the great men of
our century, only Gandhi will stand up to their judgment. Our century's art
will perhaps be remembered as a seismograph of earth-shaking events. The
earth-quakes are triggered by technical progress, and this, in turn, is made
possible by science. But science is at its greatest, and is in the end most
effective, where it seeks not to change the world, but rather to find truth.
The most famous scientist of our century is Einstein.
Would we scientists among ourselves also acknowledge him as our re-
presentative? Do we consider his extraordinary fame as well deserved? As a
physicist he has a chance, because among the sciences, natural science is the
primary pillar of the new concept of the universe, and physics is the basic
discipline of natural science. Physics took two revolutionary steps at the
beginning of our century - the theory of relativity and the quantum t·heory.
One of these theories is Einstein's achievement; in the first phase of the
other theory, his contribution equalled that of Planck and Bohr. Perhaps
Einstein is an especially worthy representative of our guild, for the very
reason that he never really wholly belonged to it. To the world around
him he was a naive genius. Yet his naivete, the naturalness of his questions,
were the heart of his genius. He posed every question directly, certainly
not in contempt of the guild's knowledge, but never in the usual scheme of
questions. Others, too, could provide answers; he was a master of question-
ing. And an unconscious master at that; he could never ask other than
directly.
The editors of this volume assigned me this theme; I have changed
its formulation only slightly. It is not a matter of evaluating each work,
or recounting Einstein's life, but of grasping the way in which his works
160 Carl-Friedrich von Weizsiicker
partly form, partly reflect the intellectual movement of his century. With
this in mind I first want to avoid the distinction between physics and philos-
ophy. Einstein was a physicist and not a philosopher. But the naive direct-
ness of his questions was philosophical. In the strenuous yet smooth course
of the accumulation of knowledge through "normal science", philosophizing
is an obstacle, because, as Kuhn says, such science always adheres to a para-
digm, the not questioning of which is one of its conditions for success. How-
ever, in crises and their revolutionary solutions, the vital question is: "What
do we actually mean by the words we use?" And this - as we were taught
by Socrates - is the philosophical question. The reverse also applies. Not
only does natural science require being stirred up by philosophical question-
ing; philosophy also needs to be stirred up by scientific answers. I still re-
member from my youth how the theory of relativity challenged - and, for
those who could see, smashed - the apriorism of academic philosophy. Less
successful historically but just as significant is the aversion of the mature
Einstein to the empiristic theory of science, which has since triumphed. At
best philosophical realism has a right, albeit limited, to refer to Einstein.
We will encounter all of these questions in following Einstein's great scientif-
ic steps.
Einstein plucked the special theory of relativity like a ripe piece of
fruit. The question was derived from experience: the Michelson experiment.
The mathematical explanation of this experiment was presented by Lorentz
and Poincare. Einstein's contribution, technically speaking, was the simple
derivation of the Lorentz transformation from two general postulates. More
philosophically speaking, Einstein reaped fame for the discovery that this
transformation was not a complication but rather a simplification; that it was
not a problem but a solution to a problem which had previously not even
been seen as such by physicists.
That the relativity of motion is a problem was indeed understood
by the philosophers since antiquity. Aristotle artfully avoided the necessity
of introducing a concept of space by defining position and change of posi-
tion of an object only in relation to other objects; a method which is satis-
factory for a closed, geocentric universe. When the theory of the infinite
universe was taken up again in modern times the problem arose again. New-
ton invented the metaphysical entity of absolute space as a solution. It is
remarkable with what respect Einstein speaks of Newton's proposal. Einstein
was one of that rare breed of revolutionaries, who really change something;
they have this capability because they have grasped the inherent logic of that
very preceding solution which it is their fate to surmount. Einstein did not
simply follow the idea of mechanical relativity, which Leibniz and Mach had
advanced against Newton. He remained faithful to the physical problem of
his time. In optics and electrodynamics physicists postulated the existence
of a physical substance, ether, which made possible the re-establishment of
the Aristotelian solution (hardly known to them any more), accounting
Einstein's Importance to Physics, Philosophy, and Politics 161
4 cf]. Mehra, Einstein, Hilbert, and the theory of gravitation, in ]. Mehra (ed.),
The Physicist's Conception of Nature, Dordrecht, Reidel, 1973.
Einstein's Importance to Physics, Philosophy, and Politics 163
the essence of the questions which are waiting for us - unanswered. What
we are missing here is - as it was the case before the special theory of rela-
tivity - not the answer but the simplicity of the question.
One has to admit that in the last forty years of his life, Einstein himself
was not successful at continuing this simplicity of questioning. This, even
more than the horrible political events, was the tragic shadow that darkened
the second half of his life. But we can learn just from the attempt at under-
standing him in this period.
Einstein formulated the problem of the theory of space and matter
as the problem of a uniform field theory. He criticized Newton for viewing
space as a "tenement building" in which bodies move in and out like tenants.
Mach wanted to accept the concept of matter as an economical description
of sensations, and reject the concept of space as a metaphysical invention.
Einstein, who began under Mach's influence, was led to the opposite solution
of the dualism of space and matter. His claim of simplicity under general
covariance forced a non-linear field equation of gravitation upon him. Here
he also hoped to find the simple solution to a problem of which nobody had
been aware before, by facing an apparent calamity and complication. The
solutions to non-linear differential equations contain singularities. These sin-
gularities might be the field lines of the mass-points. If so, then the task of
fundamental physics is reduced to designing a general field theory. Einstein
knew of only two fundamental fields - those of gravitation and electromag-
netism. After decades of unsuccessful attempts he came back to the older
thought of using a field-tensor of arbitrary symmetry as a basis and dividing
it into a symmetrical gravitation-tensor and a skew symmetrical electro-
magnetic tensor. However, he never succeeded in deriving a realistic picture
of matter.
Philosophically, Einstein proposed a conclusive theory of physics,
which, I presume, is historically due in our century or the next. Indeed, the
physics of the 19th century had already received him with the idea of such
a theory as he described ironically as an older man: "In the beginning (if
there was such a thing) God created Newton's laws of motion together with
the necessary masses and forces. This is all; everything beyond this follows
from the development of appropriate mathematical methods by means of
deduction."6 This vision of the world, as one of mass-point mechanics with
action at a distance, was in fact destroyed by the rise of field physics. Ein-
stein's conception was to make field physics a final uniform theory. But
what was the philosophical weakness of this world of mass-points? Not only
that the realities of the consciousness, the emotions and values were not
described in it. Einstein's design did not do that either. The weakness was
that one had to accept as given facts "as God created them in the beginning"
not only Newton's laws of motion, but values of masses and laws of force
the orderly harmony of what exists, not in a God who concerns himself
with the fates and actions of human beings."10
It was particularly temporality which he felt to be only subjective.
"It seems to me that the idea of a personal God is an anthropological con-
cept which I cannot take seriously. I feel also not able to imagine some
will or goal outside the human sphere. My views are near those of Spinoza:
admiration for the beauty of and belief in the logical simplicity of the order
and harmony which we can grasp humbly and only imperfectly. I believe
that we have to content ourselves with our imperfect knowledge and under-
standing and treat values and moral obligations as a purely human problem -
the most important of all human problems. "11 It is justified to say that he
took a stance consciously outside of his Jewish religious tradition, as Spino-
za himself, but within the realm of European metaphysics which stemmed
from Greek thought. If the mode of reasoning was Greek, the particular
moral earnestness with which Spinoza and Einstein applied them was deeply
Jewish. In this frame of thought Einstein was able not only to think but to
live a full life as well. Four weeks previous to his own death he wrote to the
surviving family members of his friend Besso: "And now he has preceded me
briefly in bidding farewell to this strange world. This signifies nothing. For
us believing physicists the distinction between past, present, and future is
only an illusion, even if a stubborn one. "12
Whereas Einstein's philosophy is inseparable in content from his phys-
ics, his political influence is connected with his scientific thought only by
his unmistakable personality and by the consequences of his fame, which he
could sometimes hardly bear. He commented openly about his aloofness
from society: "My passionate sense of social justice and social responsibility
has always contrasted oddly with my pronounced lack of need for direct
contact with other human beings and human communities. I am truly a 'lone
traveller' and have never belonged to my country, my home, my friends, or
even my immediate family with my whole heart. In the face of all these ties
I have never lost a sense of distance and a need for solitude - feelings that
increase with the years."!3 He wrote this in 1930. And later, words of thanks
to Hermann Broch for his Vergil: "I am fascinated by your Vergil - and
am steadfastly resisting him. The book shows me clearly what I fled from
when I sold myself body and soul to Science - the flight from the I and
WE to the IT."14
It was just this aloofness which enabled Einstein to remain true to his
naive directness in his political judgment. In this respect he is more deeply
bound to the great political tasks of the future than many of us, who have
and harmony which we can grasp humbly and only imperfectly. I believe
that we have to content ourselves with our imperfect knowledge and under-
standing and treat values and moral obligations as a purely human problem -
the most important of all human problems."
As a child, Einstein was sent, with his sister Maja, to the local Catholic
elementary school, and later to the Luitpold Gymnasium, where religious
instruction in one's own faith was compulsory, as was attendance at services.
The children also learned about Judaism at home from a private instructor.
Meanwhile, experience was teaching them basic facts about being
Jewish, as can be seen from the following excerpt from a draft of a letter
written by Einstein in 1920. He was some forty years old when he wrote it,
and at the height of his fame. Note how indelibly certain childhood happen-
ings had impressed themselves on him:
"The teaching staff of the elementary school was liberal and made no
denominational distinctions. Among the Gymnasium teachers there were a
Einstein and Zionism 171
few anti-Semites, one in particular who never let us forget that he was a
reserve officer. Anti-Semitism was evident among the children, particularly
in the elementary school '" Physical assaults and insults were frequent on
the way to school, though for the most part not really malicious. Even so,
however, they were enough to confirm, even in a child of my age, a vivid
feeling of not belonging."
The young Einstein was so impressed by his Jewish religious instruction
that he quickly became intensely religious in a formal, ritualistic sense,
refusing to eat pork and regretting that his parents did not observe the
Jewish rituals. This phase did not last. As he wrote at age sixty-seven in
his Autobiographical Notes:
"This deep religiosity came to an abrupt end at age twelve. Through
the reading of popular scientific books I soon reached the conviction that
much in the stories in the Bible could not be true. The consequence was a
positively fanatical orgy of freethinking coupled with the impression that
youth is intentionally deceived by the state through lies. It was a crushing
impression. Suspicion of every kind of authority grew out of this experience
... an attitude that has never left me '" "
It is perhaps worth mentioning here that some forty years after this
crushing experience Einstein had the grace to say, "To punish me for my
contempt for authority, Fate made me an authority myself."
For many years after his break with the Bible, Einstein seems to have
been little concerned with Judaism. While he was at the German University
in Prague he did come in contact with Zionists, but apparently he remained
quite without interest in Zionism. From Prague he was quickly invited to
the Zurich Polytechnic, where he had been a student - and where he had
initially failed the entrance examination. And from there in 1914, as is
well known, he went to a prestigious position in Berlin. But still Jewish
matters do not seem to have occupied his mind to any significant extent.
An indication of what happened next can be gleaned from the follow-
ing two quotations, even though they slightly conflict with previously quot-
ed material. Both were written in 192 9. In an article, Einstein said, "When
I came to Germany fifteen years ago I discovered for the first time that I
was a Jew, and lowe this discovery more to Gentiles than to Jews." And in
a letter he wrote, "1 first came to Zionism after my emigration to Berlin in
1914 at the age of 35, after I had lived in a completely neutral environment."
Let us not jump to conclusions. Einstein did not become a Zionist in
1914. Re-read his words: "1 first came to Zionism after my emigration to
Berlin at the age of 35."
It was actually quite a while after. As Kurt Blumenfeld said, "Till
1919 Einstein had no connection with Zionism or Zionistic ideas." As for
Kurt Blumenfeld, he was the director of propaganda for the Zionist Union
of Germany [Zionistische Vereinigung fur Deutschland]. The German
Zionists had made a list of Jewish intellectuals whom they wanted to attract
172 Banesh Hoffmann
to the Zionist cause, and Einstein's name was on the list. And so Blumen-
feld presented himself to Einstein in the February of 1919 to talk with him
about Zionism.
Note the circumstances. Two years earlier, the famous Balfour Decla-
ration had promised a national homeland for the Jews in what was then
called Palestine. While Zionists rejoiced, many successful assimilated Jews
were bitterly outspoken in their opposition, fearing that a Jewish national
homeland might tend to give them the status of aliens in the lands where
they had achieved their success. As for Einstein, he had propounded his
general theory of relativity in 1915, yet in early 1919 he was still relatively
unknown to the general public. The results of the British eclipse expedition
under Eddington were not officially announced till 6 November of that
year, and only then did the people of the world suddenly realize that there
was a mighty genius in their midst. When Blumenfeld first came to Einstein
in the February of 1919, Einstein's spectacular worldwide fame was some
nine months in the future.
Blumenfeld's task did not turn out to be easy. Einstein was extra-
ordinarily naive about Zionism. As Blumenfeld remarked, "Einstein [warmed]
up to the Zionist idea only gradually and after long deliberation. He joined
the movement when he felt that it was actually a matter of a struggle for
spiritual freedom, for human rejuvenation, and when he became convinced
that the conquest of Erez Israel for the Jewish people was a conquest through
labor and that the movement was free from tendencies of profiteering and
exploitation. "
By 1920, Einstein was beginning to speak out in Zionistic tones, say-
ing, for example, "Only when we [Jews] have the courage to regard our-
selves as a nation, only when we have respect for ourselves, can we win the
respect of others."
This change of outlook had not been brought about solely by Blu-
menfeld. The end of World War I had brought a sharp rise in anti-Semitism,
and Einstein had seen for himself the shattering effect that it had had on the
refugees who fled to Germany from Eastern Europe.
On 10 March 1921, Chaim Weizmann, in England, sent a detailed tele-
gram to Blumenfeld. Weizmann was the leader of world Zionism - he was
to become the first President of the State of Israel. In his telegram he told
Blumenfeld to persuade Einstein to accompany Weizmann on a visit to the
United States to help raise funds for Zionist causes. In particular, Blumen-
feld was to stress to Einstein the need to raise money for the creation of a
Hebrew University in Jerusalem.
Blumenfeld used all his arts of persuasion, but Einstein would have
none of it. Right away he said, "I am no orator. I can add nothing convinc-
ing. You will only be using my name." And he defeated Blumenfeld's argu-
ments so easily that Blumenfeld gave up the battle. But as he was about
to take his leave, a last desperate thought came to him. He turned to Ein-
Einstein and Zionism 173
stein and said, "I do not believe that we can weigh arguments against each
other in this case. Our work can succeed when all of us are moved by a new
spirit of national discipline .... I do not know what [Dr. Weizmannl would
say to you in my place. But I know that he has been entrusted by the Jewish
people with the responsibility of realizing the Zionist program. Dr. Weizmann
not as an individual, but as president of the Zionist organization has ordered
me to persuade you to go to America, and I have the right to expect that
you subordinate your consideration to Dr. Weizmann's decision." To Blu-
menfeld's surprise, Einstein agreed. And that is how it came about that Ein-
stein and Weizmann travelled together to America on an ocean liner in the
cause of Zionism.
Weizrnann was a distinguished scientist. Telling about the boat trip
across the Atlantic, he said, "Einstein explained his theory to me every day,
and on my arrival I was fully convinced that he understood it."
Einstein was received in America with great enthusiasm. Many honors
were bestowed on him, and his presence on the platform turned out to be a
major asset. For his unguarded account of what happened, here are excerpts
from a letter that he sent from New York to his long-time friend Michele
Besso, whom he had thanked in the celebrated 1905 paper that set forth
the special theory of relativity:
"Two frightfully exhausting months now lie behind me, but I have the
great satisfaction of having been very useful to the cause of Zionism and of
having assured the foundation of the university .... I had to let myself be
exhibited like a prize ox, to speak an innumerable number of times at small
and large gatherings, and to give innumerable scientific lectures. It is a
wonder I was able to hold out. But now it is over, and there remains the
beautiful feeling of having done something truly good, and of having inter-
vened courageously on behalf of the Jewish cause, ignoring the protests of
Jews and non-J ews alike."
The journey to America enormously strengthened Einstein's commit-
ment to Zionism, and his sense of being a Jew took on a new profundity.
From now on, guided by Blumenfeld, he spoke and wrote frequently in sup-
port of Zionism. No longer did he object that the Zionists were using his
name. He realized that his fame was a unique asset entrusted to him by
Fate, and his conscience told him that he must let it be used in the cause of
Zionism, as in other causes he saw as worthy. It was, for him, a profound
moral obligation. Unlike too many other Jews in Germany, he felt a strong
bond of kinship with the bedraggled, poverty-stricken Jewish refugees from
Eastern Europe. He could see beyond their outward appearance, their air
of vagabondage, and their lingering fear, and he recognized them not just as
fellow human beings but also as fellow Jews who, therefore, had a special
claim on his sympathy. He did not run from them as if fearing contamina-
tion from their contact. He saw that, unlike some of the more assimilated
Jews in Germany, they retained a vivid sense of belonging - "a healthy
174 Banesh Hoffmann
national feeling ... not yet destroyed by the process of atomization and
dispersion. "
Here are excerpts from a speech he gave in England in 1921 on his
way home from America:
"When I moved to Berlin ... I realized the difficulties with which
many young Jews were confronted. I saw how, amid anti-Semitic surround-
ings, systematic study, and with it the road to a safe existence, was made
impossible for them. This refers specially to the Eastern-born Jews in Ger-
many .... These Eastern-born Jews are made the scapegoat of all the ills
of present-day German political life and all the after-effects of the war.
Incitement against these unfortunate fugitives, who have only just saved
themselves from the hell which Eastern Europe means for them today,
has become an effective political weapon, employed with success by every
demagogue. When the government contemplated the expulsion of these
Jews, I stood up for them, and pointed out in the Berliner Tageblatt the
inhumanity and the folly of such a measure. Together with some colleagues,
Jews and non-Jews, I started University courses for these Eastern-born Jews,
and I must add that in this matter we enjoyed official recognition and consi-
derable assistance from the Ministry of Education.
"These and similar happenings have awakened in me the Jewish national
sentiment. I am a national Jew in the sense that I demand the preservation of
the Jewish nationality as of every other. I look upon Jewish nationality as a
fact .... I regard the growth of Jewish self-assertion as being in the interests
of non-Jews as well as Jews. That was the main motive of my joining the
Zionist movement."
And later in the speech he says: "The main point is that Zionism must
tend to enhance the dignity and self-respect of the Jews of the Diaspora. I
have always been annoyed by the undignified assimilationist cravings and
strivings which I have observed in so many of my friends."
As Einstein now saw it, Zionism was a unique revitalizing and unifying
force for all Jews. Though steeped in tradition, it looked to the future.
A few months after his return from America he said, "For the last two
thousand years the common property of the Jewish people has consisted en-
tirely of its past .... Now all that is changed. History has set us a great
and noble task in the shape of active cooperation in the building up of
Palestine ... [which must 1 become a seat of modern intellectual life, a
spiritual center for the Jews of the whole world .... A Jewish University
in Jerusalem constitutes one of the most important aims of the Zionist
organization. "
In 1922, Einstein visited Japan, where he was greeted with extraordi-
nary enthusiasm. Early in 1923, on his way back, he visited Palestine, where,
too, he was greeted enthusiastically. But here his visit had an emotional
impact that could not possibly be duplicated in any other land. He was
pressed from all sides to settle in Jerusalem and wrote in his travel diary,
"The heart says yes, but the mind says no."
Einstein and Zionism 175
The highlight of his stay was the visit to Mount Scopus, the site on
which the Hebrew University was destined to be built. His presence there
brought to the Jews of Palestine a sense of joyous fulfillment, and the rev-
erence they felt was manifest in their introductory remarks inviting him to
speak from "the lectern that has waited for you for two thousands years."
In these few words are packed the tragedy and triumph of Jewry.
With the rise of Nazism in Germany, the position of the German Jews
became desperate. When Hitler seized power, Einstein was in California. He
never returned to Germany. Instead, he severed all official German ties and
spoke out against the Nazi tyranny with the fervor and fearlessness of the
ancient Hebrew prophets. In Princeton, where he settled in America, he
found ways to rescue friends and strangers from death at the hands of the
Nazis.
After World War II, with the Nazis defeated, he was invited to rejoin
various German organizations from which he had resigned. But he refused.
And his words of refusal reveal how profound had become his sense of
Jewish identity. For example, to one organization he said, "The Germans
slaughtered my Jewish brethren. I will have nothing further to do with
the Germans." And to another he said, "Because of the mass murder that
the Germans inflicted on the Jewish people, it is evident that any self-
respecting Jew could not possibly wish to be associated in any way with
any official German institution." He never relented.
When Weizmann died, in 1952, Einstein was invited to succeed him as
President of the State of Israel. He declined the invitation gently, citing his
lack of aptitude and experience for such a post, and adding. "I am the more
distressed over these circumstances because my relationship to the Jewish
people has become my strongest human bond, ever since I became aware of
our precarious situation among the nations of the world."
And in March of 1955, less than a month before he died, he wrote to
Blumenfeld saying, "I thank you, as I should have done much earlier, for
having helped me become aware of my Jewish soul."
This article is adapted from a speech entitled "Eistein and Zionism" delivered at the
Seventh International Conference on General Relativity and Gravitation, in Tel Aviv,
in June, 1974, and published in the Proceedings of that conference (Wiley, N.Y.,
and Israel Universities Press, Jerusalem, 1975). I am grateful to Dr. Otto Nathan for
permission to quote material belonging to the Estate of Albert Einstein; and to Helen
Dukas for invaluable help in providing copies of documents from the Einstein Archives
and sharing with me her unrivalled knowledge of Einsteiniana.
177
Century had had the grand idea to found the "Royal College" (in our days
the "College de France") as the "second" Institute of Advanced Studies
in the world, the first having been the Museion created in Alexandria by
Ptolemy Soter at the beginning of the Hellenistic period Ord Century B.c.).
Science has always attempted at remaining a supranational business
by the establishment of a kind of unregistered world-wide corporation of
scholars structured according to the special domains. Neither the Church
and its prelates, nor the States and their Governments have ever liked it,
but they had to live with it, and when after two World wars Science, espe-
cially Physics, became such powerful components of the practical life
of nations in the fields of technology, hygiene etc., Science became a kind
of new power not to be neglected and requiring a statutary basis on the
national and international levels. Money had to flow into scientific enter-
prises in quantities comparable with what is needed for the maintenance
of armies.
This could be done along two lines. Either the officers of the State
would take over the organization of Science according to instructions
given by the Governments, or the scientists themselves would take the
initiative and elaborate the rules of their professional interrelations.
The money and the control over its sources however were not in the
hands of scientists; they were, - and are still, - in two hands: that of the
State, and that of industrial and other Companies. So these had to be
persuaded by the scientists to spend it on reasonable grounds if the latter
were to keep the initiative of the organization of research. Now, since man
is both a selfish and a generous animal, it could be expected that companies
and States would give "under conditions". In order to achieve a compro-
mise that would be satisfactory and favourable to the activity in science,
the speakers of the Corporation had to be endowed with at least three
qualities: to have achieved a high scientific standard, a high moral standard,
and to be skilled people in matters of administration. So, big men who had
built up or run large scientific institutions and who had proven to be in-
corruptible had to devote a good deal of their time, nay, of their career to
international understanding and to the management of scientific business,
some being more of the inspirators, others being more of the executors of
its organization, - sometimes being both at one time.
Organization has been found to be good when it is led under two
principles at a time: authority and democracy. They are not contradictory
when understood rightly. Among inspirators, Albert Einstein had a great
sense of democracy, because of a natural propension and because he had
grown up at College and University level in Switzerland, i. e. in the most
democratically minded country of the world. Among such as have been both
inspirators and executors, we might think of Arthur Compton, who spent the
last years of his life thinking and writing about the right ethics to suit scien-
tific activity. A third man whom I want to cite is Niels Bohr, from whom I
Birth and Role of the GRG-Organization 179
GR3. It has never been decided which Conference has been GR1: the Jubi-
lee Conference in Berne 1955 or the one in Chapel Hill 1957. But Royau-
mont was certainly GR2. This reminds of the Paris University, which was
founded 1150, recognized by the King in 1200, and received its final confir-
mation from the Pope in the year 1215.
Who says that the International Committee on GRG was finally recog-
nized at Warsaw? The following story will show that nothing like that was
actually the case! Anyhow, Infeld - inspite of his very poor state of health
- took very seriously the problems of the consolidation of our organization.
In particular, he maintained the opinion that owing to the tremendous
importance of the concentration of work and seeing the spreading of publi-
cations in so many journals ranging from pure mathematics over astronomy
to remote fields of physics, a new Journal had to be founded devoted ex-
clusively to GRG. He wanted to edit it himself, but he was ill and he also
hesitated on the ground, that Warsaw was outside the geographical area
where the modern "Latin" of science - even its modern "Greek" (every-
body will guess what is meant thereby) - are spoken. Before he died, he
gave me orally a sort of commission, not to drop the idea of a Journal
inspite of the reluctance shown by several members of the Committee. I
have considered it a duty to follow up the matter, and the first issue of
the GRG-Journal finally came out of Plenum Press in 1970, its preparation
having required a lot of work and securing the collaboration of a number
of referees.
But in the mean time, other events had occurred. One of them was,
that GRG, from being quasi-purely theoretical, had become an observa-
tional (not to say experimental) science with a very vast horizon. That
was a sensation for other physicists - not for relativists though. Astro-
physics - a chapter of astronomy - became "Relativistic astrophysics" -
practically a chapter of physics. It needed so its own special meetings. The
people in Texas had plans to establish research at the advanced level. They
called for a Symposium, which took place at Dallas in January 1963. The
procedure was repeated and became in the field of Relativistic Astrophysics
a series parallel to the Rochester Conferences in the field of Particle physics.
The series has since been called Texas Conferences, even though the confe-
rences may take place far away from Texas (like the "Rochester" e.g. took
place in USSR). It is an excellent supplement to the GRG-Conferences, for
if the latter cover systematically the whole field of GRG and so find their
suitable place among the big conferences in the sense defined by !UP AP
regulatives, the former allow to concentrate work on a most important
application at the boarder of physics proper and astronomy. Therefore,
those responsible for GRG have always welcome the Texas Conferences
and reciprocally. Especially, I have in former years attended these and
written big reports on them; but overwork and other duties have prevented
me to do so more recently.
182 Andre Mercier
GR 7, Nathan Rosen was elected President of the new Society and of the
Committee as such. The organization of scientific activity in the field of
GRG on the international plane has since been considered as secured and
indeed, it does work smoothly and efficaciously.
Twenty years of endeavours seemed a reasonable period and I decided
to resign as a secretary to be replaced at GR8 in Waterloo (Ontario), where
the General Assembly elected Peter Bergmann as the new president (another
former pupil of Albert Einstein's like the retiring president) and Alan Held
as the new secretary, who had already taken over the editorship of the
Journal.
All these informations may sound very administrative. But they are not
unimportant with respect to the good functioning of scientific research and
activity at large. 1979 will be the Centenary of Albert Einstein's birth. It is
something like a mile-stone at which we, scientists of the field, should be
able to take a rest and look both backwards onto the terrain which has been
travelled through so far and forwards onto the landscape which lies ahead.
With regards to achievements, specialists will be able to write beautiful
reviews on the various domains that have by and by crystallized during
more than seven decades, mostly after the Second world war. But a cente-
nary like that does not only mark a scientific advance, it also reminds of
human achievements which go back to the personality of the man under
consideration. These achievements are of scientific, moral, aesthetic and
even of an ineffable nature. A comprehensive philosophy radiates from the
whole situation in which we are, and since circumstances have made out
of me a man deeply involved in philosophy as a writer, a teacher and an
international officer, it seems appropriate to give the reader a hint as to
such items, more particularly in consideration of the experience described
so far.
Many scientists, who have not been able to study philosophy proper-
ly, have a tendency to beEeve, that science masters philosophy. Nothing
is more untrue. Philosophy is not a subject for science, it is not a science
either, only it has to be aware of scientific achievements (as well as of
other achievements of a nature different from that of scientific activities).
Philosophy is not either, as some believe it to be, a substitute for a
religion that would have become obsolete. Man is a peculiar being, because
he is deeply affected by the fact that he realizes that he does not know
much, especially not why he is down there on the middle planet where he
encounters such a mess and so many hindrances on his path. So he is very
much distressed. But at the same time, the regular relative motions of the
celestial bodies, the symmetries in crystals and plants, and many other
features of things attract his attention as being so very beautiful, good,
true and loveable, that he is filled with a joy at the prospect of being able
to understand them and of coming nearer some sort of perfection him-
self.
Birth and Role of the GRG-Organization 185
There can be no doubt that Albert Einstein has been one of those who
felt most deeply the impress of that dichotomy. Now there are two and only
two possible ways to walk from the original situation of distress towards
that state of perfection which every one would like to reach. One consists in
never being afraid of the stones and the dirt which injures and stains our
bodies, for there is a voice that tells us that this is of no moment. The
other one consists in examining at each step the situation arrived at in
order to clear it of all the obstacles which seem to prevent an understanding
of the next possible step. Both ways are there to prove our existence and
to ground our freedom.
Everybody knows that Descartes exclaimed: I think, therefore I am.
Well, to think is to cautiously walk along the second path; a thinker is a
philosopher, and philosophy is the second possible way to let our existence
show itself from our original si~uation of distressing ignorance towards one
of growing comprehension. But it is less well known that Descartes had an
experience which engaged him to also try the first possible way. Of course,
the cogito, ergo sum does not say a word of what is to be done at each step
of the cogitation. This is up to each philosopher to decide. Descartes worked
very hard elaborating his career, inventing e.g. Analytical geometry which is
recognized by all mathematicians, but proposing a physics that has been
found totally inadequate.
A few years younger, Pascal never explicitly made a comparable claim.
But all his life may be said to have illustrated one other claim which I might
formulate like this: I (i. e. Pascal) believe, therefore I am. That is what leads
one along the first path, religion if you please, i.e. the faith in God. But
such a credo, ergo sum does not explicate any of the injuries which one
experiences by being a religious person. Pascal contributed very valuable
advances in mathematics, physics and theology, and was a very great poet
even though he wrote in prose, for his French is of the most beautiful kind
that has ever been written, and he was a great philosopher too.
Descartes had many followers: Spinoza, Leibniz and others. Pascal
was more of an example and a source of inspiration, and Leibniz respected
him highly; but he had no followers.
I have not chosen my instances from Antiquity, but from the so-called
Modern times, for a very specific reason. One knows since the work of
Arrhenius on the history of science that the rise of modern science, espe-
cially Newtonian physics, would not have been possible without the Judaico-
Christian conception of Time having replaced the antique concept. For Plato
had a cyclic idea of time (which had possibly come from ancient wisdom in
India through Pythagoras), whereas the idea of historical linearity came to the
awareness of thinkers with the Bible, including that of a creation, i. e. a zero
time and, with Christian eschatology, even an end of time. Science has never
said a word about a possible end, but it has been built upon the new concep-
tion of time as of the independent variable imposed on everything and upon
186 Andre Mercier
1 I shall not quote books and articles where these things are explained at length.
188 Andre Mercier
The year 1979 will not pass away without there having been a number
of Einstein Centenary Celebrations throughout the world. Here again, pride
and prejudice might distort the accurate picture. Not only those who under-
take them, but also those who will profit by them should refrain from falling
into such a mistake.
History has to be written impartially.
189
The state of physics at that time can be described thus: there were
generally interesting special areas, such as longwave infrared, gaseous disch-
arges, spectroscopy, radioactivity, canal rays, which were being worked on in
various institutes. The theoretical foundations were thermodynamics, the
kinetic theory of gases, electromagnetism, and the electron theory of the
electrical and optical characteristics of matter. But there were no basic
questions and certainly none concerning relativity and quantum physics.
Through the papers appearing for Planck's lecture on the "Theory of Thermal
Radiation" I became acquainted with Einstein's light-quantum hypothesis 1 .
This became the object of many fantasies with Ernst Back, who having
finished his law studies changed over to physics, and who became well-
known for the Paschen-Back-effect. I do not recall Paschen's opinion on the
matter. To him, as a spectroscopist, the problem of the atom lay in the
"monochromatic undamped Planck oscillator", as he so often stated. After
all he motivated Paul Gmelin and me around the year 1912 to investigate
the pressure of light, searching for the deflection of a jet of iodine vapor
by intense transverse radiation. Otto Robert Frisch 2 first proved this "Ein-
steinian light-quantum momentum" in 1933 in absorption and emission.
After the publication of the experiment of James Franck and Gustav
Hertz 3, which was later to become famous, Back and I went to Paschen
quite upset: it was the inverse photoelectric effect, namely the release of a
light-quantum by means of an electron of the same energy. Paschen rejected
this brusquely, saying that the connection between the emission of spectral
lines and ionization had not been determined yet. We tried to link up every-
thing with Bohr's theory of the atom 4, which was not given so much atten-
tion elsewhere (in Berlin, for example), since Paschen had recommended it
to us in the summer of 1913 with the prophetic words, "That is physics for
the next thirty years." He had been impressed by the first interpretation
of the Runge-Paschen-Ritz term and term-difference law for spectral lines.
He never mentioned it again until Sommerfeld's theory of the fine-structure
of spectral rays and in his own measurements, which far exceeded the limi-
tations of accuracy for that time, seamed to settle the matter. When he
wrote the famous Annalenarbeit with the curious title "Bohr's Helium Lines"
in 1916 (Sommerfeld had come to Tiibingen for several days) he repeatedly
added to his admiration for the theory by saying "Now for the first time I
have experimentally proven the theory of relativity." Before this I had never
heard a word mentioned about it at the institute.
A. Einstein, Ober einen die Erzeugung und Verwandlung des Lichts betreffenden
heuristischen Gesichtspunkt; Ann. d. Phys. 17, 132, 1905.
2 O. R. Frisch, Experimenteller Nachweis des Einsteinschen StrahlungsriickstoGes,
ZS f. Phys. 86, 42,1933.
]. Franck u. G. Hertz, Ober die Erregung der Quecksilberresonanzlinien durch Elek-
tronenstiiGe, Verh. d. D. Phys. Ges. 16, 512,1914.
4 N. Bohr, On the Constitution of Atoms and Molecules, Phil. Mag. 26,1,1913.
Reminiscences of the Albert Einstein from 1908 to 1930 191
The discovery of X-ray interferences and the proof of the atomic crystal
lattice, the vivid idea and theory of Max Laue s and the lucid experiment of
Walther Friedrich and Paul Knipping in the summer of 1912, excited the
physicists more than the other discoveries of that time, such as the electro-
optical Stark-effect, the atomic nucleus by Ernst Rutherford or the supra-
conductivity by Heike Kamerlingh Onnes. It enlivened the discussion about
Einstein's light quantum theory: This had previously been brought into con-
nection with the concept of X-ray corpuscles or shock waves which released
and excited high energy electrons. In agreement with Paschen and Meyer I
experimented with interferences of Alpha-corpuscles transversing crystals.
In a vacuum tube we arranged within a few centimeters a Bragg-diaphragm,
which made Alpha-rays parallel. The rays fell through a mica foil onto a
fluorescent screen. But it was not possible to find symmetrically ordered
scintillations outside of the ray. At this point Edgar Meyer suggested testing
a fundamental question of Einstein's theory of the photoeffect: whether the
release of an electron occurs spontaneously with the absorption of light or
whether it occurs after an accumulation time during which radiation energy
is absorbed 6. Ultramicroscopic metal particles were bombarded with sharply
focused ultraviolet rays in an Ehrenhaft-Millikan-condensor 7 . Delays ranging
from fractions of a second to many seconds were recorded from the onset of
bombardment to the first observed changes in charge. Upon repeating the
experiment these delays varied around a mean values, which in turn depended
on various experimental conditions. The alterations in charge amounted to
one or several electronic charges. H. Joffe carried out similar experiments of
his own at Rontgen's Institute. We reported on our results and their possible
significance at the spring conference of the Society of Physics held in Zurich
in 1913. At this occasion I became acquainted with Einstein. I had already
met some of the physicists whom we revered: Heinrich Rubens, Carl Runge,
Johannes Stark, Pierre WeiB, Willy Wien. The 34-year-old Einstein was of
quite a different nature. I know very well that the recollection of earlier
sentiments is a very touchy subject; autobiographies give us enough examples
of this. The recollection of an event is a different matter; an event which
revealed quite unexpectedly and surprisingly a new human and scientific
insight, which was reinforced year after year in my sporadic meetings with
Einstein.
It was the first scientific conference I had attended where I was also to
present a lecture and I was anxious and nervous. Einstein was pointed out
to me: inconspicuous, rather casual in posture and attire, he sat in an audi-
torium (small by modern standards) in which everyone knew everyone else.
Occasionally he interrupted a lecture with a pointed question, or debated
a matter with a subdued voice marked by a slight south German accent,
always clearly worded even if improvised. In the course of the conference
we met in smaller circles at lunch or during breaks, once at the house of a
patron, where Einstein played the violin. I noticed at once his extreme
modesty. As the saving went in Zurich in those days, "Be a man, eat
Schiibli and smoke Stumpen", and such a man he was. "I go fourth class,
and still get where I'm going." He spoke so naturally that one forgot his own
inhibitions. He continually made sure that he had understood your point
of view by asking questions. He seemed to be interested in everything, he
"thought aloud". If he rejected an idea, he did it kindly, making it milder
with a witty comment. First and foremost he was concerned with the matter
at hand, free from prejudice. Arrogance and complacency were foreign to
him - he saw in them the root ot the nationalism which he hated. He spoke
about this frankly, as I have only heard since in the fall of 1914 from my
teacher Friedrich Paschen.
I remember details of a longer conversation about our experiments
together with Edgar Meyer. The much debated "sub-electrons" of the
Viennese physicist Felix Ehrenhaft and his ideas on photophoresis in con-
nection with the light-quantum issue came up for discussion. Einstein asked
for details as to why we rejected the sub-electrons 8 . Our experiments showed
unequivocally the atomic structure of electronic charge; however, the
absolute values varied from particle to particle on a wide scale. From this
we concluded the non-validity of the Stokes formula which we had used in
calculation. His opinion on our experiments concerning delay or accumula-
tion time of the photoelectric effect was that this must be a secondary effect
(as we had also concluded). An ionisation of the surrounding gases by means
of the ejected electrons impossible. It was a possibility that ejected elec-
trons attached themselves to neutral gas molecules and ions were formed
- which after having been transferred back to the particle within a short
time by means of Brownian motion or through electrical attraction -
prevented the observation of the release of an electron, and so an accumu-
lation time appeared to occur. Some time later we received a note from Ein-
stein (written on a slip of paper) with some formulas and the question
whether or not we had proved our hypothesis. So we measured the delay
time of the same particle while reducing the surrounding atmospheric pressure
9 E. Meyer u. W. Gerlach, Ober die Giiltigkeit der Stokesschen Formel, Festschrift fUr
J. Elster und H. Geitel, Verlag Vieweg 1915, Seite 196.
10 A. Einstein, Eine neue elektrostatische Methode zur Messung kleiner Elektrizitats-
mengen, Phys. ZS. 9, 216, 1908.
11 A. Einstein, Ober die von der molekularkinetischen Theorie der Warme geforderte
Bewegung von in ruhenden Fliissigkeiten suspendierten Teilchen. Ann. d. Phys. 17,
549, 1905. -- Bez. der benutzten Methode s. M. von Smoluchowski, in Vortrage tiber
kinetische Theorie der Materie, Gottingen 1914.
12 W. Gerlach u. E. Lehrer, Ober die Messung der Brownschen Bewegung mit Hilfe einer
Drehwaage, Naturwiss. 15, S. 15,1927.
13 E. Kappler Versuche zur Messung der Avogardo-Loschmidtschen Zahl aus der
Brownschen Bewegung einer Drehwaage. Ann. d. Phys. 11, 233, 1931.
194 Walther Gerlach
ones. Stern 14 then made the suggestion of investigating the so-called direc-
tional quantization with an experiment which was basically very simple:
the deflection or splitting of a silver atomic beam in an inhomogeneous
magnetic field. For want of any financial aid at a time of beginning infla-
tion, Born supported us from fees he had received by lecturing on the theory
of relativity. Due to great difficulties it was often discussed if the attempt
was even worth the effort. Niels Bohr and Max Born expected proof of
extreme directional quantization, Arnold Sommerfeld at most a semi-
classical result, Peter Debye maintained that experimental evidence obtained
from magneto-mechanical experimentation was impossible, and Fritz Haber
gave us a large sum of money from the Hoshi- Foundation to continue experi-
mentation and not give up hope. Stern and I always used to say, "The autopsy
will tell", where Stern favoured a classical rather than a quantum interpreta-
tion. Born kept Einstein posted, and he provided us with money for a strong
magnet after the first promising results became known, and helped us with
his optimism. When the experiment finally succeeded 15 he wrote the follow-
ing lines to Born: 16 "The most interesting thing at present is the experiment
of Stern and Gerlach. The alignment of atoms without collisions cannot be
explained with our present understanding of radiation. An alignment should
rightfully take over a hundred years. I did some calculations with Ehrenfest.
Rubens considered the experimental result to be absolutely certain."
At this time Einstein suggested that I should concern myself with an
entirely different issue- the question as to whether matter in motion creates a
magnetic field (evidence of such experiments were to be found in Michael
Faraday's diary). Measurements alongside streams and waterfalls were meant
here. I was to give up my academic work for the time being. After much deli-
beration I could not make up my mind to do this.
During some such conversation Einstein mentioned that the flame of a
burning candle would disappear in free fall, since it was dependent on con-
vection and therefore on the acceleration of the earth. I answered, "There-
fore a gas-filled incandescent light bulb becomes brighter when falling." I
have shown these two experiments 17 regularly in lectures since my time
in Frankfurt. A flame contained in a large, closed bell jar retreats to a glow-
ing area near the wick when falling freely, while a slightly glowing filament
in the bell jar gets brighter.
The dual nature of light had been considered already one hundred years
before. Thomas Young's transverse undulatory theory (further developed by
Fran~ois Arago and finally by Augustin Fresnel) stood in opposition to the
"valid" Newtonian concept of (quasi magnetic) polarized light corpuscles,
which was generally accepted and apparently guaranteed by Etienne Malus'
discovery of "polarization". Then Jean Baptiste Biot claimed the explana-
tion of interference using corpuscles as the most urgent task of physics.
Fraunhofer stated among others on the basis of the first absolute wavelength
measurements using his diffraction grating in air and water ~ "Interference
will always exist. Whoever can imagine anything other than a wave with
these characteristics, must adapt it to his view".
The "either-or" of that time stood in opposition to the "as well as" in
Bohr's principle of complementarity and proven experiments on wave-
particle duality. Experimenters said, when asking about energy relationships
the answer is in terms of "quanta"; when asking about a radiation field, the
answer is in terms of "waves". Einstein 18 posed the sceptical question to
the latter: Why doesn't light, which is emitted from canal rays (that is, from
rapidly moving atoms), create interference? However, he demonstrated that
"the failure of the classical undulatory theory was almost out of ques-
tion" because of an experiment derived "without special presumptions, in
particular also of those concerning the undulatory theory". Light from canal
ray atoms (of uniform velocity) creates and interference pattern of "rest" if
one of the mirrors is tilted at an angle depending on the velocity of the canal
radiation in the Michelson-interferometer. With "Einstein's tilting-mirror
experiment", radiation interferes which is emitted at varying times by par-
ticles moving in the same direction. Einstein sees the special significance of
this consideration fundamental for his reasoning, into which I had the
honor of having insight - in the fact that it "leads to a convenient predic-
tion of the expected interference patterns". After only three months Emil
Rupp 19 submitted the experimental results which "fully proved the theory",
as Einstein emphasized in the concluding statements. The "total validity of
the undulatory theory (according to Bohr and Heisenberg)" and the invalidity
of the presumption "that the radiation field which determines the inter-
ference can be produced in a momentary procedure, as proposed by the
quantum theory", were both fundamental for the progress of physics. Willy
Wien urged his student Harald Straub to verify the Rupp experiments. The
result corresponded to his reasoning, yet he was sceptical due to a previous
work of Rupp's on phosphors. After Wien's death Eduard Riichardt and I
20 H. Straub, Uber die Koharenzlilnge des von Kanalstrahlen emittierten Lichtes. Ann.
d.Phys. 5, 1930,S. 644.
21 E. Rupp Erwiderung zu der Dissertation von H. Straub "Uber die Kohilrenzlilnge des
von Kanalstrahlen emittierten Lichtes". Ann. d. Phys. 7,1930, S. 381. Antwort auf
die Bemerkung von H. Straub, Ann. d. Phys. 8, 1931, S. 293.
Reminiscences of the Albert Einstein from 1908 to 1930 199
for his proof of the mirror experiment: interference with Eintein's image
conditions, no interference without them. The wrong tilting direction in
Einstein's and Rupp's drawing did not seem to us to be sufficient proof of
fraud. While experiments to produce canal rays of homogeneous speed in
our institute continued, Riichardt succeeded in deriving the Einstein-experi-
ment within the framework of another project. The derivation precluded
once and for all the image conditions. In 1935 22 we published our correc-
tions of Einstein's derivation and drawing with the statement that Rupp had
not conducted the tilting-mirror experiments and that the interference pat-
terns had been falsified. Some time later C. Ramsauer made the same claim
in regard to other works of Rupp.
In 1937 - 38 Heinz Billing 23 finally succeeded in producing a highly
luminous homogeneous hydrogen canal ray by using the new ion-optical
method, and in proving the interference of H-light as emitted from canal
rays of varying places as predicted in Einstein's tilting-mirror experiments.
With experiments conducted under various conditions he also illustrated -
surpassing even Einstein's theory of 1926 - its conformity with Heisenberg's
Uncertainty Principle of 1927. It should also be mentioned that at the same
time Gerhard Otting 24 from our institute and H. J. Ives and G. R. Stievell
in the U.S.A. had proven quantitatively the relativistic quadratic Doppler
effect using transverse observation of homogeneous canal rays. One might
say that such a belated confirmation was not actually of any importance.
To my mind, however, the importance which Einstein himself had attached
to this experiment in 1926 justifies the efforts, not to mention the fact that
every quantitative experiment in physics has its own intrinsic value.
We never found out whether or not Einstein ever received the reprints
of the Annalenarbeit (1938), the credit for which was given him by name.
On the occasion of Albert Einstein's seventieth birthday (March 14,
1949), the Oberbiirgermeister of Ulm, Theodor Pfizer, invited a large audience
to honor the city'S "favourite son". Everyone sat crowded together on fold-
ing chairs and wooden benches in the old "Schuhhaussaal". Pfizer sent a
copy of my speech and his to Princeton. Einstein who at the time was reluc-
tant, even negative in regard to attempts at renewing old acquaintances, ans-
wered him on September 28: "Thank you for sending a copy of the article
telling of your celebration and for your letter of August 17. Please thank my
colleague Mr. Gerlach for the friendly efforts which he undertook upon this
The famous 1950 Japanese film Rashomon recounts a dramatic episode three times
over in the very different versions perceived by three of those who took part. The
account of a May 16, 1953 visit to Einstein given here differs in that there are four
versions supplied respectively by John Wheeler, Marcel Wellner, Arthur Komar and
O. W. Greenberg. The editor (J. A. W.) expresses his appreciation to them for the
permission to quote them, and to the Albert Einstein Estate for permission to
quote brief passages from Einstein's writings.
My first chance to see and hear Albert Einstein came one afternoon in
the academic year 1933-34. I was in my first year of postdoctoral work with
Gregory Breit in New York. He told me that there would be a quiet, small,
unannounced seminar by Einstein that afternoon. We took the train to
Princeton and walked to Fine Hall. Unified field theory was to be the topic,
it became clear, when Einstein entered the room and began to speak. His
English, though a little accented, was beautifully clear and slow. His delivery
was spontaneous and serious with every now and then a touch of humor. I
was not familiar with his subject at that time but I could sense that he had
his doubts about the particular version of unified field theory he was then
discussing. I had been accustomed before this to seminars in physics where
equations were taken up one at a time or, if I may say so, dealt with in retail
trade. Here for the first time I saw equations dealt with wholesale. One
counted the number of unknowns and the number of supplementary condi-
tions and compared them with the number of equations and the number of
coordinate degrees of freedom. The idea was not to solve the equations but
rather to decide whether they possessed a solution and whether it was
unique. It was clear on this first encounter that Einstein was following very
much his own line, independent of the interest in nuclear physics then at
high tide in the United States.
In 1938 I moved to Princeton and at infrequent intervals called on
Einstein at his house at 112 Mercer Street, climbing the stairs to his second
floor study that looked out on the Graduate College. Once discussing with
him my hopes some day to understand radiation damping in terms of the
interaction between the source and the absorber, he told me about his de-
bate with W. Ritz [1]. The two men joined to write up their contrasting
202 gathered by John A. Wheeler
points of view in a joint paper. In it Ritz argued that the elementary interac-
tion is responsible for the irreversibility. In contrast Einstein favored the
view that elementary interactions are time symmetric and that any irreversi-
bility is caused by asymmetry in time of the initial conditions. He also
made reference to a fascinating paper of Tetrode [2] on the same question.
Especially vivid in my mind is a call I made in 1941 to explain the "sum
over histories" approach to quantum mechanics then being developed by
Richard Feynman [3], whom I was fortunate enough to have as a graduate
student. I had gone to see Einstein with the hope to persuade him of the
naturalness of quantum theory when seen in this new light, connected so
closely and so beautifully with the variation principle of classical mechanics.
He listened to me patiently for twenty minutes until I finished. At the end
he repeated that familiar remark of his, "I still cannot believe that the good
Lord plays dice" [4]. And then he went on to add again in his beautifully
slow, clear, well-modulated and humorous way, "Of course I may be wrong;
but perhaps I have earned the right to make my mistakes".
One day something made me say, "Professor Einstein you must often
be invited to other places. Are you never tempted to visit?" "I love to
travel", he replied, "but I hate to arrive".
In the Fall of 1952 I gave for the first time the course in relativity,
general and special, from which I was to learn so much from my students
over the years. On May 16, 1953, not quite two years before he died, Ein-
stein was kind enough to invite me to bring the eight to ten students in the
course around to his house for tea. [The recollections kindly provided by
three of them follow. Arthur Komar, Marcel Wellner and o. W. Greenberg.]
Margot Einstein and Helen Dukas served tea as we sat around the dining
room table. The students asked questions about everything from the nature
of electricity and unified field theory to the expanding universe and his
position on quantum theory and Einstein responded at length and fascinat-
ingly. Finally one student outdid the other in the boldness of his question:
"Professor Einstein, what will become of this house when you are no longer
living?" Einstein's face took on that humorous smile and again he spoke in
that beautiful, slow, slightly accented English that could have been con-
verted immediately into printer's type, "This house will never become a
place of pilgrimage where the pilgrims come to look at the bones of the
saint." And so it is today. The tourist buses drive up. The pilgrims climb
out to photograph the house - but they don't go in.
A further encounter was my last. We persuaded him to give a seminar
to a restricted group [see notes on it below]. In it the quantum was a central
topic. No one can forget how he expressed his discomfort about the role of
the observer. "When a person such as a mouse observes the universe, does
that change the state of the universe?"
Mercer Street and other Memories 203
References
[1] Ritz, w., and A. Einstein, "Zum gegenwartigen Stand des Strahlungsproblems",
Physik. Zeits. 10, 323-324 (1909).
[2] Tetrode, H., "Ober den Wirkungszusammenhang der Welt. Eine Erweiterung der klas-
sischen Dynamik", Zeits. f. Physik. 10, 317-328 (1922).
[3] Feynman, R. P., "The principle of least action in quantum mechanics", doctoral
dissertation, Princeton University, 1942; unpublished; available from University
Microfilms, Inc., Ann Arbor, Michigan 49106.
[4] Einstein, A., letter to Max Born, December 12,1926.
[5] Einstein, A., letter to Niels Bohr, May 2,1920.
[6] Schilpp, P. A., ed., Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist, Library of Living Philoso-
phers, Evanston, Illinois. 1949, and subsequent paperback editions elsewhere.
204 gathered by John A. Wheeler
Arthur Komar's Remembrances of the May 16, 1953: Visit of Class in Rela-
tivity to Einstein's Residence at 112 Mercer Street, Princeton
There were about eight of us. We sat down and had tea. Miss Dukas
brought the tea. Einstein said he was so pleased to have some contact with
young people. John Wheeler asked him about the Einstein-Rosen bridge.
Why did he first introduce it then drop it? Einstein said he originally thought
of it as a unique structure reaching across two nearly flat sheets. However,
when he realized it was not unique, the bridge seemed to him unwieldy,
unattractive, and offering too many possibilities. It was not clear what to do
with them all. Arthur Komar asked what he thought of the idea of Edding-
ton for getting the dimensionless constants. Einstein replied that he was
much interested in finding a theory or an understanding of the dimension-
less constants; but he felt that there was no solution of real interest avail-
able at that time. Komar did not remember questions about the expanding
universe of gravitational radiation or the nature of electricity. He did recall
that vivid phrase at the end, "this house will never become a place of pil-
grimage where the pilgrims come to look at the bones of the saint". The
whole encounter was in English. Komar also remembered Einstein's coming
to Palmer Physical Laboratory and giving a talk containing two striking
comments. (1) The laws of physics should be simple. Someone in the au-
dience asked, "But what if they are not simple?" "Then I would not be
interested in them." (2) Einstein was asked why he rejected quantum me-
chanics. He said he could not accept the concept of a priori probability.
Someone in the audience said, "But you were the one who introduced
a priori probability, in the A and B coefficients." "Yes, I know that and
have regretted it ever since; but when one is doing physics one should not
let one's left hand know what one's right hand is doing." At the end of
this lecture he sat down, leaned back, sighed and said, "This is my last
examination. "
Mercer Street and other Memories 205
Problems
[for class in relativity in May 1953, a few days before the hoped-for visit
with Einstein]
Mercer Street
A spring afternoon,
A line of nine walk through the town,
A musty house, the shutters drawn,
A sage lives within.
Fig. 1
"Consider a sphere lmm in
diameter. It can go to and
fro between two planes,
ideally elastic."
208 gathered by John A. Wheeler
1
Fig. 2
"The objects falls with a different
acceleration if it is moving than if
it is not moving."
Mercer Street and other Memories 209
falls with another acceleration if heated than if not heated. I felt this is
not true. Came out that acceleration is independent of quality of matter:
pendulum experiments.
Change coordinate system? Then change acceleration. Then I came to
a real understanding of the equivalence of gravitational and inertial mass.
No inertial system can be preferred. That was not so clear to me at that
time. But Mach had the same idea, not the relation of gravitational and
inertial mass, but that "inertial system" was a very vicious concept. Inertia
come from the presence of other bodies? How possible? Relative accelera-
tion and against this a resistance. Quite a nice idea. But if you give up space,
you have an enormous number of distances, and unhandy consistency rela-
tions. Mach not aware of time concept. Great thing that Mach, centuries
after Newton, felt that there was something important about this concept
of avoiding an inertial system. Need absolute covariance.
Not yet so clear in Riemann's concept of space. His curvature is abso-
lutely covariant. But this was not so clear at the time this work was present-
ed by Riemann and his successors. The first to see this clearly was Levi-
Civita: absolute parallelism and a way to differentiate. Recognized that
possibility to avoid inertial system depended on existence of a r-field that
described parallelism in the infinitesimally small. This was a great advance.
It made it possible to see how to generalize relativity to include electromag-
netism.
The representation of matter by a tensor was only a fill-in to make
it possible to do something temporarily, a wooden nose in a snow man.
The theory wasn't complete, because we know the world is not limited
to gravitation. After decades I came to the idea to generalize by using
unsymmetric gij'S, the method of logical consistency gone mad. I was very
conscious of this objection. r is a field. Without this there is no hope to
express things in general relativity.
Present quantum theory based on special relativity is horribly compli-
cated. For most people special relativity, electromagnetism and gravitation
are unimportant, to be added in at the end after everything else has been
done. On the contrary, we have to take them into account from the be-
ginning. Otherwise it is as if one did a classical problem and put in the law
of conservation of energy at the end. Expect to describe a system only by
quantum numbers. There is much reasonable in this. But a field theory
seems to present us with an infinite number of quantum numbers. There
is much reason to be attracted to a theory with no space, no time. But no-
body has an idea how to build it up. Of course, to quantize space and time
is a childish idea. This is my excuse for feeling so strongly. It is pedagogic
to insist that if one has a field theory, one must demand solutions without
singularity. If a singularity is allowed, there are too many arbitrary assump-
tions, and too much arbitrariness.
210 gathered by John A. Wheeler
Questions:
leg - his name was G. W. Young - had approached Einstein, von Laue, and
particularly Schrodinger, whose assistant I was, as to whether I deserved such
a big grant for my research project. I was lucky and quite proud of myself.
I later learnt that Einstein's recommendation was the briefest one. All this
took place without my knowledge. According to Lao Tse:
dissertation accepted in toto, many years before these published errata. The
joke is, of course, on his examinators; the 'macroscopic' fool-hero is the man
who already in his late forties looked like an Italian virtuoso - some even
compared his appearance to that of a pavement artist.
This little item in the Annalen speaks more eloquently for the nobility,
the integrity of that unique giant in physics than any a paean sung in honour
of this homme celebre.
Many weird experiences with Einstein the academic teacher come to my
mind, now that I try to recall the remote past. We students often grumbled
that he had "intercourse with the blackboard" - as we put it facetiously.
He wrote and wrote and wrote, without realizing as to whether the content
of his statements would make sense to us. Often times he stopped in the
middle of writing down a relation or proposition or theorem, became lost in
thought, for minutes, and then produced some entirely novel hypothesis or
theory whose dramatic ingenuity even we ignoramuses recognized as 'com-
mensurate with the explosion of a supernova'! In those moments we were
not aware of his many foibles, his clumsiness, his lack of rapport with the
majority of the class, his oddities, his frequently almost inaudible delivery.
Only later did I learn that he had developed into a fine lecturer.
The reader will be lenient with my crime de lese majeste - I was too
young to appreciate all the virtues Einstein exhibited already in those days
to those who had an open mind. But I was a Schrodinger man, whose tem-
perament, elegance of exposition, humor, and charm, apart from his genius
as a physicist, had me completely captivated. I even imitated his gait, dressed
like him, adopted his mannerisms, and became a ludicrous copy of him, who
loathed hero-worship. He treated me with acid sarcasm when he perceived
my helpless parody - in fact, he accused me of travesty, of caricaturing
him. Still, I became his assistant and later his younger friend. I soon learnt
that Schrodinger had nothing but highest admiration for Einstein, as a
scholar, a human being, a model of unblemished moral conduct and recti-
tude.
When Friedrich Schiller's centennial of his death was the object of end-
less memorial celebrations by the press, the public, the literati, the painter-
poet Morgenstern decided to convert the name of the beloved titanic genius
into Max Zottuk. All this feverish glorification, this puerile apotheosis was
just too much for him who loved and admired Schiller in stillness, and with
passion. Well, I sympathize with Morgenstern and would prefer to call Ein-
stein no longer by his name, but toy with the idea to dub him Berthold Wal-
dinger. B. W. could have afforded to neglect his external appearance, social
duties, academic conventions. He would have overcome his innate aversion
to close relations with people. The epithets "egghead," "odd ball," "enfant
terrible" would have never aroused his ire - at most, his subtle sense of
humour.
Einstein - and the Vanity of Academia 219
It was formerly believed that, if all material things disappeared from the universe,
time and space would be left. According to RT, however, time and space disappear
together with the things. This is all.