Week001-Process of Doing Philosophy-Part1 z2GdBS
Week001-Process of Doing Philosophy-Part1 z2GdBS
Introduction to Philosophy
1
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
• the study of the most general and abstract features of the world and categories
with which we think: mind, matter, reason, proof, truth, etc. (Oxford Dictionary of
Philosophy)
• careful thought about the fundamental nature of the world, the grounds for human
knowledge, and the evaluation of human conduct (The Philosophy Pages)
As used originally by the ancient Greeks, the term "philosophy" meant the pursuit
of knowledge for its own sake, and comprised ALL areas of speculative thought,
including the arts, sciences and religion.
2
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
What is the best approach to philosophy?
We can approach philosophy by looking at its history (eg The ancient Greeks,
Descartes etc) or we can study by topic (philosophy of science, philosophy of mind etc).
Both have their merits. Whichever we choose, its important to have an understanding of
what philosophers have thought about and we will be examining key works of the key
philosophers. Philosophy is also about using our imagination to come up with new ideas
and argue in their defence, or to challenge existing ideas by providing rational arguments
against them. It is an activity. To argue effectively we need to be aware of what it is to
reason. There is little (or nothing) to be gained by proclaiming we have a ‘philosophy’
about this or that without supporting our ideas by reason or if we have no declared
reasons for holding a view to simply state ‘’that’s what I believe and that’s all there is to
it’’. Doing Philosophy
Logic
In Star Trek when Spock is referred to as being ‘logical’ it is usually taken to
mean that he is without emotion. Sherlock Holmes is considered similarly ‘cold’. Why is
this? And what is being ‘logical’ anyway?
3
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
This view of philosophy appears to result, partly from a wrong conception of the
ends of life, partly from a wrong conception of the kind of goods which philosophy
strives to achieve. Physical science, through the medium of inventions, is useful to
innumerable people who are wholly ignorant of it; thus the study of physical science is to
be recommended, not only, or primarily, because of the effect on the student, but rather
because of the effect on mankind in general. Thus utility does not belong to philosophy.
If the study of philosophy has any value at all for others than students of philosophy, it
must be only indirectly, through its effects upon the lives of those who study it. It is in
these effects, therefore, if anywhere, that the value of philosophy must be primarily
sought.
But further, if we are not to fail in our endeavour to determine the value of
philosophy, we must first free our minds from the prejudices of what are wrongly called
'practical' men. The 'practical' man, as this word is often used, is one who recognizes only
material needs, who realizes that men must have food for the body, but is oblivious of the
necessity of providing food for the mind. If all men were well off, if poverty and disease
had been reduced to their lowest possible point, there would still remain much to be done
to produce a valuable society; and even in the existing world the goods of the mind are at
least as important as the goods of the body. It is exclusively among the goods of the mind
that the value of philosophy is to be found; and only those who are not indifferent to
these goods can be persuaded that the study of philosophy is not a waste of time.
Philosophy, like all other studies, aims primarily at knowledge. The knowledge it
aims at is the kind of knowledge which gives unity and system to the body of the
sciences, and the kind which results from a critical examination of the grounds of our
convictions, prejudices, and beliefs. But it cannot be maintained that philosophy has had
any very great measure of success in its attempts to provide definite answers to its
questions. If you ask a mathematician, a mineralogist, a historian, or any other man of
learning, what definite body of truths has been ascertained by his science, his answer will
last as long as you are willing to listen. But if you put the same question to a philosopher,
he will, if he is candid, have to confess that his study has not achieved positive results
4
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
such as have been achieved by other sciences. It is true that this is partly accounted for by
the fact that, as soon as definite knowledge concerning any subject becomes possible, this
subject ceases to be called philosophy, and becomes a separate science. The whole study
of the heavens, which now belongs to astronomy, was once included in philosophy;
Newton's great work was called 'the mathematical principles of natural philosophy'.
Similarly, the study of the human mind, which was a part of philosophy, has now been
separated from philosophy and has become the science of psychology. Thus, to a great
extent, the uncertainty of philosophy is more apparent than real: those questions which
are already capable of definite answers are placed in the sciences, while those only to
which, at present, no definite answer can be given, remain to form the residue which is
called philosophy.
This is, however, only a part of the truth concerning the uncertainty of
philosophy. There are many questions—and among them those that are of the
profoundest interest to our spiritual life—which, so far as we can see, must remain
insoluble to the human intellect unless its powers become of quite a different order from
what they are now. Has the universe any unity of plan or purpose, or is it a fortuitous
concourse of atoms? Is consciousness a permanent part of the universe, giving hope of
indefinite growth in wisdom, or is it a transitory accident on a small planet on which life
must ultimately become impossible? Are good and evil of importance to the universe or
only to man? Such questions are asked by philosophy, and variously answered by various
philosophers. But it would seem that, whether answers be otherwise discoverable or not,
the answers suggested by philosophy are none of them demonstrably true. Yet, however
slight may be the hope of discovering an answer, it is part of the business of philosophy
to continue the consideration of such questions, to make us aware of their importance, to
examine all the approaches to them, and to keep alive that speculative interest in the
universe which is apt to be killed by confining ourselves to definitely ascertainable
knowledge.
Many philosophers, it is true, have held that philosophy could establish the truth of
certain answers to such fundamental questions. They have supposed that what is of most
5
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
importance in religious beliefs could be proved by strict demonstration to be true. In
order to judge of such attempts, it is necessary to take a survey of human knowledge, and
to form an opinion as to its methods and its limitations. On such a subject it would be
unwise to pronounce dogmatically; but if the investigations of our previous chapters have
not led us astray, we shall be compelled to renounce the hope of finding philosophical
proofs of religious beliefs. We cannot, therefore, include as part of the value of
philosophy any definite set of answers to such questions. Hence, once more, the value of
philosophy must not depend upon any supposed body of definitely ascertainable
knowledge to be acquired by those who study it.
The value of philosophy is, in fact, to be sought largely in its very uncertainty.
The man who has no tincture of philosophy goes through life imprisoned in the
prejudices derived from common sense, from the habitual beliefs of his age or his nation,
and from convictions which have grown up in his mind without the co-operation or
consent of his deliberate reason. To such a man the world tends to become definite, finite,
obvious; common objects rouse no questions, and unfamiliar possibilities are
contemptuously rejected. As soon as we begin to philosophize, on the contrary, we find,
as we saw in our opening chapters, that even the most everyday things lead to problems
to which only very incomplete answers can be given. Philosophy, though unable to tell us
with certainty what is the true answer to the doubts which it raises, is able to suggest
many possibilities which enlarge our thoughts and free them from the tyranny of custom.
Thus, while diminishing our feeling of certainty as to what things are, it greatly increases
our knowledge as to what they may be; it removes the somewhat arrogant dogmatism of
those who have never travelled into the region of liberating doubt, and it keeps alive our
sense of wonder by showing familiar things in an unfamiliar aspect.
6
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
as it may help or hinder what comes within the circle of instinctive wishes. In such a life
there is something feverish and confined, in comparison with which the philosophic life
is calm and free. The private world of instinctive interests is a small one, set in the midst
of a great and powerful world which must, sooner or later, lay our private world in ruins.
Unless we can so enlarge our interests as to include the whole outer world, we remain
like a garrison in a beleaguered fortress, knowing that the enemy prevents escape and that
ultimate surrender is inevitable. In such a life there is no peace, but a constant strife
between the insistence of desire and the powerlessness of will. In one way or another, if
our life is to be great and free, we must escape this prison and this strife.
For this reason greatness of soul is not fostered by those philosophies which
assimilate the universe to Man. Knowledge is a form of union of Self and not-Self; like
7
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
all union, it is impaired by dominion, and therefore by any attempt to force the universe
into conformity with what we find in ourselves. There is a widespread philosophical
tendency towards the view which tells us that Man is the measure of all things, that truth
is man-made, that space and time and the world of universals are properties of the mind,
and that, if there be anything not created by the mind, it is unknowable and of no account
for us. This view, if our previous discussions were correct, is untrue; but in addition to
being untrue, it has the effect of robbing philosophic contemplation of all that gives it
value, since it fetters contemplation to Self. What it calls knowledge is not a union with
the not-Self, but a set of prejudices, habits, and desires, making an impenetrable veil
between us and the world beyond. The man who finds pleasure in such a theory of
knowledge is like the man who never leaves the domestic circle for fear his word might
not be law.
The true philosophic contemplation, on the contrary, finds its satisfaction in every
enlargement of the not-Self, in everything that magnifies the objects contemplated, and
thereby the subject contemplating. Everything, in contemplation, that is personal or
private, everything that depends upon habit, self-interest, or desire, distorts the object,
and hence impairs the union which the intellect seeks. By thus making a barrier between
subject and object, such personal and private things become a prison to the intellect. The
free intellect will see as God might see, without a here and now, without hopes and fears,
without the trammels of customary beliefs and traditional prejudices, calmly,
dispassionately, in the sole and exclusive desire of knowledge—knowledge as
impersonal, as purely contemplative, as it is possible for man to attain. Hence also the
free intellect will value more the abstract and universal knowledge into which the
accidents of private history do not enter, than the knowledge brought by the senses, and
dependent, as such knowledge must be, upon an exclusive and personal point of view and
a body whose sense-organs distort as much as they reveal.
The mind which has become accustomed to the freedom and impartiality of
philosophic contemplation will preserve something of the same freedom and impartiality
in the world of action and emotion. It will view its purposes and desires as parts of the
8
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
whole, with the absence of insistence that results from seeing them as infinitesimal
fragments in a world of which all the rest is unaffected by any one man's deeds. The
impartiality which, in contemplation, is the unalloyed desire for truth, is the very same
quality of mind which, in action, is justice, and in emotion is that universal love which
can be given to all, and not only to those who are judged useful or admirable. Thus
contemplation enlarges not only the objects of our thoughts, but also the objects of our
actions and our affections: it makes us citizens of the universe, not only of one walled
city at war with all the rest. In this citizenship of the universe consists man's true
freedom, and his liberation from the thraldom of narrow hopes and fears.
9
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
4. Finally, we might argue that philosophical (critical) thinking protects us against
unsupported ideology, unjustified authority, unfounded beliefs, baseless propaganda, and
questionable cultural values. These forces may manipulate us if we don’t understand
them, and can’t think critically about them. This doesn’t require a rejection of cultural
values, only a reflection on them. Otherwise, they aren’t our values, ideas, or beliefs—we
have accepted them second-hand. To this you might respond that reflection is laborious,
that ignorance is bliss, and that trust in authority and tradition maintain culture.
Holism
The term “meaning holism” is generally applied to views that treat the meanings of all of
the words in a language as interdependent. Holism draws much of its appeal from the way in
which the usage of all our words seems interconnected, and runs into many problems because the
resultant view can seem to conflict with (among other things) the intuition that meanings are by
and large shared and stable.
10
Course Title: Process of Doing Philosophy – Part 1
Week No. 001 / Module 001
References:
• https://philonotes.com/index.php/2017/12/24/doing-philosophy/
• https://www.slideshare.net/t0nywilliams/doing-philosophy
• https://www.slideshare.net/t0nywilliams/doing-philosophy-9144292
• https://reasonandmeaning.com/2016/03/25/the-value-of-philosophy/
• https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meaning-holism/
11