Theory of Superstition
Theory of Superstition
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=oup. .
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Oxford University Press and The British Society for the Philosophy of Science are collaborating with JSTOR to
digitize, preserve and extend access to The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science.
http://www.jstor.org
TOWARDS A THEORETICAL
CONCEPTUALISATION OF SUPERSTITION *
I. Introduction
Then, too, we are aware that the amount of descriptive material existing
on superstitions is vast by any standards. Frazer's (1925) encylopedic
GoldenBoughand Tylor's (1888) classic work on primitive societies are
but two early examples of the bulk of ethnographic work on this topic.
Lewinsohn's (1961) book on prophecy and prediction, Willoughby's
(1935) lengthy article on magic, and Cohen's (1960) work on gambling
behaviour are likewise replete with examples of superstitious practices.
In short, the concept is too familiar to seem very strange. But upon
exanminationthis familiarity acquires a fascinating strangeness.
The focus of this fascination is the functional significance of invalid
beliefs. A number of writers have been impressed with this idea.
Malinowski's (1926) analysis of magical practices among the Trobriand
Islanders centres about the thesis that every such practice and corres-
ponding superstitious belief,' fulfills some vital function, has some task
to accomplish, representsan indispensablepart within a working whole'
(p. 132). Malinowski established the importance of superstitions by
viewing them in theirfunctional context. The serious student of cul-
ture and behaviour could no longer disdainfully dismiss superstitions
as futile primitive beliefs or esoteric phenomena. Malinowski con-
sidered superstitions to be current vital elements within a culture rather
than vestigial remnants of the past.
This conception is both tempered and extended toward psychology
in Merton's discussion(1957) of the distinction between the manifest and
latent functions of social behaviour. The application of latent function
analysis clarifies apparentirrational, paradoxical, and superstitioussocial
patterns. For instance, once the latent function of conspicuous con-
sumption is seen to be the acquisition of status through expensive
purchases, this pattern of social behaviour is better understood, and
no longer appears paradoxical. Superstitions are established in this
sense as continuous with normal or rational modes of believing and
behaving.
A third and more purely psychological point of view is contained in
Rotter's Social Learning Theory. Rotter's conception of' Generalised
Expectancies' is inclusive of a class of beliefs that might well be labelled
'superstitions'. An expectancy is defined by Rotter (1954) as, 'The
probability held by the individual that a particular reinforcement will
occur as a function ofa specific behavior on his part in a specific situ-
ation or situations' (p. 10o7). Expectancies derived from specific situ-
ations tend to generalise to similar situations. Rotter views the failure
to cross-validate generalised expectancies as responsible for superstitions.
144
THEORETICAL CONCEPTUALISATION OF SUPERSTITION
2. SomeDefinitionsandSomeQuestions
Anticipatingthe model which will later be presented,we define a
superstitionas a specialkind of expectation(or subjectiveprobability,
hypothesis, premise, belief). A superstitionmay be said to exist
whenever an individualpersistentlyor repeatedlybehavesas if his sub-
jectiveestimateof theresultof thatbehaviouris significantly
diferentfroman
objective(scientific)estimateof the effectof that behaviour. Some un-
settledproblemsas to the inclusivenessof this definitionare contained
here, but it will do for a start. However, it shouldbe clearlyunder-
stood that the term superstitionis not meant at this time in its usual
pejorativesense. The full reasonsfor this will become clearlater.
Questions that deserve examination regarding these special ex-
pectanciesincludethe following. What determineswhetheror not an
individual subscribesto a given superstition? Some people carry
charmsand amulets,consultastrologersand palmists,and some do not.
Is it the casethat some people are superstitiousand some arenot? Or
K 145
KARL E. SCHEIBE AND THEODORE R. SARBIN
3. A Cognitive Model
What does a man need in orderto participatein a culture? In the
simplestterms,he needsa body with musclesthatwork. In addition,
he needs some desires,or values. These two propositionsmay be
combinedinto the following sentence: Man wants a great variety of
things; for example,food, shelter,and clothing; children,happiness,
satisfaction,security,and a senseof self-esteem,andis capableof action.
But he lacks the sine.quanon to participatein a culture, to behave
effectively. He needsto know how to directhis actionstowarddesired
ends. In Tolman's(I958) terms,he needs to have a cognitive map of
means-endsrelationships. In the terms of the present analysis,he
needs a set of beliefs, some of which may be denoted by the term
' superstitions'.
The behaviour model here suggestedis in part borrowed from
Rotter (1954). The potentialto behaveis some functionof the expec-
tancy regardinga favourableoutcomeof thatbehaviour,and the value
of the outcome of that behaviour. Expectanciesderive from past
observationsof contiguously occurring events, and may be said to
represent perceivedcause and effect relationships between behaviours
and the outcomes of behaviours. To complete the skeleton of the
model for superstition,it need only be observedthat real cause and
1
senseis not hereintended,anaffirmative
Sincethe pejorative answerto thislast
needoffendno one.
proposition
146
THEORETICAL CONCEPTUALISATION OF SUPERSTITION
effectrelationshipsareobscure,andoften quitedifferentfromperceived
causeand effect relationships.
We are now brought up to the psychologicalproblem of epistomo-
logy. How do we come to know what we know? What is the
relationof the real world to the known world? How do we know
thatwe know? Hume argues that cause and effect relationshipsare
not ultimately compelled upon us in toto, but rather are inferences
basedupon contiguity. He saysin his Treatiseof Human Nature,' We
find only thatthe effectdoes, in fact, follow the cause. The impactof
one billiardball upon anotheris followed by the motion of the second.
There is here contiguity in space and time, but nothing to suggest
necessaryconnection.' Yet, it is often over-looked that though this
inferencebe logically unnecessary,it is psychologicallyvery powerful.
Cause and effect relationshipsare psychologicallycompelled upon us
in toto, as Heider (1944), Michotte (I963), and Piaget (1955) have amply
demonstrated. In short,it is possibleto believe that the known world
is the realworld, andto act asif it is, even thoughit might be impossible
to be ultimatelycorrectin this belief.
Consideran example: FarmerBrown wants-toplanthis corn. He
wantsto do it so as to mnaximise his autumnharvest. What is to deter-
mine when and how he plantsand cultivateshis corn? He certainly
does not proceedon a trialand errorbasis. He usesa numberof rules.
These will have to do with the calendardate, the stateof the weather,
the moistureof the soil, the type of seed, and perhapsthe phaseof the
moon or the pain in his bunions. He has probably derived few if any
of these rules by his own empirical observations, but has acquired them
from his 'cultures '. But only some of them would be called super-
stitions, and these would be so called because of some demonstration
that the application of the rule hasno effect on the outcome of the crop.
However, even if Farmer Brown were to be shown compelling
statisticswhich contradicted one of his rules (expectancies) he still might
apply the rule. Under these circumstances, we would feel justified
in calling Farmer Brown's behaviour superstitious.
To rephrase the conceptual scheme: superstitions come to exist
because of imperfect knowledge of antecedent-consequent relation-
ships in the ecology. On the assumption that an elaborate and fairly
definite set of beliefs is necessaryto support active behaviour, we con-
sider superstitions to 'fill the gap', as it were, between the objective
probability estimates available to a person, and the degree of subjective
probability required to execute behaviours. The beginning fact is
'47
KARL E. SCHEIBE AND THEODORE R. SARBIN
153
KARL E. SCHEIBE AND THEODORE R. SARBIN
from that of the surrounding communities, and this distinction is
cherished by the Hutterites. A remarkable people, they have success-
fully resisted the intrusion of science into the majority of their customs,
and do not seem much the worse for this rigidity. In fact, their child-
birth traditions function so well for them, that while the average
mother has 1I children, a severe complication is very rare. The
Hutterites have numerous superstitions about the' evil eye' and about
sexual taboos, and these are accepted from generation to generation
without much question. Alcoholism, crime, dope-addiction, and
mental disorders are present only to a negligible degree. In fact, the
current problems of this culture can be traced directly to the partially
successful attempts of outsiders to have them institute more modern
practices in childbirth and child rearing. The beliefs of this culture
have worked for them in a very efficient and satisfying fashion and are
thereby self-sustaining. The truth of this statement is demonstrable
even though we would not hesitate to label a large number of their
beliefs as' superstitions'.
Of course, not all persistent superstitions have such an obvious
functional significance. Saunders (1958) reports that beliefs regarding
medical practices came from four widely disparate sources for the
Spanish-Americansof the south-west. These people seem to be able to
accept all of these beliefs, even though many of them seem contra-
dictory. Characteristically, they try their own folk-medicine first,
and if these techniques are ineffective, they simply turn to something
else. 'A remedy is tried, and if it works no surprise is evinced, since
that is what was expected. If it does not work, the failureis rationalized
and something else is tried' (Saunders, I958, p. 191). Clearly these
folk beliefs exhibit a fair amount of inertia in the face of challenge.
Beliefs which seem inconsistent and dissonant to us are not necessarily
so for the people who hold those beliefs.
Another basis for the maintenance of a superstition is the process of
insulation against or distortion of objective information to conform to
the superstitious commitment. For example, for some individuals
agreement between the conclusion of a syllogism and one's own beliefs
functions as a criterion forjudging the soundness ofsyllogistic reasoning
(Thouless, 1959; Morgan and Morton, 1944; Thistlethwaite, 195o).
Highly prejudiced individuals are resistant to change in general
(Rokeach, 1943) and individuals with highly conservative beliefs are
resistant to contrary information (Frenkel-Brunswik, 1949).
It has been experimentally demonstrated that the extent to which
I54
THEORETICAL CONCEPTUALISATION OF SUPERSTITION
beliefs about matters of fact deviate from the truth is highly related to
the level of information the respondents possess about those facts.
Moreover, the distortions in beliefs are consistent with the evaluative
significance assigned by the respondents to those beliefs. That is,
individuals tend to believe what they want to believe where lack of
information makes this possible (Scheibe, I963).
In sum, superstitious beliefs seem to have a fair amount of stability.
If they are not challenged they are maintained. Even if moderate
degrees of challenge are made to established superstitions,the individual
is likely to prefer distorting facts or logic to discarding the superstition
(Cohen, Brehm and Latane, I959). Of course, there are interesting
individual differences in this regard: 'The passion for unity and
smoothness is in some minds so insatiate that, in spite of the logical
clearnessof... reasonings and conclusions, many will fail to be influen-
ced by them' (James, I, I890, p. I62).
6. AnotherFunctioinof Superstitions
A tertiary functional significance of muncertaintymay give rise to
superstition. James has said that uncertainty must exist in order for
man to have a sense of personal significance. Many 'classical'
psychologists would agree with him. (For instance, France, 1902).
The essence of Kierkegaard's philosophy is that man must cope with
uncertainty and unpredictability. If man were to have true vision of
cause and effect relationships, there would follow, according to some,
a complete abrogation of human responsibility. It is the uncertainties
which give life its vigour and interest. Others of a less romantic
persuasion view this line of thinking as a severe restriction on the
progress of scientific knowledge, and openly propose that we seek to
establish a completely controlled and predictable universe. The
flavour of this issue is conveyed in this statement by Skinner (Rogers
and Skinner, 1956).
A world in which people are wise and good, without trying, without
'having to be' or without 'choosing to be', could conceivably be a
far betterworld for everyone. In such a world we should not have to
'give anyone credit '-we should not need to admire anyone-for
being wise and good. From our present point of view we cannot
believe that such a world would be admirable. We do not permit
ourselvesto imagine what it would be like (p. 10o60).
We do not propose to discuss this issue here. However, it should
serve as a caution to those who would cavalierly declare that human
11 I155
KARL E. SCHEIBE AND THEODORE R. SARBIN
I56
THEORETICAL CONCEPTUALISATION OF SUPERSTITION
REFERENCES
157
KARL E. SCHEIBE AND THEODORE R. SARBIN
F. Heider, 'Social Perceptionand PhenomenalCausality', Psychol.Rev., 1944, 51,
358-374.
W. James,Principlesof Psychology,Vols.I andII, Henry Holt, New York, 1890o.
J.Jastrow,FactandFablein Psychology,Macmillan,New York, 19oo.
R. Lewinsohn,ProphetsandPrediction, Secker & Warburg,London, I96r.
B. Malinowski, 'Anthropology', Encyclopedia Britannica,First SupplementaryVol-
ume, London and New York, 1926.
R. K. Merton, Social TheoryandSocialStructure. Glencoc,Ill. : FreePress,I957.
of Causality(trans.by T. R. andElaineMiles),Methuen,
A. E. Miclhotte,ThePerception
London, 1963.
J.J.B. MorganandJ. T. Morton,' The Distortionof SyllogisticReasoningProduced
by PersonalConvictions', J. Soc.Psycho!l.,1944, 20, 39-59.
W. H. Morse and B. F. SkiInner,' A Second Type of Superstitionin the Pigeon',
Amer.J. Psychol., 1957, 70, 308-311.
of Realityiil the Clhild(trans.by MargaretCook), Basic
Jean Piaget, The Construction
Books, New York, I955.
Carl R. Rogers and 13.F. Skinner,'Some IssuesConcerningthe Control of Human
Behavior : A Symposium', Science, 1956, 123, lo57-1o66.
M. Rokeach,' GeneralizedMentalRigidit) as a Factorin Ethnocentrism', J. Abn. &
Soc. Psychol., 1948, 43, 259-278.
J.B. Rotter, SocialLearningand ClinicalPsychology,Prentice-Hall,New York, I954.
T. R. Sarbin,R. Taft and D. Bailey, ClinicalIifcrenceand CognitiveTheory,Holt,
Rinehart & Winston, New York, 1960.
T. R. Sarbin,Role-TheoreticalAnalysisof Schizophrenia,Ms. 1962.
L. Saunders,'Healing Ways in the SpanishSouthwest'. In E. Jaco (ed.), Patients,
Physicians,andIllness,FreePress,Glencoe, 1958.
K. E. Scheibe, 'On the Relationship Between Beliefs and Values, unpublished
doctoraldissertation,University of California,Berkeley, 1963.
B. F. Skinner,' Superstitionin the Pigeon ',J. Exp. Psychol.,1948, 38, 168-172.
SmokingandHealth,reportof the Advisory Committeeto the SurgeonGeneralof the
Public Health Service,1964, Washington,D.C.
D. Thistlethwaite,'Attitude and Structureand Factorsin the Distortionof Reason-
ing ', J. Abn. & Soc. Psycho!., 1950, 45, 442-458.
R. H. Thouless, 'The Effect of Prejudiceon Reasoning', Brit.J. Psychol.,1959, 50,
289-293.
E. C. Tolmnan,BehaviorandPsychological Man, University of CaliforniaPress, 1958.
E. B. Tylor, Primitive
Culture
(2 vols.), Holt, New York, 1888.
R. R. Willoughby,'Magic and CognatePhenomena: An hypothesis',in C.
(ed.),Handbook
Murclhison ClarkUniversityPress,Worcester,
of SocialPsychology,
Mass., 1935.
rS8