AP Cours 2-6
AP Cours 2-6
Lorenzo Bretscher
1 / 23
Uncertainty
We will try to understand the pricing of financial assets from an equilibrium perspective.
In an equilibrium, prices are such that they equate investors’ demand for assets with their
supply. To understand investors demand, we first need to understand how they make
choices in uncertain environments. We will consider a simple model of choice under
uncertainty.
For now, there is one period (i.e. two dates). This will be straightforward to
re-interpret in multi-period settings later on.
Uncertainty:
I The state of the world at the beginning of the period is known with certainty.
At the end of the period there are S discrete states, and we denote the state
space as ⌦ = {!1 , !2 , ..., !S }.
I The associated objective probabilities are ⇧ = {⇡ 1 , ⇡ 2 , ..., ⇡ S }, and these are
also the subjective probabilities of all agents. Clearly, ⇡ 1 + ... + ⇡ S = 1.
2 / 23
Consumption Plans
state !j 1 2 3
probability ⇡j 0.2 0.3 0.5
cons plan C (1) 3 2 4
cons plan C (2) 3 1 5
cons plan C (3) 4 4 1
cons plan C (4) 1 1 4
We want to develop a notion of how individuals choose among the set C of all
consumption plans consistently. Preferences that lead to consistent choices are
called a preference relation.
3 / 23
Consumption Lotteries
Let us assume that individuals only care about the probability distributions over
consumption and thus that preferences are state-independent. Then, we can represent
consumption plans as consumption lotteries over outcomes rather than states.
Let Z denote the set of all consumption levels z generates by any C 2 C. Each
consumption plan C is associated with a probability distribution pC , which is the
function pC : Z ! [0, 1] given by
X
pC (z) = ⇡! (1)
!2⌦:c! =z
Two different plans, C (3) and C (4) give rise to the same probability distribution over
Z.
4 / 23
Preferences over Consumption Lotteries
5 / 23
A Safe and a Risky Lottery
More general:
Suppose there are two possible states of the world: x and y . Further assume that
x materializes with probability ⇡ and, hence, y with 1 ⇡.
Notation: L = (x, y , ⇡)
6 / 23
Preferences over Consumption Lotteries
We assume that individuals have preferences over outcomes and represent them
by a preference relation ⌫, where for two lotteries p and p 0 we denote
7 / 23
An Example
8 / 23
Choice Rules
We will assume that preference relations are complete and transitive in the following.
Given preferences, how will an agent behave? We assume that given a set of choices
(lotteries) B 2 P, the agent will choose the element of B she prefers most. To formalize
this, we define an agent’s choice rule given a preference relation ⌫
Note that
(B; ⌫) may contain more than one element
If B is finite, (B; ⌫) is non-empty.
While ultimately, what we observe about a preference relation ⌫ are choices, i.e (B; ⌫),
it is convenient to try to represent them by a numerical ranking, namely a utility. We
now examine under what conditions this is possible.
9 / 23
Utility Indices
p ⌫ p0 , U(p) U (p 0 )
10 / 23
Utility Indices: Axioms - Monotonicity
Suppose that p, p 0 2 P(Z ) with p p 0 and let a, b 2 [0, 1]. The preference
relation ⌫ has the monotonicity property if
11 / 23
Utility Indices: Axioms - Archimedean Property
ap + (1 a)p 00 p0 bp + (1 b)p 00
In words: No matter how good a lottery is, if we put sufficiently low weight
on it, we find a compound lottery to which we prefer p 0 . Similarly, no matter
how bad a lottery is, if we put sufficiently low weight on it, we find a
compound lottery which we prefer to p 0 .
12 / 23
Utility Indices: Axioms - Continuity Property
p 0 ⇠ ap + (1 a)p 00
In words: For any three lotteries, there is a unique combination between the
best and the worst lottery such that the agent is indifferent between the
middle lottery and that combination.
13 / 23
Continuity Property
14 / 23
Existence of Utility Indices
15 / 23
Expected Utility
17 / 23
Independence Axiom
Example:
z 1 2 3 4
p1 0 0.2 0.6 0.2
p2 0 0.4 0.2 0.4
p3 1 0 0 0
p4 0.5 0.1 0.3 0.1
p5 0.5 0.2 0.1 0.2
Suppose we want to compare p4 and p5 . They only differ in the probabilities of
consumption levels 2, 3 and 4, so it should suffice to compare those. More formally, we
have
p4 ⇠ 0.5p1 + 0.5p3 and p5 ⇠ 0.5p2 + 0.5p3
p1 is the conditional distribution of p4 given that z is different from 1, and p2 is the
conditional distribution of p5 given that z is different from 1. The independence axiom
then says
p4 p5 , p1 p2
18 / 23
Independence Axiom
19 / 23
von Neumann-Morgenstern Theorem
20 / 23
von Neumann-Morgenstern Theorem
21 / 23
The Allais Experiment
22 / 23
The Allais Experiment
The expected utility framework assumes that agents assign probabilities to all outcomes.
In the terminology of Knight-Savage, they deal with risk (ie situations in which it is
possible to assign probabilities) as opposed to uncertainty (ie situations where one is just
clueless). In a famous experiment, Ellsberg (1961) casts doubt on the probability
assignments.
An urn contains 300 balls; 100 are red and 200 are some mix of white and blue. We
are going to draw a ball at random.
I You will receive $100 if you correctly guess the ball’s color. Would you rather
23 / 23
The Ellsberg Experiment
The expected utility framework assumes that agents assign probabilities to all outcomes.
In the terminology of Knight-Savage, they deal with risk (ie situations in which it is
possible to assign probabilities) as opposed to uncertainty (ie situations where one is just
clueless). In a famous experiment, Ellsberg (1961) casts doubt on the probability
assignments.
An urn contains 300 balls; 100 are red and 200 are some mix of white and blue. We
are going to draw a ball at random.
I You will receive $100 if you correctly guess the ball’s color. Would you rather
Lorenzo Bretscher
1 / 27
Risk and Risk Attitudes
Let us now assume that we are in an expected utility framework. Agents face
uncertainty, but can assign probabilities to all outcomes. In other words, they are
exposed to risk. We now want to examine what attitudes to risk agents’
preferences exhibit.
2 / 27
Risk Attitudes
3 / 27
Risk Attitudes
3 / 27
Risk Attitudes
3 / 27
Risk Attitudes
3 / 27
Risk Attitudes
3 / 27
Risk Aversion
Any consumption plan can be thought of as a sum of its expected value, E [W̃ ]
and a fair gamble "˜ = W̃ E [W̃ ]. Under expected utility, an agent is thus risk
averse if and only if she prefers the certain consumption E [W̃ ] to the random
consumption W̃ , or
u(E [W̃ ]) E [u(W̃ )]
By Jensen’s inequality, this holds exactly whenever u is concave.
A function u : Z ! R is concave if for all z, z 0 2 Z and all ↵ 2 (0, 1) we
have
u(↵z + (1 ↵)z 0 ) ↵u(z) + (1 ↵)u(z 0 )
When the inequality is strict, u is strictly concave.
Whenever u is twice differentiable in the interior of Z , concavity is equivalent
to u 00 0.
4 / 27
Risk Aversion
5 / 27
Risk Premium
Notation:
wealth or consumption level W
2
fair gamble "˜ with Var(˜
") =
Wc certainty equivalent of W̃ = W + "˜
⇡=W Wc risk premium
8 / 27
Absolute Risk Aversion
" + 12 U 00 (W )˜
U(W + "˜) ⇡ U(W ) + U 0 (W )˜ "2
2
) E[U(W̃ )] ⇡ U(W ) + 2 U 00 (W )
and
U (Wc ) = U(W ⇡) ⇡ U(W ) U 0 (W )⇡
So the risk premium can be approximated by
2 2
U 00 (W )
⇡⇡ = A(W )
2 U 0 (W ) 2
U 00 (W )
where A(W ) = U 0 (W ) is the coefficient of absolute risk aversion
9 / 27
Absolute Risk Aversion
The risk premium for a small fair gamble around W is approximately equal to
the absolute risk aversion at W
Absolute risk aversion is constant if and only if ⇡ is independent of W
Absolute risk aversion measures the aversion to a fair gamble of a given
(dollar) amount, say winning or losing $1000 dollars with equal probability.
Intuitively, we would expect a wealthier investor to be less averse to such
gambles, ie we would expect absolute risk aversion to be a decreasing
function of wealth (or end of period consumption). We have
✓ ◆2
0 U 000 (W )u 0 (W ) U 00 (W )2 U 00 (W ) U 000 (W )
A (W ) = = <0
U 0 (W )2 U 0 (W ) U 0 (W )
, U 000 (W ) > 0
10 / 27
Comparing Risk Aversion
An individual with vN-M utility function U is said to be more risk averse than
an individual with vN-M utility function V if for any consumption plan W̃
and any fixed W with E [U(W̃ )] > U(W ), we have E [V (W̃ )] > V (W ).
In words: The agent with utility function v will accept all gambles that the
agent with utility function u accepts, and possibly more.
Theorem: Suppose U and V are twice continuously differentiable and
strictly increasing. Then the following conditions are equivalent:
I (a) U is more risk averse than V
I (b) AU (W ) AV (W ) for all W
I (c) a strictly increasing and concave function f exists such that U = f (V )
12 / 27
Common Utility Functions
CRRA utility: constant relative risk aversion utility or power utility. Utility
functions in this class are defined for W 0 as
W1
U(W ) =
1
for > 0 and 6= 1. Differentiating we find that the absolute and relative
risk aversion coefficients are given by
Consider two consumption plans, namely one with certain consumption level W and a
second one delivering (1 ↵)W with probability one half and (1 + ↵)W with probability
one half.
With CRRA utility, the certainty equivalent of the second plan is given by
1 1 1 1 1
(Wc )1 = ((1 ↵)W )1 + ((1 + ↵)W )1
1 21 21
which implies that
1 1/(1 )
Wc = [(1 ↵)1 + (1 + ↵)1 ]1/(1 )
W
2
The risk premium is
✓ ◆1/(1 !
)
1
⇡=W Wc = 1 [(1 ↵)1 + (1 + ↵)1 ]1/(1 )
W
2
14 / 27
CRRA: Example
Risk premia for different levels of relative risk aversion and different gambles:
15 / 27
Risk Aversion and Portfolio Choice
Two assets:
risk-free asset, gross return R0
risky asset, return R̃ with mean R
Amount invested in risky asset: a
No restrictions (unlimited borrowing and short-selling)
Next period wealth:
⇣ ⌘
W̃ = R̃a + R0 (W0 a) = R̃ R0 a + R0 W0
16 / 27
Risk Aversion and Portfolio Choice
17 / 27
Portfolio Choice with a Single Risky Asset
18 / 27
The Principle of Participation
PROOF:
a⇤ > 0 iff f 0h(a)|a=0 > 0 ⇣ ⌘i
iff E U (R0 W0 ) R̃ R0 > 0
0
iff U 0 (R0 W0 ) (R R0 ) > 0
iff R > R0
So nonparticipation in asset markets cannot be explained by appealing to high risk
aversion; we need something like fixed costs of participation, or a kink in the
utility function that generates "first-order risk aversion"
19 / 27
Comparative Statics of a⇤
a⇤ solves h ⇣ ⌘⇣ ⌘i
0 ⇤
E U W̃ R̃ R0 =0
where ⇣ ⌘
⇤
W̃ = R̃ R 0 a ⇤ + R 0 W0
so that h ⌘⇣ ⇣
⌘i
da⇤ E U W̃ 00
R̃ R0 R0 ⇤
= ⇣ ⌘⇣ ⌘2
dW0
E U 00 W̃ ⇤ R̃ R0
20 / 27
Comparative Statics of a⇤
da⇤
by first order condition, hence dW0 = 0, so a⇤ is invariant to wealth
21 / 27
Comparative Statics of a⇤
Proposition If R > R0 , then a change in the initial level of wealth has the
following effect on the optimal amount invested in the risky asset:
8
> 0 for DARA;
da⇤ <
= 0 for CARA;
dW0 :
< 0 for IARA
Only DARA seems plausible: Bill Gates probably has more money invested in risky
assets than you do
23 / 27
Comparing Risks
While (under the stated assumptions) we can use a utility index or a utility
function to compare risky prospects (consumption plans or lotteries), in some
cases it is possible to rank different risks directly according to their distribution,
with minimal knowledge of an individual’s utility function.
We will now describe lotteries by means of their distribution functions. Let two
lotteries be represented by their respective cumulative distribution functions, say F
and G , defined on an interval [a, b] 2 Z . Assume that an individual’s utility
function u is weakly increasing. We will show that under these conditions
when a lottery F dominates G in the sense of first-order stochastic
dominance, individuals always prefer F to G as longs as U is weakly
increasing.
when a lottery F dominates G in the sense of second-order stochastic
dominance, individuals always prefer F to G as longs as she is risk-averse
and u is weakly increasing.
24 / 27
First-order Stochastic Dominance
25 / 27
Second-order Stochastic Dominance
Let us now assume that F and G have the same mean, so neither dominates in
the sense of first-order stochastic dominance. However, intuitively, for a
risk-averse individual one lottery will still dominate the other if it ’involves more
risk’. Second-order stochastic dominance formalizes this intuition.
For any lotteries F and G with the same mean, F second-order
stochastically dominates G if and only if an individual weakly prefers F to
G under every weakly increasing and concave utility function U.
For any lotteries F and G , G is a mean-preserving spread of F if and only if
Y = Z + "˜
For convenience, we will now state the main theorem concerning second-order
stochastic dominance using continuous distributions.
R R
Theorem: Assume that zdG = zdF . Then the following are equivalent
R R
I (1) u(z)dF (z) u(z)dG (z) for every weakly increasing concave utility
function.
I (2) G is a mean preserving
Rt spread Rof F .
t
I (3) For every t 0, a G (z)dz a
F (z)dz.
27 / 27
Modern Portfolio Theory
Lorenzo Bretscher
1 / 36
Motivation
2 / 36
Setup
We assume that an investor only cares about the mean and variance of
overall portfolio return, Rp : for any given mean return the investor prefers to
minimize variance
We assume that the investor knows the mean return of each individual asset,
R̄i , i = 1, . . . , N, and its variance and covariance with all other assets
0
Notation: we stack the mean returns into a vector R = R̄1 , . . . , R̄N , and
form the variance covariance matrix ⌃
The entry in row i, column j of ⌃ is the covariance of Ri with Rj
3 / 36
MPT - investor preferences
4 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with two risky assets
5 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with two risky assets
R̄p R̄2
w1 =
R̄1 R̄2
The variance of the portfolio return is
2 2
p = w12 2
1 + 2w1 (1 w1 ) ⇢ 1 2 + (1 w1 ) 2
2
Consider the case ⇢ = 0, and suppose you start with a portfolio that is fully
invested in the less risky asset: w2 = 1
What happens to the portfolio mean if you shift a very small amount of
wealth into the riskier asset? What happens to portfolio variance?
8 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with two risky assets
9 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with two risky assets
d p2 2
2 ⇢ 1 2
= 0 =) wMV ,1 = 2 2
dw1 1 2⇢ 1 2 + 2
10 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with two risky assets
11 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
12 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
13 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
14 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
R̄p = w1 R 1 + · · · + wN R N = w0 R
15 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
minw 12 w0 ⌃w
s.t. w0 R = R p
w0 e = 1
16 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
⌃w 1R 2e =0
So
1 1
w= 1⌃ R+ 2⌃ e (1)
Don’t be misled by the notation: there are N first-order conditions
17 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
To solve for the Lagrange multipliers 1 and 2, we use the two constraints:
0 1 0 1
Rp = 1R ⌃ R+ 2e ⌃ R= 1A + 2B
0 1 0 1
1= 1e ⌃ R+ 2e ⌃ e= 1B + 2C
0 1 1 1
where A ⌘ R ⌃ R,B ⌘ e 0 ⌃ R and C ⌘ e 0 ⌃ e
These imply that
C Rp B
1 =
D
A BR p
2 =
D
where D ⌘ AC B2
While A, C and D are all mathematically guaranteed to be positive, we
cannot say the same about B
18 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
19 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
⌃w = 1R + 2e
We aim to show that any other portfolio v with the same mean has a
variance that is at least as large. So, suppose v 0 R = w 0 R
Because w and v are both portfolios, we know that v0 e = w0 e = 1
20 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
v 0 ⌃v = (w + ⌘)0 ⌃(w + ⌘)
= w 0 ⌃w + 2⌘ 0 ⌃w + ⌘ 0 ⌃⌘
= w 0 ⌃w + 2⌘ 0 1R + 2e + ⌘ 0 ⌃⌘
= w 0 ⌃w + ⌘ 0 ⌃⌘
w 0 ⌃w
21 / 36
Mean-variance analysis with N risky assets
Because we have both necessity and sufficiency, we can say that the
mean-variance efficient portfolios are precisely those portfolios w such that
w = 1 ⌃ 1 R + 2 ⌃ 1 e for some 1 and 2
Moreover, given any two distinct mean-variance efficient portfolios, we can
construct any other mean-variance efficient portfolio by combining these two
22 / 36
The minimum-variance portfolio
An investor who wants to minimize variance at all costs will choose the global
minimum variance portfolio
To find this portfolio, we drop the constraint that w 0 R = R p , and find
⌃ 1e
1
w MV = ⌃ e =
e 0⌃ 1e
The expected return on this portfolio is
e 0⌃ 1R B
R MV = w 0MV R = =
e 0⌃ 1e C
Empirically, the minimum-variance portfolio has a positive expected return,
so this suggests that B > 0.
The variance that this portfolio achieves is
1 1
e 0⌃ ⌃⌃ e 1
w 0MV ⌃w MV = 2
=
e 0⌃ 1
e e 0⌃ 1e
23 / 36
The global minimum-variance portfolio
If all assets have equal variance 2 and correlation ⇢ between any two assets,
then the minimum variance portfolio puts equal weight on each asset:
w MV = e/N
2 2 2
Then, w 0MV ⌃w MV = ⇢ + (1 ⇢) /N ⇡ ⇢ for large N
The GMV portfolio has the same covariance with every portfolio:
0 w 0e 1
w ⌃w MV = 1
= 1
>0
e⌃ e
0 e⌃ e
0
24 / 36
A (two) mutual fund theorem
⌃ 1R
w
e ⌘
e 0⌃ 1R
We can use this portfolio together with the minimum variance portfolio to
rewrite (1) as
0 1 0 1
w= 1e ⌃ Rw
e+ 2e ⌃ ew MV = 1B w
e + 2 C w MV
Let the portfolio weights on the risky assets be w1 , . . . , wN as before, and let
the weight on the riskless asset be w0
We want to solve
minw0 ,...,wN 12 w 0 ⌃w
s.t. w0 Rf + w 0 R = R p
w0 + w 0 e = 1
We can use the second constraint to substitute out for w0 . Then the problem
becomes
minw 12 w 0 ⌃w
s.t. w 0 R Rf e = R̄p Rf
26 / 36
Adding a riskless asset
⌃w = R Rf e
Rp Rf
=
E
0 1
where E ⌘ R Rf e ⌃ R Rf e
27 / 36
Adding a riskless asset
28 / 36
Efficient frontier
29 / 36
Adding a riskless asset
Similarly to the previous section, this says that mean-variance investors would
be indifferent between trading all N + 1 assets, and trading just the riskless
asset and tangency portfolio. This is sometimes called Tobin’s mutual fund
theorem
This does not imply that all investors should hold the same portfolio.
Extremely risk-averse investors may want almost all of their wealth in the
riskless asset. Conversely, investors with high risk tolerance may want to lever
up, shorting the riskless asset in order to buy even more of the tangency
portfolio
30 / 36
Covariance properties of efficient portfolios
d R̄p
= R̄i Rf
dwi
dvarRp
= 2 cov (Ri , Rp )
dwi
because the terms in var Rp that involve wi are
31 / 36
Covariance properties of efficient portfolios
If portfolio p is efficient, this ratio should be the same for all assets.
Why? Consider adjusting two different portfolio weights wi and wj (financed
in each case by changes in holdings of the riskless asset). The effects on
mean and variance of Rp are
32 / 36
Covariance properties of efficient portfolios
R̄i Rf
dwj = dwi
R̄j Rf
33 / 36
Covariance properties of efficient portfolios
R i Rf R p Rf
=
cov (Rp , Ri ) var Rp
Rearranging,
cov (Ri , Rp )
Ri Rf = Rp Rf = ip Rp Rf
var Rp
34 / 36
Issues
35 / 36
Issues
This motivates a search for ways of identifying optimal portfolios that are based
on further theoretical considerations
36 / 36
The Capital Asset Pricing Model
Lorenzo Bretscher
1 / 30
Motivation
2 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
Assumptions:
1 All investors are mean-variance optimizers
2 All investors perceive the same means, variances, and covariances
3 All investors can borrow or lend at a given riskfree interest rate
4 All risky assets are in positive supply (i.e., the total market value of every
asset is positive) and the riskless asset is in zero net supply (i.e., the total
amount of borrowing equals the total amount of lending)
3 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
Assumptions (i)-(iii) imply that all investors work with the same
mean-standard-deviation diagram; every investor is solving the same
mean-variance portfolio choice problem
So every investor holds a mean-variance efficient portfolio
Since all mean-variance efficient portfolios combine the riskless asset with a
fixed portfolio of risky assets, we can conclude that all investors hold risky
assets in the same proportions (namely, the proportions of the tangency
portfolio, w t )
Thus, investor i has risky asset portfolio shares w (i) = (i)
wt
I The entries of w t add up to one, but w (i) need not add up to one because of
the presence of the riskless asset. (If you allocate 80% of your wealth, in total,
to the risky assets, then you can put the remaining 20% in the riskless asset.)
4 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
5 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
wt = wm
6 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
cov (Ri , Rp )
Ri Rf = Rp Rf = ip Rp Rf ,
var Rp
cov (Ri , Rm )
Ri Rf = Rm Rf = im Rm Rf (1)
var Rm
The CAPM beta, im = cov (Ri , Rm ) / var Rm , is the coefficient on Rm in a
regression of Ri on Rm
7 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
R i = Rf + im Rm Rf
What it does/says:
gives the relationship between expected return and risk (as measured by )
that holds for all individual securities and portfolios of securities
the expected return on any security i is equal to:
1 the risk-free rate plus
2 a risk premium that is equal to the security’s beta multiplied by the market
risk premium (excess expected return)
8 / 30
The Capital Market Line (CML)
Capital market line is the capital allocation line for the market portfolio!
9 / 30
Security Market Line
The security market line (SML) is the plot of the linear relationship between
expected return and beta implied by the CAPM
10 / 30
The Capital Asset Pricing Model (CAPM)
11 / 30
The CAPM with no Riskless Asset
12 / 30
The CAPM with no Riskless Asset
To get rid of the Lagrange multipliers and , we need a portfolio that plays
the role of the riskless asset in the previous analysis
Natural guess: the minimum-variance portfolio? Wrong!
The right notion is that of the zero-beta portfolio
13 / 30
The CAPM with no Riskless Asset
14 / 30
The CAPM with no Riskless Asset
w 0z R + =0
So,
1
R Rz e = ⌃w m
Pinning down any expected excess return will get rid of the constant of
proportionality 1/ . It is natural to choose the expected excess return on the
market
15 / 30
The CAPM with no Riskless Asset
1
Rm Rz = var Rm
⌃w m
R Rz e = Rm Rz
var Rm
or equivalently
Ri Rz = im Rm Rz (3)
where im = cov (Ri , Rm ) / var Rm
16 / 30
More on Zero Beta Portfolios
17 / 30
More on Zero Beta Portfolios
18 / 30
What Have We Done So Far?
The mean-variance analysis delivered two results: first, the mutual fund
theorem, which reduced the dimensionality from N assets to two mutual
funds (and if a riskless asset exists, we can identify one of these as the
riskless asset, and the other as the tangency portfolio); second, the
characterization of expected returns
Imposing equilibrium lets us identify a particular efficient risky-asset
portfolio: the market portfolio
Perhaps one of the most concrete successes of this framework is the fact that
index funds, which date from the 1970s and were inspired by these results,
are now so prevalent
19 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
20 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
Lagrangian: !
N
X
L = E[U] + W0 1 wn
n=1
where
N
X
W̃ ⇤ = W0 wn⇤ R̃n
n=1
21 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
h ⇣ ⌘ i N
X
E U 0 W̃ ⇤ R̃ ⇤ = where R̃ ⇤ = wn⇤ R̃n
n=1
22 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
where ( )
N
X
W̃ ⇤ = W0 R̃ ⇤ = W0 w0⇤ R0 + wn⇤ R̃n
n=1
23 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
Eliminate :
h ⇣ ⌘ i h ⇣ ⌘ i
0 ⇤ 0 ⇤
E U W̃ R̃n = E U W̃ R0 (n = 1, . . . , N)
24 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
25 / 30
The General One-Period Portfolio Problem
We’ve now done the analogue of the mean-variance portfolio choice problem
h ⇣ ⌘⇣ ⌘i
The first-order conditions (in any form, eg E U W̃
0 ⇤
R̃n R0 = 0 )
are often known as the Euler equation(s))
They are a restriction on the demand for assets that must hold in any
equilibrium model
Fully specified equilibrium models make further assumptions about asset
supply and about U(·)
26 / 30
Mean-Variance Analysis vs Expected Utility
W̃ = W0 R̃ = W0 (R + Z̃ )
where Z̃ ⇠ N(0, 1)
27 / 30
Mean-Variance Analysis vs Expected Utility
Density function of Z̃ :
✓ ◆
1 z2
(z) = p exp
2⇡ 2
Expected utility:
Z 1
2
E[U(W̃ )] = U (W0 [R + z]) (z)dz = V R,
1
Differentiate:
Z 1
@V
= W0 U 0 (W0 [R + z]) (z)dz > 0
@R 1
Z 1
@V 1 @
= U (W0 [R + z]) (z)dz
@ 2 2 @ 1
Z 1
W0
= U 0 (W0 [R + z]) z (z)dz
2 1
<0
28 / 30
Mean-Variance Analysis vs Expected Utility
aW 2
U(W ) = W
2
1
with a > 0, W < a (so that U 0 > 0 and U 00 < 0)
Consider initial wealth W0 and a portfolio with return R̃, mean R, and
variance 2
29 / 30
Mean-Variance Analysis vs Expected Utility
Expected utility:
h ⇣ ⌘i
E[U(W̃ )] = E U W0 R̃
aW02 h 2 i
= W0 E[R̃] E R̃
2
aW02 2
= W0 R + R2
2
Higher order moments are irrelevant
1 2
Expected utility increases in R (if W0 R = E(W̃ ) < a ) and decreases in
Problems: 1) all concave quadratic functions are decreasing after a certain
point (the ’bliss point’), which is incompatible with non-satiation and 2)
quadratic utility implies IARA
30 / 30
Arbitrage Pricing Theory
Lorenzo Bretscher
1 / 18
Reminder: Arbitrage
An asset with price equal to zero and (PV of) E[future CF] > 0!
An asset with a price different from zero and all future CF are equal to zero.
2 / 18
Factor Pricing and Arbitrage Pricing Theory
ERie = e
im Rm
4 / 18
Factor Pricing and Arbitrage Pricing Theory
This variance is very small for large N. Suppose that the maximum
idiosyncratic variance of any asset j is 2 , and that we choose to equally
weight the portfolio (wj = 1/N). Then
2
var "pt
N
As N ! 1 this goes to zero: the portfolio is well diversified
So we can ignore "pt , and we have
e e
Rpt = ↵p + pm Rmt
This is the arbitrage pricing theory (APT) of Ross (1976): if excess returns
can be explained by a market factor Rm,t
e
as in (1), with uncorrelated
residuals, then
e e
ERi,t = im ERm,t
We have derived the beta pricing equation of the CAPM without using any of
the apparatus of mean-variance analysis
The key assumption is that the residual risks "it are uncorrelated (still!)
6 / 18
Anectodal Empirical Evidence
Ri Rf = ↵i + im [Rm R f ] + "i
7 / 18
Advance Micro Devices vs. Intel
8 / 18
AMD vs. INTC
Do CAPM regression for AMD/INTC
AMD: = 3.8%, SPY = 1.42
INTC: = 2.0%, SPY = 1.02
Correlation between "AM and "INTC is 0.2
10 / 18
Factor Pricing and Arbitrage Pricing Theory
11 / 18
Factor Pricing and Arbitrage Pricing Theory
12 / 18
Factor Pricing and Arbitrage Pricing Theory
13 / 18
Factors are Useful for Hedging
If you form a portfolio with the same SPY and GLD , then you track
Barrick’s exposure to these common factors. It’s like replication with factors.
You can track exposure to both factors or exposure to just one (e.g., GLD)
14 / 18
Factors are Useful for Hedging
You want to buy Barrick Gold (ABX), but you want to hedge out the exposure to
the price of gold
15 / 18
Factors are Useful for Hedging
Regress returns of ABX on two factors: SPY and GLD (a gold ETF)
The portfolio that tracks the GLD exposure has GLD = 1.62:
I wGLD = 1.62 and wrF = 0.62
I r˜track = wGLD r˜GLD + wrf rf = 1.62 ⇥ r˜GLD + ( 0.62) ⇥ rf = rf + 1.62 ⇥ [˜
rGLD rf ]
The tracking portfolio has GLD = 1.62
So to hedge out the GLD exposure, short $ 1.62 of GLD for every $ 1
invested in ABX and invest $ 0.62 in the risk-free bond
16 / 18
Factors are Useful for Hedging
Now imagine a portfolio that tracks BOTH SPY and GLD exposure
I wGLD = 1.62, wSPY = 0.45and wrF = 1 (0.62 + 0.45) = 1.07
What is the return of a portfolio long Barrick Gold and short the tracking
portfolio?
r˜hedge = r˜abx r˜track = ↵abx + "˜abx
Let’s assume " = 0. In reality, they are not, but let’s assume this for a
moment ! r˜hedge = ↵abx + "˜abx = ↵abx
If epsilons are always zero, then we have a zero cost portfolio with certain
returns ! what should the return be?
↵abx = 0
17 / 18
Factors are Useful for Hedging
r˜abx = rf + 0.45 ⇥ [˜
rSPY rf ] + 1.62 ⇥ [˜
rGLD rf ]
18 / 18