Schelling's Positive Philosophy
Schelling's Positive Philosophy
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to The Review of Metaphysics
Preface
ed. It is a pity that this revival came too late to make possible
the publication of more than a fraction of the manuscripts, before
their destruction.1
As a result of the new investigations, it has already become
clear that the conventional opinion of Schelling is grossly unjust.
That opinion is based on the judgment of the contemporaries or
near-contemporaries. And these were subject to prejudices which
made an adequate understanding of Schelling difficult, if not
impossible. Schelling's critics were theologians, positivists and
Hegelians. If they were theologians, they looked to Schelling for
an apologetic which they did not get, nor were meant to get. If
they were positivists, they had even less sympathy with Schelling
than they had with Hegel. And if they were Hegelians (as most
of them were), they saw the most important criterion of judgment
in systematic completeness, the very point in which Schelling was
weakest; further, they were bound to regard his development
after 1804 as an aberration or an outright betrayal.
To be sure, the conventional opinion is not entirely mistaken.
Schelling does lack system and thoroughness; and his conse
quent tendency to mix the ill-considered, or even the absurd, with
the profound confounds the present student as it did the past. But
Hegelian prejudices have led to an exaggeration of this vice.
Schelling may be weak in execution, but he is strong indeed in
programmatic statement. Moreover, the latter strength accounts
at least in part for the former weakness. Schelling was able to
penetrate with extraordinary swiftness to first principles and ul
timate implications. No sooner had he conceived a system than he
perceived implications which made it problematic. While others
would plod along, working out the details of a system Schelling
had outlined, he himself already found it necessary to go beyond
it. Thus time and again he faced philosophical crises. If Schel
ling never worked out any of his systems, this is in part because
his systematic tendency was forever at war with his aporematic.
But theologians, positivists and Hegelians had this in common:
if they were prepared to admit philosophical crises at all, they
regarded them as resolved, once and for all.
1 See Manfred Schr?ter's edition of the 1811 and 1813 versions of the
Weltalter (Munich, 1946).
1. Introduction
truth .... Now I have put all my hopes in Schelling . . . ." (Journals,
ed. and tr. by A. Dm, London-New York-Toronto, 1938, p. 102).
10 Ibid., p. 104.
11 II 3.128.
12 II 3.76.
13 I 4.129. Nicolai Hartmann rightly comments: "Von allen anderen
Formen des philosophischen Monismus unterscheidet sich der Schellingsche
dadurch, dass hier nicht nur 'im letzten Grunde' alles eins ist, sondern
gerade auch im konkreten Einzelsein" (Die Philosophie des deutschen
Idealismus, Berlin, 1923, I, p. 160). Schelling wrote in the same work:
"The basic error in all philosophy is the presupposition that the absolute
Identity has actually externalized itself" (I 4.119). Now the positive philos
ophy turns to this very "error"!
lessness and evil. Thus the second question arises for the new
philosophy: why is what exists in discrepancy with what it ideally
ought to be? Why is the world "questionable"?18
The questions posed by the positive philosophy may well
appear non-sensical. How can one ask for the meaning of the
meaningless? The meaningless is either ultimately not meaning
less, or else it is a brute fact. Schelling emphatically rejects the
former alternative: is he, then, not driven toward a simple accept
ance of the facts, surrendering the quest for their meaning as
itself meaningless? But this would be to ignore the negative
achievement of the dialectic. All empirical fact, while indissoluble
into dialectic, is yet subject to all-pervasive dialectical qualifica
tions. Dialectic isolates this character of the facts and thus shows
them to be in need of explanation. Because of its abstracting
from their factuality, dialectic at the same time reveals itself as
incapable of the explanation required. Dialectic is thus "negative
philosophy," in a double sense. It negates absolute idealism as
being a false philosophy, and empiricism " as being no philosophy
at all.
Internal unity and externality, the a priori meaningful and
the a priori meaningless, are both real characters of the real world;
their togetherness in the same world is the problem requiring a
solution. This is the situation which gives rise to the positive
philosophy.
23 II 3.163.
24 II 1.560.
25 II 3.171.
26 See, e.g., this remarkable passage: "Only now does the individual
recognize the abyss between God and himself .... Hence he now yearns
for God Himself. Him, Him he wants, the God who acts . . . , who, as a
factual God, can alone deal with the factual fall, in short, the God who
is the Lord of all Being" (II 1.566).
27 Schelling makes it perfectly clear that the issue is not rationalism
vs. irrationalism. The issue is between a philosophy asserting a gap
between man and God, and the system of identity, whether in the ration
alist version of Hegel or the irrationalist of Schleiermacher. Thus Schelling
does not exalt feeling at the expense of reason; for it is open to the same
(and worse) objections. Irrationalist idealism implies the deification of
feeling rather than reason; and an irrationalism which abandons the
doctrine of identity leads to the view that "God is only the creature of our
feeling . . . , each religious idea has merely psychological significance"
(II 3.154). Because there is a gap between man and God, a leap is
required to bridge it; and this Schelling finds in will and decision. "A
free action is not a gradual transition, but absolute beginning, pure
positing . . . , decision and deed" (II 3.114). It is significant to note in
this connection that Schelling does not equate faith with religious feeling,
but asserts that it involves an act of will (I 10.183); and we may observe
in passing that contemporary existentialist theologians tend to speak of the
"decision of faith," whereas idealists are apt to speak of "religious expe
rience." It would seem that the issue between these two schools is not
dissimilar to the issue between Schelling and the philosophy of identity.
28 More precisely, Schelling means the condition of man, not qua
man, but qua individual or existing man. See II 1.569: "We have seen
that the self's need to possess God as external to his reason (as other than
mere thinking or idea) is practical. But this is not an arbitrary will; it
32 Exodus 3.14.
33 II 1.171, II 3.269 ff. See also, and especially, the searching dis
cussion in the Ages of the World, I 8.263 ff., Bolman, op. cit., 151 ff.
34 E.g., II 3.113 ff., 129 ff., and numerous other passages. See infra,
note 43.
35 E.g., II 1.565: "With the pure That . . . one can do nothing. In
order that there should be science, the Universal, the What, must enter,
but now as consequent, not antecedent to the That."
collapses, and we are left, not with an absolute Existent, but with
as many existents as there are empirical facts: we have landed,
not in the positive philosophy, but in empiricism. The negative
philosophy, it now becomes clear, has founded the positive philos
ophy only hypothetically; the positive philosophy must now
directly found the negative philosophy, and indirectly, itself.
We might summarize the situation as follows: if an absolute
Reason can explain only rationality, but not existence, and if
therefore existence, not reason, must be metaphysically ultimate,
then this absolute Existence must be the ground, not only of
other existence, but of rationality as well. Schelling must there
fore ask: "why is there reason? why not unreason?" 36 This is
the crucial problem of the positive philosophy; it is, as we shall
see, the problem on which it founders.
Schelling proceeds as follows. The absolute Existent and its
free Will are a priori unknowable. But we can consider a priori
what free will as such involves. Dialectic may examine the cate
gory of free will, or rather, the category of the absolutely free will.
What does such an examination exhibit? Free will is freedom to
will or not to will. This involves a distinction between two ele
ments, potential will and actual will. And since neither potential
nor actual will is, by itself, free to will and not to will, still a
third element is involved. This is the synthesis of potency and
act, and this alone is free to will and not to will. These three
potencies Schelling calls "that which can be" (das Seink?nnende),
"that which must be" (das Seinm?ssende), and "that which is to
be" (das Seinsollende). They are the fundamental categories of
the entire positive philosophy.
It must be clearly realized that Schelling does not move from
the absolute individual Will to the dialectical category of will;
such a move would clearly be impossible. He moves from the
category, which is as such an abstract universal, and then seeks
to ground it in the absolute Existent.37 For purposes of con
40 II 3.244 ff.
41 This is Schelling's explicit teaching in his earlier Ages of the World.
I 8.310, Bolman, op. cit., p. 200.
42 Cf. Fackenheim, op. cit., pp. 5 ff.
(iii) the world of empirical fact. All three terms are required.
Only the first term can explain why anything exists. Only the
first and second in conjunction can explain the rationality found
in the world. And only all three terms in conjunction can explain
the togetherness of rationality and irrationality which makes up
the actual world. The method of the positive philosophy may
be termed "progressive" or "metaphysical empiricism." 43 It starts
out, a priori, with the absolute Existent; proceeds, still a priori,
to consider the alternative possibilities implicit in the dialectical
unity of potencies; but discovers only a posteriori which of these
alternatives has become fact. The positive philosophy is thus very
far from indiscriminately collecting empirical evidence. It selects
for consideration only those facts which, according to its a priori
principles, can be explained only by a novel cosmic act of will.
5. Concluding Evaluation
43 See supra note 34. Cf. the following summary: "Not the absolute
Prius itself is to be proved; (this is beyond all proof, the absolute Begin
ning which is in itself certain).... But we must prove, as a fact, what
derives from it, and thus the Godhood of that Prius. We must prove that
it is God and that God exists" (II 3.129). See also this summary of the
characteristics of negative and positive philosophy: "Negative philosophy
is a priori empiricism, i.e., the a priori of empiricism, and for that reason
itself not empiricism .... Positive philosophy is empirical apriorism,
i.e., the empiricism of the a priori, inasmuch as it reveals the Prius, via
the Posterius, as God" (II 3.130).
44 II 1.573-590. The problem is also raised elsewhere; cf., e.g., II
1.331.
45 II 1.586.
46 II 1.589; cf. also II 1.314, 331.
47 II 1.587.
University of Toronto.