British Journal For The History of Philosophy
British Journal For The History of Philosophy
To cite this article: Susan James (1999): The philosophical innovations of Margaret Cavendish,
British Journal for the History of Philosophy, 7:2, 219-244
This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any
substantial or systematic reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing,
systematic supply, or distribution in any form to anyone is expressly forbidden.
The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any
representation that the contents will be complete or accurate or up to date. The
accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should be independently
verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions,
claims, proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused
arising directly or indirectly in connection with or arising out of the use of this
material.
ARTICLE
Susan James
1
I am extremely grateful to Desmond Clarke, Sarah Hutton, Quentin Skinner and Cather-
ine Wilson for their helpful comments on earlier drafts of this paper.
2
In 'An Epilogue to my Philosophical Opinions' printed at the beginning of the 1655 edition
of Philosophical and Physical Opinions, Cavendish reports that people have said that she
must have discussed this work with Descartes and Hobbes (a slightly surprising claim in the
light of her text). She replies that although she has met these great men she has barely
spoken to either of them, and has only talked about philosophy with members of her family,
among whom she names her husband William Cavendish, his brother, Charles Cavendish,
and her own brothers, who were not notable for their philosophical interests. Her husband
and brother-in-law would, however, have been useful informants. Both were close associ-
ates of Hobbes who discussed aspects of his natural philosophy with them during the 1640s.
Both met Descartes while they were in exile in Paris, and Charles Cavendish corresponded
with Descartes as well as expressing admiration for his Principles. These connections may
help to explain the fact that, by the early 1660s, Margaret Cavendish was commenting on
the works of both philosophers in print. On the Cavendish family's connections with these
and other philosophers, see Jean Jaquot, 'Sir Charles Cavendish and his Learned Friends',
Annals of Science 8 (1952), pp. 67-91; Robert Kargon, Atomism in England from Hariot to
Newton (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1966), pp. 54-76.
3
For discussions of Cavendish's natural philosophy, see Stephen Clucas, 'The Atomism of the
Cavendish Circle. A Reappraisal', The Seventeenth Century, 9 (1994), pp. 247-73; Sarah
Hutton, 'In Dialogue with Thomas Hobbes: Margaret Cavendish's Natural Philosophy' in
Women's Writing, 4 (1997), pp. 421-32; G. D. Meyer, The Scientific Lady in England. An
Account of her Rise, with Emphasis on the Major Roles of the Telescope and Microscope.
(Berkeley, University of California Press, 1955). On the gendered character of Cavendish's
natural philosophy, see Sarah Hutton, 'Anne Conway, Margaret Cavendish and Seventeenth-
century Scientific Thought' in Lynette Hunter and Sarah Hutton eds., Women, Science and
Medicine, 1500-1700 (Stroud, Sutton, 1997); Carolyn Merchant, The Death of Nature. Women,
Ecology and the Scientific Revolution (London, Wildwood House, 1982), pp. 253-74; John
Rogers, The Matter of Revolution. Science, Poetry and Politics in the Age of Milton (Ithaca,
Cornell University Press, 1996), pp. 177-211; Lisa T. Sarasohn, 'A Science Turned upside
Down: Feminism and the Natural Philosophy of Margaret Cavendish', The Huntington
Library Quarterly, 47 (1984), pp. 289-307; Lorna Schiebinger, The Mind has no Sex? Women
in the Origins of Modem Science (Cambridge, Mass., Harvard University Press, 1989). A great
deal has been written about Cavendish as an author of plays, poems and Utopias. See for
example Kate Lilley, 'Blazing Worlds: Seventeenth-Century Women's Utopian Writing' in
Clare Brant and Diane Purkiss eds., Women, Texts and Histories 1575-1760 (Routledge,
London, 1992), pp. 102-33; Emma Rees ed., Margaret Cavendish, Duchess of Newcastle,
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 221
One of Cavendish's earliest forays into natural philosophy occurs in her
Poems and Fancies (initially published in 1653) in a sequence of verses out-
lining the principles of atomism, and offering atomist explanations of various
phenomena.4 However, by the time she came to write Philosophical and
Physical Opinions, her first philosophical treatise in prose, she had aban-
doned this view on the grounds that 'the opinion of atoms seems not so clear
to my reason as my own and absolutely new opinions'.5 During the eight or
so years after these absolutely new opinions appeared in print, Cavendish
came to believe that some of her objections to atomism also applied to other
forms of corpuscularianism espoused by mechanist philosophers. The posi-
tion she developed in the revised version of Philosophical and Physical
Opinions, published in 1663, was consequently not so much anti-atomist as
anti-mechanist, and contained the distinctive philosophical claims she con-
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
tinued to defend for the rest of her life.6 By this stage, too, she was willing to
set her own views alongside those of the most famous philosophers of her
day, and clarified her own position in Philosophical Letters1 by commenting
on Hobbes, Descartes, Henry More, Jan Baptiste van Helmont and William
Harvey. Subverting a genre in which a female pupil seeks enlightenment from
a male philosopher, she casts herself in the authoritative role of teacher and
expounds her criticisms to a female correspondent.
Shortly after completing this work, Cavendish turned her attention to a
further development within natural philosophy - the efforts of the first
generation of English microscopists to acquire a better knowledge of the
visible parts of living things so that they could formulate more probable
hypotheses about the invisible particles and motions governing their struc-
ture and behaviour. Commenting on the work of Hooke, Power and Boyle
in her Observations on Experimental Philosophy,8 Cavendish dismissed
their experimental approach in favour of her speculative one, elaborated
her objections to the principles of mechanism, and reiterated her alterna-
tive view of natural causation. In her final statement, The Grounds of
Natural Philosophy? she once again summarized her position and discussed
some of its implications in a series of appendices.
1623-1673. Special Number of Women's Writing, 4 (1997); Sophie Tomlinson 'My Brain and
the Stage: Margaret Cavendish and the Fantasy of Female Performance' in Clare Brant and
Diane Purkiss eds., Women, Texts and Histories 1575-1760 (Routledge, London, 1992),
134-63; Susan Wiseman, 'Gender and Status in Dramatic Discourse' in Isobel Grundy and
Susan Wiseman eds., Women, Writing, History 1640-1740 (Batsford, London, 1992), 159-77.
4
Henry More had published Democritus Platonissans, an exposition of atomism in verse, in
1646. It is possible that this was a model for Cavendish, who later commented on two of
More's prose works.
5
'A Condemning Treatise of Atoms', included in the prefatory material of the first edition
of Philosophical and Physical Opinions, 1655.
6
Subsequent references to this work (hereafter PPO) are to the 1664 edition.
7
Published in 1664. Hereafter PL.
8
Published 1666. Hereafter OEP.
9
Published in 1668. Hereafter GNP.
222 SUSAN JAMES
THE REJECTION OF MECHANISM
10
'A Condemning Treatise of Atoms' (1655). sig. A, 3v.
11
She repeats it three years later in OEP adding that 'The opinion of atoms is fitter for a poet-
ical fancy than for serious philosophy; and this is the reason I have waived it in my philo-
sophical works' (p. 144). On the relation between the ordered natural world and the
ordered polity in Cavendish's writings see, John Rogers, op. cit., pp. 177-211.
12
OEP, p. 138.
13
OEP, p. 119.
14
Descartes, 'Principia Philosophiae' II. 20 in Oeuvres de Descartes ed. Charles Adam and
Paul Tannery (Paris: Vrin, 1964-76), Vol. VIII, p. 51. Cavendish explains in the introduc-
tory material to Philosophical Letters that she has had parts of Descartes translated for her,
and goes on to comment on his Principles.
15
Cavendish is a relentless exponent of natural variety and one of her complaints about
experimental philosophers is that 'they do not consider enough the variety of nature's
actions' (OEP, p. 91). She believes that this stands in the way of general explanations and
cites, for example, the great variety of kinds of cold (OEP, p. 96), and of swimming motions
(PPO, p. 151).
16
Henry More, Antidote against Atheism (London, 1653). See for example Bk. 2, ch. 2, pp.
51-2.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 223
in Philosophical Letters, where he asserts that no one with the least
command of his wits and faculties should be willing to infer all the con-
trivances that are in nature from no other principle than the jumbling
together of matter.17 Cavendish agrees and goes on to pursue the impli-
cations of More's image. Mechanists, she points out, are content to envis-
age bodies subject to so many motions and impacts as to be, in Thomas
White's vivid phrase, in a tumult which 'is even within all bodies'. But bodies
subjected to such wild jumblings and knockings18 would undoubtedly be
damaged, hurt, or even destroyed. 'The several strokes which the several
imparted motions make upon the sentient, and the reaction from the sen-
tient to the external parts, would cause such a strong and confused agita-
tion in the sentient that it would rather occasion the body to dissolve
through the irregularities of such forced motions.'19
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
For how can motion, being no substance but only a mode, quit one body and
pass into another? One body may either occasion or imitate another's motions,
but it can neither give nor take away what belongs to its own or another's sub-
stance, no more than matter can quit its nature from being matter... Truly,
Madam, that neither motion norfigureshould subsist by themselves, and yet be
transferable into other bodies, is very strange, and as much as to prove them to
be nothing and yet to say that they are something.22
17
Ibid.
18
Henry More, The Immortality of the Soul (London, 1659), p . 88.
19
O E P , p. 178. See also P L p. 60 and Cavendish's claim that if all local action proceeded from
one motion pressing o n another 'all c r e a t u r e s . . . would be in a perpetual dance, or sliding,
which would produce a very restless life, and wearisome to such lazy creatures as I am'.
PPO, Second Epistle to t h e Reader.
20
See e.g. Descartes, Principia Philosophiae, II. 27. A T VIII, 55. Hobbes, Leviathan ed. R.
Tuck (Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996), I. 2. F o r Cavendish's responses to
their views see PL, pp. 21, 97-8.
21
Principia Philosophiae, II. 42. A T VIII, 66.
22
PL, p. 98.
224 SUSAN JAMES
philosophers, including More. How, she asks, can sensory organs consisting
of inert matter convey sensory perceptions 'and serve only like peeping
holes for the mind'?23 And how can the pineal gland mediate between
thought and extension?24 Pursuing these objections, Cavendish recognized
that any dualist theory which treats body and mind as distinct substances
will need to explain how they relate, and her conviction that this cannot be
done is one of her reasons for rejecting More's conception of a material
world animated by an overarching spirit of nature.25
Cavendish's engagement with Hobbes's conception of thoughts as
motions is a good deal more complicated, but in her Philosophical Letters
she initially criticizes him for his mechanism.26 Starting at Chapter 1 of
Leviathan, and focusing on a passage where Hobbes tries to work within a
narrow mechanical framework, she pounces on his claim that sense results
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
from the motions of external things pressing on our sensory organs.27 First,
she objects, pressure on the sensory organs does not always result in sensory
perception - for example, a person deep in contemplation may not hear the
noise around them or feel the touch of a hand on their shoulder. Secondly,
two men at a distance can see and hear each other, even when there are
bodies between them.28 These counter-examples (to which Hobbes had
ready answers) are, however, engulfed by a now familiar type of criticism -
that it is impossible to imagine how bodies as soft and light as air can impress
their motions on our sensory organs.29 Summing up her doubts in Obser-
vations on Experimental Philosophy, Cavendish concludes that 'if motion
be no substance or body, and besides, void of sense, not knowing what it
acts, I cannot conceive how it should make such different strokes upon both
the sensitive organ and the brain, and all so orderly, that everything is per-
ceived differently and distinctly... [H]ow absurd it is to make senseless cor-
puscles the cause of sense and reason, and consequently of perception, is
obvious to everyone's apprehension, and needs no demonstration'.30
If the inadequacies of mechanism stem from its conception of bodies -
from the view that motion is not one of their essential properties, and from
a failure to take account of their fragility - a more satisfactory analysis of
the workings of nature must overcome these deficiencies. In the next section
I shall discuss Cavendish's response to the first problem - her contention
that bodies are not inert pieces of extended matter which can only move
once they are moved, but are, on the contrary, self-moving. After that I shall
23
P L , p . xxx.
24
PL, p. 111.
25
PL, pp. 211-19.
26
O n the philosophical relations between Cavendish and Hobbes, see Sarah Hutton, ' I n Dia-
logue with Thomas Hobbes', op.cit.
27
PL, p. 62.
28
PL, p. 18.
29
PL, p. 81.
30
OEP, p. 176.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 225
examine the way she resolves her objections to the transfer of motion by
appealing to the perceptive powers of material bodies. Taken together,
these arguments deal with her other objection; they depict a natural world
of bodies too frangible to stand up to continuous concussion, which never-
theless survive.
SELF-MOVING MATTER
John Henry has shown, was more widely espoused than the orthodox his-
toriography has acknowledged.39 During the second half of the century, a
good many English writers basically sympathetic to mechanism neverthe-
less maintained that there were certain types of natural phenomena it could
not explain, and appealed to various active material powers to deal with
difficult cases. In some circumstances, these philosophers made explanatory
use of an active power present in all bodies. Henry Power, for example, one
of the targets of Cavendish's polemics in her Observations on Experimental
Philosophy, posits a material spirit pervading the whole universe, and
agrees with her that the motion 'is as inseparable an attribute to bodies, as
well as extension is', so that 'there can be no rest in nature more than a
vacuity in matter'.40 A comparable view is held by Walter Charleton, a fol-
lower of Gassendi, who adopted a rather condescending tone towards
Cavendish in their correspondence.41 Atoms, he asserts, possess 'an internal
energy or faculty motive, which may be conceived the first cause of all
natural actions or motions'.42 Alongside such thoroughgoing vitalism, an
36
PPO, p. 53.
37
PPO, pp. 12-13. For further statements of this view see PPO, pp. 15-16; PL, p. 287.
38
OEP, p. 92.
39
John Henry, 'Occult Qualities and the Experimental Philosophy: Active Principles in pre-
Newtonian Matter Theory', History of Science xxiv (1986), pp. 335-81. See also John
Rogers, The Matter of Reason, op. cit., pp. 177-211.
40
Henry Power, Experimental Philosophy (London, 1664), sig. b4, b3, c2, p. 61.
41
Charleton wrote to Cavendish in 1654 thanking her for copies of The World's Olio and
perhaps Philosophical Fancies, and wrote again in 1663 to thank her for sending him her
books (though he does not say which ones). In 1667 he sent her a more informative letter,
telling her that he was not persuaded by much of her philosophy, but urging her not to be
discouraged because natural philosophers cannot determine what is true, and must content
themselves with offering plausible conjectures. He is somewhat more complimentary about
her moral philosophy and poetry. Letters and Poems in Honour of the Incomparable
Princess, Margaret, Duchess of Newcastle (London, 1676).
42
Walter C h a r l e t o n , Physiologia Epicuro-Gassendi-Charltoniana ( L o n d o n , 1654), p . 126.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 227
overlapping set of authors influenced by the medical tradition appealed to
vital properties of the parts of living things, which they described as sense.
Charleton is a case in point. In the course of explaining how the excretion
of bile is caused by irritation of the gall bladder, he pauses to ask whether
his readers will not object that this talk of irritation implies some sense other
than that of the sensory organs or common sense, and accuse him of imag-
ining it. He argues in reply that the bodily actions and motions which phys-
icians call natural do indeed presuppose a kind of sense, so that parts such
as the heart, stomach, guts and womb all possess natural sense. As he
explains, this view is opposed to that of the Cartesians who believe that all
bodily actions are caused by motions of the animal spirits in the nerves.
However, it is in line with the position taken by William Harvey, who saw,
in Charleton's view correctly, that bodily organs possess a natural sense
which enables them to respond to irritation or injury.43 Cavendish, too,
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
believes that bodily organs possess sense,44 as do animals and plants, and
indeed bodies of all kinds. For instance, using an unexceptional example
which she may have taken from Van Helmont, she classifies the purgative
power of rhubarb as a kind of sense.45 How does the rhubarb 'know' when
to purge? It possesses an ability to 'see' differences between the bodies it
encounters which is analogous to our power of vision, so that it is appro-
priate to describe its ability as a kind of sensing, which depends on a kind
of knowledge. 'Certainly sense is knowing, not only in distinguishing several
objects from one another, but for direction... And to prove the senses have
knowledge, I say the eyes direct the whole body . . . to go just to that
designed place without the mind's further notice.'46
Writers whose aim in appealing to vital motions was to strengthen
mechanism rather than attack it evidently saw no incompatibility between
the claim that bodies possessed 'a power motive' and the claim that their
behaviour could be explained as the result of the impacts of bodies on each
other.47 Hobbes, for example, although he does not use the language of
vitalism, explains phenomena ranging from the properties of inflated blad-
ders to sense perception by appealing to the interrelation between the pres-
sure exerted by one body on another, and the respective endeavours of the
43
Walter Charleton, A Natural History of Nutrition, Life and Voluntary Motion (London,
1659), pp. 119-25. For further discussion of the debate about irritability see John Henry,
'Medicine and Pneumatology: Henry More, Richard Baxter and Francis Glisson's Treatise
on the Energetic Nature of Substance', Medical History 31 (1987), pp. 15-40.
44
PL, p. 46.
45
PL, p . 514.
46
PPO, p . 79. See also P L pp. 517-19.
47
At least some of the time, mechanists insisted that matter is inert, and opponents writing
in mid-century such as Cavendish and More fixed on this description. It is interesting that
both parties tied themselves to a characterization of the position which was to some extent
out of line with the claims its exponents made.
228 SUSAN JAMES
bodies concerned.48 Endeavour, to be sure, is motion; but it is simul-
taneously the capacity of a body to react to external pressure by resisting it,
so that there is a sense in which, by virtue of their endeavour, bodies are
not inert. It is consequently quite a small step from the claim that a body
has endeavour to the claim that it has vital motion. Both More and
Cavendish grasped this implication and seized, for differing reasons, on
Hobbes's view that we see, hear and so on when our sensory organs resist
the motions caused by the pressure of external objects. 'Sense', as Hobbes
had put it, 'is a phantasm, made by the reaction and endeavour outwards in
the organ of sense, caused by an endeavour inwards from the object,
remaining for some time, more or less.'49 But if the endeavour of a sense
organ is sense, and if all bodies possess endeavour, why is it not true,
Cavendish wanted to know, that all bodies sense? And if bodies can sense
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
as the 1660s often took care not to say that matter was perceptive or intel-
ligent,53 Cavendish is certainly an exception. She repeatedly makes these
very claims, and when discussing the objection that some bodies do not, so
far as we can tell, either sense or reason, counters that just because they do
not possess animal sense and knowledge (the sort we can detect) it does not
follow that they possess no sense or knowledge at all.
All things have sense, by reason all things have animate matter, and if all things
or creatures have sensitive animate matter, why not rational animate
matter? . . . If so, why may not vegetables, minerals and elements have as much
animate matter, both sensitive and rational, as animals? which is, to have a sen-
sitive life and rational knowledge, only they want the animal shape or figure,
and such sorts of motions as are proper to the animal creature, to express their
sense and knowledge in the animal way; for had vegetables, minerals and ele-
ments the same shape created by the Creator, which is the animate matter and
motion, there might be vegetable, mineral and elemental men, beasts, fowls and
fish, as also there might be animal vegetables, minerals and elements.54
More cautious vitalists may have been sensitive to the difficulty of making
non-reductive sense of the idea that a stone, for example, can know, and
may also have been anxious to avoid sliding back into a world of
unanalysable occult qualities from which, as they saw it, they had only just
emancipated themselves. But they were also moved by religious consider-
ations, and by the danger (voiced by More and subsequently by Cudworth)
that vitalism amounted to a form of atheism. If mechanism already mar-
ginalized the place of God in the material world, vitalism seemed to make
52
More, Antidote, p . 61. See also p . 52. While More allows this much t o mechanism, h e else-
where suggests that all natural motions must be caused by a spirit of nature.
53
Henry, 1986, op. cit., p . 356.
54
P P O , p . 15. Cavendish takes u p these speculations in her Utopia, The Description of a New
World called the Blazing World, ed. Kate Lilley (Harmondsworth, Penguin Books, 1994),
pp. 133f.
230 SUSAN JAMES
the problem worse. Self-moving matter did not need God to start it up, let
alone to maintain it in motion; and once sense and reason (the traits tra-
ditionally associated with the immaterial soul) were transferred to matter,
nature emerged as self-sufficient. The doctrinal consequences of this were
deftly identified by More, who regarded the view 'that everything has sense,
imagination and a fiducial knowledge of God in it, metals, meteors and
plants not excepted' as a kind of enthusiasm tantamount to atheism.55 Yet
this is the very position that Cavendish holds. Nature, she explains at the
beginning of her discussion of More's work in Philosophical Letters, fears,
adores, admires, praises and prays unto God, as do all her parts and crea-
tures, including man, 'so that there's no atheist in infinite nature'.56 Indeed,
any other view should arouse suspicion.
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
Surely, Madam, the God of nature, in my opinion, will be adored by all crea-
tures, and adoration cannot be without sense and knowledge... I should rather
think it irreligious to confine sense and reason only to man, and to say that no
creature adores and worships God but man; which, in my judgement, argues a
great pride, self-conceit and presumption.57
Cavendish never qualifies this view, although she is aware of the challenges
to which it exposes her. In Observations on Experimental Philosophy she
denies that atheism and materialism are connected, denouncing those who
think 'that the exploding of immaterial substances, and the unbounded pre-
rogative of matter, must needs infer atheism',58 and elsewhere she professes
her loyalty to the Church, for which, she claims, she would sacrifice her life
or suffer torment.59 At a less declamatory level, she also counters an argu-
ment discussed by Boyle to the effect that the conception of the world as
eternal, espoused by the atheists Lucretius and Anaxagoras, depended on
the claim that motion is an essential property of material bodies, so that
people who adopted this latter view (as Cavendish did) undermined the
Christian doctrine of the creation.60 Cavendish addresses this argument in
her Philosophical Letters by putting it into the mouth of her anonymous
lady correspondent, who proposes that if nature is self-moving and there-
fore eternal, it is coeval with God. God, Cavendish responds, is certainly
eternal and the creator of matter; but because He is not bound by time we
do not need to infer that matter is not eternal from the fact that He created
55
More, Brief Discourse of... Enthusiasm (1656). Ralph Cudworth, True Intellectual System
of the Universe ed. Thomas Birch (London, 1820), vol. 1, pp. 234-6; vol. 3, pp. 275-6. It has
been argued that Cudworth's attack o n hylozoism is aimed at Cavendish. See John Rogers,
op. cit., p . 194.
56
PL, pp. 145-6. See also PL, p . 318; GNP, p . 237.
57
PL, p. 519.
58
O E P , p . 299.
59
PL, p . 17.
60
Robert Boyle, 'Some Considerations touching the usefulness of Experimental Natural Phil-
osophy' (1663) in Works ed. Thomas Birch (London, 1772) Vol. II, pp. 42-3.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 231
it. Furthermore, although God created matter, he may have played an indi-
rect role in the creation of this world which, as we know from the Bible,
took seven days. Since there may have been worlds before ours, this world
may have been created out of previously existing matter. If so, it was created
by God's command, but the executor of the command was self-moving
nature.61
Speculations like this were hardly calculated to strengthen Cavendish's
claims to religious conformity. They are, however, of a piece with her strict
separation of philosophy and religion, which was in turn calculated to leave
philosophers free to speculate about nature. Philosophy, she asserts, is built
on sense, reason and observation, and theology on implicit faith, so the two
cannot agree. Furthermore, while God is unknowable, philosophy is the
light he gives to man to direct him in the course of his life. This attempt to
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
remove the interests of philosophers from those of the Church would not
have satisfied many of Cavendish's contemporaries, and some of the terms
in which she describes her work would if anything have reinforced their
view of the connections between vitalism and atheism. Introducing her
readers to the revised edition of Philosophical and Physical Opinions, for
instance, Cavendish asks them to note that she does not meddle with the
particular souls of men, but concerns herself only with the general soul of
nature or rational matter, and the general life of nature or sensitive matter.
Here she allows that men have particular souls, and elsewhere distinguishes
natural souls from divine ones.62 But it is striking that the latter play no role
at all in her inclusive notion of nature, and their function is not discussed.
Self-motion enables Cavendish to deal, after a fashion, with the first of her
objections to mechanism: that if matter is inert, we cannot explain the prop-
erties of natural things. But she still has to cope with her second reserva-
tion: that these properties cannot result from the transmission of motions
from one body to another, whether they are self-moving or not. In develop-
ing an alternative account of natural causation, Cavendish relies on the stan-
dard distinction between processes by which new entities are created, and
processes in which the contingent properties of existing entities alter -
between, for example, the generation of an embryo and a change of colour
in a flower. With some minor qualifications, she believes that many natural
events belong to one of these kinds, so that a philosopher who could account
for both of them would have provided a fairly comprehensive theory of
change.
Taking the second type of causation, Cavendish attributes changes in the
61
PL, pp. 13-17. For Cavendish's view that matter is eternal see PPO, p. 2.
62
PL, p. 111.
232 SUSAN JAMES
contingent properties or accidents of bodies to what she calls perception, a
process which has a familiar ring in the context of animal perception, but
which she also extends to bodies of other kinds. The motions intrinsic to a
body, which distinguish it from the rest of matter, form it into a figure - an
object with a particular set of properties such as shape, density or colour.63
So, for example, a dog has a figure. When a woman sees the dog, its figure
is copied, imitated, printed or 'patterned out' by the sensitive matter of her
eye which senses or perceives it; when she hears the dog bark, the figure of
the sound is patterned out in her ear; and so on.64 At the same time, each
of these figures is patterned out by the rational matter in the woman's body
to form an integrated figure of a dog with several sensory properties.
Cavendish appeals to this notion of perception to explain a formidable
variety of changes in what are normally considered both animate and in-
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
animate bodies. The eye patterns out light (which, being a body, possesses
self-motion and consequently figure)65 and the external parts of bodies
pattern out heat and cold. A looking-glass patterns out a face, a billiard ball
patterns out a figure of another ball which collides with it (and in each case,
the rational matter patterns out this figure in its turn). The lens of a micro-
scope patterns out the figure of a louse;66 a shadow may be patterned out
by the ground;67 and snow patterns out a footprint.68 The crucial thing to
grasp about all these cases is that perception does not depend on the move-
ment of species, atoms, or corpuscles, or on the pressure exerted by one
body on another. 'I see a man or beast; that man or beast doth not touch
my eye in the least; but the sensitive corporeal motions straight upon the
sight of the beast or man make the little figures in the sensitive organ, the
eye.'69 Equally, when a person throws a ball into the air, the ball is the cause
of its own movement. 'I will not say', Cavendish qualifies, 'but that it may
have some perception of the hand according to its own figure; but it does
63
Cavendish does not accept a distinction between primary and secondary qualities, so that
in her view colour, as much as shape, is a real property of the object. PPO, pp. 81-6; OEP,
p. 175.
64
PL, p. 127. Cavendish's preferred term is 'patterning' or 'patterning out': PL pp. 539-40. It
is used by Hobbes, in a passage Cavendish quotes and discusses. 'Some natural bodies have
in themselves the pattern of almost all things, and others none at all.' Hobbes, 'Of Body',
in English Works, ed. Molesworth, vol. 1, p. 389. It is also used in the English translation of
Jan Baptiste Van Helmont's work, Oriatrike or Physic Refined, which Cavendish discusses
at length in Philosophical Letters: 'The seminal efficient cause containeth the types of pat-
terns of things to be done by itself, the figure, motion, hour, respects, inclinations, fitness,
equalisings, proportions, alienation, defects and whatsoever falls under the succession of
days, as well in the business of generation as of government' (p. 29).
65
PL, p . 541.
66
OEP, p. 8.
67
P L o n More, xxiv.
68
PL, pp. 104-5.
69
PL, p. 70. 'The sensitive and rational corporeal motions in one body pattern out the figure
of another body, as of an external object, which may be done easily without any pressure
or reaction.' PL, p. 68. See also PL, p . 20.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 233
not move by the hand's motion but by its own', and the hand is only the
occasion of its moving.70
Perception, itself a kind of autokinesis, was a reasonable hypothesis for
someone who believed that bodies would be destroyed by concussions, and
that motion cannot be transmitted. Nor was it entirely novel. Although
Cavendish presumably did not know it, More and Descartes had discussed
something along these lines in a correspondence dating from 1649. More
had confessed:
I feel more disposed to believe that motion is not communicated, but that from
the impulse of one body another body is so to speak roused into motion, like
the mind to a thought on this or that occasion . . . neither [the motion nor the
thought] is received into the subject, in fact, but both arise from the subject in
which they are found.71
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
70
OEP, p. 163.
71
A T (NP), 5: 383. Quoted in Alan Gabbey, 'Philosophia Cartesians Triumphata: Henry
More (1646-1671)' in T. M . Lennon, J. M . Nicholas, J. W. Davis eds., Problems of Car-
tesianism (Montreal: McGill-Queen's University Press, 1982), p . 211.
72
Letter to Henry More, August 1649, A T 5, 403-4. O n Descartes's efforts to explain t h e
motion of bodies, see D e s m o n d M. Clarke, 'The Concept of Vis in Part III of the Principia'
in Descartes: Principia Philosophiae (1644-1994). Atti del Convegno per il 350° anniversario
della publicazione dell'opera (Napoli, 1996), pp. 321-39.
73
e.g. Geraud de Cordemoy, Discernment du corps et de l'ame (1666) and Louis La Forge,
Traité de l'esprit de l'homme (1666). See C. McCracken, Malebranche and British Philos-
ophy (Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1983), pp. 94-5.
74
S e e e.g. Catherine Wilson, Leibniz's Metaphysics (Manchester, Manchester University
Press, 1989), p . 175.
75
Oriatrike, p . 30.
234 SUSAN JAMES
things to be done by itself, the figure, motion, hour, respects, inclinations,
fitness, equalisings, proportions, alienation, defects, and whatsoever falls
under the succession of days, as well in the business of generation, as of
government.'76 Cavendish relentlessly satirizes this view (which is not to say
that she learned nothing from it), criticizing Van Helmont for obscurity,77
and for appealing to immaterial entities to explain how the soul moves the
body.78 It is therefore not clear how far she relies on his work, and to what
extent her account of perception derives from it. Closer to home, the idea
of autokinesis is also indirectly raised by Hobbes in De Corpore which
Cavendish had read carefully in the English translation of 1656. In this
work, Hobbes takes motion to be an accident of bodies, and holds the
general view that accidents do not go out of one subject into another. It
follows that motion cannot leave the body in which it occurs; 'for example,
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
when the hand, being moved, moves the pen, motion does not go out of the
hand into the pen;... but a new motion is generated in the pen, and is the
pen's motion'.79 In Philosophical Letters, Cavendish comments approvingly:
'I am of his opinion that the motion doth not go out of the hand into the
pen, and that the motion of the pen is the pen's own motion.'80 She also
develops a comparable example — carving a piece of wood by hand — to
explain patterning out to her correspondent.
Madam, give me leave to ask you this question: whether it is the motion of the
hand, or the instrument, or both, that print or carve such and such a body? Per-
chance you will say that the motion of the hand moves the instrument, and the
instrument the wood which is to be carved; but I answer, how can it be the
hand's motion if it be in the instrument? You will say, perhaps, the motion of
the hand is transferred out of the hand into the instrument, and so from the
instrument into the carved figure; but give me leave to ask you, was this motion
of the hand, that was transferred, corporeal or incorporeal? If you say corpo-
real, then the hand must become less and weak, but if incorporeal, I ask you
how a bodiless motion can have strength to carve and cut?... But I pray,
Madam, consider rationally, that though the artificer or workman be the
occasion of the motions of the carved body, yet the motions of the body which
is carved are they which put themselves into such and such a figure, or give
themselves such and such a print as the artificer intended... Wherefore I say
that some things may be the occasional causes of other things, but not the prime
or principal causes.81
76
Oriatrike, p . 29.
77
'For who is able to conceive of all those chimeras and fancies as the Archeus, Ferment,
various Ideas, Blas, Gas and many more, which are neither something nor nothing in
nature, but betwixt both, except a man have the same fancies, vision and dreams your
author had.' PL, p. 238.
78
PL, p . 276.
79
T h o m a s H o b b e s , ' O f Body' in Molesworth ed., English Works, vol. 1, p . 117.
80
PL, p. 54.
81
PL, pp. 77-9.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 235
Cavendish seems to have developed this view around the time when she was
systematically working through the texts discussed in Philosophical Letters.
We first encounter it in the 1663 edition of Philosophical and Physical
Opinions, and she struggled to refine it in the works she published over the
next five years. By this stage she was already committed to the view that
nature is entirely material, and so was in a position to reject Van Helmont's
and More's immaterial principles and to welcome Hobbes's materialism.
She had also arrived at the judgement that matter is self-moving, and there-
fore disagreed with More and Descartes who, as she read them, regarded it
as inert. Finally, she was clear that there was no transmission of motion, and
was therefore ready to agree with both Hobbes and Van Helmont on this
score. That left the question: What explains sensory perception, and a vast
range of other alterations in the properties of bodies? At this point Van
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
82
PL, p. 169.
83
PL, pp. 154-81.
236 SUSAN JAMES
artist, like a carver who can carve several figures on a cherry stone.84
Although we know that rational matter can pattern out millions of figures,
and although we can speculate about its physical structure, which may, for
instance, resemble that of a screen or a fan, we cannot give a satisfactory
account of its power.85 Nevertheless, this level of ignorance is less grave than
that faced by More himself, who is unable to explain how immaterial souls
can animate material bodies,86 or by mechanists who can only appeal to the
patently inadequate properties of inert matter.87
Focusing for a moment on mechanist accounts of causation, Cavendish
adds a further objection to those already discussed. We know that our
sensory organs can pattern out a figure of a body when both light and the
body are absent.88 We perceive figures in dreams, in various kinds of illness
and in waking fantasies, and can infer that a man who was blind, deaf and
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
dumb would still pattern out some figures, although we cannot say what they
would be like. Since such non-veridical figures are sometimes qualitatively
indistinguishable from veridical ones, an adequate theory of perception
must not only account for both, but also account for both in the same way.
Philosophers who believe that normal sensory perceptions have external
causes meet the first of these conditions, usually by attributing veridical per-
ceptions to the motions of external objects and non-veridical ones to
motions of the body or soul. But precisely because they distinguish these
processes, they fail to satisfy the second condition. In adopting this
approach, Cavendish seems to believe that they illicitly divide a class of
events which, on phenomenological grounds, requires to be treated as one,
thereby falling short of a theory such as her own, which consequently pos-
sesses a significant advantage.
It is possible that this assimilation of perception to imagination has auto-
biographical roots in Cavendish's own fantasy, which seems to have been
exceptionally vivid, and a source of great pleasure to her.89 Nonetheless, it
has radical implications. Like the causes of our involuntary fantasies, those
of our perceptions lie within the body, and our capacity to pattern out
depends not so much on our environment as on our own physical organiz-
ation. Cavendish may have been aware of the sceptical drift of this argu-
ment. (If the causes of a non-veridical perception of a candle are the same
as those of a veridical one, can we reliably tell the difference between
84
PL, p. 172.
85
PPO, p. 268. Descartes, too, when discussing memory, hypothesizes that the matter in our
brains is folded like paper or cloth. See e.g. Letter to Mesland, 2 May, 1644. AT IV, 114-15.
86
P L , p . 149.
87
OEP, p. 163.
88
GNP, pp. 55-6; PL, p . 63.
89
F o r instance, she describes a winter during her exile in Antwerp when she watched young
men and women sliding on t h e ice, longing to join them, yet too careful of her dignity to
leave her carriage. Instead, she went home and imagined how she 'would slide as one of the
skilfullest and most practised'. Sociable Letters, cxc.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 237
them?) However, she does not take it up and, throughout her work, defends
a common-sense kind of realism.90
While Cavendish frequently works with a relatively small number of
explanatory categories and resists what she regards as an excessive tendency
to multiply types of natural causes, she does not spell out the strengths of a
unified account of perception and imagination in any more detail, or explain
why the phenomena should be granted such authority in this case, although
not in others. In general, however, her arguments in favour of patterning out
are underpinned by her firm conviction that her view achieves more than its
rivals. By positing a single, natural substance, it sidesteps the need to explain
how distinct substances interact, a rock on which dualism founders. By posit-
ing self-moving matter, it provides a comprehensible ontological basis for
explanations of natural phenomena, which mechanism lacks. Nevertheless,
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
her claim that concussion plays no part in accounting for the behaviour of
bodies generates enormous difficulties, among them the issue of harmonious
interaction exemplified by the snow and the boot. Solutions to this problem
that we now classify as occasionalist are barred by Cavendish's refusal to
allot God any active role in nature, and while she describes the presence of
one body as the occasional cause of its figure being patterned out by another,
she does not recognize the kind of deity who might guarantee the coinci-
dence of these events, or produce co-ordinated streams of figures.91 Instead,
she rehearses three naturalistic lines of response. First, nature is full of sym-
pathies and antipathies or 'plain ordinary passions and appetites'.92 Sympa-
thies, she writes, are 'such agreeable motions in one part or creature as do
cause a fancy, love or desire to some other part or creature', and they can
account for several types of phenomena, including actions indifferent to dis-
tance such as the attraction of a compass needle to the North Pole, actions
which require a certain distance such as the attraction of iron to a magnet,
and actions which depend on the contiguity of bodies such as infection by a
disease.93 This somewhat old-fashioned view, which can be applied to the
relations between people or to the destruction of one figure by another,94 as
easily as to the behaviour of minerals and elements, proposes that particu-
lar sympathies and antipathies are activated in particular circumstances, and
that this is why things respond just as and when they do.
Talk of sympathies and antipathies is, for Cavendish, talk of the know-
ledge that bodies possess, but she finds the subject of this knowledge harder
90
See note 63 above.
91
Cavendish argues, against the occasionalist positions which emerged from Descartes's
work, that if God can decree anything, he can decree that nature moves itself: OEP, p. 280.
She may have taken the term 'occasional cause' from Van Helmont (see note 76) but it was
also wider English currency. The OED cites Thomas Wilson's Logicke of 1551, 'Those
causes that are fetched far off, and being but half causes, partly and by the way, give only
the occasion.' 1. I. iii.
92
PL, p . 289.
93
PL, pp. 289-90. See also PPO, p. 70.
94
PPO, p. 110.
238 SUSAN JAMES
to specify. At some points she claims that individual bodies do not them-
selves contain the knowledge that enables them to respond to external
objects. A knowledge of how to see is not contained in an eye but in a whole
animal body. By some sort of analogy, the knowledge of how to turn to the
sun is not contained in a flower, but in a larger body of which the flower and
the sun are parts. And by inference, the knowledge of all natural responses
is contained in the whole body which is nature itself. How, though, is this
knowledge communicated, so that particular bodies pattern out appropri-
ate and harmonious figures? Reflecting on this problem, Cavendish arrives
at the view that all the figures patterned out by a body are in it eternally.
When a house is pulled down, its figure remains in the materials of which it
was built, however much they are scattered. Moreover, they always did
contain the figure of the house, even before it came into existence. 'Yet
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
manifestation of the reason and sense which are possessed by all natural
things,102 and the fact that creatures other than man cannot speak should
not lead us to the conclusion that their intelligence is inferior to ours. Do
not fish know more than we do about water? Birds about the air? Worms
about the earth?103 This is an unusual way of attacking the view that humans
are the pinnacle of creation. While Hobbes and some other philosophers of
the period allowed that non-human animals were capable of making certain
kinds of inference, they all believed that human rationality was superior to
that of other creatures.104 Cavendish, however, suggests that different kinds
of knowledge are unevenly distributed between species.
For there is only different knowledge belonging to every kind, as to animal kind,
vegetable kind, mineral kind, and infinitely more which we are not capable to
know... so that if a man have different knowledge from afish,yet thefishmay
be as knowing as the man.105
What distinguishes men is just the fact that they possess immortal souls;106
when they imagine themselves to be petty gods,107 they overrate their own
power by underestimating the epistemological variety of nature.
101
PPO, Part II, ch. 9.
102
PL, p. 40.
103
PL, pp. 35-6.
104
PL, pp. 30-5.
105
PPO, pp. 113-14. See also PL, p. 40.
106
PL, p. 35.
107
OEP, pp. 6, 280.
240 SUSAN JAMES
Physical Opinions, for instance, she claims that sound is received by the
sensory organs in the same manner as light, except that 'instead of drawing
or printing the outward objects received through the eye, the sensitive
matter sets or pricks down notes, or draws lines on the drum of the ear'.108
This passage, and some others like it, are in fact copied straight out of the
first edition of the work;109 and Cavendish adds a note at the end of Philo-
sophical Letters to remind her readers that in later volumes she does not
always manage to express herself accurately. When she talks about printing,
and about 'what the senses bring in',110 she explains, she means patterning:
'not that the external object prints its figure on the external sensitive organs,
but that the sensitive motions in the organ pattern out the figure in the
object.. .'1U Alongside this unclarity, she is not completely sure whether all
perception works by patterning out. In Philosophical Letters she confidently
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
asserts that
upon better consideration and more diligent search into the causes of natural
effects, I have found it more probable that all sensitive perception is made by
the way of patterning out, and so consequently the perception of sound and of
light.112
Neither can I certainly affirm that all perceptions consist in patterning out ex-
terior objects, for although the perception of our human senses is made that
way, yet Nature's actions being so various, I dare not conclude from thence that
all the various parts and figures of nature are all made after the same manner.
Nevertheless, it is probable to sense and reason that the infinite parts of nature
have not only interior self-knowledge but also exterior perception of other
figures or parts and their actions; by reason there is a perpetual commerce and
intercourse between parts and parts; and the chief actions of nature are com-
position and division which produces all the variety of nature; which proves
there must of necessity be perception between parts and parts.113
This qualification is of a piece not only with her belief that the speculations
of natural philosophers are at best probable,114 but also with her conviction
that several distinct processes contribute to natural change. While percep-
tion may account for some of these, it does not involve any transfer of
108 P P O , p . 302.
109
Philosophical and Physical Opinions (1653), pp. 121, 123.
110
PL, p. 540.
111
PL, pp. 539-40.
112
PL, p. 541.
113
OEP, pp. 163-4.
114
See Lisa Sarasohn, 'A Science Turned upside Down: Feminism and the Natural Philosophy
of Margaret Cavendish', Huntington Library Quarterly, 47 (1984), pp. 289-307.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 241
matter, and therefore cannot explain generation or the creation of new
things. As she puts it, 'The action of patterning out is not the action of gener-
ation . . . and generation must needs be performed by the way of trans-
lation.'115
Since there is in the natural world no creation of new matter, any new
object must be made from matter that already exists,116 and when the
motions constituting a body are dissipated, the matter of which it is com-
posed goes to form new entities.117 Destruction therefore precedes creation,
and every new thing is made from something old.118 For generation to occur,
the producers of a body must transfer or translate matter to it, and humans
and many other animals form their progeny by transferring some of their
own parts. As we know, the translation of matter is the translation of
motion, so a creature is capable of moving itself in some fashion from the
Downloaded by [University of Guelph] at 04:18 23 April 2013
moment of conception. But only as it grows, and its body becomes more
complex, does it gradually develop motions which allow it to manifest more
elaborate forms of behaviour. The motions of a complex body such as a
human cannot be created in an instant;119 instead, it takes time to produce
its various parts, and to enlarge and strengthen them, to the point where it
is capable of animal motion.120 Moreover, this is also true of artificial bodies.
For example, as a shipbuilder gradually adds to the matter of a vessel it
acquires the motions typical of vessels of that kind and the properties (or
as Cavendish would say, perceptions) to which they give rise, such as being
able to float while heavily loaded, or to remain upright in rough water.121
Cavendish is especially interested in the creation of humans and other
animals, but since she believes that all natural bodies are animate, one
would expect her account to apply to at least some minerals, insects and
plants. What, then, of objects which enlarge by accumulation, such as a
deposit of coal? In this case, the initial pieces of plant matter cannot develop
themselves into coal, but must wait for further dead plants and the action
of external forces. This example helps to illuminate two aspects of
Cavendish's account. First, the plant bodies which eventually become coal
must presumably possess motions or sympathies which enable them to
respond appropriately to one another, and to external pressures; and some
of these capacities are only acquired as a comparatively large body of plant
matter accumulates. So some of the motions which account for the behav-
iour of natural things are in this sense emergent. Secondly, many newly-
created bodies, animal and otherwise, are incomplete; they depend on
further transfers of matter both for their physical growth and for the
115
PPO, p. 428.
116
PPO, pp. 20, 419-20.
117
PPO, pp. 95-6.
118
PPO, p. 17.
119
PPO, p. 29.
120
P P O , pp. 31-3.
121
PPO, p. 24.
242 SUSAN JAMES
development of their appropriate motions or capacities. Returning to the
case of human beings, the motions intrinsic to a foetus become increasingly
complex and various as its body becomes more differentiated. As this
occurs, and by virtue of the very same motions, it becomes capable of an
expanding repertoire of sensations, perceptions and so on, all of which are
manifestations of its bodily structure.122 This process does not stop at birth,
and only when a human is fully physically developed does it attain perfec-
tion.
at the first instant, and not by degrees, a child in the womb, or at least a
newborn, would be as big, strong, sensible and knowing as at a ripe old age.123
122
Cavendish discusses William Harvey's On Animal Generation i n her Philosophical Letters,
agreeing with him about some points, such as that an animal is not perfectly shaped at con-
ception, though criticizing his view that generation occurs by contagion. Her own account
has a good deal in common with Walter Charleton's Natural History of Nutrition, Life and
Motion (1659).
123
PPO, p. 32.
124
OEP, p. 120.
125
PPO, p. 23.
THE INNOVATIONS OF MARGARET CAVENDISH 243
CONCLUSION
126
See Clarke, op. cit., Gabbey, op. cit., Henry, op. cit., Rogers, op. cit.
244 SUSAN JAMES
by critics of the New Science.127 Cavendish undoubtedly fits into this tra-
dition. But whereas English vitalism has often been regarded as broadly
Platonist in inspiration, evolving largely under the influence of Henry More,
her work suggests that its sources and forms are more eclectic than this view
allows. As we have seen, Cavendish shared a certain critical stance with
More, while rejecting some of his most deeply held philosophical beliefs. But
both her materialism and her analysis of perception are indebted - in so far
as they are indebted to anyone - to Hobbes, and it is its peculiar blend of
Platonist and materialist strands of argument that marks out her philosophy.
127
See Gabbey, op. cit.; Sarah Hutton, Introduction to Anne Conway, The Principles of the
Most Ancient and Modern Philosophy, ed. Alison Coudert and Taylor Corse (Cambridge,
Cambridge University Press, 1996).