Definitions of Psychology
Definitions of Psychology
DEFINITIONS OF PSYCHOLOGY
HAROLD A. HERZOG
Western Carolina University
The authors thank Stephen Handel, John Malone, T. M. Meguiar, and Raymond
Shrader for their assistance in collecting texts and other aspects of this project.
Correspondences should go to Tracy Henley, Department of Psychology, University of
Tennessee, Knoxville, TN 37996.
144 HENLEY ET AL.
Method
Table 1
Textbook Definitions
idea of the soul"). Except for definitions from 47 books which were
classed as "other" or having no definitions, the fact that definitions from
233 texts could be captured without major paraphrasing (as given in
Table 1) comes as a most interesting result.
As was noted by Hilgard, Atkinson, and Atkinson (1975), the
definition of psychology seems to have come full circle from the almost
complete mentalism of the century's turn to the return of such mentalistic
definitions in the 1980s. Several pOints nicely illustrate this idea: That
references to mind, consciousness, and mental activity account for 10 of
15 definitions prior to 1930; then from 1930 through 1969 mind,
consciousness, and mental activity are mentioned only 4 times in 58
definitions; but that in the 1980s mind and mental activity are in almost
a third of the definitions. The fact that this seems to be a growing trend
is suggested by the rise of the phrase behavior and mental activity which
was used 10% of the time in the decade 1970 through 1979, and it has
been used already in 21 % of the texts in the 8 years since 1980.
Tracing the term behavior over the 100 years shows it to have been
used in 14% of the definitions before 1930, 54% between 1930 and
1949, rising to 68% between 1950 and 1969, then declining to 64% in
the 1970s and climbing to 79% in the 1980s. This suggests a continued
growing acceptance of behavior as the central theme of psychology.
Nevertheless, it appears to be a qualified acceptance as can be seen by
comparing purely behavioral definitions with "behavior and . .. "
definitions: Before 1930 it was never behavior alone; from 1930 through
1949 it favored pure behavior just over 2:1; from 1950 through 1969
63% were pure behavior and 5% behavior and something else; in the
1970s 51 % were pure behavior and 13% behavior and something else,
and in the 1980s that shift is greater showing 41 % pure behavior and
32% "behavior and . ... "
Such trends certainly lend themselves to a Kuhnian notion of
paradigms. The early mentalism and talk of "phenomena" reflect the
psychology of Europe as it arose out of British Empiricism and the
Kantian and Hegelian philosophies from the continent. The degree to
which American psychology was still not differentiated from what we
today would call philosophy of mind in the late 1800s can be seen by a
careful study of James' Principles of Psychology (1890). Nevertheless
there was a growing sense at that time that American psychology should
be more applied and less philosophical. This change of attitude can be
marked by the splitting off of the American Philosophical Association
from the American Psychological Association in 1910 and by the
growing challenge of behaviorism (Benjamin, 1981). The turn to
behaviorism following Watson (1913) becomes manifest in the
introductory texts somewhat later as would be predicted by Kuhn.
These events could be seen as reflecting a paradigm shift in which the
old Guard mentalists died out and were replaced by younger
psychologists who had been influenced by Watson and a more applied
psychology. By 1930, this group had come to be in the position of
writing the textbooks and the shift in paradigms was complete.
DEFINITIONS OF PSYCHOLOGY 149
to the mentalists, this change just has been reflected in that simple
definition. Again, given the audience, and the data, it seems more
parsimonious to believe that no great shift in the meaning of the terms
behavior and mind is at play within the textbooks.
We conceived of and attempted to execute this examination as an
annotated descriptive study. However, some trends, such as the use of
behavior and the move toward a "behavior and ... " definition seem to us
especially significant for an attempt to say what psychology is, as well as
what is has been, and what it will be. Recently B. F. Skinner (1987)
asked hypothetically what a curve showing the appearance of the word
"cognitive" in the psychological literature would look like. His own
intuitions, that it appeared in the 1960s and rose exponentially were both
wrong and right. These data do suggest that it is on the rise, but that his
own championed "science of behavior" is still holding its own. He further
noted the increasing popularity in textbooks of something like "a science
of behavior and mental life" and argued from an almost Kuhnian
perspective that a confusion was on hand. Something about his whole
article seemed to validate our more complete use of Kuhn, which we
believe suggests that a period of "behavior and cognition" is here to
stay-until the next revolution that is.
References