Property Rights Philosophic Foundations
Property Rights Philosophic Foundations
https://archive.org/details/propertyrightsphOOOObeck
Property Rights
Philosophic Foundations
Lawrence C. Becker
Hollins College, Virginia
LluFvniv i - v, <
ST. VINCENT DE
BOYNTON BEACH
Routledge & Kegan Paul
London, Henley and Boston
First published in 1977
by Routledge & Kegan Paul Ltd
39 Store Street,
London WC1E 7DD,
Broadway House,
Newtown Road,
Henley-on-Thames,
Oxon RG9 1ENand
9 Park Street,
Boston, Mass. 02108, USA
Set in 10 on 12pt IBM Press Roman by
Express Litho Service (Oxford)
and printed in Great Britain by
Redwood Burn Ltd,
Trowbridge and Esher.
Copyright Lawrence C. Becker 1977
No part of this book may by reproduced in
any form without permission from the
publisher, except for the quotation of brief
passages in criticism.
•)
, ,V^.
Contents
Acknowledgments ix
1 Introduction 1
The need for a new theory 2
Foundations for a new theory 4
Private property and property rights per se 6
Scarcity 6
2 Property Rights 7
Rights 7
Property rights 18
Justification 22
••
Vll
Contents
8 Anti-Property Arguments 88
Social disutility 88
Self-defeatingness 94
Virtue 96
The perpetuation of inequality 96
Notes 119
Index 131
vm
Acknowledgments
The first man who, having enclosed a piece of ground, bethought himself
of saying ‘This is mine,’ and found people simple enough to believe
him, was the real founder of civil society. From how many crimes,
wars, and murders, from how many horrors and misfortunes might not
anyone have saved mankind, by pulling up the stakes, or filling up the
ditch, and crying to his fellows: ‘Beware of listening to this imposter,
you are undone if you once forget that the fruits of the earth belong to
us all, and the earth itself to nobody.’
Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Discourse on Inequality, part II
1 Introduction
1
Property Rights
2
Introduction
avoid. Those who have attacked private property have usually shown
the signs of intense frustration — rage, hyperbole, and despair at
achieving any reform by rational persuasion. Reasoned argument, when
it comes in conflict with the desire to get and keep something, is grossly
overmatched.
The riskiness of writing about property has largely disappeared. The
problem now is whether there is any longer any point in doing so. The
main lines of argument for the general justification of property have
long since been laid down; the vulnerable areas in those justifications
have been identified; alternatives to private ownership have been
proposed; weaknesses in those proposals have been explored. It seems
unlikely that any new discussion could make a significant contribution
to theory. And it seems even less likely that it could have significant
practical consequences. The changes in property rights which have
occurred in the last six or seven decades — and those which will doubt¬
less occur in the next six or seven — are startling, to say the least. But
they have not — nor are they likely to begin to — come about as the
result of a clear and comprehensive new theory of property. The
modern industrial state is so complex, its basic institutions so en¬
trenched and interdependent, that basic changes come about more by
the accidental confluence of particular interests than by design. The
action guidance moral philosophy might provide thus seems a bit beside
the point.
Yet property rights badly need philosophical discussion. Traditional
philosophical arguments for and against various forms of property are
seriously flawed. They are based on naive or hasty analyses of the
concept of rights per se and property rights in particular. They rarely
prove what they say they prove (a fact noticed by all their critics), but
they often do prove some other interesting things (things their critics
overlook). They usually address themselves to the question farthest
removed from practical concerns — namely why there should ever be
any property rights at all; what I call the problem of general justification.
They consequently slight the most important question — namely what
sorts of people should own what sorts of things and under what
conditions; the problem of specific justification. Most damaging of all,
they are each typically embedded in a general moral theory which
makes it difficult to use one argument to support, augment, or restrict
another. Utilitarians scorn claims founded on justice in original
acquisition; advocates of the labor theory are reluctant to limit the
claims of justice by weighing in the consequences for the promotion of
good (as opposed to the demotion of evil); and the defenders of
‘ownership by the property worthy’ largely ignore both utility and the
3
Property Rights
4
Introduction
5
Property Rights
Scarcity
As a final introductory note, it should be mentioned that the scarcity
of goods is regarded by most writers as the central, controlling fact of
the contexts in which problems about property rights arise. Indeed,
many writers on property feel obliged to begin with remarks to the
effect that, were it not for scarcity, there would be no need for the
institution of ownership. There is, of course, a good deal of truth in
this. Even if a good is not now actually scarce, its ownership can be
problematic to the extent that the good can become scarce — e.g. by
being used up or by being controlled by a few people. And if a good
were to be inexhaustible and unlimitedly available to all, it is difficult
to imagine that much of importance could hang on who owned what
parts of it.
But like many seemingly obvious general pronouncements, it is not
so clear, upon inspection, that this one is as uncontestable as it seems.
If it is the case, as some defenders of property have supposed, that
appropriating things is an essential part of the full development of a
human personality, then it is not necessarily true that the elimination
of scarcity eliminates the problems which call for a theory of property
rights. For it may be, then, that the preservation (through a system of
property rights) of one’s possessions has some importance just because
those things are one’s own appropriations — regardless of whether or
not they are scarce or likely to become scarce. I have therefore chosen
not to make the usual deep bow to the notion of scarcity.
6
2 Property Rights
Rights
‘Right’ has multiple meanings, and they are so deeply entrenched in
both ordinary and technical usages that the best one can hope for is to
keep the various meanings distinct and see to it that the distinctions are
attended to. Discussions of property rights are often damaged by careless
use of terms like ‘natural’ or ‘human’ rights, vagueness in distinguishing
moral from legal rights, and an imprecise understanding of the root idea
of a right. What I want to do here, as a prelude to discussing the
complexity of the concept of a property right, is to state with some
care what I take to be the root idea of a right, and then explicate the
elements of that root idea. I shall argue that all the sorts of rights
philosophers find it necessary to distinguish can be given adequately
precise definitions by reference to those elements.
7
Property Rights
or social goods, or rights with virtues, what they mean by ‘right’ seems
to be something like this:
8
Property Rights
9
Property Rights
These, then, are the elements in terms of which the root idea of a right
may be analyzed. I want to show now that one can organize various
typologies of rights simply by paying attention to the ways these
elements are filled in. Specifically, I want to show how much of an
overview of the whole concept of rights can be gotten by first consider¬
ing element (3), the general nature of the relationship between a right¬
holder and others, then element (5), the conditions which justify
right-claims. I will propose schematic definitions for most of the major
sorts of rights commonly distinguished. The definitions themselves
(though I think they are good ones) may be arguable. What I hope is
not arguable is the usefulness of this method of defining rights.
with ‘negative’ claim rights). One may wish to separate the claim rights
held against individuals from those held against institutions. And one
may wish to separate those for whose violation performance alone is an
adequate remedy from those for whose violation either performance or
compensation will suffice. When references to other elements of the
schema are added (e.g. who may hold the rights, who may enforce
them), it is easy to distinguish a great variety of types. Most of the
possibilities are straightforward enough not to need comment.
There is, however, one special sort of claim right which has been the
source of enough confusion to warrant special treatment.5 The sort I
have in mind may be called a capacity-claim, and may be described as
follows: One may wish, in asserting one’s rights, to call particular
attention to one’s status as a potential holder of rights. That is, one
may wish merely to assert, with a statement such as ‘I have a right to
get married,’ that one is of age and mentally competent — that one has
the legal capacity to get married.
This sort of claim right easily causes confusion, because the relevant
‘capacity’ or ‘standing’ is presupposed by the existence of other sorts of
rights. Having a right to score a goal in a soccer game is part liberty (no
one has a right that you not score) and part power (if you do put the
ball in the net in the prescribed manner, your goal must be recognized),
but both parts of the right presuppose that you are a player — that is,
that you have the requisite capacity or standing to exercise the liberty/
power right to score. Thus, when one asserts the right to score (meaning
the liberty/power right) one also necessarily presupposes that one has
the requisite capacity. But when the existence of that capacity is itself
at issue, one may want to ‘back up’ as it were and assert it alone. Right-
claim locutions come naturally here, they amount to the assertion that
others ‘owe’ one the recognition that one has the capacity — the relevant
qualifications or standing as defined by the right-making institutions or
considerations — to possess one or more sorts of rights.
The existence of the (legal or moral) capacity to possess rights, then,
in the sense that its recognition is owed the person having it, is the
existence of a capacity-claim right. I regard this as a claim right because
correlative duty-bearers can be specified, and the remedy for violations
(failure to recognize* capacity-claims) is the extraction of the perfor¬
mance (the recognition) from the duty-bearer.
Liberty.6 Not all rights, however, entail the existence of duties in
others. For example, we may say that one person (the right-holder) is at
liberty with respect to some others to do or not to do a given thing.
The others have no claim right against the right-holder, either to the
effect that the thing not be done, or that it be done. And the right-
12
Property Rights
13
Property Rights
14
Property Rights
abortion if she wants one, then, is to say that she is owed the necessary
services.) We may be prepared to impose the correlative duties on
medical professionals. If so, the right to an abortion is a straightforward
claim right. But suppose we are not? Suppose we want to assert that
every woman has a right to (is somehow owed) an abortion if she wants
one, but we are not prepared to impose a duty on all or any particular
medical professionals to provide the service. (This is very nearly an
accurate description of the current situation in the United States.) Such
rights stand midway, as it were, between claim rights and liberties; they
may be considered to be ‘imperfect’ claim rights, or ‘augmented’
liberties. In any case their status is problematic, particularly for the law,
because, though they assert that something is owed the right-holder,
their failure to specify who should ‘pay’ renders them unenforceable.
They are, rather, simply assertions that (a) some person (the right¬
holder, is owed or entitled to something in the sense that (b) if it is
obtained, the recipient need not accept it with the gratitude appropriate
to the receipt of a gift, but may (properly) accept it as one would
accept the honoring of a claim right; and (c) if it is not obtained, the
right-holder may appropriately respond as if an (unspecifiable) duty-
bearer had violated a claim right.
I shall call the existence of this state of affairs the existence of a
recipient right.8 It is an important and interesting sort of moral claim,9
but one which often leads to confusion. People who have in effect
persuaded themselves that such a right (say to health care) exists, often
assume that it has — or must quickly be upgraded to — the status of a
claim right. Others, recognizing only the conventional Hohfeldian
categories of rights-relationships, assume that because a correlative duty-
bearer cannot be specified, no ‘real’ right exists. Discussion then quickly
degenerates.
Claim rights (including capacity-claims), liberties, powers (including
participant powers), immunities, and recipient rights are all typed, then,
by reference to the general sort of relationship that exists between the
right-holder and others — that is, they are distinguished from one
another primarily by how element (3) in the schema is filled in.
15
Property Rights
For example, a natural right is one which arises from conditions (as
in element (5)) which may, in some plausible sense, be said to ‘occur
naturally.’ The notion of a natural right is primarily designed to mark
the distinction between rights which arise from human institutions
particularly from practices intentionally designed to be right-making —
and rights which ‘just exist.’ Rights which arise because people make
agreements with each other or because they accept the rule of law, or
the rules of a particular institution, are not examples of natural rights;
they are ordinarily called conventional or special rights. Rights which
are justified in terms of the minimum requirements for social stability,
or human dignity, are natural rights — even if the list of minimum
requirements is heavily influenced by the particular set of institutions
humans have created. The distinction is not a perfectly sharp one, but it
is clear that it is to be made in terms of the fifth element of the
analysis.
A human right is (oversimply) either a natural or a conventional
right held by all and only human beings. (A right to the same thing,
held by Martians, is then a Martian right.) The qualifier ‘human’ here
only restricts the scope of right-holders (element (1)). The conditions
under which the holder’s claim may be said to be sound are the same as
those for other rights (except that they specify the whole class of
human beings as the only right-holders).
Legal rights are those which ‘are’ matters of law in a given system. I
put ‘are’ in scare quotes to indicate a problem; one’s theory of law will
determine, in each case, what rights are matters of law. Oversimply, for
a legal realist, legal rights are those which the courts will in fact enforce.
For a modem positivist, they are those ‘recognized,’ implicitly or
explicitly, by the legal system. For the natural-law theorist, they are the
ones the system ought to recognize. Here again the primary distinguish¬
ing mark is the filling in of element (5) — the conditions under which a
right claim may be said to be justified. But of course the definition is
also concerned with elements (8), (9), and (10) — the specification of
appropriate remedies, coercive measures, and agents who may carry
them out. A given legal system may (but need not in principle) limit
the sorts of right-relationships (under element (3)) which it recognizes.
Private (legal) rights are legal rights distinguished by reference to
element (1) — who may be a right-holder. In this case, that means
individuals in their ‘non-official’ and ‘non-affiliated’ capacities (though
citizenship can be a prerequisite). With the suitable modifications, one
can have categories of private rights which are natural, special, human,
or moral.
Civil rights are private, legal rights. But in addition to that, civil
16
Property Rights
One could go on along these lines for a very long time. One could argue
17
Property Rights
Property rights
Property rights, as I shall use the term, are the rights of ownership.11
But ‘the rights of ownership’ is not an unequivocal term. It is clear
enough that ownership typically has something to do with the right to
use, the right to transfer, and the right to exclude others from the thing
owned. And most philosophical discussions of property content them¬
selves with this broad characterization, noting in passing that certain
restrictions (e.g. prohibition of harmful use) and extensions (e.g. the
right to bequeath) are usually associated with it.12 But the right of use
is itself a bundle of rights which mature legal systems separate, and
when the other elements of legal ownership are examined, it quickly
becomes obvious that a person may own things (legally) in a variety of
overlapping but quite distinct senses. Philosophical discussion will
profit from a consideration of legal analyses of the concept.
FULL OWNERSHIP
A. M. Honore has given a particularly lucid account of the ‘full’ or
‘liberal’ concept of ownership — a concept he says is common to all
‘mature’ legal systems.13 A summary of his list of the elements (‘legal
incidents’) which make up the concept is a convenient place to begin.
Honore maintains that the full or liberal notion of ownership
(though it is, of course, subject to other analyses) is most adequately
explicated by reference to the following list of elements.
18
Property Rights
(1) The right to possess - that is, to exclusive physical control of the
thing owned. Where the thing cannot be possessed physically, due, for
example, to its ‘non-corporeaf nature, ‘possession’ may be understood
metaphorically or simply as the right to exclude others from the use or
other benefits of the thing.
(2) The right to use - that is, to personal enjoyment and use of the
thing as distinct from (3) and (4) below.
(3) The right to manage - that is, to decide how and by whom a
thing shall be used.
(4) The right to the income - that is, to the benefits derived from
foregoing personal use of a thing and allowing others to use it.
(5) The right to the capital — that is, the power to alienate the thing
and to consume, waste, modify, or destroy it.
(6) The right to security - that is, immunity from expropriation.
(7) The power of transmissibility - that is, the power to devise or
bequeath the thing.
(8) The absence of term - that is, the indeterminate length of one’s
ownership rights.
(9) The prohibition of harmful use - that is, one’s duty to forbear
from using the thing in certain ways harmful to others.
(10) Liability to execution - that is, liability to having the thing
taken away for repayment of a debt.
(11) Residuary character - that is, the existence of rules governing
the reversion of lapsed ownership rights.
Honore is quick to point out that although all of the eleven incidents
are necessary for full or liberal ownership as defined by existing mature
legal systems, none of them is a necessary constitutent of ownership per
se, for people may be said to own things in various restricted senses
which omit any one or more of the incidents. One might, for example,
have the right to the income of one’s trust, but not the right to its
capital or management. Or one might have the right to management and
income of one’s house, but (due to leasing agreements) only restricted
rights to use, possession, and capital.
Further, each of the incidents is susceptible of varying definitions
not. perhaps, enough to alter its general idea, but enough to alter
emphasis and practical consequences. Transmissibility, for example, is
usually defined so as to exclude perpetuities. Harmful use may shade
into a requirement for productive use. The right to income may be
defined to permit taxation. The right to security may be defined to
permit state expropriation under certain circumstances. And so forth.
Finally, the incidents are susceptible of differing scopes. There may
be restrictions on what one can own in various senses: e.g. in the case
19
Property Rights
VARIETIES OF OWNERSHIP
Just as there is no single definition of ownership in a given legal system,
so there is no single definition of full or liberal ownership among legal
systems. The list of elements may be standard (Honore says it is), but
the definition and scope given to each is subject to significant variations.
Nevertheless, for the purposes of the discussion to follow, it will be
useful to specify the subsets of Honore’s list which it seems reasonable
to regard as varieties of ownership, leaving aside, for now, issues of the
precise definition and scope of each subset.
I suggest (on the basis of nothing stronger than a feel for the se¬
mantic proprieties) that the following subsets of the eleven elements
each constitute a variety of what may reasonably be called ownership.
The right to the capital is the only one of the elements which
seems able to define a variety of ownership standing alone. It is the
most fundamental of the elements, if only because it includes the right
to destroy, consume, and alienate. (Alienation is understood to include
exchanges, gifts, and just ‘letting go.’) This makes absence of term
rather academic, and the other incidents can be seen as protections,
extensions, restrictions, or elaborations of this right. One who has all
the rights in the list save that of capital may own the thing in a derivative
sense, but the one who has the right to the capital is ‘fundamentally’ the
owner.
It follows that, if the right to capital is enough, by itself, to claim
ownership, any subset of elements which includes it will also be suf¬
ficient for the claim. Of course, a suitably strong prohibition of harmful
use, or a whimsically short term, or a sweeping allowance of expro¬
priation may effectively destroy the right to capital, but then the
element is in effect absent from the subset.
The right to security in possession, security in use, security in man¬
agement,14 and security in income may each be regarded as varieties of
ownership. The rights to use, income, or possession standing alone, are
perhaps disputable cases, but seem to me to be too slender to support
the claim of ownership. When each is buttressed with some version of
absence of term or the right to security, the claim of ownership is
plausible. I think it is safe to say that any subset which could
reasonably be called a variety of ownership would have to include at
least one of the first five elements (possession, use, management,
income, capital).
20
Property Rights
These, then, are the likely candidates for varieties of ownership. The
right to capital alone; and thus capital plus any other element or set of
elements. The right to security in possession, or in use, or in income, or
in management; thus each of these pairs plus any other element or set
of elements. The number of combinations (about 1500 out of a total
of 2047 possible for the eleven elements) is daunting. When varying
definitions and scopes are added for each element, the number is greatly
increased.
Needless to say, the analysis to follow will not be able to concern
itself explicitly with very many of these combinations. (And one
suspects that most of the variants of the main types listed above are
not significantly different, for philosophical purposes, from those
which will be considered.) But a lively appreciation of the range
possible for property rights will be central to the discussion.
21
Property Rights
Justification
The justification of a property right will mean, in what follows, its
assertion as a conclusion from a sound, ‘all things considered,’ reasoned
argument. People can, of course, have unjustified and/or unjustifiable
legal and moral rights, de facto, by virtue of a prevailing legal or moral
code. Whether such de facto rights are ‘real’ or not I leave to one side as
a question without significant philosophical interest. To the other side
I leave questions as to whether there are any rights people ought to
have which, while they cannot be justified, are none the less known to
be just by intuition, revelation, or the ‘moral sense.’ Intuition and reve¬
lation are good places to begin a philosophical discussion, but they are
bad places to end it. When I speak of a right people have, then, I shall
rely on the context to make clear whether I mean a de facto right or
one which can be justified as a conclusion from a sound, all things
22
Property Rights
With these preliminaries out of the way, then, I shall turn to the main
task — the analysis of traditional arguments for and against private
property. (Again I shall often drop the modifier ‘private’ and speak
only of property rights or the rights of ownership. The context will
make it quite clear whether the modifier ‘private’ is implicit or not.)
23
3 The Argument from
First Occupancy
When the question arises as to why some people, rather than others,
should own things, one of the issues which comes to mind is the
question, ‘Who had it first?’ The notion that being there first somehow
justifies ownership rights is a venerable and persistent one. A close
analysis will show that it does not provide a sound basis for claims to
ownership, and thus contributes nothing to a theory of the general
justification of property rights. But it is important to consider none
the less. The reasons for its failure are illuminating.
24
The Argument from First Occupancy
limits are specified, they define the maximum an occupier could ever
rightfully claim merely on the basis of occupation. Whether an occupier
can rightfully claim this maximum — or indeed any amount at all — is
a separate issue. I shall discuss each of the four requirements first, and
then turn to the question of the soundness of the argument.
25
Property Rights
26
The Argument from First Occupancy
difference between the state of merely being somewhere and the act
of appropriating that place. One may appropriate things for various
purposes: to have a place to live, to hunt, to cultivate, to mine, or
perhaps just to keep to oneself. If a person takes a piece of land to
cultivate, but does not carry out his purpose, his appropriation of
anything more than the area on which he stands is purely intentional.
The cultivated land, however, is reasonably regarded as occupied by the
cultivator (even though he may be physically present on only part of it),
and the cultivation effectively defines the limits of the land so appro¬
priated. Similarly for other purposes of appropriation: if one’s purpose
is simply to exclude others, then until one effectively does so (i.e. has
the will and the ability to do so) one’s appropriation is purely inten¬
tional. The declarations of European explorers in the fifteenth century
were mostly of this purely intentional sort, as would be that of a
United States astronaut were he to try to appropriate the moon. No
effective means of excluding others from a whole continent existed in
the case of Cortez or Coronado, and none exists now in the case of the
moon. Should it ever be otherwise, however — as for example it would
be if the science fiction idea of impenetrable planetary defenses were
realized — then we could make sense of the notion that a nation or a
person could appropriate a planet by occupation, merely for the purpose
of excluding others. (This would not, by itself, justify property rights in
the whole planet, of course. But the concept of occupation of the
whole planet, in a sense requisite for appropriation, would clearly be
satisfied.) A rancher with a herd of three cattle, then, cannot occupy,
in the sense requisite for appropriation of pasture land, a 5,000 acre
tract. He could, however, appropriate acreage for future use (i.e. to
exclude others until his herd grows) to the extent that he could actually
keep others off the land.
It might be thought that the wide variety of purposes possible for
appropriations makes the foregoing account as liable to absurdity as
one which admits simple declarations. Suppose I appropriate merely
for self-aggrandizement, and having an exalted view of myself, decide
that only a continent would be sufficient to make me grander than I
am? Or suppose I appropriate a mountain range for aesthetic purposes?
Or 5,000 acres for privacy? Doesn’t the existence of such purposes
entail, in effect, appropriation by mere intent? I think not. Such
‘interior’ purposes either require the exclusion of others for their imple¬
mentation, and thus are limited in the same way that appropriations
purely for the exclusion of others are limited, or else they do not
require occupation at all (as when I make a song ‘my own’). In that case
they can be accomplished by intent or declaration alone, and have only
27
Property Rights
that status. All of the potentially embarrassing cases I can think of fall
into one or the other of these categories. The quantitative limits of ap¬
propriation by occupation, then, in the senses relevant to a discussion
of property rights, are reasonably regarded as the limits of the purposes
of such appropriations as implemented.
KANT’S REMARKS
The first of the two defective lines is an argument attributed to Kant.4
He argued that an act of will in appropriating a thing creates a property
right in that thing if the act satisfies the moral law and if anyone
else’s subsequent use or possession of it would injure the appropriator.
On the assumption that at least some acts of first occupancy can satisfy
the moral law (i.e. are capable of being derived from a self-consistent
28
The Argument from First Occupancy
universal law), Kant claims (1) that to deny anyone the exercise of
freedom involved in such an appropriation would be wrong, and (2)
that once appropriated, to deny anyone the continued use of the pos¬
session would be wrong. These things would be wrong in so far as they
would be unjustifiable restrictions of the exercise of a person’s freedom.
Let us see what follows from this and what is assumed by it.
If (as Kant evidently thinks) I have a natural right to, or it would in
some other sense be wrong to deny me, the greatest extent of liberty
compatible with the moral law, then it would follow that the denial of
the exercise of my freedom to appropriate (in accord with the moral
law) would be wrong. But it does not follow at all from the fact that
appropriation conforms to the moral law that permanent possession,
use, management, right to income, capital, and power of transmission
also conform to the moral law. No doubt expropriation would ‘injure’
me in the sense that it would frustrate the exercise of my freedom. But
if expropriation is ever consistent with the moral law, and indeed with
the greatest extent of liberty compatible with the moral law, then the
‘injury’ to me would not be a wrong. There is no reason to think,
a priori, that this could not sometimes be the case. In short, the argu¬
ment establishes a liberty right to appropriate but not a claim right to
keep. And that is not a property right at all. (An extension of the argu¬
ment from natural liberty can support the justification of property
rights — in a way which connects indirectly with first occupation — but
that is best left to later discussion. See below, pp. 75-80.)
HEGEL’S REMARKS
The second defective line is attributable to Hegel. At least it is sug¬
gested by passages from his Philosophy of Right.5 There, mixed together
with some interesting remarks about the genesis of property as an
expression of personality, Hegel asserts that (1) ‘a person must translate
his freedom into an external sphere to exist as Idea’; (2) what is external
is what is not personal, not free, without rights; and (3) ‘a person has as
his substantive end the right of putting his will into any and every [ex¬
ternal] thing’; (4) this putting of the will into a thing makes it one’s
own ‘because it has no such end in itself and derives its destiny and soul
from his will’; (5) this is, he concludes, ‘the absolute right of appropri¬
ation which man has over all things.’
The criticism of the argument may be brief. I do not grant that the
need asserted in (1) must include the acquisition of property rights.
Nor do I grant, as a general principle, that a need creates a property
right; therefore I am suspicious of the move from (1) to (3). But clearly
the argument, even granting (1), (2), and (3), has the same flaw as
29
Property Rights
Conclusion
The argument from first occupation, then, does not succeed in giving a
general justification of property rights. That is, it provides no answer
to the question of why there ought to be any property rights (based
on first occupancy) at all. Liberty to occupy (under certain conditions),
yes. But not any of the complexes of claim rights, liberties, powers, or
immunities comprising something which could reasonably be described
as ownership.
However, if another general justification can be found, and if (for
30
The Argument from First Occupancy
31
4 The LaborTheory of
Property Acquisition
32
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
Locke’s theory
There are several distinct arguments in Locke3 for a labor theory of
primitive acquisition, and they involve two distinct conceptions of the
root idea that labor entitles one to property. The standardly quoted
line is this:
(la) Everyone ‘has a property in his own person; this nobody has a
right to but himself.’ (27)
(lb) ‘[T] he labour of his body and the work of his hands we may
say are properly his.’ (27)
(lc) Whenever someone, by his labor, changes a thing from its
natural state (to make it more useful or beneficial to him [26, 28, 34]),
he has ‘mixed’ his labor with it — that is, ‘joined to it something that
is his own.’ (27)
(ld) He ‘thereby makes it his property,’ for ‘it hath, by this labour,
something annexed to it that excludes the common right of other
men. For this labour being the unquestionable property of the labourer,
no man but he can have a right to what that is once joined to. ... ’ (27)
(le) This is so ‘at least where there is enough and as good left in
common for others’ (27), and where what one takes is no more than
one can use. (31)
The root idea is here understood in terms of a derivation from prior
property rights. Since one’s body is one’s property, and its produce
(labor) is also one’s property, it follows (?) that the labor’s product is
also one’s property. Critics have generally focused on the final inference
rather than the prernises behind it, and they have had good sport with
the metaphors of ‘mixing,’ ‘annexing,’ or ‘joining’ one’s labor to a thing.
But these metaphors really pose no more difficult a problem than is
posed by the need to define the extent of one’s ‘occupation’ of a piece
of land; both problems can be solved in much the same way. Labor is
first distinguished from mere intent, declaration, or occupation. It is
next distinguished from play and accidental improvement (e.g. play¬
fully pushing a boulder into a boulder field and accidentaly starting an
avalanche which clears the field and makes it suitable pasture for
33
Property Rights
sheep).4 One then simply calls attention to the fact that labor is pur¬
posive. Some efforts are for the purpose of enclosing a piece of land;
some are for growing a crop; others are for creating an artifact to be
possessed and used. The extent of the land (or whatever) with which
one’s labor ‘mixes’ is thus quite naturally defined by the purposes for
which one labors. Erecting a fence counts as a mixing of labor with the
enclosed area, and cultivation counts as laboring on the soil. There are
puzzling cases, embarrassing cases (what about the airspace over the
land?). But on the whole, the metaphors are manageable ones.
The crucial problem with premises (c) and (d) is, as Nozick puts it,
why anyone should think that mixing one’s labor with a thing is a way
of making the thing one’s own rather than a way of losing one’s labor.5
It is evident that Locke was not content with these premises either. He
keeps adding remarks which produce variants of the original argument.
For example, consider this variant:
(2a) People have property in their bodies (as in argument 1).
(2b) Likewise, their labor is their property (as in argument 1).
(2c) ‘That labour put[s] a distinction between [the thing worked
on] and [what is held in] common.’ (28)
(2d) The distinction is that labor ‘added something to [the thing]
more than nature . . . had done. . . . ’ (28)
(2e) The thing labor adds — the difference it makes — is value.
Things that are unappropriated are ‘of no use’ (28) and labor is respon¬
sible for nine-tenths or perhaps ninety-nine hundredths of the value of
the products of the earth. (40)
(2f) Therefore one’s labor entitles one to property in the thing
labored on.
Strictly, of course, the argument could at most only yield the con¬
clusion that one is entitled to the value one’s labor adds to the thing,
and not to the thing itself. Locke’s reply would apparently have been
that the difference is minuscule (some 1 per cent) and that in some
cases the labor value and the thing so improved are inseparable. Nine¬
teenth-century critics — anarchists, socialists, and reform capitalists
alike — insist quite correctly, however, that the argument does not
support property in land.6 In the products of labor, yes. But in the case
of land those are the fruits of cultivation, or herding, or building, and
not the land itself. The difference here is not a small one and the two
are not inseparable.
But is the argument sound? It apparently proceeds by assuming that
the property in one’s body ‘extends’ first to (the body’s product) labor,
and then again to the product of labor by the alteration in one’s
relation to the thing which is the consequence of the labor. But how is
34
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
this so? Granted that when one labors on a thing, one’s relation to it
has been changed — i.e. before the laboring, the thing could not truly
be described as something one had labored on; after the laboring, it
can be so described. But how does that change justify the claim that
one has property rights in the thing?
I shall comment on this argument in detail in a moment, but first
let me lay out the final variant of the labor theory which can be found
in Locke. This one, though it is less often quoted, is the heart of the
issue as I see it. It begins by repeating premises (2a) through (2e):
(3a) People have property in their bodies (as in arguments 1,2).
(3b) Likewise, their labor is their property (as in arguments 1,2).
(3c) ‘That labour put[s] a distinction between [the thing worked on]
and [what is held in] common.’ (28)
(3d) The distinction is that labor ‘added something to [the thing]
more than nature . . . had done.’ (28)
(3e) The thing labor adds — the difference it makes — is value.
Things that are unappropriated are ‘of no use’ (28) and labor is respon¬
sible for nine-tenths or perhaps ninety-nine hundredths of the value of
the products of the earth. (40)
Then the new argument adds the following:
(3f) Since things are of no use until appropriated (28), and appro¬
priation in most cases involves labor which would not be undertaken
except for the expected benefits, to let others have the ‘benefits of
another’s pains’ (34) would clearly be unjust.
(3g) This is so ‘at least where there is enough and as good left in
common for others’ (27) and where one takes no more than one can
use (31). ‘For he that leaves as much as another can make use of, does as
good as take nothing at all.’
(3h) Therefore, from (a) through (e) one is entitled to the whole of
the value one’s labor adds to things, and from (f) and (g) — together
with elements from (a) through (e) — one is entitled to the other
expected benefits as well.
Here, in (3f) and (3g), is a variant of the root idea quite distinct
from that expressed in (a) through (e). The proposal is that labor is
something unpleasant enough so that people only do it in the expec¬
tation of benefits (and since unlabored-on things are of little or no value
anyway), it would be unjust not to let people have the benefits they
take pains to get. This is so at least where one’s appropriation has no
significant effect on others.
Here (3g) — premise (le) in the original argument — functions as
much to disarm objections as to state a positive requirement of justice.
Premises (f) and (g), then, taken together, constitute an argument for
35
Property Rights
the benefits people expect, but cannot get title to from premises (a)
through (e). If these benefits are ones people deserve by virtue of the
(labor) pains they have taken, then that constitutes a good reason for
granting the benefits. And if there are no countervailingly strong
reasons to the contrary, granting them is justified. This explication of
the root idea has seldom been attacked.
Locke gives, then, two distinct reasons for thinking that one’s
labor entitles one to property in the thing labored on: (1) that such
rights derive from prior property rights in one’s body and its labors;
and (2) that such rights are required, in justice, as a return for the
laborer’s pains. Both reasons, taken together, are intended to establish
security in the right to capital and the other rights normally associated
with capital — namely, possessory, use, management, and income rights.
Absence of term is also supposed to follow, and the prohibition of
harmful use (probably) follows from the restrictions in (3g). Liability
to execution for debt may perhaps be ground out of an analysis of the
powers of alienation (promises governing exchanges). At least it is
consistent with a rational system of exchanges. Transmissibility,
however, does not follow directly from Locke’s arguments, as has been
noted by some.7
36
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
37
Property Rights
38
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
those to the fruits of their labor. This means others have duties corres¬
ponding to those rights. Such duties — e.g. my parents’ duty to respect
my liberty — may conflict with their property rights in me. Where a
duty conflicts with a right it may (a) be overridden by the right; (b) be
equal to and therefore effectively ‘cancel’ the right; or (c) override the
right. The question now to be answered is why the duty of parents to
respect the liberty of their children either cancels or overrides their
property rights in those children.
The long answer would have to go through the whole account of
rights to life and liberty, showing their dominance over property
rights. But fortunately there is a shorter argument available in this case.
Locke makes the right to property in the fruits of one’s labor derivative
from one’s rights to one’s body (at least he does so in the standardly
quoted line of argument). If the property rights in one’s body are
merely summations of — or another way of stating — the rights to
liberty all humans are entitled to, then it is clear that we have grounds
for restricting the consequences of a principle derived from those rights
(namely, the principle that people are entitled to property in the
fruits of their labor) to results which are compatible with the ‘origin¬
ating’ rights (namely, the liberty rights). That is, we can rule out as
self-contradictory any consequence of a principle which contradicts the
premises which generate that principle. If we begin from the premise
that all people have property rights in their bodies, and from that
generate the principle that they are entitled to the produce of their
labors, we cannot accept an interpretation of that principle which
permits a property right in the produce of labor to outweigh or cancel
a person’s property right in his or her body. For the latter sort of right
is primary; it is from that that property rights to labor’s produce
derive.
This also solves nicely the problem of accounting for the existence
of property rights in one’s body. After all, in Locke’s account, labor is
supposed to be the only mode of original or primitive acquisition, and
if anyone acquires property in people’s bodies that way it is parents, not
the people themselves. So where do these ‘prior’ property rights come
from? Thinking of them as restatements of rights to life and liberty
gives a good answer. Of course it also means that property rights — in
this one argument at least — derive from rights to life and liberty, and
therefore one’s success in establishing property rights by that argument
depends on success in establishing those other rights. But this is a conse¬
quence natural rights theorists would accept gladly, I think.
The failure of the ‘property rights in one’s body’ line of argument.
What they might not accept as gladly is the way the account just given
39
Property Rights
makes painfully clear the need to further restrict the property rights so
derived. If their source in people’s liberty means that persons cannot be
owned, does it not also mean that ownership of land must be restricted?
‘Place one hundred men on an island from which there is no escape, and
whether you make one of these men the absolute owner of the other
ninety-nine or the absolute owner of the soil of the island, will make no
difference either to him or to them.’13 Where ownership of anything
(land, water, etc.) has the effect of abridging the liberty (property in
one’s body) from which the Lockean argument derives the rights of
ownership over things other than one’s body, the argument cannot
permit such ownership.
Worse still, the basic question remains unsettled: How is it that the
property rights to one’s body ‘transfer’ or extend to property in the
products of one’s labor? In so far as one’s labor is inseparable (by way
of ownership rights) from one’s body, it is understandable how the
first ‘extension’ — from ownership of the body to ownership of the
labor — is warranted. But the same can hardly be said for the second
extension — from ownership of the labor to ownership of labor’s
products. The products of one’s labors are clearly separable from one’s
body. And Nozick’s question remains: Why is it that investing one’s
labor in something causes one to come to own that thing? Why does it
not instead just mean that one has lost the investment?
Here defenders of the labor theory tend to make a burden-of-proof
argument. Why not? they say. Surely my working on something changes
things. I now stand in a relation to the thing labored on which differen¬
tiates me from all other persons. I produced its human value (or nine-
tenths or ninety-nine hundredths of it). Surely that makes it mine.
Unfortunately, this will not work. The phrase ‘It is mine’ is am¬
biguous here. As a reference to the fact that it (the produce of one’s
labor) is just that — and not the produce of anyone else’s, or a product
of chance — the claim ‘It is mine’ is of course true, but merely a repe¬
tition of the assertion of the unique relation which now holds between
you and the thing. The crucial question remains unanswered: What
reason is there to conclude that this altered relationship constitutes, or
warrants, or gives any support at all to the claim that you have owner¬
ship rights in the thing? Why does it not just mean that you are entitled
to public admiration? Or the gratitude of your fellows? Or perhaps
nothing more than the appropriate change in the great book which
describes the world? It is labor theorists who are making the assertion
here — that the changes produced by their labors entitle them to
property rights. The burden of proof is on them to show how it is so,
and they have not done so. I see no reason to think that they can. I
40
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
suspect that what they can show is the reasonability (in some cases)
of saying that labor grounds a recipient claim right to the thing. That is,
that the fact of one’s labor can sometimes establish that one is owed
possession or use or management in the sense that, should one not get
it, one could appropriately react as though an unspecifiable duty-
bearer had violated one’s claim rights. But that is not a property right,
and so whether or not the labor theory establishes it is irrelevant here.
41
Property Rights
tions on what this argument can justify. First, the labor has to be
above and beyond what morality requires a person to do for others.
And that can be a very large condition indeed under some circum¬
stances. For morality not only requires the fulfillment of obligations,
but the exemplification of at least some moral character traits and
occasional concessions to the principle of maximizing goods. Morality
encourages and permits much else, but it requires that much — at least
in the sense that not to do it makes one liable for reprobation.16 And
though others may not ‘deserve’ the benefits morality requires one to
confer on them, it is none the less wrong to withhold them. When
excluding others from the fruits of one’s labor amounts to withholding
such benefits from others, then such withholding cannot be justified
— at least not by the labor argument alone.
The supplemental value requirement. Second, the labor must produce
something which would not have existed except for it. This restriction
is simply designed to call attention to the difference between the land
one labors on and what is produced. Under some circumstances (such
as the draining of a swamp, the filling of an estuary, etc.), one may
fairly claim that one’s labor has produced usable land itself. But under
most circumstances, it is not the land itself that labor produces, but
something from the land. Similarly for the water in a well, stream,
or lake. The entitlement to labor’s products cannot extend (except by
convention) to the means of production — at least to the extent that
the means of production are not themselves the products of labor.
The no-loss requirement. Third, the property rights to which one
acceeds by virtue of labor must not constitute a loss to others. Many
disputes about the legitimacy of property rights can be understood as
veiled disagreements about the interpretation of this requirement. If
it is taken to mean that no one must be put at a relative disadvantage
by another’s accession to property rights, then it is doubtful whether
one could legitimately claim ownership of any significant product
of one’s labors. Even a toothbrush, in so far as it is an advantage, puts
its possessor in a position of relative superiority over those who do not
possess one.
But surely this stretches the concept of a ‘loss’ too far. The point of
this restriction is to exclude a laborer’s taking away others’ existing
goods. Equality of bad teeth is not an existing good, except in competi¬
tive situations where good teeth are a competitive advantage. So I have
not ‘taken away’ a good from others by my possession of a toothbrush.
Land and the means of production, however, are a different matter.
No doubt unused land represents a benefit to people only in so far as it
is an opportunity of one sort or another. None the less, the elimination
42
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
Entitlement reconsidered
It will surely be urged in reply, however, that there is something very
wrong with this explication of the root idea of the labor theory. Proud¬
hon’s attack boils down to ‘I didn’t ask you to work, so I should not
43
Property Rights
have to pay you in the form of property rights for the work you did.’
Mill’s reply is, ‘As long as it is no loss to you — no “payment” — why
should you care?’ All this is very well as rhetoric, it will be said, but
when the consequences of Mill’s reply themselves undermine the
theory, something is wrong. For after all, why shouldn't the industrious
gain competitive advantages over the non-industrious? Locke himself
remarks that ‘[God] gave [the earth] to the use of the industrious and
rational. . .’17 He clearly had it in mind that there could be no justice
in a system which did not distinguish, in the distribution of goods,
between the producers of those goods and the non-producers. But why
is this so? It cannot be for the reason that Mill gives (that the inequality
constitutes no loss to the unindustrious), for whenever they are thereby
put at a competitive disadvantage, they do suffer a loss. And to say that
the producers deserve the property because they earned it with their
labor is just to repeat, with emphasis, the original premise — the root
idea of the labor theory one is trying to explicate.
Further, when the reply here is taken out of the language of the
work ethic and one substitutes for ‘industrious’ the terms (equally
accurate as things actually happen) ‘aggressive,’ ‘intelligent,’ and
‘strong,’ and substitutes for ‘unindustrious’ the terms ‘passive,’ unintel¬
ligent,’ and ‘weak,’ the reply loses some appeal. Why should the aggres¬
sive inherit the earth, after all? They have, but has it been a good thing?
Why should the people with the natural advantage of intelligence
(whether acquired by inheritance or by environment) inherit the earth?
Have they earned the means which permit their acquisition? And so on.
(It should be noted that the social Darwinist rationale for the right
of the strong to the advantages conferred by property reduces to an
absurdity. As Rashdall points out, property rights — especially when
they protect possession and inheritance — quite clearly protect the
weak against the strong.18)
The final blow to the argument is this: it may be that in some situ¬
ations a laborer’s accession to liberty rights is no loss to others, but the
accession to a claim right, or a power, or an immunity, is usually a
different matter. The creation of the corresponding duties, liabilities,
and disabilities in others usually constitutes a loss of liberty for them.
Rights justified by this argument cannot, then, include claim rights,
powers, or immunities if and in so far as the existence of those sorts of
rights actually constitutes a loss to others. And all of the varieties of
ownership distinguished at the outset involve not only liberties but
claim rights or powers or immunities as well.
Yet even when all this is said, it must be admitted that a person’s
commitment to the root idea of the labor theory may not have been
44
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
45
Property Rights
dispute and which can otherwise perform the role of an axiom (for
example, axioms must be self-consistent, be stated clearly and un¬
ambiguously, and be suitably powerful or ‘at the bottom’ of many
justificatory issues).
I think it is clear that the root idea of the labor theory cannot
qualify as fundamental in either of the first two senses: there is no
logical circularity involved in asking for a moral justification of it, and
it is certainly not presupposed by the conceptualization of the problems
raised by the justification of property rights (witness ancient discussions
of property acquisition). So we are left with the possibility that it may
be fundamental in the third sense — that is, that it is the best (or a
member of the best set of) justificatory ‘starting point(s).’
This contention has some initial plausibility. The general, unquestion¬
ing approval of the idea is a modern (Western?) phenomenon, but one
which is very firmly established. So the condition that the starting point
not actually be in dispute seems satisfied. Further, the idea that
laborers are entitled to the products of their labor seems (initially)
to satisfy some of the other requirements of an axiom: generality; self-
consistency; the ability to generate determinate conclusions when
applied to cases. But in each case this initial plausibility crumbles upon
inspection.
For example, if there is general agreement that laborers should get
property rights in the fruits of their labor, there is also general agreement
that this should not be at the expense of others. Proudhon’s challenge,
‘I did not ask you to work so why should I have to pay you for what
you did?’ is as generally agreed to as the root idea of the labor theory.
That is surely part of the reason Locke and Mill were so careful to
include the ‘no loss’ requirement in their arguments. So any attempt to
treat the root idea as a plausible first principle on the basis of people's
actual commitment to it would, if it were to be consistent, have to
include a qualification equivalent to the ‘no loss’ requirement. Thus
nothing would have been gained by treating the root idea as a first
principle (since with the no loss requirement, its justification goes
through anyway).
Further, there is an insuperable problem with the generality of the
idea. Laborers are supposed to be entitled to property in the very things
they produce (and where these are inseparable from the raw materials
worked on, property in the things worked on). But it has already been
shown that this supposition must be revised in the case of the children
parents produce. And it is equally clear that it will not do for the
whole class of employees and the equally large class of people who
perform services for others. It is perhaps true that most employees
46
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
47
Property Rights
48
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
49
Property Rights
50
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
52
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
then if the laborer deserves a benefit for his or her efforts, and if
property rights in the thing produced do not exceed the proportionality
requirement, then they are obviously the only (or part of the only)
fitting benefit.
Note that this does not mean that people can come to deserve
property rights by simply having them as part of their goals when they
undertake to do something. What they do must deserve a benefit, and a
benefit of a size comparable to the value of the property rights they
want (whether full, liberal ownership or some more restricted variety).
Once this is understood, the labor-desert argument looks quite sound.
Further, the use of the goal of labor as the mark against which to
measure the fittingness of benefits allows for an account of why and
when money rewards can be susbstituted for rights to the very thing
produced. For example, if my object in gardening is to have the satis¬
faction of eating things I have grown, then substitutes (like money to buy
other produce) won’t do. On the other hand, if all I want is vegetables
of a certain quality, at certain times, at a certain convenience, then it
may well be a matter of indifference whether my entitlement is to
property in the very things I have produced or to money to buy equiva¬
lent products.
Similarly for the issue of when, and why, the recognition, admira¬
tion, and gratitude of one’s peers are more fitting than either money
or property in the thing produced. Some things, after all, are not done
for fortune. They may be done for fame, for example. One may want
to be admired — known for something. In that case, reward of money
and anonymity is a poor substitute for what is sought. (Think of
James Watson’s desire to be the first to understand DNA.29)
53
Property Rights
labor produces, and conversely, they deserve some penalty for the de¬
value their labor produces.
(2) The benefits and penalties deserved are those proportional to
the values and disvalues produced, and those fitting for the type of
labor done.
(3) When, in terms of the purposes of the labor, nothing but property
rights in the things produced can be considered a fitting benefit for the
labor, and when the benefit provided by such rights is proportional to
the value produced by the labor, the property rights are deserved;
when, in terms of the purposes of the labor, either property rights
in the things produced or something else can be considered a fitting and
proportional benefit, then either the property rights or one of the
acceptable alternatives is deserved;
when, in terms of the purposes of the labor, property rights in
the things produced cannot be considered a fitting reward, or when the
benefits of such rights is in excess of the values produced by the labor,
the rights are not deserved.
(4) Any diminution of value produced by labor must be assessed
against the laborer as a penalty deserved for the loss thus produced.
(Penalties must, of course, be proportional to the loss produced, and a
fitting remedy for that loss — fitting not in terms of the purposes of the
labor which produced it, but in terms of the purposes with regard to
which it can be considered a loss.)
It should be noted that (1) meets the standards for a fundamental
principle of the sorts explicated above (pp. 45ff), and the remaining
steps are deduced from the concepts of desert, fittingness, benefit, and
loss. I think this line of argument is sound, and is in fact what the labor
theory reduces to. I think, further, that it satisfies the stubborn desire
we have to make the labor theory work. But several things should be
noted about what it does and does not prove.
In the first place, this labor argument — by itself — gives no unequi¬
vocal grounds for the private ownership of the things produced unless
there is no substitute for it acceptable in terms of the goals of the labor.
This means that where the production of things is a means to an end
— security, power, status, the ability to guarantee the same for one’s
children, etc. — and where the state can provide those things as laborers’
deserts without granting ownership rights over the very things produced,
this version of the labor theory does not provide a justification for
private ownership of the things produced. It is thus in principle com¬
patible with socialist economic arrangements.
Second, the no-loss requirement — here understood as the double-
edged aspect of the desert principle — places a heavy tax and/or com-
54
The Labor Theory of Property Acquisition
55
Property Rights
56
5 Arguments from Utility
There are two major variants of utility arguments for property rights.
Both assert that property rights are necessary as a means to an end —
the end being human happiness. But in one variant — what I shall call
traditional utility arguments — happiness is defined very broadly, so
as to include the whole range of human satisfactions. The other variant
— what I shall call economic utility arguments — defines happiness
more narrowly; it concerns only those satisfactions which can be
sought by economic transactions and measured by ‘dollar votes.’ The
two variants are fully compatible; in fact, the economic arguments are
special cases of traditional appeals to utility. I shall give the two variants
separate exposition here, however, because there has been a tendency
in legal and economic writing to overlook or dismiss traditional
arguments, and to give economic arguments a logical primacy they do
not deserve.
meet the needs which make the institution necessary. (Similarly, mutatis
mutandis, for the definition of useful, useless, and detrimental institu¬
tions.)
(le) People need individually to acquire, possess, use, and consume
some things in order to achieve (the means to) a reasonable degree of
happiness.
(1 f) Security in possession and use is impossible (given human society
as we know it) unless enforced and unless modes of acquisition are
controlled. Such control and enforcement amounts to the administration
of a system pf property rights.
(lg) Insecurity in possession and use, and uncontrolled acquisition,
of the goods people need and want makes an individual’s achievement
of (the means to) a reasonable degree of happiness impossible (or very
unlikely).
(lh) Therefore, a system of property rights is necessary (or very
nearly so) if individuals are to achieve (the means to) even a reasonable
degree of happiness.
That, in outline, is the general justification for property rights from
‘utility.’ There are also utility arguments at the levels of specific and
particular justification. The specific form is this: Assuming the general
form of the argument, one takes premises (a) through (d) and adds:
(2e) Concerning the needed system of property rights, people
need, or persistently want, the following sorts of property rights. . . .
(2f) Denying people what they need or what they persistently want,
without a showing that the denial is necessary for some countervailing
good, is unjustifiable (and usually productive of social disorder and
further governmental repression as well).
(2g) Therefore, when there is no countervailing good to consider,
people should be permitted the sorts of property rights they need and
persistently want.
The particular form is more direct. It simply asserts that:
(3a) It would be best on balance for society as a whole, if X had
property right of sort A in thing T.
(3b) If there are no countervailing reasons to the contrary, one
should do what is best, on balance, for society as a whole.
(3c) Therefore, if there are no countervailing reasons to the con¬
trary, X should have a property right of sort A in thing T.
These arguments from utility are among the oldest, and certainly
most frequently given, justifications of private ownership. They have
the advantages of directness and (apparent) simplicity: in schematic
form, they are deductively valid; and they seem more ‘realistic’ than
talk about natural acquisition in some fictional state of nature.
58
Arguments from Utility
59
Property Rights
60
Arguments from Utility
much bleaker picture of human nature, and have found the need for
some social institutions — notably those directed toward the control
of violence — even more compelling than Hume did. This line of
theorists would have to include (though it surely did not begin with)
Augustine, and go through many Christian theologians, as well as Machia-
velli, Hobbes, and most modern psychologists and sociologists. Even
those who believe that perfection in society means the absence of social
institutions as defined here (e.g. perhaps Marx, probably classical
anarchists) do not claim that such an arrangement is possible given
conditions as they have ever actually been. This is enough to make the
point needed for the argument from utility. Given the nature of human
interactions as they actually occur, some social institutions are neces¬
sary for the achievement of a reasonable degree of happiness.
61
Property Rights
62
Arguments from Utility
63
Property Rights
64
Arguments from Utility
65
Property Rights
66
Arguments from Utility
But beyond that, particular justifications can cut through general and
specific ones when it can be shown that, even though people generally
ought not to have a certain sort of right, in a given case, people would
be better off (or no worse off) if a particular person had such a right.
Conversely, it can in principle happen that even though people in
general ought to have a certain sort of right, in a given case people
would be better off (worse off) if a particular person did not (did) have
such a right.
Here the familiar problems of the relation of utility to justice arise.
And they cannot be resolved by the (formal) device of smuggling the
exceptions for particular cases into the general or specific principles.
That move merely forces a restatement of the question: granted that
these exceptions have utility, is it justifiable, all things considered, to
make them? If, for example, making an exception improves the total
(or the average) human welfare at the expense of enslaving a few, can
one recommend such a course, all things considered? Are there not
arguments for equal liberty which conflict with such a recommendation?
If so, how is the conflict to be resolved?
The temptation to reach for the tools of welfare economics is strong
here, but as I shall argue below, those tools are of less use than might
have been hoped. The simplest — and I think best — start toward a
solution is this: when faced with conflicting arguments, treat each as if
it were of equal weight unless there is good reason to do otherwise.
Then total the arguments. Two arguments (of equal weight) for human
liberty outweigh one argument against it — and vice versa. Where there
is a deadlock it means that none of the options is rationally preferred.
Two serious problems confront the use of this justificatory scheme:
one is the question of assessing the reasons for weighting one argument
more heavily than another (and of deciding how much heavier it is);
the other is the question of the individuation of arguments (what
counts as one argument?). I have addressed such questions elsewhere.11
67
Property Rights
(utility) for a person when that person values it. (Whether things have
‘intrinsic’ worth, and whether some ‘valuings’ are better than others are
questions which are left unaddressed.) How much value a thing has for
a given person is said to be ‘measured’ by the maximum that person
would be willing to pay to get it (in terms of some standard medium of
exchange like dollars), or alternatively, the minimum the person would
be willing to take to give it up.12 Though this limits the range of
values (utilities, satisfactions) considered to those which can in principle
be exchanged and have a price, the assumption is that this will not be a
serious difficulty for a discussion of property rights.
GENERAL JUSTIFICATION
Given this concept of value or utility, economists then offer two
straightforward arguments for the general justifiability of a system of
property rights. The first begins by noting the wide variety of costs or
disutilities (in time, frustration of purpose, lost opportunities, etc.)
which can befall one who depends on non-ownership use or enjoyment
of a scarce good. Others can preempt one’s uses, interfere with one’s
enjoyment, cause one to over-accumulate to offset anticipated losses,
and so on. When the total cost of these ‘external disutilities’ — that is,
the sum of the costs of the disutilities created for each by the actions
of others — becomes greater than the costs involved in creating and
maintaining a system of ownership rights which minimizes such exter¬
nalities, then that system of property rights is justified by considerations
of (economic) utility.13 This argument is clearly sound, so long as the
dominant guiding principle is one of minimizing costs.
The second general argument concerns allocative transactions — that
is, the ways in which people deal with the resources used for the pro¬
duction of goods. Clearly, in a situation without enforced ownership
rights, one would expect such transactions to be an uneasy amalgam of
conduct in accordance with custom and social pressure, liberally laced
with deceit, threats, and open force or violence. There is certainly no
reason to believe that such transactions would maximize the total of
individual satisfactions — either with respect to allocations or with
respect to the eventual distribution of goods produced. And so, given
the assumption that it is justifiable to maximize the total of satisfactions
by tinkering with allocations, one step in that direction will be to
stabilize allocative transactions with ownership rights. Richard Posner is
thus able to argue briefly and persuasively for a system of property
rights for all significantly scarce productive resources — a system which
at least gives owners the right to exclude others as well as to transfer
their rights.14
68
Arguments from Utility
SPECIFIC JUSTIFICATION
Economic arguments for property rights take a somewhat different tack
at the levels of specific and particular justification. Here they turn on
technical concepts of efficiency, optimality, superiority, allocation, and
distribution.
Economists distinguish the allocation of resources used for the pro¬
duction of goods (land, labor, etc.) from the distribution of goods
produced. This distinction relates as much to a difference in human
69
Property Rights
70
Arguments from Utility
Second, when these materials have been used at the level of specific
justification, they have been applied to a wide range of problems raised
by property rights: liability rules governing the use of property,18
zoning regulations,19 and the issue of just compensation20 are examples.
As even a casual look at some of the legal materials will show,21 there
can be no hope here of dealing with these matters in adequate detail.
But the fact that the same patterns of analysis are used in all these
cases makes it possible to make some useful general observations about
economic arguments for specific justification.
And third, for all their hard-headed appearance, it can easily be
shown that when these materials are used to construct social policies
with regard to property rights, most of the justificatory weight must be
borne by non-economic or ‘meta’-economic principles of a frankly
normative sort — principles of justice, for example. This is not to deni¬
grate the importance of economic analysis of these questions; it is
merely to say that its results alone cannot settle the questions of specific
justification.
To see this, consider what the fundamental form would be of an
argument constructed from these economic materials alone:
(1) Property rights should be defined so as best to approximate, in
operation, the idealized free market model of efficiency in allocation
and justice in distribution.
(2) A perfectly free real market — i.e. one in which government
only enforces whatever voluntary agreements people make — would
clearly not have the character of the ideal free market. (Participants are
not always perfect competitors and rational self-maximizers, and there
are often significant transaction costs.)
(3) But it is an empirical question, in each case of a proposed
intervention in the (real) free market, whether or not that intervention
will move things closer to economic efficiency or justice as defined in
the ideal free market model.
(4) So each proposal to limit property rights with liability rules,
restrictions on use, transferability, transmissibility, possession, income
or the rest of the elements of full ownership must be evaluated for its
ability to move things toward efficient allocation and just distribution.
(5) When a proposed limitation of property rights would be no
improvement on the real market (in terms of approximating the results
of the ideal market), it cannot be justified; when a proposed change
would be worse than the real market (in terms of approximating the
results of the ideal market) it is ‘wrong’ — i.e. disjustified.
(6) Property rights of sort X best approximate the efficiency and
justice of the ideal market in the real world and are therefore justified.
71
Property Rights
It is clear where problems with this form of argument arise. For one
thing, efficiency and justice as here defined — while interesting and
seemingly operationalizable concepts — are certainly contestable when
put forward as social goals. However odd this may seem to some (what
can be wrong with a situation in which each makes only those volun¬
tary agreements about allocation and distribution that he is willing to
make?), it is none the less true. As a consideration of the examples used
in the economic literature shows, what is envisaged is a situation in
which each is free to act bounded only by existing, specific, contractual
agreements and the ability to buy what he wants. There is no reference
to principles of altruism, communitarian concerns, ‘neighborliness,’ or
the like. It is not that such things are disapproved of, of course; it is
just that, except as prudent steps toward maximizing an individual’s
own satisfactions, they do not enter into the designs for the ideal
property rights structure. What this means is that this purely economic
argument views with equanimity any obnoxious use an owner might
make of a piece of property as long as it does not violate a contract and
as long as those harmed by it are (rationally) unwilling to pay the
offender enough to make it worth his or her while to desist.22 While
such robust individualism is appealing to some, it is by no means
appealing to all. Most people, I suspect, think that motives count, and
that in so far as possible the system of property rights should be designed
to discourage malicious or casual disregard of other people’s welfare
even when it is in one’s economic interest to do so. Similarly for com¬
munitarian concerns: without some legal insulation from whatever
external disutilities others can create, individuals who do not keep
enough ‘dollar votes’ to buy off those others will be at a disadvantage.
They will thus be forced to be only rational self-maximizers. Generosity
to others, at least in so far as it in any way costs one dollar votes, will
have negative survival value. To reply by saying that if people really
believe these virtues of generosity and kind motives are important,
then they will in effect have cash value and work to one’s advantage,
is to miss the point. Unless one can count on reciprocity for one’s
good neighborliness — not just from ‘most people’ but from all the
ones whose choices can actually create disutilities for one — then self-
protective dollar votes will have to be kept. And generosity will be
expensive indeed.
In addition to this difficulty, there is a serious problem with the
notion of measuring efficiency and justice by dollar votes. How are
such votes to be distributed in the ideal model? Even if one envisages an
absolutely equal initial distribution, it is clear that the idealized free
market model is not designed to preserve equality. It would be utterly
72
Arguments from Utility
73
Property Rights
i
PARTICULAR JUSTIFICATION
This is perhaps even more obvious when one imagines the application
of economic efficiency arguments to the adjudication of particular con¬
flicts over who should have what rights. Here our concern for bringing
in existing rights to block changes which are unwanted by those who
lose from them is very strong — even when adequate compensation is
offered. Further, there are good grounds for the suspicion that com¬
pensation will in fact be offered selectively — on behalf of a quite dif¬
ferent notion of economic efficiency: that of maximizing the grand
total of marketable satisfactions per se.24 Economic utility arguments
at this level are not used to establish rights; they are used to override
them.
74
6 The Argument from
Political Liberty
The argument
One may argue in the following way for property rights as a consequence
of liberty.
(1) It is a fact that human beings will try to acquire things, control
them, exclude others from their use, modify them, and use them as
wealth.
(2) The effective prohibition of such activities — i.e. the elimination
of private property altogether — would require a comprehensive and
continuous abridgment of people’s liberty which (even if it were
possible to carry out) is at best unjustifiable and at worst flatly prohi¬
bited by the existence of political liberties to which people are entitled,
morally.
(3) The regulation of acquisitive activities, by what amounts to a
system of property rights, is likewise required to preserve liberties to
which people are entitled.
(4) Therefore, property rights are justifiable.
This is, of course, only a general justification, for it does not specify
what sorts of things people are entitled to own, and what sorts of
property rights they are entitled to have in those things. And it makes
property a derivative, rather than a fundamental, right; it assumes the
prior justification of an extensive system of political liberty.
* Throughout this chapter, the term ‘political’ is used as a modifier for ‘liberty’
in the same way it is used in the phrase ‘political science.’ I do not, for example,
mean to distinguish political from religious liberties or political from civil liberties.
All liberties guaranteed by the state are, in this usage, political liberties.
75
Property Rights
76
The Argument from Political Liberty
77
Property Rights
78
The A rgument from Political Liberty
79
Property Rights
80
7 Considerations of
Moral Character
81
Property Rights
(2) It is wasteful for things not to be well used — that is, for them
not to be employed to the greatest advantage.
(3) Waste is morally objectionable in the case of scarce goods.
(4) Some people are better able to use certain goods to the greatest
advantage than others.
(5) Thus, if goods can justifiably be owned by individuals at all,
those goods (at least if they are scarce) ought to be owned by the
people who can and will use them to greatest advantage.
This argument may include need as one of several principles for
finding out who can use a thing to greatest advantage, but it is not
based on need in the way the utility argument is. Here need is linked to
the notion of property-worthiness by way of the ‘greatest use’ and
‘prohibition of waste’ principles. The argument is clearly elitist in some
applications, but sweeping and radical in nearly all its applications. It
secures the rights of the initiated to the esoteric — whether in art or in
agriculture — but also secures a distribution according to greatest
benefit among the initiated. Since some ‘initiations’ are nearly universal
(e.g. eating), the argument would appear to support a rather egalitarian
distribution of property in the goods necessary to life. (I say ‘rather’
egalitarian because it does not support property rights for those who
are so helpless as to be unable to use even the necessities to their
advantage.)
The weaknesses in the argument lie in the second and third premises.
If the prohibition of waste is taken to be a requirement of all ownership,
so that to show that something is not being used to greatest advantage
simply eliminates or overrides any other justifications to title, then a
very tenuous claim has been made. I know of no way to justify it. If,
however, the claim is merely that waste is an objection which can
sometimes invalidate other justifications to title, then the tenor of the
argument is significantly changed. The conclusion will hold only in so
far as no competing justifications for property rights produce a differ¬
ent conclusion. The argument is at most one of a larger set of considera¬
tions justifying property rights.
There is another difficulty with premise (2), however, which
weakens the argument still further. This is the ambiguity of the phrases
‘well used’ and ‘greatest advantage.’ Are these phrases to be taken to
refer to the greatest social (or general) advantage? Or merely the
greatest advantage to the individual who owns the thing? The former
requirement is certainly plausible where the thing owned is something
which others need to have well used, and which is unavailable to them
otherwise. But this interpretation turns the argument into a version of
the argument from utility, and one which leads in the direction of
82
Considerations of Moral Character
The virtuous
We sometimes think that good people deserve to get and keep good
things — merely from the fact that they (the people) are good. More
83
Property Rights
often, we object when the wicked have good things (no matter how
honestly acquired). There is even a strand (not a mjaor one, to be sure)
in Christian theology to the effect that property properly belongs to
the righteous.1 It seems initially unlikely that anything very significant
for the theory of property rights can be built on these foundations, but
they yield some surprises.
Consider: even if it is true that what is earned is deserved, it does not
follow that what is unearned is undeserved. Or rather, perhaps one
should say that good character ‘earns’ things as much as labor does.
Specifically, good fortune (unearned by labor) is none the less said to
be deserved when it falls to the virtuous, and undeserved when it falls
to the wicked. We all share Job’s sense of injustice when the wicked
prosper and the good are struck down by calamity after calamity. It is
not that the wicked do not deserve the fruits of their (honorable) labor.
And it is not that the virtuous deserve something for nothing. It is
rather the recognition that:
(1) Some goods are the product (partly or wholly) of events which
have nothing to do with one’s intelligence, labor, or moral character.
They come by chance, or from the caprice of other agents.
(2) Such goods (hereafter: good fortune) play a significant role in
determining people’s access to (the means to) well-being, happiness —
and in competitive situations, to competitive advantage. Similarly, bad
fortune plays a significant role in determining the opposite.
(3) Good fortune is in no way deserved by the wicked, but it is in
one way deserved by the virtuous (whatever one’s definition of virtue is).
The virtuous deserve good fortune in the same way they deserve respect,
admiration, and gratitude; it is appropriate; it is fitting; it is an event
logically and psychologically compatible with good conduct and
character.
(4) Thus, to the extent that good fortune can be controlled (e.g. by
distributive measures after the fact), it should go only to the virtuous.
There are two problems with this argument, I think. The first is the
interpretation of ‘deserve’ in premise (3); and the second is the assump¬
tion that goods should go only to those who deserve them. (The first
two premises seem to me to be clearly true.)
‘Deserve’ is apparently used in premise (3) to include only ‘what one
has earned with labor’ and ‘what is logically and psychologically
compatible with one’s conduct and character.’ Problems with the
former sense have been discussed in the chapter on the labor theory.
But granting this as a legitimate usage of ‘deserve,’what about the other
usage — the one on which the whole argument hinges? Does it really
clarify matters to say that one deserves something in the sense that
84
Considerations of Moral Character
85
Property Rights
86
Considerations of Moral Character
87
8 Anti - Property
Arguments
Social disutility
The utility argument for property rights asserts that people need to
acquire, possess, use, and consume things — and that their need to do so
can only be met through instituting a system of private ownership.
Anti-property theorists do not accept those contentions, as I have
already mentioned. But some of them also advance an argument, itself
based on utility, which is designed to show that the institution of
property rights has an overall social disutility — that is, that on balance
it produces a net loss of good — no matter whether people need such
rights or not. The outlines of this argument to disutility, as I shall call
it, are as follows.
88
Anti-Property Arguments
THE ARGUMENT
(1) Any system of property rights which permits private ownership
(in the full, liberal sense) of land or the means of production which are
scarce, or are non-renewable, or are capable of monopolization,
inevitably produces inequality in wealth of a sort which increases over
generations, hardens the social order into a class structure, and (a) yields
an unjustifiable amount of poverty, and (b) yields an unjustifiable
amount of social instability.
(2) It is not necessary to permit private ownership of the things
mentioned above. That is, (a) private ownership of those things is not
necessary for survival, a reasonable degree of happiness, or the full
development of personality; and (b) prohibiting private ownership of
those things is an enforceable policy.
(3) Whatever needs are satisfied by private ownership (in the full,
liberal sense) of land or the means of production which are scarce, or
are non-renewable, or are capable of monopolization are minor
compared to the needs for social stability and the elimination of
poverty.
(4) Since the social stability people need is impossible given a system
which permits private ownership of those things (from (1) above), and
since the need for such stability outweighs any needs people have for
private ownership of those things (from (3) above), and granting that
the prohibition of such ownership is possible (from (2) above), it
follows that private ownership of those things ought not to be per¬
mitted.1
89
Property Rights
90
Anti-Property Arguments
91
Property Rights
92
Anti-Property Arguments
ownership (of the specified things) is not necessary for the satisfaction
of the needs mentioned in the utility argument for property rights.
That is, that it is not necessary for physical survival, a reasonable degree
of happiness, or the full development of personality. So far the premise
is simply a denial of the corresponding one in the utility argument.
Premise (2) goes further, however, and asserts that the prohibition of
(full) private ownership in land or the means of production which are
scarce, are non-renewable or are capable of monopolization is an
enforceable policy. This is done to fend off the objection that, like the
Eighteenth Amendment, such prohibition would be unenforceable and
therefore — whether one likes it or not — permitting private ownership
in the things specified is necessary. This is a familiar enough notion not
to need further elucidation here.
93
Property Rights
Self-defeatingness
It has often been remarked (and not by anti-property theorists alone)
that any system of private ownership which attempts to guarantee to
laborers the produce of their labor can become self-defeating when
applied to land and means of production which are scarce, or are
capable of monopolization. The following passage from an essay by
Hastings Rashdall illustrates the point nicely.
94
Anti-Property Arguments
95
Property Rights
Virtue
Plato is perhaps the first philosopher to have argued that private owner¬
ship has vicious effects on character. At a minimum, he thought that
property interfered with the development of the traits necessary for the
soldiers and rulers of the ideal state.5 Some Christian theologians have
taken passages from the Gospels and the book of Acts to mean that
private ownership — or at least anything above that necessary for an
ascetic existence — tends to block the achievement of whatever
righteousness people can attain.6 (Others simply argue that communal
ownership is a New Testament command, whether private property has
bad consequences for character or not. I do not refer to such positions
here.)
This argument runs into exactly the sort of difficulty which defeats
the corresponding argument for private ownership, the argument that
property produces good moral character. The difficulty is that although
one can easily imagine (even identify among one’s acquaintances)
private ownership as the cause of a certain character trait, one can just
as easily imagine and find cases in which it is not. If acquisitions some¬
times intensify acquisitiveness to the point of greed, they also can lead
to generosity. If ownership can produce obsessive possessiveness, it can
also produce a release from the constant worry some feel when
property held in common is entrusted to them. I can see no possibility
for a general argument here to the effect that property always produces
more vicious than virtuous character traits. So the argument from virtue
seems, like the other anti-property arguments, to be a schema for the
critique of particular systems once they are spelled out, and not an
injunction to systems of private ownership per se.
There is one area in which we typically think the effects of owner¬
ship must always be watched, however. That is the area in which
governmental officials have an economic stake in the outcome of a
case under their jurisdiction. To the extent that such conflicts of
interest make impartial adjudication impossible, it may be necessary to
hedge any system of private ownership with conflict of interest legisla¬
tion. Similarly, to the extent that conflicts of interest destroy guarantees
to consumers necessary for public safety, they may have to be further
regulated. But these are merely probable outcomes for many sorts of
systems in many sorts of circumstances. There is no more necessity here
— and thus no more possibility of general anti-property argument —
than in the other cases.
96
Anti-Property Arguments
all — is one which has its source in a theme alluded to in both the social
disutility and self-defeatingness arguments: namely that systems of
private property rights can lock members of succeeding generations into
positions of undeserved advantage and disadvantage. Significant socio¬
economic inequality defines significant differences in material (as
opposed to formal) liberty — e.g. the liberty to travel, to get an educa¬
tion, to find rewarding employment. And it is correlated with
differences in things as basic as health and life-expectancy.8 Even if the
original acquisitions were just, and even if the subsequent transfers were
procedurally just, it cannot be just — so this argument goes — to permit
the perpetuation of significant socio-economic inequality. The fact that
some people did, and others did not, acquire property and pass it on to
their heirs, is surely not sufficient justification for locking those heirs
into positions of advantage or disadvantage.
Put more formally, the argument is this:
(1) Extensive systems of private property rights (even where rights
of transmissibility are severely limited) tend to produce and perpetuate
significant socio-economic inequality.
(2) Significant socio-economic inequality — quite apart from its
propensity to create social instability — means that some members of
society will be disadvantaged not only relative to others (e.g. with
respect to material liberty), but absolutely (e.g. with respect to life-
expectancy).
(3) No matter how just the original acquisitions were, and no matter
how just (procedurally) the subsequent transfers were, those who
(through no acts of their own) fall heir to the advantages or disadvan¬
tages mentioned in (2) cannot be said to deserve them.
(4) While undeserved advantages are unobjectionable if they do
no harm to either the recipients or others, undeserved J/sadvantages
ought to be prevented (or rectified) whenever possible.
(5) Some (significant) undeserved disadvantages are produced and
perpetuated by the institution of property rights itself — regardless of
limitations placed on transmissibility.
(6) Therefore, any institution of private property rights which is
more extensive than the minimum required for social order is unjustifi¬
able.
Matters of fact. I shall assume here that this argument has its facts
straight. That is, I shall take it to be true that significant socio-economic
inequality seriously disadvantages some people, and that an extensive
system of private property rights — even if it drastically limits inheri¬
tance — produces and perpetuates some such disadvantages (e.g. the
advantages of education accessible only to the children of high achievers
97
Property Rights
98
9 The Justification of
Property Rights
99
Property Rights
100
The Justification of Property Rights
101
Property Rights
102
The Justification of Property Rights
103
Property Rights
104
The Justification of Property Rights
105
Property Rights
utility in some cases and utility more heavily than liberty in others?
Here it helps to notice that there are three fundamental sets of moral
concerns — ones related to the notion of value, ones related to the
notion of duty or obligation, and ones related to the notion of moral
character. Utility arguments are of the first sort — axiological concerns.
Liberty arguments, when they are seen as constraints on social goods,
are the second sort — deontological concerns. And arguments for the
relative weight of liberty against utility can come from the third sort —
characterological concerns. Whether the question is that of the nature
of the virtuous person or that of the nature of the virtuous (i.e. ideal)
society, to the extent that rational answers can be given to those
questions such answers can help decide whether liberty or utility is to
dominate a particular case. Which is the preferable social order: one
which allows liberty X to remain intact despite its disutility? Or one
which overrides the liberty in the interests of utility? Put so generally,
such questions do not seem very promising as routes to the needed
answers. But in specific sorts of situations, they may be answerable in a
way which leaves no doubt about the relative weights to be given to
utility and liberty. (Consider the standard example of scapegoating the
innocent to secure social order. Here there are arguments to the effect
that — with the possible exception of extreme and rare cases — social
order which depends on such practices is not a worthy goal.)5
Conflicts between utility and the desert form of the argument from
labor may be similarly analyzed (as may conflicts between liberty and
labor arguments). The arguments are separate; the best course is to treat
them as of presumptively equal weight; and the resolution of ties may
be approached by bringing in additional considerations from moral
character in the case of utility versus labor conflicts, and from axiology
and moral character in the case of liberty versus labor conflicts. This
procedure does not produce a tidy, hierarchically organized set of
principles. But I see no reason to suppose, a priori, that moral principles
are organizable in that way. The persistence of deep disagreements
among reasonable, sophisticated theorists is evidence to the contrary.
If the picture of the general justificatory framework for property rights
is thus somewhat fuzzy, we may be at least partly consoled by a remark
adapted from Wittgenstein: that a clear picture of a fuzzy thing is a
fuzzy picture.
106
The Justification of Property Rights
judge, the priority of liberty over utility may be decided by the fact
that one has been given constitutional or statutory protection while the
other has not. Or by some standard (legal) priority rule for ambiguous
cases. But the moral question cannot be settled on such narrow
grounds. The procedure above, messy as it is, seems the best way to
settle it.
107
Property Rights
DUTIES TO OTHERS
If it can be established that we have positive duties of care toward
others — that is, if beyond our negative duties not to do harm there
are positive duties to do good — then the labor theory arguments are
concomitantly restricted in their applicability. Each of the two sound
labor arguments is limited to cases in which the labor at issue is other
than what is morally required. So communitarians have an important
opening wedge here against the ‘as long as it does no harm’ argument. If
I have a prior moral duty to contribute positively to the welfare of my
fellows, then until that duty is fulfilled (or its fulfillment is guaranteed
in some way), I cannot work for myself, so to speak. That is, neither
version of the labor theory will in that case provide a sound basis for
claiming property rights.
But there are two interesting features of this limitation. First,
the moral duty to contribute (positively) to the welfare of others must
have priority over any moral requirements to work for one’s own good.
108
The Justification of Property Rights
That is, it is only ‘prior’ moral duties which are at issue here now. It is
reasonable to suppose that no positive duties to others could have
priority over a requirement (if there is one) to do the (morally permis¬
sible) work necessary for one’s own survival. And certainly many
people would hold that one’s positive duties to others cannot have
priority over even one’s liberty right to survive. That is, they would
hold that there is no moral duty of (literal) self-sacrifice. But this is
controversial, as is the further issue of whether ‘figurative’ self-sacrifice
— in the form of inconvenience, expenditure of effort, etc. — is ever a
moral duty in the absence of undertaking some special role (e.g. parent,
physician) or making some special agreement. What is interesting is just
that this important moral question is tied so directly to two important
lines of argument for property rights.
The second interesting feature of this limitation on labor arguments
is that some of my (positive) duties of care may be only toward a few
(my family, say). Thus it may be that while the labor I perform to
fulfill duties to my family does not justify the acquisition of property
rights against my family, it may justify the acquisition of property
rights for my family (me included) against everyone else. Thus one has
a basis for holding that a child’s entitlement to food, clothing, shelter,
and the like is not at all weakened by the fact that the parents
produced these things by their own labor.
EXHAUSTIBILITY
It is unlikely that any sort of property right could be justified whose
implementation entails (or makes highly probable) the exhaustion of a
significant resource by a subset of the total population. Such exhaus¬
tion would very likely constitute a loss to those left out, or be subject
to prohibitive penalties for the losses caused, or amount to an inter¬
ference with their liberty, or produce a net disutility, or perhaps all
four. Either of the last two of these circumstances would be sufficient
to prohibit it, in the absence of a conflicting requirement. And the
exhaustion of a significant resource certainly would not be required by
any of the lines of general justification (at least, I can think of no
candidate for such a requirement).
Exhaustibility therefore will be a very large consideration in specific
justifications. Goods such as space (in land, sea, or air) and matter can
be exhausted simply by appropriation — that is, given the requisite
system of property rights, a subset of the population can come to own
all that is available.6 Goods such as clean air and global water resources
are exhaustible primarily by misuse rather than simple appropriation,
but this is no less important for the theory of property rights. Uses
109
Property Rights
which pollute the air or sea, for example, are likely to be prohibited by
the general justifications of property, thus defining specific limitations
on the use and management rights of owners. Goods such as fertile
land, fresh water, fossil fuels, and wilderness areas are exhaustible either
by appropriation or by misuse, and are also likely to be hedged with
restrictions to prevent both.7
Technology and population size are important issues here. Things
which were exhaustible only in principle several centuries ago are now
in imminent danger of being exhausted. Specific justifications must
change with such circumstances if nothing else (e.g. population policy)
does; the justifiability of full, liberal ownership of land under the
social conditions which existed in seventeenth-century North America
does not guarantee that such property rights can be justified now. If
they cannot, then the ownership rights in land must be redefined. And
the question of injustice to current owners who possess the sort of title
which is now unjustifiable, is not as serious as it might seem. In most
cases, one probably will only need to change the rights of bequest and
transfer so that only justifiable sorts of title may be passed on. This
would leave the current owner’s use, possessory, management, income,
and security rights unchanged. And in situations so desperate that these
rights must be redefined, compensation may be paid in lieu of honoring
the right.
(It may be worth noting in passing that there are some goods which
are not exhaustible by human agency — at least not with foreseeable
technology. Sunlight and related radiation, magnetic energy, and
electrical energy are all in this category. Materials used to convert these
things to human use are exhaustible, of course. And sunlight can be
blocked out. But the things themselves are not now vulnerable to
exhaustion by appropriation or misuse.)
ACCUMULATION
Limitations on the sorts of property rights which can be justified arise
when goods are exhaustible, then. But they can also come from the fact
that accumulations which are prior to or much larger than the acquisi¬
tions of others can constitute a loss of competitive advantage for those
others, or a restriction of their material liberty, or a serious enough, and
widespread enough, frustration of human purposes to cause significant
social instability.8 This is the stuff of popular revolutions, and it is safe
to say that none of the general justifications would license a system of
property rights which had all these effects.
Clearly, however, conflicts between the prohibitions and restrictions
of utility on the one hand and liberty on the other are likely. This is
110
The Justification of Property Rights
HARMFUL USE
The (Millean) labor theory will not justify any use of property which
represents a loss to someone other than the owner. Liberty requires
that the use owners make of their property not interfere with the
liberty to which people are entitled. And utility prohibits uses which
have a net disutility. The ‘no harmful use’ element of full, liberal
ownership is therefore going to be a stringent one for goods which are
dangerous. Use rights allowable for guns and pesticides, for example,
a;e likely to be sharply limited. And in the case of hand guns, if
significant disutility and loss of liberty to others is entailed by extensive
private possession, it may be necessary to limit possession in order to
satisfy the no harmful use requirement.10
Many restrictions on use imposed by the general justifications are
identical with those alluded to under the headings of exhaustibility and
accumulation. But use restrictions go beyond those others to provide,
111
Property Rights
for example, a foundation for nuisance law and public safety law in
cases where no problems of exhaustion or accumulation exist. The ‘life
before property’ rule also finds a foundation here.11
112
The Justification of Property Rights
113
Property Rights
114
The Justification of Property Rights
115
Property Rights
116
The Justification of Property Rights
117
Property Rights
ownership is not only justifiable, but that the argument from liberty
requires that the greatest extent of private ownership desired by an
individual, and permitted by the general justifications, be allowed. If,
within the constraints imposed by a crowded planet whose population
is voraciously consuming its resources, this maximization principle
has a hollow sound, then perhaps we should make more than empty
gestures in the direction of changing population policies and wasteful
life-styles.
118
Notes
1 See Cicero, On Ends, book III, xx, 67; and Seneca, On Benefits,
book VII, xii, 3.
120
Notes
hardship to be born into the world and to find all nature’s gifts
previously engrossed, and no place left for the newcomer.’ For a
recent discussion which closely parallels Mill — especially with
regard to the ‘no loss’ requirement — see George I. Mavrodes,
‘Property,’Personalist, 53: 245-62 (1972).
16 What is required by morality is, broadly, what one is justifiably
liable for reprobation for not doing (though one may not usually
demand approbation for doing it). What is not required, but merely
permitted or encouraged, is what one can not be liable for repro¬
bation for not doing, and for doing which one ought to get appro¬
bation. The requirements of morality are generally expressed as
duties or obligations. This is harmless enough as long as one does
not overlook the character traits whose absence makes a person
subject to reproof (as opposed merely to the absence of positive
endorsements), and the times when a failure to choose the best
available alternative (as opposed to one which is merely adequate)
also makes the agent subject to sanction.
17 Locke, Second Treatise, paragraph 34.
18 Hastings Rashdall, ‘The Philosophical Theory of Property,’ in
J. V. Bartlett (ed.), Property: Its Duties and Rights, 2nd edition
(London, Macmillan, 1915), pp. 54-6.
19 Nozick makes interesting remarks on these issues in Anarchy,
State and Utopia (New York, Basic Books, 1974), at pp. 141 and
182. See also Ayn Rand, ‘Patents and Copyrights,’ in her
Capitalism: The Unknown Ideal (New York, New American
Library, 1966), pp. 125-9. For a review of current legal theory on
intellectual property, see the Note by Joseph E. Kovacs, ‘Beyond
the Realm of Copyright: Is There Legal Sanctuary for the Merchant
of Ideas?’ Brooklyn Law Review, 41: 284 (1974).
20 A word needs to be said here about thought-experiments in ethics.
State-of-nature imagery is sometimes compared to notions in the
physical sciences such as uniform motion. Uniform motion is an
imaginary phenomenon, but useful for the foundation of an
explanatory and predictive account of motion as it actually occurs
in experience. Similarly, it is said, though no state of nature exists
(or probably ever did exist), the concept can help construct a
justification for states of affairs which actually do or could exist.
The parallel is plausible, but dangerous. Motion exists. Uniform
motion is a linear extrapolation to the vanishing point, as it were,
of certain properties of real motion. To the extent that the notion
of a state of nature is similarly an extrapolation, the parallel looks
sound. But when it turns out that only in the ‘unreal’ conditions
can a given type of social arrangement be justified (e.g. private
ownership of all available land), then the use of the imaginary situa¬
tion in moral theory becomes something of a menace to clear
thinking.
123
Property Rights
1 Mill says ‘Private property, as an institution, did not owe its origin
to any of those considerations of utility which plead for the main¬
tenance of it when established.’ He clearly thinks that ‘originally,’
people simply took things and kept them. Civil society grew up as a
way of repressing violence. Property law was part of what was
124
Notes
125
Property Rights
126
Notes
1951) and Bartlett (ed.), Property: Its Duties and Rights, 2nd edition
(London, Macmillan, 1915).
2 Aristotle, Politics, book II, chapter 5, at 1263b.
127
Property Rights
128
Notes
129
Property Rights
130
Index
131
Property Rights
132
Index
133
Property Rights
134
Index
135
St. Vincent de Paul Li
"I /
M
The Author
Be<3
PRC
Libn
1071
Boy
Responsibility
Jonathan Glover
I
i