A Guide Heidegger: Being and Time
A Guide Heidegger: Being and Time
A Guide to Heidegger's
Being and Time
Λ ,
, ,
J
MAGDA KING
Edited by
John Llewelyn
King, Magda.
A guide to Heidegger' s Being and time / by Magda King ; edited by John Llewelyn.
—
p. cm. (SUNY series in contemporary continental philosophy )
Includes bibliographical references and index.
ISBN 0-7914-4799-5 ( he : alk. paper ) - ISBN 0-7914-4800-2 ( pbk. : alk. paper )
1. Heidegger, Martin, 1889-1976. Sein und Zeit. 2. Ontology. 3. Space and time. I.
Llewelyn, John, 1928- II. Title. III. Series.
B3279.H48 S46632
—
111 dc21
00-027620
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
To
A. K.
CONTENTS
Author’s Foreword XV 11
Acknowledgments XXI
PART ONE
What Is the Question?
Introductory 1
Exposition 5
1. A Formal Statement of the Question 5
2. A Provisional Explanation of “ Meaning” ( Sinn ):
The Theme of Being and Time Restated 6
3. Why Has Traditional Ontology Failed to Get to the
Root of the Problem of Being? 11
4. The Uniqueness of the Concept of Being: The Problem
Vll
Vlll A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
PART TWO
Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
Introductory 25
PART THREE
Division Two of Being and Time : Da-sein and Temporality
Introductory 127
Notes 369
Index 387
EDITOR S FOREWORD
Xlll
XIV A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
One are presented in a manner suited to students who have not yet
made an extensive or intensive study of philosophy, the much longer
chapters in which she treats Division Two, while still untechnical, are
models of how to read and analyze paragraph by paragraph with the
slowness a great text deserves.
Heidegger's Philosophy was one of the earliest commentaries on
Being and Time to appear in English . Its composition was virtually com-
plete before the translation of Heidegger’s masterpiece by John Mac-
quarrie and Edward Robinson appeared. Since then the long-awaited
translation by Joan Stambaugh has come out. This is the translation I
reproduce in citations, but, where there is a difference, I elsewhere use
both it and the no less insightful renderings of key terms for which
Magda King argues and upon which her comments sometimes turn.
Her alternatives are recorded in the new glossary and index.
Perhaps the most controversial departure in the original guide
compared with the Macquarrie-Robinson and the Stambaugh transla-
tions was her willingness to countenance “ man ” as a rendering of
Da-sein provided it “ be remembered that man is a purely ontic term and
is incapable of bringing into play the ontological meaning of Da sein .”
That is what she says in the second part of the first chapter of Part Two
in defense of her willingness to use the word in this way and in spite of
her acknowledgment of the reason Heidegger gives in Sein und Zeit for
using the word Da-sein rather than Mensch— though it should be noted
that in some works composed after this one he seems ready to use
Mensch in places where he would formerly have written Da-sein . Magda
King notes further that the expression “ human being” has the draw-
back that “ it defines ‘being’ by the humanity of man, whereas Da-sein
asks us to do exactly the opposite.” In favor of using “ man ” she cites its
simplicity. In my judgment the disadvantages of its use, which she her-
self stresses, outweigh this virtue of simplicity. She appears to have
come around to this view herself by the time she undertook her com-
mentary on Division Two, for there she frequently uses the term
Da-sein . Her original objection to that solution was that “ although in
many ways the best,” it is exposed to “ the danger that Da-sein might
become merely a technical term in a Heideggerian terminology,
instead of being rethought and genuinely understood.” I believe that
her own exegeses forearm the reader so effectively against this danger
that to choose Da-sein is indeed the best solution. I have therefore
opted for the now standard practice she herself appears to have come
to favor and have as a consequence made substitutions where called for
in her treatment of Division One. It seems to me that the risk incurred
by using the word Da-sein is less serious than that run by frequent
Editor's Foreword XV
recourse to “ man.” This does not mean that this familiar word has to
be eschewed altogether, so long as we keep her warning in mind. As for
her phrases “ man’s being-there” and “ man’s here-being, ” they express
admirably the ontic-ontological ambiguity on which Heidegger’ s work
turns, the original ambiguity or “ ontological difference” implicit in the
Greek word on.
Magda King welcomed and adopted many suggestions from the
first full English translation of Being and Time, for instance “ ownmost”
for Heidegger’ s eigenst , which is kept too in Joan Stambaugh’s transla-
tion . The present editor is in the fortunate position of being able to
draw on all three of these sources and others. He is of the opinion that
it is by ringing the changes judiciously through a range of available
offerings that the reader may be conducted between the extremes of
oversimplification and excessive artificiality toward a horizon where
the matter itself, the Sache selbst, is “ rethought and genuinely under-
stood.” An approach to this objective can be facilitated, or rather made
less difficult, if a neologism or paleonym can be hit upon that is unfa-
miliar without being too far-out. For example, Magda King’s “ spaceish ”
substitutes for “ spatial” a word that sounds strange enough to the Eng-
lish ear to make us think harder about what Heidegger might mean by
räumlich. It and “ timeish ” and “ worldish ” and “ published ” (for
öffentlich ) are to my mind and ear strokes of genius. She exploits the
same suffix in “ stand-offishness, ” her graphically concrete translation
of Abst ändigkeity for which Stambaugh and Macquarrie and Robinson
give the more Latinate “ distantiality.”
In his endeavor to refresh philosophy, Heidegger, like Hegel,
draws on the earthy roots of his language and dialect. So a promising
way of achieving this refreshment would be the exercise of translating
Being and Time into Anglo-Saxon. Or Welsh. Or Hebrew. For it is at the
Janus edge of the going over, the unstable instant of transition from
one linguistic field to another, that takes place the paradoxical hap-
pening of simultaneously being and not being at home that is regis-
tered in the word Unheimlichkeity one of the keys to Heidegger’s book.
This frontier can also be historical. On or near it perhaps teeters the
word dread . Although and because this was revived in certain Existen-
tialist applications of Heidegger, it has tended to get eclipsed in trans-
lations and discussions of his work by anxiety or by Angst left untrans-
lated. Alluding to A. E. Housman’s list of the physical symptoms that
accompanied his remembering a line of poetry, she remarks that “ it
might equally well be said that the first time one truly understands Hei-
degger’ s questions one knows it by a cold shiver running down one’ s
—
spine. ” That cold shiver the Schaudern that Goethe’s Faust declares to
XVI A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
—
be humankind’ s best part, Shakespeare’s “ dread bolted thunder ” can
be felt in the word dread. I have therefore respected Magda King’s pref-
erence for it, but without excluding the others. This is not the only
transcription by her that may provoke the disagreement she would
have seen as a manifestation of the alertness she wanted to encourage.
Whether or not her own lexical and philosophical alertness owes some-
thing to her having learned German and English as second and third
languages, I fancy no one will disagree that it is abundantly manifested
in this guide.
With a couple of exceptions for which she excuses herself, the
author deliberately abstains from discussing the secondary literature
already available to her. Her aim is the same as Heidegger’s: to bring
readers to experience a raw contact with the topic. Anyway, without
that accessibility how could readers be confident that they had reached
a position from which to judge the book, as of course it must and will
be judged, in light of other Heideggeriana? Texts additional to Being
and Time to which she does refer are listed in the bibliography, which
I have expanded by including information about recent editions, trans-
lations, and secondary literature. I have also expanded her notes and
the references given in her text by adding indications to this material
in them.
But it is above all in the sensitive intelligence with which its
author listens and responds to Heidegger’s own words that lies what I
consider to be the strength of this book. We can all think of philo-
sophical or other commentaries composed decades ago that retain
their power of illumination today, whatever scholarship has come up
with in the interim. I believe that A Guide to Heidegger's uBeing and
Time” has that classic quality and that generations of students of Hei-
degger will join with me in thanking State University of New York
Press, in particular Jane Bunker and Marilyn Semerad, and their phi -
losophy series editor Dennis Schmidt, for the professional manner in
which they have shown that my belief is shared.
JOHN LLEWELYN
AUTHOR S FOREWORD
The studies contained in this volume are intended to help the reader
toward an understanding of Heidegger’ s philosophy as it is expressed
in Being and Time . Even the best translations cannot avoid a certain
distortion of the original text, imposing additional difficulties on
their readers. The main purpose of this book is to help such readers
over the greatest initial difficulties presented by Being and Time . Hei-
degger claims to have made a new departure in Greek-Western think-
ing by raising a radically new problem. What this problem is, and how
it differs from the central problem of traditional philosophy, is hard
to grasp and harder to explain; but it must be at least roughly
explained and understood before any detail of Heidegger’ s thought
can fall into place.
Accordingly, the first theme of this book is simply the question
Heidegger asks. The discussion of this question will at the same time
introduce readers to Being and Time in a general way and prepare them
for the second and main theme of this book: an exposition of those fea-
tures and problems of Being and Time which are both basic to its under-
standing and are usually found hardest to grasp, such as, to mention
only one example, Heidegger’ s conception of world. The first seven
studies will deal with problems basic to Being and Time as a whole, and
the eighth will give a preview of the special problems raised in Division
Two in preparation for the close investigation of that division which
follows. A concluding study will attempt to indicate Heidegger’s answer
to the question raised at the beginning of his inquiry.
The difficulty of Heidegger’s thought was for many years held to
be almost insuperable in the medium of a foreign language, especially
English. That this opinion is no longer so widely held can be seen both
XVII
XVlll A Guide to Heidegger' s Being and Time
this has been done, the inadequacy of the English rendering is often
still so painfully felt that there is a constant temptation to go on using
the German original. With exception made for Da sein, this temptation
will be resisted in this work, on the principle that an inadequate Eng-
lish word is preferable to an unfamiliar foreign word, always provided
that it has been carefully explained how and where the English fails to
harmonize with the original. [German expressions are retained where
they occur in citations from Joan Stambaugh’ s translation. They have
also been added occasionally in brackets elsewhere. Ed.]
Heidegger’ s practice of putting into quotation marks, for no
apparent reason, such familiar words as subject, know, world , and the
like, although a minor difficulty, cannot be entirely disregarded. The
quotation marks indicate that these words are not to be taken at their
face value, either because they are used in a new sense or because they
are a loose way of speaking, not strictly appropriate to the matter
under discussion but unavoidable because they have grown from a long
habit of thought and are easily understandable to the reader.
Heidegger’ s practice will be applied in this book only within strict
limits. On the other hand, quotation marks will occasionally be used
for purely linguistic reasons. The word being, when it stands for the
substantive das Sein, may sometimes have to be distinguished from a
gerund or a present participle that belongs to the sentence construc-
tion. English is exceptional in that it does not have a noun form of the
infinitive to be, a peculiarity that can lead to confusion and obscurity
when the to be is the main theme of the inquiry. Many philosophical
works try to overcome this difficulty by spelling the gerund with a cap-
ital letter: Being. This practice, unfortunately, can lead to another con-
fusion: the mere sight of the word Being suggests the divine Being,
when what is meant is simply the humble to be. The verbal noun being
will therefore be spelled with the small initial letter, but it will stand in
quotation marks when any doubt could arise about its meaning.
Finally, two closely connected points must be briefly mentioned.
The first concerns the bibliography. Among Husserl’ s works only
those have been mentioned there to which either direct reference is
made or which were found to be especially helpful as a preparation for
Sein und Zeit . I have not discussed commentaries and critical works on
Heidegger, since to have done so would almost inevitably have raised
controversy and interfered with the main purpose of taking the reader
directly to Heidegger’s thought as that is presented in his own works.
For similar reasons, no attempt has been made at a critical
appraisal of Heidegger’s philosophy. Where criticisms and compar-
isons with other thinkers occur, these are incidental and subordinate to
XX A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
the positive task of helping the reader to a clear and firm grasp of Hei-
degger’s fundamental ideas. This is by no means easy, but once it is
done, it will put the reader in a position both to explore more deeply
Heidegger’s thought for himself and to form a fair judgment of its
power and original contribution to philosophy.
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS
I wish to thank the Niemeyer Verlag for kind permission to quote and
translate passages from the original edition of Sein und, Zeit, copyright
by Max Niemeyer Verlag, Halle/Saale ( now Tü bingen ), 1927.
The manuscript has greatly benefited from my husband’s advice
and fruitful criticism; to him I owe deepest gratitude. I gladly take this
opportunity also to thank George Kay for his most generous and con-
structive help through many years; and Thorir Thordarson and Martin
Gray for their encouragement and support.
XXI
BIBLIOGRAPHY AND
KEY TO ABBREVIATIONS
HEIDEGGER
BPP The Basic Problems of Phenomenology , trans. Albert Hofstadter ( Bloom-
ington: Indiana University Press, 1982 ).
BW Martin Heidegger: Basic Writings, ed., David Farrell Krell ( New York:
Harper 8c Row, 1977 ).
BZ Der Begriff der Zeit (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1989 ).
CT The Concept of Time, trans. William McNeill (Oxford: Blackwell ,
1992 ).
DT Discourse on Thinking, trans. John M. Anderson and E. Hans Freund
( New York : Harper 8c Row, 1966).
EB Existence and Being, ed., Werner Brock ( London: Vision, 1949 ).
EGT Early Greek Thinking, trans. David Farrell Krell and Frank A. Capuzzi
( New York: Harper 8c Row, 1975 ).
EHD Erläuterungen zu Hölderlins Dichtung ( Frankfurt: Klostermann ,1951 ).
G 4.
EM Einführung in die Metaphysik (Tü bingen: Niemeyer,1953). G40.
ER The Essence of Reasons, trans. Terrence Malick ( Evanston, Northwest-
ern University Press, 1969 ).
XXlil
XXIV A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
OWL On the Way to Language , trans. Peter D. Hertz ( New York: Harper 8c
Row, 1971).
P Pathmarks, ed., William McNeill (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1998).
PGZ Prolegomena zur Geschichte des Zeitbegriffs ( Frankfurt: Klostermann,
1979 ). G 20.
PLT Poetry, Language, Thought, trans. Albert Hofstadter ( New York:
Harper 8c Row, 1971 ).
PR The Principle of Reason, trans. Reginald Lilly ( Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 1991 ).
Bibliography and Key to Abbreviations XXV
QCT The (Question Concerning Technology and Other Essays, trans. William
Lovitt ( New York: Harper Sc Row, 1977 ).
SG Der Satz vom Grund ( Pfullingen: Neske, 1958). G10.
SZ Sein und Zeit , Jahrbuch für Philosophie und phänomenologische
Forschung , VIII. ( Halle: Niemeyer, 1927 ). G 2. Being and Time , trans.
John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson ( New York: Harper Sc Row,
Oxford: Blackwell , 1962 ). Trans. Joan Stambaugh ( Albany: State Uni-
versity of New York Press, 1997 ).
US Unterwegs zur Sprache ( Pfullingen: Neske, 1960 ). G12.
VA Vorträge und Aufsätze ( Pfullingen: Neske, 1954 ).
W Wegmarken ( Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1967). G9.
WCT What Is Called Thinking? trans. Fred D. Wieck and John Glenn Gray
( New York: Harper Sc Row, 1968).
WG Vom Wesen des Grundes ( Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1955 ).
WHD Was heisst Denken? (Tübingen: Niemeyer, 1954 ). G8.
WM Was ist Metaphysik ? Mit Einleitung und Nachwort ( Frankfurt: Kloster-
mann , 1955).
WP -
Was ist das die Philosophie? ( Pfullingen: Neske , 1956 ).
1
WP( E ) What Is Philosophy? trans. Jean T. Wilde and William Kluback (Sch-
enectady: New College and University Press,1956 ).
WT What Is a Thing? trans. W. B. Barton, Jr. and Vera Deutsch ( Chicago:
Henry Regnery, 1967 ).
ww Vom Wesen der Wahrheit ( Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1954 ).
ZS Zur Seinsfrage ( Frankfurt: Klostermann , 1956).
For details of the context and composition of Being and Time, see espe-
cially John van Buren, The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King
( Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994 ), and Theodore Kisiel,
The Genesis of Heidegger s “ Being and Time ” ( Berkeley: University of Cal-
ifornia Press, 1993).
HUSSERL
INTRODUCTORY
The main body of Being and Time is preceded by two expository chap-
ters in which Heidegger explains the question of being as it is to be
raised and worked out in this fundamental inquiry. Everything that
—
belongs to Heidegger’s question its motive and aim, the method of
—
the investigation, and the conclusions at which it will arrive is set out
in these two chapters with meticulous care and a masterliness that can
only be appreciated after much study. And yet, twenty and thirty years
after the publication of Being and Time, Heidegger still finds himself
obliged to correct misinterpretations of his fundamental work and to
point out confusions between his question of being and that raised by
traditional ontology.1
The difficulty of grasping a radically new problem is, of course,
well known to students of philosophy. In addition, Heidegger presents
his readers with unusual difficulties, the greatest of which is the frag-
mentary state of Being and Time itself. Divisions One and Two of Part
I were published in 1927 as the beginning of a much larger work , con-
sisting of two parts or halves, each containing three divisions. Heideg-
ger intended to conclude his own investigations of the problem of
being in Division Three, Part I, while the whole of Part II was to have
1
2 A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
Being and Time is an inquiry into the meaning of being ( Sinn von Sein ).
To this short formulation of his theme Heidegger frequently adds the
word überhaupt , which is difficult to translate precisely: the meaning of
being as such or in general is only an approximate statement of the full
theme ( Sinn von Sein überhaupt ). Fortunately, this difficulty need not
worry us unduly, since Heidegger does not insist on a single formula.
In an effort to make his problem concretely understandable he often
reduces it to a simple, informal question, as, for example: “ was heisst
‘Sein’?” (SZ, 26; also KPM, 202, G 3, 224, KPM( E), 153; ID, 21, ID( E ),
30). Almost literally translated, the phrase means What is called
“ being” ? Freely paraphrased, it might be rendered as What do we mean
by “ to be” ?
From these various formulations, the core of Heidegger’ s
question emerges with an apparent, not to say misleading, clarity
and simplicity. At first sight , we must confess, it is frankly disap-
pointing. Heidegger claims to give philosophy a new start , but it is
not at all evident where the newness of his question lies. It strikes
us rather as the revival of an old question that has gone out of fash-
ion . Even less does its fundamental character show itself on the sur-
face. It reminds us of the kind of problems that are usually dealt
with by logic, but most of all it sounds like a linguistic or a merely
verbal problem. Among all the doubts and misgivings aroused by a
formal statement of Heidegger’ s theme, the suspicion that he might
be concerned merely with the meaning of a word must evidently be
the first to be allayed.
5
6 Part One: What Is the Question?
"
2. A PROVISIONAL EXPLANATION OF MEANING ( SINN ):
THE THEME OF BEING AND TIME RESTATED
Heidegger' s special use of the term " meaning" ( Sinn ) was pointed out
already in our introductory remarks. Our present difficulty thus seems
to be purely terminological and should be capable of an easy solution:
we must simply find out how Heidegger defines the word “ meaning."
The matter, however, is not quite so simple, as can be readily seen when
the definition is actually given. Meaning, in Heidegger’s sense, is that
from which something is understandable as the thing it is. This defin-
ition, while perfectly correct, is for our purpose quite insufficient.
Heidegger’s terminology grows from a way of phenomenological think-
ing, which cannot be explained merely by defining words. Phenome-
nology will be made the subject of one of our later studies, but in the
meantime we must find a rough-and-ready way to understand Heideg-
ger’ s use of “ meaning.” This can be done by a concrete illustration.
Supposing in a strange town we ask what a certain building is, we
may be told that it is a theater. With this explanation the building has
—
explicitly come to our understanding as a theater that is, as the thing
it is. Supposing, however, that we are not familiar with theaters, we
must take a further step and have explained to us what a theater is. We
shall be told that it is a building intended for the production of plays.
Provided that we know at all what a play is, this particular building has
now become manifest in what it essentially is. When we understand
something as the thing it is, we have understood it in its essential being.
But where in all this is the meaning? Is it in our understanding of
the word “ theater?” No. Is it in this concrete thing, the theater itself ?
No. Is it perhaps in the explanation “ for the production of plays” ? The
“ for” shows that this thing, the theater, is in advance understood by ref-
erence to a purpose. Is that where we find the meaning? This comes
much nearer to Heidegger, but is not quite there yet. Meaning, accord-
ing to Heidegger, is that from which something is understandable as
the thing it is. From where can a thing like a theater be understood at
all? Only from a world of human existence.
Writing, producing, and appreciating plays is one of our distinc-
tively human possibilities, for the sake of which we have things like the-
aters. Only from a human world can a thing be understood as a theater.
That which makes such understanding possible, Heidegger says, is the
meaning. The meaning of the theater is the world to which it belongs.
The world of our own existence is the horizon in which our every-
day understanding moves, so that from it and in reference to it the
things we come across are intelligible to us as theaters, as buses, as
Exposition 7
knives and forks; that is, as things that can be useful for some purpose.
The horizon of our world is primarily “ meaning-giving” ; it is a mean-
ing in which we constantly move as a matter of course, so that it usu-
ally remains implicit.
One way to make this implied meaning explicit is to turn away
from our everyday world and enter into the realm of one of the sci-
ences, say, theoretical physics. At one stroke, things like theaters,
buses, knives and forks, become “ meaningless.” The horizon from
which things are now understood is the substantiality of matter. Why
has such a startling change taken place? Because the horizon, in
which the physicist’ s understanding moves, has undergone a pro-
found modification. The world of human existence has become mod-
ified into a theoretical conception of material nature, articulated into
such categories or basic concepts as mass, motion, or energy. Since
this horizon alone is “ meaning-giving” for the physicist, anything
whatever that falls under his observation must show itself and can
only show itself as a complex motion of material bodies. This horizon
gives nothing from which things could even be questioned as to their
possible relevance to a purpose; their only possibility now is to show
themselves in their material properties as moving bodies in a space-
time continuum .
Let us sum up the results we have reached so far. Meaning is that
—
which enables us to understand things as the things they are that is, in
their essential being. The meaning does not originally lie in words, or
in things, but in the remarkable structure of our understanding itself.
We move in advance in a horizon of understanding, from which and in
reference to which the things we meet are intelligible to us as so and so
and as such and such. The world of our own existence is the horizon
from which we primarily understand things as relevant to a purpose.
This is capable of modifications, for example, into something like
“ nature.” From this horizon, things become understandable purely as
substantial bodies. The modifications in the horizon of our under-
standing enable us to understand things in different ways, but in each
case only in one or another of their possibilities.
What light does this throw on Heidegger’s theme? What is Hei-
degger aiming at when he asks: How is it at all possible for man [ Da-
sein] to understand being? From what horizon does he understand
being? What does being mean? These questions, as our discussion has
shown, are not three different questions, but are one and the same.
The horizon which makes it possible for us to understand being as
being is itself the meaning of being. What is this horizon? It is, as Being
and Time sets out to show, time. Already on the first page, Heidegger
8 Part One: What Is the (Question?
— —
ontology that is to be founded that is, brought back to its source and
ground in Being and Time . The strangeness of Heidegger’s philosophi-
cal approach makes itself felt already in the concepts into which the idea
of being is articulated, among which the “ nothing” and the “ not” occupy
the most important place. This seems paradoxical indeed, for, to our
usual way of thinking, “ nothing” and “ notness” are the very opposite of
being. Our later studies will show, however, that these concepts receive
an entirely new interpretation in Heidegger’s thought, in the light of
which their central philosophical importance will become fully under -
standable. In the meantime, we shall turn to those articulations of the
idea of being that seem familiar and more within our immediate grasp.
The two closely connected articulations of what- and how-being
become much easier to comprehend when they are rephrased into
what-(a thing)-is and how-(it )-is. The being of things is manifest to us
in what they are, traditionally called the “ essence,” and in how they
—
are that is, whether they exist actually, or possibly, or necessarily. It
should be noted, however, that these traditional conceptions should
never be taken over unexamined and mechanically applied to Hei-
degger’s philosophy. The reason for this will gradually emerge in the
course of our studies. Meanwhile, a more urgent point to decide is
what we are to understand by the “ thing” whose being is articulated
into what and how.
Exposition 9
In the primary and narrow sense, things are the concrete things
that are accessible to us through the senses and are capable of an inde-
pendent existence, such as mountains, stars, plants, and animals. These
things stand there, so to speak, on their own feet, and in so standing,
they are, they exist . Things in a very wide sense, however, can mean
anything at all: beings as such and as a whole, and things in this wide
sense constitute the sphere of philosophical inquiry. Within the realm
of beings as a whole, however, the concrete, sensible things have played
an eminently important part, so that nonsensible phenomena, like
mind, knowledge, and number, have tended to be understood in com-
parison with and in contrast to them. In other words, the reality ( Wirk -
lichkeit ) of one kind of thing has tended to be measured by the reality
of another kind of thing.
But if the fundamental problem of philosophy is to be raised in a
new way, not only the idea of being but also the idea of beings must be
reconsidered and defined. The third articulation of the idea of being
gives us the widest possible concept of beings as such: they are some-
thing and not nothing. A delusion, the meaning of a poem, God, hope,
thinking, seeming, becoming, and so on, are evidently something and
not nothing, although they are not concrete sensible things in the pri-
mary sense of the word. Starting from the idea of something, a “ real
thing” is no longer played off against an “ ideal thing” and the one mea-
sured by the other; both are set off against the nothing as the totally
other to all things, and understood in their most fundamental charac-
ter as “ not nothing.” Heidegger’s idea of being formulates the demand
that ontology must start from the widest and deepest of all distinctions:
the difference between something and nothing. With this start, the
problem of the nothing would be drawn into the very center of philos -
ophy; and this, Heidegger maintains, would be the first fruitful step
toward “ overcoming nihilism” ( EM, 155, IM, 170, G40, 212 ).
All this sounds intolerably paradoxical at present, because we do
not in the least know as yet what Heidegger means by the nothing. For
the same reason , it is hard to imagine that the nothing and the not can
have anything to do with time, and yet they must have, if Heidegger is
serious in announcing that the final aim of Being and Time is to unfold
the temporal meaning enclosed in the idea of being as such.
This culminating point of Heidegger’s investigations will unfor-
tunately remain obscure even at the end of our studies, since the whole
temporal analysis of the idea of being was to have been carried out in
Division Three. But, it will be asked , what of all the works Heidegger
has written since Being and Time? Is it possible that none of them
brings at least a partial solution to Heidegger’s final problem? One of
10 Part One: What Is the Question?
hide the problem that the phrase “ the being of beings” wears, so to
speak, on its sleeve.
Ta onta means: that which is, the things that are. Formally, the
word beings approximates quite well to ta onta , but in English it is
applied mainly to living beings, and primarily to human beings. We
must now try to think this word in exactly the opposite way, because
the beings par excellence that traditional ontology has in view are not
the beings we ourselves are, but primarily things, in the sense of con-
crete sensible things. When Greek-Western philosophy speaks of to be ,
it thinks of the is of a thing; in other words, to be has come to mean pre-
dominantly the infinitive of is (EM, 70, IM, 77, G40, 98).
What do we mean when we say that a thing is (exists) ? We mean
that it is really there among the all of things, that it occurs, that it can
be found somewhere in the natural universe. When we talk of reality,
we mean primarily the actual presence of something among the total-
ity of beings. The reality of the res ( thing) in a very wide sense may be
called the central conception of being in traditional ontology. The
basic character of reality is substantiality. The seemingly irreconcilable
trends in our philosophical tradition spring mainly from varying inter-
pretations of what is meant by substance or what manner or class of
beings may properly be called substances.3 In ancient philosophy
alone, substance has been as variously defined as matter, as material
bodies, as essence, as number, as idea or form, as the indissoluble unity
of matter and form, not to speak of modern variations on the same
theme. Yet all these differences can be differentiated and all these
opposites opposed only on the ground of an underlying sameness: an
idea of being as substantial reality.
No matter how variously traditional ontology may define the sub-
stance, it always does so with a view to self-subsistence, self-mainte-
nance without recourse to other beings, unchanging presence as an
independent self. And just because independence and self-subsistence
are the basic characters of substantial being, its perfect embodiment
must be self-produced, or unproduced , uncaused, uncreated. Anything
that is brought into being is necessarily dependent, needs maintenance,
—
and is liable to pass away that is why perishable, finite beings cannot
satisfy the idea of the perfect substance.
Any problem that arises in traditional ontology is in advance
understood in the horizon of substantiality. But this idea of being, Hei-
degger maintains, is too narrow and restricted to be able to explain all
the ways and senses in which we can understand being. Above all, it is
incapable of explaining the distinctively and uniquely human way of
being. Man exists such that his being is manifest to him, and it is man-
Exposition 13
ifest to him as his own. That is why each of us must say of himself: I am.
Being and Time will show that the whole meaning and structure of the
being we express by the am is totally different from the real existence
of a thing.
Once we begin to think about it, it must strike us as curious that
the infinitive to be should have drawn its meaning primarily from the is
of things, when the am would seem to be much nearer and more easily
comprehensible to us. Does Heidegger ascribe this strange feature of
our tradition to a lack of insight or deep thought on the part of meta-
physical thinkers? Far from it. He holds that the greatness of their
thought has been the distinction of Europe. Was, then, the question,
What are beings as beings? simply a wrong start, accidentally made and
perpetuated through two and a half thousand years? Historical deci-
sions, Heidegger maintains, do not come about by accident, but spring
from the basic possibilities of man’s existence, possibilities that are nei-
ther made by man, nor, on the other hand, are merely blindly and pas-
sively endured by him, as a thing may be thought to “ endure” the con-
tingencies that happen to it.
The tendency to interpret human being from the being of things
may be roughly and provisionally explained by one of the basic ways in
which man can and usually does exist: he loses himself to the things he
meets in his world. Owing to his fundamental tendency to give himself
away, to scatter himself among his makings and doings, man literally
finds himself “ there, ” among the things with which he is busy. Hence the
impression arises that to be means I am in exactly the same way as it does
when to be is applied to a thing. Thus the to be remains undifferentiated
and is applied in the vague, average sense of presentness and occurrence
to any beings that are accessible at all, including man himself.
It is from this average understanding of being that metaphysics
grows. The horizon from which being is understood does not become
explicit and its possible differentiations cannot become even a prob-
lem. What is differentiated is not being, but beings. Traditional philo-
sophical distinctions start from beings, defining and dividing them
into regions and classes according to their essence, their whatness.
Man himself is enrolled into the region of living beings, of animals,
among which , ontologically speaking, he subsequently remains ( HU,
65ff., W, 154ff., G9, 323ff ., P, 246-47, BW, 203ff.). Man is the animal
who speaks, who has a soul, reason, mind, spirit, self-consciousness,
who can think. The interpretation of man’s essence undergoes many
changes in Greek-Western ontology; what does not change is that man’ s
existence is in advance understood as the real occurrence of a peculiar
species among the all of beings.
14 Part One: What Is the Question?
being. Logic has grown from the soil of traditional ontology; its meth-
ods, justifiable within certain limits, are applicable only to defining
beings (SZ, 3-4 ). But being is nothing like beings; it cannot be brought
to definiteness and clarity by having beings ascribed to it. As Aristotle
clearly saw, being is not the highest genus. The universality of the con-
cept of being is of a totally different order from the generality of those
concepts that gather beings into one class. While Aristotle’ s deep and
subtle reasoning cannot be entered upon here, its point can be graph-
ically illustrated as follows.
A genus, which through its subordinate species contains individ-
ual beings, can always be exemplified and thus brought to definiteness
and clarity. The genus animal, for instance, can always be explained by
pointing to a sheep or a horse. But to explain the concept of being, we
should vainly point to a horse or the sun , saying “ Look, that is what I
mean by is ” The very absurdity of this attempt shows the baffling char-
acter of our most universal concept. While everything that we can
know, feel, experience in any way is understandable to us in terms of
its being, being itself can in no way be explained from or by beings. Its
universality transcends, goes out beyond any possible beings or classes
of beings.
The uniqueness of being gives rise to the important philosophi-
cal problem: What constitutes the unity of this universal concept? The
unity of a genus, like animal, may be explained by the common char-
acter of the beings that fall under it, but this cannot be done with
being. And yet, all the ways and senses in which we use the term to be
have a recognizable and definite unity, and the philosophical task is to
explain how this unity is possible.
This is the problem Aristotle tried to solve with his teaching of
the analogous meanings of being. With this discovery, Heidegger
remarks on page 3 of Being and Time, “ Aristotle placed the problem of
being on a fundamentally new basis.” But even Aristotle, Heidegger
goes on to point out, failed to solve the problem of those “ catégorial
connections ” which he himself had raised; nor could the medieval
Schoolmen, who took over the doctrine of the unity of analogy, arrive
at any solution in principle.
Why does Heidegger draw attention so pointedly to this doc-
trine in the opening pages of Being and Time? What is it that Aristo-
tle and the Schoolmen failed to solve? Why must the whole problem
remain in principle insoluble within metaphysics itself ? The answer
to these questions must obviously throw a great deal of light not only
on traditional attempts, but on Heidegger’s own attempt to grapple
with the fundamental problems of philosophy. The whole matter,
Exposition 17
— —
other than substance for example, the category of quality, quantity,
state, or relation is said to be only in a qualified sense, being the qual-
ity, quantity, state, or relation of a substance. For example, the “ con-
crete and unique substance, ” the moon, which Aristotle holds to be
eternal and divine, is (exists ) in the primary and full sense of the word
be . But when we say “ The moon is white,” or “ The moon is eclipsed, ”
the meaning of the is has been qualified. The difference between the
subtance moon and its quality of whiteness or its state of being
eclipsed is evident: the whiteness could not exist by itself, whereas the
moon could very well change its color and yet remain substantially the
moon. Similarly, the eclipse has no separate existence apart from the
moon, whereas the moon remains identically the same without being
eclipsed. And yet, we do not speak ambiguously or improperly when
we ascribe being of a kind to quality, or state, or quantity, because in
these instances we do not mean by the word is the same as when we
speak of substance. We are using the term analogously, that is, by ref-
erence to its first and unqualified meaning.
Why does Heidegger draw attention to the importance of the
“ unity of analogy ” at the beginning of Being and Time? Because here is
the nearest approach that can be made from metaphysics toward a new
inquiry into being. Aristotle sees clearly that the problem cannot be
solved by dividing beings into genera and species, but that the “ to be”
itself must be articulable and modifiable. He sees further that the mod-
ifications can be explained by reference to a primary meaning. But even
Aristotle’s genius cannot leap out of an idea of being as being-a-sub-
stance, which determines traditional ontology from its start.
What is it, among other things, that the unity of analogy fails to
illuminate? It fails to illuminate the primary meaning of being. How is
it, Heidegger would ask, that “ to be ” must primarily mean “ to-be-sub-
stance” ? And why must substantiality mean self-subsistence, self-main-
18 Part One: What Is the Question?
Our discussions so far have had the aim of bringing the central prob-
lem of Being and Time into focus. The solution proposed by Heidegger
has to some extent been indicated, not in the hope of making it under-
standable at this stage, but in order to illuminate the fundamental
nature of the problem itself and its departure from tradition. On the
other hand, the way in which Heidegger works out his theme has so far
been only briefly mentioned, and needs a somewhat fuller discussion.
The subtides of the two divisions we have of Being and Time seem
to suggest that this work is an ontological inquiry of the usual style into
the being of man. Division One is entided “ The Preparatory Funda-
mental Analysis of Da sein ” ; Division Two, “ Da-sein and Temporality.” 6
To all appearances, Being and Time sets out to repair the omission of
traditional ontology to inquire into man’s existence and not only into
his essence. If we follow the customary division of the all of beings into
—
great ontological regions the modern practice is to separate the
—
region “ nature” from the region “ mind” it seems perfectly appropri-
ate to call Being and Time a “ regional ontology of man, ” or, to use an
equivalent expression, to call it a “ philosophical anthropology.”
The only obstacle to such a reasonable interpretation is Heideg-
ger’s own, almost obstinate insistence that his treatise is not a regional
but a fundamental ontology ( KPM, 188ff., G3, 208ff., KPM( E), 142ff.).
Its sole aim is to show how an understanding of being is at all possible,
and why the being understood in it must have a temporal character.
The inquiry into man’s existence, Heidegger insists, is only the con-
crete way toward this aim. Why is this plain and unambiguous state-
ment yet so puzzling? Because it is by no means self-evident why Hei-
degger’s sole aim should make an analysis of all the essential structures
of man’s being necessary. Why cast the net so widely to catch a single
20 Part One: What Is the Question?
something that is. He is usually too absorbed in his business with the
tree itself to notice the remarkable fact that if the is were missing from
the tree, not merely the word “ is ” would disappear, but also the tree as
tree. He might, it is true, be still aware of it in some other way which is
difficult for us even to imagine, but the tree could no longer present
itself as the thing it is, in its specific tree-being. Consequently, there
could be no such word as “ tree.” If the is were missing from our lan-
guage, there would be not a single other word and no language at all
( EM, 62, IM , 68, G 40, 87 ).
Since in his usual absorption in things, man constantly overlooks
that which enables him to exist as man , his unique understanding of
being, philosophy is needed to take being for its explicit and, accord-
ing to Heidegger, its only proper theme. At the same time, philosophy
can be nothing other than a radicalization of the vague, average under-
standing of being in which man always and already exists. “ The covert
judgments of common reason, ” and they alone, as Kant said, are “ the
business of philosophers” ( quoted by Heidegger on page 4 of Being and
Time and frequently elsewhere ). Accordingly, Heidegger chooses just
the ordinary, everyday manner of existence for the concrete basis of his
“ Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Da-sein ” ( Division One ). Its task
is not only to show what is essentially, a priori constitutive of man’s
average manner of being, but at the same time to explain the elemen-
tal trend toward the world that characterizes everyday existence. Only
when the self-disguise that lies in man’s lostness to his world has been
explicitly laid bare, can a more original and radical understanding of
being be made accessible for investigation ( Division Two ). Man’s way
to be is to understand being. This way of being is unique to man. Con-
sequently, all possible articulations in the idea of being must come to
light in the essential structures of man’ s existence, and it is only there
that they can come to light. Once this is clearly seen, it becomes evi-
dent that in examining how the whole man is, and how he wholly is,
Heidegger is far from taking a circuitous route to a distant goal. He is,
in a sense, at the goal already with the first step; that is, he is already
examining the possibilities enclosed in the idea of being as such. On
the other hand, it is true that in each of its phases the inquiry moves
into a deeper ontological level, so that while the whole of Being and
Time makes up the fundamental ontology, it is only in Division Three
that the fundamental ontology can come fully to itself.
Some of the most basic and most puzzling features of the detailed
working out of Heidegger’ s problem will be the theme of the series of
studies contained in this book. Formidable difficulties of thought and
language will be encountered by us there, but they are, in the last
22 Part One: What Is the Question?
resort, only the visible outcrop of far simpler, much more basic diffi-
culties that arise from the nature of the problem itself. To consider
these briefly is the immediate and final task of the present exposition
of Heidegger’s question.
The first difficulty is not peculiar to Heidegger, but characterizes
all ontological inquiry. It is a curious feature of Being and Time that
while it evidently addresses itself first and foremost to the philosophical
world, Heidegger by no means takes a genuine understanding of ontol-
ogy for granted. On the contrary, he constantly stresses the unique char-
acter of ontology: that its proper theme is being; that being is nothing
like beings or their real properties and qualities and cannot be derived
from our experience of them and, above all, that to realize all this is the
first indispensable step toward any philosophical understanding.
Heidegger’s frequent recurrence to this theme is so marked that
one would be inclined to ascribe it to some special circumstances con-
nected with Being and Time, were it not that the same tendency
becomes even more pronounced in Heidegger’ s later works. In these,
the reader is constantly invited not to accept on hearsay, or be content
with a merely verbal comprehension of the statement that being only
“ is” in the understanding and not in things, but to take his first step
into philosophy genuinely by experiencing for himself the impossibil-
ity of finding the is in any of the things that are concretely accessible
to him ( e.g., WHD, 107, WCT, 173-74 ).
Why is this step into philosophy so difficult to take? Partly
because being is much less easy to grasp than beings, but partly also
because experiencing things in terms of their being seems so natural
to us that it is as if it could not be otherwise. The tree, for instance, pre-
sents itself to the merest idle glance as something that is ; it seems to
bring its is along with itself. The impression is hard to eliminate that
the is somehow belongs to the tree just as much as its shape, its color,
the texture of its bark, the glossiness of its leaves. A little thought, how-
ever, will show that all these things are something; they belong to the
real of beings, so that we already understand them in terms of the are.
We may examine the tree further, we may even think of the things we
cannot directly experience, such as the processes of life going on in the
tree, growth, nutrition, chemical changes, and so on. But again, all
these things are something, they belong to beings, and not one of them
can give us the slightest hint or clue as to how we have come by the is
and the are. Only one thing is certain: being is not something in addi-
tion to beings, but is the way in which these beings come to our under-
standing. They themselves can therefore never explain how we have
come to understand them the way we do.
Exposition 23
being, however, is totally different from the “ vicious circle ” which may
lie in a deductive proof . Nor must it be thought of as a geometrical cir-
cle. It is a circling whereby being and man circle round each other. The
circularity of its problem is not a secret weakness at the heart of phi-
losophy, but rather is its distinction. The task is not to avoid or sup-
press the circle, but to find the right way to get into it. The way found
by Heidegger in Being and Time has been briefly indicated: the
approach to being is made through the analysis of the being of man. If
we now ask whether there are other ways of “ getting into the circle, ”
the question aims at taking Being and Time out of the isolation in which
we have hitherto discussed it and showing its place in Heidegger’ s
thought as a whole.
The extraordinary difference between the two divisions we have
of Being and Time and Heidegger’s later works has been the subject of
much comment. The change is indeed startling enough to have given
rise to the opinion that there is a complete break between Being and
Time and other early works, and those that come after. The manifest
untenability of this view, however, soon led to the opposite extreme.
The tendency in recent years has been to minimize the difference and
ascribe it mainly to a change of theme, of style and language. While
this view is not unsound, it still fails to go to the heart of the matter.
What changes in Heidegger’s later works is his way of “ getting into the
circle.” Being is no longer approached through man’s understanding,
but rather it is man’ s understanding that is approached through the
manifestness of being. Only some such change could explain why so
fundamental a concept as the “ horizon of understanding” completely
disappears from Heidegger’s later thought ( GE, 38ff., DT, 64ff. ).
Through a lifetime of philosophical activity, embodied in a wide range
of works, Heidegger asks the same question, but he illuminates it by
different ways of circling the same circle.
PART TWO
o§o
INTRODUCTORY
25
26 A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
existing. The inquiry into the being of world goes hand in hand with
the analysis of Da-sein’s existence. The ontological structure of
world is called by Heidegger the worldishness or worldliness of
world ( die Weltlichkeit der Welt ) .1
3. An understanding of its own being in a world enables Da-sein to
meet other beings within the world and disclose them in their being.
Some of these beings are like himself; they are fellow men, whose
being has the same character of existence as his own. Some are
unlike himself; they are things in the strict sense of the word, and
their being has the character of reality (Vorhandenheit, Realit ät ) . The
inquiry into the being of other beings goes hand in hand with the
analysis of Da-sein’s own existence (self ) and of world.
As this short sketch already indicates, Heidegger unfolds his
theme, in its threefold articulation, as a single unity. It is true that he
may turn his attention specially now to Da-sein’s self, now to world, and
so on, but since these are in advance seen as articulations of a single
understanding of being, the highlighting of one does not plunge the
other two into darkness but brings them simultaneously to greater clar-
ity. Heidegger conducts his inquiry as the driver of a three-in-hand han-
dles his team, flicking now one horse, now another, but urging them
forward all the time as one single team.
Heidegger is well aware that his approach may lay him open to the
charge of being purely “ subjective.” Hence it is his constant concern to
correct such misapprehensions, by stressing that Da-sein’ s understand-
ing of his own being in a world is precisely what gives him access to
other beings and gives them the chance to show themselves in what and
how they are. It is important that the approach to things should be
appropriate to their way of being, so that they can show themselves gen-
uinely as they are. The most difficult among all beings to approach,
however, is Da-sein himself, owing to his tendency to cover over his
understanding of his own being by giving himself away to things.
Finding proper access both to Da-sein and to other beings, and
securing original evidence for every conclusion reached, is Heideg-
ger’s constant preoccupation throughout Being and Time . The method
he employs is one founded and developed by Husserl. Heidegger’s
method, in fact, is an application and adaptation of Husserl’ s phe-
nomenology to his own problems. But it should be pointed out straight-
away that this method is one of the grave difficulties of Being and Time
for those readers who are unfamiliar with Husserl’s work, even the
basic principles of which are hard to grasp. And just because they are,
a discussion of phenomenology has been deferred to the seventh chap-
Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time 27
ter of this part, though the logical order would require it to be placed
at the beginning.
One of the characteristics of Being and Time, owing largely to its
method, is the marked difference between Divisions One and Two,
and there is no doubt that if Division Three had been added to the
work, it would have proved different again from what has gone before.
The peculiar “ phasing” of the investigation poses a problem for anyone
writing a general introduction to Being and Time . At this stage, there-
fore, the present writer has deemed it best to set out Heidegger’ s prin-
cipal themes in separate studies. The series of studies contained in this
part are grouped as follows.
V. The Basic Mood of Dread ( Angst ) and the Being of Da sein as Care
The culmination of Division One in the analysis of dread and in the
exposition of the structure of care is presented in a summarized form
and elucidated as far as possible.
29
30 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
ger’s sense, only to real beings ( things ). It is true that this and that can
also happen to Da-sein, but, just because for Da-sein its own being is at
stake, even the accidents that can befall it have quite a different mean-
ing from the contingencies that can happen to a thing. Further, we talk
—
of possibilities in the sense of potentialities for example, the poten-
tiality of a seed to grow into a tree, or the possibilities of Da-sein to
develop its inborn faculties and dispositions.
These factical possibilities, however, are obviously not what Hei-
degger has primarily in view in his inquiry. Let us turn, therefore, to
the philosophical meaning of possibility . Here again we find that the
term has a wide range. First, there is the empty, logical concept of pos-
—
sibility as the sheer thinkability of something that is, something can
be thought without contradiction or absurdity. Further, possibility is
one of the modalities or modal categories of being, in contrast to actu-
ality and necessity. Here possibility means what is only possible, but
need not be actual and is never necessary. Traditionally, possibility is
held to be “ lower” than actuality and necessity, whereas Heidegger
emphasizes that, as the ontological character of existence, possible-
being is “ higher” than any actuality (SZ, 143f.). Further, the essence,
the whatness of a thing, is traditionally also called possibility. The
essence is that which makes it possible for a thing to be as it is.
Possibility in the last-named sense is relevant also to Heidegger,
who calls it Ermöglichung. It is the constitutive “ power ” that “ empow-
ers,” “ enables, ” “ makes capable of. . . .” When Heidegger speaks of the
“ essence” (Wesen ) of Da-sein, he usually means possibility in the sense
just defined. Accordingly, the well-known statement that the “ essence”
of Da-sein lies in its existence (SZ, 42 ) does not mean, as some inter-
pretations would have it, that Da-sein first of all “ really exists ” ( really
occurs) and then proceeds to produce its own essence; that is, to make
itself into who it is by exercizing its freedom of choice. It means that
understanding itself in its own ability-to-be enables Da-sein to be Da-
sein in the most essential respect, namely in respect of its self.
Confusing as the many meanings of possibility already are, an
even greater difficulty arises from the elusiveness of this concept.
There is something quite ungraspable about a possibility, even when
we think of it in the most concrete sense as the possibility of some real
happening. The question is whether this ungraspability is due to some
failure in our thinking, or whether it lies in the very being of possibil-
ity itself. In what way can a possibility be at all?
To answer this question, let us consider an empirical possibility in
contrast to an empirical fact. Supposing on a journey we approach a
certain district and come on a scene of devastation caused by an earth-
34 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
quake the day before, the disaster comes to our understanding as a fact
which, having occurred, is and cannot be altered or undone. Now let
us suppose that we approach another district and find people fleeing
from it, because an earthquake had been predicted for the following
day. This earthquake obviously comes to our understanding in quite a
different way from the one we experienced as a fact. What and how is
this earthquake which is not yet, but is coming? It is not a fact; it is not
—
real; it does not “ exist ” at all; and yet it is as a possibility. The whole
being of this earthquake lies in our understanding it as a possibility, as
something that can be. The disaster that has already happened is a real
event, regardless of whether any man discovers it and understands it in
its reality. But an earthquake that has not yet happened, only is insofar
as there is man to discover it in its possible-being. Had the earthquake
tomorrow not been predicted, and it really happened, it would always
be discoverable as a fact, but never again as it is now, as a possibility
that bears down on us in its uncertainty and threat, not the less threat-
ening because it may not really happen after all.
Events that come toward us from the future evidently only are as
possibilities, as events that can be. The remarkable thing about them is
that their being is in advance determined by a not . The can be in itself
implies that it can also not be. It would be impossible for us to under-
stand the “ can ” unless we understood it as “ possibly not.” Even when
we are so certain of something that we say it must be, we are implying
that it cannot be otherwise, because the conditions are such that all
possibilities except one are impossible. It does not matter, therefore,
—
how some future event is disclosed for example, whether the earth-
quake is predicted by the strictest scientific calculation, or on empiri-
cal evidence, or by casting a horoscope. This determines only the
ground and degree of its certainty, or likelihood, but does not in the
least take away the not that in advance belongs to our understanding of
possibilities as such.
It is clear, therefore, that the disquieting elusiveness of possibili-
ties lies in their very being, and does not primarily arise from the
imperfection of our thinking or the uncertainty of our knowledge. But
if already an empirical possibility, such as we have discussed, is hard to
grasp, how much more so Heidegger’s interpretation of existence as
“ possible-being, ” ( potentiality-of-being, ability-to-be ). The manifold
implications of this concept are for the most part still obscure, but one
meaning at least is beginning to emerge: existence is that way of being
which is capable of going out beyond what is to what is not, and so dis-
closes not actual things or beings, but the possibility of beings, the being
of beings in the mode of possibility.
The Being of Dasein 35
—
—
as care that Da-sein exists in such a complex and excentric way ahead
of himself, thrown back on to himself , losing himself we can legiti-
mately say that “ Da-sein exists,” meaning the whole of his being and
not merely a part of it. In the articulated whole of care, it is true, exis-
tence names only one strucure, but it is a structure in a whole which is
so originally one that any one of its articulations necessarily implies
the others. When we say “ Da-sein exists,” we are already saying, though
not explicitly expressing it, that he exists factically ( facticity, thrown-
ness), and that thus factically existing, he is already falling away from
himself to the things he meets within his world. Similarly, when we
speak of thrownness, we already imply that this thrown Da-sein is in the
way of existence, because only in coming back to himself in the possi-
bilities of his being can Da-sein find himself already thrown into a
world, and not merely occur in it like a thing. Similarly, when we speak
of falling or fallenness, we are already implying existence and thrown-
ness, for only a being who understands his being in a world can lose
himself to the things he meets within it. For a stone, it is impossible to
lose itself.
Nevertheless, it is not without reason that Heidegger says emphat-
ically “ Da-sein exists, ” rather than “ Da-sein is thrown ” or “ Da-sein is
falling away from himself.” In the articulated whole of care, existence
has a certain precedence, it plays a “ leading” role. In it is gathered the
most unique character of Da-sein’s being and the possibility of its
utmost illumination. As the “ fore going” way of care, existence may be
called in a preeminent sense the “ light” of Da-sein’s being. At the same
time, as Heidegger always emphasizes, Da-sein has an ontological cir-
38 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
self is determined by the way in which he lets his being be his. No Da-
sein has freely chosen his being; he may not have wished it if he had
had any say in the matter; nonetheless, he can freely take over his being
as his own responsibility, he can turn to it face to face, letting it fully
disclose itself as singly and uniquely his. Existing in this way, Da-sein is
wholly his own self, according to the fullest possibility of his finite
being. Or he can turn away from himself, not letting his being fully dis-
close itself as his own, covering over its finiteness by throwing himself
into those “ endless ” possibilities that come to him from his world.
Existing in this way, Da-sein disowns the possibility of the utmost illu-
mination of which his being is capable and falls into the disguise that
characterizes his lostness to the world.
While these basic ways of existing are neither subconscious
“ mechanisms” nor conscious and deliberate “ attitudes, ” they definitely
imply something like a “ relation ” of Da-sein to himself. Heidegger, in
fact, frequently and explicitly speaks of the ways in which Da-sein can
“ relate himself’ ( sich verhalten ) to himself, and means: Da-sein bears
himself toward , holds himself in, stands fast in, the possibilities of his
being in one way or another, not primarily by thinking about them , but
by throwing himself into them as best he can. This “ relation ” is very
near to what we have in mind when we speak of the way in which a Da-
sein lives. It is in his “ way of living” that a Da-sein stabilizes himself as
the factical self he is, that he stands fast in the being he bears in his
thrownness as care.
But if each Da-sein’s being, regardless of how it is his, is yet essen-
tially his own, it might be reasonable to suppose that he would tend to
“ own ” his being, while a disowned existence would seem to be an
exceptional falling away from the average, the norm. Heidegger’s the-
-
sis, however, is that the opposite is the truth: Da sein’s fundamental
tendency is to turn away from himself to a self-forgetful absorption in
his occupations in company with other people. Before his existence can
be properly his own, Da-sein has usually to wrest it back from its lost-
ness to the world.
In the first place and for the most part ( zunächst und zumeist ), Da-
sein understands himself not from his own being, but from what other
people think. Instead of the utmost illumination of which he is capa-
ble, Da-sein exists in a sort of “ public disclosedness,” whose very pub-
licity is a way of covering over that each Da-sein’s being is singly his
own. In the first place and for the most part, this is the way in which
Da-sein is himself from day to day, his average day, his every day. Every-
dayness ( Allt äglichkeit ) is Heidegger’s name for the average, undiffer-
entiated way in which Da-sein exists over most of his lifetime, living
42 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
unto the day, taking for variety what the day brings, what chances and
events, what successes and failures come to him from his world. In his
everydayness, Da-sein is so decisively orientated toward the world that
the possibility of understanding himself from his own being remains
obscured. When Heidegger speaks of an “ indifferent” everydayness, he
does not mean that this mode of existence ceases to be care, or that Da-
sein no longer exists for the sake of himself, let alone that he exists nei-
ther in one definite way nor in another, but means that the difference
between an owned and disowned self does not come to light, it remains
undifferentiated.
For Heidegger’s “ Preparatory Fundamental Analysis of Da-sein” it
is precisely this undifferentiated everydayness that is of utmost impor-
tance, because it constitutes the average manner of Da-sein’s being. But
even in this levelled-down uniformity, Da-sein still exists, he still under-
stands himself in his being. Da-sein can only be average in the way of
existence and not as an egg or an income is said to be average. Even in
the extremity of disownment, Da-sein can never become merely real like
a thing, or like an only-living-organism. His way of existing can be mod-
ified but can never become a different order of being.
The everyday mode of existence, just because it is nearest and
most familiar to us, has been consistently overlooked in philosophy,
and its ontological importance has not been realized. As Heidegger’s
inquiry will show, traditional ontology draws its idea of reality not from
the way it is originally manifest in Da-sein’s everyday ness, but from a
secondary and derivative modification of it. A remarkable feature of
Heidegger’s analysis of everyday existence is its aim to show the com-
plex and mysterious character of this most familiar way of Da-sein’s
being. It remains the leading theme throughout Division One, while
the owned way of existing becomes the main theme at the beginning
of Division Two, preparing the way for the interpretation of the fun-
damental temporality or “ timeishness ” ( Zeitlichkeit ) of Da-sein’s being.
Apart from Heidegger’s special key words, such as care , thrownness, and
worldishnessy there is the purely technical terminology of Being and Time
to be considered. The new theme of this work requires new terms,
some of which are parallel to those of traditional ontology, and some
of which are taken over from Husserl’s phenomenology, often with a
shift of meaning or emphasis. Among the latter, we have already come
across meaning ( Sinn ) and ontological structure ( Seinsstruktur ). We shall
now consider the following terms:
The Being of Da sein 43
—
—
themselves as properties and attributes that is, the spatial properties,
the attribute of relatedness, and so on whereby the being of things can
be determined.
— —
business of philosophy that is, philosophy in the strict and not the
popular sense is to inquire into the a priori, but different thinkers
have given varying interpretations of how this concept is to be under-
stood. Heidegger understands it as “ fore-going and going-hand-in-
hand-with” experience ( vorgängig und mitgä ngig ). Roughly speaking,
this means that what is already there in experience as the condition of
its possibility does not lie somewhere apart from and in a time before
46 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
once more that Heidegger frequently applies the simple terms ontolog-
ical and ontic to Da-sein. This practice will be followed in this book
when the long compound expressions would be too clumsy to use.
51
52 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
— —
these ontic concepts of “ world” namely, nature, the natural universe,
the all of beings are decisively rejected by Heidegger, so much so that
when he uses the term world in any of these senses, he always writes it
in quotation marks.
Three different meanings of the term world have now been indi-
cated, and, since they must be clearly distinguished in Being and Time,
the following summary may be found helpful:
- - -
1. In the existential constitution of Da sein as being in the-world,
-
“ . . . the-world” characterizes the way in which Da sein exists. It is an
existential-ontological concept.
2. The ontic-existentiell concept of a world in which Da-sein “ lives, ”
and more specifically, the nearest workaday world of everyday exis-
tence ( Umwelt ) , forms the basis and starting point of Heidegger’ s
analysis. It is from this world that his concrete illustrations and
examples are drawn.
3. The “ world , ” always written in quotation marks in Being and Time,
means a real connection of real beings, usually understood as
nature, or the totality of beings, but sometimes also denoting a
more indeterminate whole of things, facts, people, etc., of which we
The Worldishness of World 53
lem of Being and Time, namely, How is it possible for Da-sein to under-
stand being? What does being mean? The fundamental constitution of
being-in-the-world is not, as it is sometimes thought to be, an answer to
Heidegger’s question, but is a sharper and fuller formulation of the ques-
tion to be answered. In this formula, . . the-world” is a vast question
mark, whose meaning has been briefly indicated in the preceding para-
graph, but which must now be more fully explained as follows.
Da-sein , as the finite being he is, cannot himself make the beings
he needs, and cannot therefore know anything in advance of their real
qualities and properties, which are vital to him for his own existence.
Unable to create anything, Da-sein must be able to receive what is
already there, and not merely anyhow, in an unintelligible jumble of
impressions, but in such a way that these things become accessible as
the things they are, understandable in their being. This is only possible
if they can show themselves in a coherent whole, which is not merely
an empty frame, like an iron hoop holding a jumble of things together,
but is a whole that has a definite structure of its own, so that in it and
from it the multitude of beings are in advance understandable in an
articulated coherence.This structural whole ( world ), which Heidegger
will show to be a complex of references or relations, must enable Da-
sein to refer himself to other beings in a purposeful way, and, con-
versely, to relate them to himself in their relevance to and bearing upon
his own existence.
The articulated whole of a world, as was indicated above, is always
understood by us in advance, and cannot be retrospectively glued
together from any number of sense impressions and perceptions of
actual things, events, or people. On the contrary, if these perceptions
did not take place in a previously disclosed whole, any coherent and
intelligible experience would be impossible.
The disclosure of world necessarily goes before experience, and
one possible explanation is that the world must be “ formed ” in and
with Da-sein’s own being. Da-sein himself is “ world-forming, ” or, as it
may also be expressed, “ world-imaging” (weltbildend . WG, 39, W, 55,
G9, 158, ER, 89, P, 123). This “ world-image,” of course, must not be
thought of as a sort of advance copy of a flesh-and-blood world, but as
a wholly insubstantial horizon of meaning, a whole of reference in
which we always move with so much familiarity that we do not even
notice it. The ontological problem is to show and explain in detail how
Da-sein himself must be in order to be capable of “ fore-imaging” a
world to which experience has contributed nothing. This is the prob-
lem that Heidegger formulates with the fundamental constitution of
Da-sein as being-in-the-world. 1
The Worldishness of World 55
erally means how one is, how one feels. Important also is the core of the
word, sich finden, to find oneself. The whole expression may be explained
as follows: Da-sein is a priori so that his being manifests itself to him by
the way he feels; in feeling, he is brought to himself, he finds himself.
The ontic manifestations of Befindlichkeit are familiar to everyone as the
moods and feelings that constantly “ tune” Da-sein and “ tune him in ” to
other beings as a whole. To avoid having to coin some clumsy expression
for Befindlichkeit it is convenient to call it “ attunement.”
y
—
advance prescribes how their being is discoverable for example, as
threatening, as joyful, or whatever. The understanding fore- throw of
Da-sein’s possibilities of being not only embraces them in advance as a
whole, but with the for the sake of gives a fore-image of how the things
discoverable within it can “ hang together,” how they can “ make sense.”
The relational complex of “ by means of . . . in order to . . . for . . • j
sein is not only not locked into a world of his own, but the world is his
in such a way that he in advance shares it with others like himself .
Da-sein’ s relation to other Da-seins is shown by Heidegger to be
fundamentally different from his relation to things. Being-with others
like himself ( Mitsein ) belongs directly to Da-sein’s existence (self ) and
helps to constitute its world-forming character, whereas his being-near-
to things ( Sein-bei ) is founded upon his thrownness and factical depen-
dence on a world. Da-sein cannot be with things in a mutually shared
world, because things are only inner worldly ( innerweltlich ) ; they are dis-
coverable within the world , but are unable to disclose their own being
in a world.
When Heidegger speaks of “ world ” ( nature) in quotation marks,
he usually means purely an ontic connection of things, because beings
who exist as Da-sein can never merely occur in nature like things, which
have the character of reality. The fundamental difference between the
way Da-sein relates himself to fellow existences and the way in which he
refers himself to things also helps to explain why Heidegger cannot
work out both relations at the same time in his world-analysis (SZ, Div.
One, chap. 3). The theme of fellow existences is introduced into the
analysis only briefly; its detailed elucidation is left over to a subsequent
chapter ( Div. One, chap. 4 ). The ontological structure of world is
worked out by Heidegger exclusively from the relation-complex ( “ by
means of . . .” etc. ) whereby Da-sein refers himself to things. Following
Heidegger’s own trend, the theme of Da-sein’s everyday self in relation
to other selves will be dealt with separately in this book, after the dis-
cussion of world and of the reality of things within the world has been
concluded ( Part II, chap. 4 of this book ).
Accordingly, we will at this stage confine our attention to Da-
sein’s being-near- to things, or, as it may also be expressed, his staying-
close-to the “ world ” { Sein-bei ). How are Da-sein’s dealings with things
characterized by Heidegger? Since Da-sein inhabits the world by way of
care, each of his fundamental relations must have a specific care-char-
acter: he is near to things by “ taking care” of them { besorgen ) . “ Taking
care” is an existential-ontological term whose meaning may be
explained as follows. A basic way in which Da-sein inhabits his world is
to reckon with things , to take account of things. With Da-sein’ s factical
existence, his taking care of things splits itself up into an extraordinary
variety of ways, of which Heidegger gives a long list of examples: “ to
have to do with something, to produce, order and take care of some-
thing, to use something, to give something up and let it get lost, to
undertake, to accomplish , to find out, to ask about, to observe, to speak
about, to undermine . . .” (SZ, 56 ). Among the deficient modes of tak-
The Worldishness of World 65
stood as belonging to a world and having their place within it are now
stripped of their boundaries; they no longer meet Da-sein in the hori-
zon of the primary for the sake of\ but in an indifferent world-all, a nat-
ural universe, where they occur in space as purely substantial bodies.
Theory is an only-looking which strips things of their world-character
and objectivizes them into mere material substances to be found some-
where in an indifferent universal space (SZ, 358ff.; also 112 ).
The incalculable importance of this fundamental modification in
Da-sein’s understanding of things is that it is from things as mere sub-
stances that Greek-Western philosophy takes its start. The conse-
quences of this start for Western science and technology are a con-
stantly recurring theme in Heidegger’s later works and deserve serious
study. In Being and Time, however, the ontological theme predomi-
nates, and this is our concern at present.
What are the philosophical consequences of the theoretical start
from things as pure substances? The first and most decisive conse-
quence is that the world, in Heidegger’s sense, is passed over from the
beginning and cannot become even a problem. Nature, the all of
beings, is substituted for the genuine phenomenon of world, giving
rise to perennial problems of cognition and knowledge, for whose solu-
tion countless “ theories of knowledge” have been constructed.
Traditional problems of cognition, Heidegger points out, have
their source in an insufficient interpretation of Da-sein’s being (SZ,
59ff.). The puzzle which hosts of theories of knowledge set out to
explain is how a supposedly isolated self, a subject, can get out from his
“ inner sphere” to an object, the “ world ” outside himself. But, as Hei-
degger shows, the completely unjustifiable assumption on which all
these theories are based is that Da-sein is first of all a “ worldless sub-
ject” who has subsequently to transcend himself in order to take up a
relation to his object, the “ world.” In Heidegger’s interpretation, on
the contrary, Da-sein is never worldless, and the world is not an object
to which he has to “ get out.” Da-sein is such that his own being is in
advance manifest to him in a significant reference-whole ( world ), in
which and from which he directs himself toward . . . , relates himself
to . . . whatever specific beings he may meet. Only this a priori world-
ishness of Da-sein makes it possible for him to “ take up relations” to
things in a secondary and derivative way, for example, in explicitly
investigating and explaining them, in widening and developing knowl-
edge in various directions, and so on.
It is the world-forming character of man’s being that is presup-
posed in all theories of knowledge which take their start from the “ sub-
ject-object relation ” as the supposed “ ultimate ” that cannot be further
68 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
The term Umwelt, together with two other key words, Umgang and
Umsicht, has so essential a meaning in Heidegger’s world-analysis that
it well deserves a short discussion on its own.
It is not by accident that each of these key words begins with Um .
This word is already familiar to us as the for of for the sake of . A second
meaning of Urn now appears for the first time: it indicates the spatial
relation of round-aboutness, nearness, in the sense of immediate sur-
roundings. From what we have learned so far, it is evident that for Hei-
degger the primary meaning of Urn is for, but, since something like
space essentially belongs to a world, the secondary meaning of round-
aboutness must also prove to be relevant.
We shall first consider Umwelt in its secondary meaning, because
this is how in ordinary usage the word is generally understood. Accord-
ingly, Umwelt means a world that is round -about us, a world that is near-
est, first at hand. There is no appropriate single word in English for
Umwelt . For most purposes, it can be quite adequately rendered by
“ environment, ” but this rendering will not be adopted here. Owing to
The Worldishness of World 69
world ); going about the world and about our practical business with
things; looking around, circumspection. Suggestive as all this is in itself,
what Heidegger intends to say comes fully to light only when we turn
to the Um in its primary sense of for.
Da-sein’s first and nearest world is evidently the for-world, in the
strict sense that the form, the “ how ” of its coherence is given by the for
the sake of his own existence. This prescribes the character of signifi-
cance, the specific for-worldishness of the everyday world, by the rela-
tional complex “ by means o f . . . in order to . . . for. . . .” Da-sein inhab-
its his nearest for-world by going about his business in it: his going
about is for something, whether the something is directly for his own
sake, or for the sake of others or whether it is in order to achieve some-
thing else to be taken care of. Da-sein’s going about his business for
something is in advance guided by a circumspect for-sight, which dis-
covers what things are for, under what circumstances they can be used
as means. What circumspect for-sight has “ its eye on ” in advance is the
primary world-form of for the sake of with which the whole significance-
structure of “ by means o f . . . in order to” is disclosed in an original,
indivisible unity. With the concept of circumspect for-sight, Heidegger
gives an existential-ontological explanation of what is familiar to us as
common sense. The Da-sein of common sense sees things in advance
in the light of their possible utility, harmfulness, relevance, or irrele-
vance to circumstances. The commonsense view is only possible on the
basis of an existential understanding, which fore-throws the possibili-
ties of Da-sein’s existence as his world, in the “ light” of which alone the
possibilities of things in their relevance to . . . , their bearing upon . . .
this or that situation become understandable.
But now the inevitable question arises. Is this everyday under-
standing of things not merely “ subjective” ? Is the only-looking of the-
ory not truer, because it is more “ objective” ? These questions will be
dealt with in the next chapter, where the reality of beings within the
world will be our theme.
Ill
The Reality of Beings
within the World
The preceding chapters have already shown that reality has a much
more restricted meaning in Being and Time than in traditional ontolo-
gies. Not only Da-sein’s being is taken out of the sphere of reality but
also all existential phenomena, such as, for instance, time and world.
These only “ are” when a disclosure of being happens. There is one phe-
nomenon of a rather ambiguous character, however, which requires
some consideration, and this is language. The existential foundation of
language is, indeed, obvious, and yet it is readily overlooked. The rea-
son is that the words of a language can be collected and preserved in
books, in which they acquire a certain reality within the world; they
become accessible just like things. Hence one can get the impression
that language consists of word-things to which meanings are added.
The truth , according to Heidegger’s interpretation, is exactly the oppo-
site: Da-sein’s factical existence discloses world as a significance-whole
that can be articulated into those “ significances ” for which words grow
(SZ, § 34, esp.161).
The sphere of reality is thus restricted by Heidegger to those
—
beings that are independent of a disclosure of being for example,
plants, animals, the earth, the seas and the stars. All these real things,
with their ontic properties and connections, are independent of the
disclosure that happens with Da-sein’s existence. They are there,
regardless of whether they are discovered or not. Their being, their
71
72 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
— —
ascribe all kinds of “ values” to them. The simplest utensil a knife, for
instance cannot be grasped in its being as a merely substantial thing.
The knife is essentially “ more” than a material body of such and such
properties, of such and such appearance, size, and weight. It is this
“ more” we try to explain when we ascribe a “ usefulness value” to the
knife. What happens, in fact, is that, standing, as we do, in a long onto-
logical tradition, we unquestioningly take it for granted that the knife
is merely substantially real, thereby covering over our original under-
standing of its being as relevant to . . . , handy for. . . . We first strip the
thing bare of what belongs to it as a utensil, then try to restore what we
have taken away by adding to it a value.
But, it may be asked, does Heidegger’s interpretation not apply
only to manmade utensils? These, admittedly, are “ more” than mere
substances, but what about the material bodies that are simply there in
nature? These also, according to Heidegger, are originally understood
by us in their handy-being. What, for instance, could be more handily
there than the sun, and what could be less manmade? It is not primar-
ily our labor that makes things into utensils; it is the significance-struc-
ture of our world that enables us to understand things as utensils. Only
on the ground of this understanding are we able to improve on what
we find, and so make tools that are even handier, even more “ valuable”
for some specific purpose.
As to the philosophical concept of values, and the elaborate the-
ories of values that have been worked out in the modern era of phi-
74 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
Da-sein is able to relate himself to his fellow men only because his own
being is in advance disclosed to him as being-with. This fundamental
structure of Da-sein’s self is the existential foundation of all that we
usually speak of under the title of personal relations and human soci-
ety. If, as a matter of common experience, Da-sein constantly enters
into all kinds of associations with other men, this is not the result of
the “ fact” that he is not the only one of his kind in the world, but the
other way round: he can recognize others like himself in the world and
enter into relations with them because his own being is disclosed to
him as being-with. When there are “ in fact” no others, when Da-sein is
alone, he does not thereby cease to-be-with others, and this funda-
mental character of his being manifests itself with peculiar intensity in
his loneliness, in his missing the others. Even when Da-sein thinks he
does not need the others, when he withdraws from them and has noth-
ing to do with them, this is still only possible as a privative mode of
being-with.
To our usual way of thinking, it seems the most obvious fact that
Da-sein can understand others in their being, both as like himself and
as other than himself. Ontologically, this fact is a problem that is nei-
ther obvious nor easy to explain. In Husserl’s phenomenological
75
76 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
selves; the others are those among whom I also am , among whom I also
find myself. In his self-forgetful everydayness, Da-sein is in the first
place and for the most part not himself.
What does Heidegger mean by the startling announcement that,
in his everyday existence, Da-sein is not himself ? Negatively, he clearly
cannot mean that Da-sein suddenly loses his I-character and ceases to
be a self altogether; he can only mean that Da-sein exists as a self in one
of the definite ways that are open to him. How this way of not-being-
oneself is to be positively understood will become clear in the next sec-
tion , where we shall consider Heidegger’s answer to the question Who
is the self of everydayness?
The most salient point that has emerged from Heidegger’s analysis can
be briefly stated as follows. In the everyday world, the others meet us
as what they are in their makings and doings: “ They are what they do”
(SZ, 126 ).
What Heidegger emphatically says in the sentence “ They are what
they do ” seems at first sight easy to understand. When someone asks
us “ Who is so and so? ” we almost automatically reply, “ He is a surgeon,
a businessman , a student of philosophy,” or whatever. But, when we
come to think of it, is this habit easy to explain just because it is famil-
iar ? Is it so “ natural ” that the self each Da-sein is should be manifest to
us from his profession ? How is it possible for us to characterize Da-
sein ’s self from what he does? This is the question Heidegger goes on
to answer in the paragraph which immediately follows the sentence
—
“ They are what they do” a short paragraph that is not only the deci-
sive step taken in the present analysis but is one of the key passages of
Being and Time, and, as such , is not fully comprehensible where it
stands. It is only about halfway through Division Two that this passage
will retrospectively come to clarity. Meantime, let us see how far we can
understand at present the existential-ontological explanation Heideg-
ger gives of “ who’s who ” in the everyday world.
In the first place , how does Da-sein understand himself as a self
at all? Primarily, as has been shown in our discussion of existence , from
the possibilities of his being. These are originally manifest from the pos-
sibility of a not , which belongs to each Da-sein singly and uniquely. In
the finiteness of his being, each Da-sein is sheerly uninterchangeable;
no one can stand in for him there , no one can take his being off him
and bear it for him. But in everyday being-together, Da-sein turns away
Being-with-Others and Being-One's-Self 81
from the possibility that is most his own and understands himself from
his worldish possibilities among other selves. In his everydayness, Da-
sein in advance measures his own self by what the others are and have,
by what they have achieved and failed to achieve in the world. He thus
understands himself in his difference from the others by the distance
that separates his own possibilities from theirs. “ Being-with-one-
another is, unknown to itself, disquieted by the care about this dis-
tance” (SZ, 126 ). Everyone measures his distance and so “ stands off ” as
himself from the others. This existential “ distantiality ” or “ stand-off-
ishness ” ( Abst ändigeit ) can concretize itself in many different ways. It is
there, for instance, in the care to catch up with the others, to “ do as the
Joneses do.” Or it may manifest itself in the opposite way, in going all
out to consolidate some privilege or advantage one has gained and so
keep the others down in their possibilities. All kinds of social distinc-
tions, whereby Da-sein understands his own existence by his distance
from others in class, race, education, and income are grounded in the
existential stand-offishness, which means: in the first place and for the
most part, Da-sein understands his existence by “ standing off ” from the
others and not by the genuine possibilities that lie in the uniqueness of
his finite self. In his everydayness, Da-sein looks away from the true dis-
tance, the limit of his finite being, from which alone he can become
truly transparent as the self he is, and measures his self in advance by
his distance from what the others are and do.
This existential stand-offishness implies that in everyday exis-
tence Da-sein draws the possibilities of his being from what is pre-
scribed and decided on by others. He is thus delivered over to the sub-
servience of domination ( Botmässigleit ) by the others and disburdened
of the being that is singly and solely his. In everyday being- together, Da-
sein is not himself; the others have taken his being away from him (SZ,
126 ). But who are the others? They are not this one or that one, not
anybody or the sum of all: “ they ” are just “ people, ” the people of whom
we say “ people think so, ” and “ people don’ t wear that any more.” We
call them “ they” and “ people ” to hide that we essentially belong to
them, not by what we in fact think and do but in being as we are, mea-
suring the possibilities of our own existence from what “ they ” say one
can be and do.
Since in everyday being- together, “ they, ” the others , are not any
definite others, they are essentially interchangeable; anyone can stand
in for everybody else , anybody can represent and substitute anyone
else, almost like a thing which can just as well represent its genus and
species as any other thing. With this, the ontological character of Da-
sein’s being, which is always singly and uniquely my being, comes into
82 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
a mode of not-being in the sense that it is not itself according to its own-
most possibility. This is the strictly ontological meaning of Heidegger’s
thesis that, in his everyday being-in-the-world, it is not Da-sein himself
who is there, but it is “ they,” people, who are there, oneself among them.
In the first place and for the most part, the who of everydayness, the
everyday self, is the “ they” ( Das Man ) .
Because of their interchangeability, it is in principle impossible to
pin down who “ they ” are to any definite persons. It is precisely in their
inconspicuousness that “ they ” exercise a dictatorship that can never be
brought home to anyone, so that no one can be made responsible for
it. There are many social-historical forms in which the dictatorship of
“ them” can concretize itself. It would be a complete misundersanding
of the existential-ontological idea of a “ they-self ’ to think that it applies
only to modern society in some specific political-social forms. If Hei-
degger is right at all in saying that to exist as a they-self is one of the
possibilities of Da-sein’s finitely free being, then this possibility is open
to Da-sein by virtue of his own being and not by the accident of this or
that form of society.
Indeed , no specific oppression is needed to establish the power
of “ them, ” because the tendency to level down and average out the dis-
tinctiveness of each self is there already in being-together-in-the-world.
The reduction to uniformity happens simply in taking care of a mutu-
ally shared world; in using its public facilities, newspapers, entertain-
ments, and the like. Here everybody is like everybody else. The exis-
tential tendency to average out and level down all differences is
commented on by Heidegger in the words: “ Overnight, everything pri-
mordial is flattened down as something long since known. Everything
gained by a struggle becomes something to be manipulated. Every mys-
tery loses its power ” (SZ, 127).
Heidegger goes on to explain how and why this happens. Stand-
offishness, averaging-out and levelling-down constitute the “ publicity”
{ Öffentlichkeit ) of an average understanding of being. This public under-
standing in advance leads and determines all explanations of self and
world, not because it goes deeply into things but, on the contrary,
because it is insensitive to differences of genuineness and niveau. In this
average, public understanding, everything becomes accessible and com-
monplace, and no one is responsible for having made it so. It is “ they ”
who have understood and decided how things must be. “ They” thus dis-
burden everyday existence of responsibility, for “ they ” are strictly speak-
ing nobody who could be taken to account for anything said and done; it
is always the “ others ” who have said and done so. In everyday being-
together, “ Everyone is the other and no one is himself ’ (SZ, 128).
Being-with-Others and Being-One ’s-Self 83
It is in “ them,” who are nobody, that the everyday self finds its
first stability ( Ständigleit ): it stands as not-itself. This “ standing, ” of
course, is not the sheer lastingness of a thing. Although scattering him-
self into a they-self, Da-sein can never become a pure “ what” ; even to-
be-not-himself and nobody is still only possible to a self.
“ They ” must therefore never be thought of as a genus of which
each everyday self is a sample, but as a basic way in which Da-sein can
exist as a self . It is for the sake of the they-self that Da-sein in the first
place and for the most part exists. This primary for the sake of articulates
the significance - whole of the world in which Da-sein lives and pre-
scribes the average possibilities of being-in-the-world. But just because
these possibilities are understood from what “ they ” are and do, the
everyday self covers over its own unique character. It is from the aver-
age, public understanding of being that traditional ontology took its
start and has been consistently misled by it to ascribe to Da-sein’s
essence, his self, the ontological character of a substance.
The “ owned ” self of a resolutely disclosed existence is not a dif-
ferent order of being, not some exception or genius that hovers over
“ them, ” but is a modification of “ them, ” a resolute gathering of one’s
self from its scatteredness into a they-self. “ They ” are a fundamental
existential and not some ontic quality of Da-sein produced by external
conditions. Even less are “ they, ” as is often thought, a contemptible fig-
ure of ridicule, although, it must be confessed , Heidegger’s language
in speaking of the they-self would sometimes almost justify such a con-
clusion. As against this, Heidegger’s own ontological tendency must be
held fast. Properly considered, indeed, “ they ” are far from ridiculous,
but a more shattering document of man’s finite being than the
“ owned ” self of a resolutely disclosed existence can ever be.
become the medium for uprooting Da sein from his primary under-
standing of existence and his nearness to things.
Discourse has thus always the possibility of becoming what Hei-
degger calls Gerede, a word for which we have many approximations,
none of which hits the target clean in the center. Chatter, gossip, idle
talk, groundless talk, bottomless talk, hearsay, all hover on the circum-
ference. “ Hearsay, ” although it is not a translation of Gerede, can per-
haps best convey what Heidegger means, but because it is a literal
translation of Hörensagen, a word Heidegger uses several times in Being
and Time, we shall follow the widespread practice of translating Gerede
as “ idle talk ” ; it is the kind of talk that hears, that is, understands what
is said, then passes on ( says on ) what has been learned by hearing with-
out “ getting to the bottom” of what the talk is about.2 Writing, as a
mode of communicating discourse, can bring a further uprooting into
everyday existence. Like genuine talk, so genuine writing can degener-
ate into an idle scribbling ( Geschreibe ), which is not so much a “ hear-say”
as a “ read-say,” feeding itself on what has already been written and
passing it on as a supposed contribution toward keeping the dis-
closedness of world open. “ The average understanding of the reader
will never be able to decide what has been drawn from primordial
sources with a struggle, and how much is just gossip” (SZ, 169 ).
Groundless hearsay or idle talk thus helps to “ publish ” an average
explanation of existence and world in everyday being-together. It offers
the possibility of understanding everything without going into any-
thing. It develops an average understandability to which nothing
remains hidden, so that it in advance hinders and closes a deeper and
more genuine approach to things. It is in itself a disguising and cover-
ing-over, although, as Heidegger emphatically points out, there is no
intention in it to deceive or falsify. Idle talk, simply by omitting to dis-
cover things in themselves, is a falsification of speech in the genuine
sense, whose whole function is to be discovering, that is, to be true,
according to Heidegger’ s interpretation of truth, as we shall see in a
later chapter.
All of us grow up in and draw our first understanding of things
from the average explanation of being and beings “ published” by
everyday hearsay. Much that is useful is learned from hearsay, the com-
mon basis on which, and from which, and against which , all genuine
understanding and communicating and rediscovering take place. No
Da-sein can ever keep himself “ untouched and unseduced ” by the
explanations made public in hearsay (SZ, 169). It decides in advance
—
even the possibilities of attunement that is, of the basic way in which
Da-sein lets the world touch him , concern him . “ They ” have always
86 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
already prescribed what one sees and how one feels about the world
and oneself.
In everyday being-together, whose openness is essentially consti-
tuted by hearsay, Da-sein’s existence is cut off from its primary rela-
tions to itself, to fellow existences and to the world. Its roots are slack-
ened and it sways uncannily in its hold on the disclosedness of self and
world ( Schwebe ) . Yet, even the uncanniness of this swaying is hidden by
the self-assurance and bland matter-of-courseness of an everyday
understanding (SZ, 170 ).
( c ) Ambiguity
each other that points to a basic mode of Da-sein’s being. This is ana-
lyzed by Heidegger just before the opening of the sixth and last chap-
ter of Division One. The place of this analysis, which is entitled “ Falling
and Thrownness,” already indicates its methodological importance to
the whole first division of Being and Time, providing, as it will turn out,
the basis for the exposition of Da-sein’s being as care.
new step whose connection with what has gone before is not at all evi-
dent and seems even to contradict it. The whirling movement of the
fall, Heidegger says, characterizes not only the existential constitution
of being-in-the-world but at the same time makes manifest the “ throw ”
of thrownness. Da-sein’s thrownness is never a finished fact, which hap-
pens once at birth and is then left behind: as long as Da sein in fact
exists, he “ remains in the throw, ” which whirls him away into disown-
ment to “ them ” ( SZ, 179 ).
But how is it, we ask ourselves, that the “ falling, ” which was first
explained from the fore-throw of understanding, suddenly turns out to
arise from the “ throw ” of thrownness? How do these two hang
together? Presumably, the connection would be clear if we understood
exactly what Heidegger means by saying that Da sein “ remains in the
throw, ” but this suggestive phrase fails to convey any precise meaning
at the moment. Or is it perhaps wrong to take it for granted that the
phrase must have a precise meaning? Should it not be regarded rather
as a figure of speech, suggestive, and inevitably blurred at the edges?
This would go against all that we have come to know of Heidegger’s
thought, a thought that is incomparably strict and translucently clear,
provided, of course, that the grave difficulties of penetrating to it are
overcome, and even more, that the clarity proper to an inquiry into
being is not expected to be of the same kind as the clarity proper to a
mathematical theorem or to a report of a football match. On the basis
of what our previous discussions have shown, we can confidently
expect that Da sein “ remains in the throw ” in a strict and precisely
understandable sense that will come to light when all that is most basic
to Heidegger’s thought has been brought into view. Much of it still
remains to be discovered. The next chapter, while it cannot take us the
whole way, will take us an important step nearer to clarifying the con-
nection between the fore-throw of understanding and the throw of
thrownness.
V
The Basic Mood of Dread (Angst )
and the Being of Da-sein as Care
91
92 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
understood. In order to fix the place of a thing “ over there” at such and
such a distance and in this or that direction from us, we must be able
to relate ourselves to it, so to speak, in a “ whereish ” fashion. What
enables us to do so is the disclosure of whereness ( place ) itself. This
happens directly and elementally in the nowhere of dread. The
nowhere does not arise from thinking of all possible places together
and then negating them. On the contrary, the very indefiniteness of
the nowhere brings to light purely the where, or more exactly, the
whereness solely by itself. It is only because whereness is always mani-
fest to us that we can and must relate ourselves to the things we meet
by giving them a definite where, a place. Far from being a negation of
all possible places, the nowhere is the possibility of place. It makes pos-
sible the discovery of the place and space that essentially belong to and
help to constitute the world.
The world itself is directly revealed in the nothing of dread. This
nothing is not an absolute, total nothing, nor is it an absence or nega-
tion of all things, but the sheer other to things as such. It is only
because we in advance look beyond things to the nothing revealed in
dread that things can and must show themselves to us as a whole, as
things and not nothing. Only from the disclosed whole of things can any
single thing stand out and show that it stands in itself as the thing it is.
The solid, stable standing-in-itself of a tree, a house, a mountain is pre-
cisely what we mean when we point to it and say It really is there, it
really exists.
Heidegger’s interpretation of dread complements his earlier
world-analysis. In working out the worldishness of world, Heidegger
showed how the world is as a coherent reference-whole in which Da sein
understands himself among other beings. This understanding is only
possible if beings are given the chance to show themselves in their bod-
ily presence, in what is traditionally called their real existence. It is pri-
marily the function of attunement to disclose the presence of beings as
a whole. Each mood, it was said earlier, lifts Da-sein into the midst of
beings, which are always manifest in a certain wholeness. How and why
this is so could not be explained earlier, because it is only in his analy-
sis of dread that Heidegger takes up this problem and offers his solu-
tion of it. It is the nothing of dread that opens up the horizon from
which and against which beings stand out as a whole. Far from being a
negation of all things, the nothing is the possibility of things: it gives
things the possibility to show themselves as they are in themselves. This
possibility, in Heidegger’s interpretation , is the world itself.
Hence the world cannot be a thing, a reality that exists indepen-
dently: the world is only a fundamental way in which Da-sein himself
The Basic Mood of Dread ( Angst ) and the Being of Dasein as Care 95
exists. When, therefore, dread brings Da-sein face to face with the world
itself, it brings him directly before his own being as being-in-the-world.
What dread dreads, the dreadsome, is being-in the-world itself (SZ, 187).
The revelation of Da-sein’s own being in dread does not happen
in a thinking and judging and making propositions about an object to
be dreaded , but in the way proper to attunement. Dreading itself
reveals to Da -sein elementally and purely his thrown being-in-the-world.
As a mode of attunement, dread is at the same time “ dread
for. . . T h i s cannot be for a definite possibility of a factical existence,
which threatened by this or that definite thing or event. Any such
is
definite threat is in advance excluded by the nature of dread itself.
The passage just quoted, and what follows immediately after, will
prove to be of central importance to the inquiry into the “ owned ” way
of existing to be carried out in Division Two of Being and Time . It is
dread as “ dread for . . . ,” as Heidegger points out, which makes mani-
fest to Da-sein his freedom for being his own self as a possibility. The pre-
eminent revealing power of dread lies in bringing Da-sein before the
finite freedom of his being-in-the-world, as the same being into which
he is already thrown and delivered.
With the exposition of the full structure of dread, Heidegger has
brought its strange and unique character into view. What dread dreads
is a thrown being-in-the-world. This has proved to be the same as what
dread is for. the ability-to-be-in-the-world. But not only that. As Hei-
degger emphatically points out, the sameness extends even over
dreading itself , which, as an attunement, is a fundamental way of
being-in-the-world. The sameness of the disclosing with the disclosed
world, to our usual way of thinking, appears to be something in the
nature of an empty tautology, a “ going round in a circle ” that can pro-
duce no results. Ontologically, however, it is precisely the sameness
96 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
101
102 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
BW, 119ff.).
At first sight, it might seem to be a mild kind of criticism of the
traditional definition of truth to say merely that it is derivative. But,
it must be remembered, Heidegger is not talking about just any kind
of study; he is talking of philosophy, whose business is to go to the
original source. In its sphere, any derivation is in itself a de-genera-
tion. How is the derivative propositional truth, which Heidegger
holds to have usurped a dominant place in philosophy, further eluci -
dated by him ?
Propositions, statements, judgments, or pronouncements of any
kind are ontic phenomena that belong to language. Language, as Hei-
degger’s previous inquiries have shown, requires for its foundation
existential discourse [ Rede ) , which has been defined as the articulation
of understandability. The function of communicating pronounce-
ments is to share the already disclosed being-in, self , world, and beings
within the world with the listener and so bring him into a disclosing
relation to the things talked about. Among the many possible kinds
and modes of pronouncements, the propositions that logical theories
of truth have in view are far from being primary. This is interestingly
shown by Heidegger in a simple but illuminating example. He com-
pares the everyday pronouncement “ The hammer is too heavy” with
Truth, Being, and Existence 103
said that truth is “ relative ” to Da-sein’s being. But does this “ relativity”
mean that truth is delivered over to the arbitrary invention of a subject
and to the fallibility of his thinking? This is far from what Heidegger
intends to say. Original truth as the disclosure of being, Heidegger
says, a priori determines Da-sein’s being through and through. His own
way of being is the last thing Da-sein could ever invent or think out for
himself. Truth is anything but the achievement of a subject or a prod-
uct of his thinking faculties; it is the existential structure of care that is
in advance so “ organized, ” so “ laid on,” as to make Da-sein open both
to himself and to other beings. If Da-sein is able to discover any truth
by his own efforts, this is only possible for him because he himself is let
into the original happening of truth, for which he is used and needed,
and only in being so used and needed is he able to exist as Da sein ( GE,
34ff., 59ff., DT, 62ff., 8 Iff.). It is not Da-sein who disposes of truth,
rather is it truth that disposes of Da-sein.
Just because truth is not the property or invention of Da-sein, it
in advance assigns to him the way and direction in which disclosing
and discovering can proceed. For instance, as we saw earlier, the artic-
ulated significance-whole of world ( ontological truth ) already pre-
scribes definite ways in which the things discoverable within it can
“ hang together, ” can “ make sense.” The predisclosed whole of signifi-
cance itself directs Da-sein toward . . . , refers him to . . . , other beings
in certain ways, and so enables Da-sein to take his direction from . . • >
to keep himself right by . . . , the things themselves that meet him
within his world. The discovery of things ( ontic truth ) is not arbitrary
and lawless, because it is in advance directed to bind itself to the things
themselves. This is why ontic truth must prove and verify itself in and
by the things that it brings to light.
Since, however, all the ways in which Da-sein exists are grounded
in his finite freedom, in his disclosing relation to things, he can omit
verification, he can refuse to let them show themselves as they are in
themselves, he can force them into horizons of explanation that are
completely alien to them. The seemingly obvious principle that, in an
explicit inquiry into any specific kind of beings, the way of approach ,
the method of investigation and verification, must be drawn from their
way of being and not from some preconceived notion of scientific
truth, is frequently stressed by Heidegger, who is never afraid of saying
the “ obvious” where it is necessary. In view of the widespread desire
today to approximate every explanation to the exactness of mathemat-
ics, Heidegger lays emphasis on the following points.
1. The exactness of cognition is not necessarily synonymous with
essential truth. For instance, the measurements of time and space in
Truth, Being, and Existence 105
our everyday world are ludicrously inaccurate compared with the sci-
entific measurements of events that happen to substances in an indif-
ferent universal space (SZ, § 23). Nevertheless, statements like “ It’s a
stone’s throw away,” or, “ You can walk there in half an hour, ” are defi-
nitely understandable and perfectly appropriate to a world inhabited
by everyday care. The paths on which Da-sein carefully goes about his
business are different every day, but it is precisely in this way that the
“ real world ” is originally discovered and is truly at hand. It is , therefore,
not a priori certain that when we have exactly measured, say, the dis-
tance of the sun from the earth, and measured the sun itself as a com-
plex of moving particles, we have understood it more truly than when
everyday care discovers its handiness for warmth and light, for growth
and life.
2. The prevalent tendency to regard the exactness of mathemat-
ics as the standard for the strictness of scientific truth is vigorously con-
tested by Heidegger. Exactness, he maintains, is not synonymous with
strictness (SZ, § 32, esp. 153). Mathematics is not stricter than history,
it is only more exact, and it can be so only because the existential foun-
dations relevant to it are much narrower than those required for his-
tory. As for philosophy itself , the strictness of thought it demands can-
not be approached by any ontic science, yet its findings are in principle
not susceptible of the kind of proof and demonstration that are possi-
ble to the ontic sciences. Its method and mode of verification, as we
shall see in the next chapter on phenomenology, must be drawn from
the unique nature of its own subject matter.
Since philosophy concerns itself with being, whose disclosure is
truth itself, Heidegger assigns to philosophy the highest place among
all explicit, “ thematic ” inquiries into truth. At the same time, he vig-
orously insists that no philosophy can in principle claim to be absolute
or the only possible one. Like all explanation and interpretation, it is
one of the finite possibilities of Da-sein’s existence, and as such it
stands at the same time in truth and in untruth.
As a factically existing being-in-the-world, Da-sein stands co-origi-
nally in truth and untruth. Just as the disclosing way of existence can-
not be of Da-sein’s own making, so the possibility of hiding, erring, and
covering over cannot originally be in Da-sein’s own power. Da-sein errs,
not only and not primarily because his intellect is fallible and he can-
not in fact know everything, but because hiddenness and concealment
essentially belong to the event of unhiddenness and disclosure. It is
paradoxical, and yet understandable, that the most original truth lies
precisely in revealing the hidden as hidden. It is the recoil from this
abyss of truth that sends Da-sein back to beings, at the same time
106 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
whirling him away from himself to the things within his world. Da sein
errs away from himself, not by a conscious or subconscious act of self-
deception , nor even aware of a desire to cover over the finiteness of
existence, but because it belongs to his thrown and falling way of being.
Untruth as hiddenness, erring, and covering over originally belongs
together with truth as unhiddenness, disclosure, and discovery; the two
are one and the same event.
The existential interpretation of truth , Heidegger maintains, is
the necessary interpretation of the insight into truth that lies in our
oldest philosophical tradition and is expressed in the word alë theia.
The goddess of truth leads Parmenides before the ways of discovery
and concealment, between which the thinker has to choose by under-
standingly distinguishing the two and deciding for one. This means
that Da sein stands co-originally in truth and untruth. The same tradi-
tion, moreover, has always brought together truth and being. Par-
menides said: to gar auto noein estin te kai einai ( Fragment 5, quoted in
SZ, 212, and very often in Heidegger’s later works), “ The same namely
are apprehending and being.” Although this oldest insight into the
essence of truth begins to be covered over already in Greek philosophy,
it reasserts itself at its end with Aristotle, who can still identify truth
with being and beings, calling the latter “ the unhidden, ” “ the self-show-
ing> »> « the true.”
The logical definitions of truth that later become dominant in
Western philosophy also have their roots in Greek thought. The theory
of propositional truth is an offspring of the traditional inquiry into
beings as beings and has its rightness and validity concerning the def-
inition of the substantial being of things. This truth, however, is not
only limited and derivative but is not the most important kind of truth.
Far more important to us than a correct cognition of things is the
openness or pretence that concerns our own existence, on the basis of
which we make our vital decisions and which determines the genuine-
ness of our relations with other human beings ( WW, 22f., W, 196f., G9,
196f., P, 150f., BW, 135f.).
But it is not enough merely to define the limits of logic and its
truth, nor is it enough to go back to an older tradition and revive it.
The alë theia has not merely to be rediscovered , but has to be more orig-
inally understood than was possible at the beginning ( US, 134, G12,
126-27, OWL, 39 ). The hiddenness at the heart of the alë theia,
although elementally experienced, did not become a problem for
Greek thought. Attention turned not to the remarkable event that the
unhiddenness had happened, but to what had come to light through
this event: beings as beings. Truth, as a coming to light from conceal-
Truth, Being, and Existence 107
109
110 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
At this point, therefore, we shall turn away from Being and Time
and attempt to take a few steps toward Husserl’s thought. This diver-
sion is necessary not only for a better understanding of phenomenol-
ogy, but, above all, for indicating the point at which Heidegger radi-
cally departs from Husserl. This departure has a profound influence
on the style of Being and Time, many of whose passages are incompre-
hensible without some insight into the controversial issues within the
phenomenological movement itself.
The divergence between the two thinkers shows itself already in
the concept of intentionality, which is the starting point and guiding
principle of Husserl’s thought. This concept can perhaps be best
approached from the formal definition of phenomenon: that which
shows itself in itself. Taken by itself, a phenomenon is evidently incom-
plete: the self-showing needs something to which it can show itself. The
“ something” which the phenomenon needs as the place of its appear-
ing is thought by Husserl to be transcendental consciousness. This
must not be confused with empirical consciousness, which is accessible
to us in simple reflection, and which is the sphere studied by the
——
empirical science of psychology. Consciousness which must always be
understood as transcendental consciousness is in turn dependent on
—
the phenomenon, since it is its very essence to be consciousness o f . . .
that is, it always goes out for an object, it aims at something, it means
something, it intends something. This basic character of consciousness
is called by Husserl “ intentionality.” In his thought, especially in later
years, “ intentional ” and “ transcendental” tend to become the same.
The unique and peculiar character of consciousness is that the phe-
nomena, the objects which it intends, are constituted by its own activi-
ties in respect of whatness ( essence, “ meaning” ) and in respect of that -
ness ( existence in the traditional sense).
It will be immediately evident to the reader that the disclosure of
being that Husserl ascribes to consciousness belongs to the existential
way of being in Heidegger’s thought. The difference is not a matter of
terminology: it is radical, and all the sharper because of the common
ground between the two thinkers. Both agree that the metaphysical
start from beings is not fundamental enough , and that the home
ground of philosophy can only be the transcendental ground where
the disclosure of being happens. Further, they are in complete agree-
ment that the “ place of the transcendental” cannot be simply one of
the realities among other realities in the world , but that the “ transcen -
dental subject” must exist in a totally different way from the merely real
object. It is at this point that the two thinkers radically diverge. Hei-
degger strikes out on his own interpretation of the “ transcendental
The Concept of Phenomenology 115
subject.” Each thinker works out his problem in so different a way that,
in spite of many similarities and in spite of Heidegger’s incalculable
debt to Husserl, a comparison between their thought is difficult to
make. Perhaps the best way to indicate the difference is to look a little
more closely at Husserl’s problem and the way in which he sets out to
solve it.
The task of philosophy, as Husserl sees it, is to unfold all the
implications that lie enclosed in the intentional structure of conscious-
ness. The first indispensable requirement for accomplishing this task is
to develop a reliable method for gaining access to consciousness itself ,
a method that will enable us to “ see ” the immensely complicated con-
tents and activities of consciousness just as immediately as we see the
“ real word” in an act of sense perception.
A sense perception is, of course, itself an act of consciousness.
But all our naive awareness of the real world is already, as it were, an
end product of the activities of pure consciousness. These activities lie
“ anonymously” in all our empirical experience, both of things and of
ourselves as the concrete beings we are. Husserl therefore proceeds to
suspend , to “ put into brackets, ” to put out of action, everything that we
normally accept ready-made from consciousness, and so to turn the
phenomenological “ eye ” to consciousness itself. The method proceeds
step by step, by way of a series of “ reductions, ” one of which is called
the “ phenomenological reduction.” In this, the reality of the world, as
it is naively experienced by us, is suspended, put out of action, not
because the reality is in the least doubtful or uncertain but because it
is a product of consciousness, and the aim is to get those activities into
view which first of all constitute this reality.
What is it, then, that Husserl suspends in the phenomenological
reduction? Nothing less than the is. But not only the ¿5 of things is sus-
pended; the am must also be put out of action, because what we
naively experience in the I am , is the “ empirical subject, ” the concrete
beings we are in the real world. The am is no less a ready-made prod-
uct of transcendental consciousness than the is of a thing, and must
therefore be neutralized to get the contents of consciousness itself
purely into focus.
But, it may be asked, does Husserl intend to say that everything
in the world , ourselves included, is a sort of invention, a figment of
imagination on the part of consciousness? Any such thought is as alien
to Husserl as it is to Heidegger. It is not real beings that are constituted
by consciousness, but their being in respect of what and how. This
achievement of consciousness, moreover, is so little arbitrary that it
proceeds by the strictest laws, to discover which is part of the task of
116 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
119
120 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
reached are radical enough. Have they penetrated to the last intelligi-
ble ground of the unity and wholeness of Da-sein’s being? Has the
whole of Da-sein’s being been brought into view at all? Evidently not.
Being-in-the-world is, after all , ended by death and begun, at the other
“ end, ” by birth , whereas the “ Preparatory Fundamental Analysis ” has
considered only the everyday happening “ in between.” Moreover, it is
the essential character of Da-sein that to each one his being is manifest
as mine. This is the ground of the possibility of owned and disowned
existence; but the “ Preparatory Fundamental Analysis ” has only
brought the average and disowned way of existing into phenomeno-
logical view. The incompleteness of the first phase of the inquiry has
to be remedied before it can be shown that time is the deepest origi-
native ground of the wholeness of Da-sein’s being as care, and thus the
meaning of being as such.
The starting point of Division Two proves to be the question as
to how the whole Da-sein is and how he wholly is. It is the question of
the extremest possibilities of Da-sein’s existence, in contrast to his
everyday mode of being. These extreme possibilities appear to lie, on
the one hand, in the two “ ends” of being-in-the-world that constitute its
wholeness, and, on the other hand , in owned existence, constituting
the way in which Da-sein can be wholly himself, according to his own-
most possibility. The question of wholeness and owned existence, how-
ever, is nothing other than the problem of a finitely free being.
But no sooner is this problem formulated than grave difficulties
begin to present themselves. In the first place, how can Da-sein be a
whole at all? Certainly not as a sum, or a thing, or even as a merely liv-
ing being is a whole. Da-sein can only be a whole in the way of care,
whose essence lies in its disclosing character. The task facing the exis-
tential analysis, therefore, is to show whether and how Da-sein can dis-
close to himself the whole of his being.
This task, however, seems at first sight to be impossible to accom-
plish, not for accidental but for essential reasons. We seem to be able
to get direct evidence only of the fact of the birth and death of others.
As to his own being, Da-sein cannot get behind his own thrownness, he
can only find himself already there as a thrown fact; while, at the other
end, in experiencing his own death, he already ceases to be.
These peculiar difficulties make necessary a completely different
approach to the problem from the one used in Division One. There the
existential-ontological problem was approached from the existentiell-
ontic basis of the factically existing Da-sein; here the method has to be
reversed. The first task is to find out whether it is existentially possible
for Da-sein to be a whole at all, in the way proper to his own being.
A Preview of the Tasks and Problems of Division Two 121
— —
This existential-ontological concept of death so far, it is only a
concept now demands an examination of whether a disclosure of
death is ontologically possible. It is possible, as Heidegger proceeds to
show, to an understanding which opens itself to a constant threat that
rises from the ground of Da-sein’s being, his thrownness into his
“ there.” This threat is elementally revealed in the basic mood of dread.
Understanding runs forward to this threat, fully disclosing it as the
extreme possibility of not-being-able- to-be-there-anymore. The disclo-
sure of death is thus seen to be ontologically possible on the basis of
attunement ( mood ) and forward-running understanding.
But all this is, so far, merely an ontological construction and
remains worthless unless Da-sein himself, in his ontic existence, con-
firms that the disclosure which has been postulated is possible in con-
crete experience. Where can such confirmation be found? Heidegger
finds it in what is usually called “ the voice of conscience.” That this
“ voice ” cannot be found as an observable “ fact ” by an objectively ori-
entated investigation, that its “ reality ” cannot be proved, does not
make it meaningless for the existential inquiry; on the contrary, it
shows that in conscience we have a genuine and original existential
phenomenon.
The task now is to analyze and interpret existentially the con-
crete, well-attested experience of conscience. Differently as this may be
understood and explained by each Da-sein, there is general agreement
that it is a voice that has something to say to oneself. It is, therefore,
completely in accord with experience when Heidegger sees the onto-
logical function of conscience in disclosing something, in giving some-
thing to understand, not to Da-sein in general , but to a Da-sein singly
and individually.
122 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
—
—
unity of all the main structures of care that is, existence, facticity, and
falling are only possible on the ground of Da-sein’s timeishness. All
the essential findings of the “ Preparatory Fundamental Analysis ” are
once more analyzed and interpreted in terms of time. The timeishness
of understanding and attunement, of falling and of the everyday tak-
ing care of things, of the fundamental constitution of being-in-the-
world and the temporal-horizontal structure of world, and many other
themes are worked out by Heidegger in a long chapter entitled “ Tem-
porality and Everydayness” ( chap. 4 ).
The next chapter begins with an analysis of the owned self and its
ontological interpretation. This leads to an existential exposition of his-
tory from the “ happening” of owned existence, illuminating, at the
same time, the possibility of a genuine being-with others which springs
from one’ s own self. The problem of the first “ end” of Da-sein’s being,
its beginning with birth , which seems to have been unduly neglected in
favor of its ultimate end, now reemerges with the important theme of
taking over one’ s thrownness and historical heritage as one’s own.
While in the context of Being and Time the existential interpretation of
history stands primarily in the service of Heidegger’s fundamental
ontology, it has undoubtedly a wider than purely philosophical interest
and is considered by many readers as the central piece in Division Two.
In the sixth and final chapter, Heidegger takes up the problem of
the vulgar concept of time, the world-time in which things come into
being and pass away and in which the happenings within the world take
place. As against the views expounded by some modern philosophers
( e.g., Bergson ), Heidegger interprets world- time as a perfectly genuine
time-phenomenon, grounded in Da-sein’s everyday being-with others
and taking care of things. One of the tasks of this chapter is to show in
detail how the concept of a featureless, “ unecstatic ” time has been
derived from the “ significant” time of the worldishness of everyday
care. Parallel to Division One, where Heidegger sets off his existential
interpretation of world against Descartes’s “ extended world, ” he now
sets off the connection between timeishness, man’s factical existence,
and world-time, against Hegel’s interpretation of the relation between
time and spirit.
In the last short section of Division Two ( § 83), which is the last
section of Being and Time as we have it, Heidegger comes back once
126 Part Two: Basic Features and Problems of Being and Time
INTRODUCTORY
127
128 A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
131
132 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
The aim of this section is not to list all the new terms we shall meet
in Division Two, but to select a few important ones for preliminary
study. But before coming to them , a word must be said about some
concepts already familiar to us from Division One. There is some-
times a new emphasis, a slight shift in their meaning as they enter
into the differently orientated inquiry of Division Two. This does not
call for a new German terminology, for Heidegger’ s concepts are in
The Articulation, Language, and Method of Division Two 133
Other terms familiar from Division One which may need rethink-
ing will be discussed as they occur in the text. We shall now proceed to
examine some new concepts of Division Two. The discussion does not
aim merely at giving a dictionary definition of them, but at showing
something of the direction in which Heidegger’s thought moves. It will
at the same time give us an opportunity to gather up the results
reached in previous studies. As Heidegger always reminds his readers,
these must be firmly kept in mind in the new phase of the inquiry.
( a ) Timeishness
Although this term has already been repeatedly used, no attempt has
so far been made to justify it as a translation of Heidegger’s Zeitlichkeit .
Considering that it is the central concept of Division Two, a smoother
rendering into English would certainly have been desirable. “ Timeli-
ness ” had to be ruled out as completely unsuitable, but “ temporality”
provided a possible alternative. In spite of several points in its favor,
the word has not been adopted here, because Heidegger has assigned
a definite role to it: the “ temporality of being” ( Temporalität des Seins )
was to have been elucidated in Division Three. There is both a con-
nection and a difference between the timeish way in which man exists
and the temporal character of being as such. To show this in an easily
surveyed form, two tables are set out below.
Figure 9.1 shows the main modes of being with which we have
become familiar in Division One, figure 9.2 the distinctive time-char-
acter that belongs to each.
Students of German philosophy may find it useful to recall that
Realit ät generally means the pure thereness ( existentia ) of things; that
is, its usual meaning is very near to Heidegger’s Vorhandenheit . The dif -
-
ferentiation between handy reality and substantial reality, at handness
or objective presence at hand, it must be remembered, came into phi -
losophy only with Heidegger’s Being and Time. The originality of his
analyses has led to a tendency greatly to overstress the importance of
“ handy reality” in Heidegger’s thought as a whole . For Heidegger him-
self, the philosophical importance of everyday utensils lies solely in
their belonging to a world, so that the reference-structure of world can
be directly demonstrated from their handy-being. This was not possi-
ble when the start was made from the substantial reality of mere sub-
stances, the common practice in Western philosophy.
For students of Kant it is especially important to note that the
German use of Realität as pure thereness ( existentia ) is comparatively
modern. As Heidegger points out, Kant himself still uses Realit ät in its
The Articulation, Language, and Method of Division Two 135
FIGURE 9.1
Existenz (existence)
FIGURE 9.2
Zeitlichkeit ( timeishness)
the time-character peculiar
to existence
<r- Temporalität
( temporality)
Innerzeitigkeit ( within-timeishness ) the time-character
the time-character peculiar to peculiar to being
reality as such
( c ) Heidegger's Tautologies
and how they are. The articulations of “ what ” and “ how ” were first
brought to our attention by Heidegger’s idea of being: what- and how-
being, something, nothing, and notness. The something, or more pre-
cisely, to-be-something, can be further differentiated into how-to-be
and what-to-be. But, as we can now see more clearly, all these articula-
tions of being are still only empty, formal concepts, devoid of any real
content. To enable us to fill these empty forms with concrete content
that is, to enable us to find ourselves among other beings and so dis-
—
tinguish ourselves from them , our own mode of being from theirs is
the unique function of world. It is the uniqueness of world that finds
—
expression in the phrase “ the world worlds.”
Heidegger’s tautologies, which at first seemed forced or mean-
ingless, have now proved to be highly appropriate to those phenomena
that belong to the disclosure of being. These are not an absolute noth-
ing, nor, on the other hand, can they “ be” in the same way as beings
are. Each of these phenomena, moreover, has a distinctive and unique
function in unifying, articulating, and defining being, which cannot be
replaced by anything else. They are identical only with themselves; they
are the strictly understood “ identities.” But there is still a further point
that Heidegger expresses by his tautologies. This can best be exempli-
fied by the last two tautologies, which were mentioned above but which
we have not yet discussed.
Heidegger says der Raum räumt, “ place places.” First of all a word
must be said about the English rendering, for it could be objected to
on the ground that Raum means space, while the German for place is
Ort or Platz . Nevertheless, the paraphrase comes as near as possible to
Heidegger’s meaning, because the everyday world, where something
like space first becomes accessible to us, has primarily a place-charac-
ter. This is very different both from the levelled-down space of a theo-
retically defined nature, and from the formal space accessible to a pure
intuition ( looking-at ). What a geometrician “ looks at” are not things in
space, but purely space itself and its properties. The everyday world, on
the other hand, is primarily “ placeish, ” for the essential reason that our
being-in-the-world is a staying-in , a dwelling-in. Hence the world, as the
wherein of our everyday staying and dwelling, is familiar to us as the
dwelling place, the home.
Granted, then, that the phrase “ place places” comes close to Hei-
degger’s meaning, what does it tell us? It tells us that only because some-
thing like place belongs to the disclosure of being can we understand
ourselves as occupying a place in a world and direct things to their
places within it. Place itself, as a character of being, “ gives ” us place, that
is, makes the discovery of place and space first of all possible.
The Articulation, Language, and Method of Division Two 141
and presumably will be there long after man has disappeared; it is com-
pletely independent of him. But how can the universe endure and
change except in time? If time were merely our “ subjective ” way of
apprehending, unifying, and ordering events, the independent exis-
tence of an “ objective world ” would be completely inexplicable.
This difficulty arises, in the last resort, from our tendency to con-
fuse being with beings. Let us ask once more, What does it mean that
a thing, for instance, that tree over there, is ( exists)? It means that it is
manifest to us precisely as that tree, a thing completely independent of
us, a thing in its own right. Hence when no man exists and an under-
standing of being is no longer possible, the tree itself will not cease to
endure and change, but it will no longer have the chance of manifesting
itself as enduring and changing, that is, as being in time. The objec-
tions to an existential interpretation of time prove to be untenable
when time is understood as a fundamental character that defines
being, and being means the manifestness of beings in and as themselves.
order as, say, the psychological one between timidity and aggressive-
ness, introversion and extroversion, and so on. These psychological dis-
positions can well be documented by characteristic modes of behavior.
The basic ways of existing, on the contrary, can never be so concretely
demonstrated . It is doubtful whether in any specific instance we can
know with any certainty in what way Da-sein exists.
How, then , does Heidegger set about his task ? His main foothold
lies in those characters of everyday existence that have already been
analyzed and secured in Division One. In this way of existing, as has
been shown, Da-sein falls away from himself by fleeing from a threat that
constantly pursues him. Owned existence, therefore, must lie in a res-
olute turning toward the threat that overtly or covertly determines Da-
sein’s being. The basic characters of owned existence can be shown by
going counter to the trend dominant in the falling way of existing, some-
what on the principle that by going against the stream we are bound to
arrive at the source.
This method, it may be remembered, is first employed in the
exposition of Da-sein’ s being as care ( Div. One, chap. 6 ). There it is
deeply impressive because it is based on the elemental experience of
dread. If it becomes less impressive in the analysis of owned existence,
the weakness lies not so much in the method as in the basis from which
Heidegger is compelled to start. In working out the existential concept
of death, for instance, much emphasis is laid on the everyday tendency
to explain away death by making it into a fact like other facts. What
troubles us is whether it is the whole truth, whether Heidegger is not
forced to underplay everyday existence in order to show how owned
existence must be.
On the other hand, it must be recognized that the basis on which
the inquiry must rest is strictly prescribed by Heidegger’s aim. The aim
is to explain the meaning of being by penetrating to the inmost possi-
bility of our understanding of being. All the ways in which we can expe-
rience ourselves, other beings, and things in general, are in advance
determined by that understanding. The ground of its possibility can
therefore only lie in our being itself and not in any circumstances extra-
neous to it. The solid facts and conditions in which other kinds of
inquiries can find a firm footing are not only irrelevant but inadmissi-
ble to Heidegger’s. All his evidence must be drawn purely from Da-
sein’s existence and how this is manifest in his understanding.
A few words have to be said about the method to be adopted for
the exposition of Division Two. Generally speaking, the importance of
following the development of the main argument cannot be over-
stressed. This implies a corresponding firmness in passing over details
144 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
of great interest that are not absolutely essential to the main move-
ment. This principle of exposition, however, is greatly affected and
modified by the overriding consideration that Being and Time is an
unfinished work that demands unusual methods. The normal and sim-
ple way would be to take the reader through to the end, then come
back to those difficulties and obscure passages that can be illuminated
only from the end. Since the absence of Division Three makes this
impossible, the expositor is forced to devise ways of mitigating its
absence as far as possible. The method adopted in this guide is to pay
special attention to those central themes that Heidegger leaves half fin-
ished in Division Two, obviously intending to complete their interpre-
tation in the third division. These will be discussed in great detail and,
where it is possible, suggestions will be made about their final place
and function in the solution of Heidegger’s ultimate problem.
X
Dasein’ s Possibility of Being-a-Whole
and Being-toward -Death
145
146 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
In the everyday world, it is true, one Da sein can and often must
substitute for another. In the business of taking care of the world , one
is what one does. The interchangeability of one with another in a mutu-
ally undertaken making and doing is not only possible, but is constitu-
tive of the everyday self. But all substitution fails when it comes to
dying. A Da-sein can die for another, but this does not in the least
relieve the other of his dying. Each Da-sein must take his death upon
himself. It is his utmost possibility in which his sheer ability to be is at
stake ( es geht um ). Death is a purely existential phenomenon, consti-
tuted by existence and mineness. Existence is the being that is manifest
to each of us as mine. This being that is mine is for me constantly at
stake. Death is only as the end of my existence; it is essentially my dying.
It can therefore never be a happening, a within-worldish occurrence.
That is why the substitution of another’s death for mine had to fail.
Nevertheless, the outcome of the preceding analysis is not nega-
tive. shows positively that the wholeness constituted by “ ending” in
It
death is an existential phenomenon. It can be explained only from the
existential structure of an existence, which is essentially my existence. If
the “ end ” itself is to be appropriately grasped, it can only be done in
an existential concept of death. Concepts of “ end ” and “ wholeness”
drawn from other modes of being are incapable of explaining the end-
ing of an existence. Even the extinction of life in a purely living being
must be distinguished from the existential phenomenon of death.
money is not yet put together. The money at hand is not sufficient to
pay a debt. The amount still lacking is not simply nonexistent: it is a
handy thing in the mode of unhandiness. When it becomes available
and the whole sum is put together, it still retains the character of hand-
iness. Da-sein, on the other hand, is not “ all together” when his not-yet
has been completely “ filled up.” On the contrary, he is then no longer
here at all. Clearly, Da-sein cannot be made into a whole like a handy
thing whose wholeness is the sum of parts.
But even among things, the not-yet may indicate different ways of
incompleteness. The moon, for example , is not yet full. With the grad-
ual withdrawal of the covering shadow, the not-yet diminishes until the
moon is full. But obviously, the full moon has been there all along, and
the not-yet-full applies only to our perception , not to the moon itself.
As for Da-sein, however, his not-yet is not only inaccessible to percep-
tion, it is not yet “ there” at all.
The problem of Da-sein’s wholeness is whether he himself can be
his not-yet, that is, be what he becomes. A comparison must therefore
be drawn with other living beings, to which a “ becoming” evidently
belongs. An unripe fruit, for example, goes toward its ripeness. That it
is not-yet can in no way be added to it from outside. The fruit itself
brings itself to ripeness. This “ bringing itself ’ is the way of its being. If
the not-yet-ripe fruit could not of itself come to ripeness, nothing out-
side it could ever eliminate its not-yet. In contrast to this, the incom-
plete sum can only be completed by having parts brought to it. Accord-
ing to its own way of being, the sum is totally indifferent to what is still
lacking from it, or more precisely, it can neither care nor not care for
its own completeness. The fruit, on the contrary, cannot be indifferent
toward its ripeness, for only in ripening can it be unripe. The not-yet is
already drawn into its being. Similarly, Da-sein is, as long as he is,
already his not-yet.1
But although the comparison with the fruit has brought out
essential similarities, there are also important differences that arise
from the “ end ” that constitutes the wholeness. Ripeness as an end is
not analogous to death as an end. In ripeness the fruit fulfils itself.
Death, on the other hand, does not necessarily mean that Da-sein has
come to the end of his specific possibilities. Da-sein may die unfulfilled
long after he has reached and passed the maturity possible for him.
End does not necessarily imply fulfilment. In what sense, then, can
dying be understood as an ending?
Things can end in different ways, according to their specific ways
of being. The rain ends: it stops, it vanishes. The road ends: it stops,
but it does not vanish. On the contrary, its end shows the road to be
Daseins Possibility of Being-a-Whole and Being-toward-Death 149
precisely this one and no other. Then again, end may mean being fin-
ished: with the last stroke of the brush, the painting is finished. The
bread is at an end: it is used up , no longer available as a handy thing.
Dying is not an ending in any of these senses. In death Da-sein is
neither fulfilled, nor has simply vanished, nor is finished, nor at an
end like a handy thing that is no longer available. For just as Da-sein is
constantly his not-yet, so he is always already his end. Ending as dying
does not mean that Da-sein is at an end, but that he is to ( or toward )
an end ( Sein zum Ende ). Death is a way of being that Da-sein takes over
as soon as he is. “ As soon as a human being is born , he is old enough
to die right away ” (SZ, 245 ).
The obscurity of Heidegger’s Sein zum Ende , later to be defined
as Sein zum Tode , is aggravated by the difficulty of rendering it into
English The exact translation , “ being to the end,” and “ being to
.
death, ” must remain ambiguous ( and even misleading ) until its mean-
ing can be more fully grasped. The alternative rendering of “ being
toward an end ” ( “ being toward death” ) is less exact but perhaps less
misleading, and can be used with advantage in many contexts.
At the present stage, nothing could be gained from further verbal
explanations. Heidegger’ s own phrase, though verbally clearer, is
hardly less obscure than the translation. It cannot be more at the
moment than an empty formula, a statement of the problem: How can
man be his end ? How can his wholeness be constituted by his end? This
new formulation of the problem nevertheless represents an important
turning point in Heidegger’ s inquiry. It closes the first stage of a ten-
tative approach. The attempt to grasp Da-sein’s wholeness by starting
from his possibilities, from what he is not yet but can become, has
ended in failure, for Da-sein cannot become a whole by having bits and
pieces added to him. It is now clear that if Da-sein can be a whole at all,
he can be so only from his end. All his other possibilities which lie
before his death can be understood only from the ultimate possibility
of his end.
The direction of the inquiry must therefore be entirely reversed.
It must start from the end that constitutes the wholeness. How strange
and radical the course that Heidegger now proposes to take is best seen
from the fact that Da-sein’s beginning in birth has so far not even been
considered. What would seem to us the natural course to take, to start
from the beginning, is tacitly passed over by Heidegger. The implica-
tion is that even the beginning, the birth, can be understood only by
coming back to it from the end.
The results of the inquiry alone can show whether the course on
which Heidegger sets out is justified . What has been shown so far is
150 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
so on , usually throw far more light on the life of the living than on
the death of the dying.
But just because of its ontological precedence, the interpretation
of death as the “ end ” of being-in-the-world does not and cannot make
any ontic decisions about what happens “ after death,” whether a higher
or lower way of being is then possible, whether Da-sein lives on or some
kind of immortality is possible for him. It is as much outside the sphere
of an ontological interpretation to come to ontic decisions about a
“ world beyond ” as it is to come to such ontic decisions about this pre-
sent world . It remains entirely “ this worldly” in the strict sense that it
interprets death solely insofar as it constantly stands before and
reaches into the factical existence in the world.
Finally, the sphere proper to an existential analysis of death
excludes questions which Heidegger sums up under the title of a
“ metaphysics of death.” Such questions are, for example, how death
“ came into the world, ” and what meaning it has in the all of beings as
evil and suffering. Metaphysical deliberation about these questions
already presupposes not only an existential concept of death, but also
an ontological understanding of the all of beings, and especially of evil
and negativity.
From an ontic point of view, the results of the following analysis
will show the peculiar formality and emptiness that characterizes all
ontological interpretations. On the other hand , the rich and complex
structure of the” end ” as the preeminent possibility of existence will
come all the more sharply to light. The urgent problem facing the
analysis is how to guard against arbitrary and preconceived ideas of
death. It proposes to meet this danger by keeping in view how death
concretely reaches into Da-sein’s everyday existence, whose essential
characters have been analyzed and secured in the first division.
— —
possibility is at the same time his utmost. Da-sein cannot pass that is,
outstrip, outdistance the possibility of death in his own abilitv-to-be.
Death is the possibility of the sheer impossibility of being-able-to-be-
here. Death thus reveals itself as the ownmost, unrelational, unover-
takeable possibility. As such, it stands before Da-sein in a preeminent
way. It is existentially possible only because Da-sein is disclosed to him-
self in the way of being ahead-of-himself. This primary structure of care
concretizes itself most originally in a being toward death as the pre-
eminent possibility of existence.
This ownmost, unrelational, and impassable possibility, however,
is not acquired by Da-sein incidentally in the course of his being. On
the contrary, when Da-sein exists, he is already thrown into this possi-
bility. That he is delivered over to death is not in the first place a mat-
ter of an explicit or theoretical knowledge, but reveals itself more orig-
inally and penetratingly in the mood of dread . The dread of death is
Dasein's Possibility of Being-a-Whole and Being-toward -Death 153
stant flight from it. But the flight itself testifies that even the everyday
self is a thrown being into death. Even in his average everydayness, his
ownmost ability-to-be-in- the-world is constantly at stake for Da sein ,
albeit in the mode of an imperturbable indifference toward the utmost
possibility of his existence.
A more penetrating interpretation of the everyday evasion of
death will bring more sharply into view what it is from which Da-sein
flees. This method was first employed by Heidegger in the analysis of
dread (SZ, 184; see above Part Two, chap. 5, sec. 1). This will put the
inquiry into a position to define the full existential concept of death.
The positive results of the inquiry carried out so far may now be
summed up. Death as the end of Da-sein has been formally defined as
the ownmost, unrelational, impassable possibility. In his factical being,
Da-sein brings himself before this possibility as the sheer impossibility
of existing. In his everydayness, Da-sein relates himself to this possibil-
ity by concealing and evading it.
Two important points still remain to be elucidated. The first is
how the certainty, the inescapability of death reveals itself. The second
is whether it is possible for Da-sein not merely to relate himself to his
death in the evasive, everyday way, but properly to free it as his own.
The theme of the present section is the certainty of death. In
the everyday saying, “ Death comes to us all , ” something like a cer-
tainty is already admitted. The question is, however, whether the
admission is adequate to the way in which death is certain. This ques -
tion makes a short examination of certainty and of the criterion of its
adequacy necessary.
Certainty evidently belongs to truth . In the existential interpreta-
tion, “ to be true” has a twofold meaning. Primarily it means “ to be dis-
closing and discovering, ” which is the basic character of existence. I am
disclosed to myself and am discovering things within the world. The
thing itself , insofar as it is discovered , is true in a secondary sense. Cer-
tainty has the same twofold meaning. Primarily, it is I myself who am
certain , and secondarily, the discovered ( true) thing is certain.
The primary meaning of certainty is defined by Heidegger as Für-
wahrhalten , to hold something for true. The excellence of this expres-
sion can be appreciated only when it is carefully thought over. I hold, I
keep, something for true when I can hold myself to it; I do not vacillate
156 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
exist primarily from the utmost possibility of his own self. Only when
it becomes transparent to him that this is something he can do and
could always have done, does his lostness in the everyday “ oneself ’
among “ them ” become fully manifest.
But Da-sein’s ownmost possibility is at the same time unrela-
tional . Running ahead to it gives Da-sein to understand that he must
160 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
take it over solely from himself. Death does not merely indifferently
belong to each Da-sein, but claims him singly. It individuates Da-sein
into a single self , and makes it manifest that all caring for others and
taking care of things fails when it is his own sheer ability-to-be that is
at stake. But the failure of these ways of being-in- the-world to support
Da-sein in the face of death does not cut them off from himself, for
they are an essential condition of existence as such. Da-sein exists fully
as his own self only insofar as in being-with others and being-near-to
things, he throws himself primarily into his ownmost ability-to-be, and
not into the possibilities of oneself in the everyday world.
The ownmost, unrelational possibility is impassable. It stands
before Da-sein as the extremest possibility of his existence. Running
ahead to death does not evade its impassability, but “ sets it free for it, ”
that is, opens itself to be moved and affected by it, suffers itself to be
struck to the core by it. When Heidegger speaks of a “ passionate anx-
ious freedom for death ” (SZ, 266 ), he is not thinking of a quickly evap-
orating emotion of enthusiasm, but of a soberly steadfast, suffering
openness to an end that cannot be surpassed by the forethrow of fur-
ther possibilities. This alone can set Da-sein free from his dependence
on those chance possibilities that lie before his utmost possibility, by
enabling him genuinely to understand them as finite, and to let him
choose his own from among them, instead of letting others prescribe
the average possibilities for the everyday “ oneself.”
The extreme possibility of existence to give itself up shatters all
rigid insistence on what has already been reached and achieved, and so
saves Da-sein from the danger of falling behind himself and “ becoming
too old for his victories ( Nietzsche )” (SZ, 264 ). Free for his ownmost
— —
possibilities, which are determined from the end that is, are under-
stood as finite Da-sein will not misunderstand the possibilities of oth-
ers which are overtaking his own or try to force them back into the lim-
its of his own. Death as the unrelational, impassable possibility
individuates Da-sein into a single self only to make him understanding
toward others in their ability-to-be.6 Since running ahead to the utmost
possibility at the same time discloses all other possibilities that lie
before it, it in advance encompasses the whole of a Da-sein’ s existence;
that is, it enables Da-sein to be a whole in his factical existence.
The ownmost, unrelational, impassable possibility is certain. The
way to be certain of it is determined by the corresponding truth ( dis-
— —
closedness ). Da-sein holds death for true is certain of it by running
ahead to it as his ownmost ability-to-be. He himself makes the certainty
possible for himself, and what enables him to do so is the anticipatory
forward-running way of existence. The certainty of death cannot be cal-
Da sein’s Possibility of Being-a-Whole and Being-toward-Death 161
Anticipation reveals to Da-sein its lostness in the they-self and brings it face to
face with the possibility to be itself primarily unsupported by concern taking
care of things, but to be itself in passionate anxious freedom toward death
which is free of the illusions of the they , factical, and certain of itself (SZ, 266 )
162 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
—
The existential structure of anticipation or running ahead that
—
is, of an owned way of being toward death shows that it is ontologically
possible for Da-sein to be a whole. It should, therefore, be possible for
a factically existing Da-sein to be “ in fact” a whole. And yet, the work-
ing out of this existentially possible wholeness remains a fantastic
assumption until its concretization in an ontic existence has been
demonstrated. Does any Da-sein in fact ever throw himself into an
owned being toward death ? Does he in fact bear witness to his ability to
do so? Does he ever demand it from himself that he ought to exist
wholly as himself ?
These questions already indicate the theme and task of the next
chapter. They also suggest that quite apart from Heidegger’s principal
theme, this second chapter of Division Two should be of unusual inter-
est, since in it Heidegger must lay bare the ontological source and
ground of ethics and morality. While our freedom lies in our under-
standing of possibility as such ( I can be, I am able to be) this is obvi-
ously not sufficient to explain what we usually call “ moral freedom.”
For this, we must be able to understand not only that “ I can be this way
or that,” but also to understand that “ I ought to be this way and not
that,” and be able freely to submit or not submit ourselves to the
implied demand. Further, it is evident that the demand must be made
by ourselves to ourselves, for no externally imposed command could
make the free submission to an “ I ought ” possible.
XI
Witness to an Owned Existence
and Authentic Resolution
163
164 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
preeminent mode in which conscience speaks to us. This does not con-
flict with the everyday experience of it as a “ voice, ” because what is
really meant by the “ voice ” is not an audible sound, but its function of
giving us something to understand.
There is indeed no need for conscience to be generally audible,
because it does not speak to mankind at large, but solely to myself. It is
purely the self of the everyday “ oneself, ” bemused by the noise of pub-
lic talk, whom conscience calls . The demanding and summoning char-
acter of conscience is pregnantly expressed by Heidegger when he
speaks of it as a call, rather than as an indeterminate voice.
Whom conscience calls is indubitably a Da sein in his own single self.
What he does and who he is in the publicity of the everyday world is mer-
cilessly ignored and passed over by the call. Just as dread overturns the
relevance-whole of things into complete irrelevance, so conscience pushes
the vanity of “ one’s” public position into total insignificance. It thus
deprives Da-sein of his habitual hiding place and brings him to himself.
But what is it that conscience calls to the self ? Strictly speaking,
Heidegger maintains: nothing. The call gives no information about
worldish affairs, has no objective facts to relate. The self who has been
called is not told about anything, but is summoned to himself. Accord-
ing to the existential interpretation, the primary and proper task of
conscience is not to tell us what we are to do, but how we are to be .
As a summons, conscience calls Da-sein forward into the possi-
bility of his own self. Hence it is that the call need not bring itself to
word and sound. “ Conscience speaks solely and constantly in the mode
of silence ” (SZ, 273). It thus forces Da-sein into the “ reticent stillness”
of himself. The absence of words does not mean that the call is vague
and incomprehensible, but that it demands a different kind of “ hear-
— —
ing” that is, understanding from communicating talk.
But, it may be asked, does the wordlessness of the “ silent call ” not
imply that it is a deficient kind of discourse compared to, say, a fully
expressed logical proposition? On the contrary, Heidegger implies that
it is more fundamental than any logical proposition can be. In one of
his later works, he calls language “ the sounding of stillness ” ( das Geläut
der Stille . US, 30, G12, 27, PLT, 207 ). The stillness in which conscience
speaks is the most fundamental and original speech: it is the way in
which Da -sein calls himself from the depth of his being.
But is it not premature to decide that in conscience Da-sein calls
himselfi Where is the phenomenal evidence to show that the caller and
the called are the same ? What are the phenomenal characteristics of
the caller that would make Heidegger’s interpretation at least a possi-
ble one, even if it could not be proved to be the only possible one?
Witness to an Owned Existence and Authentic Resolution 165
Conscience reveals itself as the call of care: the caller is Da-sein, anxious in
thrownness ( in its already-being-in . . .) about its potentiality-of-being.
The one summoned is also Da-sein, called forth to its ownmost poten-
tiality-of-being ( its being-ahead-of-itself . . .). And what is called forth by
the summons is Da-sein, out of falling prey to the they ( already-being-
together-with-the-world-taken-care-of . . .). The call of conscience, that is,
conscience itself, has its ontological possibility in the fact that Da-sein is
care in the ground of its being. (SZ, 277-78)
The analysis has now brought to light that the full structure, or
more precisely, movement of conscience, is that of a forward -calling
recall ( vorrufender Rückruf ) . It calls from the depth of thrownness forward
into the utmost possibilities of existence and calls Da-sein from his
everyday lostness back to his own thrown self. This circling movement
belongs to the call of care, because care itself, in its whole structure,
has the same “ circularity.”
The existential interpretation of conscience will, of course, be
unacceptable not only to the scientific, but even more to the theolog-
ical explanations of the same phenomenon. With regard to the latter,
it must be borne in mind that Heidegger neither asks nor answers the
ontic question of who conferred on Da-sein his way of existing. An
indispensable precondition for asking such a question is that we must
already understand being. To find out how such an understanding is
at all possible is Heidegger’ s sole concern. This fundamental-ontolog-
ical aim is dominant in the whole analysis of conscience, and will
come to special prominence in the next section. Its task will be to
determine the existential meaning of the Schuld ( debt, guilt, owing ),
which is universally heard and understood in every concrete experi-
ence of conscience.
And how is this thrown ground? Only by projecting itself upon the pos-
sibilities into which it is thrown. The self, which as such has to lay the
ground of itself, can never gain power over the ground , and yet it has to
take over being the ground in existing. Being its own thrown ground is
the potentiality-of-being about which care is concerned. (SZ, 284 )
-
Da sein thus constantly lags behind his possibilities, not only and
not primarily because in fact he cannot realize all of them, but because
as the not-self-originated or not-self-grounded ground he is already
behind the possibility of being his own ground. “ Da-sein is never exis-
tent before its ground, but only from it and as it ” (SZ, 284 ). His begin-
ning thus manifests itself to Da-sein from a nothing of himself, that is,
from his never having been here before his thrownness. This accom-
plished fact, however, in itself discloses the possibility of not-being-
-
here. When, therefore, Da sein dreadingly runs forward to the possi-
bility of death , he is not disclosing anything “ new” to himself, but only
lets the possibility into which he is already thrown “ stand ” before him
as a possibility, in the full clarity of its certainty and unchangeability.
The deepest owing manifest in one’ s finite being is “ never to gain
power over one’s ownmost being from the ground up” (SZ, 284 ).
It must be noted that in the short passage we have been consid-
ering, the word never recurs three times, twice in italics. This cannot be
passed over as an accident, but must be taken as a hint that the nega-
tivity which permeates care as the not-self-grounded ground comes to
light in an eminent way in the never . The hint, however, is not further
elucidated by Heidegger when he sums up the owing character of Da-
sein’s thrownness as follows:
172 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
Being a self Da sein is the thrown being as self. Not through itself, but
released to itself from the ground in order to be as this ground . Dasein is
not itself the ground of its being, because the ground first arises from its
own project , but as a self , it is the being of its ground. (SZ , 284-85)
—
—
the enduring self-sameness of a substance that “ underlies” lies to the
ground of changing qualities nor of a subject that maintains itself in a
recognizable identity and is thus constandy “ present ” to a changing
stream of experience. Da-sein’s selfhood is constituted by the way he
exists, by the way he throws himself forward to his possibilities, in
which he understands himself. Since, however, the structure of care is
“ free” to modify itself in two basic ways, Da-sein constantly stands in
one or another of his possibilities:
This passage repeats, only a little more fully, what was already
said in the analysis of dread. Da-sein’s “ free-being for the freedom of
choosing and taking hold of himself ’ is ontologically grounded in the
modifiable structure of care. This can concretize itself only in the defi-
nite choice of one possibility and the renouncing of the other. And it
is only because Da-sein is in the first place choicelessly thrown into the
negativity of ¿¿¿sownment that conscience calls him back to his freedom
for his utmost, outmost possibility. Since conscience essentially belongs
to Da-sein , not to follow its call, not to decide, is in itself a choice. Da-
sein’s freedom to decide in itself necessitates a choice. It is the seal of
its finiteness that freedom can only and must bind itself to one end and
renounce the other. Only this finite freedom can make something like
necessitation, bindingness, and responsibility at all understandable.
According to the existential interpretation , morality requires the
whole of Da-sein’ s being for its ontological foundation. Da-sein as care
is the not-determined , not-self-grounded ground of a negativity. Only
a being who is manifest to himself as determined by a denial and with-
Witness to an Owned Existence and Authentic Resolution 173
the hinge on which the question of Being and Time turns round to the
question of Time and Being. Heidegger himself is fully aware of the
host of unanswered questions he has raised in the present analysis, for
he explicitly draws attention to its incompleteness.
Shortly after the publication of Being and Time , when its completion
was still fully envisaged by Heidegger, two short but important works
appeared: “ What Is Metaphysics? ” ( WM, 1929 ) and “ On the Essence of
Ground ” ( WG, 1929 ). The first takes up the problem of negativity, left
unfinished in the section above, while the second elucidates the “ being
of ground.” Although both these short works still fall far short of
accomplishing the task assigned to Division Three, they carry their
problems an important step further forward than Division Two. The
separateness of these two works, however, is in itself a pitfall. Both deal
with the structurally indivisible transcendence of Da-sein’ s being, the
first in the direction of thrownness, the second in the direction of fore-
throw ( possibility ).
Let us first consider briefly the lecture, “ What Is Metaphysics?” It
repeats, although from a different starting- point, the main steps taken
176 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
This passage has been quoted at length because it brings the most
explicit answer Heidegger gives anywhere to the central question of
Being and Time: How is an understanding of being at all possible to Da-
sein ? The answer, however, is by no means complete nor is it detailed
enough to be without serious difficulties and obscurities. It does not
explain, for instance, how dread individuates Da-sein and brings him
singly before the nothing, and how this is revealed as the nothing of
himself. The whole stress of the present passage falls on how the noth-
ing makes manifest beings as a whole ( das Seiende im Ganzen, literally:
beings in the whole ). Beings show themselves “ in the whole” from their
178 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
every feeling Da-sein “ feels himself , ” and thus feeling, finds himself in
the midst of beings. Attunement constitutes the “ world-openness” of
Da-sein’s here-being. But, as “ On the Essence of Ground ” proceeds to
elucidate, it does not constitute the whole world-structure, for in his
thrownness Da-sein is entirely thronged about and pressed in upon by
beings; he lacks any distance to them from which they could become
fully understandable in what they are. Even Da-sein himself cannot
come to full clarity as the self he is unless he can open up a distance to
himself as he already is. This distance, this free dimension of move-
ment, is opened up by the forethrow of the possibilities of how he can
be in the midst of beings. In this, Da-sein once more transcends, goes
out beyond beings as a whole, among them first and foremost himself.
The forethrow of the whole of his possibilities of being is the original
opening up of world.
Now, how does this forethrow form a structural unity with the
throw of thrownness? The throw initiated by the nothing does not
come to a standstill when Da-sein finds that be is already here; it elic-
its the forethrow by driving beyond all “ that” and “ here.” It is the con-
stant threat of the nothing which duly drives Da-sein into going out
beyond what already is by an anticipating projection of what can be. In
dreadingly facing the nothing, he dreads for his own ability-to-be. The
anticipating forethrow of his possibilities is therefore for the sake of him-
self. The world as the whole of his possibilities of being has therefore
the primary and basic character of the for the sake of ( Umwillen ).
At this point, it is helpful to remind ourselves that the German
Umwillen literally means “ for the will of.” This makes it more explicit
that the understanding forethrow of possibilities is originally not a the-
oretical thinking out of what can be or might be, but a “ willing” going
out for it.
This is, of course, perfectly familiar to us from experience. What
makes Heidegger’a talk of the “ forethrow ” strange is only that we do
not ordinarily consider the ontological conditions which make our
daily decisions possible. What lies, for instance, in the decision of my
buying a certain house next year? “ I will buy this house ” means that I
throw this specific possibility ahead of myself without, however, letting
go of it: I hold it out before and toward myself <25 a possibility. But what
is it precisely that is thrown forward in my willing to buy this house?
Obviously, I cannot bodily remove this house or myself into a still non-
realized possibility; what I throw forward is my possible being in relation
to the possible being of this house a year hence. This makes it clear that
all understanding anticipation of possibilities transcends , oversteps
beings as a whole as they are “ here and now.” On the other hand, it is
180 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
— —
The “ original ” that is, the originating relation of freedom to
ground is called by Heidegger “ grounding, ” ( Gründen ). This is scat-
tered into three specific ways: 1. grounding as founding ( Stiften ) ; 2.
182 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
truth, which makes all ontic truth first of all possible. This under-
standing of being is formed and articulated in transcendence. It gives
the foregoing answer, the first and last “ ground ” ( reason ) to all why-
questions. Transcendence is thus in itself a “ ground-giving,” for in it is
revealed being, which is the ultimate ground and origin of the why-
question we ask in the ontic discovery of beings. The transcendental
origin of the “ why” in advance directs Da-sein to ask beings to “ prove
themselves, ” to “ give an account of themselves, ” by showing the
“ ground, ” or “ cause” for being as they are. In being “ proved ” and
“ accounted for, ” beings come to stand on a firm ground ; their well-
founded truth is stable and holds good, it can be counted on and relied
upon amidst the pressure of uncertainty and change. But just because
all ontic “ proving” and “ giving the reason for ” springs from the free-
dom of Da-sein’s finite transcendence, he can also throw evidence to
the wind, he can suppress the demand for justification and proof , or
distort and disguise it ( WG, 48-49, W, 64-65, G9, 169-70, ER, 114-15,
P, 130-31).
The preceding interpretation of freedom as a threefold ground-
ing has made it much more explicit than the rest of the essay does that
in all grounding there lies the tendency to hold and stabilize, to gather
and bind into a steadfast enduringness. This interpretation , far from
being arbitrary, only follows up the easily overlooked hint the essay
itself gives us. At this point , Heidegger himself raises the question of
whether the three very different ways of grounding have not been arbi-
trarily brought together under the title of “ ground.” Do they have any-
thing more in common than an “ artificial and playful community of
the sound of words? Or are the three ways of grounding at least in one
— —
respect although each in a different way identical? ” Indeed they are;
though, as Heidegger hastens to add, their common meaning cannot
be elucidated on the “ level” of the present treatise. Nevertheless, Hei-
degger proceeds to give us a brief but invaluable hint: each of the three
ways of grounding springs from “ the care of endurance and stability”
( .Beständigkeit und Bestand , WG, 51, W, 67, G9, 171, ER, 122, P, 132 ).
It is important to note that the core of both of Heidegger’s words
comes from stehen, to stand. In an ontological- temporal sense, “ to
stand ” means both the “ standing- there, ” the immediate presence ( exis-
tentia ) of something, and its “ staying in presentness, ” its constancy,
enduringness as itself. It is easy to see that these are the basic charac-
ters of the traditional idea of the substance, or what is for Heidegger
the same thing, of the subject. “ Standing presentness” { ständige Anwesen-
heit ) is, according to Heidegger, the temporal meaning of the central
concept of being in traditional ontology ( EM , 154 , G 40, 211, IM, 168) .
184 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
and with the world gives himself an original view (image, Bild ) , which is
not itself grasped, but which nonetheless functions as a pre-view [ Vor-
bild ] of all manifest beings, among which each existing Da-sein himself
belongs. ( WG, 39, W, 55, G9, 158, ER, 89, P, 123)
This sentence is not only obscure, but is surprising, for until now
we have heard only that the world is “ formed ” by the forethrow of the
for the sake of the possibilities of Da-sein’s being. But now this sentence-
—
obscure as it may be in all other respects clearly tells us that the world
itself gives us a kind of “ pre-view, ” an “ original image ” of beings, from
which they become recognizable as beings. How this happens, Hei-
degger does not explain. A certain pointer, however, may be found in
Heidegger’s Rant-interpretation, especially of the “ transcendental
object” and of the principle of the “ anticipations of perception ” ( KPM,
113ff., G 3, 121ff., KPM( E ) , 82ff; FD, 167ff., G 41, 217ff., WT, 214ff.).
Since, however, Kant’s thought moves in the dimension, albeit tran-
scendental dimension, of subjectivity-objectivity, its interpretation
must on no account be directly identified with Heidegger’ s own
thought. Nonetheless, with due precautions and reservations, we can
take a hint from it to explain the above passage in the following way.
In the forethrow of the for the sake of freedom gives itself a direc-
tion in which to advance, and at the same time, gathers itself , brings
itself to a stand in an “ end.” Every near and far “ aim” forms a kind of
limit within the direction of advance, but at the same time indicates the
possibility of further advance. So, for instance, my intention to buy a
house forms a provisional limit, but it already invites further progress
in the same direction; for example, planning how to furnish the house
after buying it. All forethrow of such provisional, “ realizable ” ends,
however, is in advance encompassed by the ultimate possibility of not-
-
being-here-anymore. This not to-be stands before us as a constant and
impassable limit to any further advance. In forming an unchanging,
impenetrable horizon to all our coming and going, it gives us an orig-
inal “ view ” of an impenetrable, standing “ something.” It is only
because we always already have an impassable horizon in view as a
“ something” that resists us that we can recognize and identify a con-
crete something as something when it meets us within the world.
Although this interpretation cannot be “ proved ” to correspond
to Heidegger’ s intentions, it can be at least indirectly confirmed. In
his analysis of dread , Heidegger calls the world the most original, pri-
mordial “ something” (SZ, 187 ). Since the world as a pure horizon cer-
tainly cannot “ originate ” concrete, ontic beings in the sense of “ pro-
ducing” them , it can only give us an “ image ” from which they become
186 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
The “ free will ” that is the precondition of Da-sein’s “ moral self ” has now
been shown to lie in the transcending structure of being-in-the-world.
The finite freedom of this transcendence forms and articulates the man-
—
ifold ways in which Da-sein “ owes ” that is, is the not-determined ground
of a negativity. The “ owing being” to which conscience summons Da-sein
has therefore a positive ground-character, which makes possible a
responsible decision and is at the same time permeated with negativity,
which in advance refers Da-sein to others than himself, as those to whom
he is “ owing.” The finite freedom of this positive-negative ground-being
is the existential condition of the possibility of the moral “ good” and
“ bad ,” that is, of morality as such and of the concrete forms morality can
take in Da-sein’s factical being-in-the-world (SZ, 286 ).
188 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
How the various forms of morality arise and how Da sein gains
a concrete insight into the being of the good and bad are problems to
which Heidegger takes up a strikingly evasive position. He merely
repudiates the traditional concepts of the “ good ” and of “ values, ” as
well as the concept of the bad as a “ privation of the good, ” on the
ground that they have been drawn from the traditional idea of being
as substantial reality ( Vorhandenheit ) . But any positive indication of
how good and bad may be distinguished is remarkably lacking in Being
and Time . It leaves it open to us to suppose that the “ good ” comes to
light with the original disclosure of being, which “ throws” us into our
being-in- the- world, and that is why the possibility of being-in -the-world
has the basic character of the for the sake of . But in this disclosure, the
nothing “ negates ” in the extremest way, and this, presumably, brings
the “ bad ” cooriginally to light. These suppositions seem to be con-
firmed by Heidegger’s “ Letter on ‘Humanism’ ” published twenty
years after Being and Time, assuming that we can identify what Hei-
degger calls the Heile, the wholesome, the healing, the holy, with the
source of the “ good,” and the Grimmige, the grim, with the source of
the “ bad ” ( HU, 112ff., W, 189ff., G9, 359ff., P, 272ff., BW, 237ff.). But
even if we can justifiably draw on this later work for explaining what
Being and Time leaves unsaid, it still gives us nothing more precise than
the widest of generalizations. Just because the for the sake of being-in-
the-world comprehends in itself all the ways in which Da-sein can fac-
tually be, and these ways are capable of a wide range of modifications,
we need a much more precise guidance as to which of these ways we
ought to bind ourselves to as “ good” and which we are to reject as
“ bad.” According to the “ Letter on ‘Humanism’ , ” insofar as Da-sein
— —
ek-sists “ stands out into the truth of being” being itself allots to him
those “ directions ” (Weisungen) that must become law and rule for him
-
( HU, 114, W, 191-92, G9, 360-61, P, 274, BW, 238 39 ). Here Hei-
degger himself admits the necessity for “ law and rule, ” which mani-
fests itself in Da-sein’ s being as the “ care of standingness and stabil-
ity. ” He contradicts himself , therefore, when in his analysis of
conscience he rejects the demands for concrete ethical “ norms and
rules,” which , Heidegger here says, arise from an everyday under-
standing, incapable of anything more than business dealings, and
which demands a handy rule and norm in the mutual settling of
accounts and obligations ( SZ, 288, 292ff. ). But, on Heidegger’s own
showing, the necessity of rules and laws does not arise merely from
disowned existence and its supposed incomprehension, but from the
original “ directions” of being itself, which “ directs ” us to bind our-
selves to something that holds and steadies us.
Witness to an Owned Existence and Authentic Resolution 189
The “ experience of conscience” turns up after the deed has been done
or left undone. The voice follows up the transgression and points back
to the event through which Da-sein has burdened itself with guilt. If con-
science makes known a “ being guilty, ” this cannot occur as a summons
to . . . , but as a pointing that reminds us of the guilt incurred. (SZ, 290 )
the same time is turned back toward his thrownness. How does Hei-
degger explain the undoubted experience of the “ voice ” as following
the deed ? He maintains that the actual guilty deed is only the occasion
for hearing the call, for wakening the conscience that sleeps. The
everyday explanation, however, does not get the full existential phe-
nomenon into view, but stops halfway when it sees only a series of hap-
penings one after the other. Conscience, to be sure, calls back, but
beyond the committed deed back to the original owing-being which
lies in Da-sein’s thrownness. At the same time, it calls him forward to
the ability-to-be-owing of his existence, which he is summoned to take
over as his own. It is only as this forward-calling recall that conscience
shows the original structure of care.
As against Heidegger’ s criticism of the everyday interpretation
of conscience as existentially insufficient, we may ask whether he
himself gets the whole ontic-existentiell experience into view. We must
answer No, because the “ voice” does not merely castigate us for a
committed deed; it calls for something like restitution and a firm res-
olution to become better in the future. The call for restitution and
resolution to change ourselves essentially belongs to a genuine and
full experience of conscience. Both common understanding and reli-
gious-ethical teaching reject an experience which is a mere, often self-
indulgent, wallowing in remorse, and insist that the proper “ hearing”
of the voice lies in how we act on it. This will turn out to be not vastly
different from Heidegger’ s own interpretation of the “ authentic”
hearing of the call. Furthermore, when the whole ontic-existentiell
phenomenon of conscience is taken into account, as a call for a
repenting and restituting resolution, its “ structure ” turns out to be
nothing other than a forward -calling recall. It is only because Hei-
degger takes hold of merely a fragment of the genuine experience
that he can find it to be so deficient in comparison with the existen-
tial interpretation. Similarly, his criticism of the “ warning” con-
science as being merely a reference to some future deed will not hold
water, because it again ignores the full phenomenon. He does not ask
how conscience “ warns” and how it alone can warn. It can warn solely
by bringing us to ourselves as we already are and have been and by
accusing us of being already guilty of and responsible for intending
evil. Here again the forward -calling recall structure of conscience
comes to light, as indeed it must do in every concrete experience, if
Heidegger’s existential interpretation is true and not merely an arbi-
trary invention.
One fundamental difference between existentiell experience and
the existential interpretation must certainly be admitted. The latter
192 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
aims at exposing the last ontological foundations that make the con-
crete experience first of all possible. The former have no such inten-
tion , and it is questionable whether it can be rightly accused of short-
comings because of this. The proper sphere of everyday understanding
is the concrete situation and the action it demands. This seems to be a
much truer reason for its preoccupation with “ what ought I to do? ”
than its incapability, as Heidegger avers, to comprehend anything
beyond a businesslike taking care of things. Besides, here again Hei-
degger contradicts what he himself says elsewhere. In his analysis of
everyday being-together, he showed that Da-sein’s caring-for other exis-
tences has a completely different character from his taking care of
things. While the latter is guided by Umsicht , a circumspection that dis-
covers what things are for, the former is guided by Rücksicht, a consid-
erate regard for the other’s thrownness , and by Nachsicht , a forbearing
looking-after the other as a self (SZ, 123). These ways of “ seeing” of
—
understanding which guide Da-sein’s relations to other selves, must be
—
alive already in his everyday existence and must disclose to him in some
way that his “ dealings” with other existences are different from his
makings and doings with things. Insufficient and even wrong as the
explicit explanations given by everyday understanding may be from the
existential-ontological point of view, there is no evidence to show that
it cannot distinguish at all Da-sein’s relation to himself and to other
selves from his relation to things. And the further question arises
whether everyday understanding can be justifiably criticized for its
ontological shortcomings when its own proper sphere lies in the con-
crete situation. Heidegger himself seems to feel that some kind of dis-
tinction is necessary, for at the end of his criticisms he suddenly adds
that the existential insufficiency of the everyday understanding of con-
science is no judgment on the existentiell “ moral quality ” of the self who
holds himself to it.
The call is the call of care. Being guilty constitutes the being that we call
care. Da-sein stands primordially together with itself in uncanniness.
Uncanniness brings this being face to face with its undisguised nullity,
which belongs to the possibility of its ownmost potentiality-of-being. In
that Da-sein as care is concerned about its being, it calls itself as a they
that has factically fallen prey, and calls itself from its uncanniness to its
potentiality-of-being. The summons calls back by calling forth: forth to
the possibility of taking over in existence the thrown being that it is, back
to the thrownness in order to understand it as the null ground that it has
to take up into existence. The calling back in which conscience calls forth
—
gives Da-sein to understand that Da-sein itself as the null ground of its
—
null project , standing in the possibility of its being must bring itself
back to itself from its lostness in the they, and this means that it is guilty
[ owing ]. (SZ, 286-87 )
The decisive task of the present chapter is to take a step that Heidegger
calls grund-legend .This step will “ lay the ground ” for all that has so far been
brought to light by the existential analysis. The “ ground” to be laid the
—
temporal constitution of care is “ ground” in the sense that it makes the
—
unity of care originally possible. On no account must it be understood as
a “ producing cause,” a causa efficiens. Before this decisive step can be taken,
certain problems that have an immediate bearing on it must still be eluci-
dated. The first of these is the inner connection between resoluteness and
anticipatory running forward into death. A forward-running resoluteness
will prove to be the concretization of the authentic mode of care, in which
its temporal structure first becomes phenomenally accessible. This is why
its elucidation has been deferred to the present chapter instead of being
carried out in the preceding one, where it may seem logically to belong.
The second problem to be dealt with is the methodical basis of the whole
existential analysis. The third is the ontological constitution of the self.
These preparatory discussions will now be considered in turn.
201
202 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
for-true, as a resolute holding oneself free for taking back , is the authen-
tic resoluteness to retrieve itself But thus one’s very lostness in irresolute-
ness is existentially undermined. The holding-for-true that belongs to
resoluteness tends, in accordance with its meaning, toward constantly
keeping itself free, that is, to keep itself free for the whole potentiality-of-
being of Da-sein. This constant certainty is guaranteed to resoluteness
only in such a way that it relates to that possibility of which it can be
absolutely certain. In its death, Da-sein must absolutely “ take itself back.”
Constantly certain of this, that is, anticipating, resoluteness gains its
authentic and whole certainty. (SZ, 307-308)
— —
sein can bring himself before and to himself can be authentically a
whole may nonetheless be far removed from the everyday, common-
sense understanding of existence. This, however, is no proof that it is
not a genuine , concrete possibility of a factical existence. Heidegger
rejects any suggestion that an understanding that grows from a falling
mode of being can be the judge of its own authentic possibilities. On
the other hand , Heidegger does not deny that a factical “ ideal ” of
owned existence underlies the whole existential-ontological analysis.
On the contrary, he stresses that
not only is this fact one that must not be denied and we are forced to
grant ; it must be understood in its positive necessity , in terms of the the-
matic object of our inquiry. Philosophy will never seek to deny its
Authentic Ability -to-Be-a-Whole and Temporality as the Meaning of Care 207
But the “ charge of circularity ” itself comes from a kind of being of Da-
sein. Something like projecting, especially ontological projecting, neces-
sarily remains foreign for the common sense of our heedful absorption
in the they because common sense barricades itself against it “ in princi-
ple.” Whether “ theoretically” or “ practically,” common sense only takes
care of beings that are in view of its circumspection. What is distinctive
about common sense is that it thinks it experiences only “ factual” beings
in order to be able to rid itself of its understanding of being. It fails to
recognize that beings can be “ factually ” experienced only when being
has already been understood, although not conceptualized. Common
sense misunderstands understanding. And for this reason it must neces-
sarily proclaim as “ violent” anything lying beyond the scope of its under-
standing as well as any move in that direction. (SZ, 315)
the ontological concept of the subject does not characterize the selfhood of
the I qua self but the sameness and constancy of something always already objec-
tively present [ Vorhandenes ] . The being of the I is understood as the real-
ity of the res cogitans . (SZ, 320 )
But why is it, Heidegger asks, that Kant could not exploit his gen-
uine start from the “ I think” and had to fall back into the inappropri-
ate ontology of the substantial? The answer to this question makes
explicit the steps that lead from Kant’s transcendental analysis of Da-
sein’s “ inner nature” to the existential analysis of Being and Time. Hei -
degger begins his answer by pointing out that the full phenomenal con-
tent of the “ I ” is not merely “ I think, ” but “ I think something.” To be
sure, Kant also sees perfectly clearly that the “ I ” is constantly related to
its representations and is nothing without them. For Kant, however,
these representations are the “ empirical” that are “ accompanied” by
the “ Γ; they are the “ appearances” to which the I “ hangs on.” Kant fails
to explain the manner of this “ accompanying ” and “ hanging on, ” but
it is dear that he understands them as a constant “ being present
together ” of the I with its representations. This means, however, that
the being of the I and the being of the represented are not in principle
-
Authentic Ability-to Be-a-Whole and Temporality as the Meaning of Care 215
dent upon them . Is there, then, any sense in asking whether Da-sein
-
can be “ independent, ” whether he can “ stand in-himself ” in a way
— —
appropriate to his being? If there is and Heidegger seems to suggest
that there is then the question can concern only the different ways in
which Da-sein is capable of “ standing as a self.” The authentic way in
which he “ stands as himself ’ is in the singleness of a silent, dread-dis-
posed resoluteness. A resolutely owned self does not constantly say “ I,
I, I . . . but “ ‘¿5 ’ in reticence the thrown being that it can authenti-
cally be” (SZ, 323 ). This self provides the “ primordial phenomenal
basis for the question of the being of the T ” (SZ, 323).
What, then, is the decisive result reached in the present elucida-
tion of the self ? It has shown that the tentatively raised notion that the
“Γ “ holds” the structural whole of care “ together” must be given up
once and for all, and that care cannot be stuck together with the glue
of an ontic “ I” and “ self, ” but on the contrary, the “ standingness” of
the self can only be explained from the existentiality of care. The full
structural content of care must also explain how and why an irresolute
falling into a not-self essentially belongs to it.
This means, however, that the problem of the original unity of
care still remains unanswered. On the other hand, the full phenome-
nal content of care has now been laid bare. The investigation can now
proceed to the problem of its unity. Its solution lies in the concrete
interpretation of the meaning of care.
The “ before” [ vor ] and “ ahead of ” [vorweg] indicate the future that first
makes possible in general the fact that Da-sein can be in such a way that
it is concerned about its potentiality-of-being. The self -project grounded
in the “ for the sake of itself ” in the future is an essential quality of exis-
tentiality. Its primary meaning is the future. (SZ, 327 )
The results so far achieved, however, are only the first steps in the
temporal analysis of care. The tasks to be taken in hand in the next
three chapters are briefly outlined by Heidegger in the next section.
229
230 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
that will emerge at the end of this chapter as a central and most
puzzling problem, which will direct the inquiry to the question of
history and historicity.
but its “ presenting” is held by the authentic future and past; that is, it
does not “ fall out of ” and “ run away from ” the finite time of care. The
authentic present is called by Heidegger “ Augenblick,” which is ordi-
narily translated by “ moment ” or “ instant.” As already remarked, the
literal meaning of “ Augenblick ” brings us much nearer to what Hei-
degger intends to say: Augenblick means the “ glance of the eye, ” which
instantly discloses here-being’s situation; it is an active “ ecstasis,” that
is, removal of here-being to the possibilities and circumstances which
face it in its hereness without losing itself to them. The authentic pre-
sent may be called an “ instant attending to . . .” or, briefly, an instant.
The original meaning of instare , standing-in, should remind us that
this mode of presenting “ stands in, ” is “ held by ” the authentic future
and past of care. To help keep this in mind we shall therefore use both
the term moment and the term instant .
The existentiell phenomenon of the moment or instant, Hei-
degger points out in a footnote ( SZ, 338), was most penetratingly
seen by Kierkegaard, without being existentially clarified by him.
Such clarification is not possible in the horizon of the vulgar con-
cept of time in which Kierkegaard remained caught, so that he
attempted to define the Augenblick with the help of the “ now ” and
“ eternity.” The vulgar concept of an infinite now-time, however, is
derived from the original temporality of care and is incapable of
explaining it. Hence, Heidegger says:
The phenomenon of the Moment ( Augenblick) can in principle not be clar-
ified in terms of the now. The now is a temporal phenomenon which
belongs to time as within-time-ness: the now “ in which” something
comes into being, passes away, or is objectively present. “ In the Moment”
nothing can happen, but as an authentic present it lets us encounter
[begegnenlassen] for the first time what can be “ in a time” as something at
hand or objectively present. (SZ, 338)
only because Da-sein has forgotten itself in its ownmost thrown poten-
tiality-of-being. This forgetting is not nothing, nor is it just a failure
to remember; it is rather a “ positive, ” ecstatic mode of having-been ;
a mode with a character of its own. The ecstasy ( rapture ) of forget-
ting has the character of backing away from one’s ownmost having-
been in a way that is closed off from oneself . This backing away
from . . . ecstatically closes off what it is backing away from , and thus
closes itself off , too. As inauthentic having-been , forgottenness is thus
related to its own thrown being. It is the temporal meaning of the
kind of being that I initially and for the most part am as having-been.
And only on the basis of this forgetting can the making present that
takes care of and awaits retain things, retain beings unlike Da-sein
encountered in the surrounding world. To this retention corresponds
a nonretention that presents us with a kind of “ forgetting ” in the
derivative sense. (SZ, 339 )
TABLE 13.1
The Temporality of Understanding
Inauthentic Authentic
forgetfully-presenting recollecting ( or retrieving
awaiting or recapitulating )-instant
anticipatory running-forward
When one forgets and backs away from a factical, resolute potentiality-of-
being, one keeps to those possibilitiies of self-preservation and evasion
that have already been circumspectly discovered beforehand. Taking care
of things which fears for itself leaps from one thing to the other, because
it forgets itself and thus cannot grasp any definite possibility. All “ possible”
possibilities offer themselves, and that means impossible ones, too. He
—
who fears for himself stops at none of these the “ surrounding world ”
—
does not disappear but he encounters it in the mode of no longer know-
ing his way around in it. This confused making present of the nearest best
thing belongs to forgetting oneself in fear. That, for example, the inhabi-
tants of a burning house often “ save” the most unimportant things nearby
is known. When one has forgotten oneself and makes present a jumble of
unattached possibilities, one thus makes possible the confusion that con-
stitutes the nature of the mood of fear. The forgottenness of confusion
also modifies awaiting, and characterizes it as depressed or confused
awaiting that is distinguished from pure expectation. (SZ, 342 )
—
of beings but as a pure ontological horizon that belongs to our own
being as being-in-the-worid.
What dread dreads is being-in-the-world itself. But this “ what” of
dread is not an expected “ approaching evil ” that may someday destroy
our care-taking ability-to-be. The what of dread is already here: it is
here-being itself. Does this mean that dread is not “ futural” at all ? No,
it means only that the dreading here-being does not come-to-itself in an
inauthentic expectancy.
When dread overturns our familiar at-homeness in the world, the
“ nothingness of world” reveals the impossibility of relying primarily on a
care-taking occupation with things for our own existence. The revelation
of this impossibility, however, lets the possibility of an authentic ability-to-
be come to light (aufleuchten-lassen). How this revelation is existentially
possible is explained by Heidegger in an extremely condensed way. To fol-
low him here, it is well to remember that the primary disclosing function
of attunement in general lies in its affective character: the attuned self lets
itself be affected by what it is attuned to. Now the affectivity of dread is
of a preeminent kind, inasmuch as it is the purest self-affection: the dread
of here-being is at the same time dread for this same, naked here-being-
itself as already thrown into an uncanny not-at-homeness. The dreading
here-being lets itself be affected purely by the dreadsomeness of itself.
This means in terms of temporality: the dreading here-being brings itself
back to the pure “ that” of its own thrownness. This “ back-to” cannot have
—— —
the character of a self-forgetful retreat that is, of an inauthentic having-
been nor, on the other hand, is it already a fully fledged recollecting or
retrieve that is, a gathering-up of the ownmost having-been and bringing
it forward into a resolutely taken-over existence. The latter can become a
fact only through the decision of a concrete self who resolutely answers
the call of conscience by an anticipatory forward-running recollection of
his thrown being unto death. This answer cannot be enforced by dread.
Dread can only bring a factical here-being back to its thrownness as possi-
bily recollectable ( als mögliche wiederholbare ). Thus reduced wholly and singly
to its own thrownness, the possibilities of here-being that can be thrown
forward can be drawn solely from this same thrownness itself. Hence the
dreading here-being can come-to-itself only in its ownmost ability-to-be as
a thrown being-unto-death. In bringing here-being before the recollec-
tability of its ownmost having-been, dread at the same time reveals the
possibility of its utmost ability-to-be. An authentic forward-running recol-
lection, however, remains only an existential possibility of care, unless it is
resolutely taken over by a factical self. Failing this, the choicelessly thrown
self remains in the inauthentic mode of his being.
It will now be easily understood that the present that belongs to
the ecstatic unity of dread is neither the confused presenting of fear,
Temporality and Everydayness 241
TABLE 13.2
The Temporality of Attunement
Inauthentic Authentic
fear dread
a confused bringing before a possible
awai ting-presenting anticipatory forward-running-instant
forgetting recollectability ( or retrievability
or recapitulation )
Temporality and Everydayness 243
which discovers things not as utensils for doing something with, but as
pure substances. Curiosity also springs from everyday circumspection,
but while normally we would speak of a “ scientific curiosity ” as well as
of curiosity in the sense of undue inquisitiveness, Heidegger restricts
its meaning to a greed for seeing always something new.
Curiosity arises when everyday circumspection “ sees” nothing
more at hand that needs to be done. The care of making, improving,
finishing something comes to a rest; circumspection , whose proper
function is to bring things near (entfernen) so that they can be taken
care of, becomes liberated from the workaday world to which it has
been bound. The unoccupied care, however, does not thereby disap-
pear, but gathers itself in the liberated circumspection. Since its very
essence is to bring something near, yet there is nothing at hand that has
to be done, circumspection creates new possibilities for seeing itself:
It tends to leave the things nearest at hand for a distant and strange
world. Care turns into taking-care of possibilities, resting and staying to
see the “ world” only in its outward appearance [ Aussehen ] . Da-sein seeks
distance solely to bring it near in its outward appearance. Da-sein lets
itself be intrigued just by the outward appearance of the world, a kind of
being in which it makes sure that it gets rid of itself as being-in-the-world,
gets rid of being with the nearest everyday things at hand. (SZ, 172 )
ing present , thus constantly tries to run away from the awaiting in
which it is nevertheless “ held , ” [ ugehalten” ] although in a dispersed
[ ungehalten ] way. (SZ, 346-47 )
Even a superficial reading of this passage shows that the key to its
understanding lies in the meaning of “ held ” and “ unheld.” Their mean-
ing, however, is left obscure by Heidegger, not only here but through-
out Division Two. All that we know so far is that the authentic instant
is held in thé forward-running recollection of a resolute existence and
is clearly the extreme opposite of the unheld presenting of curiosity,
which seeks to run away from even an inauthentic awaiting. How can
we grasp more precisely what Heidegger intends to say with the “ held ”
and “ unheld ” presenting? By remembering that what the analysis seeks
to show is the temporal structure of an uprooting curiosity that leads
to an increasing groundlessness of a falling here-being. The held and
unheld presenting must therefore belong to the temporality of a firmly
grounded and an ungrounded here-being respectively. Once this connec-
tion is seen, the meaning of the present analysis can be clearly grasped
and even the reason for Heidegger’s obscurity becomes understand-
able. Heidegger cannot give an explicit explanation at this point
because the ground-character of here-being is left entirely in the pre-
liminary state in which it is discussed in the second chapter of Division
Two. It was only two years after the publication of Being and Time that
the essay “ On the Essence of Ground” was published, in which the
problem of “ ground ” was carried a step further.
This essay tells us of the three ways in which a factical here-being
grounds itself, that is, stabilizes itself , gains a stand and constancy in
itself as a thrown being-in-the-world. The self-grounding character of
Da-sein is, in turn, “ grounded” in the temporality of care, which holds
the present in an ecstatic unity with the future and past. In resolutely
running-forward to its utmost possibility, here-being comes wholly to
itself as a self; it “ identifies” itself as the presenting being-in-the-world
it already is. Here-being’s future holds the instant to itself as the end by
which all presenting is in advance guided. That is why a resolute exis-
tence does not vacillatingly lose itself among the “ sights ” offered by the
world, but “ instantly” grasps what is relevant to its own possibilities and
lets go what is irrelevant.
The resolutely forward-running existence, however, must recol-
lectingly come-back-to its ownmost having-been. The recollection
nakedly reveals here-being’s thrownness which has already delivered it
over to itself in its dependence upon a world . The not-self-original
throw into a world is the reason why the hereness of a thrown existence
Temporality and Everydayness 247
TABLE 13.3
The Temporality of Falling
Inauthentic Authentic
curiosity
awaiting-
forgetting-
( running after,
running away )-
making present
^
Da-sein’s being as an attunedly falling, understanding articulating
( discursive ) being-in-the-world. It is because Da sein factually exists in a
world with others that the articulated understandability of his hereness
comes to word and concretely voices itself ( utters itself ) in language.
The existentiell-ontic phenomenon of language is therefore not a man-
made tool consisting of words into which mutually agreed meanings
have been infused , but is the signifying voicing of the already disclosed
and articulated meaning of man’s hereness. Where language is a com-
municating talk , what is communicated, shared, is not the inner expe-
rience of an isolated subject with another isolated subject but the mutu-
ally understandable hereness in a mutually shared world. A verbal
expression, however, is not always indispensable to discourse, as the
silent, wordless call of care has strikingly shown.
The distinctive function of discourse helps to explain why its tem-
porality is different from that of the other disclosing characters of
here-being. While understanding, attunement, and falling are primar-
ily constituted by one ecstasis in the unity of time , there is no definite
ecstasis that has a similar constitutive function for discourse. Speech
articulates the whole dislosedness of here-being; so that in principle nei-
ther the futural character of existence, nor the having-been of thrown-
ness, nor the presenting of falling can have a preponderant weight. In
fact, however, discourse usually expresses itself in concrete language
and speaks primarily in the mode of care-taking talking-over of the
—
world roundabout us hence the presenting has a “ privileged constitutive
function ” (SZ, 349 ).
For the reason just stated, this analysis must clearly be different
from the preceding ones. There is no immediately obvious reason,
however, why it must be so disappointingly short, occupying barely a
page. It confines itself mainly to stating the temporal problems that
will have to be dealt with, such as the tenses of verbs, the gradations in
time ( Zeitstufen ) , and the kinds of action ( Aktionsarten ) distinguished by
language. These temporal characteristics do not arise from the fact
that language expresses, among other things, processes that happen in
time, nor from the fact that speaking takes place in a “ psychological
time,” but discourse is in itself temporal, insofar as all speaking o f . . . ,
about . . . , and to . . . , is grounded in the ecstatic unity of temporality
(SZ, 349 ). With the help of the traditional and vulgar concept of time,
254 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
The inquiry now comes back to the point from which Division One
started, to being-in-the-world as a fundamental constituent of care. Hei-
degger’s first task in Being and Time was to show that Da-sein is never
merely “ here” as an isolated, relationless subject, but with his disclosed
hereness the whole complex of interlinked relations ( world ) from
which he refers himself to other beings is cooriginally disclosed. Being-
here is therefore in itself a being-in-relation-to . . . , a being-in-a-world.
The fundamental constitution of being-in-the-world carries and
makes possible Da-sein’s being-together-with things within the world,
whether in the mode of a circumspect having-to-do-with-them, or in
the mode of a theoretical-scientific observation of them. Both these
ways of taking care of things are grounded in Da-sein’s being as care.
The ecstatic temporality of care lies already in all Da-sein’s relations to
things and makes them first of all possible. To show this in detail will
be the task of the first two subdivisions ( a and b ) of the present sec-
tion. In the third subdivision ( c) the temporal analysis of being-in-the-
world will lead to the following questions:
How is something like world possible at all, in what sense is world, what
and how does the world transcend, how are “ independent ” innerworldly
beings “ connected” with the transcending world? The ontological exposi-
tion of these questions does not already entail their answer. On the other
hand, they do bring about the clarification, previously necessary, of the
structures with reference to which the problem of transcendence is to be
interrogated. (SZ, 351)
self, which first of all opens up the horizon of a “ before” into which the
self-forgetful here-being can remember the relevant utensils. The every-
day retaining, however, is not an explicit “ fixing ” of a utensil-whole, just
as the awaiting is not an explicit, theoretical contemplation of an end;
it is rather the making present that springs from the unity of an await-
ing-retaining that makes “ the characteristic absorption in taking care in
the world of its useful things possible ” (SZ, 354 ).
The awaiting-retaining making present unifies the implicitly
understood references within which everyday care circumspectly moves
without any explicit, theoretical grasp of them. The smooth, matter-of
course movement within these familiar references, however, can be
interrupted. As Division One has explained in some detail ( chap. 3, §
16 ), it is on the occasion of such breaks that the utensil-world as a
whole may first come into view, and the hitherto taken-for-granted,
inconspicuous utensils may suddenly arrest our attention by showing
themselves in the unfamiliar mode of mere substances.
What is the ontological-temporal condition of the possibility that
—
something unusable for example, a tool which fails to do its job can
arrest our attention? In the following analysis, Heidegger proceeds to
—
show the inadequacy of a “ theory of association ” to explain even our
simplest dealings with things. First, “ association ” takes account only of
the connection between “ past experience ” and “ present experiences.”
Further, as a psychological theory, it lacks an adequate-ontological
foundation. In such a seemingly simple experience as, for instance, our
attention being caught by a damaged tool, lies already the whole of
temporality. The awaiting-retaining making present is “ caught, ” “ held
up” in its absorption in the relevance- relations, by what turns out to be,
on inspection , damage to the tool. The making present is held fast by
the unfitness of the tool for the work in hand, so that it is only now that
the implicit awaited what-for, together with the presently manipulated
tool, become explicit. The making present, on the other hand,
But the unusability of a utensil is not the only way in which the
smooth flow of having-to-do-with-things may be broken. We may find, for
instance, that something we were looking forward to finding at hand is not
there at all. This discovery is made by our missing the utensil. Missing some-
thing is not merely a not-making-present ( Ungegenwärtigen ) of the utensil in
question, but rather a “ not-making-present” as “ a deficient mode of the pre-
sent in the sense of the not-making-present of something expected or always
already available.” Though deficient, this mode is positive. Missing some-
thing necessarily stands in an ecstatic unity with awaiting, since we could
never miss something unless we were already awaiting it
We can be taken by surprise, on the other hand, only by some-
thing not awaited. Just as the “ not-making-present” is not a sheer
absence of awaiting, nor is the “ not awaiting” ; it is rather a positive,
though deficient, mode of it. Otherwise, it would be wholly inexplica-
ble why Heidegger says that “ The not awaiting of the making present
that is lost first discloses the ‘horizonal’ realm in which something sur-
prising can overcome Da-sein ” (SZ, 355).
Obscure as this sentence is in many respects, one thing at least is
clear: unless the not awaiting were a positive ecstasis of temporality, it
could not possibly disclose a horizonal realm within which a surprise
can overtake a falling here-being. As we have heard earlier, the momen-
tum of the fall constricts the falling here-being more and more in a
making present that seeks to uproot itself from the hold and guidance
of a genuine awaiting.
Finally, a most important way in which a circumspect taking-care
of things can be interrupted is by knocking up against those things it
can neither produce, procure, nor guard against, avoid, or eliminate.
These insuperable obstacles are coped with or put up with by a care-
taking here-being. The “ coping with . . .” ( Sichabfinden mit . . .) is not a
merely negative acquiescing in or ignoring of things, but a specific
mode of discovering them in the character of the inopportune, hin-
dering, troubling, and endangering. Generally speaking, these things
encounter us in the mode of resistance ( Widerständigkeit ).
The way the present is rooted in the future and in the having-been is the
existential and temporal condition of the possibility that what is pro-
jected in circumspect understanding can be brought nearer in a making
present in such a way that the present must adapt itself to what is encoun-
tered in the horizon of an awaiting retention, that is, it must interpret
itself in the schema of the as-structure. This gives us the answer to our
question whether the as-structure is existentially and ontologically con-
nected with the phenomenon of the projecting [SZ, 151]. Like under-
standing and interpretation in general, the “ as ” ¿5 grounded in the ecstatic and
horizonal unity of temporality. (SZ, 360 )
—
—
“ schema” a concept whose importance is becoming more and more
evident will not yet be given. This is explicitly deferred by Heidegger
to the “ fundamental analysis of being, ” which was to have been carried
out in Division Three. There, Heidegger promises us and more pre- —
cisely “ in connection with the interpretation of the ‘is’ ( which as a cop-
ula ‘expresses’ the addressing of something as something ) ” that “ we
must again make the as-phenomenon thematic and define the concept
—
of the ‘schema’ existentially ” (SZ, 360 ).
That this promise remains unfulfilled is all the more regrettable
because there is good reason to think that Heidegger intends the exis-
tential-temporal interpretation or the “ schema” to cast light on “ the
obscurity of his [Kant’s] doctrine of the schematism ” (SZ, 23; and see
KPM, especially §§19-23, for fuller explanation of these connections ).
The preceding discussion, it is true, has cast some light on the mean-
ing of the circumspectly deliberating “ if-then ” and of the “ as.” But this
obviously cannot exhaust their meaning, for the “ schema of making
present” must conform to the manner of being in which the beings to
be explained encounter us. Our understanding of being is capable of a
wide range of modifications. If, for instance, the being of within-world-
ish beings is called “ reality, ” then handy-being ( handy reality ) is only
one manner of it, substantial reality another manner, and, as Heideg-
ger occasionally hints, there may be still further modifications of it. It
follows that even if the form of the schemata in which our explanations
move should remain the same, their meaning must be modifiable. The
same considerations lead to the conclusion that the “ is, ” which gives
268 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
the being before us, with which we are circumspectly familiar as a ham-
mer, has a weight, that is, the “ property ” of heaviness. It exerts a pres-
sure on what lies beneath it, and when that is removed, it falls. The dis-
course understood in this way is no longer in the horizon of the
awaiting retention of a totality of useful things and its relations of rele-
vance. What is said has been drawn from looking at what is appropriate
for a being with “ mass.” What is now in view is appropriate for the ham-
mer, not as a tool, but as a corporeal thing that is subject to the law of
gravity. Circumspect talk about being “ too heavy ” or “ too light ” no
longer has any “ meaning” ; that is, the thing now encountered of itself
provides us with nothing in relation to which it could be “ found” too
heavy or too light. (SZ, 360-61)
Temporality and Everydayness 269
The point to be noted here is that it is not the world that is modified
into a “ physical nature,” but that nature itself, according to Heidegger, is a
concrete “ within-worldish being” which is discoverable only within and in
transit through ( im Durchgang ) a predisclosed world. Now, taking the sen-
——
tence “ The hammer is heavy” to assert a “ physical” proposition though,
strictly speaking, there are no such things as hammers in physics Heideg-
ger goes on to analyze how it now presents the former utensil:
We overlook not only the tool-character of the being encountered, but
thus also that which belongs to every useful thing at hand: its place. The
place becomes indifferent. This does not mean that the objectively pre-
sent thing loses its “ location” altogether. Its place becomes a position in
space and time, a “ world-point, ” which is in no way distinguished from
any other. This means that the multiplicity of places of useful things at
hand defined in the surrounding world is not just modified to a sheer
multiplicity of positions, but the beings of the surrounding world are
released [ entschränkt ]. The totality of what is objectively present becomes
thematic. ( SZ, 362 )
—
—
pure and simple, ” (SZ, 38 ) that which sheerly transcends beings as
such and if this transcendens is disclosed in here-being, then here-being
must always transcend ( go out, stand out beyond ) beings as such and
—
—
as a whole. “ If the thematization of what is objectively present the sci-
entific project of nature is to become possible, Da sein must transcend
the beings thematized. Transcendence does not consist in objectiva-
tion, but is rather presupposed by it” (SZ, 363). Those theories of
knowledge, on the other hand, which take their start from the subject-
object relation as the supposed “ ultimate” that cannot or need not be
further explained, see in this relation itself the “ transcendence”
whereby a “ worldless subject” goes out from his “ immanent sphere ” to
an object outside himself. To expose the inadequacy of such theories
and of the wholly insufficient conception of here-being as a “ subject, ”
is of course only a negative, but by no means negligible, aim of Being
and Timey considering the stranglehold of such conceptions on our
whole way of thinking.
In raising the question of transcendence, the inquiry brings itself
face to face with the central problem of how being as the transcendens
can be disclosed by the transcending here-being. The problem has
been brought to the foreground by the modification of the implicit,
everyday understanding of being into the theoretical understanding of
being as substantial reality and its explicit articulation in a predesigned
plan of nature.
Whether explicit or implicit, an understanding of being, and there-
fore a transcendence of here-being must already underlie the discovery
of beings, whether in the mode of a circumspect care- taking or of a the-
oretical observation. Heidegger explicitly identifies transcendence with
being-in-the-world, as we now know from Vom Wesen des Grundes ( WG,
37ff., W, 53ff., G9, 156ff., P, 121ff.). On the ground of this fundamental
structure, the factical here-being transcends beings as such and as a
whole, among them first and foremost his own thrown self. This tran-
276 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
The question to be raised now is different from the one asked and
answered in Division One ( chap. 3). There it was the worldishness of
world, its ontological structure, that was to be laid bare. This was found
to lie in significance, which constitutes the coherent unity of world. A
significant coherence might be called the “ essence ” of world, were the
word essence not so misleading in its usual meaning of the whatness or
the inner possibility of beings. The world is not a concrete being, nor
the totality beings, but rather the significant way in which they bear on
each other and on here-being’s existence as a whole. To call this the
“ essence” of world would therefore be misleading. But the predicament
into which Heidegger’s present question puts us is even worse, for now
he asks in what way world must be , how its “ being” is ontologically pos-
sible. The “ being” of world obviously cannot mean existentia, “ reality,”
or by whatever name we call the actual thereness of beings.
The cardinal point to be noted is that the “ being” of world is not
a problem about a world “ in and by itself, ” as though the world were the
all of substantial beings that can be there in and by themselves. The
question of how these substantial beings were there and what real con-
nections there are between them before and without a disclosure of
being, is not a question for a fundamental ontology. This takes its depar-
ture from the “ ontological difference,” the basic “ fact ” that from this
differentiation beings show themselves as the beings they are only in the
light of being and, conversely, being shows itself ( in a totally different
way) as the being of beings. Since world “ is” only as an irreducible and
unique character of being, and since being only “ is ” in its disclosedness
in a factical here-being ( Da sein ), the possibility of the being of world
can lie only in its unity with here-being as a being-in-the-world.
A minor, but not quite negligible point to be noted is that Hei-
degger now takes the “ for -the-sake-of-which ” into the unity of “ signif-
icance, ” whereas in Division One he spoke of “ the for- the-sake-of-
Temporality and Everydayness 277
which and of significance ” (SZ, 143, emphasis added ). This gave rise
to the misleading impression that the everyday world was, after all,
the utensil-world.
Here-being’ s understanding of himself in connection with other
beings, that is, in a world, is an existential constituent of care. Only
when and as long as beings of the character of here-being “ are here, ”
is a world “ here ” also. Heidegger does not merely say that here-being
“ has ” a world, that the world is his world. He says more than that;
namely, that in existing, here-being is his world , that is, it is disclosed
in and with his existence. The solipsist, on the other hand, believes that
the world is “ his world ” in the-sense that all the other beings he expe-
riences exist only in his consciousness, only as his representations or
perceptions ( Vorstellungen). Heidegger’s interpretation of world as an
ontological character of here-being exposes not only the fallaciousness
of this reasoning, but also that it has arisen from a thoroughgoing con-
fusion of being with beings. Reality is confused with the real things,
their real connections and properties. The whole of reality is identified
with the totality of real beings, and this is what is usually called “ the
world.” Reality, however, is a mode of being which only “ is ” in its dis-
closedness. When this disclosure no longer happens, when, for
instance, through a catastrophe beings like ourselves no longer factu-
ally exist, then there will be no “ reality.” But this does not in the least
—
mean that real beings— the earth, the seas, the stars will suddenly dis-
solve into nothing. It means only that they would no longer be manifest
as the beings they are, they would be neither discovered nor hidden
(SZ, 212 ), and would, in that sense, remain beingless and nameless, for
only as long as there is disclosure and discovery ( truth ), can beings be
called by a name.
The disclosedness of the “ here,” as the preceding analyses of this
chapter have shown in detail, is grounded in temporality. This must
also make possible the significance which is the ontological structure
of world.
The existential and temporal condition of the possibility of world lies in the fact
that temporality, as an ecstatic unity, has something like a horizon. The
ecstases are not simply raptures toward. . . . Rather, a “ whereto ” of rapt-
ness belongs to the ecstasy. We call this whereto of the ecstasy the hori-
zonal schema. (SZ, 365 )
— —
porality can also explain and explain perhaps for the first time in a sat-
isfactory way how we can experience ourselves together with other
beings in the wholeness of a world. As long as the world is conceived as
—
a totality of beings whether these beings are interpreted as things or
—
facts, makes no difference it remains a mystery how we can experience
such a totality. Kant held that the idea of the totality of world, although
a necessary idea, lay beyond a possible experience, meaning by “ expe-
rience ” the empirical intuition of “ what is, ” that is, of the substantial
things of nature, unified by the a priori synthesis of the categories with
the pure intuition of time and space. Heidegger also maintains that the
totality of beings can never be grasped by us, but at the same time
explains why we nonetheless experience these beings in the whole of a
world: the prior disclosure of the nothing in advance gathers all beings
into a whole by making them manifest as not nothing, as things that are.
But since the “ nothing” does not “ exist” at all, it can reveal itself only to
concrete beings like ourselves as a negating as a denying or withdraw-
ing: it denies us to ourselves as our own ground and withdraws from us
the possibility of being-here-anymore. Hence the disclosure of being
that happens with the disclosure of nothing cannot be an indifferent
happening, but is a throw which hands us out to our factical selves and
directs us to the beings upon which we are dependent. Heidegger thus
succeeds in giving an explanation not only of how we can experience
the world as a whole, but why this world-horizon must refer us to the
beings discoverable within it. It may be added that Heidegger’ s expla-
nation has a compellingness which Kant’s arguments about the applic-
ability of the categories solely to the a priori forms of intuition, and
mediately to a possible empirical intuition of objects, never achieve.
Since the world is grounded in the horizon of an ecstatic tempo-
rality, it must necessarily be “ transcendent” ; that is, it must be “ further
out” than any beings that can be discovered within it. Heidegger’ s elu-
cidations of the “ transcendence of world ” will bring strikingly into view
a characteristic of his thinking: it always seems to start, so to speak,
from the outmost circumference and work inward ; whereas, our usual
Temporality and Everydayness 281
thinking works in exactly the opposite way. For instance, we are apt to
think of the past as stretching out behind us from our “ here and now, ”
and the future as stretching out in front of us from “ here and now.”
Similarly, we envisage space as radiating out in all directions, with our-
selves as a center. Heidegger, on the contrary, starts from the furthest
distance and comes back to the “ here and now.” So, for instance, he
finds the first constituent of an existential spaceishness in “ un-distanc-
ing” ( Ent -fernung ), a diminishing of distance. This peculiarity of Hei-
degger’s thought has been noted already, but it is only now, with the
exposition of the ecstatic horizon of temporality, that its full force can
strike us:
Both of these passages evidently say the same thing, the only dif-
ference being that in the first Heidegger is thinking purely of the struc-
ture of temporality, while in the second he thinks of the factical here-
being as temporality become existent. Incidentally, the language of the
first passage comes dangerously near to suggesting that temporality is
something existing in and by itself, a possibility that Heidegger has
decisively ruled out and any suggestion of which must be strenuously
resisted. What Heidegger’s language reveals is rather the concrete way
in which he “ sees ” those phenomenal structures which to us only too
often remain vague abstractions.
The main point of our passages is the constancy of the ecstatic
removals to a corresponding horizon. Temporality “ holds i t s e l f . . . in
the horizons of its ecstasies. . . .” It constantly stands out beyond itself
and stays in its distant horizons. All movement originates from and
takes place within them, as the throw forward from thrownness to the
impassable possibility of not-being-here and the throw back from the
impassable not-being-here to the factical self, already on the “ look out”
for a possible vis-à-vis. The horizon of the present temporalizes itself
cooriginally with those of the future and the having-been. As an antic-
ipating removal to a wholly insubstantial “ something” facing the pre-
senting here-being, the horizon of presentness is necessarily “ further
282 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
out” than any beings whose bodily presence becomes discoverable and
understandable from and within it.
According to Heidegger, then, our knowledge of beings does not
start from an immediate perception of them “ here and now, ” but
rather the area of openness in which we move must be much wider
than the pin-point of “ here and now.” 9 It is only in coming back from the
distance opened up primarily by an ecstatic temporality that a concrete
—
being can meet us “ in the There ” or “ in the Here, ” as we prefer to say
in discussing Division Two. ( See above, our section entitled “ The Lan-
guage of Division Two.” )
But perhaps we should also prefer to say uinto the Here, ” for Hei-
degger’s words are “ in das Da begegnende Seiende.” Compare his
phrase “ in die Zeit begegnen ” in the later discussion of “ world-time.”
The use of the accusative suggests that Heidegger really intends to say
“ into ” and not “ in.” This is his way of expressing that the “ here ” and
the “ now ” are not self-subsistent media in which our encounters with
other beings take place, but are “ here ” only with the disclosed hereness
of being. Only when and as long as a world is opened up with a facti-
cally existing being-in-the-world can beings enter into its openness and
reveal themselves as the beings they are. That these beings become dis-
coverable within the world is, of course, in no way in the power of here-
being. They must in some way be “ there” of themselves, otherwise we
could not discover them.
With the ecstatic-horizonal unity of temporality, the problem of
the transcendence of world has been satisfactorily solved. Since the
world is grounded in the schematically defined horizon of the whole
temporality, it is necessarily transcendent: it is always “ further out” than
any “ objects” can possibly be. But, it may be asked, does Heidegger not
interpret the world entirely subjectively? Indeed, Heidegger says that “ if
the ‘subject’ is conceived ontologically as existing Da sein, whose being
is grounded in temporality, we must say then that the world is ‘subjec-
tive.’ But this ‘subjective’ world, as one that is temporally transcendent,
is then more ‘objective’ than any possible ‘object’ ” (SZ, 366 ).
A hurried reading of this passage could easily mislead the reader
into thinking that Heidegger is, after all, slipping back into the much-
maligned subject-object relation. But, in fact, Heidegger is doing the
opposite. He is restating once more that the first requisite for a funda-
mental ontology is to overcome the conception of man’ s essence as
subjectivity. Not only is the subjectivity of the subject a wholly inade-
quate foundation on which to answer the questions, How is a disclos-
ing understanding of being at all possible to a finite existence? and,
What does being mean ? It only too readily gives rise to the impression
Temporality and Everydayness 283
that the self-glorifying subject, solely by his own power, imposes his
own law and order on an objective nature ( “ world ” ) which he has not
created, which he can never master, and on which he himself is depen-
dent. The existential-temporal interpretation of a finite here-being, on
the other hand, in advance conceives Da-sein as belonging to a disclo-
sure ( truth ) of being which is not of his own making, but into which he
has been “ thrown.” It is its “ power ” that confers on Da-sein the unique
task of discovering beings and so bringing them into the truth that is
appropriate to their specific ways of being. The horizonal schema, Hei-
degger claims, which defines the being of things within the world by a
“ for, ” and reveals their referredness to a for-the-sake-of-itself , is not an
arbitrary “ network of forms that is imposed upon some material by a
worldless subject, ” but rather here-being’s original understanding of
himself and his world in the ecstatic-horizonal unity of his “ here.” The
coming-back-from these horizons to the concrete beings discoverable
within them , and understanding them in their “ significant ” bearings
on a finite existence, reveals the connection between Da-sein and
things far more elementally than a theoretical observation of mere sub-
stantial objects can ever do.
Before we leave the fascinating subject of Heidegger’s conception
of world, we must briefly recur to the concept of “ schema, ” which first
became thematic in the previous subsection. What Heidegger dis-
cussed there under the title of “ schema” seemed to be only tenuously,
if at all, connected with Kant’s schematized categories. The exposition
of the “ horizonal schema, ” however, puts the whole matter into a dif-
ferent light. We can now see that the theme of Heidegger’s previous
discussion ( the “ if-then ” and the “ as ” ) was only the schema of interpre-
tation, and therefore not at all on a par with Kant’s transcendental
schema. The latter can be compared only with Heidegger’ s horizonal
schema, for this belongs to the original existential understanding of
being, and defines the being ( makes it “ apprehensible ” ) that is dis-
closed in the ecstatic horizon of temporality. However, when we try to
compare them we are struck by the differences rather than by any
resemblance. In the first place, Heidegger gives us only three
schemata. ( It is doubtful whether the “ whereto, ” the schema of factic-
ity, could be counted as a fourth.) Kant’s transcendental schema, on the
other hand, “ sensifies ” the categories, of which there are four groups,
each subdivided into three concepts that Kant regards as indispens-
able. But the greatest contrast is that two of Heidegger’ s three
— —
schemata define here-being’ s ecstatic removal to himself that is, are
existential schemata and only the “ for” defines the being of within-
worldish beings, so that it alone can be called a “ catégorial schema” at
284 Part Three: Di-vision Two of Being and Time
all. Kant’s schematized categories, on the other hand, all define being
as substantial reality . This, however, is the mode of being of things as
mere substances. The task would be to see whether the for-whatness of
handy things could be so modified into the mere-whatness of substan-
tial things as to yield all the categories Kant regarded as primordial
concepts, and whether the schematization of these categories into the
pure image of time could be really adequately explained from the
derivative concepts of time as a pure succession of nows.
It is very likely that Heidegger intended to carry out this task in
the first division of Part II of Being and Time. It would undoubtedly
have thrown a light into the “ obscurity ” of Kant ‘s teaching of schema-
tism , and especially, perhaps, upon the much-debated and highly
doubtful source and origin of the Kantian categories. Unfortunately,
the whole of Part II of Being and Time remains unwritten in the way it
was originally planned, because it required Division Three of Part 1 as
its indispensable basis.
In the bringing-close that makes the handling and being occupied that is
—
“ absorbed in the matter,” the essential structure of care falling prey-
makes itself known. Its existential and temporal constitution is distin-
guished by the fact that in falling prey, and thus also in the bringing near
which is founded in “ making present,” the forgetting that awaits pursues
the present. In the making present that brings something near from its
wherefrom , making present loses itself in itself, and forgets the over there.
For this reason if the “ observation ” of innerwordly beings starts in such a
making present, the illusion arises that “ initially” only a thing is objectively
present, here indeed, but indeterminately, in a space in general. (SZ, 369)
TABLE 13.4
The Temporality of Care
Its General Structure: Having-Been Making-Present Coming-to-Itself
The last two sentences explain not only the expressions Heideg-
ger mentions, but , at the same time , what he means by calling every-
dayness the indifferent and average way of existing. In what way does
here- being “ manifest” itself in the first place? It “ manifests” itself, Hei-
degger says ironically, in a public being-together-with that covers over
the singleness of a finite self, levels it down to the uniformity of “ what
one does,” so that everyone becomes interchangeable with and replace-
able by every other one.
This way of being-here is “ indifferent , ” insofar as one is not dif-
ferentiated from any other one. The inauthentic and authentic self
Temporality and Everydayness 291
appears equally as one, even if the latter has just “ overcome ” every-
dayness. The “ overcome” has again an ironical tone. Heidegger may be
thinking of an all too facile assumption that everydayness can be once
and for all “ overcome, ” when in fact it is so deeply embedded in care
that it can never be wholly eliminated.
In the first place, that is, in the publicity of the everyday world,
unique existence appears as an indifferent “ one.” This is at the same time
the average way in which here-being is manifest to everyman. The aver-
age is not what is always and necessarily so, but what is so “ for the most
part, ” “ usually,” “ as a rule.” What begins to appear with the “ usual, ” the
“ as a rule,” is something like a span or stretch of time, for all usage and
habit imply a long period of practice. This becomes explicit in the next
paragraph, where Heidegger describes the way ( the how ) in which here-
being “ lives unto the day, ” drifting along from day to day, whether in all
respects or only in those which are prescribed by “ them.”
Being comfortable belongs to this How, even if habit forces us to what is
burdensome and “ repulsive.” The tomorrow that everyday taking care
waits for is the “ eternal yesterday.” The monotony of everyday ness takes
whatever the day happens to bring as a change. Everydayness determines
Da-sein even when it has not chosen the they as its “ hero.” (SZ, 370-71)
are in fact asking about what Heidegger calls the stretchedness of here-
being through his days, about the events which have happened in the
course of them , not as disconnected episodes, but in the meaningful
unity and coherence of a single “ fate ” or “ destiny.” There is, therefore,
at least a rough connection between the popular sense of “ someone’s
history ” and the existential concept of it, although the two are by no
means identical, and the latter will turn out to include the history of
the “ past, ” which is the primary meaning we usually attach to the word.
The first hint of the problem of historicity already raises the
problem of the “ time ” through which here-being stretches itself. This
is the time which here-being counts upon and takes account of, which
“ accounting” is astronomically regulated and published in calendars.
The everyday “ happening” of here-being and his care-taking counting
with time must be drawn into the interpretation of temporality before
the ontological meaning of everydayness can be made even a problem.
Division Two aims at a full working out of the problem, but the ade-
quate conceptual definition of everydayness, Heidegger announces in
the by now familiar formula, “ can succeed only in the framework of a
fundamental discussion of the meaning of being in general and its pos-
sible variations” (SZ, 371-72 ).
The importance of the present short section is easily overlooked,
because the preparatory steps it takes toward the existential problem of
history remain implicit, while in following up the complex thought of
the next chapter the reader may fail to connect it up in retrospect with
what has already been said here. That is why in this interpretation I
have made quite explicit what Heidegger only hints at.
An important, perhaps the most important, implication of this
section still remains to be mentioned. The time through which here-
being stretches itself, as we have heard, is the time that is regulated by
astronomical measurements and is kept count of by calendars. But this
is also the time in which within-worldish beings arise, have a duration
and pass away, and in which all kinds of events within the world take
place. How this world-time belongs to and springs from the original
time of care will be elucidated in detail in the last chapter of Division
Two. What interests us now is that here-being himself must necessarily
enter into the time which determines the in-timeness ( Innerzeitigkeit ) of
within-worldish beings and which originates in his own temporality.
His own being-in- time essentially belongs to the factical here-being, in
contrast to his being-in -space like a within-worldish thing, which Hei-
degger rejected as inappropriate. To put the point in another way:
while it is perfectly well possible for us to conceive our “ spatial prop-
erties” as though we were merely extended bodies in space, and for cer-
Temporality and Everydayness 293
295
296 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
Da-sein [. . .] stretches itself along in such a way that its own being is
constituted beforehand as this stretching along. The “ between ” of birth
and death already lies in the being of Da-sein [. . .]. Understood existen-
tially, birth is never something past in the sense of what is no longer
objectively present , and death is just as far from being the kind of being
of something outstanding that is not yet objectively present but will
come. Factical Da-sein exists as born, and, born, it is already dying in
the sense of being-toward-death. Both “ ends ” and their “ between ” are
as long as Da-sein factically exists, and they are in the sole way possible
on the basis of Da-sein as care. In the unity of thrownness and the flee-
Temporality and Historicity 297
The specific movement of the stretched out stretching itself along, we call
the occurrence of Da-sein. The question of the “ connectedness” of Da-sein
298 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
rality of care. The origin of the time in which both history and the
processes of nature take place and by which they are measured will be
exhaustively analyzed in his next chapter, chapter 6 of Division Two.
The introductory section to the present chapter ends with a refer-
ence to Dilthey, whose researches into the problem of historicity have
inspired Heidegger’s own inquiries. Heidegger acknowledges his
indebtedness in a somewhat startling way: “ Basically, the following
analysis is solely concerned with furthering the investigations of Dilthey
in a preparatory way” (SZ, 377). The word solely in this sentence is as
exaggerated as it is misleading. In all soberness, we can say that this
fifth chapter of Divison Two takes an important step toward the central
aim of elucidating the meaning of being, and solely by virtue of doing so
does it further an assimilation of Dilthey’s investigations. This becomes
clear from the key passage of the correspondence of Count Yorck von
Wartenburg with Dilthey, quoted in the last section of this chapter.3 In
this passage Count Yorck envisages the task of working out “ the generic
difference between the ontic and the historical ” (SZ, 403). “ Ontic” and
“ historical, ” we must note, are used here in Count Yorck’s and not in
Heidegger’s sense. “ Ontic ” means the visible and tangible, the substan-
tial, in sharp contrast to the “ historical,” the spiritual, the self-con-
sciously living. The task outlined by Count Yorck, Heidegger remarks, is
the fundamental aim of all “ philosophy of life.” This aim, however, is
not formulated radically enough, as the following key-passage shows.
are still in daily use and yet belong to the “ past.” What is it in them that
has “ passed ” ? Nothing less than the world within which they were once
handily encountered by a here-being and were used by him in his care-
taking being-in-the-world. It is the world that no longer exists, whereas
the utensil that formerly belonged to that world can still be substan-
tially present. But what does the no-longer-being of world mean? There
is world only as an existential-ontological constituent of here-being.
Strictly speaking, therefore, we should not speak of a “ past” world,
since Heidegger reserves the word past ( vergangen ) for things. We
should speak rather of a world that has been ( gewesen ) . Similarly, a
here-being who no longer exists is not “ past,” but has-been-here ( da-
gewesen ) . The still present antiquities owe their historical character to
their belonging to and descent from the world of here-being who has
been here. It is he who is primarily historical. Secondarily historical are
—
the things in the widest sense not only utensils but also events and
—
nature in the sense of “ historical ground” which belong to a world,
and are called by Heidegger the “ world-historical.”
With this, however, the problem of historical-being is not yet
properly formulated. Indeed, we might be misled into thinking that
only the here-being who has-been-here is historical; whereas, Heideg-
ger intends to show that it is precisely the factically existing here-being
who is primarily and originally historical. It is in the temporality of his
being that the has-been temporalizes itself cooriginally with a making-
present-coming. The problem now becomes acute: why should the has-
or having-been determine the historical when it belongs to the tempo-
ral unity of care as a making-present-coming?
The vulgar ontic notion of history is predominantly drawn from
the “ world-historical.” Although it also understands Da sein as the pri-
mary “ subject” of history, it cannot sufficiently distinguish the tempo-
rality of the “ subject ” from the being-in-time of things. Heidegger’ s
positive task now is to show the temporal-ontological conditions on the
basis of which the “ subjectivity of the subject” is essentially historical.
back to his own thrownness. In taking over his whole being as his own
he is at the same time “ instantly ” here for his “ situation, ” in which and
from which he resolutely grasps the factical possibilities he chooses for
his own. It is these factical possibilities which now give Heidegger a lead
into the problem of historicity. The important transitional passage that
leads from the first to the second is unfortunately so condensed that
the coherence of Heidegger’s argument becomes almost invisible. The
following exposition will make the steps of the argument much more
explicit than they are in Being and Time (SZ, 383).
The first step is taken by formulating the hitherto unconsidered
question, From where, in principle, can the factical possibilities of
existence be drawn? They obviously cannot be derived from the ulti-
mate possibility that closes an existence, especially since the authen-
tic running-forward to it does not mean a contemplative dwelling
upon death, but means the resolute coming-back -to the factical
“ here.” Could it be then, Heidegger asks, that the thrownness of the
self into a world discloses a horizon from which an existence wrests
his factical possibilities?
If it should indeed be our thrownness from which we draw our
factical possibilities, then their historical character becomes immedi-
ately evident, for the temporal meaning of thrownness is the having-
been, the “ past.” The having-been, in turn, predominantly determines
the historical. It is an obvious ontic fact that no generation creates its
tasks and opportunities from nothing, but inherits them from preced-
ing generations, so that even the new departures from and breaks with
tradition are grounded in the “ past.” Heidegger’s problem is to explain
-
how the existential temporal constitution of care makes this obvious
fact possible. How can a factical here-being disclose not only his own
having-been in his own world, but go back to other existences who
have-been-here before him in their world ? The coming-back-to himself
in his thrownness discloses only the finite having-been of a single exis-
tence. Now the problem is how a wider horizon of the having-been can
be opened up, a horizon that reaches back behind and before a finite
existence, so that a continuity with the past and a handing down of
tasks and achievements becomes possible.
No sooner is this problem explicitly formulated than a difficulty
becomes evident. As Heidegger has shown earlier, our thrownness is
manifest to us from an untransgressable limit that closes our own hav-
ing-been-already-here as decisively as death closes our possibility of
being-here-any-more. The “ nothing of myself ’ is revealed in a negation
that becomes explicit in the structure of care as a no¿-determined
ground-being of a negativity ( Div. Two, chap. 2 ). Heidegger refers us
304 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
back to this negation in a single sentence: “ Did we not moreover say [at
SZ, 284] that Da-sein never gets behind its thrownness?” (SZ, 383).
—
Never to come back to myself as my own ground this is the impotence
in which the closedness ( finiteness ) of my own having-been stares me
in the face. The “ never ” seems to plunge my origins into complete hid-
denness. How, then, can that farther horizon of having-been become
accessible on the ground of which I exist historically?
Clearly, if the singleness of a finite existence were synonymous
with isolation , and if our understanding of being reached no further
than our own being, anything like history would be impossible. But
the same “ not ” that reveals my own “ that I already am” and delivers
me over to my own ability-to-be, at the same time reveals the being of
other beings and refers me to them in my impotence to be my own
ground, that is, it throws me into a world. Only in a not-self-grounded
being-with-others-in-the-world can that wider horizon of having-been
be opened up in which a finite existence “ grounds himself, ” that is,
comes to stand as himself among beings that have-been-here before
him and hand down to him his own factical possibilities. It is to be
noted that for an authentic historical being a being-with-others in the
same world is primarily constitutive. It is indeed self-evident that with-
out an understanding of other existences and a communicating dis-
course with them , no tradition could be formed, and even our most
immediate “ history ” would remain inaccessible. Even in the authentic
history of an everyday being-in-the-world , it is the ambiguous hearsay-
ing idle talk of being-with-others that transmits tradition. But whereas
the disowned oneself understands himself among the others from a
common preoccupation with things and from what is done and what
happens within the world, the resolutely owned self understands him-
self from the fully disclosed finiteness of his own existence. This dis-
closes other existences in their finite being, and makes authentic
being-with-others possible.
We have now come to the end of the transitional passage that
introduces Heidegger’ s elucidation of historical-being. Before going
any further, it should be remarked that a vital point remains unclari-
fied in Heidegger’s argument, namely, the connection between self ,
ground , and world. It is only from the essay “ On the Essence of
Ground” that we learn that being-in-the-world is essentially a “ ground-
ing,” and that one mode of grounding is “ having gained ground ”
among beings, having gained a firm stand in the soil ( Boden ) in which
all beings are rooted . All ways of grounding, as Heidegger briefly indi-
cates in the same essay, spring from the care of standingness and con-
stancy, belong to the ecstatic unity of temporality insofar as an endur-
Temporality and Historicity 305
Of ail statements in Being and Time this one brings most sharply
into focus the whole movement in which temporality temporalizes
( accomplishes ) itself. For the constitution of historical-being, the
throw-back from the nothing manifest in death is undoubtedly decisive,
since its violence carries us behind our own having-been and makes the
inherited character of our world fully understandable.
But, it may be asked, is the back-to-itself movement of temporal-
ity not the same as the “ reflexivity, ” the “ bending-back-upon-itself ” of
self-consciousness and thinking? Or if the two are not the same, how
are they related? This question is relevant to all modern transcenden-
tal philosophy whose essential dimension is undoubtedly a “ transcen-
dental self-consciousness” ( Kant’s pure apperception ). Husserl’ s phe-
nomenology, for instance, is a method of peculiar reflection that aims
at penetrating to that transcendental self-consciousness whose func-
tion is to “ constitute being.” According to Heidegger, on the other
hand, self-consciousness is only a character of a distinctive way of being,
namely of self-conscious-being (Selbstbewusstsein). The attempt to
explain being from one of its characters, Heidegger maintains, tackles
the problem from the wrong end. The task is rather to explain the tem-
poral structure of this being by virtue of which it can bring itself to light ,
so that it can be “ conscious-of-itself.” This is a decisive turning away
from Husserl and from all previous transcendental philosophy.5 Self-
consciousness ( thinking ) and its reflexivity are, for Heidegger, not pri-
mary and ultimate, but derivative phenomena that owe their possibil-
ity to the temporality of care.
Nevertheless, the new departure made in Being and Time has its
immediate historical roots in transcendental philosophy. One of
Heidegger’s early acknowledgments of this philosophical “ heritage ”
is made in his so-called Kant-book, first published in 1929, where
Being and Time is called a Wiederholung, a bringing-forward-again ( re-
collection, recapitulation , retrieval ) of Kant’ s attempt to lay the
Temporality and Historicity 311
The first thing that strikes us in this passage is that the technical
term Wiederholung, bringing-again or recollection or retrieve or repeti-
tion or recapitulation, is now used in a different sense from its earlier
use. Let us glance back to the passage where Heidegger first defined
the strictly technical meaning of Wiederholung.
The retrieve of what is possible neither brings back “ what is past,” nor
does it bind the “ present” back in what is “ outdated.” Arising from a res-
olute self-projection, retrieve is not convinced by “ something past,” in
just letting it come back as what was once real. Rather, retrieve responds
to the possibility of existence that has-been-there. But responding to the
possibility in a resolution is at the same time, as in the Moment, the dis-
avowal of what is working itself out today as the “ past.” (SZ, 385-86)
Let us now briefly consider how Heidegger works out these pre-
liminary steps of the argument.
—
tically historical self which gives rise to the question how the successive
experiences of the subject are to be retrospectively linked up into a
coherent unity. The operative word, we must note, is retrospectively , for,
as Heidegger rightly maintains, the whole of historical here-being must
in itself and in advance be constituted as a coherent unity; otherwise
no amount of subsequent putting-together could make up the whole.
The question to be asked, therefore, is this: In which mode of existing
does here-being lose himself in such a way that he must subsequently
bring himself together from scatteredness and must think out an
embracing unity which holds him together? The fundamental reason
for losing “ oneself ’ among “ them” and in the world-historical lies in a
flight from death , which “ flight from . . reveals, inauthentically, the
being-tmto-death. The anticipatory forward-running resoluteness, on
the other hand, brings the being-into-death into the authentic exis-
—
tence. The happening of resoluteness the specific movedness of an
anticipatory forward-running recollecting of inherited possibilities
constitutes the authentic historicity in which, according to Heidegger,
—
there lies already the original, unlost stretchedness of the whole exis-
tence, which does not need a restrospective coherence.
— —
self to the moral law which he, as a free existence as “ practical reason”
in Kant’s thought gives to himself. With this, however, the similarity
between the two thinkers is at an end. For one thing, the “ possibilities
of existence that can be retrieved” are self-chosen, but not self-given. For
another thing, their bindingness is not that of an unchangeable,
absolute law; on the contrary, as we have heard, recollection transforms
the inherited possibility. Its authority cannot therefore have the charac-
ter of a sheer necessitation, but rather of a “ guidance” which in advance
guides the fate of here-being. And finally, why are the “ possibilities of
existence that can be retrieved ” authoritative? Is it only because we have
inherited them from former existences? Surely not, but rather because
they are possibilities of existence, that is, of a way of being that brings itself
to light in its essential possibilities. The self-disclosure of being, however,
—
is essentially historical hence the bindingness, authority, of its retriev-
able possibilities. Now, for Kant, too, reason belongs to the essence of
man and can therefore no more be man-made than the existential way
of being. But rationality is the essential structure--of subjectivity, it
belongs to an interpretation of man as the subject that is radically ques-
tioned and reinterpreted in Being and Time. As the present chapter has
specifically attempted to show, the temporal-dialectical movement and
stretchedness of here-being cannot be sufficiently explained with the
help of the inherited interpretation of subjectivity.
The inappropriate question of how the successive experiences of
a subject can be linked up into a coherent unity arises because the orig-
320 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
tion of any one of its possible “ aspects ” may equally well claim to be
essential. What Heidegger has in mind now is a stricter and narrower
definition of the most “ proper, ” most essential object of history and
the perspective in which it can be disclosed. But from where can the
proper theme of history be drawn in such a way that it is free from the
arbitrary preference or the relative point of view of the individual his-
torian? Only from an authentic historicity , to which a retrieving disclosure
already belongs. The outstanding feature of Heidegger’s interpretation
of retrieval is that it understands the former here-being in his authen-
tic possibility which has-been.
What has “ factually ” really been there, however, is then the existentiell
possibility in which fate, destiny, and world history are factically deter-
mined. Because existence always is only as factically thrown, historiogra-
phy will disclose the silent power of the possible with greater penetration
the more simply and concretely it understands having-been-in-the-world
in terms of possibility, and “ just” presents it. (SZ, 394)
the one hand, the finiteness that throws the factically existent possibil-
ity into its singleness prohibits its perversion “ into the pallor of a
supratemporal pattern.” On the other hand, the same finiteness throws
the factical existence back upon its inherited possibility. What has-been-
here once is therefore not repeatable as a recurrent embodiment of an
unchanging ideal that exists outside time, but it is recollectable or retriev -
able; that is, it can be brought back and forward again into the trans-
forming forethrow of another existence. Hence the has-been is not irre-
trievably “ past” and “ gone ” (vergangen), but is essentially “ futural” ; it
remains in “ coming” insofar as a factical here-being comes-to-himself in
his inherited possibility. How, then, does the science of history originate
in the authentically historical existence of the historian?
Only factically authentic historicity, as resolute fate, can disclose the his-
tory that has-been-there in such a way that in retrieve the “ power ” of the
possible breaks into factical existence, that is, comes toward it in its futu-
rality. Historiography by no means takes its point of departure from the
“ present ” and what is “ real ” only today, any more than does the his-
toricity of unhistorical Da-sein , and then grope its way back from there
to a past. Rather, even historiographical disclosure temporalizes itself out
of the future. The “ selection ” of what is to become a possible object for his-
toriography has already been made in the factical existentiell choice of the
historicity of Da-sein, in which historiography first arises and is
uniquely. (SZ, 395)
Even the most critical reader of Heidegger will hardly deny the
brilliance of this exposition. It is, at the same time, an admirable exam-
ple of a “ transforming” interpretation of an earlier thinker. Further-
more, this passage is the only one where the meaning of “ de-present-
ing” ( Entgegenwärtigung) is explained at all. It is said to mean a
suffering detachment ( das leidende Sichlösen ) from the publicness of a
falling being-in-the- world that loses itself in the presenting of things
within the world. Characteristically, it is in the mood of suffering and
pain that Heidegger experiences the loosening of the bonds that keep
us sheltered in familiar and unquestioned explanations. Nothing could
be further removed from the half-baked enthusiasm or angry rebellion
that is so often associated with an “ existentialism ” mistakenly ascribed
to Heidegger.
In summing up the findings of the present section, Heidegger
emphasizes that the principal task of historical thematization is to unfold
Temporality and Historicity 325
—
the hermeneutical situation that is opened up once historically existing
—
Da-sein has made its resolution to the disclosure in retrieve of what has-
been-there. The possibility and the structure of historiographical truth are
to be set forth in terms of the authentic disclosedness ( “ truth ” ) of historical
existence. (SZ, 397 )
The basic concepts of all historical sciences are existential con-
cepts. The “ historical sciences” seem to be taken by Heidegger in such
a wide sense that they include all studies concerned with “ mind” or
“ spirit” ( Geist ) and their methods, in distinction from the sciences of
nature, whose basic concepts are concepts of reality. A theory of nature
is not dependent on an existential interpretation of historical here-
being, but for a theory of the “ sciences of mind ” (Geisteswissenschaften)
it is a necessary precondition. This was the aim approached by Dilthey.
To conceive the same aim more fundamentally and to formulate it con-
cretely as a problem has been the task of the present chapter.
Since the last thing Heidegger claims is that the problem has now
been completely solved, it may be useful to look back on what has
become clear and what remains obscure in Heidegger’ s interpretation.
Perhaps its most outstanding feature is the decisive constitutive func-
tion of authentic “ future, ” that is, the anticipatory forward-running res-
oluteness in which a factical here-being authentically comes-to-himself.
This constitutes the forward-stretching movement in which the whole
of here-being “ stands” ( endures ) as fate, and at the same time origi-
nates the rebounding movement in which here-being comes-back to his
own thrownness ( having-been ). Since, however, here-being is essentially
a being-with -others-in-the-world, the coming-back to his own finite hav-
ing-been opens up a wider dimension of temporality, in which the hav-
ing-been-in-the-world of former existences becomes accessible. These
are authentically understood in a resolutely forward-running recollec-
tion or retrieve, in which a factical here-being chooses his own factical
possibility as inherited , that is, brings the possibility in which a former
here-being existed forward into his own existence. The whole move-
ment ( “ movedness” ) in which here-being stretches himself forward and
back is the “ happening” or “ occurrence” (Geschehen ) whose existential-
temporal structure constitutes the historicity of here-being.
This short summary pinpoints the importance of authentic exis-
tence and its temporal structure for Heidegger’s interpretation of his-
torical-being. In the inauthentic happening ( “ history” ) of everyday ness,
it is just the decisive movement, stretchedness, and stability of historical
here-being that remains hidden, or is distorted and misinterpreted from
the reality of things. The chief difficulty in all this is not that Heideg-
ger’s explanations are obscure, but that in any concrete instance we find
326 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
The previous chapter took no account of the fact that all “ happening,”
both historical and natural, takes place “ in time.” It explained historical-
being purely from the existential-temporal structure of care. The “ vul-
gar” or popular understanding of history, on the other hand, explains
it as an ontic- temporal happening in time. Similarly, the scientific expla -
nations of nature define and measure its processes by time. A funda-
mental analysis of this time is one of the tasks of the present chapter,
though not its first one. Its first consideration is the elemental fact that
here-being, before any thematic-scientific investigation of nature and
history, already “ counts with time ” and orientates himself from it. This
way of relating himself to time is so original to here-being that it goes
—
before all handling of time-measuring utensils clocks and watches of
—
any kind and makes the use of clocks first of all possible.
What precisely does Heidegger mean by a “ counting with time ” ?
It is a mode of “ taking care ” of things within the world. Obviously, how-
ever, we cannot take care of time in the way of handling and using it as
we do a hammer and nails, but in the way of taking account of it, count-
ing upon it and reckoning with it. On the basis of this elemental tak-
ing-care of time, we say that we “ have” time or have none, we “ take ”
327
328 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
time or cannot “ leave ” ourselves time. But why and from where do we
take the time which we can “ have” or “ lose ” ? In what relation does this
time stand to the temporality of here-being? These questions must be
answered before the present inquiry can turn to the time in which
beings are and happenings take place. The emergence of these ques-
tions shows that the preceding analysis of temporality are not only
incomplete “ since we did not pay heed to all the dimensions of the phe-
nomenon, but it has fundamental gaps in it because something like
world-time belongs to temporality itself, in the strict sense of the exis-
tential and temporal concept of world “ (SZ, 405). On the ground of
the ecstatic-horizonal constitution of world, the beings within it must
meet us “ in time.” The time-character of within-worldish beings is
accordingly called by Heidegger “ within-timeness.”
The predominant way in which the everyday here-being exists in
his world is in a care-taking being- near-to things. Hence he first dis-
covers the time he “ takes ” for himself on the things which are handily
or substantially there. The time thus discovered is understood in the
horizon of the indifferent understanding of being as something that is
also in some way “ there ” { vorhanden ) . How the popular concept of time
grows from the taking care of time of the temporally constituted here-
being will be explained. The popular concept of time will prove to have
its origin in a levelling-down of original time.
The popular conception of time vacillates between the view that
time is “ objective ” and the view that it is “ subjective.” In this popular
conception time is something “ really” there “ in itself,” that is, has an
“ objective” being, yet it is ascribed primarily to the “ soul.” Conversely,
the time that is considered to be “ in the soul” or “ in consciousness” nev-
ertheless functions objectively. In Hegel’ s time-interpretation both pos-
sibilities are in a certain way “ elevated” { aufgehoben ) . It must be remem-
bered, however, that Aufhebung in Hegel’s thought has a threefold
meaning. It is a suspending-preserving-reconciliation. Hegel’s attempt
to establish a connection between time and spirit { Geist ) and to explain
how spirit as history can “ fall into time” will be discussed toward the
end of this chapter and compared with Heidegger’s own attempt to
explain how world-time belongs to the temporality of here-being.
The fundamental-ontological question that Being and Time must
ultimately attempt to answer is whether and in what way there is time.
Does time belong in any way to the realm of beings, so that we can legit-
imately say of it that it is? If so, what meaning can the “ is ” have when
it expresses the being of time? The peculiarity of this question
becomes evident when we remember that time is the meaning of
being, that time is the universal horizon from which being discloses
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 329
Da-sein exists as a being that, in its being, is concerned about that being
itself. Essentially ahead of itself, it has projected itself upon its poten-
tiality-of-being before going on to any mere consideration of itself. In its
project it is revealed as something thrown. Thrown and abandoned to
the world, it falls prey to it in taking care of it. As care, that is, as exist-
ing in the unity of the entangled, thrown project, this being is disclosed
as a There. Being-together-with others, it keeps itself in an average inter-
pretedness that is articulated in discourse and expressed in language.
-
Being-in-the-world has already expressed itself and as being together-with
beings encountered within the world, it constantly expresses itself in
addressing and talking over what is taken care of. The circumspect tak-
ing care of common sense is grounded in temporality, in the mode of
making present that awaits and retains. As taking care in calculating,
planning, preparing ahead, and preventing, it always already says,
whether audibly or not: “ then ” . . . that will happen, “ before” . . . that will
get settled, “ now” . . . that will be made up for, that “ on that former occa-
sion” failed or eluded us. (SZ, 406 )
stage, we must not yet think of the highly sophisticated “ dating” of time
from astronomically calculated dates in a calendar, but of its more orig-
inal “ dating” from within-worldish events by everyday care. The refer-
ence to something expressed in the “ then, when . . . , ” “ at that time,
when . . . “ n o w, that . . . is called by Heidegger “ datability” ( Datier-
barkeit ). This reference-structure, whether expressly pronounced or
not, essentially belongs to time, even where the “ dating” from some
definite event is vague or seemingly missing. The “ then, when . . . , ”
“ now, that . . . , ” and the like, in which ecstatic temporality expresses
itself already refer us to an addressing and discussing of things. And
conversely, the most commonplace everyday pronouncements for
—
example, “ it is cold ” tacitly imply the “ now, that . . . ,” because, in and
—
with all speaking of something, everyday care expresses itself as a mak-
ing present of within-worldish beings.
Heidegger himself ascribes a peculiar importance to datability, as
is shown in the following passage.
The cardinal point brought out by this passage lies in the “ and
now not yet, ” for it is from a primary view to the “ now ” that a pre-
dominantly presenting care-taking understands the spanned “ until”
namely until the waited-for given then. The ‘’ until then ” is articulatingly
—
exposed in the “ in-between, ” which can itself be “ dated.” Its datability
is expressed in the “ during which . . .” ( e.g., between now and then,
during which such and such can be expected ). The “ during” can, in
turn, be articulated and divided up by awaitingly giving further “ from
—
then till then, ” which, however, are in advance delimited by the pri-
marily forethrown “ then.”
day.” It is just in this mode of existing, of “ living unto the day,” that the
factical here-being does not understand himself as “ running along in a
continuously enduring succession of pure ‘nows’” (SZ, 409 ). The rea-
son is that when the inauthentic here-being becomes absorbed in the
things he awaitingly takes care of, and,
not awaiting itself, forgets itself, the more its time that it “ allows ” itself
is covered over by this mode of “ allowing.” [. . .] By reason of this covering
over, the time that Da-sein never understands itself has gaps in it, so to
speak. We often cannot bring a “ day” together again when we come back
to the time that we have “ used.” Yet the time that has gaps in it does not
go to pieces in this lack of togetherness, but is a mode of temporality
that is always already disclosed and ecstatically stretched out. (SZ, 409-10 )
Thus we shall call the time making itself public in the temporalizing of
temporality world-time . And we shall designate it thus not because it is
objectively present ( vorhanden ) as an innerworldly being ( that it can never
be ), but because it belongs to the world in the sense interpreted existen-
tially and ontologically. [. . .] Only now can time taken care of be com -
pletely characterized as to its structure: It is datable, spanned , and pub-
lic and , as having this structure, it belongs to the world itself. Each
“ now,” for example , that is expressed in a natural , everyday way, has this
structure and is understood as such when Da-sein allows itself time in
taking care, although unthematically and preconceptually. ( SZ, 414-15).
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 339
Heidegger does not define the being of time in this passage, but
only denies that reality is a mode of being that can be appropriate to it.
The fact that time is not a within-worldish entity does not mean that it
must be a total nothing, nor that it is “ merely subjective, ” since the tem-
porality of existent here-being is not identical with the subjectivity of a
subject. Heidegger will recur to the highly problematic “ being” of time
later in this chapter. At the moment, having completed the structural
analysis of interpreted time, he turns to the development of time-mea-
suring and its foundation in one definite mode of the temporalization
of temporality.
In comparing the “ natural” time-reckoning with the more highly
developed one Heidegger notes that a direct reference to the presence
of the “ natural clock, ” namely to the sun in the sky, grows less and less
important. We can read the time off our manufactured clocks and
watches, which, however, are ultimately regulated by the “ natural
clock.” Just like the most primitive time-reckoning, so too the most
sophisticated use of time-measuring utensils is grounded in the tem-
porality of here-being, for it makes the dating of public time possible
at all.
Already the “ primitive” here-being to some extent makes himself
independent from a direct observation of the sun by measuring, for
instance, the shadow thrown by a conveniently available thing. A famil-
iar example of this is the sundial, on which the shadow moves on a
numbered path opposite to the course of the sun.
But why do we find something like time at the position that the shadow
occupies on the dial? Neither the shadow nor the graduated dial is time
itself, nor is the spatial relation between them. Where, then, is the time
that we read off directly not only on the “ sundial” but also on every pock-
etwatch? (SZ, 416 )
—
These seemingly childish questions they are indeed just the
—
questions a child might ask serve to remind us that there is much
more to “ reading the time” than merely watching the changing posi-
tions of the clock hand ( or shadow ). In telling the time from a clock,
the essential thing is that “ we sayf whether explicitly or not, now it is
such an hour and so many minutes , now it is time to . . . , or there is
still time . . . , namely now until. . . . Looking at the clock is grounded
in and guided by a taking- time-for-oneself ” (SZ , 416 ).
The time we “ take ” or “ let-ourselves-have ” is the span between
now and then . Each “ then” implies “ and not yet now ” ; each “ at that
—
time ” implies “ and no longer now ” that is, they are understood from
a primary view to the “ now.” This tendency becomes more pro-
340 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
fied in the present section still move on a more fundamental level. The
first of these , the “ coupling” of time and space, has already briefly
appeared in Heidegger’s remarks on the sundial, where it was noted
—
that what we really find on the sundial and of course on every kind of
—
clock is nothing but spatially extended things and spatial relations.
Although none of these is “ time itself, ” it cannot be an accident that
they can be used for a measuring dating of time. As Heidegger has
shown earlier ( chap. 4, § 70 ) , it is the temporality of a factical being-in-
the-world that makes the disclosure of space possible and enables the
“ spatial” here-being to allocate to himself his “ here” from the care-tak-
ingly discovered “ there.” Hence the datability of the time taken care of
is bound to a definite place of the factical here-being.
According to Heidegger, then, untenable notions about the cou-
pling of time and space arise from a confusion of the essential databil -
—
ity of time from a within-worldish occurrence preeminently from the
—
movement of the sun across the sky with time itself as the express self-
exposition of temporality. Just as space is an irreducible phenomenon
that can never become time, so time can never be reduced to space
through its dating from spatial relations that serve as a measure. For
the time- measuring itself, as the preceding analyses have shown, it is not
the numerical definition of spatial relations and movements that is
ontologically decisive, but the preeminent making present of a thing in
every now and for every one present. In our everyday now-saying we
are so intent on reading off the number of measurement as such that
we are apt to forget the measured as such, so what we “ really” find on
the clock is nothing but stretch and number.2
The world-time so pronouncedly made public in the measuring is
the time within which within-worldish beings meet us. The time-charac-
ter of their being is within-timeness ( being-in-time ). Here again the
essentially dual role of world shows itself. Looking at the within-world-
ish beings, world- time is the time within which they are there, but look-
ing at the factually existing being-in-the-world, world-time belongs to
the ecstatic-horizonal constitution of temporality. It has, therefore,
“ the same transcendence as the world ” (SZ, 419 ). But in what way is
there world-time? What mode of being can be ascribed to it? This ques-
tion, which was briefly touched upon before, is now more elaborately
unfolded by Heidegger as follows.
The time “ in which ” objectively present things move or are at rest is not
“ objective,” if by this is meant the objective presence in itself of beings
encountered in the world. But time is not “ subjective ” either, if we under-
stand by that the objective presence and occurrence in a “ subject.” World-
342 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
time is more “ objective ” than any possible object because, with the disclosedness
of the world, it always already becomes ecstatically and horizonally “ objectified ”
as the condition of the possibility of innerworldly beings (SZ, 419 ).s
— —
haupt ) is not identical with Heidegger’s “ world ” they are two different
attempts to explain the same thing a decisive difference is that in Hei-
degger’s interpretation the world-time is already expressly exposed with
the disclosure of world, so that,
We see that Heidegger only elaborates what and how time is not .
The seemingly positive descriptions of “ more objective ” and “ more
subjective” do not, after all, tell us how time itself is . On the contrary,
the disturbing question now comes explicitly to the forefront, “ Has
time any ‘being’ at all? ”
If it has not, is it a mere nothing, “ a phantom, ” or should we more
truly say of it “ it is” than of any concrete beings? These questions are not
answered by Heidegger here, nor can they be answered until after the
“ question of being” ( Seinsfrage ) as it is posed and worked out in Being and
Time has been solved. But although the answer is once more deferred to
Division Three, these questions are not asked here merely to arouse idle
curiosity; they have the positive aim of making us doubtful whether the
distinction between the being of a self conceived as a subject and the
being of objects is fundamental enough to allow a proper answer to these
questions. It is clear that world-time can be neither “ volatized ‘subjec-
tivistically’ nor be ‘reified’ ( verdinglicht ) in a bad ‘objectification’ ” (SZ,
420). No more satisfactory than these two unacceptable extremes is a
“ vacillating insecurely” between them. The next step toward a solution
of this problem is to show how a theoretical concept of time grows out
of the prescientic everyday understanding of time, and how it itself shuts
out the possibility of understanding its intended meaning “ in terms of
primordial time, that is, as temporality . Everyday taking care that gives
itself time finds ‘time’ in innerwordly beings that are encountered ‘in
time.’ Thus our illumination of the genesis of the vulgar concept of time
must take its point of departure from within-timeness” (SZ, 420).
taking care and using tools does it become explicitly accessible?” (SZ, 420).
The word Heidegger uses for ‘’explicitly” is ausdrücklich, literally: expressly .
But the word here no longer means the original “ self-expressing” ( Sich-
aussprechen ) in which temporality ex-poses itself, lays itself out into the
open. There are several stages or gradations of “ expressness” until it
comes to a fully fledged, theoretical conceptualization. The utensil in
whose use time first becomes explicitly accessible is the clock; for here-
being, in counting with and on himself \ that is, with his own temporality,
regulates himself by the time which publicly shows itself on the clock. What
is decisive for the present stage of “ explicitness” is a calculating counting
of time, which grows from a measuring reference to the clock.
The existential and temporal meaning of the clock turns out to be mak-
ing present of the moving pointer. By following the positions of the
pointer in a way that makes present, one counts them. This making pre-
sent temporalizes itself in the ecstatic unity of a retaining that awaits. To
retain the “ on that former occasion ” in making present means that in say-
ing-now to be open for the horizon of the earlier, that is, the now-no-
longer. To await the “ then ” in making present means: in saying-now to be
open for the horizon of the later, that is, the now-not-yet. What shows itself
in this making present is time. Then how are we to define the time manifest
in the horizon of the use of the clock that is circumspect and takes time
for itself in taking care? This time is what is counted, showing itself in follow-
ing making present, and counting the moving pointer in such a way that mak -
ing present temporalizes itself in ecstatic unity with retaining and awaiting hori-
zonally open according to the earlier and later. But that is nothing more than
an existential and ontological interpretation of the definition that Aristo-
tle gave of time: touto gar estin ho chronos, arithmos kinêseôs kata to proteron
kai hysteron. “ That, namely, is time, what is counted in the motion encoun-
tered in the horizon of the earlier and the later.” (SZ, 421)4
Time is the “ what is counted,” that is, it is what is expressed and what is
meant, although unthematically, in the making present of the moving
pointer ( or shadow ). In making present what is moved in its motion, one
says “ now here, now here, and so on.” What is counted are the nows. And
these show themselves “ in every now ” as “ right-away-no-longer-now ” and
as “ just-now-not-yet.” The world-time “ caught sight of ” in this way in the
use of clocks we shall call now-time. (SZ, 421)
the origin and the originated, that is, the same as that between the
temporality of here-being and the ex-posed world-time. What makes
Heidegger’s own time-interpretation so impressive and convincing is
just that he constantly goes back from the originated world-time to its
origin in temporality. The moment a new characteristic of the world-
time appears, he immediately refers it back to the original ecstatic-
horizonal structure of temporality. If a fair comparison with Hegel is
to be made, a going from spirit to time and back from time to spirit is
essential, provided that Hegel’ s thought demands such a two-way traf -
fic. But Heidegger’s formulation of the problem, laying the whole
stress on the fall of the spirit into time, already prohibits the making of
such an attempt.
Compare:
If space is represented, that is, directly looked at in the indifferent sub-
sistence of its distinctions, the negations are, as it were, simply given.
But this representation does not yet grasp space in its being. That is pos-
—
sible only in thought as the synthesis that goes through thesis and
antithesis and supersedes [aufhebenden] them. Space is thought and thus
grasped in its being only if the negations do not simply subsist in their
indifference, but are superseded , that is, themselves negated. In the
negation of negation ( that is, punctuality ), the point posits itselffor itself
and thus emerges from the indifference of subsistence. Posited for
itself, it distinguishes itself from this or that point ; it is no longer this and
not yet that one. In positing itself for itself , it posits the succession in
which it stands, the sphere of being-outside-of-itself that is now the
negated negation. The superseding of punctuality signifies that it can
no longer lie quietly in the “ paralyzed stillness of space.” The point
“ rebels ” against all other points. According to Hegel, this negation of
negation as punctuality is time. If this discussion has any demonstrable
meaning at all, it can mean nothing other than that the positing of itself
for itself of each point is a now-here, now-here, and so on. Every point
“ is” posited for itself as a now-point. “ Thus the point has actuality in
time.” By what means the point can posit itself for itself , always as this
point, is always a now. The condition of the possibility of the point’s
positing itself for itself is the now. This condition of possibility consti-
tutes the being of the point, and being is at the same time being-thought .
Thus, since the pure thinking of punctuality, that is, of space, always
“ thinks ” the now and the being-outside-itself of the nows, space “ is ”
time. (SZ, 430 )
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 353
time is similarly something absolutely abstract and ideal.” But now the
seeming redundancy turns out to be essential to Heidegger’s purpose
of establishing that the negation of the negation is the “ most appro-
priate expression ” of Hegel’ s concept of time. Whether this is truly the
“ sole” bridge that Hegel can throw across from spirit to time will be
seen in the next subsection.
The essence of spirit is the concept . By this Hegel understands not the
universal that is intuited in a genus as the form of what is thought, but
—
the form of the very thinking that thinks itself: Conceiving itself as grasp-
ing the non-I. Since grasping the non-1 presents a differentiation , there
lies in the pure concept, as the grasping of the differentiation , a differ-
entiation of the difference. (SZ, 433)
Before going on, let us clarify this difficult text. Concept usually
means a concipere, a grasping together into one through a general char-
acteristic that is common to many. The “ intuited ” common character-
istic of the many, the genus, is thought in the form of the concipere, of
a grasping together into one. Hence the concept in its usual meaning
is the form of something thought. What Hegel means by concept, on
the other hand, is the form of the self-thinking thinking itself.
In the not-I there lies already a distinction between the I, the self,
-
and its “ other, ” the not I. The pure concept, in comprehending itself as
the I, at the same time grasps the distinction between itself and the
—
other, the not-I that is, it distinguishes this distinction. In fully com-
prehending itself the I grasps and brings back into itself the not-I that
has been distinguished from it by a negation ( the “ not” ). This bringing-
back-into-itself of its negated self, of the not-I, is accomplished by
negating the negation whereby the self, the I, has been expelled into
its other, the not-I. Hence, Heidegger says, “ Hegel can define the
essence of spirit formally and apophantically as the negation of a nega-
tion. This ‘absolute negativity’ gives a logically formalized interpreta-
tion of Descartes’ cogito me cogitare rem, wherein he sees the essence of
the conscientia ” ( SZ, 433).
If the kinship between the spirit and time is established solely by
the sameness of their formal structure as the negation of negation,
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 357
then it would seem that this goal has already been reached. Nonethe-
less, this is not nearly enough to show why the spirit necessarily,
according to its own essence, concretizes and so reveals itself in time
as history. The following citations from Hegel, and Heidegger s com-
ments on them , serve to elucidate this necessity that lies in the nature
of the spirit itself. In the first place, the concept has to be more con-
cretely defined.
The concept is the conceivedness of the self conceiving itself , the way the
self is authentically as it can be, that is, free. “ The / is the pure concept
itself that has come to existence as the concept.” 21 “ But the I is the first
pure unity relating itself to itself, not directly, but rather, in abstracting
from all determinateness and content and going back to the freedom of
the limitless identity with itself.” 22 Thus the I is “ universality f but it is
“ individuality ” just as immediately ” (SZ, 433-34 )
What must be remarked here and for all that follows is that Hegel
uses the word Dasein ( “ als Begriff zum Dasein gekommen ” ) in the tra-
ditional sense of existentia, and not of course in the sense that Heideg-
ger gives it in Being and Time . It is just for Dasein and existence in the
traditional sense that Heidegger uses the interpretative term Vorhan-
densein, being-there, presence. He is therefore quite entitled, within the
context of Being and Time , to interpret Hegel’s da-seind with vorhanden,
using the term, of course, in its widest sense and not in its narrow sense
of the thereness of a thing. What remains to be seen, rather, is whether
Heidegger makes enough of the concept that has come into existence
( Dasein ) and its relation to time. So far, what has come to light is the
pure, limitlessly free self-identity of the concept as the I. Now Heideg-
ger goes on to unfold the further implications of the concept as the
negation of negation.
This negating of negation is both the “ absolute unrest” of spirit and also
its self revelation, which belongs to its essence. The “ progression ” of spirit
actualizing itself in history contains a “ principle of exclusion.” However,
in this exclusion what is excluded does not get detached from the spirit ,
it gets surmounted. Making itself free in overcoming, and at the same time
supporting, characterizes the freedom of the spirit. Thus “ progress”
never means a quantitative more, but is essentially qualitative, and
indeed has the quality of spirit. “ Progression ” is known and knowing
itself in its goal. In every step of its “ progress, ” spirit has to overcome
“ itself ” as the truly inimical hindrance of its aim. The goal of the devel-
opment of spirit is “ to attain its own concept.” The development of itself
is “ a hard , infinite struggle against itself . ” (SZ, 434 )
358 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
— —
logical abstraction is quite insufficient. It expresses in a formal way, to
be sure the origin of movement, of life ( the “ absolute unrest ” ), in the
very being of the spirit, which drives the spirit into its self-disclosing
concretization, and drives it on through an endless fight against itself
toward its return to a self-conceiving that “ grasps, ” that is, embraces and
elevates into itself its “ externalized ” moments ( the not-I ). The spirit has
to overcome itself as its own most obstinate enemy because the seem-
ingly fixed and true differentiations and determinations for instance,
the opposition between subject and object, in which each appears as an
—
—
independent entity are set by the spirit itself in its appearance as the
“ natural ” or “ naive consciousness” ( roughly corresponding to the com-
mon understanding of everyday here-being in Heidegger ). The in itself- -
being of these seemingly fixed and independent entities like subject
and object is just the “ mere being, ” and therefore the negative and
—
“ untrue ” being which has to be mediated annulled and preservingly —
elevated into the “ true being” of the self-conceiving concept. This is
the endless struggle of the historical development of the “ concretized ”
spirit returning to itself. While these implications of the above-quoted
texts are not elaborated by Heidegger, they have to be made explicit
here in order to enable us to weigh up what Heidegger makes of them.
His conclusions are summed up in the third paragraph following the
above, but this is preceded by two important paragraphs consisting
mainly of citations from Hegel. I shall quote these three paragraphs
together and comment on them afterward.
Since the restlessness of the development of spirit bringing itself to its
concept is the negation of a negation, it is in accordance with its self-actu-
alization to fall “ into time” as the immediate negation of a negation. For
“ time is the concept itself that is there [ da ist ] , and represents itself to con-
sciousness as empty intuition. For this reason spirit necessarily appears
in time, and it appears in time as long as it has not grasped its pure con-
cept, that is, has not annulled time. Time is the pure self that is externally
intuited [looked-upon] and not grasped by the pure self , the concept
merely intuited.” 23 Thus spirit appears in time necessarily in accordance
with its essence. “ Thus world-history in general is the interpretation [ Ausle-
gung. laying out] of spirit in time, just as the idea interprets itself in
nature as space.” 24 The “ excluding” that belongs to the movement of
development contains a relation to nonbeing. That is time, understood
in terms of the revolt of the now [ aus dem sich aufspreizenden Jetzt ].
Time is “ abstract ” negativity. As the “ intuited becoming” it is the differ-
entiated self-differentiation that is directly to be found , the concept that
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 359
concept itself, it has not come into its full truth . In its simple being-
there, time presents itself to consciousness directly as an intuition, for
time is the “ nonsensible sensible,” that is, the purely “ viewable” not to
the bodily eye, but to subconsciousness. As this immediate intuition,
—
time is “ empty, ” and must be so if it is to be capable of taking up into
itself all things that appear in time, that is, show themselves, become
themselves “ viewable ” in time. Time is the pure, empty intuition as the
form in which all existing things must appear and so reveal themselves
-
to a looking upon. Hence, if the spirit is to come into existence at all it
must necessarily “ appear in time,” in which alone it can concretely
reveal itself as a historical process. This explains from the point of view
of time how it is in its own being capable of receiving the self-realizing
spirit into itself and why it is in time that the spirit must necessarily
appear in all stages of its concrete, historical “ life.” But now we must ask
back from time to the spirit. How is the spirit itself such that it necessi -
tates itself into its own concretization in time? The answer has already
360 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
been given: because the spirit is the negating of the negation, and because
this is not a mere formal abstraction, but the principle of life in the
spirit itself, it necessitates the spirit into its endlessly self-overcoming
( self-annulling) struggle, in which historical movement the spirit con-
—
cretely lives. Time as the pure, “ looked-upon becoming” that is, the
—
constant self-annulment of the now mirrors and makes directly “ view-
able” the negativity of the spirit concretized in its historical movement,
a negativity which constandy “ excludes” moments of itself into a seem-
ingly fixed and externalized “ independent being, ” and constantly strug-
gles to overcome itself by negating this negation.
Time most purely “ images ” the spirit; it is the pure “ other” self of
the self-comprehending concept. If the essence of the concept is its self-
conception, then the essence of time, the “ standing and staying” self-
sameness of the now, images the concept’s pure self-identity. The essence
of time is to present itself “ visibly” to the spirit as its own self, but as the
unmediated, not-self-conceiviing self. This is clearly said by Hegel in the
sentence “ Time is the pure self that is externally intuited [looked-upon]
and not grasped by the self, the concept merely intuited.” The essence
of time is the same as the essence of the concept, but time is the exter-
nalized, “ visible, ” and not-self-comprehending identity in which the pure
concept, come into existence as the “ I, ” can look upon itself.
The affinity between spirit and time is therefore fundamental.
Heidegger can quite correcdy express it in the “ negation of negation, ”
but ignores the concrete content of this formal “ sameness, ” brought
out by his own quotations from Hegel. At the end, he still insists on
treating the negation of negation as a purely formal abstraction.
But the most important point still remains to be clarified. Not
only is the kinship between spirit and time far more fundamental than
Heidegger admits, but the “ relation” between them is not that between
two partners of equal rank. This is indicated by Heidegger himself in
the following way: “ As something objectively present and thus external
to spirit, time has no power over the concept, but the concept is rather
‘the power of time’ [ die Macht der Zeit]” [ .Encyclopaedia, § 258]. Assum-
ing that the preposition in this last phrase implies an idea of domi-
nance like that explicitly expressed by the “ over” used in the first part
of the sentence, it has to be granted that as something external to
spirit, time can have no power over it; but this in no way explains why
the concept should be the power of time. To find out how and why the
concept is the dominant “ partner” in the relation , the questioning
must be reversed and go back from time to the concept. How can the
concept be the power either of or over time? Certainly not as the con-
cretized spirit that appears and “ is there” in time. This being-there-in-
Temporality and Within-Timeness as the Origin of the Vulgar Concept of Time 361
The end of Division Two is designed to throw the reader’s interest for-
ward to the answer to be given to the question “ Is there a way leading
from primordial time to the meaning of being? Does time itself reveal
itself as the horizon of being? ” (SZ, 437). It is therefore pertinent to ask
whether and, if so, how far it might be possible to discern the answer
from what Heidegger has already written.
The solution of Heidegger’ s problem cannot be arbitrarily tacked
on to the first two divisions of Being and Time. It must rise from them
by inner necessity. If the ground has been well and truly laid, at least
the main outlines of the answer must be discernible there, especially
when some of Heidegger’s later works, in which certain hints are made
more explicit, are taken into consideration.
An attempt will, therefore, be made here to outline Heideg-
ger’ s answer as far as possible. The short sketch to be given will at
the same time serve as a concise summary of the most fundamental
features of the way in which man exists, as far as they have been dis-
cussed in this guide .
363
364 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
of dread that originally brings Da-sein face to face with the not that closes
not only the end of his being, but dominates it from the beginning.
What is revealed by dread, however, is not a mere negation, such
as we perform in a rational judgment. Dread does not reveal by negat-
ing all things, nor by announcing an impending annihilation of the
world, but by bringing Da-sein’ s familiar, taken-for-granted being-at-
home-in-the-world into the unfamiliar mood of an uncanny not-at-
homeness. In the not-canny, not-at-home, the not is elementally
revealed as a threat that does not come from outside, but rises from
being-in-the-world itself.
The way in which dread gives Da-sein to understand the not is
totally different from the way in which he acquires some information
about a fact. “ In fact,” Da-sein may not know about death, its possibil-
ity may be kept covered over in the flight of disowned existence, dread
may never be fully experienced in a lifetime; nonetheless, as soon as
and as long as Da-sein is, the not is openly or covertly revealed as the
extreme possibility in which he already is, and which is singly and
uniquely his own.
It is the throw by and recoil from this not that throws Da-sein into
the world and so originates the movement of his being. But what is the
world itself into which Da-sein is carried by the impetus of the throw?
It is revealed by dread as “ nothing.” The whereof of dread, the dread-
some, it was said , is nowhere and nothing. But it was made clear that
the nowhere is not an absence and negation of all places; it is the orig-
inal disclosure of place itself, of the pure where itself.
The world itself, as a fundamental character of Da-sein’s being, is
directly revealed in the nothing of dread. This nothing, however, is not
the absence and negation of all things, but the totally “ other” to things
-
as such. The incomparable power of dread is to bring Da sein directly
before the nothing ( world) itself. Face to face with nothing, Da-sein is
in one leap beyond beings as a whole, among them first and foremost
himself. The transcendence of Da-sein’s being is only possible as this
confrontation with the sheer “ other” to any beings. What comes to
light in this transcendence, however, is not something outside and
beyond the world , but precisely beings as the beings they are, that is,
in their being. It is the essence of the nothing to repel, to point away
from itself, to direct and refer to beings, as totally other than itself.
Only in coming to things from the disclosed nothing of world can Da-
sein understand them in their strangeness: that they are something,
and not nothing. And only in coming to himself from the utmost limit
of his being-in-the-world can Da-sein understand himself fully as a self
existing among other beings.
366 Part Three: Division Two of Being and Time
How is it then that Da-sein can come toward himself at all? The
movement originates in the throw by and recoil from the not revealed
by dread, which throws Da-sein into the world and whirls him away to
the beings he meets within it. But at the same time, it throws him for-
ward into the extreme possibility of death , in rebounding from which he
can come toward himself in his ownmost possibility. The forethrow not
only comes to a limit, but is thrown back by it: it is the rebound that
enables Da-sein to come toward himself in his possibilities, and so exist
primarily from the future.
But it would still remain inexplicable how and why this “ coming-
toward ” should be the primary mode of time, or indeed any time at all,
unless the not itself had a time-character. If, however, the movement of
man’s being is the original unity of time as future, past and present,
the whole phenomenon of time seems to be accounted for, and it is
hard to see what function remains for the not to fulfill. Heidegger
leaves one possibility open: with the not is disclosed time itself . As the
last sentence of Being and Time suggests, it is time itself that will reveal
itself as the horizon of being. This is the problem with which Division
Three would evidently have had to deal first, before the temporal inter-
pretation of the idea of being could have been taken in hand.
In the absence of an explicit answer from Heidegger, do we have
any hints from him where we might look for an answer ? He gives us a
hint in his analysis of conscience (SZ, 284 ). Conscience gives man to
understand that he owes his being, that he can never go behind his
thrownness and exist as the ground of his own being. In calling man
back to the not revealed in his impotent thrownness, conscience makes
manifest the never . According to the whole trend of Heidegger’ s
thought, the never cannot be a mere negation of time: in it is disclosed
the pure when, i.e. time itself. If, indeed, man constantly comes toward
and back to himself from the never, then the whole movement of his
being must necessarily have a time-character, or, as one might equally
well say, a when-character. And if the never is the horizon into which
man in advance looks out, it becomes immediately understandable why
he must pro ject all possibilities of being on to time, and why all artic-
ulations and modifications of being must have a temporal meaning.
The temporal interpretation of the idea of being as such, the
final goal of Division Three, remains for the most part obscure. On the
other hand, the way toward this goal is discernible both from the two
divisions we have of Being and Time, and from Heidegger’s later works.
Above all, there can be no doubt of his answer to the most basic ques-
tion: how is it at all possible for man to understand being? The signif-
icance-whole of world enables man to understand that beings are and
Conclusion 367
what they are, i.e. their real existence and their essence. But the unity
of the world is itself only possible on the ground of time; and time
itself is revealed with the not that determines man’s existence as a self.
Notness and nothingness ( Nichtigieit ) are the fundamental exis-
tential characters of a finite being. But it must be fully evident by now
that when Heidegger speaks of the notness or nothingness of Da-sein,
he cannot mean what is sometimes understood by these phrases: that
Da-sein is a nullity in the world-all, that his being is of no account, or
that he comes from nothing and dissolves into nothing and his existence
is therefore meaningless and purposeless. Far from declaring Da-sein’s
being to be meaningless because it is finite, Heidegger shows for the
first time that an understanding of being, and with it, an understanding
of meaning and purpose, is possible only to a finite existence. Da-sein
exists finitely, not because he does not in fact last forever, but because
to him a not is in advance revealed , and this harsh , inexorable not alone
has the revelatory power to enable him to understand being and so
bring him into the dignity and uniqueness of a finitely free existence.
The disclosure of being calls Da-sein to the task of existing as the
place of illumination in the world-all. This disclosure, however, cannot
happen to some abstract Da-sein in general, but only to a single, facti-
cally existing Da-sein. The circularity of the problem of being has now
come fully to light: the manifestness of the not makes it possible for Da-
sein to understand being, but, on the other hand, his own factical self
is needed to make manifest the not. This is the ground for Heidegger’s
thesis that ontology cannot be founded upon an “ ideal subject, ” a “ pure
I, ” a “ consciousness as such, ” but only upon the factically existing Da-
sein, because he and he alone, in his own finite existence, is the place
of the transcendental.
NOTES
1. The word ontology is used throughout this book in the sense defined
by Heidegger. It is the inquiry into beings as beings. This inquiry considers
beings purely in what and how they are, i.e., in respect of their being. Hence a
second definition of ontology, namely as the inquiry into the being of beings,
is often used by Heidegger as equivalent to the definition given first. Ontology,
theology, logic, in their essential unity, constitute metaphysics as a whole. For
a discussion of the threefold unity of metaphysics, see, e.g., Heidegger’s lec-
ture, “ Die onto-theo-logische Verfassung der Metaphysik ” ( ID, 37-73, “ The
Onto-Theo-Logical Constitution of Metaphysics,” ID( E ), 42-76. A list of the
abbreviations of titles used in references is given in the bibliography ).
2. When the explanation of a key word has an essential bearing on Hei-
degger’s thought, it will be given in the main text, unless it would interfere with
the movement of an important passage. Purely technical remarks will be made
in endnotes.
3. The fundamental changes within metaphysical thinking would natu-
rally be given far more weight in a detailed discussion than can be done in this
short sketch. For example, in the Latin word substantia there lies already a pro-
found reinterpretation of the Greek idea of being as ousia. The term substance,
according to Heidegger, is thoroughly inappropriate to Greek thought. At this
stage, however, it is unavoidable to use a language that is familiar to the reader
from the best-known translations of Greek thinkers.
4. Heidegger’ s interpretation of Descartes’s cogito sum cannot be even
approximately dealt with in this short sketch. It should be noted, however,
that Heidegger is fully aware of the epochal change within metaphysical
thinking that began with Descartes. The discussion of Descartes’s “ extended
369
370 A Guide to Heidegger’s Being and Time
than it had traditionally. We cannot appropriately ask “ What is man ? ” and even
the question “ Who is man ? ” applies to him only as a factical self. The primary
and leading question concerning man’s being is “ How is man ? ”
This chapter seeks to elucidate one of the most widely known themes of Being
and Time, as it is presented in Div. One, chaps. 4 and 5 B. In view of the great
interest of the theme itself and Heidegger’s treatment of it , special care has
been taken to follow his text as closely as possible, bringing to the reader, if
only in a summarized form, as many passages from it as could be considered
within the limits of this book.
1. Joan Stambaugh says “ tolerance.” [ Ed.]
2. Joan Stambaugh translates Gerede by “ idle talk ” and uses “ hearsay ” for
Hörensagen. [ Ed.]
works, opens up a topic of great importance and interest. Its discussion , how-
ever, would lead too far away from the main theme of this study, and must be
passed over here.
that Heidegger calls “ decease.” To “ persuade” the friend that he may “ escape
death, ” Heidegger argues, helps to hide both from him and from ourselves the
ownmost possibility of existence.
The more carefully the argument is examined the less satisfactory it
becomes. It turns on the ambiguity of “ escaping death,” which introduces the
suggestion that we are trying to relieve our friend of the “ being toward death,”
instead of expressing the hope that his decease may not be imminent. Such
hopes, whether justified or unjustified, undoubtedly often help us to put off
facing death to another day, but they need not necessarily do so. Heidegger’s
own concept of death in no way implies that the hope of recovery from an ill-
ness and the desire for a longer life are incompatible with a fully disclosed
being toward death. If they were, we would be faced with the absurdity of
rejecting all medicine as a thoroughly “ disowned” business, for what could be
more “ reassuring ” than good medical care? The reassurance is itself not the
least part of medicine, since the outcome of a critical illness may well be
decided by whether the sick man himself has hope of recovery or whether he
has given himself up for hopeless.
Would a resolutely “ owned ” existence take it upon himself to assure his
friend that his decease is imminent, and so perhaps rob him of his chance of
recovery? It would seem so, considering that he is in every way the opposite of
disowned existence. Yet this conclusion is not only insupportable, but goes fun-
damentally against Heidegger’s own interpretation of dying. If death is always
and only my dying, I alone am responsible for how I take it upon myself. It can-
not be for anyone else to force me into facing it. No one would know this bet-
ter than the man who has become transparent to himself in the finiteness of
his own existence. He could indeed greatly help others to face their death, but
solely by the courage and fortitude with which he faces his own, not by telling
a sick friend that it is all up with him.
4. With a view to Heidegger’s later time-analyses, it is useful to note the
strange circumstance under which the basic when-character of time first comes
emphatically into sight. It is evident that every “ point ” which we define in time
is a “ when.” For example, we “ fix” the date of a meeting for 4 p.m. on a cer-
tain day. In doing so, we so to speak freeze the “ flow of time ” at a selected
point. Were time not definable by a “ when,” it obviously would not be of much
practical or scientific use. What is so strange about Heidegger’s inquiry is that
it brings the “ when ” for the first time to our notice where it is completely inde-
finable. What significance this may have is impossible to see at the moment,
but it may be illuminating to remember it later on.
5. This passage confirms the comment on illness and decease made in the
first section. According to Heidegger’s own interpretation, a proper being toward
death has nothing to do with “ hastening” of decease or with taking no steps to
postpone it. It is also equally far removed from any romantic “ death wish.”
6. This passage is in itself a refutation of the frequent accusations that
Heidegger’ s so-called existentialism provides the philosophical basis for and
374 A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
necessarily leads to Nazism. The basic feature of Nazism is its total and ruth-
less disregard of the existence of others, culminating in the assumption of the
right of one race to exterminate others. Heidegger’s active support of the Nazi
—
movement in its earlier days, and particularly his treatment of Husserl it is reli-
—
ably reported that he never greeted Husserl on the street after 1933 must be
regarded as an almost incomprehensible fall below his own thinking. If it
proves anything, it proves only that even the deepest ontological insight is no
guarantee that one’ s practical-ethical decisions will be equally admirable.
Whether this detracts from the thought itself is a disturbing and not easily
answered question. In 1942, when the disillusionment with Nazism may
already have set in , under threat of having the publication of Being and Time
prohibited, Heidegger allowed the dedication to Husserl to be deleted ( US,
269, G12, 259, OWL, 199-200 ). We may legitimately wonder whether Being and
Time would not be an even greater work than it is, had Heidegger allowed it to
be suppressed. Would it not have gained greatness in a different dimension
from pure philosophy ? And has this other dimension nothing to do with phi-
losophy? However that may be, one thing is certain: Heidegger’s thought nei-
ther justifies nor necessarily leads to Nazism any more than to any other polit-
ical-historical ideology. What it does is to show that the greatest extremes of
—
human conduct utter ruthlessness as well as utmost self-sacrifice— are made
possible by the existential constitution of man, from which alone they can be
understood in a fundamental way.
.
1 This remark leads us to expect that Heidegger would at least comple-
ment his elucidations of the “ I think ” with that of the “ I act.” This expectation
is all the more justified because for Kant the “ practical person, ” the “ moral
agent,” as the free, autonomous intelligence, is the “ authentic self.” But Hei-
degger, apart from the single reference quoted above, takes no further notice
in Being and Time of the practical-moral self. How would he justify this omis-
sion ? He would say that the ontological foundations of Kant’s practical self are
no more adequate than those of his “ theoretical ” or “ logical ” subject. Nor can
the two put together make up the proper foundations, for unless man’s being
is in advance conceived ( “ projected ” ) in sufficient depth and width to originate
and carry both the “ theoretical ” and “ practical ” self , a subsequent merger
between the two remains an ontologically bottomless undertaking. This
thought is expressed in detail on page 320 ( footnote ), where Heidegger says
that even if Kant’s “ theoretical reason is included in practical reason, the exis-
Notes to Part Three 375
tential and ontological problematic of the self remains not only unsolved , but
unasked . On what ontological basis is the ‘working together’ of theoretical and
practical reason supposed to occur? Does theoretical behaviour determine the
kind of being of the person, or is it the practical or neither of the two and
which one then ? Do not the paralogisms, in spite of their fundamental signif-
—
icance, reveal the lack of ontological foundation of the problematic of the self
from Descartes’s res cogitans to Hegel’s concept of the Spirit ? One does not
even need to think ‘naturalistically’ or ‘rationalistically’ and can yet be in sub-
servience to an ontology of the ‘substantial’ that is only all the more fatal
because it is seemingly self-evident.” The soundness of Heidegger’s position in
this matter can hardly be denied. Nonetheless, it does not seem fully to justify
his ignoring precisely that aspect of the self that is not only central to Kant, but
is his nearest approach to the idea of an “ authentic existence. ” The gulf
between, say, Kant’s “ feeling of reverence” ( Achtung ) , in which a free
autonomous subject submits himself to a self-given moral law, and Heidegger’ s
“ resoluteness,” whereby a free existence holds himself in readiness to be sum-
moned to himself by the call of conscience, is not nearly so deep as that
between the latter and the purely “ logical subject.” [ For further reflections on
Kant on Ί act’ see Martin Heidegger, Die Grundprobleme der Phänomenologie
( Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1975), G 24, The Basic Problems of Phenomenology ,
trans. Albert Hofstadter ( Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982 ), Part
One, chapter 3. Ed.]
3. The German text has an obvious error in the sentence “ Des Wozu
gewärtig, kann das Besorgen allein zugleich auf so etwas zurü ckkommen ,
wobei es die Bewandtnis hat.” The Wozu is identical with the Wobei and the lat-
ter must be corrected in the text to Womit . The next sentence makes it clear
beyond doubt that that is what Heidegger intended .
4. The preconcept of phenomenology is given in the introduction,
chap. 2, § 7, C.
5. Although Heidegger makes no explicit statement on this subject , it is
extremely doubtful whether he would think it possible to understand some-
thing in its bare existentia without any qualifications whatever. Even when he
speaks of something that “ only persists” ( nur besteht ), the only-persisting is pre-
cisely the mode of that something’s being, its way of being-in-time. At the very
least, being must necessarily be defined by time.
6. The interpretation given of Heidegger’s extremely condensed text
may be thought to go beyond what actually stands there. It is well warranted,
however, by earlier discussions of “ statement as a derivative mode of interpre-
tation” (§ 33), and of “ the traditional concept of truth ” (§ 44, a and b ).
7. Some interpreters might argue that in one of his late works Heidegger
turns against his own early views, for there he contrasts Aristotle’ s Physics as a
genuine philosophy with modern physics as a positive science that presupposes
a philosophy (SG, 110-11, G10, 92-93, PR, 63-64. The date of SG is 1957,
while FD dates from 1935-36 ). But this evidence is inconclusive, because it is
quite possible, and indeed likely, that by “ positive science” Heidegger means
only the actual research-work and its results, which are of course irrelevant to
the point in question.
8. See Kants These über das Sein ( Frankfurt: Klostermann, 1962 ), 9ff., 12,
33, W, 276ff., 281, 304, G9, 448ff., 453, 476, P, 339ff., 453, 360.
9. It would take us too far afield to discuss how, for instance, the future
is primarily constitutive of all identification. To identify something as the same
with itself it is not enough to compare it as it presents itself now with what we
remember of it in the past. For further detail see Heidegger’s discussion of
Kant’s “ synthesis of recognition in the concept ” ( Critique of Pure Reason, A
103-10; KPM , § 33).
18. Hegel, Science of Logic, trans. A. V. Miller ( London: Allen & Unwin ,
1969 ), vol. 1, bk 1, chap. 1, C, 82-83.
19. Hegel, Encyclopaedia, § 259.
20. Ibid., Supplement.
21. Hegel, Science of Logic, vol. 2, 583.
22. Ibid.
23. Hegel, Phenomenology , 487.
24. Hegel, Die Vernunft in der Geschichte, 134.
25. Hegel, Phenomenology , 487.
GLOSSARY OF GERMAN EXPRESSIONS
383
384 A Guide to Heidegger' s Being and Time
a priori, 45-46, 53, 67, 104, 272; see arising (.Entspringen ), 229, 247, 274
also fore-going Aristotle, aesthêsis, 112; analogy,
actuality, reality ( Wirklichkeit ), 9, 33 15-17; being, 3; fear, 238; Hegel
addressing ( Ansprechen ), 329, 331, and time, 354; phusis, 270; Physics ,
349 377; time, 344 - 45; time and
affection, 237, 240 space, 43; truth, being and
ahead-of-itself , 98, 145, 151-52, 157, beings, 106
159, 210, 216, 220- 21, 230; see articulation, 57
also fore-throw as, 112, 116, 138, 264-68, 283, 376;
aisthêsis , 112 apophantic and hermeneutic, 371;
alienation ( Entfremdung ), 89 as such, 209, 211, 223, 316, 345;
Allemann, Beda, 175 schema of presenting, 266
already, 56, 99, 151, 216, 220-21, attunement ( .Befindlichkeit ), 55-61,
249 83, 85, 93, 94-96, 161, 163, 221,
ambiguity, 87-88, 199, 243 236-42, 289; dread, 121, 153, 178,
analysis, static and genetic, 117 319; that I am, 182; timeishness,
Anaximander, 78 125
animal, 13, 16, 20, 150, 372; ratio- Augustine of Hippo, Saint, soul and
nal, 40 time, 349
anthropology, 14, 19, 150 authentic (eigentlich ) and inauthen-
anticipation, 159-61, 179 , 201-7, tic, 40-41, 163-227, 232-34,
210, 218, 231, 242, 325; see also 247-52, 278, 288-90, 291-92 ,
ahead and forward-running 333-35, 349; historicity, 295, 298,
anxiety ( Angst ) , see dread 302- 25; see also owned and dis-
apophansis, 111 owned
appearance ( Erscheinung), 110-11; average, 42, 79, 82, 84-85, 230, 290
Kant , 111 awaiting (Gewärtigen ), 231, 233, 237,
approachable, touchable ( angänglich), 242, 247 , 252, 258-61, 264 , 267,
57 286-89 , 330
387
388 Λ Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
being, to be ( Sein ) , xix , 5, 7, 13, 122-23, 125, 150, 173, 210, 216,
15-16, 22; analogy, 15-17, as 222; theory and practice, 199;
such, 209, 211, 223; and beings, time, 217-25; truth, 102, 104;
342; horizon of being, 126; how- unity, 123; whole, 37, 56, 97-100,
being, 8, 15, 112, 140; humanity, 120, 125, 241
49; I am, 13-15, 18, 20 , 32, 47, care-for, concern, solicitude
97, 115, 117; is, are, 17, 21-23, ( Fürsorge ) , 76- 78, 86, 192
30, 47, 61, 71, 115, 137, 223, categories ( Kategorien ) , 33, 43-44, 99,
254 -55, 267-68, 276, 328; mean- 116, 280; catégorial structure, 46
ing, 126; nothing, 136; substan- causality, 266
tial, 10; temporality, 134-35; tens- certainty, 155-57, 160, 204
es, 135-36; that-being, 116; time, charity, 77
126, 328; transcendens pure and choice, 194-96, 198, 203, 306, 322
simple, 256, 275; truth , 262; Christianity, 14, 309
unity, 15; what-being, 8, 15, 33, circle, 23-24 , 37-38, 95-96, 167,
113, 140 209-10 , 234 , 331, 367
being-here, see Da-sein circumspect for-sight ( Umsicht ) ,
being-in-the-world ( in-der-Welt-sein ) , 69-70, 78, 86, 243
25, 27, 45, 51-65, 74 , 89, 92-97, coming-toward , future ( Zu-kunft ) , 18,
187, 275-84, 289 36, 124 , 218- 21, 230
being near ( close ) to ( bei ) , 44, 64, 74, common sense, 70, 168, 210, 329
85, 99, 180, 216, 222, 244 , 275, communication , 308, 312
328 concealment, see covering over and
being-one’s-self , 27, 75-90 hiddenness
being-with ( Mitsein ) , 27, 56, 58, concept , 135, 350, 356
63-64, 74, 75-83, 180, 198, 222, connection , coherence of life
304 ( Lebenszusammenhang ) , 295, 315,
beings ( das Seiende ), 9, 11-13, 16, 22 , 319-20
71-74; as beings, 106; being, 342; conscience ( Gewissen ) , 121- 22,
created , 15; in the whole, 138, 163-75, 190-95, 366; call, voice,
—
176, 177 78; sinking away,
176-77; ta onta , 11-12, 110; see
163-75, 191, 193; care, 166, 167;
existentiell and existential, 192;
also ontological difference reprimanding, 191; wanting-to-
Bergson, Henri, 125, 226, 331, 376 have-a-conscience, 122-23,
bindingness, 180, 183, 319 195-96; warning, 190-91
birth, 120, 149, 295-96, 318 consciousness, 114-15, 117, 367
body, 20 considerate looking-back ( on the
boundary situation , 250 other’ s thrownness ), considerate-
ness ( Rücksicht ) , 78, 243
calculation, 15; death, 157, 158, constancy, 181, 183, 204 , 216, 226,
160-61, 184 , 333 246, 281, 304 ; see also stability
care ( Sorge ) , 25, 28, 35-36, 42, 64; conviction ( Überzeugung ) , 156
the between , 297; conscience, correspondence, see truth
122 , 163-75, 193; everyday, 105; covering over, concealing, 112 ,
ground-being, 122; selfhood , 155-56, 205, 272, 334 ; see also hid-
212-17; structure , 119- 20 , denness
Index 389
Kant, Immanuel, 2, 43, 111, 116, logical, 123, 217-25; see also signi-
117, 134, 141, 232; anticipations fication and significance
of perception , 185; awe, 319; meaninglessness, 367
being, 135; categories, 280, means, by means of , 55, 61, 64,
283-84, 375; cause, 181; concept, 69-70
135; fortune, 307; morality, 169, measurement, 225, 379; astronomi-
309, 374-75; nature, 375-76; cal, 292, 337, 339-41
practical reason , 274-75; pure medieval philosophy, 14, 16, 135; see
reason, 279; respect, 319; schema- also Schoolmen
tism , 267, 283-84; self , 213-15; metaphysics, 10, 13, 16, 20, 72, 118,
synthesis, 263, 280; time, 313, 369; death , 151; beings, 138
342; time and space, 284-85, 379; method , 109, 112-13, 117, 142-44,
totality, 280; transcendental 158, 175, 201, 212, 273;
object, 185; transcendental self- Descartes, 116-17; historical sci-
consciousness, 310; will, 195 ences, 325; violence, 207
Kierkegaard, Soren, 233 mind , 19, 325
knowledge, 67, 104 mine, 120, 147, 333, 373
Moment ( Augenblick ), 222, 233, 241,
lack , 145, 147-48, 151 248, 250, 289 , 310, 313, 319, 334 ,
language, 71, 83-86, 102, 141, 173, 348
252-55, 329, 378; speech, 329; see mood , see attunement
Index 393
morality, 162, 169, 172, 173, 187-89, ontology, 11, 22, 68, 369; essence,
198 272; fundamental, 11, 19, 25, 29,
movedness ( Bewegtheit ) , 176, 234, 46, 113, 173, 212; meaning of
297, 316, 325; movement in space, beings, 272; ontological-existen-
288 tial, existential-ontological,
42-43, 44, 48-49, 52, 70, 80 , 82;
nature, 15, 19, 44 , 45, 52, 53, 69, regional, 19, 113, 270; traditional,
269- 71; history, 300; time, 342 11-12, 19, 42, 71, 83, 99, 183
Nazism , 373- 74 order, in order to, 55, 61, 69-70, 278
necessity, 8; world, 139; historical, organism, 20, 42
10, 19, 29, 33 otherness, 138, 178, 180, 186, 280,
never, 171, 173, 174, 186-87, 304, 366 365
Newton, Isaac, 270 others, 56, 64 , 76, 99, 160; birth and
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 160; history, death, 120, 146-47
323- 24; Übermensch, 307, 378; onsia , 184, 369
will, 195 overturning ( Umschlag ) , 268
nihilism , 9 overview ( Übersicht ) , 263- 64
noein, 18-19, 66, 112 owing ( Schuld ) , 122-23, 167-75,
noema, 116 186-200, 202, 216
not , 8-9, 34-35, 39, 60, 63, 80, own, 38, 47
96-97, 98, 174, 249, 251, 304, owned, authentic ( eigentlich ), 38,
365-67; debt, 122, 170-71 40-41, 76-78, 83, 91, 95, 102,
nothing( ness) ( Nichts ) , 8-9, 93-94, 120, 123-24, 141, 143, 158, 163,
171, 175-87, 365; conscience, 167, 201-27, 245, 246, 248-50,
164 ; horizon , 232; negates, -
288-89, 291 92; attunement, 242;
138-40 , 170, 177, 206; notness, death, 158-62, 373; existence,
nullity ( Nichtigkeit ) , 39, 122, 173, 187-200, 274; future, 232-34,
224; shrinking back from, 176; 240, 252, 278; history, historicity,
time itself, 366; see also Hegel 298, 304-5, 315, 318-24; occur-
now, 187, 233, 329-36, 339-40, rence, 302, 314; past, 234, 238,
344-48; Hegel, 352-55 247; present , 233; science,
nowhere, 93-95, 365 274-75; temporality, 310-11;
understanding, 236
object (Gegenstand ), 15, 23, 68, 111, ownmost ( eigenst ) , xviii, 32, 35, 154 ,
282 157, 159, 193
obligation , 180, 188
occurrence, happening ( Geschehen ) , Parmenides, 106, 376
296-97, 305-6, 315-16, 325 past , 18; having been, 36, 124, 136,
on , to on, xv; ta onta , 11-12, 110 218-19, 234-35, 289
ontic ( ontisch ) , 48, 68, 97, 150; ontic- perception, 112, 115, 277, 282
existentiell, 46, 52 perishing ( Verendung ), 150
ontological constitution phenomenology, 6, 26, 28, 75-76,
( Seinsverfassung ) , 44, 46, 272 109-18; hermeneutic, 113
ontological difference, 178, 273, 276 phenomenon, 18, 109-11
ontological structure ( Seinsstruktur ), phusis , 270, 343
42, 84 physics, 270 - 72
394 A Guide to Heidegger's Being and Time
transcendence, 341; unity of care, values, 73- 74, 172, 180, 188
123, 216; within-timeness, 327-61,
336-43; world-time, 338, 341-42; wanting ( willing)-to-have-a-conscience
Zeitlichkeit, 370 ( Gewissen-haben-wollen): see con-
totality, see whole science
tradition, 300, 304 when, 186-87; indefinite, 206; pure,
tranquillizing ( Beruhigung), 248 366
transcendence, transcendental, 44, where, whereness, whereish , 93-94,
60; consciousness, 114, 117; Da- 132, 365
sein, 175, 177-78, 180, 275, 367; whirl ( Wirbel ) , 89-90, 106
freedom , 181, 195, 308; ground- whole, wholeness, totality, 37, 38, 43,
giving, 183; philosophy, 310; sub- 51-53, 94 , 120, 123, 139, 145-62,
ject , 114-17; time, 341; world, 177-78, 204, 206, 280; see also Da-
181, 275-84 , 280, 341 sein
Index 397
willing, 180, 195; see also sake of , for world-forming, world-imaging ( welt-
the bildend ) , 53-54 , 67, 184-85
with-world ( Mitwelt ) , 76 worldishness, worldliness
witness ( Zeugnis ) , 156, 162, 163 ( Weltlichkeit ) , xv, 26, 27, 42 ,
world , 25, 51-70, 71-74, 93, 289; 51-70, 94 , 124, 128, 338, 340
past, has been , 302; significance- world-time, 338
whole, 367; transcendence, 181,
275; world history, 315- 26; world Yorck, Paul, Graf von Wartenburg,
worlds, 140, 180 299-300; historical and ontic, 316
PHILOSOPHY
MAGDA KING
A Guide to Heidegger s
Beirut and Time
Edited by John Llewelyn
— —
and T ne, making it the essential guide for newcomers and specialists alike . Beginning
with a non-technical exposition of the question Heidegger poses "What does it mean
to be ?" and keeping that question in view, it gradually increases the closeness of focus
on the text. Citingjoan Stambaughs translation , the author explains the key notions of
the original with the help of concrete illustrations and reference to certain of the most
relevant works Heidegger composed both before and after the publication of Being
and Tinu
"Originally published in the early sixties as one of the first English-language commentar-
ies on Heidegger ’s B mg and Time , Magda King ’s masterful Guide has now been vastly
expandtd to cover the whole of B ing and Time, its renderings of Heidegger’s German
terms revised to correspond to Joan Stambaughs new translation of Bang and Time , and
its discussions of Heidegger 's later texts supplemented with references to his recendy
.
published earliest texts before B mg and Time In this expanded and revised edition
prepared by John Llewelyn , King’s Guide is now the best companion volume to use
"
—
with Stambaugh ’s new translation of B mg and Time ”
John van Buren , author of The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King —
Of all the studies of B ing and Time with which I am familiar, Magda King’s is the most
direct , the simplest, and the clearest. ”
— Joseph P Fell,J H. Hams Professor Emeritus Bucknell University — .
.. . .
··· ·.· · - ·
il '* ) M tvs ¹½³ . .. » « 1»
K
s volume in the SUNY senes in Contemporary Continental Philosophy
¡Xnnh J. Schmidt , editor
U • sr N E W YORK PRE
c 0>
9 780791 4 * 8007
^ r