Deep Learning in A Disorienting World
Deep Learning in A Disorienting World
Much has been written about the escalating intolerance of worldviews other than one’s own.
Reasoned arguments based on facts and data seem to have little impact in our increasingly post-
truth culture dominated by social media, fake news, tribalism, and identity politics. Recent
advances in the study of human cognition, however, offer insights on how to counter these
troubling social trends. In this book, psychologist Jon F. Wergin calls upon recent research in
learning theory, social psychology, politics, and the arts to show how a deep learning mindset
can be developed in both oneself and others. Deep learning is an acceptance that our
understanding of the world around us is only temporary and is subject to constant scrutiny.
Someone who is committed to learning deeply does not simply react to experience, but engages
fully with experience, knowing that the inevitable disquietude is what leads to efficacy in the
world.
It furthers the University’s mission by disseminating knowledge in the pursuit of education, learning, and research
at the highest international levels of excellence.
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781108480222
DOI: 10.1017/9781108647786
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing
agreements, no reproduction of any part may take place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2020
Printed in the United Kingdom by TJ International Ltd, Padstow Cornwall
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party
internet websites referred to in this publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain,
accurate or appropriate.
Contents
List of Figures
Preface
Acknowledgments
3 Mindful Learning
4 Constructive Disorientation
5 Critical Reflection
References
Index
Figures
6.1 The deep learning mindset, including the social learning field
Note
Ch apter 1
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
2
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
3
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
4
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
5
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
6
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
7
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
8
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
9
Causality Reductive
assumptions thinking Belief
persistence
stopping too suddenly and risking a rear-end collision. We are then forced
into System 2, which considers whether we might be overreacting.
Kahneman and others have catalogued all of the cognitive mischief that
can result when we do not step back and question what is happening at
a subconscious, System 1 level. One source lists as many as 36 different
variations (Shermer, 2011, pp. 261 ff.). Luckily, many of these overlap, and
all are interconnected (see Figure 1.1). In the center is confirmation bias,
“the mother of all cognitive biases” (p. 259). To the left are the enablers
of confirmation bias and its underlying dynamics, and to the right are its
effects, including its most pernicious, the polarization of group attitudes.
Confirmation bias is likely “the most widely accepted error to come out
of the literature on human reasoning” (Evans, 1990, p. 41). The term was
coined, most believe, by psychologist Peter Wason (1960) in an experiment
testing the willingness of subjects to question their own hypotheses about
the mathematical rule governing a series of numbers, such as “2–4–6.” He
found that when provided with additional information, subjects were able
to build upon and complexify their initial hypotheses, but they hardly
ever tried to disconfirm these hypotheses. Wason termed this phenomenon
“confirmation bias.” Defined by Michael Shermer (2011) as “the tendency
to seek and find confirmatory evidence in support of already existing
beliefs and ignore or reinterpret disconfirming evidence” (p. 259), con-
firmation bias is a term that 10 years ago almost no one other than cogni-
tive psychologists had ever heard of, and now it is seemingly in everyone’s
vocabulary. (There’s a joke about this, of course, along these lines: “Since
I learned about confirmation bias I now see it everywhere.”)
Like so many other deep insights about the human condition, the
phenomenon of confirmation bias was recognized centuries ago. Back in
the early seventeenth century, Sir Francis Bacon was an early pioneer of
empiricism. In his book Novum Organum (New Instrument), he wrote:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
10
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
11
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
12
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
13
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
14
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
15
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
16
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
17
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
18
Notes
1 The authors reference Frankfurt’s (On Bullshit, 2005) intriguing distinction
between lying and bullshit: “Whereas lying involves a deliberate attempt
at concealing the truth, which implies a concern for the truth, bullshit is
constructed absent concern for the truth” (p. 9). The idea of doing something
about the creation and spread of BS seems to be catching on, exemplified by
a popular course at the University of Washington, “Calling Bullshit: Data
Reasoning in a Digital World” (McWilliams, 2019).
2 The Dreyfus case has been cited in several sources as a dramatic illustration
of confirmation bias. One of the most engaging is a TED talk by Julia Galef
(2016).
3 Pauling did however live to be 93.
4 A good place to start would be Barbara Tuchman’s classic, The March of Folly:
From Troy to Vietnam (1984).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:17, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.001
19
Ch apter 2
How We Learn
A Short Primer
19
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
20
20 How We Learn
Frontal lobe Parietal lobe
ru s
l gy
nta
Precentral gyrus
fro us
gyr
rus
rior
upe on tal
l gy
S
dl e fr Occipital lobe
tra
Mid
opercularis
cen
Sup
Pars
tri ram
Ang
an Par
st
a
gyr rginal
Po
gu s
ular
la us
P ris
orb ars
occipital gyrus
ita
G
lis
yr
Superior temporal gyrus
us
Inferior
Lateral
frontal
gyrus Middle temporal gyrus
Anterior Posterior
Ventral (inferior)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
21
2.1 Inside Your Brain 21
Caudate nucleas
Mammillary
body
until early adulthood. The thin outside surface of the cerebrum, about the
thickness of a grapefruit skin, is the cerebral cortex containing about 100
billion neurons, which essentially manage the work of the brain.
Deep inside our brains is the limbic system, which manages emotions
(see Figure 2.2).
Among the key structures of the limbic system, two are most respon-
sible for learning. One is the amygdala, which seeks to make meaning of
experience, mostly at an unconscious level. In situations of uncertainty it
stimulates the frontal lobe to kick in, encouraging us to think it through.
The other is the hippocampus, which is more concerned with memory. It
takes in information from the senses, packages and processes the separate
stimuli, and then sends them to the cortex where the information becomes
part of long-term memory.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
22
22 How We Learn
Finally, just below the cerebrum is the cerebellum, the primary source
of motor control (Wright et al., 2016). The cerebellum is where som-
atic learning resides, the source of “muscle memory.” When a behavior is
practiced over and over again, the sequence of actions required becomes
automatic, such as typing on a keyboard, driving a car with a manual
transmission, or staying upright on skis.
This has been a drastically truncated tour of the brain, and here is
why: While technology has enabled scientists to map various sensations to
certain regions based on analyses of neural firings, as the technology has
become more sophisticated, linking regions with functions has become
murkier. For example, the cerebellum used to be thought of as almost a
separate organ, representing more primitive evolutionary stages; now it
appears to play a role in various aspects of cognition, including language.
This makes understanding the interplay between sensation and meaning-
making a more complex challenge. For example, where do emotions come
from? How are they triggered? How are they regulated? The answers to
these questions are still a matter of debate, and some of the evidence may
seem counterintuitive. More on this shortly, but first I want to provide
some further context.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
23
2.1 Inside Your Brain 23
childhood? My guess is that the reader’s first response is, “school!” Formal
schooling indoctrinates us on what to think and how –basically what is
important to know. And yes, there is certainly some truth to this. But
there is a biological answer, demonstrated by a lot of cross-cultural research
(Shatz, 1992). Consider for a moment the life of a 6-year-old. Everything is
interesting, everything is important. Kids that age are veritable sponges of
information, as every parent knows. Now imagine what it would be like if
adults had the same synaptic connections they had at age 6, and imagine
the mental chaos. Our brains use middle and late childhood to figure out
how the world works by reinforcing some networks and letting others die
out. Only those that are reinforced survive. We create individual mental
models, the key to survival dating back to our earliest days as humans, to
make meaning out of chaos.
Unfortunately, meaning making can take us in strange directions, as we
saw in Chapter 1. Here are some more examples:
In 2008 the International Center for the Advancement of Scientific
Literacy at the University of Michigan put together a short quiz and
administered it to a random sample of 2,500 US citizens. One of the
questions was, “How long does it take for the earth to go around the
sun?” The three choices were: “one day,” “one month,” and “one year.”
Only 67% of respondents had the correct answer. The clear inference here
is that about one person in every three walking down the street doesn’t
know a basic fact about our solar system –that the earth is a planet
taking a year to revolve around the sun –even though virtually every kid
in school has to make a model of the solar system at one time or other.
(King, 2015)
Now in case these researchers just picked an unusually dull group to survey,
consider this: A researcher gets the bright idea of going around with a video
camera after Harvard’s commencement exercises, when new graduates are
standing around looking smug, taking photos with their parents. She sticks
the camera in their faces, asking common-sense questions like, “Why is
it warmer in the summer than in winter?” Out of 23 randomly chosen
graduates (plus some alumni and faculty), 21 were factually incorrect, most
stating that seasons are caused because the earth is closer to the sun in the
summer and further away in the winter. One of the students answering
incorrectly had taken several physics courses at Harvard, including one in
“planetary motion”! (Harvard Smithsonian Center for Astrophysics, 1987).
These people learned the same stuff about the solar system in elementary
school that the people in the Michigan survey did, so what is going on?
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
24
24 How We Learn
It turns out that when asked to reconsider their answers, most did in fact
get it right; but they had seized upon the first mental model that came
to mind, which is the simple principle that the closer an object is to a
heat source, the hotter it will get. Retrieving a more complicated mental
model, about how the earth is tilted on its axis, which affects the angle of
the sun’s rays, is harder. These people were, in essence, relying on System
1 thinking, when what they really needed to do was to pull up System 2
(Kahneman, 2011).
Here is a short thought experiment. Read through the following care-
fully. What is being described?
A newspaper is better than a magazine, and on a seashore is a better
place than a street. At first, it is better to run than walk. Also, you
may have to try several times. It takes some skill but it’s easy to learn.
Even young children can enjoy it. Once successful, complications are
minimal. Birds seldom get too close. One needs lots of room. Rain
soaks in very fast. Too many people doing the same thing can also cause
problems. If there are no complications, it can be very peaceful. A rock
will serve as an anchor. If things break loose from it, however, you will
not get a second chance.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
25
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
26
26 How We Learn
(Dewey, [1938] 1997). Dewey, too, recognized the key role of emotion in
human judgment, seeing it as the main entry into what he called “a life of
thought.” He envisioned the human mind not as a storehouse of ideas but
as how humans make meaning of experience, and thus manage and lead
lives of useful activity. Early in his career, spurred by such social upheavals
as the Pullman Strike in 1893 –a widespread work stoppage and boycott of
the railways that turned violent –Dewey turned to schools as democracy’s
best hope. Children’s “inner nature,” he felt, grows from within but must
be completed through relationships, and thus schools must be a reflec-
tion of life. To the degree that schools are laboratories for living, society
progresses toward greater democracy and social justice. Dewey’s ideas were
central to what became known as the “progressive education” movement
(Martin, 2002). In the late 1930s, following attacks on freedom of expres-
sion in schools and universities in the United States, Dewey published
Experience and Education (1938), a powerful restatement of the role of
experience in learning. First he debunked the misunderstood notion that
children, and people generally, “learn by doing.” Some experiences, he
averred, can be “mis-educative,” that is, can be “unintelligent doing” that
results in learning the wrong things. An “educative” experience, on the
other hand, “arouses curiosity, strengthens initiative, and sets up desires
and purposes that are sufficiently intense to carry a person over dead places
in the future” (Dewey, [1938] 1997, p. 38). In this one sentence, Dewey
encapsulates core ideas of deep learning, and I will be returning to his work
extensively later in this book.
Part of what Dewey meant by “educative experience” is what has become
known as experiential learning theory, introduced by psychologist David
Kolb (Kolb, 1984). In his “experiential learning cycle,” Kolb essentially
turned formal education upside down: Instead of building knowledge by
learning abstract concepts and then applying them, what radical educator
Paulo Freire (1970) called the “banking model” of formal education, what
the learner does in real life is to build knowledge by experiencing an event,
reflecting on it, developing an abstract interpretation of it, and finally
acting on this interpretation, thus generating further experience, reflec-
tion, theorizing, and action (Figure 2.3).
This model, probably because it is simple, plausible and easy to grasp,
has been used and adapted thousands of times in every conceivable
learning context over the years, and, inevitably, due to its simplicity and
intuitive appeal, has also been the target of harsh criticism. Still, Kolb’s
learning cycle, with its clear connections to neuroscience research and to
emerging models of adult development, has had an enormous impact on
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
27
how we think about learning and about connecting learning with action,
and has led to such paradigm-changing epistemologies as action research
(cf. McNiff, 2017), and practice-based research (Jarvis, 1999).
One offshoot of the renewed interest in the interaction between action
and cognition is research into embodied cognition, “the idea that the mind
is not only connected to the body but that the body influences the mind”
(McNerney, 2011). The key to understanding embodied learning that we
do not just learn from experience, we also learn in experience. It is a felt
reaction to experience that feels “right” or “wrong,” and in adults this reac-
tion can be quite nuanced. For example, the positive feeling created by
the friendly behavior of a gracious hostess may lead someone who doesn’t
know her well to perceive her as “sincere,” while in contrast, someone who
has experienced her cordiality as superficial in prior experiences would
think of the same conduct as “smarmy.” Cognition that does not occur
from and in experience will not create learning for experience. Sharan
Merriam and her colleagues cite as an ironic example college courses that
take on issues of social justice but only in an abstract, disembodied way,
leading to students becoming quite sophisticated in critical social analysis
but unable to apply these skills in real life –or even in simulations of real
life (Merriam, Caffarella, & Baumgartner, 2007).
Aristotle understood the importance of embodied learning centuries ago,
when he described three kinds of knowing: episteme, knowing what and
why; techne, knowing how; and phronesis, knowing when. Quite simply, we
may know a lot about issues of power and inequality, for example, and be
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
28
28 How We Learn
skilled at knowing how to analyze them, but we may not know when and
in what context to use these skills most effectively. One of the most dra-
matic examples of phronesis is the story of a nomadic tribe of “sea gypsies”
in Thailand (Freiler, 2008). Most were able to survive the catastrophic tsu-
nami of 2004, unlike thousands of others. When asked how they survived
when so many others did not, they replied that they sensed a change in
their environment, both in the sea and in other living things, that caused
them to take higher ground before the tsunami actually struck. Another
example is what is known in mining as “pit sense.” In the dangerous setting
of a coal mine, miners must learn to detect minute changes in their envir-
onment as a way of constantly assessing their safety; tellingly, this way
of knowing depends not only on the miners’ individual perceptions but
also the senses of others in the mine (Freiler, 2008). Note how in both of
these examples knowing when is triggered by a sensory experience, which is
interpreted intuitively as a potential threat. Knowing when an experience
feels “right” can be powerful as well. In baseball an experienced base-stealer
will often know when to try for second base because it just “feels” right. An
expert poker player will know when it is “right” to bluff with a weak hand.
Phronesis is, in essence, practical wisdom, the ability to know when to rely
on intuition (System 1) and when to make the effort to dig more deeply
(System 2) (Kahneman, 2011). Practical wisdom is a topic I will return to
later in the book.
Intuition, as I have pointed out numerous times already, is necessary for
our survival; and it can also keep us from making wise choices. Given that
intuitive biases exist at a subconscious level, what then has to happen in
order for them to surface and be acted upon?
It turns out that we do have a solid theory about this, known as trans-
formative learning theory, developed about the same time as experiential
learning theory, and now arguably the dominant theory in adult learning.
According to its originator Jack Mezirow, adults learn to become “crit-
ically aware of how and why our presuppositions … constrain the way
we perceive, understand, and feel about our world; of reformulating these
assumptions to permit a more inclusive, discriminating, permeable, inte-
grative perspective, and of making decisions or otherwise acting upon these
new understandings” (Mezirow, 2000, p. 14). And what transcends the
cognitive traps that block the critical awareness that Mezirow describes?
What nudges us from System 1 into System 2? Mezirow (2000) asserts that
adults can learn deeply only by experiencing what he calls a “disorienting
dilemma,” a problem that does not fit into existing mental models (or
“meaning schemes,” as Mezirow called them). You experience something
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
29
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
30
30 How We Learn
Second, we would not have a disorienting experience in the first place
were it not for an emotional trigger. Without that an unusual experi-
ence is just a puzzle, one that we may be curious about and even want
to explore. We may wonder, for example, how the magician David
Copperfield could make the Statue of Liberty “disappear” in front of a
thousand spectators, but our beliefs about the laws of physics are never at
risk, because everyone knows that it’s a trick. On the other hand, feeling
“tricked” is bound to create disorientation. Recently I was waiting for
a connecting flight at New York’s Newark airport, browsing in a shop
along the concourse. I was approached by a disheveled-looking young
man who asked if I “traveled a lot.” He then proceeded to give me a long
story about how he was a recent college graduate who had been stranded
overnight by a canceled flight to Pittsburgh and could not get on another
flight until the next day. He showed me his original and “new” boarding
pass as evidence, along with a driver’s license and the business card of an
executive in the company he was about to join. He was desperate for a
place to stay overnight (and he certainly looked like he needed it), but he
had no credit cards as yet and had to pay for everything in cash. Could
I please loan him money for meals and hotel room? He took my address
and promised to pay me back right away. I took pity on him, withdrew
some money from an ATM and gave it to him, and he scurried away with
lavish thanks for how I confirmed his belief that “there were still good
people in the world.” Now, I would not be relating this story if he had
paid me back. Instead, the experience gave me a disorienting dilemma
and led to a modest shift in my self-concept, from “generous person” to
“easily duped person.”
Much of the research on human learning, particularly in adults,
supports the basic tenets of transformative learning, without necessarily
acknowledging so. Here is an especially impressive example. Higher edu-
cation researchers Ernest Pascarella and Patrick Terenzini conducted an
exhaustive investigation into learning in college, covering 35 years of
research and more than 5,000 books, journal articles, and miscellaneous
reports (Pascarella & Terenzini, 1991). The product of this work was so
massive that their students referred to it, with grudging admiration, as
“Moby Book.” The authors published an equally massive update, ten
years later (Pascarella & Terenzini, 2005). Reflecting back on decades
of research, Terenzini compiled a list of six “experiences that promote
student learning” (Terenzini, 2014). Note how similar these six optimal
learning experiences are to what has been reviewed so far on adult
learning:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
31
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
32
32 How We Learn
makes meaning of sensory stimuli. It makes meaning of a situation so that
we will know what to do in that moment. The brain will make meaning
of the same visual stimulus in vastly different ways. Approaching the first
drop of a roller coaster will produce physiological responses similar to those
when approaching the edge of a steep cliff; the former will be constructed
as “excitement,” while the latter will be constructed as “fear.” Further,
emotions are socially constructed and culture specific. Feldman states:
[Y]our familiar emotion concepts are built-in only because you grew up in
a particular social context where these emotion concepts are meaningful
and useful, and your brain applies them outside your awareness to con-
struct your experiences. Heart rate changes are inevitable; their emotional
meaning is not. Other cultures can and do make other kinds of meaning
from the same sensory input. (p. 33)
Today the key role of emotion in learning is clear and largely uncontested.
Emotion does not only stimulate learning, it is part of the learning process
itself. Emotion can be a force for deep learning, as when a disorienting
dilemma leads to reflection and perspective transformation; it can also be
a significant barrier to deep learning, as when someone encounters infor-
mation counter to his or her belief system and reduces the anxiety this
produces by resorting to myside bias.
So where, then is that sweet spot, that level of disorientation where
people experience just enough discomfort with the status quo that they
are able to reflect on what’s going on and try something new? That point
where we experience not just a felt need to change but also a desire to
change? What is the right balance between the body’s need to regulate
stress and maintain homeostasis, as neurologist and neuroscientist Antonio
Damasio (2018) has described it, and taking a creative risk that will upset
that homeostasis, at least temporarily? To address these questions, I turn
now to what we know about motivation to learn.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
33
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
34
34 How We Learn
efficacious,8 quite simply, the feeling that what we do matters, that we have
had a desirable impact on the world around us. Each of these motivators
has roots in other somatic-neurological processes. Curiosity arises from
the need to make meaning, a drive that remains largely undiminished
throughout the lifespan. The desire to belong and feel valued stems from
an innate need to feel safe, in a community that accepts us and that will
help protect us from harm. The need for efficacy stems from an innate
disposition to not only make meaning of the world but to interact effect-
ively with it. Together, these universal “motivators” help ease what Parker
Palmer has called the “pain of disconnection” from the world around us
(Palmer, 1998).
These universal sources of motivation will of course manifest them-
selves differently, depending on the social and cultural context. My own
research on the factors that affect motivation among university faculty, for
example, turned up four: autonomy, community, recognition, and efficacy
(Wergin, 2001). “Autonomy” was closely related to curiosity: the freedom
to experiment, to follow one’s own leads wherever they may go, and to do
so without fear of the consequences. “Community” was related to the need
for belonging, to feel as if one is part of a professional community that
cares about them. “Recognition” was the need to feel valued by that com-
munity, to know that others see their work as worthwhile. And, “efficacy”
in an academic community meant that faculty had a sense that their work
had an impact on their scholarly disciplines.
Fourth, motivation not only mediates learning but is a consequence of learning
as well (Wlodkowski, 2008). The more motivated someone is to learn, the
more enjoyable the learning, and the greater the motivation is to learn more.
At the same time, no matter how high, motivation will not help someone
accomplish a learning task that is significantly beyond their skill level or their
ability to cope with the increasing complexity of modern life. In fact, due to
the frustration and anxiety this causes, the likely result will be paralysis or a
desire to escape. Finding examples of this in one’s own life is, sadly, far too
easy. I was clumsy and overweight as a youngster, but I wanted desperately
to fit in with the other guys, so I went out for football. The coach used the
daily practice as a way to act out his fantasies as an army drill instructor, and
he made my life miserable. Not only did I stop going to practice, I developed
an “unathletic” identity, one that lasted into early adulthood, and led me to
avoid participating in competitive athletics of any kind.
Given this landscape, what then motivates adults to learn deeply? I have
sprinkled a few clues throughout this chapter and will now make them
more explicit.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
35
2.5 Conclusion 35
Adults want to learn lots of things, for all kinds of reasons, related
mostly to what is seen as practical and relevant to their lives. They want
learning to be self-directed, not dictated by what others think they should
learn (Knowles, 1984). They want to build new learning from life experi-
ence, to test this new learning, and to integrate it into their own lives. They
want the learning to be enjoyable, but not necessarily easy: they seek com-
petence but also value the challenge (Wlodkowski, 2008).
All of the above are necessary for deep learning to occur, but only
the last one distinguishes deep learning from the others. Deep learning
happens when existing beliefs are challenged, but only within the limits
of a person’s perceived ability to handle the challenge. To put it another
way, deep learning is achieved when an optimal tension exists: between
a perceived challenge to one’s existing belief system on the one hand, and a
perceived level of confidence in one’s ability to create new meaning in that
system on the other. Note the interaction of the “universal motivators” in
this definition, how they are not independent and additive but intertwined
and conflicting! A disorienting dilemma should make us curious, but not
so curious that we put ourselves in a place that feels isolated and unsafe.
We want to make meaning of and interact with the dilemma, but only
within socially sanctioned limits. We need to feel that changing our belief
system will make us more competent in dealing with our environment, as
long as doing so will not threaten our important social networks (and our
cherished self-images).
2.5 Conclusion
My goal in this chapter has been to lay the groundwork and provide an
evidentiary basis for proposals I make later in the book. Whereas Chapter 1
focused on the challenges to deep learning, Chapter 2 has considered the
necessary ingredients for deep learning to occur. They can be summed up
this way:
Deep learning depends on how we make meaning of experience. Most of
the time, this occurs at a level below conscious awareness, and most of the
time this is appropriate and necessary. Using existing mental models, our
brains interpret sensations based on prior experience, judge their import-
ance, and when necessary construct an emotion that leads to a behavioral
response. Small deviations from expected experience are handled smoothly.
For example, while driving we constantly monitor other motorists’ behavior,
and have learned how to detect variations from “normal.” Behavior that is
interpreted as abnormal will lead to a response dictated by the emotion the
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
36
36 How We Learn
brain constructs: say, either contempt (“where’d that idiot learn to drive”?)
or fear (“that car isn’t going to stop at the red light!”). The first leads to an
action of (real or imagined) eye-rolling, the second to hitting the brakes.
Sometimes, however, making meaning using existing neural networks and
mental models is insufficient: something feels particularly discordant or
“off”; something creates enough cognitive dissonance that it elevates an
experience to a conscious disquietude. For example, while reading the op-
ed page of the newspaper we glance at the headlines of various columnists.
For the familiar ones we have formed mental models of their views. We
read with pleasure the views consistent with ours, and with irritation those
that are not. If, however, a cherished pundit expresses an opinion that
is significantly different from our own, cognitive dissonance ensues, and
depending on the valence of the emotion constructed around that disson-
ance, we either choose to examine our beliefs or stop reading and write
off the essay as an aberration. This is easy to do if we are reading alone
but harder if the piece becomes a topic of discussion with others and we
are forced to explain why we dismissed the op-ed piece so quickly.9 Our
motivation to examine and possibly change our beliefs will then depend
on the balance between the strength of the experienced challenge and the
sense of our own competence in the moment. If the sense of challenge is
too strong we experience anxiety and the motivation to escape the discus-
sion. If the sense of competence is too strong we reinforce existing beliefs
by constructing counterarguments. In either case the opportunity for deep
learning disappears. If, however, the disorientation is experienced in a safe
social space, safe enough to unlock our innate curiosity and allow us to
imagine that changing our perspective will help us become more com-
petent in dealing with our environment, the gate to deep learning opens.
In the seven chapters that follow I explore seven keys to opening
that gate.
Notes
1 For more extensive accounts of the neuroscience of learning, cf. Changeux
(2009) and Swart, Chisholm, and Brown (2015).
2 See Vanderah and Gould (2016) for a fuller treatment of neuroanatomy.
3 Much of the material in this section is adapted from Shatz (1992).
4 Flying a kite. Thanks to Dr. Shelley Chapman for the example.
5 Nussbaum takes her title from Proust, who called the emotions “geological
upheavals of thought.”
6 Defined as, “whenever people behave for the satisfaction inherent in the
behavior itself ” (Ryan & Deci, 2017, p. 4).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
37
Notes 37
7 Ahl (2006) argues that motivation should not be regarded as something that
lies within the individual; it is rather “a construct of those who see it lacking in
others” (p. 385).
8 See Bandura (1977) for a full treatment of efficacy and learning.
9 A great example of this is the famous TV newscast by respected American jour-
nalist Walter Cronkite who, after a trip to cover the Vietnam War in the late
1960s, concluded that the war was at a stalemate, and unwinnable. Historians
have pointed to Cronkite’s announcement as a pivotal moment, leading millions
who had supported the war to then have grave doubts about it.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:36, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.002
38
Ch apter 3
Mindful Learning
38
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
39
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
40
40 Mindful Learning
potential is a “being” motive and what Maslow called “self-actualization.”
After studying those few adults who seemed to have risen to the top of the
hierarchy, Maslow concluded that complete self-actualization was quite
rare and happened only relatively late in life.2 He did, however, find many
adults who had at least some of these qualities: an accurate perception
of reality; acceptance of self and others; spontaneity and self-knowledge;
problem centering (vs. self-centering); freshness of appreciation; and having
peak experiences, deep and loving relationships, creativity, and a sense of
humor. Those whose environments did not satisfy lower-level needs did
not demonstrate a press for self-actualization and thus showed few of these
qualities. In his final works Maslow described self-transcendence, going
beyond any sense of separate self and merging with a higher purpose, a
being without any sense of an individual, “smaller” self.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
41
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
42
42 Mindful Learning
enhancing another person’s sense of being known and understood for what
he or she contributes to a relationship and to the social environment more
generally” (p. 10). When people feel that others know and understand
them, they are more likely to seek out feedback from others, which can
include not only affirmation but also “jolts” that help develop more honest
self-appraisal.
Putting these two “inside” views of self together –self-development
theory and reflected best self –suggests that we reach optimal integrity
when we feel that:
• we have the wherewithal to deal effectively with our environment;
• we have meaningful choices for how to do this;
• our dealings are consistent with our values; and
• we are recognized and valued for our contributions.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
43
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
44
44 Mindful Learning
the importance of having a strong personal identity with connection –and
independence surrounded by a nurturing community.
Kegan’s view is that development is the expanding ability to make
meaning of experience; thus, how people interpret a situation or event
depends on their developmental level. In essence, Kegan takes Mezirow’s
theory of transformative learning (2000) and attaches a developmental
perspective to it: we do not just create new schemes of meaning but do so
in a way that these new frames of reference represent increasingly complex
ways of knowing. As Kegan puts it, two processes are at the heart of trans-
formative learning:
The first is what we might call meaning-forming, the activity by which
we shape a coherent meaning out of the raw material of our outer and
inner experiencing. Constructivism recognizes that reality does not happen
preformed and waiting for us merely to copy a picture of it. Our perceiving
is simultaneously an act of conceiving, of interpreting …
The second process … is what we might call reforming our meaning-
forming. This is a metaprocess that affects the very terms of our meaning-
constructing. We do not only form meaning, and we do not only change our
meanings; we change the very form by which we are making our meanings.
(Kegan, 2000, pp. 52–53, emphasis in original)
How does this happen? Kegan argues that one’s current form of knowing is
at least in part the result of moving from “subject” to “object”:
That which is “object” we can look at, take responsibility for, reflect upon,
exercise control over, integrate with some other way of knowing. That
which is “subject” we are run by, identified with, fused with, at the effect of.
We cannot be responsible for that to which we are subject. What is “object”
in our knowing describes the thoughts and feelings we say we have; what is
“subject” describes the thinking and feeling that has us. We “have” object;
we “are” subject. (Kegan, 2000, p. 53)
“Development” is the gradual process by which what was once “subject”
becomes “object.” What we were once controlled by, we are now able to
step back from and see as part of a larger and more complex whole. Here
is an example. “Beth” is a young woman who has been brought up to
have an identity that is defined in large part by a set of strict social norms,
including gender roles. Part of this culture scripting is that her worth as
a woman will be determined by the social status of the man she marries.
She meets and marries a young man from a wealthy family and almost
immediately is subjected to verbal and physical abuse. She feels depressed
and helpless, but with the help of others in her social network, including
an insightful therapist, she begins to realize that her life does not have to
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
45
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
46
46 Mindful Learning
and molded by our environments, in the same way that Michelangelo noted
that a sculptor’s job is to take away that which prevents the sculpture from
emerging. The degrees to which one experiences competence, autonomy,
and relatedness (in self-determination theory terms) will determine the
extent to which this happens. Interactionists argue that the self evolves,
constantly changing and transforming itself in an oscillation between the
self and its environment. My position leans toward the interactionists,
namely that knowing oneself is less a matter of congruence between one’s
“true self ” and his/her environment than a constant tension between the
two, out of which development takes place. I also like what Ladkin and
Taylor (2010) say about how one’s self is best revealed, not by what goes on
in our heads but by what happens in our bodies:
The ground for a person’s awareness of self … is negotiated, made sense of,
and then expressed through the body. Enacting that self is dependent on
awareness of the somatic clues the body gives us about how we are experi-
encing a given situation … Our kinesthetic sense of ourselves is our most
primordial, [and] this would suggest that the body is a more trustworthy
ground for revealing individuals’ deeper, perhaps “truer,” motives and
emotions. (p. 66)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
47
3.2 Self-Development in Organizations 47
from them and modify our actions and even our way of thinking as a
result” (p. 4). Like Kegan, Torbert sees deep learning in adults as a process
through developmental stages, which he calls “action logics,” embedded
and largely subconscious aspects of self for dealing with the world around
us. “Conventional” action logics correspond roughly to Kegan’s “socialized
mind”; these are, in order of complexity, the opportunist, the diplomat, the
expert, and the achiever. Each relates to ways in which we make meaning
of experience:
• opportunist, how to manipulate our environment to our own
advantage;
• diplomat, how to curry favor with others;
• expert, how to master a world of thought; and finally
• achiever, how to put these first three action logics together to accomplish
something useful within existing social norms.
According to Torbert’s research (2004) more than 90 percent of organiza-
tional managers hold one of these action logics and only 7 percent operate
from “postconventional” action logics beyond these four, or in Kegan’s
terms, have developed beyond the socialized mind. Whereas those holding
conventional action logics are motivated by similarity and stability, those
with postconventional action logics are motivated increasingly by diffe-
rence and creative experimentation. People at these levels are more likely
to see their environments as complex, changing systems presenting com-
plex problems for which there are no clear solutions; they recognize the
importance of collaboration with others; and they actively seek out both
confirming and disconfirming feedback on their actions. While Torbert
does not put it this way, deep learning is a particular challenge for those
operating out of conventional action logics, because they prefer order and
stability over uncertainly and disorientation.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
48
48 Mindful Learning
As I noted earlier, Vaill asserts that the most important way to deal with
white-water conditions is to become a more effective learner. What makes
the phenomenon of permanent white water so important for learning?
Vaill (1996) sums it up this way: “Permanent white water is the meaning
we attach to our experiences. We experience both surprising, novel, messy,
costly, recurring and unpreventable events and feelings of lack of direction,
absence of coherence, and loss of meaning” (pp. 16–17). Note the similarity
of Vaill’s ideas to Mezirow’s and Kegan’s: organizations confronted with
continual white water are presented with one disorienting dilemma after
another, which, if not handled in a way that makes meaning of them, puts
those in the organization at risk of feeling overwhelmed and paralyzed.
Being effective in permanent white water requires, primarily, a different
perspective about learning itself. As I noted in Chapter 1, what Vaill calls
“institutional learning” is the dominant educational model in Western
society (similar to what Freire (1970) called the “banking model,” which
assumes that learning is simply a matter of depositing information in the
brain). Institutional learning5 is simply inadequate to deal with perpetual
white water, which requires a different kind of learning altogether. Vaill
maintains that learning in perpetual white water should have seven qual-
ities, each building on the previous ones:
• It should be self-directed. Self-directed learning is the antithesis of institu-
tional learning. One cannot be effective in creating environments con-
ducive to deep learning in others without self-direction.6
• It should be creative, characterized by a spirit of experimentation and
exploration and driven by a sense of both freedom and competence to
try new things. A creative spirit, Vaill notes, also requires that we self-
impose a sense of discomfort with the status quo –in a way to create our
own disorienting dilemmas.
• It should be expressive, interacting actively with one’s environment and
linking experience to what has come before and to what will come next.
This relates directly to John Dewey’s principles of continuity and inter-
action as criteria for deep learning. As I have noted earlier in this book,
experience can also be a barrier to deep learning, what Dewey ([1938]
1997) called “mis-education.” The meaning-making schemes that develop
to help us make meaning of experience can also block incoming infor-
mation that is dissonant with these schemes. Dewey called this “routine
action,” and it narrows the usefulness of new experience. Dewey warned
that routine habits can possess us and prevent “intelligent action.” He
could have been foretelling the challenges of permanent white water!
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
49
3.2 Self-Development in Organizations 49
• It should include both thinking and feeling, recalling the central theme of
Chapter 2, namely that reflective cognition leading to deep learning is
always stimulated by emotion. Material that has no emotional resonance
for us is a signal that at an intuitive level we do not have a strong need
to know about the subject of that material. Unless something piques
our curiosity or knocks us off balance and creates disorientation, we are
unlikely to pay much attention to it. Vaill (1996) implies that we must
develop a consciousness about feeling: “Probably none [of the three pre-
vious qualities] are possible for us if we are not able to feel learning
happening within ourselves and honor it, respond to it, build on it”
(p. 73).
• It should occur in the moment. Vaill (1996) avers that learning in per-
manent white water requires that we “find ways for as much learning
as possible to occur on the job and in all other aspects of a learner’s
life” (p. 76). One should, in other words, cultivate Torbert’s (2004)
habits of “action inquiry.” Peter Jarvis provides some details on how to
do this in his book The Practitioner-Researcher (1999). Jarvis holds that
professionals learn by reflecting on practice and by “incorporating into
their reflection any professional updating or reading they have under-
taken” (p. 133). They use this synthesis to then develop their own theories,
which they test in the next practice situation, and so the loop repeats.
(Recall my discussion of the experiential learning model from the pre-
ceding chapter.) This process embodies Freire’s (1970)concept of praxis,
an interaction between action and reflection; Donald Schön’s (1983)
“reflection in action”; and his and Chris Argyris’ notion of “double-loop
learning” (Argyris & Schön, 1978): that is, not just solving problems but
also assessing the assumptions we make about what the problem is. I will
have more to say about each of these writers in coming chapters.
• Learning should be continual. Continual learning is more than “life-
long learning,” a term that has become a vacuous cliché. Vaill’s (1996)
provocative point is that permanent white water “makes perpetual
beginners of us all. Almost nothing we have learned is immune from
challenge and change … We do not need competency skills for this
life. We need incompetency skills, the skills of being effective beginners”
(p. 81, emphasis in original). Vaill’s point is much like Torbert’s urging
to use the “vividness of each moment” to “learn anew,” as quoted above.
Vaill suggests that leader/learners in permanent white water adopt the
persona of a “reflective beginner”: someone who is able to check his or
her ego at the door, seek the advice of others, and accept failure as a
learning opportunity.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
50
50 Mindful Learning
• And finally, reflexive learning for Vaill incorporates all of these qualities
because reflection permeates everything a leader/learner does in per-
manent white water. Vaill promotes continuous reflection on each of
the six qualities, asking honest questions about each: Are we directing
our own learning or are we depending on others? Are we absorbing the
learning of others or are we exploring new territory? Are we just “sitting
there” or are we taking in what is to be learned in the moment? Are we
ignoring our feelings as clues to what is important, or are we infusing
them into our learning? Are we isolating ourselves from learning oppor-
tunities in our immediate environment, or are we taking good advantage
of these opportunities? Do we view learning as a series of disconnected
challenges, or do we seek growth with an appropriate mixture of
challenge and support?
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
51
3.2 Self-Development in Organizations 51
I write these words I find myself getting distracted by political news
popping up on my computer. I make a note to turn these off.) The second
component of personal mastery is “continually learning how to see current
reality more clearly” (Senge, 2006, p. 129). This part, I would assert, is
much harder. Our reaction as humans to cognitive dissonance is to reduce
the dissonance with a minimum of effort, resulting in all of the varieties
of self-delusion I described in Chapter 1. Here is a common organiza-
tional example. Once upon a time, strategic planning was all the rage,
and still is in some quarters, despite mounting evidence that it does not
work very well, and in fact is often counterproductive (cf. Buller, 2015).
Strategic planning is based on three shaky –at best –assumptions: first,
that change is predictable; second, that change is linear; third, that change
occurs as a result of rational rather than political decision-making. Each
of these assumptions is demonstrably false. This does not mean that stra-
tegic planning is inherently a bad idea; the problem is that once a plan
is in place there is every incentive –if you hold one of Torbert’s conven-
tional action-logics –to stick with it and not, in Senge’s terms, make
regular assessments of the current reality and change course accordingly.
I have seen this repeated over and over again in higher education: a lot of
planning –and no change.
Those with high levels of personal mastery share several qualities,
according to Senge: they have a strong sense of purpose, they are “deeply
inquisitive” about the current reality, they feel deeply connected to others,
they “live in a continual learning mode,” and –especially reminiscent of
Vaill’s (1996) notion of the “reflective beginner” –they are acutely aware of
how much they have to learn.
Now here is where Senge’s ideas intersect with a key theme threading
throughout this book. Senge (2006) argues that juxtaposing vision (“what
we want”) with a clear picture of current reality (“where we are relative to
what we want”), results in what he calls “creative tension, a force to bring
them together, caused by the natural tendency to seek resolution.” “The
essence of personal mastery,” he notes, “is learning how to generate and
sustain creative tension in our lives” (p. 132). Why, one might ask, would
someone want to be in a constant state of creative tension on purpose?
Senge’s response, somewhat unhelpfully, is, “We want it because we want
it” (p. 135), presumably because we are operating at a post-conventional
stage of development. There is a better answer to the question of why one
would want to seek out creative tension and I will explore this apparent
paradox in the next chapter.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
52
52 Mindful Learning
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
53
3.4 Mindful Learning 53
intuitive belief, when confronted with discordant information, produces
cognitive dissonance and disquietude, and we are tempted to take the easy
course of engaging in confirmation/myside bias, which serves to make the
intuitive belief even more persistent. We are more likely to do this than
not: even those at post-conventional levels of development will find them-
selves experiencing cognitive dissonance that is distinctly aversive. If the
dissonance is powerful enough we experience a true disorienting dilemma;
resolving the dilemma depends on how we make meaning of the disorien-
tation, and this in turn depends on our level of cognitive and emotional
development. If we are perceiving the world in a manner consistent with
the “socialized mind” or “conventional action logics,” we are likely to fall
back on internalized social and cultural norms, finding safety there. If we
are perceiving the world in a manner consistent with the “self-authoring”
or “post-conventional” mindset, on the other hand, we are more likely to
follow the disorientation, treating it as “object” rather than something we
are “subject” to.
In this book I argue for a proactive approach to deep learning, one that
does not depend on having to respond to a disorienting dilemma powerful
enough to breach our usual cognitive defenses. I call it mindful learning,
borrowing from Ellen Langer’s book of the same name (Langer, 2016).
In her view, mindful learning has three characteristics: “the continuous
creation of new categories; openness to new information; and an implicit
awareness of more than one perspective” (p. 4). While my conception of
it is consistent with hers, my take is based more on East Asian philosophy,
namely that mindfulness is a state of heightened alertness, one that is con-
scious of body sensations, accepting these without judgment, and focused
more on the present moment than ruminating about the past or worrying
about the future. Buddhist teacher Bhante Gunaratana captures it well:
Mindfulness registers experiences, but it does not compare them. It does
not label them or categorize them. It just observes everything as if it [were]
occurring for the first time. It is not analysis [that is] based on reflection and
memory. It is, rather, the direct and immediate experiencing of whatever is
happening, without the medium of thought. It comes before thought in the
perceptual process. (Quoted in Davis & Thompson, 2015, p. 48)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
54
54 Mindful Learning
in the way of deep learning. One of the best illustrations of this is the nas-
cent practice of using mindfulness as addiction therapy. Judson Brewer and
his colleagues have extensively studied ways of using mindfulness training
to help those with addiction disorders (including alcohol, smoking, and
drugs) overcome their cravings. They assert that, for example, a smoker’s
craving for a cigarette is a form of “affective bias.” They write,
Affective bias underlies emotional distortions of attention and memory,
preventing individuals from accurately assessing what is happening in the
present moment and acting accordingly. Mindfulness functions to decouple
pleasant and unpleasant experience from habitual reactions of craving and
aversion, by removing the affective bias that fuels such emotional reactivity.
It is the absence of emotional distortions, we suggest, that allows mindful-
ness practitioners to “see things as they are.” (Brewer, Elwafi, & Davis, 2014,
pp. 74–75)
So, when a smoker gets a craving for a cigarette, whether that craving has
a positive affect, such as looking forward to the pleasure of a cigarette after
a meal, or a negative affect, such as stress or irritability, s/he associates
smoking with satisfying that craving: it is in essence an intuitive belief, that
the way to respond to the craving is to light up. Breaking the pathological
chain works like this:
Mindfulness training teaches individuals to instead step back and take a
moment to explore what cravings actually feel like in their bodies, however
uncomfortable or unpleasant they may be. Two important insights can be
learned from this process. First, individuals learn that cravings are phys-
ical sensations in their bodies rather than moral imperatives that must be
acted upon. Second, they gain first-hand experience with the impermanent
nature of these physical sensations. (p. 78)
Patients therefore learn to make new associations with body sensations,
so that instead of thinking, “I need a cigarette to settle my nerves,” they
think, “I’m feeling anxious; what do I do about it?”
Imagine how mindful learning can serve similar purposes for the quo-
tidian matters of everyday life, unrelated to addictive behavior. Here are
some examples:
• You read that a habit of grabbing a daily latte from a coffee shop can add
up to a cost of about $1,000 per year. You realize that getting a daily latte
is exactly what you do. Your intuitive belief has been that, in the larger
scheme of things, spending a couple of dollars on a latte is a pittance.
Still, you experience some cognitive dissonance. You could brush this
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
55
3.4 Mindful Learning 55
off as a minor annoyance, rationalizing that you could be engaging in
much more expensive indulgences than this; or you could recognize this
sensation as a signal that you might want to consider how you might
otherwise spend that $1,000 if you made your lattes at home.
• You are meeting with your primary care physician for your annual
checkup. She asks about alcohol consumption. Your answer is, “about
two drinks a day.” You experience a pang of guilt, knowing that you are
fudging a bit, given that your physician told you at your last visit about
recent research tying even moderate alcohol consumption to increased
risk of stroke for those over 50 (and you are well past that). You could
react silently with, “everyone has a small vice and this one is mine,” or
you could interpret the “guilt” emotion as something you need to pay
attention to.
• You are in a business meeting and a close associate, one with whom you
have a valued relationship, makes a comment that could be interpreted
as racist. Something about the remark is disturbing. You could interpret
it as a one-off exception and dismiss it; or you could recognize that the
disturbance you felt is telling you something, and that you may want to
speak to the colleague about it.
• You are attending a soccer game and the goal keeper on your favorite
team has successfully blocked a succession of shots on goal. You think,
wow, this guy is really on his game today –and then he fails to block the
shot that wins the match. In your disappointment you could be upset
with the goal keeper for failing to come through at a critical moment,
just when he was playing so well. Or you could stop to wonder where
your anger came from: could it be a case of expecting what is likely a
random streak of saves to continue?
• As an administrator of a small college you become embroiled in a dis-
pute with faculty members over a proposed institutional initiative. You
could fume about how “faculty are always resisting change,” or you stop
and wonder whether you are engaged in reductive thinking, that pos-
sibly more complex dynamics are at work.
All of these examples, and countless others, may or may not lead to the kind
of disorientation that could result in transformative learning. They may or
may not, in other words, rise to the level of disorienting dilemmas. Getting
them into that space requires a conscious, mindful awareness that broadens
the potential for deep learning. I explore what that potential might look
like in the next chapter.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
56
56 Mindful Learning
Notes
1 As my friend and colleague Ron Cacciope reminded me, the phrase “know thy
self ” comes from the inscription on the temple at Delphi, the spiritual retreat
outside of Athens.
2 More recent research suggests that these numbers may be higher than Maslow
thought, depending on the cultural context. See Chapter 9.
3 See for example Seligman’s book, Learned Optimism (1991).
4 This is the problem I have with “andragogy” as espoused by Knowles (1984) and
others, that adults are “self-directed learners”: sometimes they are and some-
times they aren’t, depending on both the learning context and their own devel-
opmental stages.
5 Thanks to my friend and colleague Richard McGuigan, who pointed out that
“institutional learning” assumptions are not reflective of current approaches to
adult education. Vaill was referring to typical curricula in professional schools,
and professional development programs in organizations.
6 The reader may notice an apparent contradiction with a previous note about
“andragogy.” While it’s a mistake to assume that all learning in adults should be
self-directed, developing oneself to be self-authoring and thus self-directing is a
requirement for deep learning.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:21:29, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.003
57
Ch apter 4
Constructive Disorientation
57
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
58
58 Constructive Disorientation
When you raise a difficult issue or surface a deep value conflict, you take
people out of their comfort zone and raise a lot of heat … Your goal [as a
leader] should be to keep the temperature within what we call the productive
zone of disequilibrium (PZD): enough heat generated by your intervention
to gain attention, engagement, and forward motion, but not so much that
the organization (or your part of it) explodes. (Heifetz et al., 2009, p. 29,
emphasis in original)
I will have more to say about adaptive learning and its relationship to deep
learning later on; for now, I will make this distinction between PZD and
constructive disorientation: the former refers to the management of system
disruption, the latter to individual experience. Trying to create a pro-
ductive zone of disequilibrium in an organization will fail if individuals in
that organization do not themselves experience constructive disorientation.
A third term similar to constructive disorientation is the “zone of prox-
imal development,” coined by developmental psychologist Lev Vygotsky
in the 1930s (Vygotsky, 1978). Something of a pariah in his country’s edu-
cational establishment because of his progressive views, Vygotsky argued
that the most effective means of educating children is not to load them
up with information but rather to identify the difference between what
they are able to learn on their own and what they are able to learn with
adult help, and then create the appropriate pedagogical structure or
“scaffolding.” Like Dewey, Vygotsky maintained that deep learning is a
function of experience and supportive interaction with one’s social envir-
onment. While Vygotsky’s focus was on young children, we can readily
apply his thinking to adult learning: individuals need an appropriate mix
of challenge and support if they are to learn effectively.
Enter flow theory, one of the most important concepts in human motiv-
ation and learning to emerge in the past few decades, developed through the
research of Mihaly Csikszentmihalyi (pronounced, roughly, “chick-sent-
me-high-ee”) (1990). Based on a fascinating series of studies of intrinsic
motivation, Csikszentmihalyi discovered an optimal state of being, which
he called flow. A person in a state of flow is completely focused on the task
at hand, enjoys a sense of competence and control, and often loses track of
time. Csikszentmihalyi discovered that flow experiences have eight essen-
tial components: a succession of clear goals, immediate feedback to one’s
actions, an alignment between challenges and skills, a merger of action
and awareness, intense concentration and a focus on the here and now,
loss of self-consciousness and fear of failure, a sense only of a “continuous
present,” and activity that becomes “autotelic,” that is, doing something
that becomes an end in itself. Csikszentmihalyi also discovered something
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
59
Constructive Disorientation 59
counterintuitive: that even those doing work many would consider to be
repetitive and boring, such as working on a factory assembly line, would
report experiencing flow in their jobs. They would approach their work as
a process of discovery, finding new ways to fine-tune their skills and con-
tribute to the larger whole. In short, it turns out that it is not what people
do that counts, but how they do it.
Csikszentmihalyi (1997) hypothesizes that the drive to discover and
create is a product of our evolution as humans. We have evolved not only
to learn from the past but also to prepare ourselves to deal with unpre-
dictable change. This impulse, however, exists in tension with what
Csikszentmihalyi calls the “effort imperative,” the need to wind down and
conserve our energy to face the unexpected. Too much of a focus on dis-
covery leads to exhaustion; too much focus on conserving efforts leads to
listlessness and entropy.
Most of us have experienced flow: we are working on a project and
everything seems to click; we are playing tennis and at the top of our
game, seemingly able to anticipate where the next shot is going; we are so
engrossed in a book that we suddenly realize that we have been up half the
night. Not surprisingly, we are most able to learn deeply when in a state
of flow. The obvious question then becomes, what can we do to make the
experience of flow more likely? The answer, according to Csikszentmihalyi,
is to imagine flow as a state of balance between the challenge of a task, on
one hand, and a sense of competence, on the other. Flow results when an
optimal balance exists between the two, when the challenge is just beyond
the reach of a person’s competence, but close enough to grasp with effort.
Flow is also a developmental state: A novice piano student might experi-
ence flow by being able to play a “C” scale perfectly for the first time; but
maintaining flow requires another and slightly and increasingly more dif-
ficult challenge. (Note the similarity here to Vygotsky’s zone of proximal
development.)
Flow is difficult to maintain, and so we spend most of our days in less
optimal states. We find either that the tasks we are performing lack appro-
priate challenge, resulting in boredom, or that the challenge is perceived
to be too great, resulting in anxiety, or at worst, the impulse to escape the
situation altogether. Being in flow, however, is not “good” in an absolute
sense. Imagine how annoying it would be to be around someone who
was “in flow” all of the time: this person would be completely and con-
tinuously self-centered, focused on fulfilling current goals, oblivious to
the need for new learning. Csikszentmihalyi (1990) himself recognizes the
danger of flow’s “addictive potential” (p. 62). A self-centered self cannot
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
60
60 Constructive Disorientation
become more complex, and thus a slide back into a “normal” state of con-
sciousness is necessary in order to allow for other constructive disorienta-
tion opportunities.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
61
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
62
62 Constructive Disorientation
solving, adaptability, and learning” (p. 293). These complex systems are
kept healthy by fostering interaction and interdependency, while also
injecting tension sufficient to keep the energy going. As counterintuitive
as it may seem, without what Lynn Davies (2015) calls “educative turbu-
lence,” organizations and other complex systems will die. Turbulence,
therefore, is a productive force. To evolve and thrive, she writes, “a system
has to experience turbulence, to get to the edge of chaos, before settling
into a new fitness landscape. Simple perturbations can nudge a system
into creative activity” (p. 451). Note Davies’ choice of words here: simple
and nudge, not overwhelming and force. As would be predicted by flow
theory, turbulence is most likely to be a force for positive change when
it is perceived as requiring a series of incremental moves from the status
quo, in an atmosphere that values experimentation and learning. Sources
of healthy turbulence can come from both internal and external sources.
External sources would include information about the organizational
environment and how it is changing. Internal sources would emerge from
a culture that creates a welcoming environment for diversity of ideas,
honest dialogue and conflictual conversation, leading to what Young calls
“enlarged thought”:
If dialogue succeeds primarily when it appeals to what the participants
already share, then none need revise their opinions or viewpoints in any ser-
ious way in order to take account of other interests, opinions or perspectives.
Beyond this, even if we understand that we need others to see what we all
share, it can easily happen that we each find in the other only a mirror for
ourselves. (Young, 2000, quoted in Davies, 2015, p. 453)
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
63
4.1.2.1 Autonomy
Situations leading to the potential for adaptive learning will go nowhere
without both individuals and groups experiencing autonomy. Autonomy,
the first of three necessary elements in self-determination theory (Ryan &
Deci, 2017), is having the sense that what we do, we do voluntarily, under
our own volition, and not under external control. Without autonomy,
individuals feel powerless to do anything about what is happening to them,
a mere cog in a wheel, reminiscent of Charlie Chaplin’s hapless character
on the assembly line in Modern Times. In their book on self-determination
theory, Ryan and Deci (2017) describe an autonomy-control continuum.
At the pure autonomy end, individual volition is total, behavior emanates
from one’s sense of self, and motivation is purely intrinsic, a situation rem-
iniscent of flow. At the other end is pure control, wherein the individual
is forced to act in a manner incongruent with self, and so the motivation
is purely extrinsic. A great deal of research over the years has extolled the
virtues of intrinsic motivation as a means to personal development and well-
being. In self-determination theory the matter is more complex: extrinsic
motivators can, over time, become internalized and integrated with one’s
own sense of self, and thus become intrinsic. Religious beliefs, for example,
begin as extrinsic values taught by parents and/or the larger society, but
over time can become so integrated into one’s belief system that the motiv-
ation for their expression becomes intrinsic. (Consider the satisfaction
experienced by religious missionaries as they deliver the Word around the
world.) Thus, in self-determination theory, optimal motivation is “autono-
mous motivation,” a combination of one’s intrinsic motivation, driven by
innate curiosity about the world, and well-integrated extrinsic motivation.
Autonomy, Ryan and Deci (2017) note, adds an important variable to
flow theory. Flow is not just the optimal balance of challenge and compe-
tence: one could be presented with a situation having exactly this balance
and still not be motivated to act. I might be invited to play a video game,
something I am perfectly capable of doing, and still not be motivated to
participate. I need to feel curious, and that I am playing of my own vol-
ition, not because of social expectation.
In my research on motivation in university faculty (Wergin, 2001),
I found professional autonomy –the freedom to experiment, to follow
one’s own leads wherever they may go, and to do so without fear of the
consequences –to be the single strongest predictor of faculty productivity.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
64
64 Constructive Disorientation
I also found, however, that when the value placed on autonomy is taken
to an extreme, it becomes more a matter of personal privilege rather than
social obligation. When John Dewey (1981) defined freedom as “the power
to grow,” he did not include the power to be accountable only to one-
self. In any professional context, therefore, the responsible expression of
autonomy is the freedom to contribute to the common good.
4.1.2.2 Efficacy
Efficacy is universally regarded as a core element in motivation. The term is
closely related to competence, one of the two key elements leading to flow,
and the second of three key elements in self-determination theory, where
competence is defined as “our basic need to feel effectance [sic] and mas-
tery. People need to feel able to operate effectively within their important
life contexts” (Ryan & Deci, 2017, p. 11). Those who have a sense of effi-
cacy, in addition, not only feel that they are able to operate effectively,
they also feel that they are having a significant effect on their environment
(Bandura, 1977). In other words, while competence refers to confidence
in the doing, efficacy refers to a sense of confidence in the effect of the
doing, and is therefore more powerful. Competence is necessary for effi-
cacy, but not vice versa. In my research on university faculty, efficacy was
another key motivational driver. Even faculty members with long lists of
publications did not always feel efficacious: there also had to be the satis-
faction of believing that they were having an impact on their disciplines.
In an organizational context, efficacy is what gives our work meaning; it
is a feeling that what we do matters. Efficacy is the difference between
coming home from work and asking yourself, “just what did I accomplish
today?” and knowing that something you did that day made a difference
for the better. Just as volitional action is necessary for deep learning, so is
the feeling that such action will have a tangible result.
4.1.2.3 Relatedness
The third key element in self-determination theory, relatedness means feeling
socially connected and cared for by others. But in addition, “relatedness is
also about belonging and feeling significant among others … [thus] experi-
encing oneself as giving or contributing to others. Relatedness pertains,
moreover, to a sense of being integral to social organizations beyond one-
self ” (Ryan & Deci, 2017, p. 11). This last point is critical, as it ties related-
ness with efficacy. One feels not only cared for but also impactful. More
than 30 years ago, researcher Barry Staw (1983) identified two key factors
that lead to what he called “organizational motivation.” He suggested that
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
65
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
66
66 Constructive Disorientation
provide limited advice on how to stimulate these conditions. And third,
neither has situated his concept in learning theory or informed it with
existing empirical evidence. In the remainder of this chapter I will address
these limitations with suggestions that are grounded in motivation theory
and backed up by empirical research –not just from a few isolated studies
but from a convergence of findings that cut across cultures and organiza-
tional settings.
In order to achieve a state of constructive disorientation one must be
confronted with an experience that creates cognitive dissonance, perceived
as a slight imbalance of challenge over support (Csikszentmihalyi, 1990),
leading to a “creative tension” (Senge, 2006), a “productive zone of dis-
equilibrium” (Heifetz et al., 2009), or “zone of proximal development”
(Vygotsky, 1978) fueled by autonomous motivation (Ryan & Deci, 2017)
and one’s belief that the effort will be efficacious (Bandura, 1977). This is
about as close as it gets to theoretical and empirical consensus. We should
be able to recognize constructive disorientation in ourselves. But how do
we promote it in others? The evidence points to four key enablers:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
67
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
68
68 Constructive Disorientation
all. The team must perceive an organizational climate supportive of team
control over its learning and problem solving.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
69
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
70
70 Constructive Disorientation
Instead, strategic planning can be helpful if and only if it is undertaken as
an organic process within a larger strategic vision, encouraging a culture
of reasonable risk-taking and staying alert to serendipitous opportunities.
4.3 Conclusion
In this chapter I have made the case for constructive disorientation as a con-
dition necessary for deep learning. Learning that does not stem from dis-
orientation deepens one’s knowledge perspectives and increases technical
competence, and I do not mean to make light of this kind of learning: it is
not the same as what I have referred to dismissively as “drive-by learning”
or, in Newport’s (2016) terms, “shallow learning.” Just as being in a con-
stant state of flow is not an altogether good thing, neither is it possible or
desirable to be in a constant state of deep learning. Learning what, how,
and when (Aristotle’s episteme, techne, and phronesis) must of course occur;
otherwise constructive disorientation would never lead to anything con-
structive. My point, made repeatedly in this book, is that the increasingly
complex nature of the challenges we face as a society requires going beyond
technical rationality to engage in deep learning. And for this we must rec-
ognize and create opportunities for constructive disorientation, a perceived
disconnect between where we are and where we need to be, accompanied
by a sense that we are capable of dealing with that disconnect.
In order for disorientation to be constructive it must have four essential
qualities.
First, the situation must be one that makes this disconnect clear, one
that requires adaptive learning (Heifetz, 1994). Whether it relates to an
individual or a group, there must be a perception of a gap between what
is valued and the reality that what is valued is not being realized in the
current environment. This is exactly what Mezirow (1990) meant when
he conceived of a “disorienting dilemma” as the key to transformative
learning. The disorientation must be strong enough to encourage sus-
pension of assumptions and beliefs and the willingness to entertain fresh
perspectives, but not so strong that a response to the preexisting order is
triggered, as well as various immunities to change (Kegan & Lahey, 2009),
all of which relate to fear of loss.
Second, the situation must be conducive to autonomous motivation, an
amalgam of intrinsic motivation and extrinsic motivators that have become
internalized and integrated. Being aware of an adaptive challenge is not
sufficient for constructive disorientation and, eventually, deep learning.
As important as flow theory (Csikszentmihalyi, 1990) has been to our
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
71
4.3 Conclusion 71
understanding of intrinsic motivation, one is not necessarily motivated to
engage in learning when faced with an optimal balance of challenge and
support: the learning must have a volitional quality, driven by curiosity, an
innate human need to explore.
Third, the situation must empower a sense of efficacy, a feeling that not
only is one competent to engage in a learning task but also that the effort
will have a tangible result of value to the learner.
And fourth, the disorientation must occur in an environment where
one feels socially connected, cared for by others, and confident that they
are contributing to their social or organizational environment in healthy
and valued ways.
Promoting constructive disorientation in others also has four necessary
and distinctive features.
First is a clear but manageable challenge, the essence of constructive dis-
orientation. One must experience a sense of disquietude, accompanied by
the belief that one has both the competence and social support needed to
meet the challenge. The key to maintaining this balance is not to attempt
to reduce the disorientation through increasing competence, but rather
to manage the inevitable anxiety. Anything beyond a moderate anxiety
inhibits motivation to learn.
Second, building upon the previous point, individuals –and groups –
must be able to increase or decrease the level of challenge so as to match
skills with requirements for action. These learning strategies use models
embedded in problem-based learning and action learning: small groups
define the presenting problem, identify learning needs, set learning goals
and strategies, meet together regularly to share and reflect on what has
been learned, seek feedback, discuss how the problem should be redefined,
and continue the process, all under the guidance of a facilitator who keeps
the process going and the disorientation at a constructive level.
Third, the learning should be in an environment free from distractions,
one conducive to “deep work” (Newport, 2016) and “thinking slow”
(Kahneman, 2011).
Fourth and finally, consistent with flow theory (Csikszentmihalyi, 1990),
the learning activity should have clear criteria for performance, concrete
feedback, and freedom to fail. The first two of these criteria are commonly
understood; the third is not. The trend toward holding individuals and
groups accountable for measurable results, and the ubiquity of strategic
planning in organizations, left unchecked, stifles creativity, ignores seren-
dipitous opportunities, and leads to the displacement of valued goals by
quantitative benchmarks. In order for constructive disorientation to occur
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
72
72 Constructive Disorientation
the organizational culture must support experimentation and reasonable
risk-taking.
Constructive disorientation must go somewhere: one must know how
to follow it and what to do. In the next chapter I turn to the third key to
deep learning, critical reflection on experience.
Notes
1 The deleterious effects of anxiety on learning are well documented (cf.
Sogunro, 1998).
2 A humorous if unsettling diversion about such pains is Edward Gorey’s The
Unstrung Harp: Or Mr. Earbrass writes a novel (1999). Thanks to Norman Dale
for the reference.
3 See Chapter 7 for a full elaboration of this point.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:24:50, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.004
73
Ch apter 5
Critical Reflection
In searching for the truth, it may be our best plan to start by criti-
cizing our most cherished beliefs.
Karl Popper
In this chapter I explore the importance of critical reflection to deep
learning. Knowing oneself and facilitating constructive disorientation are
both necessary but insufficient conditions. Who would want to be in an
organization full of people who spend their days as learning dilettantes,
flitting from one moment of intellectual curiosity to the next, without ever
pausing to do the deep work of challenging existing ways of thinking and
potentially integrating new insights? As Kahneman and Renshon (2007)
pointed out, even in a healthy state of disorientation we scramble to find
a connection with existing perspectives, and because “System 2” thinking
makes our brains work harder, we have to make a conscious and deliberate
effort to resist defaulting to System 1 thinking. Thus, the necessity for crit-
ical reflection. In Chapter 2, I wrote about the importance of reflection
on experience as a way to develop phronesis, or the ability to know when
to rely on intuition (System 1) and when to make the effort to dig more
deeply (System 2). Deep learning, therefore, depends on how humans
make meaning of experience –on whether or not that experience will
become, in John Dewey’s ([1938] 1997) terms, “educative.”
Reflection, a “turning back on experience,” can take many forms: “Simple
awareness of an object, event or state, including awareness of a perception
thought, feeling, disposition, intention, action, or of one’s habits of doing
these things. It can also mean letting one’s thoughts wander over some-
thing, taking something into consideration, or imagining alternatives.
One can reflect on oneself reflecting” (Mezirow, 1998, p. 185)
John Dewey ([1938] 1997) was one of the first to affirm the import-
ance of reflection on experience in human learning, separating “intelligent
73
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
74
74 Critical Reflection
action” from “routine action.” For Dewey, “true” reflection meets four cri-
teria (Rodgers, 2002):
First, reflection is a meaning-making process that moves a learner from
one experience to the next with deeper understandings of its relationships
with and connections to other experiences and ideas. Recall from Chapter 3
that for Dewey, experience is more than just participating in events; it is
active interaction with one’s environment in a sort of dialectic that results in
change on both sides. As I have argued throughout this book, while experi-
ence is the basis of learning, it can also be a barrier to learning: the schemes
that help us make meaning of experience can also serve to block incoming
information that is dissonant with those schemes. Reflection is the thread
that makes continuity of learning possible, ensuring the progress of the
individual and, ultimately, society. It is a means to socially desirable ends.
Second, reflection for Dewey is a systematic, rigorous, disciplined way
of thinking, with its roots in scientific inquiry. Reflection on experience is
not “spontaneous interpretation” (Dewey, [1938] 1997), which leads one
to interpret experience based on existing schema and then to act accord-
ingly (Kahneman’s System 1 [2011]). Instead, two other elements are neces-
sary: a sense of disequilibrium causing a need for resolution, and a sense
of curiosity, both of which are essential to constructive disorientation.
Dewey’s suggested process for inquiring into experience looks a bit linear
and overly rational today, as he based his approach on the traditional scien-
tific method: that is, identifying the problems that arise from experience,
generating possible explanations for the problem(s), converting these into
hypotheses, and testing the hypotheses using objective scientific methods.
Dewey did not assume that the results of inquiry would settle the matter,
but rather would lead to “intelligent action,” which in turn would lead to
further reflection.
Third, reflection needs to happen in community, in interaction with
others, a point I have made throughout this book and explore in greater
depth in Chapter 6.
Fourth, and finally, reflection requires attitudes that value the personal
and intellectual growth of oneself and others, a value Dewey considered
critical for a democratic society. Reflection that is truly useful should be
determined by public inspection and criticism, and should be used as a
means to essentially moral ends.
Dewey largely ignored the power of emotion in learning (except when
writing about the arts) and the pernicious effects of cognitive bias. He also
downplayed the role of politics in learning. Dewey’s thinking is criticized
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
75
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
76
76 Critical Reflection
unintentional, idiosyncratic or culturally assimilated. These meaning
schemes, consisting of clusters of beliefs and values, all have emotional
origins and therefore can be extremely resistant to change, making true
critical reflection hard and even painful.
Mezirow (2000) maintained that critical reflection is the most important
element in transformative learning, and there is some empirical evidence
to back this up (cf. Brock, 2010).
For all that has been written about critical reflection and its importance
to deep learning, writers on the topic are relatively silent about how pre-
cisely the process is supposed to work. Some help comes from philosopher
Jürgen Habermas (1984), who proposed that critical reflection must begin
by gaining distance from the present, what he termed “distantiation.” Put
plainly, one must make a conscious choice to step back from the moment
in order to, appropriating Ron Heifetz’ metaphor (Heifetz et al., 2009) get
“off the dance floor” and onto “the balcony” to understand the system of
swirling dancers below. Ironically, perhaps, one must be mindful of that
moment in order to know when to do this. We must learn to listen to
our body’s signals and to discern what to notice, to develop the habit of
“mindful learning” discussed in Chapter 3, an implicit awareness of and
openness to new perspectives. This is what Mezirow (2000) refers to as
developing a more “dependable” meaning perspective, one that “is more
inclusive, differentiating, permeable (open to other viewpoints), critically
reflective of assumptions, emotionally capable of change, and integrative
of experience” (p. 19).
Thus, the first step is developing mindfulness of the sort discussed in
Chapter 3: cultivating a habit of mind that recognizes and then responds
to the signals that distantiation might be in order. These signals might
not be initially disorienting. In contrast to what Mezirow implies, deep
learning is not just a reaction to felt disorientation, but a practiced habit
that can also produce disorientation. Consider the simple example above
about staff development programs. Certainly, the easier form of reflection
would be to look to participant feedback and to reflect on that feedback as
guidance for program improvement –an example of single-loop learning.
A more critically reflective posture would be to go deeper, looking for
more subtle clues. Consider the following responses to a typical end-
of-workshop survey, asking what kept the experience from being more
useful:
The case studies handed out didn’t reflect what really goes on in my
organization.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
77
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
78
78 Critical Reflection
Here is the essence of the difficulty. Letting go of a cherished belief
results in a sense of loss of agency and efficacy and a feeling of regret, all
of which can lead to lowered motivation to learn, increased cynicism, and
even a dystopian view of human existence. Small wonder that cognitive
biases, when challenged by others, become stronger; that conspiracy the-
ories are so hard to dislodge; that superstitions are so hard to overcome!
The way through the stress of critical reflection lies in having an alternative
set of beliefs to turn to, what Mezirow (1998) calls “assimilative learning.”
Back in Chapter 1, I wrote about how difficult it was –and to some extent
still is –for me to let go of the assumption that minds are changed by logic
and evidence. I could not have coped with the new (for me) knowledge
that empirical evidence does not ipso facto change people’s minds without
having an alternative available in the form of a set of new beliefs about
how minds can in fact be changed –namely through the positive power
of emotion, personal agency, curiosity, and social norms, all of which
I explore later in this chapter and those following.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
79
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
80
80 Critical Reflection
that make it more difficult for people of color to vote. He schedules a
“mission retreat” with senior staff and board members. He wants to use
this time to create a sense of constructive disorientation in the group. He
knows that the organization faces an adaptive challenge and thinks that
he can make the case for it by inviting participants to critically examine
the organization’s existential purpose. But what then? he wonders. What
if I present an alternative vision and the group doesn’t go for it? He
realizes that he needs more than the clichéd “buy-in.” He needs for the
group to engage in the kind of critical reflection that reflects a genuine
commitment to reframing how the organization sees itself. He needs to
ensure that participants have real voice, that they do not feel co-opted by
the president’s agenda. He needs to ensure the growth of social capital, the
conscious experience of shared values and purposes. And finally, he must
be able to communicate that the group’s deliberations will lead to positive
change. Using the terms of this book, the president will first stimulate dis-
orientation with the message that chapter membership is drying up, as are
financial contributions. He will then work to cultivate a spirit of adaptive
learning, respect participants’ autonomy, build upon the group’s relatedness,
and ensure a collective sense of efficacy about the impact of the retreat on
work going forward.
None of the above is possible without authentic critical reflection, which
is not just going through the motions as a cognitive exercise, but giving
the process emotional energy as well. To underscore a point from the pre-
vious chapter: forces for stability can be extremely difficult to overcome.
My Antioch colleague Donna Ladkin (2015) has written about what she
calls “organizational mindlessness,” the tendency to rely on old categories,
act on “autopilot,” and minimize attention to new information. The key
to overcoming organizational mindlessness lies, I think, in Lynn Davies’
(2015) notion of “educative turbulence”: gently “nudging” a system into
creative activity.
Here is the end of the above scenario: the retreat did not accomplish
what the president had hoped. Participation by board members, while not
overtly resistant, was at best desultory. They simply had no energy to do
the hard work of real change. In retrospect, the president acknowledged
that the disorientation was not enough for the group to experience an
adaptive challenge. He also realized that he needed to do two things before
scheduling another retreat: first, to repopulate the board with people
having fresh ideas and a greater willingness to challenge orthodoxy; and
second, to identify points of energy for change in the organization, those
people and groups in favor of building a new order, and to encourage
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
81
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
82
82 Critical Reflection
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
83
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
84
84 Critical Reflection
on practice in both novice and experienced practitioners. They write: “It
appears that experience alone does not generate the emergence of
reflection-in-action. Rather, how one uses experience may be the more
crucial element to understanding why some individuals use reflection to
grow in their professional learning” (p. 111). Thus, reflection on practice
as a habit of mind seems to depend more on one’s propensity to reflect
(Roessger, 2014).
If true, then the development of mindful learning becomes all the more
important. At the highest level of expertise development, “know-how”
becomes mindful. Part of that mindfulness is raising consciousness about
what has become tacit. As I pointed out earlier, much intuitive learning
is helpful, even essential, to our understanding of the world. But some is
not. Intuitive theories, left unexamined, can lead to a host of cognitive
traps, persisting beliefs, and immunity to change. Mindful learning works
to deliberately create constructive disorientation and to follow it. The dis-
orientation does not have to be experienced as a jolt, as a “whoa!” moment,
a disorienting dilemma. It can be an almost indistinguishable signal that
something warrants our attention. One of the simplest and most powerful
definitions of consciousness was offered by neuroscientist Antonio Damasio
(1999), calling it “an organism’s awareness of its own self and surroundings”
(p. 4). In the context of deep learning, mindful learning is a particular
form of consciousness, the awareness that in any given moment our “self ”
has something useful and important to learn, especially when that some-
thing might conflict with our current notions of how things are.
To summarize, deep learning is wholly dependent on critical reflec-
tion, whether that learning results in transforming one’s mental models,
or deepening one’s expertise through instrumental learning. At the highest
levels of expertise, learning becomes transformative as well.
Here, then, are the first core components of what I am calling the “deep
learning mindset” (Figure 5.2), with more to be added to blank spaces in
later chapters.
So far, we have seen that constructive disorientation can stem from
two sources: one might experience a disorienting dilemma –an external
stimulus –or routine mindfulness that stays alert for signals requiring con-
scious attention. Both external and internal sources of constructive dis-
orientation engage critical reflection. Sometimes critical reflection will
lead directly to transformation of meaning schemes; sometimes it will
lead to instrumental learning in the form of expertise development. At the
highest levels of expertise the learning becomes transformative, as one’s key
assumptions about what to do and when to do it are constantly in play.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
85
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
86
86 Critical Reflection
counteract the direction of the fall. But you would be wrong. You would
never do this in practice, knowing in the moment that doing so would only
accelerate the spill. You would know instinctively to turn the front wheel
to the left. This is an example of embodied knowing, or simply, learning
through the body. All of our early learning as humans is embodied: babies
learn through sensations, toddlers by exploring through touch (Lawrence,
2012). Embodied knowledge precedes overt consciousness: a sensation
leads to a constructed emotion, which leads in turn to one being conscious
of, for example, fear. Embodied learning is what Aristotle referred to as the
second of his three kinds of knowing, namely techne, or “know-how,” and
is the essence of reflection on experience.
Intuitive learning is often referred to as “incidental learning.” As adult
educator Victoria Marsick has noted, “When people learn incidentally,
their learning may be taken for granted, tacit, or unconscious. However, a
passing insight can then be probed and intentionally explored. Examples are
the hidden agenda of an organization’s culture or a teacher’s class, learning
from mistakes, or the unsystematic process of trial and error” (Marsick
& Watkins, 2001, p. 26, emphasis added). Note the allusion to intuitive
learning as an opportunity for critical reflection. The power of intuitive
or incidental learning is hard to overstate. Research on continuing pro-
fessional education programs has demonstrated that while people may
be motivated to attend a conference or workshop to learn things from
expert presenters, the more powerful learning moments occur in “hallway
conversations” with colleagues, where participants compare notes, in an
unplanned way, on how recommended practices might work –or not –in
their own professional settings.
Back in the 1980s I directed a project sponsored by the American College
of Cardiology where we investigated the degree to which attendance at its
“Heart House” programs changed practice behavior. We found evidence of
this “hallway conversation” phenomenon: when asked how, if at all, their
practice had changed, and what most affected this change, cardiologists
pointed to these very encounters (Wergin, Mazmanian, Miller, Papp., &
Williams, 1988). (Reported changes in practice were backed up by random
audits of patient charts.) Note how closely this finding parallels the research
on transformative learning: knowledge perspectives are transformed only
when new ideas are tried on in the presence of others.
The fact that learning grows out of spontaneous everyday encounters
vastly more often than in formal educational settings has enormous
implications for deep learning. Because intuitive learning is largely uncon-
scious, unless it is deliberately surfaced and inspected it is subject to all of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
87
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:23:47, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.005
88
Ch apter 6
Great minds discuss ideas; average minds discuss events; small minds
discuss people.
Eleanor Roosevelt
• John Dewey wrote that all learning is a function of both continuity and
interaction with one’s environment. While human nature grows from
within it must be completed through relationships.
• Transformative learning theory holds that transformation is most likely
to occur, and is most powerful, when disorientation is followed by dia-
logue with one or more other people.
• Disorientation not in the presence of others can make existing beliefs
even more powerful and resistant to change.
• One’s identity (or concept of “self ”) is a major factor in motivation to
learn and is always socially negotiated.
• Deep relationships are an important, even necessary part of
self-actualization.
• “Relatedness,” the feeling of connection with significant others in one’s
life, is one of the three pillars of self-determination theory.
• Development occurs as a function of periodically renegotiating the
interaction between connection and independence.
• Relational affirmation is a key pathway to one’s “best self.”
• Adaptive learning in organizations requires a communal
understanding of the adaptive challenge and how that challenge will be
addressed.
88
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
89
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
90
• Empathy: not only the ability to put oneself in another’s shoes but also
to understand the social context behind the other’s beliefs.
• Social capital: social ties among individuals and the trust that arises from
these ties.
• Participatory forms of engagement and learning.
• Minimal power differentials and shared responsibility.
6.1 Empathy
Empathy is quite simply the vicarious experience of someone else’s experi-
ence, both cognitively and emotionally. One can be empathic without
necessarily endorsing another person’s point of view, or even caring about
how that person feels. Empathy is not compassion, sympathy for another
person’s loss, for example. It is no comfort to someone who has lost a
child to be told by someone who has not, “I know how you must feel.”
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
91
6.1 Empathy 91
Empathy is also not the same as identification with someone else, as psych-
ologist Carl Rogers noted: “The state of empathy, or being empathic, is to
perceive the internal frame of another with accuracy and with the emo-
tional components and meanings which pertain thereto as if one were the
person but without ever losing the ‘as if ’ condition” (Rogers, 1959, quoted
in Jarvis, 2012, p. 744). When presented with someone having a worldview
significantly different from our own, our intuitive response is to generate
reasons why the other’s point of view is wrong. Empathizing with diffe-
rence creates disorientation, and it can take a real effort to make that dis-
orientation constructive. One of the best examples of this was when Anwar
Sadat, as part of his historic visit to Israel in 1977, visited Yad Vashem, the
Holocaust museum. His visit had a profound effect on all concerned, a
show of empathy to the highest degree (Koven, 1977).1 But given the pol-
itical polarization that exists in most of the world today, the challenges to
empathy are strong and, unfortunately, getting stronger.
The picture however might not be quite so bleak. In an informative
TED talk, social psychologist Robb Willer (2016) describes an experi-
ment in which he and his colleagues asked a group of people to read one
of three essays on the environment, the first a standard plea for envir-
onmental protection espousing predominately liberal values (e.g., “It is
essential that we take steps now to prevent further destruction from being
done to our Earth”), one that tapped into mostly conservative values such
as the importance of purity (e.g., “Reducing pollution can help us pre-
serve what is pure and beautiful about the places we live”), and one on
a neutral topic. When surveyed later for their environmental attitudes,
those who had identified as “liberal” were strongly pro-environment no
matter which essay they read. But those who identified as “conservative”
were more likely to endorse pro-environmental policies if they had read
the essay focusing on conservative values. The lesson, according to Willer,
is that if we intend to persuade another to adopt our point of view, we
need first to understand the other person’s moral values and frame our
message accordingly. “Empathy and respect,” he emphasized, “empathy
and respect” (minute 91).
The path to helping someone else learn deeply, in other words, is to find
that space where constructive disorientation might exist, a place where one
might be able to entertain an initially disorienting idea without forcing
oneself or others to compromise deeply held beliefs and moral values (at
least initially). Empathy is the medium for finding that space.
Thus, developing empathy has more than just pragmatic value; it also
leads to deep learning itself. Developing one’s sense of self requires an
understanding of others’ perspectives and trying these perspectives on
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
92
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
93
6.1 Empathy 93
human. Thus, when a politician associates migrants with “murderers and
rapists,” an entire class of people becomes dehumanized. From there it is
not much of a stretch to see how these psychological mechanisms can lead
to “ethnic cleansing” and other atrocities against humanity.
Thankfully, studies of children, adolescents, families, college students,
teachers, counselors, and offenders, among others, indicate that not only
is empathy a function of social learning, it can also be taught (cf. Bayne &
Jangha, 2016; Daly & Suggs, 2010; Giordano, Stare, & Clarke, 2015;
Pederson, 2010; Roseman, Ritchie, & Laux, 2009; Swick, 2005; Thompson &
Gullone, 2003; Wilson, 2011). The evidence suggests that empathy condu-
cive to deep learning can be facilitated by:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
94
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
95
6.2 Social Capital 95
of course negotiating agreement from initial disagreement happens all the
time. And here Mercier and Sperber posit something that on the surface
seems counterintuitive: that these self-serving reasoning processes have
evolved for specific social purposes. They write:
People are biased to find reasons that support their point of view because
this is how they can justify their actions and convince others to share their
beliefs. You cannot justify yourself by presenting reasons that undermine
your justification. You cannot convince others to change their minds by
giving them arguments for the view you want them to abandon or against
the view you want them to adopt. (p. 331)
This is where social capital comes in: learning in groups is most benefi-
cial when group members have different ideas but a common goal. Under
these conditions the more that group members trust each other, that is,
have developed social capital, the more likely it is that they will share their
interests, lower their emotional defenses, engage in honest debate, and
learn from one another.3 In contrast, the lack of conflicting ideas in a group
can lead to kind of social capital that polarizes attitudes (Haidt, 2012), and
the absence of a common goal can exacerbate individual differences.
Therefore, social capital that leads to deep learning is facilitated when
groups:
• Have a “common bond or sense of a shared fate” (Haidt, 2012, p. 105).
I have borrowed this expression from Jonathan Haidt because it is par-
ticularly apt in this context. Having a communal sense of purpose is
what leads to a common learning goal. Under these conditions group
members are more likely to leave their egos at the door and find com-
munity (or relatedness, in self-determination theory terms) (Ryan &
Deci, 2017). As Mercier and Sperber (2017) put it, “To the extent that
members of a group share their interests, they can trust one another, and
people who trust one another have a very reduced use or no use at all for
justifications and arguments … Group discussion is typically beneficial
when participants have different ideas and a common goal” (p. 334).
• Have ideological and intellectual diversity. Note the qualifiers “ideological
and intellectual”: greater diversity of any kind does not necessarily lead
to greater social capital. The opposite, in fact, can be true. Sociologist
Robert Putnam (2007), of Bowling Alone fame (2000), has presented
some distressing data collected from communities large and small, all
over the world, demonstrating an inverse relationship between the
ethnic diversity of a community and the level of its social capital: that
is, the greater the diversity, the lower the level of trust. What makes his
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
96
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
97
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
98
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
99
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
100
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
101
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
102
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
103
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
104
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
105
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
106
6.5 Summary
In this chapter I have tried to make the case for the critical importance
of social interaction to deep learning. While acknowledging the dangers
of social and professional groups as potential barriers to deep learning,
stemming from the lack of diversity in the group, “groupthink,” and
failure to acknowledge hegemonic differences, I also presented four
ways in which deep learning can be facilitated: by promoting empathy,
developing social capital, encouraging participatory forms of engage-
ment, and minimizing (or directly confronting) differentials of power.
I have focused on social learning in smaller, bounded groups. But what
about the larger and far more complex social system of an organiza-
tion or an entire society? How does the politics of learning work at the
macro level?
In the addition to the model of a deep learning mindset I now add the
field in which social learning occurs, composed of both group discourse
and politics (see Figure 6.1), the subject of the next chapter.
Notes
1 My thanks to Norman Dale for this reference.
2 Cf. Preston & de Waal (2002).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
107
Notes 107
3 Mercier and Sperber (2017) provide a comprehensive review of this research in
chapter 15 of their book.
4 Notably, the work of Ron Heifetz, already cited extensively in this book.
5 Evidence for this can be found by browsing through the journal Action
Learning: Theory and Practice.
6 Yorks cites as the source of the learning window T. A. Stewart’s Intellectual
Capital: The New Wealth of Organizations (1997). I am probably not the only
one who, reading this passage, was reminded of former US Secretary of State
Donald Rumsfeld’s notorious distinction between “known knowns,” “known
unknowns,” and “unknown unknowns.”
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:32, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.006
108
Ch apter 7
108
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
109
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
110
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
111
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
112
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
113
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
114
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
115
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
116
7.3 Recasting Dewey
Elsewhere in this book I have discussed John Dewey’s ideas as they relate to
human learning: in short, his belief that learning is achieved by reflecting
critically on one’s experience, in the presence of others having divergent
views. Dewey believed that both children and adults learn most effect-
ively and most deeply this way –and as we have seen, Dewey’s thinking
has been backed up by decades of empirical research. Dewey wrote about
“education” in the traditional sense –formal education –but always in
the context of education as a way of life, as a cornerstone of democracy.
Democracy will survive and flourish, he believed, only when citizens
develop inquiry into their experience as a habit of mind and free them-
selves from what he called “dogmatic thinking” (Dewey, 1981). Here is his
oft-quoted definition of democracy:
Since a democratic society repudiates the principle of external authority, it
must find a substitute in voluntary disposition and interest; these can be
created only by education. A democracy is more than a form of govern-
ment; it is primarily a mode of associated living, of conjoint, communicated
experience. The extension in space of the number of individuals who par-
ticipate in an interest so that each has to refer his own action to that of
others, and to consider the action of others to give point and direction to
his own, is equivalent to the breaking down of those barriers of class, race,
and national territory which [have] kept [people] from perceiving the full
import of their activity. (p. 87)
To say that these words, composed more than a century ago, have res-
onance today is a vast understatement. Let us take a moment to unpack
this passage. Democratic societies do not obey any external authority,
including, presumably, religion. Democracies do not exist as faraway gov-
ernment institutions, but rather in the daily business of life. Successful
democracies require that people learn to understand their own beliefs
and actions, to reflect nondefensively on these in the presence of others
having different beliefs and experiences, and to use this “conjoint,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
117
7.3 Recasting Dewey 117
communicated experience” to develop new understandings in the pursuit
of the common good.
This last part of the definition is what gives learning such political heft.
Dewey has been criticized by many for being naïve about the realities of
political power; and while it is true that he viewed democracy as social
rather than political in nature, he was not at all indifferent to power (Stark,
2014), as is evident by the many political causes he engaged in over the
years. He was idealistic, yes, believing that proper education of individuals
would lead to social improvement, the primary aim of a true democracy.
But he also knew that the active engagement of a reflective citizenry is a
constant challenge, one undertaken in the face of the forces of dogmatism.
This is why he saw democracy as always unfinished, always as a process of
understanding, through inquiry into collective experience. He had strong
opinions on the perils of not doing so, as the following passage illustrates:
There must be a large variety of shared understandings and experiences.
Otherwise, the influences which educate some into masters, educate others
into slaves. And the experience of each party loses in meaning, when the
free interchange of varying modes of life experience is arrested. A separ-
ation into a privileged and subject-class prevents social endosmosis.3 The
evils thereby affecting the superior class are less material and less percep-
tible, but equally real. Their culture tends to be sterile, to be turned back to
feed on itself; their art becomes a showy display and artificial; their wealth
luxurious; their knowledge over-specialized; their manners fastidious rather
than humane. (Dewey, 1981, p. 90)
Because Dewey saw education as the fundamental method leading to
social progress and reform, he, like Freire and Horton, viewed education
as a political act. Dewey mainly wrote about individuals and their place
in the larger society, not about the power of reflective dialogue as a force
for change in organizations; but I believe that a close reading of his work
reveals five insights useful for understanding the politics of deep learning.
First is the importance and power of inquiry as a way of life, not just for the
individual but for society as whole. Dewey often wrote about finding truth
through “scientific inquiry,” but not in the narrow, positivist way of deter-
mining objective “facts,” as many of his critics have claimed, but rather,
as the ultimate pragmatist he was, by using inquiry to uncover working
explanations for the problems at hand, always subject to challenge, further
reflection, and revision. Learning, therefore, is always about the process,
not about the result (Stitzlein, 2014). Thus, perhaps counterintuitively,
Dewey presaged critical theorists, believing, like Foucault, that all truth
is contextual.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
118
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
119
7.3 Recasting Dewey 119
It might seem strange to think about John Dewey’s notions about democ-
racy within the confines of an organization: organizations are, obviously,
not democracies. And I am not arguing here that they should be. The
reason I have chosen to profile Dewey in this way (as I have Freire, Horton,
and Foucault before him) is to suggest that because the very nature of
organizations is to protect order and stability and avoid disruption (Uhl-
Bien, 2018), the keys to deep learning that I have discussed until now –
knowing oneself, creating space for constructive disorientation, engaging
in critical reflection, and doing this in a diverse social space –can all be in
place and deep learning still may not occur without political consciousness.
In this chapter I have profiled four men, all White males, albeit from
different countries and with different worldviews; while true, both Freire
and Horton well understood the forces of oppression and experienced it,
and Horton himself was a mentor to Rosa Parks, an icon of the US civil
rights movement, during her days at Highlander.
The issue is not simply one of giving a nod to other voices. That is not
good enough. Adult education programs, even those designed to decrease
inequalities, may instead have the opposite effect, namely one of “cumu-
lative disadvantage” (Kilpi-Jakonen, Vono de Vilhena, & Blossfel, 2015).
A key target of the Europe 2020 agenda of the European Commission
has been to significantly increase participation rates in adult education,
a worthy goal, but only if participation leads to the desired outcomes.
In a study encompassing 13 countries, Kilpi-Jakonen and her colleagues
(2015) explored the patterns of participation in adult learning activities
and the consequences of this participation on career trajectories. While
they noted substantial cross-national differences, they found that overall,
“higher participation rates do not necessarily lead to lower social/educa-
tional inequalities in participation,” that “those already better off in society
are better able to access adult learning and tend to see greater benefits in
career progress,” and “therefore, additional efforts should be made to make
adult learning more accessible to underrepresented groups, in particular
those disadvantaged educationally and on the labour market” (p. 543). In
short, inequalities in access lead to inequalities in learning.
The problem of social inequality and how to address it is huge –and
well beyond the scope of this book. I hope however that the points raised
in this chapter will stimulate more reflection on how learning, both indi-
vidually and in organizations, has inescapable political overtones.
As I have done in previous chapters, I end this one with some thoughts
on how explicit attention to political dynamics can make deep learning
more likely, namely to: (1) identify existing systems of power relationships;
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
120
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
121
Notes 121
persuasion, teaching or debating. Rather, parrèsia is “situated in what
binds the speaker to the fact that what he says is the truth, and to the
consequences which follow from the fact that he has told the truth”
(p. 56).4 Accordingly, one must believe that speaking truth in the face of
power will not be a futile exercise, but will contribute instead to human
discourse. Those who wish to enhance deep learning in an organization
will develop the social capital to potentially shift power relationships,
allowing truth-telling that has lower social and political risk.
4. Brafman and Brafman (2008) use the term procedural justice to refer
to humans’ expectation to be treated fairly. They review empirical evi-
dence that one’s sense of justice is determined more by the process than
the outcome, as counterintuitive as that may seem! Judging the fairness
of the deal one gets in buying a car is determined as much or more by
how the customer is treated than by the deal itself. Convicted felons’
judgments of the fairness of their treatment by the courts is related
more to the length of time their lawyers spent with them than on the
length of their sentences (Casper et al., 2008, referenced in Brafman
& Brafman, 2008). This notion of procedural justice means that when
engaging in parrèsia, discourse will be facilitated when the emphasis is
less on arguing the merits of the truths at hand, and more on talking
through how these truths have been arrived at and communicating
what in that organizational or cultural context is considered to be the
“fair” way to proceed.
Attention to politics is essential to deep learning. Does this mean that
deep learning is always political? No. Deep learning can be achieved in
numerous ways, but always through mindful, critical reflection on experi-
ence. When the outcome of this reflection threatens to disturb the political
equilibrium, deep learning becomes a political act.
There is one other way to disturb the personal and political equilibrium,
and that is through the arts, the subject of the next chapter.
Notes
1 I picked up this definition many years ago and have long since forgotten its
source.
2 As an example of the latter, see Will (2018).
3 Defined in the Merriam-Webster Dictionary as “passage of a substance through
a membrane from a region of lower to a region of higher concentration.”
4 Defining “truth” was always problematic for Foucault; as a postmodernist he
did not believe in truth in an absolute sense, but rather that what is “true”
becomes accepted by “general politics” (his term) and human discourse.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:25:41, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.007
122
Ch apter 8
The role of art is not only to show how the world is, but also why it
is thus and how it can be transformed.
Augusto Boal
On a crisp afternoon in mid-October, my wife and I are sitting on a hillside
in Richmond, VA, along with several thousand other music fans waiting for
a performance by Mavis Staples, legendary gospel and rhythm and blues
singer. She is one of the headliners of an annual folk music festival here that
draws nearly a quarter of a million people to listen to music ranging from
classic American folk to Afro-Pop. It is 2018, during one of the most div-
isive and polarizing eras in American history, and less than a month before
the mid-term elections. Walking into the festival we were greeted by cam-
paign signs and people handing out political literature. People were wearing
hats and buttons touting this or that candidate. But now I look around
and notice the diversity of people sitting together: millennials with baby
boomers, blacks with whites, multiple generations of families, some with kids
in strollers. Some people are standing, but those sitting behind them don’t
seem to mind. A burly guy accidentally steps on my hand and apologizes. An
elderly woman puts her hand on my shoulder to steady herself as she moves
through the crowd. Ms. Staples begins her performance. A couple about
my age sings and claps along. Three women of different ethnicities dance in
front of us, all moving to the music in their own way. A group of twenty-
somethings to our left, looking studiously cool, stop talking and listen. To
our right two toddlers play on a blanket spread out in the grass, taking in the
joy of the moment. This, I think, is what the arts are for.
This vignette is an example of one of the core functions of art in
society: to bring diverse groups of people together into a shared experi-
ence, creating empathy and openness to new perspectives of viewing the
world. Earlier in this book I have often alluded to the importance, indeed
the necessity of emotion in deep learning, in the form of a disturbance
122
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
123
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
124
Responsive works of art, while prompting inner reflection, beckon the viewer
to bear witness, to relate, and to learn through associated living. This pro-
cess of relational reconstruction is not simple problem-solving or individual
behavioral change. It is a generative aesthetic understanding and purposeful
interpretation by the community and individuals about how to relate, adapt,
and return to communal associated living. (p. 238, emphasis added)
So how did the communities where these abhorrent acts of violence took
place do this? Despite the differences in settings (high school, junior high
school, and elementary school), community, and magnitude of the violence
and its impact, the authors found several common themes spread across
multiple art forms. They found aesthetic responses and “artful conduct” in
each case, taking place in seven stages: (1) previous practice of “associated
living”; (2) the experience of a disruptive event (the shooting), creating the
potential for (3) a motivated aesthetic response, leading to (4) engagement
in transactional aesthetic projects,2 in turn leading to (5) movement toward
consummation and reconstruction, which (6) allows for reclamation, res-
toration, and representation; and to complete the loop (7) return to sta-
bility in associated living. In each of these communities where violence
shattered their relational bonds, works of art were able to “create an open
and accessible milieu, where it [was] safe to explore consummation and
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
125
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
126
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
127
Notice how the song begins as a bit of nostalgia but then creates
disturbance – Season was always open on me. The abruptness of this line
takes the listener from images of hard-scrabble country life to those of the
Jim Crow South. Artists are able to “work with the tension of innovation
and tradition –as well as other tensions, such as randomness and rigidity,
and the impulses of the individual and the imperatives of collectives –to
construct forms that enliven but do not overwhelm the perceptual capaci-
ties of their audiences” (Bang, 2016, pp. 369–370). This point is key: artists
are able to create a direct pathway from lived experience to constructive
disorientation.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
128
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
129
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
130
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
131
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
132
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
133
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
134
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
135
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
136
not only to experience the pain of everyday unfairness but also to create
scenarios for how life might be different.
I should pause here in my praise of aesthetic experience to acknowledge
that the power of art in politics can cut both ways. Art can disturb the emo-
tional equilibrium so as to create empathy for the other; it can also have
the opposite effect, rallying a community around a cause, in both positive
and negative ways. Consider the US war poster in Figure 8.1, depicting the
iconic figure “Rosie the Riveter.” This is a positive image that promotes
pride and seeks to inspire patriotism. Other war posters were designed to
inspire hated and xenophobia. One of the milder versions of these depicts
Uncle Sam rolling up his sleeves after the surrender of the Axis Powers,
saying, “OK Jap, you’re next!”
Perhaps more than any other artist in recent memory, Leni Riefenstahl
is an example of how artistic talent can be used in the service of dema-
goguery. A gifted German cinematographer, Riefenstahl directed the
notorious Nazi film Triumph of the Will. As reviewer David Davis
(2003) noted, “Alternating between stark close-ups and panoramic shots,
Riefenstahl glorified Hitler’s orations and his sycophantic audience of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
137
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
138
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
139
Notes 139
Aesthetic experience, as we’ve seen, can by itself lead to constructive dis-
orientation, as when we enter an empathic field through someone else’s
lived experience. Or it can produce a disorienting dilemma, as when a par-
ticularly provocative piece of street art knocks us off balance and challenges
our assumptions and sense of what is right or true. Art can shake our world
up, sometimes violently; and art can help put it back together. Aesthetic
experience can also enrich mindful learning, as we begin to appreciate
John Dewey’s point that art, and potentially aesthetic experience, is all
around us, every day.
Notes
1 Dewey dedicated the book to his friend Barnes.
2 In the Deweyan sense, learning as transaction between a person and his/her
environment.
3 Defined broadly as any form of creative expression, including visual, literary,
movement, and theatrical arts.
4 Sherif and Hovland (1961) anticipated the power of the media to effect attitude
change more than a half-century ago.
5 Words and music by J. B. Lenoir. Copyright 2007 Arc Music Corp. All rights
administered by BMG Rights Management (US) LLC. All rights reserved.
Used by permission. Reprinted by permission of Hal Leonard LLC.
6 “Banksy Shredding the ‘Girl With a Balloon’ Video,” hypebeast.com, retrieved
October 21, 2018.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Edinburgh Library, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:34:18, subject to the Cambridge
Core terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.008
140
Ch apter 9
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
141
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
142
These eight tensions all relate to the same general paradox: how do we
deal with two opposing forces, one pushing us to the edge, the other
bringing us back? We are innately curious beings, but reflection on experi-
ence is what gives meaning to that experience. Critical reflection puts our
worldviews at risk, so we need to pull back and consolidate new know-
ledge perspectives with the old. We are driven to discover, but we also
must conserve our resources, responding to what Csikszentmihalyi (1997)
calls the “effort imperative.” Disruption in our perceptual space is neces-
sary for constructive disorientation, but we must do something with that
disruption to return to homeostasis. We need to be able to recognize and
appreciate the infinite complexity of our world, but to survive, both phys-
ically and emotionally, we have to make meaning of that complexity. These
tensions between centrifugal and centripetal forces –going to the margins
and coming back to the center –are key to our understanding and man-
agement of constructive disorientation.
Whereas complexity/coherence is an essential tension at an individual
level, differentiation/integration is an essential tension at the organiza-
tional level. My colleague Laurien Alexandre and I recently published a
book chapter entitled, “Differentiation and Integration: Managing the
Paradox in Doctoral Education” (Wergin & Alexandre, 2016). In it we
cite a seminal article written by Lawrence and Lorsch more than 50 years
ago (1967), in which the authors wrote about how to deal with the differ-
entiation/integration paradox. Working from the principle that effective
performance of an organization depends on its ability to interact with,
and adapt to, a changing environment, the authors found that high-
performing organizations were able to optimize two seemingly antagon-
istic pulls, segmentation (differentiation) and unity of effort (integration).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
143
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
144
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
145
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
146
In this chapter I am using dialectical thinking in the East Asian sense: that
holding the essential tensions described above requires us to accept and
be comfortable with contradictory ways of thinking and feeling without
being compelled to resolve the contradictions.
One rather simple way to think about dialectical thinking is to imagine
three cognitive conditions: absolutist, that reality is fixed and unchanging,
including natural laws and human qualities (think: IQ tests and trait the-
ories of leadership); relativistic, that everything is contextual, and that all
knowledge is subjective; and dialectic, that both of these apparent polar
opposites are true (Kramer & Melchoir, 1990). While acknowledging that
phenomena are ever-changing and contradictory, the dialectic thinker
also recognizes the need for sense-making and good judgment in zones of
uncertainty.
This view of dialectical thinking resonates with much of what we know
about the keys to deep learning, going all the way back to the early chapters
of this book. Both absolutist and relativist ways of thinking keep us from
engaging in the sort of critical reflection that leads to honest assessment of
our beliefs and prejudices. Absolutist thinkers will resist challenges to what
to them are obvious truths, reinforced by myside bias; relativist thinkers
will shrug off diverse ways of thinking and knowing as, in the extreme,
“alternative facts”: you see it your way and I see it mine. Neither mindset
will lead to constructive disorientation –unless the person is hit with a
particularly unsettling disorienting dilemma. For example, an absolutist,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
147
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
148
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
149
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
150
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
151
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
152
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
153
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
154
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
155
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
156
Notes
1 This term appears in Sloman & Fernbach (2017).
2 Obviously, this metaphor works only for Western students, not those in Africa
for whom encountering a zebra may not be considered a rare event.
3 Interestingly, dialectical thinking is almost entirely absent among Anglo-
American philosophers, some of whom are its most vehement critics. John
Dewey studied Hegelian philosophy as a young man but abandoned it as his
pragmatist views began to take shape. See Martin (2002).
4 This position is expressed most eloquently in Immanuel Kant’s Critique of Pure
Reason (1998), in which he implies that our intellectual curiosity as humans
will always outpace our ability to answer the essential questions of life, and
thus each new generation has to confront the same moral dilemmas.
5 Cf. Baltes, Sternberg, Bassett, Labouvie-Vief, Kegan, Riegel.
6 This is true at least in Western cultures, where growth through childhood
and adolescence is defined in terms of individualism. Research examined by
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
157
Notes 157
Grossman (2018), however, suggests that in East Asian cultures dialectical
thinking emerges much earlier.
7 https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Concerto#Etymology. Many thanks to Norman
Dale for the reference.
8 Basseches, 1984. By “limited” I mean that his research subjects were all students
and faculty members at Swarthmore College.
9 Riegel’s article even contains a “Manifesto for Dialectical Psychology,” ending
with the words, “Dialectical psychologists unite! You have nothing to lose but
the respect of vulgar mechanists and pretentious mentalists; you will win a
world, a changing world created by ever changing human beings” (p. 697).
10 Consistent research findings indicate that those who are predisposed to think
dialectically are in the clear minority, even among mature adults.
11 See, for example, Scharmer (2018).
12 Three examples: learning scholar Helen Langer; organizational psychologist
Bill Torbert; and mindfulness teacher Charles Tart.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:27:28, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.009
158
Ch apter 10
Anyone who has begun to think, places some portion of the world
in jeopardy.
John Dewey
I want to accomplish two things in this last chapter: to summarize and high-
light the key themes from previous chapters; and then to shift in perspec-
tive and tone, from an academic argument for a deep learning mindset to
a more pragmatic discussion of how to put its principles into everyday use.
158
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
159
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
160
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
161
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
162
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
163
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
164
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
165
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
166
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
167
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
168
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
169
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
170
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
171
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
172
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
173
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
174
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
175
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
176
Notes
1 US readers will recognize this as a true story.
2 I am grateful to my dear friend, mentor and colleague Larry Braskamp for the
introduction.
3 Dr. Barbara Lipinski, Antioch University Santa Barbara.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. Edinburgh College of Art, on 08 Dec 2019 at 20:36:48, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.010
177
References
177
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
178
178 References
Batson, C. D., & Ahmad, N. Y. (2009). Using empathy to improve intergroup
attitudes and relations. Social Issues and Policy Review, 3, 141–177.
Bayne, H. B., & Jangha, A. (2016). Utilizing improvisation to teach empathy skills
in counselor education. Counselor Education and Supervision, 55(4), 250–262.
BBC News. (2018, December 12). Facebook scandal “hit 87 million users.”
Retrieved from www.bbc.com/news/technology-43649018.
Blackbum, A., & Hwozdek, C. (2016). Labelled brain. Retrieved from openclipart.
org.
Boal, A. (2006). The aesthetics of the oppressed. London, UK: Routledge.
Bourdieu, P. (1977). Outline of a theory of practice. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge
University Press.
Brafman, O., & Brafman, R. (2008). Sway: The irresistible pull of irrational
behavior. New York, NY: Doubleday.
Brewer, J., Elwafi, H., & Davis, J. (2014). Craving to quit: Psychological models
and neurobiological mechanisms of mindfulness training as treatment for
addictions. Translational Issues in Psychological Science, 1, 70–90. https://doi.
org/10.1037/2332-2136.1.S.70
Brock, S. E. (2010). Measuring the importance of precursor steps to transforma-
tive learning. Adult Education Quarterly, 60(2), 122–142. https://doi.org/
10.1177/0741713609333084
Brookfield, S. (2009). Engaging critical reflection in corporate America. In J.
Mezirow & E. Taylor (Eds.), Transformative learning in practice: Insights from
community, workplace, and higher education (pp. 125–135). San Francisco,
CA: Jossey-Bass.
Brooks, D. (2016, August 2). How artists change the world. New York Times.
Retrieved from www.nytimes.com/2016/08/02/opinion/how-artists-change-
the-world.html.
Brown, K. W., Ryan, R., & Creswell, J. D. (2007). Mindfulness: Theoretical
foundations and evidence for its salutary effects. Psychological Inquiry, 18(4),
211–237.
Bruni, F. (2018, December 4). George Bush and the obituary wars. New York
Times. Retrieved from www.nytimes.com/2018/12/04/opinion/george-hw-
bush-obituary.html.
Buller, J. (2015). Change leadership in higher education. San Francisco, CA:
Jossey-Bass.
Burns, J. M. (1978). Leadership. New York, NY: Harper & Row.
Burns, M., Beti, N. B., & Okuto, E. M. (2017). Truth comes in many colors: Theater
of the Oppressed for conflict transformation and trauma healing in Kenya.
In S. Erenrich & J. F. Wergin (Eds.), Grassroots leadership and the arts for
social change (pp. 189–205). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Caffarella, R. S., Armour, R. A., Fuhrmann, B. S., & Wergin, J. F. (1989). Mid-
career faculty: Refocusing the perspective. Review of Higher Education, 12(4),
403–410.
Chandler, J. L., & Kirsch, R. (2018). Addressing race and culture within a crit-
ical leadership approach. In J. Lau Chin, J. Trimble, & J. Garcia (Eds.),
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
179
References 179
Global and culturally diverse leaders and leadership (pp. 307–321). Bingley,
UK: Emerald.
Changeux, J.-P. (2009). The physiology of truth: Neuroscience and human knowledge
(M. B. DeBoise, Trans.). Cambridge, MA: Belknap/Harvard University Press.
Chater, N., & Loewenstein, G. (2016). The under-appreciated drive for sense-
making. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 126, 137–154.
Cheng, C. (2009). Dialectical thinking and coping flexibility: A multimethod
approach. Journal of Personality, 77(2), 471–494.
Cohen, C. (2006). Creative approaches to reconciliation. In M. Fitzduff & C.
Stout (Eds.), The psychology of resolving global conflicts: From war to peace (Vol.
3, pp. 69–102). Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger.
Coleman, P., & Deutsch, M. (2014). Some guidelines for developing a creative
approach to conflict. In P. Coleman, M. Deutsch, & E. Marcus (Eds.),
The handbook of conflict resolution: Theory and practice (pp. 478–489). San
Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Cranton, P., & Taylor, E. (2012). The handbook of transformative learning: Theory,
research, and practice. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Csikszentmihalyi, M. (1970). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York,
NY: Harper Perennial Modern Classics.
(1990). Flow: The psychology of optimal experience. New York, NY: Harper & Row.
(1997). Happiness and creativity: Going with the flow. The Futurist,
September–October, 8–12.
Curry, L., & Wergin, J. F. (1993). Educating professionals: Responding to new
expectations for competence and accountability. San Francisco: CA: Jossey-Bass.
Daly, B., & Suggs, S. (2010). Teachers’ experiences with humane education and
animals in the elementary classroom: Implications for empathy develop-
ment. Journal of Moral Education, 39(1), 101–112.
Damasio, A. (1999). The feeling of what happens: Body and emotion in the making of
consciousness. New York, NY: Pantheon.
(2018). The strange order of things: Life, feeling, and the making of cultures.
New York, NY: Pantheon.
Davies, L. (2015). Interrupting extremism by creating educative turbulence.
Curriculum Inquiry, 44(4), 450–468. https://doi.org/10.1111/curi.12061
Davis, D. (2003, September 12). Pro- Nazi filmmaker, Leni Riefenstahl,
101, dies. Forward. Retrieved from https://forward.com/news/8105/
pro-nazi-filmmaker-leni-riefenstahl-101-dies.
Davis, H. (2002). Too early for a neuropsychology of empathy. Behavioral and
Brain Sciences, 25, 32–33.
Davis, J., & Thompson, E. (2015). Developing attention and decreasing affective
bias. In K. Brown, J. Creswell, & R. Ryan (Eds.), Handbook of mindful-
ness: Theory, research, and practice (pp. 42–61). New York, NY: Guilford
Press.
Davis-Manigaulte, J., Yorks, L., & Kasl, E. (2006). Expressive ways of knowing
and transformative learning. New Directions for Adult and Continuing
Education, 109, 27–35.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
180
180 References
Day, D. (2014). The Oxford handbook on leadership and organizations. Oxford,
UK: Oxford University Press.
Dewey, J. [1916] (1985). Democracy and education ( J. Boydston, P. R. Baysinger, &
B. Levine, Eds.). Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
(1933). How we think (2nd ed.). Boston, MA: D. C. Heath.
(1934). Art as experience. New York, NY: Minton, Balch & Company.
[1938] (1997). Experience and education. New York, NY: Free Press.
(1981). The later works of John Dewey, 1925–1953 (Vol. 11: Essays, reviews, Trotsky
inquiry, miscellany, and liberalism and social action, J. Boydston, Ed.).
Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Dilworth, L. R., & Willis, V. J. (2003). Action learning: Images and pathways.
Malabar, FL: Krieger.
Dirkx, J. M. (2008). The meaning and role of emotions in adult learning. New
Directions for Adult and Continuing Education, 2008, 120, 7–18. https://doi
.org/10.1002/ace.311
Dissanayake, E. (2000). Art and intimacy: How the arts began. Seattle: University
of Washington Press.
Dunning, D. (2011). The Dunning-Kruger effect: On being ignorant of one’s own
ignorance. In J. M Olson & M. P. Zanna (Eds.), Advances in experimental
social psychology (Vol. 44, pp. 247–296). Cambridge, MA: Academic Press.
Dweck, C. (2016). Mindset: The new psychology of success (updated edition).
New York, NY: Random House.
Edelman, D. (2017). Acting up and fighting back: How New York’s artistic com-
munity responded to AIDS. In S. Erenrich & J. F. Wergin (Eds.), Grassroots
leadership and the arts for social change (pp. 173–186). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Elliott, D., Silverman, M., & Bowman, W. (Eds.). (2016). Artistic citizen-
ship: Artistry, social responsibility, and ethical praxis. New York, NY: Oxford
University Press.
Emerson, R. W. [1841] (2013). Self-reliance & other essays. Mineola, NY: Dover
Seashore Classics.
Erenrich, S., & Wergin, J. F. (2017). Grassroots leadership and the arts for social
change. Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Evans, J. S. B. T. (1990). Bias in human reasoning: Causes and consequences.
Hillsdate, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
Fenwick, T. (2008). Workplace learning: Emerging trends and new perspectives.
New Directions for Adult & Continuing Education, 119, 17–26.
Ferry, N., & Ross-Gordon, J. (1998). An inquiry into Schön’s epistemology of
practice: Exploring links between experience and reflective practice. Adult
Education Quarterly, 48(2), 98–112.
Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Palo Alto, CA: Stanford
University Press.
Foucault, M. (1980). Power/knowledge: Selected interviews and other writings (C.
Gordon, Ed.). New York, NY: Pantheon.
(1994). Ethics: Subjectivity and truth. New York, NY: The New Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
181
References 181
(2008). The government of self and others: Lectures at the College de France, 1982–
1983. New York, NY: Picador.
Fredrickson, R., McMahan, S., & Dunlap, K. (2013). Problem-based learning
theory. In B. Irby, G. Brown, R. Lara-Alecio, & S. Jackson (Eds.), The hand-
book of educational theories (pp. 211–217). Charlotte, NC: Information Age
Publishing.
Frei, F. (2018, April). Frances Frei: How to build (and rebuild) trust [Video
file]. Retrieved from www.ted.com/talks/frances_frei_how_to_build_and_
rebuild_trust?language=en.
Freiler, T. (2008). Learning through the body. In S. Merriam (Ed.), Third update
on adult learning theory (pp. 37–47). San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Freire, P. (1970). Pedagogy of the oppressed. New York, NY: Seabury.
Friedman, T. (2016). Thank you for being late: An optimist’s guide to thriving in the
age of accelerations. New York, NY: Picador.
Gadamer, H. (1989). Truth and method (2nd rev. ed.). New York, NY: Crossroad.
Gadotti, M. (1996). Pedagogy of praxis: A dialectical philosophy of education.
Albany: State University of New York Press.
Galef, J. (2016, February). Why you think you’re right –even if you’re wrong
[Video file]. Retrieved from www.ted.com/talks/julia_galef_why_you_
think_you_re_right_even_if_you_re_wrong.
Gasca, L. (2018). Don’t fail fast –fail mindfully. TED Talk, June 2018.
George, R. (2019, March 6). Confirmation bias hurts social science. Wall Street
Journal, Eastern edition, p. A15.
Gigliotti, A. R., Dwyer, B., & Ruiz-Mesa, K. (2018). Campus unrest in American
higher education: Challenges and opportunities for strategic diversity lead-
ership. In L. C. Trimble & E. J. Garcia (Eds.), Global and culturally diverse
leaders and leadership (pp. 211–232). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Giordano, A. L., Stare, B. G., & Clarke, P. B. (2015). Overcoming obstacles to
empathy: The use of experiential learning in addictions counseling courses.
Journal of Creativity in Mental Health, 10(1), 100–113.
Goodfellow, I., Bengio, Y., & Courville, A. (2016). Deep learning. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Gorman, S., & Gorman, J. (2017). Denying to the grave: Why we ignore the facts
that will save us. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Gorey, E. (1999). The unstrung harp: Or Mr. Earbrass writes a novel. New York,
NY: Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.
Greene, M. (1995). Releasing the imagination: Essays on education, the arts, and
social change. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Grisold, T., & Kaiser, A. (2017). Leaving behind what we are not: Applying a
systems thinking perspective to present unlearning as an enabler for finding
the best version of the self. Journal of Organisational Transformation & Social
Change, 14(1), 39–55. https://doi.org/10.1080/14779633.2017.1291145
Grossman, I. (2018). Dialecticism across the lifespan. In J. Spencer-Rodgers & K.
Peng (Eds.), The psychological and cultural foundations of East Asian cognition:
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
182
182 References
Contradiction, change, and holism (pp. 135– 180). Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Grow, G. O. (1991). Teaching learners to be self- directed. Adult Education
Quarterly, 41(3), 125–149.
Ifejika, N. (2006, September 29). What does Ubuntu really mean? Guardian.
Retrieved from www.theguardian.com/theguardian/2006/sep/29/features11
.g2.
Habermas, J. (1984). The theory of communicative action 1: Reason and the rational-
ization of society (T. McCarthy, trans.). Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and
religion. New York, NY: Vintage Books.
Halberstam, D. (1972). The best and the brightest. New York, NY: Random House.
Handy, C. (1994). The age of paradox. Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business School
Press.
Hanhijärvi, T. (2015). Dialectical thinking: Zeno, Socrates, Kant, Marx. New York,
NY: Algora.
Harris, L., & Fiske, S. (2011). Dehumanized perception: A psychological means to
facilitate atrocities, torture, and genocide? Zeitschrift für Psychologie/Journal
of Psychology, 219(3), 175–181.
Harvard Smithsonian Center for Astrophysics. (1987). A private universe [video].
Indianapolis. IN: Annenberg/CPB Project.
Hayes, S., & Yorks, L. (2007). Lessons from the lessons learned: Arts change the
world when … New Directions for Adult & Continuing Education, 107, 89–98.
Heifetz, R. (1994). Leadership without easy answers. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Heifetz, R., Linsky, M., & Grashow, A. (2009). The practice of adaptive leader-
ship: Tools and tactics for changing your organization and your world. Boston,
MA: Harvard Business Press.
Hoffman, M. (2001). Towards a comprehensive empathy-based theory of pro-
social moral development. In A. Bohart & D. Stipek (Eds.), Constructive and
destructive behavior: Implications for family, school, and society (pp. 61–86).
Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.
Horton, M., & Freire, P. (1990). We make the road by walking: Conversations on
education and social change. Philadelphia, PA: Temple University Press.
Hume, D. [1739–40] (1969). A treatise of human nature. London, UK: Penguin.
James, W. (1884). What is an emotion? In R. Richardson (Ed.), The heart of
William James (pp. 1–19). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Jarc, J., & Garwood, T. (2017). Benevolent subversion: Graffiti, street art, and the
emergence of the anonymous leader. In S. Erenrich & J. F. Wergin (Eds.),
Grassroots leadership and the arts for social change (pp. 97–109). Bingley,
UK: Emerald.
Jarvis, C. (2012). Fiction, empathy and lifelong learning. International Journal of
Lifelong Education, 31(6), 743–758.
Jarvis, P. (1999). The practitioner-researcher: Developing theory from practice. San
Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
183
References 183
Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking, fast and slow. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus &
Giroux.
Kahneman, D., & Renshon, J. (2007). Why hawks win. Foreign Affairs (January/
February), 34–38.
Kallio, E. (2011). Integrative thinking is the key: An evaluation of current
research into the development of adult thinking. Theory & Psychology,
21(6), 785–801.
Kant, I. (1998). Critique of pure reason (P. Guyer & A. W. Wood, Trans.) Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Kaplan, A. (1964). The conduct of inquiry: Methodology for behavioral science.
Scranton, PA: Chandler.
Kasser, V. G., & Ryan, R. M. (1999). The relation of psychological needs for
autonomy and relatedness to vitality, well-being, and mortality in a nursing
home. Journal of Applied Social Psychology, 29, 935–954.
Kavanaugh, J., & Rich, M. (2018). Truth decay: An initial exploration of the
diminishing role of facts and analysis in American public life. Santa Monica,
CA: RAND Corporation.
Kegan, R. (1982). The evolving self. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
(1994). In over our heads: The mental demands of modern life. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press.
(2000). What “form” transforms? In J. A. Mezirow (Ed.), Learning as transform-
ation: Critical perspectives on a theory in progress (pp. 35–70). San Francisco,
CA: Jossey-Bass.
Kegan, R., & Lahey, L. (2009). Immunity to change: How to overcome it and unlock
the potential in yourself and your organization. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
Business Press.
Kilpi-Jakonen, E., Vono de Vilhena, E., & Blossfel, H. P. (2015). Adult learning
and social inequalities: Processes of equalisation or cumulative disadvantage?
International Review of Education, 61, 529–546.
Kim, K., & Markman, A. (2013). Individual differences, cultural differences,
and dialectic conflict description and resolution. International Journal of
Psychology, 48(5), 797–808. https://doi.org/10.1080/00207594.2012.711908
King, B. J. (2015, August 27). Pop quiz: How science-literate are we, really?
NPR. Retrieved from www.npr.org/sections/13.7/2015/08/27/435148051/
pop-quiz-how-science-literate-are-we-really.
Klein, G. (2007). Performing a project premortem. Harvard Business Review,
85(9), 18–19.
Knowles, M. S. (1984). The adult learner: A neglected species (3rd ed.). Houston,
TX: Gulf.
Kolb, D. (1984). Experiential learning: Experience as the source of learning and devel-
opment. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Koven, R. (1977, November 21). A day of symbolism. Washington Post.
Retrieved from www.washingtonpost.com/archive/politics/1977/11/21/
a- d ay- o f- s ymbolism/ 0 50baf56- 0 509- 4 a2e- b cad- 1 4d0b4f2e08a/ ? utm_
term=.5abfb178e114.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
184
184 References
Kramer, D., & Melchoir, J. (1990). Gender, role conflict, and the development of
relativistic and dialectical thinking. Sex Roles, 23(9–10), 553–575.
Kreutzer, D. (1995). A facilitation approach to systems thinking breakthrough. In
S. Chawla & J. Renesch (Eds.), Learning organizations: Developing cultures
for tomorrow’s workplace (pp. 229–241). Portland, OR: Productivity Press.
Kucukaydin, I., & Cranton, P. (2012). Critically questioning the discourse of
transformative learning theory. Adult Education Quarterly, 63(1), 43–56.
Labouvie-Vief, G. (1990). Modes of knowledge and the organization of develop-
ment. In M. Commons, C. Amon, L. Kohlberg, F. Richards, T. Grotzer, &
J. Sinott (Eds.), Adult development, Vol. 2: Models and methods in the study of
adolescent and adult thought (pp. 43–62). New York NY: Praeger.
(2003). Dynamic integration: Affect, cognition, and the self in adulthood.
Current Directions in Psychological Science, 12(6), 201–206.
(2015). Integrating emotions and cognition throughout the lifespan. Cham,
Switzerland: Springer International.
Ladkin, D. (2015). Mastering the ethical dimension of organizations. Cheltenham,
UK: Edward Elgar.
Ladkin, D., & Taylor, S. (2010). Enacting the “true self ”: Towards a theory of
embodied authentic leadership. Leadership Quarterly, 21, 64–74.
Lane, D. C. (2018). Just odds: An illustrated guide to J. E. Littlewood’s Law of
Miracles. Walnut, CA: Mt. San Antonio College.
Langer, E. (2016). The power of mindful learning (2nd ed.). Boston, MA: Da
Capo Press.
Lawrence, P., & Lorsch, J. (1967). Differentiation and integration in complex
organizations. Administrative Science Quarterly, 12(1), 1–47.
Lawrence, R. (2012). Intuitive knowing and embodied consciousness. New
Directions for Adult and Continuing Education, 134, 5–13.
Lee, S. (1998). Generativity and the life of Martha Graham. In D. McAdams &
E. de St. Aubin, Generativity and adult development: How and why we care for
the next generation (pp. 429–448). Washington, DC: American Psychological
Association.
Lerner, S., & Tetlock, P. E. (2003). Bridging individual, interpersonal, and institu-
tional approaches to judgment and decision making: The impact of account-
ability on cognitive bias. In S. L. Schneider & J. Shanteau (Eds.), Emerging
perspectives on judgment and decision research (pp. 431–457). Cambridge,
UK: Cambridge University Press.
Lessing, D. (1987). Prisons we choose to live inside. New York, NY: Harper Perennial
Modern Classics.
Levitin, D. J. (2017). Weaponized lies: How to think critically in the post-truth era.
New York, NY: Dutton.
Li, Y., Sheldon, K., & Liu, R. (2015). Dialectical thinking moderates the effect
of extrinsic motivation on intrinsic motivation. Learning and Individual
Differences, 39, 89–95. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.lindif.2015.03.019
Lindeman, E. C. (1961). The meaning of adult education in the United States.
New York, NY: Harvest House.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
185
References 185
Lord, C. G., Ross, L., & Lepper, M. (1979). Biased assimilation and attitude
polarization: The effects of prior theories on subsequently considered evi-
dence. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 37(11), 2098–2109.
Lovell, J., & Kluger, J. (2006). Apollo 13. Boston, MA: Houghton-Mifflin.
Lucas, H. C. J. (2012). The search for survival: Lessons from disruptive technologies.
Santa Barbara, CA: Praeger.
Maarhuis, P., & Rud, A. (2017). Dewey, school violence, and aesthetic
response: Healing the community through arts after disasters. In L. Hersey
& B. Bobick (Eds.), Handbook of research on the facilitation of community
engagement through community art (pp. 237–266). Hershey, PA: IGI Global.
Mager, R., & Pipe, P. (1983). Analyzing performance problems: Or, you really oughta
wanna. Atlanta, GA: Center for Effective Performance.
Manuti, A., Impedovo, A. M., & de Palma, D. P. (2017). Managing social and
human capital in organizations: Communities of practices as strategic
tools for individual and organizational development. Journal of Workplace
Learning, 29(3), 217–234.
Marshall, J. (2016). First person action research. London, UK: Sage.
Marsick, V., & Watkins, K. (2001). Informal and incidental learning. New
Directions for Adult & Continuing Education, 2001, 89, 25–34.
Martin, J. (2002). The education of John Dewey: A biography. New York,
NY: Columbia University Press.
Maslow, A. (1998). Toward a psychology of being (3rd ed.). New York, NY: Wiley.
McCrimmon, M. (2005). Thought leadership: A radical departure from trad-
itional, positional leadership. Management Decision, 43(7), 1064–1070.
McNerney, S. (2011, November 4). A brief guide to embodied cognition: Why
you are not your brain [Blog]. Scientific American. Retrieved from https://
blogs.scientificamerican.com/ g uest- b log/ a - b rief- g uide- t o-embodied-
cognition-why-you-are-not-your-brain.
McNiff, J. (2017). Action research: All you need to know. Los Angeles, CA: Sage.
McWilliams, J. (2019, April 4). Is more knowledge making us less reasonable?
Pacific Standard. Retrieved April 4, 2019.
Meissner, P., & Wulf, T. (2015). The development of strategy scenarios based on
prospective hindsight: An approach to strategic decision making. Journal of
Strategy and Management, 8(2), 176–190.
Mercier, H., & Sperber, D. (2017). The enigma of reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Merriam, S. B., Caffarella, R. S., & Baumgartner, L. M. (2007). Learning in
adulthood (3rd ed.). San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Meyers, R. (2009). Saving Jesus from the Church: How to stop worshiping Christ and
start following Jesus. New York, NY: HarperOne.
Meyerson, D. E. (2003). Tempered radicals: How everyday leaders inspire change at
work. Boston, MA: Harvard Business School Publishing.
(2004). The tempered radicals: How employees push their companies –little
by little –to be more socially responsible. Stanford Social Innovation Review,
2(2), 14–22.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
186
186 References
Mezirow, J. (1990). Fostering critical reflection in adulthood: A guide to transforma-
tive and emancipatory education. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
(1998). On critical reflection. Adult Education Quarterly, 48(3), 185–198.
(2000). Learning to think like an adult: Core concepts of transformation theory.
In J. A. Mezirow (Ed.), Learning as transformation: Critical perspectives on a
theory in progress (pp. 3–33). San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Mitra, A. (2017). Innovating social change through grassroots leadership practices
in the arts. In S. Erenrich & J. F. Wergin (Eds.), Grassroots leadership and the
arts for social change (pp. 111–126). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Moody, S. (2019). Interculturality as social capital at work: The case of disagreements
in American-Japanese interaction. Language in Society, 48(3), 377–402.
Mørk, B. E., Hoholm, T., Ellingsen, G., Edwin, B., & Aanestad, M. (2010).
Challenging expertise: On power relations within and across communities
of practice in medical innovation. Management Learning, 41(5), 575–592.
https://doi.org/10.1177/1350507610374552
Motta, M., Callaghan, T., & Sylvester, S. (2018). Knowing less but presuming
more: Dunning-Kruger effects and the endorsement of anti-vaccine policy
attitudes. Social Science & Medicine, 211, 274–281.
Myers, V. (2014, November). How to overcome our biases? Boldly walk toward
them. TED Talk. Retrieved from www.ted.com/talks/verna_myers_how_to_
overcome_our_biases.
Newman, M. (2014). Transformative learning: Mutinous thoughts revisited. Adult
Education Quarterly, 64(4), 345–355. https://doi.org/10.1177/0741713614543173
Newport, C. (2016). Deep work: Rules for focused success in a distracted world.
New York, NY: Grand Central Publishing.
Nisbet, R. (1983). Prejudices: A philosophical dictionary. Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press.
Nolen, S. B., Horn, I., & Ward, C. (2015). Situating cognition. Educational
Psychologist, 50(3), 234–247.
Nussbaum, M. C. (2001). Upheavals of thought: The intelligence of emotions.
Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
Okeke, C. (2018). Crises impacting South African men’s participation in early
socio-education development of children and possible useful interventions.
South African Journal of Psychology, 48(4), 476–487.
Palmer, P. (1998). The courage to teach: Exploring the inner landscape of a teacher’s
life. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Pascarella, E., & Terenzini, P. (1991). How college affects students: Findings and
insights from twenty years of research. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
& Terenzini, P. (2005). How college affects students. Volume 2: A third decade of
research. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Pederson, R. (2010). Empathy development in medical education: A critical
review. Medical Teacher, 32(7), 593–600.
Pemberton, J., Mavin, S., & Stalker, B. (2007). Scratching beneath the surface
of communities of (mal)practice. The Learning Organization, 14(1), 62–73.
https://doi.org/10.1108/09696470710718357
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
187
References 187
Pennycook, G., & Rand, D. (2019). Who falls for fake news? The roles of bull-
shit receptivity, overclaiming, familiarity, and analytic thinking. Journal of
Personality [e- journal version]. doi: https://doi-org.antioch.idm.oclc.org/
10.1111/jopy.12476
Piaget, J. (1954). The construction of reality in the child. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Polanyi, M. (1966). The tacit dimension. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Preskill, S., & Brookfield, S. (2009). Learning as a way of leading: Lessons from the
struggle for social justice. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Preston, S., & de Waal, F. B. (2002). Empathy: Its ultimate and proximate bases.
Behavioral & Brain Sciences, 25, 1–72.
Putnam, R. (2000). Bowling alone: Collapse and revival of American community.
New York, NY: Simon & Schuster.
(2007). E pluribus unum: Diversity and community in the twenty-first century.
Scandinavian Political Studies, 30(2), 137–174.
Riegel, K. (1973). Dialectic operations: The final period of cognitive development.
Human Development, 16, 346–370.
(1976). The dialectics of human development. American Psychologist, 31(10),
689–700.
Rittel, H., & Webber, M. (2017). Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. In
J. Stein (Ed.), Classic readings in urban planning (pp. 52–63). New York,
NY: Routledge.
Roberts, L. (2015). Reflected best self engagement at work: Positive identity,
alignment, and the pursuit of vitality and value creation. Oxford, UK: Oxford
University Press.
Rodgers, C. (2002). Defining reflection: Another look at John Dewey and
reflective thinking. Teachers College Record, 104(4), 842–866.
Roessger, K. (2014). The effects of reflective activities on skill adaptation in a
work-related instrumental learning setting. Adult Education Quarterly, 64(4),
323–344.
Roseman, C., Ritchie, M., & Laux, J. (2009). A restorative justice approach to
empathy development in sex offenders: An exploratory study. Journal of
Addictions & Offender Counseling, 29(2), 96–109.
Rosenberg, M. (1979). Conceiving the self. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Rowe, N., Baker, N., & Khatab, A. (2017). The shape of water … Palestine, Badke
and let’s make noise for Gaza: Three journeys of intercultural choreographic
practice in Palestine. In S. Erenrich & J. F. Wergin (Eds.), Grassroots leader-
ship and the arts for social change (pp. 281–298). Bingley, UK: Emerald.
Rule, P. (2004). Dialogic spaces: Adult education projects and social engagement.
International Journal of Lifelong Education, 23(4), 319–334. https://doi.org/
10.1080/026037042000233476
Ryan, R., & Deci, E. (2017). Self-determination theory: Basic psychological needs in
motivation, development, and wellness. New York, NY: Guilford.
Ryan, S. (1995). Learning communities: An alternative to the “expert” mode. In S.
Chawla & J. Renesch (Eds.), Learning organizations: Developing cultures for
tomorrow’s workplace (pp. 279–291). Portland, OR: Productivity Press.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
188
188 References
Scharmer, O. C. (2018). The essentials of Theory U: Core principles and applications.
Oakland, CA: Berrett-Koehler.
Schön, D. (1983). The reflective practitioner. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Scott, K. S. (2017). An integrative framework for problem-based learning and
action learning: Promoting evidence-based design and evaluation in leader-
ship development. Human Resource Development Review, 16(1), 3–34.
Seligman, M. (1991). Learned optimism. New York, NY: Knopf.
Senge, P. (2006). The fifth discipline: The art and practice of the learning organiza-
tion (rev. ed.). New York, NY: Doubleday.
Shatz, C. J. (1992). The developing brain. Scientific American, 267(3), 60–67.
Sherif, M., & Hovland, C. I. (1961). Social judgment: Assimilation and con-
trast effects in communication and attitude change. New Haven, CT: Yale
University Press.
Shermer, M. (2011). The believing brain. New York, NY: Henry Holt & Company.
Shore, Z. (2008). Blunder: Why smart people make bad decisions. New York,
NY: Bloomsbury.
Shtulman, A. (2017). Scienceblind: Why our intuitive theories about the world are so
often wrong. New York, NY: Basic Books.
Sinclair, A. (2007). Leadership for the disillusioned: Moving beyond myths and heroes
to leading that liberates. Crows Nest, Australia: Allen & Unwin.
(2016). Leading mindfully: How to focus on what matters, influence for good, and
enjoy leadership more. Crows Nest, Australia: Allen & Unwin.
Sloman, S., & Fernbach, P. (2017). The knowledge illusion: Why we never think
alone. New York, NY: Riverhead Books.
Snowber, C. (2012). Dance as a way of knowing. New Directions for Adult and
Continuing Education, 134, 53–60. https://doi.org/10.1002/ace.20017
Sogunro, O. (1998). Impact of evaluation anxiety on adult learning. Journal of
Research & Development in Education, 31(2), 109–120.
Spencer-Rodgers, J., Anderson, E., Ma-Kellams, C., Wang, C., & Peng, K. (2018).
What is dialectical thinking? Conceptualization and measurement. In J.
Spencer-Rodgers & K. Peng (Eds.), The psychological and cultural foundations
of East Asian cognition: Contradiction, change, and holism (pp. 1–34). Oxford,
UK: Oxford University Press.
Stanovich, K. E., West, R. F., & Toplak, M. E. (2013). Myside bias, rational
thinking, and intelligence. Current Directions in Psychological Science, 22(4),
259–264.
Stark, J. (2014). The potential of Deweyan-inspired action research. Education and
Culture, 30(2), 87–101.
Staw, B. M. (1983). Motivation research versus the art of faculty management.
Review of Higher Education, 6, 301–321.
Stewart, T. A. (1997). Intellectual capital: The new wealth of organizations.
New York, NY: Doubleday.
Stitzlein, S. (2014). Habits of democracy: A Deweyan approach to citizenship in
America today. Education and Culture, 30(2), 61–86.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
189
References 189
Swart, T., Chisholm, K., & Brown, P. (2015). Neuroscience for leadership: Harnessing
the brain gain advantage. New York, NY: Palgrave McMillan.
Swick, K. (2005). Preventing violence through empathy development in families.
Early Childhood Education Journal, 33(1), 53–59.
Tart, C. T. (2001). Waking up: Overcoming the obstacles to human potential. Lincoln,
NE: IUniverse.com.
Taylor, E. W. (1994). Intercultural competency: A transformative learning process.
Adult Education Quarterly, 44(3), 154–174.
Terenzini, P. T. (2014). Remarks: Proceedings from Penn State Conference on
Engaged Scholarship, University Park, Pennsylvania.
Thompson, K., & Gullone, E. (2003). Promotion of empathy and prosocial
behavior in children through humane education. Australian Psychologist,
38(3), 175–182.
Torbert, W. (2004). Action inquiry: The secret of timely and transforming leadership.
San Francisco, CA: Berret-Koehler.
Treasure, J. (2017). How to be heard: Secrets for powerful speaking and listening
[Kindle edition]. Coral Gables, FL: Mango Publishing Group.
Tuchman, B. W. (1984). The march of folly: From Troy to Vietnam. New York,
NY: Knopf.
Tzu, L. (1988). Tao Te Ching: A new English version, with forward and notes (S.
Mitchell, Trans.). New York, NY: HarperPerennial.
Uhl-Bien, M. (2018, May 31). Plenary address: Developing and mobilizing next
generation leaders. Presentation to Next Generation Leadership, International
Leadership Association Regional Conference, Pretoria, South Africa.
Uhl-Bien, M., Marion, R., & McKelvey, B. (2007). Complexity leadership
theory: Shifting leadership from the industrial age to the knowledge era.
Leadership Quarterly, 18, 298–318.
Uzefovsky, F., & Knafo-Noam, A. (2017). Empathy development through the life
span. In J. Sommerville & J. Decety (Eds.), Social cognition: Development
through the life span (pp. 71–97). New York, NY: Routledge.
Vaill, P. (1996). Learning as a way of being: Strategies for survival in a world of per-
manent white water. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Vanderah, T., & Gould, D. (2016). Nolte’s the human brain: An introduction to it
functional anatomy (7th ed.). Philadelphia, PA: Elsevier.
Vince, R. (2004). Action learning and organizational learning: Power, politics, and
emotion in organizations. Action Learning: Research and Practice, 1(1), 63–78.
(2012). The contradictions of impact: Action learning and power in
organizations. Action Learning: Research and Practice, 9(2), 209–218.
Vince, R., Abbey, G., & Langenhan, M. (2018). Finding critical action learning
through paradox: The role of action learning in the suppression and stimula-
tion of critical reflection. Management Learning, 49(1), 86–106.
Vosoughi, S., Roy, D., & Aral, S. (2018). The spread of true and false news online.
Science, 359 (6380), 1146–1151. Retrieved from www.sciencemag.org/about/
science-licenses-journal-article-reuse.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
190
190 References
Vurdelja, I. (2011). How leaders think: Measuring cognitive complexity in leading
organizational change (Doctoral dissertation). Antioch University, Yellow
Springs, OH.
Vygotsky, L. S. (1978). Mind in society: The development of higher psychological
processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wang, W., Yang, N., Li, X., Xiao, H., Gao, M., Yan, H., & Li, S. (2019). A
pathway analysis of exploring how HIV-related stigma affects social cap-
ital among people living with HIV/AIDS in China. Psychology, Health, &
Medicine, pub. online March 21, 2019.
Warwick, R., McCray, J., & Board, D. (2017). Bourdieu’s habitus and
field: Implications on the practice and theory of action learning. Action
Learning: Research and Practice, 14(2), 104–119.
Warzel, C. (2018). He predicted the 2016 fake news crisis. Now he’s worried
about an information apocalypse. Buzzfeed News. Retrieved from www
.buzzfeednews.com/article/charliewarzel/the-terrifying-future-of-fake-news.
Wason, P. C. (1960). On the failure to eliminate hypotheses in a conceptual task.
Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 12(1), 129–140.
Weick, K., & Putnam, T. (2006). Organizing for mindfulness: Eastern wisdom
and Western knowledge. Journal of Management Inquiry, 15(3), 274–287.
Weick, K., & Sutcliffe, K. (2006). Mindfulness and the quality of organizational
attention. Organization Science, 17(4), 514–524.
Welner, K. (2013). Consequential validity and the transformation of tests from
measurement tools to policy tools. Teachers College Record, 115(9). Retrieved
from https://nepc.colorado.edu/publication/TCR-Consequential-Validity.
Wenger, E. (1998). Communities of practice: Learning, meaning, and identity.
New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
(2000). Communities of practice and social learning systems. Organization,
7(2), 225–246.
Wergin, J. F. (2001). Beyond carrots and sticks: What really motivates faculty.
Liberal Education, 87(Winter), 50–53.
(2003). Departments that work: Building and sustaining cultures of excellence in
academic programs. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
(Ed.). (2007). Leadership in place: How academic professionals can find their lead-
ership voice. San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Wergin, J. F., & Alexandre, L. (2016). Differentiation and integration: Managing
the paradox in doctoral education. In P. Blessinger & D. Stockley
(Eds.), Emerging directions in doctoral Education (pp. 225–242). London,
UK: Emerald Group.
Wergin, J. F., Mazmanian, P., Miller, W., Papp, K., & Williams, W. (1988). CME
and change in practice: An alternative perspective. Journal of Continuing
Education in the Health Professions, 8, 147–159.
Will, G. F. (2018, September 12). Trigger warning: An embarrassing fragility on
college campuses. Washington Post.
Willer, R. (2016, September). How to have better political conversations [Video
File]. Retrieved from www.ted.com/talks/robb_willer_how_to_have_better_
political_conversations?language=en.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
191
References 191
Wilson, J. C. (2011). Service-learning and the development of empathy in US
college students. Education & Training, 53(2–3), 207–217.
Wilson, S. (1988). The “real self ” controversy: Toward an integration of human-
istic and interactionist theory. Journal of Humanistic Psychology, 28, 39–65.
Wlodkowski, R. (2008). Enhancing adult motivation to learn: A comprehensive
guide to teaching all adults (3rd ed.). San Francisco, CA: Jossey-Bass.
Wright, M., Skaggs, W., & Nielsen, F. A. (2016). The cerebellum. WikiJournal of
Medicine, 3(1). Retrieved from https://en.wikiversity.org/wiki/WikiJournal_
of_Medicine/The_Cerebellum.
Yeo, R., & Marquardt, M. (2010). Problems as building blocks for organiza-
tional learning: A roadmap for experiential inquiry. Group & Organization
Management, 35(3), 243–275.
Yorks, L. (2005). Adult Learning and the generation of new knowledge and
meaning: Creating liberating spaces for fostering adult learning through
practitioner-based collaborative action inquiry. Teachers College Record,
107(6), 1217–1244. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9620.2005.00511.x
Yorks, L., & Kasl, E. (2002). Toward a theory and practice for whole-person
learning: Reconceptualizing experience and the role of affect. Adult Education
Quarterly, 52(3), 176–192.
(2006). I know more than I can say: A taxonomy for using expressive ways
of knowing to foster transformative learning. Journal of Transformative
Education, 4(1), 43–64.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
192
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:22, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.011
193
Index
accountability, 69, 89, 96, 104, 132 diagnosis bias, 110, 111
ACT UP, 132 Dunning-Kruger effect, 12, 14
action research, 27, 166, 167 enabling vs. disabling, 163
adaptive, 57 exposure anxiety, 111
Alexandre, L., 142 intuitive beliefs, 14, 15, 53, 54, 87
analytic thinking, see critical thinking intuitive theories, 84
Apollo 13, 154 loss aversion, 61, 110, 111, 167
Argyris, C., viii, ix, 6, 49, 75, 81 patternicity, 13, 15
Aristotle, 19, 27, 52, 70, 86, 89, 112, 145 reductive thinking, 13, 14, 15, 55, 111
episteme, 27, 52, 70 Boal, A., 87, 122, 134
phronesis, 27, 28, 52, 70, 73 Theatre of the Oppressed, 134, 135
techne, 27, 52, 70, 86 Bourdieu, P., 50, 79, 120
art Brafman, O., 17, 110, 121
defined, 123 Brafman, R., 17, 110, 121
as cultural vaccination, 130 brain, anatomy of, 20–22
music as a tool for deep learning, 127 Brookfield, S., 75, 78
as path to community healing, 124 Brooks, D., 129
as pathway to deep learning, 137–138 Bruni, F., 150
performance as pathway to deep learning, Burns, J., 97
132–135
photography as tool for deep learning, 130 Cartesian thinking, 25
and politics, 135–137 challenge, 35, 36, 50, 52, 58, 59, 60, 63, 66, 67,
street art as tool for deep learning, 129 71, 140, 141
autonomy, 34, 40, 41, 43, 46, 60, 63, 65, 80, 104, adaptive, 60, 70, 77, 88, 98, 143, 172
137, 144, 150, 174 Challenger disaster, 162
cognition, ix, 6, 8, 16, 19, 22, 25, 27, 31, 49, 75,
Bacon, Francis, 9, 167 129
Baldwin, James, 127 embodied, 27
Bandura, A., 64, 92 cognitive dissonance, 7, 12, 15, 31, 36, 45, 51, 53,
Banksy, 129, 130, 131, 132, 135, 139n6 54, 60, 66
“Girl With a Balloon,” 129 cognitive science, 18
Barrett, L., theory of constructed emotion, 31 communities of practice, 100–102, 105, 143
Basseches, M., 147, 149, 152 community, 29, 34, 65, 74, 95, 101, 118, 124, 125,
bias, 2, 29, 60, 74, 137, 144, 163 130, 131, 134, 136, 137, 138, 144
affective, 54 competence, 35, 36, 40, 41, 46, 48, 58, 59,
belief persistence, 15, 16, 18, 110 63, 64, 66, 71, 82, 101, 105, 140, 141,
causal assumptions, 13, 15 143
confirmation/myside, 9, 10, 11, 12, 15, 18, 32, consciousness
45, 53, 110, 146, 163 defined, 84
confronting, 162–164 constructive developmentalism, 43–45
193
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:27, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.012
194
194 Index
constructive disorientation, x, 70, 74, 75, 84, discourse, x, 3, 88, 106, 108, 114, 115, 120, 121,
96, 108 121n4, 128, 138, 143, 144, 145, 159
barriers to, 146 active listening, 170, 171
defined, 57, 66 dialogic space, 169
enabling in others, 65, 71 maieutic discussion, 118
necessary conditions for, 66, 84, 101, 137, 141, disequilibrium, see constructive disorientation
159, 162 disorienting dilemma, 28, 29, 30, 32, 35, 38, 48,
through art, 126–129 53, 70, 84, 139, 146, 151, 158, 160, 162, 165
what makes disorientation Dissanayake, E., 125
constructive, 60–65 diversity, group, 14, 62, 90, 95, 96, 97, 99, 102,
critical theory, 79, 103 103, 104, 111, 118, 122, 129, 144, 154
Csikszentmihalyi, M. double-loop learning, 49
effort imperative, 59, 142 Dreyfus Affair, 10
flow theory, 58, 59, 66, 67, 69, 70, 71, 140, Dweck, C., 166
141, 142
addictive potential of, 59 Edelman, D., 132, 133
Edison, Thomas, 10
Damasio, A., 32, 33, 84 educative turbulence, 62
dance, as a tool for deep learning, 125, 129, 131, efficacy, viii, 34, 37n8, 40, 57, 60, 64, 65, 66, 71,
132, 174 78, 80, 104, 137, 165, 174
Davies, L., 57, 62, 80 Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 89
educative turbulence, 80 emotion, 1, 7, 19, 25, 33, 35, 49, 78, 86, 124, 148
deep learning mindset, 84, 87, 106, 138, 151, 156, role of, 16, 18, 25, 29, 31–32
160, 175 role of in deep learning, 122, 128
deep work, 68, 71, 73 empathic field, 129, 138, 139, 144, 174
dehumanized perception, 92 empathy, 90–94, 98, 106, 122, 126, 129, 136,
Dewey, J., x, 25, 26, 42, 43, 48, 50, 57, 58, 64, 169, 171
67, 73, 74, 75, 88, 96, 101, 108, 113, equilibrium, in learning, 110, 121, 123, 135, 136
116–119, 124, 139, 140, 154, 156n3, 158, Erenrich, S., 129
166 essential tensions, forms of
Art as Experience, 123–124 the center and the edge, 142–144
bourgeois democracy, 118 intuition and deliberation, 141
criteria of experience, 42 the self and the other, 144
intelligent action, 48, 74 experience, 15, 27, 41, 47, 74, 114, 164
learning and democracy, 109 aesthetic, ix, 125, 128, 129, 136, 138, 158, 173, 174
mis-education, 48, 96 exposure anxiety, 17, 110, 111
mis-educative, 26, 154
and open-mindedness, 118 Facebook, 4, 12, 111
routine action, 48 fake news, 1
dialectic, 43, 74, 118, 143, 144, 145, 149 Foucault, M., 112, 114, 115, 117, 119, 120, 121n4
definition, 145 Franklin, Benjamin, 19
dialectical thinking, 145–150, 156 Freire, P., 26, 29, 48, 49, 87, 90, 108, 112, 113, 114,
and aesthetic experience, 148 115, 117, 119, 134
defined, 146 banking model, 26, 48
developing, 150–154 conscientization, 112, 134, 138
elements of, 152 praxis, 29, 49, 113
systems thinking as necessary Friedman, Thomas, 3, 4
for, 154
vs. absolutist and relativistic Gadamer, H., 163
thinking, 146 Gadotti, M., 155
vs. other forms of thought, 147 Galileo, 19, 25
dialectics, 52 goal displacement, 69
dialogue, see discourse Graham, Martha, 125
diffusion by envy, 175 Greene, M., 125
Dirkx, J., 125 growth mindset, 166
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:27, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.012
195
Index 195
Habermas, J., learning
distantiation, 76 action, 67, 71, 89, 98–100, 103, 105, 108
habitus, 50, 52, 120 critical, 104
Haidt, J., 7, 16, 94, 95, 97, 112 adaptive, 36n1, 57, 58, 60, 61, 63, 67, 68, 70,
Handy, Charles, 4 77, 79, 80, 88, 104, 137, 139n2, 154, 176
Hegel, G., 145 adult, ix, 28, 30, 58, 66, 114, 119, 126
hegemonic assumptions, 78, 79, 102, 103, 104, collaborative, 98
172 cooperative, 167
Heifetz, R., 57, 76, 98, 107n4, 108, 140, 155, 176 deep
productive zone of disequilibrium, 58, 65, barriers to, 31, 47, 48, 68, 74, 89, 98, 111, 155
66, 140 definition of, vii, viii, 158
Highlander Research and Education Center, necessary conditions for, ix, x, 32, 35, 38,
113, 119 49, 52, 60, 62, 64, 68, 70, 73, 84, 86, 90,
Horton, M., 112, 113, 114, 115, 117, 119 95, 119, 121, 129, 141, 159
Hovland, C., 127, 139n4 as a political act, 109
Hume, David, 6 as political consciousness, 112–116
why so hard, 6–18
Ibsen, Henrik, 38 why so important, 1–6
identity double-loop, 75, 77
defined, 33 drive-by, 1, 19, 32, 68, 70, 175
immunity to change, 17, 61, 84, 153, 167 embodied, 27, 131, 138, 159, 173
competing commitments, 17 experiential, 25–31, 89, 113, 166
incidental learning, see intuitive learning, experiential learning cycle, 26
learning:intuitive incidental, 81
Infocalypse, 3, 4 instrumental, 84
International Center for the Advancement of intuitive, 84, 87, 97, 138, 159
Scientific Literacy, 23 mindful, 76, 79, 84, 85, 87, 138, 141, 142, 151,
intuition, 15, 28, 73, 141, 164 156
intuitive learning, 85–87 mytho-poetic, 125
observational, 92
James, W., 25 organizational, 50, 104, 108, 115
Jarvis, C., 93 participatory, 97–100
Jarvis, P., 27, 49 physiology of, 22
JR, 130, 131, 132, 135 problem-based, 67, 83, 89
self-directed, 48, 50, 67
Kahneman, D., 8, 9, 14, 24, 28, 68, 71, 73, 74, single-loop, 75, 76
110, 111, 141, 164 transformative, viii, ix, x, 28, 29, 30, 44, 55,
Kant, Immanuel, 4, 145, 156n4 70, 76, 86, 87, 88, 105, 108, 125, 126, 128
Kasl, E., 128, 129, 144, 174 workplace, 81
Kegan, R., 5, 17, 18, 43, 44, 45, 46, 47, 48, 50, 61, learning organization, 50, 81
70, 144, 149, 153, 154, 160, 164, 167 learning paradox, 153–154
self-authoring, 45, 50, 53 Lee, Spike, 127
socialized mind, 45, 47, 53 Lessing, D., 160
Kierkegaard, S., 168, 175 Lindeman, E., 75
knowing Littlewood’s Law of Miracles, 13
embodied, 86 loss aversion, 17
Kolb, D., 26, 67
Marshall, J., 166
Labouvie-Vief, G., 148, 150 Marx, K., 145
Ladkin, D., 39, 46, 80, 92, 161 Maslow, A., 39, 40
Lahey, L., 17, 18, 61, 70, 153, 154, 164, 167 Maslow’s hierarchy, 39, 40
Langer, E., 53 self-actualization, 40
leadership meaning schemes, see mental models
embodied, 92 mental models, ix, 14, 23, 28, 31, 35, 36, 75, 81,
transformative, 97 84, 153, 159, 161
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:27, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.012
196
196 Index
Mercier, H., 10, 11, 15, 16, 77, 94, 95, 96, 97, RAND Corporation, 2
107n3 rationalist delusion, 7, 112
Meyerson, D., 173 rationality, 6, 29, 145, see reasoning
Mezirow, J., 28, 29, 44, 45, 48, 70, 73, 75, 76, reasoning, 8, 9, 11, 13, 15, 16, 77, 78, 89, 95, 112
77, 78, 96 recognition, 34, 65, 105
assimilative learning, 78 reductive thinking, 111
objective reframing, 77 reflection, 4, 26, 29, 31, 32, 49, 50, 53, 73, 74, 86,
subjective reframing, 77 98, 100, 103, 114, 119, 124, 131, 142, 153
mindfulness, 46, 53, 54, 76, 79, 84, 141, 153, 155, criteria for, 74
156, 158, 160–162, 166, 168, 174 critical, ix, x, 4, 29, 88, 108, 113, 114, 115, 119,
defined, 53 121, 126, 128, 129, 141, 146, 153, 156, 159,
minimal power differentials, 102–105 176
Mitra, A., 130, 131 characteristics of, 75
Moore’s Law, 3 and development of expertise, 81–84
motivation, 33, 40, 41, 58, 63, 78, 105, 159 and mindful learning, 78
autonomous, 63, 65, 66, 67, 69, 70, 104 defined, 73
characteristics of, 33 on practice, 81
defined, 33 relatedness, 40, 41, 46, 60, 64, 80, 88, 95, 104,
intrinsic, 60, 62–65, 67, 70, 71, 79, 104, 137, 137, 150
174 Riefenstahl, L., 136
and learning in adults, 32–35 Riegel, K., 148, 149
organizational, 64 Rogers, Carl, 91
Myers, V., 162, 164 Roosevelt, Eleanor, 88
Rowe, N., 131
Newman, M., 99 Rule, P., 169
Newport, C., 68 rumor cascades, 3
Nisbet, R., 143
Nussbaum, M., 31 Scharmer, O., 157n11, 160, 166
Schön, D., 49, 60, 75, 81, 83, 176
order response, 61, 169, 173 reflection in action, 49
organizational mindlessness, 80, 161 technical rationality, 60, 77
self, the, 38, 46, 52, 63, 84, 88, 89, 91, 144, 149,
Palmer, P., 34 150, 164, 165
Parks, R., 119 essentialist views of, 39–42
parrèsia, 120, 121 interactionist views of, 42–45
Pauling, L., 10 reflected best self, 41
Piaget, J., 43, 147 self-actualization, 40, 88
Picasso, P., 128 self-determination theory, 40, 43, 46, 63, 65, 67,
Polanyi, M., 85 88, 95, 150
polarized attitudes, 18 self-development theory, 40
political capital Senge, P., 38, 50, 51, 65, 75, 108, 140, 155
defined, 111 creative tension, 51, 57, 65, 66, 140
politics, 4, 74, 103, 105, 106, 108, 114, 115, 120, personal mastery, 50, 51
121, 121n4, 138, 143 shallow learning, see drive-by learning
defined, x, 109 shallow work, 68
harnessing power of, 172–173 Sherif, M., 127, 139n4
Popper, K., 73 Shermer, M., 6, 9
positive psychology, 40 Shore, Z., 17, 110, 111
post-truth, 1 Shtulman, A., 15
practice-based research, 27 Shulman, L., 175
procedural justice, 120, 121, 135 Sinclair, A., 161, 163
project premortem, 168 social, 94–97
prospective hindsight, 167 social capital, 80, 90, 98, 101, 102, 104, 106, 111,
Putnam, R., 95, 96, 168 118, 121, 132, 144, 159, 169, 171
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:27, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.012
197
Index 197
social learning field, 138 Twitter, 1, 3, 14, 68, 111
social learning systems, 101, 102, 103, 143 Tzu, L., 140, 145, 146, 168
Socrates, x, 4, 38, 145
Sperber, D., 10, 11, 15, 16, 77, 94, 95, 96, 97, Ubuntu, 150
107n3 Uhl-Bien, M., 61, 119, 169
Staples, M., 122, 127
Staw, B., 64 Vaill, P., 5, 38, 47, 48, 49, 50, 81, 83, 98, 105, 161
strategic planning, 51, 69, 71 institutional learning, 5, 6, 48, 81
synapses, see brain permanent white water, 5, 6, 47, 48, 50
systems sensing, 155 reflective beginner, 49, 51, 83, 98, 161
reflexive learning, 50
tacit knowledge, 83, 85, 148 Vince, R., 103, 104
Tao Te Ching, 145, 168 Vurdejla, I., 152
Tart, C., 46, 157n12, 161 Vygotsky, L.
tempered radicals, 173 scaffolding, 58, 105
Tetlock, P., 96, 97 zone of proximal development, 58, 66, 67, 140
thought leadership, 175–176
Torbert, W. Weick, K., 161, 162
action inquiry, 46 Wenger, E., 100, 101, 102, 143, 169
action logics, 47 Wergin, J., 34, 63, 83, 86, 129, 142, 171, 175
conventional, 47, 51 Will, George, 121n2
postconventional, 47, 50, 51, 53, 147 Willer, R., 91, 94
liberating structures, 98 wisdom, 28, 52, 143, 145, 148
Treasure, J., 170 Wlodkowski, R., 33, 34, 35, 93, 94
truth decay, 1
Tuchman, B., 18n4, 110 Yorks, L., 97, 98, 99, 100, 107n6, 128, 129, 144,
Twain, Mark, 19, 68 174
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:27, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.012
198
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. University of Western Ontario, on 13 Dec 2019 at 15:04:27, subject to the Cambridge Core
terms of use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781108647786.012