Speech, Media, and Ethics - The Limits of Free Expression
Speech, Media, and Ethics - The Limits of Free Expression
Raphael Cohen-Almagor
Speech, Media and Ethics
This page intentionally left blank
Speech, Media and Ethics
The Limits of Free Expression
Critical Studies on Freedom of Expression, Freedom of
the Press and the Public’s Right to Know
Raphael Cohen-Almagor
© Raphael Cohen-Almagor 2001
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
10 09 08 07 06 05 04 03 02 01
Foreword ix
Acknowledgements xi
Introduction xiii
Notes 166
Index 212
ix
x Foreword
Geoffrey Marshall
The Queen’s College, Oxford
Acknowledgements
xi
This page intentionally left blank
Introduction
xiii
xiv Introduction
and many argue that the essence of the First Amendment is to guaran-
tee a free and uncontrolled marketplace of ideas. This book will address
the question of proper boundaries.
The boundaries are designed to promote the values of respect for
others, and not harming others. Liberal ideology places the individual
at the centre: all liberal reasoning derives from seeing the individual as
the focus of analysis, and all its reasoning is aimed at the advancement
and development of the individual which, in turn, would result in the
progress of society. The tradition evolving from the philosophical
thought of John Locke (1632–1704), Thomas Paine (1737–1809), Alexis
de Tocqueville (1805–59), John Stuart Mill (1806–73) and, in our time,
John Rawls and Ronald Dworkin, places the individual, in contrast to
the collective, at the centre of analysis, viewing the state as a mere
instrument to serve the interests of the individual. The liberal state is
conceptualized as a means of protecting society from external attacks, a
framework regulating the implementation of the law for the prosperity
of the citizens, a sophisticated tool to ensure individual rights.
One assumption of the liberal ideology that this book contests is the
assumption of universalism. The hypotheses advanced in this book
and the conclusions reached are limited to modern democracies emerg-
ing during the last one hundred years or so. I believe that there are
some basic universal needs that all people wish to secure such as food,
raiment, and shelter. I believe that sexual drives are universal and that
people need to have some sleep to be able continue functioning. I also
believe that we should strive to universalise moral principles. But soci-
ologically speaking we cannot ignore the fact that universal values do
not underlie all societies. Some societies reject the moral notions of lib-
erty, tolerance, equity, and justice that liberal democracies promote.
Thus my concern is with liberal democracies which perceive human
beings as ends and which respect autonomy and variety. The argu-
ments are relevant to other countries, but because non-democratic
countries do not accept the basic liberal principles, because their prin-
ciples do not encourage autonomy, individualism, pluralism, and
openness, and their behaviour is alien to the concepts of human dig-
nity and caring, one can assume that the discussion will fall on deaf
ears. Non-liberal societies, based on authoritative conceptions and
principles, deserve a separate analysis.
That said, one of the problems of any political system is that
the principles which underlie and characterize it might also, through
their application, endanger it and bring about its destruction. This
contention is obvious when totalitarian/authoritarian regimes are
Introduction xv
The fourth chapter is concerned with the powers of the press coun-
cils in Great Britain, Canada, and Israel. It shows the inherent deficien-
cies of the councils and proposes some fundamental changes. It is
impossible to have voluntary councils, with limited budgets, and yet to
expect from them serious work. It is also not feasible to hope that the
councils, sponsored by the media, could effectively criticize their spon-
sors without fear that they might be harmed if their adjudication is not
to the liking of editors and publishers. And it is quite pointless to speak
of the desired idea and practice of self-regulation without equipping
the relevant organization, the press council, with significant powers of
sanction. Here I compare the press councils in the three democracies
and outline practical recommendations for modifications.
These chapters propose recommendations for better, more ethical
media. To paraphrase the words of Tom Kent, who headed the Canadian
Royal Commission on Newspapers in 1980, the necessary motto for
reformers, in this as in other matters, is: Be prepared for the day when
some conjunction of circumstances creates a will for change. Then
practical ideas will be handy. If this is understood by some of the peo-
ple who recognize democracy’s need for a better information service
from the press, the working principles offered here will be of use.7
The Appendix, co-authored with Itzhak Yanovitzky, is also concerned
with media ethics and the limits of freedom of expression. However,
this chapter differs from all the others in two important respects: (1) it
is an empirical study based on short telephone interviews with a rela-
tively large sample of people; (2) because it describes and analyses a
public poll that was conducted in Israel, it is difficult to suggest gener-
alizations that will be true for other countries.
The essay examines public attitudes regarding the conduct of the
media. Emphasis is given to the difference between the ‘ought’ and the
‘is’; that is, in the eyes of the Jewish public,8 what should the roles of
the media be? How do the media behave in reality? What are the main
factors that motivate the conduct of the media? The article also probes
the effect of different sociodemographic characteristics (gender, educa-
tion, religiousness, ethnic origins, and economic status) on public atti-
tudes in Israel.
A public poll was conducted among Israeli-Jews (N:501). It showed
that most people accept the premise of the public’s right to know as the
general principle that should guide the media and that does guide the
media in practice. The findings reveal that the only issue in which
the ‘ought’ received a lower score than the ‘is’ was the publication of
scoops. In other words, the public thought that the media were paying
xx Introduction
too much attention to this factor in their conduct, and that the drive
for scoops should be less prominent in their reporting. The most
important factor that should guide the conduct of the media in the
eyes of the public was observing state security. The second most impor-
tant factor that should guide the conduct of the media was objectivity.
The Israeli-Jewish public sampled here thought that the media should
invest more effort in trying to be objective in their reporting. The only
guiding factor for the media in which the difference between the
‘ought’ and the ‘is’ was relatively small was the public’s right to know.
In other words, the public thought that the media more or less operate
in the name of the public’s right to know, as they should in theory. In
addition, the Israeli-Jewish public believed that the media should invest
more effort in safeguarding individual privacy and social responsibility.
The data further show that education and religiousness have moder-
ate effects on the perception of the media. The more educated have
higher expectations from the media than the less educated, and reli-
gious Jews tend to be more disenchanted with regard to the conduct of
the media than secular Jews.
In sum, all the chapters discuss basic human rights and the limits of
free expression in liberal democratic societies. Specifically they address
the issue of democratic constraints and limits, which has not been
treated adequately by the literature.
This book is the result of work that started a decade ago. I would like to
express gratitude to friends and colleagues who conversed with me on
pertinent questions, who read parts, or all of my writings, and who
supported this project in various ways. Isaiah Berlin was a kind sup-
porter. I greatly miss his friendship, advice, and the intellectual aspira-
tion he offered me when we used to meet in his room at All Souls
College, Oxford. I am deeply thankful to Geoffrey Marshall, Wilfrid
Knapp, Bob O’Neill, David Heyd, Eric Barendt, Ed Lambeth, Jim
Weinstein, Jack Pole, Dave Boeyink, Ken Karst, Rick Abel, and Sam
Lehman-Wilzig. I am also indebted to Wayne Sumner, Ronald
Dworkin, David Feldman, Yitzhak Zamir, Haim Zadok, Aharon Barak,
Zelman Cowen, Adam Roberts, Dick Moon, Valerie Alia, Georg Nolte,
Eike-Henner Kluge, David Lepofsky, Ron Robin, Gabriel Weimann,
Jonathan Cohen, Rivki Ribak, Cliff Christians, Hugh Stephenson,
David Allen, Art Hobson, David Goldberg, Ejan Mackaay, Godfrey
Hodgson, Jan Sieckmann, and Conrad Winn for their thoughtful
Introduction xxi
Introduction
The aim of this chapter is to confront the ethical question of the con-
straints of speech. Focus is put on the harm or the offence caused by
the speech in question: can we say that sometimes the harm or the
offence brought about by a certain speech constitutes such an injury
that it cannot be tolerated? More specifically, under what conditions
can preventing offence provide adequate reason for limiting freedom
of expression?
The plan for confronting these issues is the following. The discussion
is divided into two major parts: theoretical and practical. In the first
part, I shall try to formulate the restrictions on freedom of expression
in the clearest and most precise fashion possible. Too vague and overly
broad a definition might lead to administrative abuse on the part of
the government in its attempt to silence ‘inconvenient’ views. An
imprecise definition might have a snowballing effect, paving the
way for a syndrome whereby freedom of speech might become the
exception rather than the rule. Moreover, the restrictions cannot be
occasional. We have to seek a criterion that could serve both as an eval-
uative guideline and be suitable for a range of cases, covering different
types of speech (racist, ethnic, religious, and so on). In this quest I shall
avail myself of the Millian theory on liberty, which continues to
inspire the free speech literature, discussing in brief the well-known
Harm Principle, and then proceed by formulating the Offence
Principle.
In the practical part of the essay I shall attend to a hate speech case,
which arouses much controversy, the Skokie affair, evaluating the court
decision in the light of the two principles. My suggestion will be that
3
4 Freedom of Expression
there are grounds for abridging expression not only when the speech is
intended to bring about physical harm, but also when it is designed to
inflict psychological offence, which is morally on a par with physical
harm, provided that the circumstances are such that the target group
cannot avoid being exposed to it. The term ‘morally on a par with physi-
cal harm’ is intended to mean that just as we view the infliction of physi-
cal pain as a wrongful deed, seeing it as the right and the duty of the
state to prohibit such an infliction, so should we set boundaries to
expressions designed to cause psychological offence to some target group.
It will be argued that in either case, when physical harm or psychological
offence is inflicted upon others, four considerations are pertinent:
Mill proffered two main qualifications for the immunity which free-
dom of expression should, as a general rule, enjoy, and in an earlier
article concerning freedom of the press he formulated two other quali-
fications.6 He did not introduce them systematically, but in an ad hoc
way, allowing for interference in what he conceived to be special cases.
The first qualification proposed in On Liberty is concerned with the
case of instigative speech. The second qualification considers the case
of indecent conduct that is performed in public. Let us first examine
the case of instigation.
As a consequentialist, Mill acknowledged that speech loses its immu-
nity when it constitutes instigation to some harmful action. In his
corn-dealer example, Mill asserted that opinions lose their absolute
immunity when the circumstances in which they are expressed are
such as to constitute by their expression a positive instigation to some
mischievous act. Thus, the opinion that corn dealers are starvers of the
poor may be prevented from being delivered orally to ‘an excited mob
assembled before the house of a corn-dealer, or when handed about
among the same mob in the form of a placard’.7 But, that same opin-
ion ought to go unmolested when simply circulated through the press.
Accordingly we may deduce that Mill considered as instigation a
speech that aims to lead to some mischievous action in circumstances
which are conducive to the taking of that action. It seems that in
instances such as that of the corn dealer, Mill would regard certain
speeches as instigation irrespective of whether overt harmful action
follows. Though he did not explicitly say this, Mill implied that the
intention to lead people to take a harmful action constitutes an instiga-
tion.8 However, advocacy that does not induce someone to take an
action, but which is voiced as a matter of ethical conviction, is pro-
tected under Mill’s theory. This is one of his major contributions to the
free speech literature. Mill was the first to distinguish between speech
(or discussion) as a matter of ethical conviction and instigation.
6 Freedom of Expression
Argument number one: any speech, which instigates (in the sense of
meeting the four criteria of content, manner, intention, and circum-
stances) to cause physical harm to certain individuals or groups, ought
to be curtailed. Note that this argument is a much more decisive ver-
sion of the Millian Harm Principle.14
Feinberg explains that like the word ‘harm’, the word ‘offence’ has
both a general and a specifically normative sense, the former including
in its reference any or all of a miscellany of disliked mental states (dis-
gust, shame, hurt, anxiety, and so on), while the latter refers to those
states only when caused by the wrongful (right violating) conduct of
others. He postulates that offence takes place when three criteria are
present: one is offended when (a) one suffers a disliked state, and
(b) one attributes that state to the wrongful conduct of another, and
(c) one resents the other for his role in causing one to be in that state.22
Feinberg maintains that the seriousness of the offensiveness will be
determined by three standards: (1) ‘the extent of offensive standard’ –
meaning the intensity and durability of the repugnance produced, and
the extent to which repugnance could be anticipated to be the general
reaction of strangers to the conduct displayed; (2) ‘the reasonable avoid-
ability standard’ – which refers to the ease with which unwilling
10 Freedom of Expression
witnesses can avoid the offensive displays; and (3) ‘the Volenti
standard’ – which considers whether or not the witnesses have willingly
assumed the risk of being offended either through curiosity or the antic-
ipation of pleasure.23 Standards (2) and (3) are of relevance when we
examine the circumstances in which an offensive speech is expressed.
Feinberg categorically asserts that offence is a less serious thing than
harm, and thus ignores the possibility that psychological offences
might amount to physical harm, with the same serious implications.
The next section specifically reflects on this subject through considera-
tion of Feinberg’s standards. Here, however, if we return to Mill’s sec-
ond qualification, we may say that morally wrong actions which
concern others cause one to suffer a disliked state, which one attributes
to the doer’s conduct. Consequently one resents the doer for his acts.
Nevertheless, offences against decency are problematic, since what is
offensive to one may not be regarded as offensive at all by another. If
we want to make the Offence Principle an intelligible principle, the
offence has to be explicit, and it has to be more than emotional dis-
tress, inconvenience, embarrassment, or annoyance. We cannot outlaw
everything that causes some sort of offence to others. If the Offence
Principle is broadened to include annoyance, it becomes too weak to
serve as a guideline in political theory, for almost every action can be
said to cause some nuisance to others. Cultural norms and prejudices,
for instance, might irritate some people. Liberal views may cause some
discomfort to conservatives; and conservative opinions might distress
liberals. Some, for instance, might be offended when hearing a woman
shouting commands, or just by the sight of black and white people
holding hands. This is not to say that these sorts of behaviour should
be curbed because of some people who are ‘over sensitive’ to gender or
interracial relations. Similarly, if someone is easily offended by porno-
graphic material, one can easily avoid the pain by not buying maga-
zines marked by the warning: ‘The content may be offensive to some.’
Under Feinberg’s ‘reasonable avoidability’ and ‘Volenti’ standards the
offence cannot be considered serious. Injuries, to be restricted under
the Offence Principle, must involve serious offence to be infringed. By
‘serious offence’ it is meant that consideration has to be given to the
‘reasonable avoidability’, and the ‘Volenti’ as well as the ‘extent of
offensive’ standards. The repugnance produced has to be severe so as to
cause an irremediable offence, which might affect the ability of the
listeners to function in their lives.
Let me consider in some more detail Feinberg’s ‘reasonable avoidabil-
ity standard’. Under this standard and Mill’s argument regarding public
Harm Principle, Offence Principle, and Hate Speech 11
to accept the principled line of reasoning evolves from two basic con-
siderations. First, I do not see why verbal attacks on race, colour, reli-
gion, and so on, should be regarded as a unique type of speech that
does not deserve protection. I find it difficult to see why racist expres-
sions should be thought different from verbal attacks on one’s most
fundamental ethical and moral convictions – as, for instance, in the
abortion or the euthanasia cases. I do not see why dignity or equal
respect and concern is so much at stake in the former than in the latter.
Second, there is lack of agreement on the meaning of the term
‘racism’. Different countries and forums put different types of speech
under the heading of ‘racism’. By excluding racist expressions we might
open the way to curtail expressions that we may want to defend. For
instance, Zionism was condemned as a form of racism, so accordingly
anyone who expresses his desire to live in Zion (Israel) might be consid-
ered a racist by some. This claim is less strong than the preceding, for
we can define exactly what sorts of speech should be put under ‘racism’.
However, the argument is in place because in applying common terms
from one place to another, definition might be lost on the way.
Consequently, my intention is to formulate general criteria to be
applied consistently not only in cases of racial hatred, but also in other
categories of offensive speech. Any speech, be it on religious, ethnic,
cultural, national, social, or moral grounds, should be placed within
the confines of the two principles that are suggested.27 Speech that
instigates causing immediate harm to the target group, and speech that
is designed to offend the sensibilities of the target group – in circum-
stances that are bound to expose the target group to a serious offence
(which is morally on a par with physical pain) – should be restricted.
Background
What came to be known as ‘the Skokie case’ began in April 1977, when
Frank Collin, the leader of the National Socialist Party of America
(NSPA) announced that a march would be held in Skokie, one of the
suburbs of Chicago, inhabited mostly by Jews, some hundreds of them
being survivors of Nazi concentration camps.28 The Skokie residents
obtained an injunction in court that banned the march. Referring to
the Brandenburg case, they contended that the display of the Nazi uni-
form and the swastika were the symbolic equivalents of a public call to
kill all Jews, and consequently that it constituted a ‘direct incitement
to immediate mass murder’.29 After a long legal struggle, which lasted
Harm Principle, Offence Principle, and Hate Speech 13
until January 1978, the Illinois Supreme Court, in a seven to one deci-
sion, ruled in favour of Collin.30 The main argument was the ‘content
neutrality rule’ according to which political speech shall not be
abridged because of its content, even if that content is verbally abusive.
Speech can be restricted only when it interferes in a physical way with
other legitimate activities; when it is thrust upon a ‘captive’ audience,
or when it directly incites immediate harmful conduct. Otherwise, no
matter what the content of the speech, the intention of the speaker,
and the impact of the speech on noncaptive listeners, the speech is
protected under the First Amendment to the Constitution.31
The Court dismissed the main arguments of the residents of Skokie,
declaring that the display of the swastika was symbolic political
speech, which was intended to convey the ideas of the NSPA, even if
these ideas were offensive. Similarly it was argued that the plaintiffs’
wearing uniforms need not meet standards of acceptability. The judges
further concluded that anticipation of a hostile audience could not
justify prior restraint or restrict speech, when that audience was not
‘captive’. Freedom of speech cannot be abridged because the listeners
are intolerant of its content.32
would have to see the swastika, the Nazi uniform, and so on; and if not
attending, it would have been as if to allow Nazism to pass, and pass in
their own vicinity. Skokie exemplifies the democratic ‘catch’ in a vivid
manner: the same liberty that is granted to Nazis to exercise their belief
that espouses hatred and malicious speech might endanger their target
group that wishes to maintain their peaceful life and protect what they
conceive as a fundamental right not to be harassed by hate mongers.
Acceptance of the ‘avoidability standard’ only criticizes the main
argument of the Illinois Supreme Court. It does not in itself constitute
sufficient grounds to imply that the Nazi right to freedom of expres-
sion had to be curtailed in that instance. What I have tried to establish
until now is that the seriousness of the offence was severe according to
‘the Volenti standard’ and ‘the reasonable avoidability standard’. Now
there is still a need to clarify the scope of ‘the extent of the offence
standard’, and explain how serious the offence has to be for it to be
liable to restriction. The fact that Skokie was not a case of instigation
might have been a sufficient reason to protect the expression and allow
the march, unless we can say that the expression in itself constitutes
pain that could be considered morally on a par with physical harm. In
other words, while it is true that Skokie could not fall within the
confines of the Harm Principle, nevertheless, if strong argument were
provided that the very utterance of the Nazi speech constitutes psycho-
logical damage that could be equated with physical pain, then a strong
case might be provided against tolerance under the Offence Principle,
and in accordance with ‘the extent of offence standard’. Then we may
hold, contrary to Feinberg’s presupposition, that an offence might be
as serious as harm.43
them. He does not acknowledge that people also have feelings, drives,
and emotions, which are sometimes so powerful as to dominate their
view regarding a certain object, or a phenomenon, or other people. He
is not willing to concede that a personal trauma, for example, might
prevent an autonomous person, who is usually capable of reason and
making choices, from developing a rational line of thought about the
causes of his or her trauma. As far as Haiman is concerned, the anguish
experienced by those exposed to scenes that remind people of their
trauma is a price that must be paid for freedom of speech. He admits
that it is difficult not to seem callous in holding this position, but he
‘must take that risk and so argue’.46 Otherwise, those who display Nazi
symbols would have to be prohibited from appearing not only in front
of the Skokie Village Hall but in any other public place where it might
be expected that they would be seen by survivors of the Holocaust.
Furthermore, a television documentary examining and vividly portray-
ing neo-Nazi activity might have to be censored because of its impact
on Holocaust survivors.47
Both arguments, however, are not sufficient to explain why the law
should not deal with expressions which produce mental distress, for
the ‘avoidability standard’ takes the sting out of them. The Offence
Principle, as postulated, does not supply grounds to restrict either of
Haiman’s examples. One can switch one’s television off, or intention-
ally avoid an encounter with an offensive phenomenon in the city
centre. Either of these acts may be deemed necessary to keep one’s
peace of mind. However, an intentional going away from facing an
offensive phenomenon occurring in one’s own neighbourhood entails
more than mere avoidance. It may be seen by some as surrender. This
Haiman, like Feinberg and others, fails to understand.
With regard to the second issue, the distinction between annoyance
or some emotional distress and a severe offence to one’s psyche is not
clear-cut and it is bound to awaken controversy. For the task obviously
requires professional judgements, which further complicates this issue.
These reasons, among others, have influenced the literature to the effect
that it lacks sufficient consideration regarding the potential psychologi-
cal injury that certain speech acts might cause. But these difficulties
should not make us overlook the issue. Rather, because we are aware of
the complexities that are involved, we must make the qualifications as
conclusive as possible and the requirements equally stringent, in order
not to open avenues to further suppression of freedom of expression.
As previously stated, we must insist that restrictions on freedom of
expression be as clear as possible, for otherwise they might become
18 Freedom of Expression
was just declared to restrict free speech. ‘Gross revulsion’ and ‘personally
abusive epithets’ make a more general standard for constraining free-
dom of speech. As said, one person might be offended simply at the
sight of black and white people holding hands. Another may feel gross
revulsion when watching a commercial featuring a woman in a bathing
suit. We cannot extend the scope of the Offence Principle so as to
include any potential reaction of disgust on the part of some people.
Therefore, we ought to insist on the more stringent requirement, that
which holds that restriction on freedom of speech under the Offence
Principle is permissible only if we can show that the speech in question
causes psychological offence, which may be equated with physical pain.
Now, however, we face the problem of making this distinction
between an offence which causes ‘emotional distress’, or is a ‘personal
affront’, and an offence which causes ‘psychological injury’ amounting
to physical pain, an intelligible distinction. It has been argued that
offensive acts in general cause unpleasant distressful psychological
states to one degree or another. To be offended is, by definition, to suf-
fer distress or anguish.52 It is, therefore, reiterated that the Offence
Principle allows infringement of freedom of speech only in specific
cases, when the damage is deemed irreversible. Skokie is a relevant case
because racist utterances, as stated before, have a damaging psycholog-
ical impact on the target group, which is difficult to overcome or to
reverse. Concentration camp survivors carry psychological scars with
them for the rest of their lives. Often they have sustained residual
organic and psychological damage, and find it difficult to cope with
any kind of stress, especially when it is imposed on them by malicious,
invidious Nazis who provoke them and wish to disturb their peace and
undermine their lives.53 Consequently it would appear that ‘the extent
of offence standard’ is satisfied to an extent that Feinberg himself does
not acknowledge when formulating his standards. In some instances
the seriousness of the offence is such that it can be viewed as morally
on a par with physical harm. A Nazi march in a Jewish neighbourhood
populated by Holocaust survivors is a case in point.
A further clarification is called for in order to make the argument
under the Offence Principle more precise. The Principle does not provide
grounds to restrict racial hatred as such. It insists that we should take
into consideration the circumstances in which the speech is made. In
this respect my view is somewhat different from criminal codes of some
European countries, such as Great Britain or Sweden.54 With regard to
the British stance, sections 5 and 18 of the Public Order Act 1986
are of specific relevance.55 Section 5 prohibits threatening, abusive,
20 Freedom of Expression
southern whites. The intentions of the civil rights marchers are not to
offend but to protect the rights of those who are discriminated against
by those who now claim that they are being offended. The right to free-
dom of speech is here exercised out of respect for others, aiming to
preach values that are in accordance with the moral codes of a liberal
society, not values which deny these accepted moral codes. Those who
are offended by the values adopted by the entire society implicitly
argue when wishing to prevent the demonstration that their problem is
not with the march as such. Rather, their problem is a matter of princi-
ple, which concerns their own place within a liberal society.
Hence, four major elements should be taken into account when we
come to restrict expression on the grounds of psychological offence:
the content of the expression; the tenor and the manner of the expres-
sion; the intentions and the motive of the speaker; and the objective
circumstances in which the advocacy is to take place. Accordingly we
can now lay down our second qualification of free speech. This restric-
tion is made under the Offence Principle. The argument is:
Argument number two: under the Offence Principle, when the con-
tent and/or manner of a certain speech is/are designed to cause a psycho-
logical offence to a certain target group, and the objective circumstances
are such that make the target group inescapably exposed to that offence,
then the speech in question has to be restricted.
Conclusion
Introduction
24
The Right to Demonstrate v. the Right to Privacy 25
Preserving the sanctity of the home, the one retreat to which men
and women can repair to escape from the tribulations of their daily
pursuits, is surely an important value. Our decisions reflect no lack
of solicitude for the right of an individual ‘to be let alone’ in the pri-
vacy of the home.10
always prevail.11 Having said this, we still should not impose sweeping
restrictions. We can surely understand why people prefer to voice their
opinion in front of public officials’ homes. Such conduct is undoubt-
edly relevant. We do not expect protesters against, say, raising taxes, to
picket outside the local theatre or zoo. It is understandable that they
will go to protest outside the house of the Prime Minister and the
Minister of Finance. Sometimes protest in a residential area constitutes
the most effective way of expressing an opinion because there protest-
ers can establish direct contact with the object of their protest, some-
thing they will find difficult to achieve in government precincts,
which are usually more protected. The picketing of the public official’s
home may make a more powerful impression upon him or her.
Moreover, the picketers may feel that picketing the home is the most
effective way to bring social conditions to the attention of the general
public or to obtain wider news coverage for their views.12 In deciding
whether to grant permission to carry out such a protest the police
should take into account the privacy of the public official, his or her
family, as well as the privacy interest of the public official’s neighbours.
But we should not hold as a general rule that the right to privacy
always overrides the right to voice an opinion next to his or her home.
So we are speaking here of two rights that come into conflict: the
right to picket or to demonstrate, derived from the right to freedom of
expression, as against the right to privacy. The degree to which inter-
ference in a public official’s privacy may be tolerated should be a func-
tion of his or her political, social or economic position in society. The
more prominent the position, the greater latitude we have for interfer-
ence with the public official’s privacy.13 We need to strike a balance
between the right to communicate and the right to be let alone. When
speaking of the right to be let alone I mainly focus on the public offi-
cial and his/her family. Some may feel that neighbours of officials
should enjoy that same right but I do not think this constitutes a
major consideration. Living next to a public figure entails obvious
advantages. People love to rub shoulders with public figures. I imagine
that one may be somewhat amused to meet one’s prime minister in the
garbage room and allow him or her to lift the lid for one’s rubbish.
Sometimes neighbours are in a better position to evaluate the news,
seeing with their own eyes things that are kept secret from the public.
It may also be assumed that not many neighbours, upon selling their
homes, will fail to highlight the fact that their neighbourhood is of
special repute owing to the famous public figure who resides there.
But, as with all things in life, you cannot have all pros and no cons.
28 Freedom of Expression
issues that concern the citizenry at large. They are not political figures
who need to be responsive to their public and explain the reasoning
behind a certain policy. Therefore the issue of picketing homes of doc-
tors is different and somewhat more complicated. Having said that,
I cannot agree with Justice O’Connor’s statement that because the pick-
eting prohibited by the ordinance is speech directed primarily at those
who are presumptively unwilling to receive it, the state has a substantial
and justifiable interest in banning it.29 If this were the rationale, then
no debate would ever be allowed in residential area. There would always
be someone who was not willing to hear criticism. Like Justices Brennan
and Marshall, I think that there might be room to regulate such picket-
ing but it should not be entirely prohibited.30 The picketers are entitled
to communicate their strong feelings to the doctor who performs
abortions and should have fair opportunity to convey their pro-life
statements. But they should not harass the doctor and his family, and
obviously they should not harm them.31 Regulation is legitimate.
Unqualified prohibition is not. In order for a regulation relating to
time, manner and place of expression to be enforced, the state must
show that its regulation is necessary to serve a compelling state interest,
and that it is narrowly tailored to achieve that end.32
The balancing between protecting the privacy of the home and free-
dom of expression is exemplified in Ramsey v. Edgepark where the Ohio
Court of Appeals said that regulation rather than prohibition is appropri-
ate. The court held that the trial court did not abuse its discretion when
it found appellants’ activities to be offensive to a reasonable person and
issued the injunction prohibiting appellants from intruding into
appellees’ privacy in that manner. However, the trial court did err when
it restricted appellants from picketing within 200 yards of appellees’
homes, as this restriction violates appellants’ First Amendment right to
disseminate information from a public forum, namely a public street.
Appellants have a right to picket in the neighbourhood, block or street
where appellees live. There is no invasion of privacy as long as the
picketers remain on public property and do not focus their activities
solely at a particular home.33
Obviously the government is entitled to use state powers to prevent
picketers from blocking, impeding, or inhibiting access to residential
premises. The government may also implement ordinances or injunc-
tions prohibiting petitioners from physically abusing, grabbing, intimi-
dating, harassing, touching, pushing, shoving, or assaulting persons
entering or leaving the premises.34 There is a judicially cognizable
difference between a legitimate attempt to pronounce views and to
The Right to Demonstrate v. the Right to Privacy 31
‘public people’ has been press harassment, not protest. In August 1996,
the Princess of Wales obtained an emergency injunction from the High
Court against Martin Stenning, a photographer who frequently trailed
the Princess on his motorcycle. The injunction barred Stenning from
approaching within 300 metres of her, communicating with her, harass-
ing her, interfering with her safety, security or wellbeing, or molesting
or assaulting her.68
As a matter of law, it is probable that the judge regarded the case as
involving a simple application of the principle set out in Burris v.
Azadani where the court appeared to hold that it had jurisdiction to
award an injunction in interlocutory proceedings to protect a litigant
against harassment even if the harassment would not have entitled the
litigant to damages by way of a final order.69 It is now becoming clearer
that there is a cause of action in tort in respect of harassment at
common law.
There have been cases where injunctions have been obtained to
restrain publication of photographs taken of the Princess and other
members of the royal family in intimate settings, by means of tele-
photo lenses, and so on. But the general rule is that the taking of pho-
tographs cannot in itself be controlled (except where it is likely to
cause a breach of the peace), unless the interference with the subject’s
life is so significant that it amounts to serious and probably intentional
harassment.70
As for political protests outside the private homes of politicians and
other public figures, these are simply not part of the overall British
political culture. If we observe this issue in historical perspective, dur-
ing the last century there were a few instances of such picketing. When
there was a major demonstration in Hyde Park near Prime Minister
Disraeli’s London home in July 1866, in connection with electoral
reform, there was great concern and the militia was summoned. A
month earlier, a demonstration favourable to Gladstone had taken
place outside his house (in Gladstone’s absence) in Carlton House
Terrace, following a meeting in Trafalgar Square.71 So such events were
not unheard of in the nineteenth century, but were regarded as excep-
tional and undesirable.
Peter Cook, a lecturer in legal history at the University of
Birmingham who specializes in the history of eighteenth and nine-
teenth century criminal law, points out in a personal communication
that there has been virtually no work done on newspapers’ and peace-
keepers’ records of protests at the houses of politicians. It is well
known that there were riots and other protests at the homes of major
The Right to Demonstrate v. the Right to Privacy 37
Conclusion
Preliminaries
This chapter deals with the right to compete in elections. The aim is to
review some of the decisions of the Israeli Central Elections Committee
and of the Supreme Court regarding disqualification of political
parties1 in Israel. The discussion is on two levels: philosophical and
judicial. On the first level two major questions are addressed: (a) when
should tolerance have its limits?; (b) what constraints on liberty should
be introduced in order to safeguard democracy? As for the judicial
level, here the focus lies on the issue of authority. Attention is given to
the written law and to existing normative considerations, which allow
justices exegetic latitude.
I commence discussion by reflecting on two milestone cases, Yeredor
and Neiman. While in Yeredor the court resorted to a principled posi-
tion, in Neiman the court preferred a consequentialist attitude of bal-
ancing between interests. Consequentialism has become a very
fashionable approach, especially among American justices and philoso-
phers. What is striking about it is that consequentialists are willing to
endure the costs of offensive speech now because of speculative fears of
the consequences of restriction. Hence, American liberals justify the
Skokie decision of the Illinois Supreme Court,2 saying that it helped the
cause of fighting racism in the United States and increased the aware-
ness of the general public regarding the Holocaust, yet at the same time
they give little or no consideration to the actual harm that might have
been inflicted on the Holocaust survivors of Skokie if the Nazis had
taken the option granted them to exercise (or rather to abuse) their First
Amendment right and march through this Jewish suburb of Chicago. As
described in Chapter 1, liberals warn that if we restrict speech, this
42
The Right to Participate in Elections 43
Guiding principles
Yeredor
The first important decision on the question whether a party should be
banned from participating in the elections was Yeredor.9 In Yeredor the
majority of the court addressed the issue of what should be the moral
limitations of tolerance. It explained that in order to avoid self-defeat
of democracy, it was necessary to introduce boundaries to the very
principles that underlie democracy, tolerance, and liberty. The Central
Elections Committee (CEC) decided to disqualify the Socialist List ‘for
the reason that this candidates list is an illegal organization, because its
initiators deny the integrity and the very existence of the State of
44 Freedom of Expression
which does not open its doors to acts of subversion under the cover
of legitimate parliamentary activity. As far as I am concerned,
regarding Israel, I am satisfied with a ‘self-defending democracy,’
and we have the tools to protect the existence of the State even
though we do not find them expressly specified in the Elections
Law.11
Just as a man does not have to agree to be killed, so a state too does
not have to agree to be destroyed and erased from the map. Its
judges are not allowed to sit back idly and to despair from the
absence of a positive rule of law when a plaintiff asks them for assis-
tance in order to bring an end to the State. Likewise no other state
authority should serve as an instrument in the hands of those
whose, perhaps sole, aim is the annihilation of the State.12
Neiman
The next milestone decision on this question of representation in parlia-
ment was decided 19 years later. In 1984, some weeks before the elec-
tions to the 12th Knesset were to take place, and in the light of the then
recent polls that showed that ‘Kach’, the quasi-fascist party of Rabbi Meir
Kahane, would succeed in entering the Knesset, the CEC decided not to
confirm ‘Kach’.15 It was argued that ‘Kach’ propounded racist and anti-
democratic principles; openly supported acts of terror; tried to kindle
hatred between different sections of the population; and that it intended
to violate religious sentiments and values of part of the state’s citizens.
In order to keep the ‘balance’ between the right and the left in par-
liament and to secure wide support for the disqualification decision,
the CEC also decided to ban the leftist ‘Progressive List for Peace’ (PLP)
on the grounds that the list contained subversive elements and tenden-
cies, and that central figures in the list identified with the enemies of
the state.16 Both ‘Kach’ and ‘PLP’ parties appealed to the Supreme
Court, which reversed the decisions of the CEC.17
All five justices in the appeal did not reject the idea of disqualifying
lists in order to defend democracy as such. They said that this measure
should be resorted to with caution, only in extraordinary cases. ‘Kach’
and the ‘PLP’ were not seen as such cases. Regarding the ‘PLP’, the
unanimous judgment was straightforward: the procedure used by the
CEC to disqualify the ‘PLP’ was seen as incorrect, in that it referred to
either unconvincing or old documents. The court was right in its
judgement. The ‘PLP’ ’s political platform did not differ significantly
from those of other parties that were allowed to compete in the elec-
tions, and no evidence brought before the court established that the
list constituted any danger to the state. But the decision concerning
‘Kach’ is less clear. The court should have used its authority to declare
that explicit antidemocratic ideas and aims cannot claim a right to be
represented in the Knesset.
The question of authority is strongly related to that concerning the
scope of tolerance and the restrictions on liberty. Constitutional mat-
ters in democratic societies frequently turn on the decision of the
courts; we must, therefore, examine the force of philosophical princi-
ples regarding societal norms and values, when the court formulates
judicial decisions in the absence of specific statutes empowering it to
act. This is the context in which we should consider the authority that
may be accorded to the court when it contemplates which democratic
methods of self-defence are to be resorted to on the basis of principles
underlying the constitutional text.
The Right to Participate in Elections 47
The role of the judge is also to set more defined standards for action
for both politicians and the courts when they are faced with constitu-
tional matters, especially where attacks on the very foundations of
democracy are concerned. Hence a scope exists for taking normative
constitutional principles into account. These principles may in some
‘hard cases’ convince the court to take a creative approach. Dworkin
explains that in hard cases, judges must choose between eligible inter-
pretations of some statute or line of cases by asking which shows the
community’s structure of institutions and decisions in a better light
from the standpoint of political morality. The judge’s decision will
reflect not only his or her opinions about justice and fairness but his or
her higher-order convictions about how these ideals should be com-
prised when they compete.18 Following Dworkin, I would say that two
sets of considerations inevitably play their part when judges come to
formulate a judgement. One set is related to the moral convictions
held by the judges, influenced by their personal upbringing and educa-
tional background, as well as by the tradition and values of the society
in which they live. The other is concerned with the specific legal his-
tory. Precedents and other legal facts are bound to limit the moral con-
siderations of judges but they should not exclude moral considerations
altogether. When faced with an unprecedented situation, in which
they are required to use their discretion to find a judicial solution to a
‘hard case’ (such as this one), judges should decide the case by inter-
preting the political structure of their community so as to find the best
possible justification, in principles of political morality, for the struc-
ture as a whole.19 Accordingly, if the right of people to be treated as
equals and not to be harmed by others can be defended only by creative
adjudication, then creativity is not only in order but necessary. This is
the case so long as the judge tries to make the creative decisions in line
with previous ones rather than starting in a new direction as if writing
on a clean slate. In my view, Neiman allowed room for unwritten values
of the judicial system to be taken into account. And if the court could
not find an answer in statute law and could not draw an analogy with
Yeredor, it could have referred to ‘the principles of freedom, justice,
equity, and peace’ as the law of Foundation of Law (1980) provides. The
court should have done so not only because of the alarming nature of
the Kahanist phenomenon, but also because questions concerning the
eligibility of a list to participate in the elections inevitably are con-
nected with granting legitimacy to the list in question.
None of the five justices raises this issue of licensing. In my view,
the issue concerning the eligibility of a list to compete in the elections
48 Freedom of Expression
along these lines, democracy has the right to defend itself and not to
allow that list representation in parliament to further its aims by legal
means. To ask democracy to place the means for its own destruction in
the hands of its potential destroyers is neither morally obligatory nor
morally coherent. Notice my emphasis on physical annihilation of the
state. That is, in the Israeli context, no sufficient grounds warrant dis-
qualification of a party that wishes to change the character of the state
from a Jewish state into, say, a Canaanite secular state, as distinguished
from aiming to destroy the Israeli State as such.
According to Justice Barak’s line of thought, endangering democracy
amounted to endangering the basic foundations of the state. Hence,
parties that wished to participate in the democratic rules of the game,
and to gain power to implement their ideas through legislation and
other democratic means, had first to accept democratic principles. As
Justice Bejski said: ‘Whoever claims rights in the name of democracy
must himself act in accordance with its rules.’22 However, Justice Barak
added a restrictive qualification to the Yeredor ruling: the ‘reasonable
possibility’ standard for danger, and therein lies my disagreement with
him. I do not share either Justice Shamgar’s or Justice Barak’s opinions
that in the face of such dangers a standard of some sort should be
applied in order to evaluate the danger, and it should then be decided
what defensive means to apply.
Justices Shamgar and Barak believed that all parties should enjoy the
right to be elected, including those who threatened the existence of
the state (Shamgar and Barak), or its democratic foundations (Barak),
unless the threat they posed was severe, and unless they had a reason-
able chance of translating their ideas into deeds. Their reasoning was
founded on balancing and evaluating probabilities, a process that in
this context raised substantial questions. But not just the process raises
doubts. The essential question is: why should we wait for the stage of
probable or reasonable possibility of danger to be reached, while the
list in question goes from strength to strength, and meanwhile its ideas
and acts undermine democracy and deliberately discriminate against
others? The courts acknowledged that ‘Kach’ ’s values were not compat-
ible with the fundamental values of democracy, and that it did not
reject the use of violence to further its aims. Even if we follow Justices
Shamgar’s and Barak’s reasoning which concentrates attention on cir-
cumstances, the increasing popularity of ‘Kach’ against a background
of severe economic problems, combined with societal and national
crises, posed a danger to Israeli democracy. It was not as if the political
platform of ‘Kach’ was dubious, or the intentions of its members were
50 Freedom of Expression
unclear, or they did not act in accordance with their declared aims. I
do not therefore see why such a list should be allowed representation
in parliament to help it achieve its purposes. More fundamentally, the
issue of defending democracy is a matter of moral principle, rather
than one that is contingent on the level or the proximity of the dan-
ger. Justice Barak preferred to consider circumstantial considerations,
thereby avoiding a discussion of the ethical constraints of liberty and
tolerance. I argue that moral restrictions deriving from the defence of
democracy necessitate the outlawing of antidemocratic lists. A similar
line of reasoning guided the framers of the European Convention on
Human Rights when they enacted Article 17, recognizing the necessity
of preventing specific groups from exploiting the principles enunciated
by the Convention in their own interests. Article 17 provides:
Legal measures
One year after the writing of the Neiman decision, the Knesset
decided to take legal measures to provide grounds for disqualification
of racist and/or anti-democratic parties. The Knesset amended the Basic
The Right to Participate in Elections 51
These provisions are also problematic because they state that a list
may be disqualified if any of the three grounds is ‘expressed or implied’.
The focus is on the word ‘implied’. Intentions can be implied, but activi-
ties speak for themselves. Unclear is how any one of the three categories
can be implied from attempts to bring it about. And if a list can be dis-
qualified just because one of the three issues may be implied from its
activities, or even from its purposes, then again the scope for curtailing
this fundamental right is too broad, and the slippery-slope syndrome
becomes tangible. On the other hand, the language of the laws is restric-
tive in the sense that it does not exclude racist platforms per se.
Section 7a served as the basis for the disqualification of ‘Kach’ in the
1988 elections. That year saw a boom in the number of requests to ban
parties. Altogether there were 21 (!) such requests. The ‘Kach’ represen-
tative initiated 12 of those requests. The CEC’s discussions revolved, in
the main, around two parties: the ‘PLP’ and ‘Kach’. Both of the deci-
sions reached the Supreme Court of Justice. In a divided 3 to 2 decision
the court approved the participation of ‘PLP’ in the elections. The
majority of the court was not convinced that there was conclusive evi-
dence to show that the political programme of ‘PLP’ was aimed at
bringing about the end of Israel as the state of the Jewish people.26 A
unanimous court, on the other hand, denied the ‘Kach’ appeal.27
Having the legal grounds as provided by Section 7a the court saw no
reason to accept the ‘Kach’ appeal.28
The same phenomenon reoccurred in 1992. Three parties were on
the CEC’s agenda: ‘Moledet’, and the two parties with almost identical
anti-Arab and theocratic political platforms – ‘Kach’ and ‘Kahane Is
Alive’. The Communist party, ‘Hadash’, asked to disqualify them, argu-
ing that they incited to racism and negated the democratic character of
Israel. The Civil Rights Movement, ‘Ratz’, joined ‘Hadash’ ’s request in
regard to ‘Kach’ and ‘Kahane Is Alive’. In the end, these two parties
were disqualified on the grounds of Section 7a.29
The next elections were held four years later, in 1996. The years
between 1992 and 1996 were of significant importance in the history
of Israel. On 13 September 1993 Israel and the Palestinian Liberation
Organisation (PLO) signed a peace agreement known as the Oslo
Accords. From that date Israel witnessed high-profile activity on the
part of the extreme right seeking to reverse the trend leading to peace.
The most vicious attack against Palestinians took place on 25 February
The Right to Participate in Elections 53
1994 when Dr Baruch Goldstein, candidate no. 3 on the ‘Kach’ list for
the 11th Knesset elections and designated to be the ‘Kach’ ’s representa-
tive on the Kiryat Arba council, entered the Cave of Machpellah (the
burial place of the Hebrew Patriarchs and their wives) in Hebron and
massacred in cold blood some 29 Palestinians praying in the mosque
inside the Cave. Following this murderous attack, on 13 September
1994, the government decided to outlaw both the ‘Kach’ and ‘Kahane Is
Alive’ movements.30 Before I proceed to examine the 1996 Supreme
Court’s decisions regarding disqualification of parties, let me reflect for a
moment on the outlawing measure, which is relevant to our discussion.
The decision to outlaw ‘Kach’ and ‘Kahane Is Alive’ was made in
accordance with the Prevention of Terrorism Ordinance. Section 1 of
the Prevention of Terrorism Ordinance (No. 33 of 1948) defines a ‘ter-
rorist organisation’ as ‘a body of persons resorting in its activities to
acts of violence calculated to cause death or injury to a person or to
threats of such acts of violence’.31 The Ordinance specifies the penal-
ties for activity and membership in such an organization. Section 2
holds, inter alia, that a person performing a function in the manage-
ment or instruction of a terrorist organization, or participating in the
deliberations or the framing of the decisions of a terrorist organization,
or delivering a propaganda speech on behalf of such an organization,
commits a criminal offence and is liable to maximum punishment of
20 years imprisonment. Mere membership in a terrorist organization is
liable to imprisonment for a term not exceeding five years (Section 3).
In addition, a person publishing praise, sympathy, or encouragement
for acts of violence calculated to cause death or injury, and a person
assisting the organization in its activities, is subject to criminal proceed-
ings and a maximum penalty of three years’ imprisonment (Section 4).
The outlawing of the ‘Kach’ and ‘Kahane Is Alive’ movements after
the atrocious attack at the Cave of Machpellah is yet another extreme
step Israel took in its struggle against Kahanism. It exhibited the gov-
ernment’s firm determination to foil further recurrence of murderous
attacks against Palestinians. In his opinion paper of 10 March 1994 to
Prime Minister Yitzhak Rabin, Attorney-General Michael Ben-Yair
explicitly wrote that
It is also aimed against public figures who express opinions that are
different from the opinions of the movements, and against the secu-
rity forces that prevent members of these movements from violating
the law and public order.
‘Yemin Israel’
‘Yemin Israel’ asked to be registered as a political party. The Parties’
Registrar received objections to this request, grounded on the above-
mentioned Section 5 of the Parties Law, 1992.36
In the case at hand, the Parties’ Registrar dismissed all objections to
the registration of ‘Yemin Israel’ and an appeal was made to the Supreme
Court which decided against it.37 The Parties’ Registrar reviewed the
objections and contested the view that the aims of ‘Yemin Israel’ consti-
tuted racism or incitement to racism. In his view, nothing in ‘Yemin
Israel’ ’s aims would necessarily lead to the negation of minorities’
rights. The Parties’ Registrar did not think that accepting Jewish law
principles would necessarily transform Israel into a halacha state, nor
would it result in negation of human and civic rights. The party was
entitled to pursue its ends as long as it acted within the legal frame-
work. Furthermore, its programme did not offend the right of non-
Jewish citizens to elect and be elected, nor did it constitute incitement
to racism.38
Let me note the following. ‘Yemin Israel’ ’s statement ‘the law and
constitution of the State of Israel is to be based on Jewish law’ is open
to interpretation. If the members of ‘Yemin Israel’ meant by this that
56 Freedom of Expression
the entire legal framework would be based only on Jewish law princi-
ples then Israel could no longer be considered a democracy. It would
then be transformed into a theocracy. But those who framed ‘Yemin
Israel’ ’s political platform never said that explicitly. Nowadays the legal
framework of Israel is based, inter alia, on principles of Jewish law, and
Israel can still be called a democracy.
However, I disagree with the Parties’ Registrar’s conclusion that the
party’s demand for an ‘oath of allegiance’ to the State of Israel as a
Jewish state does not offend the right of non-Jewish citizens to elect
and be elected. The Palestinian citizens of Israel can identify with the
democratic principles of Israel, with the spirit of liberty that is
enshrined in its institutions. They may appreciate, love, and identify
with certain aspects of Israeli culture (food, songs, dance, theatre, folk-
lore). They may love Israel’s beautiful location, enjoy strolling the
streets, visiting the natural spots Israel is blessed with, and finding time
for relaxation on its relatively long beaches. Some Palestinians may
admire Israel’s strength and advanced technology and others may trea-
sure the Holy places. But most of them would find it difficult to iden-
tify with the Jewish character of Israel. In the same way that Jewish
Americans would find it difficult to vow their allegiance to the United
States as a Christian nation and would protest such a demand, so the
Palestinian citizens have every right to protest against vowing alle-
giance to a religion they do not adhere to. Nevertheless, this does not
entail that ‘Yemin Israel’ should have been disqualified from registra-
tion. I contend that evidence should be produced that the party in
question is acting violently to promote its aims for it to be banned,
either from registration or for contesting elections.
‘Yemin Israel’s’ additional call for the ‘exchange of population’
between Jews and Palestinians can be seen as a guise for a transfer oper-
ation of Palestinians to Israel’s neighbouring countries. ‘Yemin Israel’
spoke of ‘consent’ of the people to be transferred but this consent was
not of the people concerned but between governments, the Israeli and
the Arab, over and above the heads of the people who would be asked
to leave. To my mind, the transfer programme is aimed at depriving
the Palestinians of their right to live in their place of origin, and it is
for the Supreme Court to address the question of whether this idea is
racist under the Penal Law. Unlike the Parties’ Registrar39 I think that
both the ‘oath of allegiance’ proposal and the ‘exchange of population’
programme are racist ideas. However, as noted before, Section 5 (2) of
the Parties Law, 1992, speaks of ‘incitement to racism’ rather than of
racism per se; therefore no sufficient ground existed to refuse the party’s
The Right to Participate in Elections 57
next to the State of Israel in its 1967 borders. The capital of the
Palestinian state would be east Jerusalem.’ The party also declared that
it would strive for a just solution to the refugee problem.54
The appellant argued that one should not read this statement as it is
but rather looks for the implied agenda. The ‘real’ aims of the party
were to settle for a two-state solution in the first instance and then
work to accomplish the further stage, which was the destruction of
Israel. Justice Cheshin was willing to accept that in evaluating the char-
acter and essence of a given party we should not examine only the for-
mal publications and the explicit agenda. Instead, we should strive to
unveil the real aims of the party, which might be camouflaged in a cal-
culated manner.55 However, a question arose as to whether the appel-
lant was in a position to prove that the destruction of Israel was,
indeed, the ‘real’ aim of the said party. The appellant based his reason-
ing on three interdependent arguments. The first argument was that
the Palestinian Liberation Organization (PLO) aimed at the destruction
of Israel, as declared, inter alia, in the Palestinian Covenant. Second,
the leader of the party in question, Ahmed Tibi, was identified with the
PLO. Consequently, Dr Tibi’s aim was similar to the PLO’s.56
In considering the arguments, Justice Cheshin held that the ends of
the PLO were revised. He mentioned the Oslo and Cairo accords signed
between Israel and the PLO; the explicit recognition of Israel by the
Chairman of the Palestinian Authority, Yassir Arafat; the explicit con-
demnation of violence and terrorism made by Chairman Arafat, and
Israel’s recognition of the PLO as the representative of the Palestinian
people. Justice Cheshin also questioned the argument that identified
Dr Tibi with the PLO. He agreed that Dr Tibi was the leader of the party
but noted that 120 people had founded the party and it was not at all
clear whether it was possible to identify the entire party with only one
person.57 Moreover, Justice Cheshin did not think that the appellant
succeeded in demonstrating that Dr Tibi could be identified with the
PLO. True, Dr Tibi served as a consultant to Yassir Arafat and the
Palestinian Authority. When asked about his activities Dr Tibi explained
that he was not a member of any of the PLO’s bodies, that his role as
consultant was limited to the peace process alone, and that he acted
voluntarily without asking for any reward. All he wanted was to help
bring about peace between the two nations. Justice Cheshin reviewed
in some detail Dr Tibi’s statements and saw no reason to question
them.58
Consequently, the appellant’s line of reasoning was quashed. No
valid evidence was presented to prove that the party in question, either
62 Freedom of Expression
Justice Cheshin did not accept this argument. He held that no crimi-
nal proceedings were opened against Dr Tibi; that the Attorney-General
reviewed this and similar arguments against Dr Tibi and decided not to
bring criminal charges against him; and that the Supreme Court was
asked to examine the Attorney-General’s decision and concluded that
the decision was reasonable.65 After all this, the court was not in a posi-
tion to hold that the party might serve as a cover for illegal activities.66
Justice Cheshin maintained that not a shred of evidence had been
adduced to show that party members might utilize the party for illegal
actions.67
Finally, Justice Cheshin probed the argument that the Parties’
Registrar should have disqualified the party owing to a clear conflict of
interests between Dr Tibi’s activities as a consultant to Chairman Arafat,
and his role as a head of a party that aimed to compete in the elections
for the Israeli Knesset. The argument was that Dr Tibi sought to
become a member of the Knesset who must uphold his allegiance to
the State of Israel, and at the same time wished to serve as a consultant
to the PLO whose interests conflicted with those of Israel. Dr Tibi
responded that once he presented his candidacy for the Knesset, and
the party was presented for the approval of the Central Election
Committee, he would then announce his resignation from his role as a
consultant.68
Justice Cheshin again reminded the appellant that Dr Tibi was,
indeed, the leader of the party and might be the most prominent figure
in the party. Nevertheless, the appellant sought to disqualify the entire
list, comprising 120 people, and not Dr Tibi alone. It was difficult to
deduce that the entire list should be disqualified because of only one
person. Having said that, Justice Cheshin felt compelled to address the
issue that was put to the court, whether the ‘conflict-of-interest’ ratio-
nale ( Justice Cheshin spoke of doctrine) constituted a ground for dis-
qualification. That issue consisted of two different questions: first,
whether the ‘conflict-of-interest’ rationale was included within Section 5
of the Parties Law; and second, assuming that it was not included
within Section 5, did the law permit the Registrar or the court to intro-
duce more grounds for disqualification, additional to those mentioned
in the law?69
As for the first question, Justice Cheshin opined that Section 5 did
not include limits to party’s registration solely on the ground of con-
flict of interest. The court was obliged to interpret the law narrowly,
but even a broad interpretation would not permit disqualification of
parties due to conflicts of interests.70 Justice Cheshin went on to
64 Freedom of Expression
address the second question and asserted conclusively that neither the
Registrar nor the court, was empowered to add or to subtract grounds
for disqualification.71
I find Justice Cheshin’s reasoning most compelling. I think he elo-
quently and masterfully analysed all the issues presented for the court’s
consideration. No wonder that Justice Cheshin’s colleagues did not
have anything to add to his skillful analysis. Justices Zvi Tal and
Yitzhak Zamir reflected in their brief judgments only on the side ques-
tion of the differences between Section 7a of Basic Law: The Knesset,
and Section 5 of the Parties Law. Justice Zamir acknowledged that this
in no way was the essential question before the court for deciding
whether or not the party in question should have been confirmed or
disqualified. Justice Tal added a minor reflection on whether the con-
tention that the ‘State of Israel is the state of all its citisens’ was as
innocent as the framers of the party in question pretended it to be. He
thought one might suspect that the hidden agenda was to reject the
Jewish character of the state. Nevertheless, Justice Tal maintained that
to disqualify a party we need clear, conclusive, and convincing evi-
dence, and this was not provided.72
Conclusion
Preliminaries
69
70 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
present. During the Lebanon War and after the massacre of hundreds
of Palestinians by Christian Phalangists in the Sabra and Shatilla
refugee camps in two harsh days (16–18 September 1982), a large
demonstration was held in Tel Aviv on 24 September. The shock and
horror of the tragic event led people to raise their voice in protest. The
following day the media reported that 400 000 people were present at
Kings of Israel Square. This became a magic figure, and the demonstra-
tion led the government to decide on the formation of an inquiry
commission (the Kahan Commission) to investigate the events in the
refugee camps and the extent of Israel’s involvement in the atrocious
massacre. This magic figure was later disputed, with the argument that
Kings of Israel Square is incapable of holding such a large number of
people. I do not argue that reporters were misled by officials about the
figure. If this was the case then the situation might be an interesting
study of the ‘politics of numbers’.16 Nor do I claim that the reporters
knew the figure was incorrect and told an outright lie. It seems that the
reporters were simply carried away in telling the story. They were so
impressed with the demonstration that an unsubstantiated exaggera-
tion made by some reporters turned out to be ‘a correct estimation’
with more emphasis on the term ‘estimation’ and less on the correct-
ness of the number.17 Accuracy and good faith on the part of the
reporter is desirable.18
In many instances journalists are not objective in their reporting
because they cannot avoid selecting and because they prefer to inter-
pret.19 In his comments on a draft of this paper, David Lepofsky argues
that in North American electronic media the line between reporting and
editorializing is rapidly collapsing. Television news reports on issues
often mix the two shamelessly without admitting it. Moreover, against
the general assumption I would like to suggest that objective reporting
in the sense of separating facts from values does not necessarily entail
ethical reporting. Another argument I wish to evince is that sometimes
journalists are not objective because there is a certain angle that they
want to highlight for various reasons, pertinent among them the
increase of ratings and sales. We can assume that each newspaper will try
to satisfy the taste and wants of its particular readership. Consideration
is given, inter alia, to major news items that cast a shadow over other
events; to preferences of politicians, celebrities, and others who influ-
ence agenda-setting; to cultural affinities of each paper’s readership,20 and
to the particular taste and preferences of the publisher or the editor who
is usually nominated by the publisher.21 John McManus22 analysed 34
case studies, each of a separate news account’s construction, at three
74 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
television stations in the western United States. His findings show objec-
tivity violations in 20 case studies, all classified as serving the self-interest
of the news organization or its parent corporation. In almost all of these
cases (18), the structure of the news organization either encouraged dis-
tortion or failed to correct obvious omissions and errors.
On many occasions the media consciously prefer not to be objective
in the sense of either providing a balanced portrayal of a given issue or
striving for accuracy in their reporting because they want to draw
attention to a specific problem, person, political platform, ideology,
dilemma, human story, mischief, and so on.23 Moreover, sometimes
their reporting is unconsciously subjective. They are not aware of tak-
ing sides in a debate by using certain terminology or by refraining from
using other terms. I will illustrate this argument below when discussing
the issue of cultural norms that justify murder. The interesting thing is
that most media people believe that they are being objective.
A poll was conducted among 50 journalists and 50 academics who
teach journalism in the United States. Forty-one journalists thought
that a connection existed between media ethics and objective report-
ing. Only nine journalists objected to the assumption. Forty-seven
journalists believed that objective reporting was something one could
achieve. Compare these figures with the responses of the educators.
Among those who taught journalism, 27 objected to the objectivity-
as-ethics assumption and 23 supported it. Forty-two educators out of
50 rejected the possibility of objective reporting. The level of scepti-
cism among the educators is noticeable.24
The journalists who supported the assumption saw their role as
providers of precise and unbiased reporting of a given event. This essay
holds that ethics sometimes requires biased or normative reporting.
The press, in their editorials and opinion columns, and the broadcast-
ing media in their analyses, should condemn practices that undermine
the basic values of democracy (see the discussion on terrorism and
racism infra). I would also suggest that journalists should be aware of
the limitations of their knowledge, which make them unaware of
manipulations performed without their notice. Sometimes journalists
unknowingly serve the interests of others.
Consider the following hypothetical yet realistic example. A brother
kills his sister because she ‘misbehaved’. A rumour that spread in the
Bedouin village that the girl was ‘too permissive’ in her attitude to
one boy in the village constituted sufficient reason to kill her so as to
defend family honour. The trial attracts wide public attention and a
reporter is sent to interview a leading specialist on the subject. The
Objective Reporting in the Media 75
specialist says that for reasons of sub judice and due process of law he
does not want to express an opinion with regard to this ‘cultural norm’
and the appropriate verdict for the killer. All he wants to do is to explain
the cultural grounds of such behaviour. He nevertheless speaks of ‘homi-
cide for family honour’. The journalist reports the interview in detail,
thinking that she has provided an objective account without noticing
that she has served the purposes of the specialist. We can assume that
those who condemn and criticise such conduct would speak of ‘murder’
rather than of ‘homicide’.25 Our journalist has provided a service to a
distinct approach without being aware of it. Similarly one should be
aware of the differences that exist between the terms ‘euthanasia’,
‘assisted suicide’, ‘mercy killing’, and ‘mercy murder’ in the field of med-
ical ethics.26 The very method of posing ethical questions, such as ‘Is
euthanasia wrong?’ assumes a certain moral assumption which – one is
right to presume – is totally different from the underlying reasoning of
someone whose question is, say, ‘Why should we legalise euthanasia?’.
A sports reporter who equates the football skills of an individual to
those of the legendary Brazilian player Pelé is making an evaluative
judgment by choosing to make this comparison with Pelé. In political
and social issues the very framing and phrasing of questions in them-
selves might involve moral claims that are evaluative and subjective.
Achievement of objective reporting free of biases is often rather
wishful thinking because journalists often cannot help being subjec-
tive. They have their own opinions, feelings, and attitudes with regard
to given subjects. They operate under compulsions, be it editorial pres-
sures, time constraints, priorities of the publisher, accessibility to lim-
ited channels of information, and the like. Journalists are sometimes
required by their editors to forego a story because it runs counter to the
interests of the publisher or of the editors. Journalists do not always
report misconduct of a politician they appreciate. They leave this to
their colleagues.27 Some journalists find it difficult to remain objective
when covering the deeds of a political group or of a sports team with
whom they identify. Others find it difficult to provide an objective
account, sometimes any account at all, of an ideological group which
they detest. They prefer not to provide it with any platform at all. One
such case reached the Israeli Supreme Court.
That is to say that the media may have an opinion, even a strong
opinion, regarding a certain issue. For instance, when doing a follow-
up to a rape story where clear evidence was produced during the trial
to prove the man’s guilt, the media do not and should not give equal
footing to the girl who was raped and to the convicted rapist. They
should not be impartial between the criminal and the victim. It is the
duty of the media to be partial, to condemn the rape, and to say
that the deed was repugnant. This is the only correct way of presenting
the moral case in hand. Likewise, it would be unthinkable to provide
an equal platform to Yigal Amir, the assassin of Prime Minister Yitzhak
Rabin, and to Leah Rabin, the Prime Minister’s widow. These two
examples are so repugnant that I hope they do not evoke any moral
dilemma. But when a moral dilemma arises, impartiality is required.
For instance, when reflecting on debatable moral questions such as the
abortion debate, the media see themselves committed to furnishing an
equal platform to both prolife and prochoice activists, and rightly so.
In arguing against moral neutrality when covering explicit immoral
conduct I advance several arguments. The first argument is one of
democracy. It holds that journalists are also citizens. They live within
the democratic realm and owe democracy their allegiance. Free speech
and free journalism exist because democracy makes them possible.
They flourish in a liberal environment and they would become extinct
in a coerced, anti-democratic society. Hence journalists are obliged to
sustain the environment that enables their liberties. They should
uphold and promote the basic values of democracy: not to harm
others, and to respect others.
The second argument is one of paternalism. It is wrong to assume
that all readers and spectators are able to differentiate between good
and evil, and that all beings are rational. The media need to be respon-
sible to those who are not fully rational, who are not able to discern
between values and mischiefs. Here I refer first and foremost to chil-
dren and youth. Violence and black-and-white slogans work better on
the youth than on mature people. The media should not simply
transmit attractions without a warning. They need to be aware of
the range of people who receive their communications. The rejection
of evil does not necessarily have to be made by the media per-
sonnel. The media could offer a platform for decisionmakers and
influential personalities to condemn detestable phenomena such as
racism. But where criminal murderers, terrorists, and hate mongers are
concerned the media are not obliged, in the name of objective
reporting, to provide quotations from both sides of a case to the
Objective Reporting in the Media 81
audience. We are not talking of equal sides who should enjoy equal
access to the media.
The third argument is one of social responsibility.38 It is, of course,
connected to the previous two arguments but it has to do more with
the shape and character of society that we wish to have. Jonathan
Kaufman and his colleagues at the Boston Globe prepared a series
attacking racial discrimination not merely because it was illegal but
because they had decided that discrimination made a bad city and they
wanted Boston to be ‘the best city it could be’.39
In a similar vein, the BBC regards impartiality as involving not
absolute neutrality or detachment from those basic moral or constitu-
tional beliefs upon which the nation’s life rests. For instance, ‘the BBC
does not feel obliged to be neutral as between truth and untruth, jus-
tice and injustice, freedom and slavery, compassion and cruelty, toler-
ance and intolerance.’40 Being a constitutional creation of Parliament,
the BBC could not be impartial towards the maintenance or dissolu-
tion of the nation or towards illegal behaviour.
John Merrill is among those who equate objective reporting with
ethical reporting.41 He thinks that reporters who make no judgments
are more ethical than those who do. Merrill asks rhetorically: ‘Why not
just report and let the chips fall where they may?’42 My conclusive
answer is: Because not worrying about the consequences of the report
is grossly unethical. Journalists should not merely seek stories, facts,
truth. Journalists as human beings, as citizens in a democracy, as peo-
ple who wish to ensure a good future for their children, have a respon-
sibility to bear. ‘Let the chips fall where they may’ reminds me of
the Leninist view (Lenin said: ‘When trees are felled, the chips will
fly’, thereby legitimising all acts of terror and violence against the
Tsar),43 stripped of responsibility, stripped of all ethical values and
commitments.44
Following the same logic, and in contrast to the demand for objec-
tivity on the part of the media that is often echoed, the media do not
have to be objective towards phenomena which contradict their basic
values. They do not have to be objective towards violence, terrorism,
racism, chauvinism, fascism, sexism, genocide and slavery.
The fourth and last argument is one of jurisprudence and law. In the
Canadian Keegstra case, Judge Quigley of the Alberta Court of Appeal
noted that persons maligned by hate propaganda might be stripped of
their sense of personal dignity and self-worth, while those whom the
hate monger seeks to influence are harmed because ‘it is beyond doubt
that breeding hate is detrimental to society for psychological and social
82 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
reasons and that it can easily create hostility and aggression which
leads to violence’.45 Later on, Keegstra appealed to the Canadian
Supreme Court without success. Chief Justice Dickson, who delivered
the opinion of the court, said that hate propaganda seriously threat-
ened both the enthusiasm with which the value of equality is accepted
and acted upon by society and the connection of target group mem-
bers to their community. The court depicted Keegstra as inflicting
injury on his target group, the Jews, and as striving to undermine wor-
thy communal aspirations. The language used by the court to describe
Keegstra was far from neutral or objective. On the contrary, it was
strong, negative, and extreme. Chief Justice Dickson explicitly stated
that there could be no real disagreement about the subject matter
of the messages and teachings communicated by the respondent,
Mr Keegstra: it was deeply offensive, hurtful, and damaging to target
group members, misleading to his listeners, and antithetical to the fur-
therance of tolerance and understanding in society. Those who pro-
moted hate speech were described as ‘hate mongers’ who advocated
their views with ‘inordinate vitriol’. Their aim was to ‘subvert’ and
‘repudiate’ and ‘undermine’ democracy, which they did with ‘unparal-
leled vigour’. Since their ideas were ‘anathemic’ and ‘inimical’ to
democracy, the court viewed them with ‘severe reprobation’. Chief
Justice Dickson asserted that expressions can work to undermine
Canadians’ commitment to democracy where employed to propagate
ideas anathemic to democratic values. Hate propaganda worked in just
such a way, arguing as it did for a society in which the democratic
process was subverted and individuals were denied respect and dignity
simply because of racial or religious characteristics. This brand of
expressive activity was thus wholly inimical to the democratic aspira-
tions of the free expression guarantee. In this manner, the court char-
acterized Keegstra as the enemy of democracy who did not deserve the
right to free speech to undermine the fundamental rights of others.46
The media should treat racists in a similar fashion.
I would also refer media professionals to two international covenants.
Article 20 (2) of the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights
states the following: ‘Any advocacy of national, racial or religious hatred
that constitutes incitement to discrimination, hostility or violence shall
be prohibited by law.’47 In turn, Article 4 of the International Convention
on the Elimination of All Forms of Racial Discrimination holds that
One of the issues on which the media should take a moral stand and
abandon objectivity in the sense of adherence to moral neutrality is
terrorism. Terrorism is defined here as the threat or employment of
indiscriminate violence for political, religious, or ideological purposes
by individuals or groups who are willing to justify all means to achieve
their goals. In the past, however, there have been incidents where ter-
rorists and heads of states were treated as equals. In 1985, during the
kidnapping of the TWA aeroplane to Lebanon, David Hartman of ABC
asked Nabih Berri, the leader of the Amal militia that was responsible
for the kidnapping, whether he had anything to say to President
Reagan. It was as if we were talking of two people negotiating, each
having his own interests that are prima facie legitimate. Nothing was
said about the murderous deeds of Amal or about Berri’s responsibility
for them. Hartman failed to realize that his direct approach had done a
service to terrorism, that he was helping the terrorist convey his mes-
sage to the public and spread fear, and that in the final analysis this
kind of approach was not conducive to resolving such crises.49 This
violent and brutal spectacle ended with the terrorists having the upper
hand partly because of the negative involvement of the media. The
media are not outside the democratic realm. They are a necessary part
of it. Media organizations have to realize that democracy and terrorism
are mutually exclusive. A zero-sum game exists between democracy
and terror. The victory of one comes at the expense of the other.
Therefore, if the spirit and ideas of democracy are dear to media editors
and commentators and if they want democracy to prevail, they cannot
be objective or neutral vis-à-vis the terrorist phenomenon. Media per-
sonnel should take sides, distinguishing good from evil.
Moreover, yet again I emphasize that journalists should be conscious
of the terminology they employ in their reports. An ephemeral terrorist
organization is not ‘an army’. People who kidnap and murder randomly
84 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
Conclusion
This chapter has discussed the main dimensions often associated with
the concept of objectivity: accuracy, balance and fairness, truthfulness,
and moral neutrality. I have accepted and encouraged accuracy, fair-
ness, and truthfulness in reporting but at the same time warned against
common tendencies that involve partisan inclinations in media cover-
age, generating biases and imbalance.58 A distinction was made
between cases where journalists are not objective in their reporting
because they consciously prefer to be subjective and cases where jour-
nalists play into the hands of others and are manipulated by their
sources. It was further argued that in cases of conflict between ‘good
journalism’ and the effort of getting ‘good stories’ (which are often bad
stories), regrettably the latter will often enjoy precedence. I closed by
urging media professionals to adhere to the values of not harming
others and of respecting others.
These are basic ethical standards that sometimes require normative
and biased reporting. Furthermore, and for similar reasons, reporters
and editors are urged not to turn a deaf ear to moral considerations. It
is plausible to think that one can sell newspapers while maintaining
some moral standards. Morality is part and parcel of liberal society. It is
significant for the shaping of democracy. It is important for safeguard-
ing journalism. Moral journalism will necessitate acknowledgement
that objectivity is not an end in itself, that on certain matters objectiv-
ity in the sense of prescribing moral neutrality is a false idea. The
media should not observe moral neutrality in the face of wrong con-
ceptions and deeds, those that aim to harm others and that discrimi-
nate against certain segments of democracy. It is required that
journalists be accountable for what they report as well as for how they
report. Media organizations have to play the role of an umpire both in
the sense of applying just considerations when reviewing different con-
ceptions and also in trying to reconcile conflicting interests, claims,
and demands. This is a delicate task, one that demands integrity: bear-
ing in mind when making decisions the relevant considerations and
demands that concern society as a whole.
5
Ethical Boundaries of
Media Coverage1
Introduction
Some think that democracy should tolerate all forms and types of
speech, for liberals must not play the anti-liberal game. Those who
make this sweeping claim argue that liberal democracies are different
from other forms of government precisely because they do not use
non-liberal tools.2 I find this claim naive and dangerous. Democracy
should set rules for speech as well as for action. Those who choose to
break and to undermine the basic democratic rules should not be sur-
prised if, in the name of democratic self-defence, the legislature might
decide to disqualify them from participation in the democratic process.
I reiterate the importance of acknowledging the democratic ‘catch’ and
the need for setting limits to the democratic principles.
The two main ground rules of liberal democracy are to avoid harming
others and respect others as human beings; treating fellow citizens as
an end rather than a means to another end.3 The emphasis is on the
notion of basic equality, that all citizens are entitled to enjoy the same
civil and political rights. Every person should be able to pursue his/her
87
88 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
Discussions of the normative roles of the media must be held within the
context of the social system in which we live. Against the assumptions
that all societies share the same universal values and that it is possible
90 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
Media responsibility
citizens’ basic rights, and the conceptions of good that guide society.
The media pass on information to the people, some of this information
is vital for the people to fulfil their obligations as citizens.12 The dissem-
ination of information should take place only after some thought has
been invested in trying to evaluate its possible results.13 This is both a
consequentialist and moral claim. The Israeli media, for instance, often
make such an evaluation regarding security issues but they are far more
careless when the privacy of individuals is concerned. The media are
expected to act with responsibility and accountability with regard to all
pieces of information. Journalists who are not troubled with the likely
harmful consequences of their reports are amoral individuals.
Journalists who live in a democracy are not abstract humans living in
some sort of natural state. They are citizens who are expected to support
the democratic process by which they operate, and to exhibit responsibil-
ity in their reporting. Entry into the world of journalism does not
exempt citizens from this basic responsibility. On the contrary, because of
the extra burden of affecting the lives of others, journalists are expected
to show sensitivity and to adhere to what Ronald Dworkin terms ‘liberal
background rights’, first and foremost respect for others and not harming
others.14 Here it is relevant to mention that Section Five, ‘Fair Play’ of the
Sigma Delta Chi (the Society of Professional Journalists) Code says:
‘Journalists at all times will show respect for the dignity, privacy, rights
and well-being of people encountered in the course of gathering and
presenting the news’15 (see Summary, Suggestion A below).
Obviously the background rights mentioned above, respect for others
and not harming others, should not be held secondary to considerations
of profit and personal prestige. Journalism does not mean only increasing
the sales of a newspaper or promoting the ratings of certain broadcasts.16
Journalism also means seeing people as ends and not as means – a
Kantian deontological approach.17 It implies that the ability to control
the power lying in the hands of journalists when they are reporting in
the name of the people’s right to know might cause unjustified harm
to others (see Summary, Suggestion I below). I now need to clarify the
meaning of ‘justified’ and ‘unjustified’ harm.
When a person acts corruptly, and there is evidence to prove it, the
media are allowed, and even obliged, to look into the issue and bring it
to public scrutiny. This is what is meant when people refer to the media
as having a watchdog role in democracy.18 To fulfil this role, the media
are sometimes justified in using means of deception that constitute a seri-
ous invasion of privacy. They are justified, provided that they have care-
fully deliberated the reasons for and against deception, the short- and
Ethical Boundaries of Media Coverage 93
long-term implications for their work and for society at large. The story
needs to be socially significant, with its exposure resulting in reducing
evil and promoting public good; it has to be clear that the benefits
resulting from the unveiling of the story outweigh the harm involved in
resorting to deception (for instance, when the story involves a crime or
administrative corruption); other alternatives to telling the story have
been exhausted and have proved insufficient, making deception a nec-
essary means for exposing the crime, and the reporters inform the pub-
lic about the reasons that prompted their resort to deception.
Accordingly, resorting to deception is justified only in exceptional cir-
cumstances. In recent years, however, we have witnessed an increase in
the use of hidden cameras in investigative reporting to reveal corrup-
tion and misconduct. One of the most illustrative stories is ABC
PrimeTime’s report on the Food Lion supermarket chain. Small cameras
that were carefully camouflaged showed vivid pictures of unsanitary
practices such as repackaging out-of-date food to be sold as fresh. After
investigating the story from various sources, ABC went behind the
scenes with hidden cameras to support and document their findings.
Upon first viewing the ABC programme I thought that this was a sound
investigation of utmost importance, of vital public interest (securing
customers’ health), designed to prevent harm to individuals and, there-
fore, justified.19 Undoubtedly this was the best way to tell the gruesome
story. Oral evidence cannot enjoy the same credibility and cannot con-
vince as pictures can. After careful reflection I think that the story could
have been told without using deception. It could be argued that Section b
of the 1992 guidelines of the Society of Professional Journalism and the
Poynter Institute for media studies, namely exhausting all other alter-
natives for obtaining the same information, was not satisfied.20 The
food could have been sent to labs to examine whether it was edible and
workers could have been interviewed in detail and their lengthy reports
submitted. The footage would have been less vivid and powerful but it
would nevertheless have told the story.
Categorizing events
The next task is to determine what can be included within the bound-
aries of ethical and responsible media coverage. In this context we may
differentiate several types of events:
failed to recognize that when you open the door to the media, they
will enter in force, making the most of the opportunity.27
A further note should be made distinguishing between people
who choose to become social figures and people who provoke public
attention as a result of a deed or a speech but wish to retain their
anonymity. On occasion, people stumble unintentionally into the
spotlight, under circumstances that are not within their control.
When this phase passes, they wish to regain their privacy and return
to normal life. With regard to these people, the media should refrain
from intruding into their private lives and should respect their pri-
vacy, especially when exposure of certain details could harm one or
more of the people involved. Look, for instance, at the painful story
of Oliver Sipple, the ex-marine who knocked a gun out of the hands
of a would-be assassin of then American President Gerald Ford.
Shortly after the incident, the media revealed that Sipple was active in
the San Francisco gay community, a fact that had not been known to
Sipple’s family, who then broke off relations with him. His entire life
was shattered as a result of this publication. Sipple’s good deed caused
him extremely harmful consequences.28
3. Heightened events. These are events that actually take place but are
not dramatic enough for reporters, so they choose to embellish
them a little. In 1985, Armenian terrorists attacked the Turkish
embassy in Ottawa, Canada. They held hostages in the embassy and
during the siege of the building one of the reporters asked if the kid-
nappers had more specific demands besides the general ones they
had stated previously. In a different incident a reporter asked the
kidnappers if they intended to set an ultimatum, when none had
been stated earlier.29 Supposedly, that reporter was not satisfied with
the existing tension and he wished to raise its level (see Summary,
Suggestion F below).30
4. Exaggerated events and twisted stories. These are reports of events
that have taken place but the media try to tamper with their true
proportions or to twist the details.31 When a famous British diplo-
mat arrived in New York, he was warned by a friend about the
American reporters. One reporter asked him: ‘Do you plan to visit
any night clubs while you are in New York, Lord Selwyn?’ Selwyn
responded: ‘Are there any night clubs in New York?’ The following
morning, the reporter’s newspaper carried a story beginning ‘ “Are
there any night clubs in New York?” That was the first question
British diplomat Lord Selwyn asked yesterday as he arrived … ’32
98 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
The New York Post told the story of a man who allegedly raped a
three-year-old girl on a grassy knoll near a crowded Manhattan
highway while passing motorists stopped to watch. The incident
was described as ‘a chilling mix of apathy and voyeurism’. But the
story was untrue. Three motorists did stop to pursue the alleged
rapist, and traffic had simply stalled behind their abandoned cars.33
In the financial and administrative arenas, the media often use
large bold headlines to report the corrupt acts of any public figure sus-
pected of embezzling large sums of money from public funds. Long
after the scandal dissipates the charges are often dropped for lack of
evidence or the dimensions of the fraudulent act turn out to be much
smaller in scope than was initially reported. This is not to say that
there is no room for reporting such stories. They must be reported,
but in a responsible manner, proportionate to the suspicions, without
exaggeration. Obviously, all embezzlement must be condemned, but
proportion must be kept. There is a substantial difference between
headlines that hint of corruption and bribery, and reports of misman-
agement of public funds or auctions.34 If after a thorough investiga-
tion the accused is found innocent, the acquittal must be reported
with the same degree of emphasis used to report the original allega-
tions (see Summary, Suggestion F below).
5. Staged events are events that probably would not have occurred had
the media not been present. Here we must differentiate cases in
which the media were invited to cover an event from cases where
the media initiated events.
During Giscard d’Estaing’s presidency, he invited his courtyard’s
workers to breakfast at his house. We can assume that the president
would not have invited his workers to his table without first
summoning media coverage. It was a public relations act by the presi-
dent. Another incident is taken from the Israeli scene, when a female
member of The Knesset chose to take a dip in the Mediterranean
specifically on the Day of Atonement, the most sacred day on the
Jewish calendar. A photographer ‘just happened to be there’ and
snapped the shot showing the MK in her bikini.
Staged events can be harmful. In March 1983, Cecil Andrews
ignited himself in protest at local unemployment rates. A local tele-
vision crew that was invited in advance by Mr Andrews captured the
event. After the event, some searching questions were raised as to
the role of the television crew: would Mr Andrews have set himself
on fire had the cameras not been there? Probably not. It is reason-
able to expect a television crew to try to stop Mr Andrews from
Ethical Boundaries of Media Coverage 99
I argue that only real events and gossip belong in the realm of accept-
able coverage. In cases covering celebrities-for-a-day, rules of propriety
100 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
Unless newspaper editors, and those who control our radio and
television programs, recognise their responsibility and act accord-
ingly, they might well find themselves facing pressure for some
kind of legislative regulation over the reporting of terrorism and
the interviewing of terrorists.44
Summary
Introduction
105
106 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
the alarm signals that people in distress emit, and how to help them,
through reassurance and referral to the appropriate agencies where
mentally unbalanced people can get help and support. In addition,
responsibility requires that teenage and celebrity suicides be viewed as
special cases that demand extra caution. This is because teenagers are
attracted to sensational headlines about suicide, and are susceptible to
imitation, and because celebrity suicides are the most often imitated.5
In any event, live suicide should not be reported.
subway system, where quite often (I don’t know the exact figures
but certainly more than a handful of times every year) people com-
mit suicide by jumping under the train wheels. Most editors feel
that reporting on suicides encourages ‘copycats’, as people contem-
plating suicide are emotionally unstable anyway, a position I tend to
agree with. I do not believe individual cases of suicide are, in unre-
markable circumstances, news. Features about suicide and why peo-
ple do it are, of course, in a different category.8
du Quebec, said that the media may write about the phenomenon but
would, in principle, refrain from publishing individual stories. The
media were aware that coverage of suicide might influence young and
unstable people, and for fear of copycat cases they exercise caution.20
On the other hand, Mr Gord Sinclair, Director of News and Public
Affairs of CJD, the leading English radio station in Quebec, explained
that murder and crimes were covered, but suicide was not a crime, and
it was of no public interest. Hence, CJD did not cover suicide in princi-
ple. But if the suicide caused a traffic accident or involved a public fig-
ure, then the event would be covered because it had aspects that were
of public interest. Mr Sinclair did not mention any ethical reasoning in
his response. I then asked him directly whether he was concerned with
the contagious effects of such a report. His answer was blunt and clear:
he was not troubled with copycat considerations.21
This was also the answer given by Mr Al MacKay, Interim General
Manager of the Cable Public Affairs Channel. Mr MacKay explained
that suicide was a personal thing, not of public interest. In response to
my direct question on ethics he said they did not cover suicide because
of lack of public interest, not because of fear of copycat cases.22
The fear of copycat as grounds for refraining from coverage of suicide
was also forthrightly dismissed by Mr Michael C. Auger, political
columnist of Le Journal de Montreal, who served also as President of La
Federation Professionale des Journalistes. He explained that sporadic
suicides, like underground suicides, did not get reported simply because
they are of no public interest. On the other hand, if the media were
worried about an emerging phenomenon, then it was within their
duties to report it.23 I will elaborate on this issue later on.
Mr Auger’s answer brings us to consider the tricky issue of ‘public
interest’. When do the media find it justifiable to report suicide?
Which circumstances evoke such interest?
Public interest
The category of ‘public interest’ encompasses several dimensions.
These are grouped under the headings of fame, drama, and phenome-
non. Let me discuss and explain each of them.
Fame
If the person who committed suicide was a celebrity, a public figure in
Canada or the world at large, then the media would report the story.
This was the only qualification that Mr Lepofsky made to the assertion
110 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
that prompted this research, that the Canadian media do not, in prin-
ciple, cover suicide,24 an assertion he repeated in a more recent inter-
view.25 As we shall see infra, this assertion is incorrect. This is not the
only ground that justifies media coverage.
One example has to do with Roger Quilliot, a former French govern-
ment minister, who committed suicide at the age of 73 in Clermont-
Ferrand, where he was mayor for more than 20 years. The brief report
said that he was concerned about his ill health.26 I did not find any dis-
cussion that expressed anxieties in regard to reporting suicides of public
figures – politicians and celebrities – because these might be imitated. It
could be argued that relatively old people in a similar condition might
be triggered to consider suicide as an option following such reports.
Drama
If the story is dramatic, captures the public eye for some reason, then
public interest prescribes reporting. Professor Fred Fletcher said that
suicides were not reported unless they were dramatic (jumping off CN
Tower). Names of suicides were not reported unless the suicide evoked
public controversy or the suicides were public figures.27
The President of the Quebec Press Council, Michel Roy, gave an
example of an exceptional story, when one of the Quebec newspapers
covered in crude details the suicide of a person who ended his life by
jumping off a bridge. La Presse, the major newspaper of the region,
published a series of photos of the man and the stages of his fall.
Subsequently the father of that person wrote a very touching letter to
the paper, which La Presse published, and the public reaction to these
was very strong and negative. The public voiced its dissent and con-
demned the decision to publish the photos. In fact, the entire press
condemned the coverage.28 Here it should be noted that Le Journal de
Montreal, the most popular tabloid in Quebec, notorious for its menu
of sex, sport, and blood, had the photos and chose not to publish
them.29
I asked Mr Roy whether the Press Council was urged to interfere,
condemning the publication because it violated the Quebec Press
Council’s Rights and Responsibilities of the Press, which holds:
However, no complaint was made to the Quebec Press Council and the
Council did not intervene. Mr Roy said that the public reaction was so
fierce that there was no real need to interfere. He assumed that La
Presse understood the public message loud and clear.
The most sensational suicide reports are those involving murder and
suicide. In such reports we find ‘juicy stuff’, characteristics of murder
stories: more details in reddish colours. The stories usually involve a
person who kills another, most often someone he or she knows well,
and then commits suicide. Murder is of public interest and the suicide
is part of the package. One such story concerned a 34-year-old man
whom the police wanted for questioning in relation to the slaying of
his wife and two boys. The report said that the man, who had been in
a state of emotional turmoil, was found hanged.31 A similar story con-
cerned a woman who shot her two-year-old triplet sons and then com-
mitted suicide. This story was full of details usually spared in suicide
stories: it said, inter alia, that she shot the boys in the head with a semi-
automatic pistol and then turned the gun on herself; that one of the
boys survived the shooting but was declared brain dead; that the
woman became despondent after finding another woman’s underwear
in her boyfriend’s suitcase; that she went to the store asking for rat poi-
son, and that she told the shopkeeper she wanted to throw herself in
front of the cars, taking her children with her.32 The story was full of
details that were entirely unnecessary for reporting the incident in the
name of ‘newsworthiness’ and ‘public interest’. This is an example
where the press resorts to sensationalism and confuses interest with
curiosity. Such mixed stories that involve self-inflicted violence as well
as violence against other people, should have, for ethical reasons, more
the characteristics of a suicide story and less of a murder story. The
media should preserve the privacy of the people involved, and be
aware of the possible consequences of the report.
Phenomenon
I
If the suicide occurs among a certain group of people, suggesting that it
is not a sporadic instance of suicide but rather part of a more general
problem, then there is justification for reporting. For instance, farmer
112 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
that age group. Dr Christine Colin, a health ministry official, said there
was no single reason why young people in Quebec decided to end their
lives, and that environment and social situation could be factors.43
Mr Henry Aubin said that teenage suicide in Quebec was apparently
about the highest in the world. He argued that La Presse in particular
provided extensive coverage of this phenomenon, and that the French
press on the whole was quite immature in its reporting. It did not
think about the ramifications of their coverage, not realizing that such
extensive coverage might elicit copycat suicides.44
Reporting of teenage suicide is tricky. On the one hand, it is of
importance to inform the public about the phenomenon. The high
rate of suicide among teenagers in Quebec should be a major concern
to be discussed in order to find some solutions for the problem. On the
other hand, the media should be aware of the likely consequences of
such reporting. It could be the trigger for another suicide of a teenager
reading the report. The media should not exaggerate in their reporting
of the phenomenon. They should not provide details about the means
of suicide in particular stories, and they should provide details on how
to handle depression, the importance of counselling, and ways to find
assistance in coping with emotional distress. Of course, they should
refrain from covering live suicide.
Several people whom I met in Toronto mentioned one particular
story that received wide coverage in the Toronto newspapers.45 The
story had several public dimensions. It concerned a 17-year-old choir-
boy named Kenneth AuYeung who was involved in a schoolboy prank
which went wrong. Someone had altered a line in the yearbook
farewell message of the outgoing principal of his choir school, alluding
to his involvement in a recent sex abuse scandal. The new principal of
the school summoned Kenneth and five other members of the year-
book committee, saying that the administration was not amused by
jokes about sexual abuse, demanding that they confess or face criminal
charges. Next day, the principal also called an off-duty police officer to
exert more pressure on the boys. The officer offered them a choice: to
confess immediately or face criminal charges of public mischief.
Kenneth AuYeung confessed.
Kenneth was a smart, successful boy who made the honour roll every
year and had never been in trouble before. For him the event was fatal.
His entire world collapsed. Two hours after his investigation he jumped
to his death from the Bloor Street Viaduct in Toronto. The media
reported the story in detail, raising the following questions: was it
appropriate to call an off-duty police officer to put pressure on the
Media Coverage of Suicide 115
II Assisted suicide
Stories that involve two or more dimensions of renown figures, human
drama, and phenomenon are of greater interest for the media. One
such story that captured the public eye and evoked public controversy
was the story of Sue Rodriguez, a 42-year-old woman who suffered
from progressive Amyotrophic Lateral Sclerosis (ALS) and had been
informed by her physicians that her prognosis was poor. While remain-
ing fully aware and legally competent, she would lose her capacity to
move her limbs, to feed and clothe herself, to swallow, and eventually
to breathe without assistance. As her condition deteriorated,
Ms Rodriguez publicly expressed, through the media, a wish to have a
physician assist her in ending her life at a time of her choosing, when
she would be unable to do so herself, rather than waiting helplessly to
die by suffocation or choking. Ms Rodriguez sought to challenge the
Criminal Code of Canada prohibition on assisted suicide, on the
grounds that it violated the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms.
The specific section of the Criminal Code is 241(b): ‘Everyone who aids
or abets a person to commit suicide, whether suicide ensues or not, is
guilty of an indictable offence and liable to imprisonment for a term
not exceeding fourteen years.’51
The Canadian Supreme Court rejected Ms Rodriguez’s appeal in a 5
(Sopinka, La Forest, Gonthier, Iacobucci, and Major) to 4 (McLachlin,
L’Heureaux-Dube, Lamer, and Cory) decision.52 Without entering into
the legal aspects involved, this was the first time that such an appeal
reached the Supreme Court, hence it excited prolonged public debates
engaging all circles of society.53 The media took much interest in
Ms Rodriguez’s situation and discussed at length the ethical dilemma
involved in her motion to be assisted to die. Of course, here the issue is
of assisted suicide, and not of suicide per se, but it demonstrates the
kind of a story that the media seek: it involved the human drama of a
person who became public figure, whose story had ethical and societal
implications. On the whole, the media were quite sympathetic to the
appeal though they presented both sides of the controversy: those who
were in favour of it and those who opposed it, mainly for fear of slip-
pery slopes.54 Ms Rodriguez was well aware of the media interest in her
Media Coverage of Suicide 117
story and co-operated with them fully until her very last days. On
5 February 1994, one week prior to her death through assisted suicide,
she advised a member of the media that a physician had agreed to
assist her in her death but would not divulge his/her name or details of
the suicide.55
Assisted suicide is interesting because it is a most complicated issue,
with which society is struggling: it involves a person who is taking his
or her life, with the help of others. Does this help make the co-operat-
ing person a murderer? It is strange to speak of murder under these cir-
cumstances because the person concerned has asked to die. However,
the law failed to adequately address this question, so all such incidents
evoke media attention.56
A related story involves Erwin Krickhahn, who was dying of Lou
Gehrig’s disease. He invited the media to watch him commit suicide,
thereby hoping to persuade Parliament to legalize assisted suicide. If
the media were to attend the event, would their presence influence the
event itself? Is it their role to advance such a cause? In the end, only
the Toronto Sun said it would assign a reporter to the suicide. The other
media chose to abstain and said they would cover the story by assign-
ing reporters to a ‘deathwatch’ outside Krickhahn’s home. For most
journalists, his was a story not to cover. Krickhahn then decided to
postpone the event.57
Another form of assisted suicide that the media felt compelled to
report because of its public dimension was police-assisted suicide. The
press reported the story of Moshe Pergament who was shot by a police
officer. Later detectives discovered an envelope addressed ‘To the offi-
cer who shot me’. The note said: ‘I’m sorry to get you involved. I just
needed to die … ’. The Globe and Mail reported that no one knows how
many people manipulate police into killing them, but two recent stud-
ies suggest it is surprisingly common: researchers who examined hun-
dreds of police shootings in British Columbia and in Los Angeles
County ‘found that in at least 10 per cent of the cases, the dead and
wounded sought death’.58
This phenomenon is clearly newsworthy. In its report, the Globe
emphasized that every time police-assisted suicide happens, there are
victims on both sides of the gun. The newspaper wanted to draw pub-
lic attention to the phenomenon, and to warn the police that some
people would wish to have police-assisted suicide. The newspaper also
wanted to show the officers who were involved in this, against their
will, that it was a phenomenon of which they should be aware, and
that similar cases took place elsewhere.
118 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
The Israeli press does not follow such ethical guidelines. Suicide stories
are covered in minute detail. This was not always the case. During the
120 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
1960s the press usually did not report suicide for ethical reasons. It was
believed that suicide stories might encourage similar conduct. Even
when public figures were involved, the reports would say ‘died in tragic
circumstances’ without elaboration.67 Over the years, the press started
to use the term ‘suicide’, but suicide stories were reported in brief in
the back pages. The drastic change took place during the 1980s, with
the increased competition between the two tabloid newspapers, Yedioth
Ahronoth and Ma’ariv, when they discovered the sensational element in
suicide stories. They would compete in providing more ‘juicy’ details,
including the means of how the suicide was committed.
Weimann and Fishman conducted a systematic content analysis of
more than 430 suicide cases published in Ma’ariv and Yedioth from
1955 to 1990. They found that the number of press reports on suicide
declined during the 1960s, increased moderately during the 1970s, and
increased dramatically during the 1980s and 1990s, an increase of
more than 500 per cent compared with 1955, despite the relative con-
sistency of suicide acts in reality. Moreover, the space devoted to suicide
stories increased steadily, as did the prominence of the stories in the
paper. While between 1955 and 1970 no suicide story exceeded a half
page in length, the frequency of articles longer than that increased from
2 per cent of the articles in 1975 to 5.6 per cent in 1980, 6.1 per cent in
1985, and 7.2 per cent in 1990. More and more stories appeared on
page one; by 1990, almost 20 per cent of all articles published appeared
there. Weimann and Fishman suggest that the growing interest of the
press in reporting suicide may be related to the tough competition
between the two popular dailies, one that led to sensationalization of
the news and increased space devoted to violence and crime.68
The Israeli press has no qualms reporting the means by which sui-
cides are committed. Weimann and Fishman show that the press
focused on the more violent modes of suicides: shooting (28.8 per cent
of all reports), hanging (20.2 per cent), jumping from high buildings
(17.4 per cent). The less violent modes were less attractive for the press,
with taking poison (the most frequent mode of suicide among females)
comprising only 8.4 per cent of the stories, far below its actual fre-
quency (34.2 per cent among females, 20.9 per cent among males).69
As may be imagined, the motive for suicide also plays a major role in
the decision whether to report it or not. It is alarming to note that the
press operates in accordance with stereotypes that distort reality and
convey a false impression to readers. Weimann and Fishman have
shown that the reality perceived through the media is very different
from the reality formally portrayed by the official statistics. They chose
Media Coverage of Suicide 121
Conclusion
The main impetus for not reporting suicide in Canada over the years
has been that it is a private matter of no public interest. The media on
Media Coverage of Suicide 123
the whole are quite responsible and sensitive where suicide is con-
cerned. Principally, newspapers rarely report routine suicide. Many feel
that reporting on suicides should be done with utmost sensitivity
because people contemplating suicide are emotionally unstable and
may be influenced by the reports. Generally, the Canadian media do
not report methods of suicide; do not report underground suicide
(which apparently is common, especially in Toronto); do not show live
suicide; and do not publish suicide statistics. They do cover suicides of
public figures and when the case involves some wider dimensions.76
This study found that suicide is reported when it is identified as a prob-
lem among sections of the population: youth; native people; Aids
patients; farmers; abused children; the particular problem of Quebec;
and when the story involves different forms of assisted suicide. Quite
naturally, the suicides of well-known figures, whose stories encompass
unusual human drama and suggest a general problem that may affect
some segments of the population, are reported more widely.
The grounds for reporting such incidents of suicide are solid and well
reasoned. The public should be aware of phenomena that exceed the
emotional distress of one particular individual. At the same time, cau-
tion demands not to sensationalize suicide stories, both for the sake of
sensitivity towards the people concerned and awareness of the conse-
quences of suicide reporting. Media reporters and editors are not
abstract humans living in some sort of ‘state of nature’. They are citi-
zens who are expected to show responsibility in their reporting. Entry
into the industry of journalism does not exempt citizens from this
basic responsibility. On the contrary, because of the extra burden of
affecting the lives of others, media reporters and editors are expected
to show sensitivity and to adhere to the liberal background rights, first
and foremost respect for others and not harming others.77 Whenever
the media cover a suicide story, they should not provide details about
how the suicide was conducted, and they should not romanticize the
deed. I conclude with Section III of the Statement of Principles for
Canadian Daily Newspapers, which is pertinent:
Introduction
The aim of this chapter is to review the work of the press councils in
Britain, Canada, and Israel. Britain and Israel are unitary states, each
with its own national press council. Canada is a federal state with
provincial press councils in all provinces except Saskatchewan. The
British Press Council and the Press Councils in Canada, with the excep-
tion of Quebec, deal only with the written press. The Quebec Press
Council and the Israel Press Council deal with both the written and
electronic media.
The press councils, however, do not possess real ability to sanction
newspapers for misconduct. The espoused idea is of self-regulation by
the press. The essay considers the history of the press councils in
Britain, Canada, and Israel, analysing the ways they developed, their
work, and how they have achieved their current status. It is argued that
the existing situation in the three democracies is far from satisfactory,
and that the media should advance more elaborate mechanisms of self-
control, empowering the press councils with greater authority and
equipping them with substantive ability to sanction.
At the end of World War II, Britain and its politicians were concerned
about the growing tendency toward concentration of ownership
(which was much less marked then than it is now), and about the ethi-
cal standards of newspaper proprietors and journalists. In 1947, the
first Royal Commission (the Ross Commission) was set up ‘to inquire
124
The Work of the Press Councils 125
The manner and tone of the reporting of the private lives of the Prince
and Princess of Wales was without a doubt in breach of the Code of
Practice. The Code was supposed to provide the framework of decency
within which all competitors must work, but in practice the media,
most notably the tabloids, clearly betrayed it every day in their publi-
cations. Their ‘acceptance’ of the Code is still lip service at best.
A notable incident that took place in 1993 demonstrated the neces-
sity of such a regulatory body to be truly independent. Photographs of
Princess Diana exercising in a gym were published in the Daily Mirror.
The former chairperson of the PCC, Lord McGregor, was quick to act,
recommending that companies should not publish their advertize-
ments in the Mirror Group newspapers. This recommendation was way
beyond his authority. The PCC was supposed to be an adjudicating
body, with Lord McGregor as the presiding judge, but here he was giv-
ing his verdict not only before hearing the evidence but even before a
complaint had been made. In protest, the Mirror Group resigned from
the PCC. The resignation of such an influential media group was a
blow to the PCC and could have led to the breakdown of this body.
Lord McGregor realized the mistake he had made and within a day he
retreated from his suggestion and the Group rejoined the PCC.35
As long as the PCC is funded by the press, it will find it difficult to
bite, on justifiable grounds, the hand that feeds its activities.36 In this
regard Mr Charles Moore, Editor of the Daily Telegraph, commented:
The PCC is too frightened from the proprietors. See what happened
to Lord McGregor. McGregor acted foolishly, but it was not for the
132 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
proprietors to tell him to go. The proprietors could bully the PCC.
They can direct their papers to attack the PCC. They might threaten
to leave the PCC.37
On 31 August 1997, the Princess of Wales and her lover were killed
in Paris. Following her death many people in Britain called for a re-
examination of the tension between the right to freedom of expression
and the right to privacy.38 Voices for governmental regulations were
heard, but with greater public support. Lord Wakeham, chairperson of
the Press Complaints Commission, conceded that the PCC’s Code of
Practice might change after consultation with editors.39 On 24 October
1997 the Newspaper Publishers Association sent a memorandum to all
national and Sunday newspaper editors, asking for their thoughts on
the amended Code of Practice.40 Bearing in mind the attitude to the
Code of Practice of leading personalities within the press I do not think
that significant changes will take place. About two months after
Princess Diana’s tragic death, I had an interview with Mr Robin Esser,
consultant editor of the Daily Mail, who said that self-regulation was
working quite well in Britain, and that there was no need to vest the
PCC with more powers.41 In turn, Rupert Murdoch was asked in an
interview whether he had any regrets regarding the conduct of his
papers during Diana’s life. He answered that his only regret was that he
had to pay too much for the paparazzi photos.42
On 12 November 1997, the Guardian published the results of a public
poll on the work of the PCC and on the Royal family. One of the ques-
tions was: ‘Do you think the current system of self-regulation by the
Press Complaints Commission is working?’ Of the respondents, 30 per
cent thought that the system was working; 59 per cent thought the
system was not working, and 12 per cent answered ‘Don’t know’.
Another question addressed the issue of privacy: ‘Would you be in
favour or against the introduction of a law giving people the right to
privacy?’ In response, 87 per cent were in favour; 10 per cent were
opposed, and 3 per cent answered ‘Don’t know’.43 This poll shows the
disbelief that the public shares with regard to the work of the press,
and the growing support for taking legal steps to protect individual pri-
vacy against press intrusion.
the process takes too long, and that people want to have a much
quicker response. He argued that the Council was respected, and later
in the same interview he testified that ‘if we find a complaint justified,
the newspaper will keep an eye for a week, and then get back to
business’.61
Moreover, its seems that at least part of the council’s work is not sys-
tematic. Michael C. Auger, President of the Journalists Federation in
Quebec, argued that the body is comprised of volunteers who have no
time to invest in the work of the Council, and that there is no respect
for the work of the Quebec Press Council, not only because it is con-
ceived as a weak body, with limited authority and a small budget, but
also because it gave different adjudications on similar issues.62 David
Pritchard, who studied the work of the Quebec Press Council, asserted
that its jurisprudence has never been indexed in any meaningful way,
and that essential principles have never been systematically distilled
from the hundreds of cases. Pritchard quoted J. Serge Sasseville, who
handled all the Quebecor’s dealings with the Council: ‘They don’t
know what they’re doing!’. He concluded that the jurisprudence of the
Council is in a ‘state of chaos’. Because the Council’s staff had no effi-
cient way to review previous decisions, and the Council did not have
the means to undertake the crucial indexing, the Council’s decisions
rarely cited precedents. Consequently, it was impossible for news
organizations to know what the landmark cases were.63 Inconsistency
is a problem shared by the press councils in the three democracies
under review.
In Canada, as noted, most people are oblivious to the work of the
Press Councils. Some try to look at the councils’ work in a positive
way. While believing that the press councils have little long-term
impact, and acknowledging that their impact on the daily working
of newspapers is also limited, these people argue that press councils
serve as a useful outlet for complaints.64 Others are far more critical.
Professor Enn Raudsepp said that the press is obliged to publish a sum-
mary of the Press Council’s adjudication, and it publishes the adjudi-
cation in brief, with a tiny headline at the bottom of the page. He
maintained that nobody is compelled to join the council, and con-
cluded, ‘it is a totally useless organisation, a window dressing’.65
The foundations for the Israel Press Council were laid in 1956. As in
Britain, journalists realized that they had better do something themselves
The Work of the Press Councils 137
Within ten days the complaint and the response to it are supposed to
be examined by the Council’s Legal Advisor (usually by the deputy).
The examiner is required to decide within 21 days from the receipt of
the complaint whether to pass it on to the Chairperson of the Ethics
Tribunal. The examiner will do so only if he/she thinks that there has
been prima facie violation of the Code of Ethics. Before the complaint is
passed to the Chairperson of the Ethics Tribunal, the President of the
Council is entitled to seek ways to settle the complaint without adjudi-
cation, provided that the complainant and the media organization
concerned agree to this.83
Once the Chairperson of the Ethics Tribunal has received the com-
plaint, he/she appoints a tribunal comprised of three members: a
public representative (Chairperson of the tribunal), a journalists’ repre-
sentative, and a representative of the publishers and editors. The
Chairperson of the Ethics Tribunal makes sure that the representatives
of the journalists, publishers, and editors are not from the same media
organ that is the subject of the complaint. The Tribunal is required to
submit its ruling within 21 days. The ruling is not required to be unan-
imous. A majority vote is binding. In the event that one of the sides
wishes to appeal against the ruling, an appeal must be submitted
within ten days. It will be adjudicated by a larger panel of the Tribunal,
comprised of five or seven members nominated by the Chairperson of
the Ethics Tribunal. Two of the members of the appeal panel must be
public representatives. The other three are representatives of the jour-
nalists, publishers, and editors.84
The Tribunal is supposed to weigh the interests of the Press Council,
and to serve as a guide and a ‘watchdog’.85 Members of the Tribunal are
elected for a period of three years and can be re-elected. In the event
that a complaint is found justified, the Tribunal can decide on one of
the following measures against the journalist and/or his/her newspa-
per: to issue a warning; to reprimand; to ask that an apology be pub-
lished; or to suspend the newspaper from the Council for a limited
period of time.86 The punishment of suspension is not a very wise alter-
native given that the Council is striving to have all newspapers become
members. In the words of President Zadok, this punishment saws off
the bough one is sitting on.87 Attorney Uri Slonim, Chairperson of the
Ethics Tribunal from the day of its establishment, some three years ago,
and Mr Bezalel Eyal, Secretary-General of the Council, said that the
most extreme measure taken by the Tribunal was to ask the paper con-
cerned to publish the Tribunal’s adjudication in a prominent place. The
newspapers usually comply with the rulings of the Tribunal.88
The Work of the Press Councils 143
Code of 1996, and the formation and work of the Ethics Tribunal –
strengthened the position of the Council. One positive sign that
reflects the status of the Council is the fact that its representatives are
consulted whenever members of The Knesset contemplate new press
laws. However, the fact that there are growing number of efforts to
legislate laws that would limit press freedom is alarming. President
Zadok is striving to have publishers and editors see the importance of
sitting on the Council, rather than sending third-rate representatives.
Subsequently President Zadok plans to convince prominent journalists
to become members. Right now, activists of the Israel Union of
Journalists sit on the Council, and these are not necessarily the most
prominent people in the industry. After solving the issue of representa-
tion, President Zadok thinks it will be easier to secure more funding
from publishers, editors, and journalists, which will foster more effec-
tive work by the Council. He does not think that funding should be
secured outside the press industry, and would like to think that more
people in the industry are more appreciative of the necessity in having
a strong Press Council, especially in the face of a growing wave of
attempts to legislate illiberal press laws.93
As a member of the Council’s plenary, I am far from satisfied with its
current conduct. The Council meets irregularly, at best three times a
year. It does not raise its voice with regard to important ethical con-
cerns on the public agenda. Its budget is ridiculous – NIS300 000 a year
(US$74 000) – and as a body it is unable to scrutinize effectively the
work of the press that funds the organization. Its image among the
public is one of a stagnant, ineffective body, whose work is obscure and
whose existence is questionable. There needs to be a major reassess-
ment of the work of press councils and a systematic reorganization of
their machinery in order to make these bodies effective entities that
really are able to fulfil their duties of supervision and monitoring the
media. The press councils should be equipped with more power, and
have the support of independent, non-partisan foundations that care
about the media and about democracy.
One of the criticisms against the work of the Ethics Tribunal con-
cerns its inconsistent adjudication. As with the British and Canadian
Press Councils, different panels of the Tribunal may decide similar
cases differently. In order to prevent this, the Tribunal’s decisions
should be published regularly, and in any event they should be circu-
lated among members of the Tribunal. The Tribunal’s judgments are
supposed to be published once in every year. However, because of the
limited budget and the past year-long dispute with the journalists,
The Work of the Press Councils 145
publishers and editors, only one such selection of judgments was pub-
lished in 1996.
Professor Amos Shapira, Deputy President of the Press Council,
thinks that this problem of inconsistent adjudication needs to be
addressed and answered through more publication and circulation of
the Tribunal’s decisions among its members.94 Justice Zamir thinks that
one of the roles of the Secretary-General (Mr Eyal is a former journalist,
not a lawyer) and the Legal Advisor is to review all the rulings and see
that the working of the Tribunal conforms to the norms and prece-
dents.95 I believe this is a major issue and that members of the Tribunal
need to be consistent in their judgments to maintain their credibility.
Inconsistency is a prescription for justified grievances. Newspapers and
journalists might feel that justice would be ill served if they were found
guilty of violating the Code when another paper is acquitted after com-
mitting the same questionable deed. Furthermore, it is unjust to incon-
sistently penalize different papers for similar ethical misconduct. One
paper would be warned while the other would be suspended for the
same misconduct. Diversity of interpretations is fine within bound-
aries. Each panel of judges should not decide inharmoniously without
being aware of precedents.
In the current state of affairs, the Council cannot work effectively.
The Legal Advisor and deputy are volunteers. The Legal Advisor is a
successful lawyer who can hardly find time to review the complaints,
and the work is currently done by the deputy. The deputy has more
time but with limited energies. There is a need to secure a budget for
an independent salaried Legal Advisor. I asked Secretary-General Eyal
whether it was possible to resolve the problem of inconsistency at least
through a steady issuing of reports that cover the work of the Tribunal.
His answer was that he had prepared another selection of the Tribunal’s
rulings, but because of budget constraints he could not have it
published. As for my suggestion to circulate the rulings, at least among
the members of the Ethics Tribunal, this too was impossible. The
budget did not allow photocopying and sending decisions to all mem-
bers, and the secretary, who is working part-time, cannot devote time
and attention to mailing the more than 150 members of the
Tribunal.96
In February 1996, the Minister of Justice and the Minister of the
Interior established a public committee to check the legal arrange-
ments relating to the work of the press in Israel. The Committee,
headed by President of the Council Zadok, issued its report in
September 1997. With regard to the Press Council, the Zadok
146 Media Ethics, Freedom and Responsibilities
Committee concluded that its voluntary status and the fact that the
Council’s decisions were not binding hindered its ability to enforce the
Ethics Code. The Committee voiced its concern that the present situa-
tion permitted the press to ignore the professional and ethical rules,
and to conduct their affairs as they saw fit. The Committee therefore
recommended the enactment of a new obligatory arrangement that
would compel the press to abide by the Code of Ethics and, at the same
time would improve the public image of the press.97
The arrangement, accordingly, would consist of two parts: on the
one hand, the authority to write and impose the professional Ethics
Code would remain in the independent hands of the Press Council; on
the other hand, the law would determine that every journalist and
every newspaper ought to conduct their affairs as prescribed by the
Ethics Code, and that they must respect the rulings of the Ethics
Tribunal. At the same time, the Committee decided to refrain from pre-
scribing sanctions for the violation of the law: ‘The sanctions would be
public, professional and moral, determined by the Press Council’s
bylaws and its Code of Ethics.’98 This arrangement of imperfect legal
obligation was deemed necessary by the majority of the committee,99 in
order to balance the interest of strengthening the normative status of
the Code and in the interest of keeping the media independent of gov-
ernmental involvement in determining the contents of the Ethics Code.
The recommended law, the ‘Press Council Law’, would hold that ‘every
newspaper and every journalist will be obliged to maintain the Ethics
Code of the Press Council, and to abide by the Council’s Tribunal’.100
The Zadok Committee expressed concern that the self-regulatory
mechanisms of the media were not working as they should, and that
something should be done to enforce the Code of Ethics. I see no harm
in the enactment of the suggested law. I do not think that this law
could undermine the independent status of the press and it might
strengthen, in a positive way, the authority of the Press Council. On
this issue my view is similar to that of Attorney Slonim, who is also in
favour of such a law, thinking that it would strengthen the status of the
Council and would provide its Ethics Tribunal with ‘more teeth’.101 The
Secretary-General of the Council, Bezalel Eyal, does not think that
this law will pass in The Knesset in the foreseeable future.102 President of
the Council Zadok hopes that it will pass at some later point by
the Knesset.103 Justice Zamir is ideologically ‘unhappy’ with the
need to resort to legislation. He would have liked the Committee to spec-
ify significant sanctions for the Council. At the same time, Justice Zamir
thinks that this might be the solution in the present state of affairs, given
The Work of the Press Councils 147
that the journalists and editors are unwilling to grant the Council further
sanctions, and reporters continue to breach the Ethics Code. This moder-
ate form of legislation could prove to be the beginning of a solution.104
The concluding section offers some further recommendations to
improve the work of the press councils.
Conclusion
Introduction
In recent years we have witnessed growing criticism of the conduct of the mass
media in Israel.2 This criticism is multidimensional (social, political, economic,
cultural, and ethical) and is grounded partially in facts and mostly in beliefs
concerning the conduct of the media. Among those who criticize the media are
representatives of the political right and left, Jews and Arabs, religious and secu-
lar, elite members and lay people, academics, judges, and media professionals
themselves.
Three typical critiques are raised against the media. First, that the media are
not an objective but a politically biased mediator. This criticism is common
among all political parties in Israel, on the right and the left, and is especially
prominent during political tensions, like election campaigns.3 Another common
criticism is that the Israeli media lack social responsibility. In this respect, some
express concern that the media’s irresponsible coverage of national events may
undermine state security4 or offend (unintentionally) public morale. One such
contention is that intense coverage of terrorist events, such as those that fol-
lowed the signing of the Oslo Accords in September 1993, increased public fears
and anxieties.5
Finally, some find the Israeli media’s pursuit of sensationalism owing to mar-
ket-driven competition to be a major flaw. The media, they argue, frequently and
needlessly invade the privacy of individuals, and consequently severely impair
the reputation of individuals, groups, or organizations.6 The use of hidden listen-
ing devices, on the instructions of the editor of the national newspaper Ma’ariv,
in the offices of its competitor Yedioth Ahronoth, is only one (although the princi-
pal) example of behaviour driven by unrestrained competition.7
These criticisms are not unique to Israel. Similar arguments are an integral
part of public discourse in most democratic societies.8 More often than not,
these arguments are not substantiated by empirical data. It may be argued that
in a considerable number of cases biased judgements lead to a perception of
biased media, and not vice versa.9
Both critics and supporters of the Israeli media ignore one of the most impor-
tant aspects of the debate: how do the media consumers themselves (that is, the
152
Appendix 153
public) evaluate the conduct of the Israeli media? The goals of this case study
were (a) to explore the attitudes of the Jewish public toward the conduct of the
Israeli media,10 (b) to examine the extent to which there is a discrepancy
between public perceptions of the conduct of the media and their view of how
the media ought to behave, and (c) to try and explain this discrepancy as a
product of existing social cleavages in the Israeli society.
The mass media are widely assumed to occupy a central role in modern democ-
ratic societies. The media are the primary providers of essential information to
the public,11 the force that sets the public agenda,12 the ‘watchdogs’ of govern-
ment on behalf of the public,13 important agents of political socialization,14 an
important mechanism of mobilization,15 and the essential platform of participa-
tory democracy.16
To a large extent, these functions of the media derive from the democratic
thinking.17 Democracy is founded on principles such as majority rule while
respecting the rights of minorities;18 representation;19 participation;20 open dis-
cussion of public matters;21 tolerance,22 and equal access to societal resources.23
Despite differences between the popular perception and the elitist perception of
democracy24 and among the various definitions of participation in democratic
procedures (passive versus active, mass versus representation, and so on),25 the
participation of the citizens in political procedures constitutes an essential com-
ponent of democratic societies. The complex and diverse nature of modern soci-
eties requires institutionalization of various mediation procedures. The mass
media are widely assumed to play this role.26
This basic ideology about the role of the mass media in society highlights the
media’s role as impartial and objective mediators between government and pub-
lic opinion. The media, in service of the public, are expected to closely follow
government procedures and facilitate social changes when such changes are
needed. The media are also said to be objective, free of political biases and parti-
san considerations (such as economic profits, and personal or institutional ben-
efits), to maintain balanced reporting, uphold social responsibility, and protect
individual privacy.27 Such an image is common among both journalists28 and
politicians,29 and is increasingly evident in public attitudes.30
This ideal type of media conduct does not exist in reality and its future exis-
tence is probably unlikely. This pessimistic view stems from recognition of the
impact of the social, economic, and political environment in which the media
operate. In an era that is characterized by an ‘overflow of information’, the mass
media have no real way of covering all events or all aspects of a given story.
Moreover, the media are aided by news selection processes that are not and can-
not be objective.31 These procedures, in turn, are not immune to pressures and
manipulations exerted by politicians and bureaucrats, advertisers,32 pressure
groups,33 publishers,34 and media owners.35
The restrictions within which the media operate are not unknown to the pub-
lic, which tends to address media content with considerable cynicism and suspi-
cion.36 This tendency causes consumers to resist the messages they receive,37
154 Appendix
and it may even lead to increased hostility towards the media and media profes-
sionals. Indeed, criticism and hostility are often interwoven, and only rarely do
the media receive praise for their conduct.38 Hence, that perceptions of biased
media exist is a predictable consequence of the normative realm that surrounds
the mass media. The questions we should ask, therefore, are: against what stan-
dards are the media judged, and do these standards vary across individuals and
groups in society because of prior dispositions.
As in many current democracies, the status of the media in Israel is quite
low.39 For example, Yuchtman-Yaar found that the Israeli press, alongside the
Histadrut (the umbrella organization of major trade unions in Israel) and political
parties, were ranked the lowest on the trust-in-institutions scale.40 In a recent
study, Yuchtman-Yaar found that the media were ranked fourth out of six with a
46 mark on his 0 to 100 trust-in-institutions scale, after the Israel Defence Forces
(82), the Supreme Court (76), and the universities (71), and before the govern-
ment (39) and the Rabbinate (33).41 Similarly, Liebes and Ribak found that
about half of media consumers in Israel reported considerable mistrust of some
or most news they were exposed to.42 In this study, individual differences in
attitudes toward the media were accounted for by four variables: level of educa-
tion, level of religiousness, age, and ethnic origin. Higher levels of education
and religiousness, younger age, and Asian-African origin were found to be asso-
ciated with higher levels of discontent with the media. In the Israeli context
two of these variables are not only measures of sociodemographic characteris-
tics, but also correspond to existing cleavages in the Israeli society. They capture
the religious cleavage between orthodox and secular Jews and the ethnic cleav-
age between Jews of European-American origin (Ashkenazim) and Jews of Asian-
African origin (Sephardim).43
This study examined the extent to which the Israeli public is content with the
performance of the media. This is done by comparing the Israeli public’s norma-
tive perception of the media’s conduct (the ‘ought’) with its perception of the
media’s conduct in practice (the ‘is’). More specifically, we attempt to answer the
following questions: what does the public perceive to be the priorities of journal-
ists and media organizations when reporting the news? Does the public think
that media priorities should be changed and, if it does, according to what guid-
ing principles? Finally, are different levels of discrepancy between desired and
actual media conduct associated with current social cleavages in Israeli society?
It is hypothesized that a greater level of discrepancy between the desirable
and actual conduct of the Israeli media will be greater among (1) more educated
people, (2) more religious people, (3) younger people, and (4) people of Asian-
African origin. The assumptions underlying these hypotheses are as follows.
People with a higher level education tend to be more critical towards the con-
duct of the media because they tend to devote more thinking to the role of soci-
etal institutions.44 Younger people tend to be more cynical towards the conduct
of the media, as they are towards other social institutions.45 Religious people are
more alienated from the predominantly secular culture in Israel and from the
media that are part of this culture, and thus are more likely to regard the secular
media as obscene, anti-religious and dangerous.46 Yuchtman-Yaar found that
80 per cent of the ultra-religious expressed no trust or little trust in the media,
compared with 63 per cent of religious Jews, 39 per cent of moderately religious
Jews (massortiim), and 20 per cent of secular Jews.47 Jews of Asian-African origin
revealed a higher level of suspicion towards democratic ideals and towards the
Appendix 155
media and their roles in society, especially when fulfilling these roles were per-
ceived as undermining state security and strength. This is because they tended
to be more hawkish in their views on security matters.48
The sample
Data for the purposes of the current research project were collected from tele-
phone interviews conducted by a survey company (Michshuv) on a random
sample of the adult (age 18;) Jewish population of Israel (N:501). The sample
characteristics are described in Table A1.
Sex
Men 46.0
Women 54.0
Ethnic origin
Asian-African 33.1
European-American 36.6
Native Israeli 26.1
Immigrants from the former 4.2
Soviet Union
Religiousness
Secular 58.0
Traditional 29.2
Religious 12.8
Age
18–34 48.2
35–54 37.2
55; 14.6
Education
Less than high school 7.9
High school education (12 years) 40.9
Greater than high school 51.2
Income*
Less than average monthly income 30.8
Average income 34.6
Higher than average income 34.6
* Average monthly household income in Israel at the time of the survey (June 1996) was
about NIS 4800.
Note: In comparison with the Central Bureau of Statistics demographic distribution, people
with higher education are slightly overpresented in the sample.
156 Appendix
Variables
The dependent variable in the research was the level of discrepancy between
attitudes about the desired conduct of the media (‘ought’ value) and attitudes
about the actual conduct of the media in practice (‘is’ value). For each respon-
dent, this level of discrepancy was calculated separately for each of the six
dimensions presented above by subtracting the ‘is’ value from the ‘ought’ value.
Possible values of this variable ranged from 0 (indicating lack of discrepancy) to
<10 (the highest possible level of discrepancy). The reliability of the items in
the questionnaire that composed this variable was measured by Cronbach’s
Alpha and was found to be satisfactory (␣:0.71). The independent variables
were sex, ethnic origin, level of religiousness (interval), age (ratio), level of edu-
cation (interval), and level of income (interval).
Appendix 157
Results
Twenty-four different answers were given by the respondents to the open ques-
tion: ‘What are, in your opinion, the primary considerations that guide journal-
ists’ selection of news?’ Each respondent was given the opportunity to list up to
three considerations. The answers were grouped into five categories: (1) per-
sonal interests of journalists (that is, journalists’ opinions and political views,
personal reputation, and personal gain), (2) interests of media organizations
(political interests, audience preferences, scoops, sensations, economic profit,
and higher ratings), (3) social values (maintaining state security, protecting free-
dom of speech, pursuing the public’s right to know), (4) serving the public (report-
ing matters of public interest, revealing facts and ‘truths’, revealing failures and
corruption); (5) ethical considerations (not offending public emotions, weighing
the possible results of the publication, safeguarding individual privacy and dignity,
weighing the possible influence of the report on the behaviour and conduct of the
public). The distribution of these categories is presented in Table A2. Because
respondents were given three possibilities regarding the considerations that
guide the media, Table A2 presents the cumulative percentage of the considera-
tions mentioned. Hence, the cumulative percentage of all answer categories is
greater than 100 per cent.
Table A2 Public opinion about the considerations that are perceived to guide
the Israeli media news selection
Table A2 shows that most respondents (71 per cent) indicated that providing
a service to the public as the main guiding consideration of media practices.
A substantial proportion of respondents also indicated partisan interests of
either media organizations (50 per cent) or individual journalists (19.5 per cent)
as the prime motive for reporting a certain story. Seventeen per cent thought
that social values guided journalists in their work, and only 6 per cent indicated
ethical considerations to be a factor in this respect. No statistically significant
cross-group (that is, sex, ethnic origin, education, income, and religiousness)
differences were found in this respect.
The next step of the analysis was to examine the level of discrepancy between
the ‘is’ and the ‘ought’. Figure A1 presents a comparison of average ‘is’ and
‘ought’ scores, indicating the relative importance respondents attributed to the
six dimensions of media conduct (that is, social responsibility, protecting state
security, pursuit of ‘scoops’, safeguarding individual privacy, objectivity in cov-
ering events, and the extent to which the media follow the principle of the
public’s right to know).
158 Appendix
10
9.3
9 8.78
8.24 8.39
8.09
8 7.46 7.53 7.66
7 6.27
6 5.57 5.28 5.66
5
4
3
2
1
0
Responsibility Security Scoops Privacy Objectivity Right to know
scores: those with higher education gave the media higher scores than did those
with less education on all six dimensions.
As for religiousness groups, secular people granted on average higher ‘ought’
scores on all six dimensions than traditional and religious people did. Secular
people also gave higher average ‘is’ scores on four dimensions (protecting pri-
vacy, safeguarding state security, demonstrating social responsibility, and pur-
suit of scoops) than did traditional and religious people. In general it seems that
as individual’s level of religiousness increases, his or her normative and actual
evaluation of media conduct decreases, hence the low ‘ought’ scores.
Negligible differences in the normative and actual evaluation of media con-
duct across age groups were apparent. Individuals from various age groups seem
to perceive the way the media ought to function in a similar manner, though
younger people tended to report slightly higher average evaluations of the
actual conduct of the media on all six dimensions.
Finally, average ‘ought’ scores among European-Americans were slightly higher
than those reported by Asian-Africans, Israeli natives, and new immigrants. By
contrast, Asian-Africans reported the lowest average ‘is’ scores of all ethnic groups.
To estimate the magnitude and significance of these group differences a series
of multiple-regression models were employed. The inherent benefit of employ-
ing multiple-regression analysis was teasing out the effects of individual inde-
pendent variables (that is, education, ethnic origin, religiousness, and age),
while controlling for the effects of other possible influences. In addition, this
analysis assisted us in avoiding possible spurious associations between the
dependent variable and the independent variables stemming from the interac-
tion of different independent variables. The dependent variable for the purposes
of this analysis was the level of discrepancy between the normative and actual
media conduct on each of the six dimensions. The independent variables
were introduced successively into the regression model according to their rela-
tive contribution to the explained variance in the dependent variable (that is, a
stepwise procedure). Only the significant results of this analysis are reported in
Table A3.
As expected, one central finding is that as the level of education increased,
the higher was the level of discrepancy. This is particularly true regarding the
dimensions of privacy and state security. In addition, the younger the person,
the higher the level of discrepancy regarding the privacy dimension. Finally, the
higher the level of religiousness, the higher the level of discrepancy regarding
all four dimensions in the analysis. As little variance existed in the level of dis-
crepancy regarding the dimension of the public’s right to know (see Figure A1),
no significant effects of demographic variables were found. Similarly, null effects
of demographic variables on level of discrepancy regarding the pursuit of scoops
were found. Finally, no interaction terms were found to have a significant effect
on the association between the dependent and independent variables.
In the next stage of the analysis we examined the answers respondents gave
to questions dealing with various aspects of their personal preferences of media
coverage. One question referred to the coverage of terror attacks that occurred
in the last months of 1996. Of those interviewed (N:490) 46.3 per cent replied
that the coverage was too extensive, 49 per cent thought that the coverage was
appropriate, and only 4.7 per cent thought that there was not enough coverage.
A weak yet significant negative correlation was found between the respondent’s
age and this variable (Gamma:90.16; p:0.001). Younger people felt slightly
more than older people that the media coverage of terrorism was too extensive.
160 Appendix
* p:0.05.
** p:0.001.
In addition, respondents were asked two related questions that dealt with the
extent to which the public’s-right-to-know principle was superior to other
values such as state security and privacy. Of the respondents, (N:493)
88.2 per cent thought that preference should be given to state security over the
public’s right to know. Only 4.9 per cent thought that we should decide the
issue in accordance with the extent of the likely harm to the state security, and
4.7 per cent stated that we should give preference to the public’s-right-to-know
principle. The rest of the respondents had no opinion on the matter.
With regard to privacy versus the public’s right to know, 62.5 per cent of the
respondents (N:496) thought that individual privacy should be prioritized over
the public’s right to know. Of the respondents, 14.1 per cent answered that the
decision should be made according to the potential harm caused to individual
privacy, while 19.6 per cent preferred the public’s-right-to-know principle under
any circumstances. No statistically significant demographic differences were
found regarding answers to both questions.
In the final stage of the analysis we examined the willingness of the Israeli
public to impose restrictions on journalists and on the freedom of press. Of the
493 respondents, 51.6 per cent were certain that there was a need to impose eth-
ical guidelines on journalists, similar to those imposed on medical and legal
professionals. An additional 32.9 per cent thought that there was a need to
impose ethical guidelines, while about 10 per cent thought that there was no
need to do so. Respondents with higher levels of education were more likely to
consider this option positively (␥:0.31; p:0.002).52
Finally, 18.8 per cent of the respondents (N:487) were certain that more
severe restrictions should be imposed on free speech and free press in Israel and
another 24.4 per cent thought that this should be done. By contrast, 30.1 per
cent did not think that there was a need to expand the existing restrictions and
Appendix 161
a further 24.8 per cent absolutely rejected such a possibility. The willingness
to restrict free speech and free press was positively correlated with level of
religiousness (␥:0.29; p:0.001) and negatively correlated with the level of edu-
cation (␥:90.32; p:0.023).53
Discussion
The purpose of the present research was to analyse the Israeli public climate of
opinion regarding the conduct of the Israeli media. First, it appears that the public
is less cynical about the conduct of the media than the American public.54 While
between 30 and 35 per cent of the American public believe that the mass media
operate in the interest of the public, nearly half of the Jewish public in Israel
believes this according to the findings of this study. This finding is particularly
encouraging as the survey was conducted in proximity to the end of the election
campaign in Israel (June 1996), which was accompanied by fierce criticism of the
media by politicians and public figures. Although we are unable to estimate public
attitudes towards the media before the elections, it seems that the Israeli media
enjoy a higher appreciation than that accorded them in the United States.
However, it is noteworthy that the Jewish public in Israel is by no means naive
about the role of personal and institutional considerations in media coverage.
Another finding that emerged from our research is that different levels of dis-
crepancy between the normative and actual conduct of the Israeli media exist
on different dimensions of media performance. The greatest levels of discrep-
ancy between the ‘ought’ and the ‘is’ concern the dimensions of objectivity in
reporting and safeguarding individual privacy. On average, the Jewish public
feels that the media give insufficient weight to these dimensions. A significant
level of discrepancy also exists regarding the extent to which the media should
be guided by standards of social responsibility and safeguarding the state secu-
rity. In addition, the public feels that the media are overly motivated by the
pursuit of ‘scoops’. The only dimension where the ‘ought’ and the ‘is’ almost
converges is the public’s right to know.
The prevailing opinion that the media are guided primarily by the considera-
tion of providing services to the public can be explained by their success in
revealing failings and corruption in public office.55 However, the level of dis-
crepancy regarding other dimensions should not be ignored. Media organiza-
tions and professionals should take these findings into consideration and
ponder the reasons for these opinions and perceptions.
The findings of this research partially support the hypothesis that the level
of discrepancy regarding the normative and actual functioning of the media is
influenced by the existing social cleavages in Israel. For example, the more
religious people exhibit a greater level of discrepancy than less religious. This
finding is consistent with past research.56 We also found a positive correla-
tion between a higher level of education and a higher level of discrepancy in
relation to privacy matters. A higher level of education also predicts lower
willingness to constrain free speech and free press, and a higher level of support
for imposing ethical guidelines on journalists. Overall, the more educated peo-
ple tend to present a higher level of expectation concerning the conduct of
162 Appendix
the media and to evaluate their actual conduct more positively than the less
educated.
Finally, and slightly surprisingly, we acknowledge the weakening of ethnic
origin as a predictor of the level of discrepancy concerning the role of the
media. A possible explanation for this is the existing overlap between origin and
the level of education on the one hand (Ashkenazim are more educated than
Sephardim), and religiousness on the other (Sephardim tend to be more reli-
gious). However, this seems unlikely given that no interaction terms between
ethnic origin and other demographic characteristics were found to be signifi-
cant in the regression analysis.
As expected, the enduring prominence of security considerations in Israeli
society57 dictates, in the eyes of the Jewish public, restrictions on the conduct of
the media. The majority of the public conceives security considerations as supe-
rior to the principle of the public’s right to know. In this regard the media are
expected to follow the principle of the public’s right not to know. Similar find-
ings were reported by Yuchtman-Yaar.58 Yet in contrast to the argument that
media coverage of terror attacks is excessive,59 about half of the Jewish public
feels that the coverage is appropriate under the circumstances.
We observe with concern the relatively high proportion of the public
(43 per cent) that supports the imposition of restrictions on freedom of speech
and press. This finding could be interpreted as an additional expression of the
lack of democratic values among large segments of Israeli society. At the same
time, this message of dissatisfaction with regard to the conduct of the media
should receive appropriate consideration by all people involved in the media:
publishers, concessionaires, editors, and reporters. In any event, it is reiterated
that regulations and constraints on the media should be self-imposed, rather
than the products of the legislature and court rulings. But if the media do not
take ethical considerations seriously, there might be a necessity to resort to legal
measures.
Appendix 163
Addendum
Question: What are, in your opinion, the primary considerations used by media
reporters (journalists, radio reporters, and television reporters) to decide which
stories will be reported and which will not?
Question: When you think of good professional media (written press, televi-
sion, and radio), what importance should be given, in your opinion, to each of
the following factors? Rate on a scale from 1 (‘no importance’) to 10 (‘very
important’).
Question: After the terror massacres at Beit-Lid, Jerusalem, and Dizengoff Street,
the evening newspapers and television broadcasts dedicated most pages and news
broadcasting to the coverage of the attacks. In your opinion, was the coverage
(98.4)
1. Too extensive
2. Appropriate
3. Insufficient
Question: When there is a conflict between the public’s right to know and state
security, which of the two considerations should take precedence? (do not read
the answers out loud) (98.8)
164 Appendix
Question: When the public’s right to know and safeguarding individual privacy
(the right to privacy) come into conflict, which consideration should take prece-
dence? (do not read the answers out loud) (99.6)
1. The public’s right to know
2. Safeguarding individual privacy
3. Depends on the level of offence caused to individual privacy
4. I do not know
Question: There are professions, such as medicine and law, which require com-
mitment to certain guidelines of professional ethics. In your opinion, is there a
need for ethical guidelines that will be binding on media reporters?
1. Yes, certainly
2. Yes, I think so
3. I do not know/have any opinion
4. I think not
5. Certainly not
Profile
Education
1. less than complete high school (less than 12 years)
2. complete high school (12 years)
3. above high school (more than 12 years)
Where were you born? (if Israeli native, ask where the father was born)
1. Asia-Africa
2. Europe-America
3. The former Soviet Union
4. Israel (the father was born in Israel)
5. Israel (the father was born in Asia-Africa)
6. Israel (the father was born in Europe-America)
The average net income per month per household in Israel is about NIS 4 800. Is the
income in your household:
1. Much below the average
2. Slightly below the average
3. About average
4. Slightly above the average
5. Much above the average
Introduction
1 For further discussion on the concept of rights, see Ronald Dworkin, Taking
Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977); Roland J. Pennock and John
W. Chapman (eds), Human Rights (New York: New York University Press,
1981); L. W. Sumner, The Moral Foundation of Rights (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1989); Michael Freeden, Rights (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 1991); Hillel Steiner, An Essay on Rights (Oxford: Blackwell, 1994); Alan
Gewirth, The Community of Rights (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1996); Annabel S. Brett, Liberty, Right and Nature (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1997); Richard Dagger, Civic Virtues (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1997); Matthew H. Kramer, N. E. Simmonds and Hillel
Steiner, A Debate over Rights: Philosophical Enquiries (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1998); Samuel Walker, The Rights Revolution (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1998); Michael J. Perry, The Idea of Human Rights: Four Inquiries (New
York: Oxford University Press, 1998); John R. Rowan, Conflicts of Rights
(Boulder, CO.: Westview Press, 1999).
2 See Alf Ross, Why Democracy? (Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
1952); Robert B. McKay, ‘The Preference for Freedom’, New York University
Law Review, Vol. 34 (1959), 1182–227; Hugo L. Black, ‘The Bill of Rights’, New
York University Law Review, Vol. 35 (1960), 865–81; Milton R. Konvitz, First
Amendment Freedoms (Ithaca, New York: Cornell University Press, 1963);
Thomas I. Emerson, ‘Toward a General Theory of the First Amendment’, The
Yale Law Journal, Vol. 72, No. 5 (1963), 877–956; Alexander Meiklejohn,
Political Freedom (New York: Oxford University Press, 1965); idem, ‘Freedom
of Speech’, in Peter Radcliff (ed.) Limits of Liberty (Belmont, California:
Wadsworth Publishing Co., 1966), 19–26; Walter Berns, Freedom, Virtue and
the First Amendment (New York: Greenwood Press, 1969); J. A. Barron,
Freedom of the Press For Whom (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1973);
Aryeh Neier, Defending My Enemy (New York: E. P. Dutton, 1979); Harry
H. Wellington, ‘On Freedom of Expression’, The Yale Law Journal, Vol. 88
(1979), 1105– 42; Franklin S. Haiman, Speech and Law in a Free Society
(Chicago and London: University of Chicago Press, 1981); Lee C. Bollinger,
The Tolerant Society (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986); David A. J. Richards,
Toleration and the Constitution (New York: Oxford University Press, 1986);
Norman Dorsen, ‘Is There a Right to Stop Offensive Speech? The Case of the
Nazis at Skokie’, in Larry Gostin (ed.), Civil Liberties in Conflict (London:
Routledge, 1988), 122–35.
3 See, for example, Anthony Skillen, ‘Freedom of Speech’, in Keith Graham
(ed.), Contemporary Political Philosophy (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982), 139–59; Andrew Belsey and Ruth Chadwick (eds), Ethical Issues in
Journalism and the Media (London: Routledge, 1992); Bud Ward, ‘Crossing the
Line?’, American Journalism Review, Vol. 17 ( January/February 1995), 12-–13;
166
Notes 167
so there is enough time to stop ideas before they materialize into harmful
action. Even if a specific view might cause harm or risk of harm to others,
the danger is not immediate, so free speech has to be allowed.
21 There are situations in which the offence done by the defamatory remarks
is immediate and irreparable, so there is no time for a reply. An example
would be the publication of false accusations against a rival candidate on
the eve of elections.
22 Joel Feinberg, Offence to Others (New York: Oxford University Press, 1985),
pp. 1–2.
23 Ibid., p. 26.
24 T. M. Scanlon, ‘Freedom of Expression and Categories of Expression’,
University of Pittsburgh Law Review, Vol. 40 (1979), p. 527.
25 David Kretzmer, ‘Freedom of Speech and Racism’, Cardozo Law Review, Vol. 8
(1987), pp. 445–513. See also Justice Matza in Iddo Elba v. State of Israel, C.A.
2831/95 (September 1996, Hebrew); and Jean-Paul Sartre, who wrote that
anti-Semitism does not fall within the category of ideas protected by the
right of free expression (Reflexions sur la Question Juive, Gallimard, 2nd edn,
1954). In addition, several international law treaties justify restricting racist
speech on the grounds of the possible connection between racist expres-
sions and discrimination. Cf. Universal Declaration on Human Rights, Art. 7;
Convention on the Elimination of all Forms of Racial Discrimination, Art. 4;
International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights, Art. 20(2).
26 But when dealing with the right to participate in elections I am in favour of
the principled approach. This is because here we speak not of free speech
alone but of speech accompanied by the ability to legislate and to overturn
the raison d’être of democracy that favours liberty and tolerance. See
Chapter 3.
27 Accordingly, pornography may be dealt with under the Offence Principle.
This issue, however, requires a separate analysis.
28 Skokie had the highest number of Holocaust survivors of any city in the
United States, outside the city of New York.
29 In Brandenburg v. Ohio, 395 U.S. 444 (1969) the court ruled that the expres-
sion of a particular idea may not be suppressed unless it is both directed to
and likely to incite or produce imminent unlawful conduct. See also Hess v.
Indiana 414 U.S. 105 (1973).
30 Justice Clark dissented without submitting any explanation.
31 Skokie v. NSPA., 373 N.E. 2d, 21 (1978). Chief Justice Vinson wrote in Dennis
v. U.S. 341 U.S. 494 (1951) that the basis of the First Amendment is the
hypothesis that speech can rebut speech, propaganda will answer propa-
ganda, free debate of ideas will result in the widest governmental policies.
Powell J. argued in Gertz v. Robert Welch, 418 U.S. 323 (1974) that under this
amendment there is no such thing as a false idea.
32 Under constitutional precedents, the threat of violence could not serve as
an argument to prevent assemblies, rallies, and the like. Terminiello v.
Chicago, 337 U.S. 1 (1949); Feiner v. New York, 340 U.S. 315 (1951); Edwards v.
South Carolina, 372 U.S. 229 (1963); Street v. New York, 394 U.S. 576 (1969);
Tinker v. Des Moines, 393 U.S. 503 (1969); and Bachellar v. Maryland, 397 U.S.
564 (1970). In Britain the most notable case is Beatty v. Gillbanks, 9 QBD 308
(1882). The reasoning of the British courts on this issue is similar to that of
170 Notes
the American courts, holding that the hostile audience problem should not
serve as grounds for suppression of demonstrations.
33 Chaplinsky v. New Hampshire, 315 U.S. 568 (1942). See also Cohen v. California,
403 U.S. 15 (1971). In Great Britain the ‘fighting words’ doctrine came into
expression in Lord Parker’s phraseology, that a speaker must insult his audi-
ence in the sense of ‘hitting them with words’ for an offence to be commit-
ted (Jordan v. Burgoyne, 2 QB 744, 1963).
34 The ‘fighting words’ doctrine is not applicable to Skokie for it gives grounds
to punish a person who, in a face-to-face encounter, states something so
provocative and insulting as to cause an immediate violent response. This
was not the case in Skokie.
35 One may suggest, following Chaplinsky, that there may be room for a
‘fighting symbols’ doctrine. I disagree. The crux of the matter in the
‘fighting words’ doctrine is that certain utterances are seen as having no
essential part of any exposition of ideas, or rather utterances which do not
communicate any ideas. Therefore they are ruled out of the Free Speech
clause of the Constitution. On the other hand, the very using of a symbol
intends to convey a certain idea, otherwise it would not be considered a
symbol. It may be intended to insult or intimidate, but one cannot employ
the reasoning of Chaplinsky here: ‘fighting words’ seem to contain no idea;
symbols, by their very characterization as such, do contain a certain idea.
36 Feinberg, Offence to Others, op. cit., pp. 87–8. I find Feinberg’s arguments
confusing, for he also writes that the feelings of a Jewish survivor of a Nazi
death camp as a small band of American Nazis strut down the main street
of his town ‘cannot be wholly escaped merely by withdrawing one’s atten-
tion, by locking one’s door, pulling the window blinds, and putting plugs in
one’s ears’. Feinberg maintains that the offended state of mind is at least to
some degree independent of what is directly perceived (at p. 52).
37 For a similar line of argument, see Lee C. Bollinger, The Tolerant Society
(Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1986), p. 60. Bollinger further argues that we
should grant wide latitude to freedom of expression, even though the
speech in question might be harmful because of the societal benefits
derived from the lessons learned through toleration (p. 198). The contesting
argument holds that to tolerate speech abusing racial groups is to lend
respectability to racist attitudes, which in turn may foster an eventual
breakdown of public order. Barendt, Freedom of Speech, op. cit., p. 161.
38 Quite surprisingly, and without much explanation, Feinberg does not jus-
tify the decision which allowed the march. He states that one can have
sympathy for the A.C.L.U. decision to back the Nazis, but he disagrees with
this stand (Offence to Others, op. cit. p. 93). In a private discussion he admit-
ted that he did not make his position explicit enough and expressed regret
for not fully clarifying his reasoning.
39 Feinberg, Offence to Others, op. cit., p. 87.
40 The same conduct can be interpreted in totally different ways, according to
the motives of the agent. Witness a farmer who takes his old donkey to be
killed. If he wishes that the donkey not be subjected to further pain, we
would regard this as a humanitarian act. But if the same farmer takes his
donkey to be killed in front of the gates of the White House, in protest at
the high interest that the farmers of the South are required to pay, which
Notes 171
brings many of them to bankruptcy, and states that a similar end awaits the
Democrat donkey (referring to the Democrat president), then this is surely a
political act and many humanitarians are likely to protest.
41 It would not make any significant difference if the Nazis were primarily
concerned to persuade the Skokie Jews of their views rather than deliber-
ately to cause offence.
42 In a private communication made to me on an earlier version of this essay.
Thomas Scanlon told me that he approves of the Skokie decision because he
did not like the idea that a local government passes an ordinance that is
effectively designed to prohibit speech it does not like. For further delibera-
tion, see Richard L. Abel, Speaking Respect, Respecting Speech (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1998), pp. 15–19, 53.
43 Feinberg, Offence to Others, op. cit., p. 2.
44 Franklin S. Haiman, Speech and Law in a Free Society (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1981), p. 425.
45 Ibid., pp. 425–6.
46 Ibid., p. 97.
47 Ibid., p. 154.
48 Bollinger, The Tolerant Society, op. cit., pp. 197–200. See also New York Times,
7 February 1978 (Dr William Niederland’s letter); D. A. Downs, Nazis in
Skokie (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1985), chaps
1, 8; and the statement of Sol Goldstein, a concentration camp survivor
whose mother was killed by the Nazis, in Aryeh Neier, Defending My Enemy
(New York: Dutton, 1979), p. 46.
49 Thomas Scanlon in ‘A Theory of Freedom of Expression’, in R. Dworkin
(ed.), The Philosophy and Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977) con-
templates that an assault is committed when one person intentionally
places another in apprehension of imminent bodily harm. He maintains
that instances of assault necessarily involve expressions since an element of
successful communication must be present (p. 158).
50 There were several occasions in which the United States Supreme Court
considered whether certain types of speech are of only ‘low’ First Amend-
ment value. Among them are the ‘fighting words’ doctrine (Chaplinsky v.
New Hampshire 315 U.S. 568, 1942); incitement (Dennis v. U.S., 341 U.S. 494,
1951); obscenity (Roth v. United States, 354 U.S. 476, 77 S.Ct. 1304, 1 L.Ed.2d
1498, 1957; Miller v. California, 413 U.S. 15, 1973); defamation (Beauharnais
v. Illinois, 343 U.S. 250, 1952; New York Times v. Sullivan, 376 U.S. 254, 84
S.Ct. 710, 11 L.Ed.2d 686, 1964), and false statements of fact (Gertz v. Robert
Welch, 418 U.S. 323, 1974). Geoffrey R. Stone, ‘Content Regulation and the
First Amendment’, William and Mary Law Review, Vol. 25 (1983), pp.
189–252 and Justice Scalia’s judgment in R.A.V. v. St. Paul, 505 U.S. 375
(1992), esp. 381–8.
51 Village of Skokie v. NSPA., 366 N.E. 2d 347 (1977), p. 357.
52 Donald Vandeveer, ‘Coercive Restraint of Offensive Actions’, Philosophy &
Public Affairs, Vol. 8 (1979), p. 177.
53 Robert C. Carson, James N. Butcher and Susan Mineka, Abnormal Psychology
and Modern Life (New York: HarperCollins, 1996).
54 Chapter 16, Section 8 of the Swedish Criminal Code (amended in 1982)
reads: ‘Anyone who publicly or otherwise in a declaration or other statement
172 Notes
Hate speech is less tolerable because it destroys the mosaic that is so impor-
tant for the Canadian identity. The Special Committee on Hate Propaganda
in Canada (the Cohen Committee) noted that individuals subjected to
racial or religious hatred may suffer substantial psychological distress, the
damaging consequences including loss of self-esteem, feelings of anger and
outrage, and strong pressure to renounce cultural differences that mark
them as distinct. Report of the Special Committee on Hate Propaganda in
Canada (Ottawa: Queen’s Printer, 1966). Other study groups and court judg-
ments have echoed the Cohen Committee’s conclusion that hate propa-
ganda presents a serious threat to society. See the ‘Report of the Special
Committee on Participation of Visible Minorities in Canadian Society’,
Equality Now (Ottawa: Supply and Services, 1984). The Supreme Court con-
cluded that messages of hate undermine the dignity and self-worth of target
group members and ‘contribute to disharmonious relations among various
racial, cultural and religious groups, as a result eroding the tolerance and
open-mindedness that must flourish in a multicultural society which is
committed to the idea of equality’. Taylor et al. v. Canadian Human Rights
Commission et al., Dominion Law Reports, Vol. 75 (4th) (1990), 593– 4. I bene-
fited from discussion with The Honourable Justice Ian Binnie, The
Honourable Justice Peter de C. Cory and The Honourable Justice Frank
Iacobucci, The Supreme Court of Canada (28 September 1998). For further
deliberation, see Mayo Moran, ‘Talking about Hate Speech: A Rhetorical
Analysis of American and Canadian Approaches to the Regulation of Hate
Speech’, Wisconsin L. Rev., No. 6 (1994), pp. 1425–514; Warren Kinsella,
‘Challlenges to Canadian Liberal Democracy’, in R. Cohen-Almagor (ed.),
Challenges to Democracy: Essays in Honour and Memory of Isaiah Berlin
(London: Ashgate, 2000); Irwin Cotler, ‘Holocaust Denial, Equality and
Harm: Boundaries of Liberty and Tolerance in a Liberal Democracy’, and
Richard Moon, ‘The Regulation of Racist Expression’, both in R. Cohen-
Almagor (ed.), Liberal Democracy and the Limits of Tolerance, op. cit.
62 Note that international treaties speak of ‘the right to freedom of peaceful
assembly’ (emphasis added). Cf. Article II of the European Convention of
Human Rights; Article 20 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights; and
Article 21 of the UN International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights.
63 Home Office, Review of Public Order Law, Cmmd. 9510 (White Paper). May
1985, pp. 23– 4.
64 It may be of interest to note that part II of the Public Order Act 1986 speaks
of imposing conditions on public processions, holding that if a senior
police officer reasonably believes that the procession in question ‘may
result in serious public disorder, serious damage to property or serious dis-
ruption to the life of the community … he may give directions imposing on the
persons organising or taking part in the procession such conditions as
appear to him necessary to prevent such disorder, damage, disruption or
intimidation’ (sect. 12, emphasis added). The courts, it seems, interpret the
above as being in line with the ‘breach of the peace’ reasoning.
65 Home Office, Review of Public Order Act 1936 (The Green Paper), April 1980,
esp. pp. 11–12, and Home Office, Review of Public Order Law (The White
Paper), May 1985, esp. p. 23. In both papers it was reiterated that consider-
ations of public order should be the sole test for banning of processions. For
174 Notes
33 Ramsey v. Edgepark, 66 Ohio App.3d 99, 583 N.E.2d 443 (1990), at 451. In
Valenzuela v. Aquino, 763 S.W.2d 43 (1989) the Texas Court of Appeals,
Kennedy J., held that injunction prohibiting residential picketing within
half a mile of owner’s home was overly broad and unnecessarily infringed
picketers’ First Amendment rights. On the other hand, a year later, the same
Court of Appeals held that a permanent injunction mandating abortion
opponents to cease picketing within 400 feet of centre of lot upon which
physicians’ home was located was content-neutral, narrowly tailored limita-
tion on place and manner of picketers’ expressive activities, and provided
ample alternative avenues of communication. Thus, the said injunction did
not violate First Amendment. Valenzuela v. Aquino, 800 S.W.2d 301 (1990).
34 Madsen v. Women’s Health Center, 114 S.Ct. 2516 (1994); Trojan Electric and
Machine Co. v. Heusinger et al., 162 A.D.2d 859, 557 N.Y.S.2d 756 (1990).
35 Hazel A. Landwehr, ‘Unfriendly Persuasion: Enjoining Residential Picketing’,
Duke L. J., Vol. 43, No. 1 (October 1993), pp. 148–88.
36 Chalfont v. Kalikow, 392 Pa.Super. 452, 573 A.2d 550 (1990).
37 Madsen v. Women’s Health Center, 114 S.Ct. 2516 (1994). See also Everywoman’s
Health Centre Society (1988) et al. v. Bridges et al., 109 Dominion Law Reports
(4th) where three defendants were found guilty of civil contempt of court
after they violated a restraining order which was issued to prevent them
from ‘watching or besetting’ an abortion clinic in Vancouver, Canada.
38 Lawson v. Murray, 119 S. Ct. 387 (1998), at 387.
39 Ibid. See also Alan Phelps, ‘Picketing and Prayer: Restricting Freedom of
Expression Outside Churches’, Cornell L. Rev., Vol. 85 (November 1999),
271, at 284.
40 State of Maryland v. Schuller, 372 A.2d 1076 (1977).
41 Roy Brown et al. v. William J. Scott et al., 462 F. Supp. 518 (U.S. District Court,
N.D. Illinois, 27 September 1978).
42 State of Maryland v. Schuller, 372 A.2d 1077 (1977).
43 Ibid., at 1080.
44 Brown v. Scott, 602 F. 2d 791 (1979).
45 The Illinois Residential Picketing Statute provides:
52 Hudgens v. NLRB, 424 U.S. 507, 515, 96 S.Ct. 1029, 1034, 47 L.Ed.2d 196
(1976).
53 Carey v. Brown, 447 U.S. 455, at 2291.
54 Stromberg v. California, 283 U.S. 359, 369, 51 S.Ct. 532, 536, 75 L.Ed. 1117
(1931).
55 Cox v. Louisiana, 379 U.S. 559, 563– 4, 85 S.Ct. 476, 480, 13 L.Ed.2d 487
(1965). After United States v. Grace 461 U.S. 171 (1983), this dictum should
be reconsidered. The court said in Grace that it is protected speech to picket
outside courthouse.
56 Adderley v. Florida, 385 U.S. 39, 87 S.Ct. 242, 17 L.Ed.2d 149 (1966).
57 Teamsters v. Vogt Inc., 354 U.S. 284, 77 S.Ct. 1166, 1 L.Ed.2d 1347 (1957).
58 Erznoznik v. City of Jacksonville, 422 U.S. 205, 209, 95 S.Ct. 2268, 2272, 45
L.Ed.2d 125 (1975).
59 Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 108 S.Ct. 2495, 2509, 101 L.Ed.2d 420 (1988).
For further discussion, see Randall M. England, ‘Residential Picketing:
Balancing Freedom of Expression and the Right to Privacy’, Missouri L. Rev.,
Vol. 54 (1989), pp. 209–23.
60 H.C. 2481/93. Yoseph Dayan v. Police Chief District of Jerusalem (not pub-
lished), para. 1 in Justice Levine’s judgment.
61 In Northern Ireland the right to march was used by the Protestant majority
to intimidate the Catholic minority. This is not the intention of the Free
Speech Principle.
62 Garcia et al. v. Gray et al., 507 F.2d 539 (U.S. Court of Appeals, Tenth Circuit,
17 December 1974).
63 United States v. Pyle, 518 F. Supp. 139, 160 (E.D. Pa. 1981).
64 Grayned v. City of Rockford, 408 U.S. 104 (1972).
65 See Justice Brennan’s dissenting opinion in Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474,
108 S.Ct. 2495, 2507, 101 L.Ed.2d 420 (1988), and Hugh J. O’Halloran,
‘Balancing First Amendment Rights to Freedom of Expression Against the
Rights of an Individual to Privacy in the Home. Schultz v. Frisby’, Marquette
L. Rev., Vol. 71 (1987), pp. 201–16.
66 For contrasting views, see Justice Levine’s judgment in H.C. 2481/93. Yoseph
Dayan v. Police Chief District of Jerusalem, infra; ‘Picketing the Homes of
Public Officials’, Un. of Chicago L. Rev., Vol. 34, No. 1 (Autumn 1966),
106– 40; Alfred Kamin, ‘Residential Picketing and the First Amendment’,
Northwestern U. L. Rev., Vol. 61, No. 2 (May–June 1966), pp. 177–236.
67 In summing up the British stance I rely, inter alia, on communications and
conversations with Geoffrey Marshall, Eric Barendt and David Feldman.
I thank them for their comments and advice. For further deliberation, see
D. Feldman, ‘Protest and Tolerance: Legal Values and the Control of Public-
Order Policing’, in R. Cohen-Almagor (ed.), Liberal Democracy and the Limits
of Tolerance (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2000).
68 See Emma Wilkins, ‘Princess wins court bar on photographer’, The Times (16
August 1996), p. 1, column e. Princess Diana’s affidavit gives details of Mr
Stenning’s behaviour towards her over an extended period. See The Times
(17 August 1996), p. 2. Earlier in 1996, a German doctor had been stalking
the Princess. He was arrested and bailed after waving a placard outside the
health club where she worked out in January (see The Times,
Notes 179
86 In several early cases, the court’s position was that regulation, not prohibi-
tion, was the appropriate policy in dealing with free speech questions. In
Lovell v. Griffin, 303 U.S. 444 (1938) ordinance requiring permit to distribute
literature was declared invalid on its face. In Schneider v. State, 308 U.S. 147,
160, 162 (1939) flat prohibition on leafleting to prevent littering was
declared unjustified. In Cox v. New Hampshire, 312 U.S. 569 (1941) the
court established that time, place and manner regulations of parades are
permissible. Saia v. New York (334 U.S. 558, 1948) and Kovacs v. Cooper (336
U.S. 77, 1949) deal with regulations of sound trucks and loudspeakers on
city streets.
87 Klebanoff v. McMongale, 380 Pa. Super. 545, 552 A.2d 677 (1989); Barrington v.
Blake, 568 A.2d 1015 (R.I. 1990), at 1021; Kaplan v. Prolife Action League of
Greensboro, 111 N.C.App. 1, 431 S.E.2d 828 (1993). In Hibbs v. Neighborhood
Organization to Rejuvenate Tenant Housing, 433 Pa. 578, 252 A.2d 622 (1969)
the court overturned an injunction barring protestors from picketing
the home of Hibbs as violative of the picketers’ First Amendment rights
because Hibbs conducted his business affairs in such a secretive manner
that no other place was available for the protestors to communicate their
views.
88 Heffron v. International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452 U.S. 640
(1981), at 654 –5; Klebanoff v. McMongale, 380 Pa. Super. 545, 552 A.2d 677
(1989). See also Phelps, ‘Picketing and Prayer: Restricting Freedom of
Expression Outside Churches’, op. cit., at 282.
89 But, as we have seen, in Frisby the court said it is permissible to prohibit
focused picketing taking place solely in front of a particular residence.
90 H.C. 2481/93. Yoseph Dayan v. Police Chief District of Jerusalem, para. 28 in
Justice Barak’s judgment.
91 H.C. 2481/93. Yoseph Dayan v. Police Chief District of Jerusalem, para. 12 in
Justice Barak’s judgment.
92 H.C. 2481/93. Yoseph Dayan v. Police Chief District of Jerusalem, para. 25 in
Justice Barak’s judgment. For further discussion, see Aharon Barak, ‘The
Tradition of Freedom of Expression in Israel and Its Problems’, public lec-
ture delivered on 13 May 1996 at Tel-Aviv University. An English transla-
tion of the text, albeit in a shorter version, is found in Justice, No. 9 ( June
1996), 3–10; idem, ‘Freedom of Expression and Its Limitations’, in R. Cohen-
Almagor (ed.), Challenges to Democracy: Essays in Honour and Memory of
Professor Sir Isaiah Berlin (London: Ashgate, 2000).
93 H.C. 2481/93. Yoseph Dayan v. Police Chief District of Jerusalem, para. 4 in
Justice Goldberg’s judgment.
94 Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U.S. 474, 494 (1988).
43 P.C.A. 7504/95, 7793/95, Yassin and Rochly v. the Parties’ Registrar and Yemin
Israel, para. 17 in P. Barak.’s judgment.
44 Ibid., para. 22 in P. Barak’s judgment.
45 Ibid., para. 27 in P. Barak’s judgment.
46 Ibid., para. 28 in P. Barak’s judgment.
47 P.C.A. 2316/96 Meiron Aizekson v. the Parties’ Registrar and the Arab Movement
for Change (28 April 1996).
48 Ibid., para. 7 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
49 Ibid.
50 Ibid., para. 11 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
51 Ibid., para. 20 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
52 Ibid., para. 27 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
53 Ibid., para. 30 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
54 Ibid., para. 12 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
55 Ibid., para. 13 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
56 Ibid.
57 Ibid., para. 16 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
58 Ibid., para. 17 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
59 Ibid., para. 19 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
60 Ibid., para. 20 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
61 Ibid., para. 23 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
62 Ibid., para. 24 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
63 Ibid., para. 25 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
64 Ibid., para. 27 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
65 H.C. 426/94 Yoseph Adler v. Israeli Police Head of Investigations et al.
66 P.C.A. 2316/96 Meiron Aizekson v. the Parties’ Registrar and the Arab Movement
for Change, para. 28 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
67 Ibid., para. 29 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
68 Ibid., para. 31 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
69 Ibid., para. 31 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
70 Ibid., para. 32 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
71 Ibid., para. 34 in J. Cheshin’s judgment.
72 Ibid., para. A in J. Tal’s judgment.
73 Cf. Glimmerveen and Hagenbeek v/the Netherlands (1980) Decisions and Reports
18 European Community H.R. 187–208.
74 E.A. 2/84. Neiman and Avneri v. Chairperson of the CEC to the 11th Knesset,
p. 304.
01 A draft of this essay was presented in summer 1996 at The 12th National
Workshop on the Teaching of Ethics in Journalism, Freedom Forum First
Amendment Center, Vanderbilt University, Nashville, Tenn., and at Conver-
sation and Community, The Australian and New Zealand Communication
Association Annual Conference, QUT (Queensland University of Technology),
Brisbane, 1996. I express gratitude to Dave Boeyink, Ed Lambeth, Mayo
Moran, and John McManus for sending me their respective writings.
184 Notes
no longer in our employ.’ See Maude Barlow, and James Winter, The Big
Black Book (Toronto: Stoddart, 1997), p. 11.
22 John McManus, ‘How Objective Is Local Television News?’ Mass Communica-
tion Review, Vol. 18, No. 3 (1991), pp. 21–30, 48.
23 Leftist ideologists advance Marxist arguments that hold that the media
actively frame and promote news stories that serve the needs and concerns
of the élite. Herman and Chomsky provide a systematic ‘propaganda
model’ to account for the behaviour of the corporate news media in the
United States. They preface their discussion of the propaganda model by
noting their fundamental belief that the mass media serve to mobilise sup-
port for the special interests of power groups and large corporations that
dominate the state, the media, the advertising industry, and private activity.
In their view propaganda is a very important aspect of the work of the
media. See Edward S. Herman and Noam Chomsky, Manufacturing Consent:
The Political Economy of the Mass Media (New York: Vintage, 1995).
24 John C. Merrill, ‘Is Ethical Journalism Simply Objective Reporting?’,
Journalism Quarterly, Vol. 62, Nos. 1–2 (1985), pp. 391–3.
25 Raphael Cohen-Almagor, ‘Female Circumcision and Murder for Family
Honour among Minorities in Israel’, in Kirsten E. Schulze, Martin Stokes
and Colm Campbell (eds), Nationalism, Culture and Diasporas: Identities and
Rights in the Middle East (London: I. B. Tauris, 1996), pp. 171–87.
26 I discuss medical ethics in ‘The Patients’ Right to Die in Dignity and the
Role of Their Beloved People’, Annual Review of Law and Ethics, Vol. 4
(1996), pp. 213–32; ‘Autonomy, Life as an Intrinsic Value, and Death with
Dignity’, Science and Engineering Ethics, Vol. 1, No. 3 (1995), pp. 261–72;
idem, ‘Reflections on the Intriguing Issue of the Right to Die in Dignity’,
Israel Law Review, Vol. 29, No. 4 (1995), pp. 677–701; ‘ “Muerte con dig-
nidad”, “calidad de vida”, “estado vegetativo”, “doble efecto” y otras expre-
siones empleadas por los medicos’, Perspectivas Bioeticas, No. 5 (1998),
pp. 26– 44 (Spanish); The Right to Die in Dignity: Au Argument in Ethics,
Medicine and Law (forthcoming); Raphael Cohen-Almagor and Merav
Shmueli, ‘Can Life Be Evaluated? The Jewish Helachic Approach vs. the
Quality of life Approach in Medical Ethics: A Critical View’, Theoretical
Medicine and Bioethics (2000).
27 Sarah Davidovitz, a columnist working for a local newspaper in Jerusalem,
was explicitly asked whether she would report misconduct of politicians she
worked with. Her answer was no less explicit. She said that she would not
report the misconduct. There are enough journalists who would be happy
to provide their readers with such news. She left it to them. Interview on
Yoman Ha’shavuah, Channel 1 Israel Television (Friday, 9 February 1996).
28 The Declaration of Independence holds, inter alia, that Israel will foster the
development of the country for the benefit of all its inhabitants; that it will
be based on the foundations of liberty, justice, and peace; that it will ensure
complete equality of social and political rights to all of its citizens irrespec-
tive of religion, race, or sex; and that it will guarantee freedom of religion,
conscience, language, education, and culture.
29 H.C. 399/1985. Kahane v. Board of Directors of the Broadcasting Authority.
Piskei Din ( Judgments of the Israeli Supreme Court), 41 (iii), 255. For a fuller
account of this case, see Raphael Cohen-Almagor, The Boundaries of Liberty
Notes 187
and Tolerance: The Struggle Against Kahanism in Israel (Gainesville, FL: The
University Press of Florida, 1994), chap. 12.
30 David E. Boeyink, ‘How Effective Are Codes of Ethics? A Look at Three
Newsrooms’, Journalism Quarterly, Vol. 71 (1994), pp. 893–904, esp. 895.
31 A Canadian editor used almost the same words during an interview I con-
ducted in the summer of 1998.
32 405/1995. ‘CLAL’ and Others v. the Broadcasting Authority and Others,
Jerusalem (16 January 1996).
33 For a different example concerning Cecil Andrews who set himself on fire
after calling upon a camera crew to film him igniting himself, see Stephen
D. Reese, ‘The News Paradigm and the Ideology of Objectivity: A Socialist at
the Wall Street Journal’, op. cit. p. 390.
34 Gideon Ezra, former Deputy Head of the SHABAC (Israel internal security)
(Communication Forum on Terror and Communication, University of Haifa,
30 April 1996). For further discussion on staging events, see A. P. Schmid,
‘Terrorism and the Media: The Ethics of Publicity’, Terrorism and Political
Violence, Vol. 1, No. 4 (1989), pp. 539–65.
35 Rilla Dean Mills, ‘Newspaper Ethics: A Qualitative Study’, Journalism
Quarterly, Vol. 60, No. 4 (1983), 589–94, 602.
36 Ronald M. Dworkin, ‘Liberalism’, in A Matter of Principle (Oxford: Clarendon
Press, 1985), pp. 181–204; Ronald M. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously
(London: Duckworth, 1977), pp. 266–78.
37 See Theodore L. Glasser and James S. Ettema, ‘Investigative Journalism and
the Moral Order’, op. cit., p. 7.
38 Standard 1 of the Society of Professional Journalists Code of Ethics speaks of
Responsibility. See also Section 1 of Associated Press Managing Editors Code
of Ethics. On the social responsibility theory, see Deni Elliot (ed.),
Responsible Journalism (Beverly Hills, CA.: Sage, 1986); Conrad C. Fink,
Media Ethics (Boston, Mass.: Allyn and Bacon, 1995), 2nd Edition, Appendix
B, p. 309; Michael Schudson, The Power of the News (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press, 1995); Kristie Bunton, ‘Social Responsibility in
Covering Community: A Narrative Case Analysis’, Journal of Mass Media
Ethics, Vol. 13, No. 4 (1998), pp. 232– 46.
39 See Theodore L. Glasser and James S. Ettema, ‘Investigative Journalism and
the Moral Order’, op. cit. p. 10.
40 Thomas Gibbons, Regulating the Media, op. cit., pp. 107–8.
41 See J. C. Merrill, ‘Is Ethical Journalism Simply Objective Reporting?’,
Journalism Quarterly, Vol. 62 (1985), pp. 391–3, at 391.
42 See J. C. Merrill, ‘Good Reporting Can Be a Solution to Ethics Problem’,
Journalism Educator (Autumn 1987), pp. 27–29, at 27.
43 For a critical discussion of the Leninist view, see R. Cohen-Almagor,
‘Foundations of Violence, Terror and War in the Writings of Marx, Engels,
and Lenin’, Terrorism and Political Violence, Vol. 3, No. 2 (1991), pp. 1–24.
44 For further deliberation on the concept of social responsibility, see Conrad
C. Fink, Media Ethics op. cit., 2nd edn, chap. 5.
45 Alberta Court of Queen’s Bench (1984), 19 C.C.C. (3d) 254, at 273.
46 Cf R. v. Keegstra [1990] S.C.J. No. 131, 763–9. See also Richard Moon,
‘Drawing Lines in a Culture of Prejudice: R. v. Keegstra and the Restriction of
Hate Propaganda’, U.B.C. L. Rev. (1992), pp. 99–143; Mayo Moran, ‘Talking
188 Notes
(19 April 1981), pp. A12–A14; Philip Meyer, Ethical Journalism (New York:
Longman, 1987), pp. 9, 58.
39 In a ‘Letter from Barcelona’, Alastair Reid of The New Yorker described
Spaniards sitting in ‘a small, flyblown bar’, openly jeering at a television
speech by Francisco Franco. In fact, the bar no longer existed. This fabricated
scene, and several other instances in which Reid acknowledged that
he might have modified events and facts, were disclosed in June 1984 in
a page one story of the Wall Street Journal. See David L. Eason, ‘On Journalistic
Authority: The Janet Cooke Scandal’, Critical Studies in Mass Communication,
Vol. 3 (1986), pp. 429– 47; Edmund B. Lambeth, Committed Journalism
(Bloomington and Indianapolis: Indiana University Press, 1992), pp. 25, 27.
Also see David Shaw, ‘ “Docudramas. Faction. Nonfiction novels. Composites.
Gonzo journalism. New Journalism. The blurring of fact and fiction… worries
me. A lot” ’, The Bulletin, No. 643 ( July–August 1981), pp. 3–6.
40 These allegations were made regarding Israeli TV Channel 1’s treatment of
the Der’ei–Bar-On–Hasson affair mentioned previously, allegations that
were refuted by both Attorney General Elyakim Rubinstein, and State-
Attorney Edna Arbel.
41 See Judge Ben-Zimra’s severe criticism of a news item broadcast by IBA’s
Channel One in 405/95 CLAL v. The Broadcasting Authority (The Jerusalem
Magistrate’s Court, 16 January 1996). Some codes of ethics address this
issue. For instance, Section 3 of the Italian Carta dell’informazione e della
programmazione a garanzia degli utenti e degli operatori del servizio pub-
blico – Rai (December 1995) requires the avoidance of sensationalism.
42 On 19 October 1994, a No. 5 bus was attacked by terrorists on Dizengoff
Street in Tel Aviv. The media started to broadcast unedited pictures immedi-
ately from the scene. Some people learned about the death of their loved
ones from the television. This kind of irresponsible coverage happened
again at the site of the crash of two Israel Defence Forces helicopters carry-
ing 72 soldiers in early February 1997, when live footage included a soldier’s
personal bag with the owner’s name clearly visible.
43 Gary Sick, ‘Taking Vows: The Domestication of Policy-Making in Hostage
Incidents’, in Walter Reich (ed.), Origins of Terrorism (New York: Woodrow
Wilson Center and Cambridge University Press, 1990), pp. 230 – 44, at 242.
44 Lord Chalfont, ‘The Price of Sympathy’, in Benjamin Netanyahu (ed.),
Terrorism: How the West Can Win (New York: Farrar, Straus, Giroux, 1986),
pp. 126–9, at 128. See also the 1988 British Ministerial directives to the BBC
and the Independent Broadcasting Authority (IBA) to refrain from broad-
casting interviews with members of terrorist organizations as defined in the
Prevention of Terrorism legislation.
45 See the recommendations of the Davey Committee. Special Senate Committee
on Mass Media, The Uncertain Mirror, Vol. I (Davey Committee), p. 127.
46 See Royal Commission on Newspapers (Hull, Quebec, Canada: Ministry of
Supply and Services, 1981), (Kent Commission), pp. 227–33, 237– 45.
47 Of course, we cannot expect small dailies with a staff of only a few reporters
to hire an ombudsman, hence the emphasis on large media organizations. In
North America there are only 42 ombudspeople, most of them in newspapers.
The Washington Post model is conceived to be the best. The Post ombudsper-
son is not an employee of the newspaper. He/she has a two-year contract,
which can be renewed once for a total of four years. The ombudsperson is
Notes 195
free to investigate any matter deemed relevant. Once a week he/she publishes
an unedited column on a specific topic. If there are extensive complaints
about the paper’s coverage, he/she undertakes a comprehensive investigation.
Discussions with Joann Byrd, former ombuds person of the Post (17–22 June
1996). For further deliberation, see the ‘Terms of Reference for the
Ombudsman Office’, Canadian Broadcasting Corporation Board Manual.
48 Following Princess Diana’s funeral, the Guardian contemplated the idea of
appointing an ‘external’ ombudsperson, in addition to the Readers Editor.
In the Guardian system, the Readers Editor is the first person to whom com-
plaints are referred. He/she will either adjudicate, and if he/she thinks it is
a substantial complaint he/she will ask the reporter for response. The Editor
cannot tell the Readers Editor what he/she should write. He/she cannot be
sacked by the Editor. At the same time the Readers Editor is a staff member.
According to the proposal, the external ombudsperson will be paid
by the Guardian Group but will not be a staff member. He/she will be
able to write everything that he/she wants and according to the planned
scheme the Guardian will publish his/her item in a prominent place in
the paper. Interview with Mr Alan Rusbridger, Editor of The Guardian
(28 October 1997).
49 One British freelance journalist said that his main concern was to make a
living, to support himself and his family. He was assigned to cover a local
election, and the editor who hired his services wanted to help the candi-
dacy of a friend who ran for office for the Tories. The freelance journalist
was asked to research the level of support which each candidate enjoyed
within the constituency, and when the figures did not flatter the editor’s
friend he was ordered to revise them ‘which’, he admits, ‘was quite disap-
pointing behaviour’. The freelance journalist’s main concern was to make a
living, so he did not like the fact that someone fiddled with the figures, but
co-operated and said nothing in protest. Testimony during 21st Century
Trust Seminar on ‘The Media and the Public Interest in the Information
Age’ (London, 12 October 1997).
50 Section IA(g) of the Quebec Press Council’s The Rights and Responsibilities of
the Press (second edition, 1987) holds: ‘Journalists and the media must be
assured that sources will remain confidential if the freedom of the press and
the right to information are to be respected’.
51 See Code of Practice Committee revised draft code (The Newspaper
Publishers Association Ltd., 1997).
52 According to the Quebec Charter of Rights and Freedoms (8), everyone is
entitled to full and equal recognition and exercise of personal rights and
freedoms without distinction as to race, colour, sex including sexual orien-
tation, marital status, pregnancy and so on. Discrimination results from
compromising or removing this right. See Quebec Press Council’s The Rights
and Responsibilities of the Press (second edition, 1987), IIB(a).
53 Alicia C. Shepard, ‘Legislating Ethics’, American Journalism Review, Vol. 16
( January–February 1994), pp. 37– 41.
54 The Daily Mail incorporated the Code of Practice into its journalists’ con-
tracts, and there were cases in which journalists were dismissed when in
breach of the Code. In one incident a reporter was dismissed because he did
not identify himself as a journalist. Interview with Mr Robin Esser, consul-
tant editor of the Daily Mail (20 October 1997).
196 Notes
Kenoye Kelvin Eke (eds), Media Coverage of Terrorism (Newbury Park, CA:
Sage, 1991), pp. 49–62. See also Hans-Bernd Brosius and Gabriel Weimann,
‘The Contagiousness of Mass-mediated Terrorism’, European Journal of
Communication, Vol. 6 (1991), pp. 63–75.
04 Nick Russell, Morals and the Media (Vancouver: UBC Press, 1995), p. 84;
David P. Phillips and L. L. Carstensen, ‘The Effect of Suicide Stories on
Various Demographic Groups, 1968–1985’, Suicide and Life-Threatening
Behavior, Vol. 18 (Spring 1988), pp. 100 –14; David P. Phillips and L. L.
Carstensen, ‘Clustering of Teenage Suicides After Television News
Stories about Suicide’, New England Journal of Medicine, Vol. 315 (1986),
pp. 685–9.
05 Elizabeth B. Ziesenis, ‘Suicide Coverage in Newspapers: An Ethical
Consideration’, op. cit., pp. 239, 242. See also Report of the Secretary’s Task Force
on Youth Suicide (Washington, DC: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1989).
06 Gratitude is expressed to the Canadian government for its research grant.
07 Discussion with M. David Lepofsky, Toronto (23 August 1995).
08 Electronic message on 30 August 1997, in response to my letter of 17 July
1997.
09 Gratitude is expressed to the Canadian government and the Israel
Association for Canadian Studies for their generous support.
10 CBC, Journalistic Standards and Practices (Canadian Broadcasting Corporation,
1993).
11 Globe and Mail Style Book (Toronto, 1994).
12 Interview with Mr Michel Roy and Mr Robert Maltais, Montreal
(18 September 1998).
13 Interview with Mr Mel Sufrin, Toronto (6 October 1998).
14 Peter Buckley (ed.), CP Stylebook: A Guide for Writers and Editors (Toronto: the
Canadian Press, 1997), p. 69.
15 Interview with Mr Michel Roy, Montreal (18 September 1998).
16 Interview with Professor Enn Raudsepp, Department of Journalism,
Concordia University, Montreal (22 September 1998).
17 Interview with Professor G. Stuart Adam, Vice-President (Academic), and
former Director of the School of Journalism and Communication, Carleton
University, Ottawa (29 September 1998).
18 Interview with Professor Christopher Dornan, Ottawa (29 September 1998).
19 Interview with Mr Henry Aubin, Montreal (18 September 1998).
20 Interview with Mr Michel Roy, President, and Mr Robert Maltais, Secretary
General, Conseil de Presse du Quebec, Montreal (18 September 1998).
21 Interview with Mr Gord Sinclair, CJD, Montreal (17 September 1998).
22 Interview with Mr Al MacKay, Cable Public Affairs Channel, Ottawa
(28 September 1998).
23 Interview with Mr Michael C. Auger, Le Journal de Montreal (21 September
1998).
24 Discussion with M. David Lepofsky, Toronto (23 August 1995).
25 Discussion with M. David Lepofsky, Toronto (3 October 1998).
26 World Report, Passages, Globe and Mail (20 July 1998), Metro, p. A10.
27 Interview with Professor Fred Fletcher, Head of the Mass Media Program,
York University, Ontario (5 October 1998).
28 Interview with Mr Michel Roy, Montreal (18 September 1998).
198 Notes
01 George Murray, The Press and the Public (Carbondale and Edwardsville:
Southern Illinois University Press, 1972), pp. 27–8.
02 Kenneth Morgan, ‘The British Press Council Experience’, in Richard T.
Kaplar (ed.), Beyond the Courtroom (Washington, D.C.: The Media Institute,
1990), p. 131; Home Office, Report of the Committee on Privacy and Related
Matters (London: Her Majesty’s Stationary Office, June 1990), Cm 1102,
p. 58; George Murray, The Press and the Public, op. cit., p. 66.
03 Louis Blom-Cooper, ‘Freedom and Responsibility: The Future of Press
Regulation in Britain’, Index on Censorship, Vol. 21, No. 3 (March 1992), p. 2.
Notes 201
47 On the Quebec Press Council, see David Pritchard, ‘The Role of News
Councils in a System of Media Accountability: Le Conseil de Quebec at Age
16’ (paper prepared for presentation to the annual meeting of the Canadian
Communication Association, Victoria, BC, 1 June 1990); idem, ‘Media
Accountability in Action: How the Quebec Press Council Handles Disputes’
(draft paper).
48 In June 1983 the British Columbia Press Council was formed.
49 Following the recommendations of the Kent Commission, in 1982 the gov-
ernment drafted a Canadian Newspaper Act that was in line with a policy
decision to regulate aspects of the newspaper industry. Both the policy and
the draft legislation were quickly abandoned, not only because of opposi-
tion from the industry, but also because the proposed Act was probably
unconstitutional in the light of the Charter’s protection of freedom of the
press. See Arthur Siegel, Politics and the Media in Canada (Toronto: McGraw-
Hill Ryerson, 1996), 2nd edn, p. 250.
50 Report of the Kent Commission, pp. 151–2.
51 Ibid., p. 152.
52 Interview with Mr Eddie Greenspon, Ottawa (25 September 1998).
53 Report of the Kent Commission, p. 152. See also Tom Kent, ‘The Time and
Significance of the Kent Commission’, in Helen Holmes and David Taras
(eds), Media, Power and Policy in Canada (Toronto: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich,
1992), pp. 21–39.
54 Maude Barlow and James Winter, The Big Black Book (Toronto: Stoddart,
1997), p. 122.
55 Some councils have additional funding. For instance, the Quebec Press
Council was donated $1 million by a private foundation.
56 This is the opinion of Professors Enn Raudsepp, Department of Journalism,
Concordia University (interview on 22 September 1998), and G. Stuart Adam,
Vice-President (Academic) of Carleton University, and formerly Director of
the School of Journalism and Communication at Carleton, Ottawa (interview
on 29 September 1998). Mr Michel Roy, President of the Quebec Press
Council, admitted that ‘the public does not know about our existence. We
should be more known’ (interview on 18 September 1998).
57 Four people work in the administration of the Quebec Press Council, includ-
ing the Secretary-General. They receive salaries. The President receives only a
small salary for expenses. Interview with Mr Robert Maltais, Secretary-General,
Conseil de Presse du Quebec (18 September 1998). Two people receive full
salaries in the Ontario Press Council, the Secretary-General and his secretary.
Interview with Mr Mel Sufrin, Executive Secretary of the Ontario Press Council
(6 October 1998). Two people receive part-time salaries in the Israel Press
Council, the Secretary-General and his secretary. The previous Secretary-
General of the Council was a volunteer. Discussions with Mr Bezalel Eyal,
Secretary-General of the Council (25 November 1998, 27 December 1998), and
Professor Amos Shapira, Deputy President of the Council (13 December 1998).
58 In 1997, the Ontario Press Council received 119 complaints. Only ten of
them were adjudicated, four were upheld, three upheld in part, and six were
dismissed, one with reservations. Interview with Mr Mel Sufrin, Executive
Secretary of the Ontario Press Council (6 October 1998); Annual Report,
1997 (Toronto: The Ontario Press Council), p. 9.
204 Notes
59 Mr Mel Sufrin told me that he was happy with the powers granted to the
Council. The papers were quite co-operative, so there was no need to have
more powers. Interview on 6 October 1998.
60 Mr Henry Aubin, senior columnist, member of the Editorial Board of the
Montreal Gazette, and member of the Quebec Press Council Board of
Directors, said that the Press Council’s adjudication is a slow process. It
takes a year, sometimes eighteen months. Interview on 18 September 1998.
61 Interview with Mr Michel Roy (18 September 1998).
62 Interview with Mr Michael C. Auger, political columnist, Le Journal de
Montreal, and President of La Federation Professionale des Journalistes
(21 September 1998).
63 David Pritchard, ‘The Role of News Councils in a System of Media Account-
ability: Le Conseil de Quebec at Age 16’, op. cit., 1 June 1990, pp. 18–19.
64 This is Mr Graham Fraser’s opinion (interview on 28 September 1998).
Mr Fraser is senior political reporter (parliamentary correspondent) for
the Globe and Mail and former Ottawa bureau chief and former Washington
correspondent for the Globe and Mail.
65 Interview with Professor Enn Raudsepp, Concordia University (22
September 1998).
66 Uri Paz, Inspection of the Media: The Relationship between the Press Council and
the Public, MA Thesis, Institute of Communication, the Hebrew University,
Jerusalem (May 1987), pp. 43– 4 (Hebrew).
67 Ibid., p. 46.
68 Ibid., p. 48.
69 Ibid., pp. 48–9. See also Moshe Zack, ‘The Press Council After Six Years’, The
Journalists Yearbook (1969), p. 336 (Hebrew).
70 Yitzhak Olshan, Judgments and Discussions ( Jerusalem and Tel Aviv:
Schocken, 1978), p. 383 (Hebrew).
71 Ibid., p. 384.
72 Ibid.
73 Dan Caspi and Yehiel Limor, The Mediators (Tel Aviv: Am Oved, 1992), p. 17
(Hebrew).
74 Israel Press Council, ‘Ad Hoc Committee, Conclusion and Recommenda-
tions’ (27 October 1998) (Hebrew).
75 Israel Press Council, Israel Press Council By-Laws, Professional Ethics Code of
the Press (updated to 1 July 1996), p. 5 (Hebrew).
76 Moshe Ronen, Media Ethics (Tel Aviv: Yedioth Ahronoth, 1998), Vol. II,
pp. 697–8 (Hebrew).
77 Interview with Professor Yitzhak Zamir, now Justice of the Israel Supreme
Court (3 January 1999).
78 Hadas Manor, ‘The Flickering of a Dying Candle?’, The Journalists Yearbook
(1993), p. 64 (Hebrew).
79 Interview with Justice Zamir (3 January 1999).
80 Interview with Justice Zamir (3 January 1999). The impotence of
the Council prompted Moshe Negbi to resign from this body. See his
criticism in Hadas Manor, ‘The Flickering of a Dying Candle?’, op. cit.,
p. 63.
81 Israel Press Council, Israel Press Council By-Laws, Professional Ethics Code of
the Press (updated to 1 July 1996), pp. 15–18 (Hebrew).
Notes 205
082 The Press Council By-Laws states that this authority is reserved for the
President of the Council or a person nominated by the President. Justice
Yitzhak Zamir and Attorney Haim Zadok, past presidents of the Council,
principally refrained from interfering in the dealings with complaints
(interviews on 31 December 1998; 3 January 1999).
083 Israel Press Council, Israel Press Council By-Laws, Professional Ethics Code of
the Press (updated to 1 July 1996), pp. 11–12 (Hebrew).
084 Ibid.
085 Israel Press Council, Ethics Tribunal, Select Decisions and Judgments (16
September 1996) (Hebrew), p. 5.
086 Israel Press Council, Israel Press Council By-Laws, Professional Ethics Code of
the Press (updated to 1 July 1996), p. 12 (Hebrew).
087 Interview with President Zadok of the Press Council (31 December 1998).
088 Interviews with Attorney Slonim (20 December 1998), and Secretary-
General Eyal (27 December 1998).
089 Statistics compiled by the Press Council. I thank Secretary-General Eyal for
the information.
090 Interview with Secretary-General Eyal (27 December 1998).
091 Discussion with Secretary-General Eyal (25 November 1998).
092 For further criticism of the Israel Press Council, see Dan Caspi and Yehiel
Limor, The Mediators (Tel Aviv: Am Oved, 1992), pp. 185–6, 207–12 (Hebrew).
093 Interview with President Zadok (31 December 1998).
094 Interview with Professor Shapira (13 December 1998).
095 Interview with Justice Zamir (3 January 1999).
096 Interview with Mr Bezalel Eyal (27 December 1998).
097 Report of the Public Committee on Press Laws, presented to the Minister of
Justice and Minister of the Interior (September 1997), p. 62 (Hebrew).
098 Ibid., pp. 62–3.
099 Four members of the Committee backed the decision. One member, Professor
Zeev Segal, thought that the recommended legislation might hinder the
work of the Press Council and its independent discretion to formulate eth-
ical norms as it sees fit. Ibid., p. 63.
100 Ibid.
101 Interview with Attorney Slonim (20 December 1998).
102 Interview with Secretary-General Eyal (27 December 1998).
103 Interview with President Zadok (31 December 1998).
104 Interview with Justice Zamir (3 January 1999).
105 Interview with Mr Anthony Smith (16 October 1997). Mr Smith is the
President of Magdalen College, Oxford. Among his many capacities,
Mr Smith was the Director of the British Film Institute for 10 years.
106 Interviews with Mr Anthony Smith (16 October 1997); Mr Charles Moore
(21 October 1997), and Justice Yitzhak Zamir (3 January 1999).
107 This is the suggestion of Mr Martin Bell, MP. Interview in the House of
Commons (21 October 1997).
108 In one of my interviews, an authority on one of the press councils told
me that on occasion the journalists exerted pressures on him to represent
their interests better. He said that he needed to remind them that he also
represents the editors and publishers. I reminded him, in turn, that the
Council is comprised also of a third, no-less important component: the
206 Notes
public. Indeed, I often felt that decisionmakers on the press councils are
preoccupied with the needs and interests of the press industry and less so
with those of the public.
109 The Israel Press Council decided (on 13 December 1998) that members of
the plenary could serve a maximum of three consecutive terms of three
years each and then retire so as to allow the introduction of new members.
Professor Asa Kasher strongly disagreed with this motion, saying that the
Press Council should be viewed as a professional body on which ethics
professionals should sit as long as they express willingness to continue
their voluntary work.
110 Interview with Mr Stephen Whittle, Director of the Broadcasting
Standards Commission (9 October 1997). For further deliberation, see
Broadcasting Standards Council, A Code of Practice (London, February
1994, 2nd edn); Broadcasting Standards Council, Complaints Bulletin, No.
54 (25 July 1995).
The Israeli Elections 1996 (New York: City University of New York Press, 1998);
G. Weimann and G. Wolfsfeld, ‘The Coverage of the Election Campaign on
Television’, Ha’ain Ha’shevieit, Vol. 5 (1996), pp. 20 –2 (Hebrew).
10 Ideally, it would have been better to include all segments of the Israeli
population in the poll. We had to limit the public poll to the Jewish
public mainly for economic reasons. If we had included the Palestinian
population (Christians and Muslims), the Bedouin, and the Druze, the
survey would have become far too costly. We may note that it is
also quite difficult to access some of these communities, and for these
reasons most public polls that are conducted in Israel are limited to the
Jewish public.
11 R. Cohen-Almagor, The Boundaries of Liberty and Tolerance, (Gainesville, FL.:
University Press of Florida, 1994), chap. 12; S. Chaffee and S. Frank, ‘How
Americans Get Political Information: Print versus Broadcast News’, Annals
of the American Academy of Political and Social Sciences, Vol. 546 (1996),
pp. 48–58.
12 M. McCombs, L. Danielian and W. Wanta, ‘Issues in the News and the
Public Agenda: The Agenda-setting Tradition’, in T. L. Glasser and C. T.
Salmon (eds), Public Opinion and the Communication of Consent (New York:
Guilford Press, 1995), pp. 281–300.
13 J. W. Carey, ‘The Press, Public Opinion and Public Discourse’, op. cit.,
pp. 373– 402. See also Justice Yitzhak Zamir’s judgment in Further Appeal
(F.A.) 7325/95 Yedioth Ahronoth v. Yoseph Kraus, Israel Supreme Court of
Justice (29 June 1998) (Hebrew).
14 D. H. Weaver, ‘What Voters Learn from Media’, Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Sciences, Vol. 546 (1996), pp. 34 – 47.
15 E. Katz, ‘And Deliver Us from Segmentation’, Annals of the American
Academy of Political and Social Sciences, Vol. 546 (1996), pp. 22–33.
16 A. Barak, ‘The Tradition of Freedom of Speech in Israel and Its Problems’,
Mishpatim, Vol. 27 (October 1996), pp. 223– 48 (Hebrew).
17 J. D. Peters, ‘Historical Tensions in the Concept of Public Opinion’, in T. L.
Glasser and C. T. Salmon (eds), Public Opinion and the Communication of
Consent, op. cit., pp. 3–32.
18 P. Jones, ‘Intense Preferences, Strong Beliefs and Democratic Decision
Making’, Political Studies, Vol. 36 (1988), pp. 7–29.
19 S. L. Feld and B. Grofman, ‘On the Possibility of Faithfully Representative
Committees’, American Political Science Review, Vol. 80 (1986), pp. 863–79.
20 C. Pateman, Participation and Democratic Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1979); Richard Dagger, Civic Virtues (New York:
Oxford University Press, 1997), esp. chap. 9.
21 J. R. Pennock and J. W. Chapman (eds), Liberal Democracy (New York and
London: New York University Press, 1983).
22 R. M. Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (London: Duckworth, 1977); R. M.
Dworkin, A Matter of Principle (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1985); R. Cohen-
Almagor, ‘Liberalism, and the Limits of Pluralism’, Terrorism and Political
Violence, Vol. 7 (1995), pp. 25– 48; F. Schauer, ‘The Cost of Communicative
Tolerance’, in R. Cohen-Almagor (ed.), Liberal Democracy and the Limits of
Tolerance (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 2000).
23 C. C. Euchner, Extraordinary Politics (Boulder, CO: Westview, 1996).
208 Notes
212
Index 213