(Palgrave Macmillan’s Critical Studies in Gender, Sexuality, and Culture) Robbie Duschinsky, Susan Walker (eds.) - Juliet Mitchell and the Lateral Axis_ Twenty-First-Century Psychoanalysis and Feminis
(Palgrave Macmillan’s Critical Studies in Gender, Sexuality, and Culture) Robbie Duschinsky, Susan Walker (eds.) - Juliet Mitchell and the Lateral Axis_ Twenty-First-Century Psychoanalysis and Feminis
Series Editors:
Titles:
Magnus Hirschfeld and the Quest for Sexual Freedom: A History of the First
International Sexual Freedom Movement
Elena Mancini
Queer Voices: Vocality, the Uncanny, and Popular Music
Freya Jarman-Ivens
On the Literary Nonfiction of Nancy Mairs: A Critical Anthology
Edited by Merri Lisa Johnson and Susannah B. Mintz
Antarctica as Cultural Critique: The Gendered Politics of Scientific
Exploration and Climate Change
Elena Glasberg
The Parallel Lives of Women and Cows: Meat Markets
Jean O’Malley Halley
Positioning Gender and Race in (Post)colonial Plantation Space:
Connecting Ireland and the Caribbean
Eve Walsh Stoddard
A Critical Inquiry into Queer Utopias
Edited by Angela Jones
Young People and Pornography: Negotiating Pornification
Monique Mulholland
Juliet Mitchell and the Lateral Axis: Twenty-First-Century Psychoanalysis
and Feminism
Edited by Robbie Duschinsky and Susan Walker
The Aesthetics of Cute in Contemporary Japanese Art
Yoke-Sum Wong [forthcoming]
Juliet Mitchell and
the Lateral Axis
Twenty-First-Century
Psychoanalysis and Feminism
Edited by
Introduction 1
Robbie Duschinsky and Susan Walker
Chapter 1
The Etiology of Hysteria in Mitchell’s Mad Men and Medusas 23
Susan Walker
Chapter 2
Siblings, Secrets, and Promises: Aspects of Infantile Sexuality 43
Daru Huppert
Chapter 3
Ideologies of the Super-Ego: Psychoanalysis and Feminism,
Revisited 57
Judith Butler
Chapter 4
Debating Sexual Difference, Politics, and the Unconscious:
With Discussant Section by Jacqueline Rose 77
Juliet Mitchell
Chapter 5
Dialectic and Dystopia: “This might come as a shock . . . ” 101
Robbie Duschinsky
Chapter 6
Marked by Freud, Mitchell, and the Freudian Project 131
Daru Huppert
Chapter 7
Hysteria between Big Brother and Patriarchy 147
Paul Verhaeghe and Eline Trenson
Chapter 8
Reframing Obsessional Neurosis: The Rat Man’s Siblings 169
Robbie Duschinsky and Rachel Leigh
vi C O N T EN T S
Chapter 9
Minimal Difference: On Siblings, Sex, and Violence 193
Mignon Nixon
Chapter 10
Crimes of Identity 207
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak
Chapter 11
Sisters at the Gate: Mean Girls and Other Sibling Phenomena 229
Gillian Harkins
Chapter 12
How Can We Live Ourselves? An Interview with
Juliet Mitchell 255
Preti Taneja
Bibliography 273
List of Contributors 283
Index 287
Introduction
* * *
simply operate upon our conscious intentions, but on our more tacit
sense of who we are and how to go about in the world. Mitchell identi-
fies this as an important factor, but suspects that this explanation still
cannot account for the continuities in women’s oppression over time and
across cultures. Mitchell did not reject socialist modes of explanation but
added to them a perspective drawn from Freudian psychoanalysis for the
purposes of making sense of the entrenchment of tendencies that run
counter to the espoused values of individuals and of society. In moving
from an analysis of false consciousness to the role of unconscious pro-
cesses, both the irrational and the intractable nature of women’s oppres-
sion became much clearer. In Mitchell’s words: “The unconscious that
Freud described could . . . be described as the domain of the reproduction
of culture and ideology” (Mitchell 1974, 413).
In the second half of Psychoanalysis and Feminism, Mitchell defends
Freud against the attacks and vilification heaped upon him by the second-
wave feminist because of his account of the inferiorized psychic status
of femininity. She highlights that this psychoanalytic account is not a
prescription of how things should be, but a description of an important
and neglected process through which women become the second sex.
The different relationship to the Oedipus crisis that forms the path-
ways to masculinity and femininity for male and female infants, forms,
for Freud, the basis of the psychic differentiation into male and female
subjectivity. That this drama leads to a state of psychic inferiority for
those whose fate is the feminine position is not inevitable: it is a result
of patriarchal culture, in which fathers are valorized and powerful, and
the power of the woman as reproductive mother is not. The hierar-
chy implicit in sexual differentiation is not, insists Mitchell, a distortion
caused by the patriarchal bias of the man who first described them.
The conditions of capitalism have led to a romantic idealization of the
nuclear family, and the ideology of patriarchy has led to a position of
psychic inferiority for women:
ideology functions, how we acquire and live the ideas and laws within
which we must exist. A primary aspect of the law is that we live
according to our sexed identity, our ever imperfect “masculinity” or
“femininity” . . . Differences of class, historical epoch, specific social
situations alter the expression of femininity; but in relation to the law
of the father, women’s position across the board is a comparable one.
When critics condemn Freud for not taking account of social reality,
their concept of that reality is too limited. The social reality that he is
concerned with elucidating is the mental representation of the reality
of society. (Mitchell 1974, 402–406)
extreme response to this threat, warding it off, is to stake out the terms
of difference by fixating on reproductive possibilities between boys and
girls (genital difference) and magnifying its social significance out of pro-
portion to its real effect. This need to emphasize difference as a condition
of what is perceived as a fragile existence and the need to murder the
potential usurper can support continuities in the denigration of women
even through variation in relations of production, over time and between
cultures. On the other hand, the successful negotiation of the trauma of
displacement and the recognition that there is room for more than one,
can lead to self-esteem, tolerance, and meaningful equality.
Siblings and the lateral axis allow Mitchell to theorize gender as sepa-
rate from sexual difference. For Mitchell, gender is a difference that need
not be a binary nor a hierarchy—just like the relationship between sib-
lings. By contrast sexual difference is the place one inhabits in the service
of reproduction, which under patriarchy is formulated as of necessity one
or other side of the binary phallus/no phallus. As Mitchell has proposed,
the sibling relationship asks the question “who am I?” of the subject, to
which a key response is differentiation by the manner of gender perfor-
mance. This differs, Mitchell suggests, from the child’s relationship with
parents who, on behalf of society’s norms, categorize and differentiate
children by reproductive sex:
With help, the ego is able to bind most of the raging energy—
never entirely and sometimes not very well at all. There remains some
identification with the violence of the traumatic experience, so that
throughout life, rages that echo or repeat the experience will be added
to already existent aggression and may erupt in personal violence or
be channelled into socially legitimated killing. (Mitchell 2013, 22)
Two months later, at the birth of her younger brother, the girl sud-
denly acquired certain linguistic modes, notably the imperfect. A con-
nection exists between the acquisition, the brother’s birth, and the
past emotion. How can we explain what happened? For the little girl
who knows she is about to have a brother or sister, the dog repre-
sented a symbol. The future schema: “brother-me-parents” has been
anticipated by “puppies-me-dog”. To assimilate this schema, the child
came to quit her position as the privileged object and took a maternal
attitude towards the newborn. It is necessary to move from a captive
attitude to an ablative attitude, from a passive attitude to a positive
attitude. We thus see the appearance of the use of the imperfect, of
the “me”, the “I”, and four future verbs. The future is an aggressive
tense: the subject takes hold in the future and makes projects; the use
of “me” and of “I” indicates that the subject adopts a more personal
attitude. The use of the imperfect shows that the young girl under-
stands that the present is extended; it is the past, but the past that
abides in the present. The imperfect is employed each time the baby is
brought up, the baby being what she was until now. (Merleau-Ponty
[1949–52] 2010, 245)
In Siblings (2003, 44), Mitchell argues, in line with Lacan and Klein,
that “representation and hence language relates to absence—what is not
there must be signified. Seriality, although it takes place within lan-
guage, is about numeracy not literacy.” Yet more recently Mitchell has
highlighted the potential significance of a sibling for language develop-
ment. She notes that “the sibling arrives when the toddler is mastering
speech; it is a time when the frustrations of inarticulacy and inexpress-
ibility occasion rage and despair”; when the child has to address others
like themselves but different, at whatever age, “the traumatic nucleus of
the experience will be referred to the typical time of two to two and a
half years, through deferred or referred action” (Mitchell 2013, 23–4).
Further developing this thought, it can be suggested that language can
involve the differentiation negotiated by the lateral axis, as well as the
relations of absence and presence negotiated by the vertical axis. We have
seen with Merleau-Ponty that lateral axis processes can be recognized as
significance for the differentiation—rather than negation—of individual
and role required for the imperfect tense. The lateral axis opens up a
space for placing past insights and for developing further work. This has
been our project in Juliet Mitchell and the Lateral Axis, in showing the
value of engagement with Mitchell’s work for contemporary concerns.
* * *
In the first chapter of the volume, Susan Walker tracks the development
of Mitchell’s theory of the etiology of hysteria. It was from this investiga-
tion that Mitchell discovered the significance of siblings for psychoana-
lytic theory, a finding she presented in her book Mad Men and Medusas
(2000). Walker first sets out Freud’s classical theory of the origins of
hysteria using the vertical axis and the Oedipus complex. She traces
how, as the theory developed, the original traumatic etiology of hysteria
was replaced by an emphasis on an incompatible idea of a sexual nature.
This shift in emphasis is, Walker notes, reversed by Mitchell who places
traumatic experiences back into the origins of hysteria. Walker outlines
Mitchell’s account of the catastrophic effect, upon the fragile baby-subject,
of the arrival of a sibling. This provokes intense ambivalence character-
ized by murderous hatred, and narcissistic love, for the new arrival who
is both nearly identical to and yet a replacement for the baby.
Walker notes Mitchell’s fascinating suggestion that the ambivalence
and desires first experienced in the pre-Oedipal sibling situation, may be
misread, in the necessary reconstruction, which takes place in the analysis
of a post-Oedipal adult, as the ambivalence and desires arising from the
Oedipal situation. This masks the effect of the lateral axis and conflates
INTRODUCTION 11
it with the effect of the vertical parent–child axis. Walker pulls together
Mitchell’s reworking of Freud’s metaphorical use of the “mystic writing
pad” to explain how trauma affects memory, and Mitchell’s account of
the regressive effect of trauma upon the hysterical adult. These two con-
cepts help the reader to understand Mitchell’s clinical observations and
explanations of some the symptoms of hysteria, such as bodily enactment
and memory loss. Walker then moves on to recount Mitchell’s use of the
Don Juan myth, to examine the forms that male hysteria may take, and
Mitchell’s suggestions for why male hysteria is denied or unrecognized,
both culturally and within psychoanalytic theory. Finally Walker outlines
Mitchell’s important emphasis on the presence of death and violence in
the hysterical condition. The close proximity of sexuality and death in
both the etiology and the enactment of hysterical symptoms are evidence
of the presence of violent hatred and love in the sibling encounter. The
chapter finishes with some thoughts on where Mitchell’s theory of the
importance of siblings for the psyche needs to be further explored and
developed.
In chapter 2, Daru Huppert explores further Mitchell’s innovative
theory of the lateral axis. He begins by noting that, prior to Mitchell,
siblings had no place within psychoanalytic thought: they were either
ignored because they did not fit within Oedipal theory, or were incorpo-
rated into that theory without remainder. As Mitchell (2013, 17) states,
“in Freud’s theoretical superstructure, sisters and brothers are placed in
the same category as mothers and fathers, and this amalgamation of par-
ents and siblings is usually followed without concern.” Mitchell’s work
gives sibling relationships a place within psychoanalytic theory, which she
calls the “lateral axis” in contrast to the “vertical axis” of parent–child
relations. At the heart of Mitchell’s account is an image of the older sib-
ling, who experiences the displacement from the position of “the Baby”
as an extreme existential threat.
In psychoanalytic terms, the newcomer represents a narcissistic injury.
Mitchell proposes that this injury is no less the experience of a younger
sibling—who has to find a place in an environment in which their older
sister or brother has already made their claim for parental attention and
availability. Furthermore, she suggests, the only child too has to face this
issue, but on a less favorable terrain: whereas real siblings can negotiate
with each other in actuality as well as in phantasy, “the ‘only’ child is
likely to have more, not fewer sisters and brothers than the child with sib-
lings. They are more active in the thoughts and feelings, the unconscious
and conscious fantasies, in the inner world of the ‘only’ child than they
are in those of its sibling peers. The ‘only’ child will ask What has hap-
pened? The ‘expected’ one has not arrived. What have I done wrong?”
12 R O B B I E D U S C H I N S K Y A N D S U S A N WA L K E R
(Mitchell 2013, 19). Huppert draws out that in Mitchell’s account of lat-
eral relations, the child’s first impulse is to presume that a sibling would
be more of themselves, a narcissistic extension of self. When this phantasy
is disappointed by the fact that the sibling is like me but different, then
feelings of hate will be evoked alongside feelings of tenderness. The issue
will be to what extent the child can recognize the other as warranting
love not because they are the same, but because of their mix of similari-
ties and differences. Huppert emphasizes that this is a difficult recogni-
tion, which is rarely a simple or linear process. However, it is helped when
a child has support from adults in making sense of their place and deter-
mining “who can stay up latest, have which piece of cake and survive the
murderous rivalries to win through to sibling and peer love, a law allow-
ing space for one who is the same and different” (Mitchell 2003, 52).
Having introduced Mitchell’s account of sibling relations, Huppert
then explores further its logic and implications. He observes that sibling-
oriented sexuality differs from the vertical sexuality of the Oedipus com-
plex. Above all, in contrast with some features of the Oedipus complex,
a wish for a baby does not form part of our sexual desire for a sibling.
He also considers that the taboos that prohibit sibling sexuality are often
organized differently. For example, he draws on his clinical experience to
suggest that siblings will often include a third child, who is not a brother
or sister, in their acts, so as to suspend, obscure, and thereby more easily
trespass the incest barrier. He also draws out that we are more likely to
have preconscious memories of early sexual wishes and acts with siblings
than with parents; Huppert urges recognition that behind these precon-
scious memories may well remain unconscious events or phantasies of
sexual wishes or hate for a sibling. Themes of keeping promises or keeping
secrets in our lives, Huppert suggests, may well receive investment from
our early and forgotten sibling relations in which these were in issue.
Huppert’s chapter closes by raising the question of whether the “sibling
complex” can be regarded as on the same level or of the same kind as the
Oedipus complex.
Juliet Mitchell’s account of the Oedipus complex continues to be at
the heart of the issues continued in chapters 3 and 4. Here, a dialogue is
presented between Judith Butler and Mitchell. In 2009 Butler addressed
a symposium held at the Centre for Gender Studies to honor Mitchell’s
retirement. Parts of this address were later published in an article for
the journal differences (Butler 2013), whereas other parts are published
here for the first time. In chapter 3 Butler praises Mitchell for the latter’s
“immeasurable influence” on subsequent feminist and psychoanalytical
thought. However, Butler also alleges that Mitchell remains tied to an
essentialist account of the difference between men and women, which
INTRODUCTION 13
fear becomes rather more explicable in light of the patient’s early mem-
ory that “he first noticed the difference between the sexes when he saw
his deceased sister Katherine (five years his senior) sitting on the pot”
[Topf ] ([1909] 2001, 276), his last memory of her before the memory in
which she dies. The Rat Man’s obsessional neurosis can, in this light, be
regarded as shaped by his confusion of love and hate for his dead sister
and father: the conflict between these feelings and those of his conscious
experience in adulthood animated obsessive symptoms directed toward
his beloved cousin, his younger sister, and a wish to exhibit his penis to
the ghost of his dead father.
Duschinsky and Leigh draw an account of what difficulties in nego-
tiating lateral relations might predispose an obsessional neurosis. They
suggest that siblings can raise two, related, issues: polarized opposition
between self and other, and the threat of encroachment. To some degree
a polarization of self-other and worries about encroachment by the sib-
ling are normative: Siblings often argue over which one has exclusive pos-
session of particular objects or spaces, for example experiencing clothes
as contaminated if handed down from older siblings. The clothes func-
tion here as a symbol of the potential encroachment of the sibling on
the existential place the subject is trying to carve out for themselves, and
the uniqueness that they fear may be required in order to warrant love.
However, it is argued that the trauma of the lateral axis can also pro-
duce more pathological behaviors, as in the case of the Rat Man where
lateral differentiation became confused with vertical negation, and love
with death. The chapter closes by reflecting on Freud’s observation that
“it is not at all rare for both of the two children to fall ill later on of a
defence neurosis—the brother with obsessions and the sister with hyste-
ria” (Freud [1896] 2001, 164). Duschinsky and Leigh suggest that same
cultural and familial forms that give the sister no recognized place and
thereby predispose her to hysteria encourage her brother to dream of
absolute presence or absence rather than degrees of differentiation, and
so predispose him to obsessional neurosis.
Relations of love and death are also explored in chapter 9 by Mignon
Nixon. Nixon takes Mitchell’s “lateral axis” and illustrates how it has been
presaged by, and provides a theoretical underpinning for, the postmodern
turn in the humanities, especially as it finds expression in commentary
on war, militarism, and sexualized violence. She begins by observing
that the separation of psychoanalytical theory from gender theory has
impoverished both. The need to understand, and think through, aspects
of “minimal difference,” “alliance and affinity,” which the lateral axis
allows, is especially important in a militaristic culture. Psychoanalysis,
Nixon claims, finds itself condemned as a defender of orthodox patriarchy
INTRODUCTION 19
by those interested in gender theory and feminism, and viewed with sus-
picion as a science of subjectivity, by a “war culture [which] disavows
subjectivity.” Nixon charts the reasons for the engagement and later dis-
engagement of psychoanalysis and politics over the last 40 years.
Nixon sees in Mitchell’s portrayal of sexualized violence a prescient
account of the atrocities that occurred in the Iraq war, and in particular
in Abu Ghraib prison, and a belated theorizing of the abundance of vio-
lent sexuality, “violence perversion,” and “strangely subjective atrocity”
in war since the time of the Vietnam war. Nixon’s chapter illustrates
how these atrocities have been has been portrayed and protested by art-
ists, such as Spero. The final section of the chapter focuses on the chal-
lenges of representing seriality (what Nixon terms social subjectivity)
and lateral relations, how it has been represented in serial art and mini-
malism, and includes a detailed account of Yvonne Rainer’s protest work
Street Action.
Chapter 10, by Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, also thinks about Mitchell’s
work and how it can help us think about violence. She considers how the
allocation of identities can provide important scaffolding for acts of vio-
lence to those whose identities then situate them as violable. In this, she
attends particularly to the identities that offer explicit or tacit support to
support acts of rape, which make rape in certain regards a collective act.
Spivak focuses particularly on the role of transcendent grounds, such as
the Kantian a priori, in formulating an image of the human as elevated
by reason—and the role of this elevated image of the human in dividing
between violable and inviolable, rapeable and nonrapeable subjects in
ways distributed by race, class, and sex. Spivak urges us to reconsider the
division between transcendental and phenomenal, which has continued
to guide our thinking about human life and ethics, and to attend to the
significance of rape as formulating and expressing the boundaries that
have been constructed for what it is to be human. Such attention brings
into view the significance of both the differences in reproductive possi-
bilities between subjects and the role of heteronormativity in organizing,
naturalizing, and simplifying these possibilities through tacit appeal to
the transcendent grounds of human life: in Spivak’s words, “reproductive
heteronormativity” can be regarded “as the social account of the tran-
scendental and unconditional discursivity of rape in the general sense.”
She draws out the implications of her argument by thinking about how
redress for rape should be enacted in global contexts without appealing to
“humanity.” Spivak also engages in a reading of cultural artifacts includ-
ing in J. M. Coetzee’s novel Disgrace and the copyright protocols for
photographs, raising questions about what counts as meaningful protection
from violation.
20 R O B B I E D U S C H I N S K Y A N D S U S A N WA L K E R
I now made a venture and told Ruth that the balls in the tumbler,
the coins in the purse and the contents of the bag all meant chil-
dren in her Mummy’s inside, and that she wanted to keep them safely
shut up so as not to have any more brothers and sisters. The effect of
my interpretation was astonishing. For the first time Ruth turned her
attention to me and began to play in a different, less constrained, way.
(Klein 1932/1975, p. 27)
INTRODUCTION 21
References
Balint, Enid. 1998. Before I was I, edited by Michael Parsons and Juliet
Mitchell, New York: Other Press.
Butler, Judith. “Ideologies of the Superego,” presented at the Centre for
Gender Studies, Cambridge University, May 2008.
Connell, Raewyn. 2012. “The books that inspired,” accessed at: http://blogs
.lse.ac.uk/lsereviewofbooks/2012/04/22/academic-inspiration-raewyn
-connell/
Flax, Jane. 1992. “Juliet Mitchell.” In The Routledge Dictionary of Twentieth-
Century Political Thinkers, edited by Robert Benewick & Philip Green,
228–229. London: Routledge.
Freud, Anna and Dann, Sophie. 1951. “An experiment in group upbringing.”
Psychoanalytic Study of the Child, 6: 127–68.
Freud, Sigmund. [1896] 2001. “Further remarks on the neuropsychoses of
defence,” SE 3, 159–188.
Freud, Sigmund. [1909] 2001. “Notes upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis.”
In Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud, Volume 10, edited and translated by James Strachey, 153–318.
London: Vintage (SE 10).
Gilmore, Karen. 2013. “Theory of sibling trauma and lateral dimension,”
Psychoanalytical Study of the Child, 67: 53–65.
Grosz, Elizabeth. 1990. Jacques Lacan: A Feminist Introduction, London:
Routledge.
Klein, Melanie. [1932] 1975. The Psycho-Analysis of Children. London:
Hogarth Press and Institute of Psycho-Analysis.
Lament, Claudia. 2013. “An introduction.” Psychoanalytical Study of the
Child, 67: 1–13.
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice. 2010. Child Psychology and Pedagogy [1949–1952],
translation by Talia Welsh, Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press.
22 R O B B I E D U S C H I N S K Y A N D S U S A N WA L K E R
Susan Walker
In her book Mad Men and Medusas (2000), Mitchell starts with an
exploration of male hysteria and ends with the discovery of the impor-
tance of siblings, and the subsequent need for a lateral “sibling” axis, to
complement Freud’s vertical “parent–child” axis. The aim of this chapter
is to outline the complex arc of this theoretical development, starting
with Freud’s original theory.
Freud’s science of psychoanalysis owes its origin to the experiences of
attempting to categorize and treat the malady called hysteria. Hysteria,
in the nineteenth century, comprised a wide range of psychological and
physical symptoms, and of personality traits. These included anesthesia
and motor control (i.e., movement) problems, abulias (inhibitions of
will), amnesia, and characterological disturbances such as craving, flirta-
tiousness, compulsive lying, shallowness, jealously, and overemotionality.
Hysteria could present with a range of physical symptoms such a pseudo-
fits, death-like trances, neurologically unexplained paralyses, contrac-
tures, and “tics.” It was noted to mimic a range of organic diseases,
but also had theatrical qualities, in which the hysterical person could
display a range of bizarre postures or movements. Dissociative states and
“la belle indifference” (i.e., a lack of concern about manifest physical
symptoms) were psychological symptoms assigned to hysteria, as were
anxiety, depression, hallucinations, breathing difficulties and choking
sensations, and loss of the ability to speak. The wide range of symptoms
present in hysteria made it difficult to describe or categorize, but, by
Freud’s time it was accepted that these symptoms were of psychological,
not physical (i.e., organic), origin.
Unlike “obsessional neurosis,” hysteria did not come into existence as
a Freudian category. Hysteria itself, as a concept, has an ancient history,
24 S U S A N WA L K E R
which has been well described (Tasca et al. 2012). In Mad Men and
Medusas, Mitchell examines the apparent “disappearance” of hysteria in
the twenty-first century, in the context of the lack of recognition of male
hysteria, and argues that hysteria, affecting both men and women, is still
present but has become hidden. This chapter will explore Mitchell’s devel-
opment, first set out in Mad Men and Medusas (2000), of fundamental
and original Freudian ideas regarding the origins and manifestations of
hysteria and indicate how these complex arguments have illuminated the
need to further explore the psychic consequences of siblings, which led
to Mitchell’s development of a theory of the lateral axis.
Freud’s initial belief was that hysterical symptoms are the result of
sexual trauma, caused by enforced sexual activity, which occurs before
sexual maturity. These were assaults, by adults, including fathers, against
children, but also assaults by older brothers against younger sisters (Freud
1896a, 151–156; 1896b, 162–185). The role of actual sexual trauma is
described clearly in his account of the “analysis” or conversation with
Katharina, who complained of hysterical symptoms, which Freud traced
back to an unsuccessful sexual assault on the girl by her father/uncle
(Freud 199, 190–201).
In the subsequent years, Freud revised his theory and the idea of a
traumatic element was to some extent replaced with the idea that “hys-
teria originates through the repression of an incompatible idea from
a motive of defence” (Freud 1991, 370–1). To defend itself from this
incompatible idea the ego deploys the defence mechanism of repression
(1894, 53–55). In Freud’s account of the origin of hysterical symptoms,
the ego “represses” the traumatic event into the unconscious part of the
T HE ET IOLOGY OF H YST ERIA 25
mind, meaning that the person no longer has any conscious awareness of
it. The excitation attached to the incompatible idea is transformed into a
physical symptom. Freud named this process “conversion,” and with this
explanation provided a mechanism whereby incompatible or repressed
ideas in hysteria can find expression through the body (1894, 48–49).
Freud later adjusted his etiology of hysterical symptoms, from one
which suggested an origin in childhood sexual abuse, to one in which
the sexual relationship that forms the incompatible idea is a phantasized
one, and thus a universal facet of human development (i.e., not limited
to victims of childhood sexual abuse) (Freud 1896b, 168, footnote 1;
1917, 370).
I was driven to recognise in the end that these reports were untrue
and so came to understand that hysterical symptoms are derived from
phantasies not real occurrences (Freud 2005, 419).
also accept that she is “castrated” and transform her desire for a penis
into a desire for a baby, originally from her father, but again deferred
until adulthood, and conceived in partnership with another man (Freud
1917, 329–338; 1924, 395–401; 1925, 402–411).
This formulation, at face value, makes it easy to see why Freudian
theory can be used to suggest that hysteria would affect women more
frequently than men. The girl child is lacking (a penis), and rejected (by
both mother and father as a sexual partner). A failure to accept this state
of affairs, and the prohibition which brings it about, and to continue to
desire (unconsciously) what she cannot have, leads to classical hysterical
symptoms affecting personality such as insatiable wanting, coquettish-
ness, and dissatisfaction, which demonstrate a sense of lack, as well as
movement between the feminine and masculine positions, in an attempt
to be the subject of desire for the mother, or object of desire for the
father. The trauma of Oedipal rejection can be reactivated by subsequent
perceived rejections or prohibited ideas later in life. The failed repression
of the forbidden desire or idea will manifest itself, in hysteria, in conver-
sion symptoms that somatically express that which is desired and which is
lost or forbidden. This is the template for hysterical symptoms of Oedipal
origin in women.
For boys the situation plays out somewhat differently. Given the above
explanation of the origins of the hysterical woman’s sense of “lack” we
might ask “what lack is the hysterical man unconsciously trying to make
up for?” Clearly the boy comes to experience his father as a threat and
as an obstacle to having his mother. He has a small penis compared to
his father (a comparative lack), but he can take his father’s place (with
another woman), not now but later. The symbolic castration introduces
the threat of the destruction of the boy’s phallic, narcissistic pleasure,
but this is an unrealized threat, unlike the “already carried out” castra-
tion of the girl (Freud 2005, 410). However Freud also believed (and
Mitchell has emphasized) that children, at and slightly preceding the
time of the Oedipal crisis, do not simply want to be the sexual partner
of their mother: they want to have a baby as she can (Mitchell 2003, 39;
Freud 1909, 1–150). This desire to produce a baby parthenogenically,
out of narcissistic plenitude, in identification with the mother, precedes
the girl child’s wish for a baby as a penis substitute. And for boys and
girls this second, somewhat eclipsed, desire is also prohibited as they
come to understand the reality of their reproductive positions, but has
separate outcomes for the girl and for the boy. This time it is the girl who
is told that she cannot have a baby now, but that she can later. For the boy
he must accept that fact that he cannot give birth to a baby. This is also a
prohibition experienced as “lack.” Mitchell coins the phrase the “Law of
T HE ET IOLOGY OF H YST ERIA 27
Mitchell formulates her theory of the lateral axis in her book Mad Men
and Medusas: Reclaiming the Effects of Sibling Relations on the Human
Condition, published in 2000. In the book, Mitchell sets out to examine
three facets of hysteria: the nonrecognition of male hysteria, including
hysterical violence; the elaboration of the death drive in hysteria; and the
neglect, in classical Freudian theory, of the role played the construction
of the psyche by lateral relationships (Mitchell 2000, ix, x). These three
are entwined at a conceptual level. In exploring the origins of hyste-
ria, Mitchell argues that the effect of trauma, and the threat of death/
a nnihilation, have been neglected, and that this neglect has facilitated
(and been facilitated by) the nonrecognition of male hysteria.
In returning to trauma as an originating factor in the genesis of
hysteria, Mitchell argues for a position that can recognize hysteria as a
universal (not simply feminine) possibility. In stressing the lateral axis,
Mitchell allows space for a type of difference that is not predicated on the
complementarity of two roles (male and female) in reproduction. It is the
recognition by the mother, of a series of children, each in the same struc-
tural and generational position, but different in their unique identities
that allows this alternative difference. Difference that is not determined
by polar opposites can accommodate diversity and “t ransversality.” The
coincidence of sameness and distinction, along a lateral axis, allows
for both/and, rather than the either/or (male/female; mother/father;
castrated/whole) of vertical relationships (Mitchell 2000, xi–xii).
Lateral Relationships
For Mitchell, sibling relationships are the first social relationship and
one characterized by love and murderous hatred (Mitchell 2000, 20).
The love derives from the child’s expectation that the sibling will be a
narcissistic extension of itself (Mitchell 2003, 29, 64). The other side
of this coin is the realization that the sibling occupies the same place
as the child, both in the family structure, and, crucially in relation to
the mother. The realization, produced by the appearance of a sibling,
that the baby/child is not the only person in the position of “child to
the parent” is experienced as a trauma and as a possible annihilation
(Mitchell 2000, 20–21). The fragile subject (baby to the mother) is
annihilated because another baby has taken its place. This annihilation
of the “baby-subject,” unlike the threatened annihilation of castration
anxiety, is actual. The child/baby has lost its subjective identity. It is, to
its immature mind, nowhere and nobody, because of the arrival of the
sibling who has replaced it. The child/baby has lost its unique identity
because the sibling is the same as it. Because of the premature birth of
T HE ET IOLOGY OF H YST ERIA 29
the human infant, and its complete dependence on its parents, displace-
ment may be fatal. The realization of a sibling’s existence can, Mitchell
argues, reawaken or cause regression to the state of infantile helplessness
and the anxieties that accompanied it. Loss of place, as the mother’s
(only) baby threatens death, and murder becomes a possible solution for
survival. On the other hand the arrival of a sibling may also be under-
stood as a narcissistic extension of the self, and someone so like oneself,
yet not oneself, can be loved, in a manner that may be on the border
of narcissistic and object-love (Mitchell 2003, 36). Mitchell insists that
both love and death are inherent in the sibling experience, and also in
hysteria, which she argues is provoked by the “catastrophic awareness
that one is not unique” (Mitchell 2000, 20).
Mitchell suggests that the love and hate inherent in the sibling rela-
tionship, when recounted and recalled from the present to the past in the
analysis of an adult, may influence the reconstruction of the (unconscious)
Oedipal emotions. It is important to stress that Mitchell does not suggest
that the Oedipal complex is unimportant, or merely a derivative of the
effect of siblings. However she does suggest that in an adult analysis, in
which unconscious desires and emotions are necessarily reconstructed,
some aspects of the love and hate derived from the sibling experience are
“read backwards” onto the parental relationships in the Oedipus com-
plex. In this way the effect of siblings may be overlooked in analysis, and
reconstructed as Oedipal desires and ambivalence.
The influence of the lateral axis on the vertical, in the genesis of
hysteria, is missed, in Freudian theory, because of the emphasis on the
vertical relations within the Oedipal complex. If the echoing effect of
past traumas upon subsequent ones is not recognized then the trauma
inflicted by a sibling earlier in the life of an infant, before the time of
the Oedipus complex, may be subsequently reinterpreted by an analyst,
treating an adult hysteric, as trauma associated with the Oedipal crisis.
Mitchell suggests that siblings threaten the existence (the being) of the
infant. The threat of “not being” is mistaken for the earlier threat of “not
having” the mother or her breast. But since the adult in analysis is inevi-
tably post-Oedipal, this “not having” is “read backwards” by the adult
hysteric, as unconscious threats around “having” or “not having” the
mother, and/or the father, in the Oedipal situation (Mitchell 2000, 47).
Thus although the craving and the conflicts around “having/not hav-
ing” (i.e., Oedipal conflicts) predominate in the clinical picture of the
adult hysteric, it may in fact be the threat to “being” (which the adult
is experiencing in the present) that precipitates a hysterical reaction, and
which echoes the threat to “being” from siblings in the traumatic past.
This lateral trauma is missed and leads to the omission of the influence
30 S U S A N WA L K E R
Trauma
Mitchell contends that the original trauma for everyone is the helpless-
ness of birth (Mitchell 2000, 291, 299). For Mitchell, a second universal
trauma is the annihilation of subjectivity, precipitated by the appearance
of a sibling, or in the case of an only child the apprehension of the pos-
sibility of a sibling. The loss of subjectivity is caused by the structural
displacement of the immature child from his or her position as “baby to
the mother.”
Mitchell regards this structural displacement (which should not be
confused with displacement as an unconscious process that constitutes
a defence mechanism) as equivalent to an annihilation of the immature
and fragile “baby-subject.” The annihilatory threat has two roots. The
first is the real risk of death to the infant if the mother does reject it upon
the arrival of a younger sibling. This threat builds upon the earlier real-
ity of the complete dependence of the baby upon the care of the mother
(or parental substitute). The second is the risk to the fragile, developing
sense of subjectivity in the infant. At this early stage, subjectivity is based
upon a “body-ego,” derived from the infant’s narcissistic investment in
its own body and the care supplied by the mother, and also by the mother’s
recognition of the baby and the identity that provides.
When the mother’s care is diverted to another baby, the infant is no
longer in the place of “baby to the mother,” and the subjectivity derived
from this position is threatened. Someone else (the new arrival) is the
same as the infant, and so both the baby’s unique identity and subjec-
tivity destroyed. The prominence of the body in terms of the infant’s
subjectivity at this stage in life may be related to the later use of the body
in conversion hysteria.
However, Mitchell argues that these traumas and threatened annihi-
lations, in themselves, do not set up a hysterical illness, but only lay the
groundwork for it. Subsequent rejections or displacements (in Mitchell’s
structural sense), which resonate with the trauma caused by the dis-
covery of a sibling, will reawaken the threat of annihilation in later life.
A present-day rejection or displacement, experienced by the hysterical
adult as a traumatic event that threatens the adult’s sense of subjectiv-
ity or “place,” or which delivers a narcissistic blow, will build upon the
original trauma of sibling displacement, and produce a hysterical reaction.
T HE ET IOLOGY OF H YST ERIA 31
The present-day adult event will take the appearance of the cause of
the hysterical symptom or illness, whose roots are much earlier. As an
example, the breaking off of an engagement (which means one is no
longer a fiancé/e and future spouse) can be experienced as both a nar-
cissistic wound and an event that threatens the adult’s sense of place,
and can trigger a hysterical reaction. Freud explained this mechanism of
resonance between originating and present-day traumas in his discus-
sion of the treatment of Fraulein Elizabeth von R:
In the great majority of instances we find that a first trauma has left
no symptoms behind, while a later trauma of the same kind produces
a symptom. (Freud 1893a 1991, 245)
Mitchell emphasizes that these events can return in a form that is not the
normal representation of memory (Mitchell 2000, 282).
Freud proposed that memory worked in the manner of a “mystic writ-
ing pad” where a double layer of celluloid and wax paper, overlying a slab
of dark wax, allows marks to be made with a stylus on the wax paper,
and then erased by lifting the paper from the wax (Freud 1925). Freud
proposed that perception is analogous to the wax paper, and memory
analogous to the permanent marks on the wax. The celluloid is necessary
to protect the wax paper, just as he proposed a protective shield against
stimuli, was part of the outermost surface of the mind. Working with
Freud’s original metaphor of memory as a “mystic writing pad,” Mitchell
suggests that psychic trauma breaks through the cellophane shield and
wax paper of “perception-consciousness” to form unconscious traces, of
which there are no wax paper marks (i.e., no memories) (Freud 1895;
1925; 1991; Mitchell 2000, 288, 291). She suggests that trauma should
be defined, not by its content, but by the criterion of whether or not it
breaches psychic defences, leaving a gap or a deathly void in the subject
(Mitchell 2000, 299). The pathological gap in the subject, she suggests,
is experienced as one of nonrecognition, and the subsequent absence of
the “I” (Mitchell 2000, 309). In the hysterical response a trauma, how-
ever small, repeats the perception, not the memory, of an earlier trauma.
The difference between memory and perception being that perception
feels and is experienced as reality, not fantasy nor memory (ibid).
Hysteria, Mitchell states, “models itself on trauma” (Mitchell 2000,
316). Mitchell notes that in hysteria, memory (of a specific event) is not
formed but is replaced by perception (Mitchell 2000, 315–6). The rel-
atively healthy process of experience and representation in memory is
replaced by oscillations between perceptual presence of the event (as in
hysterical bodily symptoms) and absence (of memory).
The concept of deferral of effect or Nachträglichkeit is revisited in
Mitchell’s discussion of trauma. A present-day traumatic event (i.e., one
that is subjectively experienced as traumatic) is, Mitchell argues, a catalyst
for the revival of a former, earlier experience of trauma (Mitchell 2000,
299). Due to resonance with earlier stages of life, when loss of place
as “baby to the mother” had the potential to be life-threatening, the
trauma of displacement is experienced by the hysteric as death-like, both
for the infant originally and for the adult who is regressed to infancy by
the present trauma, however mild it may seem to the outside observer.
Mitchell points out that many of the symptoms of hysteria, both
physical (i.e., frenetic activity, ceaseless chatter) and psychological (e.g.,
craving, compulsive lying) can be thought of as frantic attempts to fill
up the void that has opened, or has threatened to open, at the heart of
T HE ET IOLOGY OF H YST ERIA 33
version of normal male heterosexuality. She uses the Don Juan story, in
which death and compulsive empty sexual encounters, are both promi-
nent, to illustrate the apparently normal heterosexuality of the male hys-
teric (Mitchell 2000, 251–6).
The absence of Don Juan from psychoanalytical myth (as distinct from
Oedipus) is, for Mitchell, a repudiation of a clear depiction of male hyste-
ria, in which sex and violence are contiguous, lying compulsive, jealousy
rife, death feared but not accepted as final, and sexuality is serial and
nonreproductive. Mitchell finds a contemporary clinical description of
male hysteria in Limentani’s Vagina man, who is also charming, narcissis-
tic, and identified with the “women as mother” who protects him from
primal anxiety (Limentani 1984; Mitchell 2000, 261). Identification, in
the psychoanalytical sense, is a regressive “merging” with another person,
at an unconscious level. It is the developmental prelude to an emotional
tie with another person (an object choice) but can also be a means of cop-
ing with the loss of an important person.
Mitchell emphasizes that hysteria is triggered by displacement (loss of
place) in lateral relations, first of all by siblings and subsequently peers,
marital or sexual partners (Mitchell 2000, 266). For the male hysteric,
exhibiting Don Juanism, repeated sexual encounters with women, far
from being repetitive object choice, are in fact repetitive enactments of
regressive identification with the mother, the reactivation of whose origi-
nal loss (with the arrival of a sibling) causes unbearable anxiety (Mitchell
2000, 266). Mitchell sees in endless seduction and seductiveness, which
is a characteristic of the hysteric, male or female, a desperate, repeated
attempt to fill a void in the seducer.
In contrast Freudian explanations of male hysteria hinge solely around
the Oedipus conflict. Oedipal conflict involves incestuous wishes towards
the mother, which are resolved by accepting the prohibition emanat-
ing from the father, and acknowledging his prior rights to her. If a man
refuses to accept the prohibition (in Lacan’s phrase, the “Law of the
Father”) he becomes neurotic, with his Oedipal desires and position
unresolved (Freud 2005, 361 footnote; 1917, 328–338). But Mitchell
insists that what Freud could not see was his own (at the time of the
development of his theory) contemporaneous, hysterical identification
with his close friend Fleiss who stood in a peer or sibling relationship
with Freud (Mitchell 2000, 45–63).
Mitchell uses Freud’s “little hysteria,” reported in his letters with
Fleiss during which he conducted a self-analysis, as her starting point for
a reexamination of the repression of male hysteria from psychoanalyti-
cal thinking, which has persisted until the present day (Mitchell 2000,
49). She argues that, as a consequence of not fully acknowledging the
36 S U S A N WA L K E R
hysterical and the sibling element of the relationship with Fleiss, Freud
developed a distaste for the subject of hysteria, and an unconscious ten-
dency to neglect the existence of male hysteria, which has influenced
subsequent psychoanalytical and cultural understandings of the condi-
tion (Mitchell 2000, 63).
Attempting to provide an explanation for the construction of hysteria
as a female disorder, Mitchell makes a number of observations. Firstly, in
a hysterical patient the inability to accept the prohibition of incestuous
desire for the mother can appear much more pathological in a female
patient, than in a male, in whom unconscious desire for the woman/
mother can masquerade as normal heterosexuality. The “negative”
Oedipal position, in which a boy has incestuous wishes for his father,
and identifies with his mother, is recognized as hysterical, but is often
conflated with homosexuality (Mitchell 2000, 75).
Secondly, a hysterical man, who in Don Juan–like fashion, identifies
with woman after woman, in a stream of sexual conquests, which are
strictly nonreproductive in intent, can pass off his behavior as “normal”
hypersexual masculinity (Mitchell 2000, 323–326).
Furthermore, the greater numbers of women who are diagnosed as
hysterical today may be partially explained, in the developed and devel-
oping worlds, by the greater social propensity for sisters to be displaced
in the kinship structure, without an adequate compensatory mecha-
nism for them to regain their place, to re-find their feet or “standing.”
Displacement (i.e., loss of place), if it provokes a hysterical response,
throws the girl/woman back to the trauma of the original loss of the
“baby-subject” and triggers hysterical symptoms. In this way Mitchell
adds onto the classical account of a girl’s “lack” of a phallus, a social
account of a girl’s “lack” of a place.
Thus gendered social expectations can mask or highlight the symp-
toms of hysteria differently in men and women, leading to hysteria
appearing to be a gendered phenomenon, affecting primarily women and
homosexual men.
Conclusion
Mitchell draws together, firstly, the loss of “place” (displacement) of
the baby-subject, upon the real or anticipated arrival of a sibling that
results in the loss of a primitive “I”; secondly, subsequent events that
are experienced as traumatic because they connect with and recall/
relive displacement and subjective extinction; and finally the action
of “Nachträglichkeit” (deferred or retrospective effect), which allows
previous traumas to become flavored by or defined by later events or
developmental processes. This third point means that psychoanalytic
treatment, which acts from the present to examine the past, is always
uncovering events viewed through the lens of subsequent later events
and understandings.
This constellation of understandings leads directly to Mitchell’s sub-
sequent “discovery” of the importance of siblings and the existence of
sibling-induced trauma, in the genesis of hysteria, and provides an expla-
nation for why it has been overlooked in favor of an Oedipal focus.
Mitchell is firm that the potential for hysteria is a universal human
condition and that men and women are equally susceptible to it. The
genesis of hysteria is the precarious position of the human baby, born
“prematurely” and so utterly dependent on having a place, as “baby
to the mother.” The close proximity of life and death at this juncture
has profound effects on the psyche. Her firm belief in the universality
of hysteria encourages Mitchell to investigate of the fate of male hys-
teria. Mitchell starts by adding to the Oedipal prohibition (you can-
not possess your mother for she belongs to your father), which the
hysteric refuses, a second parthenogenic prohibition, which is that you
cannot, as a child, have a baby that will be an extension of yourself.
Mitchell insists that the hysteric, male or female, refuses both these
prohibitions.
The event that traumatically displaces everyone, thus reviving the
threat of death from parental neglect, is the arrival, real or imagined,
of a sibling. The profound ambivalence toward a new sibling, that is,
hatred for the one who displaces the subject, thus exposing him or her to
annihilation, and love for the sibling who is so much like oneself, must
be overcome.
40 S U S A N WA L K E R
If jealousy of the sibling, who has taken one’s place, results in a regres-
sive craving to possess the mother, and to be everything to the mother,
and /or a regressive identification involving a parthenogenic fantasy of
giving birth like the mother, then both of these wishes are likely to be
prohibited. Similarly the violent desire to kill the sibling, who has taken
the infant’s place, will also be prohibited.
If both regressive and murderous solutions are prohibited, this throws
the child back to the threat of annihilation. And the regression to this
point can be repeated, by the hysterical adult, every time a displacement
or rejection occurs in later life.
The extent to which the child is able to overcome his/her sense of
annihilation, and find a place along the lateral axis, with the sibling who
has an equal claim on both parents, determines whether sibling trauma
will produce a temporary regression or a propensity to full-blown hysteri-
cal condition (Mitchell 2000, 320).
If the trauma inherent in finding one’s place along the lateral axis is
not recognized, but only the sexual strivings and identification of hyste-
ria in the vertical axis are acknowledged, then Mitchell argues that the
male hysteric must always be seen as feminine or as homosexual. More
importantly the “deathliness” of hysteria will not be fully recognized.
Mitchell charts the development of hysteria along these lines. The
arrival of a sibling entails the reordering of the child’s place in the world,
as no longer unique but one of many, each part of a series of subjects
who are in the same structural place (i.e., peers) but not identical. One
solution to this displacement is regression to the desire to be one with/
the only one for the mother, but this move will be prohibited, and with
this the trauma of a-subjectivity (having no place/not being recognized)
becomes a threat. The regression to the trauma of potential annihilation,
caused by the arrival of a sibling, along with the murderousness, and
identification with the one to whom one feels murderous (i.e., the sibling
who is almost identical to oneself), places death and the death drive at
the heart of hysteria, as much as sexuality.
Each subsequent displacement that triggers a hysterical reaction in
the adult, is a re-ordering that cannot be thought through but is instead
treated as a trauma, and calls up the deathliness of the original trauma,
T HE ET IOLOGY OF H YST ERIA 41
Notes
1. Although in the case of the repression of Oedipal phantasies in the
boy, it is the traumatic possibility of castration that leads to repression
of both the desire and the prohibition.
2. Mitchell also uses the phrase the Law of the Mother to express the
interdict on either murdering or incestuously possessing one’s sibling.
In these ways the Law of the Mother polices the lateral axis (see later
section on “Death and Sexuality in Hysteria”).
3. In her development of her theory outlined in Siblings (2003), Mitchell
differentiates between traumatic/war neurosis and hysteria, by stat-
ing that in traumatic neurosis the trauma is happening in the present,
whereas in hysteria the originating trauma has happened in the past.
42 S U S A N WA L K E R
References
Freud, S. [1893b] 1991. “Charcot.” In The Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud Vol. 3, translated by James Strachey,
11–23. Hogarth Press, London (SE3).
Freud, S. [1894] 1991. “The Neuropsychoses of Defence,” SE3, 41–61.
Freud, S. [1895] 1991. “Project for a Scientific Psychology,” SE1, 283–397.
Freud, S. [1896a] 1991. “Heredity and the Neuroses,” SE3, 151–6.
Freud, S. [1896b] 1991. “Further Remarks on the Psychoneuroses of Defence,”
SE3, 162–85.
Freud, S. [1898] 1991. “The Psychical Mechanism of Forgetfulness,” SE3,
287–303.
Freud, S. [1901] 1991. “Fragments of an Analysis of a Case of Hysteria,”
SE7, 1–122.
Freud, S. [1909] 1991. “Analysis of a Phobia in a Five Year Old Boy,” SE10,
5–148.
Freud, S. [1910] 1991. “Five Lectures of Psychoanalysis,” SE11.
Freud, S. [1917] 1991. “The Development of the Libido and the Sexual
Organisations,” SE16, 329–38.
Freud, S. [1924] 2005. “The Dissolution of the Oedipus Complex” in The
Essentials of Psychoanalysis, 395–401.
Freud, S. [1925] 1991. “A Note Upon the ‘Mystic Writing-Pad.” In The
Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud,
Volume XIX (1923–1925): The Ego and the Id and Other Works, SE19,
225–232.
Freud, S. [1925] 2005. “Some Psychical Consequences of the Anatomical
Distinction between the Sexes” in The Essentials of Psychoanalysis, 402–411.
Vintage: London.
Freud, S. [1930] 1991. “The Future of an Illusion and Other Works” in
Civilisation and its Discontents, SE21.
Freud, S. [1955] 2005. The Essentials of Psychoanalysis. Translated by J. Strachey.
London: Vintage.
Freud, S. and Breuer, J. [1893a] 1991. “On the Psychical Mechanism
of hysterical Phenomena: Preliminary Communication” in Studies in
Hysteria Penguin Freud Library Vol. 3. London: Penguin.
Limentani, A. 1984. “To the Limits of Male Heterosexuality: The Vagina
Man” in (1989) Between Freud and Klein: the Psychoanalytic Quest for
Knowledge and Truth. London. Free Association Books.
Mitchell, J. 2000. Mad Men and Medusas: Reclaiming the Effects of Sibling
Relations on the Human Condition. London: Penguin.
Mitchell, J. 2003. Siblings. Cambridge. Polity.
Tasca, C., Rapetti, M., Carta, M.G., and Fadda, B. 2012. ‘Women and Hysteria
in the History of Mental Health,” Clinical Practice & Epidemiology Mental
Health. 8: 110–119. Published online, October 19, 2012.
Chapter 2
Daru Huppert
cannot be assimilated into the Oedipal theory, or, on the contrary, sib-
lings have been completely incorporated into this theory, with the result
that insight into the specific effects of siblings as siblings is lost.
Mitchell was the first to realize that to overcome this impasse we do
not require primarily more studies on siblings, but rather a general theory
of sibling relationships, or what she called lateral relations, in contra-
distinction to the vertical relations between parents and children. She
argues that we lose sight of siblings because we do not know how to
determine their role—and that what is thereby lost is essential, because
the effects of siblings upon the formation and functioning of our minds
differs significantly from the effects due to vertical relationships. What
is required then is a theory that, in regard to siblings, accomplishes what
the Oedipal theory does in regard to parents: it makes their effect on us
thinkable and thereby explorable. Such a theory of lateral relations will
alter the way we conceive of ourselves, of others, and our reciprocal rela-
tionships: as Mitchell (2003, xvi) notes, “bringing in Siblings changes
the picture we are looking at.”
Sibling Theory
Mitchell’s more recent work is an attempt to develop a general theory
of siblings and their influence on the formation of our mind. While it is
still being articulated, some of its essential contours have taken shape.
Mitchell (2000b, p. xi) explains that “when a sibling is in the offing, the
danger for the existing child is that he or she, previously—‘His Majesty
the Baby’—will be annihilated, for this is someone who stands in the
same position to parents (and their substitutes) as himself.” What is dev-
astating is that another being, too similar to oneself, threatens to usurp
the throne of infancy. The subject is not only displaced, deposed, and
dispossessed, he is, Mitchell insists, psychically annihilated. The essential
response to this annihilation is to try to kill the sibling, who has obliter-
ated the subject (Mitchell 2003, xv). The younger sibling in turn will seek
to defend himself, by wishing to annihilate the elder one. Destruction—
unilateral or mutual—is averted by different, simultaneously pursued and
conflicting solutions.
First there is the possibility of investing the sibling narcissistically,
as more of oneself or an extension of oneself. This solution, however,
founders because the sibling is different and this is felt to be devastat-
ing; it reawakens the obliteration initially experienced. There is also the
attempt to invest the sibling libidinously and with aim-inhibited tender-
ness, but these solutions are always threatened by the hate arising from
the feeling of being annihilated by the sibling. As a result, in infancy
SIBLINGS, SECRETS, AND PROMISES 45
and often in adulthood, the feelings of love for a sibling are labile, easily
prone to revert into hate and destruction. Yet, in Mitchell’s view, siblings
do not only have problematic effects. If the obliteration of self, elicited by
the sibling, is mourned and the destructive urges against the sibling are
sufficiently bound by libidinal and tender impulses, then murderousness
gives way to rivalry, competiveness, and eventually to a sense of solidar-
ity not only with siblings, but with other lateral figures. Siblings pro-
vide the possibility of grasping ourselves as part of what Mitchell (2003,
149) calls a series—as someone who is like others, but with differences.
In this way, we may come to realize individuality based on what we share
with others. In the language of classical psychoanalysis we could say the
Mitchell describes a development:
1. that begins with the narcissistic injury caused by the advent of a sibling;
2. develops into a crucial negotiation of the narcissism of small differences
that mark sibling relations;
3. before then moving toward object love along the lateral axis.
libido broke with any necessary link to reproduction; the latter became
merely one of its possible aims (Freud 1905). Siblings, Mitchell argues,
remind us of the nonreproductive and disturbing features of sexuality.
That is because, in contrast with some features of the Oedipus complex,
a wish for a baby does not form part of our sexual desire for a sibling. As
Mitchell (2003, 22) categorically states: “sibling sexuality is sex without
reproduction.” There are four core components of Mitchell’s claim that
the role siblings play in the formation of our sexuality is distinct from,
though related to the role played by our parents:
(a) The desire for a sibling is not organized by sexual difference, that
is, by the lack of the phallus (in the girl) or lack of an ability to give
birth (in the boy).
(b) Sexual taboos are, in general, less restrictive regarding siblings than
parents. As a consequence polymorphous perverse manifestations of
the sexual drive are more pronounced in relation to siblings than in
Oedipal sexual strivings.
(c) The libidinal investment of the sibling is initially a preponderantly a
narcissistic object choice. It is evident, though not trivial, that sib-
lings are more similar to each other than to their parents. Mitchell
gives this observation greater poignancy by claiming that, when as
children we were awaiting a sibling, we were expecting more of our-
selves. Siblings therefore easily take the position of the ideal-ego for
each other; the older one for being more capable, the younger one
occupying the role of what Freud called His Majesty the Baby. We
might say that we love our sibling according to our own image, or,
to be more precise, to our ideal image. Yet this narcissistic invest-
ment arises is impelled and imperiled by anxiety, as it seeks to fend
off the earlier experience of annihilation.
(d) Hatred and destruction, arising from the threat of annihilation,
are not differentiated from the sexual longing for a sibling, at least
initially. Passionate embraces between siblings quickly give way to
strangling; indeed, it can be difficult to distinguish one from the
other. Mitchell suggests that parental prohibitions address the vio-
lent aspect of children’s play more overtly and intensely than the
sexual aspect—the fundamental task of parents is to prevent siblings
from killing each other. What we must bear in mind is that in the
lateral axis it can be difficult to distinguish between sexual investment
and destructive proclivities.
This outline of Mitchell’s claims suggests that the form and meaning
that sexuality will take between siblings will be significantly different and
SIBLINGS, SECRETS, AND PROMISES 47
Perverse Activities
If we follow the first of the Three Essays and take heterosexual genital
intercourse as our point of departure, we find that the sexual drive shows
manifestations that deviate both in terms of the object and in terms of
activity. Heterosexual and homosexual object-choices are both possible:
a great part, often the greater part, of the sexual excitement involved in
play is shared with objects of the same sex. However, animals and other
children can also become targets of sexual strivings, and play a salient
role in the sexual fantasy and activity of children. Children are fascinated
by the open display of copulation or excretion found in animals and it
is quite common that children enact sexual desires with each other by
assuming the role of dogs, etc. With regard to children as sexual objects,
it is evident that they are so for other children. Psychoanalysis has taken
this for granted, perhaps too much so, and has instead emphasized the
less intuitively apparent Oedipal desire.
Let us proceed to the deviation of the sexual aims, or what we would
ordinarily call sexual activities; here Freud distinguishes between ana-
tomical transgressions and fixations of preliminary aims; what these cat-
egories have in common is that they do not aim at genital intercourse.
Anatomical transgressions include the mouth or the anus as sexual organ
as well as fetishism. Fellatio or cunnilingus may not be frequent in young
children, but the mouth plays a primary role in their excited play, while
the mutual inspection and stimulation of the anus is common. The use
of toys or objects in these games can have a determining influence on the
choice of a fetish (Winnicott 1971). With regard to the fixation on pre-
liminary aims, Freud describes the pairs of voyeurism/exhibitionism and of
sadism/masochism. In the Bible it required the intervention of the devil
48 DARU HUPPERT
for Adam and Eve to realize that they were naked and to develop shame;
it befalls parents or other adults to curb the exhibitionism and voyeurism
of children. Anyone who has been able to observe a kindergarten knows
that for many children furtive journeys to the toilets, to witness each
other’s genitals and excremental activities, represent the culmination of
the day’s pleasure. The sexual excitement elicited by rough play and by
fights, whether due to suffering or inflicting pain, are unavoidable expe-
riences of growing up, as are the intense and often disturbing pleasures
derived from debasing others or becoming the object of another child’s
degradation.
We have seen that the sexual activity of children shows all aspects that
Freud chose to emphasize in his study of the perversions—indeed, he
chose to limit his study of perversions to those manifestations that occur
universally amongst children. So far, I have discussed this sexual activity
without addressing the prohibitions that it may meet. This will now be
rectified.
Prohibition
Given conventional wisdom, it seems astonishing that adults generally
tolerate, if not explicitly, the often crass sexual activity among children.
Reasons for this are manifold. Perhaps most importantly, parents and
institutions have no means to hinder this play, unless they wish to put the
child under continual surveillance. Moreover parents, due to the repres-
sion of their own infantile sexuality, will tend to misapprehend the sexual
aspects of children’s excited interactions. They will see play, where their
children are striving for sexual pleasure. Parents will also feel a mixture
of resignation and a dim intuition that such play has a formative role in
the development of their child; it may also be that adults wish to grant
children experiences they enjoyed themselves while growing up. Yet rea-
sons for the uneasy and mostly unacknowledged toleration of this activ-
ity should not be sought in the adults only. Children, of course, will hide
their play.
The effects of this sexual play between children are different than
those arising from contact that may stimulate sexual feelings in a child
in regard to a parent. When Freud in a crucial observation, describes the
mother as the first seductress, he is not thinking of sexual abuse, which
I will not address in this chapter, but of the mother as providing the
necessary stimulation for the efflorescence of the child’s sexual drive.
Her behavior, at least in the formative influence that concerns Freud,
is aim-inhibited: it is delimited by the sexual barriers of disgust, shame,
pain, and morality. Amongst pre-latency children these barriers are in
SIBLINGS, SECRETS, AND PROMISES 49
Introducing Siblings
This separation also befalls siblings. Aristophanes’s parable in Plato’s
Symposium of the round beings that are cut in half by the gods, and
since then seek each other, lends itself to being read as depicting the
moment in which siblings become the objects of an intense prohibi-
tion. Indeed, adults frequently remember a particular moment in which
their parents anxiously decided to prohibit them from sharing the same
room or bathing with their sibling, etc. The reason for this prohibition
is evident: while the extent of overt sexual play and shared excitement
with siblings varies considerably, its possibility is rarely entirely absent.
All the sexual activities found between children can occur between sib-
lings and frequently do. There is, however, a significant difference: the
taboos with regard to sexual acts between siblings are severe, for they
concern incest. It may be true that in our culture these taboos are pre-
ceded by a period of relative tolerance of sibling sexuality, but eventu-
ally the prohibition is imposed, either through parents, other adults,
or institutions and the prohibition is highly invested. For this reason,
breaking it elicits not only great excitement, but also—potentially—
powerful feelings of shame, guilt, or disgust, at least nachträglich (i.e.,
after the child has established the incest taboo more firmly and, due to
some later experience, becomes fully aware of the sexual nature of his
earlier play). My clinical experience shows that siblings will often there-
fore include a third child, who is not a brother or sister, in their acts,
so as to suspend, obscure, and thereby more easily trespass the incest
barrier. In short, among siblings the possibilities of sexual transgression
are many—proximit y breeds temptation—but the prohibition can have
significant and severe consequences.
50 DARU HUPPERT
in that they depict certain sexual acts, while both alluding to and cover-
ing over other such acts and fantasies with the sibling that have under-
gone repression. This last claim I wish briefly to illustrate by looking at a
particular kind of secret shared between siblings.
The Promise
One important consequence of early sexual interactions between siblings
and of the secrets that arise from these is that they often issue in promises
or oaths between the siblings; promises to passionately love each other
more than anyone else; promises to avenge any slight or abuse suffered
by the other, etc. These promises need not have been verbally articulated
to acquire psychical force. Whether kept or broken such promises play
an important and underestimated role in sibling relationships and in the
clinical material concerning them. Often severe sacrifices are taken on to
keep such promises and sometimes a person will seek to punish himself for
having broken oaths to a sibling that he has no memory of having made.
Such promises may, of course, be conscious, as with the wish to protect
the sibling from adversity at any cost. But the reason for this promise
taking such a drastic form and gaining such force are unconscious. The
SIBLINGS, SECRETS, AND PROMISES 53
Conclusion
The themes of the secret and of the promise have helped to bring certain
aspects of our sexuality into focus, which are raised with a particular
intensity by sibling relationships. In sibling relations there will be more
sexual acts and therefore secrets—preconscious guardians of repressed
memories—than along the Oedipal line; the promises, I have looked
at, arise directly from these secrets. More generally, the material we
have discussed gives ample support to the features that Mitchell has
emphasized in sibling sexuality. Let us recall that she considers sibling
sexuality to be nonreproductive, that it is not organized around sexual
differences, that the taboos on it are less restrictive than on Oedipal
relationships, that the initial investment of the object are primarily nar-
cissistic and often difficult to distinguish from powerful destructive
urges. In Antigone we find the non-reproductive nature of her passion
(she rejects marriage to bury her brother), the absence of sexual differ-
ence (she does not love her brother passionately because he has what she
54 DARU HUPPERT
Notes
1. See Colonna and Newmann (1983), Volkan and Ast (1997), Colonna
and Newmann (1983).
2. I shall here leave out a discussion of other defence mechanisms (denial,
projection etc.) that may come into operation when repression fails.
References
Colonna, A. and Newman L. 1983. The psychoanalytic Literature on
Siblings. Psychoanalytic Study of the Child 83, 285–309.
Deutsch, H. 1932. “Obsessional Ceremonial and Obsessional Acts.” In
Psycho-Analysis of the Neuroses, translated by W.D. Robson-Scott, 175–197.
London: Hogarth Press.
SIBLINGS, SECRETS, AND PROMISES 55
Judith Butler
This chapter and the next presents a dialogue between Judith Butler
and Juliet Mitchell. In May 2009 Butler addressed a symposium held
at the Centre for Gender Studies to honour Mitchell’s retirement from
Cambridge University with a paper titled “Ideologies of the Superego.”
Parts of this address were later published in an article for the journal
differences (Butler 2013); this chapter presents Butler’s full address.
In the next chapter, Mitchell offers a reply to Butler’s account of psycho-
analysis and the oppression of women. We hope that, in presenting these
texts here, they preserve some of the excitement of the symposium as fun-
damental concepts of psychoanalytic and feminist theory were discussed
and reconceived.
I can try to meet some of these challenges in ways that, I hope, will prove
productive for further thinking on matters of kinship, ideology, and the
changing tasks of psychoanalysis.
Let’s begin with one of the most basic propositions and consider what
it implies for how we think about sexual difference, the unconscious, and
the problem of generational transmission. This proves to be a fundamen-
tal notion for her since, as she wrote in her 1999 preface, “The superego,
with its transgenerational transmission of rules and laws; the id, where
drive representatives meet what has been repressed; the ego, which com-
prises countless other egos—all are concepts which offer a way forward
into thinking about ideology as ‘how we live ourselves’ as sexually dif-
ferentiated beings.” (xxxi). I would like to focus first on the transgen-
erational transmission of rules. Mitchell insists that sexual difference has
largely unconscious dimensions, that these unconscious dimensions are
transmitted through time and across generations, and that there is a kind
of stasis or “drive to stay put” that characterizes sexual difference under-
stood in this way. If we focus further on what sexual difference is, we
find that the following formulations are central: sexual difference has to
be included among those phenomenon that “persists” and that remains
“incommensurate with the real social situation.” As a result, Mitchell
tells us, “deliberate socialization is inadequate to explain the structure
of sexual difference and the inequalities that always arise from it, despite
the fact that there is enormous diversity of social practice.” At a certain
point she tries to find other metaphors for explaining this “persistence,”
suggesting that it is perhaps more like a recalcitrance; for instance, she
asks, “Why, despite massive social, economic, and legal changes, is there
still a kind of underwater tow (my emphasis) that makes progress regress
on matters of ‘gender’ equity.” I should note here that “gender” is in
quotation marks, suggesting that it is a term that Mitchell is provisionally
willing to use, but not fully to condone. But I will return to this later as
we try and think about all of this in relation to kinship and ideology.
Although sexual difference is not exactly defined (and may well be
something that maintains a tense relationship with definition, promul-
gating metaphors of various kinds), something about its operation is
being characterized through a variety of means. It is a kind of persis-
tence; it is “a kind of underwater tow” or, again, a “current” as she writes,
“feminism seems to be rowing against a current that is ultimately the
stronger force.” She concludes here—still the new introduction—with
the following remark: “conservatism actually seems inherent in the very
construction of sexual difference—as though the difference itself has in
its construction insisted on stasis.” (xviii) This conservatism is inherent
in what Mitchell calls “the psycho-ideological living of sexual relations”
ID EOLOGIES OF T HE SUPER- EGO 59
and it is distinguished by the fact that “it is women . . . who become the
ascribed repositories of that human conservatism.” (xix)
Mitchell tells us that this conservatism is largely unconscious, although
she does not try and offer a precise topography of the unconscious. In
other words, we would not be able to locate this conservatism in a par-
ticular place. Rather, we are asked to understand this conservatism has
transmitted across generations. There is a “kind of thought” about mas-
culinity and femininity, understood as equivalent to the thought of sexual
difference, that takes place in the course of a transmission, a relay, a
transposition, and this would be understood as the particular temporal
modality of this thought which, although partially conscious, “is primar-
ily an unconscious process.” (xix) This process is a transmitted one, and
I am tempted to say that transmission is the mode of its reality, the epis-
temological modality of the thought of sexual difference itself. It does
not belong to a single psyche; when it does belong to a psyche, it is only
by virtue of its having been transmitted, and in the course of its further
transmission. So any given psyche would be a kind of way station or relay
point for the transmissibility of this thought. This point seems to me
to be important for Mitchell since she wants to establish what she calls
“a shared mental terrain,” one which ultimately serves as the condition
for understanding the nexus of the psyche and ideology.
It is interesting to note the two examples that Mitchell offers to sup-
port her claim about the transmission of unconscious ideas, especially the
transmission of unconscious ideas regarding sexual difference. But first,
I want to draw attention to the commitment that her position makes to
a semantic understanding of masculine and feminine. She not only refers
to ideas about sexual difference, which would undoubtedly include inter-
pretations and semantic delimitations, but she is willing, throughout, to
identify sexual difference with masculine and feminine. I am wondering
whether it is not possible, as some psychoanalytic accounts of sexual dif-
ference have insisted, to say that sexual difference is persistent, that it
works as “an undertow,” characterized by a constitutive conservatism,
without saying that sexual difference is invariably identified with mascu-
line and feminine. Can there be sexual difference, say, within homosexu-
ality that cannot quite be described as masculine and feminine, and what
implications would that have for separating sexual difference, under-
stood as a deep-seated and largely unconscious thought, and specific
social ways of determining that thought? In other words, at what point is
sexual difference separable from its social determinations? It would seem
that we need to assume such a separation when we claim that changes
in the social organization of men and women are impeded by a conser-
vatism that seems to be inherent to sexual difference itself. If we define
60 JUDITH BUTLER
that “the sense of guilt was present before the misdeed” and he asks after
the “origin of this obscure sense of guilt” that precedes the deed. He
concludes that this guilt derives from the Oedipus complex, not to deeds
performed, but to “intentions” or wishes to commit incest and parricide.
But let us note that even here the guilt pertains to intentions or wishes,
but not to deeds done.
The criminal act that follows from a sense of guilt seeks to install a
commensurability of guilt and crime where there is none. In other words,
there is no reason to infer from crimeless guilt that there was once a
crime, but only that there were desires which, if acted upon, would result
in crimes; it may well emerge from an anxiety over unacted desire—a
desire to have done with the anxiety—and may well be a way that the
psyche punishes itself in advance for an act it has not yet committed—
and never will. Perhaps guilt is finally more bearable than anxiety or,
indeed, fear of punishment, especially if one can orchestrate being pun-
ished by one’s hand, as it were.
In Kleinian terms, that guilt that corresponds to no act may well be
a way of managing an impulse that could possibly destroy an object of
love and dependency, and so operates as a prophylactic against destruc-
tive aims. In any case, we can see that the existence of an unconscious
sense of guilt (or partially conscious one) which seems to correspond to
no misdeed may well refer to a possible future just as well as to an inher-
ited past. But one could say that the fear of punishment follows from the
awareness of a crime and, so, the prior the awareness of a set of rules or
laws. But it could be the other way around. In that same essay, Freud
notes that “criminals from sense of guilt” was known to Nietzsche as
well. In Nietzsche, the social necessity to curb destructive impulses gives
rise to law, even forms part of the very genealogy of law. And for Freud
as well, can we really say that law precedes the possibility of crime? Or
is it rather that the understanding that certain acts will destroy those
relations upon which we depend most fundamentally, we devise law to
stop us from acting on those destructive impulses and imperilling the
social and intimate conditions of our own survival? So one question that
emerges here is whether rules and laws are transmitted, or whether they
are, in fact, remade time and again precisely in order to limit and manage
the destructive consequences of unimpeded impulse or desire?
Mitchell likens this example of guilt that precedes crime to a second
one in order to make the case for an unconsciously acquired history that
proves recalcitrant in the face of demands for social change. In the second
example, she writes, “a child raised by two parents of the same sex . . . may
make a “ ‘normative’ adjustment to heterosexuality . . . ” In fact, the argu-
ment suggests that the child emerges into heterosexuality (by which,
62 JUDITH BUTLER
I am not sure that the formation of sexual desire emerges on the basis
of a clearly readable mimesis. I want to be like the one parent and to
desire the other, so I model myself on the one I want to be like. Maybe,
but it could easily be the case that the only way a girl can inhabit a certain
feminine position is with another girl, or the only way a boy can inhabit
a certain masculine position is with another boy. Or it may be that the
adolescent seeks to respond to a maternal demand to be the husband
she never had, and the adolescent can in this instance be a boy (and so
emerge as heterosexual) or a girl (and so emerge as homosexual). It can
be that only within certain sociological framings that fantasy can come
alive, and very often there is no commensurability between the sociologi-
cal framing (queer, straight, gay, bi) and the form of desire, so that we
find straight couples with strong queer desires, and queer couples enact-
ing forms of transformed or transposed heterosexuality.
Our vocabularies tend to falter here, since we are no longer sure
whether we are to call this straight or gay, and our not being able to
call it by the right term may be part of its erotic significance and its
social importance. In any case, mimesis is hardly the route to desire,
and even if it were, every effort at mimetic doubling risks veering off
from its model, functioning through displacement or metonymy. So
this allows a lesbian to identify with the father or to find the father
in another woman, or not to find him at all, but to construct another
fantasy, one that may well be a palimpsest that does not settle into one
object or another, even though it takes place at the site of some girl. She
may well have more in common with some guy who is doing the same
sort of thing in relation to his father or some other masculine figure,
but at the site of a girl as well. Indeed, the child of lesbian parents may
well end up desiring a girl as a form of identifying with his parents
objects, or becoming part of the crowd. This may well be a greater form
of loyalty than becoming gay, which would introduce the masculine
object of desire in another way, or set up a rival for the lesbian prince
who knows he has the absolute and irreplaceable love of both of his
mothers. I heard a great story in which a young adolescent girl says to
her two dads, will you be disappointed in me if I am not gay, and they
respond, listen, if you are gay, you will be like us; if you like men, you
will be like us, so in either case, you can’t escape us! This may seem
to be a strange parental narcissism, perhaps, but one that seeks to give
permission to any possible trajectory of desire, which, of course, may
function as an interdiction all the same, especially if one considers the
potential burden of limitless options.
We could certainly say in all of these scenarios that sexual difference
is at play, and I do not have a problem with that claim. But if something
ID EOLOGIES OF T HE SUPER- EGO 65
about sexual difference persists, how do we describe it? I am not sure that
what persists are established semantic ways of organizing sexual differ-
ence, already formed legacies of the past that are relayed into the present
without translation, transposition, without some loss, without some new
twist or turn. For this reason, I am even less sure that heterosexuality is
a sure way of confirming sexual difference or providing its paradigmatic
instance. But even if both of those speculative propositions proved true
(and I am not sure how they could finally prove true), an ever more fun-
damental problem emerges in my mind. And that has to do with how we
understand “transmission” and “acquisition”—and this seems related to
the key problem of “communicating unconscious ideas” intersubjectively
and trans-generationally or, indeed, any broader thesis about shared
mental terrain or, indeed, collective mind.
First of all, we have to ask whether what is communicated actually
arrives in the form in which it is sent. In other words, is unconscious
communication transparent and effective or does it function a bit more
like Kafka’s “imperial message,” where the message is sent, but circuits
through so many detours that its arrival is never quite certain, and no
arbiter is really on site to tell us whether or not any message actually
arrived. And if the content or the message does arrive, does it arrive in a
form that recognizable, or has it undergone alterations and displacements
on the course of its journey? What are the operative presumptions behind
the idea of communication and acquisition? Does one invariably acquire
something other than what was sent? Does one receive something more
or less than what was proffered? Through what chains of displacement
does unconscious communication occur, if it really can be said to occur
at all? And is there not, as Jean Laplanche suggests, always a question of
translation? If so, through what language, or set of languages, do such
translations occur?
Indeed, for Laplanche the idea of unconscious communication is not
finally acceptable, although certainly messages are sent, interpellations
are made, and at an unconscious level. There is no guarantee and, indeed,
no possibility that the conditions of their reception accord with the con-
ditions of address. In fact, messages arrive in enigmatic form, inscru-
table. So, according to Laplanche, we cannot look to the unconscious
communication of ideas without first interrogating the conditions of
any such communication, and without asking whether content remains
intact as it is relayed from one unconscious to another. Importantly,
then, if the transmissibility of the laws of culture depend on the pos-
sibility of the effective unconscious communication of such laws, then
calling into question the transparency and effectivity of that mode of
communication has important consequences of thinking about the laws
66 JUDITH BUTLER
of culture, the laws that are said to be essential to human society, the
laws that are generally thought to be the laws of sexual difference, that
explain the persistence of patriarchy and the relative intransigence of the
symbolic order.
We can accept, for instance, that there is an unconscious operation
at work that seems to relay another time into this time, that we are not
completely of the present, and that another scene acts upon us as we try
to find our way within present time. But even if we accept this time-lag
as constitutive of the psyche, it does not follow that we have to accept a
universal set of rules or laws as belonging to that other time, or transmit-
ted from that other time. Indeed, that other time may well be an histori-
cal time, the times that belong to prior generations, but that is not the
same as saying it is the time of cultural law, of the paternal law, of the
symbolic, or of the laws that are essential to culture. This structuralist
presumption supplements the theory of the unconscious, but it is in no
way presupposed by its operation. As Laplanche departs from Lacan, he
calls into question the means and mechanisms by which the unconscious
desires of the adult world impinge upon the infant; this impingement
does not communicate an intact set of laws in clear and effective ways.
On the contrary, these enigmatic signifiers become lodged in the psychic
life of the infant and initiate the drives as both overwhelming and excit-
ing (these are, in effect, the terms through which Laplanche reformulates
the scene of general seduction.
Something of this is given a specifically historical analysis in
Psychoanalysis and Feminism when Mitchell notes in the final chapter,
“The Cultural Revolution,” that “the complexity of capitalist society
makes archaic the kinship structures and incest taboos for the majority
of people and yet it preserves them through thick and thin.” So, there
seems to be a mandate to preserve an archaism in the face of social real-
ity. How are we, then, to understand this archaism? In 1974, Mitchell
wrote, and underscored, the following important claim: “the capital-
ist economy implies that for the masses demands of exogamy and the
social taboo on incest are irrelevant; but nevertheless it must preserve
both these and the patriarchal structure that they imply.” (409) The
argument reminds me of the recent debates in France in which some
opponents of gay marriage actively worry that gay marriage will dis-
solve the institutions of marriage and family even when it turns out that
the majority of social arrangements cannot be described as family orga-
nized by heterosexual marriage. What is called “demarriage” has already
become the norm. And so we might conclude that precisely because, at
the social level, demarriage has become the norm, heterosexual marriage
must be defended at the ideological level.
ID EOLOGIES OF T HE SUPER- EGO 67
have to assume that the desire for definition is motored by drive as well.
Freud moves invariably into metaphor precisely here: “a stimuli reach-
ing the mind” a “border” or “frontier” and then finally, a mythology.
Something exceeds our conceptual grasp, and so compels us to encoun-
ter the limits of conceptualization. Mythology in this instance is precisely
the effort to give an account for that which no definition or explanation
can suffice.
How we conceptualize the drives has everything to do with how we
imagine what it is that drives convey. And what and how drives convey
has everything to do with how rules may or may not be transmitted
trans-generationally. I am not sure that drives can be effectively sepa-
rated the ideation, and that even the effort to define the drive is but
a further instance of its operation. My wager is that drives do not loy-
ally replicate the “messages” that initiate them; in fact, the messages, or
signifiers, are inscrutable and overwhelming, and they prompt a set of
displacements, so that drives, and sexuality more generally, take form
through metonymic processes that are not easily foreseen or predicted.
The trajectory of displacement is the trajectory of the drive itself. This
is why, for instance, Laplanche insists that the drive is not constrained
by biological teleologies, including reproduction. In a sense, there is
no drive that preexists that metonymic sequence or, rather, there is no
drive that is not transformed by the sequence it sets in motion. In other
words, what is passed down or, indeed, communicated, is not the same
law in the same form, and not the same law in a different form, and not
even the traumatic force of law. Rather, what is passed down is a forceful
impression, enigmatic and exciting, from an adult world whose libidinal
communications are overwhelming and unreadable for the infant. That
impression seems to carry a message, but only in encoded forms that
remain indecipherable for the infant and child and remain so to some
extent throughout adult life.
So, this is not the ordering of desire through law, but the prompting
of displacements through messages both powerful and enigmatic. But
before I seal the impression that I am trying to counter Laplanche to
Mitchell, let me confess to having some problem with the Laplanchian
idea of a “message.” This notion of communication implies, from the
outset, that some semantic content is separable from the form of its
delivery. I don’t think that can be the case, since forms of delivery are
already saturated by semantics, and that we cannot easily separate these
functions of speech and discourse from their semantic action and con-
sequence. The message, in other words, is not a propositional content
embedded in a mode of address; we would probably object if students
read poems that way, trying to dig out a propositional meaning from
ID EOLOGIES OF T HE SUPER- EGO 69
within gay families or, indeed, in extended kinship networks where there
is a distribution of parental function and position. But to ask these ques-
tions is precisely to ask how psychoanalysis must be reformulated in light
of changing kinship arrangements. It is also to ask how changing kinship
arrangements come up against a countercurrent or undertow that is not
so easily transformed through purely social means.
If we think about the variable conditions of kinship and what new
challenges they pose for psychoanalysis, we may well think about the
tasks for psychoanalysis and for feminism differently. To what extent
do we operate within certain idealized, if not normative, conceptions
of kinship when we describe the initial moments of gender assignment?
I mentioned before this example of gender assignment and familial place
in Psychoanalysis and Feminism: “Before it is born, the child is assigned a
name . . . ” Well, that is not always true, especially if the child is born and
directly given up for adoption. It can remain nameless in the interim,
or be given only a provisional name with the understanding that the
name will change. And who is the “one” who makes this assignment?
Sometimes a child is left abandoned by virtue of a natural disaster or con-
ditions of poverty. And it may be that the child is in social services, in a
series of foster homes, or ends up finally in a family situation where more
than one person is occupying the maternal function. Let us remember
Winnicott’s quite important suggestion that the maternal may not be an
object or a person, but, rather, a field, and that what one might find in
that field are “bits and pieces” of maternal function. So is there an already
ascribed place here? Or must we understand ascription and assignment as
acts that must be performed time and again, part of an iterable structure
with its own risks of failure, derailment, and reformulation?
So if we agree with Mitchell that a return to questions of kinship and
ideology are necessary, even a new examination of the “ideologies of
the super-ego,” and if we are to seek recourse to the theory of ideology
through an Althusserian interpellation in particular, then it seems to me
we have to be prepared for the fact that interpellation does not just hap-
pen once, but time and again, and that the chain of interpellative assign-
ments forms something of the social history within which a particular
psychic life is formed and lived. In this way, the infant is not born into
a structure, but into a temporally reiterated chain of interpellations or
assignments that have to be negotiated in time, that precede and exceed
the life of the child, which may well, in the case of adoption, entail a
series of geographical, if not geopolitical, and linguistic displacements.
No single set of laws replicates itself in the unconscious of that infant, but
only a series of transpositions and impingements, never fully conscious,
demanding a process of translation that can never fully return to, or
74 JUDITH BUTLER
grasp, the powerful and enigmatic impression that prompts that largely
unpredictable trajectory of the drives.
Let us note here that the act of gender assignment or, indeed, the
giving of a name, is one that already carries some enigmatic desire from
the adult world. An assignment encodes some inscrutable desire from the
adult world. It is carried in the proper name, but also in the assignment
of gender. In this sense, some trace of sexuality is already at work in the
interpellation of gender, in the sociological practice of gender assign-
ment (a point on which I disagree with Laplanche). One might even say
that through gender assignment, “unconscious thoughts are communi-
cated,” but there seems to be no nonspeculative way to ground the claim
that the laws of human society are precisely what are communicated in
and through such unconscious thoughts.
According to Laplanche, communication is invariably errant; what is
sent is not the same as what arrives. If this is true, a truth that would
also establish something of the relevance of Kafka for thinking about the
transmission of sexual difference, then what would that continual misin-
terpretation and displacement do to the “communication” of sexual dif-
ference? Perhaps then we could begin to understand why it is that some
people change their assignment, or wish to, and how keeping or refusing
the name is bound up with a larger sense of the network of kinship to
which one belongs. How else would we understand the claims made, for
instance, by the intersex movement that an infant should be assigned a
gender, but that the assignment should be subject to re-consideration by
that person as she grows older, or the demand for legal re-assignment
that has formed the political site of mobilization for so many transgen-
dered people. Or even within genderqueer or butch-femme contexts,
when pleas such as “call me a boy” or “let me be your girl” become the
site of intense erotic exchange on the part of any number of genders.
How else would we understand the violent attacks on transgendered
people on the street or the continuing pathologization of homosexual
“femininity” in boys within the DSM and other diagnostic tools? And
how do we understand compulsory maternity or even anorexia as injunc-
tions that are transmitted as part of a legacy of gender norms? Are they
not ways of communicating the “rules” of sexual difference? Are there
really rules that are not norms? And what modes do we have to intro-
duce errancy and the unforeseen into such a transmission or communica-
tion? And how might we reconceive kinship once this errant and fecund
sort of transmission becomes the way that one generation emerges from
another, at once bearing the historical weight of what comes before and
moving toward something new—what we might understand as the very
dynamic of social struggle.
ID EOLOGIES OF T HE SUPER- EGO 75
Notes
1. “[Freud] uses instinct in the traditional sense, which designates a
behavioural schema that is adapted to a particular end or aim, with a
pregiven object . . . is hereditary and innate, so not acquired . . . ” (23)
whereas “drive”—“the more properly psychoanalytic concept” (24),
which involve “primal fantasies” understood as “precipitates from the
history of human civilization.” (23–4) Laplanche, Essays on Otherness,
tr. John Fletcher, London: Routledge, 1999.
2. “Since we cannot wait for another science to present us with the final
conclusions on the theory of instincts (Triebe), it is far more to the
purpose that we should try to see what light may be thrown upon this
basic problem of biology by a synthesis of the psychological phenom-
enon.” (SE 14: 19)
3. See Laplanche, “The Drive and its Source-Object” in Essays on
Otherness.
References
Freud, S. [1915] 2001. “Instincts and Their Vicissitudes.” SE 14, 109–140.
Freud, S. [1916] 2001. “Introductory Lectures.” SE 15–16, 1–463.
Freud, S. [1933] 2001. “New Introductory Lectures.” SE 22, 1–182.
Laplanche, J. 1999. Essays in Otherness, tr. John Fletcher, London: Routledge.
Mitchell, J. 1999a. “Introduction, 1999” to Psychoanalysis and Feminism.
New York: Basic Books.
Rubin, G. 1975. “The Traffic in Women” in Toward an Anthropology of Women,
edited by R. Reiter, pp. 157–210. New York: Mon Rev.
Chapter 4
Juliet Mitchell
“Sexual Difference”
Alerted by Rose’s perception and considering my own and Butler’s work
side-by-side, I have come to believe Butler and I are writing with differ-
ent agendas, different objects, different subject-matter in mind. There
is here a déjà vu with the work of Gayle Rubin, famous for her essay
“Traffic in Women” (see Rubin 1975; Rubin and Butler 1994).
In 1974 I gave a large public lecture at Ann Arbor. The lecture was a
synopsis of the argument of Psychoanalysis and Feminism, which was in
press with Pantheon and Allen Lane/Penguin, awaiting its publication
date later that year. I was asked to meet a student of the eminent anthro-
pologist, Marshall Sahlins; I did. This was Gayle Rubin. Though we
have long ago lost touch, I kept much of Rubin’s side of our subsequent
correspondence. In one of the letters we exchanged, she wrote that our
interests diverged—that hers were with the oppression of heterosexual
supremacy where mine were with male supremacy. This distinction in
our feminisms, she commented, had not been explicit between us.
I think that Butler shares Rubin’s concern when she addresses my
work. The different concerns of Rubin and Butler on the one hand, and
myself on the other, have to date remained inexplicit. Yet much falls into
place if I now read Butler’s critique of Psychoanalysis and Feminism as an
analysis and an attack on heterosexual supremacy, which contrasts to my
concern with the position of women and “sexual difference.” The psy-
choanalytic explanation of women and of homosexuality/heterosexuality
are often confused but they are different problematics.
At the beginning of the 1970s I was writing from my practical and
intellectual concern about what, at the time, we called the “oppres-
sion” of women. In the UK we saw “oppression” as an interim, umbrella
S E X UA L D I F F E R E N C E , P O L I T I C S , A N D T H E U N C O N S C I O U S 79
term which could be used to signal we were not claiming women were
“exploited” in the highly technical sense deployed by Marx. We needed
therefore a different analysis and a different revolution. Calling ourselves
“women liberationists,” we were trying to construct this analysis on the
political Left. Butler in her Symposium paper (2009; chapter 3 of this
volume) and in her later differences article (2013) was critiquing my argu-
ment about women as though her field of enquiry—the abuse of homo-
sexuality, and mine—the oppression of women—were the same topic.
To have done this is to produce an interesting perspective, but to miss
the point of my 1974 book. My insistence on the changing times is to
underline a temporal distinction, so as to contextualize my argument.
So: different topics in different times.
First things first: we need greater clarity on the term “sexual differ-
ence.” Butler (2013) writes: “[Mitchell] is willing throughout, to iden-
tify sexual difference with masculine and feminine.” At no point does
Psychoanalysis and Feminism do this. The term “sexual difference” refers
to Freud’s (1933) essay on “Femininity.” The line that demarcates where
a woman can’t be a man and vice versa. All the aspects the line can fall
over—such as psychology, culture and anatomy are never in a reflec-
tive or one-to-one relationship with each other. “Sexual difference” is
a distinction between women and men that as a distinction is universal
in human societies: it is also a distinction without any specific or given
content whatsoever. Instead, it finds its content in variable ways which
relate to the fact that any society must place some prohibitions on sexual
desire and murder.
Let me illustrate as best I can. All men possess a penis unless for one
reason or another, they are castrated. But the important distinction is
not between a penis and a vagina, but between the penis and the phal-
lus. Everyone can at times lay claims to being phallic—for instance, the
phallic “mother”; but possession of the phallus is ultimately not possible
for anyone: some variable formulation of a universal prohibition on desire
and murder stands in the way. Butler’s perspective treats universal as if
it means “fixed,” but this is not a necessary corollary. I distinguish the
universality of sexual difference from the variability of gender; concepts
which operate on different levels of analysis.
Butler replaces my “sexual difference” with the term “sexual dif-
ferences,” thereby firmly confusing it with gender. Now “sexual dif-
ferences” is an interesting concept, developed for example by Barbara
Johnson (1998), for considering gender. But the use of the plural is never
the same as the use of the singular as in Psychoanalysis and Feminism
and my subsequent writings (2006). In the sense I intend by the term,
it does not make sense to describe “sexual difference” as performative.
80 JULIET MITCHELL
Transgenerational Transmission
Judith Butler: Let’s begin with one of the most basic propositions
and consider what it implies for how we think about sexual difference,
the unconscious, and the problem of generational transmission. This
proves to be a fundamental notion for [Juliet] since, as she wrote in her
1999 preface, ‘The superego, with its transgenerational transmission of
rules and laws; the id, where drive representatives meet what has been
repressed; the ego, which comprises countless other egos—all are con-
cepts which offer a way forward into thinking about ideology as “how
we live ourselves” as sexually differentiated beings” (Mitchell 1999, xxxi).
I would like to focus first on the transgenerational transmission of rules.
Mitchell insists that sexual difference has largely unconscious dimen-
sions, that these unconscious dimensions are transmitted through time
and across generations, and that there is a kind of stasis or “drive to
stay put” that characterizes sexual difference understood in this way. If
we focus further on what sexual difference is, we find that the follow-
ing formulations are central: sexual difference has to be included among
those phenomenon that “persists” and that remains “incommensurate
82 JULIET MITCHELL
with the real social situation.” As a result, Mitchell tells us, “deliberate
socialization is inadequate to explain the structure of sexual difference
and the inequalities that always arise from it, despite the fact that there is
enormous diversity of social practice . . . ”
Although sexual difference is not exactly defined (and may well be
something that maintains a tense relationship with definition, promulgat-
ing metaphors of various kinds), something about its operation is being
characterized through a variety of means. It is a kind of persistence; it is
“a kind of underwater tow” or, again, a “current” as she writes, “femi-
nism seems to be rowing against a current that is ultimately the stronger
force.” She concludes here—still the new introduction—with the fol-
lowing remark: “conservatism actually seems inherent in the very con-
struction of sexual difference—as though the difference itself has in its
construction insisted on stasis” (Mitchell 1999, xviii). This conservatism
is inherent in what Mitchell calls “the psycho-ideological living of sexual
relations” and it is distinguished by the fact that “it is women . . . who
become the ascribed repositories of that human conservatism.”
lateral relations of siblings, peers etc. and retained “sexual difference” for
the vertical intergenerational ones. Gender, the lateral, would seem to be
more fluid and multivalent than sexual difference. I use “gender” then
for the polymorphous possibilities and differences to which I had offered
a fanfare at the end of “Women: the Longest Revolution”:
Because Butler is talking about gender, her theory may reflect this great
fluidity, and an absence of the potential conservatism/stasis that sexual
difference brings to the arena. We now have a plethora of descriptions
of the theatres of our minds; “femininity” and its many masquerades,
“masculinity,” could be performed for sure, but not “sexual difference”
which means no more than that one sex is not the other.
The first section of Psychoanalysis and Feminism, “The Making of a
Lady” part I, starts with a chapter that offers an account of the uncon-
scious; this is followed by one on Freud’s still (in 2014) rich and revo-
lutionary understanding of sexuality. Chapter 3 explains masculinity,
femininity, and bisexuality. The purpose of this arrangement was to
demonstrate that sexual difference must be situated in the basic psycho-
analytic concepts of an unconscious mind and a sexually driven body.
Throughout the book it is made clear that of the concepts and terms
used, only “bisexuality” belongs to psychoanalysis: “we cannot say what
a woman is, only how she comes into being from a child with a bisexual
disposition.” (Freud 1933) Ditto a man.
In 1974 I presented a reading of Freud that was utterly contrary to
the ego-psychology that dominated psychoanalysis in the USA. Jacques
Lacan had not as yet hit American shores; his “return to Freud” empha-
sizing the unpalatable notion of the castration complex and penis-envy
spoke to the depth of the problem of why women faced “the longest
revolution.” This is what Rose, at the Symposium of 2009, and today
S E X UA L D I F F E R E N C E , P O L I T I C S , A N D T H E U N C O N S C I O U S 85
Gayatri Spivak (in her Juliet Mitchell Lecture 2014) have perceived as the
issue that was raised by my book of 1974. Something that despite all the
forward moves—prevents women moving forward. For Freud this was
recognized in what he observed as a “repudiation of femininity” with its
passivity toward a man, by both sexes.
In 1966 when “Women: the Longest Revolution” was published in
New Left Review, an editorial board member, Quinton Hoare wrote
a scathing attack. My memory of first looking into this riposte was of
having my breath taken away: Hoare was arguing that women, by defi-
nition, have no subjecthood. In countering his claim that the entire his-
tory of women had taken place only within the family and that women
as such could not be thought about outside its terms, I stated that “not
unless women are literally exchange products can they be identical with
objects and property.” Today the discussion has moved on well past
these arguments—thank goodness! However, that I can still feel the
impossible experience of thinking and acting as a subject while being
analyzed as only an object is testimony, unfortunately, to something
that persists.
Women, of course, range across all the other social categories with
consequently very different effects. However, I still follow a classical line
of Freud’s that the position the bisexual girl takes up to become her
woman self is to be the object of another’s desire (initially, prototypi-
cally, her father’s); this differentiates her from the position of the bisexual
boy who to become his man-self positions himself as subject of desire.
“Before” this and in a way that for my theses implicates siblings, for-
ever after as well, both sexes have been both the subject of desiring the
mother and the object of her desire. This pre-Oedipal position I call
“gender.” The person in their gender has subjecthood—the toddler is
just insisting on it when it is threatened by separation from its mother if
it murders or commits incest with its usurping sibling.
The Law
Judith Butler: We can accept, for instance, that there is an unconscious
operation at work that seems to relay another time into this time, that
we are not completely of the present, and that another scene acts upon us
as we try to find our way within present time. But even if we accept this
time-lag as constitutive of the psyche, it does not follow that we have to
accept a universal set of rules or laws as belonging to that other time, or
transmitted from that other time. Indeed, that other time may well be an
historical time, the times that belong to prior generations, but that is not
the same as saying it is the time of cultural law, of the paternal law, of the
86 JULIET MITCHELL
a scene when the man-in-the-man confronts her. She also has never
grown up. Winnicott also did not subscribe to Freud’s drive theory—
disputing in particular the death drive. I was not a clinician at the time of
writing Psychoanalysis and Feminism so had no alternative source mate-
rial as had Ferenczi and Laplanche. I could of course have used other
psychoanalytic theoreticians for my feminist aims as Nancy Chodorow
(1976) did to great effect a little later. When reading Butler’s response to
my work, it is important to remember the position I take (Freud/Lacan)
is often absent from her critique. My concern is to use Freud and Lacan
to show how we have to tackle what seems intractable within the oppres-
sion of women—the longest revolution.
Judith Butler: What propels the displacements of desire is less an effort
to evade the murderous consequences of a prohibitive law than an effort
to fathom a set of adult desires that have impinged upon, and formed, an
internal structure of the psyche. The infant is unknowing and, indeed,
helpless, in relation to these overwhelming and confusing messages
relayed more or less unconsciously by the adult world. As a result, the
sexuality that emerges, understood as a series of displacements from
instinct, is a result of this helplessness in the face of the desirous adult
world. The infant becomes an investigative theorist on such an occa-
sion, trying to fathom the strange force and direction of his or her own
impulses. The problem for infantile sexuality is not how to evade castra-
tion by punishment, but how to fathom a desire that is, from the start,
already the desire of the other.
Theoretically, Laplanche’s departure from Lacan in this regard implies
a full critique of the paternal law, linked to the structuralist account of the
exchange of women and the universalist premises of “culture.” This view
of the paternal law is countered by a conception of a non-gendered “adult
world” that generates and imposes enigmatic signifiers on an infant who
responds with both cognitive helplessness and incitation of the drive. As
a result, primary unconscious and sexual messages are impressed upon
the child (though “impression” may well be too soft a term). Moreover,
those primary others whose desires are communicated through various
practices are themselves in the grip of such messages (have themselves
been incited unconsciously by such messages). The ones whose desires
become the foreign and inciting elements in my own desire are them-
selves propelled by what is foreign and inciting, and invariably so. In this
way, transgenerational transmission probably resembles Borges’ story,
“Circular Ruins” where one person discovers that he has his reality only
in another person’s dream, and that the same principle applies to that
dreamer, whose reality is secured only in another’s dream. This goes on
for generations, without end.
90 JULIET MITCHELL
Juliet Mitchell: Here Butler shifts what she has previously ascribed to
the “drive” to “desire” where I think it belongs. However, reading this
extract against my account of Freud does produce something quite diver-
gent. Not, I think an unbridgeable gap but a really different explanation
of what is going on. This centres on the concept of the drive.
The drive is an ineffable, mythological push forward (the life drive)
and urge backward to stasis (the death drive). The drive is a hypothesis
of Freud’s, conjured up to explain phenomena within psychoanalytic
observation and treatment: the psychic conflict. Laplanche suggests that
instead of the drives being something hypothesized which drive us; they
are established instead within us by the desires of the adults toward us.
This is to change the terms—desires drive us. As I said, many analysts
have more or less disposed of Freud’s theory of the drives. Laplanche,
however, is talking about something else—that we are driven by the
desires of others. That may be so—it could happen as well. But in itself it
does not to get rid of the notion of a conflict between the desire and the
prohibition. Certainly, the neonate will not survive if there is no desir-
ous adult to tend it; however to make the desires of others foundational
of a drive changes the concept of a drive. Such a drive does not postu-
late, as does Freud’s, that a drive forces the mind to work to get what
the body needs and desires. I honestly don’t know which hypothesis is
correct or whether we still can’t have both. In Butler’s Laplanche the
drive results from communication with its displacements, its translations
but it is no less metaphoric, only somewhat more contemporary, than
Freud’s “mythology.” And how Butler describes drives is how Freud/
Lacan explain desire. Here for Butler there is apparently intergenera-
tional transmission, so transmission is not the problem—only what is
transmitted.
Certainly we are all “ungendered” a good deal of the time—but
we are also gendered and sexually differentiated even, at times, in each
other’s dreams. As a working concept is “ungendered” that different
from “bisexuality”? Butler’s Laplanche does not need either any laws, or
sexual difference. But in not needing these, I cannot see how it offers us
anything with which we might begin to grasp the oppression of women.
Indeed there seem not to be women. Perhaps the “unbridgeable” gap
between Butler and myself and where I started this reply is that she is
primarily concerned with developing an understanding of the way out
of the abuse of homosexuality as read through sexuality and, while not
underestimating this, I remain convinced that something else is going
on for women. At least that was my focus in 1974 and still in 1999 and
2014. Is this why Butler and I differ?
S E X UA L D I F F E R E N C E , P O L I T I C S , A N D T H E U N C O N S C I O U S 91
book that I argue that “the analysis of the seeming intractability of sexual
difference, and the vision for change were inseparable.”
Elsewhere in her response to me Butler writes of “the changing tasks of
psychoanalysis” and says, “We can surely ask how Oedipalization occurs
within single parent families or within gay families, or indeed, in extended
kinship networks where there is a distribution of parental functions and
position. But to ask these questions is precisely to ask how psychoanalysis
must by reformulated in light of changing kinship components.” This is
to misunderstand Oedipalization—the child of a gay couple or single par-
ent is still not allowed to murder or commit incest. Psychoanalysis is about
unconscious processes, the conscious and preconscious material of the
clinic will change, different issues will have priority in Tokyo or Timbuktu
and different psychic mechanisms will gain prominence. Unconscious
processes will be understood differently with further work but this will
not be an adaptation to changing social practices.
Unconscious processes come from two directions: there are initiating
traumas that are the hallmark of the prematurely born human infant; and
there are expressions of desires that arise within the context of premature
helplessness with its utter dependence on others. Some of which must
be not allowed, these non-allowances are highly variable as are indeed
the practices of homosexuality. Sexual difference is an effect of invariant
ones. We part company on our dominant concerns not on our attitude
to the laws. We part too on our estimation of these laws and what indeed
they are.
to, or grasp, the powerful and enigmatic impression that prompts that
largely unpredictable trajectory of the drives.
Juliet Mitchell: Despite its subtle complexity I think Butler’s argument
makes the political task too easy and too sociological. If the recalcitrance,
the “under-tow” always pulling us back, is only the “drag of history” are
we just to wait for the end of history?
Now I have written myself into what feels like an understanding, I can
properly appreciate and thank Judith for her exciting contribution. Let me
summarize; this time speaking for what I hope is Judith as well as myself:
For Judith, the multiple sexualities and internal and external differ-
ences can so displace heterosexuality which has hitherto been domi-
nant, so that it just becomes one among many with no hegemonic status
either in fact or the fiction about facts. With heterosexuality displaced,
psychoanalysis (predicated in its Oedipal centrality) will have to adjust.
Laplanche shows the way: we are the recipients of messages we barely can
grasp but which set up our drives and desires and which have no absolute
status; the transmission is itself a series of displacements without fixed
content. These messages establish the drives within individuals so there
need be no fixed laws of sexual positions.
For me: in 1974, I addressed psychoanalysis to ask why women, as
women, were not perceived as subjects; why there was always a slipping
back so that when all the socioeconomic conditions had changed so
there was no need for women’s oppression, it still persisted. In 1999
with 25 years of clinical work behind me, I used rather than addressed
psychoanalysis. Looking at the question of my 1974 book in this brief
new introduction, I thought that maybe the “solution” I had heralded in
1966 (“Women: the Longest Revolution”)—sexuality as the weakest link
breaking its bounds into multiple different sexualities and hence the end
of the “exchange of women” forming the knot of kinship—had instead
become part of the problem; as though the end result had been achieved
prematurely and the real difficulty of women’s oppression, avoided.
Today, as the rich and getting rich reproduce less and less, care-taking
has replaced reproduction; as the one declines the other grows exponen-
tially and it is still largely attached to women. For poor everywhere and
for the wretched of the earth, reproduction remains central and care-
taking is carried out by what for the rich are a declining species: siblings
(mostly sisters) and female adjuncts (aunts, grandmothers . . . ). Sexuality
without reproduction for the rich may bloom as a thousand flowers,
for the rest it is global sex-trafficking above all of women. Within each
of the three structures of sexuality, reproduction and child rearing for
women that I proposed in 1966, something holds women back and all
94 JULIET MITCHELL
affect and are affected by the economy where equality eludes them. So I
still think we have to take on board the sexual difference of women and
men particularly where that is established around reproduction (sex and
death) even if the demographic transition to nonreplacement populations
for some has displaced pregnancy and parturition on to child-care and
socialization by others.
Butler believes oppression will change through the march of history,
the slow change of kinship will get us there in the end. I think the prob-
lem is larger—at least for women. Feminism must take command of the
theory and of the political practice. We need to grasp and remove the
rock that blocks the river, to combat the undertow, and move forward.
I see everything Judith has said today in terms of this move, which is
not to say that I think it is a fair, or perhaps I should say full, representa-
tion of that later thought (of course Juliet I consider you to have com-
pletely misread me, but that is beside the point!). But it is clear that for
Judith, the inexorability of symbolic law, the idea that sexual difference
is transmitted with such power into the unconscious, offers us all a grim
unanswerable destiny. Hence, as I see it, the two central planks of her
critique today. First, that the law is not an inheritance but an endlessly
renegotiated process: the law does not take precedence, it does not neces-
sarily predate desire, but can instead be thought of, as she suggests Klein
for example thought of it, as the always imperfect response to our most
dangerous inner drives. Secondly, that even if there is such a law, its trans-
mission into the minds of new generations will be as precarious, distorted,
reworked, and enigmatic as the logic or rather illogic of the unconscious.
Freud insisted that unconscious thoughts were normal, but the processes
of the unconscious were another matter: the unconscious does not, he
said, “think, calculate or judge in any way.” “I am not sure,” Judith
writes, “that what persists are . . . already formed legacies of the past into
the present without translation, transposition, without some loss, some
new twist or turn.” And taking her cue from Jean Laplanche: “Messages
arrive in enigmatic form, unscrutable.” “What is passed down is a forceful
impression, enigmatic and exciting, from an adult world whose libidinal
communications are overwhelming and unreadable for the infant.”
And if—as I understand it—there is no infallible transmission of
the law, but rather—I quote again—“a powerful set of impressions,”
then no immutable sexual difference. In fact I will risk pushing it, if the
transmission of the law is “invariably thwarted,” then no law. We have
entered—I quote—a “non-gendered adult world.”
As I was reading this response, I have to say that there was something
about the very force of the disagreement that struck me as odd. I have no
doubt that Judith is right to point to the conservative positions occupied
by some analysts toward homosexual parenting and other new organisa-
tions of sexual life—I would however want to stress “some,” having met
on Saturday a Paris-based woman analyst who signed a recent petition
against the legalization of surrogacy in France but whose friend, another
eminent feminist thinker and psychoanalyst, had refused to do so. In fact
she had signed it not out of hostility to surrogacy—she was happy with
the idea of artificial uteruses—but because she believed sexuality should
not in any form fall under the remit of the law. Nonetheless the inherent
conservatism of psychoanalytic institutions on these questions should
never be underestimated. I also agree that the 1999 Introduction stresses
the invariance of the law with renewed force.
S E X UA L D I F F E R E N C E , P O L I T I C S , A N D T H E U N C O N S C I O U S 97
But I fail to see in anything Juliet writes a tribute to or call for what
Judith referred to this evening as “accomplished heterosexuality.” What
Juliet is talking about it, as I understand it, is precisely the law of sexual
difference—that cruel, arbitrary, and unjust law— “unjust” as Freud
explicitly termed it—which requires of all human subjects that at some
point they reorder a polymorphous perverse bisexual disposition into
a diacritic opposition between male and female according to an ana-
tomical distinction which becomes as obligatory as it is a travesty of
everything that went before, and that will subsist for ever in the uncon-
scious. The basic Freudian premise, as I say to my students when I am
teaching psychoanalysis, is that we all know, anatomically speaking, if
we are a man or a woman, but, if the unconscious knows this as Juliet
would insist, it also knows better. The moment is as fraudulent as it is
inexorable. Or as the mother of feminist theorist Constance Penley put
it to her as a child, you can be a boy if you can kiss your elbow. What
happens next is anybody’s business. You cannot legislate for the after-
effects of any one subject in terms of their subsequent sexual lives. But
that is not the same thing as to suggest—and this is the rub as I see it—
that the multifarious experiences of sexual life have in and of themselves
dispensed with the law.
Two extraordinary moments from psychoanalytic literature can I think
make this point clear. The patient of D. W. Winnicott (1971) described
in “Creativity and its Origins,” who Winnicott analyzes as experienc-
ing penis-envy toward himself from the position of an unconscious girl:
“I know perfectly well,” Winnicott observes, “that you are a man, but
I am listening to a girl, and I am talking to a girl. I am telling this girl:
‘You are talking about penis envy.’ ” “If I was to tell someone about this
girl,” the patient responds, “I would be called mad.” Or the famous
patient from Robert Stoller’s (1973) case study Splitting who was con-
vinced she had a penis. Wanting to acknowledge the force of that fantasy
while disintricating it from the body sitting before him, Stoller observes:
“Look, physically, biologically, according to a doctor’s examination,
there’s no penis. Right?” To which the patient replies: “I don’t know that
I’ve ever been examined that closely” (1973: 13). What to make of these
extraordinary moments if not to point to the stunning disparity between
the inner experience of these two patients and the inexorable law of sexual
difference to which they both do and do not submit themselves?
Judith is surely right therefore to point to the disparity between uncon-
scious desires, lived social arrangements, and the injunctions of a heter-
onormative world. But perhaps you weaken your case by requiring that
those forms of errancy and experimentation subsist outside or beyond
the reach of the law which they endlessly contest. At the same time, as
98 JULIET MITCHELL
we indeed watch the law close around the subject in Juliet’s thought,
perhaps we should also remember how far her argument in Psychoanalysis
and Feminism rested on just such a disparity between reality and norm:
In her brilliant critique of Shulamith Firestone, for example, who, in
order to read penis-envy in terms of power, had to make the mother pow-
erless. Whereas, as you insisted, the mother is psychically all-powerful for
the infant. Happily there is no perfect match between the law of culture
and how we experience each other and ourselves. We cannot therefore
dispense with either side of this equation. We have been presented with
a false alternative. I would like to effect a reconciliation of sorts since it
is, for me, in the gap between the law and its failing that transformation
takes place.
On this, a correction vis-à-vis Lacan might be in order. As much as it
refers to kinship, Lacan’s account of the law stresses its inherent perver-
sion as well as the utter fraudulence of anyone who claims to embody
it (the law and the super ego are the specific focus of his Ethics semi-
nar of 1969). He also lifted from Freud—although Freud never quite
articulated it as such—that there has been no adequate account of the
origins of law. Similarly, the emphasis on language as structure gave way
in his thought to the idea of an inherent failing of meaning: meaning,
he stated in Seminar XX, always indicates the direction in which it fails.
That Lacan ignores the superego or freezes the subject into the laws of
language—the one point perhaps on which you seem agree—is there-
fore, perversely you might say, something I would wish to contest.
A final point from my own recent thinking. I could not help but be
struck by how closely this discussion of the transmission of the law, as the
key issue for both Juliet and Judith, mirrors the preoccupation of Freud
with the question of the transmission of his own Jewish legacy. To say
Freud’s inheritance on this matter was complicated is an understatement.
Passionately affiliated to what he referred to as the “essence” of Judaism,
at the same time he dissociated himself from the lore and language of his
fathers, the injunctions of Holy Writ, and the nationalist aspirations of
his people. I see traced out in this struggle, the same tension as the one
rehearsed here today between recognizing the force of an inheritance
and discarding or reworking the worst of its effects. Today Freud’s dif-
ficult negotiation of that trajectory has become for me one of the most
powerful and effective models for thinking about how to avoid the most
dangerous components of ethnic and group identities at the same time
as we have to acknowledge, so frighteningly in the new century, their
continuing force. I would like to conclude by suggesting that we could
do worse than to think about the persistence and undoing of sexual
difference in similar terms.
S E X UA L D I F F E R E N C E , P O L I T I C S , A N D T H E U N C O N S C I O U S 99
References
Butler, J. 2009. “Ideologies of the Superego.” A paper presented at the
Symposium for the retirement of Juliet Mitchell. University of Cambridge,
May 2009.
Butler, J. 2013. “Rethinking Sexual Difference and Kinship in Mitchell’s
Psychoanalysis and Feminism.” differences 23(2): 1–19.
Freud, S. 1905. “Three Essays on Sexuality.” In Standard Edition of the
Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 7, translated and
edited by James Strachey. London: Hogarth. SE7, 123–246.
Freud, S. 1933. “On Femininity.” In Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, Vol. 22. Translated and edited by
James Strachey,112–135. London: Hogarth.
Johnston, B. 1998. The Feminist Difference: Literature, Psychoanalysis, Race
and Gender. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press
Mitchell, J. 1966. “Women: The Longest Revolution.” New Left Review 40:
11–37.
Mitchell, J. 1974. Psychoanalysis and Feminism. New York: Basic Books.
Mitchell, J. 1999. “Introduction.” In Psychoanalysis and Feminism. New York:
Basic Books.
Mitchell, J. 2000. Psychoanalysis and Feminism. New York: Basic Books.
Mitchell, J. 2000. “The Different Self, the Phallus and the Father.”
Psychoanalysis and Feminism, 382–298. New York: Basic Books.
Mitchell, J. 2006. “Procreative Mothers (sexual difference) and Childfree
Sisters (gender).” In Browne, J (ed.). 2007. The Future of Gender. Cambridge
University press pp. 163–188
Rose, J. 2009. A discussant reply given at the Symposium for the retirement
of Juliet Mitchell. University of Cambridge May 2009.
Rubin, G. 1975. “The Traffic in Women.” In Toward an Anthropology of
Women, edited by R. Reiter, 157–210. New York: Mon Rev.
Rubin, G. and Butler, J. 1994. “Sexual Traffic.” differences 6(2–3): 62–99.
Stoller, R. 1968. Sex and Gender. New York: Science House.
Stoller, R. 1973. Splitting. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
Winnicott, D. W. 1971. Playing and Reality, London: Routledge.
Chapter 5
Robbie Duschinsky
E ach of Juliet Mitchell’s texts has an iridescent quality that allows us,
as time passes, to see both particular passages and our world differently.
Part of this quality is the result of a core question that animates each
of Mitchell’s books, and which keeps being reactivated by our concrete
personal and political experiences even as circumstances are reconfig-
ured: Why are inequalities between men and women so pervasive, even
in movements that purport to be primarily concerned with equality?
Mitchell has been described as a “conservative” by scholars such as Lynne
Segal (2001) for even asking this question, since it seems to presume
sexual difference as a single, natural, and immovable binary along repro-
ductive lines (see also Grosz 1990; Chiland 2004). Yet in fact Mitchell’s
interest has been to interrogate why genital and reproductive differences
between human beings, which in themselves imply little at all about how
our lives or our society should be structured, have been figured with a
significance that allows them to support the entrenchment and naturaliza-
tion of inequalities.
In a tract for the Fabian society, asking what values a socialist should
hold, Bernard Crick (1984, 13) proposed that “only equality is specifically
socialist in itself; liberty and fraternity, however, take on a distinctively
socialist form when the three are related to each other.” This analysis
helps highlight the commitment to exploring meaningful equality, which
links together Juliet Mitchell’s early work on liberty (exploring women’s
liberation for the New Left Review) and her more recent, psychoanalytic
work on fraternity (exploring sibling relationships and gender). “This
might come as a shock,” Mitchell (2011, 2) notes, “but I never actually
stopped thinking of myself as a Marxist.” Drawing out this “red thread”
of continuity between Mitchell’s early and late work, this chapter will
102 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
We heard from W and from Delta, who gave us two very different
accounts of what had taken place in 2008 and 2009. We heard from
and questioned a number of other comrades. They were people who
had been brought as witnesses, either by W or by Delta. However nei-
ther of them were witnesses to the actual events . . .
We didn’t think that Delta raped W. And it was not proved to the
disputes committee that Delta had sexually assaulted, harassed or
abused W. We found it difficult to rule on these issues, because the
versions of events differed substantially and there were no witnesses.
The disputes committee didn’t recommend any disciplinary action
against Delta . . .
We discussed, debated, considered, changed our minds, listened to
each other, and then we came to the best conclusions that we could,
to the best of our abilities, and it’s on that basis that I put this report
to you and to the conference. (applause)
(transcript of the Disputes Committee Report to Conference,
CPGB 2013a).
She thought that if she put a complaint to the party that it would be
dealt with in line with the party’s politics and our proud tradition on
women’s liberation. Sadly her experience was quite the opposite . . . She
was questioned about why she went for a drink with him, her wit-
nesses were repeatedly asked whether she’d been in a relationship with
him, and you know, she was asked . . . about relationships with other
comrades including sexual relationships. All this was irrelevant to the
104 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
case . . . She felt she was being interrogated and felt they were trying to
catch her out in order to make her out to be a liar. She did not accept
the line of questioning, saying “they think I’m a slut who asked for
it” . . . she feels she’s been treated as this non-person. The disgusting
lies and gossip going round about her has been really distressing and
disappointing for her to hear, and the way her own witnesses have
been treated in Birmingham hasn’t been much better.
(transcript of the Disputes Committee Report to Conference,
CPGB 2013).
Twin Sisters
In discussions of her work by younger scholars, Mitchell’s tale is often
recounted: “I remember sitting at a table with all the men of New Left
Review, and going round the table with people saying ‘Well, I will think
about Algeria’, ‘I will think about Persia’, ‘I will think about Tanganyika’,
as they then were, and I said, ‘Well, I’ll think about women’—and
there was silence” (1995, 74). Mitchell went on to write Women: The
Longest Revolution. As already mentioned, Callinicos has character-
ized such works by members of the New Left Review editorial team as
106 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
Identifying the axes of identity and difference between these twin sis-
ters, Mitchell suggests that radical feminism is utterly correct to analyze
the role of sexism in positively forming our subjectivity itself, rather than
solely its material conditions of possibility. Ideology shapes what we per-
ceive and who we are as sexed subjects, not just the conditions and divi-
sions of the labor conducted by men and women. This trains attention
on the importance of experience, and “starts to grapple with the ideo-
logical and psychological oppression of women” (1971, 95). Yet Mitchell
incisively observes that “the notion of undifferentiated male domination
from the earliest to the latest times simply gives a theoretical form to the
way oppression is usually experienced,” and is therefore insufficient on its
own. An undifferentiated “full presence” of patriarchy is interpreted by
Mitchell as a conceptual trap, with no escape possible. Likewise, Mitchell
observes that a socialist orientation is required because “the unequal dis-
tribution of wealth and ownership” provide the context “from which all
lack of freedom and of possibility for realisation of individuality follows
as night the day” (1971, 177). Yet to lose attention to the diversity of
oppressions by, for example, presuming they run in ways neatly homolo-
gous or subordinate to class, serves to “evade the specific oppression of
women and idealise the role of the oppressed” (1971, 94). To presume an
undifferentiated “full absence” of patriarchy within a socialist orientation
forecloses attention to the intersection of oppressions, including within
organizations committed to the attainment of meaningful equality.
Dialectics
Fundamental to Mitchell’s movement within/beyond socialism has
been the theme of dialectical processes. A dialectical perspective, which
explores the interplay of “sameness and difference, the subject and the
108 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
other,” was one she first encountered “when as a student I read Simone
de Beauvoir’s The Second Sex and discovered that I was, as a woman, the
very site of a primal alterity” (Mitchell 2006, 35). The widespread and
crude reduction of the “Hegelian dialectic” to a static and totalizing
process of thesis, antithesis, and synthesis was an interpretation already
ridiculed by Marx and Lenin as “wooden trichotomies,” and utterly dis-
missed by Hegel, who specifically describes this “triplicity” as “noth-
ing but the merely superficial, external side of cognition” (Hegel [1832]
2010, 746). A more acute interpretation understands dialectics as social
ontology in which monism or dualism are necessarily precluded by the
ongoing weave of our existence out of contradictory relations within and
between phenomena. Hegel identifies that “the being as such of finite
things is to have the germ of this vergehen [spatial transgression/pas-
sage of time] in their in-itselfness” (ibid., 101); the reason for this is that
for a phenomenon or form of subjectivity to “positively” exist, it must
establish determinate relations of exclusion and “negation” with other
phenomena. However, this means that their very existence depends upon
maintaining a contradiction with these other phenomena. This places
contradiction and otherness, and therefore some degree of change and
sensuous motion, into the beating heart of each “positive” phenomenon
or subject: “The positive, since implicitly it is negativity, goes out of itself
and sets its alteration in motion. Something is alive, therefore, only to
the extent that it contains contradiction within itself” (ibid. 382). The
implication is that where apparent unities or simple oppositions occur as
characterization of human experience or relations, such characterizations
require critical investigation as deflections or containers of contradiction
(ibid. 416; cf. Jameson 2010).
Mitchell likewise affirms that “there is a contradiction within any-
thing that can change and one between it and its relationships to other
things” ([1974a] 1984, 91). Yet against any caricatured and crude
“Hegelian demands” (1967, 82), the dialectic for Mitchell never reaches
a moment of closure, beyond historicism and change. In Woman’s Estate
(1971, 90), she describes the concept of dialectics as positing “a com-
plex (not dualistic) structure in which all elements are in contradiction
to each other; at some point these contradictions can coalesce, explode
and be overcome but the new fusion will enter into contradiction with
something else. Human society is, and always will be, full of contra-
diction.” Whether the idealism is familialist (Marie Stopes) or radical
(Shulamith Firestone), Mitchell perceives that any “notion of transcend-
ing the divisions that plague our world,” ending the dialectic in a closed
shape, form, and established limitation, can only be illusionary; deploy-
ing the idea of “ultimate union no more solves divisions than it explains
D I A L E C T I C A N D DY S T O P I A 109
Her analysis suggests that it has above all been “the woman’s task”
to sustain femininity and the family as ostensibly natural unities. She
concludes that “women in the family are used to deflect the tide and
implications of social labour” (1971, 161), masking determinate contra-
dictions in society as merely the flaws of particular women who deviate
from the imputed “truths” of femininity and the family. Yet, Mitchell
also observes that precisely the strain of trying to contain the movement
of dialectical contradictions within the monism of femininity and the
110 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
family has resulted in the Movement for Women’s Liberation, since “out
of the increasingly numerous contradictions of their position, a sense of
their oppression is growing” (ibid.).
Mitchell’s analysis places the subjective experiences of women as both
an expression and as a containment of contradictions in the objective
relations between production, reproduction, sexuality, and socializa-
tion in society and the family. In this she is aligned with studies using
the concept of “the dialectic of negativity as the moving and generating
principle” (Marx [1844] 1977, 101), which have presumed that the tri-
als of subjectivity will co-vary with objective contradictions—until this
subject comes to recognize the contradictions it faces are common to
a whole group of subjects, and in doing so achieves the possibility of
freedom from them. Within this dialectical approach, the examination
of contradictions at the level of subjective experience and at the level of
objective conditions in society must be considered together, as part of
the very same event occurring at two different levels in potential sup-
port or disjuncture with one another (cf. Williams 1973). In Mitchell’s
usage, this approach offered a method for investigating the interrelation
between contradictions at the level of both the personal and the political,
treated as one event—but not necessarily as mirroring one another. This
agrees with Marx and Engels ([1846] 1994, 130), who argued that so
long as there exists any form of division of labour “the productive force,
the state of society, and consciousness”—each of which themselves will
be threaded by contradictions— “can and must come into conflict with
one another.”
A dialectical movement in which contradictions within a particular
form lead both deeper within and beyond it characterized both Mitchell’s
own relationship with socialism (which entered into a productive contra-
diction with feminism) and her analysis of the position of women under
patriarchy (as masks and containers for ultimately unbearable contradic-
tions between production, reproduction, sexuality, and socialisation—as
the four bases of sexism in society). This was concerted. From the time
of ‘Women: the Longest Revolution,” Mitchell (1967, 82) insisted that
her work could not be understood if readers were to enact any “separa-
tion of methodology from content. I consider that the two are correla-
tives”; indeed, perhaps the only accurate comment in Hoare’s (1967,
79) vituperative critique of Longest Revolution is to note that Mitchell’s
“method is more than a method—it demonstrates her whole ideological
orientation.” Precisely a combination of a dialectical relationship with
socialism and a dialectical analysis together led Mitchell to integrate
socialist analysis with further insights from feminism and from a further
intellectual movement, psychoanalysis.
D I A L E C T I C A N D DY S T O P I A 111
hysteria—a factor that is no doubt situated at the symbolic level, but per-
haps isn’t entirely reducible to it? It concerns a question of procreation.”
Mitchell specifies this link between hysteria, procreation, and imaginary
forms that unsettle symbolic thought, offering a new interpretation of
the “primal scene” to which Freud assigned such importance. In doing so
she deploys her ongoing attention to reproduction—criticized by theo-
rists such as Segal (2001) as crude gender essentialism. In fact, Mitchell’s
perspective is subtle, firmly eschewing both “biological determinism”
and “socialisation” theories. Mitchell’s analysis suggests that “biological
femaleness and psychic femininity in certain but by no means all situa-
tions are co-incident. Even in these instances we should remember that
there is never a perfect fit” (1988, 88–9). This perspective leaves open
the possibility of attending to “the way the anatomical male/female data
(with all its uncertainties) is mentally lived; the way the physical data, the
clitoris/vagina/penis, is phantasized and experienced; the way these are
lived in people’s heads and in their experiences” (1973, 131). This subtly
allows Mitchell to identify the fantasies of the primal scene and parthe-
nogenesis (the birth of another exactly like oneself from oneself), which
address the question of how difference occurs or does not occur within
the reproduction and birth of new identities. This question, Mitchell
insists, is shared by men and women, since “giving birth is no more psy-
chically gendered than is dying. It is, however, actually gendered—as
is having a penis, which, because it can be cut off, can also represent
the annihilation of the subject” (2000, 200–1). Since reproductive inter-
course between the parents “is a perfect image for an originary absence
of the subject at the very place where he comes into being—we are not
present at our own conception. It is, however, the catastrophe of the sib-
ling displacement which occasions a retrospective imaginary perception
of this ‘unimaginable’ event. Hysteria protests this displacement, this
absence of the subject” (Mitchell 2000, 24).
Mitchell suggests that, for both sexes, themes of sexual and parthe-
nogenic reproduction as well as death predominate in the experience of
hysteria, because each is a fundamental site that can be used to “repre-
sent the annihilation of the subject” (2000, 200–1). This potential for
an experience of annihilation in the threat of substitutability and dis-
placement, Mitchell theorizes, is a threat that every subject must either
surmount or try to evade in hysteria and which is necessarily evoked by
the potential for a sibling who is not merely an extension of the subject.
Whether through the advent of a new sibling, a potential sibling, or the
intrusion into mother-baby of the needs and demands of an older sibling,
there appears “a black hole where we thought we stood” (Mitchell 2003,
42). Together with the parent–child vertical axis, the horizontal axis of
D I A L E C T I C A N D DY S T O P I A 115
possible siblings draws out the dimensions of a frame within which every
subject is established in a matrix of relations of similarity and difference.
Perpendicular to the dialectic through which a child emerges from a rela-
tionship with an adult caregiver, in Madmen Mitchell therefore identifies
another horizontal dialectic in which “the minimal difference between
brothers and sisters is the difference that must be socially established”
(2000, 324–5). The idea of an identity which could be a self-enclosed
point is a necessary phantasy but is not a sustainably inhabitable form of
subjectivity, Mitchell proposes, because it is precisely through the matrix
of relations along the vertical line and the lateral line that we first find
our place in the world:
moments of the dialectic directly: “Because the first or the immediate [the
first-born] is the concept in itself or implicitly [as ‘the Baby’], and therefore
is the negative also only implicitly [because the next child may only exist as
a possibility], the dialectical movement in it consist in the positing of the
difference that is implicitly contained in it [learning of difference, griev-
ing for parthenogenesis]. The second [child] is on the contrary itself the
determinate, the difference or relation [faced by always being ‘the Baby’
in relation to an older ‘relation’: the sibling]; hence the dialectical moment
consists in its case in the positing of the unity contained within it [and the
younger sibling has to find its identity within a relationship coeval with
its birth]” (Hegel [1832] 2010, 745). In particular, as Mitchell ([1964]
1984) observes of Heathcliff in her commentary on Wuthering Heights,
the child loaded by their caregiver as a replacement for or in the shadow of
a dead sibling has among the more acute and rocky forms this task can take
(see also Guntrip 1975). Even the only child must negotiate the issue of
substitutability and displacement, and Mitchell’s analysis agrees with that
of Klein (1932, 73) that “an only child suffers to a far greater extent than
other children from the anxiety it feels in regard to the brother or sister
whom it is forever expecting . . . because it has no opportunity of develop-
ing a positive relation to them in reality.”
Attention to sibling relations as a site for the negotiation of sameness
and difference helps Mitchell identify why genital and reproductive dif-
ferences have been figured with a social significance that allows them to
support the entrenchment and naturalization of inequalities. Unless the
subject is provided with the symbolic and imaginary resources to nego-
tiate their place within the matrix of vertical and horizontal relations,
the threat posed by the difference comprising the lateral axis remains
active as a destabilizing trauma. Then genital and reproductive differ-
ences are picked up or suggested as symbols to staunch the trauma of
substitutability and displacement, which provides an impetus for sexual
oppression, which will take different forms depending on culture and
context. Mitchell (2003, 219–220) argues that “when the child is over-
whelmed by the trauma of one who, in the mind, was supposed to be the
same as itself inevitably turning out to be different, it finds or is given
ways to mark this difference—age is one, gender another . . . The cradle
of gender difference is both narcissistic love and violence at the traumatic
moment of displacement in the world. Gender difference comes into
being when physical strength and malevolence are used to make the sister
as lesser” (2003, 219–220). When the symbolic and imaginary resources
are available from adult caregivers and from society to allow each sub-
ject a recognized and intelligible place, with sufficient meaning and dig-
nity, then genital and reproductive differences are registered and given
D I A L E C T I C A N D DY S T O P I A 117
In the opening pages of the book, Winston Smith describes how “you
had to live—did live, from habit that became instinct—in the assump-
tion that every sound you made was overheard,” and in which, always
and inexorably for any member of the party, “Big Brother is watching
you” (Orwell 1949, 6). Panoptical surveillance works to ensure not only
outward conformity, but inward and unthinking allegiance. Any inter-
nal dynamism—whether triggered by contradiction between reality and
perception, or between desires and social injunctions—is potentially dan-
gerous since “any nervous mannerism that could possibly be the symp-
tom of an inner struggle is certain to be detected” (1949, 168). With the
generative tension of conflict with reality or the id foreclosed, the ego is
at the mercy of its ideal. Big Brother as “an invincible, fearless protector”
is opposed in Ingsoc ideology to Goldstein, “the commander of a vast
shadowy army, an underground network of conspirators dedicated to the
overthrow of the State. The Brotherhood, its name was supposed to be”;
it is the responsibility of every member of the party to feel, confronted
with an image of Goldstein, “a hideous ecstasy of fear and vindictiveness,
a desire to kill, to torture, to smash faces in” (1949, 14–5).
Over the course of the book, Winston has two visions, which begin
at the same time and progressively develop over the book. The first is
a sequence of “memory, which he could not pin down, but which was
powerful and troubling” (1949, 100). The first hint is the undue reso-
nance he finds in a media image of a mother and small child, from a
convoy of ships to England which had been bombed (an image also with
resonance to Mitchell’s biography). The vision then appears to Winston
more sharply as a dream in which “his mother was sitting in some place
deep down beneath him, with his young sister in her arms. He did not
remember his sister at all, except as a tiny, feeble baby, always silent, with
large, watchful eyes . . . they were being sucked down to death, and they
were down there because he was up here. He knew it and they knew
it” (Orwell 1949, 27). The sequence of memories gradually comes into
focus. He remembers, from late childhood, “the fierce sordid battles at
meal-times. He would ask his mother naggingly, over and over again,
why there was no more food . . . His mother was quite ready to give him
more than his share. She took it for granted that he, ‘the boy’, should
have the biggest portion; but however much she gave him he invariably
demanded more. At every meal she would beseech him not to be selfish
and to remember that his little sister was sick and also needed food . . . He
knew that he was starving the other two, but he could not help it; he even
felt that he had a right to do it” (194, 132). The big brother’s sovereign
egoism at the expense of his younger sister is consciously felt as entitle-
ment; and this entitlement is enacted as Winston’s mother gives him
122 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
more because he is “the boy” and because the family’s intense poverty
and his mother’s depression undermines her capacity to firmly establish
any frame for recognition between the siblings. Even though he gets the
food he desires, Winston is aware that he is starving his mother and sister
with his demands, though the associated guilt is sufficiently unconscious
as to allow his behaviour to continue.
After stealing her share of a chocolate ration, “his sister, conscious of
having been robbed of something, had set up a feeble wail. His mother
drew her arm around the child and pressed its face against her breast.
Something in the gesture told him that his sister was dying. He turned
and fled down the stairs, with the chocolate growing sticky in his hand.
He never saw his mother again” (1949, 133). Winston tells his lover
Julia that because he had not had access to this memory until now,
“until this moment I believed I had murdered my mother” (1949, 131).
What is curious, and which has not been picked up by commentators on
Orwell, is that Winston’s guilt is organized by a confusion of the vertical
and lateral axes through the link between the two. Klein ([1928] 1998,
190) observes that “the tendencies to steal and destroy are concerned
with the organs of conception, pregnancy and partuition,” and she
associates these tendencies with a desire to “appropriate” the mother’s
existing children into oneself and by “jealousy of the future brothers
and sisters whose appearance is expected.” As a result, “the boy fears
punishment for his destruction of the mother’s body . . . he fears that his
body will be mutilated and dismembered, and this dread also means
castration.” Winston did not murder his mother, but rather drove her
away because his selfishness was killing or speeding up the death of
his younger sister. Like Klein, he presumes that stealing and appropria-
tion are ultimately directed toward the mother, rather than identifying
the relationship between big brother and little sister as capable of its
own psychical dynamics and consequences, its own processes of love
and guilt. In his society, there are no symbolic resources usable to make
sense of lateral complexity and ambivalence: only love for Big Brother,
and hate for the Brotherhood. In another context in the novel, Winston
dismisses the working-class Proles because instead of having political
vision they only “remembered a million useless things, a quarrel with a
workmate, a hunt for a lost bicycle pump, the expression on a long-dead
sister’s face” (1949, 78).
As the book closes Winston has a further memory from his childhood:
His mother was sitting opposite him and also laughing. It must have
been about a month before she disappeared. It was a moment of rec-
onciliation, when the nagging hunger in his belly was forgotten . . . the
D I A L E C T I C A N D DY S T O P I A 123
one way to save himself. He must interpose another human being, the
body of another human being, between himself and the rats” (1949,
230). Political resistance to the coercive state is given up by Winston
at the moment at which he is forced to repeat interposing a particular
body between himself and an image of his sordid hunger. This body is
that of Julia, a “young girl” who loved him and who “stirred up some
memory which he could not pin down” when she shared chocolate with
him (1949, 100).
In describing this ultimate betrayal of Julia with images that reso-
nate with Winston’s earlier relations with his younger sister, Orwell dra-
matizes the psychical effect of a society in which lateral relations have
been systematically undermined and warped. A socialist, Orwell ([1946]
2002, 1005) argues, “is not obliged to believe that human society can
actually be made perfect, but almost any socialist does believe that it
could be a great deal better than it is at present, and that most of the evil
that men do results from the warping effects of injustice and i nequality.”
Commenting on dystopian writing as socialist meditation, Williams
(1980, 206) observed, “it is within a complex of contemporary tenden-
cies—of efficient and affluent capitalism set against an earlier capitalist
poverty and disorder; of socialism against capitalism in either phase; and
of the deep divisions within socialism itself . . . that we have to consider
the mode of dystopia” as a genre of modernist fiction generally, and
Orwell’s Nineteen Eighty-Four specifically. In this way, Winston’s dream
of a time when humans are different from one another and do not live
alone dramatizes the possibility, explored in Mitchell’s work, of change
in the social and psychological configuration of liberty and solidarity as
the condition of advance toward meaningful equality.
Concluding Remarks
Mitchell has described that “I find the question of ‘othering’ as an
abstract concept vertiginous, and my contribution here is consequently
prosaic, down-to-earth” (2006, 35). In contrast to such vertiginous ana-
lytical tools for examining social and psychological forces which disrupt
the practice of meaningful equality, Mitchell explores “the minimal dif-
ference that needs to be set up between sisters and brothers for replication
to turn into seriality” (2003, 151–2). She deploys sibling relationships as
a lens on the dialectic that must organize lateral relations if they are to
escape twin dangers: collapse into the callous sovereign egoism lauded by
capitalist ideology; or warping into dystopian isolation and homogeniza-
tion. In contrast to post-structuralist thinking in which difference and
multiplicity are held up as a counter to capitalist and socialist totalities,
126 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
loses the dynamic of historical change which only comes about through
their confrontation.” Over her career Mitchell has sustained a dialectic
between the three siblings—socialist, feminist, and psychoanalysis—in
using their ideas to interrogate oppression, contradictions, and possibili-
ties in society. This analysis both enacts in itself and critically considers
relations of lateral recognition, presenting an advance in conceptualizing
the conditions for meaningful equality.
References
Althusser, L. [1962] 2005. “Contradiction and Overdetermination.” In For
Marx, translated by Ben Brewster, 87–128. New York: Verso.
Blackburn, R. 1972. Ideology in Social Science. London: Fontana/Collins.
Callinicos, A. 2013. “Is Leninism finished?” Socialist Review, January 13, 2013.
Central Committee of the Socialist Workers Party 2013. “The SWP and
Women’s Oppression.” http://socialistunity.com/wp-content/uploads/2013
/03/SWP-internal-bulletin-special-conference-march2013.pdf
Chiland, C. 2004. “Gender and Sexual Difference” in Dialogues on Sexuality,
Gender, and Psychoanalysis, edited by Iréne Matthis, 79–91. London:
Karnac.
Communist Party of Great Britain 2013a. “Transcript of the Disputes Committee
Report to Conference.” http://www.cpgb.org.uk/home/weekly-worker
/online-only/report-of-swps-disputes-committee-and-conference-debate
Communist Party of Great Britain 2013b. “Callinicos threatens ‘Lynch Mobs’.”
http://www.cpgb.org.uk/home/weekly-worker/online-only/callinicos
-threatens-lynch-mobs
Crick, B. 1984. Socialist Values and Time, Fabian Tract 495. London: The
Fabian Society.
Feuerbach, L. A. [1843] 1986. Principals of the Philosophy of the Future,
translated by Manfred Vogel. New York: Hackett & Co.
Foucault, M. [1975] 1977. Discipline and Punish, translated by Alan Sheridan.
London: Penguin.
Freud, S. [1909] 2001. “Notes upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis,” Standard
Edition, Volume 10, edited by James Strachey, 153–318. London: Vintage.
Freud, S. [1914] 2001. “On Narcissism: An Introduction,” Standard Edition,
Volume 14, edited by James Strachey, London: Vintage.
Freud, S. [1915] 2001. “Instincts and their Vicissitudes,” Standard Edition,
Volume 14, edited by James Strachey, London: Vintage.
Freud, S. [1933] 2001. “New Introductory Lectures.” Standard Edition,
Volume 22, edited by James Strachey, London: Vintage.
Freud, S. [1938] 2001. “Findings, Ideas, Problems,” Standard Edition, Volume
23, edited by James Strachey, 299–300, London: Vintage.
Green, A. 1999. The Work of the Negative, translated by Andrew Weller, New
York: Free Association Books.
Goldstein, P. 2000. “Orwell as a (Neo)conservative: The Reception of 1984.”
Journal of the Midwest Modern Language Association 33(1): 44–57.
128 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y
Daru Huppert
Accepting this does not entail an idolatry of Freud’s texts; the very
same requirements have been critically applied to Freud (Laplanche
1979). Yet it is also true that his writings fulfill these requirements to a
degree that have rarely, if at all, been reached again. That is one reason
why his texts are exemplary. Their unique status within psychoanalysis,
however, depends on something more basic: most of the central concepts
found in this discipline derive from Freud. Those who seek to reclaim
the central meaning of his work for psychoanalysis are keenly aware that
their work takes place within his concepts. In the view I wish to propose
here psychoanalysis is a development of his thought; in other words, it
is a Freudian project; the authors named above offer different and partly
conflicting versions thereof. Although this outline of the Freudian pro-
ject may seem overly abstract and will only gain in detail as we proceed,
it can nevertheless serve as a foil to the dominant view of Freud within
psychoanalysis, expressed with particular clarity by someone like Ferro
(1999, p. 1–19), though shared by many, perhaps the majority of psycho-
analysts. In this view Freud is treated (if at all) with a deference due to a
great figure of the past, who points to the progress that has been made
since him and, to a large degree, independently of his work. Such a view
unwittingly turns Freud into an antiquarian figure, whom we must “go
beyond.” In contrast, within the Freudian project, his writings remain of
acute and immediate importance. One reason for proposing this project
is, precisely, that efforts to go beyond Freud, in general, fall far behind
him. The challenge, rather, becomes to develop the strange and unsettling
originality of his thought and to extend it onto new areas.
In this chapter, I will discuss Mitchell’s work as a successful version of
the Freudian project, though not without some critique. Given her long-
standing engagement with Freud, any attempt to show how she thinks
with him and within his conceptions will necessarily be selective. Three
points will be taken up. I will first address her initial encounter with
his writings, then her allegiance to his concepts in her later texts, and
finally I will compare Mitchell’s and Freud’s analysis in more detail with
reference to a sadomasochistic fantasy. Throughout the purpose of this
chapter is twofold: to describe what is distinctive about Mitchell’s work
and to flesh out the demands of the Freudian project.
Marked by Freud
Mitchell’s entry into psychoanalysis was through Freud and she is still
probably best known for introducing him as a crucial thinker for femi-
nism within the English language. Yet this was not the intention she
initially pursued. In her introduction written for the 25th anniversary
134 DARU HUPPERT
edition for Psychoanalysis and Feminism Mitchell (2000, xv) remarks that
she had actually planned to write a book on the family:
This passage, which may seem anecdotal, reveals some of the features
that have made Mitchell’s relationship with Freud compelling. Moreover,
it will serve to show what is required from us, if we wish to engage with
Freud. Since my focus here is on her relationship to Freud, I will not
enter into the other theme of her engagement: feminism. It is important
to note that Mitchell’s encounter with Freud was unexpected. With this
I do not mean primarily that she was planning to read only a few articles
of his, instead of writing a book in which he was to become the main
protagonist. I mean rather, that she was seized by Freud in a manner that
nothing could have prepared her for. One of the reasons for this captiva-
tion is that Freud’s object and mode of inquiry takes up the most pressing
matters of infancy. More precisely, his thought takes up the repressed
investigation of sexual questions in childhood.1 That is why, while read-
ing his texts, we are overcome by an uncanny sense, of following a line of
exploration that is deeply familiar, but which we have become estranged
from, due to the repression (never total) it has suffered. Freud’s writ-
ings affect us deeply, because they provide developed forms of thought
that take up our inchoate explorations of sexual questions in infancy, of
issues, such as sexual difference, that continue to confuse and excite us.
A main virtue of Psychoanalysis and Feminism is that Mitchells does not
try to asphyxiate what Freud has stirred up in her, instead she uses this
effect to give a stirring, lucid, and committed account of his thought.
What is required by such an account is shown by Mitchell reading the
twenty-three volumes of Freud’s complete works. A point that she repeats
throughout Psychoanalysis and Feminism is that Freud is not reducible to
any of his assertions, whether considered scandalous and absurd, by detrac-
tors, or essential, by some of his followers. For Mitchell his assertions can
only be comprehended by assessing their position within his thought.
That is why Psychoanalysis and Feminism does not begin with Freud’s
F R EU D, M I T C H E L L , A N D T H E F R EU D I A N P R O J E C T 135
conceptions of the feminine, but with his ideas about the unconscious,
which, he considered the “true psychic reality” (Freud 1900a, 617), from
which the strange originality of his conceptions derive. Implicitly she
argues that if we wish to comprehend the particulars of Freud’s thought,
we need to engage with all of it—he is not to be had for less. A reason for
this, which is often overlooked, is that throughout his work, Freud main-
tains a holism of our psychic lives. He is more commonly associated with
dividing the psyche into different systems (for example, into the uncon-
scious, the preconscious, and into consciousness) and with emphasizing
that, to a considerable degree, they function independently of one another.
Yet when discussing a particular psychic phenomenon, such as the dream,
he does so by examining the interaction of these systems. Thus, while the
entirety of the psychic forces at work within a dream is never available to
the dreamer or to the analyst—too many features are unconscious—these
forces are nevertheless present structurally in the dream. This holism of
Freud’s theory, albeit a complex holism, has a deep influence on his writ-
ings, so that his discussion of sexuality only take on their full meaning if
we relate it to his ideas of the unconscious, etc. I would argue that this
has nonintuitive implications for how we should read Freud: while it is, of
course, important to read his theories in terms of their historical develop-
ment, they should also be read as if they existed all-at-once. This may be
something that we can only strive for, yet Mitchell reading all his works
represents an exemplary approximation.
What can sustain this kind of commitment? In the passage quoted
above Mitchell writes that she has been deeply marked, indeed changed
by Freud. This is a distinctive feature of his writings, which is not given
due consideration in most academic discussions of him. I would argue
that unless Freud changes us, our encounter with his writings is merely
incidental. This is due to the impetus that sustain his texts that is perhaps
best expressed in the epigram by Vergil that Freud (1900a, ix) chose
for The Interpretation of Dreams, “Flectere si nequeo superos, acheronta
movobo,” which might be translated as, “If I cannot move the heavens,
I will stir up the underworld.” We may take the “underworld” here to
mean the repressed wishes that stir up the unconscious. In other words,
wishes that are indestructible, imperative, and constantly active, but that
we can neither become conscious of, nor satisfy. Freud’s writings are sus-
tained by an overriding desire to analyze and change this state of affairs.
I would suggest that Mitchell’s ability to translate this impetus onto
another field—a feminist discussion of sexual difference—and to do so
with such impact stems from her having been deeply marked by Freud.
This is, perhaps, the primary subjective feature that all proponents of the
Freudian project share, though, evidently, to differing degrees.
136 DARU HUPPERT
Fundamental Concepts
It is a difficult task to specify Freud’s influence on Mitchell’s later texts,
since, in some sense, he pervades all of it. An anecdote, however, may
provide a more specific orientation. About a decade ago I attended a
postgraduate seminar in Cambridge, in which Mitchell asked the stu-
dents to write down three concepts that they considered to be the most
important within psychoanalysis. She participated in this exercise and
her choice fell on sexuality, the death drive, and the unconscious. I shall
briefly discuss the role these concepts play in Mad Men and Medusas,
the book in which introduces both her theory of hysteria and of siblings.
This will allow me to point to commitments that distinguish her from
the majority of British analysts.
F R EU D, M I T C H E L L , A N D T H E F R EU D I A N P R O J E C T 137
Sexuality
One of the themes Mitchell inherited from Freud is her insistence on the
central importance of sexuality, in the extended and unsettling meaning
of the term that he first articulated. This notion, to name but some of its
aspects, entails that sexuality aims at pleasure (rather than at reproduc-
tion); this pleasure is derived from diverse and therefore perverse objects
and activities, with the excitement arising from specific erogenous zones
(such as the eyes) and impelled by component drives (such as the visual
component drive). To refer to a programmatic sentence in regard to this
view, Mitchell (2000b, 140) writes, “Insofar sexuality seeks satisfaction
rather than an object . . . it is in a sense necessarily perverse.” This posi-
tion also entails seeing sexuality as central to psychic conditions, which is
attested to by another sentence, “Masturbation, auto-eroticism and nar-
cissism are core states of hysteria” (Mitchell 2000b, 157). (To compre-
hend the full meaning of this last statement, we need to remember that
in psychoanalysis narcissism means the libidinal investment of the ego.)
Mitchell’s stance on this issue contrasts with the reticence often found
among the proponents of the Independent School of Psychoanalysis,
who concede importance to sexuality, only to emphasize something else
as more fundamental, such as maternal care (Phillips 1998). It also con-
trasts with another view of sexuality found among many Kleinians, the
other dominant stream of psychoanalysis in Britain, in which libido is
relegated to the function of a defense against primary destruction or
against psychosis; what interests in sexuality is then not sex, but aggres-
sive or reparative fantasies (Spillius 1989). The issues raised by these two
schools are significant in their own right, but they entail a movement
away from Freud’s insight into the irreducible importance of sexuality
in shaping who we are. Tellingly, both positions also revert to a more
conventional understanding of what sexuality is (Green 2000). One of
the many advantages of retaining the Freudian understanding of libido is
that it enables us to see more clearly the continuity between ordinary and
perverse sexuality. This, for example, allows Mitchell (2000b, 134–158)
a critical but nonmoralistic view of the perversions. It was one of Freud’s
great accomplishments to have established such a perspective, which,
within psychoanalysis, is becoming rare.
organic into the inorganic and finds expression in the repetition com-
pulsion as well as in the search for anesthetized states and the disinvest-
ment of objects (Green 2001). This concept has been the bête noire of
psychoanalytic theory, rejected by the vast majority of analysts, British or
otherwise, with the notorious exception of the Kleinians, who, however,
conflate the death drive with an urge to destruction, which Mitchell does
not. She writes, “The death drive is a ‘drive’ precisely, because it drives
an organism into a state of inanimacy, or inertia, to stasis or even literally
death” (Mitchell, 2000b, 140). The role this concept plays in her analysis
of hysteria is discrete, but fundamental. We find that hysteria has been
abandoned by psychiatry and partly neglected by psychoanalysis, due to
the advent of the so-called personality disorders. What was considered to
be hysteria has been largely absorbed into the categories of the histrionic
and the borderline personality disorder. This development was facilitated
by a view of hysteria, in which it is considered to be a relatively benign
condition and therefore of lesser relevance. Using the concept of the
death drive, or having it as a background, allowed Mitchell to emphasize
the repetition compulsion (2000a, 136–7, 146–7), states of emptiness
(ibid. 203–232), and feelings of annihilation (ibid. p. 298–315) in this
condition. Thereby she alerted us to the severity of hysteria and argued
against it vanishing into other categories. Insisting on hysteria also
enabled Mitchell to emphasize another concept that has been brushed
aside by the triumph of the personality disorders: the unconscious.
The Fantasy
A Child is Being Beaten is Freud’s most sustained analysis of a sadomas-
ochistic fantasy, which is found very frequently in both women and men.
140 DARU HUPPERT
Phases
Freud stipulates that the fantasy undergoes three transformations or
developments, before it is experienced in the manner confessed to dur-
ing analysis. Of the first phase, which occurs in infancy, he writes, “The
child being beaten is never the one producing the phantasy, but is invari-
ably another child, most often a brother or a sister if there is any” (Freud
1919e, 183). Freud wavers whether to call this a fantasy or a recollection;
he is tempted to call it sadistic, but he cautions us to note that it is not
the child who does the beating. In each case, analysis reveals that it is the
father who performs this act. So the first phase of the fantasy could be
stated as: “My father is beating the child” (Freud 1919e, 185). We are led
to understand what motivates this scene, if we add that the child being
beaten is a hated child. The scene can be rendered as: “My father is beat-
ing the child whom I hate.” In the second phase the person who is doing
the beating is still the father, but the child being beaten has changed: it
is now the fantasist herself. The corresponding sentence would be: “I am
being beaten by my father.” The fantasy is now unmistakably masochistic.
For Freud this second stage is the core of the beating scenarios, it is
the scene that elicits the greatest pleasure, yet it is irretrievable to con-
sciousness, even in psychoanalytic treatment. This scene is what he calls
a “construction,” that is, a necessary assumption. We find that the third
phase, which is the one confessed to during psychoanalytic treatment, is
again nearer to the first. In it the person beating is not the father, but
F R EU D, M I T C H E L L , A N D T H E F R EU D I A N P R O J E C T 141
Transformations
Let us now look in greater at detail the three transformations that the
fantasy undergoes. As Freud (1919e, 187) notes, the mother is not the
only rival of the child in regard to the Oedipal love of the father; sib-
lings must also be contended with and they are hated with the “wild
energy characteristic of the emotional life of those years.” If the sibling
is younger, it is despised as well hated, yet it nevertheless attracts a share
of the affection from the parents. In this context the beating signifies a
“deprivation of love and a humiliation” (ibid) and it means, “My father
does not love this other child, he loves only me.” The term “love” here is
meant genitally, that is, it expresses an incestuous fantasy. However, this
fantasy succumbs to repression, in the wake of which arises a sense of
guilt. For Freud the second phase of the fantasy, in which the fantasist
is being beaten, is a direct expression of the girl’s guilt (the beating act-
ing as punishment). But guilt alone cannot explain the masochistic, that
is, the sexual character of the second phase. He notes that the genital
impulse of the first phase not only suffers repression, it also undergoes
regression to an anal sadistic stage. That is why the beating expresses a
distorted version of a coital fantasy. As Freud (ibid, 189) summarizes,
“This being beaten is now a convergence of the sense of guilt and sexual
love. It is not only the punishment for the forbidden genital relation, but
also the regressive substitute for that relation . . . ” The third phase of the
fantasy primarily serves to substitute the second, deeply repressed phase.
Now the child appears as spectator and is represented by the several chil-
dren, while the father takes shape as a teacher or some authority figure.
The fantasy has become sadistic and can once again be rendered by the
sentence: “My father is beating the child, he loves only me.” Yet the stress
is now only on the first part of the sentence, while the latter part has
undergone repression (Freud ibid, 190).
Before turning to Mitchell’s work, I would like to underline the den-
sity of Freud’s psychological analysis. He not only describes the trans-
formation that the beating fantasy undergoes, but also specifies the
mechanisms by which these changes are accomplished. This ability to
explain the minutiae of psychic life is one of the characteristics of Freud’s
thinking; his penetration of detail remains a measure for any attempt
to develop or even to transform his thought. Psychoanalytic insight is
always an insight into a particular constellation.
142 DARU HUPPERT
Conclusion
During the course of this chapter Mitchell’s version of the Freudian
project has, to an extent, taken on shape, as have some of the general
features entailed by this project. What is distinctive about Mitchell’s
144 DARU HUPPERT
work is the degree to which she has been able to translate the powerful
effect that the Freudian writings have had and continue to have on her
onto the areas in which she engages. Her allegiance to Freud’s concepts
comes with a sense of common concerns and has honed a shared sensi-
bility. At the level of procedure we have seen that the Freudian project
compels us to show our ideas in the minutiae of psychic life. While
Mitchell’s sibling theory requires more detailed working out, it promises
to become deeply important to psychoanalysis. This importance is due,
not least, to her taking the Oedipus complex as the model for what she
seeks to achieve with siblings, a challenge that is formidable and that,
more generally, gives us a sense of the challenge that Freud’s work repre-
sents to anyone thoroughly engaged with him. I began this chapter, by
saying that Mitchell is considered to belong to the Independent School
of Psychoanalysis, but it may be more apt to call her an independent
Freudian—insofar as anyone can be a Freudian and not simply strive to
become one.
Notes
1. See Freud’s (1905d) development of this issue.
2. Mitchell’s chapter dedicated to the fantasy touches on an extraordinary
array of issues—ranging from Madame Bovary, to war and gender—
which I cannot touch on here.
3. Repression should be understood as acting within a particular con-
text, so that a theme, which may be conscious in one context, such
as the relationship of mutual obliteration between siblings, may be
unconscious in another context, such as the beating fantasy.
References
Bion, W. R. 1984. Attention and Interpretation. London: Karnak Books.
Ferro, A. 1999. The Bi-Personal Field. Routledge: London.
Freud, S. 1905d. “Three Essays on a Theory of Sexuality.” In The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud Vol. 7, trans-
lated by James Strachey. Hogarth Press, London, S.E. 7.
Freud, S. 1909d. “Notes Upon A Case of Obsessional Neurosis.” S.E. 10.
Freud, S. 1915e. “The Unconscious.” S.E. 14.
Freud, S. 1918a. “The Taboo on Virginity.” S.E. 11.
Freud, S. 1919e. “A Child is Being Beaten.” S.E. 17.
Freud, S. 1920g. “Beyond the Pleasure Principle.” S.E. 18.
Freud, S. 1924d. “The Dissolution of the Oedipus Complex.” S.E. 19.
Freud, S. 1926e. “The Question of Lay Analysis.” S.E. 20.
Glover, E. 1947. Basic Mental Concepts—Their Clinical and Theoretical
Value. Psychoanalytic Quarterly 16, 482–506.
Green, A. 2000. Chains of Eros. London: Karnack.
Green, A. 2001. Life Narcissism and Death Narcissism. London: Karnak.
F R EU D, M I T C H E L L , A N D T H E F R EU D I A N P R O J E C T 145
L ike many others, I (Verhaeghe) discovered Juliet Mitchell via her first
book, Psychoanalysis and Feminism (1974). The way she extended psy-
choanalysis, from the individual to family and society, was an eye-opener
to me. In the two decades that followed, I studied Freud and Lacan, but
just after the new millennium, Anglo-Saxon psychoanalysis was brought
back again under my attention when I attended Juliet Mitchell’s lecture
on siblings in New York, and later, in Vienna, her lecture on gender.
I read Mad Men and Medusas and Siblings, which reminded me of the
necessity to place psychoanalysis in a much broader framework than only
a family frame, and to assign psychoanalysis an explicit political and social
dimension (Verhaeghe, 2014a).
In this chapter we will discuss two interconnected subjects, which
we perceive as the core themes of Juliet’s books: hysteria in relation to
gender, and siblings in relation to contemporary politics. It is not the
intention of this chapter to provide the reader with an exposition of or a
detailed comment on Mitchell’s theory—other chapters in this volume
do this work, and in any case the reader is best informed by study-
ing her books. It is our intention here to present a Freudian–Lacanian
perspective, as we have developed in the Department of Psychoanalysis
in Ghent (www.psychoanalysis.ugent.be). Juliet Mitchell’s theory and
our Freudian–Lacanian framework are not the same. Lacanian psy-
choanalysis is more structural than the empirical clinical approach of
Anglo-Saxon psychoanalysis. Yet our work and Mitchell’s share the
same extension beyond previous psychoanalytic theory, as they take
into account the importance of the Other: siblings, society, and the
symbolic order.
148 PAU L V E R H A E G H E A N D E L I N E T R E N S O N
demonstrate the validity and the usefulness of his new method. He had
already a title for the book: Dreams and Hysteria. But he had to change
it into the more modest Bruchstück einer Hysterie-Analyse (Fragment of
an Analysis of a Case of Hysteria). The case study shows that he had
every reason to be modest. Dora’s dreams are big question marks, as is
literally mentioned in one of her dreams: “She asked about a hundred
times.” These questions concern her female identity, her sexuality, and
the position assigned to her by the desire of a man (Freud, 1905e, p. 94).
Instead of taking her question seriously, Freud steps into the shoes of the
Oedipal master and produces knowledge. He explains her dreams and
in the same movement, he tells her how she has to behave as a member
of her sex. Instead of accepting his masterly explanations, she stops the
treatment, after having made it clear that his explanations do not mean
that much to her: “Why, has anything so very remarkable come out?”
(Freud, 1905e, 105).
A contemporary version of Théroigne de Mericourt is Pussy Riot, that
is, the women who provoked superphallic master Putin and as a result
were convicted to three years of Siberian gulag.3 What is less well known
is that the judge declared them insane as well. In the verdict, they are
diagnosed as suffering from a mixed-personality disorder, that is: “a con-
dition that includes different combinations of a proactive approach to life,
a drive for self-fulfilment, stubbornly defending their opinion, inflated
self-esteem, inclination to oppositional behaviour, and propensity for
protest reactions.”4 The message is clear: women who dare to challenge
masculine power are insane, and the hysterical subject that challenges the
phallic master has to pay the price.
The examples illustrate how an analogous structure works within, at
first sight, quite different power relations: revolutionary, therapeutic, and
political. Traditionally, this structure is simplified to a man–woman rela-
tion, in terms of sexual repression and resistance. In our opinion, this
simplification has a defensive function, because a more fundamental dis-
cord of human nature is ignored. Lacan mentions this internal discord in
his seminal paper on the mirror stage (1966, p. 96) and explains it later
as the result of a primordial loss at the time of birth (1966, pp. 845–46).
This marks the human being with a fundamental lack and a resulting
desire to regain a lost plenitude. From early days onward, the responsibil-
ity both for the lack and the answer to it are projected on the other. This
is Freud’s reading of the Oedipus complex: the father has the penis, and
he has to give it to me.
Lacan points to the radical nature of the loss and the impossibility
to regain the original plenitude. This is structurally impossible because
the subject tries to regain what is lost via the Symbolic order. As it is
H Y S T E R I A B E T W E E N B I G B R O T H E R A N D PAT R I A R C H Y 153
precisely the introduction into the Symbolic order that caused the loss,
desire is eternal. The lack felt by the subject is the lack of the Symbolic,
and hence, also a lack in knowledge and control. Based on Mitchell, we
can say that the patriarchal processing of the original loss turns it into
a much-discussed sexual lack for women (the phallus) and a neglected
maternal lack for men (the womb). The result is a power play between
men and women. Somebody must be blamed for the lack; somebody
must have the Phallus. In this way, positions are distributed: the know-
ingly, almighty master, and his (or her) antithesis, the demanding other,
with in between them the phallic signifier. The political world and gen-
der relations are two fields illustrating the externalization of the origi-
nally internal discord.
Consider also the Enlightenment. At first sight, this period brings
light into darkness and frees us from the dominance of religion. During
the reign of religious discourse, male priests were the seat of knowledge.
Women were considered to be the source of all evil, starting with Eve.
Did the Enlightenment change this view? The weight on the spiritual
was replaced by a weight on rationality. Psychiatric patients were con-
sidered as suffering from déraison, lack of reason (Foucault, 1972). The
prohibition on the body was replaced by a prohibition on passion. It does
not take much insight to recognize the same equation: rationality stands
for masculinity, passion for femininity. Théroigne de Méricourt was not
sinful, she was passionate and hence, mad. Today, this division between
rationality and passion sounds obsolete. In the Western world, religion
has lost much of its established significance and even ideologies have
been declared dead. Does this mean that the underlying power struc-
ture has disappeared? Closer scrutiny unmasks the contemporary priests:
they are the new (pseudo)scientists, promising total knowledge, based on
cognitive brain studies. Their belief is that we are just one step away from
total knowledge, the Grand Theory of Everything, thus becoming the
(phallic) masters of the universe, in control of everything and everyone.
One of the advantages of this theory is that it does not start from gender,
reifying hysteria as a feminine tendency and ignoring phenomena that
speak of male hysteria. Another advantage is that it shows the interdepen-
dence of the hysteric and the master (Verhaeghe, 1999).5
Briefly summarized (see Figure 7.2), hysterical discourse stages the
hysterical divided subject (noted as $) in the position of the agent, driven
by its own truth (noted as object a). This truth is simple: every human
being is marked by an ontological lack, based on a loss at birth; ever
since, we are divided and looking for an answer. This is what drives us
beyond knowledge (in matters of gender, life and death drives, there
are no final answers). In order to get reassurance, the hysterical subject
addresses the other as a master (noted as S1, the master signifier), oblig-
ing him to produce knowledge (noted as S2, the reunion of all signifi-
ers). But this knowledge can never bridge (//) the gap toward the truth
(Lacan, 1991).
The other formula shows us the discourse of the master (see Figure 7.3).
The master figure (noted as S1), sitting on top of his own division (noted
as $), projects his knowledge (noted as S2) on the other. The hoped-for
result, that is, the other is satisfied and everything is under control, is
not attained. On the contrary, the product of this discourse is precisely
a renewed confrontation with the remainders, that is, what cannot be
grasped by knowledge (noted as a) (Lacan, 1991).
The confrontation between the hysterical discourse and the discourse
of the master leads inevitably to a spiral that endorses both parties in
their respective positions. The hysterical subject is looking for answers,
and provokes the master figure to demonstrate his power. The mas-
ter tries to reassure the hysterical subject with his knowledge but soon
enough, he will have to face his own failure. Whatever the quality of
this knowledge, it can never adequately tell the truth about what drives
the human subject. On the contrary, this knowledge is based on the
Symbolic and denies its inherent lack, formulated by Lacan as symbolic
castration. Acknowledging this castration would imply acknowledging
le pas-tout, the not-All, and the failure of the master. Most masters are
not willing to accept this failure. Often enough, the result is a violent
reaction against the one, the hysterical subject, who threatens to expose
their failure, their castration. This violence is then enacted in religious,
political, or scientific-therapeutic terms. That is, in terms of their par-
ticular knowledge (S2). The other is characterized as sinful, dangerous,
or disturbed.
A well-known feminist slogan tells us that the personal is the politi-
cal. The internal discord mentioned above is present in every one of us,
meaning that every one of us is marked by an original loss and divided
H Y S T E R I A B E T W E E N B I G B R O T H E R A N D PAT R I A R C H Y 155
between body and soul, between drive and mastery, between passion
and rationality. This is the personal part. Every one of us tries to come
to terms with this division. Education provides us a conventional way to
handle this division. It provides us with the conventional answers. Here
we find the Freudian Oedipus complex: the law of the father assigns
boys and girls their “legitimate” places, phallic versus castrated. Now,
the political part comes in view. Normally, says Freud, when we grow
up, this complex should be destroyed, but this is never fully the case (see
Verhaeghe, 2009). Religion, ideology, politics, and even science provide
the different stages where this structural imbalance is continued.
And each time, the hysteric identifies with these answers, thus taking
another color, namely the color of the new master. So, a religious stage
with religious masters produces religious hysteria. A medical stage with
medical masters produces medical hysteria. A political stage with politi-
cal masters produces political hysteria. On every stage, the interaction
ends inevitably with an exposure of the master’s failure. When Charcot’s
patients produced his hysterical attacks, they followed his suggestions,
and hence, his desire. But in following them, they proved at the same
time the failure of his medical approach. Obviously, the psychoanalytic
scene is not free from this structure. For Lacan (2004) acting out is an
appeal addressed to the Other and every hysterical symptom is a demand
for interpretation, that is, a demand for a final answer. If an analyst
believes that his answers are correct and absolute, he will share Freud’s
fate with respect to Dora. His interpretations will be refuted and refused.
In that respect, a traditional analyst is not that different from Charcot as
he might imagine.
This leads us to an important issue. It is said by conventional psy-
chiatry that hysteria has disappeared. Contemporary psychiatry focuses
on personality disorders, with the patient diagnosed with a “borderline
personality disorder” on top of the list. The clinical examples in Juliet
Mitchell’s recent books do not look like the classic hysterical patients.
Why should they? The stage has changed, so must have hysteria. With
a slight exaggeration we can state that the well-behaved hysteric of the
late nineteenth century, who, due to an unresolved Oedipal problem
fantasizes about forbidden sexual acts and who out of sheer feelings of
guilt develops phobic or conversion symptoms within a largely imaginary
mental world, is threatened by extinction. Today we are dealing with
a promiscuous, aggressive, and/or self-mutilating “borderline” patient
with a complex traumatic history, who may nourish an addiction and/or
an eating disorders. What social changes have elicited this symptomatol-
ogy? A Belgian psychiatrist applied the DSM IV-R criteria for borderline
personality disorder to our contemporary society. His conclusion is that
the borderline personality has become the norm, not the exception (De
Wachter, 2012). To be sure: “borderline personality disorder” is not a
Lacanian category. In our opinion, and building from Mitchell’s (2003,
pp. 20–21) account of the relationship between hysteria and borderline
personality, we perceive the latter condition as the actual pathological
position of hysteria, reformed as a response to the contemporary situation
(Verhaeghe, 2014b). No less than their nineteenth-century forebears,
the contemporary hysterical subject is based on a common identifica-
tion with the desire of the contemporary Other. But whose desire are
they identifying with? Who is the master of the contemporary hysterical
H Y S T E R I A B E T W E E N B I G B R O T H E R A N D PAT R I A R C H Y 157
subject? And what is their stage? The answers to these questions lead us
to the political field and to an unexpected extension of Juliet Mitchell’s
theory on siblings.
Depressive Hedonia
Both the neurotic and the perverse society create their own myth in
order to cover up the underlying truth about the lack in the symbolic
order. The neurotic society burdens us with the myth of the perfect
couple and eternal love: find the right (phallic) partner, and you will
be happy forever. The underlying truth is that the perfect partner turns
out to be castrated. The net result is feelings of guilt (“I don’t have the
phallus”) or disappointment (“S/he did not have the phallus, after all”).
The contemporary myth tells us that if we buy the right stuff, do the
right exercises, and work hard enough, we will have a perfect enjoyment.
“Happiness is a choice.” The underlying and disavowed truth is that total
jouissance is impossible. The new myth has a very important side effect
as it is based on the illusion of voluntarism. Everything is stripped down
to a matter of decision and personal effort. This implies that if you do
not take that decision, and do not work hard enough, it is your mistake
and your fault. As a result, Victorian guilt and neurosis are replaced by
postmodern shame and depression: if we do not enjoy, we are losers who
have failed our duty.
This idea of voluntarism is indicative for a new belief, namely total
controllability and manageability, based on our personal effort. As there
is no castration and even no lack, every one of us can and must have a
perfect body, a perfect relationship, perfect sex, perfect children, and
stay young forever. If that is not the case, the sole explanations are that
you did not put enough effort in it or made the wrong choices. Juli
Zeh has depicted this world in her novel Corpus delicti, where, what
she describes as The Method, obliges every one of us to be perfectly
healthy. This reminds me of the perverse command by Marquis de Sade
160 PAU L V E R H A E G H E A N D E L I N E T R E N S O N
The obligatory identification with the mirror stage other has seri-
ous effects on the relationship between subject, gender, and author-
ity. Patriarchal society installed a phallic gender differentiation, with
clear-cut gender roles, together with a clear differentiation between
the generations, children versus parents. The perverse society does not
acknowledge the lack and disavows castration; therefore the traditional
gender differentiation becomes blurred. It is our contention that the
contemporary man is quite feminine by Victorian standards, the con-
temporary woman might be quite masculine against the same criteria,
and possibility of a transgender subject illustrates the interstitial spaces
opened by the decline of gender differentiation through repression. At
the same time, the perverse society does not acknowledge the law of the
father; therefore the differentiation between the generations becomes
blurred as well. Mother and daughter are presented as two sisters, and
fathers are competing with their sons, especially as the father has lost his
position of authority. Big Brother has replaced the authoritarian father of
the Victorian era. His most prominent characteristic, besides the fact that
he is watching all the time, is that he is an anonymous peer. It is impos-
sible to get hold of this ghost, which means that it is impossible to knock
him off his pedestal and kill him.
“Big Brother is watching you” might very well become the iconic
formula of our times. George Orwell would be amazed to see how his
expression fits more and more a paradoxical reality. The paradox resides
in the fact that our reality needs endorsement from the virtual world via
the Internet and the social media. The fact that we are dealing with a
virtual world does not make it less real, on the contrary. Life is increas-
ingly experienced as one big reality show where something is only real on
condition that it appears on the screen and is “liked” by others; if not, it
does not exist. As a result, the world is increasingly experienced as one
big stage with an omnipresent, anonymous, and watchful eye, covering
the scene nonstop. Our body has to be perfect, our smile has to be genu-
ine, and our enjoyment has to be total.7
The disavowal of lack leads to a divergence between the texture of
our everyday lives and the conviction that everything is under control
and perfectly manageable. If not, it must be that some individual made a
mistake, because there is no structural lack; someone has to be blamed.
Many documentaries on science suggest that total knowledge is almost
there. In the meantime, this conviction has taken hilarious and painful
proportions. If the weather forecast is wrong, the weatherman has to
apologize. A painful example is the conviction of six Italian scientists,
because they failed to predict the 2009 earthquake in L’Aquila. Here as
well, failure has become a question of personal responsibility.
162 PAU L V E R H A E G H E A N D E L I N E T R E N S O N
W][dj ej^[h
jhkj^ fheZkYj
Figure 7.1
H Y S T E R I A B E T W E E N B I G B R O T H E R A N D PAT R I A R C H Y 165
I% I'
a %% I(
Figure 7.2
I' I(
I% %% a
Explanation of symbols:
I' cWij[hi_]d_\_[h
I( ademb[Z][
j^[[l[hZ_l_Z[ZikX`[Yj
W j^Wjm^Wj[iYWf[i[l[ho\ehce\iocXeb_iWj_ed
Figure 7.3
Notes
1. Jouissance is one of Lacan’s most notoriously difficult concepts, espe-
cially as it evolved during the development of his theory. It indicates the
limit between a pleasure arising from the drive that can be controlled
and one that cannot, thus threatening the subject with death. It is
Lacan’s understanding of Freud’s death drive (see Verhaeghe, 2009).
2. Indeed, the symbolic order requires a threefold structure, otherwise it
is impossible to introduce difference. To give you an idea: indicating
the left- and right-hand side of a room (two elements) requires a third
element (in most cases: our own position), otherwise differentiation is
impossible.
3. See http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Pussy_Riot.
4. See The New Yorker: http://www.newyorker.com/online/blogs
/newsdesk/2012/08/the-pussy-riot-verdict.html.
5. For a didactic explanation of Lacan’s discourse theory, see Verhaeghe,
P. (1995). Papers by the authors can be downloaded from http://
www.psychoanalysis.ugent.be.
6. The Lacanian structural reading of psychosis is different from the
Anglo-Saxon perspective (see Vanheule, 2011).
7. The circle, as described by Dave Eggers (2013), is more real than we
imagine.
8. Extract from the Carnal art manifesto. See http://orlan.eu/adriensina
/manifeste/carnal.html.
References
Allegaert, P. and Brokken, Ann. eds., 2012. Nerveuze vrouwen. Twee eeuwen
vrouwen en hun psychiaters. (Trans.: Two Centuries of Women and Their
Psychiatrists). Museum Dr. Guislain, Gent: Lannoo.
Bauman, Z. and Lyon, D. 2013. Liquid Surveillance. Cambridge: Polity Press.
166 PAU L V E R H A E G H E A N D E L I N E T R E N S O N
were destroyed. However, the first four months of case notes on the Rat
Man were found among Freud’s papers in London upon his death.
Freud publicly presented the Lanzer case no less than five times to the
Vienna Psychoanalytic Society between October 30, 1907, and April 8,
1908, and also as the opening five-hour presentation at the first Congress
of the International Psychoanalytic Association on April 27, 1908 (Jones
1955, II, 49). Given that Freud was able to report that “the patient’s
mental health was restored to him by the analysis,” this repetition appears
to have been both a mark of confidence in the capacity of the case to
illustrate obsessional neurosis and its analysis ([1909a] 2001, 249). Since
Lanzer had previously been treated without effect by the renowned psy-
chiatrist Wagner-Jauregg, Freud’s success appeared all the more remark-
able. As Beigler (1975, 276) describes, Freud was here “fashioning a cure
for the previously incurable. To have had so brilliant a result with so dif-
ficult a patient in only eleven months was no small achievement.” Perhaps,
however, the repetition in Freud’s presentation of the case together with
the survival of the case notes can also be thought of as the marks of some-
thing left troublingly unresolved and unbound. Describing his feelings
during the composition of the published text in a letter to Jung, Freud
wrote: “It just pours out of me, and even so it’s inadequate” ([1909b]
1979, 116). Even many years later, Freud would suggest that “obsessional
neurosis is unquestionably the most interesting and repaying subject of
analytic research. But as a problem it has not yet been mastered” ([1926]
2001, 113). Anna Freud (1966, 116) reports a remark from her father
that, in the study of obsessional neurosis, perhaps “a group of people may
succeed where the single individual fails.” Turning this remark at a right-
angle, this chapter will explore the possibility that it is precisely attention
to group—lateral—process which can help further advance our under-
standing of the Rat Man case and of obsessional phenomena.
Unlike the Wolf Man case study in which siblings appear clearly in the
manifest content of the published text and therefore have been the sub-
ject of ongoing discussion (e.g., Oliver 2009), the latent status of Freud’s
thoughts on the Rat Man’s sibling relationships has meant that their sig-
nificance has been little discussed. Indeed, it has not been uncommon for
commentators on the case to offer specific repudiations that the sibling
relationships have significance; perhaps the most stark is Veszy-Wagner
(1967, 602), who states that “Rat Man had three sisters who, besides
possible sexual games in childhood, later played no role.” In reframing
the “Notes upon a Case of Obsessional Neurosis,” the chapter will shed
new light on the significance of siblings to the Rat Man case study, and
through this lay the groundwork for future reflections on the role of the
lateral axis in obsessional neurosis.
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 171
for his mother, even though there has not yet been any direct reference
to this in the analytic material.” Freud replied that “Rank will prob-
ably prove to be right in his assumption that incestuous wishes for the
mother play a role, though the relationship is complicated by the presence
of four sisters” (Nunberg and Federn [1908] 1962: 1, 233). This is an
extraordinary statement: Freud is explaining that his focus on the uncon-
scious hatred of the father in the Rat Man case study is caused by the
fact that too much sibling material obscured his view of the mother! In
the published case study, perhaps responding to Rank’s concern, Freud
justified his focus on the father in the published case study on the basis
that “the theme of the rats has lacked any element directed towards his
mother, evidently because there is very strong resistance in relation to
her” ([1909a] 2001, 293).
Examining the case notes, it does indeed seem to be true that the
figure of the mother is overshadowed by the extensive notes on Lanzer’s
sibling relationships. However, this has not stopped later analysts con-
testing Freud’s account of the case, and arguing—in line with a broader
rise in attention to the mother in psychoanalytic theory in the gen-
eration after Freud—for the significance of the patient’s mother in this
paradigmatic case of obsessional neurosis (Künstlicher 1998; Mahoney
2007). Offering a good example of how attention beyond the father can
help sharpen our understanding of the case, Bass has astutely observed
that Freud’s focus on the father means that he does not consider the psy-
chical meaning of the young lady at the post office. Lanzer incurs a real
debt for the glasses to this woman, and which his obsession with paying
Lieutenant A meant that he was set to exploit her by not reimbursing
her payment.
Arguments for the missed importance of the mother have often drawn
upon a comparison of the published case with the unpublished notes
for deepening our understanding of the Lanzer case, and through it of
obsessional neurosis. For example, commenting on Lanzer’s first analytic
session with Freud, Crockatt (2013) has observed that “Freud published
his initial consultation almost verbatim with one significant omission:
‘After I had told him my terms, he said he must consult his mother.’
The patient, it will be recalled, was 29 years old at that time.” From this
analysis Crockatt is able to deftly draw out the significance of themes of
differentiation and undifferentiation in Lanzer’s symptoms: the issue of
merger or submergence into the mother is managed in part through the
way in which Lanzer dealt with and agonised over money. This conclu-
sion agrees with that of Verhaeghe (2001, 161), who argues that “in
the case of obsessional neurosis, the underlying anxiety is much greater
than in the case of hysteria. Traditionally, Freud ascribes this anxiety to
174 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
the father figure, thus making his traditional mistake . . . the fear of the
obsessional concerns the first Other, the mother, whose demanding is
interpreted as an attempt to incorporate the subject.” The December
analytical sessions in the case notes particularly address this threat of
incorporation, framed as a need to avoid relationship with the mother
in order to avoid contamination. “His mother suffered from an abdomi-
nal affection and now has a bad smell from her genitals, which makes
him very angry. She herself says that she stinks unless she has frequent
baths, but that she cannot afford it, and this appals him” ([1909] 2001,
296). Both to escape from the need to engage in a permeable relationship
with his mother and as a reaction formation against his disgust, Lanzer
“hands over all his money to his mother because he does not want to
have anything from her” ([1909a] 2001, 297). Transposed onto an anal
register, the prohibition on desire for the mother becomes disgust for her
genitals and for monetary interaction with her.
Lanzer’s Siblings
In line with such reflections, Freud observes that the patient’s “sexual
desires for his mother and sister and his sister’s premature death were
linked up with the young hero’s chastisement at his father’s hand”
([1909a] 2001, 207). He goes on to clarify that “the death of an elder
sister, which took place when he was between three and four years old,
played a great part in his phantasies, and was brought into intimate
connection with his childish misdemeanours during the same period”
([1909] 2001, 235). However, this “great part” and “intimate connec-
tion” are left unexplored. Besides these remarks, in the rest of Freud’s
published case ambivalence toward the father is shorn of its “link up”
with siblings, and ambivalence toward the father is examined alone as the
central etiological factor in the obsessional neurosis.
Attention to the significance of Lanzer’s mother in Freud’s notes on
the case has also led commentators at points to note the importance
of the patient’s siblings to his history and development. Much of this
analysis, while helpful and perceptive (e.g., Mahoney 1986), has attended
to siblings within a frame that privileges their significance primarily in
terms of the meanings for Lanzer of his mother’s reproductive capabili-
ties. However, two texts stand out as presenting sustained attention to
sibling dynamics in the case notes. One is Billig (1999), who draws atten-
tion to a passage in the case notes which begins: “He is cheerful, untram-
melled and active, and is behaving aggressively to a girl, a dressmaker”
([1909a] 2001, 278). Billig states that “behaving aggressively” means to
sexually pursue, and proposes that this is supported by the fact that the
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 175
Billig draws attention to the fact that Freud here associates Lanzer’s
“pathological changes” with his possible incest with his sister. He reads
Freud’s indefinite description as an obfuscation of definite sibling incest.
“Consequently,” Billig (1999, 152) concludes, “readers of the case history
are not informed that changes in Lorenz’s condition may be connected
with such incest.” In support for his contention, Billig notes Lanzer’s
remark to Julie’s husband that: “If Julie has a baby in 9 months’ time,
you needn’t think I am its father; I am innocent” ([1909a] 2001, 314).
He also compares the case notes with the published version of the fifth
analytic session, observing that they are identical besides the last few
lines: Freud expunged his patient’s statement that his compulsions were
figured by a sense of guilt for memories of having already committed the
most despicable deed.
In contrast to Billig’s perspective stands Zetzel’s 1965 International
Psycho-analytical Congress paper. Since it was Zetzel who first intro-
duced the equalizing concept of “therapeutic alliance” between analyst
and patient into the psychoanalytic lexicon, it is perhaps unsurprising that
she would be an exception to the neglect of Freud’s quite extensive remarks
on lateral dynamics in the Rat Man case notes.1 Zetzel’s analysis, when
considered carefully, can stand as a useful corrective to Billig’s insight-
ful but limited account of the sibling material. Zetzel (1966, 125) uses
the evidence of the case notes to observe that an important scene in
which Lanzer flew into a rage with his father coincided with the death
of his sister: “His famous—but not subjectively remembered—outburst
of rage almost certainly occurred during the course of Katherine’s fatal
176 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
illness. In this affective storm the little boy attacked his father.” This
is the only time, Lanzer states, he was beaten by his father. Whereas
the overall arc of Freud’s interpretation had situated Lanzer’s rage with
his father as an effect of a perceived threat of death if he continued to
masturbate and retain Oedipal aspirations, Zetzel emphasizes that the
threat of castration would have been indelibly marked and sharpened the
trauma of his sister’s passing. This ambivalence and confusion regarding
the meaning of his sister’s death in the context of his father’s prohibition
would have predisposed him to the obsessive symptoms which began
from his father’s death, and intensified on the death of his aunt (his
father’s sister).
Zetzel hypothesizes that the traumas of the castration complex and
the sister’s death became confused for the patient. Whereas most inter-
pretations of the “opposition between the two objects of his love, his
father and the ‘lady’ ” ([1909a], 179) following Freud have viewed this
as reflecting Lanzer’s castration complex, Zetzel’s interpretation refines
and redefines this account. Love/hate would not only be tied to sexuality/
prohibition, but also to life/death and vertical/lateral. In support of
Zetzel’s reading of the case notes, there is a footnote to the published
case in which Freud states that “his sexual desires for his mother and sis-
ter and his sister’s premature death were linked up with the young hero’s
chastisement at his father’s hand” ([1909a] 2001, 207). Freud also states
that “I traced a connection with death from his having been threatened
with death at a prehistoric period if he touched himself and brought
about an erection of his penis, and suggested that he attributed his sister’s
death to masturbating” ([1909a] 2001, 309). In further support for the
way that the meanings of sex, sisters, and death are woven together in the
Lanzer household, it can be noted that the patient’s parents had children
every two years until Katherine’s death in 1881—and then it is nearly five
years before Julie was born in 1886 (Mahoney 1986, 65).
Zetzel’s reflections suggest that Lanzer’s unconscious reproach toward
the father would have included and been sustained by an irreducibly sib-
ling component. This component would also have played a determinative
role in his love-interest in his cousin:
fact that this cousin who was herself highly ambivalent may also have
been abused by her stepfather, and was at least as disturbed in respect
of her psychosexual life as the patient, suggests that her own personal-
ity loaned itself to a relationship characterized by many infantile fea-
tures. There is a wealth of material in the original notes to support
the hypothesis that the Rat Man’s persistent attachment to his ailing
cousin represented an over-determined, necessarily ambivalent effort
to revive his sister as he last recalled her, namely, as an increasingly
tired little girl who was finally carried away to the room in which she
was to die (Zetzel 1966, 126).
toward his younger sister from infantile material, it seems more plausible
to follow Zetzel and interpret Lanzer’s behavior toward Julie as occur-
ring on the horizon of the relation with the dead older sister and of his
castration complex.
To demonstrate the value of this approach, let us take the two symp-
toms that dominate Freud’s recounting of the case: the vow to pay back
the money to the lieutenant, and the fear of rat punishment for his
cousin Gisela and (dead) father if he does not. Freud states that the
patient’s compulsions are the product of “oaths that he has forgotten”
([1909a] 2001: 260). Vows and vowing appear in four places in Freud’s
recounting of the case. One is in the text cited by Billig: because of his
sexual/aggressive acts/wishes toward Julie, Lanzer feels “fear at having
broken his vow to keep away from her.” Billig’s interpretation directs us
to the fact that the money Lanzer vowed to give the lieutenant was actu-
ally owed to the nice lady at the post office. The patient travels all over
Austria trying to pay the lieutenant and not pay the lieutenant, until he
arrives at Freud’s door and receives analysis. Then, calmer, he can simply
post the money owed to the lady. Billig’s interpretation would suggest
that the lady could not be repaid because of the “vow to keep away from
her” originally directed at Julie. However three other vows mentioned
in the text can deepen our understanding of what it means to the patient
when he vows. Besides the repayment vow, and the vow to keep away
from Julie, a third vow in the case material is the formula used by the
patient to forbid himself masturbation: “I swear on my blessed soul to
abandon it.” Lanzer had anxiety that if he broke this vow, and mastur-
bated, then “his father would be bound to die” ([1909a] 2001: 165).
When asked about his formula to prevent masturbation, Lanzer made
an association with the words used by his mother to forbid his seeing
Gisela: “On my soul, you will not go” ([1909] 200,: 262). Given the
word-for-word fit in formulation, it is implausible to see the meaning
of the vow not to approach Julie outside of the repeated vows made by
Lanzer to prohibit himself masturbation, in the context of Oedipal and
castration anxieties.
Yet if “I swear on my soul to abandon it” resonates with his mother’s
words, it also echoes with much earlier words heard by the patient.
Lanzer reports three memories of his elder sister Katherine before she
died. A first memory is a love-vow made by Katherine that “On my soul,
if you die I shall kill myself” ([1909] 2001, 264). A second memory is
of Katherine “being carried to bed” and then, sometime later, of “his
asking ‘Where is Katherine?’ and going into the room and finding his
father sitting in an arm-chair and crying.” In light of Zetzel’s interpre-
tation, the act of vowing can be viewed as invested and complicated by
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 179
confusion and ambivalence over the role of love and of his father in his
sister’s death. Furthermore, Lanzer’s third memory of his older sister
helps make further sense of Lanzer’s vow to repay the lieutenant. The
vow is made because Lanzer feels that if he does not repay the lieuten-
ant then a pot [Topf ] containing starving rats would be placed on the
buttocks of his cousin and (dead) father. This strange fear becomes
rather more explicable in light of Lanzer’s early memory that “he first
noticed the difference between the sexes when he saw his deceased sister
Katherine (five years his senior) sitting on the pot” [Topf ] ([1909] 2001,
276). Indeed, Lanzer himself appears to testify in favor of such an inter-
pretation. He tells Freud that “when his sister asked him what it was that
he liked about his cousin he replied jokingly ‘her behind’ ” ([1909] 2001,
277). Lanzer’s obsessional neurosis can then be regarded as a flight from
a genital sexuality, in which the stakes are reproductive difference and
annihilation, into obsessive thoughts in an anal register. His confusion of
love and hate for his dead sister and father remain unconscious—not only
avoided but forgotten. Yet the conflict between these feelings and those
of his conscious experience in adulthood animate obsessive symptoms
directed toward his beloved cousin, his younger sister Julie, and a wish to
exhibit his penis to the ghost of his dead father.
As well as a metaphor for the ambivalence of Oedipal wishes and anxi-
eties, the rat who threatens to bore with teeth and claws into the anus
of Lanzer’s cousin and (dead) father can also therefore be recognized
as a metonymically displaced signifier for the figure of the younger sib-
ling and of reproductive difference. The patient reported to Freud that
“he used to creep away [verkroch] and hide, filled with terror and indig-
nation, when one of his brothers or sisters was beaten” ([1909] 2001,
206). As Freud ([1897a] 1986,219; [1919] 2001) remarks elsewhere,
there may be pleasure as well as pain in both observing the beating of
a sibling, and in the phantasy that one is receiving pain/love in their
place. Furthermore, the beating of a sibling in the Lanzer household
appears to have been a moment when their genitals were visible. Fear and
indignation toward pain and sadomasochistic pleasure, precisely in the
link-up between the castration and sibling complexes, reappears in the
threat of the rat punishment to his father and cousin. The threat of “rats
creeping into [Hineinkriechen] the rectum” is interpreted by Freud as a
reversal of the theme of creeping out from, which he suggests symbolizes
a wish “that men can have babies just as well as women” ([1909a] 2001,
220). Mitchell (2003) identifies that the wish to have a child through
anal childbirth represents a foreclosure of reproductive difference. For
the hysteric, this fantasy emerges because reproductive difference repre-
sents the threat of a displaced self. By contrast, for Lanzer, reproductive
180 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
The patient had a charming little niece of whom he was very fond.
One day this idea came into his head: “If you indulge in intercourse,
something will happen to Ella” (i.e. she will die). When the omissions
have been made good, we have: “Every time you copulate, even with a
stranger, you will not be able to avoid the reflection that in your mar-
ried life sexual intercourse can never bring you a child (on account of
the lady’s sterility). This will grieve you so much that you will become
envious of your sister on account of little Ella, and you will grudge
her the child. These envious impulses will inevitably lead to the child’s
death” ([1909] 2001, 226–7).
He dreamt that he went to the dentist to have a bad tooth pulled out.
He pulled one out, but it was not the right one, but the one next to it
which only had something slightly wrong with it. When it came out he
was astonished by its size.
He had a carious tooth; it did not ache, however, but was only
slightly tender, sometimes. He went to the dentist once to have it
filled. The dentist, however, said there was nothing to be done except
to extract it. He was not usually a coward, but he was kept back by the
idea that somehow or other his pain would damage his cousin, and he
refused to have it done ([1909a] 2001, 315).
Freud tells Lanzer confidently that these dreams are about castration,
and that the big tooth is his father’s penis, which he wants to cut off in
retaliation for prohibiting his incestuous desires. However in the process
notes he expresses concern and confusion: “what could be the meaning
of its not having been the right tooth?” ([1909a] 2001, 316). Lanzer’s
own interpretation of the dreams is significant: they are about the death
of a relative. It might be wondered whether the incorrect excision of the
big tooth in the series of teeth might relate to a wish/fear that death/
the father had extracted him from the series of siblings and put him into
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 181
the deathbed, rather than his sister who only had something slightly
wrong with her (castration), which should not warrant death. The pain of
a further extraction in the second dream would hurt his cousin because,
as Freud later realized and added as a footnote to The Interpretation of
Dreams, the extraction of a tooth does not simply represent castration
but also childbirth since “in both cases (castration and birth) what is in
question is the separation of a part of the body from the whole” ([1900]
2001, 387–8). In Lanzer’s mind, his sexual desire is firmly bound up
with the threat of pain to those he loves: the danger of castration posed
by masturbation from the father becomes the same thought as the threat
to his sister if he desires her.
Freud’s/Lanzer’s Siblings
Much of the preceding analysis merely fleshes out, using material from
the case notes, Freud’s terse remark that the patient’s “sexual desires for
his mother and sister and his sister’s premature death were linked up with
the young hero’s chastisement at his father’s hand” ([1909a] 2001, 207).
Why were siblings left to the side in the published case, producing such
disparity between the detailed material on the importance of Lanzer’s
siblings for his symptoms in the unpublished notes, and their relegation to
minor figures in published case? The reason can be found explicitly stated
in Freud’s the case notes. Freud writes that there was material presented
by Lanzer, which he found himself so resistant to include in his interpre-
tations that he had “forgotten owing to complexes of my own” ([1909a]
2001, 264). This material, precisely, was the heart of the link between
the sibling and castration complexes: memories of Katherine’s vow that
“On my soul, if you die I shall kill myself” and of Katherine being taken
to bed to die in the next room and of their father crying. Freud observes
that “in both cases it was a question of his sister’s death,” which was “the
consideration which I had forgotten” ([1909a] 2001, 264).
It seems probable that among the complexes that Freud perceives
blocked attention to Katherine in his interpretations was the death of
his little brother during his childhood. Writing to Fliess, Freud ([1897b]
1986: 268) recalls that “I greeted my one-year-younger brother (who
died after a few months) with adverse wishes and genuine childhood
jealousy; and that his death left the germ of [self-]reproaches in me.”
Considering Freud’s writings specifically and thus the subsequent history
of psychoanalytic theory as a palimpsest on the surface produced by these
writings, Mitchell (2000, 239) has observed that “this unacknowledged
dead brother can be said to have ‘possessed’ the theory of psychoanalysis,
ever present in the accounts but completely unintegrated into the theory
182 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
or practice.” In the case of the Rat Man, Stroeken (2007) has identified
several reasons for identification between analyst and analysand, among
them the fact that both Lanzer and Freud came from a family of seven
children: two boys and five girls.
Yet Freud’s remark regarding “complexes of my own” in the plural
suggests that the dead younger brother may not have been the only fac-
tor in play: a second childhood constellation may also have been relevant
in limiting Freud’s attention to siblings in the published case of the Rat
Man. In the same letter to Fliess cited above, Freud relates that, together
with his nephew who was the same age as him, when he was three he had
“behaved cruelly to my niece, who was a year younger.” Highlighting
the significance of his guilt for his brother’s death and his memory of
sadistic collusion with his nephew against his niece, Freud concludes his
recollections by stating that “this nephew and this younger brother have
determined, then, what is neurotic, but also what is intense, in all my
friendships.” The content of the cruel behavior toward the niece is not
identified in the letter to Fliess. It is, however, identified in Freud’s paper
on screen memories: he and his nephew threw his niece down in a meadow
in Freiburg and snatched the dandelions she was holding. Anzieu (1986,
285) has situated this story as a screen memory for Freud’s “sexual play”
as a child with his sisters and niece, undifferentiated between sexuality
and aggression. Certainly in favor of such an interpretation are Freud’s
associations to the memory, which are of “some pictures that I once saw
at a burlesque exhibition” and that “taking flowers from a girl means to
deflower her” ([1899] 2001, 312, 316).
Freud proposes that part of the salience of the meadow memory lies
in the fact that the next time he saw this niece and nephew in Freiburg,
he was 17 and fell in love with a young girl called Gisela Fluss (whose
dress reminded Freud of his niece’s flowers). During this time, however,
Freud notes that his family had the idea for him to “marry my cousin”
([1899] 2001, 314). In the event, neither marriage with the cousin nor
with Gisela Fluss came to anything. Yet her name appears again 35 years
later, followed by three exclamation marks, in Freud’s process notes to
the session with Lanzer of November 18 in which he accidently writes
the name “Gisela Fluss” instead of the name of Lanzer’s fiancé and
cousin ([1909a] 2001, 280). This is evidence for the role of material from
Freud’s past in shaping his attention predominantly to Lanzer’s father
rather than infantile sibling experiences of love, hate, and death in inter-
preting the patient’s ambivalent love for his cousin. The weave between
love/hate would therefore only be tied by Freud to sexuality/prohibition
in the published case—leaving the threads of life/death and vertical/
lateral dangling and unelaborated.2
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 183
trauma is repressed means that the subject mistakes the existential threat
of substitutability for a matter of someone preventing them from getting
what they want. In this context, “the desperate, exuberant protests, the
labile identifications and demonstrative sexualising” of the hysteric “are
a way of asserting an existence that has gone missing” (2000, 107). The
obsessional neurotic also faces the riddle of the sphinx, which raises the
issues of life and of genitality. The riddle is dealt with in a different way
to the hysteric, however.
The hysteric protests the displacement of a singular existence through
a repression that transposes the question into the anxious and exuberant
domain of sexuality, wanting, and embodiment. The obsessional neu-
rotic, by contrast, transposes the riddle to the domain of thought, in an
anal-sadistic register. In this domain, the issue is raised of the relation-
ship between polar opposites. This relationship is framed by doubt and
encroachment—as the displaced affect is transferred between contiguous
ideas in order to maintain a polarized boundary separating it from the
idea or experience to which it belonged. For example, “defence against
the obsessional ideas may be effected by a forcible diversion on to other
thoughts with a content as contrary as possible. This is why obsessional
brooding, if it succeeds, regularly deals with abstract and suprasensual
things; because the ideas that have been repressed are always concerned
with sensuality” ([1896b] 2001, 172). If the Rat Man were to become
aware of the hate for his father, it would contaminate his consciously held
image of love.
Yet the movement of the transfer of the displaced affect between dif-
ferent thoughts produces a labile sense of doubt. This doubt protects
the boundaries that sustain the subject’s sense of self, holding in place
the constellation of defences and anxieties. At the same time, however,
this doubt about what the subject feels and thinks is the product of and
further contributes to an unsteadiness that threatens to topple the self
by contaminating the totalizing experience that organizes and defines
it: of love without encroachment by hate. For instance, in the Rat Man
case, Lanzer reports having been “angry this morning when Constanze
[his eldest sister] had invited him to go to the play with her. He promptly
wished her the rats and then began to have doubts as to whether he
should go or not and as to which of the two decisions would be giving
way to a compulsion. Her invitation had upset a rendezvous with the
dressmaker and a visit to this cousin, who is ill . . . While he was wishing
Constanze the rats he felt a rat gnawing at his own anus and had a visual
image of it” ([1909a] 2001, 308).
The potential contamination of associating thoughts, as this example
shows, produces seemingly irrational anxiety and self-reproaches, and is
186 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
fought through two forms of symptoms. On the one hand, there are
prohibitions that keep the subject from actions or topics that have been
invested with the displaced affect. Included here are linguistic prohibi-
tions, in which particular bits of language must be kept separate from
others (Holland 1975). The other symptoms formed in this context, and
a product of the first, are compulsions: “The compulsion on the other
hand is an attempt at a compensation for the doubt and at a correction of
the intolerable conditions of inhibition to which the doubt bears witness.
If the patient, by the help of displacement, succeeds at last in bringing
one of his inhibited intentions to a decision, then the intention must
be carried out. It is true that this intention is not his original one, but
the energy dammed up in the latter cannot let slip the opportunity of
finding an outlet” ([1909a] 2001, 243–4). Yet, as the prohibitions and
compulsions become associated with the transferred affect, they them-
selves become unsettling and potentially contaminating. The subject
feels at once impervious (since the conflict between conscious love and
unconscious reproach has been displaced onto the domain of thought)
and terribly vulnerable (as association continually threatens to undo the
severance of the terms of this conflict).
The importance of the lateral axis for hysteria lies in the fact that
the possibility of siblings necessarily and irreducibly raises the question
of the sphinx in its hysteric form by highlighting substitutability. The
Rat Man case shows us how the vertical and lateral can intersect in
the paradigmatic case of obsessional neurosis, as the loss of the older
sister became fused in thought with the father’s threat of castration.
Reflection on this case suggests that siblings can raise two, related
issues: polarized opposition between self and other, and the threat of
encroachment. These two themes are suggested by Freud’s comment
that the birth of a new sibling is experienced as an “egoistic sense of
injury,” and “gives grounds for receiving the new brothers or sisters
with repugnance” ([1916] 2001, 334). More precisely, as Mitchell has
theorized, the plenitude the subject imagines themselves to have as the
property of their place in the family is necessarily threatened or haunted
by the potential of substitutability. Mitchell argues that the “primary
identifications made with parents are subject to trauma (you think you
are like your parents or one of your parents but you are not – at least, not
yet),” and as such are organized around themes of “negation” (2003,
14, likely following Green 1999). By contrast, Mitchell argues that “the
primary identification with the peer group is positive and subject not
to negation but to differentiation: you are like the others but with dif-
ferences” (2003: 14). Whereas the vertical axis is negotiated in terms of
negation, the child is confronted with the difference of the sibling or
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 187
When Freud ([1914] 2001, 90–1) states that the parent’s investment
in their child is “a revival and reproduction of their own narcissism,
188 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
which they have long since overvalued,” the child more likely to receive
this overvaluation is male in our culture. Whilst girls might be enjoined
to the fantasy of being a princess, this discourse is marked by the signs
of play and fantasy, and contains within it full awareness of the dis-
appointments of reality for young female subjects (Walkerdine 1997).
Not so perhaps for boys, for whom masculinity as plenitude is enjoined
without qualifying markers: become the phallus. As a result, the boy
may be more likely to be pinioned by the contradiction between abso-
lutes of presence and negation, rather than grieved and identity made
a matter of differentiation. In the case of the Rat Man, the threat of
childhood castration and the injunction to become the phallus as an
adult had been confused with the process of lateral differentiation, so
that the patient was forced to continually displace into symptoms the
unbearable matrix of affects around sexuality/prohibition, life/death,
and father/sister.
The ego-ideal is the part of the super-ego that soaks up all the cul-
tural and parental expectations felt by the subject, and then holds the
ego to account for distance or proximity to these expectations. Despite
advances made thanks to feminist efforts, this process in our culture
remains differentiated by sex. Her position within cultural and familial
relations of power mean that a girl is, cumulatively and continually,
disillusioned regarding the possibility of plenitude. By contrast, the boy
is not only enjoined to a greater investment in the illusion of perfec-
tion, but this narcissistic investment is one which is tied to his genital
organ by virtue of the way in which his family and society respond to a
subject with a penis. When the contradiction between the disappoint-
ments of reality and inherited, ungrieved-for plenitude becomes too
great, obsessional neurosis becomes more likely. The magnitude of dis-
appointments, pulverizing too severely any taste or dream of plenitude,
may be one reason for the finding that the social class of the subjects
with clinically significant obsessional symptoms is “significantly lower,
74% being in the lower social classes” (Heyman 2001, 327). If it is
the case that “it is not at all rare for both of the two children to fall
ill later on of a defence neurosis—the brother with obsessions and the
sister with hysteria” (Freud [1896b] 2001, 164), an explanation for this
may be proposed in the organization of patriarchal cultural and famil-
ial relations. The same cultural and familial forms that give the sister
no recognized place and thereby predispose her to hysteria encourage
her brother to dream of absolutes opposed in relations of incompatible
negation rather than differentiation, and so predispose him to obses-
sional neurosis.
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 189
Concluding Reflections
Freud observed that “obsessional neurosis is unquestionably the most
interesting and repaying subject of analytic research. But as a problem it
has not yet been mastered” ([1925] 2001, 113). Drawing on Mitchell’s
work, it has been argued here that sibling relationships or the possibil-
ity of sibling relationships can play a significant role in the predisposi-
tion to obsessional neurosis. Attention to the role of the lateral axis in
obsessional neurosis raises a curious question, which has been strangely
ignored by psychoanalytic theory, and on which this chapter will close.
Freud states clearly that the riddle of the Sphinx is the question: “where
do babies come from?” Yet on the surface he has no historico-textual
support for this statement. In the play by Sophocles, no mention is
made of the content of the Sphinx’s riddle. The conventional inter-
pretation, in a tradition following from Apollodorus (1976, 145), has
the Sphinx ask “which creature has one voice and yet becomes four-
footed and two-footed and three-footed?” to which Oedipus answers
“Man.” This addresses the intersection of human beings and time in
the form of generations, spotlighting Oedipus himself in the weave
of his embodiment as exposed child, as king, and as blinded old man.
Nonetheless it decidedly does not address the issue of where babies
come from. Freud’s citation of the riddle as the question “where do
babies come from?” might then, perhaps, be read as an interpretation,
highlighting the reversibility of generation in the unconscious where
there is no linear time.
Yet there is a less well-known tradition, attributed to Theodectas of
Phaselis by Athenaeus in Book 10 of the Deipnosophistae, which does
provide a textual basis for Freud’s claim regarding the Sphinx’s riddle.
In this tradition, the sphinx ask two, linked riddles. Good evidence for
Freud’s acquaintance with this tradition is provided by a bookplate he
designed in 1910, which describes Oedipus as the one who “knew the
famous riddles,” plural (Armstrong 2005, 54). Athenaeus states that the
second riddle is: “There are two sisters: one gives birth to the other and
she, in turn, gives birth to the first. Who are the two sisters?” (d’Huy
2012). The correct answer, given by Oedipus to the Sphinx, is that the
siblings are “day and night.” Here we do have the question of where
babies come from, a textual basis for Freud’s claim. Moreover, it is a
question that is only likely to be solved by someone like Oedipus who
is, as Freud states, both a hysteric and an obsessional neurotic, disposed
to answer the question of birth with an answer focused on the issues
of singularity and generation (hysteria) and doubt between encroaching
opposites (obsessional neurosis), both raised by the figure of the sibling.
190 ROBBIE DUSCHINSK Y AND R ACHEL LEIGH
Notes
1. Unfortunately, her paper is generally misread as suggesting merely
that the patient’s remarks that evoke his older sister’s death were a
metaphor for or instance in troubled relations with his father and
mother (e.g., Myerson 1966; Solano-Suarez 2009). As Daru Huppert
observes, there has been no place provided by theory to “put” sustained
analysis of sibling relationships.
2. The moments in the Rat Man case study in which Freud identifies
the significance of clinical material relating to death, as a result, are
cut off from their sibling context. In an interpretation made possible
by this severance, Lacan ([1956] 1991: 181) would later join together
these passages into an account of obsessional neurosis in general as an
attempt to grapple with the question “Am I alive or dead?” No mention
is made of the patent’s lost sister.
References
Anzieu, D. 1986. Freud’s Self-Analysis. New York: International Universities
Press.
Apollodorus 1976. Gods and Heroes of the Greeks, translated by Michael
Simpson, Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.
Armstrong, R. H. 2005. Freud and the Ancient World, New York: Cornell
University Press.
Athenaeus 1930. Deipnosophistae, translated. Loeb Classical Library, London:
William Heinemann.
Beigler, J. S. 1975. “A Commentary on Freud’s Treatment of the Rat Man,”
Annual of Psychoanalysis, 3: 271–285.
Billig, M. “Freud’s Response to Reported Incest: The Case of Paul Lorenz,
the ‘Rat Man.’ ” Psychoanalytic Studies 1.2 (1999): 145–158.
Crockatt, P. 2013. “A View of ‘The Rat Man,’ ” unpublished manuscript.
De Georges, P. 2009. “A Thought that Burdens the Soul,” Psychoanalytic
Notebooks, 18: 55–65.
Deutsch, H. 1932. “Obsessional Ceremonial and Obsessional Acts,” in Psycho-
Analysis of the Neuroses, translated by W. D. Robson-Scott, 175–197.
London: Hogarth Press.
D’Huy, J. 2012. “Aquitaine on the Road of Oedipus? The Sphinx as a
Prehistoric Story,” Société d’études et de recherches préhistoriques des Eyzies,
61: 15–21.
Ferenczi, S. [1908] 1925. “Analytic Conception of Psycho-Neuroses.” In
Further Contributions to the Theory and Technique of Psycho-analysis,
London: Karnac.
Freud, A. 1966. “Obsessional Neurosis: A Summary of Psycho-Analytic
Views as Presented at the Congress.” International Journal of Psycho-
analysis, 47: 116–122.
Freud, S. [1894] 2001. “The Neuro-psychoses of Defence.” In The Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud Vol. 3, trans-
lated by James Strachey, 41–61. Hogarth Press, London.
R EF R A M I N G O B S E S S I O N A L N EU R O S I S 191
Mahoney, P. 1986. Freud and the Rat Man, New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press.
Mahoney, P. 2007. “Reading the Notes on the Rat Man Case.” Canadian
Journal of Psychoanalysis 15(1): 93–117.
Mitchell, J. 1974. Psychoanalysis and Feminism, New York: Basic Books.
Mitchell, J. 2000. Mad Men and Medusas, London: Penguin.
Mitchell, J. 2003. Siblings: Sex and Violence, Cambridge: Polity.
Myerson, P. G. 1966. “Comment on Dr Zetzel’s Paper.” International
Journal of Psycho-analysis 47: 139–142.
Nunberg, H. and Federn, E., editors. 1962. Minutes of the Vienna Psychanalytic
Society, Volume 1. New York: International Universities Press.
Oliver, K. 2009. Animal Lessons. New York: Columbia University Press.
Solono-Suarez, E. (2009) “Learning to Read Obsessional Neurosis.”
Psychoanalytic Notebooks, 18: 29–42.
Stroeken, H. P. 2007. “Note on the Extraordinary Similarity Between
the Worlds of Freud and of the Ratman.” International Forum of
Psychoanalysis, 16: 100–102.
Verhaeghe, P. 2001. Beyond Gender, New York: Other Press.
Verhaeghe, P. 2004. On Being Normal and Other Disorders, London:
Karnac.
Veszy-Wagner, L. 1967. “Zwangsneurose und latent Homosexualitat” Psyche
21: 295–615.
Walkerdine, V. 1997. Daddy’s Girl, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press.
Winnicott, D. [1953] 1965. “Psycho-Analysis and the Sense of Guilt.” In
The Maturational Processes and the Facilitating Environment: Studies in
the Theory of Emotional Development, London: Tavistock.
Zetzel, E. R. 1966. “1965: Additional Notes Upon a Case of Obsessional
Neurosis: Freud 1909.” International Journal of Psychoanalysis, 47:
123–129.
Chapter 9
Mignon Nixon
The individual citizen can with horror convince himself in this war
of what would occasionally cross his mind in peace-time—that the
state has forbidden to the individual the practice of wrong-doing, not
because it desires to abolish it, but because it desires to monopolize
it. . . . A belligerent state permits itself every such misdeed, every such
act of violence, as would disgrace the individual. (Freud 1915, 279)
(see Bryan-Wilson 2009). From the early to the mid-1960s, Rainer cho-
reographed and danced with a contingent of artists—a sibling group, as it
were—loosely affiliated under the name Judson Dance Theatre, derived
from the activist Judson Memorial Church in Greenwich Village, New
York, where they performed. Inspired by John Cage, the kind of move-
ment Judson choreographers pioneered is often described as task-based
performance, subjecting ordinary, pedestrian actions such as walking,
running, or manipulating objects, to the discipline of dance. One aim
of Judson was to subvert the dynamic of mastery in classical dance by
replacing virtuosic movement, solo performance, and the charisma of the
lead dancer, with nonhierarchical, inclusive procedures, incorporating
untrained performers and laying particular emphasis on the contingency
of the event. Judson Dance was not an explicitly political practice, but its
social dynamics were predicated on a rejection of mastery and hierarchy
and an embrace of what has been described as an egalitarian ethos (Bane
1980). To situate this history in Mitchell’s terms, the Judson choreog-
raphers were working on the lateral axis of a cultural form that seemed
“trapped in the vertical.”
Street Action is not a work of Judson Dance Theatre, and is not exactly
a work of art at all. It is a protest work, perhaps, or an artistic response
to a political crisis, namely, the revelation on April 30, 1970, of the
American invasion of Cambodia, followed on May 4 by the attack of the
National Guard on protesting students at Kent State, a massacre in which
four students were shot to death and another nine wounded, including
one who was paralyzed. Timed to coincide with a weekend arts festival
in Lower Manhattan, Street Action brought together some 40 students,
friends, and acquaintances of Rainer, who arranged the group in a three-
column formation, led by herself and two other dancers, Douglas Dunn
and Sara Rudner. Very slowly, the group began to move down the middle
of the street, reproducing a gait, the M-walk, devised by Rainer for a
dance work entitled The Mind is a Muscle, and adapted from the mecha-
nized movement of workers in Fritz Lang’s 1927 film Metropolis. Here,
however, the participants linked arms, “transforming the movement,” as
the art historian Carrie Lambert-Beatty has noted, “from drone-like sub-
mission to mournful solidarity” (Lambert-Beatty 2008, 239). The route
traced by the phalanx marked off a single block in a then newly defined
artistic district of SoHo. By Rainer’s recollection, that trip around the
block took an hour, and by the end of it, the group had dwindled to five.
For untrained performers, the physical discipline of the swaying lockstep
motion on straight legs, its slowness, and the requirement that the par-
ticipants keep their eyes lowered and averted, was oppressively difficult
to sustain.
202 M I G N O N N I XO N
into love. In war, Mitchell reminds us, we exploit our hatred of the same
to “generate the category of ‘other.’ ” Thinking siblings is not a refuge
from our badness, only a theory that, like psychoanalysis itself, may help
us to grapple with it. Seriality is hard won.
Notes
1. Two compelling responses to the abuses of Abu Ghraib and the psy-
chic dynamics of the war on terror are by contributors to this volume:
Judith Butler, Frames of War: When Is Live Grievable? (London: Verso,
2009) and Jacqueline Rose, The Last Resistance (London: Verso,
2007).
2. On the extent of atrocities conducted by the American military in
Vietnam, and the deceptive characterization of them as aberrations,
see Nick Turse, Kill Anything That Moves: The Real American War in
Vietnam (New York: Metropolitan Books, 2013).
3. The truism of war, “kill or be killed,” governs the distinction between
so-called legitimate killing and murder. That distinction breaks down
in many forms of modern warfare, not least bombing, but it is a crucial
line for Mitchell’s theory.
4. Seriality is also crucially significant as “the symbolization of the repeti-
tion of trauma.” See Tamar Garb and Mignon Nixon, “A Conversation
with Juliet Mitchell,” October 113 (Summer 2005), p. 20.
5. Important exceptions are Hal Foster, The Return of the Real
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/October Books, 1996) and Briony Fer,
The Infinite Line (New Haven and London: Yale University Press).
References
Arendt, Hannah. 1970. On Violence. Houghton Mifflin Harcourt.
Bane, Sally. 1980/1993. Democracy’s Body: Judson Dance Theatre 1962–1964.
Duke University Press.
Bryan-Wilson, Julia. 2009. Art Workers: Radical Practice in the Vietnam
War Era. Berkeley: University of California.
Butler, Judith. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity.
New York: Routledge.
Fornari, Franco. 1975. The Psychoanalysis of War. Bloomington: Indiana
University Press.
Freud, S. 1915. “Thoughts for the Times on War and Death,” In Standard
Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud. Vol. 14,
translated by James Strachey, London: Hogarth.
Kelly, Mary, 1983. “Preface,” Post-Partum Document, xv. London: Routledge.
Krauss, Rosalind. 1977. Passages in Modern Sculpture. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Lambert-Beatty, Carrie. 2008. Being Watched: Yvonne Rainer and the 1960s
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press/October Books.
M I N I M A L D I F F E R EN C E 205
Mitchell, Juliet. 2000. Mad Men and Medusas: Reclaiming Hysteria and the
Effect of Sibling Relationships on the Human Condition. London: Allen
Lane.
Nixon, M. 2008. “Book of Tongues.” In Nancy Spero: Dissidances, 30.
Barcelona and Madrid: Museu d’Art Contemporani de Barcelona and
Museo Nacional Centro de Art Reina Sofia.
Nixon, M. 2014. “Louise Lawler: No Drones,” October 147 (Winter 2014).
Owens, Craig. 1983. “The Discourse of Others: Feminists and
Postmodernism.” In Beyond Recognition: Representation, Power, and
Culture. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Rainer, Yvonne. 1966. “A Quasi Survey of Some ‘Minimalist’ Tendencies
in the Quantitatively Minimal Dance Activity Midst the Plethora, or an
Analysis of Trio A.” In Yvonne Rainer. 1974. Work 1961–73. Halifax:
Press of the Nova Scotia College of Art and Design.
Chapter 10
Crimes of Identity
I was honored to have been asked to deliver the 2014 Juliet Mitchell
capstone lecture at Cambridge. I was in awe of Juliet Mitchell before
I met her—I believe in 1993, with Michael Riffaterre at the School of
Criticism and Theory—and have retained that feeling. I taught her iconic
Psychoanalysis and Feminism again and again after the mid-1970s, in the
obligatory feminist theory class that I had begun to teach from the end
of the 1960s.1
In my prepared speech, I had made two points:
One, that having a certain kind of “identity” allows groups with pre-
ferred “identities” to initiate and sustain policy that, although legal, may
be construed as “criminal” by natural law, if it were humane in the col-
loquial sense. In the workshop following the talk, I was asked why these
would not be called “crimes of capital.” The answer was that capital,
the abstract as such, is not susceptible to behavioral diagnosis. As one of
the participants remarked: “whether crimes of capital would have been
possible at all if there wasn’t a certain logic of identity in place. I am
not sure whether crimes of capital would have been possible if it wasn’t
for a certain logic of gendered identity, a certain logic of class identity
that has been inscribed in the bodies of those men who have committed
these suicides.” In terms of conjuncture discourse, managing gender and
class by race-ideology, I was shifting the field of identity from capitalism-
mobilized claims to capitalism-accusing crimes. To invoke “crimes of
capital” is incorrect. To invoke “crimes of capitalism” is banal in Hannah
Arendt’s sense, and plagued by the usual rentier bad faith within aca-
demic leftism, engaged in a perennial small-stakes effort to secure a
place within capitalist globalization, unable to acknowledge complicity. 2
“Capital” or “capitalism” are faceless structural enemies. I wanted to
bring the scenario into the field of identity precisely because it is more
personalized. It inhabits the “human” in the humanities. It profits from
208 G AYAT R I C H A K R AV O R T Y S P I VA K
sexualized,” and write: “Rape is the coveted agency of that which must
be transcendentally deduced become sexualized. That agency would be
to control inaccessible origins: sperm fantasy.”8
For the moment, let us not resist the counterintuitive by the self-
congratulation of a common sense.
The problem with this is paleonymy: as “rape” proceeded in the
English language from the general sense of “theft” into sexual violence,
there is no way that this word could be understood extra-morally. This
is in fact the problem with all of the words for the inaccessibility of the
origin. “Transcendental” is understood as the supernatural, difference
as antiracist/sexist and so on. They are supposedly unconditional, but
unconditionality is always contaminated by conditions.
I warned about this in the extemporized introduction to my pre-
pared paper: perhaps you should think about rape and the way in which
Foucault talked about power, I said. As a name. But of course many of
us complained about the fact that power was also in the language—and
rape is more than in the language—so that power had a paleonymy and
therefore one was responsible for choosing just that word. Remember
that, so am I. Responsible.
Derrida’s general philosophy may be vulgarized as follows: theory is
a practice. The theorizer does not cling to concept-metaphors and estab-
lish them as master-concepts. Derrida more or less stays with this in his
writings, though not invariably. It is a difficult thing to keep up. And
so, with embracing the violence of rape as the correct description of the
violation of the animal by the making-human, I tried to take on this
challenge and suggest that this concept-metaphor should not be used
again, should be seen as universalizable, not universalized; that it should
not be naturalized. And of course, I failed.9 Can the reader walk with
me on this one? Can humanism itself be understood as the child of rape?
And thus put us in the double bind, since you do not throw the child out
with the possibility of rape.
In response to Nancy’s vigorous reminder of the dangers of my claim,
I wanted to write a piece that was going to act out all the warnings,
knowing, of course, that I should not have ventured up to the perilous
point where it became a necessity.
Time to open the prepared paper and see if it can be revised to be
safe:
The most significant crimes in our world today are committed on the
issue of identity. Identity is defined by and predicated on collective legiti-
mate birth. The great Dalit thinker, Bhimrao Ramji Ambedkar, suggested
in 1916 that caste—and this was unusual for a man who had suffered
severe caste prejudice—as a general rule of group formation could be
210 G AYAT R I C H A K R AV O R T Y S P I VA K
that the source of the word “identity” was given as Latin idem or
Sanskrit idam and both were cited as meaning “same.” Now the
meaning of the Latin word idem is not exactly “same” in the sense
of “one,” but rather “same” in the sense of multitudes or repetitions.
That which is primordial [anadi] and unique [ekamevadvitiam] is not
idem, it is rather that which can be cited through many re-citations.
To make these two meanings one is a clandestine patching up of a
loose part of the text-ile fabric of conceptuality. At least from the
outside it seems that in our solemn recitation of Hindutva [Hindu-
ness, a key word of Hindu nationalism] this clan-destiny or ruse is
at work. The little Sanskrit that I learned under the able guidance of
Miss Nilima Pyne at the Diocesan School in Calcutta allowed me to
suspect that the Sanskrit idam is also not the undiminishing singly
manifest [akshaya ekarupa]. Then I looked at the Sanskrit dictionary.
Idam is not only not the undiminishing selfsame, as a pronoun it does
not have the dignity of a noun, is always enclitic or inclined towards
the noun, always dependent upon the proximity of a particular self,
and must always therefore remain monstrative, indexed. All over the
world today, “identity politics” (that is to say a separation in the name
of the undifferentiated identity of religion, nation, or subnation) is
big news and almost everywhere bad news.11 The unremarkable and
unremarked ruse in the United States students’ dictionary [Merriam-
Webster’s college edition, I think] makes visible the fraud at the heart
of identity politics. As a memorial to that publication I submit this
outlandish deconstructed translation [I submitted on that occasion,
and later I will connect it to my use of “rape” in the current essay] of
“identity,” only for that occasion—not ahamvada [ego-ism as ipse-
ism] but idamvada. If our thinking shakes the stakes of the spirit’s
ahamvada to show idamvada [shaking up autonormativity to show
heteronormativity]—we do not want to know it, and therefore we
protect ourselves in the name of a specific national identity.12
CRIMES OF ID ENT IT Y 211
In the field of positive law, we are still fighting this one in the question
of gay marriage.
Forgive me for going through this fable so fast. Please keep in mind
the broad outlines: the unspeculable turned into the specular by nor-
mative deviation, the imaginary; the specular turned into the limited
asymmetry of speculation. This asymmetry is only limited because,
although the asymmetry of the Father alone oversees this move, it is
in the interests of guarding the infinitely repeatable as the same: the
absolute symmetry of the Idea; the patronymic; the seamless signifying
system of the symbolic.
I am more interested in Lacan’s narrativization of the unconditional
unspeculable. Lacan describes the presubjective drive falling upon the
“anatomical trace of a margin or border;”—every word here is full of
meaning—“lips, enclosure of the teeth, rim of the anus, penile f issure,
vagina, fissure of eyelid, indeed hollow of the ear. . . . Respiratory
erogeneity . . . comes into play through spasms.” In other words, border-
thinking is an undecided and primary constituent of our perception of
reality itself, where reason is fashioned out of what precedes it. It is of no
interest to me if this account is correct and therefore an instrument of
cure. The literary critic learns from the singular and unverifiable. What
is of interest to me is that here in the place before the speculations of
the subject Lacan places the extra-moral possibility of the infinite exten-
sion of rape; borders, holes in the body. In the narrative itself, classic
psychoanalysis cannot distinguish between seduction and rape and the
distinction between truth and exactitude becomes patriarchially coun-
terproductive. French Freud has not considered this particular problem
significant. Juliet Mitchell’s tremendous intervention in Psychoanalysis
and Feminism does not specifically thematize rape. What I am speaking
of today thematizes her bold parenthesis; the only mention of rape in that
early book (“That rape does indeed occur is only an indirectly related
issue”). This is the relentlessness of the unconditional.16 I am focused on
that indirection, the refraction of the transcendental. Indeed, apart from
Jeffrey Moussaief Masson’s The Assault on Truth, which treats seduction
and rape together and points at the disavowal of real sexual abuse in
Freudian psychoanalysis, rape is not necessarily a concern for those who
wish to bring feminism and psychoanalysis together. Rape in the narrow
sense is neither seduction nor incest. Where incest is supposed to distin-
guish the human from nature and seduction is morally ambiguous after
the law, rape in the narrow sense makes it hard to determine the border
of the human and the upper primates.
If Jacques Lacan, the master imaginer, implies rape as a potential
before subject signifier and ego, I attend to that imagining and suggest
CRIMES OF ID ENT IT Y 213
that redress for rape cannot be in the sphere of unconditional ethics but
firmly in the field of agency, where the intending subject is accountable
to what Kant would call “mere reason.” There we require an epistemo-
logical performance which cannot always be expected of what we have
now come to designate as “activism.” It is an imaginative training that
rape in the narrow sense, if such a thing can be thought, still extends
all the way from the most public to the most private, from war crime to
domestic violence. But this is “after,” this is in the field of agency, inter-
vention; activism. Sexual violence without consent, coercive. And the
unconditional possibility of rape in the general sense as the unaccount-
able origin of the human should at least be thinkable during the time of
the reading of this chapter.
No modern European thinker of the subject is free of German clas-
sical philosophy. The Cartesian line is more historical, the invocation of
Christianity wittingly or unwittingly reactive. Within the main tradition,
the common element is the break between the transcendental and the
phenomenal. Kant keeps the break alive; Hegel narrativizes it, staging
the break repeatedly, in various ways. Kant keeps the rupture between
(the unconditionality of) pure reason and understanding blank, although
contaminated into a textual blank, with the understanding presumably
philosophizing on the analogy of the sense perceptible manifold. Many
years ago, Rosalind Coward and John Ellis showed that Lacan had read
Hegel.17 And indeed, Lacan speaks of Descartes and Hegel as being
metonymic of psychoanalysis, unearthing part of it and disclosing it as
the whole. Here we can tabulate Lacan’s bond to Kant as well as Hegel,
as he narrativizes the unconditional and programmed material tran-
scendental by way of a manifold—the body’s borders—that will become
sense-perceptible by way of the grounding error of signifier/fantasy—
leading to the subject/ego site of conflict, secured by the specular/
d iscursive access provided for analysis. A complex trajectory, but the
Kantian imprint is determining—the necessary intuition of the drives
remaining unspeculable (though compromised here by narrativization):
rape in the general sense. Kant’s warning to Locke: the necessity of the
synthetic a priori cannot be proved, only demonstrated.
Rape in the general sense is not susceptible to proof. Its demonstra-
bility cannot be argued, although Andrea Dworkin did make a heroic
attempt, creating a clearly excessive binary opposition. At the other
extreme, such a binary opposition is legitimized by reversal because of
the incalculability of gendering—into a straightforward relationship
between desire and violence: “she, or indeed he, asked for it.”
Remaining within psychoanalysis, Mitchell moves from “killing is
raping and raping is killing” to “a suggestion of death and sex drives
214 G AYAT R I C H A K R AV O R T Y S P I VA K
being constituted in the same moment.”18 Perhaps death and sex are
somewhat naturalized here? Freud and Lacan have always found in fic-
tion the experience of the impossible. Reversing the situation and read-
ing the literary in Freud, let me propose that the ripple in the pervasive
ocean of thanatos that is the normative deviation of the emergence of life
(an unbalanced psychic machine) shares a structure with rape, if rape is
understood as generalized “objectlessness” (no individual is the object of
the “planetary” or the synthetic a priori).
The character Lucy in J. M. Coetzee’s novel Disgrace, pregnant after
being raped, gives us a sense of the “objectlessness” of rape by refusing
to be interpellated as victim:
Let me point out that Coetzee, in his usual manner, is not only mingling
race, class, and gender but also, given contemporary South Africa, the
idea of the new nation as well. Nationalism, starting from group forma-
tions preceding the formation of nation states by far, sanctions crimes of
group identity.
Disgrace’s twist, the situation of the white creole in the postcolonial
nation, could not be imagined by Kant. The best he can do is to make a
gesture toward the colonized:
The country whose inhabitants are citizens of one and the same
Commonwealth (by birth) is called the fatherland; those where they
live without this condition is a foreign country; and these, if they are
part of a wider landownership, are called provinces (in the meaning
given by the Romans), which, while not integrated into an empire as a
place of fellow-citizens, but is only a possession as a subordinate posi-
tion, must respect the ground of the ruling state as a motherland.20
say because for some reason we have sentimentalized the concept of the
human, with underived universal rights and so on, in the last few centu-
ries. I think, if we can acknowledge that real education de-humanizes so
that we can promote social justice, an endeavor that turns rape around
and makes it productive, as in the fictive example of Disgrace’s Lucy,
we would be better off. I have often connected rape-culture and bribe-
culture—thinking of both as “normal”—rape as the extra in gender and
bribe in the economic. Just as rape does not look like rape if there is sex
in it, so bribe disappears if it is simply capitalist expression of “normal”
human greed, perfectly practicable if you have received institutional edu-
cation, seen today in the resumption of subprime lending in the auto-
mobile industry, no lesson learnt after 2007. My citing these examples
will I hope assure you that I am not interested in speaking in generalized
abstractions; these examples are class marked. Therefore, not only am I
not “turning reality into nothing but abstractions” but, I am asking us
to acknowledge that in many very different kinds of areas, the structure
of a sudden and unaccountable entry into humanity—and indeed the
originary move for every possibility of being-human shares very much
more in common with the structure that I can only call rape. If we accept
this, then we are complicit with rape, we do not try to redress what
can be called rape only by making and enforcing laws in the name of
humanity; but, more practically, we act toward the artificiality of, in the
name of a forever thwarted social justice as a result of a certain kind of
education which effectively de-humanizes, if the human is understood as
not necessarily anodyne and benign as most people of our class and our
education tend to do. This is how I understand MacKinnon’s placing
of the prakrit (natural) before the Sanskrit (repaired): “The analysis is
structured to treat law as first substantive then abstract on the view that,
in this sphere and perhaps others, law is interpreted and practiced on the
basis of substantive experiences and material commitments, from which
doctrinal and formal positions inevitably derive” (p.v). Recently, sitting
at a table with an altogether accomplished art historian who suggested
that most people would like to do good to others, I had to say the entire
world does not resemble you and she later confided to her husband that
I intimidated her. This idea, of a welcome de-humanizing kept up with
difficulty, should not intimidate—but simply allow us not to claim post-
humanism when it is convenient to do so, and become aware that the
anthropocene is not just climate change, not just the bad human; it is the
double bind of the human as such.
In the discussion of gender as our first instrument of abstraction, I have
previously made three further suggestions: that this use of reproductive
heteronormativity includes everything that emerges from the difference
CRIMES OF ID ENT IT Y 217
between how much we need and how much we can make; that the
autonormativity of the Idea—infinite repeatability of the same—disavows
this; and finally, that in the field of sexual reproduction as the most gener-
alizable clue to heteronormativity, the queer use of its affective and legal
resources is “extra-moral” in the Nietzschean sense, as far as possible.
Now I am ready to take reproductive heteronormativity—provoked by
the passage in Mitchell that I have already quoted—as the social account
of the transcendental and unconditional discursivity of rape in the gen-
eral sense. This indeconstructible unconditionality, like Marx’s realm of
freedom, is not susceptible to social engineering. Therefore the redress of
rape in the narrow sense, as nonconsensual sexual violence, is only pos-
sible through agential work in three ways: (a) interventionist enforcement
of the law, (b) juridico-legal constitutionality in the making of the law;
and (c) undoing class apartheid in education and making room for long-
term imaginative training for epistemological performance—producing
problem solvers rather than enforcing solutions to problems.
I take them up briefly and in sequence.
(a) Interventionist involvement on a worldwide scale, undertaken by
what is now called the International Civil Society, must use the tremen-
dous generalizing resources of the digital. Digital redress cannot recog-
nize the contingent. You can programme for all kinds of mistakes and
compensations etc. but the contingent as such will always escape. You
can even plan for many contingencies that you can imagine but the con-
tingent as such you cannot imagine; it must be neutralized. Not only
can digital redress not recognize the contingent but it must resist all
thought of the unconditional as impractical. It must generalize in order
to redress what it perceives as gender inequality, and believe me I am not
against this. Yet it must also be recognized that the unconditional is in
unavoidable tension with this generalization that produces platforms of
action for international civil society, one size fits all gender toolkits for
field workers from urban to rural. Gendered microcredit sees income
production as such as unquestioned good. We cannot get around this if
we must solve gender problems, ranging from homophobic laws through
domestic violence, pharmaceutical dumping, absence of reproductive
rights, unequal pay, dowry trafficking, HIV-AIDS, war rape, casual rape,
genital mutilation and the like. Yet, this generalized redress produces
problem solving that cannot last, for three reasons at least: the tremen-
dous counterforce of sustainable underdevelopment, the longue durée
of internalized gendering and class apartheid in education. Short-term
problem solving must continue indefinitely, resources must be sought
and deployed. Since, however, the sources are largely corporate, their
ties with the presuppositions and values of sustainable underdevelopment
218 G AYAT R I C H A K R AV O R T Y S P I VA K
by providing a critical grasp of the legal tools of the field, [her book
can] aspire to narrow the gap between the law’s promise and perfor-
mance in [the] domain [of “social inequality between and among
women and men, legal sex equality guarantees, and the present and
possible relation between the two”] by promoting change toward
equality goals
will have too restricted a field.27 Massively important work such as hers
must be persistently supplemented by expanding the readership for her
book. (She knows this in her earlier, less legal book, which “engages
sexual politics on the level of epistemology.”) The expansion of episte-
mological training can only happen in the language the student “feels,”
CRIMES OF ID ENT IT Y 219
even as he or she learns English for the big world. Otherwise, rape/
bribe (kamini/kanchan) will work as normal, rape as bribe will work as
normal.
Attention to first language education in combination with global lan-
guages is called for. The strength of gender education should be interwo-
ven into classroom practice, rather than depend on consciousness raising
at the very start. Things must change as we go up the education ladder,
of course. Here, too, class and the historical longue durée must be learnt
through direct unconditional contact. Learned accounts must be judi-
ciously consulted as secondary, because most learned accounts do not go
below this radar.
Knowledge management—group learning with charts or cards—
and toolkits, cannot cross epistemological divides. Although structured
evaluation is certainly needed for a sense of progress in both participant
and funder, we must learn to rely on the unexpected or on contingent
results.
In this limited but crucial enclosure of redress, this last item—edu-
cation, creating a general will for social justice in all children—is not far
from Freud’s liberal revision of the Kantian sublime into sublimation,
or from Lacan’s straightforward account of the ethics of psychoanalysis,
or yet Derrida’s call for a new Enlightenment. Freud was perhaps only
a European liberal. Yet in this era of leadership talk, role model talk,
empowerment talk, the trashing of democracy as voting bloc politics
talk, self-interested, often gender-compromised culturalisms, disguis-
ing the profound aporia between unconditional liberty understood as
autonomy, and the conditions of equality for others who do not resem-
ble us—we should pay attention again to Freud’s discourse of collective
identification through leader-identification, of the emergence of the ego
ideal rather than the super-ego. Massenpsychologie und Ich-Analyse (Mass
Psychology and I-analysis), risibly translated as “Group Psychology and
the Analysis of the Ego,” still holds lessons that, in spite of Reich’s smart
and superficial work, remains to be unpacked in the context of what
I am calling rape in the general sense and its agential redress in the
narrow sense.
About creating a general will for social justice I said at the University
of Utrecht on the 300th anniversary of the Peace of Utrecht
only suggestions, that any attempt to make of rape in the general sense a
universal concept-metaphor of making human will be visited by vigorous
opposition and would undo the difference between the victim and the
perpetrator. That very danger might warn us that this transient argument
might harbor dark truths best kept transcendentalized.
First a crime of national/global identity—European agribusiness,
which has invaded an old rural development organization in the area
where I work, whose members cannot understand that they are being
invaded, as it is done cunningly through Bangladesh, remotely diasporic
Bangladeshi Germans. I wish I had the time to speak of Antonio Gramsci’s
brilliant anticipation of this.
And next, three icons, where we see three women, pictured metonymi-
cally because their appropriable—rapable—general identity can be used
to depict crimes of ostensibly other sorts of politico-economic identity.
That general identity—woman as such—does not need to be investigated
in its gendering.
I had designed the following paragraphs of this chapter as a teaching
moment—asking the readers to “read” three photographs according to
the notions of “identity” and “crime” that I had laid out in the body of
the chapter. Ut pictura poesis. I could not get permission to include the
photographs.
The first one was the picture of an Indian peasant woman being
held up by relatives, screaming with pain because of the suicide of her
husband. This accompanies a sympathetic article by Ellen Barry, “After
Farmers Commit Suicide, Debts Fall on Families in India” (The New
York Times, February 22, 2014) where she correctly describes what I am
calling a “crime of identity,” calling it “global competition” rather than
simply “globalization,” the insertion of small farming into the circuit
of (global) capital, today’s financialized agribusiness of which I speak
above. This and her veering off into examples of local cruelty, visibly hor-
rible, does not make her general sense of things negligible:
India’s small farmers, once the country’s economic backbone and most
reliable vote bank, are increasingly being left behind. With global com-
petition and rising costs cutting into their lean profits, their ranks are
dwindling, as is their contribution to the gross domestic product. If
rural voters once made their plight into front-page news around elec-
tion time, this year the large parties are jockeying for the votes of the
urban middle class, and the farmers’ voices are all but silent.
be put aside in the interest of human interest. I was not accusing the
author or the photographer of anything. I was asking the reader to imag-
ine the woman, whose name is given: Anitha Amgoth, because women
holding certain identities are easy examples where the actual “crime” is
not analyzed in any depth, only mentioned as human interest. In view of
the inevitable shift into human interest proving the personal corruption
of the global South (as opposed, I suppose to the clean “rule of law”
practices of neoliberal capitalism), I had indeed also asked why Anitha’s
face is used to illustrate this crime, which is not a crime, global capi-
tal destroying primary production in the global South—against people
identified in that specific subalternity—in the name of “development,”
aka insertion into the circuit of capital?28 I am still not quite sure as to
why I was denied access to this. I felt it as the impossibility of imagina-
tive activism under the neoliberal “rule of law” approach. I also felt that
academic freedom was here confronting an absurd version of “intellec-
tual property.” This too is a “crime of identity” in my sense against the
teacherly, if you wish, spelling out the impossibility of teaching.
The second photograph was a beautifully focused image, with the light
falling on the face of a young Afghan girl holding a book, reading. Who
can deny that the very fact of an Afghan girl reading today is a heart-
warming one. In my book Other Asias, I have discussed the attempts by
Amir Abd-ur-Rahman Khan—the “Iron Amir”—to bring Afghanistan
into state civility in the nineteenth century. 29 It is also well known by
left and right alike (see Gregory Massell, The Surrogate Proletariat) that
women in Soviet Afghanistan had access to education and were in pub-
lic life.30 Those were not the facts I was concentrating on as I offered
this picture as a teaching text: I asked the question “does anybody ask
a question (rather than provide a yes-no question for agreement) about
her internalized gendering and is anyone engaged in remotely approach-
ing the quality of education?” I have been for 30 years involved in the
training of subaltern children, and holding a book unfortunately means
nothing in terms of producing a will to social justice.
The last picture was one many of you have seen, which apparently is
no longer being used by Care.org, the picture of a very beautiful African
woman, dressed in cloth, with the caption “I am powerful.” There my
question was “does anyone ask what the word ‘power,’ kernel of the
absurd word ‘empowerment,’ signifies—or, the relationship between any
partner and this woman?” In other words, what do these women consider
normal, can we enter their world, learning how not to construct them as
forgettable items of news for public awareness or human rights work, or
nongovernmental organization (NGO) gendering work, or public inter-
est litigation or constitutional engagement? Professionals busy with these
CRIMES OF ID ENT IT Y 223
Notes
1. Juliet Mitchell, Psychoanalysis and Feminism. A Radical Reassessesment
of Freudian Psychoanalysis (New York: Basic Books, 1974).
2. Hannah Arendt, Eichmann in Jerusalem: A Report on the Banality of
Evil (New York: Viking Press, 1963).
3. Jacques Lacan, “The Function and Field of Speech and Language in
Psychoanalysis,” in Ecrits: A Selection, tr. Alan Sheridan (New York
& London: Norton, 1977), pp. 30–113.
4. Jacques Derrida, “Force de loi: le ‘fondement mystique de l’autorité/
Force of Law: The ‘Mystical Foundation of Authority,’ ” Cardozo
Law Review 11 (1990), pp. 920–1046.
5. Roland Barthes, S/Z. An Essay, tr. Richard Miller (New York: The
Noonday Press, 1974).
6. Mahasweta Devi, Imaginary Maps: Three Stories, tr. Gayatri Chakravorty
Spivak (New York: Routledge, 1995); Toni Morrison, Beloved (New
York: Knopf, 1987).
7. Mitchell, Psychoanalysis, p. xvii.
8. Mitchell, Mad Men and Medusas: Reclaiming Hysteria (New York:
Basic Books, 2000), p. 256. Recently, in an interesting film by
CRIMES OF ID ENT IT Y 225
law: that is, the very being or legal existence of the woman is sus-
pended during the marriage, or at least is incorporated and consoli-
dated into that of the husband: under whose wing, protection, and
cover, she performs everything.”
29. Spivak, “Foucault and Najibullah,” Other Asias (Boston: Wiley
Blackwell, 2007), pp. 132–160.
30. Gregory Massell, The Surrogate Proletariat Moslem Women and
Revolutionary Strategies in Soviet Central Asia, 1919–1929 (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1974).
31. Immanuel Kant, Political Writings, p. 172; translation modified. The
next passage quoted is from p. 173. It is important to keep in mind
that, in Rogues: Two Essays on Reason, tr. Pascale-Anne Brault and
Michael Naas (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2005), the last
book published during his lifetime, Derrida warned that Kant could
not serve as a solution in contemporary globality.
32. Peter Sloterdijk, In the World Interior of Capital: For a Philosophical
Theory of Globalization, tr. Wieland Hoban (Cambridge: Polity, 2013),
p. 28.
Chapter 11
Gillian Harkins
T he Lot saga is a familiar one. The Lot family of Sodom and Gomorrah
is visited by angels in men’s form; male citizens flock to the door of
the Lot home seeking to “know” the visitors. Lot offers the citizens his
daughters instead, who have not yet “known” man, but ultimately the
angels decide to punish the cities with fire and brimstone. Lot, along
with his wife and daughters, are spared this fate so long as none turns
back to look upon the cities’ destruction while they leave. Lot’s wife
however does glance backward, and as a result turns to salt. Bereft of
both human community and maternal presence, Lot’s daughters seek to
become mothers themselves by lying with their father (after an appropri-
ate plying of wine to induce lethargy and forgetfulness) and reproducing
the line through themselves. Daughters become mothers of their own
siblings, creating a new human community from the crossing of what
Juliet Mitchell calls the lateral and vertical axes of sexuality and repro-
duction (Mitchell 2003).
The parable of Genesis 19 has been much revisited over the centu-
ries, lending itself to anti-homosexual scriptural interpretation as well as
feminist and queer reimaginings of what lies beyond the limits of social
heteropatriarchy.1 A biblical prohibition on male sodomy has often been
attributed to the tale, although both biblical and lay scholars have dis-
puted this interpretation. Some scholars have also drawn attention to
the prohibition on female knowledge exhibited in the punishment of
Lot’s wife, while still others examine the positive and productive role
of father–daughter incest in the parable. Here a divine prohibition on
male–male sexual relations seems to precede the social injunction toward
father–daughter incest. Heterosexual and intergenerational incest is
linked directly to social reproduction, the response to a more sovereign
230 GILLIAN HARKINS
lost human community through sex with the father. In place of a sover-
eign prohibition (against homosexuality) that creates a social injunction
(toward reproduction), we find a lateral prohibition (against homosexu-
ality) that creates a vertical injunction (toward reproduction). The Lot
story provides an admonitory parable through the reification of Lot’s
wife: her effort to see sovereign power creates a crisis in the temporal and
logical order of lateral and vertical regulation. As a result, she is frozen
in the moment of transgression while her daughters are induced toward
intergenerational and heterosexual incest to reproduce the proper order
between lateral (community) and vertical (divine, generational) axes.
This treatment of the Lot parable offers additional revisions to the pri-
mary psychoanalytic model of Oedipus, supplementing the already well-
developed revisionist models articulated through Electra and Antigone.3
If as Mitchell suggests the Antigone play shows us “the three faces of the
sister who both cares for and destroys: the lateral would-be murderer, the
nurse and the lawgiver” (Mitchell 2003, 57), the Lot parable shows us
the two faces of the sister refracted through lateral lens of sexuality and
reproduction. This chapter takes the story of Lot’s wife as an opening,
a way into the complex problematization of “siblings” offered by Juliet
Mitchell. In Pillar of Salt: Gender, Memory, and the Perils of Looking
Back, Janice Haaken suggests that the allegory of Lot’s wife admon-
ishes against female transgression while also opening up a “disturbing
void”—no one knows what she saw before her transformation—that can
generate new symbolic representations of this “void” (Haaken 1998, 5).
This is perhaps why Lot’s wife has spoken so directly to feminist theo-
rizations and queer revisionings of the tangled relation between gender,
sexuality, and prohibition. Haaken goes on to ask how the parable might
be reimagined if the female siblings told it: “And what stories might
Lot’s daughters have to tell?” (Haaken 1998, 267). She ponders how we
might hear the stories of daughters who are sisters of one another but
also sisters of their own daughters, and so on across the generations?
The question implicitly asks not only what stories, but whose stories can
represent the “void” between lateral and vertical sexualities without fall-
ing into its abyss?
In the readings that follow, I ask how Mitchell’s treatment of
the “void” at the heart of psychoanalytic theory opens up alternative
approaches to lateral and vertical prohibitions and injunctions. I begin
with Mitchell’s own treatment of lateral relationships in Siblings, focused
in particular on how representations of history shape her theorization
of the lawgiving mother. I then turn to the cultural emergence of the
“mean girls” phenomena at roughly the same moment when sibling rela-
tions can, according to Mitchell, finally be represented at the heart of
232 GILLIAN HARKINS
Mother’s Keepers
Mitchell’s Siblings offers a counterhistory of psychoanalytic origin fig-
ures resonant with the parable of Lot. Mitchell implies psychoanalysis is
founded on a “void” very similar to the one encountered and figured by
Lot’s wife: “Psychoanalytic theory is a good illustration of its own thesis:
only what is absent can be represented; what is present cannot be repre-
sented and hence cannot be seen” (Mitchell 2003, 30). Psychoanalysis
represents the void, covering it with catachresis that does not pretend
to manifest the absence as presence but rather to represent it through a
vehicle that has no ground. The figures that emerge to “represent” this
void are always catachrestic, of a different order than the void itself; figures
such as the “law of the father,” the Oedipus complex, or the “primitive
mother” (Mitchell 2003, 51) are ways of representing that which has
been absent. They capture a historical point of exchange, where what
was present disappears and leaves in its trace a figure—such as the Father
of patriarchal order—now available to “represent” the void allegedly cre-
ated by an unrepresentable sovereign power (God in Lot’s case). These
figures appear in the wake of one system of presence, neither capturing
that which was present nor that which remains absent fully in their tenor.
Yet the grounds on which the family stands seem to shift.
Mitchell tracks the movement from God to father to object relations
mother (“primitive mother”) as part of this story of presence and absence,
presentation and representation. Just as Nietzsche figures “God” as the
void that appears in moralism’s wake, Freud figures “patriarchy” at the
site of absence just as patriarchal social relations are waning in power and
authority (are less present); object relations similarly figures “matriar-
chy” or the “primitive mother” in the breach of its social decline. In the
final decades of the twentieth century, adult centrism becomes visible
just as absolute parental power is giving way to more lateral relationships
of power. At this point Foucault can dethrone the king in favor of an
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 233
Mean Girls
It is unclear to me whether Mitchell ultimately thinks lateral relations
are fundamental and merely revealed by changes in historical condition,
or whether lateral relations are themselves historically produced and
therefore subject to displacement. In other words, are lateral relations
an ontological a-priori or are they historically contingent and variable
not only in their representation but in their presence? Is the lawgiving
mother produced or revealed by the representability of sibling relations
in the later twentieth century? Should we think of the lawgiving mother
as akin to Lot’s wife, one historical figure reified facing the void/vortex,
frozen into a pillar of salt for her children? Or is she the equivalent of the
sovereign authority Lot’s wife was banned from seeing in action, mak-
ing Lot’s wife into yet another daughter in this scenario (as wife to Lot,
representing a serial reproductivity that includes her own daughters)? Is
the crisis in the story that Lot’s wife faced the void/vortex and failed to
induce serial differentiation in her children, leaving them equivalent to
her in their reproductive fantasies and therefore prone to vertical incest?
How might we situate Mitchell’s account of sibling relations and serial
representation in its historical moment and across other examples?
Mitchell provides some clues about the answer to these questions
in her own reading of Freud’s figuration of the “death drive.” Freud
arrived at his theory of the death drive only in his late writings, begin-
ning in Beyond the Pleasure Principle, and Mitchell suggests that even
this late account is flawed due to its suppression of “the importance of
siblings” (Mitchell 2003, 35). Once we focus on “sibling murderous-
ness,” the death drive can be seen as a representation of the “psychic
role of ‘death’ ” rather than as a “drive towards annihilation” (Mitchell
2003, 35). Mitchell suggests that Freud uses “death” to represent the
void/vortex she elsewhere describes as “human neo-natal helplessness”
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 237
(Mitchell 2003, 42). Where Freud sees a drive toward annihilation that
he labels “death,” Mitchell sees the representation of death as “inorganic”
stasis (Mitchell 2003, 42) over and against representation as a process or
iteration, both in its performance (the subject survives by constituting
itself and others as figures of difference) and its specific figures (trans-
figuring hate into love, organic vulnerability into sustainable life forms).
Thus “loving one’s sibling like oneself is neither exactly narcissism nor
object-love. It is narcissism transmuted by a hatred that has been over-
come” (Mitchell 2003, 36). This re-reading of the death drive as a drive
to represent depends upon the lawgiving mother, whose failure might be
characterized as a “neglect” (Mitchell 2003, 53) that leads to “a failure of
repression” (Mitchell 2003, 36) and a return of lateral violence and sexu-
ality. This leads Mitchell to align her theory with historical observations
such as “sibling abuse in the West occurs in the context of inadequate
parental supervision and concern” (Mitchell 2003, 53), or that “in war,
both peer-group promiscuity and the rape of same-age enemy women
testify to a regression to the prevalence of sexuality between children in
childhood” (Mitchell 2003, 21).
I propose we follow Mitchell’s lead and take Mitchell’s “lawgiving
mother” as another historical figure, a catachresis before the void/vortex,
in order to explore the ramifications of this figure for treating lateral
relations in recent formations. While Mitchell seems to use violence and
aggression as signs of the law of the mother’s failure, she is very care-
ful to say that the actual mother does not bear responsibility for resur-
gent violence and aggression. There is an association in her formulations
between maternal absence and neglect with unregulated murderousness,
but it is not necessarily the absence of the mother’s law that precipitates
the problem. Instead, she asks, how we might understand violence as
a failure of allowing for lateral regulation on its own terms, without a
lawgiving mother? How might we think about a society in which lateral
regulation operated without that vertical axis? Or, as Mitchell queries,
“Is this external operation of rules and regulations necessary because
our cultural conditions do not allow for their internalization? Where
older siblings rather than parents are the main carers of younger chil-
dren, where children are left alone in their peer groups, are prohibitions
accepted and internalized? Can siblings themselves be each other’s law-
giver?” (Mitchell 2003, 53). I take Mitchell’s questions as an opportu-
nity to think about how the lawgiving mother becomes representable in
psychoanalytic theory just as lateral relations may no longer operate in
relation to this figure. Just as Mitchell suggested in relation to earlier
models of vertical regulation, perhaps lateral relations are imminently
self-regulating in ways that psychoanalytic theory has yet to represent.
238 GILLIAN HARKINS
One might say the lawgiving mother once too present in the clinical
scene arrived in theory just when this role is dwindling socially. Evidence
for this claim might be found in the simultaneous co-emergence of the
“mean girls” phenomenon alongside the appearance of the lawgiving
mother in psychoanalysis. In 2002, Rosalind Wiseman published her
bestselling nonfiction book Queen Bees and Wannabes: Helping Your
Daughters Survive Cliques, Gossips, Boyfriends, and Other Realities of
Adolescence.6 The subtitle of this volume makes maternal self-help into
daughter-help. Mothers learn what might be described as daughter-
directed helping tools that yet situate the mother as a peer, like a daugh-
ter within a lateral milieu. The mother assists with navigation of the
lateral world (rather than regulation on a vertical axis). Here we learn
terms such as “relational aggression” and other modes of peer group
gendering and sexuality fundamentally linked to aggressivity. Tina Fey
wrote the screenplay for the 2004 film Mean Girls (dir. Mark Waters)
based on this book, which became part of a broader cultural phenom-
enon in which the phrase “mean girls” came to represent lateral gendered
formations articulated through aggression and nonvertical/nonsexual-
difference-based sexuality.7
“Mean girls” seems to represent the cultural passing of the “lawgiving
mother” precisely when Mitchell can theorize it. The lawgiving mother
suddenly appears in the clinical scene through its representation in theory;
where she disappears is in the nonpsychoanalytic scenes of “self-help” or
serial representations of mothers-turned-friends. “Mean girls” articulates
a lateral relation but does so in ways that dismantle the vertical axis,
such that mothers and daughters may both participate as “mean girls”
(or their targets) in new fields of sexuality and aggression. While this has
become a stock feature of much recent popular culture, here I will use
Halley Feiffer’s 2013 play How to Make Friends and Kill Them as a quick
example of the contemporary “representation” of lateral relations among
girls in the absence of a lawgiving mother. How to Make Friends and Kill
Them focuses on the relations among three characters, Ada, Sam, and
Dorrie, as their lives change (and remain the same) across three tempo-
ral settings: childhood, teenage, and young adulthood. The play begins
in childhood, where sisters Ada and Sam have been “left to their own
devices by their alcoholic mother,” according to the play synopsis offered
by Rattlesnake Theater.8 The mother never appears on stage, although
Ada comes to stand in the place of the mother as she sways drunkenly
through the final young adult sequence of the play. During the opening
“Childhood” sequence, the audience is introduced to Ada and Sam in a
kitchen setting, where Sam repeats the phrase “you’re so pretty” to Ada
while she brushes her hair and asks for hugs. Ada is alternately preening
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 239
and enraged at the subservient Sam, whom she calls “gay” whenever
Sam expresses longing for physical contact. Eventually Dorrie enters the
scene, a classmate from school whose physical and psychological abjec-
tion triangulates the aggressivity and desire otherwise tightly routed
between Ada and Sam.
The play’s seemingly domestic setting is belied by the heightened styl-
ization of dialogue and performance, which earns How to Make Friends its
description as “surrealist” or “theater of the absurd” in various reviews.
The actors deliver lines with an intensity of affect far in excess of natural-
ist expectations, while their physical movements vacillate between the
outsized and the miniaturized in a tempo not entirely tuned to the dia-
logue. Key phrases and gestures are repeated from childhood to teenage
to young adulthood, and the characters seem to slip in and out of time
as they attempt to represent their relations to themselves and each other.
“It’s never weird with us, is it?” one sister asks the other, while love and
hate ripple across their bodies and voices. Neil Genzlinger’s New York
Times theater review situates the play directly in the “mean-girl genre,”
in which the characters find “ways to fill each other up and to tear each
other down” (New York Times 2013). Ultimately the character’s attempts
to identify with and differentiate from each other drive toward death.
Dorrie enters not as lawgiving mother, but as serial nonsibling through
whom Ada and Sam will represent their difference from and desire for
each other. By the time they have moved from childhood to teenage to
young adulthood, murderous aggressivity will win out over lateral sexu-
ality: Sam will kiss Ada passionately while she is semi-unconscious from
alcohol; Ada will push Sam down the stairs and leave her paralyzed; and
Sam will strangle Dorrie to prove that only she and Ada belong in their
childhood home.
The title of the play reminds us of the drive toward death implied in
lateral relations. Riffing on How to Win Friends and Influence People
(Carnegie1936) and How to Lose Friends and Alienate People (Tressler
2001), the play suggests that the seeming opposites “influence” and
“alienate” are resolved when mean girls kill. To sway or repulse offer
two possible modes of social agency; killing is an antisocial agency that
resolves tensions between love and hate by annihilating those serial
others marked “friends.” This is self-help meets serial killer genre. In the
serial killer genre, the presence of doubles inevitably predicts violence to
come. The doppelganger represents the need for serial violence in order
to restore identity to the one.9 In the play’s encounter between self-help
and serial killing, the childhood refusal to make “vertical” adjustments
over time necessitates the representation of “mean girls.” In this avant-
garde production, the mean girl genre is stylized into representability
240 GILLIAN HARKINS
in ways that reveal the void or vortex of the lawgiving mother. This
representation marks the loss of lawgiving motherhood as an unrec-
ognized presence, representing it as the absence that draws things to it
until self-help becomes serial killing. Thus the play represents Mitchell’s
suggestion that “sibling sexuality ranges from sex with someone whom
one experiences as the same, to sex with someone whose difference
one wants to obliterate” (Mitchell 2003, 39). But here the mean girl
genre reveals as well the specific gendering of lateral sexuality. Citing
Mitchell again: “sibling relations prioritize experiences such as the fear
of annihilation, a fear associated with girls, in contrast to the male fear
of castration” (Mitchell 2003, 3–4). Girls become the representation
of siblings as such; when sisters go unregulated, mean girls will drive
onwards toward death.
The “mean girls” phenomenon provides one way to explore how the
absence of a lawgiving mother leads to the presence of aggressivity and
lateral sexuality. How to Make Friends and Then Kill Them seems to
represent this logic as it unfolds across childhood, teenage, and young
adulthood. But this raises additional questions about how Mitchell’s own
historicization works. It might be said that “mean girl” phenomena has
existed far longer than its early 2000s depiction as itself a kind of regula-
tory principle governing the representation and circulation of lateral gen-
der relations. Certainly North American high school relations had been
depicted as riddled with enmity and aggression since the 1950s, and the
specific genre now associated with “mean girls” was already articulated
in its current form in 1980s teen movies such as Pretty in Pink (Howard
Deutch 1986) or Heathers (Michael Lehmann 1988). Perhaps the emer-
gence of “mean girls” as representation—as recognizable genre—fits
with Mitchell’s own suggestion that what is present cannot be repre-
sented, and what is represented no longer appears as presence. The phe-
nomenon of “mean girls” may not represent the absence of the lawgiving
mother so much as the presence of new mechanisms of lateral regulation.
In other words, perhaps the presence of mean girls has itself become rep-
resentation just as the regulatory principle of gendered cruelty and erotic
violence gives way to other gendered modes and erotic mechanisms orga-
nizing lateral relationship.
Keeping House
In these final sections I would like to consider what happens if we do
not presume that the absence of a lawgiving mother will reveal a fun-
damental aggressivity of girlhood. What if the representation of “mean
girls” does indicate that some other forms of regulation are currently
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 241
(Robinson 1980, 19). She pays attention to how her daughters [or the
“girls” (Robinson 1980, 10)] are differentiated by “customs and habits”:
“Sylvie took her coffee with two lumps of sugar, Helen liked her toast
dark, and Molly took hers without butter” (Robinson 1980, 15). She
represents her own difference from them on “purpose, to be what she
seemed to be so that her children would never be startled or surprised,
and to take on all the postures and vestments of matron, to differentiate
her life from theirs, so that her children would never feel intruded upon”
(Robinson 1980, 19). She represents herself as differentiated mother to
allow her children to self-differentiate and move forward into “respect-
able” (Robinson 1980, 10) lateral and vertical relations.
And yet this perfect lawgiving differentiation yields daughters who
disappear. Molly goes on missionary work in China; Helen (Ruth’s
mother) ultimately kills herself in the same lake that claimed her father;
and Sylvie travels the continent as an itinerant. Helen and Sylvie both
marry, but neither retain their husbands and Helen returns her children
to Fingerbone only to end her own life. Ruth and Lucille are raised by
their grandmother for five years before she dies and leaves them with her
sisters-in-law Nona and Lily, who leave them in turn with their mother’s
sister Sylvie, who returns to Fingerbone to live with in the house with
them. Despite the perfect telos of Housekeeping’s origin story—from
(colonial) patriarchal law to primitive mother to lawgiving mother—
latera l sisterhood does not transition successfully into lateral hetero-
sexual coupling and vertical mothering. Marriages are entered into and
exited without significance. A seemingly new generation of female sib-
lings are returned to their point of generational departure and reconsti-
tuted among existing female sibling relations (the various sisters). And
the house remains.
At this point in the story the house becomes the central regulatory
condition for relationality. “We and the house were Sylvie’s” (Robinson
1980, 59), Ruth remarks. Sylvie’s itinerant lifestyle quickly takes over the
house, which becomes filled with dirt and debris. While “Sylvie talked
a great deal about housekeeping” (Robinson 1980, 85), she “considered
accumulation to be the essence of housekeeping, and because she con-
sidered the hoarding of worthless things to be proof of a particularly
scrupulous thrift” (Robinson 1980, 180). Ruth comes to accept Sylvie’s
unique approach to bourgeois respectability, but Lucille demands more
normative accumulation and “hated everything that had to do with
transience” (Robinson 1980, 103). Lucille takes on the project of self-
improvement as a “tense and passionate campaign to naturalize herself
to” the normal world (Robinson 1980, 95), giving up on household
respectability and focusing instead on creating proper lateral relations
244 GILLIAN HARKINS
with peers. Lucille dresses them up, saying “That’s Sylvie’s house now”
and “We have to improve ourselves!” (Robinson 1980, 123) before she
ultimately gives up on Ruth and leaves to move in with “Miss Royce, the
Home Economics teacher” (Robinson 1980, 140). Ultimately Lucille
leaves the house behind to affirm that her “loyalties were with the other
world” (Robinson 1980, 95), while Sylvie and Ruth end the novel by
burning the house down and taking flight across the bridge (over the
lake that claimed both grandfather and mother).
The house itself, and the demand to make it a home, becomes the
“neonatal trauma” around which the novel is built. But in this instance it
is a trauma of natality. Hannah Arendt (1958) uses “natality” as a figure
for both birth and action, culling the nuances of labor from its conflation
with commodification in the wage. Here “women’s work” is the work
of home making and housekeeping, including the making and keeping
of kin and the management of proper vertical and lateral axes. By this
measurement, the clan is a spectacular failure. But no specific law of the
mother is to blame. Instead, the novel returns to “natality” as its vortex,
its first trauma, and it figures the movement of serial representation from
there. The conflation of labor with the wage—outside the home—is a
“presence” that creates the fundamental trauma of natality. The labor
of birth and work, of “creation,” is what therefore must be represented
in order for serial differentiation to secure possibilities for movement
and change. Here the house represents the function Mitchell attributes
to the “lawgiving mother.” It is the house, its spatial relations of ceiling
and floor, inside and outside, dirt and cleanliness, which inaugurates
serial differentiation and its representation in gendered forms. What was
demanded as “women’s work” becomes a process of serial differentia-
tion represented through various modes of making life. In place of an
aggressive drive toward death, gendering lateral relations takes shape as
a movement toward life.
This is made explicit when Ruth encounters a group of “children” in
the woods. After Lucille leaves their home, Sylvie takes Ruth into the
woods and introduces her to lateral relations very different from those
coveted by Lucille. Sylvie explains that people live in the woods, “and
now and then I’m sure there are children around me” (Robinson 1980,
148). Sylvie disappears for an extended period of time while a cold and
hungry Ruth is left outdoors to “watch for the children” (Robinson
1980, 151). As she waits to see the children, Ruth describes the woods
as follows: “Imagine a Carthage sown with salt, and all the sowers gone,
and the seeds lain however long in the earth, till there rose finally in
vegetable profusion leaves and trees of rime and brine” (Robinson 1980,
152). Here the woods are a “vegetable profusion” grown from seeds
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 245
of salt long ago sown as the sign of imperial conquest.11 The woods
become in Ruth’s mind a profusion of organic matter growing from
the remains of human civilization, itself the consequence of imperial
conflicts and geographies of expansion. The “rime and brine” of the
present are genealogical; seeds of salt grow icy “trees” that neither sig-
nify families (vehicle) nor potential material (tenor) from which to build
proper houses (ground).
It is this process of representation, the potentiality of the woods to
enable Ruth to imagine “children” outside of either families or houses,
that leads into her lengthy meditation on Lot’s wife in the wilderness:
If there had been snow I would have made a statue, a woman to stand
along the path, among the trees. The children would have come close,
to look at her. Lot’s wife was salt and barren, because she was full
of loss and mourning, and looked back. But here rare flowers would
gleam in her hair, and on her breast, and in her hands, and there would
be children all around her, to love and marvel at her for her beauty, and
to laugh at her extravagant adornments, as if they had set the flowers
in her hair and thrown down all the flowers at her feet, and they would
forgive her, eagerly and lavishly, for turning away, though she never
asked to be forgiven. Though her hands were ice and did not touch
them, she would be more than mother to them, she so calm, so still,
and they such wild and orphan things. (Robinson 1980, 153)
Ruth imagines her own capacity to create outside the confines of the
household. “If there had been snow”: a counterfactual from which is
born Ruth’s natal power. Ruth would have made a statue of a woman
whose grief froze her looking into the past, but who now appears cov-
ered in a mantle of flowers that draw the children to her. Lot’s wife
would have no longer been barren, but would instead have many children
around her to “love and marvel” at her. And the children in turn would
imagine that it was their attention, their own natal power, which made
her blossom. Lot’s wife once turned to salt when she turned away from
her own daughters; here the wild orphan children would forgive her “for
turning away” though she does not ask it, and would welcome her still
icy hands as calming, not indifferent.
Ruth imagines the statue in a place she thinks would draw children,
where the “gleaming water spilled to the tips of branches” and “frost
at the foot of each tree” would make them return “to see it again”
(Robinson 1980, 153). This is not a death drive toward an inorganic
state, but a longing to see figures that would represent an otherwise
“barren” loss. The children’s compulsion to repeat, as Ruth imagines
it, is a desire to create life, from root to branch. So she places a statue of
246 GILLIAN HARKINS
the lawgiving mother where there had been only loss, only a past that
has turned away. This ideal figure is a calm detached mother who asks
for nothing and thereby becomes “more than mother.” Ruth longs to be
that lawgiving mother to the wild orphan children, but she also imagines
them along a lateral plane, as peers who might share her consciousness
(as she once did with Lucille). Thus she imagines the “consciousness”
that she senses in the woods as “persistent and teasing and ungentle, the
way half-wild, lonely children are” (Robinson 1980, 154). This creates
an impossible desire: “I knew that if I turned however quickly to look
behind me the consciousness behind me would not still be there, and
would only come closer when I turned away again” (Robinson 1980,
154). Ruth is both Lot’s wife and the children she left behind. She can-
not look back, to genealogy or the home, nor can she give up the desire
to create figures that represent difference.
“If there had been snow,” Lot’s wife would have become the lawgiving
mother.
But there is not snow. Instead there is salt, where Lot’s wife becomes
part of the growth of salty rime branches from the seeds of a Carthage
past. Ruth joins the children she imagines in this alternative family tree,
where the drive to represent the void constitutes a lateral natality that
leads away from the neonatal trauma of the house. “For need can blos-
som into all the compensation it requires,” we are told. “To crave and to
have are as like as a thing and its shadow” (Robinson 1980, 152). Such a
“blossoming” is distinct from a drive toward death, death as the repre-
sentation of the void/vortex, or the house as a substitute for death. Here
“blossoming” is organic growth from “need” that makes the capacity
to create—to figure and materialize figuration in new grounds—into
its own “compensation.” Craving becomes “like” a “thing”; it fig-
ures “thing” as if a presence even as it makes all “having” into mere
“shadow.” Thus need enables the making of likenesses that masquerade
as things, need “blossoms” into craving and makes “having” into the
mere ghosts of things, into “shadows.” The children in the woods are
such “blossoms” on this salty family tree; neither thing nor shadow,
they are the likenesses through which natal trauma is transfigured into
a livable life.
The imaginary encounter with these children in the woods helps clarify
the lateral relations among the “sisters,” Sylvia, Ruth, and Lucille. Once
the “we” of Lucille and Ruth was “almost as a single consciousness”
(Robinson 1980, 98), but Lucille has decided they need other friends
and shifted her “loyalties [to] the other world” (Robinson 1980, 95).12
After her encounter with the children in the woods, Ruth realizes that
“having a sister or a friend is like sitting at night in a lighted house.
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 247
Those outside can watch you if they want, but you need not see them”
(Robinson 1980, 154). But without Lucille, she describes herself as
“turned out of house” (ibid.): “Now there was neither threshold nor
sill between me and these cold, solitary children who almost breathed
against my neck and almost touched my hair” (ibid.). At first Ruth feels
herself abandoned, but identifying with the “consciousness” of the serial
children who are not bothered by being cast out, she decides, “it is better
to have nothing” (Robinson 1980, 159). Having “nothing” is however
having Sylvie: Sylvie says Ruth is “like another sister to me” (Robinson
1980, 182); Ruth thinks “Sylvie and I (I think that night we were almost
a single person)” (Robinson 1980, 209). To crave is to make likeness into
things, to have likeness as the shadow that is oneself.
The police and neighbors worry about this blurring of the lateral
and vertical axes, concerned that Sylvie is “making a transient” of Ruth
by riding a freight car (Robinson 1980, 177). “When did I become so
unlike other people?” (Robinson 1980, 214), Ruth wonders after the two
burn down the house and walk across the bridge to leave town. She lists
the trauma of natality—her conception and desertion by her mother—
as normal trauma that should in fact make her like other people. Birth
and abandonment by the mother are normal traumas that make people
into serial replicas of familiar difference. Instead Ruth opines, “I believe
it was the crossing of the bridge that changed me finally” (Robinson
1980, 215). In the novel gender differentiation ultimately takes place
through stasis and movement; there are those who keep house, and
those who move through open space. Ruth and Sylvie become unlike
others by being “cast out to wander, and there was an end to house-
keeping” (Robinson 1980, 209). But the novel also situates this gen-
dering as historically and socially specific. It is not gendering as such,
but late twentieth-century gendering for whiteness as a social formation
attached to the novel’s colonial genealogy of “manifest domesticity”
(Kaplan 2005). The capacity to use imagination to create difference, to
usurp the role of the lawgiving mother and constitute new formations
of likeness, emerges from the particular natal trauma of householding
on the Western front.
All Sewn Up
Hedwig and the Angry Inch completes this meditation with the creative
destruction of “rock-n-roll” as gender performance.13 The show opens
with Yitzhak, one of Hedwig’s doubles/nemeses who is also her husband,
shouting to the audience: “Ladies and Gentlemen, whether you like it or
not . . . Hedwig!”14 In the opening line of the rock opera, Yitzhak invokes
248 GILLIAN HARKINS
one of the most famous hailings of sexual difference to introduce the star
of the show-within-a-show, the transgender performer Hedwig. But here
Lacan’s children are not riding a train that promised to arrive at its sexu-
ally differentiated destinations, “Ladies” and “Gentlemen,” but rather
are departing from those stations to find their way toward a new lateral
platform (Lacan 1957, 146–178). Hedwig’s performance of celebrity is a
constant insistence on singularity, even as the show itself is constituted
on the principle of doublings that are one. From “The Origins of Love,”
a retelling of Plato’s tale of how humans were driven into three types by
Zeus, to the doubling of Yitzhak and Hedwig (crossing and prohibiting
genders and denying room enough for two on the stage), to the erotic
entanglement of Hedwig and Tommy Gnosis, both played by a single
actor on stage but by two different actors in the film adaptation.15 The
stage show unfolds as an on-stage monologue delivered by Hedwig, who
is playing a show in a minor venue while Tommy Gnosis, her former lover
and now wildly successful protégé, performs in a major venue nearby. In
the stage production the same actor, as Hedwig, performs all the roles
save that of Yitzhak and the on-stage band members. In the film produc-
tion, one actor performs adult Hansel/Hedwig while all other existing
roles, and new additional roles, are embodied in separate actors. Thus
the seriality performed in and as “Hedwig” in the stage version is dis-
placed literally onto the screen, as a representation of serial embodied
difference.
This process of representing seriality—as one on stage, as multiple on
screen—problematizes the dynamics of absence/presence embedded in
accounts of the lawgiving mother and “neonatal trauma” thus far. The
allegedly physical borders of sexual difference are here reconstituted as
the spatial imaginaries of serial representability. Early on in the show
Hedwig tells the story of her youth in East Berlin, when she was a young
“girlyboy” called “Hansel” who loved to listen to rock music on the
radio (“Midnight Radio”). When the young adult Hansel is mistaken
for a young girl by US soldier Luther Robinson, whose offer of candy
as seduction implies a vertical relation, Hansel’s mother inaugurates a
new lateral relationship between them by providing Hansel with her own
identity: Hedwig. The mother provides a name, passport, and “sex” by
arranging the operation to make Hansel Hedwig. This will enable Luther
and Hansel to flee East Berlin through marriage once Hansel “becomes”
Hedwig/a woman/the mother. In the film production, this plays out as
a visual transformation in which many characters have a role. Hansel/
Hedwig and Hedwig are two, with a passport and operation promis-
ing to make them like one. In the stage production, however, only one
performer in one costume performs these characters on stage, creating
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 249
Notes
1. On the story’s relation to twentieth-century spectatorship, see
Martin Harries, Forgetting Lot’s Wife: On Destructive Spectatorship,
New York: Fordham University Press, 2007.
2. Siblings builds upon Mitchell’s earlier study of hysteria and siblings,
Mad Men and Medusas: Reclaiming Hysteria and the Effects of Sibling
Relations on the Human Condition, New York: Basic Books, 2000.
3. See for example Judith Butler, Antigone’s Claim: Kinship between
Life and Death, New York: Columbia University Press, 2002.
4. A note on my own method: While it troubles me to touch on each
of these texts only in passing, I find myself compelled to offer serial
observations rather than a single sustained reading of one sample
text in order to situate Mitchell’s psychoanalytic theory in relation to
historically specific moments of sibling representation.
5. Mitchell’s account of the social conditions of psychic life is beyond
the scope of this chapter; “social changes take generations to affect
the psychology of the unconscious ego and superego but nevertheless
they do have a place there in the end” (49).
6. On the mean girls phenomena see Jessica Ringrose, “A New Universal
Mean Girl: Examining the Discursive Construction and Social
Regulation of a New Feminine Pathology” Feminism & Psychology,
16.4 (2006): 405–424 and Emily Ryalls, “Demonizing ‘Mean Girls’
in the News: Was Pheobe Prince ‘Bullied to Death’?” Communication,
Culture & Critique, 5.3 (September 2012): 463–481.
7. Mark Water, Dir. Script Tina Fey. Mean Girls (2004). See also
Margert Talbot, “Girls Just Want to Be Mean” The New York Times
(February 22, 2002).
8. Rattlestick Playwrights Theater website: http://www.rattlestick.org
/how-to-make-friends-and-then-kill-them/.
9. The adult genre figures homoerotic desire and the impulse to anni-
hilate and replace as childlike in fixation and frequently seeking
Oedipal triangulation with an erotic other (in which they displace
the doppleganger for themselves); see Lisa Duggan, Sapphic Slashers:
Sex, Violence and American Modernity, Durham: Duke University
Press, 2001; Mark Seltzer, Serial Killers: Death and Life in America’s
Wound Culture, New York: Routledge, 1998.
10. A review of criticism on Housekeeping exceeds the scope of this essay;
relevant articles include W. Burke, “Border Crossings in Marilynne
Robinson’s Housekeeping” MFS: Modern Fiction Studies 37.4
(Winter 1991): 716–724; Christine Caver, “Nothing Left to Lose:
Housekeeping’s Strange Freedoms” American Literature 68.1 (1996):
111–137; G. Handley, “The Metaphysics of Ecology in Marilynne
Robinson’s Housekeeping” MFS: Modern Fiction Studies 55.3 (Fall
2009): 496–521; T. Hedrick, “ ‘The Perimeters of Our Wandering Are
Nowhere’: Breaching the Domestic in Housekeeping” Critique: Studies
S I S T E R S AT T H E G AT E 253
References
Arendt, Hannah. 1998. The Human Condition (1958) Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Carnegie, Dale. 1998. How to Win Friends and Influence People (1936), New
York: Pocket Books.
Feiffer, Halley. 2013. How to Make Friends and Then Kill Them. Directed by
Kip Fagan. Rattlestick Playwrights Theater.
Foucault, Michel. The History of Sexuality, Volume I: An Introduction, Trans.
Robert Hurley, New York: Vintage, 1978.
254 GILLIAN HARKINS
Haaken, Janice. 1998. Pillar of Salt: Gender, Memory, and the Perils of
Looking Back, New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP.
Kaplan, Amy. 2005. The Anarchy of Empire in the Making of U.S. Culture,
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Lacan, Jacques. [1957] 1977. “The Agency of the Letter in the Unconscious,
or Reason Since Freud.” Écrits: a Selection. Trans. Alan Sheridan. London:
Tavistock, 146–178.
Mitchell, John Cameron. 1998. Hedwig and the Angry Inch. Jane Street
Theater. Film adaptation 2001, Director John Cameron Mitchell.
Mitchell, Juliet. 2003. Siblings: Sex and Violence, Cambridge, UK: Polity
Press.
Morgaga, Cherrie and Anzaldua, Gloria, eds. 1984. This Bridge Called My
Back: Writings by Radical Women of Color, New York: Kitchen Table
Press.
Pateman, Carole. 1988. The Sexual Contract, Stanford: Stanford University
Press.
Robinson, Marilynne. 1980. Housekeeping, New York: Picador.
Tressler, Irving Dart. 2011. How to Lose Friends and Alienate People (1937).
CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform.
Williams, Raymond. 1985. Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society,
New York: Oxford University Press.
Wiseman, Rosalind. 2002. Queen Bees and Wannabes: Helping Your
Daughters Survive Cliques, Gossips, Boyfriends, and Other Realities of
Adolescence, New York: Crown.
Chapter 12
Preti Taneja
When sibling theory started to take shape in your mind, how far
then, did you sense the implications it could have?
That’s quite a difficult question to answer. It was such a revelation,
it didn’t really occur to me to wonder about its implications as a first
response to that revelation. I was just completely stunned—why is nobody
talking about this? First of all I thought siblings were nowhere. Then
that they are absolutely everywhere. I had re-read all the clinical material
and the historical material and anthropological material and they were
at every turn. A little while later I went to a conference on siblings, in
the European University in Florence with some historians who had been
working on cousins and affinal kinship, including siblings. Everyone was
excellent—Lee Davidoff, David Sabean. They were very welcoming but
dismissive of my naivety, my sense of revelation. Naturally, as they rightly
stressed, they had known about this all along. In a way, indeed they
had, but they hadn’t seen how staggering it was. They had been writing
about siblings and aunts and uncles and the cousinage and all of the rest
of it, the lateral was of course part of the field that they were looking
at. However, my amazement wasn’t diminished by their dismissing it. It
still seemed to me quite staggering. For them, as for most clinicians, of
course siblings were there. For me it was the size of the presence of the
sibling dimension and the size of the absence of this dimension in our
overarching thinking that staggering. So it was a revelation on the spot
of the present time, rather than the future looking how big the impli-
cations were. It was already there, huge—why wasn’t anybody making
anything of the fact that it was so huge?
I want to jump forwards in time to today, and ask you how you have
seen that theory manifest itself in the popular and in the public
256 P R E T I TA N E J A
I was looking at this question of why, despite all the social changes that
we do effect, equal pay, the vote etcetera still there is this extraordinary
inequality. Even when it seems that the economy, the democracy, com-
munism, socialism when, we should be getting closer to equality, we are
often two steps forward and one step backwards, or one step forwards
and two steps backwards—there is always that backwards drift, a sort of
entropy within sexual difference, and that’s what I was looking at 40 years
ago, but on the vertical axis. I wasn’t looking at the horizontal. However,
when I went back because it’s the 40th anniversary of Psychoanalysis and
Feminism and Judith Butler refers to the last chapter, I was amazed to
find how much there is on siblings in my conclusion.
In the general situation of sexism, men dominate over women. In the
specific culture of patriarchy, fathers dominate over brothers. So there is
a suppression of women and an oversight of siblings. There is the domi-
nance of the vertical. Even someone whose work is quite exceptional, and
who includes siblings and a “sibling complex” like René Kaës makes them
only Oedipal. I go back to a very successful book by Carole Pateman—
The Sexual Contract, (1988) in which she argues very effectively about
the importance of the lateral sexual contract between brothers. As indeed
does Freud in Totem and Taboo. But for both of them it is still in terms
of patriarchy, instead of seeing it in terms of fratriarchy. There is an essay
by Cynthia Cockburn saying we don’t use andrarchy and fratriarchy; if
we do they don’t have staying power. Well why don’t they have staying
power? So people are observing it all again, but not picking up on the
peculiarity of it, as a question. I mean the peculiarity of the simultaneous
overwhelming presence of siblings in our observations, and their over-
whelming absence in theory. I would now go further and ask—why don’t
we have them in the theory? That is a question in itself.
That is actually my next question. Let’s get to the silt at the bottom
of the river and disturb it a little bit, and ask why that is the case.
I don’t know that I have gone there yet. I think that it is probably part of
the “undertow,” the entropy. Primarily, the undertow belongs to sexual
difference, which is only a marker but one that falls over reproduction.
Reproduction is the vertical axis where we reproduce, like our mothers
and fathers before us. It is inter-generational, and we have to take over
from them in that they have to die and we have to take over and be life,
as it were, and give life. And I think that’s where the undertow on the
position of women and men is really experienced. Whereas I see gender
as a lateral relationship; siblings are the starting point of the horizontal
axis. The gendered sibling toddler must become a big girl or boy in the
social group it forms and finds. It is still gendered, but there is a gender
H O W C A N W E L I V E O U R S E LV E S ? 259
But really the idea that we are all bisexual, that gender can be this
much more flexible formation of kinship and formation of families
and different kinds of ways of thinking about social groups and
in time things will change—in its own way that is as frightening
and radical as the idea of what you call “the rock in the stream,”
that is always stopping us from progressing, this entropy pulling us
back—F. Scott Fitzgerald describes us as beating on, boats against
the current, borne back ceaselessly into the past. Gender and sexual
difference are two radical and scary ideas for contemporary society.
Exactly. I found it scary because I remembered the conclusion to Women
the Longest Revolution. (I generally try to end my book on an up note
that gets missed because the tenor of the books is so dismal that the fact
that I look for a way out gets missed!) It’s exactly that sense of liberation,
or liberality that ends the 1966 article (the first thing on this question I
published.) In the mid-1960s with the sexual revolution sexuality seemed
the weakest link, where change would come. I looked at my 1966 hopes
in 2000 and thought, well wait a minute, this is exactly where everything
has gone pear-shaped in a terrible way—for example, the sexual exploita-
tion of women is now paramount.
Women the Longest Revolution uses the weakest link to look for the
possibility of change. That was just before, or on the cusp of the Women’s
Movement. Psychoanalysis and Feminism, which was written at the height
of second-wave feminism, argues that we have to address what is intrac-
table, what is important, is what is most intractable—as Jacqueline Rose
points out in her reply to Butler. But you’re asking a question more about
something scarier in the contemplation of the fluidity of gender.
. . . I think that people who look forward to that, they are looking
forward to a nongendered family. There have been all sorts of probably
260 P R E T I TA N E J A
If you look at the way in which marriage has been made legal for
homosexual couples in some places, and yet in other parts of the
world, it is illegal, you would be killed—we have this move forwards
and the move backwards, and sexual difference seems to underpin
that fear.
Yes in the same way we can celebrate all these new reproductive technolo-
gies that liberate sexual reproduction among the rich. Also rich nations
and individuals are moving towards nonreproductive populations, and
having the poor to care for children if they have them, and the poor are
still having children in the old way. So a big divide will be rich and poor
around reproduction. You may get nongendered in the two-career fam-
ily as it used to be called, but you will still get a gender-division in the
people looking after those children. We can’t entirely escape other people
in the world—so even if the rich don’t reproduce, or marginally repro-
duce, and are nongendered, they are going to be surrounded by the rest
of the world that is gendered and in a divisive way, and reproductive in a
sexually differentiated way, and above all, highly sexually exploitative.
You have been challenged on your use of the word “trauma” in sib-
ling theory. Why do you think that resistance to the idea of it being
trauma exists?
Yes, it has been very well challenged in an extremely interesting article by
Claudia Lament; it is very good to have it raised with such intelligence
and sensibility to the whole problem. It was a question I started with
early on because another very good book by psychoanalysts preceded
my own on siblings—Vamik D. Volkan and Gabriele Ast’s Siblings in the
Unconscious and Psychopathology (1997). Sometimes they call the new
baby a “difficulty” and sometimes they call it a “trauma” for the older
child. Then I found Winnicott referring to a “separation trauma” from
the mother but not a sibling trauma, when I was already calling it a sib-
ling trauma. That seemed to legitimate calling this a trauma. The clinical
work indicated that it is traumatic. A pathological outcome will be traced
back to the pre-Oedipal experience but only a footnote will mention that
this was a time of the birth of the new baby.
It first occurred to me as a trauma because I was studying male hys-
teria. The hysteric always produces a trauma. But it’s as though they
have misplaced the trauma, or it got lost. The traumatic experience is
indicated by a crazy fear or phobia. The trauma is always something else
to what it could possibly be. The trauma in male hysteria, goes back to
H O W C A N W E L I V E O U R S E LV E S ? 261
I think it’s a law of the mother, it’s a real prohibition: “you will lose
me, I will separate from you if you do this,” and nobody wants to lose
their mother. I mean what do people cry for on the battlefield? They
need their mother, always. They can criticize their mother till the cows
come home; nobody else must do so because it is a real threat, a real
danger. There’s an earthquake—and you want your mother. But that is
not the mother of patriarchy, that’s a mother who threatened to sepa-
rate because you might have murdered, or had incest with your sibling.
After all, she did, in a sense separate, by having a sibling, who took over
your role as the baby. So it’s a threat with a possible meaning to it, just
as castration is a threat with a possible meaning to it, because women
are perceived as “already castrated” because the mother doesn’t have a
penis. Those are threats—you look at reality, and think “Oh My God,
that could happen.” This is all necessary trauma—to grow up we have
to know deep down that there are people other in the world as impor-
tant as us. As with the Oedipus complex, that can come back with any
other trauma.
Yes it’s true that on an empirical level the idea of losing one’s mother
is the great schism, in a way—it contains within it the idea of losing
oneself in the world. I’m not denigrating the idea of losing the father,
because of course that’s awful, but the idea of losing a mother, and
the betrayal that comes with that—
Yes, I think if we look at it Oedipally, the loss of father is probably also
that for the boy, and the loss of mother stays that for the girl. But if we
look just at separation from the mother in terms of the Law of the Mother,
then I think for the girl and boy it’s really terrifying to lose your mother.
This book covers a range of subjects yet it overall refrains from inves-
tigating the wider implications of sibling theory that you have articu-
lated in articles such as “The Law of the Mother: Sibling Trauma and
the Brotherhood of War.” Could you outline that thinking here?
I think that because we have seen the family largely as developing into
society, or society grown up out of the family, we haven’t seen this other
aspect of society—the repudiation of the family after the threat of separa-
tion from the mother, where she pushes the child out of the family and
into the social group. In a way this is a very positive thing, I think the
latency child is a very interesting child, a very creative child and those
childhood relationships are marvelous. I heard J. K. Rowling criticized
on a radio program for putting Harry Potter in such an elitist situation as
264 P R E T I TA N E J A
a boarding school and she said, you know, children are only interesting
at that age when they are on their own, and it was a good device to get
them away from the family. She’s absolutely right: children are fascinating
when they are first in those groups, very loving, very creative. But they
also have those first experiences of best friends and enemies, bullying.
Sibling theory effects how we look at war, and how we look at gender-
ing, as dividing between gendered girls who are not warlike, and gen-
dered males who are boys who have to become warlike. And of course
because there is fluidity—men can be pacifists and take a feminine posi-
tion, and women can equally be warlike, and commit sexual abuse and
throw bombs etc.—because there is more flexibility—but actually as
a definition, these lateral boys become warriors and these lateral girls
become nurses.
We need to think differently about society in relation to war and war
in relation to society. Put simply we always think of it as society creates
war, whereas reading through siblings and gender it is war that creates
society. It isn’t just the family and kinship, or class or race or anything
whatever that constructs society: war itself constructs society, as much
but differently from kinship. So you have kinship marriages and kinship
alliances but you also have absolutely built in a situation of war because
that is what society has been created for; war creates it.
the positive social group, the candidates for war are also a precondition
for that social group. There has to be a social group that is disowned or
attacked, that’s where the murderousness goes. Then we bring in a gen-
der perspective and say, well, this means that gender female goes into the
“life” or positive side of the social group and become future exchange
objects in a kinship group; wives, partners etc. What happens to the boy?
He becomes the soldier.
Daru Huppert, in Siblings and Sexuality, also talks about that irrita-
bility which is very interesting, and somehow because the sibling is
so close to oneself, a sort of mimesis almost . . .
Yes, that is very important for what I am interested in now, in my work
on intersubjectivity; that sort of mirroring of the self, as with Viola in
Twelfth Night, that you pointed out to me recently—she just is Sebastian
so who else is she, if he’s dead, where is she? It’s that mirroring which is
different from the Lacanian mirroring where the ego is constructed in
alienation. And that’s what irritability is, it is something on your skin so
to speak. It is about the minimal difference that exists between siblings:
too close is irritation.
War is always with us, so on the horizontal axis and on gender distinc-
tions, we have to struggle for peace. Because of the possibility of gender
flexibility there could be a struggle for peace. War and its gendering
brotherhoods can be horrific but it is not the same as the “undertow”
I wrote about with sexual difference in Psychoanalysis and Feminism.
Art also lets the creator off in a way, because imagination comes
into play, and to fictionalize or to create sculpture, you don’t have
to show your workings
Absolutely, you just show the final result and you leave it to the other
person to make what they can of it as well. You can’t really direct the
reception, if you are trying too hard to direct the reception, you are try-
ing too much in the conscious field. It is also to do with—how terrible it
was when we bombed the libraries and museums in Baghdad: there was
something if possible—an excess, a supplement to the terrible violence,
a madness beyond the mad. If it is: shall we save this museum or save
this school, of course, you save the school. But there is actually some-
thing horrific about the destructiveness of the good things of civiliza-
tion. Of course if someone gave me that choice I would save the children,
obviously, but what a horrendous choice, because you are going to the
heart of something that is the best about humanity. So that even if you
know it’s a drone that has been put in a museum, it has been put there
for its aesthetic quality, not for its destructive quality.
Where next for the theory and for psychoanalysis’ relevance to the
conditions of our times—there is greater hysteria in patriarchy,
trauma from war, ongoing gender violence . . . ?
Well just take the concept of a war on terror. It’s a new concept of war.
There have always been terrorists but no one before has gone to war with
the world. “War on terror” could tell you more about sibling theory, and
sibling theory could tell you more about the war on terror. That seems to
me to be a matter of urgency.
270 P R E T I TA N E J A
Yes the exciting thing about this project is that even though psycho-
analysis might only apply to one-fifth of the world or whatever, for
good or for ill, because of colonialism, Shakespeare does [apply to
the world].
Yes, I hadn’t thought of that, quite right. Many people think Freud is
totally irrelevant, but actually what he is looking at is not irrelevant,
and his way of looking at is isn’t totally irrelevant either. I just want to
make that as a statement. And Freud stays relevant as Darwin stays rel-
evant, even though people say well, this and this wrong, Einstein stays
relevant—even Marx. Freud is of that ilk—I mean he made a majorly
important discovery and found a way of understanding it.
H O W C A N W E L I V E O U R S E LV E S ? 271
Allegaert, P. and Brokken, A., eds. 2012. Nerveuze vrouwen. Twee eeuwen vrouwen
en hun psychiaters. (Trans.: Two Centuries of Women and Their Psychiatrists).
Museum Dr. Guislain, Gent: Lannoo.
Althusser, L. [1962] 2005. “Contradiction and Overdetermination.” In For
Marx. Translated by Ben Brewster, 87–128. New York: Verso.
Anzieu, D. 1986. Freud’s Self-Analysis. New York: International Universities
Press.
Apollodorus. 1976. Gods and Heroes of the Greeks. Translated by Michael Simpson.
Amherst, MA: University of Massachusetts Press.
Arendt, H. [1958] 1998. The Human Condition. Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Armstrong, R. H. 2005. Freud and the Ancient World, New York: Cornell
University Press.
Athenaeus. 1930. Deipnosophistae. Translated by Loeb Classical Library. London:
William Heinemann.
Balint, E. 1998. Before I Was I. Edited by Michael Parsons and Juliet Mitchell.
New York: Other Press.
Bane, S. 1980. Democracy’s Body: Judson Dance Theatre 1962–1964. Ann Arbor,
MI: UMI Research Press.
Bauman, Z. and Lyon, D. 2013. Liquid Surveillance. Cambridge: Polity Press.
Beigler, J. S. 1975. “A Commentary on Freud’s Treatment of the Rat Man.”
Annual of Psychoanalysis 3: 271–285.
Blackburn, R. 1972. Ideology in Social Science. London: Fontana/Collins.
Bryan-Wilson, J. 2009. Art Workers: Radical Practice in the Vietnam War Era.
Berkeley: University of California.
Butler, J. 1990. Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. New
York: Routledge.
Butler, J. “Ideologies of the Superego.” Presented at the Centre for Gender
Studies, Cambridge University, May 2009.
Butler, J. 2013. “Rethinking Sexual Difference and Kinship in Mitchell’s
Psychoanalysis and Feminism.” differences 23(2): 1–19.
Callinicos, A. 2013. “Is Leninism Finished?” Socialist Review, January 13, 2013.
Carnegie, D. 1936. How to Win Friends and Influence People. Cedar.
Central Committee of the Socialist Workers Party 2013. “The SWP and Women’s
Oppression.” http://socialistunity.com/wp-content/uploads/2013/03/SWP
-internal-bulletin-special-conference-march2013.pdf
274 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Freud, S. [1917] 2001. “The Development of the Libido and the Sexual
Organisations.” SE16 329–338.
Freud, S. [1918] 2001. “The Taboo on Virginity.” SE11 191–208.
Freud, S. [1919] 2001. “A Child is Being Beaten.” SE17 179–204.
Freud, S. [1920] 2001. “Beyond the Pleasure Principle.” SE18 1–64.
Freud, S. [1923] 2001. “The Ego and the Id.” SE19 12–68.
Freud, S. [1924] 2001. “The Dissolution of the Oedipus Complex.” SE19
171–180.
Freud, S. [1924] 2005. “The Dissolution of the Oedipus Complex.” In The
Essentials of Psychoanalysis, 395–401.
Freud, S. [1924] 2001. “An Autobiographical Study.” SE20 7–76.
Freud, S. [1925] 2001. “Inhibitions, Symptoms and Anxiety.” SE20 87–178.
Freud, S. [1925b] 2001. “A Note Upon the ‘Mystic Writing-Pad.” SE19 225–232.
Freud, S. [1925] 2005. “Some Psychical Consequences of the Anatomical
Distinction between the Sexes.” In The Essentials of Psychoanalysis, 402–411.
Vintage: London.
Freud, S. [1926] 2001. “The Question of Lay Analysis.” SE20 177–258.
Freud, S. [1927] 2001. “Fetischismus.” SE21 149–158.
Freud, S. [1930] 2001. “The Future of an Illusion and Other Works.” SE21 1–56.
Freud, S. [1933] 2001. “New Introductory Lectures.” SE 22 1–182.
Freud, S. [1933] 2001. “On Femininity.” SE22, 112–135.
Freud, S. [1938] 2001. “Findings, Ideas, Problems.” SE23 299–300.
Freud, S. [1955]. 2005. The Essentials of Psychoanalysis. Translated by J. Strachey.
Vintage London.
Gilmore, K. 2013. “Theory of Sibling Trauma and Lateral Dimension.”
Psychoanalytical Study of the Child 67: 53–65.
Glover, E. 1947. “Basic Mental Concepts—Their Clinical and Theoretical Value.”
Psychoanalytic Quarterly 16: 482–506.
Green, A. 1995. “Has Sexuality Anything to Do with Psychoanalysis?” The
International Journal of Psychoanalysis 75: 871–883.
Green, A. 1999. The Work of the Negative. Translated by Andrew Weller, New
York: Free Association Books.
Green, A. 2000. Chains of Eros. London: Karnac.
Green, A. 2001. Life Narcissism and Death Narcissism. London: Karnac.
Green, A. 2005. “The Illusion of a Common Ground and Mythical Pluralism.”
International Journal of Psychoanalysis 86: 627–632.
Goldstein, P. 2000. “Orwell as a (Neo)conservative: The Reception of 1984.”
Journal of the Midwest Modern Language Association 33(1): 44–57.
Grosz, E. 1990. Jacques Lacan: A Feminist Introduction. London: Routledge.
Guntrip, H. 1975. “My Experience of Analysis with Fairbairn and Winnicott.”
International Review of Psychoanalysis 2: 145–156.
Haaken, J. 1998. Pillar of Salt: Gender, Memory, and the Perils of Looking Back.
New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers UP.
Hegel, G.W.F. [1807] 1977. Phenomenology of Spirit. Translated by A. V. Miller,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Hegel, G.W.F. [1832] 2010. The Science of Logic. Translated by George Di
Giovanni. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
BIBLIOGRAPHY 277
Heyman, I., Fombonne, E., Simmons, H., Ford, T., Meltzer, H., and
Goodman, R. 2001. “Prevalence of Obsessive–Compulsive Disorder in the
British Nationwide Survey of Child Mental Health.” The British Journal of
Psychiatry 179: 324–329.
Hoare, Q. 1967. “Discussion on ‘Women: The Longest Revolution.’ ” New Left
Review 41: 78–81.
Holland, N. 1975. “An Identity for the Rat-Man.” International Review of
Psycho-Analysis 2: 157–169.
Honneth, A. 1996. The Struggle for Recognition. Cambridge: Polity.
Huppert, D. 2014. “Die Eigenschaften des Unbewussten.” In Sigmund Freud
Vorlesungen 2014. Vienna: Mandelbaum.
Ingle, S. 1993. George Orwell: A Political Life. Manchester: Manchester
University Press.
Israël, L. 1984. Hysterie, sekse en de geneesheer. Leuven/Amersfoort: Acco
Jameson, F. 2010. Valences of the Dialectics. New York: Verso.
Jones, E. 1955. The Life and Work of Sigmund Freud. New York: Basic Books.
Kaplan, A. 2005. The Anarchy of Empire in the Making of U.S. Culture.
Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Kelly, M, 1983. “Preface.” Post-Partum Document, xv. London: Routledge.
Klein, M. [1928] 1998. “Early Stages of the Oedipus Complex.” In Love, Guilt
And Reparation, Writings of Melanie Klein 1921–1945, 186–198. London:
Vintage.
Klein, M. [1930] 1975. “The Importance of Symbol-Formation in the
Development of the Ego.” In Love, Guilt And Reparation, Writings of Melanie
Klein 1921–1945, 219–232. London: Vintage.
Klein, M. 1932. The Psychoanalysis of Children. London: Hogarth Press.
Krauss, R. 1976. Passages in Modern Sculpture. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Künstlicher, R. 1998. “Horror at Pleasure of His Own of which He Himself is
Not Aware: The Case of the Rat Man.” In On Freud’s Couch, edited by. I.
Matthis and I. Szecsödy, 127–162. Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson.
Lacan, J. [1953] 1977. “Function and Field of Speech and Language.” In Écrits:
A Selection, translated by Alan Sheridan, 30–113. New York: Norton.
Lacan, J. [1956] 1991. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan: The Psychoses 1955–56,
Book III. Edited by John Forrester. New York: Norton.
Lacan, J. [1957] 1977. “The Agency of the Letter in the Unconscious, or Reason
Since Freud.” In Écrits: a Selection. translated by Alan Sheridan. London:
Tavistock.
Lacan, J. [1958] 2002. The Seminar of Jacques Lacan V: The Formations of the
Unconscious. Translated by Cormac Gallagher. London: Karnac.
Lacan, J. [1966] 2006. Ecrits. New York: Norton.
Lacan, J. 1966. “Le Stade du miroir comme formateur de la fonction du Je.”
In Ecrits, pp. 93–100. Paris: Seuil.
Lacan, J. 1966. “Position de l’inconscient.” In Ecrits, 829–850. Paris: Seuil.
Lacan, J. [1969–70] 1991. Le Séminaire, livre XVII, L’Envers de la psychanalyse.
Edited by J. A. Miller. Paris: Seuil.
Lacan, J. [1972–73] 1975. Le Séminaire, livre XX: Encore. Edited by J.-A. Miller.
Paris: Seuil.
278 BIBLIOGRAPHY
Tressler, I. 1937. How to Lose Friends and Alienate People. Palmera Publishing.
Turnheim, M. 2007. “Über die innere Spaltung der Freudschen Geste und die
Frage der Rückkehr.” In Freudlose Psychoanalyse? Vienna: Turia und Kant.
Vanheule, S. 2011. The Subject of Psychosis: A Lacanian Perspective. London and
New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Verhaeghe, P. 1995. “From Impossibility to Inability: Lacan’s Theory of the
Four Discourses.” The Letter 3: 76–100. (Digital version on http://www
.psychoanalysis.ugent.be).
Verhaeghe, P. 1999 [1987). Does the Woman Exist? From Freud’s Hysteric to
Lacan’s Feminine. New York: The Other Press.
Verhaeghe, P. 2001. Beyond Gender. New York: Other Press.
Verhaeghe, P. 2001. “Mind your Body & Lacan’s Answer to a Classical Deadlock.”
In Beyond Gender. From Subject to Drive. Edited by P. Verhaeghe, 99–132,
New York: Other Press.
Verhaeghe, P. 2004. On Being Normal and Other Disorders. London: Karnac.
Verhaeghe, P. 2004. “Phallacies of Binary Reasoning: Drive beyond Gender.”
In Dialogues on Sexuality, Gender and Psychoanalysis. Edited by I. Matthis,
53–66. London: Karnac. http://www.psychoanalysis.ugent.be
Verhaeghe, P. 2009. New Studies of Old Villains. A Radical Reconsideration
of the Oedipus Complex. (Foreword by Juliet Mitchell). New York: Other
Press.
Verhaeghe, P. 2014a. What about Me? Brunswick: Scribe Publications.
Verhaeghe, P. 2014b “Today’s Madness Does Not Make Sense.” In Lacan on
Madness: Madness, Yes You Can’t. Edited by P. Gherovici and M. Steinkoler
London: Routledge, Taylor & Francis Group.
Veszy-Wagner, L. 1967. “Zwangsneurose und latent Homosexualitat.” Psyche 21:
295–615.
Volkan, V. and Ast, G. 2000. Siblings in the Unconscious and Psychopathology.
Madison: International University Press.
Walker, T. 2013. “Why I am Resigning.” http://www.cpgb.org.uk/home
/weekly-worker/944/swp-why-i-am-resigning
Walkerdine, V. 1997. Daddy’s Girl. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Wandschneider, D. 2010. “Dialectic as the ‘Self-Fulfilment’ of Logic.” In The
Dimensions of Hegel’s Dialectic. Edited by Nectarious G. Limnatis. New York:
Continuum.
Williams, B. 1993. Shame and Necessity. Berkeley: University of California
Press.
Williams, R. 1973. “Base and Superstructure in Marxist Cultural Theory.” New
Left Review 82: 3–16.
Williams, R. 1980. Problems in Materialism and Culture. New York: Verso.
Williams, R. 1982. “George Orwell.” Culture and Society, 285–294. London:
Hograth Press.
Williams, R. 1985. Keywords: A Vocabulary of Culture and Society, New York:
Oxford University Press.
Winnicott, D. [1953] 1965. “Psycho-Analysis and the Sense of Guilt.” In The
Maturational Processes and the Facilitating Environment: Studies in the Theory
of Emotional Development, London: Tavistock.
282 BIBLIOGRAPHY
obsessional neurosis, 17–18, 24, 52, repression, 24, 31, 51, 134, 141,
124, 158, 169–90 158, 161, 184, 198
Oedipus complex, 25, 29, 46, reproduction, 93, 103, 120
80–1, 136, 140, 128, 152, Robinson, Marilynne, 246–7
155, 234 Rose, Jacqueline, 5, 14, 77, 84, 260
resolution of, 25–6 Rubin, Gayle, 72, 78
only children, 11, 116
Orwell, George, 120–5 sado-masochistic fantasy, 16, 133
same sex parenting, 61–2
parents, 136 Scott, Joan, 83
Parsons, Michael, 5 screen memory, 50, 182
parthenogenesis, 26 secrets between siblings, 51–2
Pateman, Carole, 258 sectarianism, 27
patriarchy, 4, 7, 18, 66, 87, 95, 107, Sedgewick, Eve, 62, 80
113, 164, 196, 229–30, 258 seriality, 6, 7, 45, 119
patricide, 38 sexism, 105, 258
peers, 84, 117, 197, 200, 263 Sexton, Anne, 33
performativity, 72 sexual assault, 24
personality disorders, 138 sexual difference, 13, 46, 58, 59–60,
perversions, 16, 48–9, 198 63, 78–81, 83, 92, 95–6, 237,
phallus, 7, 36, 46, 72, 78, 148–9, 258–9, 267, 269
153, 159, 188 sexual drive, 37
phantasies, 25, 113–15 sexual exploitation, 259, 260
photographs, 197, 199, 221–3 sexuality, 2, 15, 110, 135, 136, 137
plenitude, 112–13 and reproduction, 45–6
political task of emancipation, 92–4 social organization of, 62
polymorphous perversion, 46, 81 Shakespeare, William, 266, 267,
preconscious memories, 50 270
production, 102 siblings, 5, 24, 28–30, 107, 113–20,
prohibition, 17, 25, 38, 49, 80, 121–4, 136, 141–2, 174, 195,
262–4 255, 232, 257
incest, 86 death, 116, 181
murder, 79, 86 incest, 49
sodomy, 229–31 rivalry, 37
see also “Thou Shalt Nots” sexuality, 45–6, 49–50
promises, 51–3 sibling complex, 12, 54, 258
see also oaths sibling trauma, 260
Psychoanalysis and Feminism, 2, 4–5, theory of, 43–4
77–81, 91, 112, 134, 196 Singh, Jyoti, 218
Pussy Riot, 152 sisterhood, 112
social practice, 58
Rainer, Yvonne, 19, 200–2 socialism, 14, 103–8
rape, 6, 14, 19, 104–5 Socialist Workers’ Party, 14, 102–5
Rat Man, the, 17–18, 124, 169–90, Solomon, Andrew, 256
256 Spero, Nancy, 198
recognition, 117–20 Sphinx, 183–5
INDEX 291