Karl Marx - Fifth Notebook On Epicurean Philosophy
Karl Marx - Fifth Notebook On Epicurean Philosophy
Epistle IX, [1,] Vol. II, p. 25. “You desire to know whether Epicurus is right
when, in one of his letters, he rebukes those who hold that the wise man is
self-sufficient and for that reason does not stand in need of friendships. This is
the objection raised by Epicurus against Stilpo and those who believe that the
Supreme Good is a dispassionate mind.”
“Epicurus himself ... spoke similar language: ‘Whoever does not regard what
he has as most ample wealth, is unhappy, though he be master of the whole
world.'” op. cit., p. 30.
“[...] he (Epicurus) added: ‘So greatly blest were Metrodorus and I that it has
been no harm to us to be unknown and almost unheard of, in this well-known
land of Greece.'” Ep. LXXIX, [15,] p. 317.
“As Epicurus himself says, he will sometimes withdraw from pleasure and
even seek pain if either remorse threatens to follow pleasure or a smaller pain
is accepted to avoid a larger one.” L. Seneca, On the Leisure of the Wise Man,
p. 582, Vol. I.
“Epicurus also maintains that the wise man, though he is being burned in the
bull of Phalaris, will cry out: ‘Tis pleasant, and concerns me not at all.’
Epicurus will say that it is pleasant to be tortured.” Ep. LXVI, [18,] [Vol. 11,] p.
235, also Ep. LXVII, [15,] p. 248.
“We find mentioned in the works of Epicurus two goods, of which his Supreme
Good, or blessedness, is composed, namely, a body free from pain and a soul
free from disturbance.” Ep. LXVI, [45,] p. 241.
“I... remember the distinguished words of Epicurus ... ‘This little garden ... does
not whet your appetite; it quenches it. Nor does it make you more thirsty with
every drink; it slakes the thirst by a natural cure, -- a cure that demands no fee.
This is the “pleasure” in which I have grown old.’ In speaking to you, however,
I refer to those desires which refuse alleviation, which must be bribed to
cease. For in regard to the exceptional desires, which may be postponed,
which may be chastened and checked, I have this one thought to share with
you: a pleasure of that sort is according to our nature, but it is not according to
our needs; you owe nothing to it; whatever is expended upon it is a free gift.
The belly does not listen to advice; it makes demands, it importunes. And yet it
is not a troublesome creditor; you can send it away at small cost, provided
only that you give it what you owe, not what you are able to give.” Ep. XXI, [9,
10, 11,] pp. 80-81.
“[...] Epicurus, whom you accept as the patron of your indolence, and of whom
you think that he teaches softness and idleness and things which lead to
pleasure, says: ‘Happiness seldom affects the wise man.'” Vol. I, p. 416, On the
Constancy of the Wise Man [XV 4].
“Epicurus upbraids those who crave, as much as those who shrink from death:
‘It is absurd,’ he says, ‘to run towards death because you are tired of life, when
it is your manner of life that has made you run towards death.’ And in another
passage: ‘What is so absurd as to seek death, when it is through fear of death
that you have robbed your life of peace?’ [To this can be added also] the
following: ‘Men are so thoughtless, nay, so mad, that some, through fear of
death, force themselves to die.’” Ep. XXIV, [22-23,] p. 95.
“[...] friends ...the name which our Epicurus bestowed upon them (the slaves).”
Ep. CVII, [1,] [Vol. II,] p. 526. “[...] Epicurus, Stilpo’s critic.” p. 30, Ep. IX [20].
“[...] let me tell you that Epicurus says the same thing. ... that only the wise
man knows how to return a favour.” Ep. LXXXI, [11,] p. 326.
“Epicurus remarks that certain men have worked their way to the truth
without anyone’s assistance, he, among them, made his own way. And he gives
special praise to these, for their impulse has come from within, and they have
forged to the front by themselves. Again, he says, there are others who need
outside help, who will not proceed unless someone leads the way, but who will
follow faithfully. Of these, he says, Metrodorus was one; this type of man is
also excellent, but belongs to the second grade.” Ep. LII, [3,] [p]p. [176-]177.
“You will find still another class of man, -- and a class not to be despised, —
who can be forced and driven into righteousness, who do not need a guide so
much as they need someone to encourage and, as it were, to force them along.
This is the third class.” ibid.
“[It was to him (Idomeneus)] that Epicurus addressed his well-known saying,
urging him to make Pythocles rich, but not rich in the vulgar and equivocal
way. ‘If you wish,’ said he, ‘to make Pythocles rich, do not add to his store of
money, but subtract from his desires.’” Ep. XXI, [7,] p. 79.
Cf. Stobaeus, Sermon XVII [41-42]. “If you want to make somebody rich, do not
give him more money, but free him of some of his desires.”
“'It is bad to live under necessity, but there is no necessity to live under
necessity.’ Of course not. On all sides lie many short and simple paths to
freedom; and let us thank God that no man can be kept in life. We may
spurn those very necessities, said [Epicurus]....” Ep. XII, [10-11,] p. 42.
“The fool, with all his other faults, has this also, — he is always getting ready
to live .... And what is baser than getting ready to live when you are already
old? I should not name the author of this motto, except that it is somewhat
unknown to fame and is not one of those popular sayings of Epicurus ....” Ep.
XIII, [16-17 ,] p.47.
“'He who needs riches least, enjoys riches most,’ is a saying of Epicurus.” Ep.
XIV, [17,] p. 53.
“This is a saying of Epicurus: ‘If you live according to nature, you will never be
poor; if you live according to opinion, you will never be rich.’ Nature’s wants
are slight; the demands of opinion are boundless.” Ep. XVI, [7-8,] p. 60.
“The acquisition of riches has been for many men, not an end, but a change, of
troubles.” Ep. XVII, [II,] p. 64.
“... of Epicurus. He says: ‘You must reflect carefully beforehand with whom
you are to eat and drink, rather than what you are to eat and drink. For a
dinner of meats without the company of a friend is like the life of a lion or a
wolf.’” Ep. XIX, [10,] p. 72.
“'No one,’ says he (Epicurus), ‘leaves this world in a different manner than he
was born into it’ .... A man has caught the message of wisdom, if he can die as
free from care as he was at birth.” Ep. XXII, [15, 16,] p. 84.
“'When a man has limited his desires within these bounds [i.e., bread and
water, which nature demands, cf. Epistle CX, [18,] p. 548], he can challenge the
happiness of Jove himself,’ as Epicurus says.” Ep. XXV, [4,] p. 97.
“Epicurus, who says: ‘Reflect which of the two is more convenient, that death
should come to us or we go to it.'” Ep. XXVI, [8,] p. 101.
“Wealth is poverty adjusted to the law of nature.” Ep. XXVII, [9,] p. 105. “’the
knowledge of sin is the beginning of salvation.’ This saying of Epicurus seems
to me to be an excellent one.” Ep. XXVIII, [9,] p. 107.
“Writing to one of the partners of his studies, Epicurus said: ‘I write this not
for the many, but for you; indeed, each of us is enough of an audience for the
other.'” Ep. VII, [II,] p. 21.
“I am still conning Epicurus: ‘If you would enjoy real freedom, you must be the
slave of Philosophy.’ The man who submits and surrenders himself to her is
not kept waiting; he is emancipated on the spot. For the very service of
Philosophy is freedom.” Ep. VIII, [7,] p. 24.
“It was not the class-room of Epicurus, but association with him, that made
[them] great men.” Ep. VI, [6,] p. 16.
“Hence I hold Epicurus’ saying to be most apt: ‘That the guilty may haply
remain hidden is possible, that he should be sure of remaining hidden is not
possible.'” Ep. XCVII, [13,] p. 480.
“No reasonable man fears the gods. For it is folly to fear that which is
beneficent, and no one loves those whom he fears. In the end, you, Epicurus,
disarm God. You have taken from him all weapons, all might, and so that no
one should fear him, you have put him out of action. Therefore you have no
reason to fear him who is surrounded by a huge and insuperable wall and is
separated from the contact and the sight of mortals. He has not the possibility
either to give or to harm. In the middle space between this and the other
heaven, alone, without any living things, without any humans, without
anything, he seeks to escape from the ruins of the worlds which are collapsing
above him and around him, not heeding desires and without any concern for
us. And yet you wish to appear as if you honour him as a father, with a
grateful heart, as it seems to me; or if you do not wish to appear grateful,
because you receive no mercy from him, but the atoms and these your
particles have formed you accidentally and not according to any plan, why
then do you honour him? Because of his majesty, you say, and his unique
essence. If I concede you that, apparently you do this not induced by hope of
any kind, by reward of any kind. Consequently there is something which is
worth striving after for itself, whose worth itself attracts you: that is the moral
Good.” On Benefits, Book IV, Chap. 19, p. 719, Vol. I.
“'All these causes could exist,’ says Epicurus, and tries several other
explanations; and he rebukes those who have asserted that any definite one of
these exists, because it is rash to judge apodictically of that which follows only
from conjectures. Consequently an earthquake can be caused by water when it
has eroded and carried away some parts of the earth, and these have been
weakened; that which was borne by the parts when they were undamaged
could no longer be held. Pressure of the air can set the earth in motion. For
perhaps the air is set in vibration when other air streams in from outside.
Perhaps it is shaken and set in motion when a part suddenly gives way.
Perhaps it is held up by some part of the earth as by some kind of columns and
pillars; if these are damaged and yield, the weight resting on them quakes.
Perhaps hot masses of air are transformed into fire and rush down like
lightning, doing great damage to what is in their path. Perhaps some blast of
wind sets boggy and stagnant waters in motion and consequently the earth is
shaken by an impulse or a vibration of the air, which increases with the
motion itself, is carried above from below, however he says that no other
cause is of greater importance in the case of an earthquake than motion of the
air.” Questions of Nature, Book VI, Chap. 20, p. 802. Vol. II.
“On this question, two schools above all are in disagreement, that of the
Epicureans and that of the Stoics; but each of them points, though in different
ways, to retirement. Epicurus says: ‘The wise man shows no concern for the
state, unless a special situation has arisen.’ Zeno says: ‘He must have concern
for the state unless something hinders him.’ The former wants leisure on
principle, the latter according to circumstances.” On the Leisure of the Wise
Man, Chap. 30, p. 574, Vol. I.
“The pleasure of Epicurus is not estimated [...] because of how sober and dull it
is, but they seize on the mere name, seeking some cover and veil for their
lusts. Thus they lose the only good thing which they had in their badness,
namely, shame of sinning. For they now praise that over which they blushed
formerly, and they glory in vice, and for this reason even young people cannot
regain their strength since shameful idleness has been covered with an
honourable mantle.” p. 541, Chap. 12, [4, 5,] On the Happy Life, Vol. I.
“For all these [Plato, Zeno, Epicurus] did not speak of how they themselves
lived, but of how one should live.” Chap. 18, [1,] p. 550, op. cit.
“Hence God does not dispense mercy, but, untroubled, unconcerned about us,
and turned away from the world, he does something else or (and this for
Epicurus is the greatest bliss) does nothing, and good deeds affect him no
more than acts of injustice.” On Benefits, Book IV, Chap. 4, [1,] p. 699, Vol. I.
“We may dispute with Socrates, doubt with Carneades, repose with Epicurus,
transcend human nature with the Stoics, defy it with the Cynics; Nature allows
us to participate in any age.” On the Shortness of Life, p. 512, Vol. I.
“In this respect we are in conflict with the self-indulgent and retiring crowd of
the Epicureans who philosophise at their banquets and for whom virtue is the
handmaid of pleasure. They obey pleasure, they serve it, they see it above
themselves.” On Benefits, Book IV, Chap. 2, p. 697, Vol. I.
“But how can virtue rule pleasure, which it follows, since to follow is proper to
him who obeys, and to rule to him who commands?” On the Happy Life,
Chap. 11, p. 538, Vol. I.
“For those who lack experience and training, there is no limit to the downhill
course; such a one falls into the chaos of Epicurus -- empty and boundless.” Ep.
LXXII, [9,] p. 274, Vol. II.
“The Epicureans held that philosophy consists of two parts, natural and moral,
and they did away with logic. Then, when they were compelled by the facts to
distinguish between equivocal ideas and to expose fallacies that lay hidden
under the cloak of truth, they themselves also introduced a heading which
they called ‘on judgments and rules’, which is another name for logic, but
which they consider an adjunct of natural philosophy.” Ep. LXXXIX, [11,] p.
397.
“The Epicurean god neither has anything to do himself, nor does he give
others anything to do.” On the Death of the Emperor Claudius, p. 851, Vol. II.
“Then you say: ‘Is it retirement, Seneca, that you are recommending to me?
You will soon be falling back upon the maxims of Epicurus. I do recommend
retirement to you, but only that you may use it for greater and more beautiful
activities than those which you have resigned.” Ep. LXVIII, [10,] p. 251.
“I am not so foolish as to go through at this juncture the arguments which
Epicurus harps upon, and say that the terrors of the world below are idle, --
that Ixion does not whirl round on his wheel, that Sisyphus does not shoulder
his stone uphill, that a man’s entrails cannot be restored and devoured every
day; no one is so childish as to fear Cerberus, or the shadows, or the spectral
garb of those who are held together by naught but their unfleshed bones.
Death either annihilates us or frees us. If we are released, there remains the
better part, after the burden has been withdrawn; if we are annihilated,
nothing remains: good and bad are alike removed.” Ep. XXIV, [18,] p. 93.
End
“Thanks be to bountiful nature for having made that which is necessary easy
to obtain and that which is difficult to obtain not necessary.
“If you want to make somebody rich, do not give him more money, but free
him of some of his desires.
“Temperance is the virtue of the appetitive part of the soul by which, with the
help of reason, one represses longings for vulgar pleasure.
“It is the nature of temperance to be able to repress with the help of reason the
longing for the vulgar enjoyment of pleasure and to endure and bear natural
privations and suffering.” On Temperance, Sermon XVII, p. 157.
“We are born once, it is not possible to be born twice, and it is of necessity that
life is not longer (necessarium est aetatem finiri). But you, who have no
power over the morrow (qui ne crastinum diem quidem in tua potestate
habes), are putting off the moment (tempus differs). Everybody’s life is wasted
through procrastination, and for that reason everyone of us dies without
having any leisure.” On Economy, Sermon XVI, p. 155.
“I have more than enough bodily pleasure when I have water and bread, and I
do not care a straw for costly pleasures, not because of themselves, but
because of all the unpleasantness that follows them.
“We feel the need for pleasure when we are sad because we do not have it. But
when we do not experience this in our sensations, then we have no need for
pleasure. For it is not the natural pleasure which causes external annoyance,
but the striving for empty appearance.” On Temperance, Sermon XVII [p. 159].
“The laws exist for the wise not so that they shall do no wrong, but so that no
wrong shall happen to them.” On the State, Sermon XLI, p. 270.
“Death is nothing to us. For that which is dissolved is without sensation. And
that which is without sensation is nothing to us.” On Death, Sermon CXVII, p.
600.
“Epicurus of Demos Gargettios proclaimed: ‘To him for whom a little is not
sufficient, nothing is sufficient.’ He said he was prepared to dispute over bliss
with anybody if he had only bread and water.” On Temperance, Sermon XVII,
p. 158.
“For this reason Epicurus also believes that those who are ambitious and seek
after glory must not practise quietism, but must follow their nature taking part
in civic affairs and work for the common weal, for their nature is such that, if
they do not attain that for which they strive, they will become restless and
embittered through inactivity. And yet he is foolish who enlists in work for the
common weal not those who are suitable for it, but those who cannot be
inactive; inner tranquillity and inner unrest must not be measured
(securitatem animi anxietatemque metiri) either by the amount, great or
small, of what one has done, but by the good and the bad. For to omit to do
good is no less painful and disquieting (molestum est et turbulentum) than to
do evil.” On Steadfastness, Sermon XXIX, p. 206.
“When somebody said: ‘The wise man will not be affected by love. The
evidence for this is ... Epicurus ...’, he [Chrysippus] said: ‘This I take as a proof.
For if ... the unfeeling Epicurus ... was not affected by love (the wise man will
certainly not be affected by it)’ (ne sapiens quidem eo capietur).” [Here and
below Marx inserts phrases from a Latin translation of Stobaeus where the
Greek text is damaged] On Sensual Pleasure and Love, Sermon LXI, p. 393.
“Epicurus [assumes] that the gods indeed resemble man, but that one and all
they can be perceived only by thought because of the fineness of the nature of
their images. He himself however [assumes] four other substances to be
indestructible by their nature: the atoms, the void, the infinite, and the
homogeneous particles; and these are called homoeomerias and elements.”
Physical Selections, Book 1, p. 5.
“Epicurus [is guided] by necessity, by free decision, by fate. And on the subject
of fate they [the Pythagoreans] used to say: ‘To be sure there is also a divine
part in it, for some men receive from the divinity an inspiration for better or
for worse; and in accordance with this some are clearly happy and others
unhappy. But it is quite obvious that those who act without previous
deliberation and haphazardly are often successful, while others, who
deliberate beforehand and consider beforehand how to do something
correctly, are not successful. But fate manifests itself in another way, by virtue
of which some are talented and purposeful, while others are talentless and,
because they have a contrary nature, do harm; the former though hasty in
judgment attain every object at which they aim, while the latter do not achieve
their object, because their thinking is never purposeful, but confused. This
misfortune, however, is innate, and not imposed from outside (non
externam).” Physical Selections, Book I, [p] p. [15-]16.
“Epicurus [says] that the bodies are imperceptible and that the primary ones
are simple, and the bodies composed of them have weight; that the atoms
move, sometimes falling in a straight line (rectis lineis), sometimes swerving
from the straight line; and upward movement occurs through collision and
repulsion.” Physical Selections, Book I, p. 33.
“Epicurus ... [says] that coloured bodies have no colour in the dark [...].”
Physical Selections, Book 1, p. 35.
“[...] Epicurus [says] that the atoms are infinite in number and the void is
infinite in extent.” Physical Selections, Book I, p. 38.
“Epicurus uses alternatively all the names: void, place, space.” Physical
Selections, Book I, p. 39.
Cf. D[iogenes] L[aertius]. “'[...] if there did not exist that which we call void and
space and intangible nature [...].'” p. 32. [Letter] to Herodotus.
“Epicurus [distinguishes] two kinds of motion, that in a straight line and that
which swerves away from the straight line.” Physical Selections, Book I, p. 40.
“Epicurus [says] that the world perishes in many ways, namely, as animal, as
plant and in many other ways.” Physical Selections, Book I, p. 44.
“All others [assumed] that the world is animated and guided by providence;
Leucippus, Democritus and Epicurus, on the other hand, make neither of these
[assumptions], but say that it arose out of the atoms through nature not
endowed with reason.” Physical Selections, Book I, p. 47.
“Epicurus [says] that the extremity of some worlds is tenuous, that of others is
dense, and of these some are mobile, others are immobile.” Physical
Selections, Book I, p. 51.
The following passage from Stobaeus, which does not belong to Epicurus, is
perhaps one of the most elevated.
“Is there, Father, anything beautiful besides these? Only God” (by touton choris
one should understand schema, chroma, and soma) [shape, colour, and body],
“my child, rather that which is greater is the name of God.” Stobaeus,
Physical Selections, Book I, p. 50.
“Metrodorus, the teacher of Epicurus, [says] that ... the causes, however, are
the atoms and elements.” l.c., p. 52.
“Epicurus does not reject any of them” (i.e., the views on the stars), “he
adheres to the possible.” l.c., p. 54.
“Epicurus says that the sun is a big lump of earth similar to pumice-stone and
sponge-like, which has been set on fire through its holes.” l.c., p. 56.
The passage cited above from the Physical Selections, Book 1, p. 5 [see this volume,
p. 485] seems, more than the passage quoted by Schaubach, to confirm the view
that there are two kinds of atoms. In this passage of the Selections, the omoiotetes
[homoeomerias] are adduced as indestructible principles alongside the atoms and
the void; they are not eidola [images] but are explained: ai de legontai omoiomereiai
chai stoicheia [which are called homoeomerias and elements]. Thus it follows from
this passage that the atoms, which underlie appearance, as elements, have no
homoeomerias, and possess the qualities of the bodies of which they are the basis.
This is in any case false. In the same way Metrodorus adduces as cause ai atomoi
chai ta stoicheia [the atoms and the elements] (p. 52).
“Epicurus also says that the removal of pain is pleasure; and says that that is to
be preferred, which first attracts from itself to itself, being, that is, wholly in
motion Epicurus, indeed, and the Cyrenaics, say that pleasure is the first thing
proper to us; for it was for the sake of pleasure, they say, that virtue was
introduced, and produced pleasure.” The Miscellanies, Book II, p. 415.
“... Epicurus thinks that all joy of the soul arises from previous sensations of
the flesh. Metrodorus, in his book, On the Happiness Which Has Its Source in
Ourselves Being Greater Than That Which Arises from Circumstances, says:
What else is the good of the soul but the sound state of the flesh, and the sure
hope of its continuance?” The Miscellanies, Book II, p. 417.
“Indeed Epicurus says that the man who in his estimation was wise, ‘would
not do wrong to anyone for the sake of gain; for he could not persuade himself
that he would escape detection.’ So that, if he knew he would not be detected,
he would, according to him, do evil.” The Miscellanies, Book IV, p. 532.
It does not escape Clement that hope in the future world is also not free from the
principle of utility.
“If, too, one shall abstain from doing wrong from hope of the recompense
promised by God for righteous deeds, he is not on this supposition
spontaneously good (ne hic quidem sua sponte bonus est). ... For as fear
makes that man just, so reward makes this one; or rather makes him appear to
be just.” op. cit.
“Epicurus, too, who very greatly preferred pleasure to truth, supposes faith to
be a preconception of the mind (anticipationem); and defines preconception as
a notion based on something evident, and on the obviously correct image; and
asserts that, without preconception, no one can either inquire, or doubt, or
judge, or even argue (arguere).” The Miscellanies, Book II, pp. 365 and 366.
Clement adds:
“If, then, faith is nothing else than a preconception of the mind in regard to
what is the subject of discourse”, etc.,
from which one can see what here by fides intelligi debet. [must be understood by
faith]
“[...] but Epicurus, on the other hand (contra), supposes that only Greeks can
philosophise [...].” The Miscellanies, Book I, p. 302.
“Well, then, Epicurus, writing to Menoeceus, says: ‘Let not him who is young
delay philosophising’, etc.” The Miscellanies, Book IV, p. 501. Cf. Diogenes
Laertius, Letter to Menoeceus. [see this volume, pp. 406-07]
“ ... but the Epicureans too say that they have things that may not be uttered
(arcana), and do not allow all to peruse those writings.” The Miscellanies,
Book V, p.575.
According to Clement of Alexandria, the apostle Paul had Epicurus in mind when
he said:
“'Beware lest any man spoil you through philosophy and vain deceit, after the
tradition of men, after the rudiments of the world, and not after Christ';
branding not all philosophy, but the Epicurean, which Paul mentions in the
Acts of the Apostles, which abolishes providence and deifies pleasure, and
whatever other philosophy honours the elements, but places not over them
the efficient cause, nor apprehends the Creator.” The Miscellanies, Book I, p.
295.
It is good that the philosophers who did not weave fantasies about God are
rejected.
This passage is now better understood, and it is known that Paul had all philosophy
in mind.