Unit 6 Justice: Structure
Unit 6 Justice: Structure
Structure
6.1 Introduction
6.2 The Idea of Justice
6.2.1 Procedural Justice and Substantive Justice
6.5 Summary
6.6 Exercises
6.1 INTRODUCTION
Justice is of central importance in political practice and theory. In defending or opposing laws,
public policies and administrative decisions of governments, appeals are made to notions of
justice. Justice is also invoked in social and political movements, civil disobedience and satyagraha
campaigns. Thus, the civil rights or civil liberties movements are essentially movements for
justice. So are the dalit, feminist and environmental movements.
While a decent or good society or polity must have several virtues, justice is, according to a
widespread view, the first of them. In the words of the leading contemporary moral and political
philosopher, John Rawls of Harvard University, “justice is the first virtue of social institutions.”
He made that statement in his book, A Theory of Justice, which was published in 1971. Some
two decades earlier, it was proclaimed in the Preamble of the Indian Constitution that the
Democratic Republic of India stood committed to securing to all its citizens “Justice, social,
economic and political.” It is noteworthy that the Preamble lists justice above the other moral-
political values of liberty, equality and fraternity.
Rawls’s book inaugurated what has been rightly called “a golden age in theorising about justice.”
Consequently, justice, as noted by Tom Campbell, is today “the central and commanding concept
of current mainstream normative political philosophy.” In his edited volume, entitled John Rawls
and the Agenda of Social Justice, B.N. Ray observes that Rawls’s book has renewed not
only scholarly interest, but also popular interest in justice.
13
While there is a widespread agreement among ordinary peoples, politicians and philosophers
about the centrality of justice as a moral-political value, there is no such agreement among them
on its meaning and scope. On these, there are very major differences in the views of the liberal-
utilitarian, liberal-egalitarian (i.e., Rawlsian), libertarian, communitarian, Marxist and feminist
theorists. Of them, the liberal-egalitarian theory of social justice propounded by Rawls has come
to occupy a deservedly central position. Those who advanced alternative or competing theories
of justice feel compelled to present their worth or merit in comparison and contrast with Rawls’s
theory.
As a moral-political value, justice is inter-linked with such other moral-political values as liberty,
equality and fraternity. What makes a society or state just in a basic sense is its right or fair
ordering of human relations by giving to each person her or his due rights and duties as well
as due rewards and punishments. Justice does this by bringing about adjustments between the
principles of liberty, equality, co-operation, etc. Traditionally, then, the principle of justice was
taken to be a principle which balances or reconciles the principles of liberty, equality, etc. Such
a balancing or reconciling is done with reference to some ultimate value, e.g., the value of the
greatest happiness of the greatest number or the value of the freedom and equality of all the
members of a society. In this context, it may be noted in passing that it is the balancing or
reconciling nature of justice, which is represented in the figure of personified justice, who holds
a balance in her hands.
Principles of procedural justice have traditionally been based on the idea of formal equality of
persons, i.e., their equality as human beings or as subjects of the rule of law, irrespective of
their differences in gender, religion, race, caste, wealth, etc. Often, rights-based justice is seen
as procedural justice, whereas needs-based justice is seen as substantive justice.
John Rawls, whose principles of just distribution of social primary goods we shall consider
below, claims that his is a theory of “pure procedural justice.” By pure procedural justice, he
means that the justice of his distributive principles is founded on justice-as-fairness of the
procedure through which they have been arrived at and that they have no independent or
14
antecedent criteria of justice or fairness. If those principles had such independent or antecedent
criteria of justice or fairness but were lacking procedural justice or fairness, they would have
been principles of imperfect procedural justice. As we shall see below, Rawls’s libertarian critic,
Robert Nozick, maintains that the former’s theory is actually not a procedural theory, but a set
of principles of “end-state” or “patterned” justice.
The most famous formulation of a needs-based justice is Marx’s principle of communism: “From
each according to his ability, to each according to his needs.” Generally, socialists subscribe to
one or another version of needs-based, egalitarian justice. They differentiate needs, especially
basic material needs, from wants, preferences or desires. The former are taken to be objective
and universal, whereas the latter are seen to be culture-related and market-related. According
to Abraham Maslow, there is a hierarchy of human needs, ranging from our most basic needs
for fresh air, water, food, shelter to our needs for safety, love, self-esteem and self-realisation.
Obviously, needs-based justice calls for egalitarian distribution of resources within and across
countries.
15
In his critique of, and alternative to utilitarianism, Rawls derives inspiration from Immanuel
Kant’s moral idea of the freedom and equality of every human being. According to Kant, every
human being is to be treated as an end in himself or herself and not as means to the ends of
others. It is this liberal-egalitarian moral principle, which is violated by utilitarianism and which
Rawls reinstates in his theory of social justice. Both in his method or procedure of arriving at
the principles of distributive or social justice and, consequently, in the content or substance of
those principles, Rawls tries to give centrality to the moral principle of the freedom and equality
of every person.
Each person has the same indefeasible claim to a fully adequate scheme of equal basic liberties,
scheme which is compatible with the same scheme of liberties for all.
Principle 2
Social and economic inequalities are to satisfy two conditions : first, they are to be attached to
offices and positions open to all under conditions of fair equality of opportunity; and second, they
are to be to the greatest benefit of the least-advantaged members of society
These principles are listed here in the order of their lexical priority. By “lexical priority”, Rawls
means that the first principle must be fully satisfied before the next principle is applied. It means,
for instance, that “liberty can be restricted only for the sake of liberty”, and not, say, for the
sake of income or wealth. It must, however, be noted in this context that Rawls assumes that
society (his own society, in fact) to which his principles of social justice are to be applied is one
which is reasonably well-off and in which the basic material needs of all are provided for.
The main purpose of the rule of priority is to assign greater importance to equal basic liberties
than to other primary social goods. In “basic liberties,” Rawls includes freedom of conscience,
freedom of thought, freedom of the person along with the right to hold personal property,
freedom from arbitrary arrest and detention or, in other words, the freedom of the rule of law,
freedom of speech and assembly and political freedoms.
According to Rawls, these basic rights and liberties enable us to exercise and realise our “two
highest-order moral powers,” namely, (i) the capacity to understand, apply and act according to
16
the principles of justice and (ii) the capacity to form, revise and pursue conceptions of the good.
In Rawls’s view, every member of a just society must be viewed as having these two moral
capacities. These make them free and equal citizens. The moral equality of citizens means that
“they each have, and view themselves as having, a right to equal respect and consideration in
determining the principles by which the basic arrangements of their society are to be regulated”.
The freedom of the citizens includes their freedom to realise their capacity to pursue their own
conception of the good life.
Since the distribution of social primary goods will have to respect the equality and freedom and
“fraternity” and welfare, etc. of all the members of society, it cannot strictly be an equal
distribution across the board. According to Rawls, once the basic material needs of the people
are met, their right to basic liberties is to be accorded priority over their right to the other social
primary goods, which are covered by the principle of equal opportunities and the difference
principle. While he is opposed to any unequal distribution of basic liberties, he assumes that
some inequalities in income and wealth are inevitable and perhaps not undesirable. Accordingly,
the main purpose of his second principle of social justice is to keep inequalities within the bounds
of justice-as-fairness. Obviously, the distinction between just or fair inequalities and unjust or
unfair inequalities is of crucial importance in Rawls’s theory of social justice.
Rawls thinks that excessive equality in income and wealth would destroy the economic incentives
required for greater creativity and productivity. This would be harmful to both the rich and the
poor. From the standpoint of the poor (as well as of the rich), justice does not require the
complete elimination of economic inequality. Rawls believes that certain inequalities, which
serve as incentives for the greater creativity and productivity of the talented and the gifted, are
not unjust if that greater creativity and productivity are integrated into a social-structural or
institutional arrangement for distribution to the benefit of all, especially the least advantaged
members of the society. He also thinks that giving advantage to the least advantaged would
invariably entail giving benefits to everyone else.
Rawls maintains that a society can so structure or re-structure its basic institutions as to make
inequalities in income and wealth yield maximum benefits to the least advantaged – maximum
in comparison to any reasonable, alternative social re-structuring. His Difference Principle is
meant not to replace inequality with equality in income and wealth, but to transform unfair or
unjust degrees or kinds of economic inequalities into a fair or just kind or degree by maximising
the benefits of the least advantaged. According to the Difference Principle, inequalities which
are advantageous to the better off but not to the least advantaged are unjust.
Rawls’s principle of fair equality of opportunity stipulates that the state should ensure fair
equality of opportunity in the educational, cultural and economic spheres as well as provide
unemployment and sickness benefits. These require an interventionist, welfare state to run or
aid schools, to regulate the economy, etc.
The principles of justice, which we have discussed so far, have been described by Rawls as
“special” formulations of a “general” conception of justice. This general conception is stated as:
All social primary goods – liberty and opportunity, income and wealth and the bases of self-
respect – are to be distributed equally, unless an unequal distribution of any or all of these goods
is to the advantage of the least favoured.
What Rawls means by this general conception of justice is that only those inequalities are unjust
17
which, as in the case of utilitarianism, put some members or the society at a disadvantage.
This “general” conception of justice, however, does not differentiate between the different social
primary goods. It does not say, for instance, how to resolve the conflict, if any, between the
distribution of income and the distribution of liberty. It is to meet this difficulty that Rawls divides
the general conception into a “special conception” of the two principles, which we have discussed
above.
Briefly stated, Rawls’s response is that a social contract method or procedure of political
deliberation respects the Kantian liberal-egalitarian moral idea of the freedom and equality of
all persons and that an agreement or contract arrived at through such a method or procedure
is just or fair to all the parties to that contract. He, in fact, adopts such a procedure and argues
that all the contractors would agree to the above-mentioned general and special formulations
of the principles of distributive justice – principles, which he espouses and defends as the liberal-
democratic-egalitarian principles of social justice.
His social contract is hypothetical and not historical or actual. It is only meant to be a hypothetical
assembly or “original position” of “heads of families.” They hypothetically assemble (before the
formation or organisation of their society) in order to enter into an agreement or social contract
on the general principles of distributive justice, on the basis of which the institutions of their
society are to be constructed.
In order to ensure impartiality and fairness in their agreement or social contract and to incorporate
the moral idea of the freedom and equality of persons, Rawls postulates that the contractors
in his “original position” are under a “veil of ignorance” about their attributes, class, social status
or their own conceptions of the good. They, however, do have knowledge of the general
circumstances of justice such as the limited benevolence of people and the conflict of interests
over the limited amount of social primary goods. They also know that in the actual society in
which they would have to live, they may perhaps end up as the least advantaged members of
the society. Given the uncertainty about the actual position, which a contractor may come to
occupy in the actual society, it is rational for him or her (in the contracting situation, i.e. the
“original position”) to assume that he or she may end up in the least-advantaged position and,
accordingly, to choose a general principle of distribution that would give the best deal to the least
advantaged members of the society. Each contractor would, in other words, follow the “maximin
rule” of choice, which says that in an uncertain situation, one should choose so as to maximise
one’s minimum prospects.
Taken together, Rawls’s principles of social justice, ranked in the order of their lexical priority,
embody the liberal-egalitarian moral injunction of Kant; namely, that human beings are always
to be treated as ends in themselves and never as mere means to the ends of others. From this
perspective, it would be unjust to sacrifice the basic rights and liberties of some persons for the
sake of any majoritarian or utilitarian conceptions of the good. Unlike liberal-utilitarian justice,
Rawls’s liberal-egalitarian justice is marked by its concern for the equality and welfare of
everyone, including, especially, the least advantaged members of the society.
18
6.3.4 The Basic Structure of Society
Rawls has persuasively shown that social justice is of crucial importance to social life and that
it should inform constitutions, laws, policies, legal processes, etc. In fact, according to him, the
primary subject of justice is the basic structure of society. His principles of social justice justifies,
and is justified by, liberal democracy, a regulated market economy and the liberal-egalitarian
welfare state. He states that for translating his Difference Principle into practice, the government
should have four branches, viz., i) an allocation branch “to keep the price system workably
competitive and to prevent the formation of unreasonable market power” ii) a stabilisation
branch to bring about “reasonably full employment” and, jointly with the allocation branch, to
maintain the efficiency of the market economy iii) a transfer branch to attend to “the claims
of need and an appropriate standard of life” and iv) a distribution branch “to preserve an
appropriate justice in distributive shares” by taxation measures and adjustments in property-
rights.
According to him, the individual has absolute liberty rights, including the right to own property
and exchange it in the market, regardless of the end-state or pattern of distribution it may lead
to. This entitlement theory of justice, however, includes a principle of rectificatory justice, which
is meant to correct past injustices, if any, in the acquisition or transfer of property. It can be
seen that Nozick’s libertarian conception of justice is a defense of free-market capitalism. While
it is eloquent on the defense of individual rights from state interference, it is silent on the
undermining of individual freedom and equality by very rich people or corporations.
19
of the means of production, is envisaged as a society in which there will be no scarcity, no limits
to human benevolence and no state. Since the scarcity of social primary goods and the limited
nature of human benevolence are the “circumstances of justice” for Rawls’s theory, their
(presumed) absence in the communist society makes any principles of fair or just distribution
irrelevant to such a society. Instead of any such juridical, superstructural distributive principle,
the higher form of community envisaged by communism will function according to the principle:
“From each according to his ability, to each according to his needs.” In the socialist phase,
which precedes and gives birth to the higher and final communist phase, a work-based or
contribution-based principle of distribution will prevail.
The collapse of Soviet communism and the growing pace of “liberalisation” in country after
country, each with its own pattern of inequalities, have served to cast doubts on the “realism”
of the traditional Marxist hope for the elimination of the “circumstances” of injustice and for
ushering in a society in which social or distributive justice is irrelevant. In fact, departing from
traditional Marxism, some contemporary Marxists interpret the extraction of surplus value from
the workers by the capitalists as a derived form of injustice, which, according to them, rests
on a prior and larger injustice in access to the means of production. In this way, the agenda
of liberal-egalitarian social justice that has been launched by Rawls seems to be having some
impact on Marxism.
6.5 SUMMARY
In this unit, you have read about the idea and concept of justice. It is one of the important
concepts in Political Science as well as other social sciences. There are different types of
justice viz., procedural and substantive. One of the most pathbreaking works in the domain of
justice has been done by Jawn Rawls. It’s liberal – egalitarian conception of justice is basically
a critique of the utilitarian conception of justice. Of course, Rawls too has had his critics. Thus,
the marxists, libertarians and the communitarians have criticised the Rawlsian framework on
different grounds. Be that as it may, Rawls’s theory has its non-standing contemporary political
discourse.
6.6 EXERCISES
1. Briefly explain the concept and idea of Justice.
20
2. Critically examine Rawls’s egalitarian conception of social justice.
21
UNIT 7 IDEA OF DUTY
Structure
7.1 Introduction
7.2 Significance of Duty
7.3 Meaning
7.4 Duties and Rights
7.4.1 Distinct Spaces of Duties and Rights within Liberal Thought
(i) Interest Theory
(ii) Choice Theory
(iii) Autonomy
(iv) Justice
7.4.2 Duties and Rights in the Conservative Perspective
7.4.3 Duties and Rights in the Communitarian Perspective
7.1 INTRODUCTION
Rights discourse has been one of the most prominent features of contemporary political philosophy
and political agendas. It argues that persons, mainly as individuals, are the bearers of a body
of claims, liberties and powers which the rest of the society has to acknowledge and public life
should be based on such acknowledgement and support. Such an exaltation of rights has led to
a deep unease regarding duties and obligations that are called for the maintenance and reproduction
of a just and sane social order or for fostering and promoting an ideal society. The criticisms
regarding privileging of rights in the constitution of a good society has brought to the fore the
role of duties, denoting a shift in perspective, which, while seeing duties as complementary to
rights, also construes duties as marking a space of their own. Such an endeavour has led to
spelling out the role of duties much more clearly in recent literature.
Sometimes, denial of certain rights may make people rise in revolt against a system which is
by and large fair. Discourse on duty has drawn attention to the need to preserve a system which
is overall fair and one cannot rebel against such an order.
22
While rights discourse has seen itself as universally holding good, there have been currents of
thought upholding the significance of reasonable, yet diverse, ways of life and ideals which
qualify such a universal claim to different degrees. They have sought from their followers
commitment and duties to uphold ways of life and ideals distinctive to themselves. Given the
deep pluralism in which societies are being caught today, we cannot ignore such duty based
evocations present in our public life.
Thinkers, like Mahatma Gandhi, have felt that the rights discourse has been fed into the service
of an unending chain of satisfactions and gratifications and this discourse has not been sensitive
to authentically human pursuits, i.e., pursuits characteristic of human beings qua human. It has
led to wanton exploitation of earth’s resources, breeding conflicts and violence closely bound up
with such an endeavour. They have drawn attention to the need to foreground a conception of
the human person and moral duties if we have to sustain civilised ways of life.
At the same time, we cannot ignore that fascist and authoritarian orders have stressed on the
duty to contend against liberal stress on rights and the Marxist pursuit of a non-exploitative and
just social order. By stressing on duty they have attempted to instal their interpretation on
several cherished values and strivings, such as self-respect and culture.
Given such a deployment of the understanding of duty, it necessarily makes this idea a deeply
contested one susceptible to different pulls and pressures. It is also deeply caught in the contexts
of analysis and frameworks and deployed to subserve different ends and purposes. It is,
therefore, important to understand concepts and values that foreground duty. The concept of
duty has to be understood in relation to other values and strivings. This is particularly important
for us in India as duty is often associated with dharma and the latter is related to duties
associated with varna and caste orders. Foregrounding duty without being sensitive to its
associations may lead us to endorse uncritically social grading and ranking and the deep inequalities
and subordination they endorse.
7.3 MEANING
A duty generally prescribes what we ought to do and what we ought not do. It is a reason for
action. Duty specifies the terms that are binding on individuals and groups in their social
practices. It has been suggested that our conscious practices can be seen as motivated by right-
based, duty-based or goal-based perspectives (Dworkin, 1978 and Weldron, 1984). While our
practices might be governed by all these perspectives, one of them might be fundamental. A
duty-based perspective appeals to duty and the reasons embedded therein to uphold and justify
our practices. Duty-based propositions need not deny rights or satisfactions that the other two
perspectives suggest, but they necessarily assert the priority of the former over the latter as in
an argument of the kind below: “A citizen should vote and participate in shaping and forming
public life. His civic and political rights must depend upon the extent to which he participates
in public life. He cannot demand rewards and benefits from public life unless he has extended
such support and participation”.
23
Liberal transportation led to stress on rights and duties were seen as correlated to rights. If a
person possessed rights, then others – be it individuals, groups or the state as the case may be,
were invested with a determinate set of duties to protect and promote those rights. If I have
a right to physical security, others have a duty not to violate or assault such security and if it
was violated or assaulted, the state is duty bound to come to my protection. This correspondence
between rights and duties which led to the effective collapsing of duties within rights has been
challenged from within liberal thought as well as from outside its framework.
i) Interest Theory
This theory was initially stated by Jeremy Bentham who saw rights not as natural or moral, but
as products of law. He argued that the law by creating duties stipulates rights. He said, “It
makes me liable to punishment in case of my doing any of those acts which would have the
effects of disturbing you in the exercise of that right (Hart, 1978).” There is no right if there
is no corresponding duty sanctioned by law. This understanding of the relation is sometimes
called as ‘sanction theory’. It makes possession of a right as another’s legal duty and it becomes
a legal duty only if it is liable for punishment. This way of constructing duties need not preclude
social sanctions of a kind. Individuals as members of non-state organisations may be subject to
rules and to the imposition of sanctions, if they break those rules. Being subject to sanctions
means having duties and those who benefit from those duties can be said to have rights.
However, legal provisions on one hand and social disapproval on the other, may beget an
impasse in the framework of interest theory unless there is a natural or moral grounding to this
relation. But interest theory does not subscribe to the priority rights as natural or moral principles.
A case in point is when the law states that its citizens have the right to preach and practice
its religious beliefs and whenever it does so, it is restrained by threats and actual use of force
by a well organised gang and society does not establish conditions where such practices are met
with approval. In such a case we can scarcely say that the minority has a legal right to practice
its religion. A duty which has to be constantly shored up by force and coercion has little reason
in built into it why an action ought to be performed or to be avoided. Therefore, J.S. Mill was
to say, “To have a right is to have something which society ought to defend one in the possession
of. (Mill, 1910)” Even if we conceive duty as corresponding to rights, it cannot be borne on the
back of force and sanctions.
The choice or will theory counter poses itself against the interest theory stipulating the relation
between rights and duties. One of the important proponents of this theory is H.L.A. Hart. He
suggested that a right is a form of choice. The essential feature of a right is that the person
to whom the duty is owed is able to control the performance of that duty. The duty-right relation
is a chain which binds one individual, the bearer of the duty, and whose other end is in the hands
of another individual, the bearer of the right to use it according to his will. It could beget the
following relations:
(a) The right holder may waive or extinguish the duty or leave it in existence.
24
(b) After a breach or threatened breach of a duty, the right holder may leave the duty
unforced or may reinforce it by suing for compensation.
(c) The right holder may waive or extinguish the obligation to pay compensation resulting
from the breach of duty.
The choice theory invokes duties primarily with reference to rights. But the space of duty need
not be marked by reference to rights only. Duty-acts need not always correlate to right-acts.
Further several rights may not have corresponding duties.
iii) Autonomy
Autonomy is the capacity for reflection and to formulate and revise our preferences, desires,
values and ideas. The philosopher Immanuel Kant advanced a theoretical formulation of this
notion and put forward a specific conception of duty in relation to this capacity. He suggested
that the behaviour of the non-human world is governed by nature. Non-human beings did not
will to act, but acted subject to natural forces and instinct. To the extent human beings acted
on the basis of their appetites and emotions, they too acted heteronomously, i.e. according to
laws and dictates given externally and not by themselves. The characteristic mark of human
beings is their reason, which enabled them to deliberate the way they should act and will to act
accordingly. In following this reason, they acted autonomously; they acted in accordance with
their duty. The morality prescribed by reason was a matter of ‘practical necessity’. Moral
agents understood this necessity and acted accordingly. Through his capacity for autonomy, an
individual acted according to a law that he had prescribed for himself rather than on external
dictates.
For Kant, human beings have a duty to cultivate this autonomy and to act towards others as
beings possessing this capacity. The rights that people possess are expressions of this autonomy
as well as means to nourish the same. Persons possess intrinsic value and should not be used
as the instruments of others’ purposes. He defends right on the grounds of duty which comes
not from nature, but “is apriori, regardless of all empirical ends.”
His famous formulation in this regard was “Act in such a way that you always treat humanity,
whether in your own person or in the person of any other, never simply as a means, but always
at the same time as an end.”
The Kantian notion of autonomy can be seen as cherishing a valued end and constructing a
preference scheme of values based on it for duties to be pursued. Mainstream contemporary
liberalism, however, does not propose any such valued ends and purposes and remains neutral
to them. The ends and purposes are the products of choices rather than given. It is stated in
a principle, interestingly, drawn from Kant himself: Right is before Good.
One of the recent scholars who upholds the valued end of autonomy on liberal grounds is Joseph
Raz. According to him, not merely the abilities of autonomous conduct needs be considered, but
also the desirability of the autonomous life they beget. Personal autonomy consists in appropriate
mental abilities, availability of adequate range of options to choose from and freedom from
coercion and manipulation. Personal autonomy makes people to control, to some degree, their
own destiny expressed through successive decisions throughout their lives. But the good of
autonomy lies not in these abilities and conditions as such, but in the autonomous life they
promote. It does not lie merely in the act of choosing. Autonomy is valuable only if exercised
in the pursuit of good. He thinks that there are multiplicity of good forms of life and it is choice
25
among those many good forms that makes autonomy both meaningful and valuable. Freedom
understood both as the absence of coercion and manipulation and as the presence of worthwhile
options has value because it promotes autonomous lives. Rights to freedom are justified to the
extent they contribute to such an ideal.
(i) An individual X has a right if and only if X can have rights and other things being equal, an
aspect of X’s well-being is a sufficient reason for holding some other person to be under a
duty.
(ii) Rights do not entail duties which merely correlate with or correspond to those rights. Rights
are grounds of duties. Rights are the reasons for the duties to which they give rise. This does
not mean that only rights give rise to duties. Duties might be invoked by other considerations as
well.
(iii) One has a right not merely if one is an intended beneficiary, but only if one’s interest is a
sufficient reason for holding another to be under a duty.
In this consideration, the value of autonomy is qualified by rights and rights invoke a specific
set of duties although there are types of duties other than invoked in terms of rights.
Raz insists upon the importance of the general structure and culture of a society for the
possibility and viability of personal autonomy. According to him, an autonomous life can be lived
only in the context of shared institutions, values and opportunities.
It requires such things as a culture of tolerance and a range of career options. He insists upon
duties to cherish such a cultural ambience. Raz also argues that the state should be committed
to promote the good of autonomous life and its constitution and laws and policies should seek
to promote that good. In promoting such a good, the state may avow many individual rights,
although many of the goods that the state promotes may be collective goods bound up with the
performance of specific duties.
iv) Justice
John Rawls proposes a set of principles to inform a just society which, he argues, all reasonable
people will concur. These principles establish a fair and equal basis for collective life expressed
in terms of rights. These principles of justice lead to two sorts of principles: Principles for
institutions which apply to the basic structure of society, and principles for individuals which set
the duties and obligations of persons with respect to institutions and one another. Citizens are
duty-bound to support just institutions as they themselves concur to them.
For Rawls, persons are bound to abide by social practices upholding a just society on the basis
of natural duty or obligation. He, therefore, makes the distinction between duty and obligations.
Persons may be bound by natural duty or obligation. Natural duties are those moral claims that
apply to persons irrespective of their consent such as to help others in distress, not to be cruel
etc. Such duties are not tied to particular institutions or social arrangements, but are owed to
persons as persons. They are prior to social agreement or choice. Obligations, unlike duties,
describe those moral ties we voluntarily incur whether by contract, promise or other expressions
of consent. The latter by themselves are not enough to create obligations. They should be just
too.
26
The liberal tradition on the relation between rights and duties remains profoundly complex. A
great part of this complexity has to do with the kind of values prioritised under different tradition
of liberalism. Those perspectives which give priority to rights tend to make duties supportive to
rights. Those traditions which insist on certain perfectionist values that a society should promote
tend to be more emphatic on duties.
This emphasis on duties becomes significant when we move out of liberal tradition and begin
to focus on other traditions of thought. Three of them will be considered here on account of
their emphasis on duty.
It is important that every generation be inserted into the culture, mores and institutions of society
rather than every individual think that he has the right to choose culture, mores and institutions
of his choice. Traditions and legacies assign to people definite tasks and responsibilities to be
fulfilled. By performing such tasks and responsibilities, one furthers the purposes of institutions
enabling new generations to be inserted into the collective life of societies. It is by performing
such duties that everyone comes to fulfil himself or herself. Such a fulfilment contributes to
further the purposes of society and reinforce its mores and institutions. On the other hand,
insistence on rights undermines age-old and cherished institutions and hallowed ways of life. It
breeds deep insecurity and uncertainty in life prompting and promoting widespread dissatisfactions.
Conservatives argue that the arrogance of the rights-bearing individual suggests that he has
access to all the knowledge that has gone into the making of social life and that he has access
to absolutely certain knowledge to change and transform such social life. They believe that both
these claims are unfounded and hold the prospects of a far worse kind of life than the one
embodied in the ways of life they strove to alter.
Conservative perspectives often urge members of society to look at its institutions and ways of
life with awe and respect rather than through critical scrutiny. The performance of one’s duty
acquires greater purposefulness and satisfaction, if such a perspective is internalised by the
concerned social agent.
Conservatives link duty with a set of values such as trust, loyalty, dedication, cooperation,
obedience and satisfaction with one’s station in life. They stress the limitedness of human
understanding and the reach of human reason and scrutiny. Maintenance of the existing social
order and its preservation often remains their battle cry. They may not be against certain
reforms, but such reforms need to be firmly based upon existing order and its continuation.
Conservatives, by focussing on centrality of duty, have decried the stress on rights in liberal and
radical thought-currents.
27
7.4.3 Duties and Rights in the Communitarian Perspective
While the idea of autonomy is deeply influenced by Kant, communitarians are influenced by
certain ideas underscored by Aristotle and Hegel. Communitarians argue that right-based theories
ignored the fact that our capacity to conceive and exercise rights and pursue autonomy can only
develop in society, in and through relations and interactions with others. They argue that
prioritisation of rights neglects the social conditions that enable us to exercise choices. They
accuse those who accord priority to rights as subscribing to atomism, wherein individuals are
seen as self-sufficient agents outside the society.
The communitarians, therefore, reject the notion of primacy of rights, i.e., the moral stand that
individual rights have primacy over duties, virtue or collective good. They stress on duties and
duty to sustain institutions which can promote virtue and collective good.
Communitarians reject the notion of neutral political concern, central to right-based perspectives
wherein the state remains neutral to different conceptions of good life that may prevail in a
society whether such conceptions are held by the majority or by a minority. Communitarians feel
that neutral political concern vetoes collective pursuit of aims shared by the majority. They argue
that the promotion of a society sharing common values must be prior to the rights of individuals
within that society. Promotion of culture and shared values necessarily insists upon duties to be
performed rather than rights to be enjoyed. Scholars like Charles Taylor have argued that given
our dependence on the culture of freedom for our individual liberty, we must have ‘not only
negative duties of non-interference’, but also ‘positive duties to sustain such a culture’.
Such a culture of freedom requires public support which can come forth only from public
institutions, which are stable and effective. This requires that such institutions enjoy legitimacy
in the eyes of its citizens. Such legitimacy can come forth only if society is organised around
shared concerns.
Communitarians argue that even if rights are upheld, they will not enjoy respect if people are
not bound together by shared conceptions and ways of life sustained by duty. It is through duties
that we not merely reach out to others, but also sustain an appropriate milieu for the exercise
of rights.
There are different types of communitarians. All of them do not necessarily reject the significance
of rights. However, they all argue that duties are significant not merely in relation to rights, but
in protecting and promoting common good.
Gandhi argues that all men and women are equal. The doctrine of advaita upholds it. “If I am
That and besides That there is none else”, being characteristic of advaita, every being has to
be regarded as supreme. The same principle dwells in each and every one of us. By realising
this principle in us, we will be able to wholly determine our lives. This belief in equality, he says
has led him to fight “against the Brahmins themselves whenever they have claimed any superiority
to themselves either by reason of birth or by reason of their subsequently acquired knowledge.”
(Iyer, 1979)
28
Swaraj for Gandhi is a pursuit within the reach of everyone. It involves the duty of self-discipline
and a transformation on that basis. It is the rule of the mind over passions. Self-rule enables
one to pursue Artha and Kama within the bounds of dharma.
The notion of self-rule for Gandhi implied the voluntary internalisation of our obligation to others
which will be obstructed by our placing ourselves at the mercy of our selfish desires. Our civil
duties flow from such self-cultivation. For Gandhi, real rights were the results of the performance
of duty.
At the same time, Gandhi opposed domination. He held that freedom is necessary for moral
growth. He said, “no society can possibly be built on the denial of individual freedom; it is
contrary to the very nature of men.”
For Gandhi, equality is one of the greatest good to be cherished. Other goods like dignity and
integrity were closely interwoven with it. Gandhi rejected considerations such as gender, birth,
class, caste, education and nationality as justifying unequal treatment.
At the same time, Gandhi upheld the path of dharma and he considered the Varnashrama
dharma as the appropriate path of duty. But unlike the prevailing belief, he argued that the
varna system upholds, “absolute equality; although the way it is presently expressed it is a
monstrous parody of the original.” For him varna is not the ranking of status based on inherited
division of labour, nor is it the division of labour in accordance with innate abilities. For him,
“Varna is nothing more than an indication of a duty that has been handed down to each one
of us by our forefathers.” He argued that the law of varna meant that everyone followed as
a matter of dharma, duty, the hereditary callings of his forefathers in so far as it was not
inconsistent with fundamental ethics. The authentic culture for man was to free himself to
spiritual pursuits. Varna helped one to conserve one’s energy by making him expand little in the
cultivation and pursuit of his occupation of his livelihood as it is passed on from generation to
generation, thereby freeing men for higher pursuits.
He argued that varna set human-beings free for extending the field of spiritual research and
spiritual evolution. It also curbed material ambitions.
Gandhi argued that varna is binding as far as the mode of acquiring one’s livelihood is concerned.
It does not prevent any one from acquiring knowledge and skills one might wish to pursue.
Therefore, he said, “A Sudhra has as much right to knowledge as a Brahman, but he falls from
his estate if he tries to earn his livelihood through teaching.”
Gandhi related the concept of Swaraj and dharma to his other concepts such as non-attachment
and non-violence. One sets oneself free towards self-realisation and self-rule through non-
attachment to material possessions and belongings and by being free from the entanglements
of desires and passions. Non-violence rests upon extending the principle of respect and equality
towards others. The autonomy that Gandhi envisaged was not on the basis of the availability
of abundant material resources, but on the basis of conscious control, regulation and denial of
such resources. The latter set people free to make truly authentic choices while entanglement
in material possessions vitiates such choices.
29
the related rights, the second requires that people act positively to do something. The first calls
for refraining from action or non-interference, while the latter calls for action or intervention.
However, such a distinction is far too naïve. Often the so-called negative duties call for extensive
positive action. For instance the right to security does not merely call for abstinence from injury
or assault, but involves contributions in terms of taxes and public supports to maintain an
extensive system of public security. Sometimes, the so-called positive duties might be embroiled
in a complex set of abstentions and interventions. Subsistence rights, for instance, involve the
duty to support the deprived as well as extending the enabling support to the deprived to be self-
supporting on the basis of their own work. The latter may call forth a series of interventions
and non-interventions.
We have to distinguish between the duty not to violate a right and the duty to prevent violation
of rights. For instance, duty not to assault others is not the same as the duty to prevent a third
person from assaulting someone when one could protect the victim from such an attack. The
first is of greater import than the second.
There is no one to one pairing between kinds of duties and kinds of rights. The fulfilment of
rights may call for multiple kinds of duties. For every basic right, three types of duties are
suggested:
For example, with regard to personal security everyone has the duty:
iii) To provide for the security of those unable to provide for their own.
It is impossible for any right to be fully guaranteed unless all three types of duties are fulfilled,
although different types of duties have differential binding force. Duties to avoid depriving
demand that one refrains from making an unnecessary gain for oneself by means detrimental
to the claims of others. Such duties bind us not to undertake a course of action that deprives
others of a means which, without such action, would have provided a satisfaction. Further, such
an action was not called for to meet one’s basic rights as the only realistic option in the context.
The duty to protect arises when the duty to avoid is not fulfilled. It is a secondary duty enforcing
the primary duty of avoiding deprivation to others. It calls upon, sometimes individuals and at
other times groups or institutions, to enforce this duty. In many societies, the governments acting
on behalf of common interest enforce such duty.
There are three sub-categories of duties to aid which beget transfer of resources to those who
cannot provide for their own survival:
i) There are duties to aid attached to certain roles or relationships. Such duties are the concern of
only those who are in a particular relationship and are directed towards specific persons.
30
Duties of parents towards their young children and duties of grown up children towards their
aged parents come under this category.
ii) Suppose some people have acted in such a way as to eliminate the last available means of
subsistence and the responsible government has failed to protect the victims, the duty to aid the
latter falls on those responsible for the deprivation. In such cases, there is failure to perform
duties and the victims were harmed by both actions and omission of actions by other people.
iii) A third kind of deprivation is not on account of failure in duty but is, in a sense, natural such as
in situations of hurricane or earthquake. The victims in this instance are helpless in the face of
truly great obstacles to their existence. They are, however, able to maintain themselves if they
are provided with protection and if they are left alone, they will die due to lack of the means of
subsistence.
One of the major expressions of duty to aid is the duty to design social institutions that do not
exceed the capacity of individuals and groups. If duties to avoid and to protect are fulfilled,
duties to assist may not be urgently called for, but in the event of failure to avoid deprivation
and to extend protection, duty to aid could assume a great deal of importance.
The above explanation goes to suggest that the scope of duty is significantly different from that
of right, although one cannot speak of duties without eventually relating them to rights.
As the scope of duty gets markedly varied as we move beyond their immediate correspondence
to rights, there are rights which are not immediately tied up with duties:
There are four kinds of rights that are generally spoken of:
I. Claim Rights: They are the demands that one party has upon another. In such instances,
while ‘A’ has a right, ‘B’ has a reciprocal duty. Those who argue for the mutualities of rights
and duties often restrict rights to claim rights. For example, workers have claim rights on their
wages; their employers have a duty to pay them wages mutually agreed upon.
II. Liberty Rights: Often they are simply called as liberties. They do not immediately suggest
duties, for e.g., my right to wear a dress does not invoke a corresponding duty from others in
an immediate sense.
III. Powers: Laws and customs invest certain distinct capacities on people which might be
possessed by all, such as the right to vote, or confined to a select few, such as the power to
adjudicate invested in the judges. Such powers do not necessarily have corresponding duties.
IV. Immunities: Immunities are counter-posed to powers and, therefore, are protections against
the reach of powers. For instance, the power of conscription may be vested in some authorities
in a state, but immunity provides safety valves against such powers. Again, they are not
correlated with a set of duties.
Liberties, powers and immunities do not have correlated duties marking an enlarged space for
rights.
7.6 SUMMARY
Although rights and duties are often correlated, different theories and perspectives may apportion
31
different weights to rights and duties. Duties are prioritised in perspectives which valorise
substantive conception of what is good and what is bad. Within liberal tradition itself, there might
be distinct perspectives on rights and duties. While dictatorships, authoritarian regimes and
fascist leaders have underscored duties and decried rights, there are other perspectives which
have argued that rights can be honoured only if an ambience for the same is sustained through
duties. Mahatma Gandhi prioritised duties and argued that only those have claims on rights who
have performed their duties. Even if there is a correlation between duties and rights, they cannot
be paired with each other one to one. Although rights and duties often invoke each other, their
ambits markedly vary. There are rights which have no immediate correlated duties. There are
duties which, as they distance themselves from their immediate correlation with rights, lead to
sustenance of common good.
7.7 EXERCISES
1. Highlight the reasons for the growth in concerns associated with duty.
32
UNIT 8 CITIZENSHIP
Structure
8.1 Introduction
8.2 Significance
8.3 Nature of Citizenship
8.4 Liberal Democracy, Citizenship and Civic Culture
8.5 Marxism and Citizenship
8.6 Persons and Citizens
8.7 Group-Differentiated Citizenship
8.7.1 Citizenship as an Attribute Independent of Cultural Identity
8.7.2 Citizenship as a Group Differentiated Identity
i) Citizenship based on Polyethnic Rights
ii) Special Representation Rights
8.8 Summary
8.9 Exercises
8.1 INTRODUCTION
A distinctive relation that people share in common among relative equals in public life and the
rights and privileges it confers and the duties and obligations that arise therefrom, has been
noted and given expression to in several societies in the past. Citizenship denotes membership
of a political community expressing such a relation. Such a relation often deeply marks other
social relations in general and public life in particular. Some societies such as the Greeks, the
Romans and the city-states of Medieval Europe gave definitive legal and political expression to
this relation. With the rise of modern liberal states citizenship which was confined to a small
fraction of the permanent residents of a polity came to be demanded and progressively extended
to larger and larger segments of the population within such states. The demand for equality
came to be mainly expressed as equal citizenship. Further citizenship became the normative tool
for socio-political inclusion of groups struggling against prevalent forms of inequality, discrimination
and exclusion.
Today, everyone is the citizen of one or another state and even where citizenship is in dispute,
several international and domestic provisions ensure a modicum of basic rights and obligations.
While citizenship entitlement has become universal, there are unresolved contestations regarding
the criteria that should inform inclusion and exclusion of claimants to citizenship; the rights and
resources that should accompany it and duties and obligations expected of the citizen; the
relation of the citizen to the state on one hand and to the community on the other; the relationship
of citizenship to other cherished values such as freedom and equality and the civic and civilisational
values and practices that should inform citizenship. Further, an activated citizenship is seen by
many as offering solution to several ailments of the polity in our times. Given these complex
33
demands, pulls and pressures the understanding of this notion remains deeply contested in the
prevailing literature on the subject.
8.2 SIGNIFICANCE
The growing significance of citizenship has not put to rest the theoretical ambiguity associated
with this notion. The importance of the concept of citizenship to engage with a series of political
processes and values and therefore, as a major normative and explanatory variable has undergone
significant changes over time. T.H. Marshal employed it initially to explain the striving for legal,
political and social rights among the excluded social groups with particular reference to the
working class. He traced the development of citizen rights and connected this development to
the situation of the bourgeois on one hand, and the working classes on the other. Citizenship
concerns, however, are much larger and ethnic groups and minorities of all sorts have resorted
to it as a sheet-anchor. Bryan Turner explores the link between social movements and conflicts
and citizenship identity. There are some writers who argue that citizenship rights in their origin
are closely linked to elite structures. Antony Giddens and Ramesh Misra draw our attention to
the deep ambiguity surrounding citizenship rights. Janoski regrets the missing link between
citizenship rights and obligations and the absence of micro studies relating the two. In recent
years, there have been major attempts to link citizenship with group identity and to defend a
group differentiated conception of citizenship against a conception of citizenship based on
individual rights. Sociologically, there are few studies to demonstrate how marginalised people
are brought within the vortex of citizenship rights and how nations integrate strangers from other
countries and cultures. Further, we know little about the causes that drive people towards the
ideals of citizenship. There are wide differences in this regard from Marshall’s attribution of the
same to class to Maslow’s hierarchy of needs. Further ideological predilections deeply qualify
understanding and significance of citizenship. These are just a few highlights and concerns of
the growing literature on citizenship in our times.
There was no significant discussion on citizenship in social science literature in the recent past.
However, in the last decade and a half, citizenship has suddenly emerged as a central theme
in social science literature, both as a normative consideration and social phenomenon.
Certain recent trends in the world and in India have increasingly suggested citizenship as a nodal
concern. Increasing voter apathy and long-term welfare dependency in the Western World; the
nationalist and mass movements which brought down bureaucratic socialist regions in Eastern
Europe and the Soviet Union; the backlash against welfare regimes in the West and centralized,
often, one-party regimes in the Third World and the demographic shift in the Western World
towards multicultural and multiracial social composition have increasingly drawn attention to the
significance of citizenship. While the decline of authoritarian regimes which curbed citizen-
agency greatly highlighted the importance of the latter, governmental attack on welfare state
brought to the fore threats to social rights so central to the inclusionary practices of citizenship.
Critics of the welfare, socialist and authoritarian regimes have brought to the fore the importance
of the non-state arena constituted of citizenship-agency. Philosophically the decline of positivism,
which provided little scope for the free-play of citizenship-agency, has greatly heightened the
significance of the choices that citizens make discretely and collectively. In India, an active
citizenship is suggested as the need of the hour for the prevalent authoritarianism, lack of
accountability of public offices, widespread corruption, intolerance of dissent, violation of
fundamental rights, lack of citizens’ grievance ventilation and redressal, lack of public spiritedness
and work culture, transparency in administration and intolerance towards other citizens.
34
Overall, there is greater appreciation today of the qualities and attitudes of citizens for the health
and stability of modern democracy. Their sense of identity and their relationship to regional,
ethnic, religious and national identities is very important to ensure political stability in complex
and plural democracies. Certain qualities like the ability to tolerate and work together with others
who are different are important ingredients of successful democracy. Galston suggests that
together with these qualities, the desire of the citizens to participate in the political process in
order to promote the public good and hold political authorities accountable; their willingness to
show self restraint and exercise personal responsibility in their economic demands and in
personal choices which affect their health and their environment and their sense of justice and
commitment to a fair distribution of resources are called for in any healthy democracy. He says
that in their absence “the ability of liberal societies to function successfully progressively
diminishes”.
Today, there is a greater consensus than ever before that mere institutional and procedural
devices such as separation of powers, a bicameral legislature and federalism will not ensure the
health and probity of a polity. Civic virtue and public spiritedness which are integral to citizenship
are required for the purpose.
While increasingly certain rights are conceded to all human beings in normal times by states,
citizens have certain specific rights which non-citizens do not possess. Most states do not grant
the right to vote and to stand for public office to aliens. The same can be said about obligations
too. What we regard as rights of citizens today were initially a preserve of the elite. However,
eventually the great democratising processes led the large masses of residents – the marginalised,
the ethnic groups, minorities, women and the disabled persons to the benefits and burdens of
citizenship.
Just the fact that one is a citizen gives access to many rights which aliens do not enjoy. Aliens
become naturalised as citizens with attendant rights and obligations. Passive membership often
is associated with limited legal rights and extensive social rights expressing redistributive
arrangements. The state plays a major role in devising and sustaining them. Active membership
highlights citizen-agency and is closely linked with democracy and citizen participation. Most
political communities of which citizens are members today are nation-states. Therefore, when
we talk about membership of political communities, we primarily refer to membership of nation
states.
Citizenship rights are universal in the sense that they pertain to all citizens and in all relevant
respects. They are sought to be implemented accordingly. Universality of rights need not
preclude enjoyment of group-related rights and to the extent that citizens belong to relevant
groups, they are increasingly conceded such rights. Minorities and disadvantaged groups in
many societies do enjoy certain special rights. However, often equal rights of citizens are seen
as running into conflict with group-rights and cultural belonging of subgroups.
35
Citizenship invokes a specific equality. It may admit a wide range of quantitative or economic
inequalities and cultural differences, but does not admit qualitative inequality wherein one man
or woman is marked off from another with respect to their basic claims and obligations. If they
are marked off for special consideration, it is on account of the disadvantages they suffer
relative to others or due to their distinct collective identity. Citizenship invites persons to a share
in the social heritage, which in turn means a claim to be accepted as full members of the society
in which they have a claim. Therefore, it provides for equal access to and participation in the
public fora and institutions which arbitrate on social heritage. Citizenship is supposed to be
insulated from class and status considerations. However, to the extent that citizens have equal
access and participation in public life, they collectively decide to a great extent the framework
and criteria that determines public life. Therefore, undoubtedly it has a levelling impact. In this
context, one of the most important questions that comes to the fore is whether basic equality
can be created and preserved without invading the freedom of the competitive market. However,
in spite of the role of the market there has been an undeniable sociological tendency wherein
citizenship in recent years has been inevitably striving towards social equality and it has been
a significant social tendency for over 300 years now.
Citizenship involves duties as well as rights. Over the years, an array of rights have been
associated with it. The same cannot be said about the duties associated with citizenship. It has
had long term consequences in terms of increasing the role of the state and shrinking citizen-
initiative.
(i) Civil
(iii) Social
i) The civil dimension is composed of the rights necessary for individual freedom such as liberty
of the person, freedom of speech, thought and faith, the right to own personal property and to
conclude valid contracts and the right to strive for a just order. The last are the rights to defend
and assert all one’s claims in terms of equality with others under rule of law. Courts of justice
are primarily associated with civil rights. In the economic field, the basic civil right is the right
to work i.e., the right to follow the occupation of one’s choice and in the place of one’s choice
subject to limits posed by other rights.
ii) The political dimension consists of the rights to participate in the exercise of political power as
a member of the body that embodies political authority; to vote; to seek and support political
leadership; to marshal support to political authority upholding justice and equality and to struggle
against an unfair political authority.
iii) The social dimension consists of a whole range of claims involving a degree of economic
welfare and security; the right to share in full the social heritage and to live the life due to one
as per the standards prevailing in one’s society. The social dimension also involves the right to
culture which entitles one to pursue a way of life distinctive to oneself.
36
In feudal society that prevailed in large parts of the world prior to the onset of modernity, status
was the mark of class and was embedded in inequality. There were no uniform standards of
rights and duties with which men and women were endowed by virtue of their membership of
society. Equality of citizens did not qualify inequality of classes. The caste system in India too
ranked castes unequally in terms of rights and obligations, although the nature of inequality
prevalent here differed in significant respects from that of the feudal society. These ineqalitarian
orders were progressively displaced by a system based on the civil rights of the individual, not
on the basis of local custom, but the common law of the land. The evolution of different
institutions representing and embodying different dimensions of rights was uneven. In Europe,
the trajectory of the evolution of these rights can be marked as civil rights in the eighteenth
century, political rights in the 19th century and social rights in the 20th century. However, in the
colonies, particularly in India, we find the national movement and the independent regime that
followed it invoked all these threefold dimensions together.
The mode of education and other cultural institutions of liberal democratic society define its
citizens as free and equal individuals who are incidentally members of particular ethnic, class
and religious communities. Ethnic class and religious relations often beget hierarchical relations.
Liberal democracy suggests that the hierarchies generated by such communities are irrelevant
to the state in its treatment of citizens. Marxists and in recent years, the communitarians have
found that such an understanding of citizenship is idealistic and narrow and does not take
seriously the embedded nature of citizens.
However, public education in a liberal democracy till recently had the effect of relativising the
hierarchies and ranking systems generated by particularistic cultural communities. It suggested
that the identities of citizens should not be wholly or exclusively governed by the principles and
values underlying those hierarchies. Civic education which was integral to the building up of
citizenship attempted to inculcate certain normative standards such as the ideal attitudes,
dispositions and values proper to citizens. Such a civic culture was seen as supportive of
citizenship. However, it has to be noted that public education, in turn, created hierarchies
distinctive of its own where institutions and disciplines came to be ranked according to the
valorisation they enjoyed in the market. Therefore, the civic culture that liberal democracy threw
up was profoundly ambivalent.
Civic culture as a specific form of culture pertaining to public life proposes world-views, ways
of life, ideas of nature and standards of excellence that shape human behaviour and self-
understanding. It is created, transformed and reproduced by processes of persuasion. The
norms proper to civic life are expected to be internalised by citizens in their interface with civic
culture. However, while offering a normative order, ranking and directing citizen activity, a civic
culture permits significant spaces for contestation and to propose alternative ways of life. It
may, therefore, beget a widely plural understanding of citizenship. Therefore, civic culture itself
needs to be wetted by the rule of law.
37
However, civic culture has with it certain resources by which the pluralism that it begets
remains, normally, within certain limits. Civic culture lays down a civic moral ideal before its
members based on the stand point of free and equal individuality. Further, given the fact that
the self-understanding of members of a society are shaped by the moral standards of the
particularistic cultural communities to which they belong, civic culture has a strong ‘contravailing
edge’. The impact of the former begins to tell strongly from birth itself, through the rituals and
practices of the community while civic educational processes have their impact relatively late.
For Marxism the basic social relations in all class divided societies are class relations. It is the
relation between the peasantry and landlords under feudalism and between the working class
and the bourgeoisie that decisively shape the social relations under feudalism and capitalism
respectively. If class relations project themselves as basic, then social relations would be mired
in class-struggle endangering social unity that is worth relying on, and bringing to the fore, the
coercive character of the state to the full to hold classes and class-struggle at bay.
The ideology of the state plays a major role in containing class-struggle and in reconstituting
social relations on a basis other than class relations. Under capitalism, Marxists argue, social
relations are formulated by this ideology as relations between citizens. The citizens are declared
as free and equal and sometimes, as rooted in a cultural ethos and civilisational bond. The
freedom and equality of citizens has its counterpart in the exchange relations of the market
where from a one-sided view, equals gets exchanged for equals and the agents of such a system
of exchange are free to exchange the products they have. However, such an ideology formulated
by the state can be seen as superficial and partial when understanding and analysis is not
confined to the surface. In such an exercise, social relations are marked as class-relations that
are caught in an irreversible struggle between basic classes.
For Marxists, however, state ideology has a real basis in all societies including capitalism,
although that real basis lies in an exclusive and one sided projection of social reality. It is not
mere chimera. Social agents irrespective of the classes they belong to come to locate their role
and place in society in and through this ideology. In capitalist society, the force of this ideology
remains persuasive and pervasive due to the massive institutional and ideological complexes of
the state through which it is disseminated such as public education, the media, civic associations,
political parties, trade unions, legal and juridical organisations and sometimes, religious organisations
as well. The French philosopher, Louis Althusser, called them the ideological apparatuses of the
state. The consciousness of social agents, routinely and prominently, under conditions of this
ideology remains consciousness of citizens, unless and as long as it is not challenged by the
contradictions of capitalism and class struggle to overcome them.
Marxism, therefore, calls for a double critique of the notion of free and equal citizenship avowed
38
by liberal democracy without denying the worth of the notion itself. First, it expresses only the
superficial face of the market related freedoms of the bourgeois society and hides the profound
contradictions in which social relations under capitalism are caught. An entire array of public
institutions rest on this notion and in their turn reinforce it. Secondly, rights and duties associated
with citizenship are important and necessary to lay bare the contradictions of capitalist relations
and mount struggles to overcome them. Social classes cannot organise themselves, if the basic
freedoms associated with citizenship are denied to social agents.
Hoffman and Janoski suggest that (i) there are four categories of citizens who have been either
excluded from citizenship or had to put up a relentless struggle to be accepted as citizens:
i) Stigmatised Humans: They are supposed to be those who suffer from a social defilement or
infirmity. They include the class based poor, gender disqualified women, racial or ethnic groups
who are attributed low status, gender despised homosexual groups etc. They are also the most
common category of candidates for citizenship. These groups are seen as unable to perform
the duties and accept the rights of citizenship due to their narrow interests which are unlikely
to benefit the community. They are often charged by their social superiors as selling their
votes, being in the control of their husbands or caretakers and not having enough education or
mental capacity to make a decision. Cultural and value dissensions have sometimes brought
religious minorities and gay groups too within this category. These groups had to put up relentless
struggles for equal citizenship and the battles are still on.
ii) Impaired Humans: They may hail from established citizen groups but their competence to
fulfil rights and obligations may be questioned due to physical or mental disabilities that preclude
action or good judgement and make them dependent upon others. The inclusion movement in
many countries, however, has brought about significant changes in the condition of the mentally
and physically challenged.
iii) Potential Humans: They include the foetus in the womb, accident victims in a permanent
coma, unconscious patients or aged citizens who have lost all thought and activity processes
other than involuntary life sustenance. They, of course, have their rights but we can speak little
of their obligations.
39
iv) Human-like Non-Humans or Quasi Humans: Nations, ethnic and even religious groups
could be included in this category. They are endowed with certain group rights which we will
discuss shortly. There are a second type of social actors who fall in this category such as
corporations and offices whose claim for being treated as corporist units are significantly
different from nations, ethnic groups and religious communities. Corporate rights lead to
systematic class and size bias and place them in contention with the notion of free and equal
citizenship.
While understanding of cultures are widely varied, Will Kymlicka has suggested that the pertinent
notion of culture in terms of group-differentiated rights is societal culture; that is, “a culture
which provides its members with meaningful ways of life across the full range of human
activities, including social, educational, religious, recreational, and economic life, encompassing
both public and private spheres”. It is not merely shared memories or values, but also common
institutions and values. Societal culture, according to him, is expressed in everyday vocabulary
of social life and embodied in practices covering most areas of human activity such as in
schools, media, economy, government etc. He argues that culture has the capacity to survive
in modern times only by becoming a societal culture. Citizenship is deeply bound with such
societal culture, and citizens through their activity shape and reshape this culture. Societal
cultures play a major role in enabling and promoting contexts of freedoms. Kymlicka has
suggested that “freedom involves making choices amongst various options and our societal
culture not only provides these options, but also makes them meaningful to us”. It is with
reference to culture that the value of practices comes to be underscored. It is in the background
of cultural narratives that certain authoritative lines of appropriate conduct is marked for us,
conduct which, of course, can be subsequently revised by the exercise of our freedoms. This
requires according to the famous philosopher of law, Ronald Dworkin, protection of our culture
from “structural debasement or decay”. The availability of meaningful options to people largely
depends upon access to societal culture.
Cultures are modes of life which are much more enduring. While there are instances of people
making a successful transition from one culture to another, this is not a reasonable option for
a vast number of people. Of course, cultures are not sterile waters. They do undergo significant
changes over time, but across these changes they remain the self-same cultures. With liberalisation
and globalisation, there has been a greater interface between cultures, but it cannot be said that
the coming together of cultures have made people less aware of their own. If anything, it has
been just the contrary.
Margalit and Raz have advanced two major reasons for the endurance of cultures. The first,
40
cultural membership provides meaningful options. According to them, familiarity with a culture
determines the boundaries of the imaginable and if a culture decays, the options and opportunities
open to its members will shrink, become less attractive and their pursuit less likely to be
successful. The second reason is that self-identity and recognition by others at a fundamental
level depend on “criteria of belonging” and not as much on personal ‘accomplishment’. Social
identification and belonging that arises from it is important to people. Dignity and self-respect
are deeply bound up with it.
Cultural membership too makes one’s accomplishments not as isolated instances, but bonded
with and reproducing an entire tradition. When institutions are leavened by culture, the participation
of people in them becomes spontaneous and lively too. It begets relationships of solidarity and
trust.
However, people employing their freedoms do revise their attachments and belonging and for
a vast majority of people, the matrix of such a zone of belonging and exercise of their freedoms
remains the nation-state informed by societal culture.
A societal culture is not uniform. It is constituted of diverse streams and autonomous cultures.
Often people access societal cultures through such streams and autonomous cultures. The
distinct identities embedded in these streams are shaped by such a culture as they in turn shape
it as a whole.
Two types of relationships are suggested between citizenship and its cultural embeddment.
Communities assign stable and well known duties and responsibilities.There are unambiguous
standards to evaluate conduct. Communities orient human desire to definitive channels.
Communication in such communities acquires clarity and effectiveness due to sharing in common
a range of background assumptions. Communities do not entertain questions on meaning, purpose,
value and responsibility on a whole range of activities they are constituted of.
41
communities, but at the same time acknowledging the need to work with their members. In such
a conception, while a citizen is committed to his communitarian identity and moral ideal, she at
the same, respects and acts in consent with fellow citizens whose communitarian identities and
ideals greatly differ from her.
Such a double framework can be difficult for many who have strong commitments to their
community ideals. Beliefs and practices alien to us can be deeply threatening. Such a threat to
deeply held beliefs and hallowed practices in interface with such an understanding of citizenship
may give rise to parochial, sectarian, exclusivist, authoritarian and fundamentalist tendencies.
In this conception, citizenship means very different things to different communities. The rights
that different communities enjoy and the obligations they are expected to shoulder differ, although
the principles on which they are grounded are the same. These principles are the significance
of community for the constitution of the self and the need to ensure political stability under
conditions of freedom and equality.
Three types of rights are suggested under a differentiated understanding of citizenship, although
it is possible to suggest a much more complex typology in this regard, considering the kind of
deep diversity that prevails in countries like India, Russia, Indonesia and China.
i) Citizenship based on Polyethnic Rights: A large number of states are polyethnic in their
composition today, although non-western societies have a much longer experience of such a
composition. Western Societies have experienced major shifts in their ethnic composition
following their colonial expansion and in the post-colonial period. Such ethnic groups have
challenged the demand that they should abandon significant aspects of their ethnic heritage
42
and assimilate themselves to the mainstream culture. Initially, they demanded the right to freely
express themselves without discrimination in the larger society of which they were a part. It
resulted in changes in educational curriculum and opened to them the arena of music and arts
distinctive to them. Such a demand however did not make significant difference to such visible
ethnic minorities, such as the Blacks in the U.S., except a small stratum within them. In recent
years, these ethnic groups have demanded funding of ethnic associations, magazines and festivals
as integral part of the funding of arts and museums. They have sought exemption from Sunday
closing or animal slaughter legislation, motor-cycle helmet laws and official dress-codes, ban
on wearing headscarf (turban) and so on. These are stronger ethnic claims.
ii) Special Representation Rights: Special representation rights are demanded by certain groups
because the prevailing political process may subject them to some systematic disadvantage
whereby they are not able to effectively represent their views and interests. In India, Dalits
have demanded special representation rights on this ground, while the Adivasis have demanded
them along with ethnic rights.
iii) Self-Government Rights: Self-Government rights are a case of an extreme demand for the
group-differentiated right. They tend to divide people into separate political spaces with their
distinct history, territory and powers attributing to themselves the status of a separate political
community. They may arrogate to themselves the loyalty of the members and make wider
citizenship claims secondary.
Most of these criticisms apply to extreme cases and on a doctrinaire understanding of citizenship
rights and obligations. The primary issue that group-differentiated claims raise is whether a
group is included within a political community as an equal or not. If they are excluded or partially
excluded, members of such groups cannot lay much claim to equal rights. Often exclusion and
discrimination precipitate self-government claims among people inhabiting a common territory
and shared culture. Self-government and self-determination demands are largely confined today
to cultural groups claiming a distinct nationhood. Sometimes, however, the border line between
excluded groups occupying a distinct territory making demands for self-government and national
self-determination remains very thin.
43
8.8 SUMMARY
Citizenship is a highly valorised theme in recent political writings and concerns. A number of
political developments of our times have contributed to this heightened interest in citizenship.
While the notion of citizenship may go along with a great deal of economic and social inequalities,
the level playing field it suggests on the basis of equal rights may make such inequalities an issue
of target of concerned citizens. Many social movements of modern times have striven not
merely for the inclusion of excluded social groups into the body of citizens, but also for extending
and expanding the zone of equal rights. Inspite of such strivings, the notion of citizenship remains
deeply ambivalent. Liberals tend to stress on the equality and freedom of citizens. Marxists,
however, are not very enthusiastic regarding citizenship as they feel that it is a device employed
by the capitalist state to restate social relations of classes as relations of citizens.They, however,
feel that citizenship as a political device can be of immense use in activating social agents to
subject public institutions to a critique and search for alternatives. Inspite of the ambiguities in
which this concept is caught, there is a widespread agreement that the zone of citizenship be
enlarged. This concern for the expansion of the zone of rights has brought within its fold, cultural
communities and political minorities who have sought a range of rights, specific to their
predicament. They have argued that along with equal rights, their specific differences be taken
into account in ordering political communities and their institutions.
Citizen -concerns are closely related to some of the most important issues under public debate
today such as civil society, participatory democracy and civic responsibility. The altered role of
the state under conditions of globalisation and liberalisation invokes citizenship for the health of
polity. Further, the horizon of citizenship is no longer limited to membership of nation-states any
longer. Cultural and doctrinal attachments are increasingly brought in to mark a level playing
field to citizens otherwise deeply divided in terms of their cultural attachments.
8.9 EXERCISES
1. Explain the natural significance of citizenship in democratic societies.
44
UNIT 9 SOVEREIGNTY
Structure
9.1 Introduction
9.2 What is Sovereignty?
9.2.1 Some Definitions of Sovereignty
9.8 Summary
9.9 Exercises
9.1 INTRODUCTION
Generally, we say that the state is our state and it is for our benefit. All of us have rights given
by the constitution and the state has to respect them. We also know that the government is
responsible for the maintenance of peace and security. For this purpose, the government makes
laws and it has a right to punish those who disobey them. But the question is why do we obey
the law and what is state authority? We experience state authority everywhere in our routine
life; for example, when we demand some favour from the authorities and the authorities refuse
to grant us the same, we protest. We do it because we feel that we have a right to get what
we think, we deserve and the government is duty bound to work for us. If all this is well known,
then why, you might say, we have to study what we already know. But are we sure that we
know it properly or our knowledge is just scanty? The fact is that we only have a dim view
of the state power or sovereignty. It seems to be very simple, but the fact remains that it is
one of the most complicated notions in Political Science and a rudimentary understanding has
no meaning because state power is not something which is theoretical and confined to books.
We have to face it especially, when our friends and we find the government unresponsive or
45
even insensitive. Therefore, while studying political theory, we need to go into details to study
the concept of sovereignty very clearly and precisely; for after all it is with this and other basic
concepts and definitions that we would later try to understand the great complexities of the
societies we live in.
Sovereignty is”the supreme political power vested in him whose acts are not subject to any
other and whose will cannot be overridden” – Grotius
Sovereignty is “the supreme irresistible absolute, uncontrolled authority in which the supreme
legal power reside”. – Blackstone
Sovereignty is “the commanding power of the state: it is the will of the nation organised in the
state: it is the right to give unconditional orders to all individuals in the territory of the state”.
– Duguit
Sovereignty is “the exercise of final legal coercive power by the state”. – Soltaire
Sovereignty is “the concept which maintains no more-if no less-than that there must be an
ultimate authority within the political society if the society is to exist at all”. – Hinsley
Sovereignty means “the political authority within a community which has the undisputed right
to determine the framework of rules, regulations and policies within a given territory and to
govern accordingly”. – David Held
46
9.2.2 Meaning Of Sovereignty
The above mentioned definitions of sovereignty project the traditional view of sovereignty, which
emphasised the following points:
iv) The sovereign makes the laws and extracts obedience from the people.
But in the medieval ages, feudalism prevailed where there was no unified authority and it
seemed that all the achievements of the Roman Empire had gone to waste. In the feudal state,
the king’s authority was highly restricted. It was limited by the church which claimed immunity
in both civil and criminal cases. Infact, the church was the organised group during the medieval
times and the head of church-the Pope-claimed superiority over the king. Besides, the feudal
overlords and the local communities or commons in the town also challenged the authority of
the king. Thus, the king was not sovereign. His competitors came to be known as ‘Estates’ and
feudalism was a state of these estates. Barker calls it as “a paradise of estates” rather than
a pattern of a state where the authority of the state was sidelined. Thus, there could not be the
modern concept of sovereignty. Further, the law of God was supposed to be superior to human
laws, which also restricted the development of sovereignty as an absolute and indivisible concept.
Jean Bodin is the first political philosopher who propounded the modern concept of sovereignty.
He defined sovereignty as the supreme power over citizens unrestrained by law. He also
defined citizenship as subjection to a sovereign. To Bodin, the power of sovereignty cannot be
delegated; sovereignty is also perpetual and unlimited. Sovereign is the source of law and has
the unconditional right to make, interpret and execute law. Bodin also discussed the location of
sovereignty which, he argued, depended upon the form of government. Thus, it is located in the
47
king in a monarchy, while in a democracy it resides in popular bodies. But customary and
constitutional law and the institution of private property limited Bodin’s sovereign. Hobbes
further developed on Bodin and attempted to make the theory of sovereignty perfect. To
Hobbes, sovereignty is the creation of a social contract and the sovereign is that individual or
assembly who is authorised to will for the general purpose of a peaceful life. Hobbes gave vast
powers to his sovereign. His command is law and all laws are subject to his interpretation. His
authority is absolute and unlimited and the individual cannot disobey him. Sovereignty is in-
alienable and indivisible. Hobbes pointed out that limited sovereignty is a contradiction in terms.
But Hobbes very clearly put one limitation on sovereignty. The sovereign cannot command any
individual to kill, wound or maim himself. He also made it clear that sovereignty is also limited
by the purpose for which it was created. Hobbes also conceded the right to resist the sovereign
in case the life of an individual is endangered. Infact, his theory of unlimited sovereignty is a
necessary compliment to his individualism.
Another social contractualist, Rousseau located sovereignty in the people expressed as ‘General
Will’. To Rousseau, general will and sovereignty are inter-changeable concepts. Sovereignty is
unlimited, supreme and absolute. It is also inalienable and indivisible. But unlike Hobbes, Rousseau’s
sovereignty is based upon the consent of the people. It is a free acceptance by every individual
of the exercise of force by the whole group of which every individual is a part. Therefore,
nobody can refuse to render obedience to the sovereign and anyone who does so may be
constrained by the whole body of citizens. This means that the individual may be forced to be
free. Unlike Hobbes who gave all powers of sovereignty to a monarch, Rousseau vested the
power not in one individual but in the community. But both of them are one, so far as the
characteristics of sovereignty are concerned. Both of them laid down the foundations of a
totalitarian state. In between the two, John Locke stood for a limited government. Locke
justified the results of the Glorious Revolution of 1688 which devoided the monarchy of its
absolute powers in England and advocated the doctrines of popular sovereignty, supremacy of
parliament, constitutional government, limited monarchy and the rule of law. Unlike Hobbes and
Rousseau, Locke stood for a limited sovereignty. His government was a government based on
the division of power and subjected to many limitations. He did not accept the view that the
sovereign power was indivisible. He felt that different organs of the government should exercise
the legislative, executive and federative powers of the state independently of one another. His
state is subservient to the society and governance cannot be done arbitrarily. But Locke is not
consistent in his views on sovereignty. At times, he suggests that sovereignty is located in the
people and at times, it is the legislature that is supreme. He also seems to suggest that when
there is a fusion of legislative and executive powers in one person, he may be called the
sovereign. The weakness in Locke’s argument is that he recognised the force of political
sovereignty, but failed to fully comprehend legal sovereignty.
The French Revolution is another milestone in the development of the modern concept of
sovereignty. The French Revolution stood for absolute and unlimited sovereignty on the ground
that people being sovereign, there is no need to restrict the supreme power. The newly emerged
nation-states also claimed total sovereignty, both internally as well as externally. They also
asserted their right to expand at the expense of others. The Industrial Revolution expanded the
activities of the state enormously and the importance of the state as a lawmaker was asserted.
These developments led to the concept of absolute sovereignty. In England, the parliament
became supreme and its supremacy was unlimited.
48
These ideas were reflected in Hegel who stood for constitutional monarchy, but his king had
the power to veto over legislation. According to Hegel, “The State is a perfected rationality, the
eternal and necessary essence of spirit, the rational in itself and for itself, an absolute fixed end
in itself.” Hegel combined mysticism with his state. To him, the state is the march of God on
earth. He completely subordinated the individual to the state. The state has the highest right over
the individual and his freedom is the gift of the state. The state not only allows, but also enlarges
the freedom of the individual. But the state acts through laws that must be rational. They must
be applied equally. A constitutional government provides order and security in society. The
exercise of authority is according to rules that limit the discretionary powers of officials. But
the state is internally and externally supreme. Hegel also glorified war and his state had the right
to wage war because the state of war reflects the omnipotence of the state and the victorious
state can claim to be the agent of world spirit. Thus, Hegel’s sovereignty is absolute and beyond
any control. Morality and international law also do not constitute any limitation on sovereignty.
Hegel was followed by Austin who nevertheless freed the state and sovereignty from all the
mysticism projected by Hegel. He advocated a legal view of sovereignty in which sovereignty
was absolute, unlimited, inalienable and indivisible. The pluralists later on challenged Austin’s
views. We will discuss both the legal and pluralist perspectives in details. But first let us
understand the meaning of sovereignty.
49
political scientist puts it, ‘may remodel the British Constitution, may prolong its life, may legalise
illegalities… may give dictatorial powers to the government… may introduce communism, or
fascism entirely without legal restriction’. This position of the British Parliament is also summed
up in the saying that it can do everything except making a man a woman and vice versa, though
it may do even that legally. Thus, the power of the legal sovereign is absolute, without any
restriction.
In contrast, the concept of political sovereignty is very vague and confusing. It is pointed out
that behind the legal sovereign lies the political sovereign to which the legal sovereign has to
bow. Political sovereignty is not recognised by the law. It is not determinate also in the sense
that its identification is a very difficult task. Yet its existence cannot be ignored. It influences
and controls the legal sovereign. One writer has identified the political sovereign as the sum total
of all influences, which lie behind the law. In a system of direct democracy where the people
participate in law making and decision-making, the distinction between the legal and the political
sovereign is blurred. But in a representative democracy, this distinction becomes obvious where
people participate in law making and decision-making indirectly through their representatives. In
such cases, political sovereignty lies with the electorate, which has the power to make or
unmake a government at regular intervals when the elections are conducted. Infact, the elections
are the best forum in which the will of the political sovereign is expressed.
50
government existed for the welfare of the people and there could not be any arbitrary rule. To
Locke, Government was a trustee constituted through a social contract for the protection of life,
liberty and property of the people. If the government failed in its duty of protecting the life,
liberty and property of the people, they had a right to rebel against it and overthrow it.
But Rousseau is considered the father of the concept of popular sovereignty. According to
Rousseau, men by their very nature are free and equal and the system of government has to
be based upon the free will of men. This, in turn, can be achieved when the individual enters
into a contract with each other, as a result of which they become an indivisible part of a body
of sovereign people which has the supreme power of lawmaking. Rousseau also made a clear
distinction between the state and the government. To him, the government is merely an agent
of the state having a limited authority. Infact, it is the people who have delegated the power
to rule to the government and this power can be withdrawn by their will. This will of the people
becomes sovereign in Rousseau’s state to which Rousseau gave the name of the General Will.
In Rousseau’s scheme, the sovereign can only act for the welfare of the people. He writes, “It
is impossible for the sovereign body to hurt its members. The sovereign for its part cannot
impose upon members any fetters that are useless to the community”.
According to Asirvatham, the concept of popular sovereignty contains the following valuable
ideas:
i) Government does not exist for its own good. It exists for the good of the people.
iii) Easy means should be provided for a legal way of expressing public opinion.
iv) Government should be held directly responsible to the people through such means as frequent
elections, local self-government, referendum, initiative and recall.
v) Government should exercise its authority, directly in accordance with the laws of the land and
not act arbitrarily.
The concept of popular sovereignty was accepted as the basic principle of governance in the
American and French revolutions. The American Declaration of Independence expressly
declared,”We hold these Truths to be self-evident, that all Men are created equal, that they are
endowed by their Creator with certain inalienable Rights, that among these are Life, Liberty and
the Pursuit of happiness— that to secure these Rights, Governments are instituted among Men,
deriving their just Powers from the Consent of the Governed....” The Declaration clearly
recognised the people’s right to alter or abolish any government, which was destructive of the
inalienable rights of life, liberty and pursuit of happiness. The Declaration also noted the fact
that the British King had become a tyrant by his acts and therefore, unfit to be the ruler of a
free people. The French Revolution declared, “Men are born and remain free and equal in
rights”. It also pointed out that “right to liberty, property, security and resistance to oppression
are the aim of any political association and the law is the expression of general will” and all
citizens have the right to take part personally or through their representatives in its formation”
and that “all officials of the state are responsible to the people.”
The concept of popular sovereignty is very attractive. But it is shrouded with vagueness. It is
very difficult to explain it in practical terms. It is good to say that people are the basis of any
political system and their will must be reflected in the governance. But the question is what does
51
the term people mean? How do we identify them? Obviously the entire mass living in a state
cannot be identified as people because there are infants, invalids, criminals, insolvent, aliens and
others who cannot have any participation in the political system. If they constitute people then
the concept, as such, does not make any sense at all. Even the electorate cannot be called as
people because they do not constitute a political entity. Further, all people do not participate in
the election. Then the elections are won on the basis of majority. So does it mean that we should
equate people with the majority of the electorate? In any case, the number of electorate in any
country is very small in comparison to the total population and they cannot be regarded as legally
sovereign. Infact, the more we go into the details, it is only confusion and nothing else. If we
study the dynamics of modern democracy, we find that a voter is subjected to many influences
and manipulations. People’s choices are manufactured in the modern age of science and technology
and democracy has become infected with mobocracy. Popular sovereignty may be successful
in a small state with a system of direct democracy where the people directly participate in law
making. It may also reflect in devices such as the referendum. But the modern state is a big
state with a huge population. It is also a fact that the business of modern state has become too
complex and it cannot run on the basis of referendum. The concept of popular sovereignty
creates another problem. In the present system of democracy, the ruling elite as well as the
opposition claim to be reflecting the will of the people and in such cases, it becomes increasingly
difficult to discover the truth and if the concept of popular sovereignty is implemented legally,
then it may lead to instability in the government. Yet all said and done, the concept of popular
sovereignty has made a permanent contribution in Political Science because besides advocating
the idea of popular control over the government, it is a strong repudiation of dictatorship and
totalitarianism.
i) Sovereignty is necessary for the state. Sovereignty is one of the four elements of the state.
There cannot be a state without sovereignty. If state is the body, sovereignty is its spirit. The
state cannot alienate itself from the power of sovereignty. The end of sovereignty means the
end of state.
ii) Sovereignty has to be determinate .It resides in a person or a body of persons. To Austin, State
is a legal order in which the sovereignty can be located very clearly. It cannot be the people or
the electorate or the General Will since all of these are vague expressions. It is not vested in
God also. Sovereign must be a human being or a body of human beings who can be identified.
iii) Sovereign is the supreme power in the state. He is the source of all authority in the state. His
authority is unlimited and absolute. He does not take commands from any one as nobody has
a right to command him. But he commands every one within the state. His authority is universal
and all comprehensive. Sovereignty is independent from any internal or external control.
iv) The Sovereign receives habitual obedience from the people. Thus, the authority of the sovereign
is not casual. It is continuous, regular, undisturbed and uninterrupted. If a significant part of the
population refuses to accept him and renders disobedience, then he is no longer a sovereign.
52
Similarly, a short term obedience is not an attribute of sovereignty. The power of the sovereign
has to be permanent in society.
v) Law is the will and the command of the sovereign. He is the source of law. Law is a command
given by a superior to the inferiors who are in a state of subjection or dependence. Sovereign
is above the customs and traditions of society. They exist with his permission. Whatever the
sovereign permits, that alone can exist. The rights and liberties of the individual also emanate
from the sovereign and do restrict the operation of the individuals’ sovereignty.
vi) Sovereignty has the legitimate physical force to exert command and obedience and enforce its
laws.
vii) The power of sovereignty is exclusive and indivisible. It is a unit in itself that cannot be divided
between two or more persons. Division of sovereignty means its destruction.
Thus according to Austin, sovereignty is the supreme power of the state that is absolute,
permanent, universal, inalienable, exclusive and indivisible. However, these characteristics are
not acceptable to the pluralists who reject the entire thesis of Austin in toto.
The pluralists do not believe that the sovereign is determinate. According to them, the determination
was possible in old days when the king ruled with absolute powers. But in modern times the
political system is based upon the concept of popular sovereignty in which the government is
responsible to the people who can make or unmake the government. The constitutions clearly
proclaim the sovereignty of the people, but Austin will not accept people as sovereign. Similarly,
the electorate cannot be termed as sovereign because both the terms- “people” and “electorate”
are vague and do not constitute determinate human being in the Austinian sense. The task of
locating sovereignty becomes more difficult in case of a federation in which the powers are
divided between the centre and the units and both are supposed to be sovereign in their
respective fields. In such a system, the constitution is supposed to be supreme but it is not a
human being and hence, cannot be sovereign. Even in Britain where the supremacy of the
parliament is the basic law of the land, the parliament cannot be termed as totally sovereign as
it also works under limitations. Laski rightly points out that the real rulers of a society are not
discoverable.
The pluralists believe that Austin’s concept of sovereignty cannot be verified from history.
According to Laski, historically, sovereignty has always been subjected to limitations except for
a very small period when we really had a sovereign in Austin’s sense. This was the period when
the nation-state arose and the kings asserted their authority. This nation-state was the result of
the religious struggle of the 16th century and the emergence of the sovereign state was a
vindication of the primacy of the secular order over religion. Thus, there were certain historical
factors which were responsible for the creation of absolute sovereignty of the state. And if we
leave this brief period, we do not find any example of absolute sovereignty. In modern times,
sovereignty is limited. The only exception could be the British King-in-Parliament but as Laski
argues, ‘everybody knows that to regard the King-in-Parliament as sovereign body in the
53
Austinian sense is an absurd’. No parliament can defranchise the Roman Catholic church or
prohibit the existence of trade unions. Therefore, Laski says, “No sovereign has anywhere
possessed unlimited power; and the attempt to exert it has always resulted in the safeguards.”
Infact, every sovereign has to work within the society and the society works through customs
and traditions, which are the result of a long historical process and no ruler, no matter how
ruthless he is, can violate them. It has been pointed out that internally the rights of the individual
limit the sovereignty and externally, the international law restricts the operation of sovereign
power. Besides the concept of popular sovereignty gives ultimate powers to the people and
accordingly, the legal sovereign has to bow before them.
It will not be wrong to suggest that the pluralists have a great distrust of power and those who
exercise it. That is the reason why Laski objected to the absolute powers of the sovereign. To
him it is ethnically indefensible. It is ethically wrong as it retards the development of the
individual and his moral stature. Austin makes the individual completely servile to the state and
such an absolute sovereign would never grant any liberty to the individual. Laski stood for
decentralisation and argued that the state should be responsible for its actions. The state should
also protect and respect certain rights of the individual without which the individual cannot
develop his personality. Laski reminded that the state is not an end in itself; rather it is merely
a means to an end, the end being the enrichment of human lives and the position of the state
will always depend upon its capability in achieving this end.
The Pluralists also reject the notion of law as advocated by Austin. According to Austin, law
is the command of the superior and this command is from higher to inferior. Laski termed this
as ridiculous. He pointed out that to call law, as a command from the higher to the inferior, is
to strain its definition to the verge of indecency. Laws are universal in character and are applied
on both the lawmaker as well as the subjects. But in the case of a command, the commanding
authority is over and above its command and is not bound by it. Similarly, MacIver critcised
Austin’s concept of law as misleading as it denies two of the basic attributes which every law
exhibits- its universality and formality. These attributes, MacIver argues, are necessary
consequences of the structure and operation of every political system. Besides, the command
belongs to the sphere of administration, as it is a means of execution. Command does not belong
to legislation, as it is not a form of enactment. Infact, law is both permanent and fundamental
than command. MacIver also pointed out that there are many kinds of law. For example, there
are social laws, which are based on the customs and traditions of society, and some of them
also become state laws. But, MacIver says, in the great book of the law, the state merely writes
new sentences here and there and scratches out an old one. Much of the book was never
written by the state at all, and by all of it, the state is itself bound, save as it modifies the code
from generation to generation.”Therefore to MacIver, the state is both the child as well as the
parent of law and the authority of law is greater than the authority of state. The state is merely
an official guardian of law rather than its maker. It has to uphold the rule of law. Laski stressed
the fact that law is an instrument of satisfying social needs and the laws are followed not
because of any coercion, but because they satisfy the requirements of the people. Duguit rightly
says that, “Law is the product of our social life. We obey law because they are for social
interest and that it is impossible to maintain social order without them”. The absence of law
would mean anarchy where no human existence would be possible.
The Pluralists also point out that there are customs and traditions in society, which were neither
created by the state, nor the state has any control over them. Even the most dictatorial ruler
had to bow before them. Laski gives the example of the Sultan of Turkey, who, even at the
height of his power, was bound by a code of observance and it was compulsory for him to obey
54
them. Similarly, Sir Henry Maine gave the example of King Ranjit Singh who enjoyed absolute
powers over his subjects and even the slightest violation could invite severe punishment, but
even he did not violate the conventions of society. However in defense of Austin one may point
out that Austin does not deny the existence of customs and traditions by saying that whatever
the sovereign permits, he commands. But Pluralists do not accept this argument. Laski points
out that the Sultan of Turkey had the power to change the social laws in theory only, in practice
he survived by willing not to will those changes which might have proved him the sovereign of
Austinian jurisprudence. MacIver forcefully asserted that the state cannot destroy the customs,
because customs, when attacked by law, retaliate in return and in their retaliation, they attack
not only the particular law but also the spirit of law-abidingness which is the basis of state.
The Pluralists view the state as an association. Here, firstly, they distinguish between state and
society. According to MacIver, to identify the social with the political is to be guilty of the
grossest of all confusion, which completely bars any understanding of society. The state exists
within the society but it is not even the form of society. Infact, the society is composed of
different associations and the state is one of them. There are many associations like the family
and the church, which are as natural as the state and the state had no role in their formation.
Legally, the state may be unlimited because it is the source of legal enactment but then the same
is true of the Church because it happens to be the source of ecclesiastical law. The objective
of an association is to develop human personality in the specific area for which it is formed.
Thus, every association serves certain interests in society. Similarly, the state also looks after
certain interests and all these associations including the state have their own distinctive identity
and personality. Therefore, there cannot be one supreme power or as MacIver prefers to call,
a single all comprehensive authority in society. Laski asserts that we are not a universe, but
multiverse and the associations are as real as the state. The associations have their interests
to promote and functions to serve and they are not dependent on the state; rather, they grow
in the whole environment as a natural response to factors in that environment. They have an
inner life that is as autonomous as the state itself. According to MacIver, “The difference
between other associations and the state lies just in this: that the other associations are limited
primarily by their objective, which is particular, whereas the state is limited primarily by its
instrument, which is particular, while its objective is general, within the limits so imposed.” State
laws are universal and they have coercive sanctions and therefore, the state should concern
itself with those interests that are universal. Pluralists do not deny the essential differences
between the state and associations. The state has a power to inflict corporal punishment over
its citizens while the associations lack this power. Membership of a state is compulsory while
in case of an association it is voluntary. The state is also territorial in nature while the association
may cross the boundaries of different states. Similarly, unlike the associations, the state is
permanent. MacIver says, “if a state dissolves, it is like convulsion of nature. If it breaks into
two, it is with violence and fierce repulsion. This is not true in case of other associations”.
But nevertheless the state is an association and the above mentioned differences cannot give
the state a special status. At the most, state can be, as Asirvatham suggests, first among equals
and nothing more. It is only a particular group. Laski writes, “We then give to this particular
group (i.e. the state) no peculiar merit. We refuse it the title of creator of all else. We make
it justify by its consequences. We stimulate its activities by making it compete with the work
of other groups co-extensive with or complementary to itself.” As an association, the state
protects the interests of men as citizens. The state regulates the common needs in society.
But it cannot control the internal affairs of other associations. It can neither determine their
purposes nor (for the most part) their methods. As the human life and culture is diversified
therefore, the doctrine of absolute sovereignty if actually practiced would be, in the words of
55
MacIver, fatal to the harmony of social life. Laski says that the structure of society is federal
and therefore the authority must also be federal. It will be wrong to give all the sovereign
powers to the state. Laski also felt that the allegiance to various associations depended upon
their performance. Men belong to many groups at a time and a competition for allegiance is
continuously possible and no group, including the state, can claim total loyalty from the individual.
He wrote,” The only state to which I owe allegiance is the state in which I discover moral
adequacy, and if a given state fails to satisfy that condition I must, to be consistent with my
moral nature attempt experiment…Our first duty is to be true to our conscience”. The state,
as an association, cannot regulate the total life of man. Its functions are merely to coordinate
the activities of different associations in the society.
Austin’s concept of absolute sovereignty has also been criticised by the pluralists on the basis
of dangers that it poses to the maintenance of international peace and tranquility. The Pluralists
point out that the doctrine of absolute sovereignty is incompatible with the interests of humanity
as it leads to destructive wars. They believe that it is due to the notion of external sovereignty
that the world had to face the two world wars that brought so much of suffering and destruction.
With the stockpiling of nuclear weapons which can destroy the world many times and which
can only lead to mutually assured destruction (MAD), there is an urgent need to restrict state
sovereignty. Laski writes,” Internationally it is not difficult to conceive the organisation of an
allegiance which reaches beyond the limits of the state. To leave with a handful of men, for
instance, the power to make war may well seem anachronistic to those who envisage the
consequences of war. When state sovereignty in international affairs was recognised, there was
no authority existent to which that type of control might be entrusted. It is atleast arguable now
that an authority predominant over states may be conceived which is entrusted the regulation
of those affairs or more than national interests. It involves at any rate, on the international side,
abolition of state sovereignty.” To Laski, international government is “axiomatic in any plan for
international well-being. But international government implies the organised subordination of
states to an authority in which each may have a voice, but in which also, that voice is never
the self-determined source of decision”. Laski firmly believed that the concept of the sovereignty
of state would pass away, just as the divine rights of king had. Infact, the pluralists regard state
sovereignty as an obstacle towards the establishment of international order, as such a concept
has no concern for world peace and security.
i) “That the state is but one of the numerous social, economic, political and other grouping through
which men in society must seek to satisfy their interests and promote their welfare;
ii) That these different groupings are not creatures of the state but arise independently and acquire
power and authority not given by the state;
iii) That the functions of such voluntary associations as churches, labour unions, trade organisations,
professional societies and the like are as necessary as those of the state;
iv) That the monistic state is not only incapable of wielding absolute authority over such bodies,
but is incapable of regulating their affairs intelligently or administering them efficiently;
v) That the monistic concept of sovereignty is a mere legal fiction which not only misses the truth
but does incalculable harm in obstructing the evolution of society along more natural beneficial
lines”.
56
9.6.1 Pluralistic View of Sovereignty-A Critique
The pluralist assumptions and their critique of the legal view of sovereignty have been criticised
on many grounds. Firstly, the pluralists suffer from an inner contradiction. On the one hand, they
stand for decentralisation of power and autonomy of groups or associations, on the other hand,
they also want the state to play a regulating role by coordinating the activities of the various
associations. But the question is as to how the state will perform this function without overriding
powers. Infact, by assigning the job of coordination, the pluralists give back the power of
sovereignty with all its characteristics in Austin’s sense to the state. Secondly, it is pointed out
that modern society is highly complicated and the state must have power as the final judge in
reconciliation of the interests of divergent groups. The concept of welfare state and planning
has increased the activities of the state and it is dominating the entire life of an individual. No
doubt, the individual is organised in groups and the groups play a commendable role in the
enrichment of human personality but, that in any case, does not affect the primacy of state.
Besides, various groups also perform functions that are over-lapping and the pluralists seem to
have ignored this fact. These groups do not run on parallel lines and this is likely to clash and
create disorder and chaos in society and the state will have to intervene to restore order. Finally,
Austin himself will not object to what the pluralists stand for. He has only given a legal
interpretation of sovereignty, which is the true statement of facts. International law is still in the
developing stage and cannot be regarded as a limitation on sovereignty and legally speaking,
customs and traditions are also no restraint on sovereignty. The inadequacy of the pluralist
argument can be well understood when we find that even a strong advocate like Laski, later
on, criticised the pluralist view of sovereignty. He pointed out that the pluralists failed in
understanding the state as an expression of class relations. Laski accepted Austin’s monistic
doctrine when he said, “Legally no one can deny that there exists in every state, an organ whose
authority is unlimited.”
The significance of pluralism lies in its assertion of the importance of group life. As against the
absolute authority of the state, the pluralists argued for democracy and decentralisation. Though
it is difficult to accept the pluralistic abolition of state sovereignty, their contribution in explaining
and emphasising the importance of groups or associations in the context of modern complex life
can never be underestimated. As for state sovereignty, we are inclined to agree with Sabine
that, “For my own part, then, I, must reserve the right to be a monist when I can and a pluralist
when I must”.
57
Today, globalisation has become a fact of our times, a fact that has raised many questions
regarding the state and its sovereignty. The following aspects pointed out by David Held need
our attention:
i) With the increase in global connectedness, the number of political instruments available to
governments and the effectiveness of particular instruments has shown a marked decline;
border controls have lessened; and flow of goods and services, ideas and cultures has increased.
The result is a decrease in policy instruments, which enable the state to control activities within
and beyond its borders.
ii) States can experience a further diminution in options because of the expansion in transnational
forces and interactions, which reduce and restrict the influence particular governments can
exercise over the activities of their citizens. The impact, for example, of the flow of capital
across borders can threaten anti-inflation measures,exchange rates and other government
policies.
iii) In the context of a highly interconnected global order, many of the traditional domains of state
activity such as defence, communication and the like cannot be fulfilled without resorting to
international forms of collaboration. As the demands on the state have increased in the post-
war years, the cooperation of other states has become necessary.
iv) Accordingly, states have had to increase the level of their political integration with other states
so as to control the destabilising effects that accompany global interconnectedness. They have
to strengthen, for example, organisations like the International Monetary Fund (IMF) and the
World Trade Organisation (WTO).
v) With the growth of a vast number of institutions and organisations, a basis for global governance
has already been laid. The new global politics involving among other things, multibureaucratic
decision-making within and between governmental and international bureaucracies, and the
like has created a framework in and through which the rights and obligations, powers and
capacities of states have been redefined.
The sovereignty of the state continues, but the sovereign structure of the state is heavily
influenced by global tendencies, besides those found within the boundaries of the state itself.
i) After the Second World War, the world was divided between the two blocs led by the U.S.A.
and the USSR. Both of them exerted a great influence on their bloc-members in the operation
of their domestic and foreign policy. This was the reason why India and many other non-
aligned countries refused to join any of the two blocs, because in plain terms it meant putting
restriction on th country’s sovereignty and accepting the dictates of the bloc leader. After the
disintegration of the USSR, we have a unipolar or multipolar world, in which the states are
dependent on each other. The U.S.A. exerts a large measure of influence on the domestic and
external policy of many states, especially the small and the weaker states.
ii) The dominance of the U.S.A. and the USSR in their power alliances constrained numerous
states from making decisions themselves or independent of their bloc leader. The NATO (North
58
Atlantic Treaty Organisation), the SEATO (the South East Asian Treaty Organisation), the
CENTO (the Central Treaty Organisation), the OAS (the Organisation of American States),
all under the American influence and the Warsaw Pact under the Soviet leadership gave
meagre international choice to their respective member-states. Held says, “A state’s capacity
to initiate particular foreign policies, pursue certain strategic concerns, choose between
alternative military technologies and control weapon systems located on its own territory are
restricted by its place in the international system of power relations.”
iii) Each of these military alliances has its own structure, its own procedure and method of
functioning and its own policy as developed by the member-states. But the influence of the
leader goes unquestioned and the other member-states have limited options to operate on.
Giving the NATO example, Held says, “Its (NATO’s) concern with collective security has
trodden a fine line between, on the one hand, maintaining an organisation of sovereign states,
and, on the other, developing an international organisation which operates defacto, if not dejure,
according to its own logic and decision-making procedures.” The NATO is an example of a
supranational organisation in which the USA commands while the other member states merely
submit.
iv) But even without a commitment to a NATO armed conflict, Held says, “state autonomy as
well as sovereignty can be limited and checked”. This is because, he continues “the routine
conduct of NATO affairs involves the integration of national defence bureaucracies into
international defence organisations.” Such organisations create transgovernmental decision
making systems which escape the control or even consultation of any single-member state.
They lead to establish informal and yet powerful, transgovernmental personnel networks or
coalitions outside the control of and accountability to any national mechanism.
v) The membership of NATO or any other power-bloc does not abolish state sovereignty but it
certainly compels the member-states to compromise on many issues.
i) The internalisation of production has been made possible through the organisation of
multinational corporations. These corporations work across the borders and function outside
the domain of national sovereignties. The Multinational Corporations (MNCs), says Held, “plan
and execute their production, marketing and distribution, with the world economy firmly in
mind.” Though these MNCs have a national base, the nation from where they originate, their
interest is always global, as is their strategy. The states do little in controlling these corporations,
while these corporations have much to do in guiding the policies of the states where they operate.
ii) The financial organisations such as banks are becoming global progressively, no matter from
where they function- London, New York or Tokyo. A greater role is being played by the new
information technology in so far as it helps in the mobilisation of economic units-currencies,
stocks, shares and the like-for financial and commercial organisations of all kinds.
iii) With the technological advancement in communication and transportation, the separate market-
boundaries, necessary for independent national economic policies are losing importance. Inspite
of the fact that the distinctive identities are kept preserved, markets and societies are becoming
59
more sensitive to one another. To a great extent, the possibility of a national economic policy
has, accordingly, reduced so as to suit itself to the claims of international financial and fiscal
system. Likewise, as Held says, “the levels of employment, investment and revenue within a
country are often subordinated to the decisions of MNCs…”
iv) As no country is self sufficient, especially in economic matters, the states have to organise
themselves regionally and globally. There are such groups, though loose, as West-West, North
–South, South-South, East-West, the developed and the developing. These groups do affect
the economy of each individual state.
Thus we see that the internationalisation of production, finance, management and distribution is
unquestionably eroding the capacity of each individual sovereign state to do what it wants to
do. No country, howsoever strong it may be, has control over its future economic policies, for
it has to affect and get affected by the economic policies as they are pursued globally. There
is a definite diminution of state autonomy in the face of world economy.
i) The international organisations are making global decisions and the states have to respect
them. In today’s world, no state can take the United Nations for granted and each state has to
function within the framework of the UN Charter. The international organisations are setting
up international standards to be followed by the individual states. For example, the preamble of
the UN Charter asserts its determination to affirm faith in fundamental human rights, in the
equal rights of men and women and the nations, large and small. The Universal Declaration of
Human Rights contains those rights which are universal and transcend national boundaries.
They are very comprehensive and include all kinds of rights like civil, political, economic,
social, cultural and collective rights like the rights of minorities, indigenous people and the right
to development. It is becoming increasingly difficult to the states to violate these human rights.
The states have to observe these rights in their dealings with the secessionist and ethnic groups
also. Infact, there are many international organisations and numerous pressure groups that
influence the activities and policies of the national states.
ii) Then there are international organisations which work in technical areas and are non-
controversial like the Universal Postal Union (UPU), the International Telecommunication
Union (ITU), the World Meteorological Organisation (WMO). These organisations supplement
the services offered by the individual states to their citizens. These non-political and technical
organisations do influence some notable aspects of the foreign policies of individual states and
as such do not allow them to act arbitrarily.
iii) But then there are many controversial organisations like the International Monetary Fund
(IMF), the World Bank, the United Nations Conference on Trade and Development (UNCTAD)
and the World Trade Organisation (WTO) which are non-state actors and have usurped the
functions of state. They even take up a supranational role in certain areas.
iv) The operations of the IMF go a step further and almost grab the sovereign rights of a nation.
While giving loan to a particular state, the IMF may insist on certain conditions such as a cut on
public expenditure, devaluation of currency, a cut on welfare programmes, liberalisation and
60
privatisation of economy and all this diminish the sovereignty of the concerned state. The
developing countries have to tolerate the intervention of the IMF, even if it leads to many
internal troubles like food riots, or the fall of a government or even imposition of martial law.
v) Another important international organisation that has become highly controversial is the World
Trade Organisation (WTO). The World Trade Organisation is a permanent legislative body
and acts as a watchdog in the spheres of trade in goods, services, foreign investment, intellectual
property rights and in all these spheres, state sovereignty has been curtailed. The constitution
of the WTO makes the provision for the further expansion of the jurisdiction of WTO activities.
It has been pointed out that the WTO has emerged as a virtual parliament in economic matters
and possesses power to make laws on the subjects which hitherto have been the domain of
state legislation. No state can go against the decisions of WTO even if it harms their interests.
vi) The European Union (EU) provides a bigger threat to the sovereignty of the states. Members
of the EU have delegated their sovereignty in certain matters to the Union. It has an executive
body in the form of the President and members of the European Commission, legislative body
in the form of the European Parliament and the European Council (the Council is the main
decision making body and also the union legislative body which exercises legislative power in
co-decision with the European Parliament), a Court of Justice and a Court of Auditors. There
is also a European Bank with the responsibility of framing and implementing monetary policies.
The EU can make laws that are, or can be, imposed on the member-states. The EU has
become, more or less, a supranational agency, for within it, the Council has the power to make
or enact policies. It also coordinates international agreements, on behalf of the EU with one or
more states or international organisations. Accordingly, the member-states of the EU are no
longer the sole centres of power within their own borders. Within the Union, sovereignty is
clearly divided; any conception of sovereignty, which assumes that it is indivisible, unlimited,
exclusive and a perpetual form of public power-embodied within an individual state is defunct.
i) By state sovereignty, we mean the right of the state to act independently and under no explicit
influence of any other foreign government. It implies, among other thing, two points; (a) that a
state is powerful enough to protect its own autonomy in all matters of foreign policy, and (b) to
prevent domestic courts from ruling on the behaviour of foreign states. Such aspects of state
sovereignty are under strain. The EU laws, for example, hardly ensure national sovereignty to
any of its members.
ii) The UN Declaration of Human Rights and other conventions, which are the part of international
law and are increasing by becoming binding on the states, are not the results of the states
acting individually. They may not take away the sovereignty of a state, but certainly fashion it.
iii) The European Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental Rights is a
typical case, which does not fit in the framework of sovereignty. Any citizen belonging to the
European Union can demand the introduction of any right included in the Convention, but not
incorporated in the constitution of the concerned state. Obviously, the European Union does
not leave an individual state free to treat its own citizens, as it thinks fit.
iv) Though the international law is a law applicable for states, the individual is also becoming the
61
subject of international law. The International tribunal at Nuremberg stated that “crimes against
international law are committed by men, not abstract entities, and only by punishing individuals
who commit such crimes can the provisions of international law be enforced”. The tribunal
also made clear that when international rules concerning humanitarian values come into clash
with state laws, individual laws must transgress the state laws.
v) Infact the international law is no longer a law between the states only and exclusively. It is
changing and gaining ground for itself increasingly on the norms of co-existence and cooperation.
Unlike the traditional international law which assumed the separateness of the individual states,
the new international law is binding itself on the concept of togetherness and closeness of the
numerous states.
9.8 SUMMARY
Sovereignty is the supreme power of the state by which the state exerts its authority. Legally
speaking, there cannot be any restriction to its power of exerting obedience. It also monopolises
the power of using legitimate physical force. This view is best represented in Austin’s concept
of sovereignty in which sovereignty has been depicted as permanent, absolute, universal,
inalienable, exclusive and indivisible. The state essentially functions on the basis of this doctrine
only. But it is also a fact that state sovereignty has always been subjected to limitations and in
practical terms, the power of sovereignty has never been supreme. The pluralists have remarkably
projected this view where they conceived state as an association. They argued for a limited
state and division of sovereign powers between the state and other associations. Though legally
the pluralistic views cannot be acceptable, politically and socially they are very attractive since
they depict modern democratic ideals. It is also a fact that time is changing very rapidly and
theoretically the concept of state sovereignty still exists but very important in-roads have been
made especially since globalisation has curtailed the effectiveness of the state supreme power.
9.9 EXERCISES
1. Explain the development of the concept of sovereignty.
3. Differentiate between (a) real and titular sovereignty and (b) legal and political sovereignty.
4. What do you understand by dejure and defacto sovereignty? Explain the concept of popular
sovereignty.
7. To what extent do you think the pluralists’ criticism of Austin’s concept of sovereignty is
justified? Do power alliances limit the sovereignty of a state?
8. Do you think that world economy, international organisations and international law have really
affected state sovereignty?
62
UNIT 10 STATE AND CIVIL SOCIETY
Structure
10.1 Introduction
10.2 State and Civil Society: Meaning and Characteristics
10.2.1 Meaning of State
10.2.2 Meaning of Civil Society
10.6 Summary
10.7 Exercises
10.1 INTRODUCTION
The concept of state occupies a central place in Political Science. No discussion on political
theory is complete without reference to the word ‘state’. The state, indeed, touches every
aspect of human life, and this is why it has, very rightly, captured the attention of all political
philosophers since the days of Plato. To understand the state as an administrative machinery
ordering public life is to know its one aspect. Important though this aspect is, it is not the only
aspect which explains as to what it is. The state is where it operates on. Its real meaning
together with its other related implications emerges more clearly when it is understood in relation
to the domain of its area of operation, which is what society is.
What is state? What is society or civil society? What is the relationship between the two or how
do the two stand in relation to each other? What is so particular about civil society that gives
the state a different connotation? These questions have been, and actually are, central to the
themes of political theory and to these questions, answers have been addressed by numerous
political theorists.
A discussion on issues relating to these two terms, the state and civil society, would help us to
know their meanings, implications and the relative perspectives in which these two concepts
stand to each other.
63
10.2 STATE AND CIVIL SOCIETY: MEANING AND
CHARACTERISTICS
It is very common to address society as civil society, civil society as political society, political
society as state. To understand each as one or the other is to know none of them. While the
concept ‘society’ is a generic term, the term civil society denotes a type of society particular
to a time and set in a particular situation. ‘Society’ refers, in general terms, to the totality of
‘social relationships’, conscious or unconscious, deliberate or otherwise. ‘Civil Society’, on the
other hand, concerns itself to matters relating to ‘public’. This brings the term ‘civil society’
close to the concept of ‘political society’. Indeed, the two terms presuppose a society where
civility is their characteristic feature, but ‘civil society’ extends to areas far away from the
reach of ‘political society’. The institution of family, for example, is an area covered by ‘civil
society’, but it is a domain where ‘political society’ does better to stay away from. ‘Political
society’ covers a whole range of activities related to ‘political’ directly or indirectly, but it
remains wider than the term ‘state’ when the latter is treated merely as a matter of governance.
It is indeed, important to know the meanings of these terms clearly if one seeks to understand
the relationship between them, especially between the state and civil society.
The state has included, from the beginning, a reference to a land and a people, but this alone
would not constitute a state. It refers also to a unity, a unity of legal and political authority,
regulating the outstanding external relationships of man in society, existing within society. It is
what it does, i.e., creates a system of order and control, and for this, is vested with the legal
power of using compulsion and coercion.
A state, thus, is found in its elaborate system. It is found in its institutions which create laws
and which enforce them, i.e., in institutions such as the legislature, the executive and the
judiciary. It is found in the bureaucratic institutions which are attached to every executive
branch of the government. It is found in the institutions which are called into operation when
its will is challenged, i.e., the military and the police. The state is the sum – total of these
institutions. Ralph Miliband (The State in Capitalist Society) writes, “These are the institutions
– the government, the administration, the military and the police, the judicial branch, sub-central
government and parliamentary assemblies – which make up the state…”. In these institutions
lies the state power; through these institutions come the laws of the state, and from them spring
the legal right of using physical force.
The state as governance is a system related to what may be called the political system or the
political society. It includes, on the one hand, institutions such as the political parties, pressure
groups, the opposition, etc., and on the other, large-scale industrial houses, religious and caste
institutions, trade unions, etc. These institutions, existing outside of the state system, attempt to
64
influence the functioning of the state, somewhere even dominating it, and somewhere in
collaboration with it. Skocpol (States and Social Revolution: A Comparative Analysis of
France, Russia and China) sums up what Neera Chandhoke (State and Civil Society) calls
the statist perspective of the state, “the state properly conceived …. is rather a set of
administrative, policing and military organizations headed, and more or less well coordinated by,
an executive authority. Any state first and fundamentally extracts resources from society and
deploys these to create and support coercive and administrative organizations…. Moreover,
coercive and administrative organizations are only parts of overall political systems. These
systems also may contain institutions through which social interests are represented in state
policy-making as well as institutions through which non-state actors are mobilised to participate
in policy implementation. Nevertheless, the administrative and coercive organisations are the
basis of state power.”
The other strand giving the state a meaning comes from Michael Foucault (‘Truth and Power’
in P. Rabinow, ed., The Foucalt Reader, 1987) who regards the state as built on power relations
already existing in society. Chandhoke writes about Foucault, “The state, he (Foucault) concluded,
can only operate on the basis of existing relations of domination and oppression in society.”
Rejecting both the perspectives of the state, Chandhoke says, “The statists (Skocpol and others)
concentrate on the state at the expense of society, and the theorists in the Foucauldian mode
concentrate on social interaction at the expense of the state.” She concludes that the state, with
a view to understanding it in relation to society, and vice-versa, “is a social relation because it
is the codified power of the social formation.”
Chandhoke sums up the meaning of civil society “as the public sphere where individuals come
together for various purposes both for their self-interest and for the reproduction of an entity
called society.” “It is a”, she continues, “sphere which is public because it is formally accessible
to all, and in principle all are allowed entry into this sphere as the bearers of rights.”
The concept of civil society came up as and when a social community sought to organise itself
independently of the specific direction of state power. Historically, the concept, Chandhoke says,
“came into existence when the classical political economists sought to control the power of the
Mercantilist State”. With the passage of time, the concept of civil society moved on progressively:
becoming a central plank of democratic movements in eighteenth century.
65
10.2.3 Characteristics of State and Civil Society
State exists within the society. This makes the state and society analytically distinct. The two
are not the same. Society is a web of social relationships and as such, includes the totality of
social practices, which are essentially plural, but at the same time, are relational. The hierarchically
organised and maintained social practices of a given community establish, in their turn, all kinds
of power equations and relations among its members. The state comes in to give these power
relations a fixity, and thereby to society its stability. The state gives legitimacy to social relationships
as expressed in social practices because it recognises them and codifies them through legal acts.
It is in this sense that the state can be described as the codified power of the social formation
of a given time.
The state, so considered, is itself a distinct and discrete organisation of power in so far as it
possesses the capacity to select, categorise, crystallise and arrange power in formal codes and
institutions. And this capacity gives to the state its status – power, power to take decisions,
power to enforce decisions, and also power to coerce those who defy them. But the state so
considered derives its power from society. It is, in this sense, a codified power, but within the
framework of the society in which it operates.
The state, as a social relation and also as a codified power in a given society, would have certain
characteristics of its own. These characteristics can be stated as:
a) The state is a power, organised in itself. It has the power to legitimise social relations and gives
them recognition through formal codes and institutions. This gives the state a distinct and
irreducible status in society while making it autonomous from classes and contending factions
existing in it.
b) The state emerges as a set of specifically political practices which defines binding decisions
and enforces them, to the extent of intervening in every aspect of social life.
c) The state monopolises all means of coercion. No other organisation in the society has this
power.
d) The state gives fixity to social relations, and social stability to society. The social order, according
to Chandhoke, “is constituted through the state and exists within the parameters laid down by
the state.”
e) The state exists within the framework of a given society. As society responds to the changing
conditions compelled by numerous social forces, the state responds to the changing society.
The state always reflects the changing relations of society. As society constantly re-enacts
itself, so does the state.
The liberal and the marxist perspectives of civil society differ drastically. For the liberals, civil
society presupposes democratic states together with the accountability of the states, the limits
on state power, the responsiveness to the spontaneous life and the interactions of civil society.
For the marxists, civil society is the arena of class conflicts, selfish competition and exploitation,
the state acting to protect the interests of the owning classes. A definition of civil society
comprising the insights of both the liberals and the marxists must take into account the following:
a) The state power must be controlled and it has to become responsive through democratic
practices of an independent civil society
66
b) Political accountability has to reside not only in constitutions, laws, and regulations, but also in
the social fabric or what Habermas calls the competence of the ‘political public’ which, in turn,
has the following implications: (i) it implies that the people come together in an arena of common
concerns, in debates and discussion and discourse free from state interference (ii) it implies
that the discourse is accessible to all (iii) it implies a space where public discussion and debate
can take place.
d) Civil society is the public sphere of society. It is the location of these processes by which the
experiences of individuals and communities, and the expression of experiences in debates and
discussions, affirmation and constitution are mediated. It is also a theatre where “the dialectic
between the private and the public are negotiated. It is the process by which society seeks to
“breach” and counteract the simultaneous “totalisation” unleashed by the state” (Bayart, “Civil
Society in Africa”, in Chabal, P., ed., Political Domination in Africa: Reflections on the
Limits of Power). It is a site where the state is forbidden to shape public opinion and perceptions.
Despite the fact that the state has meant different things to different people, one cannot ignore
the central place the state has in political theory. One would do better, if one attempts to discuss
the meaning of the state vis-à-vis society which has come to us by a host of eastern political
philosophers.
Following his teacher Plato, Aristotle (384-322 BC) defined the state as polis (the ancient
Greeks used polis for the state) as a community, which exists for the supreme good. He says
that the state is “an association of households and villages sharing in a life of virtue, and aiming
at an end which exists in perfect and self-complete existence.”
Both Plato and Aristotle, and for that matter all Greeks, thought of polis as more than a state.
It was an arrangement of administrative machinery, a government or a constitution, but was also
a school, a church laying the guidelines for a way of life, which for them, was nothing but
67
leading a full life. For Plato and Aristotle, there was no distinction between the state and society:
the state was an organ and a part of the society; it was submerged in the society itself. In
addition, the Greeks thought of the polis as an ethical entity and that was why they assigned,
ethical functions to be performed by the rulers of the state, i.e., good, happy and complete life.
Barker writes, “It (the polis) is more than a legal structure: it is also a moral spirit”. An ancient
Greek would never imagine himself without the polis, he was only a part of the polis, a part of
the whole. Barker says, “Here (in ancient Greece) were individuals, distinct from the state, yet
in their communion forming the state.” Wayper also says “For life to be worth living must have
a meaning, and only in the polis they (the Greeks) were sure, did it acquire meaning. There was
no distinction between political, social and ethical life in ancient Greece. The society was the
state as the state was with Plato and Aristotle, a government: the freeman, the master was a
citizen, a legislator and a member of the society; he as the ruler ruled the individual as a member
of the society, all the individuals, the whole society. The slave-owing society of ancient Greek
times could hardly be expected to give a theory of state, nay a theory of society, more than that
of the government, precisely, the rulers”.
To Cicero’s writings would go the credit of giving a notion of the state which is not a polis, but
a commonwealth. Like the ancient Greeks, Cicero also regards the state submerged in the
society, a part, i.e., an integral part of the society. Cicero says, “The Commonwealth, then, is
the people’s affairs, and the people is not every group of man, associated in any manner, but
is the coming together of a considerable number of men who are united by a common agreement
about law and rights, and by the desire to participate in mutual advantages.” From this, Cicero’s
theory of state can be summed up as: (i) the state is differentiated from people’s gatherings,
i.e., society (ii) the people enter the state after they agree on certain rules, giving people a
‘legal’ status, which lead them to form ‘legal community (iii) the state exists when people agree
to participate in its affairs. In Cicero’s theory, there is a theory of state different from the theory
of society; he makes a distinction between the state and the society; his theory of state is the
theory of government as well as a theory of political community.
The medieval political theory in the West was mainly concerned with Christianity where social
life was more a religious life regulated by the dictates of the Roman Catholic Church headed
by the Pope. Christendom ruled the universe and politics was controlled by the Church. The
temporal power was regarded inferior to that of the ecclesiastical, the state acting as a footnote
to the wider world. The state, in the medieval European world, was thought of as a means for
reaching the City of God (St. Augustine), and the human law was to work under the divine
law, natural law and ultimately, under the eternal law (St. Thomas). It was not the society that
controlled the state, but those who controlled the society– the Pope, the Church priests, the
monarchs and the feudal lords– who controlled the state i.e., the state machinery.
68
from the interference of the state. The early modern political theory could not make distinction
between state, and government, … All regarded state power as political power, and political
power as the power of the government”.
The Machiavellian state (credit goes to Machiavelli for introducing the word ‘state’ in Political
Science), whether princedom or republic, is a power state, meaning thereby that it exists for
power and exists because of the power whose main interest is to maintain, enhance and enlarge
its own authority. For Bodin (1530-1596), the state is “a lawful government, with sovereign
powers, of different households, and their common affairs”, considering the state affairs as
concerning the ‘public’. “The final cause, end, or design of men”, Hobbes says, “is the foresight
of their own preservation, and of a more contented life”.
With Locke (1632-1704), the liberal theory gets impetus and the state comes to protect property,
and promote a better economic life, for liberalism comes to stay as the political philosophy of
the capitalist class, the democratic flavour joining it at a later stage of development. The early
liberal-democratic theory restricted the role of the state to the minimal, protecting life, liberty
and property of its citizens from external aggression and internal chaos on the one hand, and
providing a system of justice and public works, and amenities on the other hand, with no role
for the welfare of the people.
It was John Stuart Mill (1806-1873) first, and T.H. Green (1836-1882) later who expanded the
positive role of the state in preparing a conducive atmosphere where the individual could enjoy
a better way of life. Mill and Green introduced democratic elements in the organisation and
functioning of the state, though both could hardly leave their capitalistic shackles.
To sum up, one may, therefore, conclude that the early modern political theorists such as
Machiavelli and Bodin could hardly see beyond the omnipotent state. The contractualists, especially
Hobbes, had thought that in order for society to come into existence, a strong state is required.
The early liberals such as Locke, Smith, Bentham held the view that as the society has the
capacity to reproduce and regenerate itself, the state and its power should be minimal. But the
later liberals, J.S. Mill, T.H. Green, De Tocqueville felt that numerous social associations, while
enhancing social ability, could become instruments through which individuals could fashion a
political discourse which could limit the nature of state power. The liberal pluralistic, in the third
and fourth decades of the twentieth century were able to build a strong case for the numerous
associations, existing in society, to control the omnipotence of the state while balancing the latter
against the claims of the society.
Chandhoke discerns three theoretical moments of the Marxist theory of state. The first such
moment has been when Marx and Engels, in the Manifesto of the Communist Party (1848)
69
regard “the executive of the modern state ” as “a committee for managing the common affairs
of the whole bourgeoisie”. Marx also writes in the preface to Towards a Critique of Political
Economy (1859), “the totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure
of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which
correspond definite forms of social consciousness.” This base-superstructure model of the state
was a reaction to the liberal concept of the disembodied state standing apart from society as
also a reaction against the Hegelian model of the all-powerful state while subordinating civil
society to it. The second moment, appearing around the 1960s and with Ralph Miliband and
Hanza Alvi, questions the nature of the state and its relationship with society. In it, the state
emerges as a distinct theoretical object in its own right and state-centric theory emerged as the
dominant stream of political theory. The third theoretical moment was made possible through the
contributions of Nicos Poulantzas and Claus Off. This moment saw political theorists preoccupied
with concepts and theories. Following Gramsci, who had conceptualised the state as the political
consideration of civil society, the Marxist political theorists of the third theoretical moment began
a spiralling interest in civil society as the sphere where meaningful practices, both hegemonic
and subversive, are generalised.
By developing the concept of rights, legally ordained, and especially relating to property of the
individual, there did emerge the notion of ‘civil society’ in ancient Roman thinking. Indeed the
notion of ‘civil society’ did need such an atmosphere to shape itself, but the ancient Roman
thought could hardly rise above that, notwithstanding the attempts at making distinction between
‘private’ and ‘public’ which the ancient Romans really did.
During the whole medieval period in the West when politics took the back seat, the idea of civil
70
society got eclipsed. What related to ‘public’ as ‘political’ was limited to a very few people
called the feudal lords, barons, dukes and counts. The idea of civil society was almost unknown.
The early modern period with Machiavelli and Bodin saw the emergence of politics, but the
period itself did not witness the corresponding growth of the idea of civil society. The civil
society, as a concept, rose with the idea of individuals with rights, individuals related to the state,
and individuals related to others in society.
There is the clear reference to civil society both in Hobbes and Locke when the two sought
to make a distinction between the ‘state of nature’, and the ‘civil society’ or the ‘political
society’ after the contract was made. Both talk about the rights-bearing individuals; both sought
the state to protect these rights. It is difficult to regard the contractualists, Hobbes and Locke,
as theorists of civil society because (i) their formulations on civil society are found in an
embryonic form and (ii) their attempts, despite a rational and persuasive explanation on state
and society, remained arbitrary (see Chandhoke, State and Civil Society).
The concept of civil society has emerged clearly between the seventeenth and the nineteenth
century, especially with the classical political economy theorists such as Adam Smith. Classical
political economy, echoing individual rights like laissez faire, freedom, equality, made the institution
of state as simply irrelevant, devaluing it, and that of civil society as what Marx had said ‘theatre
of history’. This helped “the civil society”, Chandhoke writes, “as a historically evolved area of
individual rights and freedoms, where individuals in competition with each other pursued their
respective private concern.”
The advent of the idea of civil society, coming from the writings of political economy theorists,
was to have its shape vis-à-vis the state. J.S. Mill and De Tocqueville who thought that the state
had become much more powerful than desired, sought to limit the power of the state through
the mechanism devised in the ever developing concept of civil society. Chandhoke sums up this
phase of liberalism, saying: “…. Civil society was used as a concept primarily for organizing
state-society relations. The expansion of the state, it was perceptively recognized, would contribute
to the shrinkage of the civil arena. State power could be limited only with the expansion of civil
society.”
The process of democratisation in the west made it possible for civil society to expand itself,
and in the process, restricted the area of the state. But elsewhere, the concept of the state
gained prominence restricting thus, the arena of civil society. The views of Hegel, and therefore,
of Marx and Gramsci should be of some interest.
71
persons.” So, civil society, a negative institution as it is for Hegel, belongs to the “realm of
mechanical necessity, a resultant of the irrational forces of individual desires”, governed, as
Sabine says for Hegel, “by non-moral casual laws and hence, ethically anarchical.” The thesis
(the family) and the anti-thesis (the civil, the bourgeois society) merge into what Hegel calls the
state (the synthesis). Thus, the state comes to have the universality of civil society and the
specificity and the individuality of the family.
Thus, while the political economy and the liberal-democratic theorists had given primacy to civil
society, and had given the state a back seat, Hegel reverses the position and puts the state in
the position of civil society. According to Hegel, ultimately civil society is subordinated to the
state, and the individual, to the whole. “Consequently, in Hegelian formulation”, Chandhoke says,
“there can be no interrogation of the state, of its designs for universality, or of its rationale. The
resolution of the contradiction of civil society is the state, and therefore, between the people and
the state, there is no dichotomy, only legitimacy and acceptance.”
Marx, unlike Hegel who had made the civil society a hostage and who had idealised the state,
seeks to restore the civil society to the position of making it the theatre of history. But the civil
society, Marx argues, has failed to live up to its promises, had failed to create a situation where
the individual could find freedom and democratic transformation, had to seek ways and means
through which individuals could integrate into the society and the state.
Gramsci (1891-1937) following Marx and developing his theory of state takes into account the
reality of civil society. His main proposition is that one cannot understand the state without
understanding the civil society. He says that the ‘state’ should be understood as not only the
apparatus of government, but also the ‘private’ apparatus of hegemony or civil society. Building
on the Marxian notion of the state, Gramsci makes a distinction between the state as a political
organisation (the integral state, the visible political constitution of civil society) and the state as
government. The integral state keeps reproducing itself in the practices of everyday life through
activities situated in civil society. It is hegemony which provides moral and intellectual leadership
to practices in civil society. Hegemony, for Gramsci, works for both, for the dominant as well
as the subaltern class in civil society. Each class must, Gramsci says, before seizing power,
hegemonise social relations in society.
To sum up, it may be said that for both the liberals and the Marxists, civil society is primary.
While the liberals argue for the separation of civil society from the autonomy of the state, the
Marxists, on the other hand, create an alternative tradition of civil society, in which, the civil
society, with its all potentialities, has to keep itself always reorganised and transformed.
72
10.5.1 State and Civil Society: Integrative Relationship
State and civil society are not two opposite concepts. One does not stand in conflict with
another. Neither is one the anti-thesis of the other. The two should not be regarded as usurping
the area of each other. It is not a zero-sum game relationship between the two. Indeed, the
relatively stronger state would put a premium on the role of civil society, but this, in no way,
diminishes the effectiveness of civil society. The libertarian view, expressed in the writings of
Hayek or Nozick, that the state is likely to oppress civil society is, more or less, ill-founded. The
fact of the matter is that the relationships between state and civil society are reciprocal; the
relationships are of an integrative nature, each strengthening the cause of the other. It is, infact,
difficult to conceive of civil society functioning successfully without the state. We see the citizen
simultaneously constrained by the state and protected by it. It is the state which provides the
integrative framework within which the civil society operates; civil society cannot function
properly without the state. The integrative framework, as expressed in laws and rules, is
accepted as valid by all, the framework needs to be administered neutrally and in a manner
consistent with the shared culture of society. We cannot imagine life without this integrative
framework, which creates a degree of coherence and without which civil society is likely to
become uncivil. Civil society has to open up, in the face of the all-powerful state, to challenge
the bureaucratic devices lest it ends up in rigidity. It is, thus, the reciprocity between state and
civil society that is significant or at least, should be considered significant. State power is to be
exercised within the larger and wider sphere of civil society, and civil society has to keep state
power on its toes so that it does not degenerate into absolutism.
Civil society has to be more open and diversified. It has to keep the dialogue continuous and
constant with the state and within all the constituents making it. Its area has to be ordained
freely and openly, devices making up public opinion and public discourse state-free.
In liberal-democratic states, there is a constant interplay of forces belonging to the state and
civil society, each putting an imprint on the other. In dictatorial regimes, state power is used to
control civil society and civil society gets integrated into the state: the state speaks for the civil
society. Democracy alone unites the state with civil society. The state cannot exist for long if
it is not democracy laden; civil society cannot exist unless it is democratically structured and
functions democratically.
A democratic state cannot exist if it is restrictive, coercive, prohibitive, and imposing; it cannot
exist if it does not provide the civil society frame in perfect order; it cannot exist if it does not
guarantee rights and freedoms to individuals. Likewise, a democratic civil society cannot exist
if it does not allow every individual to act in the public sphere, it cannot exist if each and every
citizen does not have equal claim on the state, if each citizen is not respected as a human being.
73
10.6 SUMMARY
State is not mere governance; it is a political community as well. It is, what Gramsci says, the
visible political constitution of civil society, consisting of the entire complex of activities with
which a ruling class maintains its dominance, and the ways in which it manages to win the
consent of those over which it rules. It is, in other words, a complex of institutions and practices
resting upon the nodal points of power in civil society. It is a social relation and as such, it is
the codified power of social formation.
Civil society consists of the entire range of assumptions, values and institutions such as political,
social and civil rights, the rule of law, representative institutions, a public sphere and above all,
a plurality of associations.
The two concepts, state and civil society, have grown over time and along with them, their
characteristics also developed. They have stood in relation to each other, each giving another
a corresponding value. With the emergence of political economy and liberalism, civil society got
a definite connotation, especially in relation to the state.
State and civil society are closely related to each other. The state cannot be imagined without
civil society, and civil society cannot be thought of without the state. The two exist in integrative
relationships. The state, in democratic systems, protects civil society and civil society strengthens
the state. In dictatorial regimes, the state controls the civil society.
10.7 EXERCISES
1. How did the term ‘state’ come to be used in the West?
4. Why do Marxists regard the state as the committee for managing the common affairs of the
bourgeoisie?
9. How does democracy ensure an integrative relationship between the state and the civil society?
74
UNIT 11 POWER AND AUTHORITY
Structure
11.1 Introduction
11.2 Empirical Study of Power
11.3 Concepts of Power
11.4 Power – Marxist and Western Approach
11.5 Concept of Authority
11.6 Development of the Concept of Authority
11.7 Summary
11.8 Exercises
11.1 INTRODUCTION
The concept of power is the key to understand and analyse politics, political institutions and
political movements of the systemic process, both in the national and international arena. It is
the centre of political theory. H.D.Lasswell and A. Kaplan declared, “ The concept of power
is perhaps the most fundamental in the whole of political science: the political process is the
shaping, dissolution and exercise of power.” It is the concept of power that political science is
primarily concerned with. Thinkers like Machiavelli and Hobbes advocated the study of power
as the central theme of politics. Hobbes wrote: “ There is a general inclination of all mankind,
a perpetual and restless desire of power after power that ceased only in death.” A few decades
ago, Frederick Watkins suggested, “The proper scope of political science is not the study of the
state or of any other specific institutional complex, but the investigations of all associations
insofar as they can be shown to exemplify the problem of power.” Perhaps this view was
further strengthened by William A. Robson when he suggested, “ It is with power in society
that political science is primarily concerned – its nature, basis, processes, scope and results. The
focus of interest of the political scientist is clear and unambiguous; it centers on the struggle
to gain or retain power, to exercise power or influence over others, or to resist that exercise.”
While studying the concept of power and its various manifestations in the systemic processes,
one is reminded of what Joan Woodward said in his pioneering work, Industrial Organization:
Theory and Practice. He said, “It seems that the sociologist cannot win in his attempts to
establish a rigorous experimental framework for his research.” It has, on the whole, been indeed
a complex process of multi-dimensional character to analyse the operational structures of power,
both as a central theme of social order and also as a factor of motivation of ambitious men,
whether one looks at Hitler’s Germany or Stalin’s Russia.
Before we discuss about the various conceptual dimensions of power, it is desirable that
students of politics ought to have some basic understanding of the concept of power. Let us see
what Andrew Heywood in his work on Political Theory: An Introduction (Palgrave, 1997, P.
122) had to say in his introductory remarks on the concept of power:
All politics is about power. The practice of politics is often portrayed as little more than the
exercise of power and the academic subject is, in essence, the study of power. Without doubt,
75
students of politics are students of power: they seek to know who has it, how it is used and
on what basis it is exercised. Such concerns are particularly apparent in deep and recurrent
disagreements about the distribution of power within modern society. Is power distributed widely
and evenly dispersed, or is it concentrated in the hands of the few, a ‘power elite’ or ‘ruling
class’? Are powers essentially benign, enabling people to achieve their collective goals, or is it
a form of oppression or domination? Such questions are, however, bedeviled by the difficult task
of defining power; because power is so central to the understanding of politics, fierce controversy
has surrounded its meaning. Some have gone as far as to suggest that there is no single, agreed
concept of power but rather a number of competing concepts or theories.
Moreover, the notion that power is a form of domination or control that forces one person to
obey another, runs into the problem that in political life power is very commonly exercised
through the acceptance and willing obedience of the public. Those ‘in power’ do not merely
possess the ability to enforce compliance, but are usually thought to have the right to do so as
well. This highlights the distinction between power and authority. What is it, however, that
transforms power into authority, and on what basis can authority be rightfully exercised? This
leads, finally, to the question about legitimacy, the perception that power is exercised in a manner
that is rightful, justified or acceptable. Legitimacy is usually seen as the basis of stable government,
being linked to the capacity of a regime to command the allegiance and support of its citizens.
All governments seek legitimacy, but on what basis do they gain it, and what happens when their
legitimacy is called into question?
The annals of international history are a testimony to the study of struggle for power. Power
as a model of analysis has been explained and explored by various social and political scientists
since the time of Machiavelli and Thomas Hobbes. One could perhaps agree with the view that
the Federalists, Pareto and Mosca are power theorists. This line of thought has further been
advanced by George Catlin, Charles Merriam, Bertrand Russell, Harold Lasswell, and many
others. With the onset of liberalizsation and the globalisation of economy, the whole area of
empirical study of power has become a special sort of social theory.
Kornhauser has tried to analyse the difficulties involved in the methodologies to understand the
various centres of power in a political system in the article, “Power relationships and the Role
of the Social Scientists” in his edited book, Problems of Power in American Democracy
(1957). According to him, these difficulties could be somewhat expressed in the form of
questions such as, “What social scientist are you?”, “What parts of society want what types
of knowledge, to be used by whom, towards what end?”. It is not possible to have compatible
doctrines and models regarding methods and objectives in studying power. These difficulties
have been beautifully presented in theoretical works of political scientists like Machiavelli,
Hobbes, Locke, T.D.Weldon, Oakeshott, Butterfield, E.H.Carr and the like.
In any discussion of power, one has to keep in mind that most of the studies on power by
eminent researchers are simply reflections of simplified versions of politics outside their time;
76
these are not the presentations of the real politics of their contemporary society and time. An
objective bias in the selection of small subjects having limited ramifications could well lead to
methodological conclusions that may not be true in case of the ‘great society’. In the preface
to his well-known work on power studies, Who Governs?, Robert Dahl said, “Many problems
that are almost unyielding over a large area can be relatively easily disposed of on this smaller
canvas. It is not, perhaps, wholly accidental that the two political theorists who did the most to
develop a descriptive political science were Aristotle and Machiavelli, who, though separated by
eighteen centuries, both witnessed politics on the smaller, more human scale of the city-state.”
Most of the researchers who analyse the concept of power often start with two propositions:
that in any polity some people have more powers than others, and that power is an object of
desire, a ‘utility’. Power is understandably associated with honour, deference, respect and
dignity. One has, of course, to distinguish the power of the man from the power of the office
that guarantees authority and legitimacy.
One has also to be careful about the distinction between apparent and real power. While
analysing various dimensions of power, Maslow prefers to talk about the psycho –pathology of
ambition as well as mental framework of some men. He says, “ Their jungle philosophy (that
of authoritarians) does not change even when they grow up and come out of the jungle. It
resists new facts. It is sick because it reacts to an outgrown past, rather than to the real
present.” These persons are psychologically perverted ones because what they run after is
nothing but an illusion. Maslow concludes that “Of course for those who actually live in a jungle-
like world – and there are plenty who do so today – a jungle philosophy is realistic and
reasonable.”
77
In the Marxist approach and terminology, the concept of power is identified with the control of
state power through revolutions. Lenin said, “the passing of state power from one class to
another is the first principal, the basic sign of revolution, both in strictly scientific and in the
practical political meaning of the term”. The basic spirit of any revolution is the question of
power in the state. He said, “The class struggle becomes real, consistent and developed only
when it embraces the sphere of politics. In politics too, it is possible to restrict oneself to minor
matters, and it is possible to go deeper, to the very foundations. Marxism recognises a class
struggle as fully developed, nation-wide only if it does not merely embrace politics but takes in
most significant thing in politics-the organisation of state power”.
While differentiating between power and the state, Lenin was of the opinion that social power
existed before the origin of the state, and would continue to be there long after the “state
withers away”. Criticising the views of Pyotr Struve that the state would continue to exist even
after abolition of classes, Lenin said “First of all, he quite wrongly regards coercive power as
the distinguishing feature of the state: there is a coercive power in every human community;
and there was one in the tribal system and in the family, but there was no state…the distinguishing
feature of the state is the existence of the separate class of people in whose hands power is
concentrated”.
According to the Marxist thinkers, the sphere of politics includes all aspects of the state; it
implies all types of relationship among the classes, be it economic, ideological, semi-psychological
and other. Lenin said, “it is the sphere of relationships of all classes and strata to the state and
the government, the sphere of interaction between all classes.”
The term power is often used in a diverse sense, in both polysemantic and indefinite manner.
According to Fyodor Burlatsky, “the natural scientist speaks of power over nature, the philosopher
over the objective laws of society, the sociologist of social power, the economist of economic
power, jurists of state power, psychologists of man’s power over himself, and so on.” Thus,
although every expert talks about the importance of power, it is almost impossible to provide an
explicit meaning of power.
The western sociologist highlights power as an essential factor in all social kinetics. The French
sociologist talks of “the aura of mystery surrounding power”. Michel Halbecq writes, “At
present the phenomena of power preoccupy theorists of public law and political scientists.”
Francois Bouricoud emphasises that in its political form, power posseses the most formidable
enigma. The sociologist Crozier opines that power is present in all processes of social life. There
is indeed lack of specificity regarding the source of power. The western sociologists most often
are extremely empirical, refusing the philosophical content of power, or are in love with abstract
sociologising dimension of power. Maurice Duverger takes a positive view of power. He is
critical of viewing power or authority from a metaphysical or philosophical point of view. He
proposes that the emphasis should be given mainly to the practical methods by which power
commands respect and the means by which it obtains submission. Duverger, however, is not
very consistent in his observations. While discussing about some of the general indications of
power, he prefers to indulge in the philosophical groundings of power.
Some of the western thinkers have also talked about the biological concept of power. Going
back to the Greek days, Aristotle viewed power as a natural condition of society, nature
determining the character and process of society.
78
Aristotle said, “For that some should rule and, others be ruled is a thing, not only necessary, but
expedient; from the hour of their birth, some are marked out for subjection, others for rule. And
whereas there are many kinds of both of rulers and subjects, that rule is better which is
exercised over better subjects- for e.g., to rule over men is better than to rule over wild beasts.
That work is better which is executed by better workmen; and where one man rules another
is ruled, they may be said to have a work.”
Some of the leading western sociologists were not in favour of this tendency towards biologism.
George Burdeau, for example emphasised that power and society were born together. John
William Lapierre conceived power as the exclusive attribute of social organisation, as a social
factor inherent in the social group, and enforces the concept of power from the fact that man
belongs to a group.
Some researchers like Herbert Simon have presented a very narrow definition of power. Simon
uses the concepts of power and influence as synonyms. Others like Gerard Bergeron are
reluctant to use the term power and desire this term to be replaced by the concept of “control”
to ensure that what they say is ideological neutral. This type of approach, in effect, may not
be able to provide a scientific analysis.
A definition in “A Dictionary of Social Sciences” says: “Power in its most general sense denotes
(a) the ability (exercised or not) to produce a certain occurrence or (b) the influence exerted
by man or group, through whatever means, over the conduct of others in intended ways.” This
definition of power is deeply influenced by Max Weber’s famous formulation: “power signifies
any capacity to work one’s will within given social relations even against opposition, independent
of what that capacity is based on.” This juridical conception of power was very popular among
the western writers during the 1950s and 60s.
The western concept of power as the capacity to work one’s will is reflected in the writings
of Engels when he said, “Authority, in the sense in which the word is used here, means the
imposition of the will of another upon ours; on the other hand, authority presupposes subordination.”
While analysing both the Marxist and the western approach towards the concept of power, one
finds that the western approach is heavily indebted to the focus on institutional will: the dominant
will of a group or organisation whereas the Marxist approach relies on class will as the basis
of power. Raymond Aron and Crozier prefer to use “law” in place of “will”, and in place of
domination, they would like to offer direction, influence or control.
Power is, thus, the real ability to implement one’s will in social life and political power represents
the real capacity of a given class, group or individual expressed in politico-legal norms, while
discussing about the nature of power one has to keep an eye on the following aspects: a class
approach of power, concentration and diffusion of power accruing from the pluralistic nature of
society, different aspects of power such as economic, political, social, differentiation between
social and personal power, characteristics of power in different socio-political structures, and
isolation of legal principles from volitional ones.
In the 1930s, politics came to be viewed as a system of relationship with respect to power. Both
George Catlin and Charles Merriam were at the forefront of this trend. Later, other political
scientists such as Harold Lasswell, M.A.Kaplan, and others followed suit. Lassswell’s ‘Theory
of Elites’ wherein he highlighted the “distribution of values” as the base point of the political
process became the source point of the majority of American students of politics, and political
science came to be treated as the science of power. Thus, both western political sociology and
79
Marxist thinking on the growth of political systems have contributed a great deal towards the
development of the concept of power.
The concept of power, one must not forget, is multidimensional. Often power and influence
criss-cross each other’s area of operation. Some people talk about “intentionalist” and
“structuralist” understanding of power. According to the intentionalist, power is an attribute of
an identifiable object such as political party, social grouping or any interest group. The structuralists
understand power as a form of social system. Sociologists like Talcott Parsons and neo-Marxists
such as Althusser belong to the structuralist school of thought.
Steven Lucas, in his book “Power: A Radical View (1974)” talks about three phases or
dimensions of power. According to him, power has the ability to influence the pattern and the
process of decision-making framework. It has also the ability to influence political agenda and
control people’s thoughts. Thomas Hobbes first enumerated the notion of power as having the
capacity to make decisions in his major work Leviathan (1651). This has mostly been the basis
of conventional thinking in the area of political science. Robert Dahl in his book, A Critic of
the Ruling Elite Model (1958) has supported this concept of power, which according to him
could be both objective and quantifiable. This approach was widely adopted by political scientists
and sociologists, especially in America during the 1950s and 60s.
While discussing about power as the ability to influence the decision making process some
researchers prefer to highlight non-decision making as the “second phase of power”. In their
seminal essay, “The Two Phases of Power (1962)” P. Bachrach and Baratz insisted that “To
the extent that a person or group – consciously or unconsciously – creates or reinforces barriers
to the public airing of policy conflicts, that person or group has power.” As Schattschneider said,
“Some issues are organised into politics while others are organised out.”
The third dimension of power is its capacity to influence the thought process of an individual
or group. The ideas and views of individuals or groups are mostly influenced and structured by
factors such as family, peer groups, schools, churches, mass media, political parties, and the
overall environment at the work place. Vance Packard, in his study, “The Hidden Persuaders
(1960)” has analysed the factors that have the ability to influence and manipulate human
behaviour in a particular direction, what Steven Lucas said, “Influencing, shaping or determining
his very wants.” In his book One Dimensional Man (1964), Herbert Mareure, the leading neo-
left theorist, talks about this aspect of power in advanced industrial societies in which the needs
of the society could be manipulated through modern technology. This is what he said created
“a comfortable, smooth, reasonable democratic unfreedom.”
Authority is broadly understood as a constitutional means through which one can command
compliance or obedience and influence the behaviour of another. Whereas power is broadly
concerned with the ability to influence behaviour, ‘authority’ is understood as the right to do
80
so. Political philosophers over the decades have differed regarding the fundamental basis on
which authority rested. However, they all agreed with the view that authority has moral
dimensions. Authority is a form of constitutional power and provisions by which one can
influence the behaviour of others. Power is more concerned with ability whereas authority is
attached with the concept of right. Power is often identified with persuasion, pressure, threats,
coercion or violence. The constitutional overtone is absent in the case of power, whereas
authority has both legal and moral overtones.
Modern sociologists have approached the concept of authority from a different angle. The
German sociologist, Max Weber, considers authority as a form of power, a ‘legitimate power’.
He analyses it as a matter of people’s belief about its legitimacy. Although theoretically, the
concepts of power and authority are treated as separate identities, empirically both tend to cross
each other’s boundary. While some researchers have considered authority as an essential
feature of order and stability, others have looked at it as a symbol of authoritarianism.
Basically, both power and authority are mutually exclusive concepts. Authority is widely understood
as a means of gaining compliance. On the other hand, power involves the ability to accomplish
goals. It might take various forms such as pressure, intimidation, coercion or violence. Authority
and power are intrinsically interlinked. Authority is rarely exercised in the absence of power,
and power always implies some amount of authority.
Max Weber advocated three ‘ideal-types’ of conceptual models: such as traditional, charismatic
and legal-rational authority. In traditional society, authority was linked with established customs
and traditions. It was closely associated with hereditary systems of power and privileges. The
second form of authority is linked with the power of an individual’s ‘charisma’ or personality.
Some consider this type of authority as divinely ordained. Sometimes, this type of authority could
be ‘manufactured’ through the media and the ‘cult of personality’. And this spectre of total
power might lead to the growth of authoritarianism in political systems. This form of authority
has its limitations in liberal democratic political systems. Max Weber identifies the third form of
domination as legal-rational authority. This form of authority is very significant in modern
industrial societies and is often regarded as the symbol of large-scale bureaucratic organisations,
and it operates through a body of clearly defined rules and procedures. One must not, however,
be unaware of the darker side of the onward march of bureaucratic authority, its de-personalised
and inhuman social environmental dimensions.
Beginning from the social contract theories of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, there
has been a spate of liberal literatures in the field of social science that provided a classic
justification for authority. These liberal theories emphasised that in the absence of an established
legal authority to ensure order and stability as well as to protect individual liberty and rights,
there could be imbalance in the growth of social systems. To neutralise the authoritarian trends
in society, these liberal thinkers suggested that authority could be constrained through legal-
81
rational forms of constitutional provisions as the very basis of authority arising from ‘below’, the
consent of the governed.
The conservative thinkers, on the other hand, always regarded authority, to quote Roger Scruton
(1984) as an essential feature of all social institutions, a ‘natural necessity’ for leadership, not
a result of consent from the governed.
The conservative ideas and doctrines became very popular in the late eighteenth and early
nineteenth centuries. This was indeed a reaction against growing political and economic doctrines
that emphasised the basic philosophy of the French Revolution. Not surprisingly, two streams
of conservative ideas got reflected in the social science deliberations of the time. With the
growing trends of an authoritarian and reactionary form of conservatism in continental Europe
that refused to accept any idea of reform, there emerged in Britain and America, a more flexible
form of conservatism that preferred ‘natural change’ or ‘change in order to conserve’, in the
form of social reforms.
The conservative reforms were more in the form of traditions, history, and experience. They
perceived the society as a moral community and strongly advocated a strong government to
ensure the enforcement of law and order. They advocated non-ideological and programmatic
interactions between the state and the individual.
Since the 1970s, conservative doctrines have been facing strong challenges from the New
Right. The supporters of the New Right believe in economic liberalism or neo-liberalism and
social conservatism. Neo-liberalism is often considered a backlash of the policies of liberal,
socialist and conservative governments of the twentieth century. It believes that the breakdown
of social structures is a result of the growth of liberal and permissive values and is in favour
of traditional values, social discipline and restoration of authority.
Conservative political philosophy has always been criticised for its support for elite groups and
status quo in society. However, against this criticism, conservatives argue that as human beings
are morally and intellectually imperfect, it is always preferable to depend on the wisdom of
tradition, authority and a shared culture than to be obsessed with abstract principles of political
theory. From their stand point, authority is an intrinsic link that ensures social cohesion and
strengthens the structures of society.
The advocates of conservatism are Edmund Burke, Michael Oakeshott and Irving Kristol. The
advocates of authority strongly plead that an erosion of authority would lead to authoritarianism
and totalitarianism. Hannah Arendt argued that a strong traditional authority is indispensable for
the growth of moral and social behaviour, and provides a sense of social identity. In her book,
The Origins of Totalitarianism (1951), she suggested that the decline of traditional values and
hierarchies was responsible for the advent of Nazism and Stalinism. All said and done, the
concept of authority has not always been accepted without reservations by social scientists. It
has been considered a threat to reason and critical understanding. Such apprehensions have
been highlighted by psychological studies. William Reich (1897-1957) in his work, The Mass
Psychology of Fascism (1935) presented the view that the damaging repression brought about
by the domination of fathers in traditional authoritarian families could have been responsible for
the origin of Fascism. Theodore Adorno and others in the book, The Authoritarian Personality
(1950) claimed to have evidence that persons having strong deference for authority have fascist
tendencies. This view has been further strengthened by the psychologist, Stanley Milgram
(1974) in his studies on the behaviour of guards in Nazi concentration camps and the US military
during the Vietnam War.
82
11.7 SUMMARY
One of the major questions that often rise in any study of political science is the precise
relationship between power and authority. In Cicero’s phrase, “power lies with the people,
authority in the Senate”. His neat contrast between power and authority gets blurred as we
analyse the various dimensions of these two concepts over the decades, and confront the
realities behind these concepts. Interpretations of power and authority have varied with the
growth of ideological dimensions of political systems. There are good reasons to suspect the
exercise of ‘power’ and ‘authority’ in contemporary international systems. Although some of
the researchers are very critical of Hannah Arendt’s essay on Authority in her book, Between
Past and Future, Carl Friedrich’s study of Tradition and Authority, and Robert Nisbet’s reflections
on The Twilight of Authority as their reactions to radical egalitarianism and to the Marxist
tradition, one must not forget to see the streams of progressivism in these writings. Hannah’s
revolutionary politics, Friedrich’s faith in reason, and Nisbet’s weakness for pluralism have
revolutionised thinking in the field of social movements. Contemporary reflections on power and
authority are more in tune with grass-root oriented approaches towards the process of human
empowerment.
1. Power is central to the understanding and practice of politics. It can be exercised on three
levels: through the ability to make or influence decisions; through the ability to set agenda and
prevent decisions being made; and through the ability to manipulate what people think and
want.
2. Power is the ability to influence the behaviour of others, based upon the capacity to reward or
punish. By contrast, authority is the right to influence others, based upon their acknowledged
duty to obey. Weber distinguished between three kinds of authority: traditional authority based
upon custom and history; charismatic authority, the power of personality; and legal-rational
authority derived from the formal powers of an office or post.
3. Authority provokes deep political and ideological disagreements. Some regard it as essential to
the maintenance of an ordered, stable and healthy society, providing individuals with clear
guidance and support. Others warn that authority tends to be the enemy of liberty and undermines
reason and moral responsibility; authority tends to lead to authoritarianism.
4. Legitimacy refers to the ‘rightfulness’ of a political system. It is crucial to the stability and
long-term survival of a system of rule because it is regarded as justified or acceptable. Legitimacy
may require conformity to widely accepted constitutional rules and broad public support; but it
may also be manufactured through a process of ideological manipulation and control for the
benefit of political or social elites. (Andrew Heywood, Political Theory: An Introduction
Palgrave, 1997, Page 150.)
11.8 EXERCISES
1. Explain the concept of power and its various dimensions.
83
UNIT 12 LEGITIMATION AND OBLIGATION
Structure
12.1 Introduction
12.2 What is Legitimation?
12.2.1 Legitimation and the State
12.2.2 Legitimation and Legitimacy
12.6 Summary
12.7 Exercises
12.1 INTRODUCTION
Legitimation and Obligation are intimately related concepts. Legitimation induces obligation,
while obligation strengthens the claims of legitimation. The two concepts have captured the
imagination of philosophers from the ancient Greek times onwards. Political theorists, in every
age, have answered questions relating to legitimation and obligation in numerous ways. An
attempt to review these questions and arguments supporting them would be both interesting and
instructive.
Legitimation amounts to pronouncing what is lawful, i.e., what is in accordance with established
rules, principles or standards? It is what is related to the laws and decrees of the state,
sovereign or government. It is what has the sanction of force behind it. It is what is followed,
if violated, by punishment. Obligation is, generally, something by which a person is bound to do
certain things; something which arises out of a sense of duty; it is what binds a person to a duty,
to obedience. It is, in a sense, a state of being legally indebted. The two concepts, legitimation
and obligation, are so related that the former seeks to demand or pursue something while the
latter seeks to accept or follow. Legitimation is a matter of seeking obedience, whereas obligation
is a matter of accepting dominance.
84
A discussion on issues relating to these two concepts, legitimation and obligation, would help to
understand the meanings attached to it, implications relative to these terms and the arguments
supportive of each in the greater part of modern western society.
Legitimation is, thus, the power of the state rightfully exercised and is the acceptance so by
those on whom it exercises its control. The structure of power, and the exercise of it would be
legitimate if the idea of law and justice, including ethical values, social beliefs, existing productive/
economic relations which underlie these, coincide with those present in the given society, over
which the state exercises power, and are generally recognised by the given society as universal.
So understood, the concept of legitimation includes, if one attempts to identify its inherent
implications, in the first instance (i) the legalised patterns of state activities, (ii) the value-
systems of society in which the state exercises control and (iii) the citizens’ body recognises
the state’s power legitimately-based.
The state alone possesses power, the power to rule people, the power to administer public
affairs, the power to establish social order, the power to protect the system. The state alone
has the responsibility to safeguard the country and promote its interests. It is because of its
performance of responsibility that the state has power. Power of the state is the necessary
corollary of the duty it is supposed to perform; power, thus, is the essential consequence/product
of the job the state is called upon to do. That the state has the power, i.e., the lawful right of
85
the state to use power, is what may be called legitimation. Legitimation involves the use of the
power of the state legitimately ordained. One aspect of legitimation, thus, is the inherent lawful
authority empowered to exercise power which means, the power of the state to exercise its
authority with the provision that it has the power and more than that, the exercise of the power
is legitimate, legitimately authorised.
Legitimation is related to the state in more than one way. It is related to the state in the sense
that the state alone has the legal authority to use its power. It is also related to the state in the
sense that what the state does is legitimate by virtue of the fact that the state alone is authorised
to do what it does. It is related to the state in the sense that the exercise of the will of the state
is the legalised exercise permitted by the already framed basic rules prevailing in the political
system, written, unwritten or both. Where there is, for example, no legal authorisation of the
exercise of power, there is no legitimation there.
Legitimation, therefore, demands a set of norms, principles, rules and regulations on the basis
of which the state exercises its power. If the power or the exercise of the power of the state
is to be deemed legitimate, there is a need for the power of the state to fall back, for its support,
on certain basic and fundamental rules, i.e., a framework from which the state derives its power
and the support on which it rests. Legitimation is not only a matter of structural rules and
regulations, it is also a matter of procedure. It, therefore, requires the fundamental routes in
which the power of the state has to pass through. If the power of the state is to be legitimate,
it has to follow certain procedures, and has to work through certain already set procedures.
Legitimation is not a zigzag walking, it is a procedural following, walking on a well-established
path already laid down.
Legitimation, in the context of the state, also demands compliance from the people where the
state exercises its power. When the power of the state is accepted by the people, there is no
crisis of legitimation. A crisis of legitimation occurs when the power of the state, exercised as
it is, is challenged by the people or a part thereof.
86
Legitimation and legitimacy are complementary to each other. The former makes the ground for
the latter while the latter derives its strength from the former. While legitimation is a concept
related to the state intimately, it is legitimacy with which the state is primarily associated.
Legitimation is only the attending feature of the state while legitimacy is the soul of the state.
Between the two, legitimacy and legitimation, the former is primary while the latter is secondary.
The difference between the two is that of importance which is attached to it in relation to power
or its exercise by the state. The two concepts work more in association with each other than
in opposition to each other.
It is legitimacy or one may say self ‘legitimation’ that turns power into authority. Power
becomes authority only through legitimacy or through the process of legitimation. Power without
the process of legitimation becomes arbitrariness or mere force. It is, therefore, legitimacy
which converts power into authority. With no legitimation of authority, power becomes a brute
force. The Apartheid regime in South Africa during the white minority rule can be cited as an
example of ‘power regime’ without legitimacy. There, as is known, a white minority enjoyed all
political rights, and their government ruled over the black majority. That government had no
legitimate authority in the country, for it lacked legitimacy in the eyes of the vast majority of
the people – the Blacks.
To put the whole argument simply, it may be said that a government is government only when
it is legitimate. An illegitimate government is a contradiction in itself; a legitimate government
is an authority in so far as it is legitimately authorised to exercise power; power makes the
government an authority after it is able to legitimise itself. Legitimation alone makes the
government/state a power; it is such a government that rules the people and extracts from the
people their obedience. Legitimation works the other way as well. Legitimation provides an
element of willingness, on the part of the people, to accept the government’s power to rule the
people. It is, thus, a two-way movement – authorising the government/state to rule the people
in accordance with the authority vested in it and through procedures already established therein;
a willing body of citizens to accept the government’s authority to rule them. Delegitimation, on
the contrary, robs the state to have any claim over the people to rule them, and induces no
respect from the people for any such state/government.
Legitimation is the means through which power changes into authority and thus, a social order
is established in the society. It is what makes the government rule over its people and it is what
makes the people obey their government. Legitimation is the meeting point between the state
and the people, between the rulers and the ruled. Without legitimation, no effective social order
can be created; disorder alone would prevail where power is exercised with no legitimation of
authority. All systems of government seek obedience to the laws from the people only on
grounds of legitimation/legitimacy.
87
12.3 WHAT IS OBLIGATION?
Obligation means the act of binding oneself, binding oneself to some duty, to some contract, to
some promise. It is binding someone to do something. Obviously, it arises out of a sense of duty.
That is why, one may see an analytical connection between obligation and duty, the former
having the same meaning as that of duty. To be obliged means to have a duty. An obligation
can also be the act of obliging oneself or someone else. In such a case, a duty is the conception
of some behaviour as the object of an obligation. People are obliged to perform their duty. There
cannot be an obligation without a will imposing a duty or an obliging will.
Obligation, one may see clearly, is a two-way situation. It is a relational concept. It is used (a)
for a relation between individual persons. One is, for example, under an obligation to someone
else; people are, or say used to be, greatly obliged to one another. It is used (b) for a relation
between a person and an institution, such as the government. To be under an obligation to
someone (say individual or government) may be to owe something (in case of an individual’s
obligation to a government it may mean ‘to owe obedience’). In case of an individual’s obligation
to the state or the government, what it amounts to is that the state or the government has
corresponding rights over the individual.
To understand the term ‘obligation’ more clearly, it is better to relate the term ‘obligation’ to
‘bound’ than to ‘owing’. We may be bound to perform some action without in an obvious sense
owing anybody anything. To be ‘bound’ is not to be in bonds. What at best it means is
acceptance of a submission, or say losing a certain amount of freedom. When we accept
submission, we accept to work within certain limitations, and such a submission remains until
obligation stays; a certain amount of lost freedom is not regained until the obligation has been
discharged.
So understood, the concept of obligation includes, if one seeks to identify its inherent implications,
(i) an act of binding oneself to some duty, (ii) a situation characteristic of a relational relationship,
(iii) an authority, say the government with assured rights over the individuals, and the individuals,
agreeing to obeying the laws of such an authority.
All our legal and political obligations, obviously, are obligations of which we are all aware of.
What may be true about legal or political or both obligations, may, and possibly may not be true,
with regard to moral obligation. There are moral obligations (say the promises we make and
which are expected to be kept) that cannot come into existence unknown to the persons whose
obligations they are. There are, on the other hand, other obligations (of which this may not be
true) of caring for one’s parents in their old age and about which it may not occur to a person
that it is an obligation to be attended. We may, thus, say about a moral obligation that a man
cannot be said to have a moral obligation of which he is not aware. It is, therefore, the word
88
‘duty’ that comes close to moral obligation; and it is the word ‘obligation’ that comes close to
legal/political obligation. Duty speaks of our moral obligation. It should, therefore not be concluded
that duty and obligation stand opposite to each other. There is a measure of duty in obligation,
and there is a measure of obligation in duty. A duty demands an obligation to be attended, and
an obligation expects a duty to be attended.
An obligation, like a duty, is an obligation first, and it is, thereafter, that the obligation is legal/
political or moral; it is conscious or it is not; it is assumed or it is declared; it is voluntary
or it is involuntary. The knowledge that there does exist an obligation does not make it legal or
political, for a man not in knowledge of what obligation he has would not obligate him of his
moral obligation. Likewise assumption, voluntarily or involuntarily, should not be made the basis
for making an obligation either legal, political or moral. Thomas McPherson (Political Obligation,
1967) rightly says, “We should, I think, generally be reluctant to use the expression ‘moral
obligation’ for a duty not voluntarily assumed. Some cases covered by the expression ‘political
obligation’ by contract are certainly cases where we have obligations that we have not voluntarily
assumed.”
Obligations being of numerous sorts, there is a likelihood of these different obligations coming
into conflict with one another. A moral type of obligation can come into conflict with a legal
obligation; a political legitimation may conflict with a religious one. Any attempt to provide
resolution may involve or invoke serious struggles of conscience. The possibility of a clash
between a legal obligation and a political obligation may seem to be less real, but a conflict
between a moral obligation and political obligation may, and usually is a real one. The moral
obligation, for example, to help a friend in distress may conflict with my legal obligation to pay
my tax in time. A compulsory vaccination or say sterilisation may be an act of political obligation,
while a religious obligation may demand an almost opposite act.
A more important question with regard to numerous kinds of obligations (and this is true about
the numerous kinds of duties) is where do we stand when various obligations conflict with one
another? Are we to attend to a certain type of obligation and reject the other type? To be fair
to these numerous types of obligations or duties, one has to attend to them and it is very rare
that one likes to sacrifice/ignore one at the cost of the other. Political obligation may be more
demanding at one point of time than the other; it may seek immediate redressal, for fear of
punishment or otherwise, than compared to the other type of obligation.
One should note that an obligation is an obligation. That it is political or moral is a secondary
thing. Attending to obligation is an act of performance. Whether we attend it today or the next
day is something that depends on intensity. If we are obliged, we are obliged; accordingly, duty
is a duty. If we perform our duty, we are doing our duty. Obligation is the acceptance of an
act; its compliance is an act of our willingness.
89
12.3.3 Concept of Political Obligation
Political obligation constitutes an exterior sphere of norms and rules. It is what is found in laws
and by-laws. It is what relates to a body of duties which citizens can be legally compelled to
perform by the threat of punishment or other legal consequences. Political obligation assumes
a set of legal duties to be performed by the citizens, their non-compliance is usually followed
by punishment or prescribed by the prevailing rules/laws. This should, however, not mean that
political obligation is the same as legal obligation. Political obligation goes beyond the sphere of
legal obligation. Political obligation does demand compliance to the laws of the state, but it too
admits means to challenge the system in order to safeguard the obligation ends. It does include
the obligation of the citizens to obey the laws of the state, but it also incorporates in its sphere
a wider obligation, i.e., duty to defend the country, or to fight for justice. This latter connotation
of obligation is much more than what one would like to include either in moral or legal obligation.
The concept of legal obligation helps only in protecting the already established legal structure,
but it is for the concept of political obligation to protect the system as a whole against political
disagreement, despotism and totalitarianism, injustice, exploitation and the like. The problem of
political obligation is how to establish a legitimised political/social order. The creation or
reconstruction of a social/political order is an obligation that is subsumed under the concept of
political obligation.
Political obligation is a kind of obligation which seeks to establish a political system free from
all types of injustices and laden with the promotion of common interest. The domain of political
justice is neither the sphere of law entirely, nor that of ethics completely. It is a sphere situated
between ethics and law. It is what is related to its grounds (why to obey?) and its content (as
to what it contains so that it is obeyed).
Generally, people obey the laws. They do so because they accept the government that rules
them. They do so because they accept the system wherein the government operates. And if
they like to disobey the government, they do so because they hesitate to accept both the
government and the system as a whole.
Legitimacy of states and governments depend on how the people look at them and also at the
social world around, and what they consider to be morally right. What they consider morally
proper is the product of numerous factors which influence people. The total effect of all the
influences make up what may be called the ‘legitimation process’. Legitimacy once evolved or
grown is not a matter of all future; it is a process which goes on and on. The state goes on
because the people want it to go on. The state, one must remember, goes on not because it has
power. The overwhelming power does not last on its own. It has to have the acceptance and
support of the people; it has to have its own strength which is much more than the physical
force that it has. What it means is that the states have to have their legitimacy, i.e., the
government rules over the people because it has the legitimate right to rule.
90
12.4.1 Legitimation and Obligation: Basis of Paternalism
There are numerous bases which make a particular type of government extract obedience from
the people. In other words, legitimation of the state and government to rule people and the
obligation of the people to obey the government have their grounds in numerous theories. One
such theory may be termed as ‘Paternalism’, one that can best be expressed in the divine right
theory of the kings as well as the charismatic theory.
The divine right theory advocates that the power the rulers, as kings, have was given to them
by god. The kings rule because god authorises them to rule. They have the right to rule the
people because god has given them the power to rule. The basis of the authority of the king
is religion which makes the state a divine institution. Legitimacy, in such a theory, lies in kings
having power as ordained by god. The people are, the divine right theory claims, obliged to obey
the kings. Their disobedience does not only constitute a crime, it also constitutes a sin. Absolute
obedience is a characteristic feature of the divine right theory; political resistance is regarded
as a rebellion against the divine ruler.
The divine right theory, despite its demerits, prevailed as a gospel truth constituting legitimacy
of the rulers and also the obligation of the people to obey the divinely appointed rulers. Such
a theory provided a framework of legitimation and obligation. The kings ruled as the legitimate
holders of powers and the people accepted them and obeyed them considering all this as a
phenomenon willed by god. Religion, as the prominent factor of divine theory, legitimised both
the monarchical absolute rulers and the obligation of the people to obey them.
There is a form of paternalism known as, to use Weber’s term, ‘charismatic authority’. Charismatic
authority is a personal authority, related to the very personality of the person having power. Such
a person has power by the sheer dint of his dominant personality. “Whoever”, Thomas McPherson
says, has “power…. may be thought to have a right to it.” “We hear”, he continues, “of men
with ‘magnetic personalities’ of ‘born leaders’, and so on.” The argument runs as follows: “At
times, particularly times of crises, people want to be led, and will respond to someone who has
the confidence to put himself forward as their leader ___Wesley, Hitler, Churchill.” History
witnesses a form of charismatic authority where people, willingly, obey or confer authority on
some leaders whose strength lies in the very personality of a person. Such persons are generally
known as charismatic leaders. People accept them as leaders and give their obedience to them
because of some extraordinary personal qualities, because they represent some ideals with
extraordinary clarity. Charismatism is, as such, a form of paternalism.
Traditionalism too sounds as yet another example of paternalism. In the earliest societies, people
accepted the power of some people over themselves because they would believe that these
rulers have been followed from times immemorial. People obey because they have been traditionally
obeying. Obedience becomes a matter of practice; acceptance of such authority is also a matter
of traditionally-based belief.
91
The contract theory provides a legitimation thesis which states that the government rules
because of the title it has to rule – whether that title has been bestowed upon the Leviathan
(in the case of Hobbes) as through an agreement that the state protects the rights of the people
(as in the case of John Locke) or through a government based on the General Will (as Rousseau
would want us to believe). The state has the power to rule over the people as per the contract
entered into by the people. This very contract theory also provides an argument for peoples’
obligation to obey the government, this too through the grounds of contract. The contract theory
may not be taken too far to investigate the possibility of whether such a contract was ever made
or not. What may only be inferred is a legal right of the state to rule the people, and a legal
duty of the people to obey the state. There is no doubt that the state exists because it has to
establish law and order. Its essence lies in the external relations it maintains among people
residing in its area. There is, thus, the legal framework at its base through which people
demonstrate formal relationship. The state rules in accordance with the procedure established
by law and what the law of the land, i.e., the constitution, expects from it. The contract theory
legalises the state and gives it legitimacy to govern the people as a matter of title. On the other
hand, the contract theory also legalises the procedure of peoples’ obligation to obey the state.
People obey the state, for the contract demands from them an obligation that they are legally
bound to comply with the orders issued by the state. What this theory establishes is the legal
relationship between the rulers and the ruled, binding the former to rule the latter, binding the
latter to obey the former. This theory, indeed, leaves no scope for non-compliance; non-compliance
is followed by punishment. Legal and lawful authority, rule of law, legally-oriented framework
and a set of legal obligation and the like are some of the characteristics of the contract theory.
92
However, the consent and contract theories help evolve a democratic spirit that brings legitimation
of the governmental laws and the people’s obligation closer to each other. The government rules
because the people want it to rule; the people obey because the government rules for them. The
democratic content itself gives legitimation to the government on one hand, and demands
people’s obligation to obey the government on the other.
Referring to the legitimation and obligation crises in the post-second world war years, David
Held (Political Theory and the Modern State, 1989) gives contrasting accounts of the crises
of the state, “overloaded state” theory on one hand, and “legitimation crisis” theory on the other.
The former theory arguing from the pluralist premises (see Brittan, “The Economic Contradiction
of Democracy,” 1975; Huntington, “Post-industrial politics: How Benign Will It Be,” 1975;
Nordhaus, “The Political Business Cycle”, 1975), the latter theory arguing from the Marxist
premises (see Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, 1976; Offe, Contradiction of the Welfare
State, 1984).
Such pluralist societies, pursuing democratic values through fabulous material promises made to
93
the people in return for their support, in political arena, work through political parties which
follow strategies of appeasement. They do so because they do not want to risk their support;
they do so for fear of losing future votes. Political parties attempt to avoid strict action in any
field. They do not make promises to set the economy on the right path, nor do they seek the
enforcement of radical steps. Appeasement strategies prevail everywhere. In administration,
more state agencies relating to health, education, industrial relations, prices, and incomes increase
in unwieldy proportions; bureaucracies develop which often fail to meet the ends for which they
were originally designed.
The state in pluralist societies proves a failure in providing a firm and effective management.
It is unable to meet the cost of its programmes which it designs to meet the ever-increasing
expectations of its people in order to obtain their vote. It is unable to arrest inflation, for its public
spending processes never stop. Consequently as the state expands, it destroys progressively the
realm of individual initiative where the space for free and private enterprise is lost.
Democracy, in pluralist societies, becomes only a mechanism, and in the process loses its
humanitarian value. The state becomes incapable of managing public affairs effectively; it
becomes rather an instrument in the hands of powerful economic organised groups, and in the
process, loses its role of providing an impartial and effective administration. The individual
becomes sovereign, but only in the rhetorical sense of the term. Freedom becomes a set of
liberties without any base of equality.
The legitimation of the government, in pluralist societies, causes to be questioned. The obligation
on the part of the people to obey the state comes under cloud. A firm and decisive political
leadership, among other things, which is less responsive to democratic pressures and demands,
may provide solace.
The crises and struggles, so grown, require extensive strife intervention. While the principal
concerns of the state aim at sustaining, and if possible strengthening the capitalist economy and
managing class antagonisms, it seeks to ensure the support of powerful groups, both the business
community and trade unions. The state, in order to avoid crises, both economic and political,
94
takes up the areas of the economy and civil society; it also expands the administrative structures;
complexities increase, so increases the need for cooperation, and the expanding economy.
The state has to increase its finances so as to be able to meet the ever-growing expectations
of the people. Finance comes up through taxation, or through loans from the capital markets
which, in turn, interferes in economic growth. The permanent inflation process never ends; crisis
in public finance never ends. The system is always under stress and strain; legitimacy causes
to be doubted and obligation is always at stake.
David Held finds some common thread in both the theories – overload government thesis and
the legitimation crisis argument. The common thread is that (i) both the theories find in governmental
power a capacity for effective political action (ii) both hold the view that state power depends
ultimately on the acceptance of the authority of the state (overloaded theorists) or, on legitimacy
(legitimation crisis theorists) (iii) both the theories confer that state power is being progressively
eroded. The state is becoming increasingly ineffective or short on rationality (iv) both the
theories agree that state power is being undermined because its authority or legitimacy is
declining progressively, thus putting a premium on the part of people’s obligation to obey the
state.
12.6 SUMMARY
Legitimation and obligation are two related concepts. Both strengthen the claims of each other.
Legitimation, as a concept meaning something that is lawful, implies the legalized pattern of state
activities accepted so by the citizens constituting it. It admits lawful authority empowered to
exercise power, and more than that, the exercise of power is legitimate, legitimately authorised.
It, in the context of the state, demands compliance from the people. When the power of the
state is accepted by the people, there is no crisis of legitimation. The crisis arises when the
power of the state, exercised as it is, is challenged by the people or part thereof.
Obligation means the act of binding oneself; it to a great degree, implies a duty; to be obliged
means to have a duty. It is an act of binding oneself to some duty. It may well be characterised
as a situation of a relational relationship; an authority on the one hand, with assured rights over
the individuals; the individuals, on the other, agreeing to obeying the laws of such an authority.
Obligation, in the context of state, becomes a political obligation.
“Obligation” and “legitimation”, the two concepts have captured the attention of political
philosophers from times immemorial. Paternalism, traditionalism, the contract and context theories
have been offered to provide the bases of the legitimacy of the governments’ right to rule the
people together with the obligation of the people to obey the governments.
All systems experience problems of crises relating to legitimation and obligation. No system, in
fact, is free from crises at one time or the other, with one factor or several factors responsible
for such crises. Crises occur, whether they relate to challenging the legitimacy of the government
or people’s obligation to obey the laws of the state, not because of the casual/accidental changes
in the environment, but because of the “structurally inherent systems – imperatives that are
incompatible and cannot be hierarchically integrated” (see Habermas, Legitimation Crisis).
Referring to the advanced capitalist societies, Habermas says that such societies experience
four levels of crises: economic, rationality, legitimation and motivation.
95
12.7 EXERCISES
1. What do you mean by legitimation?
2. Distinguish between legitimation and legitimacy. How are the two concepts related to each
other?
6. Briefly summarise the contract theory’s argument for obeying the laws of the state.
8. Analyse briefly the theory of overloaded government in relation to legitimation and obligation.
96
UNIT 13 CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE AND
SATYAGRAHA
Structure
13.1 Introduction
13.2 Concept of Civil Disobedience
13.3 History of the Concept of Civil Disobedience
13.4 Theory of Civil Disobedience and Existentialist Philosophy
13.5 Gandhian Concept of Civil Disobedience and Satyagraha
13.6 Civil Disobedience in Practice
13.7 Summary
13.8 Exercises
13.1 INTRODUCTION
The concept of civil disobedience movement has become an important element in the political
power structure in contemporary world. This movement has spread around the world. It has
been exemplified by Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. in the civil rights movement in the United
States, the ‘ people’s power’ movement in the Philippines, the non-violent collapse of communism
in Eastern Europe and so on. The success of Gandhi and Dr. Martin Luther King, Jr. had a
lot to do with the emergence of satyagraha as an organisational power. To discuss about the
history of the twentieth century, without exploring the impact of civil disobedience and satyagraha
is to malign the very basis of the people’s movement and the study of social science. The
Gandhian method of civil disobedience and satyagraha has given a new dimension to the
concept of statecraft.
While delivering the most prestigious Gandhi Memorial Lecture on “Towards a World without
war- Gandhism and the Modern World” on 11 February 1992, Dr. Daisaku Ikeda said, “As we
approach the end of this century of unprecedented wars and violence, we seek as our common
goal the creation of a world without war. At this critical juncture what can we – must we- learn
from this great philosopher – a man whose spiritual legacy could rightly be termed as one of
humanity’s priceless treasures, a miracle of the twentieth century.”
The basic aim of every political system is to assist in the process of self-actualisation of
individuals to fulfil the inner requirements for a continuous moral growth. The very concept of
satyagraha has provided a new meaning and orientation to the concept of politics. Dr. Martin
Luther King, Jr. was so much influenced by the concept of civil disobedience and satyagraha
that he said, “If humanity is to progress, Gandhi is inescapable. He lived, thought and acted,
inspired by the vision of humanity evolving towards a world of peace and harmony”. The
Swedish economist, Gunnar Myrdal said, “In a time of deepening crisis in the underdeveloped
world, of social malaise in the affluent societies, it seems likely that Gandhi’s ideas and techniques
will become increasingly relevant.”
In a violent international climate, with struggle for economic hegemonism and ever escalating
97
systemic process of violence, not to mention about human rights violations, poverty, and hunger,
the concept of civil disobedience and satyagraha of Gandhi is gaining more and more momentum.
The concept of Civil Disobedience and Satyagraha has played an important role in the theory
and practice of human liberation movements. It has, indeed, continued to inspire the social and
political movements throughout the world. The Gandhian principles of non-violence and civil
disobedience are rooted in his concept of Satyagraha. The anti-nuclear and Green Movements,
the termination of statist communist administration in Czechoslovakia in 1987, and the popular
resistance movement in Kosovo against the Serbian ethnic persecution are some of the important
civil disobedience movements of the last century. The rise of racial and ethnic chauvinism, and
retrogressive character of the globalisation process have again highlighted the role of civil
disobedience and satyagraha as a strategy of social and political movements.
The concept of Civil Disobedience has a long and varied history covering almost the whole
stream of human thought from the Greek era to the present day. The justification and analysis
of the concept has been attempted from a variety of philosophical, political and linguistic angles.
The concept of Civil Disobedience implies an act or process of public defiance of a law or
policy, duly formulated and created by a governmental authority, which an individual or a group
considers to be unjust and/ or unconstitutional. The defiance of the governmental law or policies
must be a pre-meditated act and the movement has to be announced in advance. The defiance
of law might take either violent or non-violent form. It may be either active or ‘passive’. As
the basic spirit of the civil disobedience movement is to arouse public conscience, the individual
or the group must be prepared to accept punishment for the violation of law or policies. The
action or non-action of civil disobedience has to be openly insisted on in order to be qualified
as civil disobedience. The mere non-compliance of legal provisions does not itself constitute civil
disobedience.
The concept of Civil Disobedience is grounded in justice and common good, and its end must
be a limited one. The basic aim of civil disobedience movement is to arouse consciousness in
the adversaries and appeal to their conscience.
Although the methodology of civil disobedience is not restricted within the limited framework
of either violent acts or ‘ non-violent action’, for a variety of historical or psychological reasons,
most of the practitioners of the civil rights movement are committed to non-violence. Some of
the pacifist believers of civil disobedience even assume that a complete commitment to non-
violence is ethically superior to the possible use of violence.
In contemporary literature, the concept of civil disobedience has been understood as a political
strategy adopted by Mahatma Gandhi and his followers in India to oppose British colonial
administration. Martin Luther King Jr., during the Civil Rights movement in the United States,
also successfully used this strategy.
98
Referring to the concept of civil disobedience, Mahatma Gandhi said, “I shall consider it (civil
disobedience) to be a public, non-violent and conscientious act contrary to law, usually done with
the intent to bring about a change in the policies or laws of the government. Civil Disobedience
is a political act in the sense that it is an act justified by moral principles, which define a
conception of civil society and the public good. It rests then, on political convictions as opposed
to a search for self or group interest. In the case of a constitutional democracy, we may assume
that this conviction involves the conception of justice that involves around the constitution itself.”
Throughout the long history of human civilisation, there has always been a conflict between
individual freedom and political authorities of the state. The freedom to choose whether to obey
the dictates of state law or not has always been the basic theme of civil disobedience movement.
Socrates considered obedience to and search for truth as the fundamental aim of human life.
To him, justice is an element of truth. Although he strongly believed that an individual could only
develop in a well ordered society, and it was his moral duty to obey the state, he was not
prepared to sacrifice the realm of conscience. He strongly advocated that the state has no right
to force an individual to act unjustly. This is the area in which he justified the role of civil
disobedience.
The early Christians used civil disobedience movements as justification for religious and moral
obedience to God. This was the first non-violent civil disobedience movement in the West. The
doctrine of civil disobedience movement has been used as an instrument of socio-political
transformation on a number of occasions.
The modern concept of civil disobedience had its origin in the writings of empiricists like Thomas
Hobbes. The political situation of England in the seventeenth century made Hobbes espouse the
doctrine of fundamental natural rights as a basis for obedience to government. He was convinced
that in order to guarantee rights to the individuals, the state must ensure a climate of civil peace.
He was not prepared to grant the right to dissent to the individuals in the state. The only
condition under which the individuals were entitled to have the right to dissent was when the
state was not strong enough to protect the rights of the individual and to ensure civil peace in
society. The right to civil disobedience was indeed inherent in the specific conditionality of
Hobbes.
John Locke was of the opinion that the people have a “right to resume their original liberty and
to establish a new government.” Even if he was not so precise and clear about the propriety
of resistance to the authorities of the state, he was convinced that the people have the right to
have both non-violent and violent civil disobedience movements to ensure liberties, properties
and social justice.
While analysing the empirical utilitarian approach to determine the concept of the right to resist,
99
Henry David Thoreau adopted an idealistic anarchist view. He strongly believed that all civil
laws that try to encroach upon the areas of moral law have no moral justification to exist. The
Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1948, which emphasised humanistic foundations for
man’s basic rights, supports the contention of Thoreau. In his Treatise of Human Nature, David
Hume provided a libertarian concept of civil disobedience.
Jeremy Bentham advocated that conscientious citizens have to “enter into measures of resistance
as a matter of duty as well as interest.” James Mill adopted a paradoxical attitude towards the
concept of civil disobedience. He supported the right to a violent revolution while opposing the
right to advocate limited civil disobedience.
All the empiricists like Thomas Hobbes, John Locke,David Hume, Jeremy Bentham and James
Mill were in favour of a negative concept of individual freedom. They put emphasis on the
absence of restraints as the basic requirement of individual freedom. Their views against all
improper use of governmental authority provided the basic ground for the modern theories of
civil disobedience.
The Idealist School was less hospitable to the concept of civil disobedience. From Aristotle to
Rousseau and supporters of Hegelian as well as Marxist traditions, all have emphasised the
importance of state over individuals. While emphasising the positive concept of freedom, the
Idealists were of the opinion that the positive concept of freedom could only be achieved by
an unconditional loyalty to a collectivity.
The Syndicalists emphasised the obedience to democratic trade union leadership only so as to
have access to the areas of positive freedom. One must not forget that the Anarchists in the
idealist (Tolstoy) or socialist (Bakunin, Kropotkin) tradition have always pleaded for a total
rejection of state system based on the positive concept of freedom. In fact, they provided a new
approach to the realisation of man’s social self through civil disobedience.
Political theorists consider the idea of natural law as an important basis of the modern idea of
civil disobedience. Although both Aristotle and Cicero failed to develop a theory of civil
disobedience, their views on the subject have definitely paved the way for the justification of
a civil disobedience movement. Aristotle said, that “ unjust law is not a law.” Cicero was of
the view that “a true law – namely right reason- which is in accordance with nature, applies
to all men and is unchangeable and eternal.”. These views have provided a strong ground for
the civil disobedience movement.
Thomas Acquinas considered unjust laws as “acts of violence rather than laws”. To him, “such
laws do not bind in conscience.” However, he would not allow any disobedience to the Church
at all and, disobedience to the state, only in rare cases.
Modern Neo-Thomists have adopted the same cautious attitude of Acquinas regarding the
issues of civil disobedience. Pope Pius XII was criticized for not adopting a bold stand against
the genocide of European Jews. Rolf Hochhuth in his play, The Deputy (1963), criticised the
Pope for not doing enough to disobey or resist Hitler’s aggression.
In recent years, the Church has taken a bold stand regarding civil disobedience. The right to
disobedience is no more, limited to violation of divine laws. Pope John said, “For to safeguard
the inviolable rights of the human person and to facilitate the fulfillment of his duties, should be
the essential office of every public authority. This means that, if any government does not
acknowledge the right of man or violates them, it not only fails in its duty, but its orders
completely lack juridical force.”
100
13.4 THEORY OF CIVIL DISOBEDIENCE AND
EXISTENTIALIST PHILOSOPHY
The theme of alienation, drawn from existentialist philosophy, is an important aspect of
contemporary theories of civil disobedience. Albert Camus is considered a leading contributor
in this area. Although both Albert Camus and Jean Paul Sartre and other existentialist thinkers
believe that there is no valid basis for any moral or political authority’s claim to validity (or
legitimacy) or to obedience, Camus was more forthright regarding his views on resistance to
oppression. He was of the opinion that respect for the dictates of justice must precede respect
for law. In his Nobel Prize address, Camus strongly advocated his ‘ refusal to lie about what
we know and resistance to oppression’. He was not even averse to the use of physical force,
although he always regarded it as a supreme evil, to counteract the worst violence of the state.
He considered every power elite and authority of the state as the enemy of justice. He
considered pacifists as ‘ bourgeois nihilists’.
Gandhi called his concept of civil disobedience as the doctrine of ‘Satyagraha’ or ‘Truth Force’.
For him, the adjective ‘civil’ in the phrase ‘ civil disobedience’ referred to peaceful, courteous,
and a ‘civilised’ resistance. To him, the concept of passive resistance is inadequate to grasp the
full implications of the concept of ‘satyagraha’. He said that one must not only resist passively
the injustice and arbitrariness of the government, but also must do so without any feeling of
animosity.
In the earlier phase, Gandhi had spoken of passive resistance as an ‘all-sided sword’. He said,
“…it blesses him who uses it and him against whom it is used. Without draining a drop of blood,
it produces far-reaching results….Given a just cause, capacity for endless suffering and avoidance
of violence, victory is a certainty.”
Subsequently, Gandhi abandoned the term ‘passive resistance’, and chose the term ‘satyagraha’.
The concept of satyagraha is devoid of any feelings of hatred and violent means. It is based
on spiritual purity. Like Tolstoy, Gandhi was opposed to all forms of violence in his commitments
to political actions. Arne Naess, a leading theoretician on Gandhi has stressed Gandhi’s
“constructive imagination and uncommon ingenuity in finding and applying morally acceptable
forms of political action.” Satyagraha, the unique system of non-violent resistance to the
government’s arbitrary methods and actions is, indeed, his greatest gift to mankind.
For Gandhi, Ahimsa (non-violence) and Truth were inseparable. He said that “Ahimsa is the
means; Truth is the end.” Gandhi used satyagraha as a lever for social movements.
In order to understand the Gandhian concept of civil disobedience and satyagraha, it is desirable
101
to know Gandhi’s view on the subject in detail. Gandhi said, “Satyagraha largely appears to the
public as Civil Disobedience or Civil Resistance. It is civil in the sense that it is not criminal.
The lawbreaker … openly and civily breaks ( unjust laws) and quietly suffers the penalty for
their breach. And in order to register his protest against the action of the lawgivers, it is open
to him to withdraw his cooperation from the state by disobeying such other laws whose breach
does not constitute moral turpitude. In my opinion, the beauty and efficacy of Satyagraha are
so great and doctrine so simple that it can be preached even to children.”
Gandhi strongly advocated that it was the birth right of every individual to offer civil disobedience
in the face of unjust laws. He wrote in 1920, “I wish I could persuade everybody that civil
disobedience is the inherent right of a citizen, He does not give it up without ceasing to be a
man. Civil disobedience, therefore, becomes a sacred duty. When the state has become lawless,
or which is the same thing, corrupt. And a citizen that barters with such a state, shares in
corruption or lawlessness.”
In his evidence before the Hunter Committee that was constituted by the Government of India
to enquire into the disturbances in 1919, Gandhi argued that civil disobedience would be called
for and is legitimate even in a democracy. He highlighted its constitutional aspects. In his reply
to the Hunter Committee as to what he would have done towards the breakers of laws if he
would have been a Governor himself, Gandhi replied, “If I were in charge of government and
brought face to face with a body who entirely in search of truth, were determined to seek
redress from unjust laws without inflicting violence, I would welcome it and would consider that
they were the best constitutionalists, and as a Governor I would take them by my side as
advisers who would keep me on the right path.”
Some people have questioned the efficacy of satyagraha as a universal philosophy. Gandhi’s
vision was not confined to the attainment of independence from foreign rule, the control of
government by the Indians. He struggled for the Indian soul, not merely for a visible polity.
In the concept of ‘civil disobedience and satyagraha’ both ‘civil disobedience’ and ‘ satyagraha’
are deeply interlinked as a theory of conflict resolution. Gandhi said, “Experience has taught me
that civility is the most difficult part of satyagraha. Civility does not here mean the more outward
gentleness of speech, cultivated for the occasion but an inborn gentleness and desire to do the
opponent good. These should show themselves in every act of satyagraha.”
This new orientation of the concept has provided a visionary dimension to the very approaches
of conflict resolution in statecraft. The present threat, indeed, to the very existence of mankind
could only be removed by the Gandhian approach of a revolutionary change of heart in individual
human beings.
The basic aim of every political system is to create a social, political and economic climate in
which the individuals can fulfil inner requirements of their continuous moral growth. The Gandhian
method of civil disobedience and satyagraha alone helps in creating conditions in civil society
whereby all spiritual values and methods could be appreciated in the state system as a vital
necessity for progress and prosperity. Dr. King very successfully implemented this Gandhian
method during the civil rights movement. He said, “A just law is a man-made code that squares
with the moral law or the law of God. An unjust law is a code that is out of harmony with the
moral law.” In the language of Thomas Aquinas, an unjust law is a human law that is not rooted
in eternal and natural law. Any law that uplifts human personality is just. Any law that degrades
human personality is unjust. All segregation statues are unjust because segregation distorts the
soul and damages the personality.
102
Gandhi emphasised ‘civil’ in ‘civil disobedience’ to imply non-violence. Non-violence, as it is
highlighted in the analysis, has a positive as well as a negative connotation. In its negative form,
it implies ‘ non-injury’ to any living being. In its positive form, it means, ‘the greatest love’ and
‘the greatest charity’. In Buddhist literature, it is highlighted as an attitude of creative coexistence.
According to Henry Thoreau, if there is a conflict between ‘higher values’ and ‘lower values’,
then the citizen in no way should resign his conscience to the legislation of the state. He said
that “legislators, politicians serve the state chiefly with their heads; and as they rarely make any
moral distinctions, they are as likely to serve the devil, without intending it, as God. A very few
serve the state with conscience also, and so necessarily resist it for the most part…, no undue
respect for law is required as it will commit one to do many unjust things. Where ‘immorality’
and ‘legality’ come into conflict, the only obligation which I have a right to assume is to do at
any time what I think right, what I have to do is to see, at any rate, that I do not lend myself
to the wrong which I condemn”.
The Congress Party organised the Civil Disobedience Movement in pursuance of the resolution
on independence passed in the Lahore session of the Congress in December 1929.It was the
result of British refusal to accept the Congress demand for Dominion Status. Factors such as
the Lahore Conspiracy Case, the tragic death of Jatin Das in jail in 1929, the Meerut Conspiracy
Case also forced the Congress to demand independence. The civil disobedience movement got
manifested in various forms such as the widespread defiance of law, boycott of British goods,
withdrawal of support by the army and the police, and non-co-operation with the government.
Gandhi highlighted all these demands in his letter to the government in 1930 to break the salt
law.
Gandhi started his satyagraha movement in South Africa. Subsequently, on his return to India
to lead the non-co-operation movement against the British administration, he used it to remove
the grievances of the oppressed workers and peasants of Champaran, Kheda, and Bardoli. To
quote Gandhi, “… to speak of satyagraha is to speak of a weapon… a weapon which refuses
to be limited by legality. Challenge, illegality, and action – there are so many keys with which
satyagraha is equipped ….For though satyagraha rejects violence, it does not renounce illegality.”
Gandhi always emphasised the value of proper means. To him, “Improper means result in an
impure end….One cannot reach truth by untruthfulness. Truthful conduct alone can reach truth.
Non-violence is embedded in truth.”
Often Gandhi has been taken to task for his emphasis on self-suffering and satyagraha. Some
trace it to the streak of masochism in the character of Gandhi, while others have gone over to
Hindu scriptures to emphasise Indian spirituality. But the Gandhian approach to self-suffering
and satyagraha has little to do with individual self-mortification. It is a simple condition for the
success of a cause. It does not imply that there would not be any suffering in the struggle for
satyagraha. It simply means the assertion of one’s freedom and one’s right to dissent. This
method often works as a psychological way to change the minds of an opponent. Gandhi said,
“While in passive resistance, there is a scope for the use of arms when a suitable occasion
arrives, in satyagraha physical force is forbidden even in the most favourable circumstances.
Passive resistance may be offered side by side with the use of arms. Satyagraha and brute
force being each a negation of the other can never go together.”
The Gandhian concept of satyagraha is the product of his faith in religion and spiritual values.
He was convinced that the supreme law that governs all living beings and universe is nothing
but love and non-violence, and Gita carried this message of non-violence as ‘ soul force’.
103
The Gandhian concept of satyagraha is not merely an instrument of conflict resolution or non-
violent resistance to injustice. It is an integrated concept, covering the whole life process of a
satyagrahi. It includes : truth, non-violence, chastity, non-stealing, swadeshi, fearlessness, bread-
labour, removal of untouchability, and so on. Civil disobedience is a ‘branch’ of ‘satyagraha’.
All ‘satyagrahas’ can never be civil disobedience, whereas all cases of civil disobedience are
cases of satyagraha. Gandhi said, “Its root meaning is holding on to truth, hence truth force.
I have called it Love Force or Soul Force.”
In 1918, Gandhi used the civil disobedience movement in India during his campaign for the
textile workers of Ahmedabad. The Salt Satyagraha of 1930, the civil disobedience movement
for independence in 1930, and his fast unto death for the development of social conditions of
untouchables in 1939 are some of the examples of civil disobedience movements under the
leadership of Gandhi in India.
The people of South Africa used the Gandhian method of civil disobedience to demand
independence from the colonial administration. The civil disobedience movement against the
apartheid policies of the South African Government in 1952, the Johannesburg bus boycott in
1957, and the 1960 march under the leadership of Chief Albert J Luthuli against the Sharpville
massacre are some of the historic mass civil disobedience movements.
The Civil Disobedience movement by the Buddhists in South Vietnam against the American
bombing was inspired by the doctrine of non-violence. The other historic examples of civil
disobedience movements were: the movement against German occupation in Denmark and
Norway, Danilo Dolci’s strike in Sicily in the 1950s, nuclear disarmament campaign in Western
Europe, the non-violent demonstrations in Poland, the Vorkuta prison uprising in 1953 in the
erstwhile Soviet Union, the Montgomery Civil rights march in 1955, and the anti-Vietnam war
march towards the army base in Oakland in 1965.
The Civil Disobedience movement is gaining momentum day by day throughout the world.
13.7 SUMMARY
The Anti-Vietnam war, Civil Rights, Draft Resistance, Anti-Nuclear Weapons movements, and
a host of other movements in Western Europe, USA, and in other parts of the world have given
rise to a lively debate about the Civil Disobedience strategy in a democratic setup. The issue
is being debated and discussed from various angles in different parts of the world and also its
relevance in contemporary international system. Although there has been a significant volume
of conservative opinions that would not tolerate any opposition to the laws that have been
104
democratically passed by various state systems, there is also a considerable opinion of well-
reasoned persons in favour of the Gandhian concept of civil disobedience movement.
Burton Zwiebach said, “Democratic governments must include an agreement to respect differences
of opinion concerning justice and right.”
Civil Disobedience is not inconsistent with democracy. When traditional channels of meeting
public grievances are incapable of fulfilling legitimate demands, civil disobedience becomes a
strategy for the attainment of goods and social justice. Amid the fury of communalism, genocide
and the market oriented process of social injustice, the Gandhian method of civil disobedience
and satyagraha is becoming more and more popular in contemporary society.
To a superficial observer, it might appear that the concept of civil disobedience and satyagraha
goes against the very synthesis of ideals between different faiths and involves a clash of values
between the activists of civil disobedience movement and the state. In fact, the Gandhian
concept is a means for achieving social synthesis and harmony. It emphasises dialogues for a
dialectical search for truth. T.H.Green in his ‘Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation’
has rightly said, “The functions of government are to bring in those conditions of freedom, which
are conditions of the moral life. If it ceases to serve this function it loses its claim on our
obedience.” According to Barker, civil disobedience is virtually within the process of social
thought; it is a method of persuasion rather than recourse to force.
13.9 EXERCISES
1. Discuss the importance of satyagraha as a method of conflict resolution.
3. What is the relevance of satyagraha and civil disobedience in the contemporary world?
105
UNIT 14 POLITICAL VIOLENCE
Structure
14.1 Introduction
14.2 Meaning of Political Violence
14.3 Violence and State
14.3.1 Political Violence and Political Integration
14.5.5 War
14.6 Revolution
14.6.1 Meaning of Revolution
14.6.2 Three Phases of Revolution
14.8 Summary
14.9 Exercises
14.1 INTRODUCTION
Political violence in most of the modern societies is the result of social tensions, which develop
in them due to different reasons. Normally, political violence is directed against the state
106
because the state is considered the chief source of injustice and repression. As a result, different
sections of society are taking recourse to violence to solve their problems. They are following
violent methods because the state has failed to secure regular obedience from the people.
Violence is a purposeful political action to register protest of certain sections of society against
‘wrong’ policies of the government. In modern times, revolution as a form of political violence
is carried out to change the form of government and to transform social structure.
Political violence is a deliberate political activity, which has enormous ethical implications. It is
pointed out by Aristotle that men do not revolt because they catch the cold. There are serious
moral issues involved in it. Therefore, he said that the honour enjoyed by a political assassin
cannot be compared with that of an ordinary murderer. The supporters of political violence
justify it on moral grounds. They argue that they are fighting against bad government and for
a just cause. The opponents of violence condemn terrorist activities for acting against the
lawfully constituted government. Hence, one country’s terrorist is a ‘freedom fighter’ for another
country.
Aggression and violence have been a part of human history since long because men take to
violence and aggression to secure things that they did not possess or to preserve things that they
possessed. Normally, political violence is directed against the state, its property and men who
manage its institutions. Political violence may begin with rioting or mass demonstrations. But it
is always possible that it assumes different forms.
Aristotle was the first political scientist who discussed the nature and causes of political disorder.
He pointed out that change in the balance of social forces in a particular state was responsible
for political disorder. The Indian political thinker Kautilya (Chanakya) was of the opinion that
change in the attitude of one’s own people is revolt. It results from a wrong policy of the
government and immodest behaviour of the king. Thus, since ancient times, political violence
had caused disorder in the state and in modern times, the problem of political violence has
become more marked and complex.
107
Modern states are increasingly using violent methods because they want to bring about political
integration of the country as well as to hasten the process of economic development.
The modern state was built upon the demise of feudal and tribal communities, which were
autonomous entities. Once this integration was achieved in West Europe, attempts were made
there to control the arbitrary exercise of state violence by agencies of the state such as the
army and the police and their immediate controllers: Kings, ministers, generals and bureaucrats.
At present, most of the countries of Asia and Africa are undergoing this process; therefore,
politics in these states is the most violent.
In short, in the process of political integration and economic development, the level of political
violence is extremely high. The state has considerably greater potential of internal violence than
its citizens.
108
People decide to use violent methods when they think that their survival as a community is at
stake and unless they fight against it, they will have to have to suffer no end. Normally, people
exhaust legally available avenues to get their grievances redressed. But if the legal methods fail
to deliver goods, people take to violence.
After the Second World War, a large number of Third World countries became independent.
These countries faced the problem of nation building, as the process of political integration was
weak. But there was increasing political consciousness in the minds of the people. Certain
regions in these states who had a distinct cultural or religious identity demanded the right of self-
determination for their provinces. The supporters of national self-determination movement called
it a movement for national liberation while the opponents of these movements called them
secessionist movements. In India, we are facing these type of movements in Jammu and
Kashmir, Nagaland, Manipur and Assam. Most of the Third World countries are facing this
problem. Even developed countries like Great Britain and Canada faced the problem of secession
in Northern Ireland and Quebec respectively. The Irish Republican Army and the LTTE in
Srilanka are the most dreaded separatist groups in the world. These movements are marked by
excessive use of violence from both the sides. Thus, nationalism caused the emergence of
national liberation movements as well as the movements for national self-determination.
109
14.4.3 Ideology
In modern times, ideology has played an important role in the spread of political violence.
Ideology mobilises people and gives them a certain cause to wage struggle against the state.
Ideology explains the present conditions of society and asks the people to change it to bring
about a better system of governance. Most of the movements in modern times are ideological
in character. Fascism and socialism were two such ideologies.
Fascist ideas became popular in Europe between the two World Wars. Fascists glorified force
and violence and advocated the unity of interests of individuals with that of the nation state.
Fascism in Italy and Nazism in Germany used the extreme form of violence to capture political
power.
The ideology of revolutionary socialism moved a large number of people who were involved in
violent revolutionary activities. The socialists stand for the abolition of the capitalist system,
which is based on state violence. The socialists want to establish a classless and stateless
society which would end exploitation of man by man. We have examples of successful revolutions
like the Russian revolution, The Chinese revolution and The Cuban revolution. The socialists
argue that they take recourse to violence to counter state violence. There are a large number
of countries, which are witnessing violent socialist uprisings. India, Nepal, Indonesia, Burma are
the countries that witnessed violent revolutionary activities by the socialists. In India, the Naxalites
are involved in revolutionary political activities.
Many of the West European countries witnessed religious conflicts during the 17th and 18th
centuries. The conflict was between the Catholics and the Protestants. Now, modern European
states claim that they are secular and they have achieved separation between the church and
the state. But in many countries of East Europe, Asia and Africa, religious strife is common.
Inter-religious conflicts take place between two religious communities, between Christians and
Muslims, Jews and Muslims or Hindus and Muslims. There is intra-religious conflict within a
particular religious community when a particular religious sect wants to purge the religion of
corrupt practices. The fundamentalist groups, who want to purify their religion, take to an
extreme form of violence. Those people who do not approve of this ‘puritan’ view of religion
are considered as enemies of religion and an internecine warfare begins. Algeria, Egypt,
Afghanistan and several Muslim countries are facing this problem.
Culturally and ethnically, modern societies are not homogenous. Cultural and ethnic minorities
want to preserve their separate identity. Hence, they want to secure and protect their rights.
These minorities are formed on the basis of race, language and culture. They take to violence
if they feel threatened. Quebec province in Canada, Nagaland in India, Northern Ireland in
Great Britain, the Chechens in Russia, Tibetans in China and Kurds in Iraq and Iran are
examples of this. Minorities are concerned about their identity and majorities question their
110
political loyalty. In some cases like Srilanka, the struggle of minorities assumed the form of
separatist violence, which culminated in insurrection.
But it must be remembered that poor living conditions alone do not constitute a sufficient cause
to give birth to violence. The workers and farmers must develop consciousness about it in their
minds. When a section of people begins to believe, that it is being deliberately deprived of the
valued goods to which it is entitled, it takes recourse to agitation. The sources of deprivation
lie in social processes, which cause a gap between what people are entitled to and what they
receive. In modern times, due to education, learning of new skills, new consumption levels and
advertisements create a feeling of deprivation in the minds of the people. The feeling of relative
deprivation thus gives birth to political violence. Low level of economic growth causes considerable
resentment in the people. Even rapid economic development may lead to resentment if the fruits
of growth are not fairly distributed among the different strata of society.
111
can be an epoch making revolution like the French revolution of 1789. We see the emergence
of political violence in the following forms :
2) Terrorism
5) War
Those groups which are well organised mobilise people against the government and use different
methods of resistance. They declare strikes, ‘bandhs’, and hartals. Sometimes, they organise
violent demonstrations and morchas. If the central authority of the government is weak and it
lacks legitimacy, a well organised demonstration may cause the downfall of the government. But
this rarely happens. Otherwise, the impact of violent protests of the mobs is temporary in nature
because the government uses repressive measures to control it.
14.5.2 Terrorism
In modern times, terrorism has become one of the important forms of political violence as a
large number of young people join terrorist groups to bring about change in the government. The
weapon of terrorism is used by terrorists because they know that they cannot launch an open
war against the state as the state has a superior force at its command. But terrorists are
determined to use violent methods because it is their opinion that opponents understand the
language of the gun. Their power in society is also based on the gun. Terrorists use all sorts
of methods to teach a lesson to the state authorities. Their activities start with blowing up of
a bridge or breaching a wall of a dam. But in the process, they expand the area of their
operation. They get involved in activities of sabotage, murder, killing a large number of people
in sudden gun fire, hijacking of an aircraft or a bus, holding people for ransom, kidnapping,
political assassinations, extortions, setting fire to places of worship and markets, inciting caste
and communal riots etc. They succeed in harassing the state authorities because there is an
element of surprise in their actions. The Irish Republican Army, the Liberation Tigers of Tamil
Eelam, various Palestine Guerilla outfits, Al Qaeda militants are some of the most violent and
dreaded terrorist organisations. In India, we have witnessed activities of terrorists in Jammu and
Kashmir, Punjab, Nagaland, Assam, Manipur, Tripura and Mizoram. The Naga militants have
been continuing their terrorist activities for the last 4 years. Through their activities, the terrorists
want to establish a well-trained armed wing to carry forward insurrectionary activities. But most
of them do not succeed. It is true that some terrorist organisations succeed in setting up their
112
own militias but they cannot fight a well-oiled regular army of modern state which is often
supported by a super power. Guerilla warfare succeeds when the state authorities are extremely
weak and when their writ does not run beyond the capital. In South Vietnam, the Viet Cong
guerillas succeeded because of the weakness of the South Vietnamese state.
Terrorists take recourse to crime, but they are not ordinary criminals because they are ideologically
motivated and they have a vision of establishing a better society. Terrorist activities are legitimised
by their ideology. We can see three distinct phases of ideological orientation of terrorism. In its
first phase, national independence was its goal. In the second phase after the Second World
War, most of the terrorists owed their allegiance to revolutionary socialism and at present, their
orientation is religious fundamentalism or ethnic separatism. Every terrorist movement has its
own group of intellectuals who rationalise the use of violence.
All over the world disgruntled elements in the armed forces rebel against the government. This
revolt is called mutiny. Due to some economic or political reasons, the soldiers take to arms and
get involved in violent activities. For example, in 1857 the Indian soldiers of the army of British
East India Company revolted against the British rule and killed a large number of their British
officers. Normally, a mutiny is always taken very seriously by the state authorities because
soldiers posses arms and training and they are in large numbers. But if a mutiny has no
ideological base, sooner or later it is brought under control by the state authorities.
The second form of political violence is the military take over by engineering a ‘coup detat’.
Military takeover is a sharp armed insurrection by a group of army officers to capture political
power by establishing control over key installations of the state. It is a well organised operation
in which masses are bypassed. If coup leaders are confident of controlling the situation, they
may not take recourse to violence. For example in Pakistan, most of the military takeovers were
bloodless. But if the coup leaders are not confident of their success, they indulge in an extreme
form of violence to strike terror in the minds of the people. For example, in Bangladesh in 1975,
President Sheikh Mujibur Rehman and his entire family were wiped out. The military coup in
Indonesia in 1965-66 was extremely violent. All military takeovers in Afghanistan after 1973
were violent. In the military takeover, the masses are not involved and in many of the Afro-
Asian and Latin American countries, the military displaces the democratic government and
usurps power. Most of the dreaded dictators in these countries are military generals.
113
organisation and with the tacit approval of wide sections of the population, one can say that they
have assumed a serious form. It includes large scale terrorism and civil war. The revolt may
develop into a rebellion.
Rebellion is the second stage of revolt in the sense that in this phase, the rebels are ideologically
committed and they have developed a vision of future society. Due to the normally socialist or
the nationalist ideology, they are supported by a large number of people. If the rebels are able
to concentrate in a geographically peripheral area or the areas outside the efficient control of
the state and if foreign support is available to them, the rebellion assumes the form of armed
insurrection, which cannot be easily put down. The rebels normally use the tactics of guerilla
warfare because they lack the military strength to counter state forces. To circumvent the
armed superiority of the state, the guerillas try to win the support of the people through the
ideological exhortations or through the promises of redistributive policy. They promise land to
the landless, regional autonomy for ethnic minorities and political equality through the end of
foreign domination. The revolutionary guerilla warfare succeeded in countries like China, Vietnam
and Cuba but it failed in Greece, Philippines and Iran. Near perfect intelligence, mobility,
freedom from fixed logistic bases and surprise are the characteristics of successful guerilla
operations but increasingly due to strengthening of the state organisation and state forces
guerillas have not been able to achieve the successes that they had achieved against weak
states immediately after the Second World War.
14.5.5 War
War is the culmination of political violence in the sense that war brings forth two contending
forces face to face with each other and settles the issue on the basis of balance of armed
forces. War is as old as human history and violence and bloodshed are at the heart of it. There
are two types of wars : 1) war with the external enemy of the country and 2) internal war,
which takes place between the state forces and the rebels (civil war).
The external war causes widespread damage and destruction because both the parties use
massive armies, modern weapons of mass destruction and air force. The First World War
accounted for a million deaths and the Second World War was the most destructive of all wars.
Atomic weapons were used by the USA to settle the issue.
Internal war is fought between the forces of a central government and the secessionist forces.
It could be a revolt by a certain sections of the people or a rebellion by the broad mass of
people. In the 1860s, the USA witnessed a civil war between the northern and the southern
states on the issue of the abolition of slavery. Internal war is equally destructive and it may
cause widespread destruction and massacres. We have examples of violent internal wars in
Lebanon, Yugoslavia, Nigeria and India.
Thus, political violence assumes different forms in modern times. Revolution is also a particular
form of political violence.
14.6 REVOLUTION
Revolution is essentially a modern phenomenon because it wants to bring about a total
transformation of society. Revolutions are marked by widespread violence, social unrest and
ideological commitment. The new revolutionary ideology is radical, rational, democratic and universal.
114
Modern revolutions are not confined to replacing a bad ruler with a good one but they have a
modernist agenda of restructuring the entire socio-political order by the legitimate representatives
of the community.
The classical phase of revolution began in England during the British Civil War of the 17th
century that destroyed royal absolutism in England. It was followed by the French Revolution
of 1789, which witnessed unprecedented violence and bloodshed. It destroyed feudalism in
France and paved the way for the emergence of the modern capitalist society. The American
Revolution ended foreign domination and established a modern constitutional democracy in
USA. All these three revolutions transformed state organisations, class structures and dominant
ideologies. The classical revolutions were followed by the socialist revolutions of the 20th
century. It began with the October Revolution of 1917 in Russia. It was succeeded by the
Chinese Revolution in 1949 and the Cuban Revolution in 1961. Ideologically, the leaders of these
revolutions were more radical in the sense that they wanted to have a total transformation of
social, economic and political structures. Though all socialist revolutionaries believed in Marxist
philosophy and Leninist politics of international proletarian revolution, they followed different
methods to bring about the revolution.
In the third phase, revolutions were witnessed in the third world countries. The Egyptian revolt
of 1953 paved the way for the emergence of new politics in Arab countries. The Islamic
revolution of Iran in 1979 was the last of the great revolutions, which tried to reorder Iranian
society on the principles of radical Islam.
115
C. Johnson tried to understand revolution as a systemic imbalance. He is of the opinion that
revolution takes place due to the development of social imbalances and systemic disequilibrium.
These imbalances are caused because of the changes in the values of people. The changes may
also occur because of the environment within which the social system is located. These changes
must be particularly sudden and intense. He points out that disequilibrium does not cause
revolutions, as the systems can repair damage by taking corrective measures. He thinks that
the first cause of revolution is power deflation. The process of power deflation takes place
when the system fails to fulfill its obligations and it loses confidence and legitimacy. It has to
use force to maintain law and order. Second cause is the inability of the legitimate leaders to
effect’ synchronisation’ to overcome power deflation. If they are unable to restore confidence,
the ultimate loss of authority ensues and the use of force by the state is no longer considered
legitimate. As a result, the state cannot justify its monopoly over the use of force. There is a
sudden break in the effectiveness of the armed forces and commencement of special operations
against the rebels.
The third theory of revolution is the Marxist theory, which believes in class warfare. According
to Marx, our known history is a history of class struggle between haves and have nots and the
contradiction between them come in the open in the capitalist state of development. The
capitalists exploit workers by extracting surplus value from their labour and cause widespread
poverty and misery. As a result, class struggle between the capitalists and workers becomes
intense. In this struggle the state as an instrument of class rule supports the capitalist classes.
The workers bring about a violent revolution. The purpose of the proletarian revolution is to
overthrow the capitalist system and replace it with the socialist system. Establishment of a
classless and stateless society is the ultimate goal of the socialist revolution.
All these three theories point out that violence plays an important role in revolution because the
revolutionaries want to challenge and end the state’s monopoly over the use of force and they
want to establish their own control over the state.
The liberals believe in the method of education and they want to tell people that ultimately, the
use of violence is irrational in the sense that it brought out the base elements in man. Human
116
beings have registered spectacular achievement, because they have learnt to control violence.
Man has developed a new set of rules to resolve the conflicts peacefully. The economic
compulsions in national and international economy would convince people that they could gain
more in peace than in war. Violence cannot resolve the basic problems of society. Hence, the
liberals want the people to learn the operation of constitutional machinery to resolve conflicts.
They want minimum use of state violence to curb violence. They hold that the basic problems
of society could only be resolved by consensus and contract.
The state can use different methods to overcome violence, but it must first try to remove the
causes of revolt. Kautilya said that by merely killing the rebels, rebellion cannot be stopped. It
is necessary to remove the cause that is giving birth to new rebels.
As we have seen, it is the state practices that give birth to violence because it is not rebels or
terrorists who divided Ireland or drove Palestinians to exile or imposed white rule in South
Africa or killed thousands of innocent men in Iraq. State violence is the womb of terrorism,
betrayal and humiliation is its cradle and revenges its mother’s milk. Therefore, the states, which
are committed to their imperial interests by force, are unlikely to recognise that political violence
and terrorism are both a response to their policies as well as an imitation of their style. The
states should reorganise their policies on the basis of justice and fair play and stop continuing
the oppression of classes, nations and ethnic communities so that the root cause of violence is
removed.
14.8 SUMMARY
In this unit, you have studied different aspects of political violence in modern times. Political
117
violence is built in the political process itself, because the state seeks to monopolise the use of
force. There are different causes of political violence, but loss of legitimacy of the government
and inability of the political system to accommodate demands of different sections of society
are the important causes. Religious and ethnic differences also play an important role in encouraging
violence. Political violence assumes different forms including turmoil, sporadic violence and
internal war. In modern times, revolution is an important form of political violence because it
seeks to restructure basic social, economic and political institutions of the society. The state uses
different methods to overcome violence. Those who support the democratic system argue that
political violence can be overcome by redressing grievances of the people, by reforming the
system and by devising constitutional remedies, which provide for peaceful resolution of social
and political conflicts.
14.9 EXERCISES
1. What is the nature and scope of political violence?
5. Discuss briefly the role of economic conditions in the rise of political violence.
118
SUGGESTED READINGS
Abercrombie, W., S. Hill and B. Turner., The Dominant Ideology Thesis, London: Allen &
Unwin, 1980.
Almond, G. A. and S. Verba., The Civic Culture: Political Attitudes and Democracy in Five
Nations, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1963.
Almond, G. and Verba, S., The Civic Culture Revisited, Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1980.
Arora, N.D., and Awasthy, S.S., Political Theory, New Delhi: Har-Anand Publications Pvt.
Ltd., 1999.
Arrow, K., Social Choice and Individual Values, New York: Wiley, 1951.
Asirvatham, Eddy and Mishra, K.K., Political Theory, New Delhi: S. Chand & Company,
2001.
Bagart, J.F., “Civil Society in Africa” in Chabal, P., (ed.) Political Domination in Africa:
Reflections on the Limits of Power, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1986.
Barker, Ernest., Principles of Social and Political Theory, Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1967.
Barnes, B., The Nature of Power, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988.
Berlin Isaiah., Four Essays on Liberty, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1969.
Birch A. H., Concepts and Theories of Modern Democracy, London and New York: Routledge,
1993.
Blau, P. and M. Meyer., (eds.) Bureaucracy in Modern Society, 3rd ed., New York: Random
House, 1987.
Bobbio, N., Left and Right: The Singnificance of a Political Distinction, Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1996.
Brittan, S., The Economic Consequences of Democracy, London: Temple Smith, 1977.
Brooker, P., Non-Democratic Regimes: Theory, Government and Politics, New York: St
Martin’s Press, and London: Macmillan, 2000.
119
Budge, I. and D. Mackie., (eds.) Developing Democracy, London: Sage, 1994.
Burke, E., (ed.), On Government, Politics and Society, London: Fontana, B.W. Hill, 1975.
Carole Pateman., The Sexual Contract, Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1988.
Ceftwich, A., (ed.) New Dimensions in Political Science, Aldershot: Edward Elgar, 1990.
Chandhoke, N., State and Civil Society, New Delhi: Sage, 1995.
Cohen, J. and Arato, A., Civil Society and Political Theory, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1992.
Connolly, W., (ed.) Legitimacy and the State, Oxford: Blackwell, 1984.
Dahl, R., Modern Political Analysis, 4th ed., Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, 1984.
Dahl, R., Who Governs? Democracy and Power in an American City, Newhaven, CT: Yale
University Press, 1961.
Dahl, Robert A., Democracy and its Critics, Orient Longman: Yale University Press, 1989.
(Start your reading from here, as this is a collection of some of the most influential articles on
liberty in the past millenium.)
Davies, J., When Men Revolt and Why, New York: Free Press, 1971.
Diamond, L., J. Linz and S. Lipset., (eds.) Democracy in Developing Countries, Boulder,
Colorado: Lynne Rienner, 4 Vol., 1989.
Douglas, J., “The Overload Crown”, British Journal of Political Science, Vol. 6 (4), 1976.
Easton, D., A Framework for Political Analysis, 2nd ed., Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1979.
Easton, D., The Political System, 3rd ed., Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981.
120
Gandhi, M.K., An Autobiography, Ahmedabad: Navjivan, 1927.
Gelllner, E., Contemporary Political Culture: Politics in a Post-Modern Age, London: Sage,
1989.
Gerald C. MacCallum., ‘Negative and Positive Freedom’, Philosophical Review, Vol. 76, 1967.
Goddin, Robert and Pettit, Phillip., A Companion to Comparative Political Philosophy, London:
Blackwell, 1933.
Gurr, T.R., Why Men Rebel?, Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press, 1970.
Haksar, Vinit, Rights, Communities and Disobedience: Liberalism and Gandhi, New Delhi,
2001.
Hampton, Jean., Political Philosophy: An Introduction, Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Hay, Coloin., Political Analysis: A Critical Introduction, New York: Palgrave, 2002.
Haynes, Jeff., Democracy and Civil Society in the Third World, Cambridge: Polity Press,
1997.
Held, David., Democracy and the World Order, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995.
Held, David., Political Theory and the Modern State, Cambridge: Polity Press, 1995.
Henry, Shue., Basic Rights: Subsistenance, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Polcy, Princeton,
NJ: Princeton University Press, 1980.
Hirschman, N.J., ‘Freedom Recognition and Obligation: A Feminist Approach to Political Theory’,
American Political Science Review, Vol. 83, No. 4, December, 1989.
Hobsbawm, E., Nations and Nationalism since 1780, 2nd ed., Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1993.
Holder, B., Understanding Liberal Democracy, 2nd ed., London and New York: Harvester
Wheatsheaf, 1993.
Huntington, S. The Clash of Civilizations and the Making of World Order, New York: Simon &
Schuster, 1996.
121
Hutchinson, J. and A. D. Smith., (eds) Nationalism, Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press, 1994
Hyman, H., Political Socialisation: A Study in the Psychology of Political Behaviour, New
York: Free Press, 1959.
Inglehart, R., The Silent Revolution: Changing Values and Political Styles Amongst Western
Publics, Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977.
Iyer, Raghavan N., The Moral and Political Thought of Mahatma Gandhi, Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 1979.
Jeremy Bentham., Of laws in General, H.L.A. Hart ed, London: Athlone Press, 1970, p. 249
Jones, T., Modern Political Thinkers and Ideas – a Historical Introduction, London:
Routledge, 2002.
Kellas, J., The Politics of Nationalism and Ethnicity, London: Macmillan, 1991.
Lane, J.-E., Constitutions and Political Theory, Manchester: Manchester University Press,
1996.
Laqueur, W., (ed.) Fascism: A Reader’s Guide, Harmondsworth: Penguin; Berkeley, CA:
University of California Press, 1979.
Lasswell, H., Politics: Who Gets What, When, How?, New York: McGraw-Hill,1936.
Leftwich, A., (ed.) What is Politics? The Activity and Its Study, Oxford and New York:
Blackwell, 1984.
Lenin, V. I., Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism, Moscow: Progress, 1916/ 1970.
Lijphart, A., (ed.) Parliamentary Versus Presidential Government, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1992.
Lipson, Leslie., The Great Issues of Politics, Bombay: Jaico Publishing House, 1967.
122
Lukes, S., (ed.) Power, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1986. Also see his Essays in Social
Theory, London: Macmillan, 1974.
MacCallum Gerald C., ‘Negative and Positive Freedom’, Philosophical Review, Vol. 76, 1967.
Macpherson, C. B., The Life and Times of Liberal Democracy, Oxford: Oxford University
Press, 1977.
Marshall, T. H., ‘Citizenship and Social Class’, in T. Marshall (ed.) Sociology at the Crossroads,
London: Heinemann, 1950
Marty, M.E, and R. S. Appleby., Fundamentalisms and the State: Remaking Politics,
Economics, and Militance, Chicago: Unviersity of Chicago Press, 1993.
McPherson, Thomas., Political Obligation, London: Routledge and Kegan Pal, 1967.
Mehta, V.R., Foundations of Indian Political Thought, New Delhi: Manohar, 1992.
Mill, J. S., On Liberty and Other Writings, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989.
Mill, J.S., Utilitarianism, Liberty and Representative Government, London: Everyman, 1910
Miller, D., and Siedentop, L., (eds.) The Nature of Political Theory, Oxford: Clarendon, 1983.
Miller, David, (ed.), The Blackwell Encyclopaedia of Political Thought, Oxford: Clarendon,
1983.
Nozick, Robert., Anarchy, State and Utopia, New York: Basic Books, 1974.
O. Patterson, Freedom: Volume I - Freedom in the Making of Western Culture, New York:
Basic Books, 1991.
Oakeshott, Michael., Rationalism in Politics and Other Essays, London: Methuen, 1962.
Olson, M., The Rise and Decline of Nations, Newhaven, CT: Yale University Press, 1982.
Patterson, O., Freedom: Volume I – Freedom in the Making of Western Culture, New York:
Basic Books, 1991.
Paul, Miller and Paul., (ed.) Liberty and Equality, London: Basil Blackwell, 1985.
Pierre, J. and B. Guy Peters., Governance, Politics and the State, London: Macmillan, 2000.
Plant, R., Modern Political Thought, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1991.
Potter, David et., al (ed.) Democratization, Milton Keynes: Open University Press, 1997.
123
Rawls, John., A Theory of Justice, London: Oxford University Press, 1972.
Rawls, John., Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, (ed.) Erin Kelly, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard
University Press, 2001.
Ray, B.N., John Rawls and the Agenda of Social Justice, New Delhi: Anamika Publishers
& Distributors, 2000.
Ricci, D.M., The Tragedy of Political Science, New Haven: Yale University Press, 1984.
Robert Goddin and Phillip Pettit., A Companion to Comparative Political Philosophy, London:
Blackwell, 1933.
Rubenstein, R., Alchemists of Revolution Terrorism in the Modern World, London: I.B.
Tauris and Co., 1987.
Rush, M., Politics and Society: An Introduction to Political Sociology, Hemel Hempstead:
Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1992.
Russell, M., Reforming the House of Lords: Lessons from Overseas, Oxford and New York:
Oxford University Press, 2000.
Sandel, Michael., Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982.
Schwarzmantel, J., Socialism and the Idea of the Nation, London: Harvester Wheatsheaf,
1991.
See Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously, London, Duekworth, 1978, pp. 169-173 and
John Mackie, “Can there be a right-based moral theory” in Jeremy Waldron, ed. Theories of
Rights, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1984, pp. 168-181.
Seliger, M., Politics and Ideology, London: Allen & Unwin, 1976.
Smith, A. D., The Ethnic Origins of Nations, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1986.
T. Jones., Modern Political Thinkers and Ideas - A Historical Introduction, London: Routledge,
2002.
Tarrow, S., Power in Movement: Social Movements and Contentious Politics, Cambridge
and New York: Cambridge University Press, 1998.
Taylor, Charles, ‘Atomism’, in his Philosophy and the Human Sciences, Vol.II, Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1985, pp. 187-210
Tinder, Glenn, Obligation Thinking, Boston: Little, Brown and Company, 1986.
Weisberg, H., (ed.) Political Science: The Science of Politics, New York: Agathon, 1986.
Wildavshy, A., Art and Craft of Policy Analysis, Macmillan: London, 1980.
Political Theory
POLITICAL THEORY 1
Expert Committee
Prof. Rajeev Bhargava Prof. A. S. Narang Prof. T. R. Sharma
Head Faculty of Political Science Honorary Co-ordinator
Dept. of Political Science School of Social Sciences Centre for Defence and
Delhi University, Delhi IGNOU, New Delhi National Security Studies
Prof. D. Gopal Prof. Pandav Nayak Punjab University, Chandigarh
Faculty of Political Science Faculty of Political Science Dr S.V. Reddy
School of Social Sciences School of Social Sciences Reader in Political Science
Indira Gandhi National Open IGNOU, New Delhi Faculty of Political Science
University, New Delhi Prof. Thomas Pantham School of Social Sciences
Prof. Gurpreet Mahajan Former Head IGNOU, New Delhi
Centre for Political Studies Dept. of Political Science Dr. Anurag Joshi (Convenor)
Jawaharlal Nehru University M.S. University, Vadodara, Reader,
New Delhi Gujarat Faculty of Political Science
Prof. Bhanu Pratap Mehta Prof. Valerian Rodrigues School of Social Sciences
Centre for Law & Centre for Political Studies IGNOU, New Delhi
Governance, JNU Jawaharlal Nehru University
New Delhi New Delhi
MPS Programme Coordinator (s): Prof. Darvesh Gopal and Dr. Anurag Joshi
Course Editor
Prof. T. R. Sharma
Honorary Co-ordinator
Centre for Defence &
National Security Studies
Punjab University, Chandigarh
August, 2003
© Indira Gandhi National Open University, 2003
ISBN-81-266-1043-3
All rights reserved. No part of this work may be reproduced in any form, by mimeograph or
any other means, without permission in writing from the Indira Gandhi National Open
University.
Further information on the Indira Gandhi National Open University courses may be ob-
tained from the university’s office at Maidan Garhi, New Delhi-110 068.
Printed and published on behalf of the Indira Gandhi National Open University, New Delhi, by
Professor Kapil Kumar, Director, School of Social Sciences.
Laser typeset by : HD Computer Craft, EA1/75, Main Market Inderpuri, New Delhi-110012.
Ph: 31081117
Printed at :
Paper Used : Agrobased Environment Friendly
CONTENTS
Introduction
Unit 02 Democracy 23
Unit 03 Rights 32
Unit 04 Liberty 42
Unit 05 Equality 50
Unit 06 Justice 69
Unit 08 Citizenship 89
The second aspect of the study of state relates to issues about the relation between the state
and the individual. What are the areas of individual’s activities in which the state can interfere
and which are the areas in which the individual must be left alone? This brings in the question
of individual’s rights and liberties. What rights can the individual demand from the state and on
what basis are such demands justified? What rights must the state grant to the individual and
why? Closely related with the question of the individual’s rights is the question of individual’s
duties and obligations towards the state. What is the notion of duty? What is meant by political
obligation? What are the individual’s duties towards the state and why must the individual
perform these duties? Why must the individual obey the authority of the state? What are the
moral and the prudential bases of political obligation? Can the individual refuse to obey the state
and if so, under what circumstances and on what grounds?
Closely related with the question of rights and duties of the individual is the issue of citizenship.
What should be the criteria for the grant of citizenship by the state? In what respect does the
status of citizens of a state differ from the status of aliens? Can a state (or should a state) treat
all citizens alike or can it treat different categories of citizens – women, tribals, scheduled castes
and scheduled tribes – differently? There is also the question of a citizen’s right to rebel against
the state. Has the citizen any right to rebel against the state? Conversely, how far is the use
of violence by the state against its citizens justified? What violent and non-violent methods can
the state use to impose its will and assert its supremacy over them? What are the various ways
in which the citizens can protest against the wrong policies of the state? What is meant by civil
disobedience? How far it is effective as measure of protest by the citizen and subjects?
The third issue relates to the relationship between the state and civil society. This issue also has
many dimensions. What is society and how does it differ from the state? What is justice and
what are its various conceptions? What is individual justice and how does it differ from social
justice? How can a just society be brought about? To what extent liberty and equality are the
necessary ingredients of a just society? What is the most ideal mix of liberty and equality for
a just society? To what extent liberty and equality are complementary and to what extent are
they contradictory?
The fourth issue relates to the legitimacy of the state. What makes governance by the state
legitimate? In other words, how does power become authority? What are the various modes of
governance? What is democracy? Is the democratic mode of governance more legitimate than
the other forms of governance like monarchy, aristocracy and dictatorship? What leads to
legitimation crises of the state and what are the consequences of such crises? What is a
revolution? Why do revolutions occur? Do legitimation crises necessarily lead to a revolution?
To what extent civil disobedience and passive resistance are effective as measures of protest?
Is revolution more effective as compared to civil disobedience?
These and several other related questions are discussed in this book on Political Theory. It aims
at familiarising you with some of the most seminal ideas of political thinkers of the West on
these questions. There are two objectives of this book. The first objective is to help you in
clearly understanding the meaning of various concepts like state, sovereignty, justice, liberty,
equality, power, authority, rights and obligations, citizenship, democracy, civil disobedience and
revolution etc. Secondly, you should be able to comprehend the various dimensions of each of
these concepts. For example, in the discussion on justice you should be aware of the notion of
individual justice and social justice and the dichotomy, if any, between the two. Alongwith it,
there is a need for you to understand the procedural and the substantive notions of justice as
also the legal and moral conception of justice. Similarly, in liberty you should be clear about its
two aspects: negative liberty and positive liberty, while in equality you should be able to clarify
the notion of absolute (or arithmetic) equality and proportionate (or geometric) equality and
notions of political, social and economic equality. While discussing the concept of sovereignty,
you should be clear about its various types: legal, political, popular, defacto, de-jure, real and
titular sovereignty. You should also understand the monist theory of sovereignty (Austin) and the
pluralist theory of sovereignty (Laski and others). In the discussion on rights, you should understand
the different types of rights – political, economic, social and cultural rights as also different
theories of rights or the basis on which rights are justified: the historical theory, the legal theory,
the social welfare theory and, the will theory of rights etc. While discussing political obligation,
the distincion between the moral and the prudential basis of obligation must be clearly understood.
At the conceptual level, one should be able to distinguish between obligation and duty. In what
way they are the same and in what way different? How is the notion of duty related to the
ultimate ends or purposes that a society has chosen for itself? Since the question of a good
political social and political order is a value question, it necessarily implies that the conceptions
of duty will hing on how this good is conceived. To what extent, there is mutuality of right and
duties in the sense that rights have corresponding duties and to what extent, there could be rights
without corresponding duties and duties without corresponding rights?
In the discussion on democracy, it is necessary for you to understand the various models of
democracy – direct (or participatory), indirect (or representative). There is also the need to
understand the various empirical images of theory of democracy (Schumpeter and Sartori), the
pluralist theory of democracy (Robert Dahl) etc. Alongwith it, there is also the need to understand
the marxist notion of democracy and the Maoist conception of people’s democracy. In the
discussion on authority, you should understand the difference between the term power and
authority. Also, how they are different from influence, persuasion, etc. on the one hand, and
force, coercion etc. on the other. Various types of authority – traditional, legal – rational and
charismatic –as formulated by Max Weber also need to be understood. In the unit on revolution,
you should not only be able to discuss the typology of revolution, but also the etiology of
revolution. There is also the need to understand the difference between civil disobedience and
passive resistance and also how civil disobedience has been used as a weapon by Mahatma
Gandhi, Martin Luther King Jr. and others. This will also bring in the notion of satyagraha and
its relevance in the contemporary world. This book contains a gist of the ideas of major political
thinkers and political philosophers of ancient, medieval, modern and contemporary period on the
various political issues mentioned above.
The title of this course is ‘Political Theory’. Therefore, at the very outset you must understand
the meaning of the term ‘political theory’ and its various connotations. Let us examine what do
we mean by the term ‘theory’? Broadly speaking, theory is a generalisation about a particular
phenomenon based on observation and reflection. We must, however, remember that the nature
of generalisations in the physical or natural sciences (Mathematics, Physics etc.), is of a
different order (quality) than the nature of generalisations in the social and behavioural sciences
(Psychology, Economics, Sociology and Political Science etc.). Even within the social sciences,
the quality of generalisation differs from one subject to another and even in the same subject
(say Political Science) different areas of the discipline have different qualities of generalisation.
However, the nature of theory (generalisation) in natural and social sciences are fundamentally
different. The theories in natural sciences are more exact, more certain and more universal than
the theories in social sciences. The theories in the latter are not only approximate, probabilistic
but also time-space specific, In other words, we can say that political theory consists of
generalisations about the state, the civil society and the individual and their relations with one
another. Similarly, the theories of justice, liberty, equality, rights and duties, etc. are generalisations
on these themes.
While you go through the various parts of this course, you will notice that a theory has mainly
three kinds of ingredients. Firstly, there are broad reflections of the various political thinkers
about politics, reflections about the state and justice etc. Such reflections which are generally
of a philosophic nature constitute a definite tradition in Political thought right from the days of
ancient Greeks to the present. This strand of political theory constitutes what may be called
political philosophy or normative political theory. This component of political theory consists of
statements which are prescriptive in nature. They are valuational in so far as they reflect the
value preferences of various political thinkers about the political phenomenon. They are normative
in character because they seek to provide moral norms for the society. Their main thrust is not
on “is” (what exists) but on “ought” or “should” (what is desirable or what ought to be).
There is a second strand in political theory which includes accounts of major political institutions
as they have actually existed and functioned from time to time and the relations of individuals
and groups with these institutions. Such accounts are largely factual or empirical in nature. The
statements in this brand of political theory (which may be called empirical political theory) are
claimed to be value neutral. The third strand in political theory consists of statements about
political phenomenon which are causal in nature. They attempt to explain the political events
in terms of ‘if... then’ manner. For example, one many say that if there is injustice in society,
then revolution is most likely to occur or we may say that if there is large scale participation
of people in governance, then the regime is likely to have greater legitimacy.
Actually, if we were to try to place all the strands of political theory along a continuum, it would
extend from empirical end of the spectrum to the normative end like this:
CAUSAL
↓
Prescriptive Descriptive
Speculative Factual
Ought (Should) Is
Secondly, it is also possible that some works of a thinker may be more empirical than normative
while some other works of the same thinker may be more normative than empirical; and still
others may be in the nature of causal explanation of political reality. For example, Karl Marx’s
analysis of eighteenth century capitalism in Europe is more descriptive, empirical and factual in
nature; while his vision of a socialist and communist society is more normative, speculative and
prescriptive. Thus, one part of his writings may be categorised as empirical political theory while
the other may be treated as normative political theory. Not only this, while explaining the
mechanism of exploitation of the working class by the capitalist class, Marx formulated his
theory of surplus value which is more causal in nature.
This is just one way of distinguishing normative political theory from empirical political theory.
There are several other ways in which the distinction has been made between the two. Leo
Strauss, for example, has used the term political philosophy for normative political theory and
the term political theory for the empirical accounts of political reality. He has argued that
political theory tells us only about the nature of political things, while political philosophy is
a quest of wisdom. In other words, he has used the term political theory for descriptive
accounts of political things and political philosophy for normative reflections about the political
phenomenon. At a more sophisticated level, it is sometimes argued that what we call empirical
political theory tells us only about part of political reality, while political philosophy (normative
political theory) tells us about the whole. Another dimension of this argument is that political
theory gives us an idea of the particular, while political philosophy gives us knowledge of the
universal. It is further argued that what empirical political reality gives us is only opinion about
the political phenomenon, while political philosophy or normative political theory enables us to
comprehend the essence of political reality.
Bhikhu Parekh has highlighted another dimension of political philosophy as distinct from political
theory. According to him, the distinction between the two centres around the way we study
political phenomenon. Political philosophy (Normative Political Theory) is the study of the
phenomenon which is “political” in a “philosophic way”. Philosophic way implies a self-consciously
critical inquiry and interpretation of the phenomenon, while the empirical way is only description
of the phenomenon. The above discussion would show that the differences between normative
political theory (political philosophy) and empirical political theory are not only epistemological,
but also ontological.
In Unit 1 of this book, the whole discussion is aimed at clarifying the concept of political theory
and its various shades ranging from scientific (empirical) to normative political theory. The units
that follow will help you to understand how the notions of democracy, justice, equality, liberty,
rights and duties, political obligation, power, authority, legitimacy have been discussed both from
normative and scientific angles, depending on the way different thinkers have treated these
issues. This book will help you in identifying the thinkers whose account of these concepts is
largely philosophical and the ones whose analysis is largely scientific (empirical).
The second issue raised in Unit I is why do we study political theory? Here, we must remember
that, it is an attempt to find out solutions to these problems. It helps us to comprehend in a
historical perspective the values which human societies have cherished and the different ways
in which state and society have responded to these demands. The ultimate objective of all
knowledge is human good and political theory as a branch of knowledge tries to familiarise us
with the diverse ways in which human good has been and ought to be achieved. In other words,
while the first part of Unit I seeks to clarify political theory, its different strands and its scope
etc the second highlights its importance.
The next six units (Unit 2-7) describe the basic concepts of political theory and their relevance
in the globalised world viz; democracy, rights, liberty, equality, justice and idea of duty have been
discussed.
The following seven units (Unit 8-14) are focussed on the basic concepts of contemporary
politiccal theory, viz; citizenship, sovereignty, state and civil society, power and authority, legitimation
and obligation, civil disobedience and satyagrah and political violence.
At the end, the list of books and articles on many of the themes dealt in this course are
appended so that users of the print material could supplement their study by reading as many
of the works cited to gain further insights on the various studies and understanding of political
theory.