Nehamas On Beauty and Love: Berys Gaut
Nehamas On Beauty and Love: Berys Gaut
Berys Gaut
Alexander Nehamas’s Only a Promise of Happiness is a beautiful book about beauty, a passion-
ate book about passion.1 Firmly setting its face against the Kantian conception of beauty as
the object of disinterested pleasure, it skilfully defends a Platonic view of beauty as the
object of erō s, of love, where love is the desire to possess some object, rather than merely
to contemplate it. From this central core it spins out an elegant web of connecting claims
that include: a critique of Danto’s disavowal of the centrality of beauty to art in general and
modern art in particular; the futility and indeed disastrousness of any conception of beauty
that aims at universal assent; the sensitivity of interpretation to attributions of beauty and
value to a work; the denial of the existence of aesthetic principles; a defence of the view
that beauty and virtue can conflict; and many other claims. To address them all would be
impossible in the space available, so I will focus here on the central view, the conceptual
connection of beauty with love, and will examine what sort of progeny that coupling
produces.
1 Alexander Nehamas, Only a Promise of Happiness: The Place of Beauty in a World of Art (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 2007). Page numbers in the text refer to this book.
British Journal of Aesthetics Vol. 50 | Number 2 | April 2010 | pp. 199–204 DOI:10.1093/aesthj/ayq003
© British Society of Aesthetics 2010. Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the British Society of Aesthetics.
All rights reserved. For Permissions, please email: [email protected]
200 | berys gaut
A problem arises because the scope of this kind of love is limited to beings that possess
ends: persons, animals, and (if we agree that they can have goals) plants. If we think of
artworks as manifesting authors, we could perhaps make sense of taking an artwork’s ends
as one’s own, for one would be embracing the goals of its authors as manifested in the
work. But, however generous we are in its construal, this conception of love cannot take as
if beauty is the object of love (pp. 58–59). His reply is that it is impossible to love someone
we find, that is, experience, as ugly. Lovers always experience each other as beautiful, even
when they know that they are not. We always find something attractive about our friends,
be it their eyes, smiles, gestures. Consider David Lynch’s film, The Elephant Man, which is
about John Merrick, a Victorian who suffered a startlingly disfiguring disease; in the course
2 Jean-Dominique Bauby, The Diving-Bell and the Butterfly, trans Jeremy Leggatt (London: Fourth Estate, 1997).
202 | berys gaut
can’t be aware of it unless we perceive or experience directly (in a sense broad enough to
include reading) the object whose feature it is’ (p. 94). So, though beauty is always a prop-
erty of appearance, appearance is not only a matter of perceptual appearance, but also the
object of direct experience. This denial of a necessary link between beauty and perception
seems to me exactly correct and to be an important point in aesthetics, even though a sur-
3 For a defence of the inner beauty view, see my Art, Emotion and Ethics (Oxford: OUP, 2007), chap. 6.
Nehamas on Beauty and Love | 203
of her. But in terms of personal love, that is not true: I may appreciate her beauty, but I may
not take her ends as my own. And, though it follows on the notion of hedonic love (taking
pleasure in something) that I love her, that notion, as we have seen, is too general to con-
stitute the correlative attitude to beauty.
4 Mary Mothersill, Beauty Restored (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1984), pp. 342–343. Her view concerns aesthetic
features in general: I focus on beauty as an example.
204 | berys gaut
whose slightest alteration might radically shift its aesthetic features (fractionally altering the
eyes of Manet’s Olympia might be one such case). But the indistinguishability condition re-
quires that altering any feature that allows us to distinguish one canvas from another must
shift the aesthetic properties of all the canvas’s features. And that just looks false.
More importantly for our purposes, suppose that the indistinguishability condition were
Conclusion
I have argued, then, that neither personal love nor hedonic love serves as the attitude
whose formal object is beauty. Beauty remains a conceptual enigma. But I have probed only
a single, albeit important, point defended in Nehamas’s almost indecently rich book.There
is much of interest and importance on which I have perforce been silent. Nehamas stresses
the inexhaustibility of beauty—the incessant desire to know more about the beautiful
object. I remarked at the start that Only a Promise of Happiness is a beautiful book about
beauty. Given the richness of its themes and examples, it may well be, appropriately
enough, an inexhaustible one too.
Berys Gaut
University of St Andrews
[email protected]