Three Main Areas of Moral Philosophy
Three Main Areas of Moral Philosophy
1. Value Theory
2. Metaethics
3. Normative Ethics
Although S.L. doesn’t mention this the other main area of moral philosophy is called “applied
Political Philosophy is another major area of moral philosophy, although this is sometimes
In this course we will spend our time focusing normative ethics, applied ethics, and
metaethics, and although we will not specifically cover political philosophy some of the issue
we discuss will be related to central issues in political philosophy. Normative ethics, applied
ethics, and metaethics are most commonly considered the three main areas of moral
philosophy.
Normative Ethics:
A normative ethical theory tells us what actions are right and what actions are
wrong
The most famous normative ethical principle that we are all familiar with is the
Applied Ethics
rights, etc. are examples of applied issues that philosophers have spent time on recent
philosophical history.
Metaethics
Conventional morality as the name suggests are the morals arose out of conventions through
ages or even time immemorial. We might or might not know reason for them, but still they
occupy in our moral code of conduct. A very general example is standing up of students
when teacher enter a class. It is less out of respect and more out of these conventional codes.
Often we try to speak less in front of our elders, or speak in low tone and soft too, these are
the conventions that nobody told us but we learned them through observations, by watching
Reflective morality is a concept that binds the morality to notion of generation and changes in
the society. Such codes of morality are simply our reflection of any individual or society as a
whole. With each generation and sometimes even in a single generation there is a specific
change in these codes. They might even be completely flipped to be suited by the society. Or
even at same time among different societies. For example, killing animals is immoral in some
Conventional morality is inheritance by nature. We inherit from from our family, society and
so on. In the previous answer, Prashant provided a good example of respecting elders and not
think, so it is a morality that is derived out of thinking. That means applying reason on
morality, more so for the inherited morality. For example, a father who is a drunkard,
irresponsible and lazy, distorts the peace of a family. Do you still apply conventional morality
which says pay respect and keep your voice low when speaking to your elders? This is where
Kohlberg's theory of moral development (Stage 6), talks about an individual maturing into
consistency. I think this is moral decision making based on internalized processing, including
thinking.
In summary, conventional morality was created and existed for a good purpose, that is to
uphold the units family and society. Therefore, it still should be protected for the original
cause that was intended. Whenever, deviation creeps in, reflective adjustment and judgment
Importance of Freewill
least three kinds of “responsibility” may seem to be threatened by the possibility that all of
our actions and attitudes are caused by factors outside us, over which we have no control:
1 Personal responsibility is threatened by the possibility that all our actions and attitudes are
caused by factors outside us, if this would mean that our actions would not be “ours” in the
sense required for them to have significance for us. We might seem to be mere puppets, or
2 Moral responsibility is threatened by the possibility that our actions and attitudes are caused
by factors outside of us, if this would mean that we could not properly be praised or blamed
for these actions or attitudes, because they would not be “up to us” in the required sense.
Substantive responsibility is threatened by the possibility that all our actions are caused by
factors outside of us over which we have no control, if this would mean that we would lack
the kind of control over these actions that is required if they are to affect our moral
obligations to others, and others’ obligations to us. Our promises might not be binding
because they were not entered into freely. Our decisions to forego certain benefits, or to take
certain risks, may not reduce the obligations of others to help us because these decisions were
not made voluntarily.3 Each of the last two threats might rightly be called a threat to moral
responsibility, but they seem to me to be distinct. To separate them, I reserve the term moral
responsibility for the former – the one concerned with blame. I refer to the latter as a threat to
substantive responsibility because it has to do with the content of our obligations. A number
of different responses to these threats are mentioned in Justice for Hedgehogs. One response
is that we cannot help seeing ourselves as actually making choices, and cannot help assigning
significance to them, even moral significance.4 The claim is that it is not possible that
theoretical beliefs about the causes of our actions could undermine this significance.5 A
second response is that the best explanation of cases in which it is generally recognized that
agents are not responsible for their behavior – such as actions done in ignorance or under
hypnosis, and actions by young children – is that this is simply not the case.6 These agents
are causally responsible for their actions, but their actions might be morally excusable or
compelling. As to the first, even if it is true that when we are engaging in the process of
deliberating and deciding we cannot help seeing this process as something that makes a
difference and has moral and ethical significance, it is not clear what follows from this. It
might simply be the case that this is an unshakable illusion. As for the second response, it
seems to me quite clear that outside causes are not the best explanation for most excusing or
justifying conditions. But the idea that such causes undermine moral responsibility may have
other sources. Whatever these sources may be, however, if blame requires a kind of freedom
distinct from the kind of freedom required by other forms of evaluation – such as an
assessment of artistic talent – there must be something about the nature of blame itself that
explains this fact. Thus, a satisfactory resolution of this issue must begin with an adequate
characterization of blame, from which we can see why blame requires a certain form of
freedom, if indeed it does. More generally, a satisfactory resolution of any of the three
problems I have listed must start from an account of the values involved – an account of the
kind of significance that our own actions and attitudes have for us, an account of the nature of
moral blame, or an account of how substantive obligations are created and transferred by
voluntary actions – on the basis of which it can be seen whether or not these forms of
significance require some form of freedom. What incompatibilists seek to show is that it
follows from the best understanding of these values that the forms of significance in question
require a kind of freedom that we do not have if our actions are caused by factors outside us,
over which we have no control. What compatibilists seek to show is that according to the best
understanding of these values, this is not the case.8 This latter interpretive task is undertaken
in Justice for Hedgehogs. 9 Of the three kinds of responsibility I have mentioned – personal
responsibility, moral responsibility, and substantive responsibility – the first appears to be the
most fundamental. Whatever the exact nature of blame, it would seem to depend in large part
on the attitudes expressed in an action. Further, there would seem to be a close relation
between the conditions that make an attitude “belong to an agent” in the way required to
make it significant for him or her and the conditions required to make an attitude “belong to
an agent” in the way required to make it significant for others. Similarly, it would seem that
the reasons why an agent’s obligations are sensitive to his or her choices would depend on the
reasons for those choices being significant for the agent. So, I will focus initially on the first
of my three cases, the kind of significance I call personal. This is in line with the strategy of
Justice for Hedgehogs, which is to start with ethics – what it is for an individual to live a
good life – rather than with morality – what we owe to others.10 According to Justice for
Hedgehogs, there are two “ethical principles about how to live not, just in themselves, moral
principles about how to treat other people”11: I shall . . . call the first the principle of self-
respect. Each person must take his own life seriously: he must accept that it is a matter of
importance that his life be a successful performance rather than a wasted opportunity. I shall
call the second the principle of authenticity. Each person has a special, personal responsibility
for identifying what counts as success in his own life; he has a personal responsibility to
create that life through a coherent narrative that he himself has chosen and endorses.
Together the two principles offer a conception of human dignity: dignity requires self-respect
and authenticity.12 Authenticity, Dworkin continues, “is an ethical concept: it makes two
demands. First, it assigns each person a non-delegable responsibility for identifying and then
pursuing his own conception of what it is to live well, to give structure to his life through
values he endorses that sustain a coherent narrative of living.”13 However, it also demands
another kind of responsibility: The second principle of dignity demands . . . that I accept
judgmental and liability responsibility in appropriate circumstances. People who blame their
parents or other people or society at large for their own mistakes, or who cite some form of
genetic determinism to absolve themselves of any responsibility for how they have acted,
lack dignity because dignity requires owing up to what one has done. “The buck stops here”
is an important piece of ethical wisdom. The second principle also requires taking
responsibility in a different, more material, way: dignity requires that I not expect others to
subsidize my decisions by bearing their financial or other costs. I do not take responsibility
for my own life if I demand that others absorb the cost of my choices: living well means
making choices, and that means choosing a life with an eye to the consequences of that life
that I should bear myself.14 Responsibility, in this latter sense requires two capacities: First,
to be responsible people must have some minimal ability to form true beliefs about the world,
about the mental states of other people, and about the likely consequences of what they do.
Someone who is unable to grasp the fact that guns can harm people is not responsible when
he shoots someone. Second, people must have, to a normal level, the ability to make
decisions that fit what we might call the agent’s normative personality: his desires,
are purposive, and someone who cannot match his final decisions to any of his desires, plans,
these theses are put forward as ethical duties – principles we must follow – and as claims
about what is required in order to be an agent who is responsible for his or her attitudes and
actions. For present purposes, however, I want to consider them in a slightly different light,
as an account of the kind of life that a person has reason to want to live, in which his or her
actions and attitudes will have the distinctive personal significance of being his or hers. We
can then take this account as a basis for considering what kind of freedom is required in order
for an agent to have such a life. Put in this way, the thesis of Justice for Hedgehogs is this:
what a person has reason to want is an authentic life – one that accords with and reflects the
decisions he or she makes about how to live, and in which these decisions themselves reflect
his or her desires, plans, and convictions and are based on true beliefs about the world. The
crucial thing about this conception is that – apart from the part about true belief –
requirements of an authentic life have to do only with the relations among an agent’s mental
states – his or her plans, desires, convictions, decisions, beliefs, intentions, and so on – and
the actions that flow from them. Dworkin is not concerned about the causal antecedents to
one’s attitudes, beliefs, etc.16 His thesis is that as long as an agent’s life has the required
shape, the mental events that are parts of it belong to him or her in the full sense required for
does not require that they not be caused by factors outside us. But why not? Two reasons
seem to be offered, so closely related that they are really just positive and negative sides of
the same point. Put positively, the point is that what gives decisions their significance for us –
what makes them ours – is that they are reflective of our felt desires, plans, convictions, and
so on – that is, of our actual psychological states.17 Put negatively, it is that decisions that
were independent of our actual, present psychology would be based on nothing that would
give them meaning for us, or make them ours in any meaningful sense.18 A “self” detached
from our actual, empirical psychology, would be empty. I find these points entirely
convincing.19 However, we should consider why they might be resisted. It can be agreed, I
think, that whether our actions are caused by outside factors or not, any decision that is
meaningful for an agent will have to be based on current values, plans, and desires of the
agent that, at the moment of this decision, are not being questioned but are held fixed
(although they might be called into question and re-evaluated at another time). Decision and
possibility that these processes of deciding and re-evaluating are themselves determined by
factors outside of us, over which we have no control. Why should this be a threat to the
meaningfulness, for us, of our attitudes? It might be because these outside factors could force
us – so to speak – to reach certain conclusions, overriding our own judgment. But, as Hume
pointed out long ago, this is a mistake. The factors in question determine what our judgment
is; they do not override it.20 A second way in which outside causes might threaten the
meaningfulness of our decision-making process would be if the effectiveness of these causes
indicates that our normative judgments are influenced or even controlled by factors that are
normatively irrelevant. Yet, this does not follow either. The fact – if it is a fact – that our
mathematical judgments are determined by factors outside of us does not mean that these
judgments are affected by factors that are irrelevant to the mathematical correctness of the
conclusions we reach, and there is no reason to think that this is necessarily so in other cases.
Even if the account of ethical responsibility I have sketched is adequate, however, the
question remains whether the conditions that Justice for Hedgehogs holds to be sufficient for
ethical responsibility (what I call personal responsibility) are also all that is required in order
for it to be appropriate to blame agents for their actions and choices, and all that is required to
make those choices significant in altering an agent’s obligations to others. In order to answer
this question, as I said, we need to have some account of what blame involves, and how
obligations are determined. Justice for Hedgehogs does not go into much detail about these
issues. I want to elaborate, however, on one claim that it does make and to consider some
implications of this elaboration that may depart somewhat from the book. The claim I have in
mind is in a passage I quoted earlier: The second principle of dignity demands . . . that I
blame their parents or other people or society at large for their own mistakes, or who cite
some form of genetic determinism to absolve themselves of any responsibility for how they
have acted, lack dignity because dignity requires owing up to what one has done. “The buck
stops here” is an important piece of ethical wisdom. The second principle also requires taking
responsibility in a different, more material, way: dignity requires that I not expect others to
subsidize my decisions by bearing their financial or other costs. I do not take responsibility
for my own life if I demand that others absorb the cost of my choices: living well means
making choices, and that means choosing a life with an eye to the consequences of that life
that I should bear myself.21 The underlying point here seems to me correct and important.
Insofar as an individual regards her actions under certain circumstances as belonging to her in
the sense required to be meaningful for her life, she cannot deny that these actions are
significant for other people’s reactions to her, and for their relations with her; nor can she
deny that they have implications for her obligations to them – at least not on the ground that
they are not hers in the required sense. But from the fact that she cannot object to blame, or to
obligations that are held to follow from her actions, on this particular ground, nothing follows
about whether she has to accept responsibility for any particular action in either the moral or
substantive sense. The fact that any attitude that occurs in the mental life of a person who has
the two capacities – the “ability to form true beliefs about the world” and the “ability to make
decisions that fit what we might call the agent’s normative personality”22 – belongs to her
still leaves open questions of blame and the shifting of responsibilities. In one sense, this is
obvious. Good actions as well as bad actions are attributable to an agent; but the fact that an
action belongs to an agent leaves open the question whether blame or some other attitude is
appropriate.23 The point I have in mind goes beyond this. According to Justice for
Hedgehogs, a person is in control of his or her actions in the way required for moral
responsibility if he or she possesses the two capacities I have described.24 Dworkin remarks
that this idea of control is very different from the one underlying the incompatibilist’s
understanding, where the question is whether an external force was strong enough to
overcome the will’s “normal causal role.”25 But this may not make clear how different the
two conceptions are, insofar as it leaves the impression that they are simply two different
conceptions of the kind of control an agent must have over his or her attitudes in order for
them to belong to him or her in the relevant sense. The more radical position I have in mind
(which may or may not be Dworkin’s) is that the two capacities – although they are
conditions required in order for an agent to be the kind of being toward whom we can stand
in the relations that make blame and obligation make sense – are not conditions whose
fulfillment in every given case makes an attitude or action attributable to an agent. Under this
position, having the capacities that Dworkin mentions to a normal level26 does not mean that
they always work. Further, in order for attitudes to belong to an agent in the sense required
for blame, they need not be ones that the agent could control through the use of these general
capacities. A person can be blamed for attitudes and actions that were, or would have been,
quite resistant to her better judgment. The fact that she had these contrary judgments would
complicate the picture of what she is like, and could therefore modify the kind of blame that
is appropriate, but it does not change the fact that the recalcitrant attitudes belong to the agent
– they are part of what he or she is like. If an agent has the two capacities that Dworkin
describes, then every attitude that occurs in his or her mental life belongs to him or her in the
relevant sense, whether or not the attitude could be controlled by the exercise of those
capacities.27 Conditions that are often said to modify responsibility, such as ignorance of
fact, duress, and even, I would say, many forms of mental illness, do not have this effect
because they make the action one that does not belong to the person. Instead, what they do is
to affect what an action or attitude that belongs to the person indicates about him or her. By
this, I mean not what it indicates about him or her as a disembodied self, but what it indicates
about that person’s actual overall empirical psychology – about what he or she will feel and
agent in the full sense; under some description, it is his or her intentional action, performed
for some reason. The question is, what does the action tell us about the agent more generally?
In some cases, such as hypnosis or brain stimulation, perhaps, the answer is that the action
tells us nothing: any agent would have done the same in response to this treatment. But in
most cases, the answer will be a matter of degree, or rather of difference. Willingness to
perform an action that causes injury when one is under the influence of a false belief about its
consequences is something different from willingness to do so with full knowledge of its
effects. Willingness to cause harm under duress indicates something different from
willingness to do so for fun or for profit. I am not certain that this is the position that Dworkin
means to hold. But if it is, this makes clear why in his view it is the relations among an
agent’s attitudes, rather than their causal antecedents more generally, that is crucial for
responsibility.