0% found this document useful (0 votes)
27 views

Real Analysis - Sets and Relations

This document defines and explains key concepts related to sets, relations, and orderings. It introduces binary relations, Cartesian products, ordered pairs, equivalence relations, partitions, preorders, partial orders, and bounded sets. Examples are provided to illustrate these concepts. Key definitions include binary relations, equivalence relations, preorders, partial orders, partitions, equivalence classes, bounds, and greatest and least elements.

Uploaded by

Jorge Soto
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
27 views

Real Analysis - Sets and Relations

This document defines and explains key concepts related to sets, relations, and orderings. It introduces binary relations, Cartesian products, ordered pairs, equivalence relations, partitions, preorders, partial orders, and bounded sets. Examples are provided to illustrate these concepts. Key definitions include binary relations, equivalence relations, preorders, partial orders, partitions, equivalence classes, bounds, and greatest and least elements.

Uploaded by

Jorge Soto
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 8

CHAPTER 1: Sets and Relations

1 Binary Relations

In this chapter we are going to define relation formally. A relation in everyday life shows an association
of objects of a set with objects of other sets (or the same set) such as John owns a BMW, Jim has a green
Audi, etc. The essence of relation is these associations. A collection of these individual associations is a
relation, such as the ownership relation between people and automobiles. To represent these individual
associations, a set of "related" objects, such as John and a BMW, can be used. However, simple sets
such as {John, BMW} are not sufficient here. The order of the objects must also be taken into account,
because John owns a BMW but the BMW does not own John, and simple sets do not deal with orders.
Thus sets with an order on its members are needed to describe a relation. Here the concept of ordered
pair is going to be defined first. A relation is then defined as a set of ordered pairs.

Definition 1 (Ordered pair) An ordered pair is a list of a pair of objects with an order associated with
them. If objects are represented by x and y, then we write an ordered pair as (x, y) or (y, x). In general
(x, y) is different from (y, x).

Two ordered pairs (x, y) and (x0 , y0 ) are equal if and only if x = x0 and y = y0 . For example, if the ordered
pair (x, y) is equal to (1, 2), then x = 1, and y = 2. The ordered pair (1, 2) is not equal to the ordered pair
(2, 1).

Definition 2 (Cartesian product) A Cartesian product of two non-empty sets X and Y , denoted as X ×
Y , is defined as the set of all ordered pairs (x, y) where x is an element of X and y is an element of Y .
That is,
X ×Y := {(x, y)| x ∈ X and y ∈ Y }.

Definition 3 (Binary relation) Let X and Y be two non-empty sets. A subset R of X × Y is called a
binary relation from X to Y . In other words, a binary relation from a set X to a set Y is a set of ordered
pairs (x, y) where x is an element of X and y is an element of Y .

Example 1 If X = {1, 2, 3} and Y = {4, 5}, then {(1, 4), (2, 5), (3, 5)}, for example, is a binary relation
from X to Y . However, {(1, 1)} is not a binary relation from X to Y because 1 is not in Y . 

If X = Y , i.e., if R is a relation from X to X, we simply say that it is a relation on X. In other words, R is


a relation on X if and only if R ⊆ X 2 . If (x, y) ∈ R, then we think of R as associating the object x with the
object y, and if {(x, y), (y, x)} ∩ R = ∅, then we understand that there is no connection between x and y
as envisaged by R. Conventionally, we write xRy instead of (x, y) ∈ R.

1
2 Preorders and Equivalence Relations

Definition 4 (Preorder) A binary relation % on a non-empty set X is called a preorder if it has the
following properties:

(i) Reflexivity: x % x for all x ∈ X,

(iii) Transitivity: x % y and y % z =⇒ x % z for all x, y, z ∈ X.

Definition 5 (Equivalence relation) A binary relation ∼ on a non-empty set X is called an equivalence


relation if it has the following properties:

(i) Reflexivity: x ∼ x for all x ∈ X,

(ii) Symmetry: x ∼ y =⇒ y ∼ x for all x, y ∈ X,

(iii) Transitivity: x ∼ y and y ∼ z =⇒ x ∼ z for all x, y, z ∈ X.

For any x ∈ X, the equivalence class of x is defined as the set

[x] := {y ∈ X| y ∼ x}.

Definition 6 (Partition) A partition of a non-empty set X is a class {Xi } of non-empty subsets of X such
that (i) i Xi = X, and (ii) Xi ∩ X j = ∅ for any two Xi and X j in {Xi }. The Xi ’s are called the partition
S

sets.

If X = {1, 2, 3, 4, 5}, then {{1, 2, 3}, {4, 5}} and {{1, 2, 5}, {3, 4}} are two different partitions of X.
If X = R, then it can be partitioned into the infinitely many closed-open intervals of the form [n, n + 1)
where n is an integer.
We now show that a given equivalence relation ∼ on X determines a natural partition of X. Let the
relation ∼ on X satisfies reflexivity, symmetry and transitivity. We show that all distinct equivalence
classes form a partition of X. By reflexivity, x ∈ [x] for each element x ∈ X, so each equivalence set is
non-empty and their union is X. It remains to show that any two equivalence sets [x1 ] and [x2 ] are either
disjoint or identical. We prove by showing that if [x1 ] and [x2 ] are not disjoint then they must be identical.
Suppose that z ∈ [x1 ] ∩ [x2 ]. Then z ∼ x1 and z ∼ x2 , and by symmetry, x1 ∼ z. Let y ∈ [x1 ] which implies
that y ∼ x1 . Since y ∼ x1 and x1 ∼ z, transitivity implies that y ∼ z. Then, again by transitivity, y ∼ z
and z ∼ x2 implies that y ∼ x2 , so that y ∈ [x2 ]. Hence, [x1 ] ⊆ [x2 ]. By a similar logic, one can show that
[x2 ] ⊆ [x1 ]. From this we can conclude that [x1 ] = [x2 ].
The converse statement is somewhat trivial. Consider a partitions {Xi } of a set X, and let R be a
relation on X defined by, for any two elements x and y of X,

xRy if and only if x and y belong to the same element Xi of {Xi }.

We think of the elements of X being distributed into a number of sets, each of which is a member of a
given partition. Every element of X is exactly in one set. Notice that every element x of X is in the same

2
set as itself. For any x and y of X, if x and y are in the same set, so are y and x. Finally, For any x, y and z
of X, if x and y are in the same set, and y and z are also, so are x and z. Thus, the relation R is reflexive,
symmetric and transitive, and hence is an equivalence relation. Thus, there is no real distinction between
partitions and equivalence relations.

Example 2 (The Indifference Set) Let x = (x1 , x2 ) be the quantities of two goods 1 (apple) and 2 (or-
ange), and x is an element of X ⊆ R2+ , which is called the consumption set. Define the preference
relations % on X of a consumer as follows. We read x % y as “x is at least as good as y”. From %, we can
derive two other important relations on X:

(a) The strict preference relation, , defined by x  y ⇐⇒ x % y but y  x and read “x is (strictly)
preferred to y”.

(d) The indifference relation, ∼, defined by x ∼ y ⇐⇒ x % y and y % x and read “x is indifferent to y”.

The relation % is rational if (i) it is complete, i.e., for all x, y ∈ X, we have that x % y or y % x (or both),
and (ii) it is transitive, i.e., for all x, y, z ∈ X, if x % y and y % z, then x % z. It is easy to prove the
following property.

Lemma 1 If % is rational, then the indifference relation ∼ is an equivalence relation, but the strict
preference relation  is not.

For a consumption bundle x ∈ X, the set [x] = {y ∈ X|y ∼ x} is called the indifference set of x. Notice
that ∼ induces a partition of X and vice versa. 

3 Partial Orders

Definition 7 (Partial order) A binary relation % on a non-empty set X is called a partial order if it has
the following properties:

(i) Reflexivity: x % x for all x ∈ X,

(ii) Antisymmetry: x0 % x00 and x00 % x0 imply x0 = x00 for all x0 , x00 ∈ X,

(iii) Transitivity: x0 % x00 and x00 % x000 imply x0 % x000 for all x0 , x00 and x000 ∈ X.

Definition 8 (Partially ordered set) A partially ordered set (written “poset”) is a set X on which there
is a binary relation % that is reflexive, antisymmetric and transitive.

Definition 9 Two elements x0 and x00 of a partially ordered set are ordered if either x0 % x00 or x00 % x0 ;
otherwise x0 and x00 are unordered.

Definition 10 (Chain) A partially ordered set is a chain if it does not contain an unordered pair of
elements.

Example 3 The following are partially ordered sets.

3
(a) The real line R with usual ordering relation ≥ on the real numbers is a poset.
(b) Given any two vectors x0 , x00 in the m-dimensional Eucledian space Rm = {x = (x1 , . . . , xm ) | xi ∈ R
for all i = 1, . . . , m}, x0 ≥ x00 if xi0 ≥ xi00 for all i = 1, . . . , m. Rm with the vector ordering relation ≥
is a poset.
(c) The power set, P(X), of a set X is the set of all subsets of X. The power set P(X) with the set
inclusion ordering relation ⊇ is a poset. If X 0 and X 00 are distinct subsets of X with X 0 ⊆ X 00 , then
X 0 ⊂ X 00 .
(d) The lexicographic ordering relation lex on Rm is such that x0 lex x00 in Rm if either x0 = x00 or
there is some i0 with 1 ≤ i0 ≤ m, xi0 = xi00 for each i with 1 ≤ i < i0 , and xi00 < xi000 . The set Rm with
the ordering relation lex is a poset, indeed, is a chain. 

Definition 11 (Bound of a set and bounded set) Suppose that X is a partially ordered set with respect
to %, and X 0 is a subset of X. If u ∈ X such that u % x for every x ∈ X 0 , then u is an upper bound of X 0 .
Similarly, if l ∈ X such that l - x for every x ∈ X 0 , then l is a lower bound of X 0 . If a subset X 0 of a poset
X has an upper (lower) bound, then X 0 is bounded above (below). In case X 0 has both an upper bound
and a lower bound, then X 0 is a bounded set.

First, observe that a subset X 0 of a poset X may be unbounded. Consider X = R, the set of real numbers,
and X 0 = Z = {. . . , −2, −1, 0, 1, 2, . . .}, the set of integers. Then Z is an unbounded set in R. On the
other hand, if X 0 = N = {1, 2, . . .}, the set of natural numbers, then X 0 is bounded below by 1. Next,
let X = R and X 0 = {5, 10, 15}. Then both 15 and 20 are upper bounds of X 0 . Now let X = R and
X 0 = [a, b). The real number b is an upper bound of X 0 which is not contained in X 0 . Two important
observations emerge. First, a subset X 0 of a poset X may or may not contain its upper (lower) bounds (if
they exist). This gives rise to the notion of a greatest element and a least element.

Definition 12 (Greatest and least elements) Suppose that X is a partially ordered set with respect to
%, and X 0 is a subset of X. If x0 ∈ X 0 such that x0 % x for every x ∈ X 0 , then x0 is a greatest element of X 0 .
Similarly, if z0 ∈ X 0 such that z0 - x for every x ∈ X 0 , then z0 is a least element of X 0 .

A greatest (least) element of X 0 is trivially an upper (lower) bound of X 0 . For example, if X = R and
X 0 = {5, 10, 15}, then 2 is not a least element of X 0 , whereas 5 is. Notice that a subset X 0 of a poset X
can have at most one greatest (least) element. Next, a subset X 0 of a poset X may have many different
upper and lower bounds. This gives rise to the notion of a supremum and an infimum.

Definition 13 (Supremum and infimum) Suppose that X is a partially ordered set with respect to %,
and X 0 is a subset of X. An element of X is a supremum or a least upper bound of X 0 (with respect to X),
denoted supX (X 0 ), if it is the case that (a) supX (X 0 ) % x for all x ∈ X 0 , and (b) for any u ∈ X such that
u % x for all x ∈ X 0 , it holds that supX (X 0 ) - u. Similarly, an element of X is an infimum or a greatest
lower bound of X 0 (with respect to X), denoted infX (X 0 ), if it is the case that (a) infX (X 0 ) - x for all
x ∈ X 0 , and (b) for any l ∈ X such that l - x for all x ∈ X 0 , it holds that infX (X 0 ) % u.

The above definition says that if the set of upper (lower) bounds of X 0 has a least (greatest) element, then
this least (greatest) element is the supremum (infimum) of X 0 . Two important points must be kept in mind.
First, a supremum or an infimum of a set may not exist. If it exists, then it must be unique. Second, one
must be clear about the underlying set in expressing sup(X 0 ) or inf(X 0 ). Consider the following example.

4
Example 4 Suppose X = R, Y = [0, 1) ∪ {2}, and X 0 = [0, 1). Then supX (X 0 ) = 1 6= 2 = supY (X 0 ). 

Notice also that, if a subset X 0 of a poset X contains supX (X 0 ), then the supremum is the greatest element.
Similar property holds for the infimum. Following is an important result concerning the set of real
numbers.

Lemma 2 (The supremum property) Every non-empty set of real numbers that is bounded above has
a supremum. This supremum is a real number.

Proof. Let X ⊆ R be a non-empty subset of real numbers, and let U := {u ∈ R | u ≥ x for all x ∈ X},
the set of upper bounds of X. By assumption, U is non-empty. By the axiom of completeness,1 there
exists a real number α such that

x ≤ α ≤ u, for all x ∈ X and u ∈ U.

Because x ≤ α for all x ∈ X, α is an upper bound of X. This implies that α ∈ U with the property that
α ≤ u for all u ∈ U, and hence, α is a supremum of X. 
The following definition introduces the notion of a maximal (minimal) element, which is, in general,
different from a greatest (least) element.

Definition 14 (Maximal and minimal element) If x0 is in X 0 and there does not exist any x00 ∈ X 0 with
x00  x0 (x0  x00 ), then x0 is a maximal (minimal) element of X 0 .

A greatest (least) element is a maximal (minimal) element. Thus, it is a stronger notion that maximal
(minimal) element. A poset can may have any number of maximal (minimal) element. For example,
In the fence a1 > b1 < a2 > b2 < a3 > b3 < . . ., all the ai ’s are maximal, and all the bi ’s are minimal.
Consider another example. Let X be the set with at least two elements, and S = {{x} | x ∈ X} be the
subset of P(X) consisting of singletons. Take the usual set inclusion ordering, i.e., for any two sets X
and Y in P(X), X - Y if and only if X ⊆ Y . This is the discrete poset – no two elements are comparable.
Thus, every element {x} ∈ S is maximal and minimal, and for any x0 and x00 , neither {x0 } ⊂ {x00 } nor
{x00 } ⊂ {x0 }. Hence, we can conclude that distinct maximal (minimal) elements are unordered.

Example 5 (Consumer theory) In economics, we relax the axiom of antisymmetry, using preorders
instead of partial orders. Let X ⊆ Rn+ . Preferences of a consumer are represented by a preorder % (as
in Example 2). The preference relations are never assumed to be antisymmetric. In this context, for any
B ⊂ X, we call x ∈ B a maximal element if x % y for all y ∈ B, and it is interpreted as the consumption
bundle that is not dominated in the sense that x ≺ y for any y ∈ B. The notion of greatest element for
a preference preorder would be that of most preferred choice. That is, some x ∈ B with y ∈ B implying
that x  y. An obvious application is to the definition of demand correspondence. An element p of Rn++
is called a price system which maps every consumption bundle x into its market value p · x ∈ R+ . An
income level m is an element of R+ . The budget correspondence B is a correspondence from Rn++ × R+
to X which is given by
B(p, m) = {x ∈ X | p · x ≤ m}.
1 This
axiom says that, if L and H are two non-empty subsets of real numbers with the property that for all l ∈ L and for all
h ∈ H we have l ≤ h, then there is a real number α such that l ≤ α ≤ h for all l ∈ L and for all h ∈ H.

5
The demand correspondence maps any price p and any level of income m into the set of maximal ele-
ments (with respect to %) of B(p, m), which is given by

D(p, m) = {x ∈ X | x is a maximal element of B(p, m)}.

It is called demand correspondence because the theory predicts that for given p and m, the rational choice
of a consumer x∗ will be some element of D(p, m). 

4 Functions

4.1 Definition and Properties

A function from a set X to a set Y is a rule that assigns to each element x of X a unique element y of Y .
We say that y is the image of x under f , and write y = f (x). Conversely, x is an element of the preimage
or inverse image of y, written x ∈ f −1 (y). Formally,

Definition 15 (Function) Let X and Y be two sets. A function f from X to Y , written f : X −→ Y , is a


relation from X to Y with the property that for each x ∈ X there exists a unique element y ∈ Y such that
(x, y) ∈ f .

The underlying set X is called the domain of f , and f (X) is its range. If A ⊆ X, then its image under f
is given by
f (A) := {y ∈ Y | there exists x ∈ A such that y = f (x)} = ∪x∈A { f (x)}.
Given a subset B of Y , its inverse image is given by

f −1 (B) := {x ∈ X | f (x) ∈ B}.

If f : X −→ Y and f (X) = Y , then f is surjective or onto. A function f is injective or one-to-one if for any
two distinct elements x1 , x2 ∈ X, we have f (x1 ) 6= f (x2 ). A function is bijective if it is both one-to-one
and onto, i.e., if each element y ∈ Y has a unique inverse image in X. Let f : X −→ Y and g : Y −→ Z.
Then their composition, g ◦ f is a function from X to Z and is defined by (g ◦ f )(x) = g( f (x)). We have
(h ◦ g) ◦ f = h ◦ (g ◦ f ) = h ◦ g ◦ f , i.e., the composition is associative.

Theorem 1 Let f : X −→ Y be a function and B = {Bi | i ∈ I} a family of subsets of Y . Then

(a) f −1 (∪i∈I Bi ) = ∪i∈I f −1 (Bi ),

(b) f −1 (∩i∈I Bi ) = ∩i∈I f −1 (Bi ).

Proof. The proof is left as an exercise. 

Definition 16 (Increasing function) A function f : X −→ Y is (strictly) increasing if x0 > x00 in X implies


that f (x0 ) (>) ≥ f (x00 ).

6
4.2 Representation of Binary Relations

Definition 17 A function f : X −→ R is a utility function, where X ⊆ Rm


+ , representing preference rela-
tion % if, for all x, y ∈ X, x % y ⇐⇒ f (x) ≥ f (y).

Proposition 1 A preference relation % can be represented by a utility function only if it is rational.

Proof. To prove this proposition, we must show that if there is a utility function that represents
the preference relation %, then % must be complete and transitive. First, because f (·) is a real valued
function defined on X, it must be that for any x, y ∈ X, either f (x) ≥ f (y) or f (y) ≥ f (x). Because f (·)
represents %, this implies either that x % y or that y % x. Hence, % must be complete. Next, Suppose
that x % y and y % z. Because f (·) represents %, it must be that f (x) ≥ f (y) and f (y) ≥ f (z). Therefore,
f (x) ≥ f (z), which implies that x % z, and hence % is transitive. 

4.3 Examples and Graphical Representation

Let f : X −→ Y be a function, and consider the subset of X ×Y

G f := {(x, y) ∈ X ×Y | y = f (x)}. (1)

The above set is called the graph of the function f . In what follows we consider real valued functions
f : X −→ R, where X ⊆ R2 , that assign to each x = (x1 , x2 ) ∈ X a number f (x1 , x2 ) in R.

Example 6 Following are the examples of real valued functions from R2 to R.

(i) f (x1 , x2 ) = α1 x1 + α2 x2 (Linear),

(ii) f (x1 , x2 ) = Ax1α1 x2α2 (Cobb-Douglas),

(iii) f (x1 , x2 ) = min{α1 x1 , α2 x2 } (Leontief),


i 1
−ρ − ρ
h
−ρ
(iv) f (x1 , x2 ) = A α1 x1 + α2 x2 (Constant elasticity of substitution). 

Given a real valued function f : X −→ R, consider the set I(x) := {y ∈ R2 | f (x) = f (y)}. Thus, if x ∼ y
then the function f (.) is constant on the set I(x). Let this value be α. The graph of I(x) defines an
indifference curve or a level curve at the level α. The graphical representation of functions from R2 to
R is often difficult since the graphs are three dimensional. We represent such functions by their level
curves. How such level curves are drawn is a topic of discussion of Chapter 3.

5 Correspondences

A correspondence ϕ from X to Y is a function that to each element x in X assigns a non-empty subset


ϕ(x) of Y . Hence, a correspondence from X to Y , denoted ϕ : X →→ Y , is a function from X to P(Y ).
Notice that a function associates with every element x ∈ X an element y ∈ Y . In saying this we are not

7
making the distinction between the element y in Y and the subset {y} of Y which consists of one point
only. Given a correspondence ϕ : X −→ P(Y ), consider the subset Gϕ of X ×Y defined by

Gϕ := {(x, y) ∈ X ×Y | y ∈ ϕ(x)}. (2)

The set Gϕ is called the graph of ϕ. Conversely, if G is a subset of X ×Y such that for every x ∈ X the
set of points y ∈ Y with (x, y) ∈ G is non-empty, then G is the graph of a correspondence, i.e.,

ϕ(x) := {y ∈ Y | (x, y) ∈ G}. (3)

We now introduce the notion of inverse image(s) of a correspondence. Let ϕ : X →→ Y be a correspon-


dence, where X ⊆ Rn and Y ⊆ Rm , and W be any subset of Y . Define the upper inverse of W under ϕ,
denoted ϕ+−1 (W ), by
ϕ+−1 (W ) := {x ∈ X | ϕ(x) ⊆ W },
and the lower inverse of W under ϕ, denoted ϕ −1 (W ), by

ϕ −1 (W ) := {x ∈ X | ϕ(x) ∩W 6= ∅}.

Example 7 (Best response correspondence) Consider the following two-player normal form game Γ =
hN, {Si }i∈N , {ui (·)}i∈N i, where N = {1, 2} is the set of players, S1 = {s1 , s2 , s3 } and S2 = {t1 , t2 , t3 , t4 }
are the strategy sets of players 1 and 2 respectively, and ui (s, t) is the payoff function of player i which is
given as follows. A strategy t ∗ of player 2 is a best response against a strategy s of player 1 if u2 (s, t ∗ ) ≥

Table 1: Payoff matrix

t1 t2 t3 t4
s1 1, 1 1, 1 0, 0 0, 0
s2 0, 0 2, 2 2, 2 0, 0
s3 1, 0 1, 0 0, 0 3, 3

u2 (s, t) for all t ∈ S2 . In a similar fashion one can define the best response of player 1. Notice that the
best response of player 2 is a correspondence ϕ as there is no unique optimal strategy against s1 and s2 .
The best response correspondence of player 2 is given by ϕ(s1 ) = {t1 , t2 }, ϕ(s2 ) = {t2 , t3 }, ϕ(s3 ) = {t4 }.
In this example, the upper and lower inverses of the set W = {t2 , t3 } ⊆ S2 are given by ϕ+−1 (W ) = {s2 }
and ϕ −1 (W ) = {s1 , s2 }. 

You might also like