Katherine Hawley - How To Be Trustworthy-OUP Oxford (2019)
Katherine Hawley - How To Be Trustworthy-OUP Oxford (2019)
The overall aims of this book are to show that there is a core notion of
trustworthiness which centrally involves avoiding unfulfilled commit-
ments, and to explore how we face various obstacles to being trustworthy,
no matter how well-meaning we are. Aiming at trustworthiness can
force us into uncomfortable choices, and I show how the nature and
severity of these obstacles and discomforts often depend upon our social,
material, and bodily circumstances.
I have tried to write a book which will be useful—even interesting—
to readers who are unfamiliar with philosophical debates about trust and
trustworthiness. This includes people who are familiar with other areas
of philosophy, but also people who address trust using the resources of
other disciplines: I have had very fruitful cross-disciplinary conversa-
tions about trust, distrust, and trustworthiness, and hope that this book
will further those engagements. Chapters 2 and 3 (about promising and
asserting) are the most concerned with the nitty-gritty of philosophical
debate. Whilst I have done my best to make even those chapters accessible,
the book should make sense to readers who skip from chapter 1 straight
to chapter 4.
In the interest of highlighting the woods rather than the trees, I have
made relatively little reference to other philosophers’ writings in the main
body of the text, and there are neither footnotes or endnotes. But at the
end of each chapter there are section-by-section indications of sources
additional to those explicitly referenced in the text. These are intended
to acknowledge the many ways in which I have been deeply influenced
by others’ writings, and to provide initial direction for those who want
to explore the literature properly. I have not attempted to provide a sys-
tematic introduction to philosophical work on trust and trustworthi-
ness, nor to the other topics I discuss. But anyone who investigates these
additional sources will quickly find further guidance and route-maps.
* * *
vi Preface
Trust can be a hopeful leap in the dark; it can be the outcome of a detailed
investigation. Trust can be specific to a particular task, carried out by a
particular person on a particular day; it can be a generalized long-term
attitude towards the people around us. Trust can make us feel warm and
fuzzy; it can be the source of deep anxiety. Trust can be merited; it can
turn out to have been a terrible mistake.
Trust takes on many guises, and academic researchers use many
methods to study trust. Long-term opinion polls track responses to the
question ‘Generally speaking, would you say that most people can be
trusted, or that you can’t be too careful in dealing with people?’
Sociologists study proxies for trust such as community involvement.
Psychologists and economists design laboratory experiments measuring
participants’ willingness to cooperate or to take risks depending on oth-
ers’ cooperation; other psychologists study the effects of betrayal and
trauma. Historians, political scientists, and theorists of international
relations investigate how networks and attitudes of trust are built or
undermined in different contexts, and between different types of agent.
Organizational trust researchers study the effects of institutional culture
on individual trust behaviour, and examine trust relationships between
different organizations, large and small.
What can philosophers contribute to our understanding of trust? Here
as elsewhere philosophers can enhance the conceptual clarity of debates,
for example by distinguishing different notions of trust and its cognates,
by teasing apart easily confused questions and issues, or by highlighting
false dilemmas and fallacious inferences. The aim of such work is not to
supplant the contributions made by other disciplines, but to offer better-
honed tools for developing those contributions, and perhaps also for
enabling richer contacts between different disciplines. (At the very least,
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
2 Trust and Distrust
Inanimate objects can be relied upon without being trusted. And there
are plenty of circumstances in which people are relied upon without
being trusted. Suppose you regularly bring too much lunch to work, and
offer the leftovers for others to eat. Suppose you do this because you’re
bad at judging quantities, not because you’re keen to feed your colleagues.
I rely on you to provide my lunch: I anticipate that you will do so, and
I don’t make alternative arrangements. But this reliance should not
amount to trust: you would owe me no apology if you ate all the food
yourself, and I ought not to feel betrayed by this, even if I felt disap-
pointed (and hungry).
This point is often made by reference to Immanuel Kant’s reputed habit
of taking a walk at the exact same time every day, so reliably that people
could literally set their watches by him: ‘Kant’s neighbors who counted on
his regular habits as a clock . . . might be disappointed with him if he slept in
one day, but not let down by him, let alone had their trust betrayed’ (Baier
1986: 235). The people of Königsberg relied upon Kant for timekeeping,
but sensibly did not make this a matter of trust or potential betrayal.
So there is a distinction between trust in a rich sense—trust which
can be betrayed—and mere reliance. But isn’t mere reliance a kind of
trust too? After all, we do talk of trusting a shelf to hold a vase, or trust-
ing a sturdy lock to keep a bike safe from thieves, even though it would
be melodramatic to talk of betrayal if such things went wrong. Some
philosophers have chosen to distinguish two types of trust rather than
distinguishing trust from mere reliance: for example, Hollis (1998: 10)
writes of ‘normative’ and ‘predictive’ trust, whilst Faulkner (2007: 880)
distinguishes ‘affective’ from ‘predictive’ trust. At one level, this is a mere
terminological issue: I have chosen to follow more standard philosophical
usage, reserving ‘trust’ for the richer notion and ‘mere reliance’ for the
other.
But a deeper question is why I and other philosophers have concerned
ourselves with a distinction between trust and mere reliance which is
not consistently respected by our ordinary ways of talking. The answer
is that the concept of trust is central to a network of normative concepts
and assessments; mere reliance does not have such rich connections.
As already noted, trust, unlike mere reliance, is linked to betrayal.
Moreover trustworthiness is clearly distinguished from mere reliability.
Trustworthiness is admirable, something to be aspired to and inculcated
in our children: it seems to be a virtue. Mere reliability, however, is not.
4 Trust and Distrust
Two other linguistic glitches may have occurred to you. First, what
about ‘mistrust’? To my ear, and according to many dictionaries, ‘distrust’
and ‘mistrust’ are mostly interchangeable. Perhaps ‘distrust’ is a little
more definite than ‘mistrust’, and perhaps it implies better justification
for the attitude. But I don’t think that the distinction is philosophically
load-bearing, and I will stick to ‘distrust’.
Second, and potentially more troubling, is that although I have been
pressing a structural analogy between trust and distrust, in practice we
do not treat the words ‘trust’ and ‘distrust’ symmetrically. For example,
we can say that David trusts Theresa to remember his birthday, but
we cannot smoothly say that Theresa distrusts David to remember her
birthday. To express this thought, we might awkwardly say that Theresa
distrusts David with respect to remembering her birthday. But more
likely we’d just say that Theresa does not trust David to remember her
birthday. That is, we attribute distrust by highlighting an absence of trust.
Doesn’t this conflict with my claim that distrust is an attitude in its own
right, not the mere absence of trust?
I don’t think so. Although there are many situations in which an
absence of trust doesn’t amount to distrust, there are also plenty of situ-
ations in which it’s clear that either trust or distrust is appropriate, so
that the absence of one indicates the presence of the other. Here’s a
similar phenomenon. An absence of liking doesn’t amount to disliking:
sometimes we feel neutral about something, sometimes we don’t even
know it exists. Nevertheless, there are plenty of situations in which it’s
clear that either liking or disliking is appropriate, so that the absence of
one indicates the presence of the other. I don’t like students to be late for
class, which means I dislike it, but it’s awkward to say that I dislike stu-
dents to be late. Still, dislike is an attitude in its own right, not the mere
absence of liking.
It’s a nice question why English works this way, but it shouldn’t
distract us from more substantive issues about trust and distrust. For
now, we can focus on the fact that there are plenty of situations—such as
our attitudes to inanimate objects—where it is plain that trust is not
appropriate, but also that distrust is not appropriate either, and not just
because we are unable to make up our minds. We need to understand
both trust and distrust if we are to understand the different ways in
which trust can go wrong, the reasons why both trust and distrust
1.3 Reliance and Non-Reliance 7
What about the notions of reliance and non-reliance which underlie these
richer notions of trust and distrust? How are we to understand these?
I adopt Richard Holton’s view (1994) that to rely on someone to do
something is to act on the supposition that she will do that thing. Acting
on this supposition does not require an outright belief that she will do
that thing, though it is incompatible with outright belief that she will
not. Relying is not always a matter of belief, it can be justified by prag-
matic reasons (e.g. convenience or politeness) as well as or instead of
reasons which point towards the truth of the supposition that the per-
son will act that way. Moreover, unlike believing, relying is sometimes a
matter of direct choice.
In this sense, relying on someone to do something needn’t mean putt-
ing your fate in their hands. You can rely upon me to bring enough food
for everyone at the picnic whilst nevertheless bringing plenty of food
yourself, because you don’t want to seem ungenerous: you’re acting on
the supposition that I will bring lots of food, and indeed this partly
explains the large quantities you bring along. Thus reliance in this sense
needn’t imply substantial risk or genuine vulnerability. Building an
account of trust on this notion of reliability therefore leaves space for
cases in which someone trusts another without taking any significant
risks, and without making herself vulnerable through her trust.
For me, this is one attraction of Holton’s account: it allows us to inves-
tigate when and why trust can make us (more) vulnerable, without writ-
ing vulnerability into the very definition of trust. But others will prefer a
more demanding account of reliance and therefore trust, in order to
focus on what seem like the most significant cases. We can all agree that
the decision whether to rely on someone takes on special importance
when reliance brings vulnerability; circumstances in which one cannot
avoid vulnerability are of distinctive interest; moreover our duties to be
trustworthy seem to be heightened when others are vulnerable to us.
8 Trust and Distrust
I recognize all of these points, and will return to some of them later in
this book. But for now my strategy is to offer an account of trust and
trustworthiness quite generally, rather than focusing on situations of
greater vulnerability.
So relying on someone to do something involves presupposing that
she will act as expected. And trust involves such reliance, plus some
further factor we have not yet explored. What about distrust and non-
reliance? Although trust involves confident prediction of appropriate
behaviour, distrust does not require confident prediction of misbehaviour.
So distrusting someone with respect to a certain act involves not relying
upon her to act that way, rather than relying upon her not to act that
way. Extending Holton’s framework, non-reliance means not acting on a
particular positive supposition, rather than acting on the corresponding
negative supposition.
There are good questions to ask about degrees of reliance, degrees of
reliability, and the fact that suppositions are sometimes idle wheels.
When I don’t need your help, it may make no practical difference whether
or not I act under the supposition that you would help if asked.
It’s also not clear what to say about situations in which I outwardly act
as if I suppose that you will do something, yet inwardly fret that you will
not: is this reliance? Disagreements on this point may reflect broader
disagreements about what trust feels like. Some picture trust as a kind of
relaxed confidence, incompatible with inner fretting. On a different
picture, we sometimes trust—or are left with no option but to trust—
despite our doubts, and without thereby erasing those doubts. I am
inclined towards the second of these pictures, so that trust and reliance
are both compatible with anxiety. But overall I do not have anything
particularly insightful to say about borderline cases of reliance: I am
consoled by the fact that similar questions arise for many, perhaps all,
different accounts of trust. Moreover, our understanding of these grey
areas between reliance and non-reliance can only be enhanced by paying
proper attention to distrust alongside trust, as I recommend.
So how can we best understand both the difference between trust and
mere reliance, and the difference between distrust and non-reliance?
1.4 The Commitment Account 9
I think that the difference between trust and [mere] reliance is that
trust involves something like a participant stance towards the person
you are trusting . . . trusting someone is one way of treating them as a
person. But if this is right, it shows how important it is that we do not
treat the participant stance as an all or nothing affair. Even when you
do trust a person, you need not trust them in every way . . . .You can
trust a person to do some things without trusting them to do others.
(Holton 1994: 4)
and certainly not to risk betraying me if they forget to buy the champagne,
or realize they can’t afford it. Similar situations arise in even the most
intimate, trusting relationships. Imagine that I cook dinner for my hus-
band each evening and he comes to rely on this. Even if I enjoy cooking,
in this scenario I do not want my husband to make this a matter of trust.
That is, I do not want to risk betraying him in even a minor way if I don’t
cook one evening, and nor do I want that to count against my trust-
worthiness. We aspire to a completely trusting relationship—we would
like to avoid even the slightest distrust—but we do not aspire to turn
all our interactions into issues of trust, for that would be oppressively
exhausting. (What if we disagree about whether a particular issue or
interaction should be an issue of trust? I will take up such thorny issues
in chapters 5 and 6.)
Holton correctly identifies the participant stance as a necessary
element of trust, and adopting this stance is necessary for distrust too.
But relying upon someone to whom you take a participant stance does
not always mean trusting that person: some interactions lie outside the
realm of trust and distrust. Likewise, deciding not to rely upon someone
to whom you take a participant stance need not mean distrusting that
person: you may just decide to buy your own champagne, or give up any
aspiration to drinking champagne. And adopting the participant stance
can sometimes require us not to turn every interaction into a matter of
trust and distrust. But such non-trust interactions are still within the
scope of the participant stance: it’s supremely appropriate for my hus-
band to express his gratitude for my cooking, even though he should not
convert his reliance into trust.
Jones (2004) also connects trust and the reactive attitudes but in a
more modulated fashion than Holton:
For my present purposes, I will take it that the notions of accepted vul-
nerability plus forgoing the attempt to reduce such vulnerability capture
roughly the notion of reliance. One might have something a bit like this
1.5 Looking Beyond Expectations 15
attitude to an inanimate object like a car, for example. Only ‘a bit like’,
because there are crucial differences between Jones’s notion, character-
ized in terms of power, care, vulnerability, and harm, and the thinner
characterization of reliance I have adopted from Holton. But, as I said
earlier, once we have framed an account of trust and trustworthiness in
rather thin terms, we can go on to identify certain situations—perhaps
exactly those in which there is vulnerability and risk—as being of special
moral significance.
In this context, normative expectations must do the work of distin-
guishing trust from mere reliance. Normative expectations, for Jones,
are ‘multistranded dispositions, including dispositions to evaluative
judgement and to reactive attitudes’ (2004: 17, note 8): when you trust
someone, you are liable to feel resentful if she lets you down through ill
will or laziness, and whilst you might not feel resentful if she lets you
down by accident, you may still think that an apology is warranted. Jones
distinguishes normative expectations from predictive expectations: we
can normatively expect something of someone without predicting that
she will in fact do what we expect of her.
If this is trust, what might distrust be? Let’s understand non-reliance
as a refusal to accept vulnerability, or as a continuing attempt to reduce
such vulnerability. One might have this attitude to a machine one takes
to be unreliable. What more is needed for distrust? Plausibly, the norma-
tive expectations involved in distrust are exactly the normative expect-
ations which would otherwise be involved in trusting that person in that
respect. So distrust is non-reliance plus a tendency to resentment, a
tendency to judge the distrustee negatively, or tendency to think that an
apology is warranted: distrust is something like disappointed trust,
though perhaps not preceded by an episode of trust.
Because Jones pins normative expectations to specific tasks (or, rather,
to specific cared-for things), she can accommodate the important fact
that respect for others, even in very intimate relationships, can require
us to stick with reliance-or-non-reliance rather than trust-or-distrust in
certain respects. I am happy for my husband to predict that I will cook
dinner tonight, but I do not want him to develop normative expect-
ations, to be poised to resent me if I don’t cook.
Normative expectations can help us understand both trust and dis-
trust, but there is something important missing from the picture. Both
16 Trust and Distrust
Holton and Jones tell us more about the truster’s attitudes than they do
about the features of the trustee to which those attitudes are directed.
We also need a story about when trust, distrust, or neither is objectively
appropriate—what is the worldly situation to which (dis)trust is an
appropriate response? When is it appropriate to have (dis)trust-related
normative expectations of someone? This is not just a question of practical
self-interest or mental hygiene: we owe it to others to get this right.
Mistaken distrust can be insulting, and limit other people’s options,
Mistaken trust can be burdensome, or allow vulnerable others more
leeway than they can properly manage.
We also need to understand the virtue of trustworthiness and the
vice of untrustworthiness, as they are distinguished from reliability and
unreliability. To do all this, we need a basis for our judgements about
reliability: how, if at all, can we predict what others will do? (A closely
related question is key to the epistemology of testimony: how, if at all,
can we judge who is speaking truthfully?) But we also need a basis for
our judgements about when it is appropriate to trust-or-distrust, not
merely to rely-or-not-rely. Many of the relevant norms apply only when
we enter the realm of appropriate trust-or-distrust.
The commitment account of trust and distrust provides this extra
richness. Seeing others as having undertaken commitments to us engages
the participant stance; it makes us poised for certain distinctive reactive
attitudes, specifically resentment when commitments are not met, and a
measure of regret about earlier distrust when commitments are unex-
pectedly fulfilled. It also allow us to distinguish between situations in
which trust is inappropriate because the person in question is not reliable,
and situations in which trust is inappropriate because the person does
not in fact have the relevant commitment.
it that you have the right kind of motive for looking after my vase; different
accounts disagree about what the ‘right kind’ of motive might be, but
typically this will involve some sort of concern for me.
Motives-based accounts seem initially to be a good fit for the distinc-
tion between trust and mere reliance: after all, when I merely rely upon
the shelf to hold the vase I don’t impute any kind of motive to the
shelf, and when I merely rely upon you to generate leftovers for my
lunch I know that you do not do this with my interests in mind. Moreover,
motives-based accounts seem to offer a more illuminating account of
trustworthiness: it will involve acting out of the right kind of motives.
But the emphasis on motives seems less attractive when we attempt to
extend the picture to include distrust. I cannot survey every motives-
based account of trust but will focus on representative suggestions from
Russell Hardin (2002) and Karen Jones (1996) (this view differs from
Jones’s 2004 account, which as we saw above is framed in terms of nor-
mative expectations). Both theories are well developed, sophisticated,
and prominent in the literature. Moreover they differ significantly from
one another, turning on the trustee’s rational self-interest and other-
directed goodwill respectively.
Hardin argues that when we trust someone, we expect the trustee
to encapsulate our interests within her own, because she has an inter-
est in maintaining or strengthening her relationship with us. In trust-
ing you to look after my vase, I take it that you will do so because you
have incorporated my interest in preserving the vase amongst your
own interests: looking after the vase now serves your own interests.
In contrast, when I rely upon the shelf to hold the vase, I do not have
any expectation about the shelf ’s motives or interests, for I realize it
has none.
Jones defines trust as an attitude of optimism that the goodwill and
competence of another will extend to cover the domain of our interaction
with her, together with the expectation that the one trusted will be dir-
ectly and favourably moved by the thought that we are counting on her
(1996: 1). As with Hardin, it is clear how this definition entails that we
do not trust the shelf when we rely upon it to hold the vase. Moreover
reference to the trustee’s responsiveness to our counting on her permits
a distinction between genuine trustworthiness and reliable but paternal-
istic benevolence.
18 Trust and Distrust
heinous crimes. I cannot rely on this person to help me; moreover I know
that she bears me ill-will and is actively trying to frustrate my goals. But
my attitude to her needn’t amount to distrust, for she is straightforward
and honest in her campaigning. (This doesn’t mean that I should trust
her; only that I do not have grounds to distrust her.) My opponent does
not display untrustworthiness in her open campaigning against me. And
if she turns out to be more helpful than I had expected, I need not feel
remorse about my previous attitude of non-reliance.
Now, I have not explored all the options here, nor represented the full
complexity of Hardin’s and Jones’s positions. Nevertheless, I have shown
that neither account of trust can handle distrust easily, and this for
reasons which generalize to other motives-based accounts. Both Hardin
and Jones take care to distinguish genuine trust from mere reliance. But
each considers decisions about distrust only in situations where either
genuine trust or genuine distrust is appropriate, where a person’s
behaviour demonstrates either trustworthiness or untrustworthiness
(i.e. distrust-worthiness). This narrow focus means that trust, distrust,
and indecision seem to exhaust the options, leading Hardin and Jones to
think of distrust as a kind of decisive lack of trust (Hardin 2002: 90;
Jones 1996: 17; see also McLeod 2002: 34).
Instead, we should ask about the preconditions for trust-or-distrust:
what is it about the excess-lunch-bringer, the non-champagne-buyers,
and indeed inanimate objects which mean that they are not suitable
recipients of either trust or distrust in the relevant respects? The primary
reason that trust is not appropriate in these cases is that neither trust or
distrust is appropriate. And—in my view—this is because there is no
commitment involved, not because of any feature of the other person’s
motives or interests.
Might we understand trust in terms of both commitment and motive?
The idea might be that when I trust someone I take her to have a commit-
ment, and I take her to be motivated by that commitment in ways which
make her reliable. Correspondingly, perhaps when I distrust someone
I take her to have a commitment, yet take her to be insufficiently motiv-
ated by that commitment, so that I do not rely upon her. I reject these
suggestions, for reasons that I will explain more fully later: I will return
to the relationship between trustworthiness and being motivated by
commitment in section 4.1, and I comment again on the (un)importance
20 Trust and Distrust
1.7 Betrayal
does not break, the connection between trust and betrayal. The alternative
is to rule that genuine trust-or-distrust is available only to those to whom
commitments are made.
This uneasy dilemma is not generated by the commitment account
per se; rather, it arises from a tension between two tempting thoughts
about cases like that of your daughter’s friend. On the one hand, it is
natural to think of your attitude towards your daughter’s friend as trust:
you are disposed to hold many of the trust-related reactive attitudes
towards your daughter’s friend, and reasonably so. On the other hand,
it is natural to think that it is only your daughter who is betrayed if her
friend breaks her promise to her. Any account of trust (and distrust) must
make a difficult choice between retaining these two intuitive judgements
whilst weakening the trust–betrayal connection, or else retaining the
trust–betrayal connection whilst rejecting one of the two intuitions.
Motives-based accounts of trust treat distrust as an afterthought and
thus struggle to explain the wrong involved in violating trust. On such
accounts, to trust someone to do something is to rely upon her to do it
for the right sort of motives. Such trust is disappointed either when the
task is not completed or else when the motives are ‘wrong’. This makes
unfeasibly heavy demands upon trustees, putting us in moral jeopardy,
liable to betray—not just disappoint—people who have unrealistic
expectations of us. My colleagues don’t care about my interest in drinking
champagne, nor do they bear me goodwill in this respect; surely they
cannot be criticized for this. But if I foolishly persuade myself otherwise,
then on such accounts my colleagues will subsequently ‘betray’ me when
they fail to buy champagne.
Moreover understanding trust (and distrust) in terms of normative
expectations does not by itself explain when such expectations are
appropriate. If I unreasonably develop normative expectations of my
colleagues in respect of champagne-buying—whether or not I also pre-
dict that they will buy me champagne—then I will wrongly feel betrayed
when they do not buy me champagne.
Now, we do indeed sometimes develop inappropriate expectations of
one another, and end up feeling resentful or betrayed. But the commit-
ment account enables us to see this as a consequence of miscommu-
nication or misunderstanding about what commitments have been
undertaken, rather than inevitably casting the fault upon the person
1.8 Where Next? 23
who ‘fails’ to act as expected. In chapters 5 and 6 I will discuss the ways
in which such miscommunication can arise, and how it can be avoided.
When we think about trust, we wonder who merits our trust, why, and
to what degree. When we think about trustworthiness, we are anchored
by the obvious thought that to be trustworthy is to merit trust. So trust
and trustworthiness are enmeshed. My own view is that trustworthiness
is best understood in terms of commitment—to be trustworthy is to live
up to one’s commitments, whilst to be untrustworthy is to fail to live up
to one’s commitments—and correspondingly that the attitude of trust
involves expectations of commitment-fulfilment. Understanding trust
in terms of seeing commitment in others enables us to understand the
differences between distrust, suspension of judgement between trust and
distrust, and cases where we clearly judge that neither trust nor distrust
is appropriate. Moreover it gives us a grasp of what trust aims at, of what
trustworthiness requires: matching commitment with action.
Let me concede before going any further that this account does not
make sense of every ordinary use of the word ‘trust’. Nor does it capture
everything that theorists have wanted from an account of trust. I have
already noted that there is a more demanding notion of trust which ties
it more closely to risk and vulnerability: I don’t deny that trust takes on
special significance in such contexts, but I see these as special instances
of a more general attitude of trust.
In addition, I am not placing much weight on people’s motives for
living up to their commitments, or failing to do so. On my view, if
someone lives up to her commitments for purely mercenary reasons (to
earn her salary, to bank favours, to avoid punishment), or for the self-
aggrandizing pleasure of placing herself on a moral pedestal, this in
itself does not undermine her trustworthiness. But of course there are
morally significant differences between someone like this, and someone
who lives up to her commitments for more noble reasons, perhaps
involving her sense of honour, or indeed others’ dependence upon her.
And often when we trust someone we hope and expect that she will live
up to her commitments for more admirable reasons, and we may feel
24 Trust and Distrust
Additional Sources
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
28 Promising
2.1 Sincerity
wrong, even though assassinating the rival would itself be wrong. More
controversially, Smith also argues, aligning herself with Henry Sidgwick,
that ‘a promise can be morally permissible even in cases where the
promised act occurs and would be wrong were it not for the promise’
(159). That is, promising and then keeping a promise may be the overall
best option, even though it would have been wrong to take the action in
question had it not been promised. For example, it might be best overall
for a politician to make (and keep) a promise to implement a wasteful
policy, if that’s what it takes for her to win the election and implement a
host of good policies.
In effect, Smith advocates a norm on promise-making which is weaker
than the Prohibition Principle: she endorses promises like the politician’s
wasteful pledge, which the simple norm condemns. Fortunately, I do not
need to resolve this issue. My aim is to show that there are promises which
should not be made even though they satisfy very high standards of
sincerity and morality-of-promised-action, because we also assess
promises on a third dimension—that of competence.
2.3 Competence
such unkeepable promises should not have been made in the first place;
moreover, I will not distinguish individual and collective unkeepability,
important though the distinction may be elsewhere.
Call this the ‘keepability norm’: do not make promises that you can-
not keep (don’t write cheques you can’t cash). As with other norms, we
should concede that the keepability norm can be overridden by other
considerations, most obviously in extreme circumstances where good
promising is not the foremost goal. If making an unkeepable promise is
the only way to save the world, then you should go right ahead and
promise. Moreover we can again distinguish subjective from objective
evaluation, separating the question whether a promise-maker reasonably
believes her promise to be keepable from the question whether the
promise is indeed keepable.
What’s wrong with unkeepable promises? It seems almost too obvious
to say, but if you make a promise which is unkeepable you condemn
yourself to breaking a promise, thus violating the basic requirement not
to break promises. This marks a difference from the other norms I dis-
cussed above: an insincere promise may nevertheless be kept, as may a
promise to act immorally. There are no unkeepable promises which are
nevertheless kept.
But we sometimes over-promise even though the promises we make
are individually and even collectively keepable: mere keepability is too
weak a constraint. Imagine that a child is brought into hospital, very sick,
with an unidentified, unfamiliar condition. The junior doctor oversee-
ing the case promises the parents that she will save their child’s life, and
this is what she sincerely intends to do. It turns out that the child’s
condition can be treated with a particular type of antibiotic, which the
doctor happens to try first, and so the doctor saves the child’s life. Great!
Still, a more experienced physician may rightly criticize the junior doc-
tor for having made such a rash promise: after all, she had no idea what
condition the child was suffering from, nor whether it would turn out to
be treatable. The doctor could have promised to try her best to save the
child. But she should not have simply and recklessly promised to save
the child.
Likewise, we can imagine reckless promises to track down a mysteri-
ous criminal, or to win an Olympic medal some day, or to learn to speak
Polish with no trace of an accent; in each case we can imagine that the
2.3 Competence 35
child, and reasonably believed that this was possible. But if she believed
that she would in fact save the child, that belief was not justified.
A tougher challenge is this. We can imagine various sorts of cases in
which someone makes a sincere promise to do something permissible,
that promise will be kept, and moreover the promisor reasonably believes
that all this is so; yet the promise is a bad promise. These cases are struc-
turally analogous to cases in which someone has a true, justified belief
and yet lacks knowledge.
Here is one sort of case. Suppose that Usha promises to buy Alan a
pint of the best beer in Borsetshire, but has no idea which this is. She
takes advice from the confident-seeming barman, and so she reasonably
believes she will buy the best beer. But the barman is brand new, knows
nothing about beer, and picks the best one merely by luck. So Usha
keeps her promise: she buys Alan a pint of the best beer in Borsetshire.
And Usha is quite reasonable in her belief that she is keeping her prom-
ise: it’s perfectly reasonable for her to take advice about beer from the
barman, who does seem to know what he is talking about.
Still, the promise seems problematic. You may be sceptical about my
evasive use of ‘problematic’. As a stopgap, consider how Usha might feel
later when she grasps the true situation. She might think that she had a
lucky escape, that if she had known the barman was a novice she would
not have made the promise, and that that would have been safer; she
might regret making the promise, even knowing that she did manage to
keep it. This is not an ideal promise: we shouldn’t make a habit of prom-
ising in this style, and should take steps to avoid such promising.
Here is a different sort of case. Faced with taking a ball at random
from an urn containing 999 red balls and one black, Sid reasonably
believes that he will pull out a red ball, and so he does. But he should not
promise to do so; if he did promise, we’d suspect he had rigged the draw.
If Sid promised to draw a red ball, he would be sincerely promising to
do something permissible, he would keep his promise, and he would
reasonably believe all this is so. Still, this is not the sort of promise he
ought to make, not an ideal promise.
When they make their promises, Usha and Sid each have a reasonable
true belief in their own success. But their beliefs do not amount to
knowledge. So it is tempting to suppose that good promising requires
not just success, and reasonable belief about success, but full-blown
2.3 Competence 37
knowledge that one will successfully keep the promise. There is a really
bad way and an only slightly better way to spell out this suggestion. The
really bad way is to build a knowledge requirement into our ‘subjective’
evaluation of the promise-maker, to argue that a good promise is one
which will be kept, and a good promise-maker is someone who knows
her promise is good. This is a bad move because half the point of
separating subjective and objective evaluations is to exonerate people
who blamelessly violate an underlying norm. If blamelessness requires
knowledge that the norm is satisfied, then blameless violations of the
norm will be impossible.
The only slightly better way is to strengthen the norm itself: do not
make promises unless you know you will keep them. (The correspond-
ing ‘subjective’ evaluation would assess whether the promise-maker
reasonably believed she knew she would keep her promise.) Although
this is slightly better, it is nevertheless not much good, because it
imposes an enormously stringent requirement on promise-making.
Indeed, on reflection we might think that even the original success
requirement is too strong, that there are perfectly good promises which
nevertheless are eventually broken. This is not to say that it is sometimes
good to break a promise, though that may also be true if the circum-
stances are extreme. The thought is that a promise’s being broken does
not inevitably mean that it should not have been made in the first place;
one might regret breaking a promise yet not regret having made the
promise, even with hindsight.
This is a tricky business, as is reflected by some complicated remarks
from J. L. Austin:
you are prohibited from saying ‘I promise I will, but I may fail’ . . .
[however] ‘but I may fail’ does not mean merely ‘but I am a weak human
being’ (in which case it would be no more exciting than adding ‘D.V.’
[‘God willing’]): it means that there is some concrete reason for me to
suppose that I shall break my word. It is naturally always possible
(‘humanly’ possible) that I . . . may break my word, but that by itself is
not bar against using the expression . . . ‘I promise’. (1946: 170)
nature and source of our obligation to keep our promises. There are, of
course, differing philosophical accounts of why we should keep our
promises, and to some extent these correspond to variation in the detail
of what we should say about the exact competence norm. I will not
explore this issue in detail. But I will sketch how different accounts of
promissory obligations might explain certain competence-related norms
on promise-making. The literature on promising is strikingly concerned
with the temptation to make insincere promises, whilst issues of incom-
petence or recklessness rarely reach the surface. Nevertheless, the concerns
which direct us towards sincerity also direct us towards competence.
Principle D: One must exercise due care not to lead others to form
reasonable but false expectations about what one will do when one has
good reason to believe that they would suffer significant loss as a result
of relying on these expectations.
something one is not in a position to do, even if one knows the offer will
be rejected. For example, I should not offer to give you something which
does not belong to me, even if I know you will not accept my offer.
Suppose instead that the person making the offer is not in a position
to know that the offer will be rejected. Then it seems even more clear
that she should not offer a promise which would, if accepted, violate the
norms of promise-making: she does not know that she will avoid violat-
ing those norms, and even if she did, as above, this does not seem to
justify her behaviour.
I am not surveying all the possibilities here: we would need to distin-
guish different epistemic and doxastic situations for both parties, dis-
tinguish more rigorously between assessing the offerer’s actions and
assessing her blameworthiness, and perhaps be more careful about what
exactly is required by sincerity. Nevertheless, I will continue to suppose
that we should not even offer incompetent promises. The issue of offering
promises which we do not expect to be accepted may seem rather niche.
But it is relevant to a range of situations in which we offer (purported)
information to others, through attempted testimony, assertion, or telling:
this is the topic of the next chapter.
For now, I hope to have established the following points. Promise-
making is governed by norms which derive from the norm that one
should keep one’s promises. These include a norm of competence: don’t
make promises you are not competent to keep, where competence
requires both more and less than successful promise-keeping. Rival
theories of why we ought to keep our promises provide foundations for
different accounts of why it is we should not make promises we are not
competent to keep. Since promise-making is a paradigmatic, though not
entirely typical, situation in which we incur new commitments, these
constraints on promise-making give us some insight into the demands
of trustworthiness—I will explore this connection in chapter 4.
Admittedly, I have not pinned down exactly what it is to be competent
in some respect, nor what it is to succeed through the exercise of com-
petence. Yet it’s clear that something of this sort is missing in cases where
promises are problematic even though they are sincere. Appreciating the
importance of competence for promise-making raises questions that
I will explore in the remainder of the book. For example, how do we judge
our own competence so as to become good promise-makers (which might
Additional Sources 47
Additional Sources
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
3.1 Telling and Asserting 49
distrusted, does she have any obligations to speak truthfully? What if the
speaker knows that she will simply be ignored, not treated as eligible for
either trust or distrust? Indeed, issues of trustworthiness arise even
before anyone speaks, as we consider who to ask for their opinion, or
who to ask for practical help.
These concerns connect naturally with the issues around promising
and offering to promise which I discussed at the end of chapter 2. To
explore them properly, I first need to explain how and why, in my view,
asserting or telling involves a kind of promise, and so I will return to
these issues later in this chapter. For now, I will stick to the terminology
of ‘assertion’ rather than ‘telling’, mainly because this fits with the majority
of the authors I engage with. But the paradigm case is one in which an
assertion is made to an audience, and involves at least an attempt to tell
someone something.
The first of these options is not attractive. Asserting that the front
door is locked amounts to something less than promising that the
front door is locked. Someone who promises that the door is locked needs
to be in a stronger epistemic situation than does someone who asserts
that the door is locked. She seems to be taking more responsibility onto
her own shoulders when she promises, and this is why we sometimes
ask people to promise that something is true, even when they have
already asserted it—sometimes we want more than just an assertion.
But the second option—identifying assertion with a promise to do
something—can seem problematic too. In particular, where a proposition
concerns the speaker’s future behaviour, the difference between promising
to do something and asserting is crucial: if I promise to come to your
party, then (barring emergencies) I am obliged to come to your party,
whilst if I assert that I will come to your party, then at most I am obliged
to inform you if my plans change. Promising to do something seems to
be more charged with responsibility than merely asserting or predicting
that I will do it.
So it is tempting to account for assertion in terms of promising, but
difficult to see how. My preference is for the second option, that is, the
claim that asserting involves promising to do something. I need to show
how we can take this option whilst recognizing the difference between
my promising to do something and merely asserting that I will do that
very thing. That is the central task of this chapter.
I claim that asserting as to whether p involves both
taboo to discuss whether the front door is locked. One might assert that
it’s probable that the front door is locked, or possible that the front door
is locked. But for my purposes none of these will count as asserting as to
whether the front door is locked.
‘Speaking’ here is a neutral term, which could be substituted by ‘writing’
or ‘signing’ (e.g. in BSL or ASL). Speaking as to whether p can be done
without asserting—e.g. as part of a game, or whilst performing in a play.
A speaker speaks truthfully as to whether p if she says that p and p is
true, or if she says that not-p and not-p is true: speaking truthfully
requires match between words and world, rather than words and beliefs.
(Where beliefs are the topic of conversation, then beliefs are part of the
world, in the relevant sense.)
This means that, on my view, assertion involves a promise to speak in
ways which in fact match the world, not merely to do one’s best on this
front. Assertions are therefore faulty when they are in fact false, even if
the speaker could not have known this, indeed even if nobody could
have known the truth of this matter. In my view this is an advantage of
the account, since factually inaccurate assertions are indeed faulty; more
broadly this fits with the themes of chapters 4, 5, and 6, where I explore
how we can unwittingly become untrustworthy. Nevertheless, uninten-
tional falsehoods are usually treated with more sympathy than intentional
lies; I return to questions of blame and criticism later in this chapter.
I claim that assertion involves a promise, but it is not only a promise:
assertion also involves keeping or breaking that very promise. So the
promise made in assertion is unusual, because it is simultaneously made
and kept, or else simultaneously made and broken. More usually, a
promise binds us to act at some later time, specified or unspecified,
somehow offering assurance to others about our future behaviour. (We
can accept that promises often assure without determining whether this
is constitutive of their role.) One reason to value this assurance is that
guidance and insight about the future are otherwise in short supply,
especially where others’ free actions are concerned.
But it is not only the future which can be hidden from us. Often the
audience for an assertion lacks independent access to whether what is
said is true. This explains why a promise to speak truthfully can be valuable
in such a case. Even though it is simultaneously kept or broken, it is not
is immediately obvious which of these has occurred, and so the fact that
3.2 Connecting Asserting with Promising 53
speakers are not required in addition to provide evidence that they have
spoken truthfully, even if challenged.
So assertions do not automatically involve justificatory commitments,
on my view. But we can appreciate why speakers are often under pressure
to justify their assertions if challenged. My son fulfils his obligations—
keeps his promise—even though he does not show me his homework.
My main concern is that he do his homework, but I would also like
assurance on this front, so that I can relax: I value my son’s promise
more if he is also willing to show me the completed homework. Likewise,
assertions are often more valuable to the audience, and thus indirectly to
the speaker, where they are accompanied by a justificatory commitment.
So it is not surprising if assertions often come with this extra commit-
ment, even though the commitment is not incurred merely by asserting.
Such situations involve many social complexities. Perhaps my son
refuses to show his homework because he wants me to trust him, to
take him at his word. Perhaps my inability to relax otherwise does
reveal a lack of trust, but my son’s refusal to offer assurance makes
trusting even harder. More generally an assertion which does not
come accompanied with a commitment to later justify does seem to
embody a kind of challenge to the audience: take it or leave it, trust
me or don’t. When we hear a surprising assertion, we may ask in
response ‘how do you know?’ But it’s not obvious that we are entitled
to an answer to that question.
What about retraction? Suppose I promise to lock the door when
leaving your house, but forget to do so. Once I realize what I have done,
I may have a number of obligations: to let you know, to apologize, to
compensate you if possible. Related actions may be appropriate even if
I merely doubt whether I have locked the door. Moreover I might regret
my promise, and might inform you of my regrets, either before or after
I leave the house. But that doesn’t change my commitments and obliga-
tions, unless you decide to release me from the promise. None of this
amounts to retracting the promise, because promises cannot be unilat-
erally retracted once accepted.
So if an assertion involves a promise to speak truthfully, then it
involves a commitment or undertaking which cannot simply be
retracted; the commitment is immediately fulfilled, or not. Nevertheless,
we can make sense of the obligations of those who realise they have not
3.4 Promising, Asserting, and Assuring 57
When I say ‘I promise to be there at ten o’clock to help you,’ the effect is
the same as if I had said, ‘I will be there at ten o’clock to help you. Trust
me.’ (1998: 306)
For those who are tempted by the assurance view of testimony, accept-
ing my account of assertion as involving promising to speak truthfully
provides a robust framework within which to develop that view. (Still,
some caution is advised, given that it is controversial whether promising
is primarily aimed at providing assurance.)
But my view does not entail an assurance view of the epistemic sig-
nificance of testimony, as the situation of eavesdroppers illustrates.
Critics of the assurance view (Lackey 2008, Owens 2006, Goldberg 2015)
argue that, when I hear you say that p, it makes no epistemic difference
whether you are addressing me directly (thus offering me your assur-
ance and inviting me to trust you), or whether I happen to overhear
something which was not intended for my ears. Owens remarks that the
duty to keep a promise is owed to the promisee in particular, whereas
wine), or else she is promising to come to the party. The natural reading
is the second, in most contexts.
I have now set out my account of assertion in terms of making and
breaking/keeping a promise to speak truthfully. I have distinguished this
account from other accounts of assertion in terms of commitment, and
from assurance accounts of the epistemic significance of testimony.
I have also shown how other authors who have noticed the affinities
between assertion and promising have been too quick to set these aside,
because of the obvious unattractiveness of identifying an assertion that
p with a promise that p.
This means I’m now able to draw on the conclusions of chapter 2,
where I argued that promise-making is governed by norms of sincerity
and competence. Applying these norms to the special case of promising
to speak truthfully helps us understand assertion, and explain our
intuitions and disagreements about the norms which govern it.
cases which involve a time-lag between the making of the promise and the
keeping-or-breaking of the promise. One might intend to acquire an
obligation whilst lacking the intention to meet the obligation, either
because one anticipates that acquiring the obligation will generate the
appropriate intention, or because one anticipates being released from the
obligation before being called upon to act; Owens (2012) can condone
such promises as sincere, whilst Scanlon (1998) would not.
But where a promise is simultaneously made and kept-or-broken,
there is no space for such cases. Moreover, Owens allows ‘that a promise
usually carries the implication, or communicates the information that
the promisor intends to perform’ (2012: 202). So I will assume that one
ought to promise to speak truthfully as to whether p only if one intends
to speak truthfully as to whether p. Marušić (2015) would argue that
sincerity requires us to believe that we will indeed speak truthfully as to
whether p. I disagree on this point: this requirement seems to be unduly
harsh on hesitant speakers, who do know the truth of what they say,
though they have doubts about their ability to express it properly. But
this disagreement is not very significant here; at worst, it blurs the
distinction between sincerity and competence without undermining the
importance of either.
I argued in chapter 2 that good promise-making requires compe-
tence: in this instance, do not promise to speak truthfully as to whether
p unless you are competent to speak truthfully as to whether p.
Keepability is too weak: the mere possibility of speaking truthfully as to
whether p does not justify promising to do so. Success here amounts to
speaking truthfully, whilst competence involves something like a secure
or stable disposition to speak truthfully in this matter.
I am now in a position to make more explicit connections with the
standard debate about norms for assertion. If assertion is, as I claim, a
matter of promising to speak truthfully as to whether p, and simultan-
eously keeping or breaking that promise, we should expect it to be
governed both by the norms relevant to promise-making and by the
norm that promises should be kept. So we’d expect the following:
One must assert as to whether p only if
• One intends to speak truthfully as to whether p
• One is competent to speak truthfully as to whether p
• One does in fact speak truthfully as to whether p.
64 Telling
One should assert that p only if (i) it is reasonable for one to believe
that p, and (ii) if one asserted that p, one would assert that p at least in
part because it is reasonable to believe that p.
The RTBNA does not require that the assertor in fact believe that p:
Lackey condones ‘selfless assertors’, such as a creationist teacher who has
strong evidence that Homo sapiens evolved from Homo erectus, and
asserts this proposition to her pupils, without believing it herself.
Plausibly, the creationist teacher is competent to speak truthfully on
whether Homo sapiens evolved from Homo erectus, and succeeds in
doing so.
Is she sincere? I take it that the teacher does not intend to speak
truthfully, but that she does intend to become obliged to speak truth-
fully: this incurring of unmet obligation is, from her perspective, one
downside of her current job. Lackey (2008: 113) says that the asser-
tion is insincere given Bernard Williams’s account of insincerity, and
yet that the teacher does not aim to misinform her pupils about evo-
lution, seemingly because she aims only to inform her pupils that
scientific evidence supports the evolutionary claim. It is not clear to
me whether Lackey herself thinks that the assertion is insincere, nor
whether she thinks that the teacher intends to misinform her pupils,
even if this is not the teacher’s aim.
What about Weiner’s (2005) truth norm: one must assert p only if p is
true? This matches the third strand, the requirement to keep the
66 Telling
items which I secretly think are too ugly for anyone else to buy: this is a
kind gesture which pleases you whilst benefiting the charity, and I
manage not to tell any outright lies. But it would be unkind to promise
to buy all the too-ugly items, even if you would accede for the charity’s
sake: making the promise would hurtfully reveal my opinion of the
items I subsequently buy. Likewise I shouldn’t promise to fix you up a
date with my boring cousin, or promise to drive you to your surprise party,
at least not in those terms, even though each promised action is perfectly
permissible (you’re a great match for my hypothetical boring cousin).
When I promise to do something, this can enable others to make
reasonable inferences from my subsequent actions to my beliefs, via the
assumption that my action is at least partly explained by my desire to
keep my promise. And under certain circumstances enabling others to
make such inferences is morally impermissible—e.g. it is gratuitously
unkind—even though the promised action is itself permissible. (These
promises are the mirror image of those discussed by Smith (1997), such
as the politician’s permissible promise to enact an otherwise-impermissible
policy in order to get elected and do much good overall.)
Now, the ‘morality’ norm on promising which I explored in chapter 2
does not condemn such promises, but this should seem neither surprising
nor problematic. We should not expect norms specifically tailored to
promise-making to encompass every respect in which an act of promise-
making can be assessed: to achieve this, we would need an entire moral
theory providing guidance for assessing practical actions of all sorts.
How does this apply to promises to speak truthfully? It can be okay
for me to utter a sentence which expresses the claim that your mother
never loved you. But if I precede this utterance by promising to speak
truthfully, then my utterance takes on a different, crueller, aspect.
(Imagine I promise to write something true on a piece of paper, then
write ‘your mother never loved you’ and hand it over.)
So the ‘morality’ norm on promise-making has limited impact on
promising to speak truthfully, forbidding only those promises where
merely speaking truthfully would itself be morally problematic, for
example where merely voicing a thought can cause the audience to enter-
tain suggestions they would not otherwise have considered. Presenting
certain claims in fiction or pretence, or merely as supposition, can
sometimes be inflammatory and objectionable, even when it is clear
68 Telling
Additional Sources
3.1 Telling and Asserting. Hornsby (1994) and E. Fricker (2006) explicitly
work with ‘telling’, though their primary interests differ from one
another. Heal (2013) also writes of ‘telling’, with very helpful distinctions
between types of telling. ‘Assertion’ is both the title and the core term
Additional Sources 71
throughout the various essays in Brown and Cappelen (eds) (2011) and
in Goldberg’s monograph (2015), although Goldberg also discusses telling.
Kukla (2014) emphasizes the audience’s role in determining whether an
utterance is an assertion, and I draw on her work through chapters 5 and 6.
3.2 Connecting Asserting with Promising. Watson (2004) is a key dis-
cussion of the seeming differences between assertion and telling; like-
wise Owens (2006). My neutral use of ‘speaking’ is much like Cappelen
(2011: 22–4) on ‘saying’; again, verbal utterances are standing in for
writing, signing (e.g. ASL, BSL), Morse code, semaphore, etc. It’s not
obvious how far this list could be extended.
3.3 Asserting and Committing. References to Brandom and Macfarlane
are given in the text.
3.4 Promising, Asserting, and Assuring. A different, rewarding treat-
ment of assurance, in connection with J. L. Austin, is given by Lawlor
(2013).
3.5 Alternative Connections. Williamson (2000: 244–5) discusses
swearing that p.
3.6 Norms on Assertion. In addition to citations in the main text, the
essays in part 2 of Brown and Cappelen (eds) (2011) cover a lot of rele-
vant ground.
3.7 Immoral Assertions? A much richer set of discussions of speech
and ethics is gathered in Maitra and McGowan (eds) 2012. I take up on
some related questions around coercion and lies in my (2018a).
3.8 What Sorts of Norms Are These? Key references are in the main text.
4
Trustworthiness
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
4.1 Trustworthiness and Commitment 73
I began the book with trust and distrust. But trustworthiness and
untrustworthiness often seem more central to moral philosophy than do
trust and distrust themselves. Trust sometimes has value in its own
right, but usually this is conditional on the trustworthiness of the trusted
person. As Linda Zagzebski puts it, the virtue of trust is ‘a mean between
gullibility and suspiciousness’ (1996, 160–1): virtue involves wise trust-
ing and distrusting, not trust per se. We owe it to ourselves and to others
to place our trust appropriately, where appropriateness depends at least
in part on the trustworthiness of the trustee. This is especially important
where we make decisions about trust which in turn affect people who
depend upon us, whether these are our children, colleagues, friends,
or neighbours.
Different notions of trust and distrust correspond to different notions of
trustworthiness and untrustworthiness. Given the commitment account,
to be trustworthy is to ensure that our commitments are matched by
action, and thus, as a special case, to ensure that what we say in making
an assertion is true. This requires diligence in fulfilling commitments
already acquired—a trustworthy person keeps her promises. But it also
74 Trustworthiness
When I discuss these ideas with others, I find that some are reluctant
to describe this sort of person as ‘untrustworthy’, preferring to reserve
that term for those who are dishonest, insincere, or intentionally manipu-
lative. (Uncoincidentally, most of us regard ourselves as more inclined
to this kind of well-intentioned over-commitment than to outright
deception; I include myself here of course.) Isn’t incompetence in these
respects just a matter of unreliability, rather than untrustworthiness?
As I discussed in chapter 1, ordinary language is not a consistent guide
in this area, and I do not want to linger long over the choice of ter-
minology. But what is important is that untrustworthiness-through-
incompetence can have much of the same ethical and practical character
as does untrustworthiness-through-bad-intentions. Indeed, we often find
it difficult to decide whether someone really isn’t able to fulfil her com-
mitments, or whether she just isn’t willing to do so. This uncertainty can
also arise in the first person, of course, when I wonder whether I am
really trying my best to live up to my commitments.
If this seems a stretch, it may be because we can easily imagine or
remember cases in which someone over-commits without realizing that
she is taking on too much—which may make her seem less blameworthy—
whereas it is perhaps harder to imagine a case in which someone
does not realize she is being insincere in her assertions or promises.
I’ll return later to discuss whether trustworthiness requires just com-
petence or also knowledge of competence, and also to explore the nature
and consequences of commitment without proper competence. But
already it should be clear that not knowing that one is over-committed
will not serve as an all-purpose excuse for failure, nor as a mark of
trustworthiness.
It is a familiar thought that lies and false promises are morally wrong,
exceptional circumstances aside. And it might seem harsh to suggest that
incompetence or ignorance is likewise a moral flaw. It is certainly not in
general a moral flaw to lack competence or be ignorant: we are all inev-
itably multi-incompetent and multi-ignorant. Nor even is it in general a
moral flaw to lack competence which others want or need you to pos-
sess. But recall that, on my view, trustworthiness requires competence
only insofar as we have commitments. And it is morally problematic to
end up in a situation in which you are committed to doing something
you are not competent to do, absent a good excuse at least.
82 Trustworthiness
future action (or the truth of what you say), even when you yourself
possess such assurance. You may be trying to teach someone how to be
independent, to wean someone off a habit of relying upon you; parents
are often in this situation. Moreover, there is no point promising some-
one that you will throw them a surprise party on their birthday. And,
more self-servingly, we may like the fact that people are often more
grateful, or express their gratitude differently, when we act without being
obliged to do so. On the other hand, people are often grateful for assur-
ance, so this isn’t a straightforward calculation.
Doesn’t trustworthiness require us to take on new commitments? As
I discussed above, often we incur meta-commitments, whereby we
undertake to be open to future additional commitments without actu-
ally incurring them ahead of time. This means that on occasion trust-
worthiness will indeed require us to take on new commitments, as we
have undertaken to do. But where meta-commitments do not bind us,
attention to trustworthiness leaves us free to reduce our burden of com-
mitment quite substantially. This is another reason why I have tried not
to refer to trustworthiness as a ‘virtue’: on one standard philosophical
account of the virtues, they are mutually reinforcing, and indeed cannot
be fully achieved independently. The valuable trait of trustworthiness
which I am exploring here does not have that kind of relationship to
other valuable traits such as generosity or kindness.
false yet justified or true yet unjustified, and similarly trust may be
inaccurate yet justified or accurate yet unjustified. But it is not evident
that trustworthiness stands to trust as a constitutive aim, as many think
that truth stands to belief as a constitutive aim. Trust may aim at encour-
aging trustworthiness, for example, rather than aiming to recognize or
detect existing trust.
Even setting this complication aside, the relationship between per-
ceived trustworthiness and trustworthiness is more complex than the
relationship between, for example, perceived kindness and kindness, or
perceived courage and courage. There are a number of causal and con-
stitutive mechanisms which complicate the picture. For example, when
others regard us as untrustworthy, they may give us fewer opportunities to
take on commitments; this makes it more difficult for us to develop good
judgement in commitment management, to learn what our capabilities
are, and to demonstrate whatever trustworthiness we do have.
Even if we are able to incur commitments, lack of trust from other
people can make it more difficult for us to fulfil those commitments,
especially where we need cooperation and support. More generally,
being trusted helps us to acquire and develop new capabilities to act—it
can be difficult to learn new skills or acquire new capacities if others do
not trust us to learn through trial and error, for example.
When faced with a potential new commitment, how should these
complications inform our thinking? Trustworthiness, as I have argued
above, by default points towards caution. If you don’t take anything on,
you run no risk of letting other people down. But as we can now appre-
ciate, lack of commitment also means lack of opportunity to demon-
strate our capacity to live up to a commitment, and lack of opportunity
to test oneself and learn for the future. Avoiding commitment may be
the best guarantee of avoiding untrustworthiness in the short term, but
this is a limited strategy in the longer term even as regards trustworthiness
itself, not to mention other important goals.
More generally, we should expect at least a fallible connection between
being trustworthy and appearing to be trustworthy: trustworthiness
could not perform its social role if it were widely undetectable. The
same is true of commitments. In chapter 5, I will try to show how often
our circumstances—including circumstances beyond our control—can
Additional Sources 93
Additional Sources
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
96 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
ways which remain obscure to other people who occupy different, more
empowered standpoints.
Indeed, Charles W. Mills (2007) has shown how those who possess
power may rely upon on their own lack of insight as a means of perpetu-
ating this possession. Mills’s chief concern is with white ignorance in the
context of racism, but the point generalizes. Someone employed under
exploitative conditions may have an excellent understanding of how the
employer’s whims generate commitments for the employee, a better
understanding than the employer possesses or even wants to possess;
the same goes for people who are ‘self-employed’ in the gig economy. So
for all sorts of reasons we should bear in mind that there is an important
difference between having control over one’s commitments and having
insight into what they are; likewise, there is an important difference
between lacking control over one’s commitments and lacking insight
into them.
Nevertheless, insight is often helpful in achieving control of our com-
mitments. And even in relatively egalitarian company we may struggle
to grasp how our speech and actions will be interpreted by others. In
earlier chapters I dwelt upon explicit means of incurring commitment,
through promising and assertion. But there is a host of ways in which
subtle social conventions and defaults govern the incurring of less explicit
commitments. In many contexts, to accept a gift, hospitality or invitation
is to incur a commitment to reciprocate appropriately, whatever appro-
priateness turns out to require. To take a different example, often we can
become committed not just by actively claiming a commitment, but also
by failing to object or actively push back against others’ expectations of
us on this front. But it may not be clear how this opt-out works, when it
is happening, and when it is already too late to protest.
It is in the nature of these conventions that they are rarely made expli-
cit, except when we want to complain about people who violate our
expectations. And they easily vary between different families, groups of
friends, or workplaces, as well as across more obvious cultural divides
between nations or generations. This opens up the possibility of mutual
misunderstanding about what commitments different people carry, and
about what it takes for those commitments to be discharged.
How does all of this confusion place obstacles in the way of our
becoming trustworthy? First, suppose that you are fully aware of the
social conventions governing gifts, and realize that if you accept a gift, then
102 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
of, and we feel unsure whether we must act in line with commitments
others unexpectedly—mistakenly?—take us to have. This creates oppor-
tunities for guilt and for guilt-tripping, for anxiety and exploitation of
different kinds.
In thinking about how far commitment can exceed the scope of first-
personal grasp, we should at least agree that two extreme positions are
both unappealing. It cannot be that a person is never bound by commit-
ment unless she knows exactly what she is undertaking to do. Amongst
their other roles, commitment, trust, and trustworthiness are devices for
social coordination, and for reducing the so-called ‘transaction costs’ of
trying to work together. Much of this would be impossible if lack of full
transparency always voided commitments. It would also be exception-
ally burdensome if we constantly had to check on each other’s grasp of
exactly what commitments have been incurred in order to reasonably
hold people to account. Some flexibility here is a benefit to all of us, both
as it enables us to trust others without detailed investigation, and as it
lures us into commitments which we do not fully understand yet will
ultimately value. To think otherwise is to adopt a superficially attractive
but unachievable cold ideal of utterly transparent autonomy.
On the other hand, it cannot be that we have no first-person advantage
whatsoever in understanding what commitments we have undertaken.
Commitments can play their social role only insofar as they are available
to guide our actions, at least where we are intrinsically or instrumentally
motivated to be trustworthy. Indeed, we need a grasp of our existing
commitments in order to judge which new commitments we can safely
incur. To the extent that commitments lie beyond an individual’s control
or insight, they are entangled with the behaviour, attitudes, and expect-
ations of other people. But one of the guiding themes of earlier chapters
was that trustworthiness does not require us to respond to each and every
demand which is placed upon us. Sometimes when people think that we
are untrustworthy for not doing as they wish, those people are mistaken.
Sometimes when others think we have an obligation-generating com-
mitment to do something for them, they are mistaken. For these sorts of
reasons, we need to recognize that we are not just third-party observers
of our own commitments.
My remarks here blur various senses of epistemic and practical
authority, without properly pinning down the relationships between these.
But a concept of commitment which can underpin a useful concept of
104 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
another, because without social support they have no other safety net.
All of these complications further illustrate that ability to control one’s
commitments is not uniformly or equitably distributed.
In this section I have investigated obstacles to controlling our com-
mitments, and thus obstacles to being trustworthy. Even if we accept
that there is no such thing as an involuntary commitment, practical
circumstances of many kinds can make it much more difficult for people
to avoid commitments, even when they are fully aware of what is going
on; the price of avoiding commitment may be unaffordably high. In
addition, there are many situations in which we are unsure of how our
actions and speech will be understood by other people as resulting in
our having incurred new commitment. Often the mere fact of others
seeing us as committed gives us strong reason to act as they anticipate.
But it seems that at least on occasion we do have commitments we are
unaware of, generated by the social significance of our actions and words.
In chapter 6 I discuss how we can or should respond to these various
situations, but before doing so I will review other types of obstacle to
trustworthiness.
to fulfil them, yet luckily avoid commitments she is in fact not competent
to fulfil. If she lacked insight into her own competence—and lacked insight
into her own lack of competence—this would not automatically render
her untrustworthy.
Nevertheless, on the assumption that we do not want to keep our
commitments to the bare minimum, and do not want to rely on mere luck
to render us trustworthy, we will need some insight into what we are
capable of doing. So obstacles to gaining that insight are for all practical
purposes obstacles to being trustworthy. Here we encounter in somewhat
different guise the debates around norms for assertion and promising
which I discussed in chapters 2 and 3. My strategy there was not to advo-
cate for any particular norm, but rather to show how the existence of a
range of possible norms in either case could be explained by understand-
ing assertion as involving a promise-like commitment (and simultaneous
keeping or breaking of that promise). Moreover, although norms on
promise-making cannot simply be reduced to the norm of avoiding
promises that will be broken, they must ultimately be understood in terms
of that goal.
Given that trustworthiness prompts us to confine our commitments
within the boundaries of our competence, what obstacles might get in
our way? In this section, I focus on obstacles to being competent, and
then on obstacles to knowing what competences we have. But first I need
to clarify the conception of competence which is at stake here: what is it
to be competent to fulfil a commitment? The conception which matters
for trustworthiness is one which renders competence highly sensitive to
the circumstances of action: what counts is successful action (including
truthful speech in the context of assertion), rather than underlying skills
or qualities which may be frustrated by environmental conditions before
they result in successful action. This is not because successful action is
all that matters in life. Nor do I imagine that success is usually possible
without underlying skill or capability. It is because I have tied trust-
worthiness to the avoidance of unfulfilled commitment, not just to good
intentions, not just to attempts to avoid unfulfilled commitment, and not
just to being poised to avoid unfulfilled commitment if all goes well.
The fewer skills and capacities you have which are actionable in your
environment, the fewer safe but substantive commitments you can
make. Conversely, the better the match between your skills and the
5.2 Obstacles to Knowing One ’ s Competence 107
situations in which you act, the less often you will be forced to choose
between trustworthiness and commitment, because you can have both.
This is one reason why skill is valuable: it enables us to be trustworthy
without sacrificing generosity, adventure, or the opportunity to learn.
This is also a reason why it is valuable to live in circumstances which
make it easy to act on whatever skills we possess. I will review some ways
in which circumstances help determine what we can do, before discussing
how circumstances also play a role in determining what we can know
about what we can do.
Circumstances can be relevant to what we can do either through
causal influences or more directly by constituting the circumstances
under which we need to act. Causal influences here include all the very
many widely recognized factors such as education, family support in
childhood, physical training, inheritances, and past purchases or savings,
which make each of us who we are today, with all of our skills, knowledge,
material and social resources, strengths, and weaknesses.
Even granted all that history, each of us now faces different opportun-
ities and obstacles in trying to act successfully in the world. Imagine two
parents, living in different parts of the same city, both trying to get their
kids to school on time every day. The first person is financially comfort-
able, and lives within walking distance of the school; her kids have no
special medical needs or behavioural problems, and mostly enjoy school.
The second person lives in cramped temporary accommodation, and
can’t always afford to provide breakfast; her kids have a variety of special
needs, and are very reluctant to attend school. Obviously, it is easier for
the first parent to get her kids to school punctually than it is for the
second parent; if they switched places, as in an exploitative TV show,
then their ‘success rates’ would change.
Let’s imagine that these parents are in some intrinsic sense equally
as talented and capable as each other, whatever that might mean.
Nevertheless, it is much harder for one of them to act successfully in this
respect than it is for the other, since they face very different challenges
from the circumstances in which they must act. How should we describe
this difference in terms of competence? It is politically and ethically
attractive to think of both parents in my story as equally competent,
noting that whilst this level of competence is sufficient for success in the
easy environment, it is far from sufficient for success in the challenging
108 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
help or hinder our attempts to know what capacities we have. I have tied
trustworthiness to the fulfilment of commitment, in other words to suc-
cessful action. Obeying epistemic norms of commitment-undertaking is
in that sense a derivative requirement: this is a good means of ensuring
that one is trustworthy. There are many ways in which our circumstances
can create obstacles both to having the competence which is required in
order to fulfil a given commitment, and to knowing what competence
we have.
my own conscience on this matter. Or I may have to take your word for it
that my commitment is genuinely triggered because you really are stuck,
and no one else is available to help. In general, social circumstances help
determine whether I can trust you when you assure me that the condi-
tions have been satisfied, so that trustworthiness now requires me to act.
As before, in such situations we can distinguish the question of whether
someone is committed to action from the question of whether other
people sincerely regard her as committed to action. I have already
discussed the theoretical and practical uncertainty which surrounds the
role of other people’s attitudes in generating commitment for us; trust-
worthiness is at stake only where commitment has genuinely been
incurred. Depending on the framework we adopt, such uncertainties may
be understood as uncertainties about what trustworthiness demands of
us, or else as uncertainties about whether other people have an accurate
view of what trustworthiness demands of us.
How do we know what actions are demanded by our existing com-
mitments? Earlier, I discussed how epistemic obstacles can be generated
by varying local conventions of commitment. Such obstacles are also
relevant to this later temporal perspective, when we are trying to estab-
lish what commitments we have already incurred. In particular, cultural
dislocation can make it more difficult to know whether our offers to
commit have been taken seriously: if I suggest a lunch meeting, and you
don’t demur, have you thereby accepted my offer to commit to showing
up, or have you merely evaded the issue? These interactions can be a little
confusing at the best of times, but we are all the more prone to misunder-
standings when we are new to a country, a workplace, or a social circle.
As I will discuss in chapter 6, the flexibility with which we can choose
to respond to such uncertainties may depend a great deal upon our social
power, our ability to access alternative options, and the importance to us
of maintaining a reputation for trustworthiness. Some of us, some of the
time, can get away with simply blundering on through our hazy grasp of
existing commitments; some of us certainly cannot.
even once we know what our existing commitments are. This may be the
broadest category of obstacles—obstacles to action in general. As such,
it does not require special efforts to demonstrate that challenging cir-
cumstances can generate difficulties on this front: it is obvious that our
circumstances affect how we can act. By definition, challenging circum-
stances make it more difficult to act as we would like to do.
Correspondingly, this is the category where I have found least scope
for saying something which is distinctively relevant to trustworthiness.
This may be because it follows the preceding three sections: if we could
successfully overcome obstacles in all of the other three categories, then
there would be no special problem here. Obstacles to action are obstacles
to trustworthiness only when we have acquired a commitment which
demands that action of us. But if we already knew that a given commit-
ment would require us to act in a way which we would find difficult, and
if we had the freedom to decline that commitment without much cost,
then we could simply avoid getting into a situation where that obstacle
to action made it harder for us to be trustworthy. This might be a matter
of great regret, of course, if we have other reasons to want to act in that
way, with or without a commitment to doing so. But in itself it would
not diminish our trustworthiness.
Are there obstacles to appropriate action in the special case of
assertion—i.e. fulfilment of commitment to speak truthfully regarding
the matter at hand? Of course it is often not easy to have the knowledge
required for appropriate assertion. This is not a direct obstacle to trust-
worthiness: one can be trustworthy without having much knowledge or
competence, provided one can avoid becoming overcommitted. But
as we will see in the following chapter, lack of competence, and thus an
increased requirement to choose between trustworthiness and new
commitment, brings troubles of its own.
More direct challenges are faced by those who must communicate in
languages they have not mastered, those with speech or literacy difficul-
ties, or those who face other practical challenges to self-expression.
Treating assertion as simultaneous incurring and discharging (or not)
or commitment generates some complications here. For more ordinary
commitments to future action, there is a clear difference between con-
trolling what I am committed to doing (as discussed in section 5.1) and
controlling what I in fact do (the topic of this section). But with assertion,
control and lack of control over various different matters is entangled.
118 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
Additional Sources
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
96 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
ways which remain obscure to other people who occupy different, more
empowered standpoints.
Indeed, Charles W. Mills (2007) has shown how those who possess
power may rely upon on their own lack of insight as a means of perpetu-
ating this possession. Mills’s chief concern is with white ignorance in the
context of racism, but the point generalizes. Someone employed under
exploitative conditions may have an excellent understanding of how the
employer’s whims generate commitments for the employee, a better
understanding than the employer possesses or even wants to possess;
the same goes for people who are ‘self-employed’ in the gig economy. So
for all sorts of reasons we should bear in mind that there is an important
difference between having control over one’s commitments and having
insight into what they are; likewise, there is an important difference
between lacking control over one’s commitments and lacking insight
into them.
Nevertheless, insight is often helpful in achieving control of our com-
mitments. And even in relatively egalitarian company we may struggle
to grasp how our speech and actions will be interpreted by others. In
earlier chapters I dwelt upon explicit means of incurring commitment,
through promising and assertion. But there is a host of ways in which
subtle social conventions and defaults govern the incurring of less explicit
commitments. In many contexts, to accept a gift, hospitality or invitation
is to incur a commitment to reciprocate appropriately, whatever appro-
priateness turns out to require. To take a different example, often we can
become committed not just by actively claiming a commitment, but also
by failing to object or actively push back against others’ expectations of
us on this front. But it may not be clear how this opt-out works, when it
is happening, and when it is already too late to protest.
It is in the nature of these conventions that they are rarely made expli-
cit, except when we want to complain about people who violate our
expectations. And they easily vary between different families, groups of
friends, or workplaces, as well as across more obvious cultural divides
between nations or generations. This opens up the possibility of mutual
misunderstanding about what commitments different people carry, and
about what it takes for those commitments to be discharged.
How does all of this confusion place obstacles in the way of our
becoming trustworthy? First, suppose that you are fully aware of the
social conventions governing gifts, and realize that if you accept a gift, then
102 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
of, and we feel unsure whether we must act in line with commitments
others unexpectedly—mistakenly?—take us to have. This creates oppor-
tunities for guilt and for guilt-tripping, for anxiety and exploitation of
different kinds.
In thinking about how far commitment can exceed the scope of first-
personal grasp, we should at least agree that two extreme positions are
both unappealing. It cannot be that a person is never bound by commit-
ment unless she knows exactly what she is undertaking to do. Amongst
their other roles, commitment, trust, and trustworthiness are devices for
social coordination, and for reducing the so-called ‘transaction costs’ of
trying to work together. Much of this would be impossible if lack of full
transparency always voided commitments. It would also be exception-
ally burdensome if we constantly had to check on each other’s grasp of
exactly what commitments have been incurred in order to reasonably
hold people to account. Some flexibility here is a benefit to all of us, both
as it enables us to trust others without detailed investigation, and as it
lures us into commitments which we do not fully understand yet will
ultimately value. To think otherwise is to adopt a superficially attractive
but unachievable cold ideal of utterly transparent autonomy.
On the other hand, it cannot be that we have no first-person advantage
whatsoever in understanding what commitments we have undertaken.
Commitments can play their social role only insofar as they are available
to guide our actions, at least where we are intrinsically or instrumentally
motivated to be trustworthy. Indeed, we need a grasp of our existing
commitments in order to judge which new commitments we can safely
incur. To the extent that commitments lie beyond an individual’s control
or insight, they are entangled with the behaviour, attitudes, and expect-
ations of other people. But one of the guiding themes of earlier chapters
was that trustworthiness does not require us to respond to each and every
demand which is placed upon us. Sometimes when people think that we
are untrustworthy for not doing as they wish, those people are mistaken.
Sometimes when others think we have an obligation-generating com-
mitment to do something for them, they are mistaken. For these sorts of
reasons, we need to recognize that we are not just third-party observers
of our own commitments.
My remarks here blur various senses of epistemic and practical
authority, without properly pinning down the relationships between these.
But a concept of commitment which can underpin a useful concept of
104 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
another, because without social support they have no other safety net.
All of these complications further illustrate that ability to control one’s
commitments is not uniformly or equitably distributed.
In this section I have investigated obstacles to controlling our com-
mitments, and thus obstacles to being trustworthy. Even if we accept
that there is no such thing as an involuntary commitment, practical
circumstances of many kinds can make it much more difficult for people
to avoid commitments, even when they are fully aware of what is going
on; the price of avoiding commitment may be unaffordably high. In
addition, there are many situations in which we are unsure of how our
actions and speech will be understood by other people as resulting in
our having incurred new commitment. Often the mere fact of others
seeing us as committed gives us strong reason to act as they anticipate.
But it seems that at least on occasion we do have commitments we are
unaware of, generated by the social significance of our actions and words.
In chapter 6 I discuss how we can or should respond to these various
situations, but before doing so I will review other types of obstacle to
trustworthiness.
to fulfil them, yet luckily avoid commitments she is in fact not competent
to fulfil. If she lacked insight into her own competence—and lacked insight
into her own lack of competence—this would not automatically render
her untrustworthy.
Nevertheless, on the assumption that we do not want to keep our
commitments to the bare minimum, and do not want to rely on mere luck
to render us trustworthy, we will need some insight into what we are
capable of doing. So obstacles to gaining that insight are for all practical
purposes obstacles to being trustworthy. Here we encounter in somewhat
different guise the debates around norms for assertion and promising
which I discussed in chapters 2 and 3. My strategy there was not to advo-
cate for any particular norm, but rather to show how the existence of a
range of possible norms in either case could be explained by understand-
ing assertion as involving a promise-like commitment (and simultaneous
keeping or breaking of that promise). Moreover, although norms on
promise-making cannot simply be reduced to the norm of avoiding
promises that will be broken, they must ultimately be understood in terms
of that goal.
Given that trustworthiness prompts us to confine our commitments
within the boundaries of our competence, what obstacles might get in
our way? In this section, I focus on obstacles to being competent, and
then on obstacles to knowing what competences we have. But first I need
to clarify the conception of competence which is at stake here: what is it
to be competent to fulfil a commitment? The conception which matters
for trustworthiness is one which renders competence highly sensitive to
the circumstances of action: what counts is successful action (including
truthful speech in the context of assertion), rather than underlying skills
or qualities which may be frustrated by environmental conditions before
they result in successful action. This is not because successful action is
all that matters in life. Nor do I imagine that success is usually possible
without underlying skill or capability. It is because I have tied trust-
worthiness to the avoidance of unfulfilled commitment, not just to good
intentions, not just to attempts to avoid unfulfilled commitment, and not
just to being poised to avoid unfulfilled commitment if all goes well.
The fewer skills and capacities you have which are actionable in your
environment, the fewer safe but substantive commitments you can
make. Conversely, the better the match between your skills and the
5.2 Obstacles to Knowing One ’ s Competence 107
situations in which you act, the less often you will be forced to choose
between trustworthiness and commitment, because you can have both.
This is one reason why skill is valuable: it enables us to be trustworthy
without sacrificing generosity, adventure, or the opportunity to learn.
This is also a reason why it is valuable to live in circumstances which
make it easy to act on whatever skills we possess. I will review some ways
in which circumstances help determine what we can do, before discussing
how circumstances also play a role in determining what we can know
about what we can do.
Circumstances can be relevant to what we can do either through
causal influences or more directly by constituting the circumstances
under which we need to act. Causal influences here include all the very
many widely recognized factors such as education, family support in
childhood, physical training, inheritances, and past purchases or savings,
which make each of us who we are today, with all of our skills, knowledge,
material and social resources, strengths, and weaknesses.
Even granted all that history, each of us now faces different opportun-
ities and obstacles in trying to act successfully in the world. Imagine two
parents, living in different parts of the same city, both trying to get their
kids to school on time every day. The first person is financially comfort-
able, and lives within walking distance of the school; her kids have no
special medical needs or behavioural problems, and mostly enjoy school.
The second person lives in cramped temporary accommodation, and
can’t always afford to provide breakfast; her kids have a variety of special
needs, and are very reluctant to attend school. Obviously, it is easier for
the first parent to get her kids to school punctually than it is for the
second parent; if they switched places, as in an exploitative TV show,
then their ‘success rates’ would change.
Let’s imagine that these parents are in some intrinsic sense equally
as talented and capable as each other, whatever that might mean.
Nevertheless, it is much harder for one of them to act successfully in this
respect than it is for the other, since they face very different challenges
from the circumstances in which they must act. How should we describe
this difference in terms of competence? It is politically and ethically
attractive to think of both parents in my story as equally competent,
noting that whilst this level of competence is sufficient for success in the
easy environment, it is far from sufficient for success in the challenging
108 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
help or hinder our attempts to know what capacities we have. I have tied
trustworthiness to the fulfilment of commitment, in other words to suc-
cessful action. Obeying epistemic norms of commitment-undertaking is
in that sense a derivative requirement: this is a good means of ensuring
that one is trustworthy. There are many ways in which our circumstances
can create obstacles both to having the competence which is required in
order to fulfil a given commitment, and to knowing what competence
we have.
my own conscience on this matter. Or I may have to take your word for it
that my commitment is genuinely triggered because you really are stuck,
and no one else is available to help. In general, social circumstances help
determine whether I can trust you when you assure me that the condi-
tions have been satisfied, so that trustworthiness now requires me to act.
As before, in such situations we can distinguish the question of whether
someone is committed to action from the question of whether other
people sincerely regard her as committed to action. I have already
discussed the theoretical and practical uncertainty which surrounds the
role of other people’s attitudes in generating commitment for us; trust-
worthiness is at stake only where commitment has genuinely been
incurred. Depending on the framework we adopt, such uncertainties may
be understood as uncertainties about what trustworthiness demands of
us, or else as uncertainties about whether other people have an accurate
view of what trustworthiness demands of us.
How do we know what actions are demanded by our existing com-
mitments? Earlier, I discussed how epistemic obstacles can be generated
by varying local conventions of commitment. Such obstacles are also
relevant to this later temporal perspective, when we are trying to estab-
lish what commitments we have already incurred. In particular, cultural
dislocation can make it more difficult to know whether our offers to
commit have been taken seriously: if I suggest a lunch meeting, and you
don’t demur, have you thereby accepted my offer to commit to showing
up, or have you merely evaded the issue? These interactions can be a little
confusing at the best of times, but we are all the more prone to misunder-
standings when we are new to a country, a workplace, or a social circle.
As I will discuss in chapter 6, the flexibility with which we can choose
to respond to such uncertainties may depend a great deal upon our social
power, our ability to access alternative options, and the importance to us
of maintaining a reputation for trustworthiness. Some of us, some of the
time, can get away with simply blundering on through our hazy grasp of
existing commitments; some of us certainly cannot.
even once we know what our existing commitments are. This may be the
broadest category of obstacles—obstacles to action in general. As such,
it does not require special efforts to demonstrate that challenging cir-
cumstances can generate difficulties on this front: it is obvious that our
circumstances affect how we can act. By definition, challenging circum-
stances make it more difficult to act as we would like to do.
Correspondingly, this is the category where I have found least scope
for saying something which is distinctively relevant to trustworthiness.
This may be because it follows the preceding three sections: if we could
successfully overcome obstacles in all of the other three categories, then
there would be no special problem here. Obstacles to action are obstacles
to trustworthiness only when we have acquired a commitment which
demands that action of us. But if we already knew that a given commit-
ment would require us to act in a way which we would find difficult, and
if we had the freedom to decline that commitment without much cost,
then we could simply avoid getting into a situation where that obstacle
to action made it harder for us to be trustworthy. This might be a matter
of great regret, of course, if we have other reasons to want to act in that
way, with or without a commitment to doing so. But in itself it would
not diminish our trustworthiness.
Are there obstacles to appropriate action in the special case of
assertion—i.e. fulfilment of commitment to speak truthfully regarding
the matter at hand? Of course it is often not easy to have the knowledge
required for appropriate assertion. This is not a direct obstacle to trust-
worthiness: one can be trustworthy without having much knowledge or
competence, provided one can avoid becoming overcommitted. But
as we will see in the following chapter, lack of competence, and thus an
increased requirement to choose between trustworthiness and new
commitment, brings troubles of its own.
More direct challenges are faced by those who must communicate in
languages they have not mastered, those with speech or literacy difficul-
ties, or those who face other practical challenges to self-expression.
Treating assertion as simultaneous incurring and discharging (or not)
or commitment generates some complications here. For more ordinary
commitments to future action, there is a clear difference between con-
trolling what I am committed to doing (as discussed in section 5.1) and
controlling what I in fact do (the topic of this section). But with assertion,
control and lack of control over various different matters is entangled.
118 Obstacles to Being Trustworthy
Additional Sources
How To Be Trustworthy. Katherine Hawley, Oxford University Press (2019). © Katherine Hawley.
DOI: 10.1093/oso/9780198843900.001.0001
6.1 How We See Each Other 121
issues, though as ever it does not provide neat and tidy resolutions.
Commitment and competence are logically separate: one can behave
competently whilst free of commitment, and of course one can have
commitments one is not competent to fulfil, even though that makes for
untrustworthiness. In chapter 5 I treated commitment and competence
(as linked to successful action) as independent levers which we control
imperfectly, trying to bring our commitments in line with our competence
to act, and our actions in line with our existing commitments.
But from the observer’s perspective, there are inferential links around
the triad of trustworthiness, competence, and commitment, links which
rely upon the conceptual connections between these. Perhaps most
obviously, we can base judgements about other people’s trustworthiness
on our judgements (or misjudgements) of their competence and
commitments. If you regard someone as having undertaken a commit-
ment, yet fail to recognize that her actions are in line with that
commitment, then you will mistakenly infer that she is untrustworthy.
Someone who finds it difficult to get others to recognize her successful
actions therefore has an incentive not to take on such commitments
in the first place. Otherwise she risks being unfairly regarded as
untrustworthy.
Conversely, if you mistakenly think that someone has undertaken a
commitment, and accurately recognize that her actions are not line with
that purported commitment, then you will mistakenly infer that she is
untrustworthy. Someone who is often misunderstood in this way therefore
has an incentive to behave as other people think that she should, even if
her commitments do not really require her to act in that way. In the special
case of speech, this is the situation of someone who is inadvertently
taken to be making assertions when she intends only to speculate or
question, and so must be cautious about what she says.
But these inferences can also run from trustworthiness to competence
or commitment. If you regard someone as trustworthy, then you can
draw conclusions about her competence from what you take her
commitments to be, and vice versa. After all, a trustworthy person will
avoid commitments which are unmatched by competence. For example
if your friend offers to drive you to the station, and you regard her as
trustworthy, then you simply assume that she has access to a car and
knows how to drive: she would not have offered otherwise. You infer
from commitment and trustworthiness to competence.
6.1 How We See Each Other 123
To take another example, suppose that you are chatting with your
wheelchair-using friend, someone you regard as trustworthy. You talk
about your plans for a group hike and picnic, and your friend says ‘that
sounds great, I’d love to come along’. If you assume that your friend’s
wheelchair means that she can’t participate in a hike, you may assume
that she is politely or wistfully endorsing your plans, which don’t include
her. You infer from trustworthiness and lack of competence to lack of
commitment; after all, she would not undertake to do something she
cannot manage. If instead you are open to the idea that your friend is
competent to participate in a hike (if you choose an accessible route),
then you can hear your friend’s words as a commitment to come along,
indeed as an expression of her trust in you to make this feasible.
Dropping the assumption that she lacks competence on this front blocks
the inference to a lack of commitment.
When we take people to be trustworthy, and regard them as lacking
competence in some respect, we can infer that they do not have a
commitment which requires that competence. Moreover we can also
infer that they would not take on such a commitment even if we invited
them to do so. After all, trustworthiness involves an effort to avoid
commitments unmatched by competence. Such inferences colour our
interpretation of what others say, as in the case of the (in)accessible hike.
But they also affect the way in which we think prospectively about issuing
invitations or offers, and about asking for help or expertise. There is no
point asking a trustworthy yet incompetent person, since she will have
to decline any potential commitment. Mistakes and misjudgements on
this front seem compatible with at least superficial well-meaningness,
and a positive outlook on the other person’s moral character: it’s exactly
because we admire the other person’s trustworthiness that we infer
from our low opinion of her competence to a low expectation of her
commitments.
As a special case of this inferential pattern, when we take a speaker to
be trustworthy we may use the content of what she says as a guide to the
force with which it is being expressed. For example if someone says
something which appears ludicrously implausible, we may infer that she
is joking, or being sarcastic, or speaking metaphorically. Such an infer-
ence seems to depend upon an assumption about what the speaker is
likely to know: she must know how implausible this claim is, and she’s a
sensible (trustworthy) person, so surely she can’t seriously be asserting
124 Consequences
For example, someone who has only one friend, a person who makes
unreasonable demands upon her, may be forced to choose between
accepting unsafe commitments (thus risking untrustworthiness) and
losing her only social contact. Someone who needs to see a doctor, and
will struggle to make it to the appointment on time because she relies
upon poor public transport, must choose between a risky commitment
to show up on time and a certainty of not seeing the doctor at all.
People living in challenging circumstances, with few material or social
resources, will more often pay a very high price if they prioritize
trustworthiness—the avoidance of unfulfilled commitment—over other
needs or desires. Some such costs must be imposed on others: imagine
that it is a child who needs medical attention, but the parent who must
undertake to get them to the doctor’s. It is broadly possible to decide
not to make a commitment in such circumstances, but the practical,
personal, and social cost is high.
In other situations, we cannot simply decide not to accept commitment,
even if we are willing to pay the price of this choice. Whether or not we
incur a new commitment is often not a matter of direct choice. For
example, when we are unclear about how our actions or speech may
commit us, it is hard to know how to implement a decision not to take
on a new commitment. Both the demanding friend and the distant doctor
cases can be understood as epistemically transparent to the person
concerned: she knows what it would take to incur, or not to incur, this
commitment, and she understands the costs and risks associated with
each option. But in other situations we have difficulties in understand-
ing what sorts of words or actions will land us with new commitments,
ones we may be reluctant or unwilling to fulfil.
How can we handle such situations? One strategy is to try to create a
margin of safety, to avoid doing anything with even a hint of possible
commitment attached. In practical terms this would mean not accepting
any kind of favours, not doing anything which might call for reciprocation,
not showing interest in possible commitments, and so on. For the
special case of potentially informative speech, this strategy might appeal
to someone who struggles to control the force of her speech, and
cannot reliably prevent it from becoming an assertion: she might try to
speak as little as possible since she cannot be sure of making her speech
128 Consequences
skills. It is not so nice to say simply that you don’t like entertaining, or
can’t be bothered to cook—it takes nerve to request commitment-free
dinner on those grounds.
But we may struggle to know which excuses for avoiding commit-
ment will be accepted without social cost, and which will not, leaving us
with the commitment plus the negative consequences of having tried to
avoid it. A hard-pressed doctor’s receptionist, for example, is unlikely to
give us permission to just try to show up, especially if appointments are
over-subscribed. If there is a formal or informal penalty for missing
appointments, we can’t easily ask to be excused, no matter how tough
our circumstances, and asking for special consideration may itself
attract censure. Similarly, it’s not always possible to avoid the perceived
commitments associated with assertion even when we include hedging
terms—under such circumstances the safer option is not to speak at all.
How might all of this manoeuvring look to observers who are not
fully aware of the challenges posed by circumstances? From this outside
perspective, imagine someone who opts to pay the high social cost of
avoiding a particular commitment. Suppose we do not realize how difficult
it will be for that person to fulfil that commitment, or at least how
difficult it is for her to know what she can do; perhaps it’s the kind of
thing that would be easy for us to manage. Then the refusal to become
committed looks perversely unmotivated: we may simply assume that
she is antisocial, lacking confidence, or not a ‘team player’.
Or imagine someone who makes what seem to be absurdly cautious
attempts to specify exactly what she can and can’t commit to doing,
offering up conditions and potential excuses. Again, imagine that we do
not appreciate how difficult it is for this person to know whether she will
be able to act as required, perhaps because she knows how unstable or
hostile her circumstances are likely to be. To us, the person will appear
to be simply a fusspot, or self-centred, or unreliable: we won’t see these
superficially irritating behaviours as evidence of her admirable under-
lying motive.
I argued in chapter 5 that people are more likely to face obstacles to
controlling their commitments if they are living in difficult circumstances—
different types of difficulty generate different types of obstacle. My point
in the present section is that such difficulties can be compounded by
130 Consequences
and know you will be unable to turn down ‘requests’ for late working,
then you may choose not to make social arrangements with friends and
family, so that you don’t end up having to let them down when new
work commitments are imposed upon you. This sort of behaviour may
seem especially puzzling to onlookers who don’t realize your vulner-
ability to your boss: your efforts to remain trustworthy look like a
self-centred unwillingness to socialize.
Looking beyond the strategy of becoming more competent, what
about trying to become more knowledgeable of one’s existing competence?
We can try to reduce the relevant uncertainties. For example, we may
pursue cautious enquiry, attempting to make things more explicit,
investigating and questioning before we take on new commitments;
such investigation may be directed towards the expectations of the
person asking us to take on a commitment, towards the circumstances
in which we will need to act, or towards our own strengths and weak-
nesses. The more successful we are in such enquiries, the more we will
understand what we may be undertaking to do, and the more we
will understand our chances of being able to fulfil such a commitment.
This kind of caution is not cost-free. In itself it uses up time, energy,
and other resources; by assumption this challenge often affects people
who don’t have a lot of time, energy, or resources to spare. But in
addition such caution can either improve or damage our image in
the eyes of people around us. Careful examination and weighing of
potential commitments may be seen—often rightly—as a sign of
trustworthiness, of being the kind of person who takes commitments
seriously and is anxious not to incur debts that cannot be repaid. On
the other hand, if this is read as ostentatious or excessive caution it
can prompt impatience in those around us, who wish we’d just make
up our minds.
To some extent, different reactions to such caution may be linked to
disagreements about what I earlier called ‘meta-commitments’. In the
context of an ongoing relationship, whether professional or personal,
one person may view another as having already committed to taking on
new commitments, to accepting new requests or tasks, for example. If
that’s the expectation, then overscrupulousness about new commit-
ments can itself be seen as a form of untrustworthiness, a violation of
previous commitment.
6.3 Obstacles to Grasping Our Competence 133
they don’t know what evidence is available to us, or because they don’t
appreciate our lack of self-confidence—then they may struggle to
understand other aspects of our behaviour.
We use these strategies in an attempt to preserve our trustworthiness,
and our reputation for trustworthiness. But they are easily misunder-
stood by people who think we could preserve our trustworthiness
without taking these measures; such misunderstanding can lead them to
reach for other, less flattering explanations of our behaviour.
assistance of Heal (2013), that this did not play nicely with my overall
approach. Nevertheless, the traces of Kukla’s arguments and examples
lie just below the surface at various points. And, like Fricker and Dotson,
she demonstrates how philosophical concepts and distinctions can
illuminate untidy but vitally important practical situations.
Kukla is concerned with the interplay of social power and the force of
speech acts. She takes a speech act to be something which requires
substantive contribution from both speaker and audience: a speaker’s
intentions are insufficient to determine the force of what she says, even
when those intentions are recognized. Thus people sometimes try but
fail to commit themselves through speech because of their social context,
not least because of their social identities.
In one of Kukla’s fascinating examples, a woman manager works in a
male-dominated environment: she issues orders to her team using
phrasing which would mark them as orders if given by a man in that
context. Nevertheless, because of the unfamiliarity of female authority
in this environment, the woman’s utterances are heard as mere requests
rather than as orders. They get relatively low compliance, which rein-
forces the idea that the woman lacks authority. Moreover because the
woman does not see herself as merely making requests, she does not
display gratitude when the workers do comply, and so they resent her
for this ingratitude. There is no easy way out of this difficulty for the
woman manager: if she further emphasizes that she is giving orders,
she will be further resented, and if she displays gratitude, this reinforces
the idea that she is merely making requests which the workers are free to
grant or deny. (Recall the situation of an employer speaking to striking
workers, discussed in section 6.2.)
On this picture, an audience can quash the speaker’s intended force,
or transform it into a different, unintended force. If I intend to assert,
yet others hear me as merely questioning, then I am questioning.
Moreover we can extend the picture to understand how people may end
up more committed than they would like to be, rather than less commit-
ted. For example, in a committee setting, suggesting that something
should be done may be treated as offering to do that thing, especially if
the speaker is already regarded as being the kind of person who takes on
such tasks. If such a person makes a suggestion (as she sees it) then fails
to follow through with action, this will be seen as untrustworthy
6.5 Testimony and Testimonials 141
Additional Sources
6.1 How We See Each Other. Marsh (2011) discusses our duties to trust
one another, whilst Oderberg (2013) argues that we should err on the
side of over-estimating others’ reputations rather than underestimating
them. I explore some related issues in Hawley (2014b). D’Cruz (2015)
draws out the connections between trust, trustworthiness, and consist-
ency of character. Other valuable work in this broader area includes
Gambetta (2011), Jones (2012), Medina (2013), Origgi (2017), and
Williams (2002).
6.2 Responding to Limited Control of Our Commitments. Sources
listed for section 5.1 are relevant here.
6.3 Responding to Obstacles to Grasping Our Competence. Sources
listed for section 5.2 are relevant here.
6.4 Retrospective Perspectives. Sources listed for section 5.1 are rele-
vant here.
6.5 Testimony and Testimonials. I draw more explicit connections
between trust, distrust and epistemic injustice in my (2017a). Peet (2015)
provides another perspective on what can go wrong with speech, whilst
both Kukla and Dotson trace links to work such as Langton (1992),
Hornsby (1994), and Hornsby and Langton (1998). The papers collected
within Maitra and McGowan (eds) (2012) are also significant.
References
Alston, William (2000), Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press).
Altham, J. E. J. (1985), ‘Wicked Promises’, in Ian Hacking (ed.), Exercises in Analysis
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), 1–21.
Austin, J. L. (1946), ‘Other Minds’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 20: 148–87.
Baier, Annette C. (1986), ‘Trust and Antitrust’, Ethics 96: 231–60.
Bird, Alexander (2002), ‘Illocutionary Silencing’, Pacific Philosophical Quarterly
83: 1–15.
Brandom, Robert (1983), ‘Asserting’, Noûs 17: 637–50.
Brown, Jessica and Cappelen, Herman (eds) (2011), Assertion (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Calhoun, Cheshire (2009), ‘What Good is Commitment? ’, Ethics 119: 613–41.
Cappelen, Herman (2011), ‘Against Assertion’, in Jessica Brown and Herman
Cappelen (eds), Assertion (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 21–48.
Carson, Thomas L. (2010), Lying and Deception (New York: Oxford University Press).
Chang, Ruth (2013), ‘Commitment, Reasons and the Will’, in Russ Shafer-Landau
(ed.), Oxford Studies in Metaethics, vol.8 (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 74–113.
D’Cruz, Jason (2015), ‘Trust, Trustworthiness, and the Moral Consequence of
Consistency’, Journal of the American Philosophical Association 1.3: 467–84.
D’Cruz, Jason and Kalef, Justin (2015), ‘Promising to Try’, Ethics 125.3: 797–806.
Darwall, Stephen (2017), ‘Trust as a Second-Personal Attitude (of the Heart)’, in
Paul Faulkner and Thomas Simpson (eds), Philosophy of Trust (Oxford: Oxford
University Press), 35–50.
DeRose, Keith (2002), ‘Assertion, Knowledge, and Context’, Philosophical Review
111: 167–203.
Domenicucci, Jacopo and Holton, Richard (2017), ‘Trust as a Two-Place Relation’, in
Paul Faulkner and Thomas Simpson (eds), Philosophy of Trust (Oxford: Oxford
University Press), 149–60.
Dotson, Kristie (2011), ‘Tracking Epistemic Violence, Tracking Practices of
Silencing’, Hypatia 26.2: 236–57.
Dougherty, Tom (2015), ‘Yes Means Yes: Consent as Communication’, Philosophy
and Public Affairs 43.3: 224–53.
Driver, Julia (1983), ‘Promises, Obligations, and Abilities’, Philosophical Studies
44: 221–3.
Driver, Julia (2011), ‘Promising Too Much’, in Hanoch Sheinman (ed.), Promises and
Agreements (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 183–97.
Faulkner, Paul (2007), ‘On Telling and Trusting’, Mind 116: 875–902.
Faulkner, Paul (2015), ‘The Attitude of Trust is Basic’, Analysis 75.3: 424–9.
144 References
Faulkner, Paul (2017), ‘The Problem of Trust’, in Paul Faulkner and Thomas Simpson
(eds), Philosophy of Trust (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 109–28.
Frankfurt, Harry (2005), On Bullshit (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
Fricker, Elizabeth (2006), ‘Second-Hand Knowledge’, Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research 73.3: 592–618.
Fricker, Elizabeth (2012), ‘Stating and Insinuating’, Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society Supplementary Volume 86.1: 61–94.
Fricker, Miranda (2007), Epistemic Injustice (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Gambetta, Diego (2011), Codes of the Underworld (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press).
Gettier, Edmund (1963), ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’, Analysis 23: 121–3.
Goldberg, Sanford C. (2015), Assertion (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Govier, Trudy (1993), ‘Self-Trust, Autonomy, and Self-Esteem’, Hypatia 8.1: 99–120.
Grice, Paul (1989), Studies in the Way of Words (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press).
Hardin, Russell (2002), Trust and Trustworthiness (New York: Russell Sage Foundation).
Hardin, Russell (ed.) (2004), Distrust (New York: Russell Sage Foundation).
Hawley, Katherine (2003), ‘Success and Knowledge-How’, American Philosophical
Quarterly 40.1: 19–31.
Hawley, Katherine (2011), ‘Knowing How and Epistemic Injustice’, in John
Bengson and Marc A. Moffett (eds), Knowing How (Oxford: Oxford University
Press), 283–99.
Hawley, Katherine (2012), Trust: A Very Short Introduction (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Hawley, Katherine (2014a), ‘Trust, Distrust and Commitment’, Noûs 48: 1–20.
Hawley, Katherine (2014b), ‘Partiality and Prejudice in Trusting’, Synthese 191:
2029–45.
Hawley, Katherine (2017a), ‘Trust, Distrust, and Epistemic Injustice’, in Ian J. Kidd,
José Medina, and Gaile Pohlhaus Jr (eds), Routledge Handbook of Epistemic
Injustice (London: Routledge), 69–78.
Hawley, Katherine (2018a), ‘Coercion and Lies’, in Eliot Michaelson and Andreas
Stokke (eds), Lying: Language, Knowledge, Ethics, and Politics (Oxford: Oxford
University Press), 229–45.
Hawley, Katherine (2018b), ‘Creativity and Knowledge’, in Berys Gaut and Matthew
Kieran (eds), Creativity and Philosophy (London: Routledge), 60–73.
Hawley, Katherine (2019), ‘What Is Impostor Syndrome?’, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 93.1: 203–26.
Hawthorne, John and Stanley, Jason (2008), ‘Knowledge and Action’, Journal of
Philosophy 105.10: 571–90.
Heal, Jane (2013), ‘Illocution, Recognition, and Co-operation’, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume 87: 137–54.
Heuer, Ulrike (2012a), ‘Promising: Part 1’, Philosophy Compass 7.12: 832–41.
Heuer, Ulrike (2012b), ‘Promising: Part 2’, Philosophy Compass 7.12: 842–51.
Hinchman, Edward S. (2005), ‘Telling as Inviting to Trust’, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 70.3: 562–87.
Hollis, Martin (1998), Trust Within Reason (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
References 145
Holton, Richard (1994), ‘Deciding to Trust, Coming to Believe’, Australasian Journal
of Philosophy 72: 63–76.
Holton, Richard (2009), Willing, Wanting, Waiting (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Hornsby, Jennifer (1994), ‘Illocution and its Significance’, in Savas L Tsohatzidis
(ed.), Foundations of Speech Act Theory (London: Routledge), 187–207.
Hornsby, Jennifer and Langton, Rae (1998), ‘Free Speech and Illocution’, Legal
Theory 4.1: 21–37.
Intemann, Kristen (2010), ‘25 Years of Feminist Empiricism and Standpoint Theory:
Where Are We Now?’, Hypatia 25: 778–96.
Jones, Karen (1996), ‘Trust as an Affective Attitude’, Ethics 107: 4–25.
Jones, Karen (2002), ‘The Politics of Credibility’, in Louise Antony and Charlotte
Witt (eds), A Mind of One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity (2nd
edn, Boulder, CO: Westview Press), 154–76.
Jones, Karen (2004), ‘Trust and Terror’, in Peggy DesAutels and Margaret Urban
Walker (eds), Moral Psychology (Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield), 3–18.
Jones, Karen (2012), ‘Trustworthiness’, Ethics 123.1: 61–85.
Jones, Karen (2013), ‘Distrusting the Trustworthy’, in David Archard, Monique
Deveaux, Neil Manson, and Daniel Weinstock (eds), Reading Onora O’Neill
(London: Routledge), 186–98.
Krishnamurthy, Meena (2015), ‘(White) Tyranny and the Democratic Value of
Distrust’, The Monist 94.8: 391–406.
Kukla, Rebecca (2014), ‘Performative Force, Convention and Discursive Injustice’,
Hypatia 29.2: 440–57.
Lackey, Jennifer (2008), Learning From Words (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Langton, Rae (1992), ‘Speech Acts and Unspeakable Acts’, Philosophy and Public
Affairs 22: 293–330.
Lawlor, Krista (2013), Assurance (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
MacFarlane, John (2005), ‘Making Sense of Relative Truth’, Proceedings of the
Aristotelian Society 105: 321–39.
MacFarlane, John (2011), ‘What Is Assertion?’, in Jessica Brown and Herman
Cappelen (eds), Assertion (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 79–96.
Maitra, Ishani (2010), ‘The Nature of Epistemic Injustice’, Philosophical Books 51.4:
195–211.
Maitra, Ishani (2011), ‘Assertion, Norms and Games’, in Jessica Brown and Herman
Cappelen (eds), Assertion (Oxford: Oxford University Press), 277–96.
Maitra, Ishani and McGowan, Mary Kate (eds) (2012), Speech and Harm:
Controversies Over Free Speech (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Marsh, Gerald (2011), ‘Trust, Testimony and Prejudice in the Credibility Economy’,
Hypatia 26.2: 280–93.
Marušić, Berislav (2013), ‘Promising Against the Evidence’, Ethics 123.2: 292–317.
Marušić, Berislav (2015), Evidence and Agency (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
McLeod, Carolyn (2002), Self-Trust and Reproductive Autonomy (Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press).
McLeod, Carolyn (2015), ‘Trust’, in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia
of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2015/
entries/trust/.
146 References
Medina, José (2013), The Epistemology of Resistance: Gender and Racial Oppression,
Epistemic Injustice, and Resistant Imaginations (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Mills, Charles W. (2007), ‘White Ignorance’, in Shannon Sullivan and Nancy Tuana
(eds), Race and Epistemologies of Ignorance (Albany, NY: State University of New
York Press), 11–38.
Moran, Richard (2005), ‘Getting Told and Being Believed’, Philosophers Imprint
5.5: 1–29.
Nickel, Philip J. (2007), ‘Trust and Obligation-Ascription’, Journal of Ethical Theory
and Moral Practice 10: 309–19.
Oderberg, David (2013), ‘The Morality of Reputation and the Judgement of Others’,
Journal of Practical Ethics 1.2: 3–33.
O’Neill, Onora (2002a), Autonomy and Trust in Bioethics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press).
O’Neill, Onora (2002b), A Question of Trust (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Origgi, Gloria (2017), Reputation (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
Owens, David (2006), ‘Testimony and Assertion’, Philosophical Studies 130.1: 105–29.
Owens, David (2012), Shaping the Normative Landscape (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Peet, Andrew (2015), ‘Epistemic Injustice in Utterance Interpretation’, Synthese
194.9: 3421–43.
Peirce, C. S. (1932), Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, vol 2, ed.
C. Hartshorne and P. Weiss (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Potter, Nancy Nyquist (2002), How Can I Be Trusted? (Lanham, MD: Rowan and
Littlefield).
Putnam, Robert D. (2000), Bowling Alone: The Collapse and Revival of American
Community (New York: Simon and Schuster).
Ratcliffe, Matthew, Ruddell, Mark, and Smith, Benedict (2014), ‘What is a Sense of
‘Foreshortened Future’? A Phenomenological Study of Trauma, Trust and Time’,
Frontiers in Psychology 5: article 1026.
Rawls, John (1971), A Theory of Justice (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Rescorla, Michael (2009), ‘Assertion and its Constitutive Norms’, Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research 79: 98–130.
Sakulku, Jaruwan and Alexander, James (2011), ‘The Impostor Phenomenon’,
International Journal of Behavioral Science 6.1: 73–92.
Sarsons, Heather and Xu, Guo (2015), ‘Confidence Men? Gender and Confidence:
Evidence Among Top Economists’, working paper, https://scholar.harvard.edu/
files/sarsons/files/confidence_final.pdf/.
Saul, Jennifer (2012), Lying, Misleading, and What Is Said (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Scanlon, T. M. (1998), What We Owe to Each Other (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press).
Searle, John (1969), Speech Acts: An Essay in the Philosophy of Language (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press).
Sheinman, Hanoch (ed.) (2011), Promises and Agreements (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Shiffrin, Seana (2014), Speech Matters (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
References 147
Simon, Judith (2013), ‘Trust’, Oxford Bibliographies in Philosophy, http://www.
oxfordbibliographies.com/view/document/obo-9780195396577/obo-97801953
96577-0157.xml.
Smith, Holly M. (1997), ‘A Paradox of Promising’, Philosophical Review 106.2: 153–96.
Sosa, Ernest (2010), ‘How Competence Matters in Epistemology’, Philosophical
Perspectives, 24.1: 465–75.
Srinivasan, Amia (2015), ‘Normativity without Cartesian Privilege’, Philosophical
Issues 25.1: 273–99.
Stokke, Andreas (2014), ‘Insincerity’, Noûs 48.3: 496–520.
Stoljar, Natalie (2013), ‘Feminist Perspectives on Autonomy’, in Edward N. Zalta
(ed.), Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2015 Edition), https://plato.stan-
ford.edu/archives/fall2015/entries/feminism-autonomy/.
Strawson, P. F. (1974), ‘Freedom and Resentment’, in Freedom and Resentment
(London: Methuen), 1–25.
Sunstein, Cass (2007), ‘Moral Heuristics and Risk’, in Tim Lewens (ed.), Risk:
Philosophical Perspectives (London: Routledge), 156–70.
Thompson, Christopher (2017), ‘Trust Without Reliance’, Ethical Theory and Moral
Practice 20.3: 643–55.
Thomson, Judith Jarvis (1990), The Realm of Rights (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press).
Watson, Gary (2004), ‘Asserting and Promising’, Philosophical Studies 117.1–2: 57–77.
Weiner, Matthew (2005), ‘Must We Know What We Say?’, Philosophical Review
114.2: 227–51.
White, Roger (2005), ‘Epistemic Permissiveness’, Philosophical Perspectives 19: 445–59.
Williams, Bernard (2002), Truth and Truthfulness (Princeton, NJ: Princeton
University Press).
Williamson, Timothy (1996), ‘Knowing and Asserting’, Philosophical Review 105:
489–523.
Williamson, Timothy (2000), Knowledge and its Limits (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Zagzebski, Linda (1996), Virtues of the Mind (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Zimmerman, Michael (2014), Ignorance and Moral Responsibility (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).