Jacques Salvan - To Be and Not To Be - An Analysis of Jean-Paul Sartre's Ontology-Wayne State University Press (1962)
Jacques Salvan - To Be and Not To Be - An Analysis of Jean-Paul Sartre's Ontology-Wayne State University Press (1962)
by
Jacques Salvan
/ / BEING-IN-ITSELF 1
1. To be is to be perceived 1
2. To be is to be perceived by a perceiver who
is: the pre-reflective cogito 3
3. Being in itself 6
II BEING-FOR-ITSELF 10
__1. Negation and non-being 10
2. Non-being and liberty 15
3. Liberty and anguish 18
4. From anguish to bad faith: to be in order not
m~ n
5. Consciousness is not what it is; it is presence
to self 25
6. Consciousness is what it is not; that is its
facti city 27
/r.Being-in-itself-for-itself as the ideal value 29
8. From value to possibilities 31
9. Temporality 33
.-!if. Reflection 41
III BEING IN THE WORLD 46
1. Knowledge 46
2. Determination as negation 50
IX
CONTENTS
x
Introduction
sions and his City of God, the barbarians were invading his
native North Africa and the ancient world was crumbling
around him; the times could not have been more favorable
for the birth of a philosophy of crisis. That philosophy was
elaborated indeed in the anguish of the famous: "lrrequietum
est cor nostrum donee requieseat in Te": "Restless is our
heart until it may rest in Thee." The God that haunts human
consciousness, like Sartre's absolute value, is of course more
than a value; it is the most intimate part of myself: intimior
intimo mea ... , an absolute Thou, strictly the God of all
religious existentialists. Reconsidered in the light of existen-
tialism, Saint Augustine's is a most subjective philosophy
which takes its point of departure in the fact that while I may
doubt the ultimate reality of the world, I have to recognize
that I exist as doubt, therefore as thought (Descartes' eogito);
further, and this is of particular interest to us, that this con-
sciousness of existing as a thinking self is always with me,
even when my consciousness is completely absorbed by its
object (Sartre's pre-reflective eogito). It is this eogito, situ-
ated in the Here and Now, which brings together the dis-
persed elements of reality and, in a way, creates the W orId
(Heidegger's Dasein). Finally, the Augustinian notion of a
fundamental guilt attached to existence itself is a basic element
of modern existentialism, particularly in Heidegger and Sartre.
some way, they are the totality. Truth is Totality in the same
way as the truth of the paragraph is the book itself.
Kierkegaard claims that one cannot adopt the viewpoint
of the totality in this sort of objective idealism, because one
would have to be completely outside of it to do so. Hegel
appears to him as a self-appointed secretary of the absolute,
living in a shack while building his metaphysical palace. The
individual self is the real center of reference; truth is not
totality, truth is subjective intensity and absolute belief in the
absurd is better than lukewarm belief in the proven. In other
words, Truth is Faith, a communication between the believer
and God. God is not an object, a supreme Being, he is an
alter ego, a Thou, an absolute subject. When we consider our-
selves as part of a totality, we see ourselves as objects, and,
to Kierkegaard, there is no objective truth. Each subjectivity
is unique, closed upon itself, becoming itself through deeds,
and martyrdom is the supreme message, because it awakens
others to their subjectivity. The instant, which does not exist
in Heraclitean time, is our chance to become free, the inser-
tion of eternity within our becoming, our chance to make a
choice before God and to answer every alternative with "yes"
or "no." To choose is to choose oneself face to God. But,
before God, one can only feel guilty: guilty of standing, finite
and contingent, before the Infinite. Our finitude is our meta-
physical sin and we experience it in various kinds of anguish.
It is assumed in dread by the real Christian, who faces Jesus
Christ as his contemporary, not once for all but in an act of
faith constantly repeated. Of course, the average Christian is
satisfied with mere conformity to the practices of his religion;
but then he has no Self. Kierkegaard defines a hierarchy of
three planes of existence, corresponding, it seems, to the
beautiful, the good, and the true, and probably suggested by
xviii
INTRODUCTION
and even God as things; the It, indeed, is the original third
person. The I-Thou and the I-It are structures; through the
Thou a man becomes I. Buber's distinction between these two
planes will remain valid in all forms of modern existential-
ism. We might add, at this point, to our definition of this
movement that it is first and foremost a protest against objecti-
fication of the self and of the Other.
him, may precede the leap to the irrational. At the same time,
Simone de Beauvoir tells us, he disliked society but did not
dislike disliking it. As a professor in provinciallycees, he had
a difficult time fitting himself into the academic hierarchy. At
the French Institute in Berlin, where he had been sent on a
scholarship to study Husserl, it was a great relief for him to
be able to recapture the liberty of student life and forget
adult responsibility. Back in France, and already applying
Husserl's methods to various works, he was for a while dis-
turbed in his intellectual detachment by the Spanish Civil
War, but it was not until the Second World 'Var, while serv~
ing in the Army Weather Service near Strasbourg, that a
sense of responsibility toward the next generation dawned
upon him, together with the conception of a system of ethics
consisting in "assuming situations" and surpassing them in
action. The few months he spent in a prison camp confirmed
him in this resolution. Repatriated in 1941, he resumed his
teaching in Paris lycees for a while, then resigned to dedicate
himself to writing and political activities. The times were only
too favorable for a literature of crisis. The "extreme situ-
ations" imagined by Jaspers had become daily realities. Sartre
has described them in an often quoted passage of The Repub-
lic of Silence:
Exile, captivity, and especially death (which we usually
shrInk from facing at all in happier days) became for us the
habitual objects of our concern. We learnt that they were
neither inevitable accidents, nor even constant and inevitable
dangers, but that they must be considered as our lot itself,
our destiny, the profound source of our reality as men. At
every instant we lived up to the full sense of this common-
place little phrase: "Man is mortal!" And the choice that
each of us made of his life was an authentic choice because
it was made face to face with death, because it could always
XXXll
INTRODUCTION
The present work was undertaken, and its first draft com-
pleted, before the publication of Hazel Barnes' translation,
(Being and Nothingness) at a time when the public had no
access to Sartre's philosophy other than through a few super-
ficial, erroneous, prejudiced, or incomplete reviews, technical
accounts incomprehensible to the layman, or the sort of vul-
garization that does away with philosophical problems by
ignoring them. Since then, many studies have come out which,
even when fundamentally adverse, have managed to maintain
a high level of intellectual honesty. Full justification for the
present work no longer lies in the fact that it fulfils a recog-
nized need, but in the somewhat different way in which it
fulfils that need.
My presentation aims at allowing the reader to follow
Sartre's thought on three levels. The lines in italics indicate
the sequence of arguments on the philosophical plane. The
text embodies the development of these arguments on a some-
what more familiar plane of thought, and supplies their con-
crete illustration, either directly borrowed from Sartre, or
boldly supplemented by me. Furthermore, since we are deal-
ing with a sort of descriptive ontology, it seemed to me that
the reader might find it a little easier to follow a development
in which the very concept of being would figure as a sort of
guiding line. I, therefore, slightly modified the headings of
L'Etre et Ie neant, to conform to a general scheme which,
xli
INTRODUCTION
xlii
I Being-in-Itself
1. To be is to be perceived.
chair. Being as such, being per se, appears to me, not the
being of the chair. Somehow, then, the appearance of the
object-which is the being of the phenomenon-refers to being
per se, which appears to me as the phenomenon of being, yet
is not identical with the being of the phenomenon(The chair
is because I perceive it. It seems as if I, as perceiver, conferred
being upon the chair. Does this mean that, as Berkeley claims,
to be is to be perceive.f!j
r-
-----
this foundation be merely the conSClOusness of the subject? Is
it true that esse est percipi, that to be is to be p~d?
----
.consciousness is as intention. It has no contents and merely
aims at thinV
..
LIn a way yes, but not because consciousness knows the ob-
ject and knows itself at the same time; in that case we would
have to explain what knowledge~. The being of knowledge
, ,~' 3
TO BE AND NOT TO BE
3. Being in itself.
9
II Being-For-Itself
The man who says: "I hate myself for acting the way I
do," and considers this admission as a sort of justification, is
asking you to consider only his transcendent self, the self he
hopes to be some day, the self he is not; he is trying to con-
vince himself that he is not his present self: 1, the subject, a
pure and innocent consciousness, deny that I am myself, the
object of my contempt, through that very objectivation. I am
not what I am, and am what I am not, and I depend on you,
as a fellow human being, to grasp this mystery without effort.
To the extent to which I deceive myself in this process, I am
in bad faith. I disavow my actual behavior and ask to be
considered as a mere spectator of that behavior; but where is
that invisible gallery from which I have the privilege of
beholding my misbehavior?
.Being40r~itself
is a lack of being. If the for~itself could acquire
the concreteness of the in~itself, it would realize the ideal
value of being at once in itself and for itself·
.9. Temporality.
10. Reflection.
For the time being, let us note that he does not deny the
reality of tbe 'psyche; my psyche is, since it reveals itself to
my consciousness. It is like my shadow: what I see of myself
when I want to see myself. But it is only as a situation, even
if that situation is quite real for the being-for-itself, which, in
fact, can take its free leap into a transcendent future only
from a given situation. Let us remember also that reflection
confers on the data of the psyche a kind of duration which is
the original temporality degraded into a sort of being-in-
itself: a sense of "internal" or "qualitative" duration. The
being-for-itself, through reflection, may seem to have reached
a fairly concrete form, which is like a first sketch of the por-
trait it will seek in the consciousness of others. But this is
only an illusion. The being-far-itself exists primarily as tran-
scendence.
45.
III Being-In- The- World
1. Knowledge.
2. Determination as negation.
is also its past, 'or has to be its past. The self has to disperse
itself on its three temporal dimensions. It has to seek the
sense of its past in its future, but it also has to be its future
within the perspective' 'of a certain past. As I separate myself
from the past, I become not a pure negation, but the negation
of that past, a qualified negation. The sense of that negation
is in my past consciousness, which now stands out in bold
relief from among other things and other facts of the world.
This past which is now a mere datum, a thing-in-itself, and
as such my only concrete reality, I must save by grounding it
in consciousness, by giving it meaning:
The future is the past transcended (Ie passe depasse as a
given in-itself, toward an in-itself which would be its own
foundation, i.e., which would be insofar as I would have to
be it. My possible is the free resumption of that past insofar
as that resumption can save it by giving it a foundation. 52
5. World time.
came that being, the "such as it is" would vanish and could
not even be thought ... Knowledge places us in the pres-
ence of the absolute, and there is a truth of knowledge. But
that truth, although it delivers us nothing more or less than
the absolute, remains strictly human.53
61
IV Being-For-Others
Both the realist and the idealist conceitle my relation with the
other as external negation.
Sartre rejects both the idealist and the realist points of view
in regard to the existence of others:
At the origin of the problem of the existence of others, there
is a fundamental presupposition: my fellowman (autrui)
is the other, i.e., the Ego which is not my Ego, (le moi qui
n'est pas moi); we therefore detect a negation as the consti-
tutive structure of being-the-<:lther (l'hre-alltrui). The pre-
supposition common to idealism and realism is that the
constituting negation is one of exteriority.04
This is because the other appears to me through the perception
of a body. The realist sees himself separated from the other as
a chair is separated from the table: in space. The idealist may
reduce both his body and the body of the other to objective
62
BEING-FOR-OTHERS
The object that I become under the look of the other is not
of the type of the in-itself. I am still free, but my liberty has
been circumscribed. My transcendence has become a pure
datum. In the eyes of the other, I figure as limited transcen-
dence. My possibilities have been turned into probabilities.
My subjectivity has been objectified. In short, I am now a
transcended-transcendence. A somewhat forceful image of
what is meant here by "transcended transcendence" might
be suggested by the flight of a fugitive from justice, trapped
in a given area, darting in every possible direction toward
every possible issue and discovering at every move that his
space, as well as every possibility for escape, are thoroughly
covered. Even if he could not see his pursuers, he would
realize that their seeing him has alienated space for him: that
space he is standing in is no longer his own.
there are all around me signs of his presence far more im-
pressive than the human footprint on the sand of Robinson
Crusoe's island. All the tool-things of the world, and their
utensility, refer to that presence.
his rear lines, has seen his horizon closed by the enemy as by a
wall, and now his horizon opens up back of him as a refuge.
I can grasp the whole situation without ceasing to see the
soldier objectively.
85
TO BE AND NOT TO BE
These two basic attitudes are opposed to each other, but the
failure of one motivates the adoption of the other. The patterns
of behavior through which the for-itself attempts to assimilate
the other's liberty will, arbitrarily, be treated first.
the object which the other was waiting to meet and to accept
as the constant limit of any form of transcendence. He ex-
pects the loved one to become that self-limitation freely and
constantly. But, at the same time, he wants the other to retain
alterity, i.e., the negation by which the other refuses to be
him. If the lover could succeed in his design, he would be-
come, in his factual existence, the supreme value, the absolute
frame of reference, his organization of the tool-things of the
world would become that of the other: he would give the
loved one the "stars above" together with his love; he would
be a totality without losing objective concreteness. To become
a limiting object, the lover has, of course, to appear as a plenum
of being, to represent as much of the world as possible to the
loved one, in depth, in width, in power, so that the loved one
may the more easily realize the non-being of consciousness.
This latter experience has already been described as fascina-
tion. Seduction aims at arousing fascination. There is no love
without some form of seduction.
not face a look, at least you cannot look at a look, or, if you
do, you only see eyes. So long as I succeed in being a subject
for him, he apprehends himself as an object in my world,
and, as such, is not in a condition freely to recognize my
liberty, although he may feel its effects. The subsequent at-
tempts I may make to force that recognition are doomed. It
may be also that facing the glance of others is my original
reaction to his existence, and that I chose from the first con-
tact with him to build up my subjectivity on the collapse of
the other's.
with the third party and look at the second, who will become
our common object, or I may look at the third, who is looking
at the second, who is looking at me; or else I may look at both
the second and the third, disarm the look of the third party
and make them both objects for me. In this case, I may ex-
perience, through the second, the look of the third party
which is fixed upon him; he still appears as an object, but
not as an object for me. He may resent the fact that I look at
him while he is being looked at. The second and the third
parties may then look at me again to affirm in common their
subjectivity. It is, in any case, the presence of the third party
as subject which determines the consciousness of the "us."
"Us" refers to a common objectification, to a sentiment of
solidarity within that objectification. It expresses a factual
situation which has to be assumed and which corresponds
to the vanishing of the "we": "We were engaged in a conflict
when he came upon us." It is, of course, a humiliating experi-
ence, one which is particularly felt by any group conscious of
being used by somebody or by another group. And since, to
be felt, consciousness of the other requires neither the ex-
perience of his look, nor of his actual presence, some plurality
of individuals is always bound to feel that it is being used, or
objectified, by some other group or by the whole of humanity.
Hence class or nation consciousness. Class consciousness is due
neither to a feeling of common misery nor to oppression. It is
the feeling of existing for and through the liberty of the
other. "Thus the oppressed class finds its class unity in the
cognizance which the oppressing class takes of it, and the
appearance in the oppressed of class-consciousness corresponds
to the assumption, in shame, of an 'us.''' 70 The oppressed
class will react by the project of transforming the "us" into
a "we" through the affirmation of its subjectivity and of its
100
BEING-FOR-OTHERS
the can. In the same way, when I follow the signs to find my
way in the subway, I forget the individual purpose of my
trip; I am one of the other travellers; I am, as far as the
instructions given by the signs concern me, an interchangeable
human being of the type Heidegger refers to as "one," "they,"
"people." This is a form of Mitsein. If, on the other hand, I
am proceeding with others toward a common aim, as, for
instance, in an attack, or am simply working with them to-
ward the realization of a common enterprise, I experience a
different sort of collective feeling. I am then engaged in a
project which I have made mine, a project which is present
to me in the very rhythm of common action with its future
and its past. It would seem that such a form of transcendence
is at once collective and subjective. Let us not, however, forget
that, in such a case, I experience the transcendence of others
alongside of my own, as a transcendence which has the same
object as mine. It is felt neither objectively nor quite subjec-
tively. It is felt rather as a common rhythm of action. It is
properly speaking, the team-spirit; not a real Mitsein, but a
Mitmachen; not a being-togetlzer, but a doing-together:
And, no doubt, this experience may be sought as the symbol
of an absolute and metaphysical unity of all transcendences;
it seems, indeed, that it suppresses the original conflict
of transcendences by making them converge toward the
world; in this sense, the ideal we (nous-sujet) would be the
we of a humanity which would be making itself master of
the world. But the experience of the tile remains on the
ground of individual psychology and remains a simple sym-
bol of the desirable unity of transcendences; it is in no way.
indeed, a lateral and real apprehension of subjectivities as
such by a single subjectivity; the subjectivities remain out
of reach and radically separated.7l
102
BEING-FOR-OTHERS
103
V Being-In-Itself-For-Itself
Podunk.
Our past does not determine our future, nor does it con-
stitute our present. But neither can it be ignored by liberty,
for liberty exists only in relation to its past and in function
of its past. I have to recognize my past, were it only to revolt
against it, since it is my concrete being-in-itself. The present
is presence to a past, and my past follows me into the present:
Wesen ist was gewesen ist. The position I chose, the house I
built, the suit I bought are part of me, the being whom I
have to be. I cannot think of myself without thinking of my
past since I am that past; but if I can think the past and bring
it into being, that is because I survey it in the light of the
future. My transcendence would have no meaning if I did
not have a past to transcend. Yet, if it is true that conscious-
ness is always consciousness of something, it is also true that
whatever is in consciousness is there as being questioned,
which means that nothing appears to consciousness without
being chosen. No element of my past appears to my conscious-
ness without bearing some relation to my future projects. The
meaning I confer on past incidents varies according to the
nature of these projects. Outside of that constant evaluation,
my past, no doubt, is made up of raw data, constituting the
matter of Bergson's "pure memory," and I can explore that
past, as did Proust; but such exploration involves a project of
its kind.
It is only for the others that my death has any meaning, and
it is up to them to define that meaning. Death consecrates my
being for others in itself, i.e., as an object.
of the past occur, of course, only through and for the living,
from outside. For the dead, "the chips are down." Death is
the triumph of the Other. All in all, death is merely a certain
aspect of facticity and of being-for-others, i.e., nothing but a
datum.
limit his liberty? If there is only one end to all human activi-
ties, will it not become possible to tell what any man will
do in any given situation? Sartre's answer to this objection
is that if there is such an essence of man, it is merely an
abstraction which does not at all precede and determine his
existence, but merely gives the truth, or the meaning of indi-
vidual liberty. It is an ideal value which cannot be realized,
and, concretely, there are only individual projects which bear
on what to do with one's contingency. The individual has to
invent a particular manner of being; and to realize this man-
ner of being, he has to invent his ends and build up situations
out of contingent surroundings. Going from the particular
to the general, we find that empirical desire is the symbolic
form adopted in the fundamental and individual project
which defines the person; this individual project is a form of
the human project to realize being-in-itself-for-itself. But, of
course, this human project exists only in the form which we
can identify as the person.
137
Conclusion
1. Metaphysical perspectives.
2. Moral perspectives.
This treatise has not yet appeared, but Sartre has already
given us a few hints about the general principles on which his
ethical system would rest. These were further developed and
illustrated in such plays as Huis-clos and Les MOllches. They
seem to fit in with the system delineated by Sartre's disciple,
Simone de Beauvoir, in Pour une morale de l'ambigliitC, and
we may take for granted that the disciple expresses the idea
of the master when she states that, each consciousness being
an absolute, "the other steals the world from me every in-
stant," 91 and that it is quite true as Hegel claims that "each
consciousness pursues the death of the other";9::! even though,
on the other hand, each consciousness finds its solidarity with
142
CONCLUSION
The fact that this ideal is unattaz'nable does not do away with
our responsibility.
power.
149
Notes
Introduction
\. The Republic of Silence, tr. by 4. By Hazel A. Barnes in The
... J. Liebling. Harcourt, Brace, 1947. Literature of Possibility. Lincoln,
2. So he is called by F. H. Univ. of Nebraska Press, 1959.
i-Ieinemann in Existentialism and 5. By James Collins in The Ex-
the Modern Predicament. Harper istentialists, A Critical Study. Chi-
Torchbooks, 1958. cago, Henry Regnery, 1952.
3. Iris Murdoch, Sartl'e, Romantic
Rationalist. New Haven, Yale Univ.
Press, 1953.
TEXT
The references are to Jean·Paul Sartre's L'Etre et Ie neant (Paris, Galli-
mard, 1943), which will be cited as EN. Translations are by the author.
\. EN, p. 17. 8. EN, p. 28.
2. EN, p. 18. 9. EN, p. 29.
3. EN, p. 19. 10. EN, p. 34.
4. EN, p. 18. II. EN, p. 44.
5. EN, p. 23. 12. EN, p. 42.
6. EN, p. 23. 13. EN, p. 44.
7. EN, p. 27. 14. EN, pp. 46, 47.
ISO
NOTES
151
TO BE AND NOT TO BE
94. The political views condensed Russia in 1949 but also bears on
above are from Situations, III, Paris, Marx's philosophical approach.
GalIimard. 1949. "Materialisme et 95. This criticism is reproduced
revo/tltion," pp. 135-225. Sartre's almost verbatim in Critique de /a
criticism of Communism applies raison dia/ectiqut:, Paris, Gallimard.
mostly to Marxism as practiced in 1960, pp. 30-31.
152
Index
Aquinas, Thomas: his tradition, xiv Descartes: Augustine's inlluence on,
Aristotle: and christianity, xiv xiv; and existentialism, xv-xvi; his
Atheism: defined by Marcel, xxiv; de- cogito criticized by Marcel, xxiii,
fined by Berdyaev, xxv; Sartre's by Husserl, xxvi, by Sartre, 6; his
atheism, xxxix, xl "thinking substance" rejected by
Augustine: and existentialism, xiv-xv Sartre, 6; his argumentation com-
pared with Sartre's, 8; Cartesian
Beauvoir, S. de: on Sartre, xxxi, xxxii, doubt and Husserl's "bracketing,"
xxxiii, on ethics, 143 9; liberty, 16; the idea of perfection,
Heha viorism: Sartre's criticism, 76 29
Berdyaev: and existentialism, xxiv-
xxvi; on non-being, xxxiv Freud: Sartre's criticism of his sub·
Bergson: and existentialism, xx-xxi; conscious, 22-23; and psychoanaly-
source of Marcel, xxiv; source of sis, .25; Sartre rejects his theory,
Berdyaev, xxiv; compared with 108; Sartre adopts his method, 126:
Husserl, xxvii; on non-being, xxxiv, symbolic gratification, 131; Sanre
12-13; his notion of liberty criti- rejects Freudian sexuality, 136
cized by Sartre, 21; h,is "duration"
criticized by Sartre, 44, 82; his Gestalt: form and background, 51;
~.elan vital," 49; "pure memory," form, 76
115 Gnostics: source of Berdyaev, xxiv
Berkeley: esse est percipi, 3
Buber: and existentialism, xxi-xxii; Hegel: and existentialism, xiv; nega-
compared with Marcel, xxiii, xxiv tivity, xvii, 105, 106; his influence
on Heidegger's late works, xxx; on
Calvin: in Augustine's tradition, xiv non-being, xxxiv; determination as
Camus: and the school of commit- negation, 12; on essence, 20; on
ment, xxxi consciousness, 47; point of view of
Christian Science: and psychoanalysis, the totality criticized by Kierke·
25 gaard, xvii, commented on by
153
TO BE AND NOT TO BE
154
INDEX
155
The manuscript was edited by Ita Kanter. The book was
designed by Richard Kinney and Richard Berube. The text type
face is Linotype Granjon, designed in 1924 by George W.
lones, based on a face originally cut by Claude Garamond in
the 16th Century. The display face is Weiss designed by E. R.
Weiss and cut by Bauer in 1926.
This book is printed on Warren's 1854 Text regular finish
paper. The soft cover edition of this book is bound in Warren's
Cameo Brillia11t Cover and the hard cover edition is bound
in Joanna Mills Natalin. This book was manufactured in the
United States of America.
T-O BE AND
NOT TO BE
This book is a short, simplified explanation of Jean-Paul Sartre's
L'Etre et Ie neant. (BeLlg and Nothingness).
The persistent (""'lriosity of the reading public about a movement which
became popular some twenty years ago and is now affecting psychoanalysis
and theology, seems to indicate that our age is far from having exhausted
th e subject, or ';ven assimilated its basic elements.
Existentialism is at once the sternest and most helpful of philosophies.
"Man is nothing else but that which he makes of himself ... In fashioning
myself I fa shion man . . . , When a man commits himself to anything, fully
realizing that he is not only choosing what he will be, but is thereby at
the same time a legislator deciding for the whole of mankind-in such a
moment a man cannot ' escape from the sense of complete and profound
responsibility."
The import of our acts, whether casually littering a national park with
rubbish or actively defying a directive of the Supreme Court, measured by
existentialist philosophy assumes personal as well as global signi.ficance.
In an age which has not done with the throes of adjustment, whether la-
belled segregation or apartheid, some of the existentialist reverence for
man as the measure ought to be examined by thoughtful people of good
will everywhere.
Jacques Salvan is a graduate of the universities of Poi tiers, Paris, Kan-
sas, and Michigan. He has written articles on existentialism, symbolism,
and romanticism for The Dictionary oj World Literature, Symposium and The
French Review; his previous books include Le romantisme francais et I' Angleterre
victorienne (1949), The Scandalous ("lOst (1967) and various text books. Dr.
Salvan was born at Le Blanc, France, is an American citizen, and has taught
French at Washington U , and the U . of Kansas. He is professor emeritus
of French at Wayne State University in Detroit.