Causation in Tort Law: Richard W. Wright
Causation in Tort Law: Richard W. Wright
Richard W. Wright
TABLE OF CONTENTS
3. See L. GREEN, JUDGE AND JURY 29-37, 191, 195-96, 222-25, 230-31, 242-43 (1930); L.
GREEN, supranote 2; W. PROSSER, supra note 1, §§ 41, 42, at 236-37, 239, 244-50 (4th ed. 1971); id.
§§ 45, 46, at 311-21 (1st ed. 1941); see F. HARPER, A TREATISE ON THE LAW OF TORTS § 110, at
257-58 (1933); Edgerton, Legal Cause (pt. 2), 72 U. PA. L. REV. 343, 373 (1924); Gregory,
Proximate Cause in Negligence-A Retreat from "Rationalization," 6 U. CHI. L. REV. 36 (1938);
Morris, On the Teaching of Legal Cause, 39 COLUM. L. REV. 1087 (1939).
4. See, e.g., G. CHRISTIE, CASES AND MATERIALS ON THE LAW OF TORTS 245-46, 264
(1983); R. EPSTEIN, C. GREGORY & H. KALVEN, CASES AND MATERIALS ON TORTS 272-73, 309
(4th ed. 1984) [hereinafter cited as EPSTEIN, TORTS]; J. FLEMING, THE LAW OF TORTS 170-71, 179-
80 (6th ed. 1983); M. FRANKLIN & R. RABIN, CASES AND MATERIALS ON TORT LAW AND
ALTERNATIVES 269, 302 (3d ed. 1983); 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2, §§ 20.1, 20.2, 20.4;
C. MORRIS & C.R. MORRIS, MORRIS ON TORTS 154-201 (2d ed. 1980); W. PROSSER, supra note 1,
§§ 41, 42, at 236-37, 239, 244-50.
5. See infra text accompanying notes 166-225.
6. Malone, Ruminations on Cause-in-Fact,9 STAN, L. REV. 60 (1956).
7. See, eg., Cole, Windfall and Probability: A Study of "Cause" in Negligence Law (pts. I &
2), 52 CALIF. L. REV. 459, 764 (1964); Delgado, Beyond Sindell: Relaxation of Cause-in-FactRules
for Indeterminate Plaintiffs, 70 CALIF. L. REV. 881, 891-92 (1982); Pedrick, Causation, the "Who
Done It"Issue, andArno Becht, 1978 WASH. U.L.Q. 645; Pound, Causation, 67 YALE L.J. 1 (1957);
Robinson, Multiple Causationin Tort Law: Reflections on the DES Cases, 68 VA. L. REV. 713, 713-
14 (1982); Rosenberg, The CausalConnection in Mass Exposure Cases: A "PublicLaw" Vision of the
Tort System, 97 HARV. L. REV. 849, 855 n.27, 863-64 (1984); Strachan, The Scope andApplication of
the "But For" CausalTest, 33 MOD. L. REV. 386, 389-95 (1970); Weinrib, A Step Forwardin Factual
Causation, 38 MOD. L. REv. 518, 529-33 (1975); Zweir, "Cause in Fact" in Tort Law--A
Philosophicaland HistoricalExamination, 31 DE PAUL L. REV. 769 (1982); see 2 F. HARPER & F.
JAMES, supra note 2, § 20.2 & nn.16 & 17 comments at 92-93, 94-95 (Supp. 1968); W. KEETON, D.
DOBBS, R. KEETON & D. OWEN, PROSSER AND KEETON ON THE LAW OF TORTS §§ 41,42, at 264-
65 & n.7, 279-80 (5th ed. 1984) [hereinafter cited as PROSSER & KEETON]; cf. C. MORRIS & C.R.
MORRIS, supra note 4, at 188-90 (asserting that liability is sometimes imposed for policy reasons
although causation is lacking).
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW 1739
8. See A. BECHT & F. MILLER, THE TEST OF FACTUAL CAUSATION IN NEGLIGENCE AND
STRICT LIABILITY CASES 24,44 n.57, 78 n.109, 81-82 & n. 114, 85-87, 99, 104-06 & n. 157, 112 n.173,
118, 120, 124-26, 128-30, 135-37, 221 (1961); J. FLEMING, supra note 4, at 172-73; H.L.A. HART &
T. HONORt, CAUSATION IN THE LAW lxi-lxii, 7-8, 62, 101-02 & n.46, 239-41, 410, 412-16 (2d ed.
1985); Green, The Causal Relation Issue in Negligence Law, 60 MICH. L. REv. 543, 548-49, 553-55
& n.29, 560-61, 568 (1962); see also W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 243 & n.53.
9. See, eg., Calabresi, ConcerningCause and the Law of Torts, 43 U. CHI. L. REV. 69, 69 n.1,
86-87, 105-08 (1975); Grady, A New Positive Economic Theory of Negligence, 92 YALE L.J. 799, 799-
800, 804 n.21 (1983); Landes & Posner, Causation in Tort Law: An Economic Approach, 12 J.
LEGAL STUD. 109, 110-11, 134 (1983); Shavell, An Analysis of Causationandthe Scope of Liabilityin
the Law of Torts, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 463, 464, 502-03 & n.79 (1980). For my critique of the
economic analysts' views on causation in tort law, see Wright, Actual Causation vs. Probabilistic
Linkage: The Bane of Economic Analysis, 14 J. LEGAL STUD. 435 (1985).
10. H.L.A. HART & A. HONORt, CAUSATION IN THE LAW (1st ed. 1959). The recently
published second edition of this book contains a lengthy new preface but otherwise is generally the
same as the first edition. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORIt, supra note 8. Two changes relevant to the
issues addressed in this Article are discussed infra at notes 12 & 31.
11. H.L.A. HART & A. HONORt supra note 10, at 3-5, 23-25, 61-63, 65, 83-105, 123-25, 261-
62, 273-76; H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at xxxiv-xxxvi, lii-liii, 3-5, 24-27, 65-67, 69-
70, 88-111, 130-32, 291-92, 304-07. This objective is stated so emphatically and repeatedly
throughout the book that it is difficult to comprehend Izhak Englard's failure to see it and his
criticism of John Borgo, who did see it, for "misunderstanding" Hart and Honor6. Englard, The
System Builders: A CriticalAppraisal of Modern American Tort Theory, 9 J. LEGAL STUD. 27, 57
n.135 (1980) (criticizing Borgo, Causal Paradigmsin Tort Law, 8 J. LEGAL STUD. 419, 421-25 &
n.17 (1979)). Apparently, Englard does not distinguish between the prevailing academic policy-
oriented interpretation of proximate cause, which Hart, Honor6, and Borgo were attacking, and the
commonsense judgments independent of particular legal policies which Hart, Honor6, and Borgo
argue are controlling in actual adjudication.
12. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORP, supra note 8, at 65; see id. at lxxvii-lxxxi, 66-67, 302.
However, in other passages (especially in the second edition of their book), Hart and Honor6 state
that causing harm usually must be coupled with wrongful conduct to create liability. Id. at xxxv,
xiiii-xlvii, lxxv-lxxvii, 131-32, 254-55, 466.
13. A. HARARI, THE PLACE OF NEGLIGENCE IN THE LAW OF TORTS 49-56 (1962); Epstein, A
1740 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [V/ol. 73:1735
Theory of StrictLiability, 2 J. LEGAL STUD. 151, 163, 168-69 (1973). Compare Borgo, supranote 11,
at 425 & n.17, 431 & n.31, 432-40, 452-55 & nn. 55 & 59 (selecting responsible causes) with H.L.A.
HART & A. HONORt, supra note 10, at 26-47, 58-76 (same).
14. For my critique of the accounts of the economic analysts, see Wright, supra note 9.
15. Throughout this Article, the arguments presented will be descriptive rather than
normative. The normative issues will be addressed in a separate article now in progress.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW
then used to resolve the problematic causation cases that have resisted
solution under all the alternative tests. In the final section of Part II, the
steps involved in applying the NESS test are analyzed to demonstrate
that, contrary to the currently popular view among legal writers, the
causal inquiry is a factual inquiry not dependent on policy
considerations.
In Part III I address the difficult issues raised by the "increased
risk," "reduced chance," and "alternative liability" cases-cases in
which it can be proven that the defendant tortiously exposed the plaintiff
to an increased risk of injury but not that the defendant actually contrib-
uted to the subsequent injury. It is commonly argued that the causation
requirement is properly ignored or relaxed in these cases, or that the
requirement should be satisfied by a probabilistic "increased risk" con-
cept of "causation." I contend that these cases are more plausibly and
fruitfully viewed as cases that recognize a new type of injury-risk expo-
sure-in certain narrowly circumscribed situations. Causation of this
risk-exposure injury is easily established using the basic concept of causa-
tion embodied in the NESS test. Finally, I argue that the probabilistic
increased-risk concept of causation must be rejected, because it lacks the
attributive element that distinguishes causal explanations from mere
probability statements. This attributive element, which has always been
essential for tort liability, explains the courts' refusal to admit pure or
"naked" statistical evidence as proof of causation or identification.
I
THE SCOPE AND SIGNIFICANCE OF THE CAUSAL INQUIRY
IN TORT LAW
16. See supra notes 12 & 13 and accompanying text; see also Green, supra note 8, at 545, 562;
Malone, supra note 6, at 62-67; cf RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431 comment a (1965)
(substantial factor test of causation includes notion of responsibility).
1742 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
1. Malone
Malone's article contains a series of arguments that are meant to
establish the policy-dependent nature of the causal inquiry. Only one of
them is pertinent here.17
This argument focuses on the policy considerations that underlie
any decision to identify one of several contributing factors as "the cause"
of an injury. Malone notes that, depending on their respective back-
grounds and motivations, different persons may identify different con-
tributing factors as the cause of an injury. In one of his examples, an
irresponsible youth drives too fast down a road recently covered with
loose gravel, and a stone is thrown by a wheel of the car into the face of a
pedestrian. Malone observes that the neighbors may say that the parents'
letting their irresponsible son drive was the cause of the harm, while a
road engineer may say that the cause was improper road construction,
and a physics teacher may say that the impact of the wheel's momentum
on the rock was the cause. Thus, Malone states, causal determinations
are evaluative and purposive. 8
In Malone's other example, an elderly worker with a long-standing
heart ailment dies of heart failure while engaged in some trivial task for
his employer. A medical expert, says Malone, is likely to testify that the
trivial task was not a cause of the death, since he will view it as an
instance of a commonplace recurrent event with which medical science is
helpless to deal. But a judge, considering the compensatory purposes of
17. Malone's other arguments will be discussed later. See infra text accompanying notes 240-
42 & 304-30.
18. Malone, supra note 6, at 62.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW
Like Malone, Hart and Honor6 apply the causal label to a combined
tortious-conduct, cause-in-fact, and proximate-cause inquiry. Unlike
Malone, they argue that the combined inquiry is a factual inquiry based
on commonsense causal principles, rather than a policy-dependent
inquiry based on ad hoe judgments of legal purpose or social expedi-
ency.28 However, their commonsense principles are essentially the negli-
gence and intentional tort prongs of the tortious-conduct inquiry and
have nothing to do with causation. The causal label is not only mislead-
ing, but also makes it difficult for them to account for strict tort liability
and certain types of proximate-cause cases.
Hart and Honor6 divide their causal analysis into two steps. The
first step is the cause-in-fact inquiry, which determines whether the
defendant's conduct actually contributed to the injury. If it did, it was a
condition for the occurrence of the injury. 29 The second step is a confla-
tion of the tortious-conduct and proximate-cause inquiries, in which
Hart and Honor6's commonsense "causal" principles are used to deter-
mine whether the defendant's conduct can be distinguished from the
other contributing factors ("mere conditions") as "the cause" of the
30
injury.
According to Hart and Honor6, the central notion in the common-
sense concept of causation is that the cause is the factor which "makes a
difference" by interfering with, intervening in, or otherwise changing the
normal or reasonably expected course of events. Thus, a contributing
factor is treated as the cause rather than as a mere condition if it was (1)
a voluntary human intervention that was intended to produce the conse-
quence (for example, deliberately breaking a vase) or (2) an abnormal
action, event, or condition in the particular context (for example, a freak
27. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8,at 5-7, 12-13; Williams, supra note 21, at 63-65, 69.
In another "Rumination" published fourteen years later, but much less well known (outside
Louisiana), Malone reversed his position and insisted that the causal inquiry is purely factual and
should be sharply distinguished from the independent policy considerations that enter into
determination of the responsible cause. Malone, Ruminations on Dixie Drive It Yourself Versus
American Beverage Company, 30 LA. L. REv. 363, 370-71 (1970). For a valiant effort to reconcile
the two Ruminations, see Note, When Cause-in-Fact Is More Than a Fact: The Malone-Green
Debate on the Role of Policy in DeterminingFactual Causationin Tort Law, 44 LA. L. REV. 1519,
1540-41 & n.89 (1984).
28. See supra note 1I.
29. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8,at 109-11; see id. at 72. Hart and HonorE use
the "necessary element of a sufficient set" test in this cause-in-fact inquiry. See infra text
accompanying notes 226-83.
30. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORP, supra note 8,at 1-2, 24-25, 33, 72-73, 110-11.
1746 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
40. See supra note 12 and accompanying text; see also H.L.A. HART & T. HoNORt, supra note
8, at 117-18, 131-85, 135 n.9, 205-53 (tort liability discussed in terms of causal connection between
tortious conduct and harm, and liability negated despite such causal connection if there was an
intervening abnormal physical occurrence or intervening tortious behavior).
41. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at xxxv-xxxvii, xlvii-lv, 3-7, 24-25, 65-67, 88-
111, 130-32, 254, 304-07.
42. See id. at 85-86.
43. See supra note 32.
44. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORE, supra note 8, at 51-52, 57, 59-61, 71, 81-83, 133, 186. Hart
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1749
and Honor6's position on this issue is influenced by their view that volitional human actions, unlike
physical events, are neither subject to nor explainable in terms of causal generalizations. Id. at 51-
52, 55-57, 60-61; accord Kadish, Complicity, Cause and Blame: A Study of the Interpretationof
Doctrine, 73 CALIF. L. REV. 323, 326-27, 332-35 & n.8 (1985); Williams, supra note 21, at 66-68.
But, with human actions just as with physical events, if all the relevant circumstances (accumulated
experience and knowledge, mood, and so forth) were the same, surely the decision or action also
would be the same. To assert otherwise is to assert that human action is random or arbitrary. Cf
H.L.A. HART & T. HONOR-, supra note 8, at 56-57 (acknowledging that generalizations apply to
human action, but nevertheless denying repeatability in identical circumstances). Human action is
less regular and predictable than physical events because humans learn from prior experiences and
new information, because the range of relevant conditions is much broader, and because the
applicable causal generalizations are much more complex and less well understood. See generallyT.
BEAUCHAMP & A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 314-27; J. MACKIE, THE CEMENT OF THE
UNIVERSE 120-26 (1974); Moore, Causation and the Excuses, 73 CALIF. L. REV. 1091, 1112, 1124-
27, 1132-37 (1985).
45. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 41-42, 75-77, 136, 152-53, 183-84; W.
PROSSER, supra note 1, § 44, at 274, 276-78, 282.
46. W. PROSSER, supra note 1, §§ 7-8, at 30-33; id. § 9, at 35; id, § 17, at 99-100; id. § 24, at
126-27; id. § 31, at 145; id. § 32, at 150-51.
47. See supra note 31 and text accompanying notes 33-38.
1750 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
theory of recovery, even when responsibility defeasible through defenses or other subsequent
pleadings).
54. E.g., O.W. HOLMES, supra note 1, at 67-68, 72; Ehrenzweig, Negligence Without Fault, 54
CALIF. L. REv. 1422, 1426 nn.13 & 18 (1966), and the sources cited therein.
55. Eg., PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, § 75, at 536-38; id. § 78, at 555-56; Ehrenzweig,
supra note 54, at 1450-51 & n.l; see O.W. HOLMES, supra note 1, at 77, 93-95, 115-18.
56. E.g., O.W.HOLMES, supra note 1, at 85-88; Ehrenzweig, supra note 54, at 1444-45.
57. Epstein, supra note 13, at 152, 168-69.
58. These defenses include reciprocal causation of harm to the defendant by the plaintiff,
assumption of the risk by the plaintiff, and trespass on the defendant's property by the plaintiff.
Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 167-68, 174, 185, 201.
59. Epstein, supranote 13, at 152, 171; Epstein, IntentionalHarms, supranote 49, at 398. This
erroneous assumption also appears in most economic analyses of tort liability. See, eg., Brown,
Toward An Economic Theory of Liability, 2 J. LEGAL STUD. 323 (1973); Shavell, Strict Liability
Versus Negligence, 9 J.LEGAL STUD. 1 (1980).
60. Epstein, supra note 13, at 153-60, 169-71.
61. Morris v. Platt, 32 Conn. 75 (1864); Vincent v. Lake Erie Transp. Co., 109 Minn. 456, 124
N.W. 221 (1910). Both cases are discussed in Epstein, supra note 13, at 157-60. See also Bolton v.
Stone, 1951 A.C. 850, rev'g [1950] 1 K.B. 201 (C.A. 1949), rev'g [1949] 1 All. E.R. 237 (Manchester
Assizes 1948). Bolton is discussed in Epstein, supra note 13, at 169-71. In Bolton, the defendant
cricket club maintained and used a playing field not only with the knowledge that cricket balls might
be hit out of the grounds and endanger passersby such as the plaintiff, but also with the knowledge
that one of the objects of the game is to hit the ball away from the opposing team, the further away
the better. Although balls are rarely hit out due to the size of the playing fields, those that are hit out
earn extra points. See 1 THE ENCYCLOPEDIA OF SPORT 447 (1898). Thus, although the risks to
passersby such as the plaintiff were slight, the possibility was knowingly and eagerly pursued as an
integral part of the defendant's activity. This latter aspect of the case, together with the likely
severity of the harm should a ball actually escape the grounds and hit someone, may well explain (a)
the House of Lords' unease in refusing to hold the defendant liable, (b) the public interest in the case,
and (c) the decision of the Cricket Clubs of England to compensate the plaintiff despite the lack of a
holding of legal liability. See Epstein, supra note 13, at 170. It seems unlikely that the case would
have aroused such controversy if the possibility that cricket balls would escape the grounds had been
completely unintended, unknown, and unforeseeable.
1752 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
62. Epstein, supra note 13, at 158-59 & n.22, 173; Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 169, 213;
Epstein, Intentional Harms, supra note 49, at 398, 414.
63. Epstein, supra note 13, at 161-63; Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 478-79. But see Epstein,
supra note 13, at 183 (but-for test applied to dangerous position of vase), 184 (same: dangerous
condition of car).
64. Epstein, supra note 13, at 160, 165-66, 168-69, 190-91, 194-95; Epstein, Defenses, supra
note 49, at 167-68; Epstein, Intentional Harms, supra note 49, at 398-400; Epstein, Reply, supra note
49, at 479-80.
65. This point has also been made by Borgo, supra note 11, at 427-31; see supra note 48.
66. Epstein states that his theory is predominantly normative. Epstein, supra note 13, at 151;
Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 477. Nevertheless, he recognizes that any plausible normative
theory cannot stray too often or too far in its results from the commonly accepted notions of
responsibility embodied in traditional tort law, and he claims to base his theory on those commonly
accepted notions. See Epstein, supra note 13, at 151, 163-64, 166; Epstein, Reply, supra, at 479, 503-
04. Indeed, he argues that his theory best accounts for the results reached by the courts. Epstein,
supra note 13, at 165-66, 189; Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 168-69, 173-74, 204-05, 213-15;
Epstein, Intentional Harms, supra note 49, at 406-07; Epstein, Reply, supra, at 480.
67. Epstein, supra note 13, at 166-67; Epstein, Intentional Harms, supra note 49, at 399;
Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 480-81.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1753
68. Epstein, supra note 13, at 166-67. See generally Moore, supra note 44, at 1132-36
(distinguishing action from mere causal sequence).
69. Epstein, supra note 13, at 172.
70. Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 483-84.
71. Epstein, supra note 13, at 174. See generally Moore, supra note 44, at 1129-32
(distinguishing compulsion from mere causation).
72. See Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 175; Epstein, IntentionalHarms, supranote 49, at
399.
73. Epstein, supra note 13, at 175; Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 174-75.
1754 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
[caused] harm to B." 74 Note that two instances of causation are implied
by the expression "resulted in." First, some act or event must "trigger"
the dangerous condition, and, second, the triggered condition must then
cause the harm.
Epstein attempts to avoid the charge that this paradigm, by use of
the expression "resulted in" (he overlooks the verb "created"), defines
causation in terms of itself. He says that the expression "resulted in"
must be replaced in each particular case with a description of the act or
event which is the immediate cause of the harm, using one of the three
previously elaborated paradigms-force, fright or compulsion.75 How-
ever, even if both the expression "resulted in" and the verb "created"
were interpreted and used in this restricted fashion, it would only push
the circularity one level deeper, since-as we have seen-the three previ-
ous paradigms themselves contain implicit, unelaborated causal state-
ments. Moreover, Epstein does not actually restrict either term in this
fashion.
Thus, in Epstein's examples dangerous conditions are "created" by
"storing" or "handling" explosives, by "placing" or "leaving" an object
in a precarious or obstructive position, or by "manufacturing" a defective
product. And dangerous conditions are "triggered" by a "small change
in conditions, like temperature and humidity," or by mere use of a defec-
tive product (which might simply be turning it on or eating it).7 6 Clearly,
given these examples, the creation or triggering of dangerous conditions
is not limited to the use or threat of force, unless "force" is construed so
broadly as to encompass any action.
Similarly, in Epstein's examples dangerous conditions, when trig-
gered, can cause harm not just by "releas[ing] or otherwise set[ting] in
motion large forces" that are associated with the dangerous condition
itself, but also by absorbing or "redirecting" forces that are not associ-
ated with the dangerous condition. For example, an obstruction in a
highway is treated as a dangerous condition that "results in" injury to B
when B drives into it or swerves to avoid it." Here "results in" cannot
be replaced by one of the three previous paradigms: the obstruction did
not hit B, or offer to hit B, or compel anyone to hit B. Rather, the con-
verse is true: the obstruction was hit by B or, in the swerve case,
"offered" to be hit by B!78
obstruction (or other object, in the swerve case). There is no embedded paradigm, "A hit (or offered
to hit) B" that would support an action by B against A for damages suffered by B when B hit the
obstruction. See supra text accompanying notes 71-73. Nor, unless we are to twist language, can it
be said that A compelled B to hit himself. B hit the obstruction (or other object), not himself.
79. Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra note 49, at 56-57, 68, 100; Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at
486-87.
80. Epstein, supra note 13, at 185; see id. at 179.
81. Id. at 179.
82. See id. at 177-78; see also Epstein, IntentionalHarms, supra note 49, at 415 (barbed wire as
a dangerous condition).
83. Epstein, supra note 13, at 180, 185; Epstein, IntentionalHarms, supra note 49, at 399-400,
431; Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 479-81.
1756 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
84. Epstein, supra note 13, at 195 n.104; Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 202; Epstein,
Intentional Harms, supra note 49, at 432; Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra note 49, at 51. In the
emotional distress cases not involving the use or threat of force, Epstein adheres to the force
limitation and denies liability under his "invasion model." He suggests that liability in these cases is
based on "breaches of implied contracts for good social behavior" and that the "contractual mold" is
appropriate since these cases "all involve direct personal contact between plaintiff and defendant."
Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra, at 64 n.44. This reasoning, of course, would apply to almost every
tort. Epstein's discussion demonstrates the difficulties created by his narrow view of tort theory and
his frequent resort to dubious contractual arguments to escape those difficulties. See also Epstein,
Reply, supra note 49, at 481 (drivers on highway are not strangers since they are "bound together by
. . . statutory. . . bonds," thus calling for "complicated notions of 'avoidance of harm' which are
not captured by my paradigms").
85. Epstein, IntentionalHarms, supra note 49, at 432-41.
86. Id. at 432-34, 441; Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra note 49, at 50-53. Compare Epstein, supra
note 13, at 164-69 (nonreciprocal causation defines rights), with Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra, at 58-
60 (question of causation depends on prior definition of rights) and Epstein, Reply, supranote 49, at
498 & n.64 (references to Epstein's gradual recognition of the primacy of rights analysis).
87. Epstein, IntentionalHarms, supra note 49, at 433.
88. See Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra note 49, at 63-64 & n.40, 82, 92-93; Epstein, Reply, supra
note 49, at 488-500.
89. Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra note 49, at 50, 74-102; Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 483-
84, 488-89, 503.
90. Epstein, supra note 13, at 161-63, 164-65, 168, 184-85; Epstein, Reply. supra note 49, at
478-80.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1757
The gap between Epstein's theory and the actual practice of the
courts is narrowed somewhat in the reciprocal-causation cases. In these
cases, both the plaintiff and the defendant have harmed each other under
one of the causal paradigms. The plaintiff's reciprocal causation of harm
to the defendant provides a defense, in the second stage of the pleadings,
to the plaintiff's prima facie case against the defendant, which was estab-
lished in the first stage. Epstein then allows the plaintiff, in a third stage
of the pleadings, to reestablish his claim by proving that the defendant's
conduct was tortious.97 But by then it is too little and too late. The
tortious-conduct inquiry is never reached in the many cases in which the
pleadings do not progress beyond the first stage because there is no recip-
rocal causation. Even when the tortious-conduct inquiry is reached,
Epstein refuses to consider one of the principal types of tortious con-
duct-negligence-because of his strong distrust of imprecise liability
principles.9" Thus, under Epstein's theory, a driver whose car acciden-
tally breaks down on the highway and who sets out adequate warnings
for other drivers is liable to, but cannot recover from, the operator of a
truck who negligently crashes into the car. The driver of the car creates
a dangerous-condition by blocking the right of way, the truck's crashing
into the car merely completes the paradigm, and the truck operator's
negligence is (according to Epstein) immaterial. 99
It should by now be clear that causation is not equivalent to respon-
sibility, nor is it prima facie sufficient for liability. The tortious-conduct
and proximate-cause inquiries are distinct from the causal inquiry, and
all three are required to complete the liability analysis under traditional
notions of legal responsibility.
An important question remains, however. Is the causal inquiry a
significant part of tort analysis, or is it, as alleged by Malone and feared
by Hart, Honor6, and Epstein, dominated by the tortious-conduct and
proximate-cause inquiries?
97. Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 177-84; Epstein, Intentional Harms, supra note 49,
passim.
98. Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 172; Epstein, Reply, supra note 49, at 482; see supra
note 52 and accompanying text. But cf Epstein, Defenses, supra,at 177-84 & n.49 (statutory duties);
Epstein, Nuisance Law, supra note 49, at 71-72 & n.58 (reasonableness considerations in highway
cases); Schwartz, The Vitality of Negligence and the Ethics of Strict Liability, 15 GA. L. REV. 963,
986-89, 994 (1981) (discussing Epstein's reliance on negligence notions in certain situations); supra
note 84 (reasonableness considerations in emotional distress cases).
99. Epstein, supra note 13, at 180-81, 191-92 & n.99; Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 177-
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1759
100. E.g., G. CALABRESI, THE COSTS OF ACCIDENTS 6-7 & n.8, 131-97 (student ed. 1970);
Calabresi, supranote 9; Green, supranote 8; Pound, supra note 7; Thode, The Indefensible Use of the
Hypothetical Case to Determine Cause in Fact, 46 TEx. L. REV. 423 (1968).
101. For a discussion of the difficulties that this restriction creates for the wealth-maximizing
theories of tort liability, see Wright, supra note 9.
102. See infra text accompanying notes 161-64.
103. E.g., Weeks v. McNulty, 101 Tenn. 495, 48 S.W. 809 (1898); Texas & Pac. Ry. v.
McCleery, 418 S.W.2d 494 (Tex. 1967); Peterson v. Nielsen, 9 Utah 2d 302, 343 P.2d 731 (1959);
Sowles v. Moore, 65 Vt. 322, 26 A. 629 (1893); see RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 432
(1965); RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 519 (1938).
1760 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
104. Those who have at least noted the point include A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8,
passim; Carpenter, Workable Rules for Determining Proximate Cause (pt. 2), 20 CALIF. L. REV.
396, 408-19 (1932); Phillips, Reflections on Factual Causation, 1978 WASH. U.L.Q. 661, 663;
Williams, supra note 21, at 64-65, 70-71, 73-75; see also H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8,
at xxxvii-xxxviii, lviii-lxi, 117-21, 208-11, 293-94; R. KEETON, LEGAL CAUSE IN THE LAW OF
TORTS 4-9, 12-13, 18 (1963). The economic analysts generally have assumed the tortious-aspect
approach when they address the causation issue, but many have assumed the overall-conduct
approach in their articles on tortious conduct. See Brown, supra note 59, at 327-29, 333-34 (overall
conduct); Calabresi, supra note 9, at 79, 85-86 (tortious aspect); Calfee & Craswell, Some Effects of
Uncertainty on Compliance with Legal Standards, 70 VA. L. REV. 965, 975, 990 & n.56 (1984)
(overall conduct); Grady, supra note 9, at 804, 814-15, 824-25 (tortious aspect); Landes & Posner,
supra note 9, at 111-18 (tortious aspect); Landes & Posner, The Positive Economic Theory of Tort
Law, 15 GA. L. REv. 851, 868-70, 880-82 (1981) (overall conduct); Shavell, supra note 9, at 463-64,
481-82, 489 (tortious aspect); Shavell, supra note 59, at 10, 11 n.18, 15 (overall conduct).
105. 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2, § 20.5, at 1138 & n.17 (But cf id. § 20.2 n.4
comment, at 93-94 (Supp. 1968)); R. KEETON, supranote 104, at viii-ix, 10-16; Cole, supra note 7, at
459-60, 473-75, 482-86 & n.80, 491, 498-507 & n.133; Crowe, The Anatomy ofa Tort-Greenian, as
Interpreted by Crowe, Who Has Been Influenced by Malone-A Primer, 22 Loy. L. REV. 903, 904-
05, 920-22 (1976); Epstein, supra note 13, at 152, 168-69, 181; Green, supra note 8, at 544 & n.3,
546-52, 562, 569 n.77, 576; Henderson, A Defense of the Use of the Hypothetical Case to Resolve the
Causation Issue-The Need for an Expanded, Rather than a Contracted, Analysis, 47 TEx. L. REV.
183, 185, 195-98, 200-01, 212-13 (1969); Morris, supra note 3, at 1096-97, 1104; Thode, supra note
100, at 424-25, 428-29; see also Pedrick, supra note 7, at 656-57 & n.41.
Although Robert Keeton claims to be using the tortious-aspect approach, he substitutes the
"harm within the risk" approach to proximate-cause limits for the tortious-aspect approach to
cause-in-fact. See infra text accompanying notes 118-26. Keeton and Thode each report Warren
Seavey's rejection of the tortious-aspect approach. R. KEETON, supra note 104, at 12-13; Thode,
supra note 100, at 429 & n.23. Pedrick cites Prosser as also supporting the overall-conduct
approach, but the cited portion of Prosser's text uses the defendant's negligence (excess speed) rather
than his conduct as a whole (driving) as the basis for the causal inquiry. Pedrick, supra note 7, at
656 n.41 (citing W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 237 & n.6).
106. E.g., J. FLEMING, supra note 4, at 170-71; C. MORRIS & C.R. MORRIS, supra note 4, at
154-201; W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 30, at 143; id. § 41, at 236-43; id. § 42, at 249; id. § 45, at 289;
PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, §§ 41-45, at 263-321; Smith, Legal Cause in Actions of Tort (pts.
1-3), 25 HARV. L. REV. 103, 223, 303 (1911-1912).
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1761
results that are consistent with the decisions of the courts. I then elabo-
rate the tortious-aspect causation requirement and apply it to a broad
range of cases to demonstrate its importance in determining liability.
107. E.g., Crowe, supra note 105; Green, supra note 8; Thode, supra note 100; see also L.
GREEN, W. PEDRICK, J. RAHL, E.W. THODE, C. HAWKINS, A. SMITH & J. TREECE, CASES ON THE
LAW OF TORTS (2d ed. 1977) (no discussion of actual causation issue).
108. Green, supra note 8, at 569 n.77.
109. Id.
110. Id.
111. Id.
1762 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW (Vol. 73:1735
112. For another unsuccessful attempt to replace causal analysis with tortious-conduct analysis,
which also relies on causal arguments, see Landes & Posner, supra note 9, at 110- 11, 115-16, 119-22,
criticized in Wright, supra note 9, at 452-55.
113. The answer is yes. See infra text accompanying notes 274-76.
114. Green, supra note 8, at 569 n.77.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1763
made the defendant's conduct negligent, rather than the aspects of the
conduct itself that created that type of risk. 9 He then restates the
requirement in a third formulation that is very similar to Green's
approach:
A negligent actor is legally responsible for the harm, and only the harm,
that not only (1) is caused in fact by his conduct [as a whole] but also (2)
is a result within the scope
120
of the risks by reason of which the actor is
found to be negligent.
Under this formulation of the Risk Rule, the only causal require-
ment is that the injury have been caused by the defendant's conduct as a
whole. The second part of the formula merely requires that the injury fit
the description of one of the risks that made the defendant's conduct
negligent. It calls for a comparison of the injury with the relevant risk
description (the so-called "negligent aspect" of the conduct), rather than
an inquiry into the causal connection between the injury and some prior
2
act, omission, or condition.' 1
For example, Keeton discusses a hypothetical case in which the
defendant negligently placed an unlabeled can of rat poison next to food
119. Thus, in his primary example, Keeton describes the negligent aspect as "placing the poison
where it was likely to be mistaken for something intended for human consumption." Id. at 5; see id.
at 8-9. This is a description in terms of the risk created, rather than a description of the conduct
(placing unlabeled poison near food) which created the risk. See also id. at 14-16, 126-27 n.l 1.
120. Id. at 10. For Keeton's distinction between the conduct as a whole and the negligent
aspect of the conduct, see id. at 4-5.
There are some important differences between Keeton's and Green's respective approaches.
For example, Keeton limits the relevant risks to those that were foreseeable at the time the defendant
acted (or failed to act) and were the basis for characterizing the defendant's conduct as negligent.
That is, his "harm within the risk" proximate-cause analysis builds on the foreseeability analysis
employed in the determination of negligence. Id. at 10-11, 18-22, 51, 56. Green, on the other hand,
would identify the relevant risks as part of a broad social-policy analysis of the duty issue, in which
foreseeability of the risk is not necessary and is only one of many considerations. Foreseeability of
the type of consequence, but not the manner of its occurrence, is an important part of Green's
elaboration of the negligence (breach of duty) issue. The negligence-foreseeability formula, however,
is seen merely as a useful method for presenting the ultimate issue of culpability or responsibility to
the jury, which can and often does impose liability despite lack of foreseeability of the injury. Green,
supra note 8, at 562-64, 566-68 & n.72, 570-74; Green, Foreseeabilityin Negligence Law, 61 COLUM.
L. REV. 1401 (1961).
121. R. KEETON, supra note 104, at 48; see id. at 52-59. This confusion of causal analysis with
"harm within the risk" analysis leads Keeton to assert that "the Risk Rule is indeed a rule of
causation in a cause-in-fact sense" and that the proximate-cause inquiry is therefore a causal inquiry.
Id. at 13; accord, Robinson, supranote 7, at 756 n. 143, 757 n. 144; see R. KEETON, supra note 104, at
17-18, 81. Unfortunately, this confusion now pervades the fifth edition of Prosser's hornbook, of
which Keeton is a coeditor. Prosser's longstanding insistence that the actual-cause inquiry is factual
and that the proximate-cause inquiry (as distinct from the preliminary issue of actual causation) is
noncausal and policy-dependent has been systematically replaced by statements regarding the policy-
dependent nature of the actual-cause inquiry and the causal nature of at least part of the proximate-
cause inquiry. Compare W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 237; id. § 42, at 244, 249-50; id. § 43, at
250-51; id § 45, at 289, with PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, at xix; id. § 41, at 264-65; id. § 42,
at 273, 274, 279-80; id. § 43, at 280-81; id. § 45, at 321.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1765
on a shelf in the kitchen of his restaurant. The shelf was next to a hot
stove, and the heat from the stove caused the can of poison to explode.
The force of the explosion killed a delivery man. The defendant did not
know, arid had no reason to know, that the rat poison might explode.
The defendant's conduct as a whole-placing the can on the shelf or,
broader yet, operating the restaurant-was a cause of the injury. How-
ever, Keeton states, the defendant is not liable because the description of
the injury ("injury by explosion") does not match the description of the
risk that made the defendant's conduct negligent ("injury by
poisoning"). 122
But suppose a customer died by poisoning as a result of eating the
rat poison, which was deliberately served to him by someone who knew it
was poisonous. The defendant's negligence did not contribute to the
injury, yet the defendant will be liable under Keeton's Risk Rule unless
the risk is described more precisely, for example, "injury by accidental
poisoning." Suppose then that a customer is poisoned accidentally and
nonnegligently as a result of being fed some substance other than the rat
poison. The risk must be detailed even further: "injury by accidental
poisoning with the rat poison that the defendant placed on the shelf."
What if a government health inspector accidentally contaminates the
customer's food with the rat poison, after opening and inspecting the can,
which had been properly labeled and moved away from the food several
days earlier? We must add a qualifier, "as a result of mistaking the
poison for food," to the previous description of the risk. Suppose the
government inspector mistook the poison for food even though it was
now away from food and properly labeled. We must add a further quali-
fier: "because the rat poison was unlabeled or near food."
At this point, we have included in the description of the risk a
description of the aspect of the defendant's conduct which made that
conduct negligent: having unlabeled poison around, or having poison
(even if properly labeled) near food. Moreover, we have included in the
description the requirement that the negligent aspect have been a cause
of the victim's injury: "injury. . . because the rat poison was unlabeled
or near food." Unless the description of the risk explicitly or implicitly
includes this tortious-aspect causation requirement, the Risk Rule will
encounter difficulties similar to those described in the previous para-
graph. Contrary to the courts' practice, the rule will permit the defend-
ant to be held liable even though the tortious aspect of his conduct was
not a cause of the injury. The same problem exists with respect to the
first and second formulations of Keeton's Risk Rule, since Keeton inter-
prets the terms "negligence" and "negligent aspect" in them to mean the
type of risk that made the defendant's conduct negligent, rather than the
23
aspects of the defendant's conduct which created that type of risk.'
Keeton occasionally incorporates the tortious-aspect causation
requirement into the description of the risk, in order to avoid liability
that otherwise would exist under the Risk Rule. 124 More often, his dis-
cussions of specific cases implicitly assume that the injury not only must
have been within the broadly stated risk, but also must have been caused
25
by the tortious aspect of the defendant's conduct or activity.'
In sum, the Risk Rule mandates results that are inconsistent with
those reached by the courts, unless the tortious-aspect causation require-
ment is incorporated into the description of the risk. But, as with
Green's duty analysis, this awkward and circuitous method of posing the
causal inquiry creates a substantial danger of misperceiving or mishan-
dling the causal element in the liability analysis. Instead, as some propo-
nents of the risk theory have recognized, 126 the "harm within the risk"
limitation should be viewed as a (proximate-cause) supplement to the
tortious-aspect causation requirement, rather than as a substitute for it.
127. Carpenter, Workable Rules for DeterminingProximate Cause (pts. 1-3), 20 CALIF. L. REV.
229, 396, 471 (1932).
128. Id. at 257-58.
129. Id. at 231 (loaded gun discussion); id. at 231 n.5 (Butz case); id. at 253-54 (Teis case).
130. Id. at 408-19, 471-539.
131. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 34; see also id. at 12-13, 27-28 & n.40, 87-90.
132. E.g., id.at 34-42, 54, 58, 59-61, 85, 90-91, 140, 169-86. The authors' discussion of Kernan
v. American Dredging Co., 355 U.S. 426 (1958), is particularly interesting. The defendant's act of
carrying a kerosene signal lantern at a height lower than that mandated by statute was deemed
sufficient to hold him liable for the ignition of petroleum vapors on the surface of the water, even
though the purpose of the statute was to prevent collisions between ships, not the ignition of surface
vapors. Becht and Miller, expanding upon a footnote by Justice Harlan, 355 U.S. at 442 n.1, note
that the negligence was the omission of a signal lantern at the required height, not the presence of
one at the lower height (which was not in itself prohibited). If there had been a lantern at the
required height in addition to the one at the lower height, there would have been no negligence
(breach of the statute), yet the vapors would still have been ignited. Thus, the negligent aspect was
not a cause of the injury. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 38-41. But see H.L.A. HART &
T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 289 (failing to note this point). If the defendant's attorney had
correctly identified the negligent aspect and stressed the lack of causal connection between the
negligence and the injury, rather than conceding negligent causation and relying on the "harm
outside the risk" argument, he probably would have won the case.
1768 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
This clearly was a necessary condition for the plaintiff's injury. They
therefore conclude that the negligent-aspect causation requirement is sat-
isfied. They refuse to consider, as part of the causal inquiry, whether the
unsafe condition of the wall contributed to the injury, since the condition
of the wall was not a part of the plaintiff's conduct. 133
But the unsafe condition is a necessary element in the description of
the plaintiff's negligent conduct. The act of "sitting on a wall" is not in
itself negligent. The act of "sitting on an unsafe (weak, structurally
unsound) wall" is negligent, when it is coupled with the mental element
required for negligence (actual or constructive knowledge of the unsafe
condition). The act of sitting and the unsafe condition are both necessary
to make the plaintiff's conduct negligent. Therefore it must be estab-
lished that both the act and the condition contributed to the injury before34
it can be said that the plaintiff's negligence contributed to the injury.,
In general, the tortious aspect of a person's conduct or activity is a
cause of an injury only if each of its necessary elements (act, omission,
condition, or circumstance) contributed to the occurrence of the
injury. 135 If a certain element did not contribute to the injury, but was
necessary to make the conduct or activity tortious, then it cannot be said
that the tortious aspect of the conduct or activity was a cause of the
136
injury.
The actor's mental state (intent, or actual or constructive knowledge
of a certain risk), which is required in addition to the conduct or activity
itself in order for the conduct or activity to be considered tortious, does
not enter directly into the causal inquiry. Instead, the intent or knowl-
edge is used to determine which acts, omissions, conditions, and circum-
stances constitute the tortious aspect of the conduct or activity. For
example, in the explosive rat poison case, the actor was aware (or should
have been aware) of its poisonous nature, but was not aware (and had no
reason to be aware) of its explosive nature. Therefore, the poisonous
nature of the substance was a constituent of the tortious aspect of the
actor's conduct, but its explosive nature was not.
Becht and Miller's overly broad conception of the tortious aspect of
conduct forces them erroneously to concede negligent causation and to
133. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 183-84; see also J. FLEMING, supra note 4, at 192
& n.43; Malone, supra note 27, at 371.
134. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 210; see infra text accompanying notes 268-
73.
135. When there is more than one tortious aspect, each must be considered, and the tortious-
aspect causation requirement is satisfied if any of them contributed. For example, in the rat poison
case, there were two tortious aspects: (1) having unlabeled poison around and (2) having poison
(even if labeled) near food. If either tortious aspect contributed to the injury, the tortious-aspect
causation requirement is satisfied.
136. See H.L.A. HART & T. HONORI, supra note 8, at 117-20, 208-11; Carpenter, supra note
127, at 409-10.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1769
rely instead on the "harm outside the risk" rationale to limit liability in a
number of cases. 37 It also leads them to adopt Green's and Keeton's
approach to causation of injury in the strict liability cases. They assert
that, under strict liability, the causal inquiry is applied to the defendant's
conduct as a whole.138 Presumably, they again would use the "harm
outside the risk" argument to limit liability.
Properly understood, the tortious-aspect causation requirement
applies to all tort actions, not just to negligence actions.
In the traditional strict liability cases, the tortious aspect of an activ-
ity includes all the acts, omissions, and conditions necessary to make it
ultrahazardous or abnormally dangerous: for example, the keeping or
use of a highly explosive substance, a poisonous fugitive substance, a
highly radioactive or toxic substance, a vicious or wild animal, a foraging
animal, or a large bulk accumulation of liquid. That tortious aspect
must be a cause of the injury, as the original Restatement of Torts made
clear: "[O]ne who carries on an ultrahazardous activity is liable to
another. . . for harm resulting thereto from that which makes the activ-
' 139
ity ultrahazardous."
Unfortunately, however, the academic proponents of the risk theory
succeeded in rewording section 519 in the Restatement (Second) to make
it conform to Keeton's Risk Rule: "(1) One who carries on an abnor-
mally dangerous activity is subject to liability for harm to [another]...
resultingfrom the activity . . . .(2) This strict liability is limited to the
kind of harm, the possibility of which makes the activity abnormally dan-
gerous. '""4° This Risk Rule formula will produce unintended results
137. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 61-62 (plaintiff negligently stood on unrailed
portion of icy platform, but was injured by wall falling on that portion of platform rather than by
slipping on ice); id. at 150-51, 199 (accident occurs while plaintiff or defendant is engaged in secular
activity in violation of Sunday blue law). See also their confusing discussion of the license cases at
id. at 141-50, 194-99.
138. Id. at 46, 48, 168.
139. RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 519 (1938) (emphasis added).
140. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 519 (1977) (emphasis added). Among the Advisers
to the Reporter for the Restatement (Second) were such prominent academic proponents of the risk
theory as Eldredge, James, Robert Keeton, Page Keeton, Malone, and Seavey.
The Restatement (Second) also dropped the language in the original Restatement which limited
liability to those whom the actor "should recognize as likely to be harmed" by the miscarriage of the
activity. However, the drafters apparently assumed that this limitation was retained by the "kind of
harm" language in § 519(2). Thus, comment e to § 519(2) refers to risk and injury "to those in the
vicinity" of a possible explosion, and the accompanying illustration 1 rejects liability when the actor
"has no reason to know of the presence of B's mink ranch nearby," even though "[t]he noise of the
blasting frightens the mink and the fright causes them to kill their young."
The mink illustration is based on Madsen v. East Jordan Irrigation Co., 101 Utah 552, 125 P.2d
794 (1942). The result seems inconsistent with RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 522(b)
(liability despite unforeseeable contributing action of animal) and also the Risk Rule itself.
Frightened or startled reactions to the noise of blasting, as well as direct effects of the force of the
blast, are foreseeable and "within the risk," and the peculiar reaction of the mink in such situations
1770 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
is a well-established characteristic. See, e.g., Wildwood Mink Ranch v. United States, 218 F. Supp.
67 (D. Minn. 1963); Gronn v. Rogers Constr., 221 Or. 226, 350 P.2d 1086 (1960); Summit View,
Inc. v. W.W.Clyde & Co., 17 Utah 2d 26, 403 P.2d 919 (1965); Foster v. Preston Mill Co., 44 Wash.
2d 440, 268 P.2d 645 (1954); MacGibbon v. Robinson, [1952] 4 D.L.R. 142 (B.C.); R. KEETON,
supra note 104, at 135 n. 100. In the Madsen case, the defendant irrigation company presumably was
familiar with the area and, at any rate, was blasting only 100 yards from the mink ranch. Both the
vibrations and the noise terrified the mother mink, which reacted in a natural way (for mink). The
result is justified only as an application of the principle that a person need not take excessive care to
avoid injury to extrasensitive plaintiffs and, correspondingly, should not be held strictly liable for
"harm [that] would not have resulted but for the abnormally sensitive character of the plaintiffs
activity." RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 524A (1977).
141. See supra text accompanying notes 122-23.
142. Cf RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 519 comment e (1977); R. KEETON, supra note
104, at 105.
143. Greenman v. Yuba Power Prods., 59 Cal. 2d 57, 62-64, 377 P.2d 897, 900-01, 27 Cal. Rptr.
697, 700-01 (1962); Codling v. Paglia, 32 N.Y.2d 330, 342, 298 N.E.2d 622, 628-29, 345 N.Y.S.2d
461, 469-70 (1973); RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 402A (1965).
144. Thus, it is not true, as Keeton claims, that "[n]o concept of risk is resorted to in
determining the issue of liability for intentional tort." R. KEETON, supra note 104, at 100-01.
145. Boomer v. Atlantic Cement Co., 26 N.Y.2d 219, 257 N.E.2d 870, 309 N.Y.S.2d 312
(1970); Morgan v. High Penn Oil Co., 238 N.C. 185, 77 S.E.2d 682 (1953); Jost v. Dairyland Power
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1771
was necessary to the finding of negligence, but this is not clear. If "unguarded operating fan on floor
near workmen" was sufficient for negligence, the tortious-aspect causation requirement was satisfied
and liability seems appropriate, absent contributory negligence. See H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt,
supra note 8, at 118-19.
151. W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 36, at 192-93, 196.
152. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORC, supra note 8, at 210-11, 293-94; Carpenter, supra note 127,
at 409-10, 414-15. Writers who assert that the illegal conduct was a cause of the injury erroneously
apply the causal inquiry to the conduct as a whole rather than to the illegal aspect of such conduct.
E.g., A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 150-51, 199; L. GREEN, JUDGE AND JURY 234-35
(1930); W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 36, at 193.
153. 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2, § 17.6, at 995-97; H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt,
supra note 8, at 210-11; W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 36, at 193 n.53, 202-03. But see G.
CALABRESI, supra note 100, at 267-74, 301-08; Cole, supra note 7, at 459-62, 598-607; Green, supra
note 8, at 569 n.77; Morris, supra note 3, at 1096-97; Thode, supra note 126, at 1348-49, 1351-52;
Thode, supra note 100, at 430-31. For a cogent critique of Thode's argument, see Strachan, supra
note 7, at 389-91.
154. W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 36, at 195-96 & n.77.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1773
In the above cases, it can also be said that the harm was not "within
the risk." The "harm within the risk" theory, however, cannot account
for some other cases. Thus, if an unlicensed driver causes an automobile
accident or an unlicensed medical practitioner causes a medical mishap,
the harm is the sort which the legislature meant to prevent through its
licensing requirements. To describe the risk as restricted to "injury at
the hands of incompetents"' 5 5 is to rely on and incorporate the tortious-
aspect causation requirement. The tortious aspect is "driving or practic-
ing medicine without a license." Although the overall conduct of driving
or practicing medicine contributed to the injury, 5 6 the failure to have the
required piece of paper (the license) did not.157
A similar problem exists when the defendant is violating the statu-
tory speed limit, but a child darts in front of his car whom he could not
avoid even if he were driving at the legal speed. The injury in such cases,
as even Green admits, 5 ' is "within the risks" meant to be avoided by the
speed limit. Some argue that the injury is not within the risks, which are
said to be limited to those involving "lack of control."'5 9 But the risks
meant to be avoided include not only literal loss of physical control of the
car but also inability to swerve or stop in time to avoid hitting something
or someone. The injury is "within" this latter risk, but there is no liabil-
ity since the tortious aspect (excess speed) did not contribute to the
injury. Liability can be avoided under the "harm within the risk"
approach only by incorporating the tortious-aspect causation require-
ment in the description of the risk. 6 °
When the tortious-aspect causation requirement is satisfied in a par-
ticular case, the courts often hold the defendant liable even though the
injury was unforeseeable or "outside the risk," especially when the tor-
155. Id. at 196; PROSSER & KEETON, supranote 7, § 36, at 226; see Green, supranote 8, at 547-
48.
156. PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, § 36, at 223-24; Williams, supra note 21, at 74-75; see
A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 141-42.
157. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 117-20; Carpenter, supra note 127, at 412-13,
414. A legislature or court might decide, however, that the lack of license should be treated as some
evidence or even as prima facie evidence that the driver or practitioner was incompetent to engage in
the activity and that the injury was caused by some unspecified instance of that incompetence
(negligence). E.g., N.Y. CIv. PRAC. LAW § 4504(d) (McKinney Supp. 1984); 2 F. HARPER & F.
JAMES, supra note 2, § 20.3, at 1120-21; Williams, supra note 21, at 74-75. But see A. BECHT & F.
MILLER, supra note 8, at 143-50.
158. Green, Are There Dependable Rules of Causation? 77 U. PA. L. REV. 601, 619 (1929).
159. E.g., 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2, § 20.5, at 1138 & n.16, 1148; id. § 20.6, at
1156 n.23.
160. See Cole, supra note 7, at 766-67; Henderson, supra note 105, at 189-92, 195-97; Thode,
supra note 126, at 1345-47; Thode, supra note 100, at 427-28, 430-31. To avoid the argument that
the excess speed did contribute to the injury by bringing the defendant to the precise place where the
child darted out at the precise time that he darted out, I assume here that the defendant had just
begun speeding. Otherwise, the tortious-aspect causation requirement is satisfied, and the defendant
must rely on noncausal proximate-cause arguments to avoid liability.
1774 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
tious conduct was intentional or negligent. 161 Even the risk-theory pro-
ponents acknowledge this.1 62 In the statutory context, this approach is
reflected in expansive interpretations of the statutory purposes, 163 or
occasionally even by frank imposition of liability for injuries conceded to
be "outside the risk."'" Thus, the causal inquiry, focused on the tor-
tious aspect of the defendant's conduct, plays an extremely significant
role in both establishing and limiting legal responsibility.
II
THE NATURE AND CONTENT OF THE CAUSAL INQUIRY
In Part I of this Article, I analyzed the role that the causal inquiry
occupies in tort-liability analysis. In this Part I examine the nature and
content of the causal inquiry itself. As will be seen, efforts to articulate a
comprehensive, factual test of actual causation have failed repeatedly.
The causal inquiry therefore increasingly has been viewed by academics
as just one more manipulable policy tool that has little or no inherent
165
substantive content.
In this Part I attempt to rebut this prevailing view by elaborating a
causal test that incorporates the traditional Humean philosophic account
of the meaning of causation, as modified by John Stuart Mill. This test,
which I call the "NESS" (Necessary Element of a Sufficient Set) test, was
first suggested by Hart and HonorS. As elaborated here, the NESS test
states that a particular condition was a cause of a specific consequence if
and only if it was a necessary element of a set of antecedent actual condi-
tions that was sufficient for the occurrence of the consequence. A sub-
stantial portion of this Part is devoted to developing this test and
applying it to resolve the problematic causation cases that have resisted
solution under all the previously proposed tests.
First, however, the previous tests are examined in order to provide a
basis for comparison with the NESS test, to introduce the various types
of problematic causation cases, and to develop some of the concepts and
161. E.g., In re Kinsman Transit Co., 338 F.2d 708, 723-25 (2d Cir. 1964), cert. denied, 380
U.S. 944 (1965); H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 176-78, 254-90; W. PROSSER, supra
note 1, §§ 43-44, at 250-80; Smith, supra note 106, at 127-28, 233-52, 321-27. Some proximate-cause
limitations on liability do exist. The primary instances are when the injury would not have occurred
but for unforeseeable tortious conduct by others or independent abnormal events or conditions. See
H.L.A. HART & T. HONORA, supra note 8, passim; Carpenter, supra note 127, at 471-539.
162. See, eg., L. GREEN, supra note 2, at 177-85; 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2,
§ 20.5, at 1139-51; id. § 20.6, at 1155-56, 1160-61; R. KEETON, supra note 104, at 28-32, 39, 49-54,
60-78, 96-97, 100-03, 109-10, 117; Green, Foreseeability in Negligence Law, 61 COLUM. L. REV.
1401, 1417-24 (1961); Williams, The Risk Principle,77 LAW Q. REV. 179, 181-87, 193-203 (1961).
163. 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2, § 17.6, at 1004-05; PROSSER & KEETON, supra
note 7, § 36, at 226-27.
164. See the discussion of the Kernan case supra note 132.
165. See sources cited supra notes 6, 7 & 9.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1775
arguments that underlie the NESS test. The first section discusses the
traditional "but for" (necessary condition) test and distinguishes the two
types of overdetermined-causation cases that the test fails to handle prop-
erly: the duplicative-causation cases and the preemptive-causation cases.
Subsequent sections discuss modifications of or alternatives to the but-for
test.
Finally, in the last section, the steps involved in applying the NESS
test are analyzed in detail to demonstrate that, contrary to the currently
popular view, the hypothetical inquiry associated with the but-for neces-
sary-condition analysis does not undermine the factual nature of the
causal inquiry. The miscellaneous arguments advanced by Malone to
establish the policy-dependent nature of the causal inquiry are also
examined and rejected.
house. The fires converge and together burn down the house. Each fire
was a duplicative cause of the destruction of the house. Yet, application
of the but-for test would result in a finding that D's shot was not a cause
of P's death in the first example and that neither C's nor D's fire was a
cause of the destruction of P's house in the second example.
A different sort of objection to the but-for test focuses on the hypo-
thetical or counterfactual nature of the inquiry that the test calls for. A
number of writers have asserted that the hypothetical nature of the but-
for inquiry necessarily involves or at least invites introduction of policy
67
considerations into a supposedly factual inquiry.1
While it might be thought that these difficulties could be avoided by
substituting a sufficient condition test for the but-for necessary-condition
test, this substitution would eliminate almost every potential cause, since
few if any acts are sufficient by themselves to produce any particular con-
sequence. Thus, in the scientific and philosophic literature on causation,
it is usually stressed that the cause of an event must include all the condi-
tions which together are sufficient to produce the consequence. 168 Conse-
quently, both lawyers and philosophers often conclude that this scientific
or philosophic concept of causation is of little relevance or use in the
69
law. 1
On the other hand, the sufficient-condition test could be interpreted
to mean any condition that is sufficient in combination with other condi-
tions to produce the consequence, even though it is not sufficient by itself.
Under this interpretation, however, anything could be treated as a cause
1 70
simply by adding it to an already sufficient set of conditions.
Judges and legal writers have responded to the actual and perceived
deficiencies in the but-for test in several different ways. A few writers
have tried to improve the but-for test by modifying the manner in which
it is applied.' 71 Most judges and writers, however, have adopted the sub-
stantial-factor formula, either as a supplement to or as a substitute for
the but-for test depending on their degree of dissatisfaction with the but-
for test. 172 Others have relied on an undefined and irreducible notion of
167. E.g., J. FLEMING, supra note 4, at 172; Cole, supra note 7; Malone, supra note 6, at 67-68;
see also sources cited infra note 284.
168. E.g., T. BEAUCHAMP & A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 85, 291; H.L.A. HART & T.
HONORt, supra note 8, at 17-18, 21 & n.16; W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 237 n.8; Williams,
supra note 21, at 63, 66.
169. E.g., RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 431 comment a (1965); T. BEAUCHIAMP & A.
ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 283-94; A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 9, 12; J. FLEMING,
supra note 4, at 171 & n.2, 192 & n.43; H.L.A. HART & T. HONOR~f, supra note 8, at 2, 9-16, 68-69;
Calabresi, supra note 9, at 69-70, 105-06; Epstein, supra note 13, at 160-61; Morris, supra note 3, at
1088; Williams, supra note 21, at 66-68, 75-76.
170. Sosa, Introduction, in CAUSATION AND CONDITIONALS 1-3 (E. Sosa ed. 1975).
171. See infra text accompanying notes 176-89.
172. See infra text accompanying notes 190-208.
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW 1777
been for this, this is an actual cause of that."176 For example, if a victim
is killed instantaneously by a bullet wound while already dying from a
knife wound, he would not have died, as he in fact did, at the earlier
moment and by a bullet wound if not for the firing of the bullet. Without
the bullet wound, he would have died later, from the effects of the knife
wound. This, however, did not in fact happen. Thus, the bullet wound,
but not the knife wound, is a but-for cause of the death "when and as" it
happened.
This form of reasoning is nothing more than proof by tautology.
For example, consider Perkins' treatment of the case in which the victim
is struck simultaneously by two bullets, each of which would have been
instantly fatal by itself: "[He] would not have died when and as he did
die (by two bullets) had only one been fired. 'One might have caused the
result, but in fact both did so.' "177 The factors believed to be causally
relevant (the two bullets) are incorporated into the description of the
manner of occurrence of the injury (death by two bullets), and they are
then demonstrated to be causally relevant because we cannot construct
that precise description without them.
Such an approach could just as easily have included the victim's
knife wound, his silk shirt, or the air temperature in the description of
the manner of occurrence of the injury. If so included, each of these
conditions would also be proven under Perkins' test to be but-for causes
of the harm. We do not include them because we do not believe they
were causally relevant. But that is precisely the issue the test is supposed
to determine. The test "proves" only what has already been decided. It
does not tell us how that decision was made or help us to make it in hard
78
cases. 1
176. R. PERKINS, CRIMINAL LAW 689 (2d ed. 1969) (emphasis in original).
177. Id. (emphasis in original) (citation omitted).
178. Hart and Honor6, although recognizing that prior causal determinations are hidden in this
method, seem to approve its use. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at xli-xlii, 124-25, 235
& n.56, 252-53; accord J. FLEMING, supra note 4, at 173-74; R. KEETON, supra note 104, at 7; Rizzo,
The Imputation Theory of Proximate Cause: An Economic Framework, 15 GA. L. Rav. 1007, 1020
(1981).
179. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 17; see also id. at 210.
180. One of their examples, discussed in the text, refers to being hit by "different parts of the
car" (manner of occurrence) as well as to "slightly different injuries" (result), but almost all the
other examples refer to different details of the result. However, their suggested approach of using
the but-for test at short intervals throughout the causal process, rather than only once at the time the
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1779
Miller assert that, using the but-for test applied "in minute detail, it
would probably appear that the defendant's fire was a cause, for the posi-
tions of the smoke, ashes, and some parts of the ruins might well have
been caused by [i.e., not have existed but for] the defendant's fire."18 1
Again, this assertion begs the question. Under this approach, the
defendant's fire was a but-for cause only of the precise "positions of the
smoke, ashes, and some parts of the ruins," not of the destruction of the
house, for which these precise details are irrelevant. The detailed
description will be useful only if the plaintiff wishes to recover for dam-
ages that would not have occurred but for the precise position of the
smoke and debris-a most unlikely lawsuit.
If being a but-for cause of even the most trivial detail of a harm were
sufficient to make the defendant a cause of all the harm, the detailed but-
for approach would prove too much. Becht and Miller discuss an exam-
ple in which an inattentive driver hits a pedestrian who suddenly ran into
the path of the driver's car. If the driver had been attentive, he could
have swerved a little, but not enough to avoid impact with serious injury.
Nevertheless, a detailed application of the but-for test shows that the
driver's inattentiveness "was a cause of the injuries actually suffered,"
since "the injuries would have been at least slightly different and would
have been inflicted by different parts of the car if the driver had
swerved."' 8 2 Becht and Miller admit that both laypersons and lawyers,
using the common knowledge of causation upon which Becht and Miller
rely so strongly, 183 would conclude that the driver's inattentiveness was
not a cause in such a case. They suggest that laypersons and lawyers
make this mistake by failing to pay careful attention to the precise
details.' 8 4 But laypersons and lawyers, even after considering the precise
details, would still assert correctly that the inattentiveness was not a
cause of the serious injury, although it may have been a (but-for) cause of
some details associated with the injury. These details have causal signifi-
cance only if they contributed to the seriousness of the injury.
Becht and Miller realize that they, rather than the laypersons and
lawyers, must give way on this issue. They compromise their usual
causal principles by "equating the injuries." They reluctantly disregard
process is completed, is similar to Perkins's detailing of the manner of occurrence. See id. at 15-17,
19.
181. Id. at 18.
182. Id. at 28. Becht and Miller use the phrases "hypothetical inquiry" and "construction of
parallel series," but they acknowledge that their approach is a narrow form of the but-for test. The
test is applied step-by-step and in minute detail, and it excludes consideration of causes that the actor
could not have prevented. Id. at 17-21, 32; see infra text accompanying notes 211 & 219.
183. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8,at 9-11; see infra text accompanying notes 209-11,
217.
184. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8,at 28-29.
1780 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
C. The Substantial-FactorFormula
Those theorists and judges who are unwilling to engage in contor-
tions such as the ones illustrated above to rescue the but-for test from its
inadequacies usually have turned to the substantial-factor formula, either
as a supplement to the but-for test (to apply to the overdetermined-causa-
tion cases) or as a complete substitute for it.
The substantial-factor formula was created originally not as a test of
actual causation but as a guide for resolving proximate-cause issues. The
originator of the formula, Jeremiah Smith, was content with the but-for
test as a test of cause-in-fact, with the usual exception for the overdeter-
mined-causation cases. 1 90 He wanted to devise a practical alternative to
the probability or foreseeability tests for determining the proximate-
cause limitations on liability, because he believed that those tests were
unsound and inconsistent with the results in many cases.19' He proposed
the following formula: "Defendant's tort must have been a substantial
factor in producing the damage complained of."192 ' The accompanying
explanation and alternative formulations clearly stated that the defend-
ant's tort could not be a substantial factor unless it satisfied the but-for
test (with an exception for simultaneous independent sufficient causes); in
addition, it would have to be an appreciable and continously effective or
efficient factor in producing the harm, up to the time of occurrence of the
193
harm.
Thus, the substantial-factor formula was meant to be used as the test
of legal (proximate) cause, but also incorporated the but-for test (and its
exception) for cause-in-fact. Smith's approach was adopted essentially
190. Smith, supra note 106, at 108-09 & n.20, 227, 312, 314 n.36, 316-17 n.41. Smith's
exception for overdetermined causation, however, was very narrow. It encompassed only a very
small subset of such cases-those in which there are two independent simultaneous tortious causes,
each by itself sufficient to produce the harm. Id. at 109 n.20, 312, 316-17 n.41.
191. Id. at 105, 115-28, 223-52, 308-09.
192. Id. at 309.
193. Id. at 310-12, 314 n.36.
1782 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
202. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 131-34; H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note
8, at 97, 293-94; C. MORRIS & C.R. MORRIS, supra note 4, at 174-75; Malone, supra note 6, at 88-97.
203. L. GREEN, supra note 2, at 153-58.
204. E.g., W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 240 & n.33. The fifth edition of Prosser's
hornbook, edited by others, recognizes the policy judgments inherent in the substantial-factor
formula. PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, § 41, at 266-69.
205. E.g., Prosser, Proximate Cause in California,38 CALIF. L. REV. 369, 375-78 (1950).
1784 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
212. Id. at 21-24. Becht and Miller assert that an omission can only be a negative cause-that it
can only contribute by failing to prevent or block the positive causal sequence that actually produces
the result, rather than by itself triggering the actual causal sequence that produces the result. Id. at
170-71. But an omission can trigger an actual causal sequence. For example, an omission to salute
causes a soldier to be disciplined, or an omission to put money in the parking meter causes the
driver's car to be ticketed. The mental perception of the omission provides the connecting link.
213. Id. at 41-42.
214. Id. at 52-63.
215. Id. at 54; see also id. at 33, 52, 63, 65, 140.
216. Id. at 66.
1786 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
some difficulty with a case in which the defendant negligently welds the
roof of a car, leaving a sharp edge, and the driver's head is crushed
against the roof at the weld point when the roof is smashed in during an
accident. They steadfastly assert that the case is one in which direct per-
ception or inference, unaided by any hypothetical inquiry, shows a lack
of causation by the sharp weld, just as direct perception or inference
shows that the color of the roof was not a cause of the injury.2 17
The direct-perception argument relies on the notion that there are
observable and describable causal qualities or forces in objects or events.
Becht and Miller eventually concede that this notion is naive as com-
pared with the Humean account, which is based on causal generaliza-
tions. 1 8 Even if the direct-perception notion were creditable, it is
difficult to imagine how the lack of causation by the sharp weld could be
perceived in the circumstances given. It is also difficult to understand
what is meant by "direct inference." An inference is based on some con-
cept of how things generally happen-that is, on causal generalizations.
Causal generalizations incorporate the belief that the cause is in some
sense necessary for the occurrence of the consequence. The but-for test is
simply the means by which we determine whether this element of neces-
sity exists in the particular case.
Becht and Miller argue that, even if it is true that they are explicitly
or implicitly using the but-for test in every case, they are using a less
restrictive version. Unlike the usual version, they compare what hap-
pened with what would have happened in as minute detail as possible.
Moreover, in those cases in which there was more than one positive
causal sequence that led to the injury, they only require that the defend-
ant's act or omission have been necessary for the continuation of the pos-
itive causal sequence with which it was associated, rather than requiring
that it have been necessary for the injury itself.2" 9
The first distinction-their use of minute detail-is nullified by their
tactic of "equating the injuries" to avoid finding but-for causation when-
ever there is a slight difference between the actual process or result and
the hypothesized process and result.22 °
The second distinction, however, is a real one. It enables them to
find that causation exists in many of the overdetermined-causation cases.
For example, in the merged-fires case the defendant's tortious conduct
will be treated as a cause of the destruction of the house if it was a but-for
cause of one of the fires, even though the house would have been burnt
down by the other fire anyway. The defendant's tortious conduct was a
but-for cause of one of the duplicative causal sequences, and that is suffi-
cient to establish the causal connection to the destruction of the house.22 1
Becht and Miller's causal-contribution analysis ends up being very
similar to the "necessary element of a sufficient set" test. 222 However, it
is not exactly equivalent. Indeed, it produces anomalous results precisely
to the extent that it varies from the latter test. Becht and Miller's
approach requires that the tortious act or omission have been a necessary
condition for one of the positive (actual) causal sequences that contrib-
uted to the injury. They are therefore forced to deny that causation
exists when the overdetermined-causation problem results from duplica-
tive or preempted conditions that affect the same positive causal
sequence, rather than from the existence of multiple positive causal
sequences.
For example, they discuss the case in which C negligently fails to
discover and repair defective brakes in a car before renting the car to D,
who, unaware of the defective condition of the brakes, negligently fails to
try to use them to avoid hitting P. P is hit, but he would not have been
hit if the brakes had been working properly and D had used them. C's
omission (the failure to inspect and repair the brakes) was not a neces-
sary condition for the occurrence of the positive causal sequence that
produced the injury, since D made no attempt to use the brakes. Simi-
larly, given C's omission, D's omission (the failure to try to use the
brakes) was not a necessary condition either. Becht and Miller unhap-
pily but firmly conclude that neither omission was a cause of the injury,
but would hold both C and D liable to avoid a "morally indefensible"
and "inexcusable" result.223
The same problem occurs with acts. Assume that a cable has a max-
imum safe load capacity of one ton when it is in good condition. C negli-
gently weakens the cable (for example, by cutting a few of its strands) so
224. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 57-58 & n.85. See infra text following notes 245
& 250 for the disposition of the case under the "necessary element of a sufficient set" test.
225. This point, at least with respect to omissions and the tortious aspect of acts, was not missed
by Green, who was a lifelong critic of the but-for test. In his earlier writings, he had focused the
causal inquiry on the negligent aspect of the actor's conduct. After reading Becht and Miller's book,
however, he insisted that the "orthodox analysis" limits the causal relation issue to the question of
whether the actor's conduct as a whole contributed to the injury. Green, supranote 8, at 546, 549-
51. He also claimed that there is no need to distinguish omissions from acts since "omissions to act
are merely incidents in a longer line of affirmative conduct and are easily resolved into it." Id. at
546; see id. at 546-47. We have already seen that this approach produces anomalous results unless
the tortious-aspect causation requirement is smuggled back in as part of the duty or proximate-cause
analysis. This is, in fact, what Green and his followers have done, with mixed success. See supra
text accompanying notes 111-26.
226. H.L.A. HART& A. HONORt,supra note 10, at 105-10, 116-19, 122, 216-29; H.L.A. HART
& T. HONORS, supra note 8, at 111-17, 122-25, 128-29, 235-53.
227. Fleming incorporated much of Hart and Honor6's exposition, including its deficient
aspects, into the second edition of his treatise. J. FLEMING, THE LAW OF TORTS 178-81 & n.h (2d
ed. 1961). The exposition has been retained with slight modifications in subsequent editions. E.g., J.
FLEMING, supra note 4, at 170-71, 173-74. Professors Cole, Becht, and Miller omit the necessary-
condition element and treat the test as a "sufficient set" approach. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1789
note 8, at 202-04, 222, discussedsupra note 222; Cole, supranote 7, at 485, 486 n.80, 488, 495, 505 &
n.133, 769, 770 n.16. Professors Fraser and Howarth also mention the NESS test, but attribute it to
Professor Papineau rather than to Hart and Honor6 and reject it, after misapplying it, in favor of a
probabilistic increased-risk "causal" test. Fraser & Howarth, More concern for cause, 4 LEGAL
STUD. 131, 133 & n.19, 135-38, 140-42, 145-56 (1984). Similarly, Mario Rizzo converts the INUS
(Insufficient but Necessary element of an Unnecessary but Sufficient set) test, which is similar to the
NESS test and was elaborated by Mackie subsequent to Hart and Honor6's book, into a
probabilistic-linkage test. Rizzo, supra note 178, at 1009-16; see infra text accompanying note 234.
228. T. BEAUCHAMP & A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 4-11, 80-81, 87-88, 91-92, 139-43;
H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 10-11, 14-15.
229. T. BEAUCHAMP & A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 23-24, 84-87, 92-97, 114-15, 132, 136-
37, 141; H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 10-11, 44-49; Mackie, supranote 21, at 23-24,
27-32, 35-38.
1790 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
2. The Duplicative-CausationCases
As elaborated, Hart and Honor6's NESS test is only slightly less
restrictive than the Restatement's substantial-factor exception to the but-
for test, which only applies when each of two actively operating factors
was sufficient by itself for the occurrence of the injury. 2 35 Hart and
Honore do not require that each of the factors have been actively operat-
ing, but they seem to require that each have been sufficient by itself for
the occurrence of the injury. 236 For example, in the merged-fires cases,
they assume that each fire would have been sufficient by itself for the
destruction of the plaintiff's house. The NESS test then confirms causal
contribution by each fire. Each fire was necessary for the sufficiency of a
set of actual antecedent conditions that did not include the other fire.23 7
The requirement that each factor have been sufficient by itself (when
combined with the background conditions) is too restrictive and is not a
part of the basic concept of causation that is reflected in the NESS test.
238. Corey v. Havener, 182 Mass. 250, 65 N.E. 69 (1902) (noisy motorcycles); Anderson v.
Minneapolis, St. P. & S. Ste. M. Ry., 146 Minn. 430, 179 N.W. 45 (1920) (merged fires). The cases
are discussed in Malone, supra note 6, at 90-91.
239. E.g., Michie v. Great Lakes Steel Div., 495 F.2d 213 (6th Cir.), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 997
(1974); Warren v. Parkhurst, 45 Misc. 466, 92 N.Y.S. 725 (1904), afid, 105 A.D. 239, 93 N.Y.S.
1009 (1905), aff'd, 186 N.Y. 45, 78 N.E. 579 (1906); see J. FLEMING, supra note 4, at 176.
240. Malone, supra note 6, at 89.
241. The term "tortious conduct" should always be interpreted to mean the tortious aspect of
the actor's conduct. See supra text accompanying notes 135-45.
242. Malone, supra note 6, at 89 (emphasis in original).
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW
243. I assume that the injury was not accelerated or aggravated by the extra units of pollution.
If it was, causal contribution would be even clearer. I also assume that the units of pollution arrived
simultaneously at the site of the injury. Obviously, if five units arrived before the other two and
produced the injury before the other two arrived, the first five units were causes of the injury and the
last two were not. Their potential effects were preempted by the effects of the first five. See infra text
accompanying notes 247-51.
1794 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
fire is broken down into portions; in the latter case, the amount of the
first defendant's pollution is broken down into portions.
The NESS test would attribute causal status to a very small fire that
merged with an overwhelming large fire. The very small fire was a dupli-
cative cause of any resulting injury. Whether the person who tortiously
caused the very small fire should be held liable for any or all of the result-
ing injury is an issue of policy or principle that comes under the heading
of damages. 2 "
The same analysis applies to the weakened-cable hypothetical.2 41 In
that example, a cable with a maximum safe load capacity of one ton was
weakened by C, who negligently cut a few of its strands so that it would
break if subjected to a one-ton load. D then negligently put a two-ton
load on the cable, which would have caused it to break even if the cable
were in good condition, and the cable broke at the weakened point. C's
weakening of the cable was necessary for the sufficiency of a set of actual
antecedent conditions which included a load of at least one ton, and the
sufficiency of this set was not affected by the fact that the load was more
than one ton. Indeed, the causal contribution of C's weakening of the
cable is evidenced by the fact that the cable broke at the weakened
point.2 46 Similarly, D's overloading of the cable was necessary for the
sufficiency of a set of actual antecedent conditions that included a cable
with a load capacity of at most one ton, and the sufficiency of this set was
not affected by the fact that the cable had a capacity of less than one ton
as a result of the weakening. C's weakening of the cable and D's over-
loading of it are duplicative causes of the cable's breaking and the result-
ing injury to the plaintiff.
3. The Preemptive-CausationCases
So far, the discussion has concentrated on the duplicative-causation
cases. I turn now to the preemptive-causation cases. Hart and Honors
mention situations in which the defendant asserts that someone else
would have shot the plaintiff or stolen his property if the defendant had
not done so.24 7 The defendant's argument would succeed under a literal
application of the Restatement, which adheres to the but-for test unless
the alternative factor was "actively operating."24 But, under the NESS
test, the defendant's tortious act clearly was a cause of the injury, since it
244. See infra text accompanying notes 258-73.
245. See supra text accompanying note 224.
246. Of course, if the cable broke at another point, Cs weakening of the cable would not be a
necessary element of any sufficient set of actual antecedent conditions. See infra text following note
250.
247. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORIf, supra note 8, at 124-25, 249-50.
248. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 432(2) (1965); see supra text accompanying note
235.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW
251. Thus, the court's holding in State v. Scates, 50 N.C. (5 Jones) 420 (1858), that the
defendant could not be held liable, even though medical witnesses testified that his burning of a child
was the "primary cause" of the child's death, if an independent blow by someone else hastened the
death, is clearly erroneous unless the blow was an immediate, preemptive cause of the death. The
case is discussed in H.L.A. HART & T. HONOR, supra note 8, at 242.
252. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at xl, 124-25, 207, 249-50.
253. I at 250-51.
1985] CA USATION IN TORT LAW 1797
but this also was not one of the actual conditions. In each instance, the
defendant's tortious act is a preemptive cause of the injury and the result-
ing economic loss, and the subsequent preempted condition is not a cause
260
of the economic lOSS.
courts shift the burden to the defendant to establish that (1) the injury
would have occurred anyway as a result of independent nontortious con-
ditions, (2) he contributed to only a part of the injury, or (3) he is entitled
to contribution from the other defendants based on relative tortious
contribution.2 65
The causal issue is almost always confused with the policy-laden
damages issue in the overwhelming-force cases involving passive condi-
tions. When an overwhelming force combines with an active condition,
the courts are less likely to confuse the two issues. Thus, in the merged-
fires cases, the courts generally recognize that the defendant's smaller fire
that combined with a much larger fire nevertheless contributed to the
injury. If the defendant avoids liability, it is not due to a lack of causal
contribution but rather due to noncausal limitations. For example, the
defendant usually can avoid liability if he proves that the other fire was
independently sufficient and of nontortious origin, or perhaps even if it
was also of tortious origin if it was so overwhelming as to make the
defendant's contribution relatively insignificant.26 6 On the other hand,
the defendant is unlikely to escape liability even though his contribution
was a very small part of the total cause if it was necessary for the conse-
quence or, although unnecessary, was combined with a large number of
similarly small contributions, as in the pollution cases.26 7
When the overwhelming force combines with a passive condition,
however, most courts and commentators tend to fall back on the but-for
test and erroneously deny causal contribution. 268 For example, the
courts deny that the defendant's negligent failure to construct an ade-
quate dam or to keep runoff pipes free of debris was a cause of flooding
that would have occurred given a normal storm, if the actual storm was
an extraordinary one that would have caused flooding even if the defend-
(1972); Landes & Posner, Joint and Multiple Tortfeasors: An Economic Analysis, 9 J. LEGAL STUD.
517, 550-51 (1980); Robinson, supra note 7, at 716 & n.12.
265. In addition to the cases cited supra notes 262-64, see Michie v. Great Lakes Steel Div., 495
F.2d 213 (6th Cir.), cert. denied, 419 U.S. 997 (1974); Maddux v. Donaldson, 362 Mich. 425, 108
N.W.2d 33 (1961). Some courts have adopted a "comparative causation" allocation formula in the
strict product liability cases, since there is no negligence or fault as is required under the
comparative-negligence (fault) rubric. E.g., General Motors Corp. v. Hopkins, 548 S.W.2d 344
(Tex. 1977). However, from a purely causal standpoint, each necessary (or NESS) condition is
equally a cause. At best, the comparative-causation formula is a camouflage for a "comparative
responsibility" approach (surely a better and more helpful term), in which the types and degrees of
tortious conduct involved and the policies underlying each type of tortious conduct are weighed to
allocate liability. E.g., H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 232-34; see Robinson, supra
note 7, at 758-68. At worst, the comparative-causation formula invites resort to mechanistic,
generally inapplicable calculations of relative energy or force, which have little to do with the basic
principles and goals of tort liability. E.g., Epstein, Defenses, supra note 49, at 179-80; Epstein, Reply,
supra note 49, at 478 n.5.
266. E.g., Kingston v. Chicago & N.W. Ry., 191 Wis. 610, 615-16, 211 N.W. 913, 915 (1927).
267. See cases cited supra note 239.
268. This point is noted in Malone, supra note 6, at 92-94.
1800 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
ant had not been negligent.26 9 Similarly, they have stated that the
defendant's negligent failure to remove a rotten pole is not a cause of
injury when the pole is knocked down by a car that hits it with such force
that it would have been knocked down even if it were not rotten.270
These are overdetermined-causation cases that are entirely analo-
gous to the merged-fires cases and the weakened-cable case.27 t Thus, if
the rotten pole broke at its weak point, the weak condition clearly con-
tributed to the injury. It was a necessary element of a sufficient set of
actual antecedent conditions that included an impact with at least
enough force to knock down a rotten pole. The sufficiency of the set was
not affected by the fact that the impact had a greater force, unless the
impact knocked the pole over in its entirety rather than breaking it at its
weak point. Similarly, the failure to remove debris from a dam's runoff
pipes or to build it high enough to prevent flooding during a normal
storm is a duplicative cause of flooding that occurs during an extraordi-
nary storm. The unremoved debris or inadequate height is a necessary
element in a sufficient set of actual antecedent conditions that includes an
at least normal storm, and the sufficiency of this set is not affected by the
fact that the storm was larger than normal.
A few courts have recognized that the defendant's tortious conduct
contributed to the injury in these passive-condition cases. Indeed, some
courts have held the defendant liable even when the injury would have
occurred anyway as a result of independently sufficient nontortious con-
ditions 272 However, if the noncausal policy limitations adopted in the
merged-fires and successive-injury cases are followed, the defendant
should be able to avoid liability in such circumstances. These policy lim-
itations, rather than the false denial of causation, explain the ultimate
result in those cases in which liability is denied because the injury would
have occurred anyway due to the extraordinary force of a storm.
Conversely, given the usual policy limitations, the defendant should
not escape liability when the duplicative or preempted condition was also
of tortious origin-for example, when the defendant's rotten pole is
knocked down by a negligent driver and an innocent third party is
injured. This case is the same as a merged-fires case in which the defend-
269. E.g., City of Piqua v. Morris, 98 Ohio St. 42, 120 N.E. 300 (1918); RESTATEMENT
(SECOND) OF TORTS § 432(l) illustration 2 (1965); A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 90-93;
L. GREEN, supra note 2, at 150-51; PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, § 41, at 265-66 & n.16.
Contra RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 450; Malone, supra note 6, at 92-94.
270. E.g., Gibson v. Garcia, 96 Cal. App. 2d 681, 687, 216 P.2d 119, 123 (1950).
271. See supra text following notes 245 & 250.
272. O'Connor v. Chicago, M. & St. P. Ry., 163 Wis. 653, 654, 158 N.W. 343, 344 (1916) (weak
tree blown down by storm that would have blown down sound tree); Nitro-Phosphate & Odam's
Chem. Manure v. London & St. Katherine Docks, 9 Ch. D. 503, 527 (C.A. 1878) (levee built too low
overflowed by extraordinarily high tide that would have overflowed levee built to proper height); see
Carpenter, supra note 127, at 418-19.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW
278. E.g., Weeks v. McNulty, 101 Tenn. 495, 48 S.W. 809 (1898). Contra Fraser & Howarth,
supra note 227, at 135-36.
279. E.g., M'Williams v. Sir Williams Arrol Ltd., 1962 Sess. Cas. 70 (H.L.); Qualcast
(Wolverhampton) Ltd. v. Haynes, 1959 A.C. 743; H.L.A. HART & T. HONOR9, supranote 8, at 127.
Contra Fraser & Howarth, supra note 227, at 135-36.
280. McLaughlin, supra note 175, at 155 n.25.
281. See supra text accompanying notes 250, 258-60. Becht and Miller conclude that neither C
nor D was a cause. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 210. This erroneous conclusion results
from their application of the but-for test to two factors that were both in the same causal sequence.
See supra text accompanying notes 222-24.
282. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 239-40 & n.70.
283. A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 205-10. Becht and Miller rely on the tautological
"would not have died when and as he did" argument. Id. at 210; see supra text accompanying notes
176-78. The applicable NESS analysis is discussed supra text accompanying notes 249-50.
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW 1803
tional but-for test. But the concept of causation is much more subtle and
complex than the but-for test. Thus, whenever the but-for test is not
satisfied, the factfinder must utilize this more complex notion of causa-
tion, with its often subtle distinction between actual sufficiency and mere
apparent (preempted) sufficiency, before the causal inquiry can be
concluded.
1. The Hypothetical-InquiryArgument
Many legal writers assert that the counterfactual analysis of neces-
sity "takes the eye off the ball" by asking what would have happened,
rather than focusing on what actually happened, and thereby injects pol-
icy issues into the causal inquiry. Some writers deplore this alleged effect
28 5
of necessity analysis,"8 4 while others embrace it.
The message of the preceding sections of this Part, however, is that
the notion of necessity is fundamental to the concept of causation,
although it is subsidiary to the notion of sufficiency rather than being the
direct and exclusive criterion of causal contribution as in the but-for test.
Efforts to escape from necessary-condition analysis by applying the
causal inquiry to the actor's conduct as a whole or resorting to une-
laborated formulas or paradigm cases are therefore ultimately futile.28 6
The causal question is not simply "What happened? ' 28 7 but rather
"How did it happen?" Since Hume, it has generally been accepted that
there is no inherent causal force or quality in objects which can be
directly observed. We observe only certain successions of events and
284. E.g., Green, supranote 158, at 605; Green, supra note 8, at 556-57, 559; Thode, supranote
100, at 426-27 & n.15, 431; Note, supra note 27, at 1531-33; see Epstein, supra note 13, at 160-61.
285. E.g., Malone, supra note 6, at 67-68 & n.9; sources cited supra note 7.
286. See supra text accompanying notes 49-99, 107-17 & 190-225.
287. E.g., W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 237; Epstein, supra note 13, at 160; Morris, supra
note 3, at 1088-89; Thode, supra note 100, at 431, 433-34.
1804 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
speed rather than at eighty miles per hour, they are using policy consid-
erations to drastically reduce the range of conjecture about what would
have happened if the defendant had not been driving at eighty miles per
297
hour.
This argument depends on the common but fallacious assumption
that the courts are trying to determine what would or might have hap-
pened if the defendant had not been driving at eighty miles per hour.
Insofar as the causal inquiry is concerned, the courts are not interested,
and should not be interested, in that broad inquiry. They are interested
only in determining the causal effect of the tortious aspect of the defen-
dant's conduct. For example, in the speeding cases the courts want to
know whether the excess speed (the tortious aspect) was a necessary ele-
ment in some set of actual antecedent conditions that was sufficient for
the occurrence of the accident. They therefore change only the tortious
condition when setting up the counterfactual situation. They remove the
speed in excess of the legal speed from the set of actual antecedent condi-
tions to determine whether the set would have been sufficient without it.
They want to know whether the tortious aspect (the excess speed) actu-
ally contributed to the accident. They do not want to know, as part of
the causal inquiry, whether the defendant would have driven at the legal
speed if he had not driven at eighty miles per hour, or whether he might
have been more attentive or otherwise more careful if he had been driv-
ing at the legal speed. The causal issue is restricted to the narrow ques-
tion of the actual effect of the excess speed given the other conditions
(attentiveness, etc.) that actually existed.
Similarly, the courts do not change the actual conduct of the plain-
tiff or third parties when they set up the counterfactual situation. They
are not using policy considerations, but rather careful causal methodol-
ogy, when they remove only the defendant's excess speed in order to
determine the causal effect of that excess speed in the actual
298
circumstances.
Of course, once a court sets up the counterfactual situation by elimi-
nating the particular tortious condition, it must then determine the hypo-
thetical consequences of that change. As even Malone admits, 99 in most
cases there is little difficulty, for example, when the change is removing
the explosive character of a substance or the act of firing a gun. The
analysis becomes more complicated when human reactions to the
changed situation must be estimated. Again, however, the analysis is
usually fairly easy and not too speculative. People's reactions generally
will be fairly predictable using causal generalizations in which there is a
297. Id. at 771, 784-85, 792-97; see also Malone, supra note 6, at 67.
298. Contra Thode, supra note 100, at 426 n.15.
299. Malone, supra note 6, at 71 & n.25.
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1807
2. Malone's Arguments
Malone attacks the factual nature of the causal inquiry differently.
He does not challenge the process by which the counterfactual setting is
established, and he recognizes that causal generalizations provide the
foundation for any particular causal judgment. Instead, he presents an
array of arguments to demonstrate that the policies underlying particular
legal rules affect both causal judgments themselves and also the courts'
selection of the degree of confidence that those judgments must attain in
order to sustain liability in a specific case.
Malone notes that causal judgments, like any other evaluation of
raw evidentiary data, involve interpretation and the drawing of infer-
ences based on the past experience and "judging personality" of the per-
300. Cole, supra note 7, at 778-79; accord A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 175-76.
301. Cole, supra note 7, at 771-74, 777, 784-91.
302. T. BEAUCHAMP& A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 119-20, 131-37, 145-49; Mackie, supra
note 21, at 24-25, 30-31.
303. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 45-48; see T. BEAUCHAMP & A.
ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 141; infra text accompanying notes 366-72. Contra Cole, supra note
7, at 791-92.
1808 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
308. Although there are undertones of epistemological skepticism in this portion of Malone's
article, I do not believe that he is arguing that there are no real facts, or that we cannot perceive or
agree on the existence of any facts because of our subjective filtering of sense data. See T.
BEAUCHAMP & A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 16-17, 33-79, 88, 96-97, 112-15, 131-45, 152-55,
259-60; A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 2-3, 9, 11.
309. Malone, supra note 6, at 67-72, 84-86, 88-89.
310. See supra text accompanying notes 235-60.
311. Malone, supra note 6, at 88-94; accord Carpenter, supra note 262, at 943, 952; see supra
text accompanying notes 241-42.
312. Malone, supra note 6, at 68-79, 85-88, 94-96.
313. See cases cited infra note 335.
1810 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
versely, the cases which seem to raise the burden of proof are generally
either cases in which the court rigidly adheres to the but-for test despite
good evidence of causal contribution, or cases in which the court believes
the evidence is insufficient to support any well-grounded belief (rather
than pure speculation) even on the issue of causal contribution. 14
For example, it usually is difficult to establish that proper lighting
probably would have prevented the victim's falling down the stairs, or
that proper construction or maintenance of a sidewalk to prevent irregu-
larities in the surface probably would have prevented the victim from
slipping on it when it was covered with ice. But the plaintiff often may
be able to establish in such cases that the lack of light or the irregular
surface more likely than not satisfied the NESS test and therefore con-
tributed to the accident. Thus, the plaintiff may be able to prove that the
lack of light was necessary for the sufficiency of a set of actual antecedent
conditions which included a person of "at least X size" descending the
stairs at a rate of "at least Y steps per minute," and that the sufficiency of
this set was not preempted but rather reinforced by the existence of the
additional conditions of greater size and faster descent. Similarly, the
irregular surface might well have been necessary for the sufficiency of a
set containing a sidewalk of "at least X slipperiness." As Leon Green
clearly recognized, in these cases as well as in the more familiar overde-
termined-causation cases, the but-for test distracts attention from the
31 5
issue of causal contribution.
As long as the but-for test is considered to be the applicable test of
causation in these cases, there will be a strong urge to lessen or shift the
burden of proof when the court perceives that causal contribution may
well exist. While that approach was adopted in the original Restatement
of Torts,3 16 the Restatement (Second) states that the plaintiff bears the
usual (more likely than not) burden of proof in these cases.3 17 Although
the Restatement (Second) deemphasizes but-for language in favor of sub-
stantial-factor language, the but-for language has not been entirely elimi-
nated and the substantial-factor language is typically nebulous.
3 18
Consequently, the overall discussion is hardly enlightening.
314. E.g., Taylor v. City of Yonkers, 105 N.Y. 202, 209, 11 N.E. 642, 644 (1887) (rigid
adherence to but-for test); New York Cent. R.R. v. Grimstad, 264 F. 334 (2d Cir. 1920) (pure
speculation on causal contribution).
315. Green, supra note 8, at 556-59. But see id. at 560-61 (ratifying Malone's argument).
316. RESTATEMENT OF TORTS § 432(1) comment c and accompanying illustrations (1934),
cited in Malone, supra note 6, at 73 n.26.
317. RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 433B(1) comment b and accompanying illustrations
(1965).
318. See A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 135-37. The story in England is similar. For
a brief period, the practice was to shift the burden to the defendant when a statutory duty had been
breached to show that the precaution would not have averted the injury. Vyner v. Waldenburg
Bros., 1946 K.B. 50 (C.A. 1945). But then the House of Lords declared that the plaintiff must
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW
"prove his case by the ordinary standard of proof in civil actions: he must make it appear at least
that on a balance of probabilities the breach of duty caused or materiallycontributed to his injury."
Bonnington Castings Ltd. v. Wardlaw, 1956 A.C. 613, 620 (emphasis added) (opinion of Lord Reid).
In subsequent cases the House of Lords has reaffirmed that contribution to the injury is sufficient to
establish cause-in-fact, although the commentators continue to be mesmerized by the but-for tes'
and to view the decisions as exceptions to the actual-causation requirement that were adopted for
moral or policy reasons. E.g., M'Ghee v. National Coal Bd., 1973 Sess. Cas. 37 (H.L. 1972),
discussed in Fraser & Howarth, supra note 227, at 141-42; Weinrib, supra note 7. Weinrib takes a
broader view of actual causation than most, but still argues that policy factors were determinative.
For an earlier case very similar to McGhee, see Gardiner v. Motherwell Mach. & Scrap Co., 1961
Sess. Cas. 1 (H.L.). See supra text accompanying note 261.
319. Malone, supra note 6, at 82-85. The alternative-causation cases are discussed infra text
accompanying notes 342-62.
320. Malone, supra note 6, at 78.
321. Id. at 86.
322. Annot., 13 A.L.R.2d 11, 21-24 (1950), cited in Malone, supra note 6, at 88 n.68.
323. Malone does not mention the conspiracy of silence among medical professionals. This
practice was bolstered by the locality rule which limited testimony to doctors from the same locality
and sometimes even the same school of practice. See, e.g., Brune v. Belinkoff, 354 Mass. 102, 235
N.E.2d 793 (1968); Bowles v. Bourdon, 148 Tex. 1, 219 S.W.2d 779 (1949).
1812 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
est. '' 324 Usually they will be unable to state that the consequence would
not have occurred but for the defendant doctor's negligent mistreatment
or failure to treat, or even that the mistreatment or failure to treat con-
tributed to the consequence. At best, they often may be able to testify
only that the mistreatment or failure to treat reduced the plaintiff's
chance of recovery-for example, from forty percent to twenty percent,
or from eighty percent to seventy percent.3 25
The problems presented by these reduced-chance cases, as well as
the similar increased-risk and alternative-cause (for example, hunting-
accident) cases, are explored in Part III. For now, it is important to note
that the problems are correctly perceived by courts and commentators as
problems related to proof of causation, which are resolved by turning to
the policies or principles that underlie the actual-causation requirement
itself rather than the policies or principles that underlie the particular
rule that was violated.3 26 Indeed, the few cases that have allowed recov-
ery in the reduced-chance context generally have been medical-malprac-
tice cases, despite Malone's contention that the "policy thrust" of the
327
rules in this area is too "short and timid" to permit such recovery.
Finally, it should be noted that shifting, lessening, or raising the bur-
den of proof on causation does not make the causal inquiry itself any less
factual. The causal inquiry is still an empirical, factual one that results in
a certain degree of confidence that causation did or did not exist in a
particular situation. The decision as to how high that degree of confi-
dence must be, and who bears the burden of producing evidence to sup-
port that degree of confidence, is a distinct issue of policy or principle. In
the criminal law, the prosecution bears the burden of establishing a very
high degree of confidence: "beyond a reasonable doubt." In tort law, the
plaintiff generally bears the burden of establishing a "more likely than
not" degree of confidence. But in each context, the causal inquiry itself is
a factual one.
Nevertheless, a demonstration of frequent ad hoc shifting or lessen-
ing of the burden of proof on causation would indicate that the actual-
causation requirement, rather than being a fundamental criterion of tort
liability, is just one more manipulable doctrine. But no such ad hoc
324. Malone, supra note 6, at 87; see Annot., supra note 322, at 22-23.
325. Malone, supra note 6, at 86-87.
326. See, e.g., sources cited infra notes 335, 339, 348; Delgado, supra note 7; Robinson, supra
note 7.
327. Malone, supra note 6, at 81, 87. See, e.g., Kallenberg v. Beth Israel Hosp., 45 A.D.2d 177,
357 N.Y.S.2d 508 (1974), aff'd mem., 37 N.Y.2d 719, 337 N.E.2d 128, 374 N.Y.S.2d 615 (1975);
Herskovits v. Group Health Coop., 99 Wash. 2d 609, 664 P.2d 474 (1983). For useful reviews of the
medical malpractice cases, see King, Causation, Valuation, and Chance in Personal Injury Torts
Involving Preexisting Conditionsand Future Consequences, 90 YALE L.J. 1353, 1365 n.38, 1367 n.45,
1368-69 n.53 (1981); Note, Increased Risk of Harm: A New Standardfor Sufficiency of Evidence of
Causationin Medical Malpractice Cases, 65 B.U.L. REV. 275, 281-92 (1985).
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1813
III
CAUSATION, PROBABILITY, AND RISK: PROBLEMS ON THE
FRONTIERS OF TORT LIABILITY
328. Malone, supra note 6, at 71, 77, 78; accord Carpenter, supra note 262, at 943, 947, 952.
329. See infra text accompanying notes 334-62.
330. Interestingly, Malone himself acknowledges these points in his later, less well-known
writings, where he insists that the causal inquiry is "exclusively a fact inquiry" which "should be
maintained utterly devoid of any policy overtones." Malone, supra note 27, at 371; see Note, supra
note 27, at 1540-41 & nn.88 & 89.
331. See Calabresi, supra note 9; sources cited supra notes 6-8.
1814 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
tort cases.332
I have demonstrated elsewhere that the probabilistic increased-risk
concept cannot be substituted for the actual-causation requirement in the
general run of cases without reaching results that are far removed from
3 33 I
the traditional notions of liability that are applied by the courts.
argue here that, even in the risk-exposure cases, more satisfactory results
are reached by adhering to the actual-causation requirement while recog-
nizing a new type of injury-risk exposure-in certain narrowly circum-
scribed situations. The argument is developed by first analyzing the
more traditional reduced-chance and increased-risk cases and then exam-
ining the currently more topical alternative-causation cases.
Finally, I attempt to clarify the fundamental distinction between ex
ante statements of probability or increased risk and ex post statements of
causal contribution. This distinction helps to clarify the risk-exposure
cases and justify the courts' reluctance to accept naked statistical evi-
dence as proof of causation.
332. See Calabresi, supra note 9; Fraser & Howarth, supra note 227; Landes & Posner, supra
note 9; Rizzo, supra note 227; see also G. CHRISTIE, supra note 4, at 246; Shavell, supra note 9.
333. Wright, supra note 9, at 452-55.
334. See supra text accompanying notes 312-27.
335. E.g., Zinnel v. United States Shipping Bd. Emergency Fleet Corp., 10 F.2d 47 (2d Cir.
1925) (missing lifeline); Reynolds v. Texas & Pac. Ry., 37 La. Ann. 694 (1885) (unlit stairway);
Dunham v. Village of Canisteo, 303 N.Y. 498, 104 N.E.2d 872 (1952) (delay in treatment);
RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 433B(1) comment b and accompanying illustrations (1965);
Green, supra note 8, at 558-59 & n.41.
336. E.g., McAllister v. Workmen's Compensation Appeals Bd., 69 Cal. 2d 408, 445 P.2d 313,
71 Cal. Rptr. 697 (1968); M'Ghee v. National Coal Bd., 1973 Sess. Cas. 37 (H.L. 1972); Clarkson v.
Modem Foundries, [1957] 1 W.L.R. 1210 (Leeds Assizes); see Note, IncreasedRisk of Canceras an
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1815
In other cases, however, the plaintiff may be unable to prove that the
tortious aspect of the defendant's conduct more likely than not contrib-
uted to the injury. He may be able to prove only that the tortious
aspect-for example, failure to provide the proper lifesaving equipment
or to properly diagnose and treat the patient-reduced the victim's
chance of avoiding the injury from, say, forty percent to twenty percent.
In these cases, unlike the carcinogenic-exposure cases, there is no incre-
mental, cumulative contribution. The omitted safeguard or treatment
either would or would not have prevented the injury.
One approach to these cases, when the plaintiff cannot establish that
the tortious aspect more likely than not contributed to the injury, is to
reduce the plaintiff's burden of proof to permit recovery even though the
degree of confidence in causal contribution is less than fifty-one percent.
This approach, which has been adopted by a few courts,3 37 weakens the
actual-causation requirement. It does not, however, make the causal
inquiry any less factual.
A second approach is to allow recovery for the reduced chance of
avoiding the injury, rather than for the injury itself. To apply this
approach, the courts would have to recognize the chance of avoiding
injury, in a case where injury actually occurs, as a legally protected inter-
est. If the chance interest is deemed to be legally protected, at least
against "significant impairments, ' 338 a court must then address the
actual causation issue: did the tortious aspect of the defendant's conduct
more likely than not contribute to a (significant) impairment of the
chance interest in this case? If not, the court should not permit the plain-
tiff to recover, no matter how strong the policies underlying the rule that
was violated.
The second approach preserves the integrity of the actual-causation
requirement, while also addressing the basic issues in these cases. Should
the defendant completely escape liability when his tortious conduct
reduced the victim's chance of avoiding an injury that has actually
occurred? This is an issue of policy or principle concerning the types of
interests that should be legally protected. It should be faced and resolved
explicitly, not covertly by diluting the actual-causation requirement.
Actionable Injury, 18 GA. L. REv. 563, 580-81 n.68 (1984). The author of the Note, however,
erroneously assumes that the defendant's contribution was the sole cause if it was independently
sufficient for the occurrence of the cancer. Id.
A defendant who has tortiously contributed to a certain instance of cancer or illness may seek
contribution from other contributing tortfeasors, or from the plaintiff herself if the plaintiff also
contributed (e.g., by smoking). The defendant may even escape liability entirely if he can prove that
the cancer or illness would have occurred anyway as a result of independent nontortious
contributing conditions. See supra text accompanying notes 258-73.
337. See supra note 327.
338. Compare the "significant harm" limitation applicable in private nuisance cases.
RESTATEMENT (SECOND) OF TORTS § 821F (1979).
1816 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
When the policy issues are carefully distinguished from the causal issue,
the liability analysis is greatly improved. For example, if it is admitted
that the interest being protected in these cases is the chance interest,
recovery should be limited to the value of the lost chance rather than all
the damages attributable to the injury itself. A practical method of valu-
ing the lost chance is to multiply the total damages attributable to the
injury by the amount of reduction in the chance of avoiding it.
The second approach appears to be gaining recognition as the pref-
erable one in these cases.3 39 Under this approach, a plaintiff who is actu-
ally injured can recover for the injury itself if he can prove that the
tortious aspect of the defendant's conduct contributed to the injury. If
he cannot prove this, but can prove that the tortious aspect contributed
to a specific reduction in his chance of avoiding the injury, he can recover
for the reduction in the chance.
Some writers have argued that the courts should go even further.
They would allow recovery for risk-imposition even when no tangible
injury has yet resulted from the imposition of the risk.34 Such a dra-
matic extension of the category of protected interests would raise serious
theoretical and practical problems.3 ' In any event, the issues involved
are not causal ones but questions of policy or principle concerning the
types of interests that are to be protected against invasion. They will be
resolved most clearly if they are seen as such.
B. The Alternative-CausationCases
In the alternative-causation cases, several tortfeasors each indepen-
dently exposed the victim to the risk of a specific injury that subsequently
occurred. It is clear, however, that only one (or a few) of the tortfeasors
actually contributed to the injury. The plaintiff is unable to establish
which one (or few) actually contributed. For example, in the leading
case of Summers v. Tice,342 the plaintiff was struck in the eye by a single
339. See O'Brien v. Stover, 443 F.2d 1013, 1018-19 (8th Cir. 1971); James v. United States, 483
F. Supp. 581, 587 (N.D. Cal. 1980); Herskovits v. Group Health Coop., 99 Wash.2d 609, 622-36,
664 P.2d 474, 480-87 (1983) (Pearson, Stafford, and Utter, JJ., and Williams, C.J., concurring);
PROSSER & KEETON, supra note 7, § 41, at 272; Green, supra note 8, at 558-59; King, supra note
327, at 1376-87; Malone, supra note 6, at 80-81.
340. Note, supra note 336; Note, Increased Risk of Diseasefrom Hazardous Waste: A Proposal
for Judicial Relief 60 WASH. L. REV. 635 (1985).
341. Dworkin, Fear ofDisease andDelayed Manifestationof Injuries: A Solution ora Pandora's
Box?, 53 FORDHAM L. REV. 527 (1984). The courts have yet to accept this argument, even those
courts with the most liberal attitudes toward liability. For a recent example, see Collins v. Eli Lilly
Co., 116 Wis. 2d 166, 191 n.10, 342 N.W.2d 37, 49 n.10, cert. denied, 105 S. Ct. 107 (1984),
discussed infra text accompanying notes 356-57. It should be noted that tangible injury includes
emotional distress, as in the "cancerphobia" cases. E.g., Ferrara v. Galluchio, 5 N.Y.2d 16, 152
N.E.2d 249 (1958).
342. 33 Cal. 2d 80, 199 P.2d 1 (1948).
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW 1817
pellet when the two defendants independently fired their shotguns in his
direction. Obviously, only one of the defendants actually caused the
plaintiff's injury, but there was no way to determine from which gun the
pellet came. The court held the defendants jointly and severally liable for
the injury. It shifted the burden of proof on causation to them, on the
ground that it was better to have the loss fall on the two negligent
defendants than on the innocent plaintiff. 43
Summers represents a significant departure from the usual applica-
tion of the actual-causation requirement. Prosser incorrectly states that
the court "merely extended the rule as to the burden of proof on the issue
of apportionment of damages." 3" The rule that Prosser cites shifts the
burden to the defendants to allocate the loss among themselves only after
the plaintiff has established that each defendant contributed to the
injury.3 45 In Summers, however, we know that one of the defendants is
being held liable for an injury to which he did not contribute. This
knowledge also distinguishes Summers from the reduced-chance cases.
As the number of defendants increases, the departure from the usual
principles of tort liability becomes ever more apparent and difficult to
justify. Thus, if there are N defendants, we know that N - 1 of them are
343. This rationale for joint and several liability was adopted long before Summers in Tidal Oil
Co. v. Pease, 153 Okla. 137, 139-40, 5 P.2d 389, 390-91 (1931) (cattle drank from one or both of two
streams poisoned by different defendants); accord Bowman v. Redding & Co., 449 F.2d 956, 967-68
(D.C. Cir. 1971); Abel v. Eli Lilly & Co., 418 Mich. 311, 325-29, 343 N.W.2d 164, 170-72, cert.
denied, 105 S. Ct. 123 (1984); Cook v. Lewis, [1952] 1 D.L.R. 1 (Can. 1951); RESTATEMENT
(SECOND) OF TORTS § 433B(3) (1965).
Although the Summers court noted that ordinarily defendants have better access to evidence on
causation, this was not true in the particular case, and thus was not the basis for the court's decision.
Sindell v. Abbott Labs., 26 Cal. 3d 588, 601-03, 607 P.2d 924, 929-30, 163 Cal. Rptr. 132, 137-38,
cert. denied, 449 U.S. 912 (1980).
Some writers have tried to justify the imposition of liability in the alternative-causation cases by
arguing that the act of each defendant, in conjunction with the other's act, deprived the plaintiff of a
chance of establishing who caused the injury. E.g., A. BECHT & F. MILLER, supra note 8, at 105
n.155; Weinrib, supra note 7, at 525-26. But this argument proves too much. It could be applied to
any case in which there are alternative potential causes, including those attributable to the plaintiff,
innocent third parties, or natural conditions or events. Acceptance of the argument means that the
defendant is being held liable because he prevented the plaintiff from being consoled by the
knowledge that the defendant was not a cause of his injury. The argument has little merit and
distracts attention from the real issues.
For example, in Haft v. Lone Palm Hotel, 3 Cal. 3d 756, 478 P.2d 465, 91 Cal. Rptr. 745
(1970), the argument is entirely gratuitous. The absence of a lifeguard almost surely contributed to
the drownings, and the court properly insisted that the duty to have a lifeguard remained in effect in
the absence of the statutorily specified warning. The warning, if provided, would simply have
reinstated the assumption-of-risk defense that ordinarily could not be invoked by someone who
failed to comply with the statutory lifeguard requirement. See Osborne v. Salvation Army, 107 F.2d
929, 931-32 (2d Cir. 1939) (no assumption of risk if victim was member of class that statute was
meant to protect); Rovegno v. San Jose Knights of Columbus Hall Ass'n, 108 Cal. App. 591, 291 P.
848 (1930) (absence of lifeguard contributed to drowning).
344. W. PROSSER, supra note 1, § 41, at 243 n.56.
345. See sources cited supra note 264.
1818 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
being held liable even though they did not contribute to the injury. As N
increases, the probability that any particular defendant is the one who
caused the injury becomes increasingly small. The argument that the
negligent defendants, rather than the innocent plaintiff, should pay for
the injury becomes more a penal argument than a tort argument. As
Professors Harper and James note, "the only fault which should be rele-
vant to the question of civil liability is fault which has caused (or contrib-
uted to causing) the harm."34' 6 The argument even runs counter to a basic
tenet of the criminal law. In effect, the argument asserts that it is better
that N - 1 defendants who did not contribute to the injury should pay for
it than that the one who did cause it should go free. Moreover, the one
who did cause it still may pay for little or none of the damages, due to
contribution or insolvency.
The Summers rule disadvantages plaintiffs as well as defendants.
The underlying rationale of Summers requires that all the alternative
causes of the injury have been tortious and that all the tortfeasors be
joined as defendants. These requirements ensure that the injury was tor-
tiously caused and that the person who actually caused the injury is
before the court. Thus, in a case in which forty persons were firing, but
only seven of them were negligent, the Summers rationale was held inap-
plicable and the plaintiff obtained no compensation.3 47
These problems with the alternative-liability rationale of Summers
have had to be confronted in the recent DES cases. In these cases, the
plaintiff alleges that she contracted cancer as a result of her mother's
ingesting the drug DES while pregnant with her. Typically, the plaintiff
is unable to identify the particular firm or firms who supplied the DES
that her mother ingested twenty or so years earlier. Because there are
hundreds of firms that supplied DES, many of which no longer exist,
most courts recognize that the Summers rationale and requirements
break down in these cases.3 48
In Sindell v. Abbott Laboratories,349 the California Supreme Court
modified the Summers approach to accomodate the most obvious proce-
dural and fairness problems. It stated that the plaintiff need not identify
346. 2 F. HARPER & F. JAMES, supra note 2, § 20.2 n.24 comment, at 95 (Supp. 1968).
347. Burton v. Waller, 502 F.2d 1261 (5th Cir. 1974), cert. denied, 420 U.S. 964 (1975).
348. E.g., Sindell v. Abbott Labs., 26 Cal. 3d 588, 603-04, 607 P.2d 924, 930-31, 163 Cal. Rptr.
132, 138-39, cert. denied, 449 U.S. 912 (1980); Martin v. Abbott Labs., 102 Wash. 2d 581, 591-95,
689 P.2d 368, 375-77 (1984); Collins v. Eli Lilly Co., 116 Wis. 2d 166, 183-84, 342 N.W.2d 37, 45-
46, cert. denied, 105 S.Ct. 107 (1984). But see Abel v. Eli Lilly & Co., 418 Mich. 311, 329-35, 343
N.W.2d 164, 172-75 (approving use of the Summers approach in the DES context), cert. denied, 105
S.Ct. 123 (1984). However, the court, referring to some of the procedural and fairness problems,
reserved judgment on whether modifications should be made to the approach and on the "validity of
any verdict that may result." Abel, 418 Mich. at 331 n.14, 339-40, 343 N.W.2d at 173 n.14, 177
(emphasis in original).
349. 26 Cal. 3d 588, 607 P.2d 924, 163 Cal. Rptr. 132, cert. denied, 449 U.S. 912 (1980).
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1819
and join all the firms that were operating in the relevant market at the
time that her mother took the DES, but only enough firms to account for
a "substantial percentage" (undefined but apparently between fifty and
seventy-five percent) of that market. In addition, it replaced the defend-
ants' joint and several liability, which holds each defendant responsible
for the entire injury, with several (separate) liability based on each
defendant's proportionate share of the market.
The substantial-percentage requirement apparently is intended to
ensure that there is a substantial probability that the firm which actually
caused the particular plaintiff's injury is before the court. The limitation
of each defendant's liability to a proportion of the damages equivalent to
its share of the market is intended to ensure that, over a large number of
cases, the defendant is in effect being held liable for the injuries that it
actually caused. That is, the two modifications of the Summers approach
are intended to replicate the actual-causation requirement as applied to
DES injuries in the aggregate, so that each individual plaintiff recovers
for her injury and each defendant firm is held liable, in the aggregate,
only for the injuries that it caused.35 °
However, two aspects of the Sindell approach undermine its ability
to replicate the actual-causation requirement in the aggregate. First, the
Sindell court apparently would allocate one hundred percent of the dam-
ages for each injury among the joined defendants based on their relative
market shares, even though the joined defendants usually would repre-
sent less than one-hundred percent of the market. 351 Thus, the joined
defendants (usually the largest firms) will be held liable for more than
their expected share of the total DES damages. Second, unless the total
number of DES injuries is very large, there will be only a very rough
correlation between the injuries actually caused in the aggregate by a
particular firm and those for which it is held liable under the probabilis-
tic market-share approach. If there is only a relatively small number of
injuries in the aggregate, the extent to which the actual distribution of
injuries among firms varies from the predicted distribution, based on
market share, may be quite substantial.35 2
The Sindell result is much more plausible theoretically if it is viewed
as liability for having tortiously exposed the plaintiff to a certain type of
risk, rather than liability for having caused a certain proportion of the
actual injuries themselves. In effect, the Sindell court recognized a new
350. Id. at 613, 607 P.2d at 938, 163 Cal. Rptr. at 146; see Rosenberg, supra note 7, at 873, 881-
83.
351. 26 Cal. 3d at 612-13, 617, 607 P.2d at 937, 940, 163 Cal. Rptr. at 145, 148.
352. For example, although there is an equal probability of a "heads" or "tails" on each toss of
a coin, the fewer times the coin is tossed, the less likely it is that the actual result of the series of
tosses will be approximately equal numbers of "heads" and "tails." See, e.g., H. BRUNK, AN
INTRODUCTION TO MATHEMATICAL STATISTICS 153 (3d ed. 1975).
1820 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
353. Viewed in this way, the Sindell result is an extension of the risk-exposure approach to the
reduced-chance cases. See supra text accompanying notes 338-39.
354. If there are risk-creating characteristics that vary among the products of different firms,
they should be taken into account. See Rosenberg, supra note 7, at 867 & n.68.
355. Sindell, 26 Cal. 3d at 617, 607 P.2d at 940, 163 Cal. Rptr. at 148 (Richardson, Clark, and
Manuel, JJ., dissenting).
356. Martin v. Abbott Labs., 102 Wash. 2d 581, 594-95, 603-04, 689 P.2d 368, 377, 381-82
(1984); Collins v. Eli Lilly Co., 116 Wis. 2d 166, 191 & n.10, 342 N.W.2d 37,49 & n.10, cert. denied,
105 S. Ct. 107 (1984).
357. Collins, 116 Wis. 2d at 193-200, 342 N.W.2d at 50-53.
19851 CAUSATION IN TORT LAW
However, it allows each defendant that proves its absolute share of the
total market to reduce its liability in accordance with that absolute mar-
ket share. The remaining defendants split the remaining damages.3 58
One other group of alternative-causation cases remains to be dis-
3 5 9 in which an uncon-
cussed. The leading case is Ybarra v. Spangard,
scious patient's shoulder was injured during or immediately after an
appendicitis operation. The California Supreme Court held that the
patient could use the doctrine of res ipsa loquitur against all the doctors
and nurses who had anything to do with him while he was unconscious,
in order to raise an inference of negligent causation against the doctors
and nurses as a group. Each would then be held jointly and severally
liable if he or she failed to come forward with an absolving explana-
tion. 360 The court was clearly determined that a conspiracy of silence
should not deprive the patient of his remedy.
Ybarra seems to go even further than Summers. It is not only
unlikely that all the defendants in Ybarra contributed to the injury, but
also unlikely that they all were negligent. However, the decision can be
reconciled with the tortious-aspect causation requirement if it is viewed
as imposing a form of enterprise liability. The court itself mentioned that
all the defendants could be treated as permanent or temporary employees
of the supervising surgeon or the hospital.3 6 1 When all the defendants
are connected through contractual or commercial relationships into a
common enterprise and can adjust the risks and liabilities among them-
selves, and persons injured by that enterprise ordinarily will have a diffi-
cult time pinpointing the tortious source of the injury, it may be
appropriate to treat the defendants as a group entity-an enterprise-
which tortiously caused the injury, and to let the members of the enter-
prise allocate the liability among themselves or absolve themselves, as
they see fit. The other situations to which the Ybarra rationale has been
applied all fit this analysis.362
363. E.g., L. COHEN, THE PROBABLE AND THE PROVABLE (1977); M. FINKELSTEIN,
QUANTITATIVE METHODS IN LAW (1978); Jaffee, Of Probativity and Probability: Statistics,
Scientific Evidence, and the Calculusof Chance at Trial,46 U. PrrT. L. REV. 925 (1985); Kaye, The
Laws of Probabilityand the Law of the Land, 47 U. CH. L. REV. 34 (1979); Kaye, The Paradox of
the Gatecrasherand Other Stories, 1979 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 101; Nesson, The Evidence or the Event? On
JudicialProofand the Acceptability of Verdicts, 98 HARV. L. REV. 1357, 1377-90 (1985); Rosenberg,
supra note 7, at 855-59, 869-74; Saks & Kidd, Human Information Processing and Adjudication:
Trial by Heuristics, 15 LAW & Soc'Y REV. 123 (1981); Tribe, Trial by Mathematics: Precision and
Ritual in the LegalProcess, 84 HARV. L. REV. 1329 (1971); Williams, The Mathematics of Proof (pt.
1), 1979 CRIM. L. REV. 297; Brilmayer & Kornhauser, Quantitative Methods and Legal Decisions
(Book Review), 46 U. CH. L. REV. 116 (1978).
364. E.g., Calabresi, supra note 9, at 71-72; Fraser & Howarth, supra note 227, at 137-41;
Landes & Posner, supra note 9, at 111-16, 134; Rizzo, supra note 178, at 1009-16, 1037-38; Shavell,
supra note 9, at 468-69; see G. CHRISTIE, supra note 4, at 246; Robinson, supra note 7, at 758-60,
764-65. For my criticism of the views of Calabresi, Landes, Posner, and Shavell, see Wright, supra
note 9.
365. E.g., Kaye, The Laws of Probability and the Law of the Land, 47 U. CHI. L. REV. 34
(1979); Kaye, The Limits of the Preponderance of the Evidence Standard: Justifiably Naked
Statistical Evidence and Multiple Causation, 1982 AM. B. FOUND. RESEARCH J. 487, 488-89, 492
n.22, 514; Rosenberg, supra note 7, at 870-73; Saks & Kidd, supra note 363, at 149-54; Tribe, supra
note 363, at 1344-50, 1361 n.102.
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW 1823
tistical data generally cannot perform even this function and therefore
properly are rejected as evidence of causation or identification.
Causal explanations and causal predictions are applications of
causal generalizations to empirical data. The causal generalizations
themselves are derived inductively from empirical observations of
repeated successions of conditions and events. A causal generalization,
however, is not just a statement of observed statistical correlation. The
essence of a causal generalization is the belief that we attach to the gener-
alization: the belief in its causal or lawlike character. A causal general-
ization asserts that the antecedent conditions produce or cause the
subsequent event-that they are necessary elements of a set of conditions
that is sufficient for the occurrence of the event. It is precisely this qual-
ity of causal generalizations that distinguishes them from mere statistical
reports and gives them explanatory and predictive power.36 6
When we seek to understand and explain the occurrence of an event,
we compare the observed sequence of actual events (the "particularistic"
empirical data) with the antecedent conditions and the associated conse-
quence that are specified in the causal generalization. Usually, very few
of the necessary antecedent conditions must be observed in addition to
the consequence to induce us to believe that the causal generalization is
applicable in the particular circumstances. This is true even when the ex
ante probability of the consequence given these circumstances was very
low-for example, A, a very poor marksman, shoots B from a great dis-
tance with a crooked gun in a high wind under conditions of poor visibil-
ity. 3 67 The empirical observation of the consequence itself is a "vital part
of the evidence which supports an explanation of that event. ' 368
Indeed, as Hart and Honor6 have stated, the force of a particular
causal explanation usually depends on its referring to only a few of the
antecedent conditions and its relying, explicitly or implicitly, on causal
generalizations that are framed in broad or even platitudinous terms. It
is unnecessary, even if it were possible, to explain a particular occurrence
by detailing all the antecedent conditions so that we finally arrive at a
universally true statement of invariable and unconditional causal connec-
tion. As the precision and detail of the description of all the antecedent
conditions increases, our ability to predict the effect improves. Beyond a
certain point, however, the explanatory force of the description does not
improve, but rather lessens as it increasingly becomes a description of a
unique event rather than an instance of some broad generalization appli-
369. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 44-47; see T. BEAUCHAMP & A.
ROSENBERG, supra note 21, at 141, 295-99, 301-02.
370. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORS, supra note 8, at 47; Mackie, supra note 21, at 37.
371. H.L.A. HART & T. HONORt, supra note 8, at 31-32, 48-49. See generally L. COHEN, supra
note 363.
372. See supra text accompanying notes 296-303.
1985] CA USA TION IN TORT LAW 1825
who caused Sue's death, but they do not help us to determine whether
Joe or Mike actually was the cause.3 77 At most, they tell us the relative
amounts of ex ante risk that Joe and Mike imposed on Sue, when they
are combined with the causal generalization that links firing a gun in
someone's direction with killing that person. Thus, they can be used to
allocate liability that is based on exposing someone to the risk that was
realized. Nevertheless, they are of little use in establishing who actually
caused Sue's death.
The courts generally have perceived the critical distinction between
naked statistical evidence and causally relevant particularistic evidence.
For example, in Smith v. Rapid Transit, Inc.,3 78 the court refused to
allow the jury to infer that one of the defendant's buses caused a particu-
lar accident when the evidence merely showed that the defendant's buses
were the most frequent users of the route on which the accident
occurred. Unless the statistical evidence is so compelling that it pre-
cludes any possible alternative explanation, it will be insufficient by itself
to induce the belief that the asserted causal connection actually existed.
In sum, so long as tort liability continues to be based on individual
responsibility, liability will be imposed on a defendant only if it is
believed that the tortious aspect of his conduct actually contributed to
the specified legal injury. This belief is the essence of a causal explana-
tion, as distinguished from mere probabilistic statements of increased
risk. The belief will arise in a particular case only if there is sufficient
evidence that not only supports the suggested causal explanation involv-
ing the defendant's tortious conduct, but also makes it the most plausible
suggested explanation. Ordinarily, only particularistic evidence fitting
the relevant causal generalizations can accomplish this task.
CONCLUSION
PUB. AFF. 101, 127-33 (1984); see also Nesson, supra note 363, at 1377-79, 1383-85 (acceptable-
stories theory).
377. Many writers have confused the betting odds that a person is willing to accept on the
existence of a certain fact with the belief that the person actually has in the existence of that fact.
E.g., Kaye, The Paradox of the Gatecrasherand OtherStories, 1979 ARIZ. ST. L.J. 101, 105; Tribe,
supra note 363, at 1346-48; Wagner, Book Review, 1979 DUKE L.J. 1071, 1072-73 & n.6. As the
text indicates, a willingness to accept betting odds does not necessarily imply any belief in the actual
existence of the fact in question. Jonathan Cohen has written extensively and persuasively on the
inductive nature of causal belief and the inapplicability of mathematical probability theorems to such
belief. L. COHEN, supra note 363, summarized in Schum, A Review of a Case Against Blaise Pascal
and His Heirs, 77 MICH. L. REV. 446 (1979); see T. BEAUCHAMP & A. ROSENBERG, supra note 21,
at 312-14; Nesson, supra note 363, at 1385-90.
378. 317 Mass. 469, 58 N.E.2d 754 (1945).
1985] CAUSATION IN TORT LAW 1827
this century has led to frequent confusion of the causal and noncausal
issues in tort scholarship. More recently, it has led to a general denigra-
tion of the significance and even of the meaning of the concept of causa-
tion in tort law.
In this Article, I have argued that the concept of causation has a
definite substantive content that was first elaborated by the philosophers
David Hume and John Stuart Mill. I have tried to demonstrate the ana-
lytical clarity and power that results from a proper understanding of the
concept of causation and its connection, through the tortious-aspect cau-
sation requirement, to the concept of legal responsibility. A voluminous
literature that confuses the two concepts can be sorted out and inte-
grated. Problematic cases can be solved. Restrictions on naked statisti-
cal evidence can be explained and justified. The policy issues posed by
recent cases on the frontiers of tort liability can be correctly identified.
I have concentrated on these descriptive issues and problems. How-
ever, this Article also has important normative implications. The deni-
gration of the concept of causation during this century has seriously
eroded the traditional view of tort liability as a system of corrective jus-
tice, which protects individual autonomy by redressing injuries if and
only if they were caused by the tortious aspect of the defendant's con-
duct. Tort scholarship instead has been dominated by books and articles
that view tort liability as a (poor) system for providing general compen-
sation for losses 379 or as a (poor or great) system for maximizing social
wealth. 8 0
But the concept of corrective justice embodied in the tortious-aspect
causation requirement clearly continues to control the decision of actual
tort cases. Despite more than a half-century of academic assaults on the
causation requirement, the courts almost invariably reach results that are
consistent with it. The requirement and the underlying concept of cor-
rective justice exert a very strong normative pull, even when judges do
not articulate that pull but rather couch their decisions in the currently
fashionable language of loss-spreading and wealth-maximization.
As I have noted elsewhere, 3 1 the concept of corrective justice has
fallen on hard times in recent years because of difficulties encountered in
defining its two principal elements, causation and rights, rather than
from any normative or descriptive weakness in the concept itself, which
continues to be both more normatively appealing and more descriptively
379. E.g., R. KEETON & J. O'CONNELL, BASIc PROTECTION FOR THE TRAFFIC VICTIM 1-3, 11-
75, 249-50, 261-65 (1965); Englard, supra note 11, at 28-29, 62, 67-69. See generally Symposium:
Alternative Compensation Schemes and Tort Theory, 73 CALIF. L. REV. 548 (1985).
380. E.g., G. CALABRESI, supra note 100, at 239-87 (poor system); Landes & Posner, The
Positive Economic Theory of Tort Law, 15 GA. L. REV. 851 (1981) (great system).
381. Wright, supra note 9, at 435-36, 455-56.
1828 CALIFORNIA LAW REVIEW [Vol. 73:1735
accurate than any alternative theory of liability. This Article has defined
and elaborated the causal element in the concept of corrective justice. In
another article, now in progress, I address the rights element by elaborat-
ing a principled theory of tortious conduct. I hope, through both arti-
cles, to make explicit the principles that have provided the foundation for
tort liability over the centuries, but which require more detailed elabora-
tion in these skeptical times.