The Object and Method of Metaphysics
The Object and Method of Metaphysics
1
Table of Contents
2 Analogy 8
2
Introduction: Why Study Object and Method?
All of the courses I’ve taken on Metaphysics have started with an overview of the
speculative sciences, the object of Metaphysics, or an introduction to its Method. From a
theoretical perspective, the reason is clear: it is important to outline how a science will proceed
and show that a science such as metaphysics is even possible.
However, there are other considerations from a pedagogical perspective. New students
unfamiliar with the subject may not appreciate or even adequately understand an explanation of
its object and method. In the case of metaphysics, the conceptual framework required to
understand the method and object is often taught in the class itself. So, a practical conflict
appears between the theoretical requirements to establish the object and method and pedagogical
efficacy. This is one of the main reasons that led me to select object and method as a topic for
this paper. I felt that a review of metaphysics as a science at the end of the course may provide
Secondly, many of the critiques against metaphysics have much to do with its method or
object. For example, Hume, Kant, and some members of the Vienna Circle all argue against
metaphysics as a science from an anthropological or epistemological perspective. Their
arguments are primarily against the possibility of metaphysics as a science, as a human endeavor.
Is human reason capable of grasping and expressing metaphysical truths? Although it is well
beyond the scope of this paper to provide a complete answer to any of these criticisms, I believe
that an adequate understanding of the object and method of metaphysics are an important first
step. As St. John Paul II said, “If I insist so strongly on the metaphysical element, it is because I
3
am convinced that it is the path to be taken in order to move beyond the crisis pervading large
sectors of philosophy at the moment, and thus to correct certain mistaken modes of behaviour
In this paper I will argue that analogy is central to understanding metaphysics--both in
providing a unity to its object as well as being integral to the method of metaphysical inquiry.
Aristotle’s famous lines in Book Γ of the Metaphysics define what this study is: “There is
a science which investigates being as being and the attributes which belong to this in virtue of its
own nature.”2 First, Aristotle is defining this field as a science.3 Second, he outlines what it
studies.
If metaphysics is a science, then it has certain characteristic that belong to it as a science:
it is knowledge of causes, it is discursive going from what is known to what was previously
unknown, it produces knowledge that is necessary and universal, etc.4 It also follows that
metaphysics has its own proper method, since each science must follow a method and use
instruments that are are in line with its object. For example, physics and chemistry are both
positive sciences that study very similar objects, but the methods and instruments they utilize are
very different. Once the object of study is defined, then the proper method can be determined.
1
St. John Paul II, Fides et Ratio, 83.
2
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Γ, 1.
3
This is clearly science in the traditional sense, and not the restrictive sense of positive empirical science.
4
cf. Aristotle, Posterior Analytics, bk 1, n. 6-8.
4
In Aristotle's understanding of a science, a study is defined by the material object (the
field or item being studied) and the formal object (the aspect that is being studied).5 There are
several sciences that may study the same material object. However, these are distinguished by
the formal object under which the material object is studied. For example, man is the material
object of both medicine and ethics. However, these sciences have a different formal object.
Medicine studies man as a living organism, while ethics studies man as a free moral agent.
quantum ens). The material object of this science is “being.” Aristotle means to say that
metaphysics is not restricted to study a certain type of being; it is not just animals or mobile
entities, but anything that “is.” The formal object is “as being.” It does not study a being
inasmuch as it is mobile (as physics does), but only inasmuch as it is being. Just as medicine
does not take into account certain aspects of man, but instead focuses on man as an organism,
metaphysics ignores the specific qualities of each particular type of being and only focuses on a
being as a being. Metaphysics studies all beings, but only under the aspect of being. This is
different from all other sciences, "since none of the other kinds of knowledge examines
The meaning of “being qua being” is much clearer when expressed in Latin (ens in
quantum ens) or Greek (τὸ ὂν ᾗ ὂν) than in English. Neither of the classical languages carries the
ambiguity of the English word "being." From a linguistic perspective, ens a nd ὂν are participles
5
cf. Thomas Harper, S.J., The Metaphysics of the School, ch. II.
6
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Γ, 1.
5
of esse and εἶναι respectively. However, in English “being” (ens and ὂν) can mean that which is
(id quod est) as in “a being” or “an entity.” It can also mean “the being” (esse a nd εἶναι) as an
act, which we often render as "to be." As Boethius points out, “a being” and “the act of being”
are not the same thing.7 It is interesting that at times Joe Sachs translates this same ὂν ᾗ ὂν both
as "what is insofar as it is"8 and "being as being."9 The former seems to be a better translation
than the latter, insofar as it does not have the ambiguity of the English word “being” contained in
the latter translation. So, when Aristotle defines metaphysics it is clear from a semantic
perspective that he clearly is not talking about “to be” in the sense of the act of being.
In reading through the contents of the Metaphysics, it’s also clear that Aristotle doesn't
reach the act of being itself (later the focus of Thomistic metaphysics). So, when Aristotle
discusses “being qua being,” he is expressing the object of metaphysics and main question
driving the science as “what does it mean to be a being?” rather than “what is the meaning of ‘to
be’?” This is also indicated by the answer he gives to this question: to be a being is to be
substance. This is why the heart of the Metaphysics (books Ζ, Η, and Θ) try to answer the
question of what it means to be a substance. This only makes sense if he is answering the
question of what it means “to be a being” and not what it means “to be.” So, any version of
"being" here should be understood to mean "a being" or “all beings,” rather than the act of being
(or esse).10
7
cf. Boethius, De hebdomadibus, Regula 1. “Diversum est esse et id quod est.”
8
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Γ, 1.
9
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Γ, 1.
10
Some would even argue that the subject of metaphysics is “being” understood as the most general and
abstract of terms. However, Aristotle had a very practical approach--as seen in his other writings. Besides
the theoretical arguments against this notion, it seems a Greek man of his times, with his feet so firmly
planted on the ground, would be speaking of concrete beings, rather than vague abstractions.
6
1.3 The Unity of Metaphysics
The problem of the unity of metaphysics can refer to two related questions. First, the text
itself seems to have many disconnected parts, repetitions, and possible contradictions. This
criticism is exemplified by historians such as Werner Jaeger,11 and has been responded to at
length by Giovanni Reale.12 The second question is intimately related to the first. If metaphysics
studies ens qua ens, another problem quickly appears, since “being is said in many ways.”13 How
can one science deal with different objects? How does the Metaphysics treat of both God and
substance? This second problem is actually part of why Jager proposes a lack of textual unity. He
states that Aristotle’s “original metaphysics was theology, the doctrine of the most perfect
being.”14
However, Aristotle himself provides the answer in the concept of analogy. Just as
“healthy” is used in many ways (a food that causes health and a subject that is in good health),
but its various meanings all stem from one principal meaning; in the same way, the answer to the
11
Werner Jaeger, Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, pg 170. “We must reject all
attempts to make a literary whole out of the remaining materials by rearranging or removing some of the
books, and we must condemn the assumption which overhastily postulates their philosophical unity at the
expense of their individual peculiarities.”
12
cf. Giovanni Reale, Il concetto di filosofia prima e l'unità della metafisica di Aristotele.
13
Aristotle, Metaphysics, Γ, 2.
14
Werner Jaeger, Aristotle: Fundamentals of the History of His Development, pg 216.
7
2 Analogy
In Aristotelian and Thomistic logic, a spoken or written word signifies a concept (held in
the mind), which in turn signifies reality.15 Logically speaking, we use words in a sentence to
express concepts and make assertions (ἀπόφανσις) about reality. We affirm or deny a predicate
of a subject. However, there is an ambiguity that exists within language. A word can be
predicated of another in three ways: it can be univocal, equivocal, or analogical.
A word is used univocally (una vox, one voice) when it has a single meaning. The
meaning of the word “elephant” is totally unambiguous. It refers to a single concept. A word is
equivocal (aequus vox, equal voice) when there are more than one unrelated meaning. A baseball
“bat” and a mammalian “bat” do not have anything in common conceptually. The word “bat”
applies equally to both concepts. The words are the same, but represent entirely different and
unrelated concepts.
However, there is a way of predicating that falls between univocal and equivocal
language. There is predication in between pure diversity and absolute unity. Analogy (ἀναλογία)
in Greek initially referred to a mathematical proportion or a ratio. In Aristotelian and medieval
logic, analogy came to mean predication that is partly the same and partly different. Analogical
predication is similar to univocal predication in that the various meanings of the word have a
conceptual unity. It is different in that analogical predication does not have a single meaning. It
is similar to equivocal predication because each usage of the words is different, but it is
8
distinguished from equivocal usage in that the meanings are not given equally16 and are not
unrelated.
Analogy can be studied and understood from a linguistic perspective: How do words
come to possess or express different, but related meanings? It can also be seen from a logical
perspective: how do different but related concepts express something that is true; how do these
concepts relate to one another; and where is the primary source of meaning?
However, analogy can also be understood from an ontological perspective. A food or
medicine that is “healthy” really does cause a subject to be “healthy.” There is a true causal
relationship between the object that is healthy in a secondary sense (the medicine) and the
subject that has health primarily. There is an analogy of being in father and son, because of the
causal relationship. There is an ontological analogy on the level of being, when we look at a
things nature.
Starting with Cajetan’s De Nominum Analogia, analogy was divided into two main types:
analogies of proportionality and analogies of attribution (or simple proportion).
With the analogy of attribution there is a resemblance between terms, which has its
source in a relation πρός ἓν or ad unum. This can be both extrinsic and intrinsic. Extrinsically,
there is no real similarity. Only one term possesses the characteristic found in the analogy. Then,
all the others are called by that term because of their relation to the first. The example given by
As we will discuss later on, analogical meanings often refer to a primary single meaning.
16
9
Aristotle and St. Thomas is health,17 since health is only in the subject that is healthy. An
intrinsic analogy of attribution would be a cause that makes a similar effect (ex. Father, son;
God, creation). This is also called an analogy of participation. In the case of God and creation,
being is really in both God and His creation, but in analogous ways.
In an analogy of proportionality, A is to B as C is to D. Ex. puppies are to dogs as kittens
are to cats. The analogy of proportionality can be either improper (extrinsic) or proper (intrinsic).
With improper proportionality, there is no real basis for similarity. The analogy is only founded
on a similarity discovered by the knower. Improper proportionality is also called metaphoric
proportionality, since this type of analogy includes similes and metaphors.18
The second analogy of proportionality is proper (or intrinsic) proportionality, where there
is a real causal relationship between between the two terms. The often used example is the
faculty of seeing (which is intrinsic to the eye) and faculty of understanding (which is intrinsic to
the mind). In each of these cases we are talking about a really possessed faculty. It is proper,
because the attribute is really connected with the subjects (or intrinsic to them).
17
It’s interesting that this example is used by St. Thomas to illustrate both multa ad unum and unum ad
alterum: “multa habent proportionem ad unum, sicut sanum dicitur de medicina et urina, inquantum
utrumque habet ordinem et proportionem ad sanitatem animalis, cuius hoc quidem signum est, illud vero
causa; vel ex eo quod unum habet proportionem ad alterum, sicut sanum dicitur de medicina et animali,
inquantum medicina est causa sanitatis quae est in animali.” St. Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologiae, I,
q. 13 a. 5.
18
Cajetan, De Nominum Analogia, n. 25. “Fit autem duobus modis analogia haec: scilicet metaphorice et
proprie. Metaphorice quidem, quando nomen illud commune absolute unam habet rationem formalem,
quae in uno analogatorum salvatur, et per metaphoram de alio dicitur.”
10
Types of predication:
1. Univocal
2. Equivocal
3. Analogy
a. Attribution
i. Extrinsic
ii. Intrinsic (participation)
b. Proportionality
i. Proper (intrinsic)
ii. Improper or metaphoric (extrinsic)
Being can be predicated analogously in two ways: foundationally being is an analogy of
First, in the case of beings in Γ2, Aristotle is referring to the concept of beings as an
analogy of intrinsic attribution. “There are many senses in which a thing is said to be, but all
refer to one starting-point.”19 According to Aristotle, being refers first to substance and second to
accidents. However, God for St. Thomas as ipsum esse subsistens would also be considered the
primary meaning of “being” according to res significata. Second, each being (ens) participates in
being (esse) to a different degree according to its essence. This participation is an ontological
So, analogy provides an answer to the question of the unity of the object of metaphysics.
The object of metaphysics is being (ens) as it refers to substance and inasmuch as it possesses
being (esse) through participation. The princeps analogatum is both substance and esse per
essentia, God.
11
2.4 Analogy of Abstraction
St. Thomas does not see the object of metaphysics as something abstractly unreal. On the
contrary, he sees the object of metaphysics as necessarily more real than the objects of either
math or physics. Its object is not like the others--an abstraction formed by simple apprehension.
The concept of being is instead formed by the second operation of the intellect, judgment. St.
Thomas sees the first operation (simple apprehension) as corresponding to a thing’s nature and
the second operation (separatio) as corresponding to a thing’s being (esse). By its very nature,
We conclude that there are three kinds of distinction in the operation of the
intellect. There is one through the operation of the intellect joining and dividing
which is properly called separation; and this belongs to divine science or
metaphysics. There is another through the operation by which the quiddities of
things are conceived which is the abstraction of form from sensible matter; and
this belongs to mathematics. And there is a third through the same operation
which is the abstraction of a universal from a particular; and this belongs to
physics and to all the sciences in general, because science disregards accidental
features and treats of necessary matters.20
The difference between abstraction and separatio is crucial to understanding Thomistic
metaphysics. Simple apprehension can consider one thing as separate from another without it
being so in reality. However, for separatio to be truthful (conforming to reality), it must not
separate in the mind what exists in reality united. So for St. Thomas, to consider substance apart
from its accidents is a matter of separatio rather than abstraction, since he views them as really
distinct--not inter res, but in re. He says, “the consideration of substance without quantity
belongs to the order of separation rather than to that of abstraction.”21
St. Thomas Aquinas, In librum Boethii De Trinitate, q. 5, a. 3.
20
21
St. Thomas Aquinas, In librum Boethii De Trinitate, q. 5, a. 3.
12
It is clear that even in the operations of the intellect that form the objects of the three
speculative sciences, St. Thomas sees an analogy of abstraction.22 “In other words, the term
‘abstraction’ does not have a univocal meaning. It is analogical, signifying activities of the
intellect which are essentially diverse from each other, although proportionately the same.”23
Another important analogy used by Aristotle and St. Thomas is act and potency. First,
Aristotle says that act is not defined, but only known by induction and grasped by analogy.24
Then, this pairing of act and potency is used by Aristotle in two different ways: as accidents and
substance, and then form and material. St. Thomas will also use act and potency when explaining
the relationship of esse and essentia. St. Thomas will also thoroughly make use of analogy when
As with many of Aristotle’s works, he begins by discussing what others have thought. In
some cases, he takes these opinions as a starting point. In other cases, he identifies what is wrong
in their thinking. Aristotle calls this approach dialectic (διαλεκτική). While truth is not found in
the opinion (δόξα) of others, it can provide an orientation to begin the study.
22
Despite the fact that St. Thomas does use the term “abstraction” to refer to separatio I tend to side more
with Fabro in rejecting Cajetan’s theory of the three degrees of abstraction.
23
Maurer, Armand, The Division and Methods of the Sciences, Introduction, XXIII.
24
Aristotle, Metaphysics, bk. Θ, n. 6. “Our meaning can be seen in the particular cases by induction, and
we must not seek a definition of everything but be content to grasp the analogy.”
25
St. Thomas, Summa, Prima Pars, Question 13.
13
Part of the Metaphysics moves along by deduction--a demonstration starting with true
premises and first principles leading to a necessary conclusion. However, the sources of these
premises and first principles is often induction--the inference of general truth from particulars.
There is a difficulty in using deduction when dealing with metaphysics, because much of the
subject is related to first principles themselves. As Aristotle points out, there must be some first
principles which cannot be demonstrated. Without certain axioms to begin, logical discourse
One specific axiom Aristotle addresses is the principle of noncontradiction. Since it is the
very first principle of thought, it cannot be demonstrated. However, although it cannot be
demonstrated syllogisticly, Aristotle shows that the truth of the principle can be seen by the
process of refutation (ἔλεγχος). This is the method primarily used by Socrates, also known as
reductio ad absurdum. Elenchos (or refutation) is the process of using a syllogism to make
evident the falsity of an opposing position by showing the resulting contradictions when the
position is brought to its conclusion. Much of the Metaphysics uses elenchos because it deals
primarily with first principles, which cannot be demonstrated, only defended.
Finally, the whole of book B uses the method of aporia (ἀπορία), which poses a problem
in their most radical form. The aporia develop each problem to a seemingly impassable point.
This method is useful, because it helps to show the difficulties and apparent contradictions in
greater clarity.
14
3.3 Method According to St. Thomas
Since most of metaphysics deals with first principles and what is not directly sensible, it
requires a special method appropriate to dealing with these truths. As mentioned previously, St.
Thomas starts with separatio as the “distinction-separation proper to metaphysical reflection (for
example, distinguishing esse from essence in creatures or God from creatures).”26 However, it is
the resolutio (or analysis) that is the method of metaphysics outlined by St. Thomas in De
Trinitate. It is a movement from effect to cause or from particulars to universals.27 It is the
opposite of composition, or compositio, which goes from universals to particulars.
The resolutio and compositio can be accomplished in two ways: by intrinsic causes
(secundum rationem) or extrinsic causes (secundum rem). The result of resolutio secundum
rationem is knowledge of ens commune and the transcendentals (the properties of being as
being). The result of resolutio secundum rem is knowledge of the ultimate cause of all beings.
The resolutio secundum rem is a movement from one thing to another, from the finite to the
infinite, from effect to the efficient, exemplary, and final cause.28 The resolutio secundum
rationem, however, finds the constitutive parts (substance, form, essence, etc) and the
26
Mitchell, Jason, Being and Participation, The Method and Structure of Metaphysical Reflection
according to Cornelio Fabro, pg. 665.
27
St. Thomas Aquinas, In librum Boethii De Trinitate, q. 6, a. 1. “secundum viam resolutionis, in
quantum ratio ex multis colligit unam et simplicem veritatem.”
28
St. Thomas Aquinas, In librum Boethii De Trinitate, q. 6, a. 1. “Ultimus ergo terminus resolutionis in
hac via est, cum pervenitur ad causas supremas maxime simplices, quae sunt substantiae separatae.”
29
St. Thomas Aquinas, In librum Boethii De Trinitate, q. 6, a. 1. “Quandoque vero procedit de uno in
aliud secundum rationem, ut quando est processus secundum causas intrinsecas.”
15
However, it is important to note that although resolutio secundum rationem does not
proceed from one thing to another, that does not mean that the intrinsic causes are not distinct or
are just a logical distinction. While all the transcendentals are by definition convertible with ens
(and therefore logical distinctions), the intrinsic causes are not, as both Aristotle and St. Thomas
point out. The resolutio secundum rationem is a logical analysis to arrive at the real distinction of
16