Enhancing Analytical Reasoning in Intensive Care Unit
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning in Intensive Care Unit
KEYWORDS
Bayes theorem Bias Clinical reasoning Heuristics Logic Noise Probability
Set theory Venn diagrams
KEY POINTS
Intensivists often rely on heuristic principles that lead to severe and systematic errors in
reasoning.
Reasoning foundations can be described mathematically using logic, probability, and
value theory.
Intensivists should familiarize themselves with basic statistical and probability principles
to enhance analytical reasoning and avoid biases.
Bayesian reasoning is the framework surrounding the calculation of posterior odds of
events.
Noise is likely pervasive in the intensive care unit and should be mitigated.
INTRODUCTION
Division of Pulmonary and Critical Care Medicine, Hub for Collaborative Medicine, Medical
College of Wisconsin, 8701 Watertown Plank Road, 8th Floor, Milwaukee, WI 53226, USA
* Corresponding author.
E-mail address: [email protected]
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
52 Barash & Nanchal
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Table 1
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
Heuristics
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
53
54
Table 1
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
(continued )
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Adapted from Croskerry P. Achieving quality in clinical decision making: cognitive strategies and detection of bias. Acad Emerg Med. 2002;9(11):1184-1204. https://
55
doi.org/10.1111/j.1553-2712.2002.tb01574.x; with permission
56 Barash & Nanchal
number of people who have the disease to the number of true and false positive tests
which here is 1 in 51. The approach of indiscriminate testing (ie, casting a wide net
without sound hypotheses hoping that some test will return positive and will, in turn,
lead to a diagnosis), which is commonly described as a “shotgun approach to medi-
cine,” more often than not is a setup for diagnostic error and downstream administra-
tion of inappropriate therapies and iatrogenic harm. The process of deriving posterior
or conditional probabilities, commonly known as the Bayesian approach is useful in
interpreting test results. This approach is described in some detail later in discussion
in the mathematical concepts section.
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning 57
highly improbable. However, closer scrutiny reveals that the probability of developing
daptomycin-related eosinophilic pneumonia in 4 out of 5 patients in the ICU is orders
of magnitude higher than 10 out of 20 patients on the floor. Accurate diagnosis with
such a low probability of occurrence on the ward is quite the feat.
Misconception of regression
If 2 variables X and Y have the same distribution and the average X score for a group of
selected individuals deviates from the mean of X by k units, then the average of their Y
score usually will deviate from Y by less than k units. This phenomenon called regres-
sion toward the mean occurs frequently in everyday life and was described by Galton
more than 150 years ago.4 Let us return to the example of CLABSI. Mere observation
will clarify that a particularly outstanding period of performance on the occurrence of
CLABSI will inevitably be followed by a period whereby the performance was worse
than the preceding period and vice-versa. Often this prompts extensive critical quality
reviews during the period when performance deviated from organizational goals (often
set at zero infections!) and accolades when performance exceeds them. This schema
of administering rewards and admonishments is widespread and may lead to misper-
ceptions about their effectiveness when changes are most likely to occur secondary to
regression alone.
Fallacies of conjunctive and disjunctive events
These biases, particularly common in medicine are the consequence of anchoring. Psy-
chological studies5,6 indicate that people tend to overestimate the probability of
conjunctive events and underestimate the probability of disjunctive events. An example
of a conjunction fallacy occurs when a trainee alleges sepsis from pneumonia and uri-
nary tract infection (UTI) when asked for a diagnosis. Even if the probability of pneu-
monia and UTI are individually high, the probability of them occurring together is
quite low—that is, the overall probability of a conjunctive event is lower than the prob-
ability of each elementary event. This phenomenon is a simple explanation behind
Occam’s razor or the parsimony in diagnosis. Of course, deviations from this principle
are bound to occur. A patient may have both pneumonia and UTI at the same time; it is
possible but less probable. In the same vein, a trainee’s judgment that the cause of
sepsis is more likely from pneumonia rather than pneumonia or UTI constitutes a
disjunction fallacy. Although the likelihood of pneumonia may be high, the likelihood
or either pneumonia or UTI is higher than the probability of each elementary event.
Biases in the evaluation of compound events are pervasive and influence a myriad of
actions such as administration of therapies (eg, choice of antibiotics) and obtaining lab-
oratory/imaging studies which have numerous downstream influences on iatrogenic
harm (eg, Clostridium difficile colitis), costs of care as well as patient safety and quality.
MATHEMATICAL CONCEPTS
Set theory/Venn diagrams/logic concepts
Set theory is a branch of mathematical logic that pertains to the study of sets or collec-
tion of objects. Probability theory uses the language of sets which can be illustrated in
the form of Venn diagrams. Probability is nothing but a scientific method of measuring
uncertainty or quantifying randomness. Basic operations of sets include intersection,
union, difference, and symmetric difference (Fig. 1).
Probability concepts
Probabilistic reasoning asks a clinician to answer 2 basic questions: (1) how represen-
tative is the patient’s presentation of known disease and (2) what is the likelihood of
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
58 Barash & Nanchal
Sensitivity
The proportion of true positives among those that have the disorder.
Specificity
The proportion of true negatives among those who do not have the disorder.
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning 59
Predictive values
The absolute probability that the disorder is present or absent. It is important to note
that predictive values depend on both test characteristics and the prevalence of the
disorder. For example, an early warning system that has a sensitivity and specificity
of 99% will have a positive predictive value of only 33% if the prevalence of clinical
deterioration is 5 out of 1000 admissions. In other words, for every 100 alerts, on
average, 67 will be false positive.
Likelihood ratios
The probability that a specific result is obtained in patient with the condition is divided
by the probability that the same result is obtained in patients without the condition. A
theoretic advantage of likelihood ratios is that they are independent of prevalence. In
case of dichotomous measures, the likelihood ratio for a positive result can be calcu-
lated as sensitivity/1-specificity and the likelihood ratio for a negative result as 1-sensi-
tivity/specificity.
Bayes theorem/reasoning
In 1736, Reverend Thomas Bayes (b. 1701) anonymously published “An introduction
to the doctrine of fluxions: and a defense of mathematicians against the objections of
the author of the analyst.”8 In it were the first echoes of what, many years later, would
be translated and reworked into Bayes theorem.
For epistemic rationality, probability estimates need to follow rules of objective
probability. The most important of these are as follows: (a) Probabilities always vary
between 0 and 1, (b) if an event is certain to happen, its probability is 1.0, (c) if an event
is certain not to happen, then its probability is 0, and (d) if 2 events cannot both
happen, then they are mutually exclusive and the probability of one OR the other
occurring is the probability of each added together.
An important concept is that of conditional probability. Conditional probabilities
concern the probability of an event A given that another event B has occurred. If A
and B were mutually exclusive, then the probability of A occurring given that B has
occurred would be zero. Thus, conditional probabilities usually deal with events that
are not mutually exclusive. (A simple example of mutually exclusive events is the diag-
nosis of cholecystitis in someone who presents with fever, jaundice, and right upper
quadrant pain but has previously undergone a cholecystectomy. Given that cholecys-
tectomy has occurred, the probability of cholecystitis is zero.) Bayes theorem de-
scribes the probability of an event occurring while using knowledge about the local
prevalence or risk factors of the condition itself. These represent the post and pretest
probabilities, respectively. Mathematically, the Bayes theorem is represented via the
formula.
PðAÞPðBjAÞ
PðAjBÞ 5
PðAÞPðBjAÞ1Pð:AÞPðBj:AÞ
where P(AjB) describes the likelihood of A occurring given B is true, P(BjA) describes
the likelihood of B occurring given A is true, P(A) describes the probability of A occur-
ring, P(B) describes the probability of B occurring and P(:A) describes the probability
of A not occurring which just 1 – the probability of A occurring. For judgment and de-
cision making, the Bayes theorem has special importance because it allows a formal
framework of updating beliefs in a hypothesis given new evidence. In clinical practice,
it can be stated as posttest odds 5 pretest odds X likelihood ratio. Arriving at, and be-
ing confident in these values, is the crux of Bayesian reasoning.
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
60 Barash & Nanchal
Using the sensitivity and specificity of a test, a likelihood ratio (LR) is calculated and
poses the question “what is the likelihood this patient has disease ‘X’ if presenting with
complaint or test ‘Y’.” Table 2 defines general values for LRs and their approximate
effect on changing the posttest probability. Fig. 3 shows a conversion graph for deter-
mining likelihood ratios from the sensitivity and specificity of positive and negative test
results.
There is the tremendous utility of Bayesian reasoning in the critical care environ-
ment wherein patients often present with a gamut of complex problems, physical ex-
amination findings, historical features, and laboratory/imaging investigations.
Instead of asking the clinician to consider the full range of differential diagnoses
for a particular set of data, Bayesian reasoning ask the clinician to determine which
is most likely based on the aforementioned information. Mathematically, if there is a
hypothesis (H) and a set of collected data elements (D) then
PðHÞ PðHjDÞ
PðHjDÞ 5 PðHÞ PðDjHÞ 1 pðwHÞ PðDjwHÞ where P(H) is the probability of the hypothesis
prior to collecting the data and (P w H) is the probability that some alternate hypoth-
esis is true before collecting the data. It is important to note that P(wH) may repre-
sent any number of different hypotheses and that P(H) 1 P(wH) may not equal 1.0.
P(HjD) is the probability of hypothesis after the observed data pattern (posterior
probability). Similarly, P(DjH) is the posterior probability of data given the hypothesis
and P(DjwH) the posterior probability of data given alternative hypotheses. Here it is
important to realize that P(DjH) and P(DjwH) are not complements and may not add
up to 1.0. An illustrative example is an elderly patient presenting to the ICU with hy-
potension and altered mental status whereby the initial probabilities of septic shock
and cardiogenic shock may be assigned probabilities of 0.5 and 0.2, given that from
prior experience 50% and 20% of such patients presented with septic or cardio-
genic shock, respectively. After physician examination reveals cool extremities,
delayed capillary refill, and echocardiogram reveals a wall motion abnormality with
depressed ejection fraction a clinician may judge that given these findings, the prob-
ability of cardiogenic shock is 0.6 and septic shock is 0.2. Thus, the posterior prob-
abilities of cardiogenic and septic shock would be calculated as 0.54 and 0.45,
respectively.
An important question revolves around clinician estimates of pretest probabilities.
Judgment relies on several factors including the knowledge of the epidemiology of
Table 2
Approximate values for calculated likelihood ratios
Approximate
Change in
Likelihood Ratio Probability
Positive likelihood ratio value (1LR)
1 10%
2 115%
5 130%
10 145%
Negative Likelihood ratio value (LR)
0.1 45%
0.2 30%
0.5 15%
1 0%
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning 61
Fig. 3. Conversion graph for determining likelihood ratio from sensitivity and specificity.
(Adapted from Fischer JE, Bachmann LM, Jaeschke R. A readers’ guide to the interpretation
of diagnostic test properties: clinical example of sepsis. Intensive Care Med. 2003;29(7):1043-
1051. https://doi.org/10.1007/s00134-003-1761-8; with permission.)
the suspected disorder, utilization of risk calculators, or other validated analyses and
clinical gestalt. Of course, the time available for decision making may influence one’s
ability to apply these concepts. An applicable scenario is that of a middle-aged female
who presents with fevers, hypoxemia, cough with expectoration of dark phlegm, and a
dense right basilar infiltrate on CT imaging. A plausible hypothesis may be pulmonary
blastomycosis. If using basic epidemiology alone, someone practicing in the south-
western USA might conclude that the likelihood is low and forgo additional investiga-
tion. Another clinician, practicing in a rural town in the upper Midwest, whereby
blastomycosis is known to be hyperendemic, may conclude the pretest probability
is high enough to either test via urinary antigen or, to even treat empirically while
testing is pending. Risk calculators such as the PERC score9 (for ruling out pulmonary
embolism (PE)), LRINEC score10 (for diagnosing necrotizing soft tissue infection), and
PLASMIC score11 (for predicting ADAMTS13 deficiency in thrombotic thrombocyto-
penia purpura) are just a few examples of readily available tools that may help a clini-
cian, in the right circumstances, increase or decrease the likelihood that a disorder
exists. As with all categorical variables, however, it is vital to understand the popula-
tion in which these tests were developed and the limitations of the test. The PLASMIC
score, for example, may only be used in a patient that already has thrombocytopenia
and evidence of microangiopathic hemolytic anemia to then determine the probability
that TTP exists.
In clinical practice and at the bedside, it is common for clinicians to use medical
gestalt in estimating the pretest probability of a disorder, but limitations and failures
exist. First, it should be noted that any estimate of the pretest probability of the disease
will be a function of that clinician’s biases and prior experience with such cases,
knowledge about the presentation of the disease state and understanding of the utility
of a certain complaint or examination findings as increasing or decreasing the likeli-
hood of the disease existing. A wide variability in clinicians’ assessment of pretest
probability exists, adding to the lack of standardization. For example, Kline12 evalu-
ated clinician gestalt in estimating pretest probability for acute coronary syndrome
(ACS) or PE in patients presenting with chest pain and dyspnea. Not surprisingly, cli-
nicians significantly overestimated the presence of ACS (17% vs 4%; P < .001) and PE
(12% vs 6%; P < .01) when compared with a validated computerized method. On the
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
62 Barash & Nanchal
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning 63
probability of disease is below the testing threshold and given if it is greater than the
test-treatment threshold. Additional testing is performed if the probability lies between
these 2 thresholds with treatment contingent on the results of the test. An excellent
visual and mathematical review of this concept can be viewed in reference number 9.
A related approach uses game theory first developed by Von Neumann.17 Game
theory is the study of interactions between individuals by applying mathematical
models of conflict and cooperation. These concepts may be applied to understand
the complexities of treatments in the context of a variety of provider, patient, and fam-
ily uncertainties.
Regardless of the approach, an important concept in value theory is that of the “ex-
pected value.” To illustrate this concept, let us assume that a particular patient has
one of the 2 diagnoses D1 and D2 with probabilities of 3/5 and 2/5, respectively.
Let us also assume that there are 2 treatments T1 and T2. T1 is 80% effective for diag-
nosis D1 and 30% effective for diagnosis D2. Similarly, T2 is 20% effective for diag-
nosis D1 and 90% effective for diagnosis D2. The expected value of treatment T1 is
3/5 80/100 1 2/5 30/100 which is equal to 60/100. The expected value of treat-
ment T2 is 3/5 20/100 1 2/5 90/100 which is equal to 48/100. In other words, given
the same circumstances, 60 out of 100 patients would receive effective treatment if T1
were used as opposed to 48 out of 100 if T2 were used; hence T1 should be the
preferred therapy. Assignment of treatment values may often require consideration
of intangibles such as moral and ethical standards which require physician judgment.
Values may be negative in cases whereby treatment may be associated with consider-
able harm. Often probabilities of diseases or syndromes are not known, and the physi-
cian must use judgment to assign them. However, an alternative method for
determining the optimal treatment is by maximizing the number of patients expected
to be cured. For the same treatment values given above let F be the fraction of patients
receiving T1 and (1-F) the fraction receiving T2. If all patients had disease D1, we
would expect to cure 80/100 F 1 20/100 x (1-F) which equals 0.2 1 0.6 F. Similarly,
if all patients had disease D2 then we would expect to cure 30/100 F 1 90/100 (1-F)
which equals 0.9 to 0.6 F. From these 2 equations, the number of people cured is
maximized when F 5 7/12 whereby we would expect a cure in 55% of patients.
Thus, a proportion equal to 7/12 should receive treatment T1 and 5/12 should receive
treatment T2. In recent years, these concepts have gained traction in the medical liter-
ature; one study demonstrated a reduction in antibiotic misuse by discretizing clinical
information using a game-theoretic approach.18 Although many other nuances may be
considered in the final decisions regarding disease processes and therapies, these
concepts provide a valuable workable framework to think about complex problems.
NOISE
There are two components to errors in judgment—bias and noise. Although much
attention has been paid to bias, the role of noise which may be equally or more impor-
tant is often ignored. To fully understand error, it is imperative, we understand both
bias and noise and their relative contributions. Simply defined noise is variability in
judgements that should be identical.19 This variability may occur when different indi-
viduals judge the same situation or when the same individual judges identical situa-
tions. The simplest example of noise in medicine is 2 physicians arriving at separate
the diagnosis for the same patient. Diagnosis involves judgment and obviously, the
judgment of one or both physicians is incorrect (we may not know which); the diver-
gent opinions constitute noise. It is also well known that physicians arrive at different
diagnoses when presented twice with the same case.20–22 Noise invades both
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
64 Barash & Nanchal
SUMMARY
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning 65
DISCLOSURE
The authors (M. Barash and R.S. Nanchal) have nothing to disclose.
REFERENCES
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
66 Barash & Nanchal
18. Diamant M, Baruch S, Kassem E, et al. A game theoretic approach reveals that
discretizing clinical information can reduce antibiotic misuse. Nat Commun 2021;
12(1):1148.
19. Kahneman D, Sibony O, Sunstein CR. Noise a flaw in human judgement. London:
William Collins; 2021.
20. Robinson PJ, Culpan G, Wiggins M. Interpretation of selected accident and emer-
gency radiographic examinations by radiographers: a review of 11000 cases. Br
J Radiol 1999;72(858):546–51.
21. Detre KM, Wright E, Murphy ML, et al. Observer agreement in evaluating coro-
nary angiograms. Circulation 1975;52(6):979–86.
22. Banky M, Clark RA, Pua YH, et al. Inter- and intra-rater variability of testing veloc-
ity when assessing lower limb spasticity. J Rehabil Med 2019;51(1):54–60.
23. OECD. Geographic Variations in Health Care. 2014.
24. Hurley MP, Schoemaker L, Morton JM, et al. Geographic variation in surgical out-
comes and cost between the United States and Japan. Am J Manag Care 2016;
22(9):600–7.
25. Appleby J, Raleigh V, Frosini F, et al. Variations in health care: the good, the bad
and the inexplicable. London: King’s Fund; 2011.
26. Speciale AC, Pietrobon R, Urban CW, et al. Observer variability in assessing lum-
bar spinal stenosis severity on magnetic resonance imaging and its relation to
cross-sectional spinal canal area. Spine (Phila Pa 1976 2002;27(10):1082–6.
27. Farmer ER, Gonin R, Hanna MP. Discordance in the histopathologic diagnosis of
melanoma and melanocytic nevi between expert pathologists. Hum Pathol 1996;
27(6):528–31.
28. Palazzo JP, Hyslop T. Hyperplastic ductal and lobular lesions and carcinomas
in situ of the breast: reproducibility of current diagnostic criteria among commu-
nity- and academic-based pathologists. Breast J 1998;4(4):230–7.
29. Neprash HT, Barnett ML. Association of primary care clinic appointment time with
opioid prescribing. JAMA Netw Open 2019;2(8):e1910373.
30. Philpot LM, Khokhar BA, Roellinger DL, et al. Time of day is associated with
opioid prescribing for low back pain in primary care. J Gen Intern Med 2018;
33(11):1828–30.
31. Linder JA, Doctor JN, Friedberg MW, et al. Time of day and the decision to pre-
scribe antibiotics. JAMA Intern Med 2014;174(12):2029–31.
32. Hsiang EY, Mehta SJ, Small DS, et al. Association of primary care clinic appoint-
ment time with clinician ordering and patient completion of breast and colorectal
cancer screening. JAMA Netw Open 2019;2(5):e193403.
33. Kim RH, Day SC, Small DS, et al. Variations in influenza vaccination by clinic
appointment time and an active choice intervention in the electronic health record
to increase influenza vaccination. JAMA Netw Open 2018;1(5):e181770.
34. You X, Tan H, Hu S, et al. Effects of preconception counseling on maternal health
care of migrant women in China: a community-based, cross-sectional survey.
BMC Pregnancy Childbirth 2015;15:55.
35. Goddard SL, Rubenfeld GD, Manoharan V, et al. The randomized educational
acute respiratory distress syndrome diagnosis study: a trial to improve the radio-
graphic diagnosis of acute respiratory distress syndrome. Crit Care Med 2018;
46(5):743–8.
36. de Groot MG, de Neef M, Otten MH, et al. Interobserver Agreement on Clinical
Judgment of Work of Breathing in Spontaneously Breathing Children in the Pedi-
atric Intensive Care Unit. J Pediatr Intensive Care 2020;9(1):34–9. https://doi.org/
10.1055/s-0039-1697679.
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.
Enhancing Analytical Reasoning 67
37. Koyner JL, Garg AX, Thiessen-Philbrook H, et al. Adjudication of etiology of acute
kidney injury: experience from the TRIBE-AKI multi-center study. BMC Nephrol
2014;15:105.
38. Vincent JL. The clinical challenge of sepsis identification and monitoring. PLoS
Med 2016;13(5):e1002022.
39. Tsugawa Y, Newhouse JP, Zaslavsky AM, et al. Physician age and outcomes in
elderly patients in hospital in the US: observational study. BMJ 2017;357:j1797.
40. Rodriguez-Ruiz A, Lång K, Gubern-Merida A, et al. Stand-alone artificial intelli-
gence for breast cancer detection in mammography: comparison with 101 radi-
ologists. J Natl Cancer Inst 2019;111(9):916–22.
41. Richens JG, Lee CM, Johri S. Improving the accuracy of medical diagnosis with
causal machine learning. Nat Commun 2020;11(1):3923.
42. Gulshan V, Peng L, Coram M, et al. Development and validation of a deep
learning algorithm for detection of diabetic retinopathy in retinal fundus photo-
graphs. JAMA 2016;316(22):2402–10.
43. Seymour CW, Gesten F, Prescott HC, et al. Time to treatment and mortality during
mandated emergency care for sepsis. N Engl J Med 2017;376(23):2235–44.
44. Pun BT, Balas MC, Barnes-Daly MA, et al. Caring for critically ill patients with the
ABCDEF bundle: results of the ICU liberation Collaborative in over 15,000 adults.
Crit Care Med 2019;47(1):3–14.
Downloaded for Anonymous User (n/a) at Taipei Medical University from ClinicalKey.com by Elsevier on February 21,
2022. For personal use only. No other uses without permission. Copyright ©2022. Elsevier Inc. All rights reserved.