0% found this document useful (0 votes)
48 views

MIT6 436JF18 Hw1solutions

Uploaded by

Umer Javed
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
48 views

MIT6 436JF18 Hw1solutions

Uploaded by

Umer Javed
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 9

MASSACHUSETTS INSTITUTE OF TECHNOLOGY

6.436J/15.085J Fall 2018


Problem Set 1

Readings:
(a) Notes from Lecture 1.
(b) Handout on background material on sets and real analysis (Recitation 1).
Supplementary readings:
[C], Sections 1.1-1.4.
[GS], Sections 1.1-1.3.
[W], Sections 1.0-1.5, 1.9.

Exercise 1.

(a) Let N be the set of positive integers. A function f : N → {0, 1} is said to be


periodic if there exists some N such that f (n + N ) = f (n), for all n ∈ N.
Show that the set of periodic functions is countable.

(b) Does the result from part (a) remain valid if we consider rational-valued
periodic functions f : N → Q?

Solution:

(a) For a given positive integer N , let AN denote the set of periodic functions
with a period of N . For a given N , since the sequence, f (1), · · · , f (N ),
actually defines a periodic function in AN , we have that each AN contains
2N elements. For example, for N = 2, there are four functions in the set
A2 :

f (1)f (2)f (3)f (4) · · · = 0000 · · · ; 1111 · · · ; 0101 · · · ; 1010 · · · .

The set of periodic functions from N to {0, 1}, A, can be written as,

!
A= AN .
N =1

Since the union of countably many finite sets is countable, we conclude that
the set of periodic functions from N to {0, 1} is countable.

(b) Still, for a given positive integer N , let AN denote the set of periodic func-
tions with a period N . For a given N , since the sequence, f (1), · · · , f (N ),

1
actually defines a periodic function in AN , we conclude that AN has the
same cardinality as QN (the Cartesian product of N sets of rational num-
bers). Since Q is countable, and the Cartesian product of finitely many
countable sets is countable, we know that AN is countable, for any given N .
Since the set of periodic functions from N to Q is the union of A1 , A2 , · · · ,
it is countable, because the union of countably many countable sets is count-
able.

Exercise 2. Let {xn } and {yn } be real sequences that converge to x and y,
respectively. Provide a formal proof of the fact that xn + yn converges to x + y.
Solution: Fix some ϵ > 0. Let n1 be such that |xn − x| < ϵ/2, for all n > n1 .
Let n2 be such that |yn − y| < ϵ/2, for all n > n2 . Let n0 = max{n1 , n2 }.
Then, for all n > n0 , we have
ϵ ϵ
|(xn + yn ) − (x + y)| ≤ |xn − x| + |yn − y| ≤ + = ϵ,
2 2
which proves the desired result.
Exercise 3. We are given a function f : A × B → R, where A and B are
nonempty sets.
(a) Assuming that the sets A and B are finite, show that

max min f (x, y) ≤ min max f (x, y).


x∈A y∈B y∈B x∈A

(b) For general nonempty sets (not necessarily finite), show that

sup inf f (x, y) ≤ inf sup f (x, y).


x∈A y∈B y∈B x∈A

Solution:
(a) The proof rests on the application of the following simple fact: if h(z) ≤
g(z) for all z in some finite set Z, then

min h(z) ≤ min g(z) (1)


z∈Z z∈Z
max h(z) ≤ max g(z). (2)
z∈Z z∈Z

Observe that for all x, y,

f (x, y) ≤ max f (x, y),


x∈A

2
and Eq. (1) implies that for each x,

min f (x, y) ≤ min max f (x, y).


y∈B y∈B x∈A

Now applying Eq. (2), let’s take a maximum of both sides with respect to
x ∈ A. Since the right-hand side is a number, it remains unchanged:

max min f (x, y) ≤ min max f (x, y),


x∈A y∈B y∈B x∈A

which is what we needed to show.

(b) Along the same lines, we have the fact that if h(z) ≤ g(z) for all z ∈ Z,

inf h(z) ≤ inf g(z) (3)


z∈Z z∈Z
sup h(z) ≤ sup g(z). (4)
z∈Z z∈Z

These follow immediately from the definitions of sup and inf.


As before, we begin with

f (x, y) ≤ sup f (x, y),


x∈A

for all x, y. By Eq. (3), for each x,

inf f (x, y) ≤ inf sup f (x, y),


y∈B y∈B x∈A

and using Eq. (4),

sup inf f (x, y) ≤ inf sup f (x, y).


x∈A y∈B y∈B x∈A

Exercise 4. A probabilistic experiment involves an infinite sequence of trials.


For k = 1, 2, . . ., let Ak be the event that the kth trial was a success. Write down
a set-theoretic expression that describes the following event:

B: For every k there exists an ℓ such that trials kℓ and kℓ2 were both successes.
" #
Note: A “set theoretic expression” is an expression like k>5 ℓ<k Ak+ℓ .

Solution: B = ∞
# "∞
k=1 ℓ=1 (Akℓ ∩ Akℓ2 ).

3
Exercise 5. Let fn , f, g : [0, 1] → [0, 1] and a, b, c, d ∈ [0, 1]. Derive the
following set theoretic expressions:

(a) Show that

{x ∈ [0, 1] | sup fn (x) ≤ a} = {x ∈ [0, 1] | fn (x) ≤ a},


n n

and use this to express {x ∈ [0, 1] | supn fn (x) < a} as a countable combi-
nation (countable unions, countable intersections and complements) of sets
of the form {x ∈ [0, 1] | fn (x) ≤ b}.

(b) Express {x ∈ [0, 1] | f (x) > g(x)} as a countable combination of sets of


the form {x ∈ [0, 1] | f (x) > c} and {x ∈ [0, 1] | g(x) < d}.

(c) Express {x ∈ [0, 1] | lim supn fn (x) ≤ c} as a countable combination of


sets of the form {x ∈ [0, 1] | fn (x) ≤ c}.

(d) Express {x ∈ [0, 1] | limn fn (x) exists} as a countable combination of sets


of the form {x ∈ [0, 1] | fn (x) < c}, {x ∈ [0, 1] | fn (x) > c}, etc. (Hint:
think of {x ∈ [0, 1] | lim supn fn (x) > lim inf n fn (x)}).

Solution: First observe the following set relations



! ∞
[0, c) = [0, c − n1 ] [0, c] = [0, c + n1 )
n=1 n=1

! ∞
(c, 1] = [c + n1 , 1] [c, 1] = (c − n1 , 1].
n=1 n=1

All conversions between strict and non-strict inequalities following from these
relations and properties of the inverse image, i.e. homomorphism of arbitrary
set operations. We will use the shorthand notation

{f < a} := {x ∈ [0, 1] | f (x) < a}.


#
(a) Let x ∈ n {fn ≤ a}. Then, fn (x) ≤ a for all n =⇒ supn fn (x) ≤ a, by
definition of sup as a is an upper bound for {fn (x)}. Therefore, as x was
arbitrary,

{fn ≤ a} ⊂ {sup fn ≤ a}.
n
n=1

4
Let x ∈ {supn fn ≤ a}. Then supn fn (x) ≤ a and for all n fn (x) ≤
supn (x) ≤ a. Therefore, as x was arbitrary,

{sup fn ≤ a} ⊂ {fn ≤ a}.
n
n=1
#
Hence {supn fn ≤ a} = n {fn ≤ a}. By De Morgan’s this relation also
implies

!
{sup fn > a} = {fn ≥ a}.
n
n=1

Similar results hold for inf.

Let f = supn fn . Using the above comment

{sup fn < a} = {f < a}


n
= f −1 ([0, a))
!∞
= f −1 [0, a − k1 ]
k=1
!∞
= {sup fn ≤ a − k1 }
n
k=1
!∞ ∞
= {fn ≤ a − k1 }.
k=1 n=1

(b) Using countability and density of the rationals


!
{f > g} = {f > q} ∩ {q > g}
q∈Q
!
= {f > q} ∩ {q ≥ g}
q∈Q
!
= {f ≥ q} ∩ {q > g}.
q∈Q

5
(c)

{lim sup fn ≤ c} = { inf sup fk ≤ c}


n→∞ n≥1 k≥n

1
= { inf sup fk < c + m}
n≥1 k≥n
m=1
∞ !∞
1
= {sup fk < c + m}
m=1 n=1 k≥n
∞ ! ∞ !∞
1
= {sup fk ≤ c + m − 1ℓ }
m=1 n=1 ℓ=1 k≥n
∞ ! ∞ ! ∞ ∞
1
= {fk ≤ c + m − 1ℓ }.
m=1 n=1 ℓ=1 k=n

(d)

{ lim fn exists} = {lim inf fn = lim sup fn }


n→∞ n→∞ n→∞
= {lim inf fn < lim sup fn }c (lim inf fn (x) ≤ lim sup fn (x))
n→∞ n→∞ n→∞ n→∞
⎛ ⎞c
!
= ⎝ {lim inf fn < q} ∩ {q < lim sup fn }⎠ (part b)
n→∞ n→∞
q∈Q

= {lim inf fn ≥ q} ∪ {lim sup fn ≤ q}.


n→∞ n→∞
q∈Q

The sets {lim inf n→∞ fn ≥ q} and {lim supn→∞ fn ≤ q} can be expressed
as countable combinations using part (c) and the fact that

− lim sup fn (x) = − inf sup fk (x)


n→∞ n≥1 k≥n

= sup inf (−fk (x))


n≥1 k≥n

= lim inf(−fn (x)),


n→∞

i.e. {lim inf n→∞ fn ≥ q} = {lim supn→∞ (−fn ) ≤ −q}. More specifi-
cally,
" ∞ ∞ ∞ ∞ ! ∞ [ ∞ [
∞ \∞
!#
\ \ [ [ \ \
1 1 1 1
{fk ≥ c − m + ℓ } ∪ {fk ≤ c + m − ℓ} .
q∈Q m=1 n=1 ℓ=1 k=n m=1 n=1 ℓ=1 k=n

6
Using one of the later two expressions of part (b), we can drop one of the
outer intersections
" ∞ ∞ ∞ ! ∞ [ ∞ [ ∞ \ ∞
!#
\ [ [ \ \
{fk ≥ c + 1ℓ } ∪ {fk ≤ c + m1
− 1ℓ }
q∈Q n=1 ℓ=1 k=n m=1 n=1 ℓ=1 k=n
or
" ∞ [
∞ [
∞ \

! ∞ [
∞ \

!#
\ \ [
1 1 1
{fk ≥ c − m + ℓ} ∪ {fk ≤ c − ℓ} .
q∈Q m=1 n=1 ℓ=1 k=n n=1 ℓ=1 k=n

Exercise 6. Let Ω = N (the positive integers), and let F0 be the collection of


subsets of Ω that either have finite cardinality or their complement has finite
cardinality. For any A ∈ F0 , let P(A) = 0 if A is finite, and P(A) = 1 if AC is
finite.
(a) Show that F0 is a field but not a σ-field.
(b) Show that P is finitely additive on F0 ; that is, if A, B ∈ F0 , and A, B are
disjoint, then P(A ∪ B) = P(A) + P(B).
(c) Show that P is not countably additive on F0 ; that is, construct a sequence of

disjoint sets Ai ∈ F0 such that ∪∞ ∞
i=1 Ai ∈ F0 and P (∪i=1 Ai ) ̸= i=1 P (Ai ).
(d) Construct a decreasing sequence of sets Ai ∈ F0 such that ∩∞
i=1 Ai = Ø for
which limi→∞ P(Ai ) ̸ = 0.
Solution:
(a) The empty set has zero cardinality, and therefore belongs to F0 . Further-
more, if A ∈ F0 , then either A or Ac has finite cardinality. It follows that
either Ac or (Ac )c has finite cardinality, so that Ac ∈ F0 .
Suppose that A, B ∈ F0 . If both A and B are finite, then A ∪ B is also
finite and belongs to F0 . Suppose now that at least one of A or B is infinite.
We have A ∪ B = (Ac ∩ B c )c . Since Ac ∩ B c is finite, it follows that
A ∪ B ∈ F0 . This shows that F0 is a field.
To see
"∞that F0 is not a σ-field, note that {2n} ∈ F0 for every n ∈ N, but the
set n=0 {2n}, the set of even natural numbers, is not in F0 .
(b) Let A, B ∈ F0 be disjoint. If both A and B are finite, then P (A ∪ B) =
0 = P(A) + P(B). Suppose that either A or B (or both) is infinite. Since A
and B are disjoint, we have A ⊂ B c and B ⊂ Ac . It follows that A and B
cannot both be infinite. Therefore, P(A ∪ B) = 1 = P(A) + P(B), and P
is finitely additive.

7
"
(c) Note that {n} ∈ F0 and n≥1 {n} = Ω. However, P({n}) = 0 while
P(Ω) = 1, hence P is not countably additive.

(d) Let An =#{n, n + 1, . . .}. Then (An )n≥1 forms a decreasing sequence of
sets with n An = Ø. But P(An ) = 1 for all n, hence limn→∞ P(An ) = 1.

8
MIT OpenCourseWare
https://ocw.mit.edu

6.436J / 15.085J Fundamentals of Probability


Fall 2018

For information about citing these materials or our Terms of Use, visit: https://ocw.mit.edu/terms

You might also like