Week 1 & 2 Module 1 & 2 - Social Issues & Professional Practices
Week 1 & 2 Module 1 & 2 - Social Issues & Professional Practices
GENERAL INSTRUCTIONS
1. This module is made to help you continue education amidst the threat of this COVID19 pandemic
which has affected not only the Philippines but the entire world. This includes lessons and
activities that will help you develop further understanding in the study of computing.
2. You will be provided with a hard-copy of the module. This is expected to be finished in one week.
Note: There are activities with specific directions on their mode of submission so make sure to
read, understand and follow the directions properly. Some activities are to be submitted only
online to also improve your ICT skills so it would be better to have access to the internet from time
to time.
3. For those who have limited or no access to strong internet connectivity, you can write your
answers on a long bond paper which will be collected weekly in exchange for the next module.
You can directly indicate your answers, provided that they are labeled accordingly.
4. It is highly recommended that you jot down important details of the lessons in the modules to
serve as your personal notes in a different notebook or any piece of paper since modules will be
retrieved at certain schedules.
6. Further questions and clarifications will be entertained through email, messenger or SMS. You
can also write them on a separate bond paper which will be collected together with your answered
modules.
7. Do not send any unnecessary information to the contact details given to you. Refrain from sharing
these to respect your teacher’s privacy.
INTRODUCTION
Computer scientists must understand the relevant social, ethical, and professional issues that
surround their activities. The ACM Code of Ethics and Professional Conduct provides a basis for
personal responsibility and professional conduct for computer scientists who are engaged in system
development that directly affects the general public.
The formal study of ethics goes back at least two thousand four hundred years, to the Greek
philosopher Socrates. In the past two millennia, philosophers have proposed many ethical theories. In
this module, we review some of them. A useful theory allows its proponents to examine moral
problems, reach conclusions, and defend these conclusions in front of a disbelieving yet open-minded
audience.
The term ‘ethics’ broadly describes the way in which we look at and understand life, in terms of
good and bad or right or wrong. It is a branch of knowledge that deals with moral principles. Moral
theories are the frameworks we use to justify or clarify our position when we ask ourselves “what
should I do in this situation?” or “what is right or wrong for me?”. There are many moral theories and
there is no one right theory. They converge and often borrow from one another (Wallace, Susan).
Let’s Explore!
Learning Modules in IT 207 Page 3 of 12
2nd
Term – 2nd Semester S.Y 2020-2021
The words "moral" and "ethics" (and cognates) are often used interchangeably. However, it is
useful to make the following distinction:
Morality is the system through which we determine right and wrong conduct -- i.e., the guide to
good or right conduct.
A theory is a structured set of statements used to explain (or predict) a set of facts or
concepts.Ý A moral theory, then, explains why a certain action is wrong -- or why we ought to act in
certain ways.ÝÝ In short, it is a theory of how we determine right and wrong conduct.Ý Also, moral
theories provide the framework upon which we think and discuss in a reasoned way, and so evaluate,
specific moral issues.
Seen in this light, it becomes clear that we cannot draw a sharp divide between moral theory
and applied ethics (e.g., medical or business ethics). For instance, in order to critically evaluate the
moral issue of affirmative action, we must not attempt to evaluate what actions or policies are right (or
wrong) independent of what we take to determine right and wrong conduct. You will see, as we
proceed, that we do not do ethics without at least some moral theory.Ý When evaluating the merits of
some decision regarding a case, we will always (or at least ought to always) find ourselves thinking
about how right and wrong is determined in general, and then apply that to the case at hand.Ý Note,
though, that sound moral thinking does not simply involve going one way -- from theory to applied
issue.Ý Sometimes a case may suggest that we need to change or adjust our thinking about what
moral theory we think is the best, or perhaps it might lead us to think that a preferred theory needs
modification.
Most take moral theories to be prescriptive. The descriptive accounts of what people do is left
to sociologists and anthropologists.Ý Philosophers, then, when they study morality, want to know
what is the proper way of determining right and wrong. There have been many different proposals.Ý
Here is a brief summary.
Theories of Morality
(1) Moral Subjectivism
Right and wrong is determined by what you -- the subject -- just happens to think (or 'feel') is
right or wrong.
In its common form, Moral Subjectivism amounts to the denial of moral principles of any
significant kind, and the possibility of moral criticism and argumentation.Ý In essence, 'right' and
'wrong' lose their meaning because so long as someone thinks or feels that some action is 'right',
there are no grounds for criticism.Ý If you are a moral subjectivist, you cannot object to anyone's
behaviour (assuming people are in fact acting in accordance with what they think or feel is right).Ý
This shows the key flaw in moral subjectivism -- probably nearly everyone thinks that it is legitimate to
object, on moral grounds, to at least some peoples' actions.Ý That is, it is possible to disagree about
moral issues.
Cultural Relativism is closely linked to Moral Subjectivism.Ý It implies that we cannot criticize
the actions of those in cultures other than our own.Ý And again, it amounts to the denial of universal
moral principles.Ý Also, it implies that a culture cannot be mistaken about what is right and wrong
(which seems not to be true), and so it denies the possibility of moral advancement (which also
seems not to be true).
Right and wrong is determined by what is in your self-interest.Ý Or, it is immoral to act contrary
to your self-interest.
Ethical Egoism is usually based upon Psychological Egoism -- that we, by nature, act
selfishly.Ý Ethical egoism does not imply hedonism or that we ought to aim for at least some 'higher'
goods (e.g., wisdom, political success), but rather that we will (ideally) act so as to maximize our self
interest.Ý This may require that we forgo some immediate pleasures for the sake of achieving some
long term goals.Ý Also, ethical egoism does not exclude helping others.Ý However, egoists will help
others only if this will further their own interests.Ý An ethical egoist will claim that the altruist helps
others only because they want to (perhaps because they derive pleasure out of helping others) or
because they think there will be some personal advantage in doing so.Ý That is, they deny the
possibility of genuine altruism (because they think we are all by nature selfish).Ý This leads us to the
key implausibility of Ethical Egoism -- that the person who helps others at the expense of their self-
interest is actually acting immorally.Ý Many think that the ethical egoist has misunderstood the
concept of morality -- i.e., morality is the system of practical reasoning through which we are guided
to constrain our self-interest, not further it.Ý Also, thatÝ genuine altruism is indeed possible, and
relatively commonly exhibited.
Many claim that there is a necessary connection between morality and religion, such that,
without religion (in particular, without God or gods) there is no morality, i.e., no right and wrong
behaviour.Ý Although there are related claims that religion is necessary to motivate and guide people
to behave in morally good way, most take the claim of the necessary connection between morality
and religion to mean that right and wrong come from the commands of God (or the gods).Ý This view
of morality is known as Divine Command Theory.Ý The upshot is that an action is right -- or obligatory
-- if God command we do it, wrong if God commands we refrain from doing it, and morally permissible
if God does not command that it not be done.
Divine Command Theory is widely held to have several serious flaws.Ý First, it presupposes
that God or gods exist.Ý Second, even if we assume that God does exist, it presupposes that we can
know what God commandsÝ But even if we accept theism, it looks like even theists should reject the
theory.Ý Plato raised the relevant objection 2500 years ago.Ý He asked:
Is something right (or wrong) because the gods command it, or do the gods command it
because it is right?
If the latter, then right and wrong are independent of the gods' commands -- Divine Command
Theory is false.Ý If the former, then right and wrong are just a matter of the arbitrary will of the gods
(i.e., they might have willed some other, contradictory commands).
Most think that right and wrong are not arbitrary -- that is, some action is wrong, say, for a
reason.Ý Moreover, that if God commands us not to do an action, He does so because of this reason,
not simply because He arbitrarily commands it.Ý What makes the action wrong, then, is not God's
commanding it, but the reason.Ý Divine Command Theory is false again.
Right and wrong are characterized in terms of acting in accordance with the traditional virtues
-- making the good person.
The most widely discussed is Aristotle's account.Ý For Aristotle, the central concern is "Ethica"
= things to do with character.Ý Of particular concern are excellences of character -- i.e., the moral
virtues.
Aristotle, and most of the ancient Greeks really had nothing to say about moral duty, i.e.,
modern day moral concepts.Ý Rather, they were concerned with what makes human beings truly
'happy'.Ý True 'happiness' is called Eudaimonia (flourishing / well- being / fulfilment / self-
actualization).Ý Like Plato, Aristotle wants to show that there are objective reasons for living in
accordance with the traditional virtues (wisdom, courage, justice and temperance).Ý For Aristotle, this
comes from a particular account of human nature -- i.e., the virtuous life is the 'happiest' (most
fulfilling) life.
Aristotle thought that humans had a specific function.Ý This function is to lead a life of true
flourishing as a human, which required abiding by the dictates of rationality and so acting in
accordance with the traditional virtues.
Comes out of the criticism that all other moral theories are 'masculine' -- display a male bias.Ý
Specifically, feminists are critical of the 'individualistic' nature of other moral theories (they take
individualism to be a 'masculine' idea).Ý Rather, feminist ethics suggests that we need to consider the
self as at least partly constructed by social relations.Ý So morality, according to some feminist moral
philosophers, must be ground in 'moral emotions' like love and sympathy, leading to relationships of
caring.Ý This allows legitimate biases towards those with whom we have close social relationships.
(7) Utilitarianism
Right and wrong is determined by the overall goodness (utility) of the consequences of action.
Utilitarianism is a Consequentialist moral theory.
Basic ideas:
All action leads to some end.Ý But there is a summum bonum -- the highest good/end. This is
pleasure or happiness.Ý Also, that there is a First Principle of Morals -- 'Principle of Utility',
alternatively called 'The Greatest Happiness Principle' (GHP), usually characterized as the ideal of
working towards the greatest happiness of the greatest number.Ý The GHP implies that we ought to
act so as to maximize human welfare (though Bentham thought we should include all sentient
animals in his utilitarian calculations).Ý We do this in a particular instance by choosing the action that
maximizes pleasure/happiness and minimizing suffering.
Jeremy Bentham -- the first to formulate Utilitarianism -- did not distinguish between kinds of
pleasures.Ý However, Bentham's student, John Stuart Mill, produced a more sophisticated version of
Utilitarianism in which pleasures may be higher or lower.Ý The higher pleasures (those obtained, e.g.,
through intellectual pursuits), carried greater weight than the lower pleasures (those obtained through
sensation).Ý The upshot is that in determining what action to perform, both quality and quantity of
pleasure/happiness count.
Learning Modules in IT 207 Page 6 of 12
2nd
Term – 2nd Semester S.Y 2020-2021
Note: Utilitarians are not a Hedonist.Ý Hedonists are concerned only with their own happiness.
Utilitarians are concerned with everyone's happiness, so it is Altruistic.Ý In general, morally right
actions are those that produce the best overall consequences / total amount of pleasure or absence
of pain.
Modern versions of Utilitarianism have dropped the idea of maximizing pleasure in favour of
maximizing the satisfaction of all relevant peoples' preferences and interests.Ý Also, some distinguish
between Act Utilitarianism and Rule Utilitarianism.Ý Act Utilitarianism is pretty mush as described
above, where we make the utilitarian calculation based on the evaluation of the consequences of a
single isolated act.Ý It is thought by some that this leads to a number of significant problems -- for
instance, that one person may be harmed if that leads to the greatest good for everyone.Ý To
overcome these problems, some advocate Rule Utilitarianism -- the view that we should adopt only
those rules (for governing society) that produce the greatest good for all.
How can we determine accurately what the consequences of an action will be?
Do people have rights that cannot be overridden by the goal of the best consequences for all?
Basic ideas:
That there is "the supreme principle of morality".Ý Good and Evil are defined in terms of Law /
Duty / Obligation.Ý Rationality and Freedom are also central.Ý Kant thought that acting morally was
quite simple.Ý That is:
Good Will (i.e., having the right intentions) is the only thing that is good without qualification.Ý
So, actions are truly moral only if they have the right intention, i.e., based on Good Will.
- only can be a law of "universal conformity" -- "I should never act except in such a way that I can also
will that my maxim should become a universal law".
This is called the Categorical Imperative = Principle of Universalizability (something like The
Golden Rule).Ý The basic idea is that we should adopt as action guiding rules (i.e., maxims) only
those that can be universally accepted.Ý Consider someone wondering if they could break a promise
if keeping it became inconvenient.Ý We might formulate the following maxim governing promises:
Kant had another way of formulating the Categorical Imperative that is worth noting.
Never treat anyone merely as a means to an end.Ý Rather, treat everyone as an end in themselves.
We can understand this by noting an example, i.e., the slave society.Ý What is wrong with the
slave society, following the above principle, is that a slave is treated as a means to the slave owner's
ends, i.e., as an instrument or tool, not as a person.Ý The upshot is that no person's interests (or
rights) can be overridden by another's, or the majority.
Many think that this way of formulating the Categorical Imperative shows that Kantianism is clearly
anti-Utilitarian.
Is it true that having good intentions is the only thing that counts morally?
Must we always ignore good consequences?
Is it always wrong to treat people merely as a means to an end? (Can we do otherwise?)
We are to act in accordance with a set of moral rights, which we possess simply by being human.
Rights-based views are connected to Kantianism and are Non-consequentialist.Ý The basic
idea is that if someone has a right, then others have a corresponding duty to provide what the right
requires.
Most distinguish between positive and negative rights.Ý A positive right is one in which the
corresponding duty requires a positive action, e.g., giving a charitable donation in order to sustain
someone's right to life, shelter, education, etc.Ý A negative right is one in which the corresponding
duty merely requires refraining from doing something that will harm someone.Ý Some claim -- e.g.,
Libertarians -- that only negative rights count morally.Ý For instance, the right to life does not require
that we give what is needed to sustain life, rather merely that we refrain from taking any action that
would take life. [Note: others argue that there is really no significant distinction between positive and
negative rights, arguing that a positive right can be understood negatively, and visa versa.Ý Also, that
there is no morally significant difference between, for example, letting someone die and killing them.Ý
Obviously, this is a hotly disputed issue.]
Where do rights come from?Ý From nature (we have them simply by being human)?Ý From
principles of Justice?Ý Or, from Utilitarian procedures?
How do we decide between competing rights?
(10) Contractarianism
The principles of right and wrong (or Justice) are those which everyone in society would agree
upon in forming a social contract.
Through a thought experiment, Rawls developed a way of getting people to come up with
universal principles of justice.Ý The basic idea is nothing new -- i.e., of impartial developing a social
contract ofÝ universal principles -- but many find Rawls' novel method very appealing.Ý The idea is to
start by thinking, hypothetically, that we are at the beginning of forming a society and we want to
know which principles of justice to ground the society.Ý However, in this 'original position' we do this
without knowing which position we will occupy in the future society -- we don't know if we will be rich
or poor, male or female, old or young, etc.Ý We then advocate those principles that will be in our self-
interest (though we don't know what 'self' that will be).Ý This forces us to be impartial, and if we are
rational, to propose universal principles.Ý The idea of the thought experiment is not to think that we
actually begin again, and construct a society from scratch.Ý Rather, we can use the thought
experiment as a test of actual principles of justice.Ý If a principle is one that would not be adopted by
people in the original position, behind the 'veil of ignorance' (about who they will be), then it is unjust
and should be rejected.
[Rawls claims that people in this original position will choose conservatively when developing
principles governing the distribution of benefits and burdens.Ý This conservatism, Rawls claims, will
lead to the choosing two basic principles: (1) that each member of the society should have as much
liberty as possible without infringing on the liberty of others; and (2) the 'maximin' rule for decisions
about economic justice -- namely, that they will choose those rules that would maximize the minimum
they would receive.Ý In other words, make the society in which the least well off are in the best
possible position.Ý Deviations from equality of distribution of benefits and burdens is justified only if it
advantages the least well off.Ý Rawls thought that some inequalities would be adopted because
rewarding on the grounds of merit and hard work, for example, would lead to a society in which there
was a greater production of social benefits, so the least well of would be better off than in a society of
pure equality.
Let’s Expand!
Ethics are a structure of standards and practices that influence how people lead their lives. It
is not strictly implemented to follow these ethics, but it is basically for the benefit of everyone that we
do.
Ethics are unlike laws that legally mandate what is right or wrong. Ethics illustrate society’s
views about what is right and what is wrong.
Computer ethics are a set of moral standards that govern the use of computers. It is
society’s views about the use of computers, both hardware and software. Privacy concerns,
intellectual property rights and effects on the society are some of the common issues of computer
ethics.
Privacy Concerns
Hacking – is unlawful intrusion into a computer or a network. A hacker can intrude through the
security levels of a computer system or network and can acquire unauthorised access to other
computers.
Malware – means malicious software which is created to impair a computer system. Common
malware are viruses, spyware, worms and trojan horses. A virus can delete files from a hard
drive while a spyware can collect data from a computer.
Data Protection – also known as information privacy or data privacy is the process of
safeguarding data which intends to influence a balance between individual privacy rights while
still authorising data to be used for business purposes.
Anonymity – is a way of keeping a user’s identity masked through various applications.
Effects on Society
Jobs – Some jobs have been abolished while some jobs have become simpler as computers
have taken over companies and businesses. Things can now be done in just one click
whereas before it takes multiple steps to perform a task. This change may be considered
unethical as it limits the skills of the employees.
There are also ethical concerns on health and safety of employees getting sick from
constant sitting, staring at computer screens and typing on the keyboard or clicking on the
mouse.
Environmental Impact – Environment has been affected by computers and the internet since
so much time spent using computers increases energy usage which in turn increases the
emission of greenhouse gases.
There are ways where we can save energy like limiting computer time and turning off the
computer or putting on sleep mode when not in use. Buying energy efficient computers
with Energy Star label can also help save the environment.
Social Impact – Computers and the internet help people stay in touch with family and friends.
Social media has been very popular nowadays.
Computer gaming influenced society both positively and negatively. Positive effects are
improved hand-eye coordination, stress relief and improved strategic thinking. Negative
effects are addiction of gamers, isolation from the real world and exposure to violence.
Computer technology helps the government in improving services to its citizens. Advanced
database can hold huge data being collected and analysed by the government.
Computer technology aids businesses by automating processes, reports and analysis.
Computer Ethics
Ethics deals with placing a “value” on acts according to whether they are “good” or “bad”. Every
society has its rules about whether certain acts are ethical or not. These rules have been established
as a result of consensus in society and are often written into laws.
When computers first began to be used in society at large, the absence of ethical standards about
their use and related issues caused some problems. However, as their use became widespread in
every facet of our lives, discussions in computer ethics resulted in some kind of a consensus.
Today, many of these rules have been formulated as laws, either national or international. Computer
crimes and computer fraud are now common terms. There are laws against them, and everyone is
responsible for knowing what constitutes computer crime and computer fraud.
1) Thou shalt not use a computer to harm other people: If it is unethical to harm people by
making a bomb, for example, it is equally bad to write a program that handles the timing of the
bomb. Or, to put it more simply, if it is bad to steal and destroy other people’s books and
notebooks, it is equally bad to access and destroy their files.
3) Thou shalt not snoop around in other people's files: Reading other people’s e-mail
messages is as bad as opening and reading their letters: This is invading their privacy.
Obtaining other people’s non-public files should be judged the same way as breaking into their
rooms and stealing their documents. Text documents on the Internet may be protected
by encryption.
4) Thou shalt not use a computer to steal: Using a computer to break into the accounts of a
company or a bank and transferring money should be judged the same way as robbery. It is
illegal and there are strict laws against it.
5) Thou shalt not use a computer to bear false witness: The Internet can spread untruth as
fast as it can spread truth. Putting out false "information" to the world is bad. For instance,
spreading false rumors about a person or false propaganda about historical events is wrong.
6) Thou shalt not use or copy software for which you have not paid: Software is an
intellectual product. In that way, it is like a book: Obtaining illegal copies of copyrighted
software is as bad as photocopying a copyrighted book. There are laws against both.
Information about the copyright owner can be embedded by a process
called watermarking into pictures in the digital format.
8) Thou shalt not appropriate other people's intellectual output: For example, the
programs you write for the projects assigned in this course are your own intellectual output.
Copying somebody else’s program without proper authorization is software piracy and is
unethical. Intellectual property is a form of ownership, and may be protected by copyright
laws.
9) Thou shalt think about the social consequences of the program you write: You have to
think about computer issues in a more general social framework: Can the program you write
be used in a way that is harmful to society? For example, if you are working for an animation
house, and are producing animated films for children, you are responsible for their contents.
Do the animations include scenes that can be harmful to children? In the United States,
the Communications Decency Act was an attempt by lawmakers to ban certain types of
content from Internet websites to protect young children from harmful material. That law was
struck down because it violated the free speech principles in that country's constitution. The
discussion, of course, is going on.
10) Thou shalt use a computer in ways that show consideration and respect: Just like
public buses or banks, people using computer communications systems may find themselves
in situations where there is some form of queuing and you have to wait for your turn and
generally be nice to other people in the environment. The fact that you cannot see the people
you are interacting with does not mean that you can be rude to them.
Let’s Ponder!
A. Jonidel, a gifted high school student, wants to become a lawyer in the future. Because she
comes from a poor family, she needs a scholarship in order to attend college. Some of her
classes require students to do extra research projects in order to get an A. Her high school has
a few older PC’s but there are always long lines of students waiting to use them during the
school day. After school, she usually works on a part-time job to help support her family.
One evening Jodinel visited the library of a private college few miles from her family’s
apartment, and she found plenty of unused PC’s connected to the Internet. She surreptitiously looked
over the shoulder of another student to learn a valid login/password combination. Jodinel returned to
the library several times a week, and by using its PCs and printers she effectively completed the extra
research projects, graduated from high school with straight A’s and got a full-ride scholarship to attend
a prestigious university.
Questions:
B. Parents nowadays, allow their children to play computer games because according to them,
computer games help, in one way or another, in developing the decision making and analytical
skills of their child. Do you agree? Why or why not?
________________________________.