0% found this document useful (0 votes)
66 views16 pages

PopulismIsNotTheProblemPre Publication

Uploaded by

Federico Abal
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
66 views16 pages

PopulismIsNotTheProblemPre Publication

Uploaded by

Federico Abal
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 16

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.

net/publication/312888241

Populism is not the problem. It's part of the solution

Article  in  Critique · January 2017

CITATIONS READS
0 1,338

1 author:

Torbjörn Tännsjö
Stockholm University
171 PUBLICATIONS   668 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

Priority Setting in Health Care View project

All content following this page was uploaded by Torbjörn Tännsjö on 04 February 2019.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.


Populism Is Not The Problem. It’s Part Of The Solution

How Best To Contain The New Wave Of Aggressive And Missionary Nationalism

By Professor Torbjör Tännsjö (Stockholm University)

January 10, 2016 Picture: Bryan Snyder/Reuters.

---------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------------

This article is part of The Critique’s January/February 2017 Issue “Stick It To The Man: A Year

Of Anglo-American Populist Revolt Against A Changing Culture & An Obtuse Political

Establishment”

The words ‘populist’ and ‘populism’ have in many contexts turned into slurs. They appear in

these contexts heavily loaded with negative emotive meaning, but with either little or no

descriptive sense. For example, the Professor of political science Donald Brand says of this

1
election that ‘a populist outsider has captured the pinnacle of power in the American system: the

presidency. Trump’s success will encourage other populists on the left and the right to find a path

to power’ (’Populism is the Congress’s Next Big Threat’, Fortune, 9 November 2016). This

comment is typical of people who seem complacent with regard to the current economic and

political status quo, but nevertheless accuse successful politicians with large leftist or right-wing

public support of being populists. The obvious problem with this broad use of the term ‘populist’

is that there is little connecting the ideology of politicians on the right and on the left. There is

little uniting the beliefs of Trump and Sanders, Farage and Corbyn, Syriza in their heydays and

Golden Dawn respectively. They have only one thing in common — they are all targets of the

negative sentiments of those who characterize them as ‘populists’--- a label that they do not

themselves readily accept.

Maybe this criticism of the cavalier way in which the concept of ‘populism’ is used is unfair.

Could we not, on a charitable interpretation, find some descriptive meaning in this loose talk

about populism? Here are a number of suggested ways to think about populism in very broad

terms.

We sometimes hear that populists offer simple solutions to complex problems. But is not

simplicity a virtue in politics just as it is in science? In science, given the available data at our

disposition, we opt for the hypothesis that, other things being equal, the simplest explanation of

this data will do. We make an inference to the best (simplest) explanation. In politics, once a

problem has been identified, should we not, other things being equal, also opt for the simplest

solution to it? I think we should, so the problem cannot be that populists offer simple solutions to

complex problems. Perhaps the idea is that populists offer simplistic rather than simple solutions

2
to complex problems. However, what measures are considered in their totality to be simplistic

and what measures are considered straightforward is a moot question.

A person’s attitude or stance towards the status quo, will likely affect their view of what is

considered simplistic or straightforward. If for example you are satisfied with the status quo as

you conceive of it, and want to keep it that way, then all suggested reforms may sound hazardous

and simplistic to you since they put in jeopardy what you cherish. However, from the standpoint

of those who want to bring about transformative changes to their societies, a defence of the status

quo is, in the present context, no less problematic or unhelpful in its simplicity than the various

reforms they are trying to put forward.

We also hear that populists typically attack ‘the elite’. This may be true of both the political right

and the political left, and it may seem to be something that unites them and differentiates them

from those who find the existence of an elite class quite natural and highly desirable. However,

the right and the left seem to react very differently to the elites they identify. The explanation for

this divergence is that they use the same term but differ on the meaning of the term. The right

focuses on culture and values while the left focuses on socioeconomic characteristics. In some

cases, the two categories partly overlap. However, in many cases they don’t. It then transpires

that the right and the left have very different approaches to what they characterise with the same

term, ‘the elite’. From a leftist perspective, Trump is part of the economic elite, the 1% profiting

in greater amounts from the perverse widening of wealth inequality that is concentrating scarce

resources at the very top of society. From Trump’s own perspective, although he is indeed rich

(and proud of it), he does not consider himself a member of the ‘elite’ class that is currently, and

has been for many years, disconnected from the values and concerns of average working-class

3
Americans. He is rich, and brags about it, but he doesn’t share the values cherished by those he

conceives of as part of the technocratic elite (where one doesn’t brag about one’s riches).

Of course, if we look closely at the political platforms of Trump and Sanders there are some

shared interests, but Sanders and Clinton have even more elements in common. We should not

forget Nelson Goodman’s observation that ‘every two things have some property in common’.1

What we need to focus on here is politically important and salient traits. It is not plausible to say

that there are so many vital political principles which unite Trump and Sanders, in opposition to

Clinton that they both ought to be characterised as ‘populists’. Moreover, what may at first look

like common positions may well turn out, in the final analysis, to be very different. Even Sanders

himself thought at first that he and Trump had a shared view on infrastructure investments only to

have to note, as a second thought, on his blog on 22 November 2016:

“Unlike Trump’s plan, which creates new tax loopholes and is a corporate giveaway,

my Rebuild America Act would be paid for by eliminating tax loopholes that allow

hugely profitable multinational corporations to stash their profits in offshore tax

havens around the world”.

These points of tension between Sanders and Trump seem to suggests that the journalist, John B.

Judis, was on to something when he observed in an article for The Guardian:

“There is no set of features that exclusively defines movements, parties, and people

1Nelson Goodman,”Seven Strictures on Similarity”, in Problems and Projects, (Indianapolis


and New York, The Bobbs-Merill Company, 1972), p. 443.

4
that are called “populist”: the different people and parties that are placed in this

category enjoy family resemblances of one to the other, but there is not a universal set

of traits that is common to all of them”.

Does the inadequacy of the above criteria mean that we should give up on the term ‘populism’?

Judis tries himself to distinguish between many different political movements within this family,

and this is feasible, of course, but the explanatory value of the word ‘populism’ is then lost. Each

of these movements follow their own logic. However, I don’t think we should give up on the term

altogether. I think we should be bolder. We can indeed salvage the term by giving it a clear

descriptive meaning, while doing away with its emotive overtones, without deviating from at

least one common usage of it.

In what follows I will argue that the present political situation is in many ways critical. The US

and the world faces, after the election of Donald Trump, what should be characterised as

existential threats, not only from the possibility of nuclear war, but even more obviously so from

global warming. At the same time, societies seem to be falling apart, torn by political movements

we haven’t seen for decades. This means that we need to find new political means of handling the

situation. In addressing the global civic unrest, and the resulting global political disruption,

populism will turn out to be an asset rather than an enemy of democracy. Populism is not the

problem of our age; rather it is part of the solution to our twenty-first century woes

If despite what political commentators argue, populism is not the main problem confronting those

still grappling with the shock of Brexit and the Trump presidency, what exactly is the crisis at

hand? I agree with the diagnosis of one of the putative left wing ‘populists’, Yanis Varoufakis, in

5
an article in The Conversation:

“The election of Donald Trump symbolises the demise of a remarkable era. It was a

time when we saw the curious spectacle of a superpower, the US, growing stronger

because of – rather than despite – its burgeoning deficits. It was also remarkable

because of the sudden influx of two billion workers – from China and Eastern Europe

– into capitalism’s international supply chain. This combination gave global

capitalism a historic boost, while at the same time suppressing Western labour’s share

of income and prospects. Trump’s success comes as that dynamic fails (14 November

2016)”. 2

Varoufakis observes, correctly in my view, that important segments of Western societies find

themselves marginalised. The gap between the rich and the less well-to-do continues to widen.

As fear and despair continue to spread, the soil is ripe for all sorts of radical political initiatives.

But this means that there are both dangers and possibilities facing us.

The main danger comes from the political right. But here we need to be precise. The terms ‘right’

and ‘left’ in politics typically designate different approaches to social inequality. The more

egalitarian you are, the more to the left you stand. On the other hand, the less you tend to

2 Available from the Internet: https://theconversation.com/trump-victory-comes-with-a-silver-


lining-for-the-worlds-progressives-
68523?utm_medium=email&utm_campaign=Latest%20from%20The%20Conversation%20for%
20November%2013%202016%20-
%206038&utm_content=Latest%20from%20The%20Conversation%20for%20November%2013
%202016%20-
%206038+CID_9a75a06c3a6611f2a0018c7ce3abfaba&utm_source=campaign_monitor_uk&utm
_term=writes%20former%20Greek%20finance%20minister%20Yanis%20Varoufakis

6
consider inequality a problem, the more to the right you stand; at least on my preferred

understanding of the terms. And if this is how we conceive of the left and the right, it is not right-

wing policy as such that poses a special threat to democracy in our time, it is a version of right-

wing policy with a particular nationalistic bent.

In discussions about populism we often hear that this traditional divide between the left and the

right is now dated. It is associated with a materialist understanding of politics, where the working

class is supposed to vote for the left and the upper classes to vote for the right. However, in

today’s world, new political dimensions have become more important. And there seems to exist

supporting research, mainly by Inglehart and Norris, to this effect, which is often quoted by the

likes of, Fareed Zakaria, for example, in his ‘Populist on the March’, Foreign Affairs 17 October

2016:

“Inglehart and Norris point out that this old voting pattern has been waning for

decades. “By the 1980s,” they write, “class voting had fallen to the lowest levels ever

recorded in Britain, France, Sweden and West Germany. . . . In the U.S., it had fallen

so low [by the 1990s] that there was virtually no room for further decline.”

This observation is probably correct when it comes to voter patterns. However, the economic

realities remain, and, as I will argue below, if we want to counter the present fears we need to

return to this sort of ideological politics. This is what we need to do if we want to counter the

nationalistic trend.

That being said, it bears repeating, we must be careful with how we understand our terms. The

7
word ‘nationalism’ can characterize two main approaches to organizing a nation. On one

understanding of the term, a ‘nationalist’ holds on to the universalistic ideal that each people

should have its own state. This kind of nationalism could be characterised as liberal, and it was an

important ideological source behind many European movements during the 19th century. It

played a similar role during the second half of the 20th century, when former colonies fought for

independence. We see a late (and probably) lost attempt to realise this ideal in the Israel/Palestine

conflict with the idea of two nation states side by side. Few believe that this is feasible anymore

and personally I don’t believe it is desirable either, but I will leave this issue aside in the present

context.

There is another meaning of the term ‘nationalism’, however, where it designates an aggressive

and missionary attitude to one nation in particular, wiz one’s own. This is not an universalisable

ideal, it is pure national egotism. You support your own nation against all the others. And this is

indeed a dangerous creed. It was once upheld by Hitler and the Nazis, and we hear it echo in

Trump’s assertion that he will make America great again, and, even more so, in his idea of

‘America first’.

We sometimes hear talk about a new ‘nationalist international’ but this makes little sense. Parties

with this kind of ambition can enter into temporary alliances but, because of their different and

conflicting goals, such an ‘international’ will be inherently unstable. We should not expect

aggressive and missionary nationalists to sustain a system such as the United Nations.

In the 1930s such nationalist parties overtly attacked democracy. This is rare in today’s world.

However, what is typical of these movements is that they hold their own views about what Robert

8
Dahl has called the ‘boundary’ problem. They want to close the borders and even expel some

members from their own states, since they are not considered part of the nation. While genetic

criteria were once used to delineate one’s own people, we now meet rather with ethnic and

cultural and religious ones. The effect is the same, however. Some people don’t belong to the

people and should not be included in – and should even be expelled from — the demos. The

economic situation makes such a time as this ripe for this kind of aggressive and missionary

nationalism. This means danger. So what is the solution?

The answer to that question depends on what you believe the problem to be. As I have explained

before, some seem to believe that populism is the problem. Hence, to obviate the dangers from

aggressive and missionary nationalism — and make the world safe for the elites — we should opt

for the kind of democracy that is not populist. We should attempt to keep ordinary people out of

politics. However, I actually think the opposite is true. We should include them.

In my book Populist Democracy. A Defence (London and New York: Routledge, 1992) I

conceived of democracy as a method of decision-making, where the will of the majority (in a

given demos) is decisive for the political outcome. In many contexts this ideal is realised through

a direct method. People meet, put forward proposals, discuss, and take a vote. However, in nation

states, let alone on a global level, this is not possible. But then it is possible to approach this ideal

(if it is considered as an ideal) through a proportionate electoral system, where the people vote for

their favoured parties, these parties get represented in proportion to the votes they gain from the

people, and then form a sovereign parliament politically representative of the people. The

parliament legislates in a directly democratic manner and it selects the government, again in a

directly democratic manner.

9
This is roughly the kind of political system upheld in countries like Germany and in Scandinavia.

Here it makes sense to think that the parliament reaches the decision the entire people would

make, were it possible for it to meet (under the oaks, as Rousseau had it). Hence it is an

approximation of the populist ideal (if it is seen as ideal).

I wrote my book in opposition to William Riker’s earlier Liberalism Against Populism (San

Francisco: Waveland Press, 1988). I accepted the word ‘populist’ for the kind of democracy I

defended — and he attacked, but I rejected the term ‘liberal’ for the kind of system Riker

advocated. I still think ‘liberalism’ is a misnomer and I will come back to that. Instead I will

bluntly speak of his favoured notion of democracy as an ‘elitist’ system.

Riker belongs to a tradition which originated in Joseph Schumpeter’s Capitalism, Socialism, and

Democracy (New York: Harper and Brothers, 1942). On their joint favoured notion of

democracy, democracy is not a system allowing the people to rule itself, it is a system where the

people are allowed to decide who should rule them. This, of course, comes closer to the US

reality than the systems I referred to in Germany and Scandinavia. So why should we prefer a

system where the people’s role is restricted to the choice of rulers over a system where the people

rule themselves? Why should we prefer the U.S model to the Scandinavian one?

Some of the arguments to this effect build on the claim that populist democracy is impossible.

The very idea of a ‘will of a people’ is bad metaphysics and makes no sense. This was

Schumpeter’s take on the issue. This is incorrect. There are clearly ways to operationalize the

notion of a will of the people, otherwise political systems like the ones in Germany and

10
Scandinavia wouldn’t exist.

Other arguments are to the effect that problems in the theory of social choice shows that often

there is no unique will of the people. This was Riker’s take on the problem. The opinions form

cycles where there is a majority of proposal A over B, of B over C, and finally of C over A.

Hence, the idea that the majority will of the people should be guaranteed to translate into social

choice, makes no sense.

However, there is a simple solution to this problem, as I have argued in my book. A decision

method is democratic (in the populist sense) if and only if (i) it selects any one of the items in a

(top) cycle like the one mentioned above and (ii) it is such that, had there been a unique

Condorcet winner (a proposal that is preferred by a majority to any other proposal), this

Condorcet winner would have been selected.

I conclude that populist democracy is possible. However, if it is, then it makes sense to ask

whether it is desirable or not. I think it is. Both Schumpeter and Riker have argued that it is not.

Their main argument why it is not, relies on the belief that while ordinary people may be good at

tending to their private affairs, they are no good when it comes to political matters. Hence, they

should be kept away from political deliberation and decision-making. Once they have elected

their leaders, there should be no room for ‘political back-seat driving’. This argument has been

developed in so many ways, but it boils down to this elitist view of ordinary people’s political

capacity.

Now, if this pessimistic view of ordinary folk is true, then it makes sense indeed to say that it is a

11
problem when ordinary people get engaged in politics, are tempted by different proposals from

political leaders to the right and the left, and vote for them. They may all be heading in the wrong

and even disastrous direction.

I doubt that this elitist view of ordinary people is correct. And we must hope that it is incorrect.

We must hope that at least it is possible to educate us people at large, so that we become capable

of handling political affairs in a responsible manner. We must hope so, since, if we ordinary folk

are not capable of handling political affairs in a responsible manner, then we seem to face what I

will call an elitist paradox: If ordinary people are not fit to take a responsible stand on political

matters, then it is highly unlikely that they can make wise choices about whom should lead them.

Are we not faced with a demonstration of this contradiction in the election of Trump as

president? American people are not used to discuss political matters in the manner we do here in

Scandinavia, where we have representative political systems with several parties, presenting

different platforms to the electorate. Hence, they are also poor judges of political leaders. Many

are likely not to vote at all when presented with a binary choice like the one in a presidential US

election — roughly half of the population —and many others to go where their sentiments lead

them rather than with what their more reasoned self would prescribe. This is what we should

expect if in accordance with the elitist ideal they are invited to assess merely the quality of the

candidates, not their political platforms. My belief is that, had the same people lived in a

different and less bi-polar political culture, where they had been presented with a variety of subtle

political alternatives to choose from, they would have behaved better.

12
I have thus defined and defended a notion of populism that I think can be generally useful for

political discourse. Are any of the two putative populist politicians, Sanders or Trump, ‘populist’

in my favoured sense of the term? I am not aware of any detailed stand they have taken on

constitutional matters, but I doubt that Trump is a ‘populist’, in this sense. The existing system

has shown to be well suited to his ambitions. However, in some of his speeches Sanders seems to

have at least a leaning towards this kind of populism: ‘If we are going to transform America, we

need a political revolution. Millions of people have to stand up and get involved in the political

process in a way we have not in many, many years.’ (I have the quotation from John B. Judis, ’All

The Rage: Sanders and Trump represent two different sides of American populism — and

the uprisings they sparked could topple the established political order’, New Republic 19

September, 2016.)

This massive political involvement would only be possible, I submit, under a proportionate and

representative democratic system of the sort envisaged in my book on populism, aimed at

allowing the people, not only to select its leaders, but to govern itself.

This leads me to an additional comment on terminology. I claimed that Riker’s term ‘liberal’ was

a misnomer when applied to the elitist political idea that ordinary people should not rule

themselves; they should just decide who should rule them. And the reason why this is a misnomer

is that there exists a truly liberal tradition dating back to J.S. Mill, where democracy is considered

to have an inherently pedagogical aspect as well. Democracy is not only a way of deciding

political matters. The representative democratic institutions help us ordinary folk to a better

13
understanding of society and our role in it. Or, as Mill puts it in Considerations on Representative

Government (London: Parker, Son, and Bourn, West Strand, 1861)3:

… the most important point of excellence which any form of government can possess

is to promote the virtue and intelligence of the people themselves. (p.30)

The only decent answer to the aggressive and missionary nationalism we now confront comes

from left-wing policy designed to deal with the real economic problems facing people in Western

democracies through egalitarian and other measures.

This task is certainly not as easy as The Economist describes it:

“Part of the answer is to draw on the power of liberal ideals. New technology,

prosperity and commerce will do more than xenophobia to banish people’s

insecurities. The way to overcome resentment is economic growth—not to put up

walls. The way to defeat Islamist terrorism is to enlist the help of Muslims—not to

treat them as hostile. The main parties need to make that case loudly and

convincingly”.

What is missing here is crucial. It is crucial to come to grips with glaring inequalities,

unemployment, and other problems correctly identified by both the right and the left. And the

3Accessible from the Internet: https://books.google.se/books?id=0-


cTAAAAQAAJ&printsec=frontcover&dq=Considerations+on+Representative+Government&hl
=sv&sa=X&ved=0ahUKEwiW55qO4q_QAhUIdCwKHcfDDWUQ6AEILTAB#v=onepage&q=
Considerations%20on%20Representative%20Government&f=false

14
solutions proposed by the left promises to lead to a better world, I submit. The solutions proposed

by the right spell disaster. So while we welcome populism, in the manner here defined, we should

also welcome the political conflict between the traditional left-wing and right-wing solutions to

these economic problems. The important point here is that a populist democratic system gives

much more room for the kind of political discussion, deliberation and conflict between ideas, that

is helpful for a left-wing project, than an elitist system.

It is easier for Trump to gain support from a people not used to political deliberation than from a

people well versed in it. It is easier to build a counterforce to, and to contain, an aggressive

missionary nationalism in a political climate where people are not kept from, but trusted with,

genuine political thinking aimed at granting them political power. Hence my claim that populism

is part of the solution to problems we are now facing.

15

View publication stats

You might also like