Group Experiment: and Other Writings
Group Experiment: and Other Writings
FRIEDRICH POLLOCK
THEODOR W. ADORNO
AND COLLEAGUES
Preface ix
Translators’ Introduction xv
ANDREW J. PERRIN AND JEFFREY K. OLICK
Foreword i
FRANZ BÖHM
Introduction 9
3 Quantitative Analyses 72
Afterword 148
Notes 185
Index 19 9
List of Tables and Figures
Tables
2.1 (originally Table 14) 59
2.2 (originally Table 15) 66
3.1 (originally Table 65) 77
3.2 (originally Table 66) 79
3.3 (originally Table 67) 79
3.4 (originally Table 68) 81
3.5 (originally Table 69) 85
3.6 (originally Table 70) 85
3.7 (originally Table 71) 86
3.8 (originally Table y 2) 87
3.9 (originally Table 73) 87
3.10 (originally Table 74) 88
3.11 (originally Table 73) 90
3.12 (originally Table 76) 94
3.13 (originally unnumbered) 96
3.14 (originally Table 77) 99
3.15 (originally Table 78) 102
List o f Tables and Figures
Figures
3.1 (originally Figure 7) 75
3.2 (originally Figure 8) 77
3.3 (originally Figure 9) 78
Translation N otes
A N D R E W J. PERRIN
JEFFREY K. OLICK
o r many read ers, the very existence of this volume—the first large-
F scale English translation of Gruppenexperiment, the Frankfurt School’s
first major project after their return from exile—may seem surprising. The
Frankfurt School of critical theorists—principally Theodor W. Adorno,
Max Horkheimer, Herbert Marcuse, and Leo Löwenthal—is not mainly
known as an empirically minded group of social scientists. In this intro
duction we explain the book’s importance in terms of the history of social
science and of current issues in social and democratic theory.
In 1941, Paul Lazarsfeld published an essay in the Frankfurt School
journal, Studies in Philosophy and Social Science (Lazarsfeld 1941), at
tempting to explain the difference between the kind of work he was pursu
ing at the Princeton Radio Research Project and that of Adorno, who had
recently left the project because of intractable intellectual differences with
Lazarsfeld. In his essay, Lazarsfeld distinguished between what he called
“administrative” and “critical” research. Administrative research, according
to Lazarsfeld, concerned matters of variation and behavior within an estab
lished social system, while critical research aimed at comprehending that
social system as a totality. As part of an effort to smooth things over with
Adorno (and with Max Horkheimer, who had sponsored Adorno’s partici
pation in the project), Lazarsfeld argued that administrative and critical
Translators' Introduction — ' xvi
1970, 42; Claussen 2008, 189; Jenemann 2007, 1-3).2 As scholars, they
cast their lot with social science as an entirely appropriate approach to
ascertaining totality. They identified themselves as social scientists and
wrote largely for an audience of social scientists (Held 1980, 36-37). Their
criticism of social science, however thoroughgoing, was a critique from
within social science and an argument for a radical objectivity instead of
the contrived objectivity of the emerging mainstream (Jay 1973, 224). As
Adorno put it in his autobiographical essay, “We followed what I believed
to be the plausible idea that in the present society the objective institutions
and developmental tendencies have attained such an overwhelming power
over the individual that people . . . are becoming, and evidently in increas
ing measure, functionaries of the predominant tendencies operating over
their heads. Less and less depends on their own particular conscious and
unconscious being, their inner life” (Adorno 1968, 230).
This critique permeates not just the philosophical work but also the
empirical studies the IFS produced, beginning with its prewar Studies on
Authority and the Family (IFS 1936), through its influential and contro
versial The Authoritarian Personality (Adorno et al. 1950), and on into the
postwar research agenda beginning with Gruppenexperiment (Pollock
1955), an important yet virtually unknown study of public opinion in
postwar Germany. In this volume we present the core of the public opin
ion research in Group Experiment in its first large-scale English transla
tion.3While the intellectual forces behind these projects (and the empirical
work that followed them well into the 1960s) were diverse and perhaps
even contradictory, this body of work demonstrates the extent to which, in
exile, the Frankfurt School and its associates cross-fertilized with the ma
jor developments of American social science. They used these tools and
approaches toward their overarching goal of locating and coming to terms
with the pathologies of anti-Semitism and fascism in Europe’s recent past
and diagnosing the persistent ills of mass society.
and Critical Theory,” “is wholly distrustful of the rules of conduct with
which society as presently constituted provides each of its members. The
separation between individual and society in virtue of which the individ
ual accepts as natural the limits prescribed for his activity is relativized
in critical theory” (Horkheimer 1972, 207). At the same time, consider
ations both Marxist and pragmatic prevented the Frankfurt scholars from
adopting an esoteric, detached theoretical approach. Thus they produced
a wide variety of empirical work in Germany and the United States,
which ties directly into the intellectual project of twentieth century criti
cal social science, rather than, as conventionally assumed, standing en
tirely against it.
The Frankfurt School’s history is complex, reflecting the turbulent envi
ronment in which its scholarship developed. It originated, for practical
purposes, in 1930, when Friedrich Pollock hired Max Horkheimer to take
over the directorship of the Institut für Sozialforschung (Institute for So
cial Research, IFS) in Frankfurt, the reincarnation of an Institute for
Marxism founded by wealthy philanthropist Felix Weil (Coser 1984). The
choice of Horkheimer marked the Institute’s recognition that Marxism
was in crisis and endorsed Horkheimer’s ambition of blending social phi
losophy and social science to address that crisis (Wiggershaus 1994,
36ff. ). Horkheimer quickly assembled a group of intellectuals whose
names remain at the core of the Frankfurt approach: psychologist Erich
Fromm, economist Friedrich Pollock (who coordinated the Gruppen
experiment),4 sociologist Leo Löwenthal, philosopher Herbert Marcuse,
and philosopher cum sociologist and musicologist Theodor Wiesegrund
Adorno. The group’s famously bleak outlook on the crisis of modern
politics and culture as they had developed since 1914—not an uncommon
evaluation across the political spectrum in Weimar Germany—emerged
out of these scholars’ interactions with one another as well as with their
interlocutors, most importantly Georg Lukâcs, Walter Benjamin, Bertolt
Brecht, and Siegfried Kracauer.
As this eclectic mix implies, from early on the Frankfurt School was
concerned with aesthetics, politics, culture, and media—and, crucially,
with the ways these combined with one another to create and reproduce
what they called the “totally socialized society” (vergesellschaftete Gesell
schaft). Gerhard Schweppenhäuser (2009, 51-76) makes a strong case
that the concept of the “totally socialized society” is one of the threads
that ties together Adorno’s entire oeuvre; it is “the antithesis of successful
mediation between general and individual interest” (58). The term appears
in several places throughout Adorno’s work, signifying the importance of
the concept in the Frankfurt diagnosis of modernity. We return to verge-
Translators9Introduction ~ xix
Thus, as Adorno suggests, the cynical fascist agitator manipulates his audi
ence by reducing it to a consuming public all too eager to believe the
David-versus-Goliath image of the “Lone Wolf” (Adorno 2000b, 4-6)
struggling against the tide of Communism and moral degeneration.6
The major philosophical work Adorno and Horkheimer produced dur
ing their California stay was Dialectic o f Enlightenment, a diagnosis of
modern culture and society that has become one of their best-known and
most read works (Hullot-Kentor 2006, 24-25). The audience’s status as a
mass is addressed in Dialectic o f Enlightenment, particularly in the most
famous essay therein, “The Culture Industry: Enlightenment as Mass De
ception.” Building upon Adorno’s 1936 rebuttal (Adorno 1977) to Benja
min’s essay on the mechanical reproduction of art (Benjamin 2008), “The
Culture Industry” argues that industrialization of cultural artifacts—
principally music (see Witkin 2002) and film—totalizes the audience expe
rience, incorporating all possible critique. This is partially due to the tech
nology involved. Since the audience for mass art such as radio and film
cannot “talk back,” these technologies become “democratic” as compared
to the “liberal” telephone which fosters interactivity by its very nature
(95-96; see also Klinenberg and Perrin 2000; Fischer 1994). While the
specific claim—that radio and film cannot allow a way for the audience to
respond—is no longer true (Herbst 1995), the ways in which audience re
sponse has been implemented and channeled bolster the more general
claim that industrialized culture tends to homogenize and “massify” its
audience, thereby neutering potential critique.7 Massification was diag
nosed by Horkheimer and Adorno in “The Culture Industry”: “film . . .
trains those exposed to it to identify film directly with reality.. . . The re
quired qualities of attention have become so familiar from other films and
other culture products already known . . . that they appear automatically.
The power of industrial society is imprinted on people once and for all. . ..
Each single manifestation of the culture industry inescapably reproduces
human beings as what the whole has made them” (Horkheimer and
Adorno 2002, 100). A society is massified to the extent that it is addressed
and, therefore, constituted as an undifferentiated mass audience—the re
sult of a thoroughly industrialized culture industry and a cause of the to
tally socialized society.8
The audience, in turn, must be prepared to receive these messages as
they are sent out, and it is to that problem that Adorno and colleagues
turned in their 1950 survey analysis, The Authoritarian Personality. Co
ordinated through the Survey Research Center at the University of Cali
fornia, Berkeley, The Authoritarian Personality is based on a large-scale
survey and in-depth interviews in which the researchers postulate, identify,
Translators' Introduction — xxii
The progress of a science that is able to develop methods with the help of
which it can register and under some circumstances predict the truly subtle
reactions, opinions, and wishes of people is undeniable. It is also an indisput
able gain that one can check political and economic decisions against the re
actions of the governed. Nevertheless, one should also not fail to recognize
that the convergence of social-scientific methods toward those of the natural
sciences is itself the child of a society that reifies people. The democratic po
tential of the new methods is thus not unquestionable, as is so gladly assumed
particularly in Germany after the suppression of public opinion by the Hitler
regime. It is not incidental that modern “opinion research” grew out of mar
ket and consumer research. It [opinion research] implicitly identifies man
Translators' Introduction — ■ xxiv
under the rubric of consumer. As a result, the diverse tendencies to social con
trol and manipulation that can be observed to derive from modern empirical
sociology in the realm of consumer analysis or “human relations” are not
merely incidental to the method itself. While they [opinion researchers] are
led by the principle of the equality of people and allow no privilege in evalu
ating the attitudes of individual subjects, they nevertheless treat these subjects
as they are constituted by the dominant economic and social relations, with
out examining this constitution itself. The difficulty becomes obvious when
the point is to convey with representative surveys what opinions and mean
ings people have toward questions of general public interest—in other words
as soon as one wants to deal with the problem of so-called public opinion
with the techniques of empirical social research (20-21).
The research design was thus framed as a corrective to, not an indict
ment of, then-current public opinion research. The methodological intro
duction brims with reference to the latest American techniques, including
those in studies by Hadley Cantril, Leonard Doob, Walter Lippmann,
Lazarsfeld, Harold Lasswell, Bernard Berelson, Janowitz, and Kurt Lewin.
These latent, unofficial opinions, Böhm avers, are unsightly but crucial, as
they express the unvarnished political psyche of the research subjects.
Adorno, however, resists assigning pure authenticity to these opinions;
rather, the group method “was meant to call forth real social behavior that
simultaneously reflects and produces ‘public opinion.’ Its medium is the
conversation and the interaction between those who are talking with each
other; official inhibitions (Zensuren) are deactivated, new controls within
the group induced” (Adorno 2010, 200). Thus the study does not actually
claim that the opinions expressed in the focus groups are more authentic
than others. Rather, it pursues a more modest claim: to borrow language
from social science that emerged 40 years later, these opinions are present
in the respondents’ cultural repertoires (see Swidler 2001, 24-25; Tilly
2006) and can therefore be evoked in the presence of particular stimuli
(Merton et al. 1956).
The critique of public opinion research contained in Gruppenexperi
ment begins with Böhm’s colorful metaphor of the “Sunday best.” Opin
ions harvested from individuals by telephone or in-person visits—the
bread and butter of conventional public opinion research—are not false or
bad. They are just partial and situational. Like any other social institution,
and doubly so an institution at the time quickly becoming a taken-for-
granted standard (see Igo 2007), public opinion research deserves to be
studied and understood as a modality within which knowledge and ideas
are generated, as Adorno argued later on in “Opinion Research and Pub-
licness,” also reprinted in this volume:
The current identity of market and opinion research in America, which are
also bound together terminologically in Germany, is, throughout, in the sense
of the observation of common sense, that no radical difference prevails be
tween the preferences for the names of a political candidate and for those of
a brand name, as would be expected according to the theoretical differentia
tion between the autonomous and mature/responsible folk and the surround
ings (Umkreis) of the servitude (Kundenschaft) to mass products. Under this
aspect, opinion research would not be a mere technique, but just as much an
object of sociology as a science that inquires into the objective structural laws
of society (Adorno 2005, 122).
Translators' Introduction xxvi
Mounting the critique of public opinion research required all the tools
in the Frankfurt arsenal: empirical, social-theoretical, philosophical,
even aesthetic as they considered the representative apparatus contained
within techniques of social research. Survey-based public opinion re
search was ascendant at the time, supported both by its affinity with in
dustrial statistics and marketing and by its high-modernist scientific flair
(Converse 1987). It is precisely because this apparatus was so daunting
that the critique is so multifaceted and provides an important point of
connection among the Frankfurt School’s diverse themes. It is also why
the critique is of enduring value now rather than simply of historical
interest.
The first element of the critique has become commonplace since Grup
penexperiment. Essentially, it holds that survey research offers insufficient
opportunity for respondents to express their true beliefs. The authors take
pains to point out that they are not advocating “the conventional organi-
cistic and irrationalistic cliché that surveys would be too mechanistic for
talking about the ostensible totality of the person or of the community”
(Adorno 2010, 200).10 In other words, the authors do not criticize the
closed-choice, reductive nature of survey instruments for painting an in
sufficiently complete picture of their respondents as complete subjects
(see, in this regard, Perrin 2004). But survey research encourages each
respondent to have an opinion, even on matters about which they may
care little and know less. It also implicitly weighs each of these opinions
as equally important, both in comparison to other opinions held by a
given respondent and in comparison to opinions on similar matters held
by other respondents. As the authors point out in their discussion of the
Gruppenexperiment method, these ideas are the products of modern bour
geois society, which creates the opinion environment in which individuals
are set (see also Jepperson 1992, 4). “The concept of public opinion pre
supposes a social organization or group whose members have more or less
the same experiences.” As a result of this principle, Gruppenexperiment
endeavors
the two: “It would be a bad science that sealed itself off against observa
tions that emerge from the material for the sake of the chimera of absolute
proof.”
Chapter i (Chapter I in the original) contains the work’s theoretical and
epistemological critique of standardized public opinion research. The chap
ter begins by acknowledging that polling techniques have a key advantage
over earlier methods. Prior studies had been forced to concentrate on the
ideas and communications of elites because there were no tools for ascer
taining the views of non-elite citizens; polling thus carried a democratic
sensibility in its capacity to represent the views of the non-elite public. After
acknowledging this advantage, though, the chapter then quickly turns to
the limitations on the techniques’ democratic characteristics. This is no
small matter; analysts from George Gallup (Gallup and Rae 1940) to Frank
Newport (Newport 2004) have argued that the public opinion poll is an
inherently democratic instrument because it considers each respondent’s
opinion regardless of social position, a virtue the Group Experiment schol
ars praise as well (see also Igo 2007). But their praise is quickly tempered
by an indictment of social scientific methods as “the child of a society that
confronts men as an ossified reality”—that is, as a totally socialized society
whose totality dominates the subjectively held opinions of its members.
It is a “cliché of the Modern,” the authors of Gruppenexperiment argue,
to assume that all citizens have opinions on all matters—a position ex
plored in much greater detail by Inkeles and Smith (1974) and Jepperson
(1992), apparently without foreknowledge of the Frankfurt work in the
area.15 Beyond the empirical mistake this represents, though, it leads to
“seducing interviewees into . . . accepting stereotypes” instead of articulat
ing authentic opinions. Goaded by the public opinion apparatus into ex
pressing an opinion, interviewees just refract the dominant views of the
society of which they are part. Because of the totally socialized nature of
the opinion environment, “opinion research needs to free itself from the
prejudice that opinions are . . . stable properties of individuals” and, in
stead, “approach as closely as possible the conditions under which actual
opinions are formed, persist, and change.” The critical theorists then pro
pose the focus group study and the railroad compartment metaphor to
allow subjects to discuss and debate important issues without the con
straint of a closed-ended question schema. However, the chapter is at
pains to avoid arguing that this “pilot study” is the be-all and end-all of
social research; rather, it is intended to illuminate the psychodynamic pro
cesses that underlie the overt statements of the participants. Evaluating the
groups’ responses to the Colburn letter provides the material for charac
terizing the groups both qualitatively and quantitatively.
Translators*Introduction ~ xxxi
referring to the speakers, not their speech, an elision made all the more
significant because critics had taken The Authoritarian Personality to task
for a similar confusion (Jahoda 1954; Martin 2001).16 Although the au
thors are at pains to delineate the study as being talk-centered and as fo
cusing on what people can say as opposed to what they will do, at various
places throughout the chapter participants’ statements are called “behav
ior” (Verhaltung). For example, in Chapter 3 we read, “If we register con
cession of complicity as a positive attitude within our frame of reference,
the following groups [those older than 50, those younger than 20, and
women] behaved a little bit more positively than the average.” Speech is, of
course, behavior as well, but it is hard to justify the notion that the partici
pants were behaving as residual Nazis, particularly given that the very
reason for asking the question is that fascism had recently been so very
much more than mere speech. This linguistic slippage, coming as it does in
the midst of overall methodological humility, reveals the underlying con
ceit of the project, which was to demonstrate the remaining potential for
fascist revival in postwar Germany.
Additionally, the similarity among the groups in their attitudes toward the
Eastern Bloc indicates an “impressive example of what one . . . is expected
to say,” and the increase in ambivalence toward Jews among more-educated
participants is taken as evidence for university-educated respondents being
more anti-Semitic. But ambivalence is higher among higher-educated re
spondents for most of the areas—perhaps complexity of thought was
misread as ambivalence in the discussions.
Following the quantitative analysis of Chapter 3 comes the intensive
qualitative analysis in Chapter V in the original, “Guilt and Defense,”
which we have not included here, where our focus is on the theory of pub
lic opinion developed in the Gruppenexperiment rather than on the sub
stantive findings about postwar Germany. Adorno himself wrote the
“Guilt and Defense” essay; it is the only part of Gruppenexperiment at
tributed explicitly to him and included in his collected works. In it, Adorno
traces the participants’ discussion of guilt, and the defensiveness that went
along with it, as the beginning of an arc that culminated in his famous
Ï959-62 lecture/essay, “The Meaning of Working Through the Past” (Adorno
1960). This important intervention in the debate over German guilt and
how—and whether—to “master” the recent past, we argue in the introduc
tion to our companion volume, cannot be adequately understood outside
the context of Gruppenexperiment and the debates that followed it.
Chapter 4 (Chapter VI in the original) takes the material from an en
tirely different angle from the previous chapters.17 Pursuing questions aris
ing from American social science about how groups form, persist, and
Translators' Introduction — xxxiii
exert social control over their members, the chapter uses the transcripts to
illustrate the process of “integration.” It is most concerned with integra
tion in groups that did not exist prior to the experiment—i.e., that were
made up of randomly recruited participants thrown together for this pur
pose. The chapter presents a fictional discussion cobbled together of ex
cerpts from the real discussions. It uses these to illustrate a six-step model
of integration: strangerhood, orientation, adaptation, familiarity, confor
mity, and the fading of the discussion. The importance of the argument
here is less clear than in the earlier chapters. In one sense it is an attempt
to contribute to the general progress of social science; the content, it ar
gues, is secondary to the form of the group integration. The emphasis is on
making connections to American group process social psychology, for ex
ample that of Robert F. Bales (Bales 1950). But paying attention to the
excerpts selected for analysis demonstrates something else as well. The
chapter is a micro-level investigation of the process by which individuals
observe, test, and adopt ideological positions from the opinion environ
ment in which they find themselves. It is, in other words, the micro-macro
link for the book’s theory of totally socialized society.
Nonetheless, the chapter is not limited to an abstract social psychologi
cal investigation of group cohesion. Rather, the authors argue, “it seems as
if the function of the discussion for our participants is more to effect a
certain sociopsychological situation and constellation than to address an
objective question.” Participants’ psychological desire to belong—to con
form to the group—often trumped their desire to express genuine beliefs.
“If this is true, it implies a warning to be cautious about statements of
public opinion. It would be wrong to interpret them according to their
content as the conviction of the speaker, since they are first and foremost
formed by the person’s attachment to a social situation, by the pursuit of
belonging to a collectivity or by bestowing a certain form on it. These mo
tives are more important than rationality, which is often used only in the
service of such aspirations.” As additional proof for the participants’ de
sire to preserve the group, the book notes that even participants who never
spoke during the discussion agreed to have another group discussion. “We
can conclude from this,” the chapter argues, “that the group sessions satis
fied not only the drive for expression, the wish to have an audience, but
also the desire to be part of an audience.”
A reasonable reader could infer from this finding that the focus group
approach is no better than polling and could even be worse. If subjects are
working to please other members of their specific groups, both by saying
what the others expect and by silent acquiescence, why privilege this
group-mediated expression over scientifically gathered poll results? The
Translators' Introduction — xxxiv
had to provoke many to resist; thus the division between the in-group and
the enemy was predetermined by the stimulus. By presenting an outsider,
Sergeant Colburn, in the central function of setting the provocative terms
of the discussion, the experimental design at the same time offered a target
for latent aggression.”
Nevertheless, the theory advanced in Gruppenexperiment is actually con
sistent with much more recent repertoire-based theories of action articulated
by cultural sociologists (see, e.g., Swidler 2001; Lamont and Thévenot 2000;
Perrin 2006). These theories understand cultures as providing a collection of
resources upon which subjects may call to interpret and approach matters
with which they are presented. Cultures differ in the content of these collec
tions, the relative weight of elements in these repertoires, and the elements
that fail to make it into the collective repertoire (Perrin 2005). Thus the prin
cipal finding of Gruppenexperiment is not that ordinary Germans, in 1949,
remained actively fascistic—a claim that would have been both empirically
indefensible and anathema to the dialectical, even anti-essentialist, thinking
that pervades the Frankfurt School’s scholarship both before and after Grup
penexperiment. Rather, the crucial finding is that, given the right social set
ting and linguistic cues, ordinary Germans in the immediate postwar occu
pation were able to enact elements of fascism with distressing ease. Fascist
elements, that is, remained in the postwar Federal Republic’s repertoire, and
subjects were all too ready to wield these tools when pressed. It is precisely
this defense that Adorno raises as the basis of his response to Hofstätter’s
critique:
hoc or even arbitrary. For example, Table 3.1 (table 65 in the original)
lists demographic groups that deviate from the average by 9% or more,
while Tables 3.2 and 3.3 (tables 66 and 67 in the original) used 6 % and
7%, respectively. Similarly, the aggregated system for scoring overall
“positive” versus “negative” attitudes, while not technically wrong, is dif
ficult to interpret because the authors did nothing to standardize the scale.
In other words, the index runs from a minimum of -658 to a maximum
of +292. Scores are presented as numbers along this scale (see Table 3.11
[table 75 in the original]). This makes it difficult to evaluate how positive
or negative a given group is relative to others, since the scale’s midpoint is
not zero.
The analysis is also exclusively bivariate—that is, no attempt is made to
evaluate the ways multiple characteristics of speakers and groups might
interact. While multiple regression—the standard tool for handling such
problems in later social science—had not yet become widely available,
other, simpler techniques could have allowed for such controls had the
researchers’ quantitative sensibilities been stronger. The overall sense one
gets is that the authors were at once taken by the potential for modern
quantitative techniques and deeply suspicious of hypostasizing these
methods—a reality we know to be true from other writings (see, e.g.,
Adorno 1976). For example, in his introductory sociology lectures much
later (1968), Adorno said,
nation of critical bite and fealty to the real world, throughout their postwar
careers. Consider Adorno’s aphorism from “The Essay as Form,” in his
decidedly non-sociological Aesthetic Theory: “Nothing can be interpreted
out of something that is not interpreted into it at the same time” (Adorno
1996, 4-5). This insistence on the creative role of interpretation owes its
meaning to the same socio-Freudian sensibility (for more on that concept,
see Hullot-Kentor 2006, Chapter 1) that underlies more political Frank
furt writings ranging from the writings on Martin Luther Thomas to “The
Stars Down to Earth” and Gruppenexperiment, namely its search for “ob
jectivities.” An essential claim in Gruppenexperiment is that, to oversim
plify it, things are not always as they seem. Citizens interpret into—not
just out of—messages, discussions, experiences, even fictional letters from
foreign soldiers. What people interpret into such messages, then, is what
deserves analysis. Scholars must interpret into their responses through a
depth hermeneutic that reveals the objectivities behind the subjectivities.
This strategy was not new to Gruppenexperiment, of course. But its affin
ity with Frankfurt scholarship from before and after the project estab
lishes the extent to which the empirical portion of the IFS’s agenda was
linked with the rest of the Institute’s work.
Consider, too, the concept of “totally socialized society” (vergesell
schaftete Gesellschaft), which we introduced above. This phrase bears
clear resemblance to earlier Frankfurt work such as The Authoritarian
Personality; but perhaps none so clearly as Dialectic o f Enlightenment, in
whose most commonly read essay (“The Culture Industry”) total sociali
zation by culture disables creative thought. The phrase itself was appar
ently first used in Gruppenexperiment, but it returns elsewhere in Frank
furt writings, sometimes much later. After having introduced it here,
Adorno returned to the concept several times during his career, including
in his introduction to The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology (Adorno
1976, 55; originally written in 1969); in “Culture and Administration”
(Adorno 1978, 101; originally written in i960); in Negative Dialectics
(Adorno 1973, 284; originally written in 1966); and, perhaps most reveal-
ingly, in volume 1 of Notes to Literature (Adorno 1991, 44; originally
written in 1958). Horkheimer, too, had used similar themes, as in his 1947
“Rise and Decline of the Individual” (Horkheimer 1947, 140-141), as did
Herbert Marcuse (e.g., Marcuse 1964) in his diagnosis of the overwhelm
ing power of ambient ideology over individuals.
Translations of vergesellschaftete Gesellschaft have varied somewhat. It
has been rendered as “totally socialized society” (as in Adorno 1976, 55),
“wholly socialized society” (Adorno 1991, 44), and simply “socialized
society” (Adorno 1978,101). The translation offered in Negative Dialectics
Translators' Introduction — xlii
School, the first major publication after the scholars’ return to Germany
has received virtually no attention. This is a major difference with other
works. Indeed, in recent years, even secondary material such as Adorno’s
notes on his dreams (2007) and letters to his parents (2006) have been
translated and published, making the lack of such a generative work as
Gruppenexperiment all the more puzzling. The disappearance of Grup
penexperiment raises three questions. First, why did a major empirical
study, with important theoretical and political implications, carried out by
famous (if controversial) scholars, fail to influence social science research
in the decades that followed? This question may offer insight into a sec
ond, broader question: why has the Frankfurt School been remembered so
much more for its speculative and philosophical work and less for its em
pirical research, which was to have had an equal place at the table accord
ing to Horkheimer’s original program for the IFS? Third, how might post-
war survey research, and the critiques that have emerged since, have been
different had the critique in Gruppenexperiment been more central to sur
vey research’s representational ontology?
As we show in the companion volume to this one, Gruppenexperiment
was not ignored upon its arrival. The response to Hofstätter’s hostile re
view framed Adorno’s postwar approach to the question of guilt. Further
more, this controversy echoed through the later work of the IFS as well as
that of Habermas and Dahrendorf, among others. We can only speculate,
though, as to the reason it retreated so quickly from public and scholarly
attention. One cause, surely, is the increasing specialization of academic
work in the postwar period, such that critical work in the ontology of
public opinion was often strictly separated from the everyday scientific
practice of public opinion research. And since the Frankfurt School was
assigned to the first category (The Authoritarian Personality notwithstand
ing), a large-scale empirical study seems peculiarly out of step with the
work of a group generally believed to have been hostile to empirical re
search altogether.
This view, again, relies on a mistaken understanding of Adorno’s—and,
by extension, the Frankfurt School’s in general—relationship to empirical
work. As noted above, throughout the controversy documented in The
Positivist Dispute in German Sociology and into Adorno’s 1968 lectures
on sociology, the Frankfurt scholars maintained a consistent epistemologi
cal stance. Specifically, they reiterated the approach that critical theory
could exist only in dialogue with observed reality, but that at the same
time the technics of observation themselves worked to shape what was
observed. Indeed, Adorno’s late (1964) acknowledgment of Habermas for
uncovering the critical history and theory of the public sphere highlights
Translators’ Introduction xliv
• The expressivity critique. This critique holds that polling allows for
too little information to flow from the public to the pollster. Citizens
are not allowed to engage in creative or expressive activity, since
their only role is making a choice among a predetermined set of
options. Polling thus changes the state of having an opinion from
being an active decision (expressing an opinion) to a passive one
(having an opinion at the ready when asked). This concern is quite
Translators’ Introduction ~ xlix
References
Abbott, Andrew. 2004. Methods o f Discovery: Heuristics for the Social Sciences.
New York: W. W. Norton.
Ackerman, Bruce, and James S. Fishkin. 2004. Deliberation Day. New Haven,
Conn.: Yale University Press.
Adorno, Theodor W. i960. “Was bedeutet: Aufarbeitung der Vergangenheit.” Radio
Lecture, Hessischer Rundfunk, February 7. In Theodor Adorno, Critical
Models: Interventions and Catchwords. Translated by Henry W. Pickford,
89-103 New York: Columbia University Press, 1998. Also in Theodor Adorno,
Guilt and Defense: On the Legacies o f National Socialism in Postwar Ger
many, 213-227. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press, 2010.
---------. 1968. “Scientific Experiences of a European Scholar in America.” In The
Intellectual Migration: Europe and America, 1930-1960, ed. Donald Fleming
and Bernard Bailyn, 33-70. Cambridge, Mass.: Belknap/Harvard University
Press.
---------. 1970. “Einleitung.” In Emile Durkheim, Soziologie und Philosophie, trans.
Eva Moldenhauer, 7-44. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
---------. 1973. Negative Dialectics. Trans. E. B. Ashton. New York: Continuum.
(Orig. pub. 1966.)
---------. 1976. “Introduction.” In Theodor W. Adorno, Albert Hans, et al., The
Positivist Dispute in German Sociology, trans. Glyn Adey and David Frisby,
1-67. New York: Harper ÔC Row. (Orig. pub. 1969.)
---------. 1977. “Letter to Walter Benjamin, 18 March, 1936.” In Ernst Bloch, Georg
Lukacs, Bertolt Brecht, Walter Benjamin, and Theodor Adorno, Aesthetics and
Politics, ed. and trans. Ronald Taylor, 120-126. London: Verso.
---------. 1978. “Culture and Administration.” Trans. Wes Blomster. Telos 37 (Fall
i 978):93- i i i . (Orig. pub. in German, i960.)
---------. 1982a. Against Epistemology: A Metacritique: Studies in Husserl and the
Phenomenological Antinomies. Trans. Willis Domingo. Cambridge, Mass.:
MIT Press.
Translators' Introduction — ' lit
---------. 1982b. “On the Fetish Character in Music and the Regression of Listen
ing.” In The Essential Frankfurt School Reader, ed. Andrew Arato and Eike
Gebhardt, 270-299. New York: Continuum.
---------. 1991. Notes to Literature. Vol. 1. Trans. Shierry Weber Nicholsen, and ed.
Rolf Tiedemann. New York: Columbia University Press. (Orig. pub. 1958.)
---------. 1994. “The Stars Down to Earth.” In The Stars Down to Earth and Other
Essays on the Irrational in Culture, ed. Stephen Crook, 34-127. New York:
Routledge. Originally published in Telos 19 (Spring 1974): 13-90.
---------. 1996. Aesthetic Theory. Trans, and ed. Robert Hullot-Kentor. Minnea
polis: University of Minnesota Press.
---------. 2000a. Introduction to Sociology. Trans. Christoph Gödde. Stanford:
Stanford University Press.
---------. 2000b. The Psychological Technique o f Martin Luther Thomas ' Radio Ad
dresses. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
---------. 2005. “Opinion Research and Publicness (Meinungsforschung und
Öffentlichkeit).” Trans. and Introduction by Andrew J. Perrin and Lars Jarkko.
Sociological Theory 23 (1): 116-123. (Orig. pub. in German, 1964.)
---------. 2006. Letters to His Parents. Trans. Wieland Hoban, and ed. Christoph
Gödde and Henri Lonitz. New York: Polity.
---------. 2007. Dream Notes. Trans. Rodney Livingstone, and ed. Christoph Gödde
and Henri Lonitz. New York: Polity.
---------. 2010. Guilt and Defense: On the Legacies o f National Socialism in Post
war Germany. Trans, and ed. Jeffrey K. Olick and Andrew J. Perrin. Cam
bridge: Harvard University Press.
Adorno, Theodor W , Else Frenkel-Brunswik, Daniel J. Levinson, and R. Nevitt
Sanford. 1950. The Authoritarian Personality. New York: W. W. Norton.
Adorno, Theodor W , Hans Albert, Ralf Dahrendorf, Harald Pilot, and Karl
Popper. 1976. The Positivist Dispute in German Sociology. Trans. Glyn Adey
and David Frisby. New York: Harper ÔC Row.
Albrecht, Clemens, Günter C. Behrmann, Michael Bock, Harald Homann, and
Friedrich H.Tenbruck. 1999. Die intellektuelle Gründung der Bundesrepublik:
Eine Wirkungsgeschichte der Frankfurter Schule. Frankfurt: Campus Verlag.
Altemeyer, Bob. 1981. Right-Wing Authoritarianism. Winnipeg: University of
Manitoba Press.
Apostolidis, Paul. 1998. “Culture Industry or Social Physiognomy: Adorno’s Cri
tique of Christian Right Radio.” Philosophy and Social Criticism 24 (51:53-84.
---------. 2000. Stations o f the Cross: Adorno and Christian Right Radio. Durham:
Duke University Press.
Austin, John Langshaw (J. L.). 1962. How to Do Things with Words. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Bales, Robert F. 1950. Interaction Process Analysis: A Method for the Study of
Small Groups. Cambridge, Mass.: Addison Wesley.
Benjamin, Walter. 2008. “The Work of Art in the Age of Its Technological Repro
ducibility: Second Version.” In The Work o f Art in the Age o f Its Technological
Reproducibility and Other Writings on Media, ed. Michael W. Jennings, Brigid
Doherty, and Thomas Y. Levin, 19-55. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.
Translators9Introduction ~~ liii
Espeland, Wendy Nelson, and Michael Sauder. 2007. “Rankings and Reactivity:
How Public Measures Recreate Social Worlds.” American Journal o f Sociol
ogy 113 (ι):ι-4θ .
Etzkorn, K. Peter, and Kurt H. Wolff. 1954. “Hans Vogel: The Case Study of a
Young Farmer on a Visit to the United States.” Studies in German-American
Postwar Problems (SGAPP), No. 2. Unpublished manuscript, Department of
Sociology and Anthropology, The Ohio State University, Columbus.
Eulau, Heinz. 1951. “Review: Social Science at the Crossroads.” Antioch Review
i i ( i ) : i i 7- i 28 .
Fields, Karen E. 1995. “Translator’s Introduction: Religion as an Eminently Social
Thing.” In Emile Durkheim, The Elementary Forms o f Religious Life, trans.
Karen E. Fields, xvii-lxxiii. New York: Free Press.
Fischer, Claude S. 1994. America Calling: A Social History o f the Telephone to
1940. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Frankfurt Institute for Social Research. 1956. Aspects of Sociology. Preface by
Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno. Trans. John Viertel. Boston: Bea
con Press.
Fraser, Nancy. 1989. “What’s Critical About Critical Theory? The Case of Haber
mas and Gender.” In Unruly Practices, 113-143. Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press.
Gallup, George, and Saul Forbes Rae. 1940. The Pulse of Democracy: The Public-
Opinion Poll and How It Works. New York: Simon & Schuster.
Gamson, William A. 1992. Talking Politics. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Ginsberg, Benjamin. 1989. “How Polling Transforms Public Opinion.” In Manipu
lating Public Opinion: Essays on Public Opinion as a Dependent Variable, ed.
Michael Margolis and Gary A. Mauser, 271-293. Pacific Grove, Calif.:
Brooks/Cole.
Gitlin, Todd. 1978. “Media Sociology: The Dominant Paradigm.” Theory and So
ciety 6 (2):205-253.
Greenberg, Stanley B., and Theda Skocpol. 1997. The New Majority: Toward a
Popular Progressive Politics. New Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
Habermas, Jürgen. 1968. Knowledge and Human Interests. Trans. Jeremy J. Shap
iro. Boston: Beacon Press.
---------. 1989. The Structural Transformation o f the Public Sphere: An Inquiry into
a Category of Bourgeois Society. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. (Orig. pub.
1962.)
---------. 2006. “Political Communication in Media Society: Does Democracy Still
Enjoy an Epistemic Dimension? The Impact of Normative Theory on Empiri
cal Research.” Communication Theory 16:411-426.
Habermas, Jürgen, Ludwig von Friedeburg, Chrisoph Oehler, and Friedrich Weltz.
1961. Student und Politik: Eine soziologische Untersuchung zum politischen
Bewußtsein Frankfurter Studenten. Neuwied am Rhein, Germany:
Luchterhand.
Held, David. 1980. Introduction to Critical Theory: Horkheimer to Habermas.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Translators*Introduction — Iv
Herbst, Susan. 1995. “On Electronic Public Space: Talk Shows in Theoretical Per
spective.” Political Communication 12:263-274.
Herzog, Hertha. 1941. “On Borrowed Experience: An Analysis of Listening to
Daytime Sketches.” Studies in Philosophy and Social Science 9 (i):65-95.
---------. 1944. “What Do We Really Know About Daytime Serial Listeners?” In
Radio Research: 1942-1943, ed. Paul F. Lazarsfeld and Frank N. Stanton,
3-33. New York: Duell, Sloan, and Pearce.
Hofstätter, Peter. 1963a. “Bewältigte Vergangenheit?” Die Zeit June 14. Available
at http://www.zeit.de/1963/24/Bewaeltigte-Vergangenheit (accessed July 6,
2010).
---------. 1963b. “Was verspricht man sich vom Schulfach Zeitgeschichte?” Die Zeit
June 21. Available at http://www.zeit.de/1963/25/Was-verspricht-man-sich
-vom-Schulfach-Zeitgeschichte (accessed July 6, 2010).
Horkheimer, Max. 1947. “Rise and Decline of the Individual.” In Eclipse o f Rea
son, 128-161. New York: Oxford University Press.
---------. 1972. Critical Theory: Selected Essays. New York: Continuum.
Horkheimer, Max, and Theodor W. Adorno. 2002. Dialectic of Enlightenment.
Trans. Edmund Jephcott. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press. (Orig.
pub. as Dialektik der Aufklärung, 1947.)
Hullot-Kentor, Robert. 2006. Things Beyond Resemblance: Essays on Theodor W.
Adorno. New York: Columbia University Press.
Igo, Sarah E. 2007. The Averaged American: Surveys, Citizens, and the Making of
a Mass Public. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Inkeles, Alex, and David Horton Smith. 1974. Becoming Modern: Individual
Change in Six Developing Countries. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University
Press.
Institut für Sozialforschung. 1936. Studien über Autorität und Familie. Paris:
Alcan.
Jacobs, Lawrence R., and Robert Y. Shapiro. 2000. Politicians Don’t Pander: Politi
cal Manipulation and the Loss o f Democratic Responsiveness. Chicago: Uni
versity of Chicago Press.
Jäger, Lorenz. 2004. Adorno: A Political Biography. Trans. Stewart Spencer. New
Haven, Conn.: Yale University Press.
Jahoda, Marie, ed. 1954. Studies in the Scope and Method of The Authoritarian
Personality. Glencoe, 111.: Free Press.
Jay, Martin. 1973. The Dialectical Imagination: A History o f the Frankfurt
School and the Institute o f Social Research, 1923-19jo . Boston: Little,
Brown.
---------. 1984. Marxism and Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukâcs to
Habermas. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Jenemann, David. 2007. Adorno in America. Minneapolis: University of Minne
sota Press.
Jepperson, Ronald L. 1992. “National Scripts: The Varying Construction of Indi
vidualism across the Modern Nation-States.” Ph.D. diss., Yale University.
Jepperson, Ronald L., and Ann Swidler. 1994. “What Properties of Culture Should
We Measure?” Poetics 22 (4):359-371·
Translators* Introductum Ivi
Mendelberg, Tali. 2002. “The Deliberative Citizen: Theory and Evidence.” Re
search in Micropolitics 6:151-193.
Merritt, Anna J. and Richard L. Merritt, eds. 1970. Public Opinion in Occupied
Germany: The OMGUS Surveys, 1945-1949. Urbana: University of Illinois
Press.
---------, eds. 1980. Public Opinion in Semisovereign Germany: The HICOG Sur
veys, 1949-1955. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.
Merritt, Richard L. 1995. Democracy imposed: U.S. Occupation Policy and the
German Public, 1945-1949. New Haven: Yale University Press.
Merton, Robert K., Marjorie Fiske, and Patricia L. Kendall. 1956. The Focused
Interview: A Manual o f Problems and Procedures. Glencoe, 111.: Free Press.
Morgan, David L. 1997. Focus Groups as Qualitative Research. 2nd ed. Newbury
Park, Calif.: Sage.
Mutz, Diana C. 2006. Hearing the Other Side: Deliberative versus Participatory
Democracy. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Neumann, Franz. 1953. “The Social Sciences.” In The Cultural Migration: The Eu
ropean Scholar in America, ed. Franz Neumann et al., 4-26. Philadelphia:
University of Pennsylvania Press.
Newport, Frank. 2004. Polling Matters: Why Leaders Must Listen to the Wisdom
o f the People. New York: Warner Books.
Noelle-Neumann, Elizabeth. 1984. The Spiral O f Silence: Public Opinion— Our
Social Skin. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Nowotny, Stefan. 2003. “The Condition of Becoming Public.” Transversal: Real
Public Spaces (September). Trans. Aileen Derieg. Available at www.eipcp.net/
transversal/1203/nowotny/en (accessed June 10, 2010).
Olick, Jeffrey K. 2005. In the House of the Hangman: The Agonies o f German
Defeat, 1945-1949. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
---------. 2007. “Collective Memory and Nonpublic Opinion: An Historical Note
on a Methodological Controversy about a Political Problem.” Symbolic Inter
action 30 (i):4 i-5 5 .
Olick, Jeffrey K, and Andrew J. Perrin. 2010. “Introduction.” In Theodor W.
Adorno, Guilt and Defense: On the Legacies o f National Socialism in Postwar
Germany, trans, and ed. Jeffrey K. Olick and Andrew J. Perrin, 3-42. Cam
bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Osborne, Thomas, and Nikolas Rose. 1999. “Do the Social Sciences Create Phe
nomena? The Example of Public Opinion Research.” British Journal of Sociol
ogy 50 (3>:367- 396·
Page, Benjamin, and Robert Y. Shapiro. 1992. The Rational Public: Fifty Years of
Trends in Americans’ Policy Preferences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Paley, Julia. 2001. Marketing Democracy: Power and Social Movements in Post-
Dictatorship Chile. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Perrin, Andrew J. 2004. “Who’s Afraid of Linear Regression?” Newsletter of the
Sociology o f Culture Section 18 (3)11. Available at www.ibiblio.org/culture/
newsletter-archive/cult183.pdf (accessed June 10, 2010).
---------. 2005. “Political Microcultures: Linking Civic Life and Democratic Citi
zenship.” Social Forces 84:2 (December): 1049-1082.
Translators' Introduction — ’ Iviii
---------. 2006. Citizen Speak: The Democratic Imagination in American Life. Chi
cago: University of Chicago Press.
Perrin, Andrew J., and Katherine McFarland. 2008. “The Sociology of Political
Representation and Deliberation.” Sociology Compass 2 (4)11128-1244.
Perrin, Andrew J., and Stephen B. Vaisey. 2008. “Parallel Public Spheres: Distance
and Discourse in Letters to the Editor.” American Journal o f Sociology 114
( 3 ):7 8 i - 8 io.
Pickford, Henry W. 1997. “Critical Models: Adorno’s Theory and Practice of Cul
tural Criticism.” Yale Journal o f Criticism 10 (2)1247-270.
Plessner, Monika. 1991. “Miteinander reden heißt miteinander träumen: Grup
penstudie mit Horkheimer.” Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung Nr. 226, vom 28.
Pollock, Friedrich. 1955. Gruppenexperiment: Ein Studienbericht. Frankfurter Be
iträge zur Soziologie, Nr. 2. Frankfurt: Europäische Verlagsanstalt.
---------. 1976. “Empirical Research into Public Opinion.” In Critical Sociology:
Selected Readings, trans. Thomas Hall, and ed. Paul Connerton, 225-236.
New York: Penguin.
“Proposal for the Reopening of the Institute of Social Research at the University
of Frankfort [sic] on Main.” 1949. American Sociological Review
14:681-682.
Roth, Guenther, and Kurt H. Wolff. 1954. “The American Denazification of Ger
many: A Historical Survey and an Appraisal.” Studies in German-American
Postwar Problems (SGAPP), No. 1. Unpublished manuscript, Department of
Sociology and Anthropology, The Ohio State University, Columbus.
Sasson, Theodore. 1995. Crime Talk: How Citizens Construct a Social Problem.
New York: Aldine de Gruyter.
Sawyer, R. Keith. 2001. “Emergence in Sociology: Contemporary Philosophy of
Mind and Some Implications for Sociological Theory.” American Journal of
Sociology 107:3 (November): 551-85.
Schudson, Michael. 2006. “The Troubling Equivalence of Citizen and Con
sumer.” Annals o f the American Academy o f Political and Social Science
608:193-204.
Schweppenhäuser, Gerhard. 2009. Theodor W. Adorno: An Introduction. Trans.
James Rolleston. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press.
Shibutani, Tamotsu. 1952. Review of The Authoritarian Personality. American
Journal of Sociology 57 (5): 5 27-5 29.
Sniderman, Paul M., and Thomas Piazza. 1993. T/?e Scar of Race. Cambridge,
Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Stendenbach, F. J. 1964. “Sociology in Germany since 1945.” Social Science Infor
mation 3:7-51.
Stern, Frank, and William Templer. 1992. The Whitewashing o f the Yellow Badge:
Antisemitism and Philosemitism in Postwar Germany. New York: Pergamon
Press.
Sunstein, Cass R. 2000. “Deliberative Trouble?: Why Groups Go to Extremes.”
Yale Law Journal 110 (1)71-119.
Swidlei; Ann. 2001. Talk of Love: How Culture Matters. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Translators' Introduction — lix
N otes
16. Although the Jahoda volume containing these critiques did not come out until
1954, when Gruppenexperiment was nearly complete, similar criticisms had
circulated since the original publication of The Authoritarian Personality.
While the book was generally reviewed positively upon its release, a recurring
concern was the question of the stability and ontological reality of the authori
tarian “types” it identified (Bunzel 1950; de Grazia 1950; Eulau 1951; Lass-
well 1951; Shibutani 1952).
17. Wiggershaus (1994, 473) attributes Chapter 4 to Volker von Hagen, an associ
ate of the IFS at the time. While Gruppenexperiment’s preface credits von Ha
gen with writing a monograph, it does not link him specifically to Chapter 4.
18. A similar point, though made in very different form, can be found in Victor
Klemperer’s LTI (Klemperer 2000), written in the mid-193os but first pub
lished in 1946.
19. Hofstätter’s review, and Adorno’s reply, appear in the companion volume
(Adorno 2010).
20. On the latter concern, see Schudson 2006 for a thoughtful corrective.
Group Experiment
and Other Writings
Foreword
FRANZ B Ö H M
R ously admiring and being puzzled by it. Which aspects are admirable
and which are puzzling?
Well, this report compiles prevalent opinions about certain particular
questions, for example, about guilt for what happened in the Third Reich,
about democracy, about the Jewish question, etc. Before we are shown the
findings of these surveys, we are informed about how the Institute for So
cial Research’s working group went about the project, which was aimed at
determining what opinions are in circulation and which groups tend to
hold which of these opinions—whether one aggregates the groups or
whether one distinguishes them from each other, for example, the young
and the old, the college-educated and not, the urban and the rural, those
who were in the war for just a few years and those who were in it for
many years, housewives, unskilled workers, white collar workers, inde
pendent business men, the self-employed, etc. We learn how the surveys
themselves were conducted in such a way that the respondents could ex
press themselves candidly and without inhibitions. In short, the entire ex
perimental design is spread open before us so that we are in a position to
form our own impression of how conclusive the results are.
What is admirable is this account of the methods used, the actual devel
opment of a new method for interviewing, [and] the intellectual effort that
was involved in the investigation of the results. For researchers working
Group Experiment and Other Writings — - 2
* The Erd-Geist (spirit of the earth), which we render with “gnome,” refers to Goethe’s
Faust, volume I.—Eds.
Foreword — ’ 3
have I not been forced to hear .. . what fierce, uncurbed defiance! And were
this spirit universal—
Friend, friend!
O! this is worse, far worse, than we had suffered
Ourselves to dream of at Vienna. There
We saw it only with a courtier’s eyes,
Eyes dazzled by the splendor of the throne.
We had not seen the war-chief, the commander,
The man all-powerful in his camp. Here, here,
‘Tis quite another thing.
Here is no emperor more”1
What is it then in reading the investigation at hand that evokes this shock?
I suggest that there are two things.
First, it is the more than clear perception that alongside so-called “pub
lic opinion,” which expresses itself in elections, referenda, public speeches,
newspaper articles, radio broadcasts, party and group programs, parlia
mentary discussions, and political assemblies, there is non-public opinion,
whose content can differ considerably from the content of public opinion.
Its sentences, however, circulate alongside those of public opinion like the
coins of a second currency; in fact, they may even be more durable and
stable than actual public opinion, which we flaunt like a courtier before
the official public, especially to foreign countries, and which we pride our
selves as being our actual and sole opinion, as if they expressed what we
actually mean even though they are really only the things we say when
wearing our Sunday best. Yes, it almost seems as if what circulates among
us as public opinion represents the sum of opinions (in themselves contra
dictory) we wish people believed we had as our real opinion, while non
public opinion is the sum of (in themselves equally contradictory) opin
ions we truly have.*
The second shocking thing is the more than clear description of what
non-public opinion actually looks like. It was exactly what many of us
actually think!
In other words, one shock comes from the perception that we have two
opinion-currencies, each of which comprises a whole bundle of different
opinions. And the other shock befalls us at the sight of the values that
make up the unofficial currency.
* Böhm here deviates from the epistemological position staked out in Adorno’s discussion
elsewhere (Adorno 2010, 200) by suggesting that non-public opinion is more authentic than
public opinion. Adorno’s position takes a more situational approach.—Eds.
Group Experiment and Other Writings — ' 4
This latter shock raises the uneasy question of whether it can be justified
to disclose to the public a scientific investigation into the quality, quantity,
and circulatory speed of unofficial opinion-currencies. Could such a publi
cation not harm our prestige, our good political and social reputation? Is
there not a great danger that such a publication could do damage if mis
takes were made in the scientific investigation of unofficial opinion? Should
one wash the dirty laundry of one’s questionable opinion completely in
open in front of the entire domestic and international public? Does it not
just boil down to a denunciation if one reveals these actually circulating
opinions, which are not even allowed—presumably deliberately— into the
inventory of a nation’s official public opinion? Should one not keep the re
sults of scientific research of such a nature secret, that is, merely pass them
on to the government, away from the public? And how do things stand
with the Parliament? Is not promulgation to the parliament tantamount to
public disclosure?
Just to pose these questions is to reject them. In a liberal state, what is
going on among the people and in society must be known openly. The only
concerns that legitimately require secrecy are in the sphere of government
planning, such as the date a currency reform will be put into effect or cer
tain diplomatic negotiations. In these cases the government has to answer,
so to speak, for its actions, but need not disclose the preparations and
bases for the decision in statu nascendi.
Secondly, it would be more than foolish to conceal something that any
visitor traveling to Germany, every tourist or journalist, can hear shouted
from every rooftop if he only pays a little attention. If this visitor now notes
that such overt issues are officially hidden from the outside or are treated as
secret, even by science, then the effect is even worse than that created by the
most unfavorable consequence of knowledge of the fact itself. Thirdly, it
plainly violates the task and ethos of science to conceal findings. Tactical
and diplomatic considerations have no place in science. And, fourthly, one
can no longer speak of a liberal constitution where there is no longer a
lively belief that frank talk and self-expression, discussion itself, is a remedy
for all kinds of public damages. If the people themselves, if even science
retreats behind the curtain behind which “top secret” governance takes
place and “prescribed terminology” rules, then we have taken a step from a
free and open society to an organized army of “political soldiers.” This is
true even though no totalitarian state is imminent; this would require a
second aspect, namely an ice cold stratum of associates with the talent,
brutality, and willpower required to play on such a wicked organ.
It is, thus, imperative to make the non-public opinion of a people an
object of public political and scientific discourse. In this way, non-public
Foreword ~ j
and requires it to prosper. And second, it assumes that the opinions mak
ing up non-public opinion are original creations of the thoughts and ef
forts of the people, i.e., of the entire nation. Both of these are errors.
The faithful of non-public opinions are anything but shy and reticent.
They are by all means inclined to articulate their opinions in a highly pro
vocative manner or to state them to others’ faces with smoothly penetrat
ing urgency, if the environment is such that they need not be bashful. The
merit of experimental sociology is not simply that it investigates, that is to
say extracts, these opinions from the people at all (indeed the interviewees
happily made friends with the tape recorders and spoke quite willingly
into them). Rather, the merit lies in the establishment of the concrete form
of this non-public opinion, in the insight into some of its core structures
and typical views, which distinguish particular selected groups.
Nevertheless, it is also a mistake to assume that this treasure trove of
non-public opinions is a creation of the national spirit, as for instance in
the development of language, fairy tales, common law, sayings and similar
manifestations of folk wit and wisdom. One need only consult this report
to see that, with enough time, people believe and assert all sorts of differ
ent things. These are not expressions of the thoughts and feelings of ordi
nary people trying in their own way to orient themselves in the complex
whirl of events and relationships in a modern industrial nation and a mod
ern constitutional state. Rather, these are, almost without exception, dis
carded clothing from the wardrobe of maxims, slogans, and idea scraps of
an age of industry and of science, deformations of real coins of opinion
that once had official value and then, on the way from barroom discus
sions and miscellaneous forms of political hot air, made their way into the
ordinary vocabulary of discussions within families, with children, and with
colleagues. It is a body of thought that over a greater or lesser period of
time has been run through the mills of a kind of intellectual and emotional
assembly line until it took a cookie-cutter form*among those who not only
refuse reflection but who have a downright marked aversion for those of
their fellow citizens who feel the need for such reflection. Moreover, many
of these opinions refer not to judgments about facts and events but to the
content of these facts and events themselves. The people do not want to
know how Frenchmen, Americans, Russians, etc. are or think, what the
occupying powers did, what happened in Hitler’s concentration camps,
etc. Instead, they have a preconceived and surely thoroughly false opinion
about this and fight tooth and nail against learning the plain truth. They
also do not accept any instruction on these facts. In general they do not
form their judgments starting with facts, but they turn around the facts so
as to fit their preconceived judgments. Some of them even know this, but
consider it a virtue in accordance with the principle that objectivity is a
sign of decadence. Here we have, for example, one of those maxims typical
of the treasure trove of non-public opinions. A very large proportion of
them have a pronouncedly Machiavellian character, that is, the character
of a lesson and a mode of thought that were originally in no way popular,
but instead were the modes of thought of renaissance courts, masters, and
conquerors who could not care less about individual suffering and the fate
of people who occupied social spheres below the aristocratic level. Here we
have a master mentality, a master mentality of the crudest and most heart
less sort, that has spread to every Tom, Dick, and Harry over the course of
centuries.
The reader will notice another very strange thing in this report. Namely
this: how ineffectively actual public opinion bounced off the hearts and
minds of a very large proportion of our population. Most of these people
read their newspaper every day and listened to the daily radio broadcasts,
which exposed them to this public opinion. Not even continuous repeti
tion in the years after the war was able to demolish the non-public opin
ion, which was supplied in a completely different manner, even though
neither the press, nor radio, nor parliamentary debates, nor party meetings
were at its disposal. Only in the editorial department wastebaskets did the
mostly anonymous expressions of non-public opinion accumulate into
significant piles; and they were—quite rightly—thrown into the trash and
did not reach the publicity channels for transmission of official opinion. So
there must be other more effective channels through which non-public
opinions course. These channels probably consist of discussions in fami
lies, in train cars, and among colleagues, among which family discussions
seem to me to be by far the most important ones. For the thought of par
ents imprints itself indelibly onto children, and the prejudices that fathers
express emphatically at the table sound like venerable wisdom to their
children’s ears. Even if the children later recognize the error, they still feel
hurt again, in memory of the beloved authority, when such opinions are
sharply criticized in their presence. I myself remember quite well the flood
of prejudices and overwhelmingly hateful maxims with which I was show
ered by 6-year-old fellow pupils in my first school days. Most of these
children and their parents were thoroughly good-natured children and adults
throughout, but their views were despicable, and I took away quite a shock
at the time.
Group Experiment and Other Writings — ’ 8
Two problems arise in this context: What are the prospects for the better
refined perspectives of actual public opinion to prevail over the poorly
washed and often articulated noxious perspectives of non-public opinion?
And what are the chances, in turn, that the poorly washed perspectives of
non-public opinion will finish off the better refined public opinion along with
the group that works honestly on its behalf and on its further refinement?
I want to close with that question. What was merely intended to be a
preface has become the improvised cry for help of a reader who was all
too profoundly impacted by the reading, and who has not yet succeeded in
processing his impressions.
Introduction
opinion formation. By the same token, the group investigation shares two
traits with the experiment. The participants are not simply observed in
their everyday context, but are brought together specifically for the purpose
of the study. The group investigation, in particular, works with a standard
ized “basic stimulus” and a series of similarly standardized arguments and
counter arguments in order to ensure comparability between the individual
sessions.
Our research design was guided by the experience that a study only
yields productive results if one reflects on the process and allows it to
change over the course of the research. Insofar as our research aim was
social-psychological—that is, related to how socially relevant behavior
comes about within individuals—this study was based on depth psychol
ogy in the Freudian sense. Freud accepted the characteristic collective be
havioral patterns worked out by authors such as Le Bon and McDougall,
but did not base them on an independent group-subject; instead he derived
psychological mass phenomena from the psychodynamic of individuals
within the group. Identification with the collective as such is the decisive
mechanism. Our material contains a surfeit of evidence for the power of
such mechanisms of identification.4
The study builds upon American investigations, including our own re
search on prejudice,5 which in many cases shed light on social phenomena
with the help of Freudian categories. Like these investigations, the group
experiment does not use psychoanalytic ideas only in its design. Its find
ings also confirm psychoanalytic statements. We found evidence for mech
anisms like projection, reaction formation, repressed feelings of guilt, etc.,
all of which belong to the zone of defense of the unconscious by the ego.
Furthermore, we constantly came upon examples of subjective opinion
and opinion formation that literally called for such concepts due to their
contradiction of objective reality and their irrational character. They es
sentially demanded psychoanalytic interpretation.
The interpretive problems only became completely clear after the dis
cussions themselves were finished and the transcripts were available. Just
one of the many questions we had to face was how to quantify spontane
ous, essentially qualitative material at all.6 The quantitative part of this
report shows how we tried to answer this problem. Even weightier was the
question of how to consider free, qualitative categories rather than mate
rial that was already coded and categorized. One has to expect objections
such as “reading things into the material” and “subjective arbitrariness.”
Today, such objections are so automatic that they often lead—in contrast
to their original critical, antidogmatic impulse—to a prohibition on think
ing (Denkverbot). The whole area that Max Weber called understanding
Introduction ~ 13
would be a bad science that seals itself off from what emerges out of the
material for the sake of a chimera of absolute provability. We are by no
means blind to the fact that a shadow of relativity clings just as much to the
quantitative as well as the qualitative interpretations: there the inevitable
residues of rigid computational methods do incomplete justice to the life of
the discussions and the meaning of individual statements; here the danger
that the idea overshoots what the facts support according to the relevant
interpretive norms, which demand the verifiability of every intellectual op
eration through every other researcher in the same discipline.
The question of validity of interpretation is inseparable from the rela
tionship between quantitative and qualitative analyses. The more qualita
tive material and qualitative interpretation comes to the forefront due to
the special question of the investigation, the more urgent it becomes to
check the qualitative findings in a quantitative way if at all possible; or, in
the face of the limits we faced statistically in this regard, at least to point
out possibilities for such an examination. Obviously, the more statements
that can be extracted from a case, the more possible it is for the qualitative
analysis to draw conclusions beyond the individual case.
By the same token, it would be futile in the case of our material to con
duct the quantitative analysis without the qualitative categories of under
standing. By using techniques such as the elaboration of a codebook that
was highly differentiated qualitatively for the quantitative examination,
the attempt was made—following American efforts—not only to let quan
titative and qualitative methods complement one another, but to unify
them to a certain degree. We are, of course, aware that the basic divergences,
from which our considerations emanate, also remain to date unresolved by
such attempts, if they can be resolved at all. Statistically this problem takes
the form of the problem that, in the case of qualitatively rich research instru
ments, the resulting numbers for each individual category are so small that
they can hardly be assigned any relevance. A theoretically sufficient, qualita
tively defined matrix of categories for quantification makes virtually impos
sible the generalization on behalf of which one originally undertook the
quantification, and leads one right back to qualitative analysis again. Hence,
in the final report, we maintained a separation between the quantitative and
qualitative parts, and indicated their relationship only occasionally.
The relationship between quantitative and qualitative examination con
stitutes only one aspect of a broader problem, which is actually the deci
sive problem for the value of this research. That is the question of how far
one may generalize the findings. Let it be emphatically highlighted here
that the numerical findings, taken in isolation, must not make any claim to
validity beyond our circle of participants. In the text there will be several
Introduction — 15
AIM, M E T H O D S , A N D
CIRCLE OF PARTICIPANTS
C H A P T E R O N E
I. Theoretical Preliminaries
i. Subject and Method o f Empirical Sociology
During the last two decades, sociology has experienced an extraordinary
upsurge due to the systematic development and refinement of its methods
of data collection. Sociology today lays claim to assertions about subjects
that were previously left largely to theoretical construction or even non
committal speculation. This is particularly true of research on the opin
ions, attitudes, and behavioral patterns of large groups or the total popu
lation. It is supposedly possible to ascertain reliably not only objective
social conditions but also the ways people respond to them.1 Based on
this, the hope arises of understanding modern industrial mass society bet
ter by adopting an epistemic paradigm modeled on the exact sciences and
thereby approaching a practical solution to established problems between
man and his society.
Social scientists of all disciplines and practitioners from all areas of the
economy, administration, and social welfare have been extraordinarily im
pressed by the accomplishments of modern data collection methods. By set
ting strict boundaries on researchers’ idiosyncrasies and prejudices by con
fronting them with facts, these methods also contain a democratic potential
compared with old-school sociology such as institutional analysis. Every
body counts equally in sampling techniques. This opens up the possibility
Group Experiment and Other Writings -— 20
* The reference is to Max Weber’s emphasis on Verstehen (understanding) as the basis for
sociological analysis as compared with other, principally Marxian, concerns with objective,
systemic analysis. See Max Weber, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociol
ogy, ed. Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1978),
vol. i, pp. 8 -1 1. —Eds.
The Group Discussion Method — z i
ing this constitution itself. The difficulty becomes obvious when the point
is to convey with representative surveys what opinions and meanings
people have toward questions of general public interest—in other words
as soon as one wants to deal with the problem of so-called public opinion
with the techniques of empirical social research.
Individual Opinion and Public Opinion Under the old paradigm it was
by no means beyond dispute that one could determine reliably what public
opinion toward certain questions was. Today, on the other hand, it is as
sumed that public opinion can be elicited and measured everywhere.3 We
put trust in a standardized technique. Interviewers from polling institutes
pose a number of questions to a statistically representative cross-section of
the population. The answers obtained are grouped according to their con
tent and analyzed in relation to objective characteristics of the respon
dents. The findings are then presented in tabular form and interpreted as
public opinion. Depending on the method applied and the size of the sta
tistical cross-section, public opinion is considered reliably ascertained within
a set margin of error.4 The problem of the concept of public opinion is
hardly considered. Instead, it is simply postulated as known by stating the
percentage of the sample—and, hence, of the entire population for which
the sample is representative—that answered a question in one way or
another. Yet the legitimacy of this procedure obviously depends on the
concept of public opinion itself. The problem is only elided, not solved, by
simply tailoring the definition beforehand to match the possible results of
sample polls.
Even the concept of individual opinion poses considerable difficulties,
and would have to be clarified in order to understand the concept of pub
lic opinion in a concise way. Traditionally, “opinion” refers to the contents
of a person’s consciousness, without judgment as to its truth or untruth. If
a person believes that two times two equals four, that is his opinion just as
if he believes that two times two equals five. Both types of judgment, how
ever, differ not only in their objective content (which is independent of
opinion), but also in their internal structure. Only one of these judgments
contains an adequate relation to the facts. The act of holding an opinion
varies accordingly; in the first case it is an actual synthesis, a logically
legitimate evaluation of experience. In the second case psychological, if not
outright pathological, determinants prevail. The concept of opinion under
lying opinion research does not account for this difference. The relation of
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 22
consciousness to objectivity does not come to the fore. Beliefs are treated
as if they are final, not traceable to a deeper source of legitimacy. In fact,
the individual’s thinking-in-that-way really depends on aspects of what is
thought that are not reducible to the subjectivity of opinion holding. Com
mon opinion research’s concept of opinion, which deems itself to be scien
tifically devoid of assumptions, actually presupposes a nominalistic episte
mology. It operates with a subjective concept of truth,5 without even
targeting the problem of objectivity at all. The much-heralded objectivity
of this concept is nothing but a generality aggregated from these subjec
tivities, the common denominator of the opinions irrespective of their
objective coherence.
But the concept of opinion is not problematic merely because it cannot
actually separate opinion from truth. Indeed, the assumption of the exis
tence of an opinion of every individual is questionable. That everyone pos
sesses his own opinion is a cliché of the Modern. In earlier social epochs,
the spiritual cosmos was, on the one hand, much too strongly constructed
and strictly controlled for everyone to be able to have or to have been able
to develop a private opinion about everything—the expression itself is
specifically liberal; on the other hand, the information and communica
tions possibilities were too limited for the overwhelming majority of peo
ple to have been in the situation to have an opinion about everything
imaginable. Today, when in the large industrial states information about
nearly everything is widespread, the mass of informational material has
grown to such an extent with the complexity of all social relations that it
is even difficult for the expert himself to form an opinion about everything
in his own most narrow field. The oft-lamented indifference of the demo
cratic individual toward public issues might come in part from his feeling
powerless in this respect, from his not having enough time, energy, or
schooling to familiarize himself with the data necessary to form an opin
ion. Insofar as opinion research proceeds from the assumption that one
has to have an opinion about everything, it succumbs to the danger of
misleading people in its interviews to statements about which they have no
real conviction, which are not even their opinions.6 Exactly this contradic
tion between being compelled to have an opinion and being incapable of
doing so misleads numerous individuals into accepting stereotypes. These
relieve them of the futile effort to opine, but, nonetheless, bestow upon
them the prestige of joining in.7 This contradiction proves effective in the
discussion of general questions across all social strata. In any case, modern
means of transportation and communication have generally facilitated the
formation of opinions, no matter how they come into being. Precisely be
cause of the immeasurably increased possibilities for communication,
The Group Discussion Method 23
* French in the original, translated as “the general will” or “the will of the people” (volo
nté générale) and “the will of all” (volonté de tous). See J. J. Rousseau, The Social Contract
and Discourses, trans. G. D. H. Cole and J. M. Dent (London: Everyman, 1913), p. 203; and
Rousseau, On the Social Contract, trans. Donald A. Cress (Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987),
p. 31.—Eds.
The Group Discussion Method — 25
force and power must be distinguished sharply and clearly from the pub
licly articulated aggregation of multiple contradictory tendencies.16 The
conception of public opinion as analog to the volonté de tous is based on
a model of a purely competitive society. Everybody is supposed to enter
social life as if he has nothing but his own mind and to proceed to form his
views as an autonomous being. However, just as homo oeconomicus en
ters competition with far more than the diligence of his own hands, the
judging intellect is far from a tabula rasa. From early on every individual
carries with him a group of uncountable views, mostly solidified by the
dominant intellectual climate and accepted without thought. Later on,
the individual is subject to the pressure of this same intellectual climate,
the more so since resistance against it requires a strength of ego few can
muster. Individual opinions, which appear to be the elementary* particles
of standard opinion research, are in truth highly derivative and mediated.
What was initially introduced here as “intellectual climate”—German
classical philosophy calls it the “objective spirit”—actually predates indi
vidual opinions. This is not some speculative construction but an effect of
the tangible domination of the economic and social apparatus of produc
tion over consumption—including over supposedly intellectual consump
tion. This domination—and not a gestalt-theoretical organic conception—
stands behind the “entirety” of public opinion, behind the Tönnian “unitary
power”17 which other authors have identified as a collective factor or
group opinion with its own independent existence.18 While it is borne by
the individuals and based upon their thinking and feeling, it is not built up
from their individual opinions. Rather, it confronts every individual as
something already preformed, solidified, and often overwhelmingly pow
erful. Making public opinion into a kind of intellectual “thing in itself” is
only the reflection of a social state in which the individual experiences
conditions as autonomous, forcing him to adapt to them.
True public opinion would epitomize this objective spirit, mirroring the
social conditions and tendencies of power, the gestalt characteristic of the
entire society. Since this consciousness exists above the heads of all indi
viduals, it does not mesh with each individual’s consciousness; in fact, it
contradicts that of many. In their attitudes and opinions it is modified,
sometimes changed beyond all recognition by the whim of individual intel
lectual fate. Nonetheless, public opinion exists objectively, an expression of
* The reference is to elementary in the Durkheimian sense, that is, as an elementary par
ticle. See Durkheim, Elementary Forms of Religious Life (New York: Free Press, 1995); see
also Fields’ “Translators Introduction” thereto, pp. lix-lxi.—Eds.
Group Experiment and Other Writings 26
social totality; at the same time, though, it is also an expression of the so
cial facts* washing over the individual.
This conception of public opinion is attached to the dominant relations
of power in society. Yet this fact is not acknowledged by an empirical and
positivistic science incessantly appealing to “facts.” It is often conceded
that public opinion has a supra-individual character. Public opinion re
searchers acknowledge that traditional ideas, feelings, thoughts, customs,
and behavioral patterns exist in public and continuously mold people’s
opinions. They also do not deny the interrelations between individuals and
these institutional powers of intellect, nor among individuals themselves.
Yet, in the end, they call public opinion the sum of individual opinions re
sulting from all these processes of influence. This sum and not the objec
tive spirit becomes the substrate of opinion research because only individ
ual opinions can be counted and measured. Although the principle “science
is measurement” is far too stark for American scholars today, it continues
to function as an implicit criterion for the scientific method. Therefore, no
one can simply declare that the positivistic-atomistic conception of public
opinion does justice to the issue. That discontent is counteracted by agnos
ticism: “the nature of public opinion is not something to be defined but to
be studied.”19 People are consoled by the idea of a future in which so much
empirical material will be gathered that the question of the nature of pub
lic opinion can be decided. This blinds us to the fact that the collection of
material for this clarification presupposes an inadequate, unrealistic con
cept of public opinion. When speaking of theory, one does not mean a
theoretical conception of the entire society within which the concept of
public opinion is situated, but one limits oneself to formulating and to
testing hypotheses that can only be verified or falsified using atomistic-
additive methods. This insufficiency of the “philosophy” underlying opin
ion research is based on a problematic notion of society and therefore calls
into question the reliability of the seemingly objective research methods.
Sampling as a Tool for Sociological Research The survey method owes its
existence to administration’s need for information about the conditions
and people to be overseen and the desire of large-scale economic enter
prises to be informed in advance about the extent and kind of demand
questions that arouse the emotions of the interviewees, and when the in
terviewee himself is conscious only superficially (if at all) of the implica
tions of such questions. Contradictory tendencies in an individual’s opinion
do not mean that he lacks an opinion, but that these opinions are multilay
ered or antagonistic in themselves. Since such antagonisms are intertwined
in the most diverse ways with the objective antagonisms of society, it is
particularly important for sociology to follow them if empirical surveys are
to gain as accurate a picture as possible of the relation between people and
their social environment. It is obvious that one method alone does not suf
fice for this task; a combination of several methods is necessary for ap
proaching the complex phenomenon of opinion formation.
The Antinomy of Empirical Research and the Institute's Pilot Study This
critique of survey methods is not nullified by specifying exactly the statisti
cal error of representation according to the rules of mathematical proba
bility. That is because one can only calculate the extent to which the com
position of the sample corresponds to that of the universe from which it
was taken. But one cannot specify the degree to which the problems of
the interview method affect its reliability and then eliminate these er
rors.29 The critique refers not to the technical precision of the method but
to its epistemic adequacy, the matter of inferring public opinion from
standardized questions posed to statistically selected individuals. Such
criticism is not meant to discredit the survey method as such. Its achieve
ments are beyond doubt the closer its questions are to market and con
sumer research and to less affectively charged topics. It is only problem
atic to hypostatize the method, because of its mathematical presentability,
as a privileged instrument of objective knowledge across opinion research
and to exceed the limits of the method that inhere in the form of its rela
tion to the object.
Empirical social research faces a kind of antinomy. The more exact its
methods become, the more these methods are at risk of replacing the ac
tual object of interest with one defined in “operational terms,” in other
words, narrowing the issue itself to whatever can be ascertained by survey
methods and neglecting what is socially relevant. The sterility of some em
pirical studies, and the frequent sense that one would have expected the
results ahead of time—a critically justified observation cannot be refuted
simply by the counter argument that there is a difference between what is
expected and what is actually known— is not just the result of a lack of
imagination or theoretical conception in designing studies. These prob
lems are fundamentally connected with the method itself. By the same to
ken, the history of sociology has often enough demonstrated the opposite
risk: arbitrariness and untested dogmatic claims. We are far from demand-
The Group Discussion Method — 31
ing that science should refrain from including the new methods of “fact
finding” [English]. All the same, in the excitement of discovering the new
method, one must not forget that it is vulnerable on particularly important
questions of knowledge about society. This is true exactly where the
method holds itself in highest regard: in objectivity or knowledge about
the true object. Because of this contradictory situation, corrective tech
niques to help the new method understand its own problem have to tie in
to the state of empirical social research. Empirical social research needs to
overcome the underlying reasons for its own shortcomings with tools de
rived from it, and to nudge social research into being a tool for real social
insight. It must not content itself with safe but irrelevant claims about
dead, reified templates of reality. It is a matter of merging scientific objec
tivity with meaningful insight into the essential, which often eludes precise
methods.
The undertaking of the Institute for Social Research reported here is an
experimental contribution to this task, with all the preliminary and ques
tionable aspects that can hardly be avoided given the paradox of the task
itself, and certainly cannot be avoided during the first steps. The goal is a
procedure that will eventually lead beyond the limits of quantitative meth
ods. In no way is the claim made that this is the first attempt in this direc
tion. For a long time, depth-psychological interviews, projective tests, de
tailed case studies, and other techniques have been applied to correct and
supplement common survey methods.30 The group technique discussed
here differs from all these attempts, however, by not being content with
post hoc modifications. Instead, it investigates an earlier stage: studying
opinions in statu nascendi.
FIRSTLY: People’s opinions and attitudes toward topics that claim general or
public interest and which can therefore become objects of public opinion do
not form and act in isolation but in continuous interrelation between the in
dividual and the society that affects him both directly and indirectly. They are
often not specifically fixed, but have an only vague and diffuse potential.
Often they become clear to the individual only in interaction with other
people. They may be present latently, but they do not really take shape until
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 32
these take hold in the individual. Equally important, however, was the de
velopment and the testing of the “group discussion method,” a new method
whose conception emerges from the critique of contemporary survey
methods. The goal was to reveal the participants’ attitude and the interre
lation between individual and group which importantly co-constitutes this
attitude in dialogue insofar as one participant attempts to persuade the
other group members of the truth of his own view, and by the influence the
group opinion (the group standards) exerts on individuals’ attitudes: in
short, by the dynamic nature of dealing with the topic. The project avoided
studying attitudes, opinions, and patterns of behavior in isolation—a state
in which they almost never occur. In addition, the group discussion should
allow for apprehending multiple aspects of the opinions and attitudes si
multaneously in their multilayered, contradictory complexity.
The study sought to create a situation in which people could speak sponta
neously and frankly in order to provide for the necessary range of reac
tion, to cater to the different reaction rates of individuals, and to eliminate
everything in the experimental design that might strengthen internal resis
tance. Therefore, the discussions could not follow a preset agenda or a list of
points to be systematically discussed. Rather they had to be conducted as
freely as possible, without rigid topical restrictions, and without forcing the
participants to express themselves. The often prolix breadth of the discussions
of particular themes was usually allowed because only this made it possible
to obtain the free associations crucial for assessing the stated opinions and
attitudes. These associations were of especially crucial significance for the
analysis of the discussions since they made it possible to infer the utterances’
latent content. It is, in turn, only from these that information can be gained
about the attitudes that reside below and underlie the surface opinions.
The question of how the participants were to be confronted with the
objects of research was resolved after great initial difficulties by including
the topics in a letter written for the project and recorded on audio tape [See
the Colburn Letter, 177-178.—Eds.]. After a short opening address from the
investigator, the text was played to the participants and put up for discus
sion. This foundation mainly had the task of raising the topics for discussion.
Apart from that, it was designed to exert a stimulating effect by touching
on psychologically sore spots and breaking through the participants’ re
serve, which is often observed in discussions of affectively charged topics.
In the first place, therefore, it was supposed to mobilize mechanisms of
defense and rationalizations in order to reveal what they usually conceal,
as in psychoanalytic techniques.32
The situation in a train compartment served as a kind of model for the
group discussions. It frequently happens that strangers talk about the most
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~~ 34
fact that his true name was not recorded and could not be known to his
fellow participants without his consent.
One objection could be that the anonymity granted in the discussions
encouraged irresponsible drivel, since speakers were not bound to what
they said. In some cases there were indications that participants played cer
tain roles in the discussions that prompted them to say things that were at
odds with their other attitudes and seemed at times to be clearly contradic
tory to those attitudes. Such contradictions between normal attitudes and
expressions of opinion during the group discussion can be explained pri
marily by the fact that in most people several tendencies struggle for domi
nance. One of these usually prevails, while others are visible only in excep
tional cases. That such phenomena can be observed in the discussion
suggests a positive interpretation of our experiment—the experimental de
sign caused a reduction of the controlling function of consciousness and,
thus, granted access to deeper layers of consciousness.34
Depth psychology long ago disproved the common view that a person
who knows himself to be free from responsibility would just talk, without
any particular goal, for the sake of making himself appear important or to
malevolently mislead the listener. In the same way that wine reveals but does
not invent, the irresponsible drivel in the discussion can be very informative
for those attitudes which are rarely visible and are hidden in an interview
based on multiple-choice questions. One can even assume that people whose
political opinions are the object of research are rather more likely to give
irresponsible answers to an unknown interviewer (for example, to get rid of
him) than to chatter about something irrelevant in a carefully organized
group discussion.
After distributing pseudonyms, short statistical questionnaires were
handed out. These asked for common information such as age, marital sta
tus, profession, education, etc. The questions were formulated in such a way
that answering usually led to some questions, through which more personal
contact between the participants and the staff could be established before
the beginning of the discussion. After a short introduction from the investi
gator and the playing of the basic stimulus, the discussion generally fell into
two parts of 45 minutes to 1 hour each. The first section was entirely free
discussion. In the second part the investigator inserted “standardized argu
ments” into appropriate sections of the discussion. The aim of this part was
to give participants the opportunity to make their statements more precise
and most importantly to gain further insight into the process of opinion
formation and change.
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~ 36
The Function o f the Moderator Based on the above, it should be clear that
the discussions—and in particular the first part—were not steered substan
tively but only moderated formally. The best way to do this could only be
determined experimentally. Thus, we experimented with different methods of
moderation in the first research phase. From the experience gained, we finally
developed a technique that differs crucially from the usual ways of moderat
ing discussions. As a result of this experience we compiled the “moderator
instruction,”37 according to which the rest of the study was conducted.
The preliminary tests showed that the investigators alone were not able
to record the observations necessary for interpreting the discussions. The
necessary concentration on the discussion and constant interaction with
the participants did not permit them to take notes at the same time. Thus,
after the first pretests an assistant was assigned to each investigator. The
assistant was charged with the task of recording the topics of the discus
sion in shorthand and recording observations on the behavior of the group
and of individual participants.
The Group Discussion Method ^ 3 7
Recording the Discussions It was clear from the beginning that only elec
tronic recording would suffice for the group discussions. It was the only
way to reproduce the complete course of the discussion and the intensity
of the speakers’ affect. In addition, participants almost invariably got used
to the microphone and recorder quickly, while the presence of a secretary
writing feverishly can severely affect the realism of the discussion.
Now, it would be wrong to assume that the tape recording readily al
lowed a complete transcription of the discussions. Even in the most favor
able case it was not possible to identify and transcribe all statements with
the help of the audio tapes; a few remained unintelligible. This is essen
tially because the group discussions proceeded with little organization
due to their spontaneity. Numerous participants speak unclearly or in a
dialect hard to understand, and many participants often talk at the same
time. These difficulties could have been avoided by more rigid moderation
but had to be accepted since the frankness of the statements clearly de
creases with increasing discipline of discussion. This would therefore have
strengthened the controls whose effects the experiment was designed to
limit.
The Individual Interview From the beginning, it was assumed that the
group discussions, conceived and developed as tools for opinion research,
would not fail to affect the participants. Thus, we sought to try to gain
some insights into these effects. It was particularly important to determine
the consistency of the articulated opinion: to find out whether opinion
changes observed in the discussions were “stable,” or whether the partici
pants reverted to their initial attitude at some point after the discussions.
A survey of approximately one quarter of the participants (400 total)
was conducted 4 to 6 weeks after the completion of the discussions as an
attempt to consider this direction. The questionnaire was developed after
a detailed review of around 50 discussions.38 It included questions relating
to the main topics of the research as well as some to provide additional
information about the psychological structure of the interviewees. The in
terviews were principally conducted by the moderators and their assistants
in order to utilize the trusting relationship which had developed between
them and the participants in the course of the discussions, to gain as open
and sincere answers as possible. These interviews were therefore not inqui
sitions by strangers as criticized above, but talks between two people who,
as a general rule, had gotten to know each other under particularly favor
able circumstances.
These individual interviews yielded an abundance of valuable material,
but their goal was achieved only to a limited extent. This is, in part, because
Group Experiment and Other Writings 38
4. Analysis o f Stimuli
When the following discussion refers to the “stimuli” used, this should
not be understood as an attempt to determine with scientific rigor indi
vidual differences in reactions to the same stimulus. We consider stimuli
as those conditions set up to induce the participants to talk and make
their attitudes and motivations known where they would otherwise have
been inhibited. We also do not consider factors that influenced the partici
pants’ reactions in particular ways without having been planned and
standardized as part of the experimental design; these act as stimuli as
well. Among those are, for example, the effects of the respective composi
tion of the group, the specific group climate resulting from the composi
tion, the personality of the moderator, etc. The combination of these fac
tors excludes from the outset any thought of experimental methods,
which always require the isolation of stimuli so that the reactions can be
measured.
The Basic Stimulus The basic stimulus was of central significance for the
group experiment. It not only had to stimulate, to induce the partici
pants into talking, but also had to set the topics for discussion insofar as
this could be done without coercion. It was a functional analog to the ques
tionnaire in survey methods, but without its rigidness. Hence, great care
had to be devoted to the construction and extensive testing of the basic
stimulus.
A number of criteria were set up for the formulation of the basic stimu
lus. These arose in part from the study’s topic and in part from the meth
ods intended for its execution.
FIRSTLY: The basic stimulus had to relate directly to the subject of the re
search, i.e., to questions of political ideology. Among those questions were,
for example, Germans’ relation to foreign countries and the occupying
powers, attitudes toward democratic and totalitarian forms of government
The Group Discussion Method — 39
are behind us,” “of course, I do not know to what extent they are indepen
dent or just recount what they have heard,” “often they just say what they
think we want to hear,” etc. These statements qualifying the depiction of
good characteristics of the Germans were meant to increase the sense of
objectivity, since unqualified praise would easily have seemed unnatural, as
clumsy flattery, or as pro-German bias. We were surprised by what oc
curred: the qualifications were often interpreted as attacks just as the criti
cal statements were later on. The psychic reservoir from which many of the
participants drew was largely collective narcissism. Although they were
gathered in small groups, they acted as members of a mass or at least be
haved as if they were in a mass as soon as there was talk of “we,” which, for
them, replaced the notion of Germany.
Among many participants their entire reactions seemed to be set up ac
cording to the binary scheme of for us vs, against us. This behavioral pat
tern should remind us that the problem of mass psychology is in no way
limited to times when masses are immediately present. Phenomena of mass
psychology can also occur in social situations in which individuals find
themselves relatively isolated. Stubborn and unreflective reactions can
occur whenever the psychic zones characteristic of mass psychology are
touched. These reside in the domain of collective identification.
The third and longest part comprises a detailed criticism of character
istics and behavioral patterns of Germans. Again, the critical comments
are qualified with the aim of developing rapport with the group. This
third part of the letter is the focus of the basic stimulus, as it concen
trates the arguments that are designed to break through the partici
pants’ reserve by means of their content, formulation, and psychological
approach.
The categories used in the analysis of the basic stimulus arise from the
main topics of the object of investigation mentioned above. It is important
to recognize, though, that these are not separate phenomena independent
of one another, but rather question complexes forming structural wholes.
Thus, even though the following isolates individual questions and, hence,
breaks apart from this structural whole, one should not overlook that such
a methodological operation must not lead to hypostatizing the crystallized
factors as independent variables.
The structural whole of the third part is best characterized by “ethno-
centrism.”40 By this we mean the attitude that contrasts the (good) in
group with the (bad) out-group, distinguishes between “us” (the Germans)
and “them” (the foreigners), and projects all imaginable bad things onto
the latter. The basic stimulus touches on five sensitive spots of ethnocen-
trism, namely:
The Group Discussion Method ~~ 41
These sensitive spots corresponded to the following phrases from the basic
stimulus:
“They believe they have exclusive rights to culture and are, thus, vastly
superior to us.”
“Even though we beat them, they believe themselves to be better and
more capable than us.”
“.. . they have a hard time accepting that now they are no longer in
charge in the world.”
“. . . even though they, naturally, are behind us (in technology).”
“. . . that they attempt to learn as much as they can from our modern
techniques.”
“. . . they cannot understand at all that one admits the mistakes of
one’s own country and talks openly about them.”
“. . . that the Germans are learning from the ground up what practical
democracy actually means.”
“The risk is that, tomorrow, they will again follow a Hitler or Stalin, as
soon as they convince themselves that they can come to power again
that way.”
wide range of reactions and to reveal the hidden and repressed manifesta
tions of ethnocentrism. These levels were:
the ideology of the superiority of the “German race,”
the bitterness against the DPs,4^
the degree of recognition of the extent of the persecution of the Jews.
These three topics are introduced here as levels of ethnocentrism be
cause of possible differences in the degree to which particularly anti-
Semitic attitudes are conscious. We assumed that participants who identi
fied partially or completely with national-socialistic racial theory during
the discussions would likely also have conscious anti-Semitic attitudes. For
the other two groups—those participants who thought German bitterness
against the Jews was justified or that the extent of the persecution of the
Jews is generally greatly exaggerated—we assumed that less conscious,
hidden forms of ethnocentrism were at work. In the first case, we sus
pected a suppression of feelings of guilt leading to the projection of aggres
sion onto the victims; in the second case, the effect of a defense mechanism
resulting in a distortion of reality. According to these hypotheses, the fol
lowing arguments were formulated:
“They imagine that their good traits, which I do not deny, grant them
a sort of privilege in the world.”
“They are still not free from the Nazi view that they are a master
race.”
“They are also still bitter toward the Jews.”
“One only hears . .. complaints about the DPs’ trading on the black
m arket. . .”
“They act especially strangely when there is talk about racial persecu
tion in America.”
“I have always explained to them that among us it is a matter of 10 or
20 cases a year, while among them it involved millions . . .”
“. .. while their state, however, managed lynching itself and in a
disproportionally higher scale.”
We have to note again here that breaking apart the structural whole of
the study question and the isolated examination of subproblems, al
though unavoidable for the analysis of the stimuli, is only partially pos
sible. This is particularly true of the guilt complex, since the question of
guilt can never be discussed outside the context of the actions constitut
ing guilt. Thus, it was impossible to avoid the fact that the stimulus argu
ments, particularly those aimed at the guilt complex, touched two sensi
tive spots at once. This reality would have to be judged as a deficiency in
The Group Discussion Method 43
“The Ami is quite right saying that the Germans should just be left alone and
that they will rise again by themselves. Everything else he says, like that the
Germans think they are better than others, the thing with guilt, etc., is just
babble.”
Group Experiment and Other Writings —' 46
Stimulus Argument:
“How can one speak of guilt at all in the face of these huge processes? All
these are processes decided beyond our control. We are just chess pieces
moved back and forth. The individual does not have any say in that.”
Counter-Argument:
“Well, democracy really is not as powerless as you think it is. Just consider
America. In the last election the whole apparatus creating public opinion, the
press, broadcasts, enormous financial means, were against Truman. Yet he
was elected because the majority of the population, the little people, believed
they would fare better under him as president. Is that really nothing?”
Counter-Argument:
“Well, should one just throw Europe down the throat of the Russians? And
are the American soldiers in Korea not also fighting for us today? We can no
longer separate our interests from those of America.”
Finally, the fourth stimulus argument returns to nationalism and the ob
session with power by authoritarian personalities. The counterargument
tries to ascertain how possible it is to counteract such an attitude by ap
pealing to a desire for peace.
Stimulus Argument:
“We should not be bothered with all this prattle about international under
standing. The only thing that counts is power, and everybody tries to seize as
much power as possible.”
Counter-Argument:
“Why are you so opposed to the idea that the world could become beautiful
and peaceful? One of the reasons it doesn’t work could be that people are so
opposed to it.”
The fact that stimulus arguments were only used after a trusting relation
ship was established may have contributed to the arguments’ fitting natu
rally into the discussion. This makes them a useful tool for revealing impor
tant additions to the opinions expressed in the first part of the discussions.
5. The Interpretation
the aim of this study was from other group experiments. These are not
primarily concerned with ascertaining opinions and attitudes but with in
vestigating communication between members of the group as well as with
group phenomena like integration, cohesion, influence of the “group
leader,” behavior toward outsiders, etc. It is therefore adequate in those
cases only to record the participants’ statements that directly relate to the
objects of investigation; everything else is extra. Thus, American studies of
group dynamics usually limit themselves to registering the participants’
reactions in a few categories, without recording the actual wording and
drawing on their whole depth and complexity for interpretation.50 Even
Bales, w h o undertook to examine the entire communication process in
order to gain insights into the effect of the group situation on group mem
bers and the principles of behavior within groups, made do with only
twelve very abstract observational categories.
Our investigation, by contrast, was not primarily concerned with study
ing such group phenomena. Rather, we sought to observe the attitudes and
reactions of individuals in group situations. Understanding the group dy
namics was not the main aim of the investigation but a step on the way to
better understanding opinion formation. Accordingly, the interpretation
had to be geared to categorizing the reactions of individuals as completely
as possible in order to gain insights into their attitudes toward problems
that were not posed by the group situation as such but by reality. This
meant that the content of the contributions to the discussion had to be
considered with greater completeness and complexity than other group
experiments.
This is not the place to describe in detail the differences between the
categories used in other experiments and those used in this investigation.
As an indication of our attempt to register every particular it is enough
to point out that the content of the discussions was processed with the
help of a coding key comprising hundreds of categories, while other stud
ies use only a small fraction of that number. The difficulties arising from
the development of a suitable method for quantification were corre
spondingly high. In the beginning, the material to be processed seemed
to defy coverage by relatively simple, quantifiable categories because it
was too varied. After reviewing more transcripts, however, it became
apparent that the material was not amorphous. Rather, it was already
pre-structured to some extent by the basic stimulus and the standardized
arguments. Moreover, a set of topics was objectively important. An anal
ysis of all of these factors and the resulting categories provided the first
starting points for compiling the index, which allowed us to process the
discussions quantitatively.
The Group Discussion Method — 49
The Brittleness o f Language One of the most striking findings is that people
virtually speak two languages. This appeared in all groups and with the
same clarity among former officers and farmers, tram conductors, and ur
ban merchants. In the language of their profession and of daily contact,
they are able to express themselves rationally and somewhat clearly. The
language shows certain objectively conditioned symptoms of decline, yet
within this language the speakers succeed in reacting coherently and mean
ingfully to all problems posed to them. When they are confronted with
highly emotionally charged problems, however, this language fails them,
and they are forced to resort to a second one, which has in common with
language only the use of words. Actually, it is stammering. This second
language seems to be much less a means of expressing thoughts or even
emotions than to serve the effort to suppress manifestations of the uncon
scious. It is characterized by a certain brittleness. This is caused by the
conflict between the intention to argue rationally and the irrational im
pulses activated by the basic stimulus. The conflict situation appears to
destroy language; it reduces the ability for meaningful, intelligible expres
sion. By doing just that, however, it unearths the real psychological layer.
The irrational, whose expression the speaker unconsciously tries to pre
vent, emerges in the structure of the second language. Its seeming sense
lessness turns out to be absolutely meaningful at closer inspection, since it
provides insight into the latent psychological mechanism effective in the
speaker.57
TH E Q U A N TITATIVE ANALYSIS
OF T H E D ISC U SSIO N S
C H A P T E R T W O
9 73 3 T3 3
C/5 rD CO 8 n
c^ 5· o
n V5
0 π 5
3
ο 3 SI55'
i δ
rD 3
Su CL CO
3
Q- Q.
α C
55 n 0
Ό 5' r3“
tu
S
α.
QTQ D
3 “ CO
i
n> a
CO
it
e
a 3
n 3
3 ^w
3
rt> 3
CL rf
2
CL 3
3 -· sr
w «
3* »
( continued)
o 3
rD
S
M CL
t/T
C 3
U/5 -C
w
*3
3 ci
Έ ’vC5/5
ce 3
u oc:
>
‘3 0
ce CJ
oc
«J a
-3 Z o
C
Λ S È
“"
OC O § Έ
£ S Sf
a>
-2
_c U ^I
Ξ
«Λ 3
cu .2 ■-
3
ε -C 1 -c 2I
c-c
J= *H 2 G
ce
ce (/) cU 3 D Ë. Ç.
c V <υ 'ΰ
-a
.2 o ”5 c -e 'I
ce ^ E *- C
.aL- ·c— ςΛ C 1 sc
ce u. o ëü ܰ : iX c 13
.Ü ce ‘5 E
ε
3
1V _c
ce
î cûV
M
—
C
ε-> 2 e . 4u i~I
4W <υ υ
o«Λ 2 -π -c ce £"
> ε
ff H 4-* < o δ. g
< O |\ 00 ON d U
£ - - N U "3
OC c«e wC
G 5/5 ÎJ
*3 « .-
je
"w =J
Om ■g g
Ü3û 4-· O ce o
C
<υ 2
Ο ε
3
ff c §
E u
< •ë !
O
C
C S JS
u
2T CJ
'S
O £o c
^
a c 2
O av2
o^
4>
G
n i
a>
a
ce
-c 0 ^3
oc
3 g S .
2 •s
3 S
_û i>*Λ
ce
“Τ ■c 13
r ~vs
cS3o ce :§
•S c 2 ■O *o Λw
.2 o -2 C y .S
κ 3 * cu
.aUi 'c“ ë
c 3 3υ ^ίξ- 2«
-Û
B S O U i2 $
U *G Jg C/5
N 1i> JZU o
-C «>-> _"3 uC/-5
oèî h H
ON O Ë
l2 a
The Organization o f the Discussion Materials ~~ 61
1. Form of government
2. Federal Republic of Germany (Bonn)
3. War guilt
4. Joint responsibility for concentration camps and war atrocities
5. Anti-Semitism
6. U.S. occupation
7. United States of America
8. England
9. France
10. Eastern Bloc states
11. Remilitarization
12. German self-assessment
however, does not suggest that the discussions can be divided into chrono
logical sections sticking to single topics. In the course of the discussion,
the statements’ subjects change in irregular succession. The discussion
jumps around. In some statements, different topics are frequently inter-
locked to such an extent that it became necessary to decompose individual
sentences and subsume them under different categories. An example of
this:
I.: I don’t believe that the Germans, or let’s say even the majority of the
Germans, rubbed their hands when the Americans sustained casualties (in
Korea).
speakers who adopted the stereotype as their own gives way to open aggres
sion in some passages: “he (Adenauer) should consider dying instead!”
It becomes clear here how the stereotype that “public funds are wasted
in Bonn” can influence attitudes toward the Bonn government. In inter
preting the origin of this stereotype, though, it is important to add that its
usage is relatively independent of social status. The pretension of wasting
public funds has always been used as a standard phrase in the demagogical
polemic against democratic forms of government. The agitation with this
stereotype is not only directed toward poor audiences. It accepts any rea
son for its adoption—from the resentments of those paying high taxes to
jealousy toward the social position of “the gentlemen in office.” This indif
ference toward diverse motives suggests that the effectiveness of such a
stereotype is no longer particularly tied to the reality from which it arose:
in this case economic misery. Instead, it appears to have originated in the
disposition to oppose democratic government. Factually, the stereotype is
wrong. Moreover, it is freed from its tethers to these facts. In turn, it con
nects to an authoritarian personality structure, which a large number of
our participants use to argue against the democratic form of government.
They use the stereotypes like stones to cast at others.
3. Summary *
The categories of the descriptive coding scheme, which was developed
with the help of two examples, reduced the material to a manageable
Category
' 3"-i o "3 GTQ
TT
03
O O
CO O a3“
2.2.
3 ο n
3 3“ 3“
O O SO
Q
TQ ^ 2 o O 3
O 3 C L·
< S
'-IO-
Quotation
oζ/5 £ CTQ Γ.
a. SO Q. n CTQ 3CO*
c oa. 3- σ- o
government from all the oversight.
especially his present life, his past life?
a government where all of us really got to know the character of this person,
2. H (O 0 O F o -
3 3 ^ O C F ÿ
Ά Q_ 3 S CT
8
& o< c o< V5 ^ 3
Ο Ο 5
5Λ co ” 21 w ! · § o
'1
3 7 Q 0 M 5^ cίΛ
£
•-i »n - 3 “^ 0 3 ΞΓ* ^
Approving Statements
w COQ- s 1
C C c 3 2 3 - 5: f i rf O o3 o< (A CO D- c 3
^ 3·
SP * OsoTQ
7Γ 3 Λ \ O “ o
Ûi L· = 3n “ -n
cr 3 - 'S’
I 3 ·-»
3
3
co ^ 2_
o»
CL. c
SO o æ o
—
cC O o a. û. 3 *3 0 o 33
C C T5 O * I c 3 ΙΓ 5 ' c
g ο p 5 CL < yi < G- <·
c ^ - o i 5 ·-g’ 3 O'
■n — •s3 s3o-
*§■ ? S S. on 0D
O _
c3 “ cr^ £^ 3
^
c o
dp CO 3 “ w § <
-■ W 3 -3 C 3 3 3 35’ o « S
^ ^ 3 c 2 . =?-» On 0 ^ 0
X O r*t => g 3 " Ο 'n < 3
O* C O ^ S'5 3 w ι—. C ig lS &
C ^ ST P - i 3 «« 3-1 3
c = 5/5 3 îr 3 cO -so i" S O CO
-■ S 3- C CL·^
3C“ w * I—
3 t· o X CO St Q. °
?-» û- 3
c ,.* o C/î
3“
c 3
O
“ 5T c 3 - o3 ?H
C C- C ?T 3 c 3 ~ 9 c' — ^
G- — 3
3 C V3 3 ^ 2Γ X-
! ' i f ét ο 8 Ι ?= 0« G- co ^ c
35 3 ; 5 § li CT =· ί 2 n
ûi C 3 T3 §-■ 2-c ^ o 3 3“ C 2.° δ
e .2 : g
C
;λ ’ 5 3- il 2 ? a- R.
7T o
-n W 'yj O O Q.
3 ? § 39 CO « o< 3co-
J» Q. — X c c
c»-I c <-*
o o “ fio c ^ ^
•n C 3
(Λ Q 3
c o <
TD O 3 c
Q. 3
C g" Q.
w J3 2 3 ^ 03“ -
O
c c 3 S SO 3“ 3 " ?= =
cûj vT 32 C 3 O CL.
SL W !Λ O 0 1 ?
er O“ 3 C
S 5 '>
^c s« O 33
c
c cCT 3 = 3
*3 3 N C
S E 5’ n O 2
F 2.™ 5’ 3“ O 3 C
09 O 3
0 - 3
C M
S-'L 0 3 C
O — 3* N
- 1 C
“/î o O -, —· O
s/J oS
CO 0 3 3
C/î‘ * C b) 3 Q
TQ O
C 3“
CO *3 3 O
{O a.
v<* c »
S
3 ■g 3a. 3CL
o
3
jjE
our governm ent should listen a bit more to the people and to the opposition, namely
0/ Ο
R.: I believe especially here in Western Germany and especially in im portant questions
wo
§ 1Λ Cbß
H.: Let’s look back to 1933 for once. There w as an econom ic crisis. Hitler came and
-O OJ
Ο.: I believe how ever that a democracy, in the w ay the Americans imagine it for us,
o 3 'S 5
σ' 8 "cë s •#s ^3 0/
^ -C >
can’t be created from one day to the next. A monarchy w as the basic idea for
y ο c Tu,3 CJ E ce CJ
Λ S C
£3 ce
Im 05/3 -C
3 cj
JE of ce -C -O CJ 6/3 0/ 3
0 ce É Ό
TC3 bß 5/3
E O
ce ff 03 OJ
"O ■5
5/3
ce
ce b£ £
3 ΈC O
03
N
remedied unem ploym ent, and this was an improvement, after all.
c
<υ OJ 0 c ce 5/3
E v2 I c
o X ‘3 d 5Λ Λ
ce b C
c V
E cx
cj
03
*
OJ
Im "O Im Îm OJ ce
c M -E -C
-Q v2 os 8 — 5/3
V E
ce JE - O ^3 E 3 -ö
"ce T3 0 c C
ufc 0 <
<υ
"Ό O .ä C
03 5fl O J bßC
c r> — -£ c §
E ce I>m fr «
c
0 ce Ö 5/3 ce ’> 25 Λ -
Ό
Ö g <υ -2 — O -O 5/3 VM *
X
CJ
Λ
H
C
ce
__
- £ §D y
s
—
«
OJ
5
mu
bß
c
rrj —
1Λ«4- ·*"
QJ
>
03
<m
Mm
o
5/3
c 5/3 0
ce 3
c 5</3υ ebJD rt
-Ό
Im r t)
I
5 ce
0
OJ >
j x ce 3 o 12 ÖX3 ce -s ^
E bß •3 - C .E £ δ
<υ ce * s o Έ <u υ .2 5
Ό -C Q c
-σ SP c 2 g -s ‘Sc "α-Ό
ο ·*..-* 5V
Qj £
3 *- /5
<υ 03 3■ £ Λ
ce
_c °U S
M V Mg “ -O
Λ
^ 0 □ ■- <υ O- Ö JD >N P 5/3
5/3
$ : ü
C _ c -w
C
Ο <υ E C cj ^
JE
c Έ
bp 3
O
X ^
2 Ä
-û _e 0 2
«
·-5u/3> m^ou 1t> _o
JE
- 0 « « 03 Cu' ■SI
the Social D em ocrats.
tM ?
a> a/ l_l r' r
cx <u ___ _ ,0 P 2 § 2 < .b
o ?_ CX v_2 3 *-· ^ u
-Ό CX ce I . E c *s
C n £ C w =
Λ > os X ÜJC.2 -c ^ c
03 Icem "£ o3 s Jcn J 5/3
·^
5 £ x> cx: ^ Sf'G 9
O 2 γΓ . · O q « $ 5/3 X
*
■a* .22 «
-C
4-> ^
^ am ong us?
-■2-2 2 Û -S 8 « Λ o
.2 *7 2ί c
t
E ο«λ"
2 C
5Λ ^
/5 ,0 s 8 : - « S -S - -o
C -
C
flj c 5J
E ·
<υ *:
■ g ä JS -Ό JE U .. = 3 §I
0 o !§ < ; *5w «
E
N ^
Insufficient consideration o f the opposition
C
So far unsatisfactory developm ent o f
_o
•Μ
Λ a/
Λ çx E
V G λ O <
-o 'fi * 3 a e
Λ >S -Ό ÖJD
Cu
0î3r C
lm CJ
c
o C
2
υ
O 3 Im
‘D V ÿ C J 8
u
Λ
Cu
3 SC E
V
T3
s I
·$ U
„ O
5 Q
CJ
J
E
a/
o i? "V -s -o
under Hitler
CJ O— 3 Su. 3
dem ocracy
C g 03 O O O
.2 o U- -C (J _o
CJ
-C
CJ ΰ wυ Ο «T 3 rt
S '-‘- 5/3 3
Λ
o
Λ
O O 5g ^3
c
2 i -S -û
Im
CL C u 2 »°M
^ ·£ 3 £ 3
O
<υ oj 2C
ν'
ο Ο Λ
Û Û Û
ÛE^
σ
ο
σ σ
et
n
p ÿ
C 3 tTJ g 3 et S-
3“ οη S σ* o Q
TQ et"
et O s>
Ρ JJ
33 ο
Ρ s>
3* o
ο ^ P
o ·-» C l.
et
% 2. £L
ρ et 3
ΪΛ η p
3 «
3
C/3
et et
ο Ο Ö.
et
-η “<η
Ρ -ι
r. C
*3
et
3
et
et
3“
et sr l
i
et
O
3
C £ TJ i·—·i C co
JO
:r » et2. 3 r*
ce*
3 " " ί? ί
et
et fit *■22< C
et cr ’ S T» et
3
fit et$ -3— (Λ 3“
i et et
U 3 2 Π
-n Ä O O 3
H - et
j/3 **·» n
et
S: 5 “ ol g c/5' 3' COL· 3. 5et5’ 3* 3*
* *'*< f 3 - g. et C/3 c/3
et et
C/3 —-
c3 S' ft S C/3 Q- «-* *·<
" i 5· C 3 Q. O E 5 ’ 3 T
5 ’ et
et _« 2
et °
<-»· et QTQ
et T3 C/3 *et-n
» O g. “ -o O - S- Cl w
fit 3 £ο O 3- ~
■-i r*
ΕΓ et_
et □r fit n ^ et et
" §■ J r i s C
T Q*,3 et
3 3“
- Q T
et
Q S 2r f-r et
et fit et " 3 û. 2 . û.
fit . . et -
O 3 -0 -3
? o *3 TJ ûi
-T 3 r
α ^
-- et
fit o 3“
£ 3“ R
fit
O
fit C c
et
?r
C/i
fit 2. O
3
θ o
c
s- ^ 3- Q. -7T
CL· n r-f 3t
3 et
n f re O
et
2“ crq
n S'5 7Q Z 2 o
S et
fit nfit Q. o
^i ICD c/3 et n
fit 3 — 3“
•-N C-
Q
TQ 3 -· *3 P f?
3 fit
et P
3 C
~ < et 3*
ET os
(λ n û-
-■ O c 3“ O
et *■*■»
^ n·
“ ûi J
Ό â-*■
<
5 CTQ<T> TJ et
r* ers 2 <
_
/ Ο γ et
2 1 -· 0
c X— "2.
^ =r 2"» « et
s· *
C et
n 3r_r? *3 3*
3 et ^ C
The Organization o f the Discussion Materials — - 69
Quantitative Analyses
I. Preliminary Results*
Our quantitative findings can be grouped into four areas. To begin with,
the preparation of a coding manual created a catalog of nonsingular opin
ions and reactions and, thus, offered a first insight into the emotions and
beliefs that make up the object of our study. We already mentioned that,
after using half of our transcripts to formulate the categories necessary for
coding the material, the other sixty transcripts showed no accumulations
of opinions and reactions that could not be classified easily with the avail
able categories. This fact argues in favor of the completeness of these catego
ries, at least in relation to our circle of participants. A comparison between
the quotations reproduced in this chapter as illustration for the different
categories and the complete transcripts shows that even attitudes with low
frequency are represented in our catalog of categories.
The numerical data gained so far can be summarized in two different
ways. Not only can we analyze the reactions of the statistical groups based
on demographic factors, for each topic individually—as we have in our
account up to this point—but we can also compare the distribution of re
actions within each statistical group with that of all the speakers in our
circle of participants. The conformities or deviations might tell us some
thing new about the dominant ideology and the role of subjective factors.
We can also trace the counts of graded codes as well as those about the
participation in the discussion of each statistical group across all topics and
see whether relevant group characteristics emerge. In this way we can more
clearly reveal the characteristics of the groups in relation to their attitudes to
ward democratic values as well as their interest in individual political topics.
differences in attitudes of each group toward each of the seven major topics
in comparison to those of each other group as well as to the average attitude
of all speakers in all groups (the general average) to each topic. These graphs
depict the percentage deviation in attitude of twenty groups from the general
average attitude on the topic. The computation was not made in percentages
but in percentages of deviation from the general average.2
Attitude toward Democracy The topic of democracy has the largest par
ticipation in discussion of all topics (53% as compared with the average of
39% for all speakers for all seven topics). The following groups partici
pated particularly often:
University graduates: 71%
High school graduates: 64%
War veterans: 64%
We find particularly low participation for the topic of democracy among
young people (20 years old and younger), who also stand out for the low
percentage of their speakers on other topics.
The average attitude of all participants toward democracy shows:
• approval among one-tenth.
• disapproval among approximately one-fifth.
• ambivalence among the great majority, approximately two-thirds.
At the top of advocates of a positive attitude3 toward democracy (average
10%) we find unskilled workers (20%) and participants 20 years old or
younger (15%), while university graduates (6%) and farmers (3%) show the
smallest percentage of approval. Overall, every tenth woman and every tenth
man spoke positively about democracy. Between the ages of 20 and 50 years,
our speakers become less positive with age, until the group of participants
aged 50 and older again shows a more positive than average attitude.
A negative attitude toward democracy (average 22%) is displayed partic
ularly by farmers (39%) and soldiers with more than 6 years of service
(32%). Lower numbers of a markedly disapproving attitude toward democ
racy are documented for:
University graduates: 15%
High school graduates: 15%
Housewives: i4 % 4
Women: 13%
The men show almost double the women’s percentage of rejection (25%).
Ambivalent attitudes toward democracy are characterized by their enor
mous breadth and relatively high uniformity.
Quantitative Analyses — 75
‘ lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.1
More than two-thirds of all speakers on the topic (68%) display neither
an unreserved commitment to democracy nor a radical rejection. Groups
showing above-average ambivalence are:
University graduates: 79%
Women: 77%
Housewives: 76%
High school graduates: 75%
We questioned what this high percentage of speakers who feel neither
cold nor hot toward democracy actually means and examined it in relation
to the other statements against the background of the group atmosphere.5
Even if we hesitate to regard ambivalent reactions generally as essentially
rationalizations of underlying rejection (which they certainly are in many
cases), we have to state at least that the broad zone of ambivalence pervad
ing all statistical groups clearly demonstrates that among two-thirds of our
“population”6 no definite attitude had emerged at the time of our research.
This would mean that the large majority was probably susceptible to posi
tive as well as negative influences. This interpretation is complemented by
the small percentage of approving and disapproving participants (except
for the two exceptions mentioned above). It is disquieting at least that, on
average, the number of outright enemies of a democratic system is double
that of its unreserved friends.
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~ 76
To the extent that we can discern a regularity from the relatively small
range between the percentages of the gradations, one can say the fol
lowing: it seems as if the personal negative attitude toward democracy
decreases with increasing educational level.7 Yet the negative attitude
does not decrease in favor of a commitment to democracy but in favor of
an increase in ambivalent statements. The inverse picture appears for
the length of military service, where the rejection grows dramatically
with increasing years of service, mainly at the expense of ambivalent
attitudes.8
80
60
48%
40
20
ψ ^ ^
Yrs Military Service
Figure 3.2
Attitudes toward Jews For comparison’s sake, we reduce the four grades
of attitudes toward Jews to three—positive, negative, and ambivalent. By
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~ y8
Approve ] Ambivalent
•lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.3
Table 3.2. Groups deviating from the average frequency of positive reactions
by 6% or more in their frequency of non-anti-Semitic attitudes
Table 3.3. Groups deviating from the average frequency by 7% or more in their
frequency of ambivalent attitudes toward Jews
80
60
51%
40
20
Figure 3.4
Table 3.4. Groups deviating from the average by 10% or more in the frequency
of negative attitudes toward the West
Attitudes toward the East A look at Figure 3.5 seems to prove that the
overwhelming majority of our participants has a fixed attitude toward the
East. More than four-fifths of all speakers speak against the East (83%),
Group Experiment and Other Writings — - 82
Figure 3.5
about one out of twenty supports the ideology and policy of the Soviet-
Russian domain, and only 12% of the speakers on the topic express am
bivalence. The frequency of ambivalent attitudes amounts to only one-
third of the average frequency of ambivalent speakers for all seven major
topics (37%). No other topic has such a low level of ambivalence.
Doubts on the explanatory power of this picture arise, however, when
we look at the degree of participation in the discussion. At 31% it is sig
nificantly below the average (39%), and we again have to ask ourselves
what the silence of more than two-thirds of our participants means. Did
they not speak because they agreed with the disapproving remarks of the
speakers, or did they not want to oppose the dominant opinion of their
group? Or were they afraid of reprisals which could arise for them in case
of a Russian invasion due to their rejection of the East?15 Reports from
our moderators permit the conclusion that—at least in some cases—the
silence meant agreement with the disapproving remarks. We cannot yet
say to what extent this interpretation is valid or how much other motives
might have affected the silent participants. Even more than for all of the
other topics, the results of the quantitative analysis apply only to the speak
ers themselves.
Thus, even though we cannot say anything certain about the actual atti
tude of our “population” toward the East, the same reaction of almost ev
ery statistical group presents an impressive example of what one says and
what one is expected to say.
Quantitative Analyses ~ 83
Very few groups deviate from the average frequency of rejection by even
around eight percentage points.16 These groups are high school graduates
and white-collar workers. Their speakers’ antagonism against the East is
expressed at a frequency of around 90%. The other extreme—if we can
talk at all about extremes in the face of such small percentage differences—
features students, with only 73% disapproval, young people of 20 years of
age or less (75%), and, strangely enough, farmers (74%).
The frequency of approval of the East varies between zero and 17%.
Deviations of 1% or more from the average in favor of the East emerge
among farmers, with the shocking frequency figure of 18%,* war partici
pants with less than 2 years of service (11%), 20-35-year-olds, participants
age 50 and older, and those with a grade school education (7% each).
On the other hand, there are no uncritical remarks on the East among
participants 20 years of age and less and among high school graduates;
among university graduates, white-collar workers, and the 3 5-50-year-olds
the frequency of approval of the East amounts to 2% to 3%.
Larger deviations from the average ambivalent attitude can be found
only among participants 20 years of age and less and among students
(25% and 24% higher frequency) on the one hand, and, on the other
hand, among the oldest age group, high school graduates, and farmers
(7-8% lower frequency).
The difference in frequency among the age groups and the other statisti
cal groups is either too small or too inconsistent to infer regularities from
it. The attitude of the male and female speakers toward the East is virtu
ally identical (as is their participation in the discussion). In contrast to
their attitudes toward other topics, the positive attitude (i.e., the rejection
of the East) increases among the speakers with longer terms of service.17
* It is unclear how farmers could agree 18% of the time when the top degree of agreement
was reported as 17% in the same paragraph.—Eds.
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 84
80- —
60- —
40- — — 36%
20- — A
■ i i ■ r r n ■ n ■ · ι ι·ι~η i ■
■1
0-
<r & * v?
Yrs Military Service
Figure 3.6
the discussion. Most silent were women and young people 20 years of age
or less; only about every fourth participant from these two groups spoke
on the topic.
Approximately two-thirds of the speakers (59%) rejected rearmament,
a little bit fewer than one-third approved of it with reservations (29%),
and only every eighth speaker (12%) was an unqualified spokesman for
armament [Tables 3.5 and 3.6].
These average numbers, however, offer too crude a picture. The differ
ences between the attitudes of many groups are particularly interesting.
While the average rate of approval of rearmament shows a frequency of
only 12%, there are groups with a frequency between 18% and 24% and
others among whom it sinks as low as 4%.
In contrast, the frequency of negative attitudes increases to 83% (un
skilled workers),18 while the lowest percentage of speakers who are hostile
toward rearmament amounts to 38% (20 years of age or less).19
Remarkably, the frequency of disapproval among unskilled workers is
double that among students and participants aged 20 years or less.
Also, those who approve conditionally of remilitarization are distrib
uted very unevenly among the statistical groups.
The tabulation of the numbers shows that the first impression of an
overwhelming, unconditional rejection of remilitarization has to be cor
rected. Among strata that are particularly important for the formation
of public opinion and also among a large part of those who would have
Quantitative Analyses 8y
Table 3.5. Groups deviating from the average by 3% or more in the frequency
of approving attitudes toward remilitarization
Table 3.6. Groups deviating from the average by 5% or more in the frequency
of ambivalence toward remilitarization
to supply officers and enlisted men of the new army, unconditional and
conditional approval were more frequent and disapproval rarer than on
average.
The frequency of approving remarks increases with higher education
from 9% (grade school) to 19% (high school) to drop back among the
university graduates to 7% due to other overcompensating influences.
This hypothetical influence of the degree of education on the frequency of
positive reactions toward the topic is displayed impressively in Table 3.7.20
The higher the level of education, the more positive the attitude (mea
sured by the sum of approvals and conditional disapprovals) and the smaller
the unconditional rejection.
As to age groups, the approval sinks from 24% frequency among the
youngest to 8% among the 35-50-year-olds, while the frequency of dis
approvals almost doubles between the young people 20 years old or less
and the 35-50-year-olds—from 38% to 65%, only to turn again to a posi
tive direction among the participants over 50 years of age.
Women, men, and all war participants of 2 years or more of service
display approximately the same average frequency among the three
categories.21
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 86
(in % of frequency)
I π- II
I II Positive plus III
Groups Positive Ambivalent Ambivalent*1 Negative
Grade school 9 25 34 66
Junior high 18 22 40 60
High school 19 33 52 48
University 7 47 54 46
Average of all 12 29 41 59
speakers
aAdding rows I and II is methodologically justified since an examination of the tran
scripts as well as the reports of the assistants in the sessions showed that the majority of
ambivalent reactions evinced approval “at a price.”
German Self-Assessment
in % of people who responded in each category for this subject*
30%
<f * * ?
Yrs Military Service
Figure 3.7
Table 3.8. Groups deviating from the average by 9% or more in the frequency
of critical remarks about the Germans
Table 3.9. Speakers of the smallest professional groups according to critical and
ethnocentric judgments
(in %, based on the number of speakers)
Table 3.10. Groups deviating from the average by 6% or more in the frequency
of ethnocentric remarks
<υ _
"□ So
0> 5 ^
-Ö 2 12
3 o o
1L»1^ Ice—1 u. JT
Ö
JDu-s a>i. ce
L» û£ _0C
ΛM Ifi Îa
yy~\ _ O b 7^Γ ττ-Ό
u^, 00 o •g _ w
C 00 o
a | i <υ K 00 o1 4^- H1 r^1, I\ 00 C H 2 0N01 HT1j-
^ 0\ O
2 rl i vL
4c
-1
OJC
c
O
υ>
L
Λ
5CΛ
L
3
O T3<υ
3
‘■Μ
< 2 -ao
<υ +
•B 2 -a -a
cce c 0
ce o
>s £O HN
os 5kΛ
* k*
i/5 -C
V> ___
c a> + 2 ^ CS S ^ ^0
ls~\ f<S >s μ >S H tv iL H
-Ç ON
O Ci H O ~ _h _~1_ °l/~, -3
1_ 3. .ÊP N M
2 ,+ h X + -3
+ X i ,+
ce
u
U
C
O
U ’■
cCE
eJ
-a
cL> <υ 3
£ a ÖJD ■
UÜΌ
<
Ui
U
Ο
ε
■CΌ
eU« __
Λ
75
gC ^οοN S ^^ Μ
Η
^ Ό >s Η Η
[2 J , J , νο ϋ
75
U
<υ
-*
U 2*->
§ C J*
! J2 ο 2
03 U £ Λ
— Ο w
^ > -α .υW ^£
> ri S
·~ Μ ο <«- Μ «Λ ο (\ £ ^ Ο /T ^ 0\
-C μ VO · - ΟΝ 00 C ^ ° ° ο Μ ΟΝ | \
& ± + 3 ± ± ë ^ + Ζ + + $ + + I, ± ±
«>
75
*_ _ g _ _
S2 00 Μ ^ ΙΤ\ 1/*>
3 0 \ "Ο tJ- Η
Ο ΗΗ □ Η μ
IÜ Ä + +.
<
υυ
’>
U
C U
.2 ^
% ο
^ο ε
5
>η
Ο Λ
Η>
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 92
Attitude Types
in order of their values
Figure 3.8 illustrates the order of the twenty statistical groups, ranked
according to the indices computed from the attitudes toward the major
topics.
The table of the types of attitudes seems to contradict all of our previous
experience with the attitude of our participants. Just three out of twenty
groups have to be classified as negative. When referring to the predominantly
negative attitude of our participants, we proceeded from average values of
attitude toward all or individual topics for all or individual groups. No mat
ter how one calculates the average, it is always apparent that the average
frequency of the negative attitude is considerably higher than that of the
positive attitude. The computation of the indices, however, was based on the
percentage deviation from the overall average of all groups for each topic.
This is to say that the [three] groups with negative attitude types are more
negative on average than the already largely negative average and vice versa.
With all due reservations arising from the data as well as from the
method applied, we can make the following assertions about the individ
ual statistical groups of our participants:
i . Women are more likely to display a positive attitude toward demo
cratic values than men. They rank among the top of all positive
speakers.
Quantitative Analyses — - 93
2. The youngest and the oldest age groups express themselves posi
tively concerning the problems of our major topics considerably
more often than the two age groups between 20 and 50 years; the
frequency of negative statements increases from the first to the third
age group and decreases subsequently.
3. Among our participants, education relates to attitude in a curious
way. Participants with a high school diploma but without a univer
sity education are ranked in the top of the positive part of our order,
while speakers with a university education belong to the opposite
extreme. The speakers with only grade school or junior high educa
tion show an average type of attitude.32 On the other hand, ambiva
lence increases with educational level.
4. Since only six occupations were represented strongly enough to
justify a separate quantitative analysis, we can make statements only
about these few professions. Housewives and students make up the
positive extreme; farmers the negative counterpart. In the category
of average attitudes, white-collar, skilled, and unskilled workers
follow housewives and students after a considerable gap.
5. Furthermore, there seems to be a clear correlation between length of
military service (which for our older participants coincides with the
time between their entry into war and their captivity) and attitude
toward the major topics: the four groups for length of service can be
easily arranged on a scale from a more positive attitude among the
speakers without military service through the clearly more negative
attitude of the two groups of 0-2 years and 2 to 6 years of service
to the extremely negatively minded group of war participants with
6 years of service or more. Parallel to this curve runs the increasing
participation in the discussion with increasing term of service. This
increase in negative attitude with increasing military service is
understandably also seen among those age groups whose male
participants were largely also doing a longer term of service.
Due to space restrictions, we reproduce here only the extremes from the
first four major statistical groups as well as the skilled and unskilled workers’
groups, which are classified as averages, from among the twenty profiles. We
also discuss the profile compiled from the statements of all speakers related
to all seven major topics for the average attitude of the entire circle of
participants.
Figure 3.9
Table 3.12. Topics for which the frequency of attitudes of female speakers
deviates by 11% or more from the average distribution of attitudes
(in % of deviation)
For five out of the seven major topics, female speakers’ opinions are
more positive than the general average, and, likewise, their negative state
ments are less frequent for five topics. For five topics, ambivalent state
ments are more frequent in this group than among the average and less
frequent for two (Jews and remilitarization). The high percentage of am
bivalent statements for the topic of democracy (more than three quarters
of speakers compared with about two-thirds for the general average) is
striking.
Women participated a roughly average amount in the discussion, but not
evenly: for the first four topics the participation in the discussion is 2%-22%
Quantitative Analyses — 95
lower, for the remaining three it is 3% - i 8% higher. For the following top
ics, female speakers display considerable deviations from the average dis
tribution of attitude [Table 3.12].
The indices of the test topics confirm the general view: for the topics of
complicity and Jews as well as for the topics of the West and democracy,
women present the highest positive number (+94 and +140). This does not
come only from the above-average frequency of speakers’ positive opin
ions toward those topics, but also from the considerably below-average
frequency of negative speakers for five of the topics.
In contrast, the attitude toward remilitarization is more negative than
average, a behavior much more pronounced among housewives (n = 237;
positive -25% , ambivalent -14% , negative +12%). In contrast to the
alarming general average of our participants for the attitude toward demo
cratic values, women as a group stand out as by far one of the most posi
tive. However, the high percentage of ambivalent statements, particularly
for topics like democracy and complicity, urges caution in evaluating the
results.
Men The profile contrasts in virtually every respect with that of women.
Figure 3.10 shows that the frequency of positive statements is predomi
nantly below average, while the frequency of negative attitudes is above
average for six of seven topics. However, these deviations from the average
exceed the 15% limit only for two topics.34
Men’s Attitudes
in % of men who responded in each category for this topic*
Democracy
Germany
Guilt
Jews
Remilitarization
The East
The West
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive I I Ambivalent Negative
‘ lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.10
Group Experiment and Other Writings — ’ 96
Table 3.13.
The West and
Guilt and Jews Democracy
Men -4 6 "3 4
Women +25 +40
Men more negative in attitude 71 74
than women, in points
-1— 1— i— 1— L T T 1— 1—
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive I I Ambivalent Negative
’ lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.11
is above the average, and that of negative attitudes below it, and some of
the differences are quite sizable. For the topics of complicity, the West, re
militarization, and the East, the frequency of negative statements is the
lowest of all statistical groups.
Yet this positive impression is disturbed by a series of factors. In addition
to the small total number of groups, it is important to note the above-
average frequency of ambivalent attitudes, with the exceptions of the topics
of democracy38 and Jews, and the above average frequency of ambivalent
attitudes as well as the abnormally low participation in the discussion.
These young people rank at the top of all groups with respect to the average
frequency of ambivalent attitudes and at the bottom with respect to partici
pation in the discussion.
All these data lead to the conclusions that our young people have a ten
dency to respond positively to democratic values in general, but that their
attitudes are still rather undecided and, hence, probably also very suscep
tible to influence.
in % of people in the group who spoke in each main category for this topic*
Guilt
The West
Democracy
Remilitarization
Jews
Germany
The East
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive I I Ambivalent Negative
•lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.12
Guilt
r — 1— 1--------- 1--------- 1--------- Γ ΠΖ
— ---------
--------- 1T
----------
-------- 1T---------T
1---------r
_ L
The West
--------- 1--------- r~---- - ■ri “ "“ i1*-- ,, jl·,. -T . .
______ 1______ 1______ 1______ L_
Democracy
--------- 1--------- 1--------- 11--------- 1—------ 1--------- 1--------- 1---------
Remilitarization
--------- 1--------- 1--------- 1 ------ 1 ,1 J______
Jews i ^ H 1 1
Germany
The East
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive I I Ambivalent Negative
*lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.13
Figure 3 . 1 4
Figure 3.15
similarly negative to the profile constructed from the behavior of only 135
participants.
Table 3.15. Topics for which the distribution of students’ attitudes deviates by
15% or more from the frequency of the general attitude
(in % of deviation)
Democracy +40 ~ z 3
Germans +33 -* 5 -3 6
Jews +31 -31 +5
Remilitarization +17 +62 “ 34
The West +60 -28
Guilt +21 -18
groups, both men and women, and different degrees of education. When
comparing this group to other profiles it is immediately clear that we are
dealing with one of our positive groups. The students take the lead in the
frequency of positive speakers and in the low frequency of negative state
ments. Yet the spectrum of ambivalence is broad in their case, too; they rank
third place there, after the university graduates and the 20-year-olds. Their
participation in the discussion is above average.
The profile presents striking deviations from the average (Table 3.15).
Their relatively high positive and relatively low negative frequencies for
the four test topics are remarkable.44 Furthermore, their very frequent am
bivalence toward the topics of the West and remilitarization together with
a relatively low frequency of negative statements toward these two topics
is also interesting.
One can probably infer from the profile above that students at the time
of our survey show a strong disposition toward accepting democratic val
ues, but that a broad area remains for influencing their final decisions.
Farmers The exact opposite can be said about the speakers who were
farmers, who present in all respects the extreme of negative attitudes among
our participants. The frequency of all positive statements is far below
average, that of negative statements far above average, and the ambiva
lent spectrum is significantly smaller than for the average of all groups.
The farmers participate in the discussion about as frequently as the
average.
Table 3.16 shows that the farmers also outstrip all other groups in
regard to negative (and low positive) attitudes on individual topics. They
attain by far the highest negative number for the indices for the four test
topics.45 The far-below-average spectrum of ambivalence indicates that we
Quantitative Analyses — -103
. 1 'π 1 1 1 — 1— 1—
Guilt
_J_______1_______1____ I 1 1 Γ Γ, "ηΡ'ώΡ jîffiMCi
The West ■1
_J_______1 1 Γ^*Τ Ί ^
Democracy t
_J_______1 1 J 1 1 T .ggMMfljMBiL
Remilitarization ■
___1_ _ _ _ 1___ “Τ ~ ' t “ Ί i J" ΐ
Jews IITP — 11_ _ _ _ _ 1,___ _ _____ ______ ______ _____
□ ____ —
Germany a i_ _ _ _ Γ Ί i 1 ^... Τ '
The East
L -l - 4— i i I 1 1 1
10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive Ambivalent Negative
•lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.16
Table 3.16. Topics for which the distribution of farmers’ attitudes deviates by
14% or more from the frequency of the general attitude
(in % of deviation)
Skilled Workers The following two profiles of skilled and unskilled workers
present a middle position among our twenty statistical groups. Ordered by
the index for the attitude toward six topics (without the East), the skilled
and unskilled workers are in the average attitude type. Ranked by the index
for their attitude toward the test topics, however, both groups prove to be
rather positively minded, and they receive the seventh and eighth positions in
that scale.
Despite much similarity, the two groups show differences that may be
important for their evaluation.
For some topics, the frequency of positive statements is significantly above
average (Jews +43%, democracy and complicity both +20%, Germans
+ 14%) and of negative statements below average (complicity -8% , de
mocracy -18%).
On the other hand, the attitude toward the West and toward remili
tarization is not insignificantly more negative than the average. The higher-
than-average frequency of criticism against remilitarization probably re
flects the brusquely dismissive attitude of the Social Democratic Party.
It is part of the tradition of this group that they attain the highest num
ber of all statistical groups in the frequency of positive statements on the
topic of Jews. The frequency of ambivalent speakers is much lower among
the skilled workers than the average—on the scale arranged according to
the frequency of ambivalent attitudes, this group is in the third to last po
sition. In its decidedness to speak in favor or against a topic, it ranks be
hind only unskilled workers and farmers. The participation in the discussion
among skilled workers is also far below average: they rank at the fourth to
last position.
It does not quite fit the common image of the skilled German worker
with his traditional union and political schooling that his profile shows a
frequency of 70% ambivalent speakers for the topic of democracy. This
surprising finding is emphasized by the ratio of positive to negative atti
tudes for the topics of complicity (1:8) and the West (1:8.5), both of which
deviate considerably from the ideal of a democratic attitude. Insofar as
representative significance can be attached to our group of skilled workers,
political education still has major work to do.
Quantitative Analyses ~ 105
Guilt
The West
Democracy
Remilitarization
Jews
Germany
The East
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive 1 I Ambivalent Negative
•lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.17
Guilt
The West
Democracy
Remilitarization
Jews
Germany
The East
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
■ ■ 1 Positive I 1Ambivalent Negative
•lines denote mean percentages of approve, ambivalent, and disapprove with respect to all data
Figure 3.18
Table 3.17. Indices (sum of the percentage deviation from the average) of the
frequency of ambivalent attitudes among four degrees of education
of ambivalent speakers for the topic, and the ratio of positive to negative
statements is about 1:1.
The frequency of critical statements toward remilitarization is above
80%, a number that only occurs elsewhere among the negative attitudes
toward the East. While the unskilled workers rank third to last in the par
ticipation in the discussion, they uphold, as was already mentioned, the
first position in their definitiveness for or against a topic. There is proba
bly a close correlation between the frequency of ambivalent statements
and the degree of education; the latter seems to increase with the former
[Table 3.17].
Since the majority of unskilled workers possesses only a grade school edu
cation, this would at least partially explain their definitiveness. We probably
have to trace it back less to political maturity than to the overpowering
force of the dominant ideology.
Negative
Figure 3.19
Guilt
The West
Democracy
Remilitarization
Jews
Germany
The East
0 10 20 30 40 50 60 70 80 90 100
Positive 1 I Ambivalent Negative
Figure 3 . 2 0
Apart from the topic of the East, the frequency of positive attitudes pre
dominates only for the topic of German self-assessment, namely in rela
tion to the negative speakers as well as to the ambivalent ones.
Significantly more speakers participated in the discussion of the first
three topics than of the other four. The lowest average participation in the
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 108
Table 3.18. Ratio of positive to negative statements for six major topics
among all participants
discussion is found for the topic of Jews (=22%), the highest for the topic
of democracy (=53%).
Integration Phenomena in
Group Discussions
i. General Information
* The qualitative analysis is presented in full in the companion volume. Guilt and Defense.
—Eds.
* The text refers to sozialen Kontrolle and to “social control” (English in the original).
—Eds.
Group Experiment and Other 'Writings ~ no
2. On Terminology
A short discussion of the two basic concepts of group and integration is
appropriate for terminological reasons. Both have been used in sociology
with widely varying meanings, so we have to outline what these terms mean
in this study.
The Concept o f Group There are three characteristic types of group con
cepts in traditional sociological literature. Some authors (e.g., Oppenheimer;
Geiger; Bogardus)2 define the concept of group in such a way that it be
comes a collective name for most social structures. Others (particularly
Sombart, Vierkandt, L. v. WieseŸ use the term group for a specific category
of social structures. And sometimes the concept of group is hypostatized. It
is understood as an entity that preexists its members. Thus, for Vierkandt,4
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions ~~ h i
for example, a group is a structure that has a life of its own, is an entity
for itself, and has its own conditions, characteristics, and patterns of
behavior.
Comparing the actuality of our discussion groups with these concepts of
group, the first of these formal concepts seems to be most applicable to
our group discussions. We will provide closer—and if necessary changing—
specifications of our groups in the course of this investigation. A first fea
ture which all of our groups have in common can already be indicated
here: the groups are small in the sense that they have few members, and,
hence, there are immediate personal contacts among all members.
The word group is an example of “occasional expressions” in logic.*
This means that, by nature, group is an open concept defying any univer
sal definition. It can be compared to the X in algebra, which can be in
serted into completely different formulas and the specific value of which
results from the respective formula. By analogy, the concept of group gains
meaning only when the structure identified by it is understood concretely
through the social situation and constellation. If the nature of the group is
to be specified, one has to proceed from this insight, not from a formal
definition.
* The term is from Edmund Husserl, Logical Investigations, (New York: Humanities
Press, 1970), vol. 1, Section 26. “Occasional expressions” are expressions whose meaning
depends on the particular context of their use.—Eds
Group Experiment and Other Writings 112
i. Strangerhood
All arranged groups shared the phase of strangerhood at the beginning of
the session, although this varied in nature. We will begin the presentation
of our model and analysis with this phase.
The investigator opens the session with a brief explanation about the pur
pose of the discussion, and the assistant plays the base stimulus on a tape
recorder.
The phase of strangerhood at the beginning of the discussion is marked
by cautious phrases and prophylactic clichés. Numerous such words and
phrases such as ‘T think,” “a little,” “sure enough,” “perhaps,” and similar
can be found at the beginning. The implicit question of what others might
say is always dominant. The participants are, moreover, uncertain as to the
attitude of the moderator.
In our discussion, Mrs. P. is the first one to try to learn something about
the moderator’s attitude. The moderator repeats a passage from the base
stimulus:
In.: Well, Mr. Colburn says that there is a risk that they (the Germans) will
follow Stalin or Hitler because they long for a strong man.
P.: Surely, this is not the case . . . No, we are wiser now, don’t you think?
She addresses her question to the moderator in order to discern his atti
tude. He enjoys a certain authority, formally supported by the design of the
experiment. In the arranged groups in particular, the participants focus on
the moderator at the beginning of the session. He is expected to lead the
discussion firmly. The moderator does not answer the question, but passes it
on to the group:
In.: You think that we have become wiser through experience? Ladies and
Gentlemen, what do you think about it?
M.: That one has learned something from it, from the past. It’s probably not
so simple.
The reaction of the other cannot yet be predicted, and, thus, the partici
pants formulate their statements as tentatively as possible. Accordingly,
Mr. M. says:
M.: Of course, an accused person will always deny his guilt. This is a
completely natural phenomenon. At least, he will find grounds for
his justification. In my view, this is an obvious thing, if a German is
judging from his German perspective. We have to be clear about the
fact that an Englishman also judges only from his perspective. But what
appears to be red from the English perspective can appear to be blue
from the German perspective. The question of which of these two
representatives of those perspectives is right would have to be decided
by a third person.
2. Orientation
In the next phase of discussion, people try to gain certainty about the at
titudes of the other participants.
A common way to evoke group reactions so one can adjust one’s habit
to them is by referring to supposedly popular opinions. Such contribu
tions often start with the words “people say.” By distancing oneself in such
a way from the opinion and passing it off as somebody else’s, a speaker
can adhere to it in case of agreement from the group, while possible objec
tions can be neutralized by retreating from the referenced opinion without
consequences.
The following example is typical for referring to an opinion to elicit the
group’s attitude toward it. The [female] participant A. continues the dis
cussion in our model session:
A.: One often hears older and younger people say: No, it won’t work like
this. Here in Germany there has to be some man at the top, someone has
to dictate. Otherwise, it won’t work with the Germans. This opinion is
actually quite common . . .
The group does not approve of the referenced opinion. Yet, after a few
minutes, Mrs. A. ventures a second time in a similar direction, i.e., she again
Group Experiment and Other Writings — ' 116
The other participants disagree with her excitedly, several at the same
time. Mrs. A. is lectured that one must not expect the group to tolerate
such a view. She reacts immediately and hurries to add:
A.: That’s exactly the bad thing about it, that it is repeated and that one
does not get to the bottom of things and that one does not actually make
an effort to take up democracy, intellectually.
Other participants act similarly to Mrs. A., advancing views for which
agreement is unlikely as those of other people or groups.
If participants want to learn about the group’s attitude on delicate sub
jects, they like to start with harmless remarks, in order to touch the hot
potato only bit by bit. They, so to say, increase the dose of caution in the
statements. That this procedure is intended to provoke the group’s reac
tion, which is necessary for their own orientation, is demonstrated by the
words of the participant E.:
£.: In order to arouse disagreement, I want to express myself in an exagger
ated way. Since 1945, as they have tried to force the concept of “democ
racy” on us in Germany, this feels to me like remedial help for children
who have been held back . . .
His preface shields him in any case. If disagreement emerges, he can re
treat and say that he was trying to provoke; if no disagreement emerges—
and this is the case in our discussion—he can further develop his idea and
reveal that what he called an exaggerated expression is, as will be shown,
just a moderate part of his true view. He goes on to speak of National So
cialism as an “experiment,” which “unfortunately” failed, because it was
impossible to keep the leadership under control. After that he marks his true
view as follows:
£.: I believe every place will get to this point in the not too distant future,
that is, an authoritarian form of government, in which democracy still
functions insofar as it occurs as background organization without
impeding decisions as such.—An American told me recently that the
United States is governed by a democracy that is really corrupt, although
he had drunk a lot of whiskey,.
It is easy to construe the affinity between the sentences cited first and
last. E. wants to say that there is no reason for a German to learn to strive
for a certain form of government if its downfall elsewhere is already
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions ~~ u y
3. Adaptation
The adaptation phase clarifies which people within the group adopt which
behavioral patterns. It is comparable to a crystallization process, the result
of which leads to a determinable structure of the group opinion.
The same form of appearance of adaptation can have different causes.
Two of the most important should be mentioned: (1) the adapting partici
pant is labile or unstructured and actually adapts to another participant’s
view, sometimes without consciously accounting for it; (2) the adapting
participant adopts another’s attitude only outwardly, in order to conform,
while in reality he thinks completely differently and disguises his true opin
ion in the face of others.
There are two other behavioral patterns that, from a psychological point
of view, have to be separated from both of those above. Yet they often be
come manifest in a similar way: (3) a participant can actually be persuaded
by the arguments of another; (4) a participant thinks that an earlier speaker
took the words out of his mouth, i.e., both share specific, closely related
dispositions for opinions; thus, the later speaker would have expressed the
same thing as the earlier one in any case. These two processes cannot, of
course, be called adaptation. In an actual discussion these types of adapta
tion overlap one another. For our example discussion, we only make use of
the first three types.
Reflecting earlier remarks is a clear sign of adaptation and sometimes
becomes manifest midsentence. Our participant T. tries to make up for a
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~ 118
The words “or much more” (vielmehr) start the adaptation, because T. is
mildly alarmed to remember from earlier remarks that two group members
identified themselves as having been expelled. Of course, they would have
to feel offended if someone discussed their fate in such unfavorable terms.
T. cannot change the content of what has already been said; he tries by
way of form to make up for it by stopping his idea and talking about some
thing else in order to wash away the bad impression. He seamlessly con
nects to the sentence concerning cannon fodder:
T. : This is exactly how it’s going to be, when a troop is deployed, that the
Germans are located where things are worst, because not enough people
died in the bombings . . .
This is a very fine-tuned taking into consideration of what had been said
earlier, which now has its effect only formally. Most often, however, adap
tation proceeds more primitively, in that a participant directly adapts to
another’s attitude.
Sometimes it seems as if the later speaker maintains the idea that he ar
rived at his view without being influenced, while in principle he simply re
formulates the idea expressed earlier by another participant. The following
example is a case in point. Referring to the change in America’s political re
lations to Soviet Russia in the years after 1945, the participant T. says about
the American statesmen and their knowledge of Russia:
T : . . . in the end people suppose that a politician has a long view . . . The
entire (Bolshevistic) system actually has already existed for 20 years, and
there are enough emigrants who fled from Russia, who found a new home
in America . . .
Either he thinks that his stated opinion is entirely his own or he wants
to evoke this impression, because he does not refer to T.’s contribution.
This is a case of unconscious adaptation.
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions 119
The few following words of the group member T. shed light on the social-
psychological element effective during adaptation. By all means, adapta
tion is not always performed for the sake of others whom people wish to
please or whom people do not wish to have as enemies. Adaptation can well
be an indication of something lying deeper: the idea that the group is an
objective authority capable of deciding on correctness and incorrectness, on
truth or falsity. This is a symptom of clinging to authority. This also comes
through in T.’s words:
The several others cited by T. are not participants in the discussion, yet
it stands to reason that he will say later: I participated in a discussion in
which people were of the same opinion. It is comforting to find opinions
to which one is predisposed in a group or to have them confirmed by it,
i.e., to experience the kind of collective reinforcement that American soci
ology calls “social support” [English].13
Sociologists and psychologists have repeatedly stated that group mem
bers are inclined to regard their group as an objective authority. In the end,
trust in the working of democratic institutions is based on the assumption
that the mistakes and eccentric opinions of individuals are cancelled out in
a sufficiently large collectivity. It is believed that, using Simmel's phrasing,
“collective opinion approaches objective truth.”14 If the individual observes
other people sharing his experiences and opinions, the content of these ex
periences and opinions is “transplanted” from a sphere of pure subjectivity
into objectivity, as Vierkandt says. This is, he assumes, due to the fact that
the group is the natural source of objectivity.15 As Durkheim highlights, the
sanctioning of the group as objective authority causes adaptations, often in
the form of mere imitation. Imitation within a discussion simply means
repetition, as in the following passage:
D.: Let’s take an example from recent history for illustration. The German
people are absolutely against a war. Yet, we find the press full of topics
like military buildup and remilitarization, even though we have a
democratic government. Where, now, is the voice of the people?
Shortly after this, a second speaker puts the same idea in very similar
words:
M .:. . . even though we have a democracy, even though the German people
want peace, we find in the press the echo of war and war cries, the
tendency to make a possible war palatable to the people .. .
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~ 120
4. Familiarity
All the phases described so far could have appeared in any discussion, even
one that does not develop toward firm group integration. The decision as
to whether the group finally integrates or splits is made only in the famil
iarity phase. (Of course, whether its members act in parallel with one an
other in an atomistic and unrelated way is decided earlier.) For our model
we leave aside the possibility of splitting.
Only familiarity allows for a general group consensus, as it is now con
stituted in our example discussion. Meanwhile an atmosphere was created
in which the participants agree in principle and where a weak difference in
opinion shows itself at most in insignificant details, such as whether chari
table gifts or “frontline soldier”-packages were sent to the German soldiers
in Russia during the Second World War. Yet on the questions they deem es
sential, group members tend toward consensus in this phase. Thus, Mrs. M.
and Mrs. A. confirm their agreement:
M.: May I quickly say on that: a people will come together if it hasn’t been
filled with hatred, right.
A.: That’s it: A people comes together!
In.: That’s a very important thought.
M.: Yes, a people always finds itself.
A.: And also politics is just hatred in my eyes, where politics is done, it’s just
agitation against one country or another.
Large parts of the discussion consist of such passages, which are accom
panied by approving murmurs and affirming nods from the listeners. One
contribution fits the next so well that sometimes one can succumb to the
illusion that only one person is speaking. Often, one participant even inter
rupts another in order to complement, substantiate, or strengthen his state
ment. Women in particular easily reach this level of mutual consent. In this
state of the group it happens now and then that a participant, completely
used to agreeing, inadvertently endorses contradicting views, without his or
the group’s realizing it.16 If a participant contradicts himself, if a later state
ment is not in tune with an earlier one, this usually remains unnoticed by the
group. It has, so to say, a short memory. It is crucial that a second statement
contradicting the first is not contrary to the momentary group consensus.
Otherwise, it would be suspect and would certainly not evade attention.
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions 121
Yet when the investigator poses the specific question to the entire group
of whether they agree with T’s opinion—Russia and America agree on the
* Henry Morgenthau Jr., U.S. Treasury Secretary during the war, had proposed a plan for
de-industrializing Germany after the war so as to prevent Germany from being able to remili
tarize. The plan was never formally implemented, though it served as a symbol for the belief
that America wanted to destroy Germany through a harsh, vengeful peace. It is not incidental
that Morgenthau was the highest-ranking Jew in American government. See Jeffrey K. Olick,
In the House of the Hangman: The Agonies of German Defeat, 1943-1949. Chicago: Univer
sity of Chicago Press, 2005.
Group Experiment and Other Writings — - 122
T.: I was mistaken in this point, because I don’t want to say now that they
just want to destroy the Germans. They just use the Germans; the
ideologies of those two are opposed to each other, and the Germans are
the best instrument against this.
5. Conformity
In our model session, we call conformity the phase during which there is no
deviation of individuals within the group from the general tendency of opin
ion expressed. A consensus has been reached allowing no space for remnants
of deviation, let alone for antagonism. The members identify with one an
other. They feel united. We can see this clearly in their behavior; they speak
more and more frequently of themselves as “we.” The individual seems to be
only a spokesman, even a function of the group. To a larger and larger de
gree, his contributions conform to the group opinion. They are, in a way,
molded by it. Any individuality is more and more renounced. Quite fre
quently, the group opinion in this phase expresses the dominant opinion.22
A major motive of conformity in our model group is collective defense
against reproach. It takes the form of reckoning: American acts of war are
used to compensate for the extent of German guilt. The following passage
documents this attitude and, at the same time, illustrates how a speaker
starting with light aggression can escalate to outright hostility if he is sup
ported by the group.
At first, when the bombing of city X by the American Air Force comes
up, the participant J. argues, as outlined elsewhere,23 that the destruction
of X was “unfair,” since, in contrast to other cities, no war matériel was
produced there. The next speaker agrees with him and explains that “they”
consciously wanted to commit a crime.
Thereupon J., supported in his views, strikes out with full aggression:
It’s obvious: this was dirty business by the Americans. I have to say here:
The end justifies the means. The Americans didn’t attack many large
heavy industry enterprises (IG-Konzerne). Why? Because the major
capitalists’ dough was in there (approving laughter). Absolutely, it’s still
standing there, the heavy industry tower, it’s still standing upright,
straight as an arrow. Even more, the Volkswagen factory! Not a single
bomb in the Volkswagen factory! Certainly, they did not let it stand to
make us happy that we can build Volkswagens afterward. Again the
capitalists have wound up with significant sums.
It is interesting that J. introduces a completely new aspect to his own
argument and only remains constant in the tendency to attack “the” Ameri
can as the enemy, a tendency for which he can count on the group’s ap
proval. He has judged the group opinion accurately, as the reactions show.
The next speaker starts:
U .:. . . this was a completely clear consideration, since they not only left the
heavy industry factories in one piece, but they also left all the barracks in
one piece .. .
and other speakers deal with the topic similarly.
Group Experiment and Other Writings — ' 124
Freud studied identification for masses, in particular for those who have
a leader.26 At first, a leader seemed to him indispensable for the formation
of masses, i.e., for the emergence of emotional bonds constituting identifi
cation. The individuals identify with one another by mutually accepting
the leader as ideal. Furthermore, the illusion exists that the leader loves all
of them with equal love. Freud himself, however, encouraged an investiga
tion of whether the leader as an object of libidinal aspiration is nonetheless
substitutable for the nature of the group. We will come back to that ques
tion in the next section.
Identification in our group is established such that one person perceives
commonalities with another, i.e., it is a “partial” one according to Freud.
The commonalities exist in that the people agree in either the attitude
or the intensity of the affective charge concerning a certain topic. In part,
we explained the orientation phase as a result of the search for such com
monalities.
In the conformity phase—which we regard as the highest degree of
integration—identification of almost all of the conversation partners with
one another has been accomplished. We also recognize this in the paradoxi
cal appearance that the group members are no longer listening properly to
one another. This demonstrates the primacy of the libidinal factor over ratio
nality. The only ones who listen closely are individuals who want to object,
thus those who have not identified with the others. However, the other par
ticipants, we should perhaps say more precisely, listen with half an ear,
secure in the knowledge of their agreement. They take in what is said enough
so that they can notice glaring deviations from conformity and that they can
register striking words—keywords, as it were—which, beyond the general
tendency of the utterance, are suited to arouse the latent joy of acclaim and
approval. Sometimes, the discussion gets hung up on a striking formulation
like the slogan below: “Think less politically—more economically!”
(Acclamation: Party discipline does not exist!)
K.: Everyone can do what he likes. He just has to pay more attention to the
economic situation.
A .:. . . We are too mired in the parties. We should have a voice from an
economic viewpoint instead.
(Acclamation: More economy and less politics!)
A.: Moreover, I believe that we should not vote based on party membership,
but economically. The party is no longer so interested in the masses. We
saw it before the war, where did that lead with 28 parties, and now it has
come that far again. They are just interest groups in my view. We should
think economically. Because with this party business we’ll go to the dogs,
just like before the war.
(Acclamation: Indeed! Then dictatorship will arise again!)
Group Experiment and Other Writings —’ iz6
K.: I’m of the view, as Mr. A. says, away from the party system, I completely
agree, and setting up economic groups . . .
Z.: In any case, this would be much better, we would again work econom
ically instead of politically. This would be much more reasonable. We
can’t get ahead at all with all these party politics.
Often the topics that the group returns to repeatedly are the sensitive
spots of the respective social group, its specific existential or prestige con
cerns. For example, a sensitive spot for young men who find themselves
confronted with the possibility of being drafted is remilitarization. Or the
question of economic competition from foreign countries for a group of
exporters; or the measures of the Soviet government in a discussion group
made up of inhabitants of the border zone area.
For the observer of group behavior, conformity has a passive appearance.
In this phase the group members let things happen to them; they subordi
nate themselves to the group, to its atmosphere and its vaguely sensed, un
written codex (assimilating to the thinking ratified by the group, the mode
of argumentation etc.). This subordination happens voluntarily in the sense
that there is no apparent individual will to unify the group. The compulsion
for integration is an unconscious phenomenon, not the result of an indi
vidual’s act of will. It can be regarded as proven that the consensus of even
just a majority within the group can have a suggestive effect. We touched
on that when we discussed the group as objective authority. Yet it would
have been premature to assume a suggestive effect already in the famil
iarity phase within the discussion group. As Vierkandt says, the larger
the degree of “communal proximity” (in our terminology: the degree of
integration), the bigger impression the fact of agreement makes upon the
individual.27
Conformity is not only present in passive phenomena, it can become
manifest actively too. This is the case when the unity of the group is exposed
to attacks of any kind. Attempts to question, violate, or disrupt the confor
mity of the group can emanate from individual participants, including the
moderator. If the group is tightly integrated, it answers these attempts by
excluding the attacker at once, by labeling him as enemy, by attacking him
on the group’s behalf. Often the moment of exclusion is audible: the group
laughs at the person concerned.
In our model session it is Ms. S. who is unwilling to approve of or even
put up with each unreasonable argument. She feels compelled to intervene
when the main speaker tries to rationalize his anti-American polemic:
M.: It’s being brought in in a way, since where does all this stuff come from?
It’s just being imported from America.
Ms. S., however, does not cease in her effort to convince different speak
ers that some of their statements are untenable. She fails with this inten
tion, is unable to teach the group; instead, the aggression against her argu
ments spreads to others, and the entire group fights against Ms. S., until, in
the end, she says:
S.: Yes, my standing is very difficult here. There was Mr. M. . . . yes, every
body really is arguing against me!
On the other hand, an individual can enjoy the protection of the collec
tive, to the extent that it is sufficiently integrated. The group members also
feel this, and some almost solicit the group’s protection. Mrs. H. tries to do
so with the following remark:
H. : . . . the Marshall plan does not erase the mistake they (the Americans)
made years ago. Roosevelt was about to . . . already the big evildoer, that
they . . . for God’s sake, b u t. . .
The “for God’s sake” is, as becomes clear from listening to the recording,
just performed shock; basically it is nothing but begging for collective cover.
It is also received with complete understanding by the group laughing ap
provingly. The speaker feels secure in her daring, because she can count on
the group to provide cover. Thus, she mocks her own daring. The expecta
tion of being protected by the group contributes considerably to reducing
psychic blockages which earlier prevented latent attitudes from individuals’
deeper layers from being verbalized.28
The more passively a group member has behaved toward the group’s
stream of opinion, the more his activity, and that of his colleagues in the
group, is aroused when an individual aspires to leadership. Group members
are ready to subordinate themselves to the group as a whole; they withhold
allegiance to an individual who seeks to “lead.” The group is very subtly
sensitive toward such intentions, and reacts with clear rejection of the in
dividual who strives for leadership. This does not preclude one or another
from temporarily winning much acclaim or the group from regarding his
opinion as binding for the group or asking for his comment. But he is not
allowed to exert pressure, to show a desire to dominate.
eluded here. Yet, this would mean that a remarkable phenomenon, which, as
the analysis shows, belongs logically to the process of integration, would
remain disregarded: the fading of the tension, the fading of the intensity of
the discussion.
As if the group has reached a goal with conformity preserved against vari
ous obstacles and has accomplished an achievement after which no further
effort is necessary, the group’s activity decreases in some respects. From the
outside this state is characterized by less value being placed on incisive for
mulations. The contributions become shorter, and fewer interruptions take
place. The content of most statements repeats things that were said earlier or
at least adds to topics already treated. One could exaggerate and say that the
situation appears as if the conversational partners have (almost) nothing left
to say to one another. The following evidence supports this interpretation:
G.: Mr. N., I don’t know if I understood you correctly. I want to make sure.
Do you believe in the possibility of an accord between East and West?
N.: No.
G.: No? Then I don’t have anything to say. But then I also absolutely don’t
know why they want to try to negotiate with them. Or did I misunder
stand you? I want to make sure.
N.: No, in the sense of negotiating with the Soviets now?
(Shout: Yes, yes.)
N.: You can’t negotiate with gangsters!
G.: Then I don’t have anything to say, right?!
Thus, the group in no way falls apart with a decrease in tension. Pre
cisely the consensus, the conformity, ensures that no more tense moments
arise in the group. The moderator often feels compelled to conclude the
session in the face of this development.
The fact that energy wanes after the group has become tightly inte
grated can be explained in part as symptoms of fatigue. In addition, how
ever, another factor might be at play. It seems as if the participants do not
seek to overcome their fatigue because integration itself matters more to
them than does the factual content of the discussion. As important as the
topics might be to some, the individuals should be primarily concerned
with adopting a certain position within or toward the collective and, thus,
creating and stabilizing the structure of the collectivity (to which they be
long, or which they may want to impress). To a large extent, the facts only
provide a vehicle for the discussant to achieve collective identification. For
them, the latter is the internal purpose of the gathering; when it is achieved,
the energy, too, is exhausted, and the discussion wanes.
In other words, it seems as if the function of the discussion for our par
ticipants is more to effect a certain sociopsychological situation and
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 130
We now turn to what the actual conditions for the realization or nonreali
zation of integration look like in the group discussions. With this, we be
gin correcting our model based on reality. The next task, already begun, is
contrasting the proceedings of the discussion in characteristic groups with
the model constructed here.
common situation, from which solidarity among all Germans would have
to result; it was just not directly explicitly related to the disposition to give
one’s opinion.
The bonding feature of this common hardship is also emphasized by the
speakers of a group of unemployed cited below:
Z.: But the letter writer doesn’t say why we can’t commit ourselves to
democracy overnight: there are 7 million refugees from the East, 1Vz
million unemployed and millions of welfare pensioners who have an
income significantly below the subsistence minimum. These social
problems haven’t existed in any democracy yet . . . We’ll arrive at a
democracy, sooner or later .. .
H.: I still want to say the following: We mustn’t forget that we lost the war
and that the powers opposed to our people brought about an even more
difficult predicament than before. I actually want to use the expression
that Germany is over-burdened (überhitzt), i.e., it’s a real trick to feed 50
or 59 million or even much more from this little piece of soil we live on*
In all these statements the word “we” stands for “we Germans.”29
* In “Guilt and Defense” Adorno quotes this same passage but uses only the 50 million
figure (Adorno 2010, 91).—Eds.
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions ~~ 133
And among a group of farmers from the Main area, the following remark
was dropped:
The participants in this and many other discussions were happy that
their words could have an effect beyond the circle they were otherwise ac
customed to. The recording guaranteed that they were not just speaking
for the moment.
Feeling o f One's Own Importance After the group discussions, most of the
participants said they did not regret the time spent in the discussion. The
majority even expressed spontaneously and very pointedly a desire to
be able to participate in such a group session again. We have reason to as
sume that we have before us the effect called “group cohesiveness” [En
glish] in American “Group Dynamics Research.”31 This effect of cohesion
itself results from the possibility of satisfying psychic needs and wishes
which group membership seems to provide. By counting and measuring,
American experiments have supported the hypothesis that the more group
membership is a means for satisfying needs, the more desirable it is for
the individual.32
In the case of our discussions, the satisfaction of demands can be seen in
the discussant’s feeling of being taken seriously for the duration of the dis
cussion, of being an accountable, acting subject. The sense of authority to
speak as a group member authorized, as it were, on behalf of the many who
were in the same position (“I suggest we ask the people, i.e., us here”) is
crucial. It functioned as an integrating factor. People who are weighed down
by the feeling of their own insignificance and powerlessness were particu
larly grateful that for once their words would be heard. At the conclusion of
a session with peasants they said:
Acclamation: This should be done more often, so that the little people also
get a chance to speak!
Unemployed or poor participants, who were forced to live under the most
meager conditions, showed a particular tendency to play real parliament in
the sessions. In one of these groups, genuine speeches to the people were de
livered. We found a strong affinity for the cliché “Mr. previous speaker” in
groups with low-ranked social status. This holds for groups who placed high
Group Experiment and Other Writings — 134
X.: . . . And that’s the idea, and over and over I’m glad that we’re speaking
so clearly in discussions, because, on the basis of our experience in life as
little people, we can finally tell these big statesmen what they did
badly . . .
Apparently, it is not just the simple drive for expression finding its satis
faction in the group session, but, beyond that, the wish to achieve something
with words.
the private talk. The imprecise and unimaginative character of his private
statements also caught the attention of the moderator.
Social Control All of what has been dealt with so far in terms of collective
psychic processes within the group can be traced back to the effectiveness
of “social control” [English] in the broadest sense. The social control mech
anism can be seen in that the individual consciously or unconsciously an
ticipates others’ reactions when in their presence and adapts his or her be
havior accordingly.35 The role of social control is of special importance for
our study goals insofar as we can identify in our discussion groups a social
agent that effectively makes the prevailing ideology in society the “domi
nant” one. General standards (e.g., “We Germans . ..”) and group standards
(e.g.,“We Catholics . ..”) are imposed upon the individual by “functionaries
of the dominant ideology.” Their function is to exert pressure. If a function
ary of society is an individual, we are dealing with a person of authority, an
“opinion leader” [English]. He can, as we will see in the following examples,
come into conflict with another agent of social control [English]. In our ex
ample, it is the group itself that is able to impose a certain ideology via the
person of authority. It is important here to note the connection between
social control and the individual’s anonymity within the discussion group.
The more confident the individual participant is in his anonymity, the less
he is subject to social control and vice versa. This hypothesis, however, has
to be qualified because of the other factors alongside individual identifiabil-
ity and the expectation of reward and punishment influencing the individ
ual within the group, e.g., the desire to be seen, even by people one does not
know personally, as a decent human being, a good patriot, a loyal comrade,
or not to be regarded as an outsider.
In general, however, social control will be most effective if the individual
knows and respects its functionaries.
Of course, this is especially so where certain concise norms of behavior
have formed for the relationship between the individuals and specific others
(e.g., superior—subordinate). We found this in a group of nurses with their
head nurse, among a youth organization and its regional leader, as well as
among a group of resettled Germans who already met for discussion out
side the study, and in which the main speakers of the regular meetings also
dominated in this, i.e., functioned as opinion leaders [English]. Control can
also be located on a nonpersonal level. For example, within a student group,
observers could detect a kind of intellectual control, i.e., the participants
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions ~ 137
considered the knowledge value of what was said and were sensitive when
the intellectual standard sank.
A well-integrated group can, however, revolt against the pressure exer
cised by a superior if the superior’s claim for authority conflicts with the
group’s advocated ideology. In a group of urban police officers, the social
control exercised by an individual because of his rank changed into the col
lective group’s control, to which the individual who had lost his authority
willingly submitted later on. The process is described below: the highest
ranking officer of the mentioned police group acted with a notable claim to
prominence from the beginning of the discussion, after he felt that a certain
amount of esteem was paid to him. It was left to Mr. Unger* to open the
discussion, and it was soon apparent that the participants were also obe
dient to his views. U. spoke the most of all participants. He reinforced his
words by banging on the table. The other group members hardly dared
to take a stand on a new topic before U. had spoken. At first, they cau
tiously stated the bare facts, without taking a stand. They spoke more freely
only after U. had stated his attitude toward the respective topic. However,
they did not take the risk of an overt protest, but sowed the seeds for an
opposing position by suggesting that the problem could be considered from
different points of view (for example, an economic instead of a political
one).
The situation came to a crisis when the group had to realize that, unlike
the majority of police officers, U. did not base his arguments on the political
theses of Social Democracy, but held a contrary view. The fact that he did
not accept the demand for new elections for the Bundestag—which the SPD
[Social Democratic Party] had put forward back then—was already taken
badly. His position began to teeter without his being conscious of it at first.
With complete confidence in his dominant position, he made the mistake
of letting himself get carried away, remarking that the “capitalist” had
nothing to gain from a war, a view that was ideologically diametrically op
posed to the group. He tried to make his voice heard against the building
objections with the words “Gentlemen,gentlemen!”, which aroused laugh
ter from the group. His reaction
U.: You can laugh or not, I don’t care!
Here the text gives the full surname (Unger) instead of the customary first initial.—Eds.
Group Experiment and Other Writings ~~ 138
Negation is simply what is easiest, and, thus, large masses, whose elements
cannot agree on a positive goal, unite around it. The negative character of the
bond uniting the large group becomes evident particularly through its norms.
This is already indicated by the phenomenon that binding arrangements of
any kind have to be the easier and less extensive, the larger the scope of ap
plication is supposed to be, all else being equal.37
things and did not have anything to say on the topics. The same was expe
rienced with women in a housing camp. In these sessions the interrelations
common in the other groups were missing. We can connect this with the
hypothesis that an individual uninterested in the topics within an inter
ested group is not integrated into the group. Now, since the interest of the
individual can change from topic to topic, it can be assumed that a change
in topic can also involve variation in the attachment of the individual to
the group.
The participant U., who up to that point had shared the views of M. and,
like him, acted as a kind of spokesman, saw that the time had come to sup
plant his rival. In clear opposition to M.’s glorification of soldiers’ work, he
commented ironically:
M. replied:
M.: Wait a minute. I spoke to a very old communist who absolutely despises
war to the last. And I told him: Listen, dear grandpa, soon you’ll be 80
years old and your great-grandchildren will play on your knees, and you
won’t know what to do, then you fetch the picture box and at the very
bottom, under the newsprint, a yellowed picture comes up, you’ll take it
in your hand and say: Gosh, here I am as a soldier, those were good times!
Guaranteed, everybody says that!
M. had to use the trick of citing his own view as that of the supposed
addressee (whose answer he did not mention at all), but this still did not
gain attention. U., however, was not impressed by this statement; he con
tinued the attack against M.’s opinion in a very drastic manner of speaking.
In order to take the aces from M.’s hand, he said:
U.: . . . I carry with me my discharge letter from the army, it is not like
th at. . .
However, what he learned “among the Prussians” was “not so very de
cent.” With very vivid words he critiques “the” Germans’ fearful respect
for authority:
U.: This is what the German suffers from: Fear of the one who is called
doctor or whatever, what have you, or director or whatever, his knees
shake . . .
Yet U.’s usurping behavior was also rejected by the group, and he was
told:
T.: . .. just start with yourself, when you’re in your job . . .
From this point onward, M., like U., no longer had a major influence
on the group and participated noticeably less in the discussion than
beforehand.
Only in rare cases do speakers who are overtly seeking a leading posi
tion manage to win over a subgroup within the discussion forum. When
subgroups are formed, these become integrated more in a narrower
sense, yet also do not allow an individual to become too strong; over the
Group Experiment and Other Writings — - 144
long term, they, too, accept only the supremacy of the collective, not of
an individual.
Antagonism In case of antagonism within the entire group, the fronts can
very well shift, and the composition of individual subgroups can change.
Yet, as a matter of fact, constant parties evolved in the majority of really
antagonistic groups. The opposing subgroups then feuded throughout the
entire discussion, completely independent of the topic and, thus, of factual
concerns. Evidently personal, not content-related, factors influenced the
stated opinions. The antagonism was therefore predetermined, inherent
in the persons. In very many cases we succeeded in tracing the differences
responsible for the antagonism. Mostly these were ideological oppositions,
which were activated by the basic stimulus. Thus, an arranged group with
long-established residents and refugees was dominated by an antagonism
between the two parties, one of which argued for a militant nationalism
while the other advanced pacifistic ideas. In a group of women, two com
munists formed one side, women from the bourgeois class the other. We
mentioned above that a group that remained completely atomistic (made
up of overnight guests in a public shelter) began to be grouped into em
ployed and unemployed. Also, preexisting religious tensions could lead
to antagonism during the discussion. Hostilities caused by living closely
together in emergency shelters were not suspended during the discussion.
Often two generations confronted one another in a hostile way, and among
women an animosity between unmarried and married women seems to
have existed at times.
Of course, there were enough cases of opposition based on factually and
not personally motivated differences in opinion, even if they were rarer than
the discussed personal antagonisms. Factually justified objections often met
a willingness to respond to the arguments of the opponent. In contrast to
personally motivated antagonism, they did not, as a general rule, lead to
personal groupings, which themselves could have tended toward integra
tion or disintegration.
From all this it follows that we may not draw the conclusion from the
present study on discussion groups that every group must invariably
become a firm unity, in which the individual is collectivized and shaped
by force.45 Even if adaptation to the group situation is almost never
absent, few groups attain the highest degree of integration, and only a
fraction of these keep it for the entire discussion. Moreover, there can
be no talk of the individual inevitably submitting to the group. In most
groups there are individuals who more or less stave off the pressure
from the group. Apart from that, there are forces in both directions
Integration Phenomena in Group Discussions ~~ 145
for example, try to ascertain in each case whether and when the individual
phases of integration occur and which topics facilitate and inhibit integra
tion, and it will be possible to deepen the understanding of the process of
integration for small groups by using the conceptual and theoretical tools
developed here.
Afterword
I. M ethodological Problems
Given the circumstances at the time, we had to keep the instructions for
the groups’ composition fairly elastic to be able to bring together 120-130
groups at all. This evokes the danger that sectors of the population that were
relatively easy to attract were favored. Another selection effect was intro
duced whenever we approached organizations seeking participants—the
leaders of the contacted organizations might have selected those members
whom they expected to be willing, and they might have nominated those
whom they credited with a certain degree of intelligence and verbal skills.
Yet our contact persons emphasized time and again that we were not at all
interested in “elites.” Naturally, not all of the persons invited to participate
accepted the invitation, and even among those who did, a certain fraction
nevertheless failed to show up: based on our observations these were espe
cially those who consented only reluctantly or after coaxing. However,
we developed techniques in the course of the study which, if refined in the
future, will control these sources of error.
Silent participants presented a problem for adequate interpretation of the
discussions, as became clear at the beginning. “Silent participants” are those
who did not speak at all or who spoke on only a few topics. This problem
is analogous to the problem of “no answer” or “no opinion” in survey re
search. Later interviews with “silent participants” revealed a wide variety of
reasons for their silence. Some are too shy or appeal to lack of experience
speaking in public. Despite the intervention of the moderator, reserved par
ticipants are not always able to get a word in edgewise in the face of more
impulsive or reckless ones. Others considered their ideas superfluous, be
cause other group members had already expressed what they wanted to say.
Others did not have an opinion and—in contrast to the interview method—
did not feel compelled to express themselves. Still others are too tired or too
indifferent; some, finally, deem themselves to have such an extremist attitude
that they prefer not to proclaim their views.
The nature and the weight of these motivations varies considerably;
generalizations about the silent participants cannot yet be made. However,
the more their number can be reduced, the more reliable the findings will
be. We are working on developing methods to accomplish this.
One possibility for improving the experimental design would be to
use two sharply contrasting basic stimuli in comparable pairs of groups.
One could also consider designing experiments in such a way that the
groups can be understood as statistical units from the beginning. Fur
thermore, one could evaluate factors like the influence of the moderator,
the seating arrangement, the time of discussion, etc., through systematic
observation and, if need be, take them into account in the interpretation
of the data.
Afterword 151
The most disconcerting result of the study was the low frequency of positive
statements about democracy and what that implies. The almost unanimous
rejection of the East, which was registered as indication of a democratic at
titude, is by no means to be taken as evidence of such an attitude without
further examination—our study does not allow differentiating between lib
erally minded participants and narrow-minded nationalist ones. In any case,
it is important to consider whether our participants are indeed so “ negati v-
istic,” whether their general outlook is as narrow as the transcripts suggest.
In particular, it is possible that the negativity of the statements is an effect
of the discussion situation and could in reality be different. The following
considerations relate to the possibility of such factors.
To start with, many participants probably perceived the basic stimulus—
despite its moderate language—as a reproach, which demands a defense.
The defensive stance causes more drastic claims than would be made other
wise.1 But that begs the question: Why was the letter interpreted in this
way, even altered in the minds of many participants, and why did they be
lieve that a defense was required? Part of the answer is surely that the basic
stimulus evoked the circumstances of the collapse and thus opened old
wounds. This caused comparatively strong reactions.2 In order to approach
this complex, a controlled experiment3 would be required, one confronting
sociologically comparable groups of participants with stimuli containing dif
ferent nuances.
Furthermore, one has to account for a possibility, which, of course, ap
plies to empirical research in general, far beyond the scale of our study.
Empirical sociology is concerned with observable, isolatable facts and not
with social totality, which as such cannot be adequately “observed.” There
fore, the empirical social researcher is tempted to attribute phenomena to
the particular situation or subject area with which he is concerned at a
particular time, even though these phenomena may not come from these
but from social interrelations well beyond his reach. Hence, it is conceiv
able that the tendency to say no is not so much explained by the rejection
of something concrete—like democracy or foreign countries—but that it
is a symptom of a general “malaise” about the entire social condition.
This “malaise” is merely channeled by the concrete rejection, without ac
tually being directed at it. Saying no without consequences, without com
mitting oneself to actual resistance and oppositional action, is an outlet
for onerous dissatisfaction. Since our group discussions resemble a casual
conversation, the prevalence of grumbling and spouting off will not come
as a surprise. The pleasure of “being someone” by acting hostile toward
Group Experiment and Other Writings — ’ 152
It is not only the material on the seven main themes presented in the quanti
tative section nor the profile of the most important demographic and pro
fessional groups that await further assessment. Qualitatively as well this
volume* contains more in the way of examples of what needs to be done
rather than having worked through the entire material. Thus, there is no
description or analysis of the views that came up on economy and society.
The categories applied to only 25 discussions in Guilt and Defense5 would
have to be systematically examined for all the transcripts.
Above all, however, it is important to bear in mind that only a fraction
of the qualitative monographs are included in this volume. In the follow
ing, we would like to address some of these monographs.
* Wolff’s analysis was never published, but was produced as a mimeograph by the Depart
ment of Sociology at the Ohio State University. See Kurt H. Wolff, “German Attempts at
Picturing Germany: Texts,” Studies in German-American Postwar Problems (SGAPP), no. 3,
(unpublished manuscript, Department of Sociology and Anthropology, The Ohio State Uni
versity, Columbus, August, 1955).
Afterword ~~ 155
3. Social-Philosophical Interpretations
Certainly, sociology’s contribution is not exhausted by empirical research,
and it is one of sociology’s most noble tasks to exceed the ascertained facts
by developing theoretical considerations, and to integrate them in a broader
context. This task was also fulfilled in the analysis of the group discussions.
For example, this impulse motivates the social-theoretical construction of
the complex attitude toward rearmament. This construction seeks to place
the frequently contradictory aspects of the changing views within an histori
cal process. Above all, however, this is the place to mention the very substan
tial language study written by two students of philosophy. It definitely takes
a philosophically critical stance, is neither “value-free” nor stringently in
tune with the established standards of empirical research, and is also outside
of the methods of academic sociolinguistics. But it still offers perspectives
that would be unavailable using common techniques based on the ideal of
scientific or philological objectivity. While the extent of the study did not
permit us to include the text in this volume, Appendix B, written by the
authors themselves, offers at least a somewhat more detailed presentation
of its essential content.
A P P E N D I X A
We call participants who did not speak at all “the totally silent” (Totalsch
weiger). If we include the themes discussed in the definition for participa
tion in the group discussions, then there are participants who spoke on all
themes and participants who did not speak on all themes. We call the lat
ter “the partly silent” (Teilschweiger).
Here we seek to identify the factors that reduce the number of totally
silent participants. Their reduction is relevant for general methodological
reasons; it is also particularly important for generalizing the results of the
group discussions to the population.
3. The duration of the discussion. This has a small effect, and only if
the discussions take about two hours or longer.
4. Theoretically available speaking tim e1 per participant. The more
time theoretically available, the smaller the quota of the totally
silent. Definitionally, there are two ways to increase theoretically
available speaking time: increasing the num erator or decreasing the
denominator. Only in the latter case was the number of the totally
silent reduced.
5. The number of topics discussed per group. Individual participants’
likelihood of taking part in the discussion increased with larger
numbers of topics discussed in a group.
6. The investigator. The investigator influences the proportion of the
totally silent to a small degree mainly through the mechanism of
affecting the length of the discussion by discontinuing the discussion
too early or because of his or her personality.
We can conclude from these results that group size is the most impor
tant factor for reducing the proportion of the totally silent.
From a Monograph on
“Aspects of Language” *
Language o f Passivity
* This Appendix was excerpted for the Gruppenexperiment volume from a monograph
called “Aspects of Language” by Hermann Schweppenhäuser and Rainer Köhne. The mono
graph remained unpublished but was apparently circulated informally to some extent, and
René König refers to it along with the rest of the project in a 1954 letter to Adorno (König,
Briefwechsel, Bd. i, Wiesbaden, VS Verlag 2000, pp. 454-456).
Appendix B ~~ 162
P.: . . . The other thing here is again a bad game of intrigue between the
Americans and the Russians. This doesn’t concern us Germans at all, what
they are doing. Monopolism and capitalism, they want to shove us in, us,
the other states, too, right? Because if the Russians advance to the
Atlantic—and they will not stop in Germany, they will proceed to the
Atlantic—I don’t have anything to lose, right? I could be transferred to
Siberia, I don’t care. I don’t have anything to lose, from a personal point
of view. I only have one suit and this one, otherwise I don’t have a thing.
And I won’t protect the next person. I’ve had it, right? What do I care
about a bureaucrat or a director up there? He can kick the bucket just
like me, right? That’s out of the question. I don’t care anymore. Only my
own self . . .
to the desperate tone that pervades the entire statement. Consequently, the
sentence: “I could be transferred to Siberia, I don’t care” precisely excludes
the speaker’s self as a mere body, as disposable “human material.” This de
sire for absolute passivity simultaneously echoes the defiance of the outlaw
and the excluded. Because of this defiance, the speaker does not segue from
his rejection of remilitarization to a discussion of how remilitarization could
be avoided and also does not attempt to persuade other participants.
The spectator’s attitude comes to the fore particularly when participants
express a strong wish for a change in reality. They appear like an audience
member who wants to interfere in the course of a play but remains wedged
in a seat.
One participant, for example, criticizes the state of democracy:
B.: . . . Democracy? We haven’t really even been shown what democracy is,
because that would mean self-determination . ..
The spell these people are under could hardly be more obvious than in
this remark. The comment reflects that spell; it simultaneously expresses
the conflicting conclusions that “what democracy is” “wasn’t shown to us”
and that it means “self-determination.” Linguistically, this comment re
mains restrained by collective passivity: self-determination should be intro
duced, but at the same time remains a matter for another subject. Auton
omy becomes the charge that autonomy is not granted from without.
People expect effective action to change reality to come from external
sources—certainly not from themselves. These external sources may be a
government or an anonymous “someone.” This can never become an active
subject, though, since every individual in the collective resorts to counting
on that anonymous collective. The refrain “but why doesn’t anybody do
anything?” recurs countless times and in manifold variations (such as “they
should . . .”) in the discussions.
Reality confronts these people as a compact and closed scene instead of
as a network of living human relations. Individuals can therefore no longer
intervene in it with action. The following passage (already quoted above)
is typical:3
Pf.: I’m 63 years old and was able to watch two world wars. I myself never
participated. After the First World War, we recovered more in the first
three years than today after five years. At the outbreak of the Second
World War, or before the outbreak of the second war, a terror was
organized in the Nazi regime that could not be opposed by the man in the
factories, the worker. The terror was so vast that we were ordered to all
kinds of festivities and events. After the horrors of the war began and the
big air raids here on . . . came, as we could watch here from up close—so
Appendix B 164
one can really not speak today of German guilt, because those were not,
in my opinion, strategic targets, that one in this way without further
ado . . . that one just leveled entire villages.
The dominant phrases show that the reality of the bombing war and
totalitarian terror is experienced as a multiple spectacle. The passage “was
able to watch two world wars. I myself never participated” draws a sharp
distinction between the observer and the observed, who “participated.” Later
the language describes the terror as having been “whipped up” (aufgezogen).
This expression traces back to the phrase that a rally should be “whipped
up,” a phrase common in the national-socialistic organization. Terror itself
appears as a spectacle, and the language betrays the nuance of brawling,
roaring, monotonous marching at the mass rallies, which are associated
with the following sentence: it directly links terror “to all kinds of festivities
and events,” which the people were required to attend. The arrangement
and mandate of the allegedly spontaneous national-socialistic movement
cannot be articulated more clearly than by the link between “terror” and
“whipping up.” The experience, which is congealed into a cliché, is articu
lated in a very similar way in the next sentence with the topic of the “hor
rors of the war,” about which it is said that they “set in” like something
exactly pre-calculated. In the process, the speaker, who links his words to
gether as people did against all sense and yet with official sanction for thir
teen years in Germany, makes the exact point that the air raids fit into the
Imperial Ministry for Popular Education and Propaganda’s scheme of war
propaganda just as well as the required “festivals and events.” It might, in
deed, have been experienced as something that “set in” like the heavy brass
in an orchestra.
It is also said that one “could watch” the air raids. The term used in this
context, “air raids,” certainly does not evoke good spirit in the speaker, yet
inspires the reminiscence of similar terms from advertising for entertaining
events (“Bombenstimmung” [terrific atmosphere], “Stimmungskanone”
[great joker], for example). The physiognomy was explored by Karl Kraus in
“The Last Days of Mankind.”4 The jargon of the years of war itself, cobbled
together out of manifest and cryptic elements, releases the repressed humor
of the word rather than the nuance of dread, which refuses such a usage of
language. Finally, referring to “strategic targets” and using the standardized
phrase “leveled entire villages” in today’s language, reifies the object. It es
tranges it from experience, making it something merely stated and therefore
indifferent.
Similar to people’s perception of what happens to them as a piece of an
exhibition, they talk about what they do collectively as a piece of this uni
versal exhibition. They do not intend it to be as ironic as it sounds:
Appendix B ~ i 6j
Thus, the world turned suddenly against Germany because the Germans
demonstrated so much ability. Moving ahead appears as an action itself
and ability seems to exist for demonstration. This is underlined by the ex
pression “to present,” which suggests ostentatious offering. The history of
the Hitler empire is neutralized to a stage performance, against which the
audience—the foreign countries—revolts as a collection of skills. The ac
tual cause of the revolt (the aggression of Hitlerian ability) never comes into
question. The content of action turns into an exhibition of form divorced
from actors’ intentions:
The limits of the language people glean from their relation to their envi
ronment, which is reified to mere spectacle, also comes up in the remarks
about Jews. Consider the following quotation from among many similar
ones:
U.: I think the Jewish problem as such is not about the Jewish religion or the
Jewish race. The charges pressed against Judaism today concern in the
first place Jewish emigrants from the East, who live a loose life, a cheap
skate’s life, an indolent life, and hence considerably harm Judaism as such.
The speaker does not say that indolence, loose living, and the cheapskate’s
life, which are attributed to the Jews, do real damage—they are charged
with “demonstrating” something, which one cannot observe. This takes
place entirely in a mode of speaking which is otherwise an adequate para
phrase for the fossilized expression “unbearable,” which rigorously cuts off
every discussion. As in reality, Jews are pilloried yet again by language: the
participant’s speech resembles the hail of the surrounding crowd. Particu
larly in the rhythm of the last passage similar to a chorus—“demonstrate
a loose life, a cheapskate’s life, an indolent life, and hence considerably harm
Judaism as such”—the speech degenerates into an empty mass. It is not set
up to evoke understanding and an answer, but to fight. Correspondingly, the
speaker attributes a certain meaning to the term “Jewish problem” by link
ing it to the predicate “to affect.” The result is an elimination of any reflec
tion suggested by the initial association of “Jewish” and “problem.” This
again goes with the catchword “as such,” which occurs twice in the speech
Appendix B — ι66
In this passage, the denial of the Jew’s humanity goes with the widespread
usage of the words “to comport” and “to conduct.” They measure behavior—
and truly not only that of Jews—according to a prescriptive ideal. This
can be traced back to the language of the barracks; in “to comport” there is
the image of the corporal evaluating an exercising recruit. The phrase that
one “carried out” orders was characteristic for the persecution of people
in the Third Reich. It is in accordance with the facts. The victim, with
whom there is no further communication, is no longer acknowledged,
was abused merely as a physical entity. The murder was commanded, with
out relation to the victim: gassing occurred because of statements in a ques
tionnaire.
When some speakers indicate their actual misery with clichés like “im
portant question of the day,” it almost sounds like they are romanticizing
it. An unemployed refugee speaks in such a tone about having “resorted”
(sich begeben) to the refugee camp. Two characteristic passages of his
speech should be cited:
T.:. . . If somebody wants to campaign for a political party, please do it
elsewhere. I would rather discuss important questions of the day. I’m
from the eastern zone and had to go. Subsequently I resorted to the
camp Ülzen . . .
T: . . . I personally endeavored to find work, in Essen as bricklayer
re-trainee . . .
It appears that he felt prominent within this small group by being the
kind of person one normally only reads about in the newspaper. His manner
of speaking resembles the diction of a story about celebrities: “I resorted”;
“I personally endeavored.” This indicates a function of the media that is as
important as it is fatal. It provides people with formulations they can adopt
for their own use. They are thus reconciled with the fact that they are forced
to endure passively that about which they are incessantly informed.
In a literal sense, people seem to bite off more than they can chew when
they use the pompous, superlative terms too common in today’s language.
According to Theodor Haecker as well, these terms are “Collosi of aver
ageness, [ . . . ] which produce a colossal effect,” and the linguistic usage of
which is a “mode of mediocrity.”5This can be found in the following state
ment concerning the term “global scale.”
R. : .. . Today’s conflict between East and West has already assumed a global
scale. We see that time and again just by considering its proportion on a
globe.
It is striking that the listing of such pompous terms often ends in an “etc”:
N .: .. . And I’m of the opinion that this development, as well as the terrible
tragedy of the last war, must be rated as the force of history, as something
supra-personal, that one . . . has to mark as historical development, which
does not happen within the purely personal sphere, but within supra-
personal powers, in nations, Weltanschauung [World views.—Eds.] etc.
The disjuncture between the actual experience and its conceptual and
linguistic mastery could hardly be clearer. The more opaque, the more
total the catastrophe that has been experienced, the more hollow are the
pompous conceptual clichés with which it is seemingly mastered, and
which are based on concepts that are in themselves correct. Instead of even
trying to explain what was deemed beyond human capacity, the speaker at
Appendix B — ι68
M.: One cannot understand that at all, that this is supposed to be democ
racy; I cannot understand this, what democracy means since the Ameri
cans came over and killed women and children here. Just this one thing in
X, where three times a hundred thousand were dead in one day.
The meaning is no longer felt; rather, it functions like the rhetorical de
vice of a demagogue, who effectively supports the cliché of the defenseless
“women and children” with the phrase “three times a hundred thousand
[ . . . ] in one day.” This number appears like the record figures of an adver
tisement turned around in the negative. Hitler blared out numbers in the
same tone of voice.
The frequent use of numbers and the insistent performance of calcula
tion is also reminiscent of something beyond confusing oneself and others
with abstract sizes. The rationalistic opposite—trust in the reliability of
numbers—seems to play an equally important role. Using numbers provides
an air of precision and demonstrates expertise—numbers easily pass as true.
An example of the gesture of exact calculation to hide pure nonsense:
so that the American GI pays 170%. And these are devoured by the State.
However, I cannot prove this allegation . . .
5 .: . . . These gentlemen (the American occupying soldiers) learned for the first
time what Kultur means, and interior design ( Wohnungseinrichtung)—in
America they really don’t know this . . .
Appendix B — ■ 171
K .:. . . And the American has shown us in how he has occupied Germany,
that he can be just as brutal and just as big a rogue and a troublemaker as
the Russians . . .
. . . And as far as I know the Negro is a bloodthirsty person and caused a
lot of devastation here . . .
M .:. . . The Frenchman is among the worst! . . . The worst is the Frenchman;
he stops everywhere—wherever he can, gets in the way of everything.
P.:. . . Well the Frenchman is the worst sadist I have ever known . . . He can
look at his own brother being put through a meat grinder, alive, and is
only interested in making sure he is not personally harmed. He is a real
coward, cares only about himself . . .
H .:. . . Where, why is the Jew persecuted, why did he get into the KZ, why
the Jew of all people? What is it about him that he—and we really want
to be clear on this—was and perhaps is hated not only in Germany, but
around the world? There must be something about him that stirs up and
goads others . . . Well, my private opinion is: it is his business sense and
extreme cleverness. Perhaps he does not even have evil intentions with
these, but he simply has them, and they somehow snub everybody else. He
has success in business. He does that with the utmost cleverness, with
terrific shrewdness, and arrives at his goal, while others who want to earn
their money honestly always go broke.
H. : . . . Well, it is actually strange . . . that the Jew has never managed to
found a real nation. He sits around in dribs and drabs in other countries
and, of course, is regarded as a parasite by these countries . . . and the Jew
is allowed to go everywhere and is allowed essentially to pick off the best
bites, and people are offended by that.
U .:. . . The German is a good technician, the Jew is a good merchant. Can
one criticize him for that? . . .
And our Adolf Hitler was quite right when he said that the German
is the best soldier in the world . . .
T.:. . . and now we turn to the heart of the question, on which you’ve
touched, Mrs. W.: Everyone clings to the hope that a person might arise to
bail us out, indeed bail out all of Europe and the whole world, beyond
just our people. The preconditions for this exist in Germany more than
anywhere else. If no such personage can be found now, the German
people will head toward total Bolshevism and other nations will follow
very quickly. We can see that today through election results . . . but those
who did not go to the polls, and those who did go only as a compromise
to the middle-of-the-road parties . . . These are actually people who yearn
for something to rally around which would overcome rationalism,
Appendix B — ' 172
intellectual Bolshevism, and the local and American Bolshevism. The most
fertile soil for such a leader is in Germany itself.
B.: . . . One has to consider that the popular sense (!) ( Volksintelligie) of the
German people consists directly of the cry for the Führer.
—all of them become focal points of dogmatic monologues, for the sake of
which the participants are allegedly arguing; they become linguistic vehi
cles for aggression against the “victors,” from whom one does not want to
accept (annehmen) anything.*
Taking this speech as the unmediated expression of the speakers them
selves instead of recognizing it as being codetermined by National Socialist
speech ignores the common type of person who cannot respond to other
ways of thinking or other characteristics; who is “against” things from the
outset, who does not examine himself and who searches for guilt first of all
in the “stranger.” This misrecognition forgets what National Socialist lan
guage initially released—or created—in the people, which might have been
expressed differently under a different influence. They are not yet National
Socialists just because they are impressed by these linguistic gestures. Cer
tainly, they can get absorbed with imitation to such a degree that it becomes
difficult to distinguish. With the gesture of aggressive talking down, which
no longer concerns the issue but is meant to intimidate, one participant ac
cuses foreign countries of unjustified dismantling:
O .:. . . Yet, one has begun to rob Germany, totally, one dragged off all
patents, which are worth millions and billions, everything was pulled
apart and dismantled and taken away—whether it was the Russian or the
Frenchman or the Englishman—everything was snapped up. Now,
Germany is nothing but an empty cloud of dust! . . .
Here speaking is just wild gesture. The immaterial patents turn into
mountains of tangible material only to visualize the criminal action of
dismantling—rendering the gesture of accusation effective in the first place.
The denunciatory synonyms do not suffice to describe their “removal.”
Similarly, immense numbers are plucked out of the air, which render mani
fest the speaker’s inability to do enough to make his point. The picture of
the empty cloud of dust, which signifies the Nazi legacy of a desolate Europe
more than a Germany not-at-all-dismantled, functions in a projective man
ner similar to passages in Hitler’s speeches where, for example, he alleges a
conspiracy of foreign countries.
By the speakers’ not letting anything affect them, not wanting to continue
talking, their claims lose their substance and content. This constitutes a pos
sible discussion only by transcending the individual linguistic formula. The
claims regress to “claims” in the sense of brute force. Many speeches in the
group session seem to be designed in such a way—and here we believe that
they indeed reflect an element of reality—as if a thesis could come into force
by the mere bodily effort of speaking. Concise, logical conclusions from
premises are replaced with argument by attrition, which seeks to force the
listener and possible objector to capitulate to a loud and confused stream
of words. A speech which is a singular aberration in anacoluthia* and at the
same time its forcible coverup, and finally abruptly gives up the topic as
proven is presented here:
B.: I’d like to return to Mr. T’s remark that the Germans always get blamed
for the last war. The true root of the problem, as the previous speaker said,
lies in the Treaty of Versailles. If you rape a people at gunpoint, as
happened in Versailles in 1921, to deprive an overpopulated country of the
possibility of living and brutally take away everything, this people is forced
to emigrate and has no ability to spread out. By taking the colonies from
it, then giving them to people who can’t possibly govern them like today’s
Frenchmen, who have to abandon their colonial areas because they are too
spineless to hold onto them. Americans do not understand European
politics. We Germans are in an unpleasant situation, we are threatened by
the Romanians on one side and on the other side by the Slavs—cramped
with about 70 million people in a small space. This, of course, is a political
necessity from our side and cannot be maintained even today. The mistakes
of our government—these enfants terrible, as the foreigners say about our
German politicians—that’s true, though. Germans are indeed impatient.
They do not wait until affairs have fully developed, but instead act like a
bull in a china shop. But the people cannot be held responsible for this. It
is the responsibility of today’s new victors, as they call themselves—in
truth they are actually losers—the true victor will be someone else—to
provide the opportunity to spread out. Because it will have to return at
some point that even today we are overpopulated. We have 12 million
* Anacoluthia refers to a sentence that lacks grammatical structure, starting out in one
direction and abruptly taking up another.—Eds.
Appendix B ~ 174
refugees who were forcibly expelled from the Sudetenland, from Silesia,
from Poznan, from Pomerelia, and from Austria—and who thus support
the cause of Bolshevism. The Americans allow this to pass but today we
face a fact, this is a signal, that America did not control the true political
situation of Europe—something that can be excused—in general in 1945.
And guilt—when he says, Hitler wanted or instigated the war—the true
reason for the war can be found in the Treaty of Versailles.
already dead: it remains accepted and simply repeated. Speech is the ques
tionable expression of subjects who are subjects only nominally—the par
roted, empty gesture of fractured subjectivity.
The omnipotence of language that is itself already destroyed, which dic
tates the impotence of speech, is that of the objective mind: the inhumanity
of conditions have hardened into a language which determines from the
outset what and how far one is allowed to think and perceive. Already
with language, however, these conditions are accepted without criticism or
resignedly. The societal premise has been established for linguistic behav
ior: accepting and hence futile adaptation. Once the language roaring
from newspapers, loudspeakers, and advertising ceases bringing people to
their senses, it becomes instantaneously adopted. Anyone who speaks can
hardly help reproducing what is incessantly heard and read.
Speech adheres throughout to a licensed, ossified vocabulary. It is made
up of the instances and agencies which determine and reflect reality. Admin
istration, technology, and commerce contributed as much to this vocabulary
as the rudiments of National Socialist language as well as the vocabulary
of the military* of both wars, and the mass media which at the same time
spread it far and wide. The people remain enclosed like windowless monads
inside the language constituted by such vocabulary, papered over with
linguistic clichés and jumbled fragments of experience. Language no longer
helps people to get a picture of reality—as is revealed from language itself
taken at its word. Language commands through order, instruction, and ad
vertising. Being rhetorical and a pool of mangled clichés, it relieves people
of reflection. Interspersed with administrative and technical categories, with
scientific terminology, it reifies life itself. Being euphemistic, filled with cyni
cism and petrified jokes, it allows neither for concern nor for human
emotion from the outset. Being the epitome of adherence to the facts, it
dethroned what remains: the incommensurable, suffering, and hope.
People uphold the appearance of autonomy and reflection while they sur
render to language. Imitation and repetition in particular are meant to make
something out of powerlessness—yet they reveal it all the more drastically.
The more insecure the reflection, the more demanding and bombastic the
words and sentences, the more apodictic the tone; the more conscious the
powerlessness, the stronger the drive for importance, which takes advantage
of established language. Modern speech can be characterized by the mean
ing that the phrase “to have something to say” has assumed. At one time,
* The original refers, in quotes, to the “Barras” of both wars, soldierly slang for the
military.—Eds.
Appendix 8 — 176
* The German word Unmündigkeit (naïveté or childishness) is used as a pun with Mund
(mouth) here.—Eds.
Final Version of the
Basic Stimulus (Colburn Letter)
T H E O D O R W. A D O R N O ( 1 9 6 4 )
P sons. For example, one wants to reliably predict the result of an election.
The techniques employed were originally developed for market research.
Unreflexive, practical sociology gets by with this. To be sure, limited to what
sociology has always concerned itself with, it considers it easy, superficial,
and simple. Nevertheless, an element of necessity calls for the development
of a new discipline, which would gladly encompass the whole of social sci
entific knowledge.
The German term “opinion research” (Meinungsforschung) drops, for the
sake of brevity, a key adjective, which alone identifies its concern: research
on public opinion. That adjective refers to the idea of publicness. Looking
at the history of public opinion research determines how it came to this.
Publicness, the increasing scrutability of actions within their social sur
roundings, reaches back immeasurably far in history. The concept of
publicness itself* was first conceived with the beginning of the bourgeois
era, sometime in the seventeenth century. Since then, the public character
(Öffentlichsein) of all possible ways of thinking, ways of conduct, and ac
tions, has been conscious of itself as an idea and has been threatened.
* Adorno differentiates here between the practice of publicness (the increasing scrutability
of actions) and the normative concept of publicness, which he takes to be the new develop
ment. The distinction becomes important later in the essay.—Eds.
Opinion Research and Publicness — ' 180
* Adorno refers here to the practice of governing “behind closed doors” by national and
international leadership without regard for the involvement of the public.— Eds.
Opinion Research and Publicness ~~ 181
the anticipated scientific control of the market. The growth of market re
search corresponds to this tendency; it is applied market research, trans
mitting those dead-end ways to communicating spiritual objects. The idea,
introduced by P. F. Lazarsfeld, of administrative social research, empirical
social research for purposes of administration, describes the reality correctly,
appropriately; incidentally, market research is only one root of opinion re
search, the other is the social survey, whose history in Germany is also con
nected with the name of Max Weber. The current identity of market and
opinion research in America, which are also bound together terminologi-
cally in Germany, is, throughout, in the sense of the observation of com
mon sense, that no radical difference prevails between the preferences for
the names of a political candidate and for those of a brand name, as would
be expected according to the theoretical differentiation between the autono
mous and mature/responsible folk and the surroundings (Umkreis) of the
servitude (Kundenschaft) to mass products. Under this aspect, opinion re
search would not be a mere technique, but just as much an object of sociol
ogy as a science that inquires into the objective structural laws of society.
But its meaning must not exhaust itself. It steps exactly into the space
that was formed by the transition of the idea of public opinion to those of
production and control: it could, following its potential, show how much
it manipulates the opinions of the population, to what extent actual public
opinion is a reflex of usurpation. The potential for improvement springs
from the limits of manipulation. To choose only the most drastic example,
that submits the assumption of every non-naive survey to political sociol
ogy: the results are demonstrated only if the populations actually determine
the information on which their sensible political decisions depend from the
very beginning. Where that is not the case, opinion research, without social-
critical intentions, spontaneously turns into social criticism. It can determine
the reasons for insufficient trust in information, through analysis of infor
mation sources and of that which they supply the population, just as of the
position of consciousness of those questioned, who are modeled for their
part again through the whole social conditions, especially such as the con
sciousness industry, under which they live. Sensible research on public opin
ion, as they say in America, “on the other side of the fence,” namely by the
masses themselves, is able to do that further, if the so-called organs of public
opinion really represent these, and if these opinions are spontaneous and
sensible or, alternatively, if they fall into line with mechanisms of social con
trol. Research on public opinion could restore something of that, which the
replacement of these opinions committed by market organs, since the idea
of publicness in political life became real. To be sure, that incorporates the
demand that opinion research not hypostatize itself, that it not confuse the
Opinion Research and Publicness — 183
data it gathers with the final immediate truth, but remain conscious of its
own state of mediation through the societal structure and through the in
stitutions of opinion formation, which try to grab more and more power.
Opinion research can fulfill its promise only if it applies its results and un
dertakes question formulations that hold to the objective social facts. Once
previously objective societal institutions like the press monopolized the
democratic title to public opinion, public opinion became centralized and
therefore moved in opposition to the idea of living subjects, whose diverse
opinion it should record, so opinion research is caught up in the attempt,
equally abstract, isolated, to isolate the naked subjective moment of opin
ion, the meaning of individual persons, and to confuse that, which is the
naked reflex of objective, societal legalities, with the basis of social reality.
Opinion research then turns into ideology, understandable through the
claim that organs of public opinion like the mass media would have con
formed to the opinions of the populations, which, for its part, returns to
the manipulation of public opinion. Opinion research easily assists the ma
nipulation of consciousness at the expense of objective reality. But it shows
through this to the same dialectic as the sphere of the political, to which the
idea of opinion was indigenous and to which it still belongs. It is an ideology
which, once it achieves critical competence, will be able to dissect ideology
and to change its conclusions of existence.
Notes
Foreword
i . Friedrich Schiller: The Piccolomini, or the First Part of Wallenstein, a Drama
in Five Acts, trans, by S. T. Coleridge, London (Longman) 1800, p. 15
Introduction
1. The appendix provides material from preparatory work for such comparative
research. This material might serve for formulating questionnaires and repre
sentative surveys for our topic. [This material is not included in the English
appendixes. -Eds.]
2. R. F. Bales: Interaction Process Analysis, Cambridge, Mass., 1951. The funda
mental difference is the fact that Bales’ interest throughout is in the group as
such, while our study is interested in the group participants. We do not treat
problems of group dynamics as ends in themselves, but rather as evidence of
collective influences on individuals.
3. Consider those experiments, motivated by Kurt Lewin and essentially based
on his topological psychology, that have been conducted in the United States
for about two decades. These experiments seek to investigate group structures
and group phenomena. These experiments are characterized by an experimen
tal design modeled after natural science. It seeks to manipulate only the inde
pendent variables and to hold all other factors constant. They thereby create—
quite consciously—such an artificial situation that one can expect an outcome
approximating reality only in the most fortunate cases. See K. Lewin: Princi
ples of Topological Psychology, New York 1936.
Notes to Pages i i - i 3 ~ 186
4. See Chapter 4 and T. W. Adorno: Guilt and Defense, Cambridge, Mass. (Har
vard University Press) 2010.
5. See the series Studies in Prejudice, edited by M. Horkheimer and S. Flower-
man, New York 1950, especially volume III, T W. Adorno, E. Frenkel-
Brunswik, D. J. Levinson, and R. N. Sanford: The Authoritarian Personality.
6. The difference between the quantitative and qualitative was only introduced
into the material by the scientific analysis and must not be considered abso
lute. Insofar as all quantification refers to qualitative facts, which can only be
analyzed statistically after preparation, the categories of understanding, which
make quantitative studies meaningful in the first place, stem from the qualita
tive area. We cannot unpack the epistemological problem of distinction here;
we maintain the concepts as developed in actual research. The oppositions re
fer, of course, to the very deep question of how the objectifying method in so
cial sciences actually shapes its subject. It also has to be stated that, in the
practice of social science, the separation of quantitative and qualitative meth
ods can never be accomplished in a pure way. (See B. Berelson: Content Analy
sis in Communication Research, Glencoe, 111., 1952, pp. 135ff.)
7 . M. Horkheimer (editor): Studien über Autorität und Familie, Forschungsberi
chte aus dem Institut für Sozialforschung, Paris 1936.
23. Best translated as Bezugssystem [reference system]. See Glossar zur Verdeutsc
hung englischer Fachausdrücke aus der Methodik der empirischen Sozialforsc
hung, Beitrag des Instituts für Sozialforschung, in: Praktische Sozialforschung,
edited by R. König, Dortmund and Zürich 1952, p. 295. [Ironically the trans
lation offered there is Bezugsrahmen.—Eds.]
24. A common term in survey-method for a type of questions for the answering of
which the interviewee has to choose between a number of preset alternatives.
See M. Parten: Surveys, Polls and Samples, pp. 189L; W. Albig: Public Opinion,
p. 192.
25. See S. Freud: Gesammelte Werke, London 1940-52, vol. X, p. 225; S. Freud:
Instincts and their Vicissitudes, p. 131, in: Standard Edition of the Complete
Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, trans, by J. Strachey, London (Hog-
arth Press) 1957, vol. XIV, pp. 109-140.
26. See P. R. Hofstätter: Die Psychologie, pp. i64ff.
27. See W. Hollitscher: The Concept of Rationalization, in: Journal of Psycho
analysis, XX, 1939.
28. There might be certain differences between Germany and America, but these
must not be overestimated. The American ideal of extroversion makes it easier
than in Germany to talk about personal matters in a rather unrestrained way,
and the reliability of survey findings might profit from that. However, this will
ingness seems to have its limits when the discussion transcends the preconscious—
particularly about actually emotionally charged zones. See K. Lewin: Resolving
Social Conflicts, New York 1948, pp. i8f.
29. See C. F. Schmid: Basic Statistical Concepts and Techniques, in: P. V. Young:
Scientific Social Survey and Research, New York 1950, pp. 329ff.; M. Parten:
Surveys, Polls and Samples, pp. 499ÎÎ.
30. See P. V. Young: Scientific Social Surveys, pp. 265ff.; M. Jahoda and others:
Research Methods in Social Relations, New York 1951, pp. 209ff.; T. M.
Newcomby Personality and Social Change, New York, 1943, PP* I 73^·
31. See the description of the circle of participants in Chapter II [not included in
this translation.—Eds.]. The groups between eight and sixteen participants
comprise three quarters of all groups and two-thirds of the entire circle of
participants.
3 2 . See the below section on stimulus analysis.
3 3 . Indeed, such concerns were voiced repeatedly.
34. See S. Freud: Gesammelte Werke, p. 65ff; S. Freud: On the History of the
Psycho-Analytic Movement, in: Standard Edition, vol. XIV, pp. 7-66, p. 27ff.
35. See Chapter 4.
36. See the description of the circle of participants in Chapter II [not included in
this translation—Eds.].
37. See Appendix. [Reference is to an Appendix not included in the translation.—
Eds.]
3 8 . See Appendix. [Reference is to an Appendix not included in the translation.—
Eds.]
39. See the wording in its final version in this volume. In the British zone, the
American was made a British soldier.
Notes to Pages 40-49 ~ 189
in: Berelsort and Janowitz: Reader in Public Opinion and Communication, pp.
265ff. B. Berelsort and P. F. Lazarsfeld: Die Bedeutungsanalyse von Kommuni
kationsmaterialien, in: Praktische Sozialforschung, edited by R. König, pp.
14iff. Institut für Sozialforschung: (Article) Sozialforschung, empirische,
in: Handwörterbuch der Sozialwissenschaften, 6. Lieferung, Stuttgart 1954,
pp. 4 3 off.
53. See Chapter 1.
54. See A. H. Barton and P. F. Lazarsfeld: Some Functions of Qualitative Analysis
in Social Research, in: Frankfurter Beiträge zur Soziologie, vol. 1.
55. The following statements of one of the leading scholars in American social
research directly relate to “anthropological procedure,” but apply analogously
to all qualitative research. It is said that this kind of research:
“represents only the first step in science, because its rich interpretations
are not based on relations which have been quantitatively established. They
are inferences which either represent a wholistic type of judgment or are
based upon what the investigator regards as his most central observations.
There is little attempt at specification of the types of data which are neces
sary for the measurement of a given variable. Hence, it frequently makes
difficult and often impossible the verification of relations by another investi
gator. The history of social psychology illustrates the importance of the rep
lication of findings in that many of its initial results have not been confirmed
by later investigations. Only when we attain the level of standardizing our
specifications for data can we see the extent to which reported findings are
true generalizations.”
The author then states that the conflict between quantitative and qualitative
method can be solved easily by using the latter only in the initial stage of the
investigation.
“This stage can utilize to the full the advantages of seeing the situation as a
whole and of attempting to grasp the fundamental relationship. From this study
can come the insights which can furnish the hypotheses for later, more detailed
quantitative study.” D. Katz, in: L. Festinger and D. Katz: Research Methods,
pp. 64f.
56. Lately, under the lead of Lazarsfeld, the scholarly literature has been con
cerned to an increasing degree with the significance of qualitative analyses for
empirical social research. See the summary with bibliographic references of
Dorwin P. Cartwright: Analysis of Qualitative Material, in: L. Festinger and
D. Katz: Research Methods, pp. 4 2 iff.
57. See the preliminary remarks for part III [not included in this translation—Eds.].
4. It follows from the aim of our study as well as from the character of the mate
rial unearthed by it that the objective significance of the statements, i.e., their
declarative value about reality, cannot be the subject matter of the analysis. Our
interest is focused on the significance of the statements for the attitude of the
participant, not their value for a correct assessment of the question discussed.
5. T. M. Newcomb, Personality and Social Change, New York, 1943, PP· H 9ff
6. Ibid., pp. 2i7ff.
3. Quantitative Analyses
1. In the following, we assume—if not explicitly indicated otherwise—that the
speakers reflect the attitudes of the individual discussion groups as well as of
the statistical group to which they belong. We cannot yet say to what extent
this assumption is backed up by more than experience. The explanations in
Chapter 4 about phenomena of integration, for example, apply to this ques
tion. Likewise we count among this the impressive internal consistency of the
attitudes of the individuals who make up the discrete statistical groups, as long
as the relevant group contains a minimum number of individuals. Only then
can we expect that the speakers are articulating essential factors and not other,
nonessential influences.
2. Comparing percentages of the individual statistical groups with the average
serves only the purpose of an ordering scheme that establishes relations. One
would have to include the different sizes of these groups in order to arrive at an
exact quantifiable assessment of the demographic groups in their relation to the
average. This is because the larger groups contribute more to the computation
of the overall average than do the smaller ones. As a result, the relatively smaller
percentage deviations of the larger groups (e.g., men or those with grade school
education) are more important for the interpretation than are those of the
smaller groups.
3. Recall that we evaluate the code “approval” as positive attitude, “disapproval”
as negative, etc., except for the topics of the East and German self-assessment
(where we proceed conversely). See Chapter 2.
4. It is worth noting that the small percentage of rejection of democracy among
women and housewives is almost equal, even though the housewives consti
tuted less than half the women speakers (110 of 274).
5. Even among groups with the smallest ambivalent attitude (unskilled workers
54%, farmers 58%) the number of ambivalent remarks accounts for more
than half of the speakers.
6. In the statistical sense: the circle of participants.
7. Grade school: 25% of rejection; high school: 22%; high school graduate:
15 % ; university: 13%.
8. o- 2 years: 20% of rejection; 2-6 years: 24%; 6 years and more: 32%.
9. With an almost average participation (42%) only 8% of their speakers acted
ambivalently, none positively.
10. 20 years or less: 37% of the speakers; 20-25 years: 49%; 2.5-30 years: 56%;
30 years and older: 48%. [As in the original, the highest age category in the
Notes to Pages 76-89 ^ 192
footnote is 30 years and older, not 50 years and older as implied in the
text.—Eds.]
11. Up to 2 years of military service: 52% of speakers; 1 -6 years of military ser
vice: 59%; 6 years and more: 63%.
12. Grade school: 54% of speakers; high school: 50%; high school graduate:
46%; university: 45%.
13. It is remarkable that the university graduates show above-average participa
tion in all of the other topics. See the profile, Figure 3.8.
14. See the profile, Figure 3.8.
15. See Chapter 1.
16. See Table 30 in the appendix [not included in this translation—Eds].
17. 0-2 years of military service: 78% disapproval, 11% approval; 2- 6 years of
military service: 84% disapproval, 5% approval; 6 years and more: 86% dis
approval, 4% approval.
18. The significance of the unusually high frequency of disapproving speakers
among unskilled workers is emphasized by the fact that this group’s participa
tion is generally far below average and it essentially reaches the average for
this topic (32% as compared with 36% on average).
19. Unskilled workers: 82%; farmers: 67%; housewives: 66%; general school:
66%; 20 years or less: 38%; students: 39%; university graduates: 46%; high
school graduates: 48%.
20. Adding rows I and II in Table 3.7 is methodologically justified since an exami
nation of the transcripts as well as the reports of the assistants in the sessions
showed that the majority of ambivalent reactions evinced approval “at a price.”
21. Men’s participation, however, is significantly higher than women’s (39% ver
sus 28%), and the negative attitude among women is a little bit higher than
among men.
22. Participation frequency among students: 37%; high school graduates: 39%;
junior high: 42%; university graduates: 47%.
23. In general we refrained from interpreting findings for statistical groups of
fewer than 100 participants. These groups make such small subgroups for
classification that their significance is even more problematic than with larger
subgroups of our “population.” It is still interesting that something like a cor
relation between degree of education and attitude toward the Germans in also
reflected in these smallest groups.
24. Participation of women = 33%; of men = 28%. The only other topic in which
women participate remarkably more often than men is the topic of Jews (26%
versus 21%).
25. The construction of models of such attitude-types and their confrontation
with profiles gained from statistical material was started. However, it was not
complete at the time this report was finished. See the Afterword.
26. See Figure 3.19.
27. The narrowly limited validity of the underlying data made more complicated
presentation methods seem inadequate.
28. This average is based on the classification of the profiles of the demographic
groups and must not be confused with the average of the attitude toward the
topics.
Notes to Pages 89-98 — 193
29. Students, for example, were also included in men or women, their age and edu
cational groups, and according to their military service.
30. The attitude toward the East was not considered for the construction of the
index because the high average of the positive attitude tends to blur the differ
ences among the other topics. See the difference in average with the East and
without the East on Figure 3.19.
31. The numbers added in brackets display the index. It goes without saying
that these numbers can indicate only the approximate relative position in
the respective order of all groups, and that they serve as a rough illustration
at best.
The second number for each group is the combined index of the “test top
ics.” Based on the idea that four of our seven topics are particularly character
istic for the speakers’ attitude toward democratic values, we constructed an
additional measure. It is based on the sum of percentage deviation of the fre
quency of each group’s attitudes toward the topics of complicity, Jews, the
West, and democracy from the general attitude toward the same four topics.
Introducing this additional index changes the status of the statistical groups.
These changes, however, generally alter the picture only a little. An exception
is the occupational group of unskilled workers, which ranks thirteenth accord
ing to the index including six topics and advances to the eighth position in the
ranking according to the test topics.
The pro-Jewish attitude was classified as ambivalent in the computation of
the indices. Classifying it as positive together with the non-anti-Semitic atti
tude changes the status of the groups only marginally. For the indices includ
ing all topics, the change amounts to one point each for four groups, while the
other sixteen groups maintain their status. For the indices comprising the test
topics, the status similarly does not change in twelve cases; it changes by one
point each for six groups and by two points each for two groups.
32. This does not imply a high degree of ambivalence but that the frequencies of
positive and negative statements roughly balance each other.
33. The graphical profiles are obtained by registering the frequency of speakers of
the respective group for each topic in percentages and comparing them with the
average attitude of all speakers. Each table, furthermore, displays the participa
tion in the discussion of the group as well as its deviation from the participa
tion of all groups.
34. Frequency of positive remarks below average for the West (-22%), complicity
( - 20%).
35. According to the index for the test questions, they rank 13.
36. See also Table 1 and Chapter II [These are not included in this translation—Eds.]
37. For the positive attitude: the West -33%, the East -10%; for the negative at
titude: Jews +16%.
38. For this topic, the average frequency of ambivalence is so high (68%) that
considerable deviations upward are hard to imagine.
39. Among the age group 50 years and older, all these influences are presumably
modified by the experience of the First World War and the years of peace pre
ceding it. See Chapter II [Not included in this translation.—Eds.].
40. Jews (+29%).
Notes to Pages 100-119 — * 194
41. We are using this abbreviated group label instead of the inconvenient “partici
pants with high school diploma but without university education.”
42. “University graduates” (speakers with university education) are ranked in sec
ond place in regard to the frequency of ambivalent attitudes, immediately fol
lowing adolescents up to 20 years.
43. In contrast to their silence toward the topic of Jews, the university graduates
participate between 14% and 57% more often in the discussion concerning all
other topics than the average of all groups.
44. The index for the test topics is +125 and takes the fifth position in this rank.
45. The combined index of the farmers is -477; the next highest negative index for
the four test topics is -284 (university graduates).
46. Even though we do not discuss the attitude toward the East in the analysis of
the profiles due to reasons mentioned above, we wish to at least point out that
a friendly attitude toward the East is three times as high among the farmers’
group as among the average of all groups.
Afterword
1. See T. W. Adorno: Guilt and Defense, Cambridge, Mass. (Harvard University
Press) 2010.
2. Nietzsche developed a psychological explanation for this form of reaction of
“anaesthetiz[ing] pain through feeling”: “generally this is sought, quite wrongly
it seems to me, in the defensive counter-strike, a merely reactive protective mea
sure, a ‘reflex movement’ in the case of any kind of sudden injury and danger,
like the way in which a frog still seeks to escape a corrosive acid once decapi
tated. But the difference is fundamental here: in one instance, the desire is to
prevent further injury, in the other, to anaesthetize by means of any more intense
emotion a secret pain and torment which is becoming unbearable, and so to
exclude it from consciousness for a moment at least. And for this purpose a feel
ing is required, the most intense feeling possible, and, in order to stimulate it, the
first pretext which happens along. ‘Someone must be to blame for the fact that I
do not feel well’—” From E Nietzsche: On the Genealogy of Morals. A Polemic,
trans, by D. Smith, Oxford (Oxford University Press) 1996, pp. 105E
3. See Handwörterbuch der Sozialwissenschaften, Tübingen 1954, Empirische
Sozialforschung, Kontrolliertes Experiment, p. 424.
4. See Chapter 4.
5. See T W. Adorno: Guilt and Defense.
Appendices A & B
1. Theoretically available speaking time = Duration of the discussion/Size of group.
2. See Aspekte der Sprache, vol. IV of the Manuscripts on the “Gruppenstudie”
in the Institut für Sozialforschung, Frankfurt am Main.
3. See T W. Adorno: Guilt and Defense, Cambridge, Mass. (Harvard University
Press) 2010.
4. See Karl Kraus: Die letzten Tage der Menschheit, Zürich 1945, f°r example
Act III, Scene 45, pp. 406E
Notes to Pages ι6 γ -ι8 ο ~~ 197
Institut für Sozialforschung (IFS). See Marcuse, Herbert, xv, xviii, xli
Frankfurt Institute for Social Research Marquis, Donald G., 133032
Marres, Noortje, xxxiv, xlv
Jacobs, Lawrence, xlviii Martin, John Levi, xxii
Jäger, Lorenz, xxiii, xxxviii, xxxix Massification, xxi
Jahoda, Marie, xxii, xxxii Mass society, xvii, 169
Janowitz, Morris, xvi, xxiv Maus, Köhne and Heinz, xxxix
Jarkko, Lars, 179 McDougall, William, 12, 119012
Jay, Martin, xxii, xxxii, xxxviii, xlii McFarland, Katherine, xxxiv
Jenemann, David, xvi, xvii, xix, xxii Mendelberg, Tali, xxxiv
Jepperson, Ronald L., xxvi, xxx, xxxvi, xlix Merritt, Anna J. and Richard L., xxix
Jews, xxvii, xxxi, xxxii, 13,41, 4 3 »79» 97, Merton, Robert K., xxv, xxviii, xlvi
98, 108, 139, 165, 166, 171, 178; Military service, attitude according to term
attitudes towards, 77, 78, 100, 101; of, 91,93
problem, 165-166; question, 1 Morgan, David L., xxviii
Morgenthau Jr., Henry, 121
Karplus, Margarete, xxxix Morgenthau Plan, 121
Katz, Elihu, xix, xx Mutz, Diana C., xxxiv
Kellner, Douglas, xlii
Kendall, Patricia L., xxv, xxviii Nagel, Ivan, xxxix
Klinenberg, Eric, xxi National Socialism, xxiii, xxix, xxxiv, xxxv,
Köhne, Rainer, xxxiv, 161 xxxvii, 41-43, 46, 59, 63, 96, 97, 116,
Kohut, Andrew, xlviii 126, 163, 164, 170, 172, 173, 175, 177
König, René, xxii, xliv, i8n23, 161 Neumann, Franz, xxxviii
Korean War, 47, 60, 61, 62, 121, 178 Newcomb, Theodore Mead, 7005
Kracauer, Siegfried, xviii Newport, Frank, xxx, xlviii
Kraus, Karl, ι 64Π4 Nietzsche, Friedrich, xxxviii
Noelle-Neumann, Elizabeth, xxix, 2on2
Lamont, Michèle, xxxvi Non-public opinion, xxiv, xlvi, 3, 4, 5, 6, 7,
Language, xxvii, xxxiv, 161, 166, 174; 8, 148, 149
brittleness of, 51; and speech, 174
Lasswell, Harold, xxiv Occupation, attitudes according to, 102,
Latour, Bruno, xxvii, xxxiv, xlv, xlix 103, 104, 105, 106. See also Profession,
Lazarsfeld, Paul, xv, xvi, xix, xx, xxiv, attitude according to
xxxix, 23m i, 27022, 49, 49Π54, 50056 Oehler, Christoph, xl
Le Bon, Gustave, 12 Olick, Jeffrey K., xxii, xxiii, xlii, xliv
Leib, Ethan J., 1 Opinion, xlvii, 2, 9, 13, 19, 20, 21, 23nio,
Levinson, Daniel J., 1205, 40040 3 1, 3 2, 5 3, 69; act of holding, 21 ; and
Lewin, Kurt, xxiv, 1 m3, 138036, 141, attitude, 23n8; collective nature of, 33;
141044 contradictory tendencies in, 29; forma
Lezaun, Javier, xxxiv, xlvii tion, 12; instability of, 28; polling,
Lichterman, Paul, xlvii, 1 xxviii-xxx, xxxiii, xlv, xlviii, 21; public,
Lippit, R., 48050 xxiv, xxv, xxvi, xxxiii, xxxiv, xlv, xlix, 3,
Lippmann, Walter, xxiv, 2in7 5, 7, 8, 9, 20, 21, 24, 25, 26, 31, 32, 108,
Löwenthal, Leo, xv, xviii 180, 18 1, 183; public, concept of, 21;
Lukâcs, Georg, xviii research, xxiii-xxvi, xxx, xxxiv, xxxvi, xl,
Lynching, 1 3 ,4 1 ,4 3 , 178 xlv, xlvii, xlviii, 1, li, 10, 20, 21, 22, 23,
Lynd, Robert, xvi 25, 3°» 37» J79» 182, 183; surveys, xxiii
Oppenheimer, Franz, 1 ion2
Maclver, Robert Μ., 11 ιη6, 112Π9 Osborne, Thomas, xlix
MacKenzie, Donald, xlix
MacKinnon, William Alexander, 23012 Page, Benjamin, xlix, 1
MacKuen, Michael, xlviii, 1 Page, Charles H., 11 in6
Index — 202
Paley, Julia, xxvii, xlix Social science, xxii, xxiii, xxv, xxx, xlii, 13,
Parten, Mildred, 2m 3, 27020, 28ni4 19, 20; American, xxiii, xxviii, xxix,
Perrin, Andrew J., xxi, xxii, xxvi, xxviii, xxxii, xxxvii, xlvi, 10, 154; methods, xxx.
xxxi, xxxiv-xxxvi, xlii, xlvii, xlix, See also Sociology
179 Sociology, i i , 19, 20,4 9 , 155; in postwar
Piazza, Thomas, 1 Germany, 10
Pickford, Henry W., xx Sombart, Werner, 1 ion 3
Plato, 13 Spencer, Herbert, 11 in 5, 112
Plessner, Helmuth, xxxix Stanton, Frank N., xix
Plessner, Monika, xxxix Steigert, Nikolaus, xxxix
Polling. See Opinion: polling Stendenbach, Franz Josef, xxxviii, xliv
Pollock, Friedich, xviii, xxii, xxiv, Stereotypes, 22, 62, 64, 65
xxviii Stern, Frank, xxix
Princeton Radio Research Project, xv, Stimson, James A., xlviii, 1
xvi Sunstein, Cass R., xxxiv, 1
Profession, attitude according to, 91, 93, Surveys, xxvi, xxvii, xliv, 1, 27, 30, 32, 37;
102 method, 26, 3 1, 32, 43
Publicness, xl, xlvii, 179, 180, 181 Swidler, Ann, xxv, xxxvi, xlix
Public opinion. See Opinion: public
Templer, William, xxix
Radio, xxi, xxiv, 3, 7 Tenbruck, Friedrich H., xxii, xliv
Rae, Saul Forbes, xxx Thévenot, Laurent, xxxvi
Refugees, 132, 139, 167 Thomas, Martin Luther, xx, xl
Remilitarization, attitudes towards, 60, Tiedemann, Rolf, xx
61, 83, 84, 85, 86, 97, 102, 104, 119 Tilly, Charles, xxv
Rice, Stuart A., 19m Tönnies, Ferdinand, 24, 25016, 25017
Roosevelt, Franklin Delano, 128 Totality, xv, xvi, xvii, xxix, 11, 24, 154, 171
Rose, Nikolas, xlix Totally socialized people (vergesellschaftete
Rousseau, Jean Jacques, 24η 15 Leute), 20
Russian occupation, 59 Totally socialized society (vergesellschaftete
Russians, 6, 34, 46, 59, 66, 72, 106, 118, Gesellschaft), xviii, xix, xxi, xxx, xxxiii,
121, 122, 162, 171, 178 xxxiv, xli, xlii, xlv, xlvi, xlviii, 23
Trombadori, Duccio, xlvi
Sanford, R. Nevitt, 12η 5, 40040 Trotter, William, 122
Sasson, Theodore, xlvii Truman, Harry, 46
Sauder, Michael, xlix
Sawyer, R. Keith, xxxiv United States, xvi, xviii, xix, xxii, xxvii,
Schachtei; Stanley, 133031, 140043 xxviii, xxxviii, 59, 61.
Schiller, Friedrich, 3m
Schmid, Calvin F., 30029 Vergesellschaftete Gesellschaft. See Totally
Schudson, Michael, xxviii socialized society (vergesellschaftete
Schweppenhäuser, Gerhard, xviii, xxxix Gesellschaft)
Schweppenhauser, Hermann, xxxiv, 161 Vierkandt, Alfred, 110, 1 ion3, 119m 5,
Science, 4, 14, 26, 31 1 2 7 ,Ι27Π27, 144045
Sell, Hans Joachim, xxxix Volksgemeinschaft, xv, 169, 172
Shapiro, Robert, xlviii, xlix, 1 von Friedeburg, Ludwig, xxxix, xl
Silent participants, xxix, 150, 157; partly, von Haselberg, Peter, xxxix
157,158,159; totally, 157
Simmel, Georg, 119014, 138, 152 Warner, Michael, xlv, xlix
Skocpol, Theda, 1 Weber, Max, 11, 12, 49, 182
Smith, David Horton, xxx, xxxvi Weil, Felix, xviii
Sniderman, Paul Μ., I West, the, xxii, xxxi, 98; attitudes toward,
Social control, 109, 136, 137 80, 81, 97, 102, 103
Index 203