0% found this document useful (0 votes)
108 views735 pages

Morrison Spin BitzV1

Uploaded by

A Collins
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
108 views735 pages

Morrison Spin BitzV1

Uploaded by

A Collins
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 735

Version 0.

999…
See www.spinbitz.net for more info.
Copyright © 2007 by Joel David Morrison. All
rights reserved. No part of this book may be
reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or
transmitted, in any form or by any means
without prior written permission from the
author or his estate.

All artwork and design, both internal and


external, was created by the author, unless
otherwise specified.

Page | 3
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
This is a highly collaborative work, drawing, often unconsciously, on many
sources both known and unknown and working at many levels, across many
disciplines spanning nearly the whole spectrum of human knowledge and
ideas. The net is cast wide, but as such it cannot possibly hit all relevant
points in-between, and it also cannot penetrate with equal depth into all its
points of contact. The vast depth and complexity of these systems of human
thought makes the construction of the linear linguistic interface between
them seem like (in the words of Stanislaw Lem) “giving birth to a leviathan
through the eye of a needle—which turns out to be possible, if the leviathan
is sufficiently reduced. But then the leviathan looks like a flea. Such are my
problems when I try to adapt [this emergent system of living concepts] to …
language.”i
Writing such a book is like skinning an 11-headed dragon into one long
and thin strip of leathery scales. How can one retain the iridescent living
beauty and patterning of the scales? Or the elegant curvature and
serpentine motions of the intertwining necks? Or the form of the
musculature in the legs, torso and arms? … To strip away the metaphor, how
can one retain the emergent structure and inter-connective synergetic
harmony of the simultaneous actions of hundreds of billions of nerve-cells
and electro-chemical gradients as they emerge into the higher-level thought-
patterns that make up this living system of concepts if one reduces it to a
single, long line of alpha-numeric text which the reader must transcode and
attempt to bring to life, bit by tiny bit? Can I effectively convey the broad
simultaneous network of interconnected ideas after it is run through the
spaghetti machine of human language? This question, at the interface of

i
(Lem, Imaginary Magnitudes, Golem XIV), oooh such grandiosity to take the perspective of Golem
XIV, but its resonance to our human nature provides such a clear line of departure, illustrating the
holarchical nature between deep embodied semantics and higher-level syntax.

Page | 5
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

communication itself, depends as much on the reader as it does on the


writer.

As Gerald Lebau so eloquently stated in the preface to his 1965 work, The
Nature of Matter and Energy:
All in all, this is a highly interconnected and interdependent set of
concepts. No one part can be fully understood until all of it has been
finished. The reader’s patient indulgence is urgently requested. The major
intellectual effort required to complete the book should be most
adequately rewarding.
Ultimately, we have to progress linearly in unfolding this complex nonlinear
system, so our communication depends critically on the patience of the
reader to allow the nonlinear intuition of critical underlying concepts and
contexts—that have not yet been given their time on the stage—to naturally
and fully emerge. As Deleuze might say, the reader must allow the “plane of
consistency” in the text to fully arise, lest a premature criticism enforce a
false reading in this highly inadequate linear method of communication.
To this end I have attempted to give as much nonlinearity as possible to
the construction. I have supplied many visual diagrams, and I have tried to
format the book hierarchically by subject, and sequentially by generality—
from the general to the specific—and have given cross-references (and
hyperlinks for the ebook format) where possible (see the back of the book
for formatting specifics). The book should unfold adequately for most
readers in the sequential format, but it can also be approached nonlinearly
by subject—jumping to new subjects or levels of generality/specificity as
needed, in order to explore, or give context to the current position on the
chosen nonlinear trajectory.

My only wish is that this book be enjoyed, because only if it is enjoyed will it
be understood. Let the dialogue unfold as you, the creative reader, see fit. If
it is not fun following a sequential format, then by all means skip around.
Hopefully the formatting and style of the book will be adequately
accommodating.

Page | 6

stone-walled into compartments
form is stolen from potential
like the exoskeleton of a new insect
liberating protoplasm to wander
into the labyrinthine tomb of its own hardening limbs.

the chitinous infant now begins to crawl


single-file and into battle.

on the field is found every form of armor


concealing identity
dividing unity into multiplicity—

beneath them all, breathing calmly … in time ...


the singular form awaits conception.

At the beginning of the twenty-first century, we stand at an historical fault-


line between vast, colliding monoliths of thought. These living fossils rise
and fall in competitive fluctuation, straddling a deep, layered axis of
polarities manifesting as seemingly irreconcilable dichotomies competing
for control of the collective mind. These competing factions, both ancient
and modern, include: the exoteric vs. the esoteric; science vs. religion;
materialism vs. idealism; reductionism vs. holism; rationalism vs.
empiricism; continuity vs. quantum; being vs. nothingness; the epistemic vs.
the ontic; orthodoxy vs. the heretic; flux vs. stasis; the absolute vs. the
relative; immanence vs. transcendence; causality vs. randomness; order vs.
chaos; and determinism vs. free-will.
Violently clashing in reverberating fits throughout the distorting echo-
chamber of history, beneath their rigid exteriors these polarized ideologies,
methodologies, territorial alignments and paradigms secretly and
unconsciously feed each other through the differences which oppose, inter-
relate and unite them. On the surface, they seem wholly at odds, and yet
deep within they remain locked in a tight symbiosis of interpenetrating

Page | 7
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

interfaces. And through us, these living monoliths grope and crash their way,
ever onward, inward and upward, to a deeper, vaster, higher, more coherent,
comprehensive and organic coalescence.
Slowly drifting and converging through the infinite “space of
possibilities,” the rigid and cracked empirical, logical and mathematical
exteriors of the pragmatic, exoteric and quantitative systems move toward
integration with the expanding soft and supple center of ancient esoteric
wisdom—the common, unmoved, yet ever-yielding core of singular
“metaphysical” understanding manifesting throughout all cultures of man
and intrinsic to his deepest intuitions. This ubiquitous, esoteric wisdom is
only divided and conquered—flattened into layers and layers trampled
under foot with each successive generation—by the fossilization of
differences in the superficial details of the rigid and arbitrary categories of
man’s symbol-systems. It is merely the institutionalization of the different
arbitrary mappings—to the same living and breathing core—that stands
between them.

“There has only ever been one ontological proposition…

…Being is univocal.

A single voice raises the clamour of being…”i

i
— Gilles Deleuze, Difference & Repetition

Page | 8
A NOTE TO THE READER...........................................................................................5
PRELUDE: SPELL-BINDING ........................................................................................7
CONTENTS (QUICK).................................................................................................9
CONTENTS (FULL) .................................................................................................10
FORMATTING NOTES .............................................................................................20
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY .....................................23
PROLEGOMENA: NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM .........58
PART ONE: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY..................... 106
THE INTERFACE BETWEEN INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL RATIONALISM ...........107
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT (EOTC) .............................................................108
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM (VCS).......................................................125
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEWORK (UF) ........................................................................155
PART TWO: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS ...................................................... 202
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION ........................................204
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION ....................................309
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE SECOND TIER ................372
RECONNECTING THE LOST THREAD OF MATHEMATICAL RATIONALISM: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ,
IMMANENCE AND THE CALCULUS ...........................................................................402
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX ...............................434
PART THREE: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL RATIONAL-EMPIRICISM ... 486
PHILOSOPHY: THE INTEGRATING ART OF THE CONCEPT ..............................................487
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY AND “THE NUCLEATION OF OBSERVABILITY” ................488
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH .................................................544
LEIBNOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES ...............................................663
TABLES AND LISTS ....................................................................................... 719
BIBLIOGRAPHY ........................................................................................... 722
INDEX ....................................................................................................... 726

Page | 9
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

A NOTE TO THE READER ................................................... 5


PRELUDE: SPELL-BINDING ................................................. 7
CONTENTS (QUICK) ......................................................... 9
CONTENTS (FULL) ......................................................... 10
FORMATTING NOTES ...................................................... 20
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY 23
Overview.................................................................................. 28
Uncovering the Project of Esoteric Rationalism ...................... 33
Clearing Away the Dust of the Great Chain of Being........................................... 39
Post-Post-ism-ism: Condition-Critical in the Ontic-Shadow of
Post-Kantian Dualism .............................................................. 43
The Gyth of the Miven ........................................................................................ 45
The Kantian Legacy: “Rationalism” vs. “Empiricism” .......................................... 49
“Post-Metaphysics” and “Post Ontology”: An Acategorical Stance .................... 50
Aside: A Wilber Encounter of the Third Kind .................................................. 54
Post-Metaphysics and the Transcendental Injunction ........................................ 55
PROLEGOMENA: NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF
THE CONTINUUM .......................................................... 58
The Tao of Rationalism: Pulverizing the Categories ................ 59
What is Nondualism? .......................................................................................... 59
What is Rationalism? .......................................................................................... 62
Nondual Rational-Empiricism and the Acategorical Imperative ......................... 65
The Nondual Rational as Trans-“Rational” .......................................................... 69
The Exoteric Face of Esoteric Rationalism .......................................................... 70
The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism.............................................................................. 74
Principle 1: Chord 1: The Fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism (PNDR)
............................................................................................................................ 87

Page | 10
CONTENTS

Principle 2: The Un-Principle of Principles: ......................................................... 88


Infinite Division Equals Indivisibility .................................................................... 88
A Note on Descartes ........................................................................................... 91
Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-
bias .......................................................................................... 94
Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of Immanence in Transcendence (Yin in Yang)
............................................................................................................................ 98
A Brief Note on Foundationalism: Logical and Ontological ................................. 98
Substance and Bundle Views of Substance ....................................................... 102

PART ONE: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE


PHILOSOPHY ..................................................... 106
THE INTERFACE BETWEEN INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL
RATIONALISM ............................................................ 107
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT (EOTC) ....................... 108
Phase ONE: Unity .................................................................. 112
Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind
............................................................................................... 114
Phase THREE: Triunity: Cultivating the Interface of Polarity. 116
Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR) ......................... 119
Chord 3 Example: The Inverse Unified Field ..................................................... 119
Detecting the PAR ............................................................................................. 122
The Omni-Non: The Binary Logic of the Absolute/Relative Interface ............... 122
Con-Fusions at the Interface ............................................................................. 124
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM (VCS) ................. 125
Vision-logic Interfaces: Vision-logic and Blind-logic .............. 126
The Plane of Immanence ....................................................... 132
The VCS: Breaking Away from the Plane of Immanence....... 134
The Two VL- Axes: Immanent/Transcendent and Transitive. 137
The Transitive Axes: In Through the “Attic Window” ........................................ 139
The Immanent/Transcendent Axis .................................................................... 140
Coordinates on the Immanent-Transcendent Axis ....................................... 144
I/T Omni- and Uni-axes ................................................................................ 146
I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non ..................................... 147
A Concluding Note on the VCS: Integrating the Differentiations
............................................................................................... 153
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEWORK (UF) ................................. 155
Univocity ................................................................................ 156
Page | 11
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Univocity: Introduction ..................................................................................... 156


Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual .................................................. 158
Spinoza’s Univocity ........................................................................................... 160
Univocity as Multiplicity .................................................................................... 165
Univocity and Numerical Distinction/Identity ................................................... 168
Univocity and Force .......................................................................................... 170
Univocity and Essence....................................................................................... 172
Polarity and Univocity ....................................................................................... 176
Horizontal or Transitive Polarity ................................................................... 176
“Vertical” Polarity: The Polarity of Polarity ................................................. 177
Univocity and the Fundamental Question ........................................................ 178
Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity ......................................... 178
Hegel’s Dialectic vs. Univocity ........................................................................... 180
Hegel’s Dialectic as Performative Contradiction ............................................... 182
Univocity as Deep Infinity: Prigogine and Leibniz ............................................. 184
Univocity and Immanent Determinism ............................................................. 186
Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID) ..................... 188
Symptomatology: Nomothetic vs. Idiographic Explanations ........................ 188
Univocity and the Eternal NOW ........................................................................ 189
Exploring the Univocity Framework ...................................... 192
The Axis of Univocity ......................................................................................... 196
The Univocity Framework In Action: Leibniz and the “Principle of Macrocosm
and Microcosm” ................................................................................................ 197

PART TWO: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS ................... 202


MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION ... 204
Pre-rational Con-fusion and the Paradoxes of the Infinite ... 209
Implicit Holonic Set-Theory and the Part-Whole Axiom ................................... 209
The Galilean Part/Whole Paradox ..................................................................... 215
Hilbert’s Paradox of the Grand Hotel ................................................................ 218
A Note on “Operational” ................................................................................... 222
The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite .................................... 224
The Finite, The Infinite, and Scope .................................................................... 224
The Identity vs. the Opposite: Post-Modern Con-fusion and Pre-modern Naiveté
.......................................................................................................................... 224
A Foot in the Door to Paradise: Cantor’s Quick Fix ........................................... 231
The Cantorian Turn to Immanence: From the Uni- to Omni-Axis ................. 233
A Final Cantorian Solution? .......................................................................... 234
The Pearl Principle ............................................................................................ 238
Principle 6: The Pearl Principle of Axiomatic Encapsulation ......................... 240
Unity and Nonduality ............................................................ 242
Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE .................................................................................. 243
Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity ................. 248
Finite Unity: “Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two” ......................................... 249

Page | 12
CONTENTS

Principle 8: Chord 6: The Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity (or The


Principle of Holonic Polarity) ........................................................................ 251
The Polarity of Infinity and (Primitive) Number ................................................ 253
Trans-Trans-Bias: Pre-echo-echo ...................................................................... 255
The (Binary) Cycle of Unity ................................................................................ 257
The Orbit of Unity ......................................................................................... 263
The Double Orbit .......................................................................................... 265
Spinoza, the Infinite, the Indefinite and the Imagination ................................. 267
A Note on Fuller’s Finite Absolutism ............................................................. 269
The Triune Infinite: Interfacing Emptiness ............................ 271
Cantor’s Three Infinities .................................................................................... 271
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite .................................................................................... 273
Order 1: The Absolute Infinite ...................................................................... 275
Order 2: The Aspect Infinite .......................................................................... 276
First and Second Phases of the Aspect Infinite ........................................ 277
Order 3: The Modal (or Bounded) Infinite: ................................................... 282
The Platonic Sphere as Root Modal Infinite and Primitive Infinite Number
................................................................................................................. 284
The Fractal ............................................................................................... 285
The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attributes and Modifications . 288
VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-logic Equations
............................................................................................... 291
The Vision-Logic Equations ............................................................................... 293
The Root VLE (I/T Axis and the Absolute Infinite) ......................................... 293
The 2nd Order VLE (Aspect Infinite) ............................................................... 294
The 3rd Order VLE (Bounded Infinite) ............................................................ 294
Summary List of VLE ..................................................................................... 295
Note: The Cycle of the Infinite ...................................................................... 296
Boundary and Dimension: ..................................................... 298
Dimension from the Omni-Non......................................................................... 298
Rectilinear vs. “Nuclear” Dimensioning Systems .............................................. 299
Side-Note: Euclidean vs. Non-Euclidean Dimensions ........................................ 308
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION 309
Phase ONE: The Immanent-transcendent Axis as Implicit Origin
In Mathematics ..................................................................... 310
Phase TWO: Unit-closure and the Finite Unit-Identity .......... 311
Phase THREE: The Transitive-axis and Agglomeration ......... 314
The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias.................................................................... 315
Transitive Number as Agglomeration: The Natural Numbers ........................... 319
Addition and Closure on the Transitive-axis ..................................................... 321
Subtraction, Closure Violation and Transitive Zero as Negation ....................... 323
Transitive Zero: A Return to Origin ................................................................... 325
The Implicit Recursion of Numerical-Addition .................................................. 326

Page | 13
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Phase FOUR: Transitive Interfacing with the I/T Axis............ 327


Multiplication Through Division ........................................................................ 327
Recursion, Iopol, Violation of Closure and the Acategorical Imperative ........... 332
The Ratio and the Expanding/Contracting Holonic Solidus ............................... 334
The Rational and the Deleuzian Intensive Forces ............................................. 337
The Absolute Value and the Intensive Forces ................................................... 337
The Polarity of Zero: The Amphibian of the Transitive and Immanent ............. 338
The Orthogonality of Inverses and the Offset Origin-Identities ........................ 341
The Kernel of the Trans-Trans Asymmetry and Instability at the Crossroads of
the Transitive and I/T Axes................................................................................ 343
Phase FIVE: The Trans-Rational as Second Tier..................... 345
I/T Powering and Rooting: Unfolding the Onion of Operations ........................ 345
Absolute Value and the Square-Root Property ................................................. 351
The Imaginary as Vestigial Transitive Axis at the I/T Interface.......................... 351
The Implicit Axiom of Perpendicularity in Trans-Biased Pre-Rationality....... 352
Imagining the Unimaginable: Realizing the Unreal ...................................... 353
Four-Dimensionality: Trans-Biased vs. Immanent/Transcendent ................. 355
Structural vs. Representational Relation ...................................................... 361
The Trans-Rationality of the Irrational Numbers .............................................. 368
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE
SECOND TIER ............................................................. 372
The Maps of Interface Mathematics ..................................... 373
The Map of the Holarchy and VCS Axes of Mathematical Operations .............. 373
The Core SpinbitZ Diagram ............................................................................... 375
The Saw-tooth Curve of Iopol Inversion in the Evolution of Number and
Operation .......................................................................................................... 381
The Binary Cycle of Identities, Axes and Unities.................... 383
Functions and Graphs From the Second Tier......................... 388
Unpacking the Onion of Operations ................................................................. 388
The Cartesian Axes and the Image of the Trans-bias ........................................ 389
The Implicit Iopol of Function Operations ........................................................ 392
Looking for Holes in the Rational Functions: Locating Asymptotes .................. 392
The Immanent Function ............................................................................... 394
The Balanced (Rational) Function ................................................................ 394
The Trans-Trans Function ............................................................................. 395
The Transcendent Function .......................................................................... 396
Embryology Through the Exponent and Logarithm .......................................... 397
Unpacking the Onion: Expanding Logarithmic Functions ............................. 400
The Trans-Rational: Ontogeny Recapitulates Phylogeny .................................. 401
RECONNECTING THE LOST THREAD OF MATHEMATICAL
RATIONALISM: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, IMMANENCE AND THE
CALCULUS ................................................................. 402

Page | 14
CONTENTS

Leibniz, Spinoza, the Triune Infinite and the Calculus ........... 403
The Inception of the Calculus ............................................................................ 403
The “Ghost of Departed Quantities” and the Problem with the Infinitesimal .. 404
Fixing “The Limit” of the Unlimited ................................................................... 406
The Hidden Leibnizian Thread ........................................................................... 407
The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite...................................................... 409
Leibnizian Pre-Echoes of Cantor........................................................................ 411
The Nondual-Rational Interface Solution .............................. 415
Reconnecting to the Deleuzian Alternative Lineage ............. 418
Hegel’s Calculus of Misrepresentation .............................................................. 418
Deleuze and the “Differential Point of View of the Infinitesimal Calculus” ...... 424
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
.............................................................................. 434
The Acategorical Perspective and the LOMA ........................ 435
Paradox and the LOMA: A Geometrical Example .............................................. 437
Paradox as Transitive Illusion of Perspective .................................................... 441
Galileo, Cantor and the Transfinite ....................................... 444
The Two-Floors of the Transfinite ..................................................................... 447
Summary: The Nondual/Interface Definition and Resolution of the Nature of
Infinity ............................................................................................................... 449
Back to Zeno .......................................................................... 450
Swirling in the Presocratic Soup ........................................................................ 451
From Muck Into Form ................................................................................... 452
Parmenides and Second-Order Philosophy ................................................... 453
Corso and Recorso: Self-Similarity in the History of Philosophy ................... 454
Plurality is Unity: Zeno’s Core Paradox ............................................................. 456
Post-Socratic Scope Con-Fusion .................................................................... 458
Parmenides, Heraclitus, and the Cycle of Unity and VL-Axes ....................... 461
Simultaneous Division “Through and Through” ................................................ 463
Aside: Countable and Uncountable, Linear vs. Parallel and the “Hard
Problem” of Consciousness........................................................................... 467
Zenonian Plurality and the Binary Interface of the VL-Axes .............................. 467
The Paradoxes of Motion and the Many Faces of Plurality ............................... 470
The Dichotomy: “Motion Cannot Take a Start” ............................................ 472
The Achilles: “Motion Cannot Come to its End” ........................................... 472
The Stadium: “The First Two Arguments Combined for Extended Bodies” ... 473
The Naked Paradox (The Arrow): “Motion is Self-Contradictory” ................ 475
Tuning and Triuning the Naked Zenonian Interface .......................................... 477
Further Cultivating the Zenonian Third ............................................................. 478
Paradoxical Postscript and Epitaph: Kan’t and the Antinomies
of Pure Reason ...................................................................... 481

Page | 15
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

PART THREE: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL


RATIONAL-EMPIRICISM ........................................ 486
PHILOSOPHY: THE INTEGRATING ART OF THE CONCEPT ......... 487
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY AND “THE NUCLEATION OF
OBSERVABILITY” ......................................................... 488
Section I: Bridging the Interpretive Rift ................................. 489
Orientation........................................................................................................ 489
Overview of the Problem of the Attributes ...................................................... 490
The Interpretive Rift: Subjectivism vs. Objectivism? ......................................... 491
Section 2: The Crossroads of Hidden Polarities ..................... 496
Ontic/Epistemic Visa Versus Subject/Object..................................................... 496
The Ontic/Epistemic Polarity ........................................................................ 498
Clarifying Our Terminology: The Objective-Ontic Shift ........................... 498
The New Ontic/Epistemic Polarity........................................................... 500
The Attributes as Both Formative and Descriptive Protocols .................. 502
The Attribute Polarity: “Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two” ......................... 504
The Intersection of Polarities and the VCS .................................................... 504
Cognitive Interfaces – The Nucleation of Observability ................................ 506
From Modes to Heaps and Holons .......................................................... 506
A Note on the Attributes .............................................................................. 510
Attribute Parallelism: Connected Isolation and the Explanatory Gap .......... 512
The Problem of the Attributes Revisited ........................................................... 514
“Transcendental Empiricism” and the “Cogito of the Dissolved Self” .............. 515
Section 3: The Polarities in Action, and a Resolution of the
“Hard Problem” ..................................................................... 517
The Roles of Extension ...................................................................................... 517
Extension as Transitive Expansion ................................................................ 517
Extension as it Relates to Perception ........................................................... 518
Extension as it Relates to the Essence of Substance ..................................... 522
The Mind-Body Problem and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object .......... 527
The Mind-body Problem as a Limitation of the Fundamental Descriptive
Protocols ...................................................................................................... 527
Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and
Object ........................................................................................................... 531
Identity Theory, Neutral Monism and Nondual Rationalism ........................ 536
Concluding Note On Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity ............................................. 541
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH ........... 544
Interfaces at the Crossroads.................................................. 545
Condition Still Critical: Waking Up from the Post-Op Nightmare
of the Kantian Radical Ontotomy .......................................... 548

Page | 16
CONTENTS

The Triune Epistemic: An Outline of the Interfaces ............... 552


Ontic-Epistemic: The One vs. the Ten-Thousand Things ................................... 552
Crossing out the Cross-Talk: -ic Versus -ology................................................... 552
The Subject/Object and Ontic/Epistemic Interfaces ......................................... 554
Reality, Meaning and Language: Aristotle’s Three Levels of Being ................... 558
Interfacing AQAL Metatheory and the Integral OS ............... 560
From Dependent- to Tetra- Arising: The Conceptual Embryogenesis of AQAL . 563
Identifying Quadrant Absolutisms .................................................................... 564
The AQAL Map and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System .................................. 566
“All is Perspective” Visa Versus “All is Holonic” ................................................ 569
Holarchy as Anatomy: The Atom and the Network—the Holon and the Rhizome
.......................................................................................................................... 573
Depth vs. Span: Further Untangling the Trans-Trans-Bias ................................ 576
The Problem of the Infinite Holarchy ............................................................ 581
Evolution is Involution Seen in Reverse......................................................... 583
Aside: The Black Hole and Meditation .......................................................... 586
Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos .......................... 589
Holarchic and Holonic Depth: The Rhizome and the Tree............................. 592
Embodiment, Knowledge and Meaning: the Rise of the
Sensory-Mnemonic Interface ................................................ 596
Defining the Scope of Scope ............................................................................. 596
The “Truth of Relativity” Vs. the “Relativity of Truth” .................................. 599
The Cogito Interface: The Root of the Empiric and Epistemic........................... 599
Sex Cells: “Deep Evolution” is Intelligent Design .............................................. 601
Evolution and the Problem-Child .................................................................. 603
Shotgun Creationism: The Engineering Interface ......................................... 604
The Interface of Intercourse ......................................................................... 606
Sex and the Big Biological Bang ................................................................... 607
Insane in the Mem-brain: Embodiment, Meaning and the Mnemonic Primitives
.......................................................................................................................... 609
Language Learns to Speak: Genetic Mnemonics and Causal Languages ..... 609
Sex, Feedback and Evolutionary Sensation ................................................... 610
Deep Evolution and the Intensive Forces ...................................................... 611
Interface Biology .......................................................................................... 612
The Evolution of Sensation ........................................................................... 614
The Self-Aperture and the Sensor-Effector Polarity .......................................... 617
The Emergence of Meaning in Deep Evolutionary Embodiment ...................... 620
Percept and Concept ......................................................................................... 621
The Symbiogenesis of the Rational and Empirical............................................. 622
The Symbiogenesis of the “Forms of Sensibility” and the Sensation of Form... 623
The Embryogenesis of Theories of Perception ...................... 628
Phase One: Unity is Blind .................................................................................. 628
Phase Two: Polarity and the Naïve Genius of Evolution ................................... 628
Phase Two…Minus-a-Half: Directly Indirectly Anti-Realistic ............................. 630
Phase One-Half-Minus-Two: Anti-Realism and the Contracted Cogito ............. 631

Page | 17
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Phase Three: The Interface Model of Perception ............................................. 632


Trans-Folding Models of Knowledge and Truth .................... 633
Knowledge Acquisition: Rationalism, Empiricism and Constructivism .............. 633
Quadrant Interfaces and PAR-Tunnels: Cogitism, Formalism and Other Theories
of Knowledge .................................................................................................... 635
The “Schmiderialism” Tunnel ....................................................................... 635
Realism, Phenomenalism, and Pragmatism ................................................. 637
Knowledge, Truth, Scope Con-Fusion, and the Infinite Regress........................ 638
Infinitism and Affirmation ............................................................................ 640
Naiveté, Dogma and Skepticism ................................................................... 640
Correspondence and Analogy....................................................................... 642
The Fold and “Ruin” of the Object ................................................................ 644
Foundationalism: Crystalline Pyramids In Emptiness........................................ 645
Transcendental Determinism and the Captive Will ...................................... 647
Coherentism: Water-Tight Rafts Over the Abyss .............................................. 650
Logic as Circuitry .......................................................................................... 650
Coherence Floats: Up the Creek Without a Paddle ....................................... 651
Lost and Foundherentism ................................................................................. 652
Gettier, Internalism and Externalism ................................................................ 654
The Gettier Problem and the True Relations of Knowledge.......................... 654
Internalism: Bounded in Nut-Shell ................................................................ 655
Externalism: Opening the Interface .............................................................. 656
Internal or External to What?....................................................................... 656
The Interface Model of Epistemology: A Concluding Sketch ............................ 657
Integrating the Differentiations ................................................................... 658
Interface Epistemology: A Glossary of Terms ............................................... 660
LEIBNOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES ......... 663
Recap on the VLE .............................................................................................. 665
The Root VLE (I/T Axis and the Absolute Infinite) ......................................... 666
The 2nd Order VLE (Aspect Infinite) ............................................................... 666
The 3rd Order VLE (Bounded Infinite) ............................................................ 667
Spinoza: A Nondual Sketch .................................................... 668
Polarity: Substance and Modification—Emptiness and Form ........................... 668
Triunity: Substance, Modification and the Attributes ....................................... 669
Spinoza: Immanent in Transcendent, and Visa Versa ....................................... 670
Leibniz: A Reactionary Chiaroscuro ....................................... 672
The Culmination of the Proto-Rational ............................................................. 673
The Spinozan Heresy ......................................................................................... 675
The Principle of Action, and the Inner-Spinoza ................................................. 676
The Elements of a Reaction of “Pure Transcendence” ..................................... 680
God is Not Nature......................................................................................... 680
Spinoza’s God is Not God ............................................................................. 680
The Possible is Not Actual ............................................................................ 681
The Prime Chooser ....................................................................................... 682
Impermanence: Man is Not Mortal .............................................................. 684

Page | 18
CONTENTS

The Monadology: Substance is Not Infinite .................................................. 685


The Action of Reaction ...................................................................................... 686
Monads and Indra’s Magic Hall of Mirrors................................................... 686
Monadic Immaculate Conception and the “Problem of Sex” ....................... 687
“Metaphysico-Theologo-Cosmolonigology,” and the Best of Non-Possible
Worlds .......................................................................................................... 688
The Universe’s New Clothes .................................................................... 690
Compossibly Impossible .......................................................................... 691
God, the No-Brainer: Metaphysical vs. Moral Necessity ......................... 691
Transcending into Transitivity ................................................................. 693
Principle 9: Chord 7: The Principle of Pure Transcendence as Transitivity .... 695
Principle 10: Chord 8: The Principle of Infinite Possibility (or the Principle of
the Proton Pseudos) ..................................................................................... 696
Transcending Freedom into Fatalism ........................................................... 696
Immortality…as a “Speck of Dust”? .............................................................. 698
Driven Into Infinite Improbability ................................................................. 700
The Leibnizian Dilemma: Spinozism or Atheism ........................................... 701
God is not a Monad: Leibniz is a Spinozist ............................................... 703
God is a Monad: Leibniz is an Atheist ...................................................... 703
The Imminent Collapse ................................................................................. 704
Magnum Disharmonium.......................................................................... 704
Presumptive Salvation ............................................................................. 704
The Two Travelers ........................................................................................ 705
The Mannerist Aesthetics ................................................................................. 707
Animality, the Fold, and the Infinite Baroque Machine ................................ 710
Leibniz: Immanent Versus Transcendent God, with No Visa! ........................... 712
The “New Harmony” ............................................................. 714
Acknowledgements ........................................................................................... 718

TABLES AND LISTS............................................... 719


List of Illustrations ........................................................................................ 719
List of Equations (VLE) .................................................................................. 721
List of Principles ............................................................................................ 721

BIBLIOGRAPHY ................................................... 722


INDEX .............................................................. 726

Page | 19
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Footnotes
In order to help the reader remain undistracted by the many notes and
references, and to increase the reader’s own control of the flow of such a
complicated experience, I have differentiated the notes into three types
(naturally), with their own simple hierarchical order of operations (see
below), and placed them at the foot for easy access. The reader will very
quickly become accustomed to the symbology and easily and unconsciously
become aware of which notes to entirely ignore and which to possibly
explore, according to his purposes.
1. Subject-Tangent (i): This is the default; just a regular note, a tangent
of thought, or a curiosity leading perhaps nowhere in particular… It
will have no specific symbol other than the roman numeral they all
share in common, such as.i
2. Subject-Link (*): This note signifies a subject reference, or a hyperlink
(for the ebook) for splitting off into a related but different subject
trajectory in the book. This note will be followed by an asterisk, as
such,ii* and the note itself will contain only a reference or hyperlink to a
different section of the book, along with perhaps a bibliographic
reference.
3. Bibliographic Note (¥): This is simply a bibliographic reference, for
those tracing back to original sources. It will be followed by a ¥, as
such.iii¥ Page numbers, where available, will be included with the
“quote,” such as (p66).

i
e.g. Bucky Fuller mentions that Roman numerals were generated from the common numbering
system of notches or slashes, where larger bundles of slashes, say of five, are marked with a slash
through them so as to be counted by fives. This new symbol of the slash then evolved, for example,
into the symbol ‘V’.
ii
* e.g. See this page.
iii¥
e.g. (Ouspensky) p. 56

Page | 20
Order of Footnote Operations: These types are arranged in order of
importance to the reader in controlling the nonlinear flow of his/her
experience. As such, the bibliographic note takes lowest priority, and the
quick subject-tangent the highest. Where any of these are combined, they
will be subsumed under their next higher order. For example, in any
instance of combination with a subject-tangent, the note will be subsumed
under this default subject-tangent referent, e.g. i . If the reader has further
interest in the subject-tangent, for example, he may also find a subject-link
and/or bibliographic note. But where the subject-link and bibliographic
note are combined, the referent of the subject-link (*) will be used. And only
where the bibliographic note stands on its own, will we find its referent, ¥.

Index and Definitions


Given the volume of new terms in this work, the index will contain
references to key places in the text where these new terms are defined. This
will be noted simply with the sub-term “definition of.”

Page | 21
Page | 22
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

SpinbitZ is a toy: a playful, whirling, churning, folding and unfolding set of


concepts and visual interfaces, created, and to be used, ultimately for
enjoyment. It is not to be taken absolutely, as an attempt to unveil THE
TRUTH about ultimate reality. This conceptual toy emerged slowly, but
spontaneously, as the most creative, difficult, artistic, rigorous and enjoyable
endeavor that I have undertaken.
“Joy emerges as the sole motive for philosophizing,” says Deleuze. While
this is necessarily a personal motive for philosophy, there are certainly
transpersonal and evolutionary layers of motivation as well. All animals
play, and this play serves the critical function of flexing, strengthening, and
even creating, mental muscles, skills, perspectives, patterns and intuitions
for use in other spheres. The Rubik’s cube, recall, was played for hours,
days, and months on end by the most serious of scientists and
mathematicians.
Indeed, while SpinbitZ can be seen as a sort of puzzle for the ever-
curious, unlike the Rubik’s cube, it is a puzzle that while figuring it out—
while playing with the toy—a valuable meta-perspective and conceptual
toolset will begin to emerge into the curious and open mind of the reader. It
then becomes a visual interface for playfully understanding, integrating,
cross-fertilizing, and inter-harmonizing many aspects of human creative
endeavor; from art, to science, to philosophy, and to mathematics.
This is the value and function of this philosophy; to integrate the
fragmented forms of knowledge through a perceptual (empirically

Page | 23
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

engendered) “vision-logic” interface; a meta-paradigm or meta-system space


in which to see things anew and from a critical and integrative distance. In
the process of integration, the new forms have a new conceptual field in
which to play; a new playground. Thought systems, once constrained to an
older interpretation, a fossilized and outmoded territory, become
“deterritorialized” in a new context, and thus liberated to be expanded
within and upon—their project and purpose, perhaps, more fully realized.
This is indeed the deeper creative and evolutionary function of
philosophy, because—as Buckminster Fuller would argue—in a world of
increasing specialization, if no-one specializes in comprehensive
generalization, then who is looking at the big picture? In that case we are
indeed “divided and conquered” by our own educational system; a royal
road which forces individual specialization into one narrow field of study in
order to “have a career” and “make a living,” but at the expense of
integration and mutual understanding between other specialists. To be
sure, visionaries like Fuller often have to step entirely outside “the career,”
and outside the educational system itselfi to do just that, on behalf of
humanity; to take a step back and get a good look at where we are at, as the
whole of human-kind, and where we are heading. And most importantly, this
function of philosophy serves the purpose of evaluating where we could go if
we could take stock of our options and allow our collective creativity to
emerge.
That, as well, is the function of meta-paradigm and meta-system
explorations such as SpinbitZ. To create and expand a system in which we
can take a step back and begin to scientifically or rigorously compare,
contrast, integrate, cross-fertilize and cross-catalyze more specialized
systems themselves (such as science, philosophy and mathematics and their
subsets), and ultimately to transcend-and-include the useful parts and let
the not-so-useful parts fade away . . . or come to rest in the unfolding archive
of humanity to be made use of later.

SpinbitZ emerged naturally from my method (as primarily an artist) to


playfully understand and integrate whole fields of concepts in the most
comprehensive, organic and integrated way possible.
I have always been averse to doing homework—for example in
mathematics—and as a child I would rather spend my class-time doodling
on the text-book or the desk. The artist in me recoiled from the tedious job
of the calculator.ii I have also had a problem with accepting and memorizing
the mathematical principles that seemed so unexplainable, unvisualizable,

i
Fuller was twice expelled from Harvard
ii
…though, at one point, it embraced and took over the difficult job of the camera, so it’s not merely
the rigor that it recoiled against, but rather the level of generality, perhaps.

Page | 24
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

arbitrary and even contradictory. I always want to ask WHY? And to see in
my mind’s-eye what is happening to lead to such a rule or habit.
Toward these ends and driven by these unconscious goals and
propensities for pleasure and vision in understanding, this meta-
mathematical system (Interface Mathematics) emerged; unfolding slowly,
yet spontaneously and intuitively. Rather than doing much of the homework
in my college algebra classes—which was designed to drill in the seemingly
arbitrary rule-systems and abstract concepts that otherwise have no
conceptual grounding—I would instead tease out the details of this new
system as they emerged from interfacing the new rules with the embryonic
meta-mathematical form already breathing itself to life in my mind.
Surprisingly, as I became more and more capable of visualizing, or
internally sensing the interactions and relations within the emerging
organism of this system, the whole of fundamental mathematics, with its
abstract and seemingly arbitrary principles, began to make intuitive and
visceral sense. It began to speak to me; no longer in riddles, but in pictures
and clear, sensible structures that mirrored my view of the kosmosi itself—
holarchical, boundless, endlessly unfolding. ii Mathematics no longer seemed
abstract and arbitrary, like random bits of code needing strings of
meaningless mnemonics to tie them down to a rigid and brittle chunk of
habitual finger-memory.
Ultimately, as it developed, I had to do less and less of the rote
memorization in the homework in order to pass my tests. And new ideas
presented in the class just seemed to illuminate, resonate and reinforce
hidden places already present in the system. The algebra class began to get
very exciting as I would continue to tease out how the mathematics naturally
unfolded in the vision.iii

The experience of interfacing this conceptual system with mathematics is a


particularly clear and vivid example, but the same basic function and
experience occurred over a longer time-frame with my much earlier and
more detailed studies in science and philosophy. Indeed, the largely

i
Kosmos is the ancient Greek term not merely for the physical or objective universe (the cosmos)
but for ALL of reality, putting the subjective, and other spheres, on equal (neutral, nondual) footing.
ii
Holarchical means; wholes made of deeper parts, which are wholes made of deeper parts, which
are wholes made of deeper parts, and so on…
iii
In retrospect, I suppose it would have had the same “intellectual mustiness” which Fuller spoke of
when discovering some of his many generalized principles, laying dormant for an eternity to be
uncovered…if it hadn’t been overwhelmed by the feelings of sneaking into the graveyard of
respectable philosophy and digging the jewels off the dead fingers of my heroes, Spinoza and
Leibniz, and trying to get the crypt-keepers to trade it in for gold; rather than being content to stare
at the mausoleum frontispieces. No, this has an earthier feel, and the jewels have unexpectedly
turned to seed…readied to teraform the largely forbidden and deserted planet of esoteric
rationality.

Page | 25
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

unconscious embryogenesis of the meta-system itself unfolded in these


earlier studies. As in my experience with mathematics, as the interface
evolved I gradually began to make sense of the fields of study, as the
paradoxes, irreconcilable dichotomies and antinomies, that seemed to be
taken for granted by my professors, for me began to melt, often
spontaneously away.
The surprise and exhilaration felt in this application to mathematics is
perhaps a result of having interfaced with a deeper property of the
formation of concepts in general—what I call the “embryogenesis of the
concept”i*—manifesting in the intensely creative fields I was studying,
namely science, philosophy and later mathematics.
The Mathematical model, therefore, naturally mirrors—in a simpler and
distilled form—the emergent ontological and epistemological model
outlined in this work, as well as the physical model to be outlined in SpinbitZ,
Volume II. This convergence and self-similar embryogenesis between these
fields of concepts allows the explorer to use the very same core concepts and
tools for each field or facet of understanding. It allows one to build a
coherent and integrated whole, the benefits of which are impossible to
describe at this level of generality. They must be felt when the whole system
can finally be seen in the mind. When you find the “plane of consistency”ii in
this model—when it begins to make sense as a whole—then the effects and
uses will become intuitive and apparent.

But all of this was only made possible from a training in the visual arts. As
Rudolph Arnheim says in his book, Visual Thinking, “the arts are the most
powerful means of strengthening the perceptual component without which
productive thinking is impossible in any field of endeavor” (p3). Having
started my life as a visual artist, I gradually discovered that my artistic
expressions were becoming more and more philosophical as time
progressed. I would often notice that in the back of my mind, as I lay
thinking, an unconscious and intricate visual form was taking shape in my
visual field; line by line, curving and collecting into shape after shape,
unconsciously informing and solidifying the conceptual construction. Finally
the philosophy began to rise above, transcending-and-including this ever-
present and often unconscious visual art-form.
The same sort of process must have occurred, in some form, with M.C.
Escher, when he wrote in an essay entitled Approaches to Infinity:
However, it may happen that someday someone will feel a specific and
conscious longing ripening within him to approach infinity as purely and
as closely as possible by means of his representations. This may happen

i
* See the section Embryogenesis of the Concept (EOTC), p106.
ii
As Deleuze calls it.

Page | 26
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

to someone who has not absorbed much factual knowledge—someone


who has not done much studying of previous generations, someone who,
as plastic artists do, fills his days with the designing of more or less
fantastic images.
The art remains a key factor in the expression. It is an integral part of a
symbiosis; an interface which informs and empowers the logic of the
philosophical vision. And often it is through explicit catalysis in the creation
of visual diagrams—vision-logic interfaces—that the philosophy itself
necessarily unfolds. The linear expression of verbal ideas gains a new
perspective through the non-linear and highly parallel expression in a visual
form. They feed into and rebound off each other. With visualization, the
whole mass of concepts can finally be seen simultaneously, nonlinearly, as
one vibrant whole, instead of spaghettified by the linearity of language —
l-e-t-t-e-r b-y l-e-t-t-e-r, word … by … word … sentence by sentence.

The diagrams used in this construction are therefore found throughout this
work as they will help the reader to process the abstract linear verbiage
through the deeper, nonlinear and vastly parallel sensory functions that all
humans possess. It is ultimately through the senses, transcended-and-
included in higher, more abstract, cognition, that the sense of the text is truly,
integrally, embodied.
This is the general goal of SpinbitZ; to make sense of abstract thought
through the employment of the human interface of sensation; to empower
the conceptual imagination through images. Philosophy as the integrating
art of the concept; a philosophy of vision-logic interfaces—and hence an
Interface Philosophy.

Page | 27
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

Interface Philosophy is a study of concepts through the use of percepts—or


more precisely, a study of the conceptual roots, relations and patterns of
concepts where they merge with percepts into vision-logic interfaces. This
then, is an exploration of the perceptual embryogenesis of the concept, and
thus an examination of the empirical roots of Rationality itself.
In digging into the perceptual core of conceptual relation, the concepts of
boundary and polarity will be seen as fundamental, just as they are
fundamental to perception. Indeed it would seem that nothing can be
conceived or perceived without boundary. A conceptual distinction itself is a
boundary. Polarity, as well, is key to both percept and concept, and all
senses are based on the polarity of contrast. And indeed, polarity will be
seen as the opposable thumb of the conceptual mind—fundamentally
indispensable as the most primitive and powerful form of conceptual
relation. Certainly as well, polarity lies at the very heart of a conceptual
understanding of nonduality.
But, polarity and boundary have a curious relationship, because
boundary can be seen as the intervening third, or “triune interface” between
the two poles of a polarity; such as the boundary between the within and
without, or between black and white. And inversely, polarity can be seen as
the integration between the two halves of a boundary, such as in the Taoist
concept of the identity of opposites, as in Yin and Yang.
Applying these simple fundamental concepts and tools together, the
polarity of the bounded and the boundless, the finite and infinite, will take
center stage, providing a triune interface and meta-view on the concept in
general; a “univocity framework.” This is therefore largely a work about
interfacing infinity—bounding the boundless and unbinding the bounded. It
is also about “pulverizing” and rebuilding the categories surrounding the
infinite. Indeed, the infinite will no longer be seen as a “disastrous regress,”
but as a boundless source of emergence; a fullness to Emptiness, and a
“positive infinity,” what Deleuze calls “the secret of Grand Rationalism.”
And hence in order to truly transcend-and-include the rational into the
“trans-rational,” one must first interface rationally and conceptually—and
indeed perceptually and thus empirically—with the nature of the infinite.
One thus moves beyond the common confusions and paradoxes of the
infinite, by transcending the common pre-rational set of concepts which
generate them.

Page | 28
OVERVIEW

In also tracing a nondual thread of Rationality to its historical roots, we


will discover that only the dualistic, exoteric (or commonly understood)
forms of rationality begin with the Greek trinity: Socrates, Plato and
Aristotle. By reconnecting to the earlier nondual truths of Heraclitus and
Parmenides, we find the conceptual axis-mundi itself (what Lao Tzu called
“the door to all wonders”) spinning at the hidden core of Zeno’s paradox, and
thus at the core of nondual Rationality. Through a fusion of Art, Science,
Mathematics and Philosophy—and with the help of nearly a hundred vision-
logic interfaces—we’ll trace this embryogenesis of the concept of Rationality,
as it reconnects to the alternative historical lineage of rationality uncovered
by Deleuze, with a nondual fusion of the systems of Spinoza and Leibniz.
In esoteric Theosophy it is said that in the “shock” of the interface
between Spinoza and Leibniz “the essence and Spirit of esoteric philosophy
would be made to appear.” Unfolding through these vision-logic interfaces,
the “cultivating thirds” of this Interface Philosophy finally appear to
reconcile many of the dualities plaguing the history of exoteric
Rationality. In its nondual interface with empiricism and Integral theory, for
example, a detailed sketch of an Interface Epistemology is
unfolded. Operating at the crossroads of the ontic-epistemic (reality vs.
knowledge) and subject-object polarities, the evolutionary symbiogenesis of
the exoteric dichotomies at the foundations of human knowledge is
examined, illuminating and reconciling the “ontic-shadow” of post-
modernity.
The process of reanimating these hidden nondual truths demonstrates
that mathematics itself mirrors this holarchic embryogenesis and
structure. Unfolding in layer upon layer, this Interface Mathematics
transitions from the “oppositional forces” of dualism, ultimately again to the
“intensive” and integral truths, and originary axis-mundi of the nondual. In
making mathematics visible, visceral and understandable—a Vision-Logic
Coordinate System is constructed revealing two fundamental axes of
conceptual thought (one of which is this axis mundi). Spinoza’s “three
infinities” are then shown as the triune interface, or cultivating third
between these binary axes, for illuminating and reconciling the many
paradoxes of infinity—e.g. Zeno’s and Galileo’s—as they wind their way into
the truths of our modern mathematics of the continuum and set-theory.

But there is no pretense that these concepts reveal an absolute Truth, or a


Platonic ideal form underlying reality itself. Nor is there any notion that the
concepts are complete and all-encompassing in themselves…or even entirely
correct. These are ultimately just foundation-level patterns of concepts
which help make sense of higher-level patterns and systems of concepts,
such as mathematics and philosophy. Interface Philosophy is thus the
interfacing of concepts with concepts, and ultimately through percepts—and
thus it is the interface between rational and empirical methodologies for the

Page | 29
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

purpose of converging upon higher level systems of order and integration


within concepts themselves. Through this, however, it is hoped that the
systems of concepts will come closer and closer to their most natural and
integrated form, and thus closer and closer, perhaps, to Truth.
Interface Philosophy is a set of conceptual tools which I spontaneously
evolved for myself, in my own interfacing with concepts, systems and the
world around me. It is simply an expressive and receptive conceptual
outgrowth which I have found essential in my contemplation of such
abstract and often difficult ideas as the paradoxes of infinity, number,
freedom, causation, mind, body, thought and matter—all of which will be
explored in depth herein.

In Interface Philosophy, the interface is key. It is used in many different


ways, as we have already begun to see. For example, on the very surface, the
polar capitalization in the title SpinbitZ stands for the interface between the
philosophies of Spinoza and Leibnitz (more commonly called Leibniz). The
conceptual polarity found between their systems is embodied in SpinbitZ,
with its beginning at the curvilinear S and its ending at the rigid pointy Z.
We will start SpinbitZ with an emphasis on Spinoza, who focused on
continuity, unity and the serene—as seen in the S and felt in the very sound
of the word Substance.i And we will end with an emphasis on Leibniz, who
focused on the individual, the multiple and the discrete aspects of the
monad. But in Leibniz we find a profound tension between the one and the
ONE, or between the monad and the Leibnizian transcendent God. And
naturally this deep tension, contrast or “chiaroscuro” as Deleuze termed it, is
seen and felt in the Z, and in the ending sound of līb’nĭts.ii¥ And so this is our
simple mnemonic through which to focus on the general distinction and
polarity between these two philosophies. It is ultimately a polarity between
the continuous and the discrete—the ONE, and the ALL of infinitely many
ones—and thus a polarity between unity and multiplicity.
In the end we will effect an integration of the key aspects of Leibniz’s and
Spinoza’s respective systems. We will ultimately find that when the mythic
elements are removed, contrary to received opinion Leibniz’s philosophy
converges on essentially the same underlying nondual and univocal
structure of rationality that we will initially explore through Spinoza.
Spinoza, like Parmenides before him, focused on indivisible continuity and
the ONE, whereas Leibniz, like Heraclitus or Anaxagoras, emphasized and
exalted the infinitely divisible and the ALL. Ultimately, however, these are
merely the two poles of the ONE-ALL, enfolding and unfolding in a truly

i
When referring to Spinoza’s “substance” herein, we will capitalize it to make the distinction to the
common philosophical term and to distance ourselves from its foundationalist baggage.
ii¥
http://www.answers.com/Gottfried%20Leibniz

Page | 30
OVERVIEW

nondual Rationality. This, as we will see, brings us far closer to a trans-


rational empiricism than to our old, second-hand notions of Rationalism.
With the symbiogenesis and interface between percept and concept at
the heart of an Interface Philosophy, we will indeed discover a
symbiogenesis between Rationalism and Empiricism. So, despite our focus
on the so-called rationalists themselves, the trajectory produced in this
work, as a whole, can be called a Nondual Rational-Empiricism, or equally a
Nondual Empirical Rationalism. As it stands, the emphasis on Empiricism
won’t be reached until near the end of this work, in the section on Interface
Epistemology, where we will explore at great length the empirical roots of
rationalism, and the rational roots of empiricism, in a tight symbiogenesis of
percept and concept, and of subject and object. Indeed, this empirical
emphasis is to be expected of a philosophy rooted in percept—and it is
found to be subtly lining the exposition throughout.

SpinbitZ evolved largely through a fusion of the systems of Spinoza and


Leibniz, but also through catalysis with Gilles Deleuze, Ken Wilber,
Buckminster Fuller, Gerald Lebau, and others. And Nondual Rationalism
and Interface Philosophy unfold in SpinbitZ together, indeed
symbiogenetically. But there is a critical distinction to be made. The
practical application of a trans-rational and vision-logic level Interface
Philosophy, is what allows the underlying synthesis in Nondual Rationalism
to emerge. And indeed we will find that only when rationality is embodied
nondually is it truly and fully rational. In the end, the truths of the rational
and the nondual are entirely complimentary, each supporting and evolving
the other.
A truly trans-rational philosophy necessitates a fully developed
rationality, not just in the rational methods of exposition and discourse, but
in the synthesis between the core elements of rationalist meta-
mathematics—such as the Leibnizian view of the calculus and Spinoza’s
Triune Infinite—as well as the esoteric understanding of the rationalist
ontologies and epistemologies. Therefore the concept of the rational used
herein will include and integrate the truths from both mathematics and
philosophy.
These critical, embryonic and ultimately nondual ideas of the rationalists
were lost in the flow of history. And those ideas that remained were
flattened and distorted into an irrational chain of myths; forced into a single
over-arching category, conveniently pushing the entire pre-Kantian era into
an ill-fitting boundary outside the body of sanctioned philosophy. This
represents at a socio-cultural level what psychologists call a “shadow
element,” a distorted aspect of the self broken off in the process of
psychological (and in this case, psycho-social) development.
The main goal and program herein, therefore, is to reconnect to this lost
thread of philosophical and mathematical rationalism, with its unrecognized

Page | 31
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

trans-rational roots and resonances in both Western empiricism and the


nondual philosophies of the East, such as Taoism and Madhyamaka (middle-
path) Buddhism. This critical project was aborted through the modern and
post-modern historical misinterpretations (and in many cases, just plain
ignorance) of the key embryonic insights and conceptual tools developed
mainly by Spinoza and expanded through Leibniz (among others). These
misinterpretations, incorporated wholesale into modern academia, were
fostered by the reactionary anti-modern and anti-rational movements such
as the “infinite representation”i and negative dialectic of Hegelian “absolute
idealism” and the absolutized relativism of deconstructive postmodernism.
As it turns out, from this Deleuzian alternative place in history, the
second-hand academic version of Rationality, inherited by so many brilliant
thinkers, seems withered and misshapen by comparison. From this
Deleuzian plane of consistency the esoteric project of Rationalism becomes
vibrant and healthy; ready to explode in long forsaken directions, into a
completely new toolset of concepts and perspectives.

i
As Deleuze calls it, and as we will explore later.

Page | 32
This project emerged into consciousness as a spiraling visual interpretive
fusion of the systems of Spinoza and Leibniz. The systematic fusion began to
occur even before I learned of the recognition in esoteric philosophy of the
possibilities of this fusion for the emergence of “the truths of the archaic
doctrine.” This process was catalyzed through contact with many different
sources in science, art and philosophy, but most distinctly the work of R.
Buckminster Fuller (Bucky) and his absolutely beautiful Synergetic
Geometry,i* and Gerald I. Lebau with his work on a qualitative and causal
understanding of fundamental physics.ii
During my exploration and creation process I stumbled upon the work of
others, such as Gilles Deleuze and Ken Wilber, whose conceptual schemes
were deeply resonant, and in some places virtually identical to my own—
beneath the arbitrary and ultimately minor differences in word choices and
category lines. I have since gone back and infused their additional insights
into my own, allowing for further (if always unfinished) creative synthesis
and resonance, ever fueling this soft, organic explosion.

Having started my exploration of philosophy, mathematics and rationalism


in the West, there is naturally a focus on western thinkers, as this is my
home. But the more I explore of the East, the more I recognize that I have
started, certainly not at “the beginning,” and perhaps not even with the most
sophisticated forms of early rationality, math and science. I have come in

i
* See Part Two: Interface Philosophy (p200), and Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and the Nucleation of
Observability (p486) in this volume.
ii
Sorce Theory is a new theory of matter and energy based on an explicitly causal and unified
metaphysics matching in its general form the holarchical terrain explored (through its catalytic help)
in this book. See www.anpheon.org and the section Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement in
SpinbitZ: Volume II.

Page | 33
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

through the “attic window,” just as Western mathematics itself, as


Buckminster Fuller recognized, came in through the attic window of
mathematics with its beginnings in rectilinear, as opposed to radial (or
holonic), coordinate systems.
The earlier knowledge systems of the East seem every bit as detailed and
profound as their early counterparts in the West, and indeed the same basic
schools of thought seem to have emerged on both sides—beneath, yet again,
the arbitrary and minor differences in words and category lines.
Relatively speaking, I have just begun my exploration of the exquisite
knowledge of the East, and so only the most salient and well-known of these
concepts will make it into this current work, as they naturally seem to
resonate with the ideas of the philosophers of the West. These include the
general concept of nonduality, Nagarjuna’s notion of “Emptiness,” the
Buddha’s “dependent arising,” and what I am calling the absolute and
relative “scopes,” found in the “Two Truths Doctrine” of Buddhism. All of
these concepts are crucial, I have discovered, for expanding the project of
rationalism into the “post-post-modern” era.
As I continued to explore the project of Rationalism, I began to discover
that the interpretations I was spontaneously generating in my readings of
Spinoza, for example, were very different from the inherited formalisms that
my professors were giving me (many of whom never studied Spinoza’s
actual writings). I seemed to naturally converge on a much more coherent
and consistent (and ultimately nondual) interpretation of Spinoza in my
readings, while my professors interpretations seemed clouded and
disrupted by arguments that only served to distort and fracture the
coherence of Spinoza’s intended meanings, so as to count the project of
Rationality as a whole, a failure.
After writing my first formal paper on Spinoza, Spinoza’s Attribute
Polarity, and in preparation for my next one, Spinoza and Leibniz: An Identity
of opposites, (the ideas of both are included in this volume), I discovered the
luminous and obscure work of Gilles Deleuze, and that I am not at all alone
in my unorthodox Spinozism. At about the same time, I discovered the vast
and beautiful net cast by Ken Wilber in his Integral philosophy. It seemed
that while Wilber’s philosophy was entirely resonant with the alternative
Spinoza that Deleuze and I had converged upon, Wilber’s actual views on
Spinoza were a repetition of the academic party line that I encountered in
my university courses. Wilber was espousing what Deleuze and I would
consider an essentially Spinozistic “univocal” philosophy,i but he was, and is,

i
…minus the inherited Leibnizian-Kantian-Hegelian shadow-element from academia, as well as the
explicit grounding in the nondual framework of Univocity, which we will explore in much greater
depth later on.

Page | 34
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM

quite unaware of its resonances in the esoteric and emerging understanding


of Spinoza.i

But Deleuze’s interpretation of Spinoza is certainly not without its critics,


and controversies. For example, Pierre Macherey, one of the most acclaimed
of contemporary Spinoza scholars in France, is highly critical of Deleuze on
this point. According to Simon Duffy (in his “The Logic of Expression in
Deleuze’s Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza: A Strategy of Engagement”)
Macherey asks whether or not Deleuze’s interpretation “is consistent with
the original sense of the work he purports to analyse, or does it rather
misrepresent Spinoza’s philosophy?”ii¥
Duffy says:
In order to respond to this kind of questioning it is necessary to be clear
about the conception of the history of philosophy that is being brought to
bear on both the text of the Ethics and on Deleuze’s reading of the Ethics
in Expressionism in Philosophy. If a study in the history of philosophy
solely strives ‘after a faithful, correct reading, attempting merely a risk-
free identical reproduction or charting of what is written in the Ethics as
though it belonged to a realm of past thoughts’,iii¥ and as though Spinoza’s
thought ‘could be captured once and for all, grasped definitively in the
ideological context in which he lived and died’,iv¥ then the presupposition
that there is an original sense of a work accessible only to the erudite
historian of philosophy would be acceptable as unproblematic, and any
problematization of this presupposition would thereby be determinable
as a misrepresentation of the ‘original sense of the work’.
In other words, in order to get a fresh look at the text in question, we must
“deterritorialize” it, as Deleuze might say, from past interpretations that
have become fossilized and might channel our own interpretation into a
mere repeating of past hermeneutic dead-ends or errors. Otherwise, it is
those past interpretations—which, especially in the post-Kantian era, cannot
be held as absolute and pre-given—that would serve as the sole criterion for
success in any further interpretation.
In Wilber-speak, we must jump out of the “kosmic groove”—or better
yet, the “kosmic rut”—of academic/exoteric Spinozism, if we want a fresh
look at Spinoza in the context of our modern era. This is precisely what

i
I have had several discussions with Wilber on this issue, and he continues to state that Spinoza is a
“dedicated Cartesian.” When challenged on this issue, however, he did not attempt to back up his
claim, so the appearance is that he got it from a second-hand source, without the context.
ii
¥ Pierre Macherey, ‘The Encounter with Spinoza’, trans. Martin Joughin, in Martin Patton (ed.)
Deleuze: A Critical Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p.142. This is one of the questions central to
Macherey’s problematization of Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza in the ‘The Encounter with Spinoza’.
iii
¥ Ibid., p. 148.
iv
¥Warren Montag and Ted Stolze (trans. and eds), The New Spinoza (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1997), p. x.

Page | 35
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

Deleuze and many other thinkers have done, and even more now are
continuing to do. And this ever-renewed examination is critical, if indeed
Spinoza’s message was ahead of the times into which it was initially
injected—an era which cast its interpretive, enlightening and ultimately
obscuring forms upon it in the “History of Philosophy.” If Spinoza’s message
is for the future, then the future—perhaps indeed our “now”—must be freed
of the interpretations of the past in order to understand Spinoza’s message.

Duffy writes:
According to this conception of the history of philosophy, one way to
understand the ‘importance’ or ‘influence’ of the different figures in the
history of philosophy on contemporary thought would be to determine
‘the citations, the references, and the borrowings (acknowledged and
unacknowledged) that bind contemporary thought to the texts of’ these
figures, which would thus put each of them ‘in the position of a
predecessor or forebear whose thought “anticipated” the concerns’ of
contemporary thought.
Many thinkers have done just this with respect to Spinoza, exhuming the
influences of Spinoza’s thought in various contexts in the sciences, in history,
the humanities, and in philosophy, to name a few. For example, Matthew
Stewart, in The Courtier and the Heretic, examines Spinoza and Leibniz in a
very fresh and unbiased light, demonstrating that Spinoza’s philosophy was
directly influential to the empirical philosophy of John Locke, and that
Spinoza is not the “rationalist” that is generally claimed of him. Stewart
deftly shows that Spinoza is very much a forebear to radical empiricism,
such as that espoused by David Hume (we will explore this connection in
greater depth later on). Indeed, Deleuze himself sees Hume as a critical link,
and kindred spirit, in his alternative chain of history, with Hume following in
the path (if unconsciously through the work of Leibniz and Locke) laid out
by Spinoza.i

Duffy continues with an exploration of the modes of historical analysis:


‘Another way’… ‘would be to situate the contemporary “reception” of
Spinoza in the history of Spinoza studies, as the most recent in a series of
“readings” of Spinoza from the atheistic Spinoza of the seventeenth
century to the pantheist Spinoza of the eighteenth and early nineteenth
centuries to the monist of the twentieth century’.

i
Another thinker demonstrating the influences and resonances from Spinoza's work is the modern
neuroscientist, Antonio Damasio, whose book, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling
Brain, demonstrates that Spinoza's philosophy can serve as a general basis for contemporary
explorations into the neurobiology of the emotions.

Page | 36
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM

And so we can see that the interpretation of Spinoza has changed radically
through the years, depending on the historical context in which it is
addressed. It is therefore anything but pre-given and static.
Indeed, in the last few decades there has been an explosion in Spinoza
scholarship. As Kenneth Surin states in his entry on Baruch Spinoza in The
Deleuze Dictionary;
In the last few decades the writings of Louis Althusser, Etienne Balibar,
Pierre Macherey, Antonio Negri, Deleuze and others, have marked a
resurgence of interest in the thought of Baruch Spinoza, in which
Spinoza’s … ontology has been used as a framework for constructing a
matrix of thought and practice not regimented by the axioms of Platonic
metaphysics, the epistemology of Rene Descartes, and the transcendental
rationalism of Immanuel Kant and Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel.
Titles like, The New Spinoza, i ¥ Spinoza’s Modernity, ii ¥ and The Savage
Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza’s Metaphysics and Politics,iii¥ are merely the
cusp of this evolving hermeneutic. And this trend readily seems to follow
the gradient of history, from Theism, to Secularism and to the new surge of
Integralism, and the resurging interest in ancient Nondualism. This
integration is occurring between many dualities across the sphere of
knowledge, but in Spinoza studies it is specifically occurring between
“eastern” and “western” interpretations and between and beyond his
intrinsic “rationalism” and “empiricism.”
The Spinoza hermeneutic follows a gradient from reactionary theism—
seeing the “god intoxicated man” as an atheist and heretic—to romantic
pantheism, to scientific-materialist monism, and now, at the interface
between the 20th and 21st centuries, we have the philosopher of univocity
and infinite difference (in Deleuze), the radical modernist and rational-
empiricist in Matthew Stewart, and—reinterpreting and integrating them
all—we find Spinoza, the nondual trans-Rational empiricist herein.

Deleuze, like Nagarjuna, before him, implores us to think “acategorically,” to


“pulverize the categories” inherited through a past hermeneutic—the forces
of representation—driven by the distorting effects and purposes of power.iv
This acategorical or aperspectival thinking is the injunction required to
explore this Deleuzian “alternative lineage that challenges the Hegelian
concept of the dialectical progression in the history of philosophy,” as Duffy
states. He quotes Deleuze, from Difference and Repetition, giving a general

i
¥ (Montag and Stolze)
ii
¥ (Goetschel)
iii
¥ (Negri)
iv
It was Jürgen Habermas who explained how power necessarily distorts the channels of
communication.

Page | 37
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

outline of the Deleuzian project (and please note that it is clearly nondual in
purpose):
The task of modern philosophy is to overcome the alternatives [:]
temporal / nontemporal, historical / eternal and particular / universal.
Following Nietzsche we discover, as more profound than time and
eternity, the untimely: philosophy is neither a philosophy of history, nor a
philosophy of the eternal, but untimely, always and only untimely — that
is to say, “acting counter to our time and thereby acting on our time and,
let us hope, for the benefit of a time to come.”i¥
Indeed, Deleuze’s “task” he set for Philosophy echoes the task that Nagarjuna
set for himself, in his “philosophy of the middle-path,” which was to
overcome the dominating philosophical dichotomy of his time, to pulverize
the categories dividing the “eternalists” and the “nihilists.”

Duffy continues [my notes]:


Rather than … providing a representation of Spinoza’s metaphysics,
Deleuze instead wants “to put [Spinoza’s] metaphysics in motion, in
action … [to make it] carry out immediate acts.” [Deleuze] therefore does
not offer an alternative representation of the movement of the Hegelian
dialectical logic but rather an alternative logic [in place of the Hegelian
dialectic] that is “capable of affecting the mind outside of all
representation,” a logic capable “of inventing vibrations, rotations,
whirlings, gravitations, dances or leaps which directly touch the mind”
[and this is the goal and power of Interface Philosophy with its deep roots
in the tools of nondualism and esoteric rationalism, as operationalized
through the use of sensation and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System]. ii¥
Not only does Deleuze trace out an alternative lineage in philosophy, but in
so doing, he necessarily traces out an alternative lineage in mathematics,
specifically of the calculus. This is because (among other reasons) with the
rationalists, philosophy and mathematics were deeply intertwined. Duffy
says this “alternative lineage in the history of mathematics is implicated in
Deleuze’s alternative lineage in the history of philosophy by means of a
convergence between the logic of the differential [in the calculus] from the
differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus and the logic of
expression,” all of which we will explore and expand upon in much greater
depth in the section on the calculus.iii*

i
¥ From Duffy’s notes, “DR, xxii. The Nietzsche citation is quoted by Deleuze from: Friedrich
Nietzsche, ‘On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life’, Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J.
Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), p. 60.”
ii
¥ Quotes from, Difference and Repetition, p. 184., qtd. In Duffy
iii
* See Reconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and
the Calculus, p400.

Page | 38
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM

In the abstract to his article (The Logic of Expression…) Duffy writes:


Spinoza’s philosophy should not be represented as a moment that can be
simply subsumed and sublated within the dialectical progression of the
history of philosophy, as it is figured by Hegel in the Science of Logic, but
rather should be considered as providing an alternative point of view for
the development of a philosophy that overcomes Hegelian idealism.
Indeed, Deleuze demonstrates, by means of Spinoza, that a more complex
philosophy antedates Hegel’s which cannot be supplanted by it. Spinoza
therefore becomes a significant figure in Deleuze’s project of tracing an
alternative lineage in the history of philosophy, which, by distancing itself
from Hegelian idealism, culminates in the construction of a philosophy of
difference. Deleuze presents Spinoza’s metaphysics as determined
according to a ‘logic of expression’, which, insofar as it contributes to the
determination of a philosophy of difference, functions as an alternative to
the Hegelian dialectical logic.
And Duffy ends his article with:
The strategy of reading the Ethics as determined according to the logic of
expression marks not only the originality of Deleuze’s interpretation of
Spinoza, but also one of the points where Deleuze can be considered to
depart from the Hegelian and Cartesian Spinoza familiar to scholars
working in the field of Spinoza studies, by tracing an alternative lineage in
the history of philosophy that expresses the convergence between
Spinoza’s ontology, the mathematics of Leibniz, and the metaphysics of
[Duns] Scotus. The Deleuzian domain of engagement with Spinoza is
determined therefore by deterritorializing a fairly traditional reading of
Spinoza from a particularly Cartesian and Hegelian point of view to that of
a more Scotist and even Leibnizian point of view.

The traditional exoteric/academic post-Kantian view of the history of


philosophy passes on an interpretation of Spinoza which emerged, like a
rumor, through a distorting chain of influences; from a collapse into
Cartesianism, to disfiguring interpretations by Leibniz, Kant, Hegel, the
empiricists, the romantics, the existentialists and finally to the post-
modernists. This collective interpretation serves mainly to disfigure the
“expressive” body of Spinozism, according to Deleuze, rather than to
illuminate it, or make it come alive within its own plane of consistency.
For example, the popular book The Great Chain of Being, by Arthur
Lovejoy, compresses all of pre-Kantian philosophy into a metaphysics
identical with the medieval notion of the Great Chain of Being (GCB). This
GCB view, as Ken Wilber expresses it, accepts the idea that “pre-given,”
Platonic, eternal and unchanging ontological forms, structures, levels,
essences or gradations pre-exist the actual objects and/or subjects of
existence. This presents an essentially Platonic chain or ladder of
Page | 39
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

absolutized concepts, templates, Forms and categories which all phenomena


supposedly emanate out of and can be forced into; we descend into the Great
Chain of Being from a perfect transcendent God (above and beyond all else),
to lesser and lesser gradations of spirit, through mind and ultimately to the
crudest pre-existing forms of matter.
Spinoza’s philosophy—as interpreted through Deleuze’s “organizing
principle” of univocity—while naturally inheriting some of the simplistic
terminology of the Great Chain of Being metaphysics, fits this medieval
system like a giant squid might fit into Procrustes’ infamous bed. Tentacles
chopped off here, a beak poked in there, and even the tip of the head lopped
off—all to fit the historical function of this crude medieval device—to force a
needed perspective into the history of philosophy, providing a distinct line
centered on Kant’s “critical philosophy,” and pushing the disturbing
implications of Spinoza’s radically “ungrounded” modernism into the archaic
past.
For example, (and note that all of the following we will explore in much
greater depth later), Spinoza’s “God” is not a pre-existing transcendent form
(although Leibniz’s exoteric God arguably is). It is, rather, both immanent
(intrinsic or indwelling) and transcendent, operationalized herein,
epistemically, as merely a transcendent emphasis on a boundless, or
“empty,” “immanent-transcendent axis.”i* In other words, Spinoza’s God is
not the top of any chain of pre-existing Platonic forms levels or planes of
perfection or existence, as is absolutely central to the idea of the Great Chain
of Being. Indeed, Spinoza’s God is no form whatsoever, but the opposite of
any form at all. His God is ultimately merely identical with The Absolute
Infinite, or the positive (non-regressive) notion of infinity as “the secret of
Grand rationalism,” an idea which Deleuze adopts from Merleau-Ponty.
Spinoza’s God/Substance is “The Boundless,” the ineffable Absolute and, in
this sense, identical with Nagarjuna’s Emptiness in polar opposition to Form.
Spinoza’s metaphysics has no pre-existing or eternal ontological
structures. That is the whole point of the expressive polarity between his
“substance” and its “modifications” or “modes.”ii Substance and/or God, in
Spinoza, is not a form or a structure. It is not even the “formless,” as in the
homogenous or amorphous, because formlessness is a type of form.
Substance is defined in the “escape” from modal (structural), finite and
relative thinking—in the medieval and foundational infinite regress—to the
acceptance of the foundationless, and boundless Emptiness of The Infinite,
or The Absolute (the ineffable “absolute scope” and the positive infinity of
the rational) and Spinoza’s immanent causation. Spinoza’s modes are
always ontic (really existing relative) structures (as are Wilber’s holons), but

i
* see, The Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS), p123
ii
Expressed through the “cultivated third” of the attributes, seen herein as specialized functions of
the nondual concept of “dependent origination.”

Page | 40
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM

(also like Wilber’s holons) they are not eternal, pre-given and Platonic.
Rather, modes are always relative forms emergent within time and their
ultimate essence is never their own, but shared univocally and inter-
expressively with all other modes of the univocal Substance. The individual
essence of any Spinozan mode, as we will see, does not precede its existence,
but is a function of its emergent homeostatic nature to “persist in its own
being.”i* Forms—or modes, in Spinoza—participate in eternity only insofar
as they recognize and embody the understanding of their ineffable and
boundless source in (Nagarjunan/Spinozan/Deleuzian) logical-Emptiness.
This concept of “real difference”—as opposed to numerical difference—in
Spinoza, gives all forms and modes a necessary dependent arising, in direct
opposition to the Cartesian system rampant with numerical or absolute
distinctions, such as his duality of substances. Indeed, it is this Spinozan
concept of difference as a dependent arising that turns all of Descartes’
axioms against him, turning his Dualism into a nondual Rationalism.
There is, then, in Spinoza, no Great Chain from matter, to mind, to the
various forms and gradations of spirit. Indeed, this is the entire purpose of
Spinoza’s polarity of “attributes,” Thought and Extension (mind and matter,
within and without, or “I” and “IT,” respectively), which apply to all finite
and emergent forms at any level of “excellence.” This notion of the attributes
as expressing the essence of infinite Substance in the distinction between
fundamental perspectives—generally the within and without—is a very
common interpretation among Spinoza scholars and enthusiasts. It can be
found everywhere from Albert Einstein, to Darren Staloff,ii to Will Durant.
Spinoza does not collapse Thought to Extension, nor mind to matter, but
maintains a critical parallelism and polarity. Indeed, this polarity—or
identity of opposites—of the attributes, and this concept of real difference
enforcing a dependent arising of all form, is precisely how Spinoza converted
the Cartesian dual rationalism (and largely a pre-rationalism, as we will see)
into a fundamentally Nondual Rationalism.
And hence, the lumping, by Lovejoy, of all pre-Kantian ontology into the
term “metaphysics”—disparaged and devolved from the revolutionary
insights of the key esoteric rationalist and modernist, Spinoza, to an
absolutized categorical mythology, straight from the dark ages—is indeed a
procrustean bed which served more to give power to the reactionary critics
of radical modernity and Rationalism (the Idealists and post-modernists)
than to accurately interpret the key rationalists on their own terms, and
from their own plane of consistency.

i
* See Univocity and Essence, p170.
ii
Staloff calls the attributes the “descriptive protocols,” as we will explore both the descriptive and
the formative aspects of the attributes more deeply in the section Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and
the Nucleation of Observability, p486

Page | 41
Post-post-ism-ism is a “critical” condition running rampant through the
body of post-post-modern Philosophy. It’s Kant’s fault … or the fault-line of
those who interpreted and transformed his critical philosophy into a
respectable profession fit for the LCDi of exoteric academia. Kant, like
Descartes, set himself the task of reconciling science and religion, and
protecting each from the other—“Am I going to have to separate you two?”
And like Descartes, Kant’s procedure was a radical division, a dich-otmy
between two zones of the Philosophical body. Both Kant and Descartes had
the best of intentions, but you know what they say about the road to Hell…
Descartes’ project merely ended up in an inside-out bicameral
fissurotomyii between the mind and the brain. No problem, we’ve just about
recovered … finding little tricks to get the two halves to (feebly) interact
again. Kant, however, accidentally ended up nearly severing the
Philosophical body from its head.iii Beyond the poetry of this metaphor, we
will come to find that the very core of the epistemic emerges at the
crossroads of these actually orthogonal dualities—cultivated into their
respective polarities and triune-interfaces.

The head of Philosophy, in this metaphor, is representation—the epistemic,


the real illusion—while the body of Philosophy is sub-representation—the
ontic, the real beneath, or prior to the illusion. After Kant’s “radical
ontotomy,” the patient of Philosophy will never be the same. But it was this
decapitating fault-line that allowed post-Kantian Philosophy—now fully
separate from the troublesome and unpredictable anima-mundi of the
Body—into the gleaming, predictable halls of academic Science. There have
been many brash young surgeons who have attempted the reconstruction,
but this condition-critical has now been passed off as normal, the patient
assumed healed and happy. It is now considered dangerous to Philosophy to

i
Lowest common denominator…
ii
The transitive (horizontal) severing of the subject/object polarity, as we will come to understand
shortly.
iii
The severing of the ontic from the epistemic on the orthogonal or vertical immanent/transcendent
omni-axis, as we will see. This is the crossroads of the subject/object and ontic/epistemic polarities,
on the transitive- and immanent/transcendent omni-axes, respectively.

Page | 42
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

attempt a re-connection between the dark sub-representational Body and


the bright clarity of its representational Head.

The problem, we will explore near the end of this book, is that the ontic was
early on con-fused with The Absolute. Kant split the ontic and epistemic into
the illusory phenomena and the untouchable noumena. And hence forth,
making an ontic claim was equated with making claims about the ineffable
Absolute, or making absolute (dogmatic) claims in general—a waste of time
and a serious symptom of dementia.
The solution to this aspect of the post-Kantian mishap, we will find, is
simple, once the Vedantic doctrine of the Two Truths is allowed as a
distinction between the relative and absolute scopes—allowing the ontic to
regain its healthy esoteric capacity as the real and relative world of sub-
representational form it always was (Brahma), and the epistemic to be the
real illusion (Maya) it still wants to be.i* It was this holarchy between
relative-reality and real-illusion that Kant’s radical ontotomy, perhaps
accidentally, rendered asunder. And ontology and its rational and
transrational truths have been languishing in the obscurity this post-
modern, ontic-shadow ever since.ii*

Another problem with the post-Kantian aftermath is that it is generally


considered that Kant drew the line at the bounds of experience, beyond
which metaphysics and ontology could not rationally go. This is not the case
at all. Indeed, Kant—one of the most hyper-Rational (borderline
pathological) of philosophers—was himself doing ontology and metaphysics
far beyond the limits of experience. In fact it is generally known that Kant’s
absolute categories of the understanding themselves seem to have been
derived arbitrarily with little logical justification, and as function of his
language. Indeed, it is also well-known that Kant, newly “awakened” from
his “dogmatic slumbers,” was roused to rescue metaphysical certainty itself
from the universal acid of Hume’s radical skepticism which reduced
everything to the mere coincidences of appearances. As the historian Will
Durant says, the “Critique [of Pure Reason] is not precisely a criticism, but a
critical analysis. Kant is not attacking ‘pure reason,’ except at the end to
show its limitations. Rather he hopes to show its possibility and to exalt it
above the impure knowledge that comes to us through the distorting
channels of sense.”
Where experience could not go, Kant echoed the Rationalists, we must
resort to logic and reason. Indeed, Kant used reason to explore the very

i
* See the section, Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch, p541.
ii
* For the continuation of this metaphor, see the section, Condition Still Critical: Waking Up from
the Post-Op Nightmare of the Kantian Radical Ontotomy, p545.

Page | 43
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

limits of reason itself. Through logic and rationality he plumbed the very
nature—the reality beneath the experience—of the thinking and knowing,
rational mind. He was exploring the ontology of rationality or “pure reason,”
and what he found was knowledge prior to experience, i.e. innate knowledge
in the form of what he considered absolute categories, actually a
metaphysics upon which to firmly ground the relative certainties of science.
The forms or categories of reason (logic and sensibility or intuition)
were, for Kant, transcendental or a priori, meaning they exist and find their
justification for existence before or prior to experience (this is more
precisely immanent rather than transcendent, as we will see, however).
Experience itself, Kant argued, cannot exist without these ontic categories of
the epistemic.
As is commonly acknowledged even in academia, Kant was turning
metaphysics into a science. For Kant, Metaphysics in the bad or unscientific
sense, was reasoning or simple belief beyond the means or categories of
understanding, not beyond experience itself. This bad metaphysics is dogma,
not rationality and surely not ontology, given that Kant himself deduced his
own fundamental categories ontologically and as ontic forms at the very
nature of the knower himself. (To be sure, it is only because the ontic and
epistemic form a polarity and indeed a holarchy that to practice fundamental
epistemology—e.g. seeking the nature of the knower—is to practice a form
of ontology.)

As we will also demonstrate, Kant was chasing a chicken-and-egg problem,


and he had to draw the line somewhere relevant to the human dilemma he
was facing. Experience and reason cannot be reduced one to the other,
however, not even to Kant’s “fundamental” (and arbitrary) categorical eggs
of reason. There is no ultimate a priori line to be drawn (nor immaculate
eggs to be found) in the ontic sand of the nature of pure reason.
As Matthew Stewart writes in his comically serious The Truth About
Everything [[my comments]]:
Two related stories about Kant are important to most histories of
Philosophy. The first is that Kant marks a radical turning point in the
history of metaphysics. The philosophers before Kant, so the story goes,
were concerned to develop metaphysical systems, and Kant
demonstrated that such systems would never work. The second, more
specific story is that Kant proved that knowledge is conditioned by the
nature of the knowing subject, or something of the sort. Kant himself told
this story. Borrowing an expression from Hume, he proudly announces
his own “Copernican Revolution” in philosophy. Prior to Kant,
humankind had apparently been under the impression that knowledge
must conform to the nature of the object [[the “myth of the given”]]. Just
as Copernicus had shown that the earth revolved about the sun, and not

Page | 44
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

the reverse, so Kant supposedly proved that the object of knowledge must
conform to the subject’s faculties of knowledge, and not the reverse.

… These stories about Kant are myths. The Kantian philosophy is not a
real turning point in the history of philosophy. It is a continuation of the
project of which the metaphysics he criticizes is merely one possible
expression. … Most of his philosophy can be understood as a reenactment
of what I have grandly called the dialectic of empiricism, which is itself an
instance of the search for the Holy Grail of Philosophy. To be sure, Kant
had a huge influence on subsequent philosophers, especially on the breed
who would become the professionals of the modern university. But this
just means that his name is useful as a collection point for a host of beliefs
and reconstructions, mostly based on misunderstandings.
This may indeed be somewhat of an exaggeration, but there are certain
truths in this account as well. Indeed, we will find Kant’s dichotomy
between the Rationalists and Empiricists entirely ill-fitting, when it comes to
Spinoza, and thus all the arguments against Spinoza via his status as
“Rationalist” will be found suspect as well.
The limits Kant imposed on experience were themselves purely
anthropocentric, and in this sense decidedly anti-Copernican. Copernicus
removed Man and his earth from the center of the Cosmos, whereas Kant
placed Man and his faculties back into the center of Philosophy, where he
had been with the sophists before him, for example. Kant’s exemplar was
also the Newtonian revolution, of which he was a champion. But it was the
Einsteinian upheaval after him which—while simultaneously refuting his a
priori absolute of Euclidean space and Newtonian physics—demonstrated
that all bodies, such as the earth, are indeed the center of their own warped
spaces, just as man is the center of Kant’s universe. Unlike Kant, however,
Einstein showed that the objects of physics and their warped fields are One.
The objects do not simply generate their fields, anymore than the fields
generate their objects. They arise together. In Einstein’s universe, an object
of matter is a congealed field, tied into self-stabilizing knots of energy. This
is similar to the principle of complementarity in quantum physics. Particles
no more can be reduced to waves than waves to particles. They co-evolve
and co-create one another in the very same act. And in this same self-
aggrandizing sense, after the “Einsteinian Revolution” of Interface
Philosophy, subject and object (or given-myth and mythic-given),
necessarily arise together, in a structural coupling or symbiogenesis, of
sorts, as we’ll see.
In effect, Kant created a metaphysics of experience, with his metaphysical
and ontological a priori (immanent) and “transcendental” categories of
experience. This metaphysics itself is often used—post-Kan’t (sic)—to deny
pre-Kan’tian metaphysics based on the assumption that these earlier
systems necessarily go beyond the categories of experience and thus cannot
be verifiable and scientific. Kant, however, outlined an entire set of

Page | 45
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

categories based in the a priori understanding—his Transcendental Logic.


These include causality, relation and even substance. Thus if a metaphysical
system uses logical relation and causality then that system is verifiable by
the means of logic and causality which are themselves a priori categories of
experience. And, as we will see, these categories themselves are derived
through a deep coupling with experience prior to the human modes of
experience to which Kant had set his anthropocentric, chicken-and-egg
limits. This logical or relational verifiability is in the same way that a
mathematical proof cannot be verified by empirical means but only by
means interior to its logical relations. Indeed, the notion of infinity itself is
purely logical and thus entirely amenable to the understanding, and this
understanding underlies all of Kant’s supposed antinomies. Infinity is
simply boundless, in any of its forms. It is only the limited imagination that
cannot fit the unlimited infinite into its domain. But the forms and details of
logic are not bound by the perspectival restrictions of the imagination any
more than is a mountain restrained in size by the horizon. And thus a
metaphysical system is open to demonstrations and relations of the infinite
so long as it unfolds its relations in a consistent and coherent manner. But
then it can only “prove” its conclusions in the realm in which it is limited,
namely logic and relation, as opposed to empiricism and objectivity insofar
as our inter-objective experience with mathematics and logic is neglected.
Kant wanted to find out what happens when “pure reason,” beyond the
limits of human experience, confronts only itself, but Kant’s own pool of
experience was far more limited than ours today. Kant was unaware of the
empirical facts of evolution and of the embryogenesis of the forms of the
understanding far prior even to his a priori categories. In the light of this
new experience with the natural world—e.g. evolutionary and cognitive
science—we will find that experience and reason emerge together,
symbiogenetically, or structurally coupled, in the very process of evolution.
The “fundamental” categories are themselves inherited from billions of years
of experience with the problem-solving intelligence (primitive rationality) of
evolution. The “forms of sensibility,” we will see, are not ultimately a priori,
in the anti-Copernican anthropocentric sense, but symbiogenetic with the
sensations or experience of form. And one of the core elements of reason is
the rational “acategorical imperative,” which, by itself, pulverizes the
categories required by dogma.
Kant shattered the “myth of the given,” and handed us merely the “given
of the myth,” the given of the ontic forms underlying the illusion of
experience itself. His self-proclaimed “Copernican Revolution”
demonstrated that the world is not simply given to the mind as it is in itself,
but that the mind, as it is in itself, is given to experience and interpret the
world. The mind, according to Kant, generates and imposes its own pre-
given a priori structure and order (e.g. the categories of Time and Space) on
the world before it can experience anything.

Page | 46
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

This is thesis and antithesis—from the mythic-given of sub-


representation, to the given-myth and “benign user-illusion”i¥ of the a priori
forms of representation. The synthesis is naturally the interface between
the two. As Hegel would say, “The laws of logic and the laws of nature are
one. And logic and metaphysics merge.”ii¥ It is not the mind itself from
whence the a priori categories arise. This is simply because the mind does
not, and indeed cannot, exist by itself. The mind and the world are not
ultimately other, but two forms of the same inter-expressive sub-
representational “stuff,” and as Bodhidharma says, “vision arises where they
meet.” They interact through deeper forms of inter-expression or causation
common to both. The conscious mind does not generate these deeper forms
and it does not create itself, but it is actually given by prior form. It is
emergent from deeper emergents of deeper emergents, perhaps ad
infinitum.
The mind then does not, of itself, create Time and Space and simply
project them onto the timeless and spaceless world. But through its
interface with the inseparable world of real duration and real relation—with
which it is One—the categories of sensibility and the understanding are
differentiated into abstraction in the very process of the formation and
deepening of experience long before the human level of complexity arises.
The mind can only know relation—as opposed to the absolute “thing in
itself” free from relation—because there is only relation to be known—
infinite relation, “pure” relation—of which knowledge is emergent or
transcendent from sub-representational form.
As seen in the categories, Nature herself is given as the mind and to the
mind to experience in its interface with the world, a part of itself. Or—to
render it from the other side—the world gives itself experiences of itself
through its interfaces with its minds. The experience of the “myth” is simply
the interface between the two forms of the “given” emergents. Maya is the
experience in the interface between the inner and outer Brahma. This
within/without boundary is ultimately the interface of the positive infinity
itself,iii* an infinite axis first broken open into operation in philosophical and
mathematical rationality, as we will see. So it is only with a proper and
esoteric understanding of rationality that this interface can be assimilated
into a healthy trans-rationality.


… from Daniel Dennett
ii¥
Qtd in Will Durant, The Story of Philosophy.(Durant)
iii
* See I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.

Page | 47
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

Perhaps the most problematic consequence of the Kantian legacy is the


divide-and-conquer pigeon-holing methodology he used against his
immediate historical predecessors—especially Leibniz and Spinoza—forcing
them into his procrustean bed of rationalists vs. their opponents, the
empiricists. As Matthew Stewart writes in The Courtier and the Heretic.
In the histories of philosophy that dominate the trade, it was Immanuel
Kant who sealed the fate of the two greatest philosophers of the
seventeenth century. In his effort to tame philosophy into a discipline
suitable for the modern academy, Kant trained his attention on the
methods whereby philosophers purported to justify their claims to
knowledge. He divided his immediate predecessors into two groups: the
empiricists, who allegedly relied on sense experience to base their claims
to knowledge, and the rationalists, who were said to derive their truths
from pure reason. According to Kant’s peculiar scheme, Leibniz and
Spinoza wound up playing on the same side of history. Together with
Descartes—the man Leibniz loathed and Spinoza regarded as seriously
confused—they became the three rationalists. Leading the empiricist
opposition was John Locke—the same whom Leibniz regarded as a
wobbly crypto-Spinozist. He was joined by the Irish philosopher George
Berkeley, whose view that physical objects are only ideas in the head
strikes most readers as distinctly unempirical, and David Hume, whose
ideas about the mind and causality look remarkably like those of Spinoza.
Hegel, who very much liked to see history move along in groups of
three, strongly championed Kant’s version of events; and the British, who
were pleased to see a trio of their greatest philosophers of the period
lined up against three continental musketeers, were more than happy to
go along with the story, too. As a result, in philosophy classes to the
present, where irony tends to be a scarce commodity in any case, Spinoza
and the man who dedicated his life to expunging Spinoza’s name from the
world’s memory [Leibniz], are presented as happy partners on the same
side of a debate about the epistemological foundations of academic
philosophy. Only very recently have scholars begun to rescue Leibniz and
Spinoza from the revisionist schemes of their philosophical successors.
In the conventional histories of philosophy, Leibniz and Spinoza
ultimately fall victim not to progress but to the idea of progress—an idea
that first gained currency toward the end of the eighteenth century and
that has since been taken up with gusto by all those who have a stake in
presenting philosophy as a respectable, quasi-scientific discipline. Once
we set aside suspect narratives of the history, however, it becomes clear
that, far from being left behind by their modern successors, Leibniz and
Spinoza remain unsurpassed today as representatives of humankind’s
radically divided response to the set of experiences we call modernity.
Much of modern thought simply wanders in the space between the two
extremes represented by the men who met in The Hague in 1676 (p309-
10).

Page | 48
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

Along with tacitly following Arthur Lovejoy in lumping most, if not all of pre-
Kantian metaphysics with the Great Chain of Being, Ken Wilber defines
‘metaphysics,’ “in the bad sense” also as a postulation of ontological entities
which cannot be empirically proven by science. Ironically, this would place
much of science (and its hidden Foundational metaphysics)—such as
“[insert your Ultimate Fundamental Object here] Theory,” and Cosmology—
in the category of “bad metaphysics” or bad ontology. They all do indeed
make fundamentally unjustifiable and unproven claims about the very
nature of reality.i
This problem, to me, is part of a subtly imprecise, reactive and ontic-shy,
inherited definition of post-metaphysics, in this post-Kantian era of rampant
post-post-ism-ism. There are clear and restrictive limits on empirical reality
that science and logic must at least attempt to move beyond. Indeed, science
does this all the time, and of necessity, as does Integral Post-Metaphysics
with its logical necessity of an infinitely deep holarchy of ontically real
holons.
Language, Buckminster Fuller tells us, was the first industry. It is based
on the collective technology and invention of the word. Likewise all
“language games” are forms of technology. ii And as we would expect from
the dialectic of progress, any technology that can be used, can also be
abused. The technology of metaphysics is no exception. Metaphysics is
abused, as Kant noted, in the taking of dogmatic stances, in postulating
ABSOLUTELY the existence (not necessarily the existence of the absolute) of
entities that cannot be proven. And more to the point, bad metaphysics is
the absolute belief in these entities despite its detriment to the rationality
and well-being of the user.
Post-metaphysics, and post-ontology, if it is to emulate the objectivity of
science, cannot be fundamentally opposed to merely postulating ontically-
real entities that cannot be proven empirically, because this is a necessary
function of science and philosophy at the limits of the augmented senses—in
the zone of pure-reason. Again, Kant himself identified the forms of logic
and the forms of sensibility as the forms of understanding itself necessary to
understanding anything. Mere hypothesis is not a belief system in itself, and
if we restrict ourselves to the merely empirical, then we end up with a
variant of logical positivism that no longer dares to wonder about what lies

i
Indeed, there is a rampant Foundational metaphysics hidden under much of Science, despite the
fact that Foundational truth-claims—a main feature of medieval Philosophy and Theology—have
been demonstrated extremely problematic and indeed illegitimate during the last century of
Philosophical progress.
ii
… or “life-forms” as Wittgenstein called them.

Page | 49
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

beyond the provincial pale of the augmented senses. A sad and safe little
representational world would that be.

In any Integral and post-postmodern model, rationality should be


transcended-and-included, not transcended-and-negated. Rationality is a
tool, and as we will see, its very core contains the thread of an “acategorical
imperative.” Thus—as demonstrated very clearly in the violently corrosive
encounter between medieval dogma (metaphysics in the bad sense) and
Spinoza’s nondual-rational philosophy—the very nature of truly rational
metaphysics points directly into a post-metaphysics, and a post-ontology,
beyond the dogma of the absolutized category. It is in the nature of the
rational mind to leave itself open endlessly to new questions and analyses,
and not to end on some given dogma. Dogma occurs when the acategorical
truth of rationality breaks down into the irrationality of unwarranted and
detrimental belief.
Post-metaphysics and esoteric rationality is then a post-ism-ism. It is
still a post-mythology, but it opposes a rationality-turned-mythology—a
rationality twisted from its intrinsic acategorical stance to the ends of pre-
rationality and its transcendent-biased absolutized categories and power
structures. In short, post-metaphysics and esoteric rationality opposes the
absolute category, and not necessarily the category of the absolute, as we
will see. Esoteric rationality is the acategorical imperative of the open
question. Its goal is to transcend the post-Kantian ontotomy of the Body of
Philosophy in its radical attempt to divorce itself from the isms and dogmas
of the careless skeptics and priests.
The categories of metaphysics, in Nondual Rationalism and Interface
Philosophy—as in Integral Post-Metaphysics—can no longer be absolutized
into a dogmatic stance, not even the absolutized-relative dogma of radical
skepticism. Indeed, Nondual Rationalism, and especially Interface
Philosophy, can take on any metaphysics whatsoever while maintaining the
relative status of its truth claims. Metaphysics in Interface Philosophy,
becomes a categorical or conceptual operating system or merely an
application or program—a conceptual interface of relative categories. Install
if you wish, and take it for a test run, but be aware that it is only an interface
between you and the hardware of reality, and that you may have to perform
a hard reboot if it fails.
Thus, post-metaphysics is not ultimately a feature of the metaphysical
system itself, but a cognitive or conceptual aperspectival stance which
imposes an acategorical imperative—a meta-metaphysical and meta-
categorical framework—in which the absolute truth claims of any
metaphysics are suspended in the relative world of justification, partly
through the rational truth that all truth claims may be subject, endlessly, to
further analysis. Indeed, this unbounded stance of analysis is at the very
core of the synthesis of Nondual Rationalism, as we will see. It is a resonant

Page | 50
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

thread to the positive infinity and secret of Rationalism. And, as we will see,
the Vision-Logic Coordinate System and the Univocity Framework, form a
meta-metaphysical framework within which metaphysics can find no
foundational ground with which to dogmatize and ism-ize itself.

For example, while it may indeed be true that Spinoza believed in his system
as ultimately True, it may also be true that in his age of rampant dogma, a
deep faith in one’s own way out of dogma was essential to his emotional,
intellectual and even to his physical growth and survival. It is also the case,
however, and critically so, that nothing in Spinoza’s philosophy depends on
any absolute belief whatsoever; as Deleuze says, even Spinoza’s ontological
proofs are “not hypothetical, but genetic.”i¥ Spinoza’s ontological proofs do
not attempt to prove a transcendent God, as do Leibniz’s. They show how
the relative concept, interfacing with the absolute, is properly, logically,
consistently, rationally and non-dually generated.ii Spinoza’s philosophy
does not rely on the belief in the properties of an existing entity. It merely
shows how to consistently and non-dually define it. Indeed, as we will see,
Spinoza renders the truths of the nondual traditions into the logic of
rationality. The positive infinity and secret of rationalism is the logical
equivalent of Nagarjuna’s Emptiness, while Spinoza’s concept of real
difference is the logical equivalent of dependent arising. Spinoza shows how
and why the truths of nonduality are entirely compatible with the truths of
rationality, and indeed how and why they are unavoidable and unassailable
for any logical and rational mind.iii*
Indeed, it will be shown herein how and why the positive infinity of the
rational does not give rise to antinomies, as Kant thought, but that the
necessities of logic and relation demand the existence of the infinite.
Regardless of whether the infinite can fit into the finite or indefinite
imagination of man, it can very simply fit into his logical and rational
understanding, itself informed in deep evolutionary symbiogenesis with
experience, intelligence and memory. To be sure, only through affirming and
incorporating the necessity, in the rational, for the infinite can the nondual
synthesis between the relative and the absolute be truly accomplished. Just
as only through incorporating the necessity of Emptiness in form, at some
level or zone, can the nondual begin to present itself.
Spinoza demonstrated that there is a valid way to generate and conceive
the nondual absolute in the crystalline rigor that the geometrical method of
the Ethics helped to provide. More than he believed in his absolute


Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, p79
ii
We’ll see this more explicitly through our “embryogenesis of the concept” in the section Spinoza: A
Nondual Sketch, p664.
iii
* See Spinoza: A Nondual Sketch, p664.

Page | 51
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

knowledge of its properties, he believed in the rigor of its underlying form


and nondual truths, as well in the transformative power in its theory of
emotions. Spinoza was a test case of his own model, and in the history of
Western philosophy there is no better example of a philosopher who lived,
practiced and embodied his philosophy. His theory of the emotions, Spinoza
declares, helped him to achieve “blessedness” or transcendence from the
passive into the active emotions in the “intellectual love of God.”

The rational stage of development gives us the open-ended tools of logical


synthesis and analysis. Any Integral and post-metaphysical system,
therefore, must transcend-and-include these tools to make it successfully
and fully into a healthy stage of trans-rationality. But it can only do so if the
rational tools and truths themselves are properly developed. We will find,
however, that the tools of rationality were buried under layers of mis-
representation. They lay rusting, trampled under-foot in the dirt of
obscurity. Resurrecting and expanding this tool-set is part of the project of
this work, in order to properly and much more powerfully transcend-and-
include the truths of the rational into the trans-rational free from the post-
Kantian ontic-shadow.
Thus, we can state that part of the definition of the trans-rational and
post-metaphysical must be the abstinence of making truth claims contrary
to, or without regard to, the truths of the rational stage of development. And
we can also state that such a system must be in accord with the available
evidence and methodologies from the scientific and empirical world. Where
no empirical evidence exists, then, we have only the tools of logical synthesis
and analysis, along with trans-rational intuition. Those metaphysical
systems, such as Dogmas, that run counter with the injunctions of the
cognitive tools evolved so far are therefore “metaphysics in the bad sense.”

Page | 52
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

After getting to know Ken Wilber—working directly with him at his Integral
Institute for the past two years—I dearly love and greatly admire the man.
But he is, after-all, a man. And when the exalted authority of one man stands
in the way of the emergence of pragmatic and logical truths in another, less
known sphere, this authority must be questioned. It is in this healthy and
loving way that I attempt to inform the exoteric Received View of Spinoza in
Wilber’s work with my studies in esoteric rationalism .
In a recent encounteri¥ with Ken, he made the claim that Spinoza’s
philosophy could not be post-metaphysical because Spinoza himself was not
enlightened. But Wilber also makes the claim that Spinoza was “by his own
admission a dedicated Cartesian.” Indeed, Spinoza wrote an early book on
Descartes, within the confines of which he remained true to the Cartesian
system, but only in order to render it and study it correctly. It is this early
dedication to which Spinoza spoke, and to which Ken alluded. In Spinoza’s
mature work, as noted by most Spinozists, he went radically beyond
Cartesianism.
I challenged Wilber on this claim, stating that the majority of Spinozists
would disagree with the assumption that Spinoza could be classified as a
dedicated Cartesian. He then promptly retracted it, with the off-hand
comment that it was irrelevant to his points. On the contrary, it is precisely
relevant. The fact that Wilber could not defend his own claim shows that he
adopted the maxim second-hand, and perhaps has lost the context. Anyone
who really knows Spinoza’s philosophy—i.e. from studying him in depth, not
just in passing on the way to a vast meta-theory of everything (and
everyone)ii—knows that Spinoza was profoundly anti-Cartesian. This is why
the Theosophists consider that Spinoza’s philosophy, when reconciled with
Leibniz’s (reactive interpretation), would reveal the “spirit of esoteric
philosophy” in opposition to the philosophy of Descartes.
Again, the esoteric understanding of Spinoza is profoundly anti-, or trans-
Cartesian. Indeed, as Deleuze states in Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza,
[my emphasis] “…there is no Cartesian axiom [in Spinoza]…that does not
take on a new meaning, hostile to Cartesianism, on the basis of the new
theory of distinctions. The theory has as its fundamental principle the
qualitative status of real distinction. Detached from all numerical
distinction, real distinction is carried into the absolute, and becomes capable
of expressing difference within Being, so bringing about the restructuring of


ISC call, May 12, 2007
ii
Wilber’s limitations here are to be expected of a human being, rather than a god. His net was cast
wide and his focus was on the eastern forms of nonduality, not on “Rationalists,” such as Spinoza.

Page | 53
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY

other distinctions.”i¥
The Spinozan theory of distinctions, as we will see, transforms the
dualistic independent arisings in Descartes, ultimately into dependent
arisings. This dependent arising is one of the key elements of nondual
philosophy, and it is a necessary outcome of the acategorical imperative of
esoteric rationalism itself, as we will see.
Given that Ken Wilber has not found the plane of consistency in Spinoza’s
philosophy—following his claims that Spinoza is a “dedicated Cartesian,”
which he cannot back up—then it is clear that Wilber has not properly
followed the injunctions of the Spinozan paradigm.ii This assertion, then,
that Spinoza was not enlightened, is a clear and uncharacteristic example of
metaphysics in the bad sense. It is a truth claim about the nature (ontic) of
Spinoza’s mind that not only cannot ultimately or absolutely be verified, but
one whose relative merits Wilber himself has not attempted to validate with
the relative truth claims available to him, namely reading Spinoza to the
point of understanding, or even reading the main Spinozists, rather than
merely his critics. In order to assert that Spinoza was not enlightened one
must first understand Spinoza, and when one understands Spinoza, one sees
that he was anything but a “dedicated Cartesian.” As Matthew Stewart
noted, Spinoza considered Descartes to be seriously confused, as any
nondualist to any dualist.

As we will see, there are many thinkers who have found enlightenment
through Spinoza’s philosophy and who feel indeed that Spinoza was
enlightened himself. These are thinkers who have studied Spinoza in depth,
i.e. thinkers who have followed the injunctions of the Spinozan paradigm,
such as Arthur Schopenhauer, the Theosophists, and many others in both
eastern and western nondual systems.

Another key to the definition of post-metaphysics, then—as given by Ken


Wilber—is that any post-metaphysics must have an injunction for
transformation beyond the merely cognitive sphere of concepts. Wilber
states that the Spinozistic philosophy cannot be post-metaphysical because
Spinoza had no injunctions for transformation, say, in the emotional or
“spiritual” sphere. Now, anyone who knows Spinoza knows that the sole


Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, p. 38
ii
A paradigm is a function of technology, and a philosophical system itself is a technology; an
invention based on the industry of language.

Page | 54
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW

purpose of his philosophy was as a means to achieve blessedness in the


“intellectual love of God.”
As is well known in the history of philosophy, Spinoza did not merely
philosophize, but he was among the few western philosophers to have truly
lived his philosophy. This is why Deleuze calls him the Christ of philosophy,
and the common image of him is that of a saint. Like Aurobindo, writing was
itself a practice for Spinoza. But more than this, Spinoza’s philosophy of the
emotions—when lived as Spinoza implored his readers to do as well—was
full of injunctions for moving philosophy into the practical sphere of
emotional transformation, away from the “passive” or reactive emotions, to
the higher “active” emotions such as the intellectual love of God. For
Spinoza, as we will see, the emotional and the intellectual spheres were
never separate. Philosophical injunctions necessarily transcended-and-
included emotional ones. This is why Deleuze called Spinoza’s philosophy a
“Practical Philosophy.” Philosophy, for Spinoza, was a practice for
emotional, spiritual and intellectual development, none of which could ever
be separated, because the intellectual love of God was itself an emotion
manifesting the spiritual in the intellectual.
And further, Wilber states that maps of reality themselves can often be
“psycho-active.” Indeed, as the maxim goes, “right thought leads to right
action.” And it can easily be inverted, “right action leads to right thought.”
The I and the IT quadrant, for both Wilber and Spinoza, are symbiogenetic.
One does not exist separately from the other, and thus what you do in one
sphere influences the other, and back and forth simultaneously.
It is in this way, that Philosophy itself, if lived and practiced, can be an
injunction and a psycho-active map for radical transformation. And, in my
own case, art as well was a very powerful means for transformation, before
the explicit emergence of my philosophizing. Philosophy practiced as an art,
then, is perhaps even more powerful, given that it quickly removes the
philosopher into an aperspectival stance from which to better philosophize
and transform—turning ever new interior subjects into the exterior objects
of art and writing.

Page | 55
Page | 56
Page | 57
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

From Wikipediai¥ we find (my emphases):


The term nondual is a literal translation of the Sanskrit term advaita. That
is, things remain distinct while not being separate. … Nondualism can
refer to one of two types of quality. One is the quality of union with
reality, God, the Absolute. This quality is knowable and can be gained
spontaneously and via practice of inquiry. A second quality is absolute by
nature, or to put it in words, “conceptual absence of ‘neither Yes nor No’,”
as Wei Wu Wei wrote. This latter quality is beyond the quality of union. It
may be viewed as unknowable.
And continuing:
the belief that dualism or dichotomy are illusory phenomenae.
In this work we are focusing on the knowable, or the relative and cognitive
understanding of nonduality, as opposed to the absolute and ineffable aspect
of the nondual. But we are approaching the nondual from the cognitive
aspect rather than the experience of nonduality which can only be achieved
relatively, and explicitly by advanced meditation techniques, or possibly in
spontaneous peak-experiences of awakening or enlightenment.
This system, however, will explicitly reserve a space or a “scope” for the
absolute and ineffable aspect of the nondual in order that the “inseparable
distinction” itself can be maintained with clarity. This will give perspective,
context and detailed relief to the relative understanding of the nondual in
‘symbiogenesis’ (other-engendering) with the absolute. And along with that,
the space reserved, and softly enforced, will allow ontological speculation to
arise and be entertained without allowing it to become absolutized, because
the absolute-scope itself is formally beyond the polarities involved and
necessary for conceptualization to occur. In short, this aspect of the system
ensures that the relative scope is the place where concepts will unfold (such


Wikipedia: nondualism

Page | 58
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

as the whole realm of form, including ontological conceptualization), while


the absolute scope merely gives the relative its context and meaning through
the identity of opposites.

The interpenetrating, or symbiogenetic use of opposites (embodied in the


ancient Taoist yin/yang symbol)—wherein “things remain distinct while not
being separate”—is called polarity, and it will be explored in great detail
throughout this work. Polarity is the key cognitive element—indeed it is
absolutely fundamental and ubiquitous—in the Tao Te Ching, long
considered a seminal work in nondualism. The polarities found in the Tao
Te Ching are manifold, from the masculine/feminine, power-through-
yielding of the traditional Yin/Yang, to the inter-expressive and
interdependent polarities of up/down, light/dark, sense/nonsense,
good/bad, freedom/control, etc, etc.
Polarity is the “opposable thumb of the mind,” and hence it is also
ubiquitous and foundational in this work, as it unfolds the embryogenesis of
the concept. As in the Tao Te Ching—Nondual Rationalism explores in depth
the relative scope of nonduality in polarity, leaving the ineffable absolute
scope pointed to, and poetically hinted at—indeed it is given an infinite and
ineffable altar (the epistemic parameter of the absolute scope) to reside in—
yet remaining necessarily unspoken, in and of itself. Our work herein is
therefore centered on, and empowered through the use, and explicit
operationalization of polarity—even as it unfolds and interfaces with the
absolute scope itself. Polarity is the nondual aspect of Nondual Rationalism
(or NDR).

Another key aspect of modern nondualism comes from Nagarjuna, also


called “the second Buddha,” by the Mahayana (Great Vehicle) traditions of
Buddhism. Nagarjuna was a philosopher from 2nd century India who
developed what is called Madhyamaka, or “middle-path” Buddhism. In the
forward to “The Four Noble Truths,” a famous talk by the 14th Dali Lama
(Tenzin Gyatso), middle-path philosophy is described essentially as a
polarity between absolutizations of the absolute and relative scopes. In
Nagarjuna’s time these took the form of, on the one hand, “eternalism”—the
view that the essence of an object (say a form or a soul) is eternal and
unchanging—and on the other hand, “nihilism”—the belief that all things are
temporary, or ephemerally self-annihilating. Nagarjuna effectively says,
along with Heraclitus, that only change or interdependence is eternal and
unchanging—or, along with Spinoza, that the fundamental essence of an
object is univocal existence itself (substance), which it interdependently and
inter-expressively shares with every other object or phenomenon (ALL is
ONE). In short, eternity is senseless without time, boundlessness or
Emptiness is meaningless without Form, and vice versa on all counts.

Page | 59
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

This polarity between the absolute and relative also gives rise to the Two
Truths Doctrine of Buddhism, a foundational element in Nondual Rational
Epistemology, or Interface Theory.i* This, we will find, is foundational also
to the notion of Univocity,ii* which Deleuze sees as the key element in his
interpretation of Spinoza, and this will be operationalized as the polarity of
absolute and relative scopes.
Toward the goal of laying out a middle-path between these extremes of
relative nihilism and absolute eternalism (or essentialism), Nagarjuna
developed a concept he called sunyata, or Emptiness, which essentially
means that all manifestations of existence, what we might call objects or
modifications, are empty of their own self-contained essence (i.e. they are
empty of the metaphysical essences which Plato called forms or ideas).
Nagarjuna, like Deleuze, basically implores us to think acategorically, and he
even titled one of his later books, Pulverizing the Categories. Indeed, this
common categorical, or essentialist thinking, is the “essence” (pardon the
term) of the “forces of representation” which, Deleuze argues, have distorted
the reading and interpretation of philosophy (mainly Spinoza and Leibniz,
herein) throughout History via an essentialist and idealist (Platonic) lens.
(This will be explored later through the explication of the concept of the
transcendent-bias.)
This Nagarjunan (and Deleuzian) pulverizing of the categories is effected
through what is called dependent origination, or dependent arising, in the
sense that the essence of an object or phenomenon is not self-contained, but
is fundamentally dependent on the context in which it emerges or arises.
And specifically, all opposites are dependent on each other for their identity
in the very process of origination. In Taoism, this idea is called the identity
of opposites, and it is a key concept throughout this work.

At a deeper level, Emptiness and dependent arising can be seen as an inter-


dependence between the absolute and relative scopes in the sense that all
relativities, i.e. objects or manifestations, are not independent in themselves,
but are dependent on Emptiness, or absolute ineffable existence, which
includes the ALL, as ONEiii infinite and fundamentally interdependent, or
inter-expressive multiplicity. This is the meaning behind Spinoza’s univocal
polarity of Substance and its modes, expressed through the triune interface
of the attributes (We will explore this in much more detail in the section on
Univocity and elsewhere). Or as the Heart Sutra puts it, “That which is

i
* See, Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch , p541.
ii
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
iii
As we will see in Unity and Nonduality (p239), this ONE is not to say that there could be TWO.
Infinite or absolute unity is not numerical, because it is not relational. There is a very important
difference between infinite and finite forms of unity, or the forms of unity from the absolute and
relative scopes, respectively.

Page | 60
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

Emptiness is not other than Form, that which is Form is not other than
Emptiness.” This is the identity of opposites (polarity, not duality) of
Emptiness and Form, or The Boundless and Boundary, or The Infinite and
the Finite, or The Absolute and the Relative. These are all different polarities
expressing (at least herein) the same basic meaning.

Nondualism, then, as far as it can be spoken (relative scope), is essentially


the concept of polarity, and this polarity takes many forms and is found in
many directions and trajectories of thought; from the fundamental (vertical)
absolute/relative polarity of Emptiness and univocity, to the (horizontal)
mind/matter, up/down, left/right, good/bad, warm/cool, etc, etc,
representational polarities populating the Tao Te Ching, and even to the
Maya/Brahma, (Illusion/reality, or ontic/epistemic) polarity of ancient
Hindu, and modern Western Philosophy.

As Matthew Stewart says in his The Courtier and the Heretic (my emphases):
In the most widely accepted versions of the history of philosophy, Spinoza
and Leibniz are understood to represent a speculative metaphysical
program that long ago succumbed to academic progress. In fact, talking a
broader view of events, it is clear that the two greatest philosophers of
the seventeenth century remain unsurpassed, and should perhaps be
considered the twin founders of modern thought. We live in an age
defined by its reaction to Spinoza and to all that he recorded in his
philosophy. And there is no more compelling expression of this reaction
than the philosophy Leibniz developed in the long years after his return
from Holland (p16).
And see this quote from Madame Blavatsky, in her The Secret Doctrine
(again, my emphases):
It may be correctly stated that were Leibnitz’ and Spinoza’s systems
reconciled, the essence and Spirit of esoteric philosophy would be
made to appear. From the shock of the two—as opposed to the
Cartesian system—emerge the truths of the Archaic doctrine.
In contrast to the above emphases on Spinoza and Leibniz as “the twin
founders of modern thought,” or as expressing “the essence and Spirit of
esoteric philosophy,” “as opposed to the Cartesian system,” Rene Descartes
is long considered by academia the father, and indeed the epitome, of
philosophic modernism and Rationalism. Yet curiously, both Leibniz and
Spinoza vehemently, rigorously and indeed brilliantly disagreed with
Descartes at the most fundamental of levels, while at the same time forming
systems which (as we will explore herein) are curiously resonant and

Page | 61
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

unified in their anti-Cartesianism, as well as being foundationally allied


(again opposed to Cartesianism) with the key insight and operational axis of
rational mathematics and the mathematical ratio, as we will soon see.

Rationalism is many things, but clearly it is not simply, fundamentally, or


even mostly, Cartesian. Descartes, himself, was notoriously, and very
problematically, a metaphysical dualist. This doesn’t mean (at least not
explicitly) that he fights metaphysical duals, as did Don Quixote, but that he
believed in the existence of two, fundamentally distinct, substances (or roots
of existence): Mind vs. Matter. The problem with this dualism remains: If
there is no underlying or common causality (substance) between them, how
do these two substances interact, say, when my mind decides to move my
fingers around my keyboard in typing this sentence?
This is the historical incarnation in the West of the exceedingly irrational
mind/body problem; the two-headed dragon-shaped windmill, which, to this
day, can be seen lurking the halls of academia, only to be ritually drawn and
slain quarterly by the ever-victorious professor of the History of Philosophy.
And when Descartes, the arch-dragon of rationalism falls, with his dual
snapping sets of metaphysical jaws, he drags down each of his two
underlings—the lesser rationalists and henchmen—Spinoza the
foundationalisti and “dedicated Cartesian,”ii and Leibniz, the fatal-optimist of
infinite, fantastic opulence.
And so the “holy grail of philosophy”iii is yet again snatched away for
another quest and another tenure, safely folded into the dark recesses of
unconscious academic gamesmanship—tightly guarded by the rigid spines
of countless rows of textbooks, all echoing the same glorious tale of victory
over the dicephalous dragon of Rationalism, Descartes.

Clearly, at any rate, Descartes, the dragon of dualism, cannot be seen as a


knight of nondualism, at least not on his own terms, and his system (though
perhaps not his style of exposition) is, in the end, quite irrational, as most
scholars would agree,iv so on these terms, he can’t be considered a key, or
representative, Rationalist.

i
A key interpretive error we will correct herein, with the help of Deleuze.
ii
According to Ken Wilber’s brief encounter with Spinozistic history.
iii
See Mathew Stewart’s The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy.
iv
This is not to be considered a definitive account of the fundamental irrationality of the Cartesian
system. For that, consult virtually any modern professor of philosophy. And this is not to say that
Descartes does not have his truths as well, but simply that they are compromised by irrationality of
his metaphysics, and his desire to secure absolute certainty, at whatever cost.

Page | 62
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

As Stewart says:
In the most widely accepted narratives of the history of thought,
Descartes’ so-called dualism is often taken to represent a fundamental
revolution in ideas and the starting point of modern philosophy. In style
and method Cartesian philosophy did indeed mark an important, hugely
influential breakthrough in European letters; but in substance his work is
perhaps better understood as an attempt to conserve the old truths in the
face of new threats. His dualism was in essence an armistice of sorts
between the established religion and the emerging science of his time. By
isolating the mind from the physical world, the philosopher ensured that
many of the central doctrines of orthodoxy—immortality of the soul, the
freedom of the will, and, in general, the “special” status of humankind—
were rendered immune to any possible contravention by scientific
investigation of the physical world. Conversely, the complete self-
sufficiency of the machine-like material world guaranteed that physical
science could proceed without fear of contradiction from revealed
religion. … For men such as Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibniz, solving
the mind-body problem was vital to preserving the theological and
political order inherited from the Middle Ages and, more generally, to
protecting the human self-esteem in the face of an increasingly truculent
universe. For Spinoza, it was a means of destroying that same order and
discovering a new foundation for human worth.
Spinoza’s answer to the mind-body problem marks a radical break in
the history of thought—the kind that happens only every millennium or
two (p164).
What then is Cartesian in Nondual Rationalism given that Descartes’
metaphysical dualism is so clearly and obviously irrational, or pre-rational
and pre-modern? What specifically did Spinoza or Leibniz inherit, or even
pass over, from Descartes, that we may find useful in outlining and
expanding Nondual Rationalism? Many things, such as his focus on the
direct interface of experience in the cogito—a key element and limit
(relative boundary) of Nondual Rational Epistemology—and some general
elements of his system of physics, such as the focus on vortices (spin) in the
formation of the solar system (a spinning bit)—both of which will be
explored in Volume II—but mainly what was emulated in Descartes was his
geometric style of rigorous explication.
Descartes geometric style, while still being very readable and personable,
was definitively rational. Both Spinoza and Leibniz admired and expanded
on this style, and particularly the use of rigor and logic which Descartes
inherited from earlier mathematical treatises, such as Euclid’s Elements.
Spinoza inherited and perfected this style to demolish Descartes’ inherent
irrationalism, the key tenets of dualism, to replace them with a
fundamentally nondual metaphysical system wherein mind and body are
mere attributes or ways of perceiving, conceiving and expressing “the
essence of Substance,” which is ultimately infinite and unbounded existence

Page | 63
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

itself (in line with the existentialists, but opposed to academic accounts of
Spinozism and Rationalism).

From the definition of rationalism in the online Britannica dictionary we find


(my emphases):
[Rationalism is a] Philosophical view that regards reason as the chief
source and test of knowledge. Rationalism has long been the rival of
empiricism, the doctrine that all knowledge of matters of fact ultimately
derives from, and must be tested by, sense experience. As against this
doctrine, rationalism holds reason to be a faculty that can lay hold of
truths beyond the reach of sense perception, both in certainty and in
generality. In stressing the existence of a “natural light,” rationalism also
has been the rival of systems claiming esoteric knowledge, whether
from mystical experience, revelation, or intuition, and has been opposed
to various irrationalisms that tend to stress the biological, the
emotional or volitional, the unconscious, or the existential at the
expense of the rational.
From this definition we find many of the key aspects of the common
(academic) understanding of rationalism: (1) an emphasis on reason, (2) the
rival of empiricism or experience-ism, (3) the rival of esoteric knowledge,
such as (chiefly) intuition, (4) opposed to irrationalisms that stress the
biological, emotional, unconscious and existential. Let’s examine these key
aspects one by one and see if this category fits our key rationalists
comfortably, or like a procrustean bed.

Does rationalism—as embodied in the key rationalists Spinoza and


Leibniz—stress reason and reject emotion? Most certainly both Spinoza’s
and Leibniz’s systems can be seen as attempts to push reason to its absolute
limits in (for Spinoza) the intellectual love of God, and for Leibniz, an
understanding of God as an infinite system of monads (substances) based
explicitly on principles of logic. But notice, even here, that Spinoza, while
emphasizing reason, or the intellect, mixes it critically with the emotion of
love. Indeed, he states that emotion can only be overcome, not with pure
reason, but with higher (more reasonable) emotions, such as the intellectual
love of God. There is no spurning of emotion in Spinoza, but rather a
program for overcoming the state of passivity with respect to them.
Spinoza endorses not the rejection of emotion, but the active interfacing
of emotion with its own higher forms. Spinoza recognizes that there is
indeed a rationality inherent in all emotions. They are a rational outgrowth

Page | 64
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

of evolutionary problem-solving; i serving a rational (if pre-cognitive)


purpose, with the higher emotions involved in the higher forms of cognition,
such as reason and the intellect. In Spinoza, reason is never divorced from
emotion. It does not conquer emotion, but rather emotion is harnessed to
conquer itself and lead to more reasonable or rational kinds of emotions,
like the intellectual love of God.

As Matthew Stewart says (and note here the specific nondual emphasis):
The endpoint of Spinoza’s philosophy—the intellectual love of God, or
blessedness—transfigures all that precedes it. … It is the union of the
individual and the cosmos, of freedom and necessity, of activity and
passivity, of mind and body, of self-interest and charity, of virtue and
knowledge, and of happiness and virtue (p177).
Does Spinoza or Leibniz reject or spurn experience, or stress reason at the
expense of experience? Not so at all. Indeed, Spinoza was a great fan of
scientific and empirical methodologies, and none of his rationalizations
contradict, or occlude empirical data (and he would likely not allow them to,
if he found out they did). Rather, they are born from it and help to organize
it. Indeed, as Antonio Damasio has shown, Spinoza’s psychology of the
emotions has held up extremely well and even today can provide insights to
neuroscientists, such as himself (see his book Looking for Spinoza).
Spinoza’s metaphysics, as well, was, and still is, attractive to many
empirically centered scientists, such as Albert Einstein, who called himself a
“disciple” of Spinoza.
Indeed, Spinoza can even be seen as a progenitor of empiricism for many
reasons. Firstly, Spinoza’s philosophy was directly influential to John Locke,
as Locke purchased and studied all of Spinoza’s work in depth, during his
exile in Holland. Leibniz himself, as Matthew Stewart goes on to show, drew
many parallels between Locke’s empiricism and heretical Spinozism, such as
Spinoza’s rejection of the notion that the body was known empirically to the
degree that we can say that the higher functions of cognition, such as
consciousness, could not arise with it in its increasing complexity.
Spinoza asks, “What can a body do?” He says (my emphases):
Nobody as yet has learned from experience what the body can and cannot
do ... solely from the laws of its nature insofar as it is considered
corporeal. For nobody as yet knows [again, clearly from experience] the
structure of the body so accurately as to explain all its functions, not to
mention that in the animal world we find much that surpasses human
sagacity, and the sleepwalkers do many things in their sleep that they
would not dare when awake ... [the human body] surpasses in ingenuity
all the constructions of human skill.

i
intelligent evolution, as it were…

Page | 65
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

Can the complexity of a body lead to consciousness? Spinoza says, in effect,


we simply do not have the empirical data to show that it can’t, so there is no
reason to suppose a dualistic Cartesian disconnect between mind and body.
Rather, Spinoza says, mind and body are the different ways, or perspectives
(attributes),i* from which we can get to know the nature of reality, or the
“essence of Substance.” Leibniz (initiating a chain of Spinozistic
misrepresentation) saw this very modern element in Spinoza’s work—of
emergence in the evolution of mind, essentially predicting the general truths
of cognitive science and the gradient of animal intelligence, from amoeba to
human being—as indicating a reductive materialism. This materialism only
appears, however, when the polarity (nonduality) and parallelism of
Spinoza’s attributes are neglected or misunderstood, and we take only the
outside, objective view, or the view from the attribute of Extension of
Spinoza’s immanence.ii*

Spinoza was indeed a direct progenitor to the line of intellectual descent we


know as Empiricism. Stewart says:
Leibniz’s unstated intuition that Locke was something of a Spinozist, is
probably more insightful than is generally allowed in modern
interpretations of the great empiricist’s work. … the parallels between his
[Locke’s] work and that of Spinoza extend well beyond those suggested
by Leibniz. To be sure, as a conciliation-minded member of the Christian
establishment, Locke toned down or obfuscated some of the more radical
implications of his Spinozism—a task for which his inimitably wobbly
prose was well suited (p268).
Essentially, Locke incorporated Spinoza’s empirical elements, such as a focus
on the empirical reality of the body, and on the senses and experience in the
formation of the mind (as well as his rational notion of democracy), while
abandoning his more radical and modern notions, such as the mortality of
the body and individual human soul, the unity of determinism and free-will
(commonly and incorrectly seen as the removal of the notion of free-will), all
of which also greatly alarmed the pre-rational and pre-modern aspects in
Leibniz.
Indeed, one of the radical elements in Spinoza’s modernism was his use
of empirical methodologies in scriptural analysis. In his Theologico-Political
Treatise, Spinoza applies an empirical approach, stating that Nature herself
should be approached empirically. It is from the empirical data, not based
merely on reason, that we must draw our principles and definitions about
the natural world, and therefore as well, about the relevance and meaning of

i
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486).
ii
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486).

Page | 66
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

the natural artifacts of man, such as the scriptures. Spinoza writes [my
emphases]:
I hold that the method of interpreting Scripture is no different from the
method of interpreting Nature, and is in fact in complete accord with it.
For the method of interpreting Nature consists essentially in composing a
detailed study of Nature from which, as being the source of our assured
data, we can deduce the definitions of the things of Nature.i¥
Matthew Stewart continues, noting the similarity between Spinoza’s position
and that of David Hume, who is generally considered by academia, the arch-
empiricist. He begins with a quote from Spinoza himself [my emphases]:
“the human mind … has not an adequate but only a confused and
fragmentary knowledge of itself, of its own body, and of external bodies.”
That is to say, in Spinoza’s world, our knowledge of ourselves, just like
our knowledge of particular things in general, is mediated through the
body itself, and is therefore always imperfect or fallible and open to
revision. Thus, minds are every bit as complex and multifarious as the
bodies of which they are the ideas. (It is worth noting that Spinoza’s
position is quite close to that which the historians of philosophy
ascribe to the radical empiricists, such as David Hume, and not at all
consistent with the “rationalism” with which he is often incorrectly
identified) (p172).
Again we see the tight procrustean bed of academic/exoteric “rationalism”
projecting its ill-fitting categorical boundaries into wounds on the sprawling
esoteric body of Spinoza’s philosophy, and again we invoke the ghost of
Deleuze and Nagarjuna to implore the reader to pulverize the categories
inherited from the past. Again we incant the acategorical imperative of
nondualism and invite the reader to look outside the academic box of
rationalism to explore Spinoza’s philosophy anew; to see it beyond
“rationalism” and even as a trans-rationalism, in this sense as beyond the
common stifling restrictions of the term.
As I will show in the chapter on the symbiogenesis of subject and objectii*
and in the section The Symbiogenesis of the Rational and Empirical, this
intimate connection between rationalism and empiricism is emergent in the
very process of the development of consciousness as a function of what we
will call the “mnemonic primitives,” wherein the brain, and its rational (or
irrational) concepts cannot even begin to grow (and cannot continue to
exist) without external sensory stimulation. There is a direct coupling
between percept and concept—between experience and rationalization—
encoded at all levels, from the most primitive rudiments of ‘mental’
evolution and individual development at the level of cellular ‘sensation’ and


TTP, chap. 7, G III.98/S 87
ii
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.

Page | 67
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

reflexive ‘intelligence,’ to the highest degrees of the human perceptual


faculties and cogitations.
Stewart writes:
In the histories of philosophy, since the days of Immanuel Kant (including
my own, incidentally), Spinoza is typically classified as a “rationalist”…
Along with a number of other recent commentators (see Mason, for
example), I now find this label to be worse than useless; Spinoza was, if
anything, closer to the positions of radical empiricism (p327).
For this reason, and following in both the nondual and the esoteric
rationalist traditions, we conceive of rationalism not at all in opposition to
empiricism, but in a critical symbiogenesis with it. Thus Nondual
Rationalism can just as rightly be called nondual rational-empiricism, when
the emphasis is dully placed. In this volume, the focus is largely placed on
fleshing out the buried tools of the rationalists, but the roots and extensions
of nondual rational-empiricism will be explored to much greater depth and
height in volume II.

Stewart goes on to call Spinoza’s philosophy a radical break and opposition


to the bulk of philosophy up to that point; a rebellion against the received
Platonic doctrine that the mind is a “special kind of thing, endowed with free
will and immortality, whose possession grants humankind an exemption
from the order of nature” (p170). This essentialism is “the creed that
Spinoza sets out to destroy,” like Nagarjuna before him, and Deleuze after
him, with an unspoken acategorical imperative. “In fact,” says Stewart,
“Spinoza’s philosophy, if true, pulverizes not just the theories of his
philosophical predecessors, but also many of the religious doctrines they
sought to protect…. (my emphases)” Indeed, both Descartes and Leibniz—at
least on the public/exoteric surface—fall in this latter category, as
rationalists holding on to their exoteric pre-rationalism for mutual
protection of both the existing pre-rational establishment and the
blossoming rational.
Spinoza, whom Stewart clearly sees as the first “modern” philosopher”—
a father to both “rationalism” and “empiricism,” while being beyond the
modern academic categories of “the rationalist” and “the empiricist,”—
essentially predicted the fields of rational democracy, evolution through
natural causes without the need for a designer, and cognitive- and neuro-
sciences, (this last point is also shared by the noted modern cognitive-
scientist, Antonio Damasio, in his Looking for Spinoza). In this sense,
Spinoza’s philosophy, which we are taking as foundational to Nondual
Rationalism, is actually a trans-rationalism at its highest and deepest, most
fundamental points—many of which will be expanded herein.

Page | 68
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

So we have seen that Spinoza is not against the emotions, he does not
consider them irrational and does not seek to supplant them with pure
reason. He also does not spurn the faculties of experience, which he calls the
“first kind of knowledge.” In fact experience is critical to inform rationality,
in Spinoza. But what about intuition? Indeed, Spinoza’s view can hardly be
seen as against intuition when he considers intuition the highest form of
understanding, the bleeding edge of the intellect. It is intuition, or “the third
kind of knowledge,” that enables us to know God in the way that affords us
with “the intellectual love of God.” So we see that the circle is completed
with the recognition that intuition is the highest form of knowledge which
allows the emotions to elevate us to the intellectual love of God.

But what about Leibniz? Was he as trans-“rational” as Spinoza? Matthew


Stewart shows in great detail, which we will explore later on, that Leibniz
was essentially, and covertly, a Spinozist, and his philosophy consists of an
elaborate attempt to overcome his own Spinozism.i Leibniz demonstrates in
his own notebooks that his goal is to disguise and subvert his own Spinozism
so as to make it palatable to the public, in order to create a new and unified
Theology and Theocracy, or “city of God,” as opposed to Spinoza’s fully
rational dream of a democratic state where the individual is sovereign and
the state serves the purposes of individual freedom.
For example, following a debriefing by Tschirnhaus (a mutual friend of
both Spinoza and Leibniz) on Spinoza’s “secret philosophy” found in his
Ethics, blatant Spinozisms creep into in Leibniz’s notes, denoting, for
instance, that God and “Nature” are One.ii But later on, Leibniz suddenly
recants his unwitting advance, or “collapse,” into Spinozism (Nondual
Rationalism and modernism) saying [my notes and emphases]: “God is not
something metaphysical, imaginary, incapable of thought, will, or action, as
some represent him [not that Spinoza actually represented God as
imaginary, or incapable of thought or action, as Leibniz consistently
represents Spinoza’s views], so that it would be the same if you were to say
that God is nature, fate, fortune, necessity, the World. Rather, God is a
certain substance, a person, a mind.” Leibniz then sets himself the task, “It
must be shown that God is a person, i.e., an intelligent substance.”iii¥ “Behind
the ‘It must be shown,’” Stewart interjects, “lies a characteristically

i
This is a simplistic view of the matter, of course, and the full picture of Leibniz’s Spinozism will be
explored here: Leibniz: A Reactionary Chiaroscuro, p668.
ii
And contrary to modern assumptions, Spinoza's “Nature” is not merely the physical or material
world, but the whole of Reality.
iii¥
Leibniz: A VI.iii.518; DSR, p. 26.

Page | 69
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

Leibnizian anxiety—an unspoken ‘or else.’… Or else what? What if he should


fail to prove that God is a person and not ‘something metaphysical’? (p184)”
Stewart continues, a few pages later, “In his notes from April, Leibniz
once again rebels against Spinoza’s teachings. ‘Is the mind the idea of the
body?’ he asks himself, clearly referring to Spinoza’s doctrine. ‘That cannot
be.’ If the mind is the idea of the body, he reasons, then it must perish with
the body; and this contradicts the doctrine of personal immortality (p186).”
The doctrine of personal immortality, you will note, is to ascribe an absolute
quality or essence—that of eternity—to a form, a relative being. This
reaction against Spinoza, is a return to a classically essentialist, pre-rational,
Platonic notion, that the human being has an individual pre-given and
eternal essence, a personal soul, that is free from the relative world of time,
and its dependent arisings. Leibniz’s anti-Spinozism is essentially anti-
Nagarjunan and anti-Deleuzian, in this pre-rational demand—a demand that
will launch spectacularly bizarre ramifications echoing throughout his
monadology.

On a ferry, in his journey to his first and only face-to-face meeting with
Spinoza, Leibniz pens a draft of an argument that he would soon make
directly to Spinoza. In this argument, titled ‘That a Most Perfect Being
Exists,’ Leibniz proves, through his own Principle of Sufficient Reason, that
Spinoza’s God is possible and indeed logically and rationally necessary,
indeed unavoidable, given this core principle of Leibniz’s entire philosophy
(p191).
In the argument, Leibniz “duplicates in abbreviated fashion the first
crucial propositions in Spinoza’s Ethics: Substances are radically distinct and
can be understood one without another; but all things in the world are
understood through the unique and ultimate reason for all things; therefore,
there cannot be two or more substances in the world; therefore, there is only
one substance, and all things are modes of this one substance” (p192). Thus
Leibniz begins with his “irrevocable commitment to the Principle of
Sufficient Reason—that for every thing there must be a reason—and ends in
a declaration of belief in the core doctrines of Spinoza” (p192). Leibniz then
makes a clearly deliberate false attribution of the argument to “Plato in the
Parmenides”i¥ rather than to the obvious owner, “Spinoza in the Ethics.”

Stewart goes on (my emphases):


Nor can there be any doubt that Leibniz knew in what direction he was
heading. In his notes from the meeting with Tschirnhaus in February, he
attributes to Spinoza the claims that “God alone is substance … and all
creatures are nothing but modes.” Even more telling is a note Leibniz


A VI.iii.573.

Page | 70
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES

made to himself on one of the letters to Oldenburg that he picked up in


London. Where Spinoza says, “All things are in God and move in God,”
Leibniz writes: “One could say: all things are one, all things are in God in
the same way that an effect is contained within its cause and properties of
a subject are in the essence of the same subject.” Leibniz here implicitly
acknowledges that his own speculations—notably, his repeated
suggestion that the things of the world are to God what properties are to
an essence—are elaborations of the central doctrine of Spinoza’s
philosophy.
“An attribute is a predicate which is conceived through itself.” Leibniz
continues in his shipboard draft. (Spinoza himself says: “Each attribute …
must be conceived through itself.”) “An essence is…” Suddenly, the
manuscript breaks off in midword, midsentence: Essentia est pr…
Something throws Leibniz off; his quill quivers; he stops to think
about what he is doing. He retreats from philosophy to the “philosophy of
philosophy.” His next lines are perhaps the most revealing he ever
committed to paper:
A metaphysics should be written with accurate definitions and
demonstrations. But nothing should be demonstrated in it apart
from that which does not clash too much with received opinions.
For in that way this metaphysics can be accepted; and once it has been
approved then, if people examine it more deeply later, they themselves
will draw the necessary consequences. Besides this, one can, as a
separate undertaking, show these people later the way of reasoning
about these things. In this metaphysics, it will be useful for there to be
added here and there the authoritative utterances of great men, who
have reasoned in a similar way. …
At this point, Leibniz was a Spinozist and he knew it. His strategy would
be to conceal his true views wherever they offended the orthodox, to cite
great men such as Plato and Parmenides as a diversion, and, in general, to
work for the day when Spinozism might emerge out from under the false
accusations of heresy and claim its rightful place in the sun. In the
meantime…Leibniz would censor himself…of…thoughts that the world
was not ready to receive (p193-4).

Because Leibniz is operating on rather veiled and exoteric motives—as


should be clear, even from this brief section of Stewart’s masterful historical
work—it is difficult to know what he really believed and what he merely
argued. As a courtier and barrister, Leibniz was constantly arguing things
that he clearly did not, could not an need not hold true. This was his job.
Even if he did believe his publicly stated, and often quite irrational,
philosophy—contrary to his admission that “nothing should be
demonstrated in it apart from that which does not clash too much with
received opinions”—it is clear, as we shall see, that Leibniz possesses a deep
sense of rationality, while at the same time clinging to elements of pre-
rationality, such as the transcendent humanoid God of the pre-rational
Catholic and Protestant churches, the immortal (Platonic essentialist)
human soul and absolute human freedom of the will—all of which are

Page | 71
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

strictly independent arisings (e.g. “windowless monads”). Indeed, it is


Leibniz’s attempt at rationalization of these profoundly pre-rational, and
dualistic/essentialist ideas that gives his system such profound tension, or
“chiaroscuro” as Deleuze called it, endowing it with all the fascinating,
fantastic and “Baroque” embellishments, arabesques, lacunae and
irrationalities that this imposes on his covertly-Spinozist system.i*

For now, then, and until we get to the section wherein we draw out the
identity of opposites between them, we can think of Leibniz as essentially a
covert-Spinozist in self-reflexion and reaction, and hence a covert trans-
“rationalist,” with a bizarre mix of pre-rationalisms and irrationalisms
thrown in the mix, for good exoteric measure—though this is not to
underestimate the beauty of his logical insights and monadology formed in
reaction to his own Spinozism.

i
* See, Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of Opposites, p659.

Page | 72
This work presents a new view of Rationalism that integrates the key
philosophical and mathematical insights of the rationalists. These include;
mathematical rationalism and the basic properties of rational numbers,
Leibniz’s calculus as the mathematical aspect of his infinite monadology,
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite,i* and Deleuze’s Spinozistic notion of univocity, as
the operational framework for his trans-foundational metaphysics. These
key insights will unfold within a nondual framework implicit in the ideas of
the rationalists themselves, as we have already started to see.
A key aspect of Nondual Rationalism, as discussed above, is the
Nagarjunan polarity of Emptiness and Form, as well as the notion of the
identity of opposites.ii How can we understand this polarity of Emptiness
and Form in a convergent understanding of mathematical and philosophical
rationalism? And what is the identity of opposites in this context?
In nondual mathematical rationalism (Interface Mathematics), the
polarity of Emptiness and Form, or absolute and relative, can be translated
rather simply as the polarity of infinity and number.iii* ‘Infinity,’ in this
sense is taken from the ancient Greek apeiron as boundlessness, which
“derives from the archaic a-peirar … a rope, knot or bond, i.e., something that
has to be put around or upon something else from the outside, not just an
end or a limit which is intrinsic to it.”iv¥ In Interface Mathematics and

i
* See Spinoza’s famous letter on the infinite.
ii
It may be objected outright that the nondual is fundamentally ineffable and hence, “The tao that
can be told is not the eternal Tao.” The Tao that is spoken and described throughout this work is the
Tao as it manifests only in the relative world (the relative scope). This framework of Nondual
Rationalism actually makes the statement, and holds open the space, that the absolute, which
includes all forms of boundlessness such as the boundless time of “eternity,” is indeed ineffable
precisely because it is not relative and relational, but its identical opposite.
iii
* See The Polarity of Infinity and (Primitive) Number, p250.
iv¥
(Verelst, Zeno's Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality)

Page | 73
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

Nondual Rationalism, then, infinity as apeiron or absolute openness is in


polar or identical opposition to ‘number’ as the most abstract and general
concept of closure or relative boundary available to the forces of
representation. This “bounded infinite” within number, as we will see, is the
primitive encapsulated “infinite number,” enfolded within all number and
only broken into operation with the invention of the mathematical ratio.
In order to integrate all aspects of rationalism (e.g. philosophical and
mathematical) this infinity, boundlessness or Emptiness within number
must correlate with the infinity opened up in the mathematical ratio, which
is the core of the mathematical definition of the Rational numbers and of
mathematical rationalism. But more pointedly, it must explain the meaning
of (or define) the “undefined” ratio with zero in the denominator, such as
1/0. Indeed, a key question which we will answer in much more detail later
is, “What is this limit on definability for the rational numbers?” Or, “Why,
exactly, does placing a zero in the denominator produce these ‘undefined’
results?” And, “Is a limit on definability not in essence a limit on limits
themselves, and hence merely the unlimited and Infinite once the double-
negative has cancelled out?”
Let us not get bogged down in complex and premature questions, but
instead come back to the more simple and general question directly at hand;
“What is it about the infinity, Emptiness and boundlessness opened up with
the Rational numbers that can provide us with the ‘essence’ of Nondual
Rationalism, both mathematical and philosophical, which can then serve, in
the form of a simple principle, as our Ariadne’s thread through this labyrinth
of the continuum, and through the history of rationalism itself?” The answer
is rather simple once it is visualized and held intuitively in the mind as a
whole, but we must traverse a bit of basic mathematical abstraction to get
there.

Note that all of this will be expanded in much greater detail in the
section, on Interface Mathematics. We will explore just enough basic
mathematics here to give us a thread for tracing the essence of Nondual
Rationalism as we proceed through this labyrinth. Note also, that the level of
mathematics explored herein, while meta-mathematically, or philosophically
advanced, covers mainly the basics, or fundamentals of mathematics itself,
though we do get into the philosophy of the calculus and Set Theory, later
on. So from a mathematical point of view, this is largely elementary stuff;
addition, subtraction, fractions, etc. Philosophically and meta-
mathematically, however, it breaks open into a new way of understanding
and organizing these fundamentals in resonance with nondual-rational and
trans-rational Interface Philosophy and Mathematics, helping to provide a
fundamental and much needed cohesion between physics and mathematics.

Page | 74
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

An integer (in “integer space”) can be seen as a “numerical identity,” an


absolute numerical category separated from the next integer by an
unbridgeable gap, a numerical vacuum, so to speak. The rational numbers,
on the other hand, are a function of a higher-level relation between two
integers. The mathematical ratio is a division between two values or
magnitudes, e.g. one divided by two, or 1/2. The slanted dividing line in this
fractional notation is called the “solidus,” while the horizontal line used in
1
the vertical notation, , is called the vinculum, and we will use them both
2
herein interchangeably to denote the conceptual dividing interface itself,
regardless of notation.
This rational division, or ratio across the solidus or vinculum opens up
the space between the integers allowing the Rational numbers to possess
any value between those of the integers. For example, 4/3 is one third of
the way between 1 and 2, and 10/3 is one third greater than three, while
908/300 is between 3 and 4, but a mere 8/300ths more than 3, which, from
our frame of reference, might very well be entirely negligible.

The Rational numbers, in fact, ultimately trace out a continuity in the


number-linei with the characteristic that between any two of the infinite
integers, “an infinity” of Rational numbers can be found. Leibniz famously
calls this quality of the continuum opened up by the rational numbers, the
“the labyrinth of the continuum.” This is because, contrary to Euclid, it is
impossible to form a continuous line from an infinity of extensionless points,
because, in any infinite number of points, between any two, there is yet an
infinity of other points that would need to be added. In the continuum, there
is a mind-boggling and labyrinthine “infinity of infinities” within the infinite
integer number-line itself, and even within any number-line interval
whatsoever. But when we think of infinity as simply boundlessness, or
apeiron, rather than an object, this infinity of infinity is simply a common-
sense aspect of deep-level boundlessness.

i
It is now known that the Rational numbers in themselves do not completely compose the
continuum of “the real numbers”, because of the existence of irrational and transcendental
numbers, or “Dedekind cuts” in the rational continuum. But it is the “violation of the closure
property,” in the inversion of the input-output polarity (See Recursion, Iopol, Violation of Closure
and the Acategorical Imperative, p329), initiated in the mathematical ratio that first makes contact
with the continuum and opens the higher level functions of number to this immanent infinity of the
“immanent-transcendent axis,” which the “trans-rational” numbers enfold into. We will see,
however, that because Dedekind’s cuts are “infinitely thin”, the continuity of the Rationals is not
broken, but rather simply not complete. If this seems a conundrum, it will make sense later, for
example, once the concept of an aspect infinity is understood (See The Triune Infinite: Interfacing
Emptiness, p268).

Page | 75
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

This infinity within, or immanent to, the number-line at any interval—


which is opened up by the mathematical ratio of the rational numbersi—is
the source of Zeno’s famous paradoxes of the infinite.ii This infinity within,
this indwelling or immanent infinite—in opposition to the transitive right-
left, up-down, positive-negative, etc, etc, infinities of the integer number-
line—is also central to Nondual Rationalism. But we must find our way, step
by step, to a more comprehensive view of this central, and indeed ever-
present, “point” in the labyrinth.

Think of the two numbers or magnitudes of the ratio relating across a


vinculum as two kids playing on a seesaw, their weights inter-relating across
the fulcrum in the middle. If both weigh the same, or are the same weight-
value, there is a balance, and we have unity, however we may choose to
represent it:

1632 & *%@ $!!! 1


1= = = = 1|1
1632 & *%@ $!!! 1

Beyond the sequential differences between divisor and dividend, or input


and output, there is a perfect symmetry to the ratio, both quantitatively and
qualitatively, in both form and function, between the bottom and top
numbers, (or the immanent and transcendent directionalities as we are
calling them herein),iii just as there is a symmetry between the right and left
sides of the seesaw. It doesn’t matter who is on what side, or in which
direction the seesaw is facing. If the two sides weigh the same, there is
balance and unity, and if one side weighs more, then the other side weighs
relatively less, and vice versa. The Rational numbers are fundamentally a
function of relation; the ratio.
This perfect symmetry and polarity between the immanent and
transcendent aspects of the ratio often goes unnoticed and neglected. In fact
this neglect is encoded into the very language of mathematics and in the
direction of operation in division; from top to bottom, or numerator to

i
This is the “violation of the closure property,” which we will explore in much greater detail later.
ii
We will discuss Zeno’s paradoxes in much greater detail later throughout the book, but specifically
in the section on the paradoxes of the infinite. See, Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.
iii
Note that we could call the transcendent direction “ascendant”, in order to ward off the possible
confusion with the transcendental numbers, which are certainly not to be confused with the
rational. But immanence and transcendence are key to the main axis of the framework of Nondual
Rationalism, as we will see, and they are key to the meaning of the mathematical ratio. We will
reserve the term “ascendance” for additive increases, while the multiplicative transcends and
includes addition through its recursivity. This will be discussed in greater detail in the section on,
Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.

Page | 76
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

denominator.i Indeed, in line with a central theme in the Tao Te Ching,ii we


will find this as part of an overarching “transcendent-bias,” (or a “yang-
bias”) operating throughout mathematics, philosophy and science—but the
recognition of this hidden balance is key to unlocking the core of Nondual
Rationalism.
Let’s take this see-saw analogy further to see the transcendent bias more
clearly. Imagine that the kid on the right side of the see-saw (denominator)
had his mouth taped shut, while the kid on the left side (numerator) were
arbitrarily given the right to scream out his joy or disappointment
depending on his state of elevation in the relation. If he goes up above his
variably-weighted friend, then he screams in glee, “Positively fantastic! I’m
greater than one!,” while his friend is forced to experience his
disappointment in silence. We, on the outside of the fenced-in playground,
hear the value of the see-saw in general elevated above unity, at the expense
of what we cannot hear, the other kid, stuck dumb-rendered and unhappy on
the ground.
The bias inherent in the Rational numbers or fractions is controlled by
the active frame of reference,iii and this is placed in the top or transcendent
position of the numerator. The advent of the function of the ratio opened up
the denominator, the immanent position, to allow it’s new functionality, and
now, in this new rational number-space, intrinsic to every integer is a
denominator of unity, dividing every integer by the original categorical
quantum of mathematics, the number one.
From the active frame of reference of the numerator and its increasing
(ascending and transcending) integer values, an increase in value of the top
number directly increases the transcendent value of the rational number
itself, more and more until we “reach” the unreachable infinite. The active
frame of reference is the aspect of the ratio that is in control of numeration
and value. Conversely, because the ratio, like the see-saw, is a reciprocal,
symmetrical and inversely balanced (polar and nondual) relationship, an
increase in value of the bottom number decreases the transcendent value in
the same ratio until you reach the unreachable immanent infinity (apeiron)
opened up, exclusively, in this very function of the rational number.
Numbers began their evolution at one and transcended or ascended into
higher and higher values. Counting was their purpose, their “fitness
function,” and reason for coming to be. The Rational numbers came later,

i
This is the input/output polarity (iopol), we will explore in Interface Mathematics.
ii
Tao Te Ching, verse 42, by Lao-tzu, from a translation by S. Mitchell, states: “All things have their
backs to the female and stand facing the male. When male and female combine, all things achieve
harmony.”
iii
Note that while the transcendent number (numerator) may hold the active or default frame of
reference, the immanent number (denominator) is the active divisor to the divided, or dividend of
the numerator.

Page | 77
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

transcending-and-including the integers, as a function of the relation


between two of them, but fundamentally operating on a new “axis;”
immanence vs. transcendence. The ascending-transcending bias i is
therefore a natural and pervasive feature of the number-system in general,
as the number-system is indeed a transcending-and-including holarchy [a
hierarchy of holons, or wholes that are always parts of higher level wholes,
and so on] of functions built on other functions, ultimately built on
numerical identities serving the very human function of labeling and
inventorying increasing agglomerations of real objects. This is the
transcendent-bias in stark relief.

transcendent active
transcendent bias
immanent passive
and…
increase
increase transcendent bias
decrease

not…

decrease
increase immanent bias
increase

Transcending and including (recognizing and accounting for) this


transcendent-bias, to get to the nonduality and neutrality, the open ground
of rationalism, this must be seen as a true polarity, and the qualitative
differences between the values that seem so absolute through the active
frame of reference of the transcendent numerator, must be seen, in a sense,
as relative to the active frame of reference of the inherited interpretation. In
other words, the differences in quality between immanent and transcendent
positions are a function of the active frame of reference and order of
operations of division. The numerator’s frame of reference is active as the
determinant of value, and the denominator’s is passive as the context for its
meaning.

i
We’ll see this as the “trans-trans-bias,” where ascendancy equates to the transitive, and the
transitive/transcendent mapping will be explicitly demonstrated through graphing basic functions.

Page | 78
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

This transcendent-bias in operation in mathematics—and human


thought in general (as we will see)—manifests in our tendency to see
infinitely increasing values as normal Infinity, and infinitely decreasing
values as undefined or approaching an actual limit at zero, as is the case with
the errors of interpretation surrounding Zeno’s paradox and the
infinitesimal of the calculus.i* This immanent infinity, however, is the
inverse pole of the infinite axis specific and unique to the rational numbers,ii
and critical to Nondual Rationalism. And similarly, opening up the meta-
mathematical understanding of this polarity to its true relative and
reciprocal nature, is the key to understanding the thread of rationalism as it
winds its way through the labyrinth of history.

To approach this thread more clearly, let’s see what happens when the value
in the denominator dips below the unit-value of the integers, the
fundamental categorical numerical-identity 1, without reaching or crossing
zero. Let us do this through the rational process of division, recursively
dividing the immanent value by 5:

1 1 1 1
1, 5, 25 , 125 , …
1 0.2 0.04 0.008

1 1
244140625_, … | … undefined_ .
0.00000000 4096 0

The value of the whole ratio, or the rational number, begins in balance, at 1,
and (as the voice of the screaming kid reveals his glee at being lifted into the
air) increases to 5, 25, 125, and … 244140625. The increase in overall value
continues toward infinity to the point that when, and only when, we finally
get tired of making distinctions that are too small to be relatively meaningful
and we then reach over the infinite abyss …|… and artificially plug in 0
(because we can’t reach 0 through division), the equation becomes
undefined.
Why, when we increase toward infinity (apeiron) as we indefinitely
“approach” zero through division of the denominator, do we not actually
“reach” infinity when we finally skip the immanent infinity, represented here
in decimals, and plug in zero? Were we increasing toward the undefined all

i
* See, Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200
ii
Specifically, in the violation of the “closure property” which we will discuss in great detail in
Interface Mathematics

Page | 79
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

along, while we thought we were increasing toward infinity? Is infinity itself


then really the undefined? (But we are getting way too far ahead with this
question, so let’s drop back a few bridges.)
What then is the significance of the zero in the rational denominator if,
just as the infinity in the numerator can’t be reached through multiplication,
the zero in the denominator can’t be reached through the rational process of
division? What is the significance of the fact that the rational immanent zero
returns an “undefined,” hence indefinite, and non-finite number, as does the
infinity in the numerator? Are these inverted similarities merely
coincidental?
In line with our earlier recognition, beyond the transcendent bias, that
the transcendent and immanent operations (the numerator and
denominator, respectively) are directly inverse and reciprocal in their
power relations, we can see that a decrease in the value of the bottom
number should be the inverse-identical (identity of opposites) of the
increase in the value of the top number, and the “limit” at zero should be
infinity, not merely the undefined.
Zero, then, in the denominator (as is generally recognized already by
mathematicians and philosophers of mathematics alike) is the rational
equivalent of infinity in the numerator, just as a crane pulling up the left side
of the seesaw will achieve the same effect as a fat man sitting on the right;
the very same side will “touch” the (untouchable) ground of infinity
(apeiron),i no matter the mechanism. It is the simple inversion in this
“relation of powers”ii across the solidus-fulcrum (from which we have a
preferred transcendent point of view)—and the fact that we have as yet not
operationalized the intrinsic infinite axis upon which the Rational numbers
operate—that hides this rather obvious fact from us and from being
explicitly operationalized in mathematics.
This immanent infinity, denoted in the rational denominator by zero, is
simply unexpected from the default transcendent and transitive frame of
reference of the Integer or Natural number-line, with its inherited notion of
zero as merely an empty integer. And so this inverse rational infinity goes
by the name of undefined rather than infinity.
This reciprocity of the Rationals is the source of R. Buckminster Fuller’s
statement, “multiplication through division.” This is what is taking place
when we divide the divisor. We multiply. But just as it makes no sense to
divide any number by zero, it also makes no sense to multiply a number by
infinity. Infinity (apeiron) can’t be reached or multiplied by, finitized or de-
fined, regardless of the position of the boundlessness across the solidus, and

i
To illustrate the inherent finity in this analogy for the “groundless” infinite.
ii
As Hegel claims is the essence of the calculus, which we will come to in the section on the calculus.

Page | 80
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

regardless where it occurs in the reciprocity of this polar relation of powers,


whether immanent or transcendent.

The infinity and “essence” of Nondual Rationalism must then be, at least in
part, this infinite divisibility that exists between and within all integer unit-
values, hidden by the cipher and dividing toward ever smaller and smaller
quantities indefinitely and unboundedly. On this immanent axis, of the
Rationals, there is no final level of value; no final numerical form to reduce
Emptiness to, or vice versa, and no reachable limit at immanent zero. Hence
immanent, rational, “undefined” zero is actually unlimited, unbounded and
infinite Emptiness. This infinite divisibility, infinite depth or immanent
infinity, is the unbounded Emptiness of mathematical rationalism which we
will take as a key property and root operational axis (positive infinity) of
Nondual Rationalism itself, both mathematical and philosophical. And
indeed, this unboundedness in the rational zero is encoded in Nagarjuna’s
definition of Emptiness.
From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, we find [my emphases]:
Nagarjuna saw in the concept sunya, a concept which connoted in the
early Pali Buddhist literature the lack of a stable, inherent existence in
persons, but which since the third century BCE had also denoted the
newly formulated number “zero,” the interpretive key to the heart of
Buddhist teaching, and the undoing of all the metaphysical schools of
philosophy which were at the time flourishing around him. Indeed,
Nagarjuna’s philosophy can be seen as an attempt to deconstruct all
systems of thought which analyzed the world in terms of fixed
substances and essences. Things in fact lack essence, according to
Nagarjuna, they have no fixed nature, and indeed it is only because of this
lack of essential, immutable being that change is possible, that one thing
can transform into another. Each thing can only have its existence
through its lack (sunyata) of inherent, eternal essence. With this new
concept of “emptiness,” “voidness,” “lack” of essence, “zeroness,” this
somewhat unlikely prodigy was to help mold the vocabulary and
character of Buddhist thought forever.
Unlike the Natural numbers or the integers, the Rational numbers are
composed in a function of relation—a polarity of two numbers, each playing
on the other defining the value in a global symbiosis for the rational number
itself—and hence they possess no intrinsic immutable essence or
numerical identity of their own. The integers, on the other hand, are
categorically “closed,” self-defined, numerical identities, in a sense; they
have a unit “closure property” that is “violated” and pulverized in the
function of division itself. Each integer can only mean one thing and have
one identity separated from all others and categorically identical to any
integers of the same value. The Rationals, however, can be formed in an

Page | 81
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

infinite number of ratios. The number 2, for example, can be written as 2/1,
4/2, 16/8 or 3446/1723, and it is “infinitely close”i to its “nearest neighbor,”
which naturally cannot even be defined, because it has no nearest neighbor,
but infinitely many of them. Indeed, the relationship itself, is endlessly
mutable, forming a continuum of possible states in between. (See Figure 1,
below)

i
To invoke the labyrinth before an explanation is at hand.

Page | 82
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

Figure 1: The Holonic Solidus:


This diagram illustrates the new axis of the Rational numbers as extending infinitely
toward, but never reaching “immanent zero” or the zero of the rational, newly defined
as an immanent infinity, once the operational axis of the Rational numbers is
acknowledged. Notice specifically that the Rational numbers have no intrinsic
negativity. From its two poles at 0 and infinity, all Rational numbers are intrinsically
positive, or “intensive” in correlation with Deleuze’s positive infinity of the rational.
The negativity that some Rational numbers possess comes from transcending -and-
including their transitive elements. This is why it makes no difference which side of
the solidus the negative number is on, in order for the rational number to be negative.
The negativity of the transitive numbers is transcended -and-included within the
rational numbers.

Page | 83
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

So we can see here a precise break between the infinity of Rationalism and
that of pre-rationalism. The pre-rational (transitive or regressive) infinity
passes from one side of infinity to the other, right through the integer-zero
as merely the absence of another self-defined integer on its way from the
positive to the negative transitive values. In contradistinction to this
positive/negative opposition, the mathematical ratio, of itself, can’t even
produce negative numbers, but rather merely an infinity of positive
intensities on either side of “unity” (one), approaching, but never reaching
immanent zero or transcendent infinity. The Rationals are operating on a
new axis,i* and this is why the pre-rational (transitive) axis of infinity does
not know what to do with this new role for the cipher as an immanent
infinity once the mathematical ratio introduces the “violation” or
“pulverization” of the “closure property” of the fundamental unit underlying
the pre-rational integers.
Mathematical ratios, and hence rational numbers, have no intrinsically
negative values. Try as we might, but they can’t be reached by either
multiplication or division.ii* And hence the “negative infinity” of the
Rationals (to entertain the transcendent-bias further) is in the immanent
direction, and on the positive side of the integer-axis, ever toward the
“unlimit” of zero.iii The rational zero as infinity, then, will remain undefined
until the transcendent bias is lifted and we can explicitly and operationally
see the infinite axis, and indeed the infinite interminable pole “terminating”
at the immanent zero, the inward pole of the positive infinity of the
Rationals.
The idea that negative numbers and the negative infinity—as well as the
positive and negative transcendent polarity itself (toward increasing
positive or negative values on either side of the infinite integer number-
line)—are in this sense pre-rational, is further supported by the observation
that the ratio is indifferent to the placement of the pre-rational negative sign.
You can put it in the numerator or the denominator or on the rational
number as a whole and you get the same negative rational number. The
negative infinity of the integers, which would oppose the positive infinity
found in both of them, is simply not the negative infinity of the Rationals. It
is this infinite divisibility and depth, this positive immanent infinity between
the integer-unit one and its non-limit at the rational (infinite) zero, that fills
the role of the “negative” on the immanent axis (which as a whole is positive,

i
* See, The Orthogonality of Inverses and the Offset Origin-Identities, p338.
ii
* See, The Kernel of the Trans-Trans Asymmetry and Instability at the Crossroads of the Transitive
and I/T Axes, p340.
iii
The rational numbers, then, are intrinsically “intensive,” as Deleuze speaks of the “forces” of the
sub-representational. Rational numbers, as we will see, are the mathematical equivalent of the
forces of immanence and sub-representation.

Page | 84
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

or intensive), and in turn gives a new, unexpected and as-yet-unaccepted role


to the cipher itself, as we will see.i*

And now we close upon our Ariadne’s thread, the central principle of
Nondual Rationalism that will guide us, and indeed pull us, through the rest
of the labyrinth as it gets clearer and clearer what this thread really consists
of and the forms, strands or chords it morphs or resonates into, pulling
them, as well, from the deep-infinity of Emptiness. Indeed, this will be
merely one strand of what will become an “Ariadne’s Cable,” getting stronger
and stronger as it ties Nondual Rationalism directly to the senses and hence
to sensibility and the roots of understanding.

Clearly the generalized (a posteriori) “essence” of Nondual Rationalism must


open to continuity. It must have something to do with the infinite intensive
axis intrinsic to the Rational numbers and to rationality itself. It must enfold
the infinite divisibility and depth between or within any unit-value or
interval and hidden behind the new as-yet-undefined role of the rational
cipher. It must include the essence of Leibniz’s labyrinth of the continuum
and transcend the negative infinity of the pre-rational number-line. And yet,
from the nondual traditions we know that this can’t be the totality of it. It
can’t be merely infinite divisibility; it can’t be merely continuity, or merely
immanence. It must embody the essence of polarity and the identity of
opposites, and hence it should at least seem self-contradictory, paradoxical
and ineffable at the relative surface, as we wave seen it echo throughout the
centuries in one paradox or another, such as Zeno’s.
If we define the essence, or “fundamental” feature of Rationalism as this
infinite divisibility (and immanence), what then is the opposite of infinite
divisibility that may serve as its nondual identical? Infinite indivisibility?
Can we see indivisibility as the “same thing” as divisibility? We can indeed if
we take them to the “absolute limit” of limitlessness, Emptiness or infinity
(i.e. at the absolute scope).
We will find with much more clarity as we progress that indeed the
infinite divisibility and immanence of nondual- or trans-Rationalism is the
identical-opposite (the conceptual symbiont) of the indivisibility inherent in
the common notions of the continuum. Indeed, it is the infinite divisibility
itself that necessitates that every single and finite division can’t be absolute
or ultimate. There is always a deeper level to divide and hence the
continuum is never ultimately or finally divided. With the modern
mathematics of the continuum, we know that an infinite division is infinitely
small, thus leaving no gap itself in the continuum. It is merely an idealized
aspect of infinitely precise position, and between any such two points, no

i
* See, The Polarity of Zero: The Amphibian of the Transitive and Immanent, p335.

Page | 85
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

matter how close they may seem, the gap is filled with yet another infinity of
indivisible points. The continuum is therefore—by the same infinite
principle—fundamentally indivisible precisely because it is infinitely divided,
leaving no gaps. Division, as it traverses the immanent axis toward its ever
unreachable “limit at zero,” endlessly approaches an “infinitely small point,”
and hence an absolute division is merely one of an “infinite number” of
extensionless and unreachable position, abstracted out of the labyrinth of the
continuum.i
If this seems paradoxical, don’t worry, it will make much more sense
when the framework of Nondual Rationalism is in place. Indeed, it would be
entirely suspect if it were not seemingly paradoxical and difficult to grasp
when dealing with the infinite and the nondual.
And so we can state our principle of Nondual Rationalism as the
following identity of opposites:ii

Explanation: Infinite divisibility necessitates that there can be no fundamental or


absolute division because there will always be a deeper level of divisibility, and hence,
with infinite divisibility the absolute is fundamentally indivisible. This, we will see, is a
nondual codification of the truths underlying Zeno ’s general paradox, which itself was
not so much refuted by the modern mathematics of the continuum, but vindicated by
it. Cantor showed that Zeno’s paradox is a natural feature of the mathematical
iii
continuum. * Infinite divisions are infinitely small , and any possible gap between two
divisions is filled with an infinity more , thus leaving no gaps in the continuum.

Zenoid-Scholium: (A loose allegory) Imagine a chunk of matter is divided in two. Now


imagine each chunk divided in two as well. And each of these in turn … ad infinitum.
What is left when everything is made out of division? A continuum of nothing, or an
infinitely folded Parmenidean unity of Being?

i
This is Leibniz’s notion of a mathematical point as a “terminus,” not a real entity. It is merely a
direction of unbounded division, the pole of an Immanent/Transcendent axis.
ii
And our “principle of principles” could state that a principle is merely a tool. A man-made habitual
element of a system of thought whose repeated use will prove beneficial when implemented in his
entirely fictional construction.
iii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 86
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

After discovering the principle of Nondual Rationalism in my study of


mathematical rationalism, I recalled—what was likely operating in my
subconscious all the while—that the critical distinction between the two
substances in Cartesian dualism is that Matter is infinitely divisible while
Mind is fundamentally indivisible. This distinction, in a sense, is also carried
into both Spinoza and Leibniz’s definitions of the attributes. The PNDR,
implicit in Spinoza’s philosophy, therefore, directly and simply undercuts
Cartesian or Mind/Matter dualism (and its resonances in the Mind/Matter
dualism found in Leibniz, to support his pre-rational elements) and dissolves
the absolutized distinction by engaging the Taoist identity of opposites to
softly call forth a dialogue between them. This is, again, an extension or
variation—in the form of a simple principle, a kind of koan—on the idea of
dependent arising, and in the chapter on Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity, this is
explicated much further into the concept of “the symbiogenesis of subject
and object.”

Explanation: The principles used throughout this text are not conceived or used as
fundamental truths about reality, i.e. Laws of Nature, but merely as pithy and
distilled rudimentary or fundamental elements of the system itself. Sometimes they
are used as rigidified building-blocks—or as Gerald Lebau would say, as “needles” to
the softer, more intuitive semantic “noodles”—and sometimes they are used as
resonant keys to unlocking paradoxes and conundrums of the evolving text. Indeed,
the Fundamental Principle of Nondualism itself is the key to unfolding its resonant
chords, the other principles in this unfolding system.

The fundamental principle of Nondual Rationalism can be further


demonstrated as follows. If we take any region of extension and impose
upon it a time-ordered, “stepwise” or sequential process of recursive
division occurring through time—say, dividing each segment in half, ad
infinitum, or dividing space into an infinitely nesting series of spheres (see
Figure 2, below)—what we end up with is essentially the continuum of the
rational numbers. The mathematics of the modern continuum developed by

Page | 87
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

Cauchy and Cantor, et al shows, however, that the Rational numbers do not
exhaust the full order of the continuum. The rational numbers, Cantor
showed, are of the exact same order of infinity (aleph null) as the natural
numbers. And the natural numbers, Cantor said, are “countable” or
“denumerable,” while the continuum itself (the continuum of “real
numbers”) is uncountable.

Figure 2: Space in the Process of Infinite Division by Spheres:


This diagram is copied from Fractal Horizons, edited by Clifford Pickover. (Frame)

The time-ordered and sequential rational continuum, then, is incomplete,


and slicing through it intermittently is an infinite series of “Dedekind cuts.”
These cuts themselves, however, are of zero-dimensional thickness, like an
infinitely thin line crossing another. The gaps of incompleteness in the
rational continuum are thus “infinitely thin,” and nonextended, and thus
from the viewpoint of the rational numberline, nonexistent. But they are

Page | 88
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

gaps nonetheless given that the immanent infinities of these Dedekind cuts
and infinite “irrational” numbers cannot be reached by the function of the
ratio. Thus when you undertake a time-ordered process of division carried
to infinity, not all points on the continuum will be reached, just like the
Rational numbers can’t reach the “irrationals” or transcendentals. What is
left over from this stepwise division process, then, is called “Cantor dust,”
which is essentially the difference between the countable and uncountable,
or first and second transfinite orders of the infinite (and between the
transitive and immanent/transcendent VL-axes, as we will see).

As we will discuss further in the section on Zeno’s paradoxes,i* however,


Karin Verelst and others have demonstrated that if we conceive of the
division not as time-ordered, but as already existent in the “eternal NOW”
(or Spinozan sub specie aeternitatis) that mathematical abstraction affords
us—or as occurring simultaneously “through and through” as a holarchical
“binary tree” of division (a “Zenonian semi-lattice”)—then the infinite
division itself is equivalent to the order of the uncountable infinity, which is
the modern mathematical continuum itself.
It is in this absolute sense, then, that “infinite division equals
indivisibility,” and what Zeno showed, we will see, is precisely this. His
“paradoxes,” merely demonstrated the fact of this seemingly contradictory
nondual truth which modern mathematics has operationalized and thus
ultimately vindicated. What we will find is that Zeno, all along, was not
denying the possibility of motion or plurality, but merely demonstrating the
first principle of his teacher Parmenides, that the ultimate is ONE. Thus by
taking the concept of plurality to the absolute scope of first principles (e.g.
infinite division) we end up with the indivisibility of the Parmenidean
“Being-now.” This “paradox of plurality,” Verelst shows, underlies all of
Zeno’s paradoxes of motion, and thus what Zeno demonstrated is not that
motion is impossible, but indivisible—every segment of apparent motion is
indivisible from an immanent and transcendent, instantaneous and eternal
“Being-now.”

Thus we will find that the fundamental principle of Nondual Rationalism was
introduced at the very beginnings of rationality itself, but it was originally
conceived as a “contradiction” or “paradox.” And ever since the Aristotelian
introduction of the principle of contradiction—inaugurating the exoteric and
dualistic form of rationality to come—dualistic rationality could not codify
and operationalize the nondual reality (polarity) underlying the very
inception of rationality itself. And so it was conceived as an anomaly to be
refuted. Indeed, Verelst shows that every attempt at refutation since has

i
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 89
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

injected artificial “non-Zenonian” premises, namely time itself, into the


Zenonian concept of infinite division. This gave rise to the now discredited
Aristotelian distinction between potential and actual infinity, which Verelst
demonstrates underlies in disguised form all of the subsequent refutational
strategies against Zeno’s paradox. What Zeno showed is really that there is
duality underlying rationality itself, and we will see in much greater detail
just how this duality can be “tuned and triuned”i* into a nondual polarity and
unity—a triune interface—unfolding at the very heart of Nondual
Rationalism and Interface Philosophy.

It must be clarified and/or reiterated at this point why we are taking the
unorthodox position that Descartes is a proto-rational thinker, as opposed to
a fully rational one. There are several reasons.

1. Cartesian philosophy does not explore the implications of rational


mathematics and the labyrinth of the continuum, or what Deleuze
calls immanence and it does not operate upon the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. Leibniz, for example, with his
infinitely holarchical monadology, invented the calculus in the
process of his deep exploration into the rational continuum, the
positive infinity and the secret of rationality. And Spinoza’s whole
system was founded on immanence in transcendence (yin in yang),
with the univocal unity of Substance, whose essence is expressed
through its attributes, as the equals-sign between the indivisibility of
mind and the infinite divisibility of matter. But Descartes
mathematical system operationalizes the Rational numbers strictly
transitively, as opposed to immanently, and his invention of the
Cartesian coordinate system is our prime example of the transitive
axes. It must be noted, however, that Descartes physical or natural
philosophical system does indeed possess infinite depth, but it was
simply not explored to the degree, or taken as fundamentally and
seriously as the immanence found in Spinoza or Leibniz.ii

i
* See To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
ii
Deleuze claims, in Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, that the critical distinction between the
“post-Cartesianism” in Spinoza and Leibniz, and Cartesianism itself, is that Descartes does not
address the idea of expression, which both Spinoza and Leibniz take up with a passion in their own
ways. In Spinoza, this expressionism works its way through the univocity of immanence and through
Leibniz it works through an equivocity, due to his own transcendent-bias. Indeed, their respective
uses of expression, univocal vs. equivocal, constitutes, for Deleuze, the prime distinction between
Spinoza and Leibniz.

Page | 90
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR

2. Cartesian philosophy is imbued with the transcendent bias (which


we could almost claim of Leibniz as well, but his deep exploration of
immanence, and his secret Spinozism, saves him here, making his
transcendent-bias seem very much an after-thought, which it is
almost doubtful he believed in himself), in that God (the absolute) is
conceived as a wholly transcendent being. And in Malebranche’s
occasionalism this God syncs up Descartes’ problematic duality of
Matter and Mind only on those occasions that demand his attention,
such as when I move my fingers on the keyboard right now. An
absurd fix for an absurd and irrational problem, to say the least.
This transcendent-bias captures the Leibnizian and Spinozan
critique of Descartes as “having constructed too ‘fast,’ too ‘easy’ a
philosophy,” as Deleuze puts it in Expressionism in Philosophy:
Spinoza. “Descartes proceeds so quickly in all areas that he misses
sufficient reasons, essences or true natures: he everywhere stops at
what is relative.”
3. Descartes is a dualist, and in this work, the integrated view of
Rationalism directly implies, and indeed necessitates, nonduality.
Given that Descartes is the epitome of Dualism, then there is an
error in his rationalism. We have already cleared up his error
rather simply through the Principle of Nondual Rationalism and the
identity of opposites, but this works immanently, not
transcendently. We could easily call this immanent principle as it
manifests in Descartes’ work, by his term God, but this renders
Descartes’ metaphysics essentially a Spinozism. Descartes himself
failed to recognize how God reconciled his own problematic
dualism. This resulted in the infamous, and rather absurd, pineal
vortex explanation and the even more absurd occasionalism of his
follower Malebranche (as well as the vastly improbable parallel
mind-body fatalism of the Leibnizian “pre-established harmony”).
So, In other words, it is a stretch to include Descartes in our
classification scheme as a nondual-rationalist. It can, of course, be
argued that Descartes philosophy included three substances: mind,
matter and God. In this view, then, Descartes would be
differentiating and outlining, in a categorical format, the triune
interface explored and integrated in nondual forms of Rationalism.
But his lack of integration between these categories, regardless of
their number, still categorizes him as a dualist, in the context of the
nondual traditions. He did attempt, after-all, to integrate his two
substances via the pineal gland, rather than through God as did both
Spinoza and Leibniz in their radically different ways—Spinoza with
his univocal ONE-ALL and its attributes, and Leibniz with his pre-
established harmony.

Page | 91
Page | 92
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS

Modern Rationalism is generally identified most strongly with Descartes,


and with the notion of foundationalismi in the escape from the infinite
regress. Descartes, however, was not only, and infamously, a dualist, but he
was also a theological apologist. Indeed his whole project can be seen in the
light of this purpose, to protect Theology, its pre-rational transcendent God
and the absolutized category of the immortal soul from the burgeoning
mathematical sciences and rational philosophies and from the corrosive
effects of doubt on the search for absolute certainty. Likewise, however,
while Descartes served to protect the independence of the Mind and soul
from dependence on change or death,—and at the same time protecting
Theology from the mutating effects of modernity and rationality—he also
served to protect science, or natural philosophy, from the stifling dictates of
Theology. As Matthew Stewart said, Descartes offered “an armistice of sorts
between the established religion and the emerging science of his time.”
The idea and Cartesian goal of absolute certainty is itself, however, an
absolutization of the transcendent or emergent possibilities of the mind, at
the expense of the dependency of representational mind itself on the
unknowns and unknowables of immanence, and its immediate environment.
Spinoza’s response, as Deleuze points out, was radically different from this
dualistic approach which seeks an independence for the mind. He asks,
“What can a body do?” We simply do not know that the immanence in
bodies is incapable (nondually or non-reductionistically) of manifesting the
emergence of higher levels of intelligence and representation in human

i
We will discuss foundationalism in much greater depth later. See Foundationalism: Crystalline
Pyramids In Emptiness, p641.

Page | 93
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

awareness, and into our categories of mind and matter. We have no


empirical knowledge that a nondual dependent arising, or “symbiogenesis of
subject and object”i* is impossible, and therefore we have no recourse or
reason to absolutize the concepts of Mind and Matter into an irreconcilable
pair of categories.
As discussed above, this transcendent-bias toward absolutizing concepts
and a posteriori generalized categories into Platonic forms and essences
taken a priori, is one of several points that pushes Descartes toward the
relative category of a non-rationalist, and indeed a Mind/Matter essentialist.
And we have already seen the transcendent-bias transcended-and-included
in the rational numbers, which we will explore in great detail in Part Two:
Interface Mathematics.
Descartes’ own mathematical thinking was essentially transitive, and
lacking in immanence (or expression, as Deleuze noted). And the
transcendent bias—as we will see—is operationalized transitively, not along
the Immanent/Transcendent axis (and we will see that this immanent-
transcendent axis is the nondual-rational, or trans-rational,
operationalization of the positive infinity, the secret of rationalism as it
embodies the polarity of yin and yang as well). This transitive
operationalization of the transcendent-bias, is called simply the trans-bias,
or alternately, the trans-trans-bias, to make explicit the double-mapping of
the transcendent to the transitive, which we will see in much more detail
later.ii*

Essentially the trans-bias can be understood briefly thus: organisms have


evolved the higher sensory/cognitive functions because it substantially
increases their “differential reproductive success.” The senses look outward
and provide, in their functionality, both an individual and an evolutionary
growth or transcendence. The outwardness of the senses, however, is
mapped individually in lines of sight, or sound, or directions of touch, from
one side of the individual to the other. The directionality in these lines of
sensation, is a key feature of the definition of the transitive axes (as we will
soon see in depth), in that these directional lines of sense, never deal with
the infinite immanence within the individual, but pass it over like a blind-
spot, generally taking this ever-present immanence for granted. Lines of
thought or sensation cannot approach infinite immanence operationally
because the zero begins as merely a point on the line which it passes over
like any other.

i
* See the section in Spinoza's Attribute Polarity Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the
Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
ii
* See The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.

Page | 94
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS

It is from this evolutionary focus on the outside—this arms race to


accumulate the intelligence of directionality in the senses—that the
imagination is born. This symbiogenesis of subject and object, a process,
which we will cover in much greater detail later,i* directly encodes the trans-
bias into human conceptual thought. This is why we find it so difficult to
conceive of infinite immanence, and why we always feel a sense of cognitive
vertigo when we can’t find a final resting place, or footing for the mind; an
ultimate foundation, a fundamental substratum, a “ground of Being.”
Indeed, the vibrations of sensation themselves, skip right over the
immanence in their transitive motions, so the transcendent-bias is encoded
by the very nucleation of matterii itself to allow for its own emergent
properties, such as the propagation of waves which occurs at all known
levels. iii The forces of immanence can only be accessed through the
“violation of closure” in the process of division, such as the physical
disruption of the atom in the atomic bomb, or the mental omni-directional
shrinking of the frame of reference of conception or perception. It is the
closure itself that allows agglomerative evolution (and mathematics and
philosophy) to begin in the first place, so in any transcending-and-including
evolution, there will be a bias for the initial, properties transcended-and-
included in the foundations of the evolutionary form, or embryogenesis of
the concept. In mathematics, this closure begins, as we will see, with the
formation of the first number, one, the quantum from which all the integers
are made. And in philosophy it begins with the closure of the concept of the
Form, or the Platonic absolutization of the Idea. Just as in reality (at least at
our level) it “begins” with the formation of atoms which can agglomerate
into higher levels of units such as cells, and so on.
The power of intelligence and therefore of transcendence granted to the
agglomerative, evolved organism in sensorially mapping his exterior
transitively, in lines (axes) of direction, encodes the transcendent-bias
directly into the gene-pool of all organisms with sensory functions, as this is
translated into the differential reproductive success that (among other
intelligent properties) drives evolution forward into higher and higher levels
of transcendence.

This transcendent-bias can also be seen in the phenomenon of group-mind.


We have a bias for transcending ourselves and merging into a larger whole
(or holon), and we tend to spurn (at least collectively) the lone individual—
exploring his own infinite differences in immanence—until, perchance, the

i
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
ii
…and number, as we will see.
iii
See Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement in SpinbitZ: Volume II

Page | 95
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

fruits of individual difference make themselves readily apparent to, and


accepted by, the group at large.
The power and bias stemming from this tendency can be startling when
we come face to face with the irrationalities and atrocities that can manifest
when the effect gets magnified and corrupted, such as in cults of personality.
This effect shows up as, for example, the willingness of individuals to do
things for the group that deeply violate their own individual morals, such as
the Nazi effect, and the public ridicule—and even violent ritual murder and
dismemberment—of “unorthodox” and “heretical” geniuses.
The transcendent-bias here can be embodied and called forth readily in
the image of a herd of animals, driven by fear, back to back, fiercely facing
their external enemy, encroaching on all sides.

Acknowledging the transcendent-bias can also be seen as a deep concern in


the Tao te Ching. The polarity in the immanent-transcendent axis is actually
enfolded in the polarity of Yin and Yang. Yin is the female, the inward, the
esoteric, the subtle and hidden forces of immanence, in quiet emergence and
birth. Yang, on the other hand, is the male, the outward, the clear, the
obvious; the active forces of transcendence. When Lao Tzu says, “All things
have their backs to the female and stand facing the male,” he is recognizing
this transcendent-bias. We face the outward, the light and obvious, and
shrink from the inward, the dark, complex and difficult. When he says,
“When male and female combine, all things achieve harmony,” he is
recognizing, among other things, the need to embody (or operationalize) the
immanent/transcendent, yin/yang polarity, and to recognize, optimize and
naturally flow with the forces of each.

This identity of opposites between the immanent and transcendent is a


crucial key to Nondual Rationalism, and it can be seen as a corollary—a
correlating and strengthening strand—to the original Ariadne’s thread, the
Principle of Nondual Rationalism.

Page | 96
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS

Explanation: Immanence and Transcendence form an identity of opposites (a polarity)


wherein, on the immanent-transcendent axis, any immanent form can be seen as
transcendent to deeper forms of Emptiness, and vice versa. This can be seen as a
corollary to the Principle of Nondual Rationalism: Infinite divisibility equals
indivisibility, in that infinite division is essentially inf inite immanence, the infinite
multiplicity of The ALL, whereas absolute indivisibility maps to the transcendent
unitary identity in The ONE. This, we have seen, is directly and simply encoded in the
polarity of yin and yang (immanence and transcendence, respectively).

There are two distinct categories in the epistemic function of


foundationalism: ontological (or causal) and logical. Ontological
foundationalism is the assumption that there is a causal “Ground of Being,” a
“first cause,” upon which all else in the system depends, and which needs no
causal justification in order to maintain or justify an epistemic belief in it,
while logical foundationalism is the assumption that there is a single
foundation of logic, an axiom or set of axioms, upon which an entire system
of logic rests, that likewise needs no justification.
Foundationalism is said to have a pyramidal structure, with a foundation
upon which all else rests. This structure is in contrast mainly to
“coherentism,” i in which all propositions and ideas logically and/or causally
justify each other by the coherence and consistency of the system as a whole.
Coherentism can thus be visualized as a circular or web type structure that
works together as a whole to support and distribute its own ontological and
epistemic weight.

While it is true that Spinoza rendered his system in the geometrical style of
Euclid and Descartes—with a foundation of axioms, propositions and
definitions—the system of concepts itself can take many different types of
rendering. Deleuze’s interpretation of Spinoza demonstrates that, contrary

i
We will discuss both foundationalism and coherentism in much greater depth later. See Trans-
Folding Models of Knowledge and Truth, p629.

Page | 97
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

to the rigid logical, axiomatic structure into which Spinoza rendered his own
system, this same system can also be rendered in a way that is
fundamentally different, and indeed non-foundationalist. Interface
Philosophy take this further and gives Deleuze’s rendering according to his
“logic of expression” a more accessible and explicit depiction in Interface
Epistemology. This will mainly be taken up SpinbitZ: Volume II, but it has
already, and will continue to inform and be worked out in the context of this
work, given the interdependency of ontology and epistemology themselves.
For now a few comments on foundationalism will suffice to set the desired
context of this concept (in relation to the pre-rational regressive infinity, and
the transcendent-bias) for the rest of this volume.
In Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, Deleuze shows that, contrary to
the common academic conception, Spinoza’s system does not begin or rest
on the concept of God or Substance, and therefore it is not necessarily a
logical or ontological foundationalism. In the appendix to the book, Deleuze
gives a schematic breakdown of the Ethics according to his logic of
expression. He states, “These eight propositions [the first ones in the Ethics,
1-8] are not hypothetical but categorical; it is thus false that the Ethics
‘begins’ with God.” He goes on, “Only here [in the propositions 9-14] do we
reach the idea of God as absolutely infinite substance” (p 337).
Indeed, according to the interpretation herein, Spinoza does not begin
logically, or even sequentially with a definition of God or Substance from
which all else follows, and upon which all else logically rests. Rather,
logically, he begins in the middle, with a critical definition of the finite in its
own kind, as that which is limited or surpassed by another modification of
the same kind. It is The Infinite (The Absolute), or Substance/God, which
hinges or turns on this definition of the finite, the mode, or the relative, as
that which is not limited by anything else.
Spinoza ultimately sets up a polarity, defining the infinite or
Substance/God (our absolute scope) as the identical-opposite of the finite
(our relative scope), i.e. that concept which is unlimited, independent and
unsurpassed by another deeper cause because it was explicitly defined as
the identical-opposite, the context of Emptiness, for the relative scope itself.
Indeed, Deleuze also shows how, with univocity, substance “turns around
the modes,” giving what we are demonstrating herein as a true polarity
(between the absolute and relative scopes, essentially, similar to Nagarjunan
Emptiness and form). Unfortunately, we will not have the time herein to go
much beyond this superficial rendering of Deleuze’s expressionist reading,
though it is resonant throughout, beneath the differences in terminology.
The reaching of substance, in Spinoza, is ultimately attained only in the
abandonment of the immanent representational regress of finite causes,
logical/causal dependency and relativity (the relative scope), to a positive
acknowledgement of the infinite depth of dependent existence itself (the
absolute scope) as the identical-opposite of the finite, or the mode (the

Page | 98
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS

relative scope). Essentially, this is an acknowledgement that the relative


scope of modal existence is meaningless without the absolute scope, and vice
versa; a particularly Nagarjunan realization when framed in this way.
Furthermore, this abandonment of the problem of the infinite regress is a
typically coherentist move. The infinite regress presents no problem for
Spinoza, but rather its very necessity crucially demonstrates the nature of
the relative scope, in conjunction with its identical-opposite in the absolute,
namely that the interface of the finite (relative) and infinite (absolute) gives
rise to the indefinite. This will be explained in much greater depth in our
exploration of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, which is an organizing principle
throughout his Ethics.
This “deep infinity,” i conceived positively and non-regressively, or
acknowledged and affirmed, as the necessary identical-opposite of the finite,
is Spinozan substance, but it is always in a polar arrangement with the
modes, the relative scope—just as Nagarjuna’s absolute (Emptiness) is
always in a polar arrangement with the relative (Form). But, critically, it is
in triune arrangement with the attributes—just as the polarity of Emptiness
and Form can be seen in triune arrangement with the concept of dependent
arising of forms at all levels of Emptiness. Again, this is a crucial pre-echo to
the Triune Infinite that pervades Spinoza’s Ethics.

When we conceive of a fundamental ground of Being, i.e. as a substance,


which at some particular depth, underlies and manifests all modifications or
beings, this is an ontological and causal foundationalism. It is also the
default academic and common visualization of Spinoza’s system, which
accounts for the reason he is so often considered a onto-/logical
foundationalist and, in our age of scientism, a materialist and reductionist. In
the context of the interpretation of Spinoza’s substance as an infinite and
omni-local axis of depth (i.e. immanence and Emptiness), this ground of
Being as substrate is necessarily transcendent to the infinite depths below it,
and hence it is also dependent on them for its own emergence. This level of
substance, causal-substrate or ground of Being is then necessarily a
modification from these deeper levels of immanence (or yin), and not
properly a Substance, in Spinoza’s sense of the word as independent and
non-arising, and hence as Emptiness and absolute scope.
We can see, then, that in this nondual-rational, or trans-rational,
interpretation, Spinoza’s metaphysics is neither a logical nor an ontological
or causal foundationalism. It is often mistaken as such because it does have
an absolute from which the relative unfolds and enfolds, or expresses
through the triads of substance, as Deleuze might say, and to which it is
always dependent in its own arising, but it is always manifesting, or

i
a phrase borrowed from M.C. Escher

Page | 99
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

expressing the absolute and relative in a polar arrangement, as “substance


[also] turns around its modes.”

To the general reader, the positive infinity, or infinite depth opened up by


the process of dependent reasoning (and by the mathematical ratio and the
violation of the closure property) may seem an infinitely deep problem, i.e. a
“disastrous infinite regress,” rather than a sought-for solution. But the
“regress,” in this pre-rational and negative way of conceiving of the infinite,
is a direct function of the backward-looking frame of reference of the default
foundationalist mind-set itself. The idea that we must search the past, or the
inward levels of logical or causal substrates, for an arbitrarily and tacitly
preconceived “ultimate beginning,” is what initiates the regress in the first
place, and if we fail to find our preconceived boundaries (e.g. a ground of
Being) in this regressive operation, it is not a problem for infinity or eternity
itself, but for our failed foundationalist preconceptions.
A positive conception of the infinite regress as also entailing an infinite
progress, a forward-directed emergence and transcendence from infinitely
deep complexity, is a key feature of integrative, non-reductionistic or open-
ended (and non-dual) modern ontologies and epistemologies. Furthermore,
this deep infinity is key to the revolutionary mathematical fields of the
calculus, complexity science and Chaos Theory, and a key feature of fractals.
Indeed, as Leibniz said in 1692—pre-echoing by two hundred years Cantor’s
crucial adoption of an “actual infinite,” and Mandelbrot’s exploration of the
fractal by three hundred years—“I hold that Nature makes frequent use of it
[infinity] everywhere, in order to show more effectively the perfections of its
Author.” And in the burgeoning field of complexity science, indeed we are
finding the infinite in use everywhere, as infinite recursion is essential to
fractal geometry, and Nature herself is increasingly seen to be
fundamentally, and at all observed levels, fractal. We see this now, as well,
in the exciting fields of Self-Similar Cosmology,i and even more so in the
physical models put forth in SpinbitZ: Volume II.

The last century of ontology and epistemology, coupled with the discoveries
of quantum and complexity science, has rendered moot the lingering,
peculiarly medieval, fear of the infinite regress and thrown it into positive
relief. Instead of viewing the problem from the negative point of view of
looking backward or inward to find an origin in space, scale or time, and
fretting when these hypothetical beginnings can’t be found, the problem is
turned on its head. If there are no origins to begin with—in other words, if,
contrary to our tacit predispositions, the universe is eternal and infinite (as
conceived in Buddhist nondual schools of cosmology), in both depth and

i
See Rob Oldershaw’s Self-Similar Cosmological Model, for instance.

Page | 100
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS

span, then the search for an origin is itself a false problem engendered by the
false premise that such an ultimate beginning or ultimate foundation
necessarily exists. The problem of the regress itself is seen to be merely a
projection of a regressive, point of view on the infinite or the unbounded
nature of reality.
This regress, however always occurs from the transcendent perch of the
emergent mind and its generalized, a posteriori, categories of representation.
This is why the transcendent-bias, the infinite regress and foundationalism
always go hand in hand. Falling from the transcendent perch of the mind,
and into the infinite abyss, the transcendent-biased mind can’t see its
regress for what it is. It fails to recognize that it started from transcendence
and emergence in the first place, ignorant of the depth (infinite or not) of its
causes, and that the forces of immanence play a role in its very formation. It
also fails to recognize, therefore, that it is going backward in time and
causation to look for an immanent cause after the fact, and that any ultimate
cause or immanent substrate, will also be transcendent from the deeper
levels on the immanent-transcendent axis. The transcendent-bias then
reappears in the very attempt at absolutization of this immanently located
transcendent plane. The bias then encounters itself and its own necessary
failure in absolutizing the relativity of planes or forms in the Emptiness and
boundlessness of the immanent-transcendent axis.

The epistemological framework for foundational ontologies would counter a


“disastrous regress” by positing a root-level scale or substratum of axiomatic
origin for the higher-level modifications and forms made therefrom. One of
many problems with this scenario, however, is that a medium cannot have
conceivable properties with which to be modified without deeper levels of
complexity and form. As a logical corollary, a foundational level of axioms
cannot be questioned and indeed there can be no logical or epistemological
justification for the existence of those axioms. Hence in foundational models
they are said to be “self-justifying,” which, as scholars seem to generally
agree, is merely a statement of belief that they need no justification, and very
often the foundation-level axioms are far from intuitive or self-evident.
This is intimately related to the foundational dichotomy of the “substance
and bundle views of substance.” Substance views posit that the ontological
foundation (generically called substance) is an amorphous and property-less
substratum in which properties (or modes) inhere, and from this foundation,
patterns, modes and objects, with their attendant properties, can emerge.
Bundle views, on the other hand, posit that such an amorphous substance
without properties is meaningless and that properties themselves are the
only things that are real, having and needing no substance in which they
inhere.

Page | 101
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

Each absolutized view has a damning criticism of the other, each opening
the other to yet another dependent arising, and identity of opposites. The
bundle-view critique of the substance-view can be explained thus;
properties and modifications could not inhere in substance if it had no
inherence properties in the first place. In other words, if substance had no
properties to begin with, such as the property of modifiability, then how
could it ever be modified into patterns, modes, objects and higher-level
properties, in the second-place? Doesn’t modifiability presuppose
properties that can be modified, at the very least generalizable as the
property of modifiability or inherence itself? Isn’t substance, therefore, at
the very least, necessarily pre-modified with the property of modifiability—
whatever that must entail? Conversely, is it really any better to take the
view that there is no substance to reality and that it is all merely bundles of
properties ultimately inhering in … absolute nothingness?
With this dichotomy of opposing and equally bizarre paradoxes in mind,
it is clear that each contains a truth in its critique of the other, as well as a
relative truth in its basic concepts. Therefore, as is usual with controversies
that rage for centuries with brilliant proponents for each side, the truth is
likely somewhere in the middle. This is specifically true in the case of heated
intellectual controversies over competing models each of which has a broad
base of adherents all recognizing some validity to their preferred model.i
A case in point is the “nature v. nurture” debate in which it is now
understood that both sides were correct and that nature and nurture both
play key, indeed symbiogenetic roles in the development of the individual. It
is clear therefore, and we have many historical precedents to spur us on, and
an integral model (Integral Methodological Pluralism) to pull us forward,
into the view that some integration of this useful differentiation between
substance and bundle views is in order.
But what can a “substance-bundle view of substance” look like (to
temporarily retain the cumbersome nomenclature)? And for the logical
aspect, what would an axiomless-axiom look like? A useful clue for resolving
the “substance-bundle” dichotomy can be found in the identity of opposites
and in our Principle of Nondual Rationalism: Infinite divisibility equals
indivisibility.
In nondual philosophies all dichotomies and opposites are symbiogenetic
(to use a more modern and precise vocabulary) or “other-engendering and
other-necessitating.” In other words, neither substance nor its modifications
can exist one without the other. Neither substance nor its bundles
(properties formed from low-level modifications) are foundational, but both
must exist at every conceivable level whether the substance appears

i
Indeed we will come to see this historical pattern of conceptual differentiation, which generates a
highly polarized false-dichotomy, which in turn must finally be integrated into a symbiotic (and
symbiogenetic) conceptual polarity, or indeed a complimentary set of practical axes, or praxes.

Page | 102
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS

continuous and amorphous or not. This is explicitly embodied in the non-


dual notion that form and Emptiness are one, and this is also embodied in
the theosophical notion of a “rootless root.”
In the context of the Principle of Nondual Rationalism, we can see the
bundle views as correlating with infinite division of substance into its
deeper properties, and the bundle views as the assertion that the absolute is
fundamentally indivisible with respect to properties. We saw that in the
case of numbers, this infinite divisibility actually gave rise to the
fundamental indivisibility of the absolute, in that there can be no end to
division and therefore the absolute cannot finally and ultimately be divided.
As an analogy, we can say that because there is, and can be, no final
propertyless substrate, and therefore there are always deeper levels of
modification leading to properties, then substance, at all levels, can have the
property of further modification, or dissolution.
This means that the substance-bundle dichotomy, as should be expected,
is purely a function of the foundational bias in modern thinking, which has
only begun to wind its way out from the abstractions of the ancient
monasteries of nondual practices and the modern ivory towers of academic
epistemology.i Substance views appear correct when we are at a level that
appears amorphous, yet the fact that this amorphousness and morphability
are themselves properties tells us that there are yet deeper levels of
morphology statistically arising as these emergent properties. Conversely,
at this point the bundle view might appear correct if it were not for the
recognition of the absurdity of the assumption that properties (bundles)
could inhere in nothingness, and again that there are always deeper levels of
substance in which these properties inhere, or from which they emerge.
This means that at every level there are necessarily both substance and
bundles, stuff and its properties. And yet again we can see this in the context
of dependent arising, and the identity of opposites.

It must be mentioned that precisely because of this irreconcilable


dichotomy, Substance, for Spinoza, was not defined as matter, or even an
immanent substrate of matter to give “substance,” in the common way of
understanding it, to modifications. The substance in the substance-bundle
view dichotomy is not Spinozistic substance. It is merely an “amorphous

i
This treatment, of course, is only meant to be suggestive of the solution, and in order to rigorously
counter the many objections from academia regarding this clearly “easy fix” for a problem that has
been raging for centuries, I would have to fully explicate the implications and intrinsic connections.
This I plan to do in SpinbitZ, but for now, the suggestion indeed may be all that is needed for some
to grasp the usefulness of the solution and begin to employ it.

Page | 103
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM

aspect”i of matter, not Emptiness and the infinity or boundlessness of


immanence and transcendence at the absolute scope.

But what of an “axiomless-axiom,” as in the category of logical


foundationalism? The pattern should be obvious; the axiomless-axiom is
the logic-version of the rootless-root. The only irreducible axiom of a
system must be the postulated irreducibility itself, and it must be
maintained in “epistemic space,” i.e. with the unambiguous treatment of
these axioms as purely mental constructs, or “orienting generalizations,” as
Ken Wilber might say.
This is essentially Spinoza’s Substance, the positive infinity as the secret
of rationalism, and the single “axiomless-axiom,” which renders Spinoza’s
system a “foundationless-foundationalism,” in that its very foundation is
foundationlessness, or Emptiness, itself, i.e. the absolute scope. This
axiomless-axiom will be expanded in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System
(VCS) as the single (yet non-/omni-local) axis abstractly embodying the
infinite regress itself in positive form taken as an a priori unity, also as an
infinite progress, (depending entirely upon the direction one is “traveling”)
with no beginning nor end (boundaries) in time, scale or space.

i
Note that this “amorphous aspect” is also the definition of the “ether” in Gerald Lebau’s Sorce
Theory

Page | 104
Page | 105
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Nondual Rationalism—as we have seen and will see in much greater detail—
in contrast to modern exoteric rationalism, is already a trans-rationalism.
The esoteric project of rationalism in this book is now in a healthy state of
completion (though, at this page it has yet to unfold in its entirety). And so,
as we will see, through the use of the higher-level—trans-rational and
vision-logic level—Interface Philosophy, the mathematical and philosophical
elements of Nondual Rationalism will unfold in perfect harmony and
operation upon the axis inherent to the rational itself, the
Immanent/Transcendent axis at the core of the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism. Thus, a Nondual Rationalism naturally forms the transcended-
and-included “foundation” for a nondual philosophy, and in this case it forms
the base of trans-rational Interface Philosophy.
In the embryogenesis of this work, these two philosophies unfolded in a
tight symbiogenesis, the interfaces forming a higher-level scaffolding and
perspective from which to see the resolutions to the deeper dualities and
paradoxes. At this point in the game, we have yet to see much of this unfold,
but it will become readily apparent as we progress.

Page | 106
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

Because evolution itself, on its various planes, unfolds from simplicity to


complexity through a process of “multiplication through division” and
“differentiation and integration” (e.g. cellular mitosis from a single cell to an
integrated multicellular organism), the ideal explication of conceptual
categories and orienting generalizations should be, at least in part, a similar
organic process of growth, just as it also occurs in the definition of healthy
development in the integral models of developmental psychology.i This
cellular growth process is a multiplication-through-division whereby a
general conceptual unity or category is broken into a specific, integrated and
functional multiplicity through a recursive differentiate-and-integrate
process.
We have already seen this process in the development of dependent
arising, from the general concept of dependent arising through the more
specific attribute parallelism of Spinoza to the tetra-arising of Ken Wilber.ii
Indeed, we can see this process occurring all the time in conceptual
development. First there is a general concept of organismic development.
Then there is a theoretical distinction made, such as that between nature
and nurture (i.e. genetic vs. conditional/environmental factors). Next,
factions divide up along opposing sides of this line, exploring each option on
its own terms in opposition to the other. This creates a controversy,
dichotomy and dualism that cannot be resolved at this level of factional

i
See the work of Ken Wilber, for an overview.
ii
See From Dependent- to Tetra- Arising: The Conceptual Embryogenesis of AQAL, p560).

Page | 107
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

distinction. Only when we recognize from a higher level that the distinction
itself is important, not any side over the other, can we move forward. And in
this way the original conceptual distinction and differentiation, the new
functional polarity, is integrated into a higher level of functioning as we
move from simplicity to complexity in the embryogenesis of the concept.

A. B.

Figure 3: Embryogenesis of the Concept:


A) A generalized image of cellular differentiation. B) The embryogenesis of the
worm c. elegans.

This ideal process—an embryogenesis of an “orienting generalization


holarchy”—would begin with unity and maximum generality (a single
conceptual cell) and end with an integrated and comprehensive multicellular
conceptual organism. When such a scheme is viewed from the outside—and
this is the function and power of a Vision-Logic Coordinate System—one can
ascend or descend to any level of generality or detail one needs, from
indefinitely detailed multiplicity to simplified conceptual unity. One can
then jump into the system at that level. This would enable people of
virtually all stages of intellectual development to understand the system
naturally at their current preferred level of specificity.
Ideally, this holarchical unfolding begins with a chosen orienting
conceptual holon of abstract unity which is then divided (multiplication
through division) into a polarity. The focus is then placed on the integrating
interface between the two poles of the polarity which manifests the inherent
triunity in all polarity: the interface itself becomes the “cultivated third”i¥ in
the triunity. In some cases, it could go the same for the next levels of
recursion; the conjoined interfaces, integrations and intercourses between


“cultivated third”: a term borrowed from Michel Serres

Page | 108
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

the compartments are given focus and manifest a new integrating level of
further differentiation. Or it could be that the new holons from the first
division, undergo a similar process of differentiation themselves, a holonic
mitosis, and the process repeats.
These two methods, analogous to sex, in the first instance, and mitosis in
the second, would likely be intermixed throughout the developing organism,
depending on the specific natures of the conceptual holons and their
interfaces and relations between other holons. In any case, the previous,
more general conceptual level of description is transcended-and-included by
a more specific and detailed version of itself. Unity differentiates into
polarity which integrates through triunity which differentiates further into
multiplicity, “the ten thousand things” and so on.
The critical point is that ideally, this history would be recorded, or
reconstructed, so that one can see the whole from the outside (the level of
vision-logic, which we will explore shortly) and travel up and down between
levels of description, from general unity to specific multiplicity, because this
orienting and zeroing-in general-to-specific, transcend-and-include
holarchical historical procedure ensures that the ONE is included in
differentiation to the MANY just as the MANY is transcended and integrated
back into the ONE.

This is an idealized description of the evolution of knowledge systems from


simple to complex. “Complexity is but the many faces of simplicity,”i¥ but it
can only unfold this complexity, in such a simple and orderly fashion, near
the root level. At the higher levels, the complexity takes on its own, far more
interesting and critical forms and attractors.
To be sure, these abstracted categories at all levels are designed to fit the
function of the model at hand (the categories and concepts herein are no
exception), and it is indeed arguable (as we have discussed) that properties
themselves cannot exist without the substance already being modified and
complexified (enfolded) at deeper levels, and those properties required for
such complexity and modification can’t arise without deeper levels, ad
infinitum. In other words, ultimate simplicity and unity is ultimate
abstraction in the representational layer of the embryogenesis of the
concept. In reality, Unity is Multiplicity, the ALL is the ONE.

With this ideal embryogenesis of the concept in mind, the delineation of this
conceptual scheme will hopefully unfold in the most natural progression as
it works itself out through the basement level tombs of the pyramid of
complexity.


From Gerald Lebau

Page | 109
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

In retrospect, however, it is interesting to note that this book, while


working along a similar process of the embryogenesis of the concept, was
also simultaneously written inside out, from complex to simple, or from
specific and higher-level to general and fundamental. In the real world, as
individuals, we begin in the middle and work in both directions
simultaneously—differentiating and integrating, transcending-and-including
in both immanent and transcendent directions, and mapping it all out,
transitively and conceptually—creating the future at the same time we
reconstruct the past, in this embryogenesis of the concept.
As I progressed in my differentiating-and-integrating of the details, I
moved nearer and nearer to the most fundamental guiding concepts and
principles of the whole. There is as much “rhizomatic writing,” as Deleuze
puts it, or sprawling, nonlinear, tangential “lines of flight” as there is a tree-
like hierarchy in the actual embryogenesis of this work. This is why this
book has been so difficult to write. So much of it does not fit into a linear
hierarchy of importance. It is all extensively interdependent so that the
concepts introduced first inevitably end up lacking in the much needed
context that must wait until later down the line.
Indeed, much of this work was culled from a much larger and far more
sprawling work (simply titled SpinbitZ), essentially an unpublished 600
page collection of notes. By the end of writing this sprawling complex I had
found the root level distinctions and concepts needed to make much more
sense of the whole thing. Much of this work herein, is then effectively
turning much of that immanently directed process inside out and beginning
where I ended in my research, remapping, infusing and integrating those
fundamental final elements throughout the whole, in part through the use of
the EOTC.

Page | 110
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

This is the simplest, most abstract and general level of conceptual


orientation. The absolute level of Unity is purely abstract, enfolding all
possible descriptions and polar conceptions. Because it is the indivisible
essence of everything and beyond or prior to polarity, all adjectives and
analogies apply to it equally and therefore none have any conceptual
differential advantage over any other. That is why the absolute is ineffable.
This is also why some people choose to call the absolute ‘conscious,’ or
‘intelligent’ or ‘living,’ and others not. All and none of these adjectives apply
simultaneously, because all of their identical-opposites are also necessarily
enfolded at the absolute scope.
In the embryogenesis of the concept, absolute Unity is not the ultimate
ground of Being, but merely the simplest, most general level of description
available that conveys, contains, or exfoliates the desired message,
resonance or feeling of the whole. Furthermore, in the representational
level of the embryogenesis of the concept, Unity is not even the
chronological beginning. It was, and is always, “historically” brought into
being from multiplicity, specifically through the extension of polarity and the
relative scope to its ultimate self-defining end, to find its context-defining
identical-opposite in the absolute.
In the case of this ontological system, however, Unity is nondual: it is “not
two,” and in the same sense that it is “not two,” it is “not one.” Unity is never
without its identical-opposite, multiplicity, in the ALL is ONE; the
representational and the sub-representational.
In Interface Mathematics we will differentiate Unity into two different
kinds, according to the difference in scope, from relative to absolute.i These
two kinds of Unity are then finite “unity” and infinite “Unity,” because finity
and infinity (apeiron) are the mathematical aspects of the relative and
absolute scopes, respectively.
Essentially, the Unity at the absolute scope, is non-quantitative. It is not
one; not a finite “unit” or “unity.” It is rather, the ALL-is-ONE of infinite Unity
and multiplicity, because it enfolds the totality of existence, as a Deleuzian
infinite difference and multiplicity, in a single symbol. There is no other
thing or symbol, at this absolute scope, to give this Unity the operational
context of a number. This is yet another pre-echo of the critical polarity

i
* See, Unity and Nonduality, p239.

Page | 111
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

between infinity and number, essentially the same resonating fundamental


polarity of scope we keep encountering, and which is the essence of
Nagarjunan nonduality. In the quantitative sense, we will encounter it in the
concept of boundary, or finity, in that a number itself is essentially and
necessarily represented as a boundary, in the nondual context of the
boundlessness of Emptiness, or infinity.

Page | 112
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

Alan Watts explained the concept of polarity very simply when he said, “The
axis of opposites is the perception of polarity. The difference between them
is explicit, but the unity is implicit.” We speak (explicate) in terms
(terminals) to make things nice and simple, black and white, but we know
that between black and white there is always at least a little grey on the
edges of vision.i
Mankind breaks into consciousness through the use of sensory, and then
conceptual contrasts: light-dark, hot-cold, sharp-dull, loud-quiet, and so on.
This is the defining feature of the relative scope: one sensation or concept in
relation to the other.

M. C. Escher writes in his essay, White—Gray—Black:


Life is possible only if the senses can perceive contrasts. A “monotonal”
organ sound that is held too long becomes unbearable for the ear, as does,
for the eye, an extended solid-color wall surface or even a cloudless sky
(when we are lying on our backs and see neither sun nor horizon). It
seems, so I have been told, that the following torture was practiced by the
people of an ancient culture: the head of a prisoner who was to receive
punishment was tied immovably in place in such a way that his eyes could
not observe anything other than an evenly lit, smooth, white-plastered
wall surface (one can possibly imagine it as being concave).
The sight of that “nothing,” completely lacking in contrast, on which the
eye cannot find a supporting or resting point (as a result of which an
awareness of the concept of “distance” also disappears), becomes in time
unbearable and leads to insanity, since our willpower isn’t strong enough
to keep our eyes closed continuously.
Isn’t it fascinating to realize that no image, no form, not even a shade
or color, “exists” on its own; that among everything that’s visually
observable we can refer only to relationships and to contrasts? If one
quantity cannot be compared with another, then no quantity exists. There
is no “black” on its own, or “white” either. They only manifest themselves
together and by means of each other. We only assign them a value by
comparing them with each other.

i
…or if one is lucky, always in the center of it.

Page | 113
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

This passage brings to mind my own experience, albeit self-imposed, with


sensory uniformity. I sleep to a background of white-noise; painstakingly
searching the radio-waves for a reliably dead channel. In a sense it is
“turning up the silence,” as I crank up the “noise floor,” to drown out the
distracting sounds around me. Occasionally—when I would enter a certain
entheogenic, contemplative state—as my brain tried to grasp and make
sense of the uniformity—interfacing my mind with this rather loud
homogeneous and smooth “floor,” or “wall” of noise—I would experience the
most complex and beautiful soundscapes. It sounded and felt as if I were
inside a battle arena for helicopters and weed-eaters spinning and whipping
their whooshing and humming threads and blades around my head in fractal
patterns, surrounding, infusing and fabricating a vastly intricate auditory
space; creating it all out of the reactionary “thin air” of the brain’s attempt to
deal with—to relate to—unrelenting uniformity, homogeneity and
immanent Unity.
This self-imposed auditory insanity was indeed breathtakingly and
frighteningly beautiful, but if I did not will it into action myself and release
myself into this monstrous and powerful state of mind, I can certainly
imagine the torturous mental state that could ensue.

Polarity is one of the most, simple, pervasive, powerful and critical concepts
to become aware of. It can be seen virtually everywhere in thought and
nature at the most rudimentary and fundamental levels. Observation itself
functions on polarity in multiple ways. The nerve cell either fires or not and
all perception is, at the basis, contrast dependent. Perception breaks into
subtleties as it matures, certainly, similar in this way to the embryogenesis
of the concept, but in the beginning it is fundamentally polar, and retains a
strong element of polarity throughout its course.
We cannot function without differences and extremes. In thought and
language, pairs of opposites are ubiquitous. And for pinning down a
distinction they are as indispensable as an opposable thumb. As powerful as
they are, however, they can easily be abused through ignorant and/or
dishonest manipulation, such as in a bait and switch, or in the very common
rhetorical and political divide-and-conquer devise of the false-dilemma.

Page | 114
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

At every polarity there is a boundary, an interface. This accounts for the


psychological power of the number three. It gives resolution to duality in
the recognition of unity in polarity. These interfaces exist everywhere there
is a gradient, and that is indeed everywhere at some perceivable level—e.g.
the markedly different properties of the surface of water as opposed to its
depths and the air above it; the present as interface between the past and
the future (memory and anticipation); the human as interface between the
animal and the divine, as a recognition of the gradient between the origins
and potential (the current stage as a “developmental interface”) of humanity;
the triunity in the dialectic (thesis, antithesis and synthesis). And Ken
Wilber’s “pre-trans fallacy” is a perfect example of the codification of this
realization into a cognitive tool for straddling any developmental interface
and triuning its polarity.
In The Two Hands of God, Alan Watts gives a good illustration of the
triunity of polarity:
[Polarity] is something much more than simple duality or opposition. For
to say that opposites are polar is to say much more than that they are far
apart: it is to say that they are related and joined—that they are the
terms, ends, or extremities of a single whole. Polar opposites are
therefore inseparable opposites, like the poles of the earth or of a magnet,
or the ends of a stick or the faces of a coin. Though what lies between the
poles is more substantial than the poles themselves—since they are the
abstract “terms” rather than the concrete body—nevertheless man thinks
in terms and therefore divides in thought what is undivided in nature. To
think is to categorize, to sort experience into classes and intellectual
pigeonholes. It is thus that, from the standpoint of thought, the all-
important question is ever, “Is it this, or is it that?” Is the experience
inside, or is it outside? By answering such questions we describe and
explain the world; we make it explicit. But implicitly, in nature herself,
there are no classes. We drop these intellectual nets and boxes upon the
world as we weave the imaginary lines of latitude and longitude upon the
face of the earth and the, likewise imaginary, firmament of the stars. It is
thus the imaginary, abstract, and conceptual character of these divisions
which renders them polar. The importance of a box for thought is that the
inside is different from the outside. But in nature the walls of a box are
what the inside and the outside have in common (p49-50).

Page | 115
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

The phrase, “the walls of a box are what the inside and the outside have in
common,” brings us to the triunity in polarity. In the following diagram I
have emphasized the triuning Emptiness of polarity in the ancient Chinese
Yin/Yang (see, Figure 4, below), showing the walls of the box of this ancient
“Diagram of the Supreme Ultimate.”i¥

Figure 4: The Yin-Yang of Emptiness and


Form:
The values of the polarity have been
removed so we can focus on the triuning
interface between the poles; walls or
interfaces without which the opposites
couldn’t emerge and persist. And thus
arises another polarity, that between the
original polarity, now seen as the white
space, and the interface itself, the black
lines which divide it, i.e. Emptiness and
Form.

Between all poles there is an interface and beneath all interactions there is
deeper ground of Being. This triunity can be seen in the “lazy eight” infinity
symbol below, where each lobe is formed from the continuation of the curve
of the other and both are unified through the one curve passing between
them, (see Figure 5, below).
The Escher drawing with the infinity sign presented as a mobius strip
shows more clearly the duality of finite unity, and inversely, the unity of
finite duality.ii* The single circular strip can be twisted in such a way that
the distinction between the inside and outside dissolves, revealing it for the
relative division that it always was.


<http://www.hartford-hwp.com/archives/55/069.html>
ii
* See Finite Unity: “Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two”, p246.

Page | 116
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

A.

B.

C.

Figure 5: Polarity:
A) The infinity sign. B) Escher Drawing “Mobius Strip II.” C) The lower half of a
diagram from Buckminster Fuller’s Synergetics, originally illustrating the polar concept
of involution and evolution.

In The Joyous Cosmology, Alan Watts says:


The principle is that all dualities and opposites are not disjoined but
polar; they do not encounter and confront one another from afar; they
exfoliate from a common center. Ordinary thinking conceals polarity and
relativity because it employs terms, the terminals or ends, the poles,
neglecting what lies between them. The difference of front and back, to be
and not to be, hides their unity and mutuality.
It is thus when anyone draws attention to the implicit unity of polar
opposites we feel something of a shock. For the foundations of thought
are shaken by the suspicion that experiences and values which we had
believed to be contrary and distinct are, after all, aspects of the same
thing....( p49-50)

This is the identity of opposites, which has been implicitly in operation


throughout the text so far, and which is key to Nondual Rationalism. Indeed,
Page | 117
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

from this analysis of polarity and the identity of opposites, we can draw
another thread from a resonance with our original Principle of Nondual
Rationalism, to entwine in our Ariadne’s Cable, leading us out of
(transcending-and-including) the labyrinth of the continuum.

Explanation: Given the identity of opposites, any term (or terminal of a polarity) whose
identical-opposite is neglected when taken to the absolute scope , will rebound, reflect
or refract into its identical-opposite. This is because the absolute scope is ineffable
and the very opposite of relation. Terms, concepts and other relations, have no
function at the absolute scope, and the identity of opposites always re veals itself when
taken to extremes.

We have already seen the PAR in action in Chord 1, the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism, “Infinite Division Equals Indivisibility,” because the concept of
divisibility (neglecting to include its identical-opposite of indivisibility),
when taken at the absolute scope (whose quantitative property is infinity),
“necessitates that there can be no fundamental or absolute division because
there will always be a deeper level of divisibility, and hence, infinite
divisibility necessitates that the absolute is fundamentally indivisible.” In
this way, divisibility, taken to its absolute scope, becomes indivisibility,
enacting our Principle of Absolute Reversal, because infinity is boundless.
See the example below which will help make sense of both the Principle of
Nondual Rationalism and the Principle of Absolute Reversal, and note also
how it resonates with our Principle of Immanence in Transcendence.

We can find a simple Zenonian and Parmenidean example of this principle in


action in the current state of fundamental physics. Physics has long been
operating on what I call a “solid-bias” intrinsic to human evolutionary
thought (this will be detailed in SpinbitZ: Volume II), where solidity is
generally opted for by the lowest common denominator, the “forces of
representation” operating in human thought and communication. This

Page | 118
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

conceptual/representational preference for solidity over fluidity is due to


the simplicity (the lack of internal moving parts) of solidity, and due also to
our evolutionary formative feedback with solids, as “man the tool-maker.”
Furthermore, Science, with its premature abandonment of rationalism, and
indeed metaphysics, in the enlightenment, has gotten stuck in a medieval
foundationalist outlook, always looking for the smallest, simplest, most
“fundamental particle” (foundational solid), the absolute “building blocks” of
existence.
This is the ancient Greek atomos, the “uncuttable” ultimate solid
constituent of reality, floating, bouncing and colliding in the (existing)
nonexistence of the void.i After the uncuttable “a-tomoi” were apparently
discovered, and then surprisingly (to some) turned out to be “cuttable” after
all, physics continued its search for the final uncuttable solid building blocks.
To this end, the standard model of particle physics has reduced all of reality
to a growing “particle zoo” of mathematical solids known as “point-
particles.”
Nonduality, however—not to mention the ultimate quest of modern
unification theories in physics—necessitates that ALL is fundamentally ONE
“substance”—a unified field. It is commonly assumed that a foundational
atom-void, particle-based model is a postulation of a single substance—that
stuff which makes up the a-tomoi—but this is incorrect. The atom-void is a
tacit polarity between two substances with opposing absolutized (yet
minimally inter-expressive) properties; the solidity of particles and the
fluidity or non-solidity of amorphous space (such as air), the uncuttable and
the infinitely cuttable, and ultimately between thingness (form) and no-
thingness (Emptiness). Perhaps it is tacitly assumed that since nothingness
does not exist then to postulate its existence (?) as space or the void, in
addition to the fractured somethingness or substance of the atomos, is still
to assume a singular substance—the atomos. But since this nothingness
(this now existing non-existence of the real void), is what defines the limits
of the myriad atomic somethingnesses, then this nothingness plays a causal
role in the very identity of the atoms as well as providing the causal context
for the atoms, the field of interaction and inter-expression of the “laws of
motion”. The existing non-existence of the void, the Emptiness, in a sense,
limits, forms and cuts the uncuttable substance of the atomos into its
fractured multiple identity.
These esoteric considerations aside, due to the constant feedback or
interface of science with empirical reality, this absolutely uncuttable atomos

i
Most rational physicists have come to understand that space, or the vacuum, is not void but rather
teeming with an abstraction called “energy” which simply means “the ability to do work.” But since
Einstein's initial and self-confessed premature reaction was to throw away the term (a)ether as
denoting the substantial aspect of the vacuum, now the term is anathema and we must speak in
abstractions like “energy”.

Page | 119
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

(taking form, solidity and indivisibility to the absolute scope) has been cut so
much by the intervening nothingness (in the minds of the physicists) that
the original Greek a-tomoi are now extensionless points existing in a sea of
nothingness. This is the “infinite smallness” of the mathematical point, the
absolutized relativity of somethingness and form down to the absolute
immanent size of nothingness. Having no extension, they are, fundamentally
uncuttable. They take up no space and have no diameter to halve.
So we already see that Form, when taken to the absolute scope, the
infinity of infinite smallness, becomes the non-form of Emptiness. And we
can see that this is a resonance of our Principle of Nondual Rationalism, that
the infinite divisibility in the foundational search for the “fundamental
particle,” the inverse-ultimate form, has ended in the non-particle, the non-
form of the mathematical point—the implicit singularity of Emptiness.
In other words, since the size of these point particles is zero, this
nothingness of “empty space” is effectively divided by merely another
sizeless nothingness—the idea of form which has lost its size and extension,
and indeed its existence in either the imagination or reality. The
absolutized somethingness of physics is dually-described yet
ultimately a single infinite nothingness. Taking somethingness and Form
to the absolute scope has rebounded, reflected or refracted through the
ineffable absolute to return its identical-opposite, Emptiness. And, as a
corollary, a solid has reflected off the absolute in the form of a fluid: The
Inverse Unified Field.

It is quite an interesting time in history that modern Physics has reached the
EXACT inverse of the truth necessitated by the metaphysics of causality and
esoteric science. By abandoning rational philosophy, with its irreducible
nondual aspect of extension, the physicists have “somehow” (ad hoc and
acausally) reached the simple axiomatic level of the Inverse Unified Field, or
a “unified nothingness,” which is now only describable by similarly causally-
empty and abstract entities such as “space-time,” “extra-dimensions,”
“probabilities,” “randomness,” and “uncertainty,” because nothingness—
whether pseudo-extended as an existing nonexistence, a void, or non-
extended as a point-particle—does not, and cannot ‘possess’ real properties
or causality. This logically-derived unity (inverted or not) is ironically quite
an accomplishment and a testament to the self-correcting power of
empirical mathematics, driven by a medieval foundationalism, and operating
on blind (acausal) quantitative logic in the face of human misconception and
misinterpretation.i

i
The unconscious metaphysical inversion of substance into its opposite, the void, with its
incompatibilities and nonfunctional paradoxes shows directly that physics is incorrect at the very
core of its reductionist paradigm, the solid-/particle-bias. When the model finally becomes too top-
heavy, with its umpteen-dimensional, semantically void, space-time knots leading to ultimate

Page | 120
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

A common way to tell if this Principle of Absolute Reversal is in need of


invoking, is with the use of the terms ‘pure,’ ‘infinite’ or ‘eternal,’ (or with
similar extremes) especially in ontological, metaphysical or epistemological
contexts. According to the PAR, equating the absolute with the pure state of
any aspect, such as “pure consciousness,” one must also take its identical-
opposite, or at least qualify this purity as not invoking an absolute stance. So
if the absolute is pure consciousness, it is at the same time pure
unconsciousness, because one pole cannot exist without the other and the
absolute transcends, includes and exfoliates all polarities.
This can be seen in the concept of locality. When we take the absolute
negation of locality, the assumption is that we reach non-locality. But non-
locality can be seen as the identical-opposite of omni-locality. Indeed, they
share the same aspect of formlessness. Locality itself necessitates the
separation of one locality at the exclusion of the others. When you remove
that locality, you end up in the same place as when you add everything
negated: Formlessness, or Emptiness. (Note the resonance here with the
Inverse Unified Field.)
Likewise, “infinite freedom,” as infinite anything, is to limit the unlimited
(the absolute), by a concept (the relative). The infinite is ineffable,
unrelatable, yet infinitely relatable, because it both unfolds and enfolds all
poles, term-inals and relations. This is why we fall into conundrum when we
place concepts at the infinite, absolute level. The absolute is not a concept,
such as freedom or causation.
By the Taoist identity of opposites and its extension into the PAR, if you
place one opposite at the absolute level, you must place its opposite there as
well. Thus infinite freedom must equal infinite causation, and vice versa.
This ancient operation in the identity of opposites may indeed be the source
and resolution of all our cherished paradoxes. We will see the above as a
pre-echo in the concept “Infinite determinism equals indeterminism,” yet
another resonant strand in our Ariadne’s Cable of Nondual Rationalism.i

The above interface with the Principle of Absolute Reversal and the absolute
and relative aspects of locality, provides a nice illustration of a recurring
aspect of the interface between the absolute and relative scopes. Generally it

incomprehensibility, then the whole thing will flip right-side up again in the true nature of a
scientific REVOLUTION. See SpinbitZ: Volume II.
i
* See Principle 1: Chord 1: The Fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism (PNDR), p84.

Page | 121
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

is the case that when a relative concept is taken to the absolute scope of the
ALL-ONE or omni, its meaning is effectively negated. This can be readily
seen with the relative concept of number taken to the quantitative or
multiple aspect of the absolute scope, i.e. infinity. This generally results in
the common subtle oxymoron “infinitely many,” or an infinite number.
Spinoza intuitively recognized the common con-fusion of this intrinsic
polarity and preferred the term “numberless” rather than an infinite number
or infinitely many. Infinity, in this sense, is therefore the dissolution of the
boundary of number itself. It is the logical Emptiness of the relative world of
quantitative form. And so taking number to the omni of infinity turns it into
the non of the numberless or boundless.
The omni-non is the binary logic aspect of the interface of the absolute
and relative. This common absolute-inversion from the ONE-ALL to the non,
is the intuitive source and inspiration, I believe, of Leibniz’s cosmic
fascination with binary logic, leading to the invention of our modern
computational infrastructure.

Laplace wrote:
Leibniz saw in his binary arithmetic the image of Creation. ... He imagined
the Unity represented God, and Zero the void; that the Supreme Being
drew all beings from the void, just as unity and zero express all numbers
in his system of numeration. This conception was so pleasing to Leibniz
that he communicated it to the Jesuit, Grimaldi, president of the Chinese
tribunal for mathematics, in the hope that this emblem of creation would
convert the Emperor of China, who was very fond of the sciences ...
This polarity (which he saw in the emblem of polarity itself, the yin-yang
symbol) between Unity and the void is that between the fullness and
emptiness conceptions of the absolute; in nondual philosophy it is generally
held that Emptiness is fullness and vice versa, as one. The void, Leibniz
speaks of, however, is the immanent infinity of the rational zero, not the pre-
rational concept of zero as negation, or immanence as regression.i* Indeed,
the axis of the Rational numbers as well as the positive infinity of
philosophical rationality, as we will see, has an implicit binary form, toggling
between the origin-identity at one and the immanent infinity at zero. His
idea, therefore, that “the Supreme Being drew all beings from the void” is
echoed in our Cycle of Unity, where the 1 of finite unity is the interface
(solidus/vinculum) of the I/T uni-axis of the ONE-one. (This will make sense
only after absorbing the context of the appropriate section,ii* or upon
reading this the second time. Such are the compromises imposed from the
linearity of language.) Furthermore, this is the creation of the first unit-

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 122
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT

closure and primitive number 1 of pre-rational mathematics, from the ONE


to the interface of the monadic one.
Often, therefore, to make this aspect of the absolute-relative interface
explicit, it will be invoked with the term ‘omni-non,’ as in omni-non-locality
or omni-non-directionality. We saw already how the idea of omni-locality is
essentially identical with the idea of non-locality, given that a location
necessitates a separation and exclusion from other locations which both the
omni- and non- view negate. In other words, locality is an implicit polarity,
and when this polarity is violated in either omni- or non- directions
(affirmative or negative, respectively), we pass through the PAR and reach
the identity of opposites underlying the concept as a whole. The omni-non
simply recognizes the identity between the omni and the non at the absolute
scope.

As Ken Wilber shows, with his pre-trans fallacy—and as I have found


repeatedly in my search for understanding—at the transition points
between levels in the transcending-and-including holarchy of the
embryogenesis of ideas, confusions can arise by failing to take into account a
distinction in operation unconsciously at a deeper level. These deeper-level,
implicit, or “pre-fused” differentiations, are easily equivocated across or
conflated, causing constant confusion in their higher-level discussions. At
the interfaces of conceptual embryogenesis, then, confusions arise by the
conflation of prefused distinctions. This specific kind of confusion will be
denoted by the hyphenated term, con-fusion, so that we can draw them out
more clearly as they arise. It is important to note also that one of the most
common con-fusions in intellectual discourse is between the pre-rational
and dualistic prefused distinction of the absolute and the relative scopes.
We’ll continue to see this in action, as we proceed to reconcile the past with
the emergence of Nondual Rationalism.

Page | 123
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Page | 124
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

Weaving a luminous tapestry from the ideas of ancient and modern


philosophers; from the science of perception; from the art-work of children;
and from scientific writings in physics and astronomy—Rudolf Arnheim’s
researchi demonstrates that thinking itself (not merely visual experiences or
thinking about art, for example) is inherently perceptual. This is convergent
with the modern conception of evolutionary development and
embryogenesis, ii as a transcend-and-include process, where the more
primitive forms and functions, such as the senses found in the lower
animals; sight, sound, taste, touch, and even the internal senses of the
emotions, iii etc, are not merely transcended, but also included in the
operations of the higher cognitive functions and rationality. Indeed, without
sensation, and the memory functions (i.e. “mnemonic primitives”) encoded
therefrom in the symbiogenesis of subjectivity and objectivity, there could
be no higher levels of conceptualization in human cognition.

i
See Arnheim’s Visual Thinking, for example.
ii
Transcension-and-inclusion can also be seen as implicit in Haeckel’s “biogenetic law,” “ontogeny
recapitulates phylogeny,” which says that the ontogeny, or embryogenesis of an individual
organism, recapitulates, or transcends-and-includes, its phylogeny, or its entire evolutionary history.
iii
emotions being an inner form of sensation, as described by the neuroscientist Antonio Damasio

Page | 125
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Arnheim shows that the modern dichotomy between thinking and


“seeing,” between reasoning and perceiving and between concept and
percept, is patently false and deeply misleading and that even the
fundamental mechanisms at work in the visual cortex involve processes
typical of reasoning, such as the spontaneous distinction, comparison and
sorting into the various categories of shapes, objects and effects in the visual
field. Far from being merely a “lower” function, our
perceptual/emotive/intuitive infrastructure—directly encoded with
rationality through the intelligence of evolution interfacing with empirical
reality—is the fundamental means by which we organize events, originate
concepts and evolve our languages. Words themselves invoke perceptual,
sensorial or emotive effects,i to the extent that they “make sense” at all to us.
If we can’t perceive it sensorially, intuitively or at least emotively (or even
through the encoded memories of motor sensations), then we indeed find it
difficult, if not impossible, to understand and really communicate. It is
surely no coincidence that perceptual roots infuse our terms for
understanding: “I see,” “what a true visionary!” “ahh, that makes sense,”
“becoming enlightened,” “a bright individual,” “a sound judgment,” “very
sensible,” etc.

Arnheim sums it up nicely in his Art and Visual Perception: A Psychology of


the Creative Eye:
We have neglected the gift of comprehending things through our senses.
Concept is divorced from percept, and thought moves among
abstractions. Our eyes have been reduced to instruments with which to
identify and to measure; hence, we suffer a paucity of ideas that can be
expressed in images and an incapacity to discover meaning in what we
see. Naturally, we feel lost in the presence of objects that make sense only
to undiluted vision, and we seek refuge in the more familiar medium of
words. … The inborn capacity to understand through the eyes has been
put to sleep and must be reawakened.
Arnheim’s point, contrary to the interpretations of many of his critics, was
not that perception, in itself, was the highest level of cognition,ii but merely
(as the evidence clearly shows) that a training, or even a dabbling, in the
arts—i.e. a “percept-training” where the senses are more effectively
transcended-and-included (integrated) into the higher forms of abstract
thinking—greatly enhances the ability to think conceptually. This is
because, according to Arnheim, there is no real division between percept
and concept. A training in the arts strengthens the very foundation of
concepts themselves, the perceptual infrastructure of the imagination, the

i
…even if diffused over many instances into a vague generality…
ii
Which would be a rather “green-meme,” or holarchy-demolishing interpretation.

Page | 126
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

engine of conceptual creation, which—as Einstein (one of the most creative


of our mythic-scientist heroes) will advocate—is “more important than
knowledge.”i
Some commentators takes issue with Arnheim’s focus on visual
perception, at the expense of other modes. The leading-edge integral
thinkers, however, conclude that the artistic, or aesthetic line is merely one
of many simultaneously important lines of development, or intelligence. It is
not my belief that Arnheim means to exclude the other senses, or
intelligences in his focus on visual perception. It is likely, rather, that he
merely finds vision the most interesting for his tastes, and perhaps the most
useful for his research.
It is indeed well-known that primates, humans included, are primarily
visual creatures (with perhaps more space in the brain actually devoted
directly to visual perception, than any other perceptual modality), as far as
the five or so external senses are concerned. There are good reasons for
this. Vision has an extremely high “sensor density” or parallelism, coupled
with a greater, more precise, aspect of directionality, than any of the other
senses. Vision also has a very accurate near-/mid-range three-dimensional
simultaneous resolution, and an impressive two-dimensional directional-
resolution many light-years into the cosmos, as compared with the next
closest in range, hearing, which is effective, really, only for many miles.
Furthermore, take the retina—with its densely integrated, massively parallel
frequency and intensity detectors (cones and rods, respectively)—and
compare it with the cochlea; its frequency and intensity detectors are not
integrated all together, in parallel, but arranged linearly, single-file, from
lowest to highest frequency along a single spiraling line of cilia-hairs. There
is thus an element of linearity to the audio channels, which is not present in
the video, at least where spatial simultracking is concerned. Of the “five”
senses, therefore, it would appear that vision is the most nonlinear,
massively parallel and sensorially precise for the purpose of “simultracking,”
and interrelating (networking) many spatiotemporal phenomena at once.ii
This unique quality of vision is likely the reason for its inclusion in the
term “vision-logic.” Vision-logic is, in a sense, a meta-vision; it is taking the
“networking” capacity of the visual sense and transposing or transcending-
and-including it at a higher (meta-conceptual) level (e.g. the level of logic) in
the networking of perspectives themselves. This is why it is also called
“network logic.” But with “vision” at the meta-level in “vision-logic,” we are
not excluding, but transcending-and-including the other senses and their
training (and even creative listening or interpreting) modalities in the full

i
There is a bit of ambiguity, however, regarding the distinction between percept and concept which
will be cleared up in the section, Percept and Concept, p617.
ii
The audio sense does, perhaps, a better job of this in the temporal, and emotive realms, but lacks
the resolution in the spatio-temporal.

Page | 127
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

spectrum of the arts. Vision at this level, in a sense, simply means “percept,”
and so, accurately speaking, we might call this a “Percept-Logic Coordinate
System,” though this would lose the unique network connotations that
vision-logic has come to embody.
Vision-logic, therefore—with its integrated concept-percepts—becomes
opposed to “blind-logic,” where “concept is divorced from percept, and
thought moves among [mere] abstractions.” Blind-logic has a limited,
hollowed out, semantic foundation and so it lacks the groundi or medium
within which to move, so to speak. Unable to find a ground within which to
find subtle reconfigurations and variations, it is stuck in a single perspective.
It can’t, therefore, find new modes of “seeing” the whole. Blind-logic
generally lacks the ability to lift itself out of the rooted perspective of mere
words, syntax; it cannot escape the “word-binding” so common to abstract,
sophistic, logic (e.g. lawyer talk) which can “prove” the “truth” of even the
most obvious of absurd conclusions; thought, such as this, easily becomes
“spell-bound” to its surface-level machinations, as does its unwitting
audience.

Because of the above properties—with respect to primate, and especially


human cognition—vision is uniquely suited to enhancing, solidifying and
expanding conceptual and theoretical or cognitive work. This is why we find
the use of diagrams so helpful in academia and industry, such as in scientific
and medical visualization, which can allow the researchers and practitioners
to get a simultaneous, intuitive view of the whole—a new perspective, from
which so many new aspects can come to light. It is also a quick way to
communicate an idea. Audio aids, such as rendering out mathematical or
data curves as audio forms, can give a good feel for such things as temporal
relations, sequencing and harmonics, but they are being used less often than
visual stimuli; animation, imagery and now virtual worlds.
Again, this is not to exclude the other senses, but merely to compare and
contrast their strengths and weaknesses, their lines, as opposed to their
levels, of evolutionary intelligence, as it were. And to be sure, we are
neglecting in this work, as Arnheim has done in his, to build the case for the
other senses; a task which would be extremely valuable for the project of
rationality in general, and for the evolution of knowledge as a whole,
because we know, for example, that some of the greatest theoretical thinkers
were practicing musicians and composers, rather than visual artists. Clearly
the acoustic-temporal-emotive percept-concepts that training in music (or
even intently listening to it) cultivates cannot be underestimated.

~~

i
An instance of the Deleuzian “plane of immanence.”

Page | 128
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

So what is a vision-logic interface? In this model there is a running theme


about polarities and the triune interfaces between them, unifying the
dualities and dichotomies through acknowledging and empowering the
common forces that separate and unite them. But the whole model itself is
an interface between the imagination and the many percept-void “modern,”
“post-modern” and “post-post-modern” abstractions; a sensorial interface
infusing the dichotomies and paradoxes with a deeper context for meaning
and resolution; between the finite and the infinite, between the discrete and
continuous, the local and omni-local, freedom and determinism, etc. A
vision-logic interface is a visceral connection, through imagery (or any other
sense), objects or animation (verbalized or technologically rendered), and
critically, between aperspectival (vision-logic level) logic/insight and the
imagination of the writer and viewer.
The aim of vision-logic interfaces, such as the Vision-Logic Coordinate
System, is to reconnect concept and percept; to reawaken the “eyes” of
modern thought which have been put to sleep by the paucity of sense in
intellectual abstraction; to reinvigorate the anemic, disfigured forces of
imagination in modern intellectual discourse. This is what Buckminster calls
for in his idea of a “return to modelability” in geometry, mathematics and
ultimately science. Indeed Fuller’s oft-used term “conceptuality” explicitly
refers to concept inclusive of percept and the critical, exploratory forces of
the imagination. He says in Synergetics: Explorations in the Geometry of
Thinking [[my comments and emphases]]:
The greatest of all the faculties is the ability of the imagination to
formulate conceptually. … The artist was right all the time. Nature is
conceptual. … Conceptuality requires the generalization of patterns
gleaned from special-case experiences [[percepts]] and thus defines the
basic event experiences that constitute structure. We may think
conceptually of assemblies of triangles or basic, generalized, structural
arrangements that will hold true at either an atomic-nucleus size or a
super-galaxy size, because all angularly defined systems are conceptually
independent of the relative sizes of special-case experiences (section
501).
This was Fuller’s aim, to which we are fully sympathetic: to reconnect the
“cultural chasm” between the humanities and the scientists which C.P. Snow
had earlier identified. The surreal, or lucid artist, Roberto Matta had a
similar direction, intuition and aim to that of Arnheim, Fuller, myself and
others, (if perhaps more intuitive, poetic, nonlinear and difficult to grasp), in
what he calls “morphological psychology.” He says [[my interpretive
attempt and emphases]]:
In the area of consciousness, a morphological psychology would be the
diagram of ideas. It should be conceived before optical images may give
us the form of ideas [[e.g. a meta-system]] if we want to stay in the

Page | 129
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

transforming medium [[the vision-logic level of cognition, open to all


sensorial/conceptual integration]]. The optical image is only a theoretical
section within the morphological fall of the object [[images, in themselves,
are flat or 2d, and only working in a single perceptual mode, vision, in an
ultimately n-dimensional, n-sensorial/-conceptual-synaesthetic mental-
space]]. … Reality is the sequence of the explosive convulsions modeled
in a pulsatile and rotative medium exposed to rhythms. The eye as the
agent of memory [[percepts as “mnemonic primitives” i* ]] is a means to
simplify. … Without a vision from the eye, any representation stays blind.
And the reasoning that follows stays insufficient, impotent.
Terrance McKenna, in an Omni interview, also gives us a poetic rendering,
but focusing more on the possibilities of the evolution of vision-logic and
language (or “vision-language”) itself.ii This DMT-inducediii vision is similar
to ones I have personally experienced, where (as far as is describable in
words) vast meaning, which would normally engulf the thinker in
conceptual complexity, becomes condensed into visual objects outside the
subject. These objects then become capable of a higher level rapid motion,
transformation and assembly into larger and larger integrated concept-
percepts. McKenna says [[my comments]]:
They are teaching something. Theirs is a higher dimensional language
that condenses as a visible syntax. For us, syntax is the structure of
meaning; meaning is something heard or felt. In this world, syntax is
something you see. There, the boundless meanings of language cause it to
overflow the normal audio channels and enter the visual channels [[back
to its powerful sensorial roots and foundations]]. They come bouncing,
hopping toward you, and then it’s like—all this is metaphor; they don’t
have arms—it’s as though they reach into their intestines and offer you
something. They offer you an object so beautiful, so intricately wrought,
so something else that cannot be said in English, that just gazing on this
thing, you realize such an object is impossible. … The object generates
other objects, and it’s all happening in a scene of wild merriment and
confusion.

i
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
ii
See S. Lem’s Imaginary Magnitude, for a fantastic discussion on the possibility of “meta-
languages,” complete with a diagram of a future evolutionary-linguistic scenario.
iii
DMT, or dimethyltryptamine, is classified as an “entheogen,” similar to other drugs that induce
“religious” or mystical visions of a unity (or vast plurality) with God or the cosmos.

Page | 130
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

Deleuze’s concept of “the plane of immanence” describes the distinctive


conceptual, intuitive and semantic foundation underlying each and every
philosophical system. This “plane,” unique for each system, like Arnheim’s
realm of percepts, exists beneath (immanent to) the level of words and
categories, and the words and categories are only mapped a posteriori to this
plane (though they each feed into the evolution of the other). This
connection, between the systemic-map and the plane of immanence,
functions in such a way that two systems can share the same general plane
of immanence (basically semantics) while appearing, at the level of words
(basically syntax), entirely opposed. The superficial difference, in these
cases, is due solely to the respective differences in the mapping of critical
words to the same general plane, and it has caused countless arguments
over what later become seen as purely nominal distinctions, supposing the
participants are lucky enough to see it at all.
Deleuze and Guattari give a tantalizing account of this concept in their
final collaboration, What is Philosophy?.
Concepts are like multiple waves, rising and falling, but the plane of
immanence is the single wave that rolls them up and unrolls them. …
Concepts are the archipelago or skeletal frame, a spinal column rather
than a skull, whereas the plane is the breath that suffuses the separate
parts. Concepts are absolute surfaces or volumes, formless and
fragmentary, whereas the plane is the formless, unlimited absolute,
neither surface nor volume but always fractal. Concepts are concrete
assemblages, like the configurations of a machine, but the plane is the
abstract machine of which these assemblages are the working parts.
Though we could undertake this project using Deleuze’s notion of a plane of
immanence we find this metaphor literally too flat (or transitive) in its
connotations and too simplistic and vague in its conception to function
adequately. Therefore, we transcend-and-include this plane of immanencei
into a Vision-Logic Coordinate System with not only planes of immanence,
but, among other details, an endless axis of immanence, a rootless-root, a
deep infinity, upon which the planes (as transitive modalities) emerge and
submerge, evolve and involve, unfold and enfold.

i
…not to suggest an actual genealogy of the conception itself from Deleuze’s plane of immanence,
but merely a conceptual unfolding for this current explication.

Page | 131
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Though of course it is obvious from the above quote that the plane of
immanence is not really a “plane” at all, but something much more alive and
complex, a “fractal…abstract machine” with “assemblages” and “working
parts,” an embryogenesis, prior to the concept, sub-representation, if you
will. In this sense the VCS is, or includes, the plane of immanence, though as
a service to the concept itself, we abandon the term “plane” in general, and
delineate the working parts, the “anatomy, physiology and embryology,”i of
this abstract machine in more dimensions than a “plane” will connotatively
allow.

i
To quote the first part of Gerald Lebau’s acronym, ANPHEON, “the anatomy, physiology and
embryology of Nature”.

Page | 132
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

“Vision-logic,” a term borrowed from developmental psychology, denotes a


stage in intellectual development, a “meta-vision” whereby one can
transcend the limits of singular perspective and attain an understanding,
simultracking, integrating many perspectives at once, i.e. “integral-
aperspectival.” It is also called “network logic,” in the sense that it can
actually begin to make networks of perspectives; moving among them,
forming comparisons, higher-level systems of inter-perspective translation,
co-operation and conjunction, integrating and transcending.
As Ken Wilber states in A Brief History of Everything, vision-logic is “the
capacity for taking multiple perspectives and then integrating them to some
degree. Unlike formal operational thinking, which tends to be single
perspective, abstract-formal, and monological …, vision-logic is postformal
and ‘integral-aperspectival’ (p191)” A loose analogy can be drawn with the
difference between the limitations of a painter vs. those of a sculptor. The
painter must represent his vision from a single perspective (or a fractured
perspective if he is a cubist), but always onto a flat plane. The sculptor, on
the other hand, can execute his vision in three dimensions, view it from any
angle he wishes and effectively work in them all simultaneously because he
is operating volumetrically rather than merely on a flat plane.
Now expand this analogy further (nearly transforming it beyond
recognition), and imagine that the sculptor can shrink into his own creation
and inhabit the various nooks and crannies and that eventually he settles
down in one location and lives out his long life even perhaps forgetting
about the sculpture as a whole and coming to believe that this one viewpoint
and its visible landscape is the sole design.i
A Vision-Logic Coordinate System serves the function of uprooting such a
provincial inhabitation allowing the territory to again become an object of

i
This is similar to Phillip K. Dick’s conception of God, getting lost in his own creation…and it is
ironically similar to the role of the author, as I am right now lost inside this creation as I create it.

Page | 133
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

perception as a whole in the mind, with the capacity to descend and ascend
at will to see the whole object/system from various vantage points in a
higher-dimensional space. The VCS serves the function of visualizing and
coordinating conceptual relationships (networks) free from a singular
rooted perspective, and at the vision-logic, or integral-aperspectival level of
cognition which, as Ken Wilber states in his A Brief History of Everything,
“synthesizes, integrates, and sees networks” between otherwise opposing
systems, rather than being rooted defensively and offensively within any of
them.
This may seem a daunting and unrealistic task, but it is actually quite
simple, taken step by step. And, with the help of language, we will bootstrap
this conceptual and inter-dimensional space from the 2D frame of this paper
(or computer screen). The flat diagrams and linear text will suggest to the
mind the intuitive, non-linear and aperspectival forms, the plane of
immanence, from which they were derived. These emergent (non-platonic)
forms are to be used loosely, intuitively and organically, as orienting
generalizations from the aperspectival vision-logic level of cognition.

It must be pointed out again, at this point, that in harmony with the
Deleuzean definition of philosophy as an essentially creative act, this system
itself is purely imaginary, and indeed a synthetic and even an aesthetic
creation; a toy demi-mythology; Philosophy as the art and play of the
concept. This system does not claim existence for itself outside the mind or
the paper. As in Buddhism, in this demi-mythology of an imagined world of
ordinary concepts, an enlightened man is more powerful than any of its
would-be gods, and one must always be on the look out for any enslavement
by these concept-gods (platonic forms), as well as ways to transcend them
(negating if necessary, but including if possible).
The system is not conceived as a ‘pure’ platonic form preexisting all
human thought and action that must descend into impure materiality. But it
does indeed map—in the general and abstract way of all maps—a deeper
and vastly more complex emergent territory beyond itself; A dynamic reality
of conceptual attractors, dimensions, drives and motions, pushing and
pulling the mind in these abstract intuited directions which are only mapped
a posteriori, and even empirically, to the artificial geometries (points,
boundaries, axes and planes) and concepts of the system.i These basic
emergent directionalities of thought, can be found in virtually all

i
This is the essence of Deleuze’s conception of Empiricism, an intensely creative and conceptual
endeavor coupled always and ultimately with immanent and causal explanations of emergent and
sensate reality. That is why he considered Spinoza one of the key empiricists, as opposed to
Descartes who imposed his system from the outside, from the limitations of his own mind, rather
than recognizing the limits of the mind to grasp the immanent capabilities of matter to be at one
with mind as aspects, or attributes, of a single immanent causal reality.

Page | 134
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

philosophical systems, and in the hidden structure of mathematics itselfi and


they are essential for the task ahead, as we will see.

i
* See the section on Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.

Page | 135
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

In the embryogenesis of the concept, the ineffable absolute breaks into the
relation of cognitive operation i first in the polarity of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and then in the orthogonal transitive axes. In
this vision-logic meta-system, then, we have only two main “axes,” “vision-
logic axes” or “VL-axes” which are conceptual forms of directionality as a
pre-operational context for the operations of mathematics itself. Because we
have only two VL-axes in mathematics there is an underlying binary form to
mathematics, and it manifests into various cycles between zero and one, as
we will see. These VL-axes are the immanent/transcendent (I/T) and the
transitive, and, as we will see, they correspond roughly to Cantor’s
uncountable and countable infinities.ii* Unlike the axes of the Cartesian
system, the orthogonality between these VL-axes is not really perpendicular,
and the VL-axes are merely forms or concepts of directionality, of motion,
and not necessarily linear, as we will see. They are often, however,
necessarily represented merely “on paper” as linear and perpendicular axes,
such as in the main diagram of the VCS which we will encounter below, and
doing so can be very beneficial, so long as their real nonlinear and non-
rectilinear nature is kept in mind. So the term ‘VL-axis’ can function by
operationalizing a polarity, and invoking the diagram and the differentiating
orthogonality represented therein, rather than forcing the mind to conceive
of each of these directional concepts as uni-directional and perpendicular
linearities. Viewing them as single linear axes would collapse the system to
the merely transitive, as we will see.

i
A conceptual “symmetry breaking”
ii
* See To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox (p432) and its subsections Galileo,
Cantor and the Transfinite (p442), and Back to Zeno (p448).

Page | 136
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

It is best to imagine these VL-axes as being abstracted from the absolute


infinite as mere concepts or “directional aspects” of the infinite (aspect
infinitiesi), rather than constructed from the finite as indefinitely expanding
sequences. These VL-axes, or conceptual directionalities, are roughly and
respectively the singular omni-directional in/out polarity (I/T axis)—the
“axis” opened up in the rational numbers, as we have already seen—and the
infinite uni-directional polarities, often collectively called the “transitive
axis.”ii
The quickest way to verbalize this distinction is through a common
mathematical example which we will explore below. We will start with the
transitive axes (uni-directions, and each one of itself a typical axis) since
they are the most familiar and indeed the birth-place of organized thought in
polarity, opposition and relativity, but it is the immanent/transcendent
omni-directional VL-axis which is primary, before thought and number, and
from which the transitive axes naturally “exfoliate” and find their reference
before mathematical operations can even begin.
The polymath and “visionary” R. Buckminster Fuller, in his Synergetic
Geometry renders in spectacular relief the idea, which Interface
Mathematics expands still further, that the development of mathematics
(from the transitive to the immanent) occurred in reverse order to the
hidden order of the system (from immanent-transcendent to transitive
operation and back to immanent-transcendent). As Bucky relates in his
historic 36 hour lecture, Everything I Know:
I was really so terribly impressed when I was a kid by the fact that
whereas chemistry was always … associating and disassociating in
beautiful, whole rational numbers, physics was always coming out with
irrational numbers. And I felt that what was really causing it was that we
were really using yardsticks that were not the logical yardsticks—that we
came in the attic window and were trying to measure all the rest of the
windows by the attic window or something….But it was a flat earth
anyway so you might as well plan on cubes, and that’s the way to divide
the Universe. The minute you get into the spherical you’re going to realize
that they [the cubes] are not going to work very nice…
It is the immanent-transcendent axis of volumetric, omni-directional, radial
expansion/contraction, we will find, that is essentially the primary axis of
his exquisite geometric, intrinsically rational and trans-“Rational”
dimensioning system, and indeed, the primary VL-axis in the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System and Interface Mathematics and Philosophy.
Fuller followed this notion to its exquisite culmination in his Synergetic
Geometry, which Interface Mathematics effectively serves, among many

i nd
This is the essence of the concept of the “Aspect Infinite,” which is the 2 order infinite, found in
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
True to the Tao, the omni (infinite) is singular and the singular is omni (infinite) — ALL is ONE.

Page | 137
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

other things, as a conceptual bridge and meta-mathematical context for.


Unfortunately the vast details, important benefits and utter beauty of this
fascinating geometrical system will have to remain beyond the scope of this
book.

Picture the sequence of integers on the familiar Cartesian coordinate system.


It extends infinitely up and down the scale, in both positive and negative
directions. Between any two numbers there is always a finite and discrete
(quantized) number of integer coordinates to be found. This intrinsic finity
(boundedness), within an extrinsic or indefinitely extending positive and
negative infinity, is the defining feature of the transitive VL-axis, and it arises
as a function of the inherent quantized and composite uni-linear nature of
this level of the system. This is also what gives the transitive-axis its
“countable” nature, as we will see, as opposed to the uncountability of the
infinity of the Immanent/Transcendent axis.

These are the two main elements of the transitive: its uni-linearity and
its quantized, or discrete nature. Each of the two main elements, uni-
linearity and quantization, alone, is enough to denote the transitive quality.
The transitive axis only gets into continuity when it begins to move into
operation on the immanent-transcendent axis, such as in the real number
line, as we have seen with the labyrinth of the continuum opened up first in
the rational numbers. But it is critical to note that any line is transitive, even
if it has elements within it derived from immanent-transcendent operations.
The Cartesian axes, then, even though they can represent the rational
numbers, are intrinsically transitive-axes, because they are a composite of
linear dimensions.

The category, transitive, includes any of an “infinite number”i of dimensions


as a linear direction, as seen from any possible fixed scale of reference; from
any fixed unit, even if that fixed unit is opened to deeper levels of
immanence by the “violation of the closure property” in the mathematical
ratio. If the axis is linear, it’s transitive, and a single transitive axis is simply
an axis, whereas the transitive-axes taken together are called the transitive-
axis, which is a VL-axis in orthogonal opposition to the
immanent/transcendent VL-axis. However, the VL-axes, used with their
descriptors (e.g. immanent/transcendent or transitive) won’t require the
VL- tag at the beginning, so long as we remember that these are pre-

i
Or “numberless,” as Spinoza might say, to avoid the oxymoronic pitfalls that befall us when thinking
of the infinite in terms of a number, or the finite.

Page | 138
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

operational and pre-mathematical axes, at the vision-logic level of the meta-


paradigm.
The Cartesian coordinate system, is the traditional embodiment of the
transitive axes, but they can be oriented and/or skewed into any single, or
multiple set, of directions imaginable. Thus the transitive axes, each taken
separately, are uni-directional, but they operate within an “omni-
directional” or even a “non-directional” space.i This is in opposition to the
immanent-transcendent axis which, in a sense, IS the omnidirectional, and
indeed the “omnidimensional” space, within which the transitive uni-
directions, or uni-dimensions, operate—exfoliating from, and always in
reference to, a specific location on the I/T axis. This will become much
clearer as we proceed.

In my adolescence, I had an abstract dream of a “disembodied flight” across a


ticking strip of “acoustic ridges,” like a pull-string for interfacing and
accelerating the gear system of a toy car. At every crossing of a ridge of the
strip, I would hear and feel very distinct … TICK … and another … TICK …
TICK, TICK, TICK, |||||||||||||… . As I continued my bodiless travel along this
linear, acoustic and tactile axis of ticking units, the pattern soon became
tedious, monotonous, overwhelming. I quickly developed a trick: I began to
skip units, to expand awareness up and out, and then down and inward, at
will. I began to see patterned regions on the infinite line, places to which I
would jump, connecting and collecting organizations—organisms, forming
and informing an emerging whole.ii
This strange little dream, typical of the abstraction of many of my
oneironauticiii escapades, gave rise to the idea in my early philosophy, of “the
unit as the collapsible scale.” This concept of scales as expanding and
collapsing endlessly to and from their units, “a doorway into the identity of
within and without,” as I called it, was an early anticipation of the concept of

i
…invoking the Principle of Absolute Reversal to invoke the identical opposite, omni=non.
ii
Interestingly, this was also the period in my life when I was experimenting with the interface
between tedium and excitement, or repetition and difference in music.
iii
“Oneirology is the scientific study of dreams. The term comes from the Greek oneiro which means
dream.” An oneironaut, then, is a creative practitioner, or explorer of dreams.

Page | 139
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

the holon, the “part-whole,” which had been invented decades earlier by
Arthur Koestler, but about which I was ignorant. This simple idea—that
every unit is a collapsible and expandable scale, the very environment of
deeper, “collapsed” units, (or every part is a whole) and its corollary that
every scale is collapsible to, or expandable from, a unit (or every whole is a
part)—necessitates an “endless holarchy” of collapsible/expandable unit-
scales.
When reading over my old notes, I found it fascinating that this transition
from the transitive “ticker-line” to the immanent-transcendent holonic axis,
or the “scalaxis,”i as I originally called it, was directly enacted, and indeed
discovered in this simple little dream. In retrospect, it seems but a vivid
reenactment of Zeno’s hypnotic brand of toys—which themselves break into
the fundamental binary VL-axes of conceptual relation—but used as a seed
for my wanderings in the conceptual space of the new biological genome. I
include it here for a nice little diversion into dreamland, perhaps providing a
self-similar historical echo, and a convenient segue; an intuitive bridge from
the transitive to the immanent-transcendent dimensions in an infinite
holarchy of unit-scales.ii

As we have seen in the prolegomena (and in the Principle of Nondual


Rationalism), the Immanent/Transcendent axis is first operationally
accessed in mathematics with the “violation of the closure property” of the
integers in the function of the mathematical ratio culminating in the notion
of a continuous numberline. But it is the evolution of the immanent
operations of the calculus, or perhaps the trans-rational escape into
immanence in the “irrational” (or wholly rational)iii and transcendental
numbers which define the most salient mathematical aspect of nondual-
rational philosophy, as opposed to the transitive, dual/oppositional
(positive-negative) Cartesian coordinate-system, which mirrors the surface-
level, relative-bound, proto-rationality, dualism and transitivity of the
Cartesian philosophy.
As we have also seen, a priori continuity is the essence of the immanent-
transcendent axis, because continuity entails infinite divisibility, and, as
Nondual Rationalism demonstrates, division is the first mathematical
operation on the immanent/transcendent (I/T) axis.iv The I/T axis is, very

i
With the adjective form, ‘scalactic’ having a nice sci-fi ring to it.
ii
One of the motivations for using the term immanent-transcendent axis, rather than ‘scalaxis,’ is
that operationalizing the idea of ‘transcendence’ as a common, and fundamental aspect of reality,
will help bring it “down to earth”, so to speak, and help reconcile the transcendent-bias, and
immanent-transcendent dualism infecting pre-rational modernity (and post-post whatever).
iii
…and here we find yet again a transcendent-bias in that immanent boundless numbers are
“irrational” and transcendental numbers are merely transcendental.
iv
And here we see the age-old dichotomy between the continuous and the discrete embodied as the
distinction between the two conceptual directionalities in the VCS.

Page | 140
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

roughly, the mapping of this immanent and transcendent infinity as a


continuous “axis of scale,” between the omni-directional concepts of “infinite
smallness” (immanence or yin), and “infinite largeness” (transcendence or
yang), neither of which terminate (being infinite and unbounded) at any
final level.
The I/T axis is the axis mundi, or world axis of esoteric philosophy. It is
the axis between the micro and the macro universe. We encounter the I/T
axis and its polarity (as well as the concept of involution and evolution, to be
explored later)i* in the following quote from Plotinus, “there is nothing
transcendent that is not also immanent,” and in this aphorism from
Heraclitus, “The way up is the way down, the way down is the way up.” The
I/T axis has been implicit throughout recorded history in one form or
another. As Karin Verelst demonstrates—in her article Some remarks on the
relation between the microcosmical and macrocosmical instantiations of the
mythological World-Axis—the axis mundi is found virtually throughout all
religions and philosophies of the world. In the trinity of Western religions,
Judaism, Islam and Christianity it is generally symbolized as a tree, such as
the trees of life and good and evil, as well as the Kaballistic Tree of the
Sephiroth. It is also found in the East, in the religions of India, China and
Indochina. In Taoism, for example, it is known as “the door to all wonders,”
and in ancient Mesoamerica it is symbolized in the form of a mountain, for
example the Mayan sacred mountain Mixik Balamil at Zinacantan.
Take the following quote from the Corpus Hermeticum of the 3rd Century,
“God is an intelligible sphere whose center is everywhere and whose
circumference nowhere.”ii And the I/T axis is found in tetrahedral or
systematic-structural form in Buckminster Fuller’s idea of the
“Omnidirectional Halo” which he describes thus, “The difference between
nonconceptual, nonsimultaneous Universe and thinkability is always two
tetrahedra: one as macro, to complete the convex localness outside the
system, and one as micro, to complete the concave localness inside the
system, to add up to finite but nonconceptual Universe.”
It must again be emphasized that despite the linear connotations of the
word “axis,” and the necessary linearity of some of the vision-logic
renderings (or interfaces), the I/T “axis” is not properly conceived as linear
or uni-directional at all, but rather is inherently omnidirectional. The I/T
axis is an axial representation of the unbounded polarity of volumetric, or
geometric expansion or contraction (see Figure 6, below).

i
* See, Evolution is Involution Seen in Reverse, p580.
ii
Notice the modal-centric emphasis on locality, as in the center is everywhere. The law of absolute
reversal requires that this polarity be switched to operationalize its inverse. It then becomes “God is
an intelligible sphere whose center is nowhere and whose circumference everywhere.” It works
from either an inward or an outward perspective.

Page | 141
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Figure 6: The Main VCS Diagram:


This diagram is perhaps the
simplest of the many ways to
represent the distinction between
the immanent and transitive axes,
but it is critical to note that the
diagram flattens the
dimensionality of the transitive
space into planes in order to
represent the I/T axis uni-
directionally. The omni- and non-
directionality of the I/T “axis” is
here drawn, unfortunately but
necessarily, as a linear “axis”
rather than an inherently
volumetric, spherically
coordinated polarity.

In the figure above, the I/T axis is drawn, unfortunately but necessarily, as a
linear, unidirectional, “axis” rather than an omni-directional expansion or
contraction. The transcendent “direction” on this axis zooms outward from
any “position” (fixed volumetric scale) on the I/T axis and the immanent
“direction” zooms inward. The familiar 3-dimensions, xyz and all infinite
uni-directions in-between, have been collapsed—for the sake of higher-level,
aperspectival, visualization—into the transitive plane fixed upon the central
I/T axis. Also note that the orthogonality between these VL-axes is
represented by perpendicularity, which is also entirely misleading.
Perpendicularity is simply the easiest and most direct way to visualize
orthogonality. The orthogonality between these two VL-axes, however, is
best understood as a scale invariance between transitive relations. In other
words, in a system of transitive relations, such as any mathematical
geometry (or self-similarity), if you change the scale itself (changing
coordinates on the I/T axis) the pattern of relations will always remain the
same.
The crucial function of this diagram is to demonstrate the relation
between transitive planes as fixed with respect to specific positions on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, and that these “positions” correlate in this
higher-dimensional interface, not to position itself, but to size or scale. But it

Page | 142
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

is more crucial, when needed, to be able to forget the unfortunate flatness of


the transitive axes and planes, and the linearity of the immanent-
transcendent axis in this rendering. We will see a more accurate rendering
below of this critical distinction which, when used in conjunction, will help
us recall the omni-directionality and continuity of the immanent axis, vs. the
linearity of the transitive and that the transitive axis always functions from a
fixed frame of reference.
The crucial point here is that the transitive axes regularly collapse (or
instantaneously manifest) the immanent/transcendent infinities, as Zeno
demonstrated, otherwise any distance between two points would be infinite,
and the hare could never overtake the tortoise, nor the arrow reach its mark,
since there are an “infinite number” of “infinitely small” intervals to cross
between them.i

The most crucial distinction between the I/T axis and the transitive
polarities is that the I/T axis deals exclusively with a priori volumetric
omni-directionality, inward-and-outward, and the transitive axes are
exclusively unidirectional abstractions, such as the 3 uni-directions
that make up Cartesian coordinate space.

A quick look at coordinates on the I/T and transitive axes will help make the
distinction clear. To aid in representation, we can use an enclosing surface, a
sphere (see Figure 7, below), representing or embodying the particular
volumetric scale. This sphere is a coordinate, on the I/T axis; a fixed scale
which is inherent to (unfolding as) the particular transitive axes,

i
It is clear, however, that an infinitely small distance, were it not a contradiction in terms, would
take zero time to cross, which we will explore in greater detail in Interface Mathematics.

Page | 143
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

represented as a plane on the main VCS diagram (above).i And so even the
rational and continuous numberline, such as that drawn on a Cartesian
graph (or any of the single lines passing through the infinity within the I/T
axis below), is, in a sense, merely a uni-directional, or transitive, cross-
section or rendering of the spherical/omni-directional I/T axis.

Figure 7: The Nuclear VCS Diagram With Coordinates:


This diagram is from Part Two: Interface Mathematics (p202) section later in this book,
so some of the notation may be a bit unfamiliar, but it offers another way of visualizing
the difference between the I/T and transitive axes. The I/T axis repre sents the infinite
omni-directional aspect of scale and the transitive represents the uni -directional axes
of measurable distance.

i
…and as we will see, the sphere is the most general representation of number, in identical
opposition to this same immanent-transcendent axis (the identical opposite of number), The
Infinite.

Page | 144
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

On the immanent-transcendent axis, coordinates (i.e. “positions” on the


representational axis, not necessarily in space itself) denote inherently
spherical or volumetric differences, as degrees of omnidirectional expansion
and contraction, of the “spherical coordinate,” regardless of real-world
position. In other words, the position on the immanent-transcendent axis
does not represent spatial position. It represents scale, denoted by the
variable size of the sphere (see above), which itself is the representation of
the actual coordinate in “immanent-transcendent space.” This “immanent-
transcendent space” (a space of “intensive forces,” as Deleuze might say) is
merely mapped abstractly, as a visual aid, by the linearity of a transitive axis,
as in the main VCS diagram (see Figure 6, two figures above, p143).
This omnidirectional expansion and contraction inherent to the
immanent-transcendent axis, is opposed to the linear, unidirectional
movement from position to position, number to number, on the transitive
axes, where changes in position on the axes correlate, often directly, to
actual changes in space.i
The coordinates on the transitive axes are fundamentally composed of
quantized finite unities or unit-spheres, and merely abstracted as infinitely-
precise positions (implicit singularities) with no volumetric extension
whatsoever. This is very loosely analogous to the difference between scalars
(magnitudes) and vectors (directions), except that scalars are represented
as a function of abstract magnitude and the I/T axis maps the polarity of
volumetric scale itself as magnitude.

The immanent-transcendent axis, can be further analyzed, delineated and


differentiated, into ONE omni-axis which is composed of an “infinite number”
(or the numberless ALL) of uni-axes; this is the univocal ONE-ALL relation, as
we will see.ii* The omni-axis is best demonstrated mathematically as a
“Zenonian binary tree and semi-lattice,” as shown by Karin Verelst in her
paper, Zeno’s Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality, and as
we explore in great depth later.iii* In this paper Verelst demonstrates that
this “simultaneous ‘through and through’ division”—what we are calling the
omni-axis—is identical to Cantor’s uncountable infinite and the cardinality

i
Note that we are not concerned here with the use of transitive axes to represent non-spatial, or
non-physical aspects, at this point, except for the representational use of the transitive-axis to stand
for the immanent-transcendent axis in the main Vision-Logic Coordinate System diagram (two
figures above).
ii
* See, for example, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
iii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 145
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

of the transrational continuum—and thus it is the conceptual incarnation of


our PNDR.
The uni-axis is the I/T axis as we have already seen it in the Nuclear VCS
Diagram above. The uni-axis is always centered on a single position,
whose “infinitely small” Euclidean point is its unbounded immanent pole,
and whose transcendent pole “reaches to” the unreachable transcendent
infinity of the ONE-ALL. The uni-axis, therefore, is always conceived through
the relative aspect of position or finite locality (relative to any other) and,
therefore, ultimately through the “eye” or aperture (boundary or spherical
“yard-stick”) of the transitive unit i.e. the spherical coordinate making up the
linear directionality of the transitive-axis.i* The I/T uni-axis is the immanent
and transcendent, internal and external boundless dimension of this
spherical, a priori-extended unit.ii*
Conversely, the immanent-transcendent omni-axis (or just the “omni-
axis” as we will often call it) enfolds into its concept the labyrinth of the
continuum of extension itself, and all of its “infinitely infinite” positions;
EVERY conceivable and inconceivable, rational and trans-rational location—
each one of which is the immanent pole of a uni-axis. The omni-axis, then,
contains all, or omni-, of the uni-axes. This omni-axis, therefore, “is an
[abstract] sphere whose center is everywhere and whose circumference is
nowhere.”iii
The omni-axis can be seen as the abstracted and generalized essence of
the ancient esoteric anima-mundi (or world soul), with its ONE as ALL,
whereas the uni-axis can perhaps be seen more as the axis-mundi of the I/T
axis in general, with its ONE vs. its one implicit singularity and immanent
pole.

Because the immanent pole of each uni-axis represents an “infinitely small”


Euclidean point, or an implicit “singularity,”iv it is thus the identical opposite
of extension and continuity itself. It is therefore the non-extension of the
abstracted immanent aspect of infinitely precise locality. This is why the
labyrinth of the continuum itself exists, because the continuity aspect cannot

i
* Recall Figure 7: The Nuclear VCS Diagram With Coordinates:, p144.
ii
* See, The Nondual-Rational and Empirical Embryogenesis of Mathematics, p217.
iii
It is also the polarity of Spinoza’s Substance/God, with omnilocal immanence-in-transcendence
equating to Substance, and omni-local transcendence-in-immanence equating to “God.” This last
point takes us far afield, but see Leibnoza Von Spinbitz (p659), to jump the line and explore further.
iv
We are not here using the term ‘singularity’ in its strictly mathematical and operational sense.
Rather, we use the term to highlight the infinity hidden in the “infinitely small” Euclidean point.
Indeed, this implicit infinity is the very source of the immanent infinities (mathematical singularities)
found when physicists of the early twentieth century tried to calculate the energy of an electron—
represented as such a point—as an inverse-squared function of the distance to its center and its
non-existent terminating surface.

Page | 146
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

be formed agglomeratively from its identical opposite in the Euclidean point.


But, as we will see,i* and according to the Principle of Absolute Reversal, the
identical opposite of the extensionless point in the continuum is found by
taking the concept to the ineffable absolute scope, and this is the polarity
enfolded in the uni-axis, i.e. between the immanent point and the
transcendent continuum.
The uni-axis is thus the omni-non of extension with its polarity and
cultivated third between omni-extension in the ONE and the non-extension
of an immanent singularity at one Euclidean point. An interesting feature,
therefore, shared between the infinite I/T uni-axes, and the one omni-axis
which they compose, is that they ALL converge and overlap at the
transcendent pole of the ONE. At the same time, however, the immanent
poles of any two selected uni-axes, at whatever scale you may choose, are
separated by an “infinite number” of other uni-axial singularities (see Figure
8-A below).ii* This recognition—that two points can be “infinitely close”
together and always infinitely far apart, in terms of other points—is one of
those counterintuitive, labyrinthine aspects of the absolute scope of
immanence (or yin) and continuity which Leibniz recognized in his
exploration of the continuum. He reconciled it finally, as we will see, in his
secret “Spinoza studies,” of 1667iii when he acquired Spinoza’s (now famous)
Letter XII on the infinite. At this time, Leibniz began to see mathematical
points not as Euclid saw them, as elements “composing” the continuum, but
the reverse, as Spinoza saw them, essentially as immanent aspects
(singularities) abstracted from The Infinite univocal ONE is ALL.iv*
Identically-opposed to the immanent singular infinity of the I/T uni-axis
is the infinity of singularities of the omni-axis. The omni-axis is the I/T-axis,
and its Euclidean singularity, conceived not as a finite unityv*—or “one”
single uni-axis and abstracted position—but as an infinite totality of uni-
axes, “composing” or a posteriori abstracted from the labyrinth of the a priori
continuum of the undifferentiated absolute scope. Because the omni-axis is
omni-local, it is also non-local, in the sense that it does not differentiate one
uni-axial position from any other, but conceives of them all as an
undifferentiated continuum of loci making up the singular ALL of extension.
To take on ALL positions is to take on none of them and thus the omni of

i
* See Exploring the Univocity Framework, p190.
ii
* This is another aspect of the trans-trans-bias. See The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
iii
As Samuel Levey termed it in his article “Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually Infinite Division
of Matter.”
iv
* For further information, see, for example, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite (p270) and Reconnecting the
Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and the
CalculusReconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence
and the Calculus (p400).
v
* See the related discussion on The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 147
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

position is also its non, as we would expect with the Principle of Absolute
Reversal and the univocal aspects of the absolute scope.i*
The omni-axis is the IT axis whose locality aspect is “seen” (or unseen) at
the absolute scope, through the “eye” of Infinite Unityii* to give us omni-non-
locality.iii Poetically speaking, in the omni-axis, the pupil of the eye of
locality and its boundary is fully and entirely opened, so that the eye itself—
and its limiting/enabling differentiated, boundaries, positions and
perspectives—has actually disappeared in the complete omni-directional
opening of its boundary. This, in part, is the continuity aspect of The Infinite.
The omni-axis is the VCS representation of the ‘ONE-ALL’ tautology and
identity of univocal multiplicity, whereas the uni-axis is merely the locus of
the ‘one’ of “finite unity;” i.e. the immanent singularity and its boundary,
respectively.iv* This distinction between the absolute unbounded ‘ONE’ and
the relative ‘one’ of boundary will be explained in much more detail in the
section on Unity and Nonduality. But it is important to note that both the
uni and omni forms of the immanent-transcendent axis—as all VL-axes of
the Vision-Logic Coordinate System—are mere abstracted aspects of “The
Infinite,” as we will see in the section on Spinoza’s Triune Infinite.v
Recalling the two previous diagrams of the immanent-transcendent axis,
we can simplify, modify and compare them, side by side, to differentiate-
and-integrate the omni- and uni- axes (See Figure 8, below). The interface or
cultivated third of the immanent/transcendent polarity in its omni-non-local
aspect (i.e. the omni-axis), is a transitive “plane,” (see side A of Figure 8,
below). Recall, however, that the image of the plane is a mere convenience,
both of speech and of imagination. For the sake of higher-level,
aperspectival, visualization and simplification of the omni as a uni-
directional axis, the familiar 3-dimensions—xyz and all infinite uni-
directions in-between—have been collapsed into the “transitive” planes
fixed upon the central I/T “axis.” Such transitive planes—“planes of
existence” or “levels of reality” as they are often called in cosmogonic
textsvi—in the real world correspond to the emergent/transcendent, yet
relatively fixed scales (or “Kosmic grooves”) of nature, such as the “Planck

i
* See Exploring the Univocity Framework, p190.
ii
* See Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
iii
… incorporating in the omni-non the identical opposite necessary at the absolute scope…
iv
* See Unity and Nonduality (p239), and The (Binary) Cycle of Unity (p254).
v
The I/T omni-axis is, mathematically-speaking, non-operational, due to its taking on of the
properties of the absolute scope in its omni-/non-locality. In other words, in order to operate
mathematically, one position (ideal point and immanent pole of an I/T axis) from the infinite must
be abstracted and selected so as to construct the first number in Operational Mathematics, the
volumetric boundary (a real-point). We’ll explore this in much more detail later. See for example
Empirical/Experiential Beginnings: Bucky’s “Operational Mathematics” (p217), The (Binary) Cycle of
Unity (p254) and The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation (p306).
vi
See, for example, The Secret Doctrine, by H.P. Blavatsky or Ken Wilber’s Integral model.

Page | 148
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

scale,” the level of atoms and the level of cells. The “transitive plane,”
therefore, is actually a planar cross-section of an infinite volume or extension
whose vastness is defined relatively and transitively to a specified scale
(coordinate on the I/T axis) of a priori volumetric spherical units. Each one
of these nested (holonic) units, however, is the spherical and omni-
directional I/T interface of a single uni-axis.

Page | 149
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

A. B.

Figure 8: The Omni and Uni Axes and Interfaces:


Figure A shows an “expanded view” of the omni axis and the “transitive planes” as the
interfaces of the immanent and transcendent directions in the omni -axis. If we
collapse the representationally expanded planes, again overlapping the spheres making
them concentric, however, we can see that the transcendent direction is not really
upward, or linear, but outward, from all points of the continuum. Each of the
boundless series of nested spheres in the transitive plane of the omni -axis is the
interface of a uni-axis (B) ALL of which are contained in the omni -axis, and each of the
points making up the volumetrically extended continuum of the omni -axis is the
immanent pole or Euclidean singularity of a uni-axis. Note also, that as we move
immanently on the omni axis, the number of uni -axes between any two (and their
spherical interfaces) increases indefinitely, and —at the absolute scope of The Infinite
ONE-ALL—actually is infinite.

Page | 150
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM

At this point an interesting relation has begun to appear between the ALL-
ONE, the omni-non and the aspects of position and extension (or continuity).
The omni-non of position, recall, is the ALL-ONE, or the “omni-uni” of
extension (the omni-axis), and the omni-non of extension is the omni-uni of
position (a single uni-axis between the ALL-ONE and the singularity). This
gives us an interesting polarity between the aspects of position and
extension (or continuity) when taken at the absolute scope of the omni, or
the ALL—which is the infinite multiple aspect of the ONE of Infinite Unity at
which both omni and uni axes converge.i* The aspects of extension and
position, when taken at the absolute scope, appear to be identical opposite of
each other, in this sense. But in quantitative terms, the uni-aspect of the uni-
axis (the one singularity) is finite and the uni-aspect of the omni-axis (the
ONE of ALL uni-axes) is infinite. The quantitative difference between the
uni-aspects of the uni- and omni-axes (i.e. the ‘one’ and the ‘ONE,’
respectively), therefore, presents us with the critical polarity underlying the
Cycle of Unity, as we will see.
While the omni- and uni- axes converge at the transcendent pole, the
interfaces of each are vastly different. The interface of the uni-axis, as we
have seen, is an arbitrarily defined mathematical, or real-world emergent,
spherical/spheroidal boundary, whereas the interface of the omni-axis is an
infinite expanse of a mathematical/metrical or physical substrate; e.g. a
cubic grid or an “isotropic vector matrix” of imaginary or real metric units or
a relatively uniform volumetric expanse of real atoms; a “level of reality,” or
a “plane of existence.” The polarity between the I/T interfaces, therefore,
swings us from the unity of the relative (finite unity) in the unit-interface of
the uni-axis, to the unity of the absolute (Infinite Unity), in the ALL-ONE.
This is key, as we will see, in the Cycle of Unity.

i
* See Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.

Page | 151
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

The tendency when we delineate all of this stuff and break it down into its
subcomponents, with infinite levels of transitive planes exfoliating from an
immanent-transcendent axis (itself composed of two types), is to forget to
put it back together. The immanent-transcendent and transitive axes
ultimately form an orthogonal polarity, a conceptual symbiosis. The first
unit, the number 1, emerges from the uncountable I/T axis as the decided
unit-boundary, the chosen scale of measurement, allowing the transitive
operations of addition and subtraction (and in physical reality,
agglomeration and evolution) to begin. Then, with the operations of
division, the immanent-transcendent axis is again invoked or awakened as
the mathematical ratio dissolves or “violates” the “closure property” and
opens up the immanent pole of the Rational numbers (all of which we will
discuss in detail in Interface Mathematics).
Furthermore, these infinite levels abstracted and represented on the
immanent-transcendent axis, do not necessarily exist somewhere else, in the
erewhon of “mere mathematics,” or in different worlds, but, as SpinbitZ:
volume II will explore in depth, they emerge into every scale as the very
forms of the relative, such as the “ergodic” and fractal complexities of nature
(see Saturn’s rings, for instance that manifest the infinite complexity in its
energy fields, as an instance-definition of ergodic).
With this conceptual framework in mind, our task ahead will be much
simpler because we have made explicit the many implicit, “pre-fused”
differentiations that so often conflate and “con-fuse” these absolute-level
discussions, manifesting in the various paradoxes of the infinite, and of free-
will vs. determinism, for example. We can now cast aside the shells so often
unwittingly employed in the game of philosophy and, perhaps for the first
time, begin to move these symbols around freely, on our conceptual game-
board, in the light of reason.

Page | 152
Page | 153
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Page | 154
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

This section operationalizes the concept of Univocity into a rigorous and


intuitive framework that provides a simple conceptual “space” for open and
honest ontological speculation, maintaining the necessary nondual relativity
of this ontological space and its resident or emergent concepts and relative
truths in polar contrast to the Truth of the absolute scope. This
operationalization of Univocity enacts and softly enforces the principle of
nonduality by explicitly recognizing the fundamental
Nagarjunan/Spinozan/Deleuzian polarity between the absolute and relative
“scopes.”

Univocity is explained by Deleuze as “the idea that all events are compatible;
they are ‘inter-expressive’. Being has one voice but can only express
differences.” And Todd May says, “What univocity implies is not that
everything is the same, or that there is a principle of the same underlying
everything, but, instead, precisely the opposite. With univocity comes
difference, difference for the first time taken seriously in itself.”i¥
Univocity means that every expression of existence is different in a
fundamental sense from every other. And yet the unity aspect of the concept
signifies that these differences are fundamentally causally intercompatable,
or ‘inter-expressive.’ This is the identity of opposites of difference and
similarity, because indeed without this inter-expression or inter-relation,
differences could not interface or relate in order to really differ. And thus,
with univocity, difference (or relativity) is “taken seriously in itself” and
given a framework for actualization and understanding.ii It is this basic, or
“fundamental,” framework, expanded and operationalized herein, upon


(May)
ii
Actualization and understanding are ontic and epistemic respectively. See the section below,
Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity, p176.

Page | 155
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

which any healthy and “holistic,” or integral rationality must be built (in
some form or other), and we have already seen it as the implicit essence of
ancient and esoteric nondual/perennial philosophy,i such as Taoism, Advaita
Vedanta Hinduism, Madhyamaka Buddhism. It is also seen in the West in
some forms and levels of Christianity, Neo-Platonism, esoteric Spinozism,
and in some of the pre-Socratics, such as Heraclitus.
This fundamental “causal” or “expressive” intercompatability of
univocity, giving meaning and truth to relativity (instead of relativity to
Truth), is what Deleuze sees as the core of rational/empirical philosophy as
it winds its way through western History from the Stoics to Duns Scotus to
Spinoza to Leibniz to Nietzsche to Bergson, through Deleuze and beyond.
This univocal relativity, or multiplicity, is the defining essence of Spinoza’s
Substance,ii for instance, as opposed to its common academic intepretation
as a “principle of the same,” or a foundational material substrate, underlying
and unifying everything. And as we have discussed, the re-emerging esoteric
understanding of Spinozism, catalyzed by Deleuze and others, is essentially
nondual and non-foundational.
Nondual Rationalism takes it further, at least explicitly, and shows that
the more coherent understanding of Spinoza’s Substance is ultimately based
not on any foundational “transitive-plane” (substrate) immanent to
observed reality (e.g. Deleuze’s plane of immanence), but rather on the
positive, a priori, and non-regressive notion of deep infinity, which we have
operationalized in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System as the immanent pole
or emphasis of the Immanent/Transcendent axis. It is the identification of
Spinoza’s Substance with the notion of positive infinity in Deleuze, and with
the immanent pole of the immanent/transcendent “axis” herein, that brings
rationalism out of its modern academic exoteric misinterpretation as a
foundationalist formless-absolutism or even a materialism or scientism (or
“eco-philosophy,” as Ken Wilber might put it), and into a nondual,
“foundationless-foundationalism” or a “rootless-rootism,” that re-opens and
re-animates the project of rationalism and sets it on its feet again.
In true rationalism, unshadowed by the reactionary misinterpretations
and pre-rational tendencies (e.g. the transcendent-bias, or the “forces of
representation”), of post-/modernity, the one foundational principle (or

i
Aldous Huxley defines it as “the metaphysic that recognizes a divine Reality substantial to the world
of things and lives and minds; the psychology that finds in the soul something similar to, or even
identical with, divine Reality; the ethic that places man's final end in the knowledge of the immanent
and transcendent Ground of all being; the thing is immemorial and universal. Rudiments of the
perennial philosophy may be found among the traditional lore of primitive peoples in every region
of the world, and in its fully developed forms it has a place in every one of the higher religions” (The
Perennial Philosophy, p. vii).
ii
Throughout this work, I will be using “Substance” rather than “substance,” capitalizing the S to
denote an absolute scope. This can serve as a reminder that we are not talking about a foundational
substrate, but rather the I/T axis itself, if mainly an immanent emphasis.

Page | 156
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

axiom) is that there can be no foundational principles, i.e. that axioms,


principles, truths and laws themselves, are emergent, relative, fallible and
generally epistemic (e.g. Sheldrake’s “habits of Nature”), rather than
absolute, eternal and handed down from a transcendent God to be
implantedi in a fallen Nature (Eve).
This is the axiomless-axiom or foundationless-foundationalism, as we
have seen, and it is basically an epistemological analog the nondual and
univocal ontology.ii*

The defining feature of the nondual is polarity. And, of the ancient


traditions, the most useful nondual tool is the Taoist concept of the identity
of opposites, visually and viscerally embodied in the yin-yang symbol. The
identity of opposites states that in the very heart of any opposite is its other,
without which it would be inert and meaningless. And, as we have
discussed,iii* a polarity is the equivalent of a conceptual opposable thumb.
Without the use of polarity, the conceptual “opposable thumb,” the mind
finds it virtually impossible to “grasp” ideas or concepts: it can’t relate.
In the univocal context, opposites or polarities, as the simplest, most
general forms of difference, are fundamentally inter-expressive. They share
a unity in this one voice, where “divergence is affirmed and disjunction
becomes a positive synthesis…[and] all events, even contraries, are
compatible.”iv¥
This triune nature of the interface in polarity we have discussed is
inherent in the principle of univocity. In the same way that insides can have
no meaning or expression without outsides, so the relative scope can have
no meaning or expression without the absolute ... and vice versa. The
identity of opposites (or dependent arising) is the univocal “quantum
tunneling” between opposed numerical identities (absolutized concepts)
revealing the infinite axis of difference within (e.g. Emptiness). These are
the immanent forces of intensity characteristic of univocity, which dissolve
and support the representational surface-forces of opposition (see Univocity
and Force, p170, below).
Nondual traditions take this principle of polarity at the absolute scope
(albeit tacitly) and use it to break the bonds of single-concept absolutisms,
terms as terminals, or “mono-poles” (e.g. materialism and idealism), that
unceasingly attempt to “mono-polize” the infinite and eternal enfolding and

i
(((or artificially inseminated)))
ii
* See also the section Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity, p176.
iii
* See the previous section Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind, p112.
iv¥
Logic of Sense, 177 qtd in Widder’s Genealogies of Difference by Beth Metcalf

Page | 157
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

unfolding completeness of the hidden and ineffable absolute scope. We want


ultimate understanding, and so we attempt to encapsulate the Absolute, or
populate the absolute scope with what we can understand; e.g. terms,
concepts, Forms and Ideas, and generally the favored pole of any meaningful
polarity, such as matter over mind, consciousness over non, or Emptiness
over form, or vice versa on all counts.
But the logic of Univocity softly “forbids” identities (mono-poles) from
colonizing the absolute scope because this would absolutize similarity at the
expense of difference, spreading a “principle of the same,” like a “gray goo,”i
to the infinite, which would deny the active property and infinite difference
of nondual existence, modification and the relative scope itself.ii In other
words, these mono-polizations are static foundationalisms or reductionisms,
taking the finite unity of the concept to the infinite extreme of the absolute.
This is the general feature of traditional interpretations of monisms, such
as academic/exoteric Spinozism, rational materialism, empiricism or
idealism. We have already seen in the Inverse Unified Field that the seeming
monism of atomism, a single indivisible kind of stuff flitting around in the
void, is not properly a monism, but rather a dualism between stuff and anti-
stuff, matter and void, or form and the formless. In the monistic system of
academic/exoteric Spinozism, for example, the absolute scope is
“colonized”iii by the formless mono-pole (i.e. formless absolutism). Platonic
or Berkeleyan idealism, on the other hand, would take the opposite tact
(interestingly similar to atom-voidism), and absolutize the form mono-pole
of concepts and ideas. Leibniz’s monadology, however, at least at the
immanent pole of the uncountable I/T axis, would be a good example of a
nondual symbiogenesis of form and Emptiness in his infinite immanent
holarchy, which is identical in form to the esoteric view of Spinozism, we will
find, which we have already seen in the Principle of Nondual Rationalism.
This monistic mono-polization of the absolute scope and violation of the
logic of the Univocity Framework, illustrates explicitly that a traditional
monism is not a nondualism, and hence is actually a tacit dualism—in this
case, between form and the formless (Emptiness). Placing one pole in the
erewhon of the absolute scope and leaving the other in the relative creates

i
The idea in nanotechnology that a single self-replicating “nano-bot” could replicate itself at an
exponential rate, and take over the earth with the monotonous similarity of its ceaseless repetition.
ii
…which self-recursively generated the absolute scope in the first place. See the coming section on
Polarity and Univocity, p174.
iii
Given that the absolute scope is defined by its absence or opposition to relativity, it makes no
sense to think of it in terms of space or location. The absolute scope can't be colonized period, and
it is not a place outside the relative world. It is merely the relative world attempted to be “seen”
from an infinite perspective, and this is already a “contradiction in terms”, which, we have seen, is a
natural property of the absolute scope. See also the section, Part Two: Interface Mathematics
(p200) and Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486) which explain
how a point of view is the identical opposite of the Infinite.

Page | 158
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

an absolute distinction between them, and hence these vertical alignments of


absolute polarities are “forbidden,” or simply meaningless, in the Univocity
Framework.i
Conversely, any “monism” with a Univocity Framework is more properly
considered a nondual system because Nondual Rationalism demonstrates
(as we will seeii*) that univocity is an ontological application of the identity
of opposites and polarity, which at the absolute scope is the defining feature
of the nondual. In Univocity, the absolute scope is the emptiness in form. It
is the opening of the relative scope to its identical opposite. A monism is
formed by absolutizing this polar distinction through the use of concepts.
As we will see, and which may be intuitively obvious, verticality and
horizontality correspond to the I/T and the transitive axes, respectively. The
vertical polarity of univocity—the abstract rootless-root-polarity of the
immanent-transcendent axis—is the axiomless framework, or vision-logic
interface that operationalizes and softly enforces the logic of the nondual
which “forbids” the vertical alignment of conceptual polarities that term-
inate in the absolute scope. It does this by specifying the epistemic absolute
scope as the identical-opposite to the epistemic relative scope, and hence to
relativity and polarity itself.
The absolute scope is actually launched from the relative scope, through
the application of polarity (the root of relativity) to itself (see, Polarity and
Univocity, p176, below). Relativity, then, to reach its identical-opposite in
order to give it meaning and context, operationalizes the absolute scope
necessarily as ineffable and holds open the space of deep infinity (logical
Emptiness) to ensure that no mono-poles can colonize the absolute scope
and collapse into “flat-land” foundationalisms and absolutisms.

As Beth Metcalf says in her article, Univocity is Multiplicity, “Deleuze’s


Univocity is Spinoza’s Univocity. However, Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza is
not that of the common sense appropriation by traditional Representational
forces. Deleuze sees something new in Spinoza.”

i
Polarities completely within the relative scope, however, can be vertical or horizontal, because the
relative scope is the home of polarity. These vertical polarities include any holarchical emergent,
such as the ontic/epistemic polarity, though a vertical, or holarchical polarity has a necessary
transcend-and-include asymmetry to it, characteristic of holarchies in general, and this is the actual
or ontic source of the transcendent-bias itself.
ii
* See Polarity and Univocity (p174), below.
iii¥
Translation by Yirmiyahu Yovel

Page | 159
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

What is it that Deleuze discovers in Spinoza which is opposed to


“traditional Representational forces”? Nondual Rationalism recognizes,
among other things, a transcendent-bias in operation behind traditional
Representational forces. As we have discussed,i* it is this transcendent-bias
that generates the medieval and pre-rational metaphysics of
foundationalism and the regressive or negative infinity that appears when
the foundation crumbles into the analytic abyss. The modern orthodox or
traditional viewii sees Spinozism through this implicit transcendent-bias,iii
reinforced with a history of transcendent-biased mis-interpretations, from
Leibniz to Kant to Hegel, and hence it sees a foundationalism or even a
materialism whose ultimate level of reality is a single amorphous and inert
(dead) substrate of material “stuff,” a “principle of the same,” or an abstract
generality, eternally underlying, unifying and ultimately denaturing—as
Hegel and Leibniz would famously claim—all modifications or differences.
This would be a monistic (as tacitly dualistic) and reductionistic
representation of Spinoza as absolutizing the formless, or Emptiness (unity
or generality), over form (multiplicity and difference). In modern academia
this would be called an “intertheoretical reduction” of form to the formless,
and generally the immaterial to the material.
Hegel accomplished this faulty interpretation of Spinoza—which has
lodged itself into distortions of the very lens through which academia views
Spinoza—in part by a simple and subtle remapping of Spinoza’s meaning
with respect to his words. He distorted Spinoza’s resonance between what
Deleuze would call his plane of immanence (implicit meaning) and his “plane
of transcendence,” (explicit concepts), and thus moved academia away from
the “plane of consistency” in Spinoza. Hegel confused Spinoza’s expository
geometrical method with the concepts it was meant to convey. As Will
Durant explains:
It was by combining Spinoza with Kant’s epistemology that Fichte,
Schelling and Hegel reached their varied pantheisms; it was from conatus
esse preservandi,iv the effort to preserve one’s self, that Fichte’s Ich was
born, and Schopenhauer’s “will to live,” and Nietzsche’s “will to power,”
and Bergson’s élan vital. Hegel objected that Spinoza’s system was too
lifeless and rigid; he was forgetting this dynamic element of it and
remembering only that majestic conception of God as law which he

i
* See the section, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias (p91).
ii
A flatland straw-man generated in reaction to modernity and rationality mainly by its theocratic
critics, Leibniz and Hegel, both of whom were idealists.
iii
And Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486) points out the
objective-ontic shift that renders Spinozism into a materialism.
iv
Spinoza’s modern, homeostatic, complexity-science, strange-attractor conception of “essence” as
“The endeavour, wherewith everything endeavours to persist in its own being…” from the Ethics,
Part III VII. This, as we will see in Univocity and Essence (p170), is a “reciprocal” or polar notion of
essence that does not precede existence, but is symbiogenetic with it.

Page | 160
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

appropriated for his “Absolute Reason.” But he was honest enough when
he said, “To be a philosopher one must first be a Spinozist.”
A major difficulty for modern philosophy students is that Spinoza inherited a
lexicon “stuffed with medieval barbarisms such as ‘substance’ and
‘attributes,’” i ¥ which was custom evolved for developing pre-rational
foundationalisms. But nowhere does Spinoza ever say that his Substance
exists at any single or particular level, immanent or transcendent to its
modifications, or that Substance, at any level, can exist without being actively
formed or modifiedii or that Substance is equated with matter. Quite the
contrary, Spinoza makes it clear that Substance is the rootless-root of
existence; activity itself, but only in the sense that—as the absolute scope
and axis of Tao—it enfolds and unfolds all polarities, including flux/stasis,
and hence it can’t be acted upon, set in motion or stabilized, by anything
else, because as the absolute, there isn’t anything else. Spinoza says in his
precursor to the Ethics—essentially a rough draft called the Short Treatise on
God, Man and his Well-being, iii —“God, it is said, inasmuch as he is a
supremely perfect being, cannot be passive.” And indeed, Nondual
Rationalism shows the precise reason that mono-poles (terms) such as
‘passive’ and ‘active’ simply have no function or power at the absolute scope
allowing us to more closely reach the plane of consistency in Spinoza’s
thought. Hence Hegel’s claim that Spinoza’s Substance was too rigid, too
passive, or too positive, is based on a category error; a failure to understand
Spinoza’s Substance univocally (see also Univocity and Polarity, p176). It is


Mathew Stewart, The Courtier and the Heretic, p179
ii
Spinoza says that substance can be conceived of axiomatically or logically without modifications,
but this establishes the relationship of immanent-causal, and logical dependency between eternal
Substance and its temporal modifications (i.e. between the absolute and relative scopes); a
dependency enforced by the geometric logic of the exposition, not the univocal framework itself.
Indeed the Univocity Framework takes a reciprocal, polar or nondual approach to the Substance-
modification relation, and with Deleuze, takes Substance to “turn around its modes” just as
Emptiness turns around form, and vice versa, on both counts.
The relation does not specify an actual duality or that substance can exist without its expressions in
modifications. Indeed, existence is expression. Substance is “logically prior” not temporally, given
the axiomatic geometric framework through which Spinoza chose to represent his model.
Furthermore, Spinoza says that the intellect conceives and perceives the essence of Substance
through the attributes, but what is it that the intellect ultimately conceives and perceives?
Modifications. Through the attributes they appear as modifications of Thought or Extension
(internal vs. external, respectively), but Spinoza tells us that the only thing that really exists is
Substance (deep infinity) and its modifications. Therefore, in a sense, modification itself is part of
the essence of Substance, and vice versa. Indeed, “active modification” seems to be a descriptor for
existence itself, which Spinoza says “pertains to the essence of Substance.” And this notion of an
essential polarity between Substance and its modifications, brings us right back to the polarity of
Emptiness and form. Emptiness (also called Fullness) is the infinite depth of Substance, Leibniz's
labyrinth of the continuum, and our principle of nondual rationality as infinite divisibility =
indivisibility, and form is the necessary inclusion of modification in the unbounded levels of active
existence.
iii
also called the “The Book of God.”

Page | 161
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

entirely likely that Hegel confused the rigidity of the geometric style, or the
“presentation layer” of The Ethics with its actual content.
Substance is eternal, or eternity itself,i not because it is static and
immovable, but because it is existence itself taken at the ineffable scope of
the Absolute, which enfolds and unfolds all polarities, including flux/stasis.
There is simply nothing beyond the absolute scope of “ALL is ONE,” by
definition, to act on (or stabilize) Substance, because the absolute scope was
generated from the application of polarity to itself in order give it dynamic
context and meaning in its identical-opposite.

Furthermore, the medieval, exoteric notion of substance already had a very


specific and neutral meaning as merely that neutral foundation which
“stands beneath” the forms of perception; i.e. sub-stance, the substrate of
raw existence not specified as to its materiality or non. But Spinoza
departed from that traditional foundational view of a substrate, or plane of
immanence, and adopted a univocal view which Deleuze recognizes as the
positive view of infinity (apeiron), and I have operationalized as the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis, the axis of Tao, or the absolute scope.ii
As we will see, this interpretation allows us to transcend foundationalism
and coherentism while integrating the truths of each.iii*
In Spinoza, modifications don’t occur without Substance and Substance
doesn’t occur without modifications, regardless of scale. This means that
substance, as the identical-opposite of modifications, is not a function of
scale. It is not an amorphous or unmodified substrate residing at some
particular level (I/T coordinate) immanent to its modifications in order to
counter a “disastrous regress” brought about by falling from the perch of the
transcendent-bias. Rather, Spinoza’s Substance is generated in an escape
from the regress, not to a foundational substrate, but to the a priori positive
infinity of the absolute scope and Immanent/Transcendent axis itself.
Spinoza’s Substance is therefore ultimately (absolute scope) both immanent
and transcendent to its modifications. It is the All is One, or as George Luis
Borges says, the “One, who is all His stars.”

i
Because Substance is at the absolute scope, saying “Substance is 'eternal'” necessitates that we
simultaneously mean the identical opposite, that substance is infinitely and irreducibly
instantaneous. And hence the fully univocal statement about the temporal aspect of Substance
would be “Substance is instantaneous and ‘eternal’“ or the “eternal NOW,” as it is commonly
phrased. Univocity as Deep Infinity: Prigogine and Leibniz (p182), and Univocity and the Eternal
NOW (p187).
ii
Substance can be considered merely an immanent emphasis on the Immanent/Transcendent axis
of which God is its identical opposite transcendent emphasis, and more identical than opposite, in
this case.
iii
* See Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch, p541.

Page | 162
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

The two attributes given by Spinoza, which express the essencei* of


Substance, are merely the aspects essential to the way in which modes can
be formed, perceived, conceived and comprehended. In Spinoza, the
attributes are not ultimately separate. They form a polarity of the within
and the without at all unbounded levels of modification on the I/T axis. This
is why they are strictly parallel: you can’t causally interact or connect what
is not disconnected and you can’t unify what is already inseparable.ii
As we will discuss in the section on Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity (p488),
the attributes are merely two ways of conceiving/perceiving the one
Substance, and they arise from the nature of a priori, yet emergently
modified and active Substance, each modification (or holon) of which
necessitates an inside and an outside. This “sub-representational” polarity is
the root of the ontic parallelism of the attributesiii* and, in Wilber-speak, this
is an essentially “AQAL-compliant” and post-metaphysical view, though
Spinoza enfolds the multiple and singular polarities into his single attribute
polarity: he hasn’t yet made the differentiation into the plural quadrants in
this embryogenesis of the concept of dependent arising (see From
Dependent- to Tetra- Arising: The Conceptual Embryogenesis of AQAL, p563).
The point of this parallelism is to prohibit what Wilber calls a “quadrant
absolutism” or “quadrant reductionism,”iv* and the effect, when understood
in this way, is that mind, or the Within (Thought), can’t be reduced to matter,
or to the Without (Extension), and vice versa, in either its singular or plural
forms.

On a side note, Deleuze says that univocity is the organizing principle of


Spinoza’s system. Yet he is often criticized for this unorthodox
interpretation because nowhere does Spinoza even mention the term
‘univocity’. But it seems rather clear that a system can have specific
operational properties and qualities without the author mentioning them by
a specific name, especially given that the name might not be known to the
author, and the pervasive principle might be in use quite subconsciously.v

i
* See the section Univocity and Essence (p170) below, to see how Spinoza's use of “essence” is
thoroughly modern and indeed contrary to the modern notion of “essentialism.”
ii
This parallelism exactly mirrors the “tetra-arising” of the two singular quadrants, 'I' and 'IT'
(within/without respectively), in Ken Wilber's AQAL matrix. And, according to Wilber, this is one of
the key features of any “Integral post-metaphysics,” the other being an emergent and non-
foundational (i.e. nondual) ontology.
iii
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
iv
* See Identifying Quadrant Absolutisms, p561.
v
Indeed, as we will see, Spinoza’s Ethics can be shown to operate fundamentally on his notion of the
Triune Infinite, even though he only explicitly mentions this triunity in his famous letter on the
Infinite. See the section on Interface Mathematics and Nondual Rationalism, below.

Page | 163
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

In his attempt to understand Spinoza, Deleuze simply recognized an


organizing principle in action that was apparently not explicitly known or
acknowledged by Spinoza himself. And even though Deleuze famously
explains his unorthodox studies of other philosophers as sneaking behind
their backs and producing offspring which are recognizably theirs, yet
changed and monstrous (“buggary”i¥), I have to see Deleuze’s monster as
Spinoza’s legitimate and beautiful child because when I look at it I see
Spinoza ever more clearly. Indeed, my own Spinozist monster, produced
before meeting Deleuze/Spinoza, ii * and in reconciling the traditional
hermeneutic problems of Spinozism, i.e. finding the plane of consistency in
Spinoza, the model bears a striking resemblance to that of Deleuze’s Spinoza.

In another article, The Immanence of Univocity, Metcalf says, “This Univocity


says that Substance is qualified as really and formally distinct... [Substance]
is never qualitatively the same. Even in itself, it is not the same. It is
difference in itself.... if we think that Univocal Being means that Being is ‘the
One’ or that Being has a common, unitary ground to which ‘the Many’ beings
are identical, then we are still talking about the One/Many that never
reaches the Multiplicity of Univocity.” The absolute scope is both the ON and
the All, and cannot be likened to an absolute similarity or an absolute
difference, one without the identical-opposite of the other. This “One/Many”
with a “common, unitary ground [the “One”] to which ‘the Many’ beings are
identical” is the standard foundational interpretation of Spinozism which the
exoteric forces of representation (orthodox academia) generated in reaction
to modernityiii and rendered incoherent. It was largely an unconscious,
collective straw-man effigy; a reaction against the foundations of rational
Modernity, which threatened the entrenched pre-rational, transcendent-
biased, theocratic power structures and the immortality projects of the
“center of gravity” of Enlightenment-era society; its “immortal soul,”
absolute free-will, and theocratic power structures based thereupon.iv We
can see this directly in the massive denouncement of Spinoza all across the
social structure of the times.
Deleuze, however, gives a more coherent, and trans-foundational
(univocal and nondual) interpretation with the discovery of Spinoza’s
Univocity. And many others have recognized the nondual aspect of
Spinozism, even seeing it as a Western form of nondual Buddhism or


Deleuze, Negotiations
ii
* see my article, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486), now
expanded as a chapter in this volume.
iii
through Spinoza's critics, Leibniz and Hegel, et al.
iv
See The Courtier and Heretic by Matthew Stewart

Page | 164
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

Vedanta. For example, Schopenhauer said about Bruno and Spinoza, “The
banks of the Ganges were their true spiritual home; there they would have
led a peaceful and honored life among men of like mind.”
Nondual Rationalism reconciles and integrates the two independent
unorthodox accounts of Spinozism, the Eastern and Western esoteric
readings, by recognizing and explicating the realization that Univocity is
nonduality, and thus the East and West meet in Spinoza/Deleuze. These two
unorthodox accounts, along with others such as the insights from Matthew
Stewart, together represent a much stronger front to the slights of orthodox,
exoteric, flatland, lowest-common-denominator (LCD) appropriations by
“traditional Representational forces.”
Opposed to the foundational One/Many monism (and tacit dualism),
where the Many are reconciled and unified by the distant (immanent or
transcendent) One, Deleuze recognizes instead the identity of “ONE is ALL”
as invoking the a priori infinite multiplicity of univocity. This can be stated
as the identical-opposite,i “Unity is Multiplicity,”ii meaning that there is no
separation or distance between Unity and Multiplicity or between ONE and
ALL. They are one and the same, an inverse identity, or an identical-
opposite, and this is operationalized directly in the I/T omni-axis, with its
absolute poles in the ONE of transcendence and the ALL of omni-local
immanence. As Metcalf notes, “Univocity is not opposed to multiplicity.
Univocity is not to be confused with the one opposed to the multiple. Rather,
Univocity IS multiplicity,”iii¥ just as the absolute scope is the relative scope,
in its other-engendering context. The appearance of separation itself is
merely one of epistemic scope; absolute vs. relative, and it is the principle of
Univocity which mediates as a triune interface between the polarity of
scopes.
With this identical-opposite we can easily recognize the “ONE is ALL” as a
function of the absolute scope, because, as we will see in much more detail,
the absolute scope can only be addressed by such inverse-identities or
tautologies.iv It cannot be adequately addressed (not mono-polized) by
conceptual mono-poles (i.e. concepts, or terms). This is because the absolute
scope enfolds and unfolds, or gives context to, ALL relativity, polarity,
boundary, difference and distinction. And hence, as in the nondual

i
…commonly confused for a “paradox” or “oxymoron”
ii
Note that both terms of the polarity are in the absolute scope. See the discussion in Polarity and
Univocity (p174) for details.
iii¥
Metcalf, Bergson and Univocity
iv
This brings us to Wittgenstein’s notion of a tautology as the only possible “atom” of logic (ruling
out axioms). As would be expected of the absolute scope, these logic atoms are devoid of factual
content and there can be no natural ordering of these tautologies, i.e. they cannot be related one to
another because they are at the absolute scope.

Page | 165
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

traditions, the absolute is ineffable. To eff the ineffable we relative beings


must use relation, otherwise we can’t relate.
In the case of ONE is ALL, the identity is between absolute Unity (ONE)
and absolute Infinity (ALL),i this is the quantitative identity of opposites of
the absolute scope. We have already noted the absolute sense of this
inverse-identity, but here we can see a relative aspect as well. The ONE is
ALL can be seen as the interface between the relative and absolute scopes of
The Absolute. The ONE is the Absolute taken by itself,ii* from the absolute
scope, and the ALL is the Absolute taken from the “pure relational” (or
quantitative) view; the relative scope. This relative view of the Absolute
(ONE), “absolute Unity,” returns its identical-opposite, “absolute
multiplicity,” Infinity, the Everything or ALL. This is critically opposed to the
Many, which does not explicitly, or even generally, indicate the infinite ALL
of the absolute scope.
To put it simply, the ONE and the ALL, or Unity and Infinity, are the same
thing, namely aspectsiii* of the absolute, but seen from different epistemic
scopes. It is the function of univocity to mediate between the two scopes;
absolute and relative.iv
With this identity of the ONE is ALL, Spinoza’s Substance as
immanent/transcendent omni-axis, necessarily becomes infinitely
modifiedv* and non- or trans-foundational because there is no principle of
the same, and no axiomatic foundation, underlying and unifying its
modifications into an absolute transcendent (or immanent) principle. As
Beth Metcalf says “Whereas the Many in relation to the One merely makes
the modes turn around Substance, Multiplicity makes Substance turn around
the modes.”vi This is rather obvious in terms of polarity, or the identity of
opposites. In the balance of the two, neither Substance nor its modifications
can have any meaning in isolation, regardless of the scale of those
modifications, or of Substance. vii * And indeed, Spinoza sets up his
distinction in the univocal form of a polarity, at the very beginning of his
Ethics.
Substance is infinitely deep Emptiness and no single immanent plane of
modification—of the infinite possible on the omni-local

i
The ALL is The Infinite or 1st order infinite, see the forthcoming section, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite
(p270).
ii
* See, Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
iii
* See Spinoza’s Triune Infinite (p270) for a discussion on “aspect infinities”.
iv
This is another example of the principle of “absolute reversal” in which, any concept, taken at the
absolute scope, ends up at its identical opposite. See, Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute
Reversal (PAR), p117.
v
* … as we have already discussed in the section, Spinoza’s Univocity, p158.
vi
See, Univocity as Multiplicity, p163.
vii
* See Substance and Bundle Views of Substance (p99).

Page | 166
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

Immanent/Transcendent axis (omni-axis)—can be ultimate, amorphous


(self-identical) or foundational. Univocal Substance is infinite—our
unbounded “difference in itself.” And a limit to difference on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis (i.e. a plane of immanence) would still be a
limit. Furthermore, by the Principle of Immanence in Transcendence (yin in
yang), it would also necessarily be a transcendent plane, relative to those
beneath it from which it emerged.
In short, a nondual and univocal monism is an infinite pluralism via the
identity of opposites of the One-All or Unity-Multiplicity. Univocity is the
monism=pluralism identity of opposites in Nondual Rationalism.

A numerical distinction (or identity) is one in which the distinction (or


identity) itself is conceptualized as absolute, i.e. at the absolute scope. A
common such distinction in philosophy is a “substance,” typically conceived
as an independent foundation upon which dependencies, modalities,
properties, differences, etc, arise.i* Univocity recognizes, however, that
identity and distinction are only meaningful and real as relativities, i.e. at the
relative scope. This means that even in infinite difference and immanence,
there must be a common emergent “ground” of causal intercompatability
and inter-expressivity (not of absolute similarity or generality, however) in
order for particular distinctions to relate and really differ. This “common
ground,” or plane of immanence is the triunity in relative or transitive
polarity; the cultivating third, ii exfoliating and allowing the transitive
polarities to emerge.
It is critical to note, however, that this plane of immanence is relative to
its transcendent emergents, and is therefore not taken at the absolute scope
as an identity itself, or a general “principle of the same.” A plane of
immanence is properly and abstractly conceived as an emergent level, scale
or substrate of difference on the Immanent/Transcendent axis and therefore
necessarily as transcendent to the immanent pole and its limitless depths of
modification and immanent causation (Emptiness) from which it emerges.
Indeed, the absolute scope of Substance is only conceived as independent
because it is the absolute scope itself, in its immanent aspect in polar

i
* See Substance and Bundle Views of Substance (p99).
ii
…as opposed to the “cultivated third” of transcendent and/or a posteriori unification.

Page | 167
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

opposition and union with its transcendent aspect, God. The dependency of
Substance occurs not in the transitive direction, as in the dependent arising
and “real difference” of the modes, but in the polarity and logical relation
between Substance and its expression in and as modification. Because
Substance/God is the absolute scope, maintaining the logical Emptiness of
the form of modification in dependent arising, it can’t be conceived as
dependent in any relational or transitive way, but only as the ONE-ALL
tautology itself. This is precisely why Spinoza says it can’t be conceived as
passive. It is activity itself, in identical opposition to its forms in passivity
which it enfolds.
As opposed to the forces of representation, Univocity does not unify
distinction after the fact, but provides the real and relative ground of infinite
variability, and infinite difference itself, which allows for, and indeed
necessitates, the emergence of real difference, Spinoza’s version of
dependent arising. “When there is no numerical distinction of individuals,
there can finally be real distinction.”i¥ Note that Deleuze does not give a
causal/visual reason for this necessary difference in every mode, but herein
it is very simply understood with deep infinity, the Immanent/Transcendent
axis and the infinite holarchy of relative form and modification.

As Deleuze says in his Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, “Numerical


distinction is never real….real distinction is never numerical” (p34). When
parsed out in terms of scope, this is simply a recognition that real distinction
is necessarily relative and sensibly conceived only at the relative scope, not
the absolute, as tacitly conceived in the numerical distinction. This is again
why the absolute scope of Substance/God is independent. Numerical or
absolute distinction is unreal. It can only be tautological, as in the ONE-ALL.
As we will see in Part Two: Interface Mathematics (p202), this is also the
difference between Infinite Unity and finite unity. Infinite Unity is not
numerical because numbers are conceived in Interface Mathematics as
boundaries whereas Infinity is simply boundless and hence the identical-
opposite of a number. Infinity is the unbounded essence, the ONE = ALL, and
Unity = Infinity (Infinite Unity), of the ineffable absolute. Number, on the
other hand, is inherently relative as it functions to relate various quantities
in the most general terms of pure categorical relation (pure relation).
Deleuze also notes, in the same work, that “…there is no Cartesian axiom
[in Spinoza]…that does not take on a new meaning, hostile to Cartesianism,
on the basis of the new theory of distinctions. The theory has as its
fundamental principle the qualitative status of real distinction. Detached
from all numerical distinction, real distinction is carried into the absolute,
and becomes capable of expressing difference within Being, so bringing


Metcalf, Deleuze Versus Hegel

Page | 168
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

about the restructuring of other distinctions” (p38). This carrying of real


distinction into the absolute is simply the identity of opposites of the ONE-
ALL. A singular distinction, of itself, must exist in relation and real
distinction from other distinctions, and thus accessed at the relative scope.
As we will see in the section Spinoza: A Nondual Sketch (p668), this move
to real distinction enforces a nondual dependent arising of all modification
and the field of relation, i.e. the relative scope. This is the critical move, in
the Ethics toward a nondual model.

As we have seen (and as we will see in more detail in the next section,
Univocity and Polarity), Deleuze/Spinoza’s Univocity is essentially an
operationalization of the Taoist identity of opposites, polarity or nonduality
and Nagarjuna’s polarity of Emptiness and Form. This means that all
dualistic notions, such as Hegel’s dialectic, are Ultimately inadequate, i.e.
meaningless at the absolute scope. This is why his criticism of Spinoza’s
Substance (which we are taking as the absolute scope) for neglecting the
negative or oppositional element of the dialectic, entirely missed its mark.
And indeed, Spinoza’s absolute is only positive in the sense that it is no
longer negative, disastrously regressive, oppositional and relative. It is the
positive infinite in that it affirmatively “exists” a priori, or more properly, it is
existence itself, along with all other relative terms and oppositions enfolded
as ALL is ONE.i
In What is Univocity?, Metcalf says, “…with Univocity, representation is
temporary surface effect. Univocity always keeps the representational plane
of transcendence open to the sub-representative plane of immanence.” And
as Deleuze points out in Difference and Repetition,ii¥ “Forms of the negative
do indeed appear in actual terms and real relations, but only in so far as
these are cut off from the virtuality [immanence] which they actualize, and
from the movement of their actualization.” In other words, forces of
opposition and negation are “temporary surface effects,” and occur only in
transitive representational ignorance of the immanent forces (the inter-
expressive cultivating thirds) that allow for the emergence of real and

i
And we will find, as we have already briefly seen, that the rational numbers, with their “violation of
the closure property” of the integers and natural numbers, also operate no longer on the
positive/negative opposition of the integers, but on the “intensive forces” of the infinite space
between “immanent-zero” and one, the sub-representational realm beneath the numerical
identities of the Natural numbers and the transitive integers.
ii¥
p207, qtd in Metcalf.

Page | 169
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

relative polarity and difference in the first place. And as we will see in much
more detail in SpinbitZ: Volume II,i* even forces of immanence in physics are
always transcendent or emergent when conceived or perceived at any
particular scale, level or “plane,” i.e. at the relative scope.
Deleuze describes forces of Univocity as intensive, as relative and inter-
expressive degrees of sub-representational power emergent from the
infinite difference which monads can enfold as a singularity.ii And, as
Metcalf says in her article Force Relations, “There is no opposition to other
degrees since they are all singular. Each is positive, singular intensity.”
Clearly, however, there is relation and polarity at this level of univocal
forces, but this is exactly the point. The forces of Univocity are the
modifications and relations on the relative plane of immanence, the
cultivating third which allows opposition to emerge and which allows its
poles to really inter-relate and inter-oppose.
Metcalf continues, “All intensive forces fit together without opposition or
lack, because they are singular degrees of real distinction, ontologically one.”
This brings us to a fascinating correlation with a cutting edge model of
fundamental physics, called Sorce Theory,iii which we will explore in much
greater depth in the SpinbitZ: Volume II.iv Similar to Deleuze’s forces of
Univocity, Sorce Theory’s “singular” force (sorce) of pressure, emerges into
opposition (negativity) only through positive differences in relation, i.e.
polarity. This polarity is the distinguishing feature of the forces of electro-
magnetism, and we will examine in SpinbitZ: Volume II how the polar and
indeed univocal forces of electro-magnetism are immanent, or fundamental
to those seemingly monistic forces such as the extremely weak force of
gravity.v
“However,” Metcalf continues, “Univocity includes both a plane of
transcendence and a plane of immanence. Now, the plane of transcendence
is not cut off from its source. With Univocity, representation is actualized in
really distinct worlds that remain open to all the singular forces of intensity.”
Perhaps contrary to Deleuze, it is not quite so simple a matter as to merely
switch dualistically between intensive and oppositional forces when moving
between these two levels. And, as we should by now expect, this is yet
another polarity, because the intensive and oppositional (which are also the
continuous-inhomogeneous, and discrete) are symbiogenetic and

i
* see Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement .
ii
Just as the unit-identity in Interface Mathematics enfolds the infinity of the immanent pole within
it (which the ratio breaks open again in its “violation” of “unit-closure”) as it is first selected from the
immanent-transcendent axis as the defining scale in the operational interface between mathematics
and reality.
iii
Sorce Theory is a purely causal unified field theory. See www.anpheon.org .
iv
Which currently exists in the unpublished paper titled, Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement
v 40
electro-magnetism is around 10 times stronger than gravity

Page | 170
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

recursively emerging along the Immanent/Transcendent axis, as we will see


in SpinbitZ: Volume II.
But Deleuze is reacting against the dualistic tendencies and biases at the
level of representation or individuation.i* Specifically, Deleuze targets
Hegel’s absolutization of oppositional and representational forces at the
expense of the intensive and sub-representational forces of Univocity,
polarity and nonduality. This feature of Hegel’s thoughtii Deleuze naturally
calls “infinite representation,” since infinity, or unboundedness, is the
quantitative aspect of the absolute scope. Deleuze is clearly, therefore
essentially rejecting Hegel’s absolutized representation in the forces of
opposition in his dialectic.
In conclusion, Deleuze is correct to criticize Hegel there, but he draws
perhaps too simple an alternative between merely two planes, as we will
see. It is possible also, that Deleuze intends, by his planes of immanence and
transcendence something more akin to our immanent-transcendent omni-
axis, in both its immanent and transcendent aspects.

One of the key existentialists, Jean-Paul Sartre—in his focused reaction


against the exoteric, or the “received ideas” of “rationalism” or Platonism
from his era—converged on a very simple definition of existentialism as the
notion or belief that “existence precedes essence.” This is a simple reversal
of the essentialist notion, attributed to Aristotle,iii that “essence precedes
existence,” and this notion can serve as an orienting generalization for our
definition of essentialism. As should be directly clear, however, if either
essence or existence “precedes” the other—at the absolute scope, as this is
indeed taken—then we have a reductionism and a monism, not a
nondualism.
An essence, in the traditional sense, is basically a platonic form, or an
eternal and perfect template and category for the instantiation of always
imperfect manifestations. The encyclopedia entry on the subject defines an
essence basically as a category with a finite number of properties which
completely defines its instances.iv¥ This is a form of numerical identity or an

i
* …or cognitive nucleation, see Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”,
p486.
ii
at least where it interfaced with Hegel’s failed attempt to find the “plane of consistency” in
Spinoza’s thought.
iii
if problematically, as we will see below.
iv¥
Wikipedia: essentialism

Page | 171
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

absolutization of a concept or category, and, as we have seen, this is an


explicitly invalid operation in the Univocity Framework and Deleuze’s
univocal and essentially nondual reading of Spinoza. As we should by now
expect, this is brought about by a transcendent-bias. As Metcalf notes, “This
is the Representation of numerically distinct substances which can share a
common concept in the same essence. These are the forms and subjects of
closed Representation on the plane of transcendence cut off from the plane
of immanence.”i¥
But Deleuze/Spinoza’s univocity denies the principle of the same, or the
generality of the concept, that would precede and govern its real instances.
As Metcalf says, “For Spinoza’s Univocity there are no substantial or
essential forms. They always come in compositions of complex infinities.”ii¥
Indeed, univocity, with it’s positive or deep infinity and uncountable I/T axis,
shows that all instances are necessarily and fundamentally different from
each other and that there are necessarily an infinite number, or numberless
details that would define the “essence” of any “instance,” and make it really,
inter-expressively, different and relative to any other.iii* This is part of
Deleuze’s project for undermining or counteracting the forces of closed
Representation (e.g. the transcendent-bias, or the “plane of transcendence”
cut off from the plane of immanence) which give rise to essentialism and
Platonism, and this essence as infinite depth is also found in Leibniz’s
“hyper-essentialism” (note the Principle of Absolute Reversal in action with
hyper-enacting the property of essentialism to arrive at its opposite).
But Deleuze shows us that Spinoza added something new to the
traditional definition of ‘essence.’ That something new is a “reciprocity” (i.e.
a polarity),iv* says Deleuze, between the essence and the existence of the
modification itself.v¥ This polarity means that essence cannot be separated
from existence in order to precede it in the first place. In Spinoza, there is no
longer the dualism between the perfect realm of essences and the imperfect
realm of real manifestation.
Essence, for Spinoza, is the property “wherewith everything endeavours
to persist in its own being.”vi¥ Spinoza’s essence is an inseparable aspect of
modal existence which appears surprisingly modern in its approach. It is a
mere tendency of modal existence to “persist in its own being.” Today this
could be called “homeostasis,” or even a “strange attractor” from complexity
science.


Beth Metcalf, The Immanence of Univocity
ii¥
Deleuze, A Thousand Plateaus p.254, qtd in Metcalf, The Immanence of Univocity
iii
* See Univocity as Deep Infinity: Prigogine and Leibniz (p182) below.
iv
* See Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486

Deleuze, Spinoza Practical Philosophy
vi¥
Ethics, Part III VII. “The endeavour, wherewith everything endeavours to persist in its own being,
is nothing else but the actual essence of the thing in question.”

Page | 172
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

This is an extremely modern, and anti-platonic notion of essence as


emergence and homeostasis, not a Platonic essence as a Form separated
from its expression or existence. Thus, in Spinoza, essence does not precede
existence, but is reciprocal, or symbiogenetic with it (i.e. nonduality or
polarity). With Spinoza’s reciprocity of existence and essence and his
univocal infinite difference, this template kind of one-way connection, of
essence manifesting and directing individual existence, is broken. He was
not conceiving of essence as a numerical identity, but univocally as the inter-
expressivity of infinite difference, i.e. as infinite existence itself as it
manifests in the bounded forms of modifications. And hence, Spinoza, for
Deleuze, is no essentialist.
Recall that, according to noted historian of philosophy Will Durant,i it
was Hegel’s neglect of Spinoza’s essence as the active property of existence
to “persist in its own being” that led him to taint the whole of academia with
his false assumption that Spinoza’s Substance/God was passive, lifeless and
rigid. Spinoza’s essence is not our modern notion of a rigid, Platonic
template-Form to which malleable, fallen matter must con-form, but an
active tendency of self-persistence and growth potential, the precursor of
Fichte’s Ich, “Schopenhauer’s ‘will to live,’ … Nietzsche’s ‘will to power,’ and
Bergson’s élan vital.”ii¥
Under the exoteric forces of Representation, the terms have changed in
meaning through subsequent readings and in different contexts. Conceptual
differentiations have occurred and subsequent interpretations have placed
earlier thinkers on either side of a dichotomy they never held. Spinoza
simply held no ultimate, foundational or reductionistic distinction between
existence and essence. For Spinoza, essence did not precede existence. The
essence of Spinoza’s Substance was existence itself (“existence pertains to its
essence”). Indeed, Nietzsche called Spinoza his metaphysical predecessor
(along with some of the pre-Socratics, such as Heraclitus) and he was a key
proto-existentialist in this sense, as well as others.
The point of the univocal reinterpretation of essence, is to re-integrate
the essence/existence distinction and correct the historical errors of
alignment brought about by the exoteric and lowest-common-denominator
forces of Representation. These forces have put Spinoza on the wrong side
of an essence/existence distinction he never held.
Furthermore, at the absolute ineffable scope, as we will see in greater
detail below, all distinctions are moot and hence it is meaningless for any
property to precede any other. Any such precedence would be a monism
and tacit dualism between the absolutized property and its antithesis.

i
* See Spinoza’s Univocity, p158.
ii¥
Will Durant, The Story of Philosophy

Page | 173
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Essence is the Latin attempt at interpreting Aristotle’s puzzling to ti een


einai, and it is assumed by exoteric academia that Aristotle was an
essentialist in that he took essences to constitute reality as it is in itself.
But Spinoza appears to disagree with the idea that Aristotle was an
essentialist, especially given his “hylomorphism.” Indeed, in Spinoza’s rough
draft of the Ethics, the Short Treatise,i¥ he seems to be taking a stand with
Aristotle, but against the Platonic separation of formal essence and
existence.
Now, in the first place, it cannot be rightly said that there is confusion in
Nature, since nobody knows all the causes of things so as to be able to
judge accordingly. This objection, however, originates in this kind of
ignorance, namely, that they have set up general Ideas, with which, they
think, particular things must agree if they are to be perfect.
When Spinoza says, ‘Ideas,’ we can note the equivalents as Forms, essences,
absolutized concepts, or numerical identities. He continues:
These Ideas, they state, are in the understanding of God, as many of
Plato’s followers have said, namely, that these general Ideas (such as
Rational, Animal, and the like) have been created by God; and although
those who follow Aristotle say, indeed, that these things [essences, Forms,
Ideas, etc] are not real things, only things of the mind, they nevertheless
regard them frequently as [real] things, since they have clearly said that
His providence does not extend to particular things, but only to kinds; for
example, God has never exercised His providence over Bucephalus, but
only over the whole genus Horse.
In other words, Spinoza is saying that Aristotle’s expressed view is that
essences are mental categories, generalizations over many varied instances.
Thus, Spinoza says, although Aristotle was not a metaphysical essentialist,
his followers exhibited the trait despite stating otherwise. That would be a
prime example of the “traditional representational forces” of exotericism or
orthodoxy in action in the 17th century followers of Aristotle.
In the chapter on Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity, we will see the ontic aspect
of the attributes as “formative protocols,” as opposed to the “descriptive
protocols” of the epistemic.ii These formative protocols are not “essences” in
their current Platonic connotation as Forms, numerical identities, or
pregivens, but rather they are obvious truths about polarity, such as the
symbiogenesis of within and without, and the homeostasis of “nucleated”
organisms. It is essentially a nondual (and post-metaphysical) reading
because polarity is shown to be the emergent, not pregiven, meaning of the

i ¥
Also called the “Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being,” see:
http://www.yesselman.com/ShortTreatise.htm)Spinoza
ii
Or the sub-representational vs. the representational, respectively.

Page | 174
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

distinction of the attributes at both representational and sub-


representational levels.i

Polarity is the essence, or defining feature of the nondual and of univocity.


And univocity, we will see, is the very limit of polarity; where polarity (the
core relation of the relative) self-referentially applies itself to itself to form
the absolute scope in identical opposition to the relative. This is where
relative thought grounds itself in its engendering other; its identical-
opposite which gives it context and meaning; the absolute.
There are two basic directions of polarity in univocity; horizontal and
vertical. These correspond to polarities aligned, but not identical, with the
immanent-transcendent and the transitive axes, respectively (See the Main
VCS diagram (Figure 6, p143)). We could also, then, call them transitive and
immanent-transcendent polarities, or rather, transitive and holarchical (at
least when neither term enters the absolute scope). For our purposes,
because horizontal and vertical are simpler, and also generally sufficient,
this will be the common usage when referring to directions of polarization in
the Univocity Framework.

We have already seen many horizontal, transitive polarities at work so far.


These include all dualities or oppositions that emerge at the same level, or
transitive-plane, in the holarchy of emergence, such as mind/matter,
inside/outside, up/down, left/right, good/bad, etc. Horizontal or transitive
polarity emerges from the cultivating third (the triunity manifesting into
polarity) of the sub-representational realm where “divergence is affirmed
and disjunction becomes a positive synthesis…[where] all events, even
contraries, are compatible,”ii¥ or inter-expressive.

i
Note that we can have no absolute truths of the sub-representational, or any level, nor are our
concepts themselves, including the concept of sub-representation (ontic), subrepresentational.
They merely point to sub-representation to break out of the forces of closed Representation which I
show possess a transcendent bias which in turn forces a foundationalist reading of Spinoza as an
essentialist and this in turn forces an idealist, or epistemic-absolutist counter-reaction, the
beginnings of which we see in the Leibniz/Kant/Hegel hermeneutic trajectory. It is this historical
trajectory, appropriated into orthodoxy as a representational reaction to the incomplete project of
rational-empiricism (or modernity) itself, that Deleuze rejects as a distortion of Spinoza's Univocity.
ii¥
Deleuze, Logic of Sense, p177. Quoted in Metcalf.

Page | 175
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

“Vertical” polarities, similarly rely on emergence, but they are oriented in


the very direction of that emergence—inwardly and outwardly in their
holarchical embryogenesis. Therefore, generally, it is the case that a
“vertical” or immanent/transcendent polarity is also a binary section of a
much larger holarchy. A key example of this type of polarity is the
ontic/epistemic where the epistemic, or representation, is necessarily a
subset of sub-representational reality, the ontic,i* yet it transcends it in
emergence into true, unpredictable novelty.
Univocity itself, however, can be seen as a vertical polarity, in that it is
the application of the concept of polarity, or relativity, to itself, in order to
reach its opposite in the absolute or the “axis of Tao” which enfolds and
unfolds all difference and polarity. In the same way that difference requires
a deeper level of inter-compatibility or inter-expressiveness, so relation, at
any level requires a deeper, more absolute, level of unity within which to
inter-relate or be understood. This gives us an immanent direction for the
absolute scope, but there is also a transcendent direction. Yet, again, the
absolute scope of the infinite cannot be reached given that it is the openness
of emptiness or unreachability itself. And in this same way, relativity itself
requires the absolute, represented operationally herein, in both vertical
directions, by the ONE-ALL tautology of the immanent-transcendent omni-
axis. And, recall, this is also another expression of the principle of
nondualityii* with relativity being a function of form and with the absolute as
the infinite depth of Emptiness (immanent/transcendent omni-axis),
breaking away the ground of any absolutized substrate of form or relation.
Because this necessary ground of inter-expressivity is conceived of as
within, it is common to assume that the absolute scope itself is also simply
within. But, as we have seen, the identity of opposites as it unfolds into our
principle of immanence in transcendence, as well as our principle of
absolute reversal, precludes such a mono-polization of the immanent over
the transcendent in the absolute scope, or vice versa, as is more often the
exoteric case. It is also simple to see that there is a within everywhere in the
infinite without, and thus as well in all forms of transcendence. There is
always immanence in transcendence, and vice versa, because both occur on
an infinite axis where each is relative to the other.
It is for this reason that vertical polarity of univocity is not necessarily
identical with the immanent-transcendent axis, though conceptually aligned
with it. The vertical polarity of the absolute and relative scope, for example,
is not a polarity between a transitive plane and the immanent causation

i
* See, Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity (p176), below.
ii
* See the previous section, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156.

Page | 176
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

within, but between the transitive/relative and the infinite immanence and
transcendence of the immanent-transcendent omni-axis itself. It is the
polarity between polarity-transitivity-relativity and the ineffable tautology
of the ONE-ALL.

With univocity as the polarity of polarity—where the relative scope, in the


very same act, reaches for and creates its context and engendering other in
the absolute scope—we can see the very essence of the “fundamental
question” which asks the ultimate “WHY” of thingness and relativity itself.
The fundamental question asks “Why does anything (or thingness itself)
exist at all?” and “Why not ‘no-thingness’?”. This is the very act of the
relative scope in reaching for its self-defining context. This ever expanding
context is the core of the relative scope, so it is fundamentally intrinsic to the
relative scope to ask questions of its own context. The relative scope asks
the WHY-relation of its own self. When it tries to grasp itself as a whole, it
cannot do otherwise than to seek its context which gives definition to
wholeness itself. This polarity of context and wholeness is the outside
emphasis of the polarity of parts and wholes which necessitates the holon:
the part-whole which is always a part of another whole and is always made
of parts which are also wholes.
But thingness and no-thingness are two sides of the same coin, just as are
the absolute and relative scopes. They are ultimate thesis and its relative
antithesis. Because, however, this is the relative scope itself seeking its
identical opposite, we can go no further than their synthesis in univocity,
and the absolute scope must be maintained in the purity of its concept, free
from relativizing and colonizing poles of other (subordinate) concepts which
would seek to absolutize at the expense of their own engendering others.
The absolute scope must remain in Emptiness such that the duality of
monopole-ization cannot occur, for when it does, it is no longer the absolute
scope, yet the concept which reduced it to relativity is still assumed absolute.
This generates the all-to-common con-fusion of scope at every
absolutization of a relative concept.

Before representation can “reach” the unreachable absolute in its aspect of


immanence it must pass through and affirm its source; sub-representation.
Representation is the nursery of reason. It is the emergent realm into which
all concepts and percepts are born; a realm which they inter-expressively co-
create through the cultivating third of their source. The source of
representation is its inverse-identity, sub-representation”: together, sub-
representation and representation are essentially the ontic/epistemic

Page | 177
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

polarity, respectively, and they are both purely (and infinitely) relational.i
Before univocity can “reach” the unreachable absolute in the immanent
direction, then, it must first orient in the relative vertical polarity of the
ontic/epistemic.ii

Through the identity of opposites in the ontic and epistemic we can see also
that ontology is epistemic and epistemology is ontic. In other words,
speculation about the nature of reality is necessarily representational, and
representation is necessarily real. Or even simpler, the map of the territory
is a feature of the territory itself.
The commonplace representational conflation between the map and the
territory is perhaps a main cause of our tendency to think that ontology (the
study of reality) is the study of the absolute scope, and to cast out relative
truths about relative reality when we merely want to proactively eliminate
its absolute truth claims (absolutist ontology). See Figure 9, below.

Figure 9: Ontic-Epistemic Polarity:


The ontic-epistemic polarity reminds
us that ontology is a form of
knowledge (the epistemic) and that
epistemology and all other forms of
knowledge, are fundamentally real
(ontic).

i
…or taken to its limitless limit, the absolute/relative polarity.
ii
The dialectic must demand that even the dialectic has its opposition, otherwise it is an
absolutization of the relative operation of the dialectic itself. The trick is to shift from the relative
scope, with its infinite holonic and operational transcension and immanence, to the absolute scope
with its “ALL is ONE,” nondual unity, enfolding and unfolding all polarity and relativity.

Page | 178
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

One very subtle violation of the Univocity Frameworki may be found in


Hegel’s use (or abuse) of the concept of the “dialectic.” Hegel takes issue
with Spinoza, recall, claiming that Spinoza’s system is rigid, and that it does
not allow negativity, or “the forces of opposition,” as Deleuze might say, into
his “substance.”

Hegel says in his Science of Logic:


… with Spinoza, substance and its absolute unity has the form of an inert
unity, i.e. of a unity which is not self-mediated, of a fixity or rigidity in
which the Notion of the negative unity of the self, i.e. subjectivity, is still
lacking.ii¥
As we will see,iii* the properties of infinite or absolute unity, in Spinoza or
anywhere, do not allow for the relative term-inals or mono-poles of
polarities such as inert vs. active, or rigid vs. fluid. Hegel is here supposing,
perhaps (to give him the benefit of the doubt) that Spinoza is absolutizing
finite unity without taking into account the ineffable properties of the
absolute.
If, however, in the Univocity Framework we take Spinoza’s Substance as
immanent aspect of the absolute scope in polar relation to the relativity and
dependence of its modes, then the functions of the relative scope, such as
polarity and opposition, simply cannot otherwise apply. This is because the
epistemic absolute scope was generated from the relative scope as its
engendering other, to give it context in its identical-opposite. If we give it
properties of relation, such as opposition and negation (or subjectivity vs.
objectivity), we have merely transposed it back into the relative scope,
negating its function and meaning, and we end up in infinite representation
and absolutized relation. The absolute scope, recall, is not a place; it is not a
stuff or a substance, in the common sense of the word. It is merely a
category in the mind to keep the relative scope open to its identical opposite
in Emptiness, to enforce the nondual realization of the ineffability of
ultimate reality and to hold open an epistemic “space” to ensure that no
relativity can be taken as absolute, or vice versa.

i
A violation of this framework, recall, results in a reductionism, absolutism or foundationalism.
ii¥
Science of Logic § 565
iii
* See Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.

Page | 179
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Hegel’s insistence, therefore, that Spinoza’s Substance neglects to take


into account the forces of opposition of the dialectic, is a violation of
nonduality and univocity. It is to confuse the absolute with the relative
scope and to attempt to populate the absolute scope with one’s favored
relative concept, in this case, the dialectic and the “negative unity of the self.”
This is a relative absolutism because it forces a polarity (an opposition)
within (not with) the absolute scopei negating the Nagarjunan-Spinozan-
Deleuzian absolute/relative polarity in an absolutization of the relative.
Following Kant, Hegel’s system is also tacitly an epistemic reductionism
encapsulated at the level of representation and the absolutized individual
identity. It neglects to include its opposite in the sub-representational and
the pre-individual—the pre-self-conscious.
Univocity can be seen as the unity of the intensive and oppositional
forces in an affirmative and symbiogenetic (and therefore positive)
conceptualization, as opposed to Hegel’s negative absolutization of the
purely oppositional, and Representational forces of the self-conscious
Dialectic.

Beth Metcalf explains it thus:


Within Representation, there is merely an abstract differentiating process
of similarities and differences, genus and species of numerically distinct
substances. Whereas Deleuze’s Univocity says being in one sense and that
of which it is said is difference; Hegel’s infinite representation says being
in several numerically distinct senses and that of which it is said is
internally related to the infinite variation of conceptual identity. They are
not similar in any way. ... because Hegel never reaches the sub-
representative forces of Univocity. DR264 [[as Deleuze says in “Difference
and Representation”]], “The entire alternative between finite and infinite
applies very badly to difference, because it constitutes only an antinomy
of representation…. because both fail to capture the… sub-representative
source..”ii¥
According to Deleuze, Hegel demands that beyond the oppositional or
negative elements of the dialectic there can be only either a) pure
undifferentiated Being or b) absolute nothingness, both of which Hegel
rightly rejects. Deleuze sees this as a false dichotomy, however, and rejects
these choices in favor of a positive view of infinity, or the absolute, which
moves beyond representation and numerical distinction, or absolutized
identity, and sees difference and unity as two views of the same absolute, the
identical-opposites of the relative and absolute scopes. This can be seen
essentially as a nondual view with its identity of form and Emptiness

i
…recall that the absolute scope enfolds and unfolds all polarities
ii¥
http://users.rcn.com/bmetcalf.ma.ultranet/index.htm

Page | 180
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

mapping to difference and unity, respectively, but also vice versa, at the
absolute scope (given the PAR).
This “infinite representation,” as Deleuze calls Hegel’s use of the dialectic,
is part of Hegel’s “absolute idealism.” The problem, as Deleuze sees it, is not
idealism, per se, but that Hegel has absolutized and closed off the level of
Representation and self-consciousness, and further that he has done so in a
negative way as pure opposition. Deleuze sees Representation and the
forces of opposition always as transcendental, meaning that it is essentially
emergent from deeper levels of reality. In other words, it is always
dependent and relative, not absolute and independent. The opposition of
the absolute scope can only reflect back to the relative scope. But there is
opposition of Substance, as the immanent aspect of the absolute scope, in the
transcendent aspect of God, in the identity and tautology of the ONE-ALL.

It is simple to see Hegel’s absolutized dialectic, in his criticism of Spinoza, in


terms of a performative contradiction. The dialectic can be seen as a process
of converting duality to polarity: thesis and antithesis, mapping respectively
to the “positive” vs. the “negative” and unified inter-expressively in the
cultivated third and “synthesis” in polarity. But the application of polarity,
the dialectic, to itself produces the self-negation of negation or the self-
negation of opposition. If polarity—or the negative and oppositional
Hegelian dialectic—exists at the relative scope (as it must), then absolutizing
the dialectic would mean applying the dialectic (or polarity) to itself. This in
turn means that polarity can’t exist without its opposite, non-polarity, the
non-relative or absolute scope. The dialectical synthesis of the two, then, is
Deleuze’s inter-expressive Univocity and tautology of the ONE-ALL, the
synthesis and identity of opposites of Unity and Multiplicity, the absolute
and relative views of the absolute. To be sure, these are not levels of reality,
but aspects of the same reality at all levels. That’s why the ONE-ALL is a
tautology, not a true opposition. It doesn’t take us anywhere because there
is nowhere else to go at the absolute scope. In this sense, polarity
(relativity) is intrinsically self-transcending, and other-engendering of the
concept of the absolute, but the opposition of the absolute can only return
(through the PAR) the relative—and hence Substance turns on its modes.

And so, Hegel’s absolutization of the dialectici can be seen as a performative


contradiction given that it fails to apply the dialectic to itself in order to give
it context in its opposite—in order to really reach the unreachability of the
absolute. But Hegel’s representational and relative oppositional dialectic

i
Perhaps only insofar as his mis-mapped and mis-targeted criticism of Spinoza is concerned.

Page | 181
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

fails even to transcend itself and reach the sub-representational intensive


forces of univocity, let alone the absolute. Hegel’s dialectic divides itself
endlessly, indefinitely according to the oppositional forces of Representation
and its numerical identities, never reaching the unity of the absolute which
gives difference and opposition (polarity) its inter-expressive meaning. Like
two opposing mirrors Hegel’s dialectic remains trapped in self-conscious
illusion and absolutized Representation, dualistic opposition and relativity.
It never reaches the sub-representational or the plane of immanence. At this
level, this plane of immanence, instead of negative oppositional forces
transcending and negating each other, Deleuze sees forces of intensity,
transcending and including, rather than negating each other.
Because the absolute scope (e.g. the nondual or the ‘‘axis of Tao”) enfolds
and unfolds all polarity, univocity is actually the positive negation, or the
acceptance, affirmation and transmutation of opposition; the negation of
negation in the positive infinite. The root-polarity, the positive infinity of
esoteric rationalism, is the polarity of polarity vs. non-polarity—in other
words, the relative/absolute polarity, the univocity axis or the dialectic of
univocity whose synthesis returns us to the positive infinity (logical
Emptiness) of esoteric rationalism. This is the root polarity because the
absolute has returned home, from its journey through the world of form, the
relative and sub-representational, to its engendering other in the ineffable
absolute. The concept has returned to its source through the non-concept,
the sub-representational or the plane of immanence. In this root conceptual
polarity, where concept opens to its annihilating/generating antithesis/pre-
thesis, the absolute unfolds and then enfolds polarity itself.

The relative, representational nature of the mind forces us to see even


polarity itself in terms of the deeper absolute/relative polarity. To push it
further, to demand that the absolute scope itself must have opposition
(other than the relative scope itself, from which it was symbiogenetically
born), is merely to fail to touch the absolute, to fall back into the relative
across the root polarity/dialectic. In the terms of the Hegelian critique of
Spinoza, Hegel is wrong to think that Spinoza’s absolute-scope Substance has
no opposition. Its opposition merely takes the vertical-polarity form of the
concept touching and then reflecting off the aconceptual; form reflecting
back into its own originating Emptiness, and vice versa. It cycles back
vertically within the root polarity from Substance back into its modes, from
the absolute to the relative scopes, and back again.
In Spinozan terms, Substance and its modes are the root polarity, the
absolute/relative univocity dialectic or axis. To push this dialectic deeper is
a scope con-fusion, a categorical error; to defy the relative nature of
knowledge and the nondual and indeed to revert to the mythical, pre-
Nagarjunan, pre-Kantian, representational absolute; the “holy grail of
philosophy” that seeks operational and therefore relative absolutes.

Page | 182
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

In Leibniz-Kant-Hegel, the univocity pendulum has swung the other way,


from the medieval relativization of the absolute in ascribing
anthropomorphic qualities to God, to the post-modern absolutization of the
relative, in lifting the properties of the dialectic (or hermeneutics, or social
construction, or whatever) to the absolute scope. In the Univocity
Framework, however, these two opposites, as all opposites, are seen
necessarily as identically opposite anthropocentrisms. They both attempt to
dissolve the core of nondualism in the absolute/relative polarity through
conceptual encapsulation of the absolute in the relative, or populating the
absolute scope with conceptual mono-poles, but from two different sides of
the same operation. The Hegelian, post-modern, transcend-and-negate
dialectic is the inverse identity of the pre-modern negative-regressive
foundational infinite. They are both functions of the transcendent-biased
modes of absolutized representation (relativity) and are therefore also
epistemic absolutisms.

Univocity can be understood much more clearly in its relation to deep (or
positive) infinity. This is illuminated from the other direction by Leibniz—
from the point of view of identity or similarity rather than difference—in his
principle of the “identity of indiscernables.” This is the idea that two things
with absolutely the same properties are in actuality necessarily the same
thing. The idea is that, at the very least, a mere difference of position in
space of two otherwise identical entities (were this identicality otherwise
possible) will manifest differences in expression, because every position in
“space” is necessarily different from every other. According to Leibniz (and
contra Descartes and Newton) the concept of space or extension, as an
abstract, isometric (and perhaps platonic) Emptiness—principle of the
same—imparting no real, active/causal or physical difference on objects or
expressions located differently within it, is a superficial and misleading
generalization, if taken absolutely. Space itself, according to this view, is
composed of, or has the property of, infinite depth of real difference, infinite
activity (anima) and infinite modification, very similar, in this sense, to the
active properties of the modern “quantum vacuum,” with it’s “zero point
energy.” And therefore any particular region of space will impart its own
unique properties, stemming from this infinite depth of active detail, upon
objects located within it.
And even before Leibniz, Spinoza conceived of extension as an attribute
of infinitely active Substance, i.e. the essence of Substance conceived and/or
perceived from the outside.i In Deleuze’s view of Spinoza, and similar to my

i
* See Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.

Page | 183
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

own interpretation, Spinoza’s Substance is ‘‘pure immanence,”i or what


Spinoza called “immanent causation.” As we have seen,ii however, Spinoza’s
Substance is more properly identifiable not as an immanent plane or
substrate,iii because any substrate is necessarily a modality or relativity and
Spinoza reached his Substance (absolute scope) through an “escape of the
mode” and the infinite immanent regress of modality and the relative
scope.iv* Spinoza’s Substance, as an “escape” of the foundational, modal
regress of the relative scope, therefore represents a final coming to rest in
the a priori unity of deep infinity, i.e. the Immanent/Transcendent axis itself,
and the absolute scope.

A fascinating modern correlation of this idea of univocity as deep infinity


and Leibniz’s “active space,”v can be found in the work of Nobel Prize winner
Ilya Prigogine with his solution to the notorious ‘‘arrow of time” problem in
thermodynamics. The problem, simply put, is that the laws and equations of
thermodynamics are too general to account for the ‘‘arrow of time” that we
experience and record in daily life. Because of this abstract, general
(representational) aspect, the equations operate identically in both the
forward and reverse directions and contain or express no arrow of time
whatsoever.
Prigogine solved this problem through a concept he called “active-
matter,” which, as the identical opposite of Leibniz’s concept of “active
space,” appeals (if unconsciously) to the positive infinity of esoteric
rationalism in the sense that matter (the tangibility aspect of space) also has
the property of infinite depth, activity and modification.vi Because matter, in
this view, has the active property of infinite depth of detail,vii no finitely
detailed law, equation, generalization or set of initial conditions (i.e., no
principle of the same) can absolutely predict or determine the outcome of
any sufficiently complex event, such as those in thermodynamics. And thus

i
As Deleuze called it.
ii
And as will be discussed in greater detail in the section Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of
Opposites, p659.
iii
…although a modal substrate is perhaps not quite what Deleuze meant with his “plane of
immanence.”
iv
* Recall the transcendent-bias and the pre-rational, negative/regressive infinity discussed in the
section, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias, p91.
v
…though Leibniz consciously dissolves the absolute distinction between space and matter.
vi
Space and matter, then, as should be expected, present no real dichotomy in Nondual Rationalism,
but merely a polarity based on solidity or tangibility of existence at the interface with our senses.
This is why open air, which we now know is full of “stuff” is generally considered a space. The
concept of “outer-space” is a new one to make a more refined distinction between a new kind of
space that is too intangible to be detected directly, such as with wind, by our senses.
vii
Recall our Principle of Nondual Rationalism, infinite division equals indivisibility, and how this
would naturally seem to lead to a “unified” view of reality.

Page | 184
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

“time” and process will necessarily deviate (if sometimes imperceptibly)


from the physical laws, whether the equations are run forwards or in
reverse. Indeed, this is the general category into which entropy falls and it is
this constant deviation from the equations of thermodynamics (run forward
or reverse) that is the general direction or “arrow” of time.

Spinoza’s “immanent determinism”i* can be seen in a very similar light, and


this is really the only way to consistently and coherently interpret his words
on the subject. Spinoza is generally considered a radical determinist, even a
reductionist—where all events are ultimately “determined,” necessary or
reduced to their indwelling or immanent causes. As Matthew Stewart points
out in The Courtier and the Heretic:
One of the most notorious propositions of the Ethics is: “Things could not
have been produced by God in any manner or in any order different from
that which in fact exists.” This is a logical inference from the proposition
that the relation of God to the world is something like that of an essence
to its properties [recall Spinoza’s essence as existence]: God cannot one
day decide to do things differently any more than a circle can choose not
to be round, or a mountain can foreswear the valley that forms on its side.
The view that there is a “necessary” aspect of things may be referred to by
the sometimes inappropriate name of “determinism.”
But, as Stewart goes on, such a view of Spinoza as a mere determinist or
reductionist, is a very superficial reading. This is precisely because Spinoza
takes his determinism to the absolute scope of immanence—to the
essence=existence of God and Substance, where it rebounds and reflects into
radical indeterminismii—Spinoza is at one and the same time, in this very
sense, a radical determinist and an indeterminist. Stewart says:
Of course, Spinoza acknowledges, in the world we see around us, many
things seem to be contingent—or merely possible, and not necessary.
That is, it seems that things don’t have to be the way that they are… In
fact, Spinoza goes on to say, every particular thing in the world is
contingent when considered solely with respect to its own nature. In
technical terms, he says that “existence” pertains to the essence of
nothing—save God. Thus, at some level, Spinoza stands for the opposite
of the usual caricature of the determinist as reductivist, for, according to
his line of thinking, we humans are never in a position to understand the
complete and specific chain of causality that gives any individual thing its
necessary character; consequently, we will never be in a position to

i
* See Transcendental Determinism and the Captive Will (p643), for a discussion of Transcendental
Determinism and the problem of the freedom of the will, which it causes..
ii
Recall our principle of absolute reversal…lasrever etulosba fo elpicnirp ruo llaceR

Page | 185
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

reduce all phenomena to a finite set of intelligible causes, and all things
must appear to us to be at some level radically free. (In this sense,
incidentally, he should count as a radical empiricist.)
This fundamental inability of Representation to reach or encapsulate the
deep infinity of Nature, i.e. to bound the unbounded, is a simple function of
the polarity of the finite and infinite, or the relative and absolute scopes,
respectively, as we have discussed. Any process that has a beginning or an
end, is necessarily relative, and therefore finite or bounded, even if
indefinite, with bounds yet-te-be-determined.i* The simple point is that just
as the finite cannot overtake the infinite (you can’t count to infinity),ii so the
relative scope cannot encompass or equal the absolute scope in its
immanent or transcendent aspects (this is an explicit function of the
univocity-framework and the different properties of horizontal vs. vertical
polarities at the absolute vs. relative scopes, as we will see).
In this way, unbounded or “infinite determinism”—determinism at the
absolute scope of deep infinity—is identical to indeterminism, in that it
necessitates the inability to absolutely know the (infinitely detailed) causes
of any event/object. As such, it is logically, rationally and empirically
impossible to predict or determine absolutely, the outcome of any process
and to put the ultimate causes into a finite set of intelligible laws, such as
those of thermodynamics. In this sense, Spinoza, in the 17th century, had
already solved the “arrow of time” problem, implicitly, in his radical
(absolute scope) “determinism.” It just took exoteric science 300 years to
catch up. Indeed, Spinoza’s modes, as seen through the attribute of
Extension, are already composed of Prigogine’s 300 year-old active matter,
and they already existed in Leibniz’s decades-old active space, i.e. Extension
itself.
The identity of opposites (with its implicit Principle of Absolute
Reversal), and the Univocity Framework, necessitate that, at the absolute
scope, infinite determinism and indeterminism are merely two ways of
stating the same thing. This is because, as we have seen, at the absolute
scope of the modifier ‘infinite,’ all polarities are enfolded as one. In other
words, the concept of determinism itself (as all concepts) is relative and it
has no ultimate (absolute scope) meaning apart from its (identical) opposite.
Therefore, we come to another resonating chord from our Principle of
Nondual Rationalism, which itself reverberates from the ancient principles
of nondualism, such as the identity of opposites. As will be explicated
further through the Univocity Framework, this univocal essence of deep-

i
* … i.e. a third order infinity (see Order 3: The Modal (or Bounded) Infinite:, p279).
ii
Note that even children are operationally aware, at some level, of the absolute scope, when they
jump out of the modal and relative games of magnitude invoking the modifier of, “I’m infinity!”.

Page | 186
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

infinity in active-matter/-space ultimately (absolute scope) comes down to


the following identity of opposites: infinite determinism = indeterminism.i

Explanation: Given the identity of opposites and the Principle of Absolute Reversal,
determinism, when taken to its absolute scope, rebounds or reflects of f the ineffable
absolute into its identical-opposite. An infinitely deep determinism necessitates the
inability to absolutely and completely determine, from any level or region of levels, the
outcome of any event/object; Emptiness precludes the self-identity of the forms of
time.

An instance of these distinctions in action can be seen in the different forms


of scientific explanation. Nomothetic explanations are general case
explanations using laws governing and derived from generalized categories,
whereas idiographic explanations recognize the immanent idiosyncrasies of
the individual object or event and attempt to tell the story of that particular
event/object. An example of a nomothetic explanation would be the
mechanical laws of physics, such as F = MA, whereas an example of an
idiographic explanation would be the explanation of a medical case file
culled from an exhaustive examination of the patients history of symptoms;
a symptomatology.

i
…which we could denote with the simple hyphenated variant, in-determinism…

Page | 187
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

It may indeed be the case, given the transcendent bias, that the
nomothetic explanation exclusively is imposed on the immanent world of
the quantum because we expect things to get ultimately and categorically
simple in our post-medieval and foundationalist scientific mind-set. Without
recognizing the infinite difference of immanence (Leibnizian/Prigoginian
active-space/matter), we can’t see deviations from these categories and laws
for what they are; emergent properties from immanent complexity. And so
we assume that conceptual randomness, opposing our simplified categories,
rules in this domain, rather than recognizing the limits of the nomothetic
explanation and the need for the idiographic.
This is a classic example of the transcendent-bias in action. Given the
Principle of Infinite Determinism, above, the resolution to the conundrum is
simple. Embrace the immanence of univocity and there is no need to discard
the idea of causation or determinism when our categories and laws give way
to the idiosyncrasies of the individual object-event. The call for randomness,
in every case, can be seen as the conflict and break-down of the nomothetic
categories in the entropic face of infinite difference and idiosyncrasy.
Randomness, then, calls for the idiographic methodology, in a univocal
polarity of explanatory function between the nomothetic use of the principle
of the same and the idiographic use of the principle of infinite difference.
Indeed, the laws were formed as general cases from a symptomatology in
the first place. In our foundationalist mind-set we simply expected them to
govern absolutized categories, with absolutized laws, rather than real idio-
singularities of infinite difference in interactions of infinite detail.
The Univocity Framework, therefore, opens the way beyond the closed
oppositional forces of the categories of Representation, to a recognition of
the need for an evolutionary history—a symptomatology—for each
individual “particle,” in order to get a full account of the infinite determinism
equals indeterminism of any single event-object, and indeed to account for
the “arrow of time,” in the eternal NOW. No two events are alike or
ultimately predictable, not because there are no determining factors
involved (i.e. randomness), but because there are infinitely many.i And again
we can see here the polarity of the omni-non between the categorical forces
of Representation and the acategorical imperative in the Univocity
Framework.

The above is understood more explicitly as follows. As we have discussed,


the absolute scope is best mapped (relatively) by the I/T omni-axis, giving us

i
…this is another instance of the omni-non...

Page | 188
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

the quantitative aspecti* of the ALL in the ONE. This omni-axis, when
applied to the absolute scope of the aspect of duration or time, translates
into the identity of opposites commonly called “the eternal NOW,” or simply
Eternity = NOW. This is also implicit in Spinoza’s sub specie aeternitatis, and
Spinoza’s concept of immortality in the participation of eternity in the
instant.
Deleuze explains this through a Stoic lens; “Univocity is the pure empty
form of time (Aion). Sense is on the plane of Aion,ii* that pure instant which
divides every present into both future and past directions at once.”iii¥
Eternity is the infinite transcendent pole (or directionality), of the absolute-
scope of the temporal axis. And the “infinitely small” or sizeless irreducible
instant, the NOW, is the absolute-scope of its immanent pole. Neither
absolute pole—the eternal or the NOW—is reachable through any transitive,
linear or finite (relative) means, such as multiplication or division into ever
larger or smaller intervals of time, represented to the mind as either
memory or anticipation. In principle, any interval, in space, time, or
whatever, can be divided or multiplied further. This means ultimately that
the linearity of time, i.e. the existence of a ‘‘time-line” consisting of moments,
one after another, from the past to the future, is a purely relative and
sometimes representational function. Neither the past, the future or the
‘‘time-line” itself, exist at the absolute (and sub-representational) scope. In
the immanence of the eternal-NOW, there is no absolutely and
transcendently predetermined future waiting for a “near eternity” to become
the past. There is no inescapable predetermined chain of events or tireless
iron grip of the dead hand of fate. At the absolute scope there is only the
single irreducible and unreachable, yet ever-present and inescapable, NOW
of existence, “nowing”iv in infinite difference and irreducible multiplicity for
all eternity.v See, below.
As Bucky Fuller says in his Synergetics:
The norm of Einstein is absolute speed instead of at rest. “At rest” was
what we called instantaneous in our innocence of yesterday. We evolute
toward ever lesser brain comprehension lags—ergo, toward ever
diminishing error; ergo, ever diminishing misunderstandings; ergo, ever
diminishing fear, and its brain-lagging painful errors of objectivity;
wherefore we approach eternal instantaneity of absolute and total
comprehension. The eternal instantaneity of no lag at all (529.31).

i
* See the section on the Triune Infinite and specifically the “Aspect Infinities.”
ii
* The “mnemonic interface” discussed in Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of
Observability”, p486).
iii¥
Logic of Sense, qtd in Metcalf
iv
And “wowing,” as Bucky Fuller would say.
v
We can see here implicitly enfolded the opposite-identity of the noun-verb polarity which is a
version of the deeper stasis-flux polarity.

Page | 189
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

Figure 10: The Tree of Singular Time:


In the Eternal Now of the singular individual, the present alone exists yet it vanishes
into immanent nothingness from any transitive frame of reference - the tree seems to
vanish into the nothingness of the immanent singularity of the instant at the interface
between the roots of the past and the branches of the future.

Page | 190
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

In Nondual Rationalism, the principle of univocity is our primary interface or


cultivating third between the fundamental polarity of scopes: the absolute
vs. the relative. Because the closest relative-scope approximation of the
absolute scope in the VCS is our immanent-transcendent omni-axis, and the
best representation of the relative scope is the transitive-axis, (note: recall
the VCS main graphic, p143), therefore the Univocity Framework also serves
to regulate the interaction between the two primary “axes” of the Vision-
Logic Coordinate System. Transitivity is where dualities appear, and they
are resolved by the vertical polarity (e.g. in the various forms of dependent
arising or emergence), represented by, or operationalized upon, the I/T axis.
The fundamental relativity—where the relative scope finally points
outside itself to the absolute, forming the absolute/relative polarity of
univocity and Nagarjunan nondualism—serves to balance the transcendent-
and representational-bias and to deflect any unconscious attempt at
absolutization by the relative (e.g. reductionism) by reminding us of its
identical-opposite in the ineffable absolute. This includes absolutization of
the immanent-transcendent omni-axis itself as actually being the absolute
scope, rather than merely pointing to it as an enfolded and unfolded
tautological aspect or identity in the ONE-ALL.i*
The Univocity Framework shows us that any absolutization of the
relative scope—which would include any concept without its identical-
opposite (such as matter, mind, or perspective vs. non-perspective)—is a
contradiction in terms. This is the message of nonduality made explicit and
operational in the Univocity Framework. Univocity, as the prime mediator
or polarity between the absolute and relative scopes (e.g. between “Identity
and Difference” or the “the One – All” (DR37) in Deleuze) maintains the
essence of the nondual, prohibiting absolutization of the relative and
epistemic (e.g. “the relativity of Truth”) while opening up a space for the
truth and necessity of the relative in ontological or metaphysical speculation.
It is important to keep in mind that the ontic (or sub-representation) is
not the same as the absolute, but is merely the world of form (all of which is
necessarily relative) in its real, as opposed to representational, aspect. And
even while immanent (a plane of immanence), every form or mode in the
ontic is necessarily always emergent, or transcendent (“transcendental

i
* See the Order 2: The Aspect Infinite, p273.

Page | 191
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

empiricism”), given its relative existence, or “position,” on the


Immanent/Transcendent axis. Recalling our principle of immanence in
transcendence, any position on the I/T axis is always both immanent and
transcendent, depending on from where it is viewed. Therefore, while
univocity opens the space for ontological speculation, it maintains the
relativity of that space, in effect guaranteeing that any ontological
speculation is necessarily relative and cannot be absolutized.i
For the sake of visualization we can imagine the two primary scopes of
the Univocity Framework as forming two layers, one on top of the other (see,
Figure 11 below). In this case we have arbitrarily represented the absolute
scope as above, and seemingly transcendent to, the relative, which is half-
true, but we must keep in mind that as much as the absolute is transcendent
(which is infinitely so) it is also immanent (again infinitely so). And this is
implicit in the relative representation of the absolute scope by the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis as a whole, each pole of which is a
directional aspect of Absolute Infinity, which epistemically is the
quantitative aspect of the absolute scope.
When you conceptually “arrive” at infinity (the absolute scope) in either
immanent or transcendent “direction” you have (necessarily) found the
open-ended immanent/transcendent omni-axis itself. This is because the
infinite (unbounded) cannot be a boundary (a relativity) on the omni-axis, or
a point on the uni-axis (a unit of scale) that can be reached and surpassed,
but must be seen (necessarily from the relative scope) as the infinite omni-
axis itself. This is the main feature of absolute-scope polarities; necessarily
containing (unfolding and enfolding) their identical-opposites, they are
intrinsically identities, paradoxes or tautologies, such as “ALL is ONE” or
“infinite division equals indivisibility.”

i
Thus Univocity actually enforces or enacts (operationalizes) the message of nonduality, and this is
why it is the most effective core of any “Integral Operating System.”

Page | 192
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

A. B. C.

Figure 11: The Univocity Framework Template:


The center panel (B) of this graphic lays out the template for the side panels (A,C)
i
which give examples of the framework in action. Panel A shows an absolute
polarity, which, of necessity contains its opposite and results in an identity or
tautology. Panel B shows a relative polarity, which cultivates through triunity into a
symbiogenesis or structural coupling at an interface. In the main triptych, the
sections designated by the ontic/epistemic polarity are the relative scope, whereas
the section directly above the relative scope is the absolute scope. The top -most
section of the triptych describes each of the three panels below it.

The primary function of the Univocity Framework is to interface and


mediate the absolute and relative scopes, therefore we can draw another
axis (vision-logic level axis), the “univocity axis,” between them, to show this
interface, connection and orientation (the center vertical axis in the above
diagram, and in the center of every “univocity pendulum”). However, as are
all axes and real polarities, the univocity axis itself is fully operational only
within the relative scope (the real world of form), as it points (but does not
reach) outside itself to the absolute. The univocity axis merely serves to

i
It is interesting to note the similarity of this diagram to an earlier dream of mine. In this dream, a
dark bony woman was constructing and speaking a sign language with triangles and a pendulum
form in the middle out of her many long bony fingers.

Page | 193
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

orient the relative and absolute scopes and to denote the vertical direction
in the framework. In the relative scope, the I/T axis is aligned with the
univocity axis, but again, both immanent and transcendent directions point
(in their infinite aspects) to the absolute scope. This is because they deal
with the omni/non polarity of the aspect of locality, rather than the
transitive left-right types of polarities.
This aspect of the immanent-transcendent axis, where each pole points
to the absolute scope, is contrary to the diagram which necessarily has to
show one pole closer to the absolute scope than the other. In this case, it
shows the immanent direction as pointing toward, or emerging from, the
absolute scope. This is because we are counteracting the transcendent-bias
and focusing on the ontic as the emergent triune-interface between the
relative and absolute scopes. The point is that the epistemic is an emergent
subset of the real-world of form, the ontic, but it is also true that the ontic is
both immanent and transcendent to the interface of representation, or the
epistemic. So in this sense, the epistemic can be seen as the triune interface
between the immanent and transcendent aspects of the ontic.i*
Circles in the above univocity diagram denote modifications, or modes,
while lines denote emergence or directionalities of thought. Solid lines (and
solid circles) denote real, or ontic, directions (emergence or an actual
identity) while dotted lines denote representational lines. The principle of
Absolute Reversal (and the identity of absolutized opposites) is denoted by
the triangular line that reflects off the boundary of the absolute scope, since
relativities make no sense and have no function in the absolute scope.
The two examples (A, C) illustrate the two main kinds of polarity,
absolute and relative, respectively. The absolute polarity, seen in the
absolute scope level of example A, illustrates the seemingly “paradoxical”
nature of absolute scope polarities, such as “infinite division equals
indivisibility,” and that the two poles (and the polarity itself) are illusory, or
representational and relative aspects (dotted circles) of the same
absolutized concept, e.g. divisibility. In example C, we have the relative
scope polarity (a real polarity, as opposed to an identity or tautology) of the
symbiogenesis of subject and object where the real duality is reconciled (and
symbiogenetically emergent) by the cultivating third of the sub-
representational (and immanent) “mnemonic primitives” at the “interface”
between subject and object.ii*
These two examples are both horizontal polarities in the Univocity
Framework, but we can also see the vertical polarity, or the holarchy of the
ontic and epistemic (or the sub-representational and representational,
respectively). As discussed, if a vertical polarity has one pole within the

i
* see Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
ii
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.

Page | 194
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

absolute scope, we have a violation of the Univocity Framework and the


principle of absolute reversal. Any mono-pole taken to the absolute scope
necessarily reflects into its opposite in the relative scope. The only
polarities allowable at the absolute scope are those that have both poles
(identical-opposites) in the absolute, and these break down to tautologies,
seeming paradoxes and (numerical) identities, and are thus not real
polarities or differences.

In the Univocity Framework graphic above we have the two fundamental


scopes, the absolute and the relative. Between these two scopes we have
stretched another axis, the univocity or “primary scope axis.” Each of these
scopes has fundamentally different conceptual and operational properties.
But further, any polarity orthogonal or perpendicular (horizontal) to this
primary scope axis between the absolute and relative scopes, will be
confined to one of its primary poles, i.e. either the absolute or the relative
scope, and will be subject to the operations of that level. At the absolute
scope, the polarity will be “nonreal,” and non-relational, or merely
tautological (an identity), whereas at the relative scope, the horizontal
polarity will be a real difference, an interface of some sort, like that between
left and right, up and down or subjectivity and objectivity.
The axis of univocity represents this primary ontic relation between the
absolute and relative scopes, and what it ultimately means is that the
absolute and relative are one, but only “seen” or addressed differently via
different conceptual scopes due to the polar nature of human
comprehension itself.i* This ONE-ALL relation of univocity ultimately means
that unity can only be understood as identical with infinite difference, which
brings us back to our identity of opposites in the understanding of univocity
as a function of the polarity of polarity.ii*
The absolute level is the level of unity and identity and (in explanation of
Wittgenstein’s logic of axioms, where axioms are always tautologies) this is
the level of tautology and paradox. For example, given Leibniz’s Identity of
Indiscernables as expressing the identity aspect of univocity, the only “thing”
that can be absolutely identical to anything else is that “thing” in relation to
itself. An orthogonal polarity at the absolute scope, therefore, will be merely
a dual or cyclical representation of the same absolute identity, i.e. a
tautology, whereas a polarity at the relative level (the level of polarity itself
which we project on the absolute in the primary polarity of univocity) will
be a “true” (or non-tautological) polarity, i.e. a real difference in dependent

i
* See the section, Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind, p112.
ii
* see the sub-section above, “Vertical” Polarity: The Polarity of Polarity, p175.

Page | 195
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

arising,i e.g. the symbiogenesis of subject and object, the dependent arising
of mind and matter, or Fuller’s “unity is plural and at minimum two,” which
says that any mode (finite unity) necessitates, at least, an inside and an
outside.

Perhaps the best way to really understand the Univocity Framework is to


see it in action in the detection and correction of errors in univocal or
nondual thinking. In The Courtier and the Heretic, Matthew Stewart provides
a ripe example from the metaphysics of Leibniz. In Leibniz’s monadology, a
monad or individual is, first and foremost, immortal, and hence is conceived
as a substance, complete or independent unto itself.ii Because of this need in
Leibniz’s “popular religion” of his monadology for a personal or individual
immortality, monads are famously considered “windowless” and incapable
(and not in need) of interacting with their environment including any other
monad. They are, in essence, independent numerical identities or
absolutized logical and metaphysical categories incapable of dependent
arising. Stewart says:
In order to rid the world of Spinoza’s theory of mind [as modal, relative
and hence mortal], Leibniz must first annihilate Spinoza’s idea of
Substance. For, in declaring that God alone is Substance, Spinoza reduces
human beings to mere modes of Substance, and thereby renders our
minds material and mortal [[dependent]]. Leibniz’s strategy is therefore
to replace the idea that God alone is Substance with the claim that there is
a plurality of substances in the world. By identifying the mind with these
new substances, Leibniz intends to secure for humankind a degree of
indestructibility, power and freedom that his rival philosopher associates
only with God [[independence]] (p245).
Leibniz is here misunderstanding (or purposefully neglecting and
misrepresenting, as is often the case with Leibniz) the inherent polarity and
identity of opposites, of Substance and its modes, the ONE and the ALL of its
infinite multiplicity, and the absolute and relative scopes of Substance. For
Spinoza, there is only Substance and its modifications, and modifications are
not independently real, just as forms have no independent and inherent
identity in Emptiness. A mode participates in immortality (sub specie
aeternitatis) because it is an aspect or modality of God and Substance. To

i
Note that with univocity the relative and the absolute are fundamentally interdependent, or inter-
expressive. This means that Einstein’s absolutization of the relative scope in his relativity theories
violates the Univocity Framework, which actually explains why it is fundamentally incomprehensible
and irrational, as we will see.
ii
This, already, is an obvious violation of the principle of dependent arising.

Page | 196
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

absolutize the mode—giving it the boundless properties of the absolute


scope with respect to time, i.e. the property of timelessness, or eternity—is
to absolutize the relativity of boundary and the form of personal identity; to
confuse the worlds of Emptiness and form, Substance and mode.
[Leibniz] further infers…that the number of such substances is infinite for
roughly the same reason that the number of points on a line is infinite
[recall the labyrinth of the continuum]. No matter how small a slice of the
universe you take, it will contain an infinite number of substances. … he
dubs these substances with a name derived from the Greek for “unity,”
first used by his predecessor Giordano Bruno… monads.
… As substances … monads must be entirely self-contained. That is,
they depend on nothing else to be what they are. The most important
implication of this is that they cannot interact with one another in any
way at all—for, if they did so, one monad could conceivably alter the
nature of another monad, and this would imply that its nature depends on
the activity of some other substance, which, by definition of substance, is
not permissible. Thus, monads are—in Leibniz’s notably poetic
language—“windowless.” They can’t see out, and you can’t see in.
Stewart goes on a bit later…
One of the most striking and controversial inferences that Leibniz draws
from the substantial nature of the monad is that a monad’s future is
written into its essence from the very beginning of things. He expresses
this daring doctrine in terms of logic as well as metaphysics. The
“complete” concept of a substance, he says, must contain all the predicates
that ever have been and ever will be true of it.
Instead of windows, Leibniz says, eternal monads flash into existence
complete with “mirrors” that can show them, in some aspect, the entire
universe and their place in it, all somehow without any real conduit to the
outside, since they can’t have any windows or external dependencies. It
makes one wonder how a monad could act on such causeless information
without it “changing his nature.” This monad-mirror, gives Leibniz’s system
a strange version of infinite depth of complexity, like a hologram or the
Hindu concept of “Indra’s net,”i but at the expense of dependent arising
necessary for a nondual view of relative modalities, such as boundaries and,
it would seem, monads. Stewart says:

i
Indra's Net: “Hinduism and Buddhism give life to the idea of Indra's Net. In the heaven of Indra, a
vast net or web of silken strands spans across space infinitely in every direction. Every intersection
of gossamer thread hosts a shining luminous pearl or multifaceted jewel. The surface of every jewel
completely reflects every other, and the net as a whole. Likewise, each reflected jewel in itself
reflects every other, that reflects every other, that reflects every other, without end, as mirrors to
infinity. Indra's Net may alternately be known as ‘Indra's Pearls,’ or the ‘Jewel Net of Indra.’” (from
answers.com)

Page | 197
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

By means of these “mirrors” of consciousness, each monad replicates the


entire universe of monads within itself; and so each monad is a “universe
in prototype.”
Leibniz is here trying to have it both ways in order to make room for the
independence of personal immortality in opposition to the radical rationality
and modernity of his own inherent Spinozism. Indeed, Leibniz’s entire
philosophy, as Stewart shows, can be seen as a reaction against the
modernity of Spinozism, and the absolute category of the monad is the
cornerstone of this reaction. Leibniz wants independent monads—an
infinity of substances—who can see outside without the causal inter-
dependencies (interface of dependent arising) necessary for perception.
This is clearly an absurd result of his reactionary metaphysical postulates of
monad/selves as isolated/eternal substances. These monad-substances are
numerical or absolute distinctions, and given our rules of the absolute in the
Univocity Framework, an absolute distinction, difference or polarity, cannot
stretch vertically into the relative; a mono-pole is “forbidden” to mono-
polize the absolute scope at the expense of its identical-opposite. And, recall,
such an absolute polarity can only therefore be a tautology, otherwise it is a
contradiction in terms, a conflation of prefused scope, and a violation of
univocity and Nondual Rationalism. Stewart continues (my emphasis):
Leibniz refers to this strange vision of worlds within worlds as “the
principle of the microcosm and macrocosm”—meaning that the
microcosm contains or replicates the macrocosm all the way down to the
infinitely small. He expresses the same notion in his claim that the
ancient doctrine that “All is One” must now be supplemented with the
equally important corollary that “One is All.”
This is truly a fascinating idea, and one that we will explore and make sense
of in great depth.i* But according to the identity of opposites and the nature
of the horizontal polarity at the absolute scope, the absolute plural and the
absolute singular must be identical; ALL can only and always equal its
identical-opposite ONE, it cannot equal “one” monad in relation to the
infinitely many other individual monads which it can see in its magic Indra’s
mirror. Polarity at the absolute scope is tautological. The absolute, by
definition, cannot be split into a symbiogenetic and purely relative polarity,
but only an absolute identity and tautology; e.g. ONE = ALL.

This may be easier to understand in terms of the principle of univocity;


(absolute) unity (or Identity) has one voice and can only express (relative)
difference. Since the unity (absolute scope) can only express difference
(relativity), then difference at the scope of unity is not real difference, but
merely identity. A polarity at the absolute level of identity can only be a dual

i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 198
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK

way of seeing/saying the same identical “thing,” because this “thing” (the
absolute level) enfolds and unfolds all things, concepts, their opposites and
polarities and cannot be encapsulated by any of them.
The polarity of the ancient “All is One” is, and always was, horizontal and
absolute; an identity and ultimately a tautology, however useful it is as such.
With his monad as the boundary between “macrocosm and microcosm” (the
solidus in I/T and in the vision-logic equation ∞/∞), Leibniz has tacitly
shifted (equivocated) from the absolute scope of unbounded or Infinite
Unity,i to the relative scope of the monad, the mode or finite unity.ii It is
only, and exactly, half true that the monad contains within itself the All of
Infinite Difference. The other half of the All that the monadic interface
exactly bisects is the infinite without, or the transcendent pole of the
immanent/transcendent uni-axis which the monadic interface conceptually
spans.iii
The original “ALL is ONE” is, therefore, already and necessarily an
absolute identity (in mathematical terms, an “equality”) and thus “ONE is
ALL” is already the same statement as “ALL is ONE.” In other words, if ALL =
ONE then it follows necessarily, and indeed trivially, that ONE = ALL, just as
it follows from 2+2=4 that 4=2+2. But it doesn’t follow, necessarily (or at
all), that “one = ALL.” An identity necessarily goes both ways and none,
because, ultimately, they are the same “thing.” The line in the equation and
its arbitrary direction are an artifact of the linearity of symbolic thought, not
of the identity itself.
But given that Leibniz is talking about his monad, and hence the relative
scope of the “one,” not the “ONE,” this trivial identity and reversed tautology
of ALL=ONE is clearly not the sense in which he means “All is One” in his
principle of macrocosm and microcosm. The con-fusion is cleverly hidden in
the conflation of the undifferentiated, pre-fused and undisclosed scope
parameters of the term “ONE,” which provides for the undetected point of
ambiguity upon which this equivocation turns to the “one”. In Leibniz’s tacit
shift from absolute to relative scope in his principle of macrocosm and
microcosm—from the ONE to the one—the finite unity of the monad, the
“one” is taken as the illogical, or otherwise tautological, numerical (absolute)
distinction between the “one” and the “ALL,” forcing the independent
(tautological) attribute of the absolute on the monad rendering it necessarily
“windowless,” and merely self-identical. We will see, however, that indeed,

i
And the scope of the 1st order Absolute Infinity. See the section on The Triune Infinite: Interfacing
Emptiness (p268), and also the section on Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
ii
… the level of the 3rd order infinite, or bounded infinite
iii
Leibniz’s corollary in the “principle of macrocosm and microcosm” is true, however, in the sense
that the interface could not exist without the infinity within and the infinity without, the I/T axis of
the ONE is ALL. The within/without and the triuning/tuning-in interface (the I/T and its solidus
divider) are also polar opposites.

Page | 199
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY

in the sense that the monadic interface (and real difference) is composed of
an infinite depth of detail, it does indeed rest in the absolute of the ONE, and
refract into the ONE-ALL through the Cycle of Unity (p257).
Leibniz equivocates either unknowingly and/or simply to justify the
principle of the macrocosm and microcosm with a twist on an ancient
truism. And all of this complex verbal wizardry—with its smoke-and-
mirrors sleight-of-hand scope-equivocation and con-fusion—in turn is to
justify the absolutized immanent mono-pole of the monad, eternal and
independent (absolute scope), yet whose beginning in time is dependent
(relative scope) on the choice of a providential transcendent God who could
not really have chosen other than this “best of all possible worlds.” And
thus, to conserve this univocity violation, God must create each eternal and
independent monad in a flash of transcendent-bias and a puff of scope con-
fusion, each with a magic mirror that can see Indra’s Net without causing a
change or a perception in the unobserving observer.

Page | 200
Page | 201
Page | 202
Despite the wild success of mathematics in its pragmatic roles in science and
technology, mankind has long been plagued with paradox and confusion
when it comes to infinity and number and the relation of mathematics to
physical and mental reality. Typical discussions about these mathematical
issues, in both specialist and vernacular tongues, hide a tangled mess of
oxymorons, equivocations and deeply rooted ideological conflicts. These
confusions (and indeed con-fusionsii*) hide behind seemingly innocuous
common phrases such as “infinitely small,” or “infinitely many,” as well as
more formal and rigorous philosophical/mathematical problems such as the
paradoxes of the infinite; the philosophical and commonsense problems
with the limit and the infinitesimal of the calculus; and the controversy and
confusion surrounding Cantor’s notion of the transfinite in modern set
theory.
The bulk of these problems, it will be shown, arise ultimately from
misunderstandings and con-fusions about the fundamentally polar, nondual
and univocal relationship between infinity and number (the finite)—which,
as we have seen and will see in much greater detail below, are the
quantitative aspects of the absolute and relative scopes, respectively.iii* This
con-fusion in turn arises from errors in the common meta-mathematical and
philosophical paradigm, an aborted, distorted and pre-mature rationalism,


From “To Believe and to Think”, qtd. in Escher on Escher p.150)
ii
* A con-fusion is a conflation of a prefused distinction. See Con-Fusions at the Interface, p122.
iii
* see Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind, p112.

Page | 203
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

through which (among other things) we conceptualize and understand


mathematical operations.
This current mode of under-developed mathematical understanding
(meta-mathematics) is characterized by an extreme level of abstraction, i.e. a
paucity of percept in its abstract concepts. This is due to the academically-
common disabling separation of concept from percept—the causal, visual,
and hence visceral, connection to the imagination and intuition, and our
evolved cognitive interface with reality. This percept-anemia results in a
lack of conceptual coherence and explanatory power in mathematics, easily
accounting for the difficulty of learning and hence the fear, and even dread,
which mathematics is notoriously capable of invoking in students. Problems
in thinking, teaching and learning arise because the deeper percept-based
distinctions underlying mathematical thought remain fused at the pre-
rational level with its transcendent-bias and dominance of representational
forces, i.e. concepts abstracted from their originating percepts.
We will find that the utilization and expansion of our Vision-Logic
Coordinate System (VCS) and Univocity Framework, for understanding the
basic elements of mathematics, such as number and infinity, as well as for
distinguishing between the different operational polarities (axes) tacitly
underlying the various operations in mathematics, readily resolves these
paradoxes and confusions. It grounds the mind in an experiential model for
deeper understanding. This deeper understanding then provides for a
powerful resonance between mathematics and nondual-rational, or trans-
rational, philosophy, an integration seen more explicitly in the work of
Leibniz, for example (and Spinoza as well, to the extent that he was a
mathematician).
We will add to the VCS and Univocity Framework, much greater clarity
and understanding through making a distinction between the different kinds
or degrees of infinity, as first hinted at by Spinoza and later adopted by
Leibniz, and adding the “VCS meta-tags” and “vision-logic equations,” to help
us quickly keep track of these deeper-level distinctions and to reason about
them simply and symbolically, as well as perceptually. Elucidating these
distinctions between aspects that were previously fused and conflated (and
hence con-fused) in common thinking, renders discussions about infinity in
all its various forms much more specific and clear, and therefore much
easier to understand and communicate. This revitalized and fleshed-out
distinction dissolves the common paradoxes and confusions rather
effortlessly when understood and applied properly.
Given this new foundation in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System, the
whole thing (metaphysics, mathematics, physics, epistemology) fits together
in a much greater harmony in the conceptual mind. With this model,
mathematics has been rendered into its holonic and truly rational and
nondual form which exactly matches the form of modern “trans-
foundational” holonic notions of reality, such as Ken Wilber’s “Integral post-

Page | 204
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

metaphysics,”i as well as the emerging fractal cosmologies of Rob Oldershaw


et al, and the emerging holonic paradigms of fundamental physics.ii
Through the re-integration of concept with percept at the vision-logic
level of cognition—with the help of the Vision-Logic Coordinate System
(VCS), the patterns, tools and operations used in one domain become
naturally transferable to the others because all conceptual domains are
enacted in their deeper, self-similar, holonic percept-based forms.
Consequently, the principles, VL-axes and basic concepts at the meta-level of
the VCS and the more abstract and general level of meta-mathematics and
even mathematics itself, sets up a harmonious self-similar resonance
echoing among all these knowledge domains, integrating the differentiations
into a more evolved whole; making an organism out of a mere collection—a
holon out of a heap.

The problems with mathematical thinking, however, extend far beyond the
percept-impoverished common meta-mathematics and lead directly to
metaphysical or epistemological errors with the relation of number (an
epistemic or representational holon or “meme”) to reality (the ontic-level of
a sub-representational or real distinction, or unity, such as an atom or
apple). Since the whole of the philosophies and sciences is a transcend-and-
include holarchy, these deeper metaphysical and epistemological problems
(which extend beyond mathematics) have contributed to the unfortunate
abandonment of causation in modern physics and its 21st century trajectory
into highly abstract (blind-logic) and convoluted mathematics, such as the
“higher-dimensionality” (what I call black-box metaphysics) found in String
Theory, which lacks any causal and experiential method for understanding
its arcane and highly inelegant mathematics. We will explore this in great
depth in SpinbitZ: Volume II.
Modern meta-mathematics and hence mathematical physics are “non-
modelable” and in effect, pre-rational. They do not function in harmony with
the perceptual foundations of the human mind, and hence cannot be
modeled effectively in the imagination—and, as a subset of self-similar
reality, the mind should naturally be able to echo itself into a reflexive
understanding of its own unified or nondual substrate as dependently
arising in both external (objective) and internal (subjective) reality. The
limits and functions of standard mathematics are abstracted, simplified and
generalized far away from those of causation and physical reality, so if
mathematics is to replace causation in our models, then special care must be
taken to define and account for those differences, enabling us to retain a

i
minus its shadow element of academic misinterpretations and aborted rationality and the
performative contradictions forced therefrom.
ii
… such as Steven Rado’s Aethro-Kinematics and, most importantly, Gerald Lebau’s Sorce Theory

Page | 205
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

reasonable calibration (Fuller’s “modelability”) between number and


objective, causal reality, and between arithmetic and geometry.

Mathematics, as understood herein, is the art and science of pure relation, or


the representational artifice and interface of the abstract realm of form in
univocal polarity with Emptiness (e.g. the polarity of Infinity and number).i
In the embryogenesis of the concept, from generality to specificity,
mathematics operates at the very root of relation, or as Henri Poincaré puts
it, “the harmony within.” As we will see, this harmony within of pure relation
is abstracted from percept into recursive layers of concept; an unfolding,
complexifying differentiating-and-integrating, holarchical embryogenesis of
symbolic operation which has lost track of its perceptual and imaginative
origins.
Mathematics is merely a tool for abstracting and interfacing the
quantitative/multiplicative aspects of the finite and infinite at the most
abstract and general level of relation. This depth of generality in the
embryogenesis of the concept gives mathematics its power and extreme
applicability for modeling relation in virtually all fields of conceptual,
exploratory or empirical endeavor. This power from generality, however, is
the very reason that mathematics can so easily be abused. There is so much
raw resonance with reality-based complexity evident in this art and science
of pure relation that it is very difficult to draw the line between reality itself
and the novel worlds intrinsic to the medium itself. This difficulty naturally
makes it easy to confuse the two and fall into the essentialism of
mathematical Platonism.
Mathematics transcends-and-includes the pre-mathematical. It brings
with its own emergence new forms not previously existing and not
mirroring anything else. As an emergent, it possesses its own nature, apart
from its mirroring or mimetic properties. Indeed mathematics seems to be a
more general, rarefied and rigorous laboratory for the study of
conceptualization itself, so its study maps directly to the study of semantics,
in the immanent direction, and to philosophy in the transcendent, as we will
see. So the study of math, from a vision-logic point of view, provides a kind
of general embryogenetic map of conceptual thinking which helps to avoid
conflations and confusions, such as paradoxes, in all sorts of fields. Math,
being the art and science of pure relation, seems to provide a simple or
distilled example of thinking, in general. All the paradoxes of math and
philosophy, for example, are rendered moot when the proper (nondual)
meta-context is available.

i
And in this designation, we are making no fundamental distinction between logic and mathematics.
Mathematics may be a form of logic or logic a form of mathematics, it is not clear, and perhaps, at
this level, meaningless.

Page | 206
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

This view of mathematics as the art and science of pure relation,


however, does not rule out the mathematical aspects or “essence” intrinsic to
reality or relation itself drawn out by neo-/Pythagoreans and Platonists.
Quite the contrary. Reality can at once be both mathematical and other than
(or beyond) mathematics as the art and science of relation. It is real relation
itself, in this interface of mathematics with reality, that endows mathematics
with its power of modeling relation. This is, in effect, a power of self-
similarity between reality and its real echoes into its representational
interfaces, and the same self-similarity is at work in the interface between
knowledge itself (episteme) and reality (the ontic) interpenetrating and
harmonizing throughout Nondual Rationalism, as a whole.

Starting from R. Buckminster Fuller’s integrated percept-concept notion of


“a return to modelability” and “Operational Mathematics,” a simple
topological or visual analysis of infinity and number as a polarity and triune
interface of the unbounded and the bounded (Emptiness and form), presents
a natural and intuitive solution for understanding the fundamental
difference and inter-expressive relation between mathematics, number,
mathematical operations and the various forms of the infinite. This system
grounds mathematics in the visual, holarchical and conceptual categories,
distinctions and limitations necessary to unify mathematics with nondual
and integrative ontology and epistemology. Once understood, this visual
model renders the commonly hidden errors of mathematical thinking
glaringly obvious and rather elementary—like trying to put a square peg
into a round hole. This is the value of visual-visceral thinking; it uses the
evolved and powerful transcended-and-included sensorial capacities of the
human mind in visualization to aid in self-similar correlation and reflection
between the abstractions of mathematics the mind and physical reality. This
simple visual and conceptual grounding solves the many common
mathematical paradoxes through the development of a clear, distinct and
integrated perceptual and conceptual context.

Page | 207
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

In the perceptual foundations of the mind operates a hidden logic of sets.


This logic is encoded in the very process of development. It is the logic of the
relation of the parts to the whole. We encounter this part-whole relation as
an infant onwards, inescapably in the interaction with the parts and wholes
of our relative world. We see it, feel it, hear it, and even smell it and taste it,
whenever something falls to the earth and breaks apart, or when we pull
something apart into its constituents, or put something together making a
larger whole.
When you take apart an orange, for example, you can see, feel and smell
that you have broken beneath the aromatic boundary of rind and are now
operating at the collective level of wedges. When you break through the
skin-boundary of those wedges, pulling them apart, you can again easily
sense that you are now operating at a different and even deeper level; the
realm of those squirting little sacks of juice. One wouldn’t imagine, in this
natural percept-concept mode of thinking, that a little sack of juice is equal
in size, quantity of taste, or magnitude to an entire orange full of them.
Similarly, it is senseless to think that an innermost Russian doll is the same
size as the outermost, or the inner core of an onion equal in circumference to
the outer skin, or that it contains as many onion shells within it.
A set, in this “implicit holonic set theory,” is a collection of parts taken at
a higher level, as a whole, a boundary. A holonic set is a bounded-collection,

Page | 208
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

a whole made of parts, and parts that make a whole; a whole-part or a part-
whole, or simply a holon.i A good example would be a collection of marbles,
taken at a higher level in a sack. At a still higher level we can take another
collection of many sacks of marbles in a still larger sack. And any sack of
sacks of marbles will still be part of a larger environment, such as the child’s
bedroom where the game of marbles is played. There is no set that is not a
subset of a larger set; no whole that is not a part of a larger whole. And in
the set-holarchy, it is naturally unthinkable that one of our marbles can be
equal in size to the whole sack of marbles which contains it, or that a sack at
the first level has the same number of marbles as a sack of sacks of marbles
at the second level surrounding it, or that a single marble is equivalent in
size to a room in which a game is played with them.
We naturally, implicitly and “unthinkingly” are programmed by evolution
to keep track of the immanent or transcendent (emergent) levels in the
holarchy of bounded-collections as we break them down into parts or build
them up into wholes. This natural, intuitive or implicit logic—founded upon
the human perception of sets as bounded collectionsii—is encoded, if
abstractly and incompletely, in the “part-whole axiom” of classical
mathematics which states simply that “every set is greater than its proper
subset.” Everything we experience in the relative world of form is bounded,
in some sense, and made of deeper collections. These “implicit sets” are, in
essence, boundaries around deeper collections, themselves boundaries
around still-deeper collections—potentially, logically, and very possibly, ad
infinitum. It is only when the self-identity of abstract categories comes into
play that these natural faculties have no ground or traction in difference and
begin to slip, leading to paradox.
In the implicit holonic logic of sets, for example, it makes little sense to
have a collection of nothings, or an “empty collection.” The more sensible
way to phrase it would be that we have no collection at all; a non-collection.
This brings us to a question, indeed an equivocation—a juicy semantic
ambiguity buried under a mountain of dry concepts and categories, hidden
at the very core of the controversies of modern (axiomatic) set theory. Is a
set a collection or a container? If it is a collection, or a “collection of
objects,”iii as it is commonly claimed, then the “empty set” (as I will show in

i
Note 1: The use of ‘holon’ in a theory of sets, is necessarily more abstract and general than a holon
in the typical use, such as that by Ken Wilber. Abstracted out of the typical equation is the necessity
of the notion of emergence, since we are dealing with holarchies of mere “classes” or abstract
categories. When using implicit holonic set theory to refer to real-world holarchies, emergence
must again be factored in. Note 2: We could also call this holon the “anatom” in that it is the
antithesis of the atom. The anatomic corpuscle in not indivisible, but infinitely divisible. It has an
anatomy.
ii
…and this, in turn is part of a holarchy, as we have seen in the section, Vision-logic Interfaces:
Vision-logic and Blind-logic, p124…
iii
From Wikipedia: Axiomatic set theory: The basic concepts of set theory are set and membership. A
set is thought of as any collection of objects, called the members (or elements) of the set.

Page | 209
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

more depth below) is inconceivable, unimaginable and illogical, and merely


implies the absence of a set; a non-set. If a set is a container, on the other
hand, which is needed to make sense of the non-collection of the empty-set,
denoted, for example, by the notation {}, then an infinite set—such as that
used extensively by Cantor and modern axiomatic set theory—is infinitely
illogical and inconceivable, because a container cannot sensibly be “infinite in
size”; a boundary, by definition, cannot be boundless. An infinite container,
then, would likewise be a non-container.
In axiomatic set theory, this naïve question brought on by the rigorous
application of the imagination is considered moot. Along with it, the
percepts that originally formed the basis of our notions of set-relations have
been buried under a mass of conceptual abstraction. At this level sets are no
longer conceived by means of the sensorial imagination as either boundaries
or collections, or even more sensibly as bounded-collections, but, in
actuality, only abstractly and technically as categories, or “classes.” As the
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states (my emphasis), “The language of
set theory is based on a single fundamental relation, called MEMBERSHIP.”
The more modern and rigorous definition of a set is that it is “determined by
its elements.”i¥ This new definition is at once more verbally precise and yet
more semantically general or ambiguous. Indeed, it is this generality of
classes which provides its power and high degree of applicability. But one
must always be wary of what is lost in this kind of transition up or down the
EOTC, and in this case, as we will see, what was lost led to a critical paradox.
This paradox in turn, forced the transition from “naïve” to “axiomatic” set
theory, which effectively, though incompletely, reinstated the previous
restrictions of the holonic logic of sets implicit in the human mind, but in
purely “axiomatic” or syntactic machinations, leaving the perceptually
embodied human mind in the dark.

What is the cost of this transition from the implicit, specific and empirically-
derived holonic notion of sets to the explicit general notion of sets as classes
with relations of membership? What is lost in the divorce of concept from
percept in the modern purely categorical notion of sets? As we have seen,
this abstraction of classes—now freed from the perceptual clues and
restrictions of implicit holonic set theory—allows a tacit equivocation of sets
as collections and as boundaries or containers, while blurring the
distinctions and relations of both. In effect, the axiomatic and categorical
modern notion of a set has been stripped of its immanent/transcendent
holarchical information and rendered purely in terms of a transitive-plane of
self-identity. All sets as categories are now conceived in freedom from
natural holarchy, causing a naïve disruption of the connections of percept


Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Set Theory; < http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ >

Page | 210
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

taken for granted and forgotten in the movement into concept. These lost
connections in naïve set theory are the bonds symbolically or axiomatically
replaced in the newer axiomatic versions of set theory, and, as we will see, in
the study of mereology, literally the logic or study of parts.
In the naïve, abstracted freedom of the categorical set, breaking from the
holarchical, immanent/transcendent percept-aspect of sets as containers,
allows for the “infinite set,” such as the universal set—or the boundless
category of ALL categories (note the absolute scope). Unlike any holonic or
real-world set, the universal set appears to be a member of itself, i.e. it’s own
subset. The universal category of all categories, is itself a category, and so, it
would seem—according to these abstract rules of class and membership—it
is a sub-category of itself. (This, we can quickly see, leads to an infinite
regress of self-recursion, akin to the “grandfather paradox” in similarly
abstract musings on time-travel.)
Likewise, equivocating in abstraction in the other direction, away from
the explicit definition of a set as a “collection of objects,” or subsets, allows
the implicit holonic aspect of a set as a whole, a boundary or a container, to
re-emerge. This equivocation, in turn, allows the undisclosed set-as-
container to contain a collection of nothing, providing us with the useful, but
problematic, empty-set. Without this implicit equivocation from sets as
collections to sets as containers the empty-set would be meaningless—a
non-set—just as in the other direction we get the non-container of the
infinite set (boundless boundary). Yet at the same time, this equivocation to
sets-as-containers explicitly denies Cantor’s special use of the unbounded or
infinite set in his transfinite orders due to the absurdities of the “infinite
container.”
An empty collection is simply not a collection at all. It is a non-collection;
a non-set. Even in terms of the common definition of a set as a “collection of
objects,” the empty set is explicitly not a set. There is no “collection of
objects” in the empty set. And in the more abstract notion of sets as defined
by the “fundamental relation” of sets and membership—“a set is determined
by its elements”—there are no elements in an empty set, and there can be no
relation between a set and its non-existing elements. It clearly takes a tacit
equivocation in the definition of a set (as a collection, not a container) to
reach the empty container of the empty-set—the non-relation between a
class and its missing members—and this is easily achieved in axiomatic set
theory when concept (and reason) is freed from the causal/empirical
restraints of percept, our interface with reality, implicit in the holonic logic
of sets.
This equivocation can be seen clearly in attempts to make sense of the
empty-set. The article in Wikipedia on the “empty set” states (my
emphasis): “The empty set is not the same thing as nothing; it is a set with
nothing inside it, and a set is something. This often causes difficulty among
those who first encounter it. It may be helpful to think of a set as a bag

Page | 211
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

containing its elements; an empty bag may be empty, but the bag itself
certainly exists.”i¥ Recall the definition of a set as “a collection of objects.”
We now have a new definition of a set as a “bag” or container for, not of
objects, or even just an empty container. Both of these aspects of sets were
abstracted from the implicit holonic logic of sets, but when taken separately,
and indeed equivocated between, they allow sets that have lost their
immanent/transcendent aspects and “violate” the Univocity Framework,
reaching into the absolute scope. This, in turn, causes the well-known
problems with both the universal and the empty set.
The universal and the empty set each form two identical-opposite non-
holonic, and absolute-scope aspects of modern set theory. The universal set
is the aspect of absolute unbounded affirmation—allowing the “collection of
objects” to be conceived, non-holonically, as its own sub-collection. And the
empty-set is the non-holonic aspect of absolute unbounded negation,
allowing the tacit definition of sets as containers to be filled with the non-
collection of emptiness. The empty set, unlike the universal set, explicitly
cannot be a member of itself, because then it would no longer be empty. It
would be filled with an empty, abstract, infinite recursion of its self-negating
self, similar to the universal set.ii
Neither the universal set nor the null set, are “proper” sets, in the implicit
holonic logic of sets because they break from the implicit logic of sets as
bounded-collections, or part-wholes; they break from the relative world of
form into the absolute realm of the formless. They possess the absolute and
unbounded aspects of affirmation and negation, respectively. A set, in this
empirical/sensorial holonic logic, is necessarily a relativity; a part-whole,
collection-container, set/member relation. A holonic set is a relation with
other holonic sets, but critically within in an infinite, unbounded holarchy: a
critical univocal polarity of polarity, between the absolute and relative scope
of the infinite and finite; the boundless and bounded; the holarchy and the
holon. A set is the relative, bounded aspect of the univocal polarity. The
universal set breaks from the container aspect of the holonic set, which in
turn is needed to sustain the notion of the empty-set in its tacit breaking
from the explicit definition of the set as a collection. They each break in the
opposite direction from relative-scope, holonic percept-concept of the
bounded-collection—the whole made of parts, of the implicit holonic set
theory—to the absolute scope of the formless and unbounded.

So, what happens when we mix the two non-holonic, absolutized aspects
of the universal and null sets? Suppose that we can form a set of ALL sets, a
universal set of sets that, like the empty set, are not included in themselves.


Wikipedia: Empty-Set; <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empty_set>
ii
The empty set is the set-theory equivalent of the “omni-non” which we will explore a bit later.

Page | 212
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

In the freedom afforded by abstraction into the universal set-aspect of


absolute affirmation, we then ask ourselves whether this class is contained
in itself. This “set of all sets that do not contain themselves as a member”
does fit its own class-membership description, and therefore it enters into
the abstract member-relation and becomes a subset of itself. But if it now
does contain itself as a member, then suddenly it does not fit its own abstract
properties and hence it does not belong in its own set. And if it now does not
belong in its own set, then it does, and back and forth ad infinitum. So, from
either assumption, the opposite follows. This antinomy is commonly called
“Russell’s paradox,” after its discoverer, Bertrand Russell.

The paradoxes of logic and mathematics arise only when we “violate” the
Univocity Framework—breaking from the relative scope, unwittingly mono-
polizing the unbounded absolute with the relative concepts of sets, and
deviating through abstraction from the natural holonic set-logic with its
inherently delineated, perceived and conceived holarchical levels
(immanent/transcendent relations) of bounded-collections. Russell
discovered his paradox in the abstract set-theory of Frege (now called “naive
set-theory”), and it occurred precisely because of the naïve abandonment of
percept-restrictions leading to the ambiguity in the classical system of
classes. This conceptual abstraction—freed from its own holarchical
foundation of perception and imagination—failed to keep track of the
holonic levels in the implicit percept-logic of sets. This “violation” and
equivocation in turn, as we just noted, allowed both the universal and the
empty set to exist, coexist and interact, with “disastrous,” or perhaps
revealing, results.
Russell was deeply troubled by this paradox he found in Frege’s work, as
it impacted his own work, and interestingly, his own solution to the paradox
was based on applying a hierarchy or holarchy aspect in his theory of
“types,” in order to keep track of the different levels of set membership.
Even Frege himself had an implicit holarchical solution to the problem as it
occurred in his theory of properties; he avoided it by a distinction between
levels of concepts in which a concept can never take itself as argument. The
implicit holonic logic of sets naturally precludes this self-recursion, or self-
confusion, along with the problematic universal and empty sets, or
otherwise makes their “paradoxical” properties naturally explicit and
accountable, delineating these as special cases and not “proper” sets.
Indeed, as the study of mereology has found, the move from naïve
classical set theory to modern axiomatic and “Zermelo-Fraenkel” set theory
is essentially a move to reinstall—in abstract, explicit mechanisms—the
logic needed to keep track of the levels of sets and to restrict these violations
of the sensorial holonic logic already implicit, yet buried under abstraction,
in the stratified human mind. It is not generally recognized, however, that
the part-whole relation, itself derided as naïve, was the correct logic all

Page | 213
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

along, and the move into axiomatic set theory was a move to reinstall the
truths of this naiveté in the sense-barren abstraction of the set as category.
The incorrect naiveté , it is clear from an outsider’s retrospect, is the naiveté
of the categorical set conceived purely transitively, without its
immanent/transcendent holonic aspects.

The goal throughout the rest of this unfolding of Interface Mathematics is


not to replace modern axiomatic set theory, in any of its variations, but
merely to inform it with an implicit, intuitive percept-logic of sets; to
reconnect the concepts back with the percepts from which they were
abstracted into far more general and hence useful symbolic mechanisms.
The end result will be to know the place from which we started more
thoroughly, having re-examined and reconnected our roots in perception.

The modern notion of the infinite, in axiomatic set theory, has its roots in the
paradox discovered by Galileo. In the Two New Sciences, Galileo laid bare an
apparent contradiction in the property of “infinite sets,” such as the whole
numbers (0, 1, 2, 3, …). Galileo noted that the whole numbers seemingly
contain the much smaller subset of the “perfect squares”i (0, 1, 4, 9, 36, 49,
64, 81, 100 …) with the spaces between the squares growing rapidly, filled
with non-square whole-numbers, such as the many non-square whole
numbers between 81 and 100, for example. Both the perfect squares and
the whole numbers are infinite in extent, yet the number of whole numbers,
seems to be vastly larger than the number of squares, with the gaps between
squares growing ever larger. Yet, given that the squares are derived by a
multiplication of each and every whole number with itself (a “one-to-one
correspondence”), there are then, of necessity, exactly as many perfect
squares as whole numbers.
The set of whole numbers and its subset of squares are then apparently
equal in size, and this is clearly a violation of the part-whole axiom, which
states that a subset must be smaller than its set. It is this paradox which
essentially led to the abandonment of the part-whole relation implicit in the
holonic logic of sets, and which, we will find, led to Cantor’s notion of the
transfinite orders of infinity as well as modern axiomatic set theory.
Or as Spinoza puts the problem, so much more simply, “If an infinite
quantity is measured by parts equal to a foot, it will consist of an infinitely
many such parts, as it will also if it is measured by parts equal to an inch.

i
… or we could just as accurately say the “perfect triangles,” as we will see…

Page | 214
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

And therefore one infinite number will be twelve times greater than
another.”i¥

From Galileo’s Two New Sciences:

Salviati: This is one of the difficulties which arise when we attempt,


with our finite minds, to discuss the infinite, assigning to it those
properties which we give to the finite and limited; but this I think
is wrong, for we cannot speak of infinite quantities as being the
one greater or less than or equal to another. To prove this I have
in mind an argument which, for the sake of clearness, I shall put
in the form of questions to Simplicio who raised this difficulty.
I take it for granted that you know which of the numbers are
squares and which are not.
Simplicio: I am quite aware that a squared number is one which
results from the multiplication of another number by itself; this
4, 9, etc., are squared numbers which come from multiplying 2, 3,
etc., by themselves.
Salviati: Very well; and you also know that just as the products are
called squares so the factors are called sides or roots; while on
the other hand those numbers which do not consist of two equal
factors are not squares. Therefore if I assert that all numbers,
including both squares and non-squares, are more than the
squares alone, I shall speak the truth, shall I not?
Simplicio: Most certainly.
Salviati: If I should ask further how many squares there are one might
reply truly that there are as many as the corresponding number
of roots, since every square has its own root and every root its
own square, while no square has more than one root and no root
more than one square.
Simplicio: Precisely so.
Salviati: But if I inquire how many roots there are, it cannot be denied
that there are as many as the numbers because every number is
the root of some square. This being granted, we must say that
there are as many squares as there are numbers because they
are just as numerous as their roots, and all the numbers are
roots. Yet at the outset we said that there are many more
numbers than squares, since the larger portion of them are not
squares. Not only so, but the proportionate number of squares
diminishes as we pass to larger numbers, Thus up to 100 we have
10 squares, that is, the squares constitute 1/10 part of all the


Ethics, Part I, Prop XV, Note.

Page | 215
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

numbers; up to 10000, we find only 1/100 part to be squares;


and up to a million only 1/1000 part; on the other hand in an
infinite number, if one could conceive of such a thing, he would
be forced to admit that there are as many squares as there are
numbers taken all together.
Sagredo: What then must one conclude under these circumstances?
Salviati: So far as I see we can only infer that the totality of all
numbers is infinite, that the number of squares is infinite, and
that the number of their roots is infinite; neither is the number of
squares less than the totality of all the numbers, nor the latter
greater than the former; and finally the attributes “equal,”
“greater,” and “less,” are not applicable to infinite, but only to
finite, quantities. When therefore Simplicio introduces several
lines of different lengths and asks me how it is possible that the
longer ones do not contain more points than the shorter, I
answer him that one line does not contain more or less or just as
many points as another, but that each line contains an infinite
number.

As we have seen in the implicit holonic logic of sets, the “infinite set”—such
as both the set of whole numbers and the set of perfect squares—though
perfectly adequate as abstract, general classes are not proper holonic sets
because they are boundless, not bounded, collections. They are merely the
abstracted “collection aspect” of implicit-holonic sets, conveniently
neglecting and equivocating from the container aspect of sets needed to
make sense of the empty set.
We will come to see “infinite sets” more clearly as “set aspects,” or
“aspect infinities,” rather than bounded-collections with definitive numbers
of elements, magnitudes or “cardinalities.” This new way of looking at things
will illuminate and resolve the truth behind this paradox in accord with
Galileo’s own reasoning that aspects of the finite, such as relative
magnitudes, do not really and fully apply to The Infinite. We will do so,
however, without nullifying Cantor’s great achievements in the
operationalization of the quantitative aspects of infinite sets, but only with
added clarification as to what is really taking place in these operations, thus
dissolving the controversies surrounding the Cantorian transfinite and the
modern axiomatic theory of sets.

For the time being, however, we have the tools in hand to see a simple
resolution of the Galilean paradox as a function of scope con-fusion in the
Univocity Framework. As we have seen, the quantitative aspect of the
relative scope is the finite. It deals with the bounded and with all relations,
such as the hierarchical or holarchical relations of one magnitude to another.
The absolute scope, on the other hand, has the quantitative aspect of the

Page | 216
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION

infinite and unbounded. It is therefore unable to deal with relation having


no boundaries “between things” with which to relate.
An infinite set, therefore, reaches into the absolute scope, drawing out
the quantitative aspect of the absolute in the unbounded and infinite. It
therefore possesses the quality of the absolute scope in its ultimate inability
to relate, one with another. In other words, an infinite set is not a relative
set, but a “finitized” and relativized aspect of the absolute scope. This is why
two infinite sets, such as the squares and wholes—as Galileo intuited and
Cantor effectively confirmed, as we will see—cannot properly be compared
as to their “number of elements,” and indeed, they actually have no number
of elements, but simply the numberless quantitative aspect of the infinite.
Infinite sets can relate one with another, and to finite sets only univocally, as
multiple aspects or voices of the one absolute; The Infinite.

The German mathematician David Hilbert presented us with another


paradox which can help illumine the problematic pre-rational view of
infinity still in action in modern mathematical reasoning, or meta-
mathematics.

From the Wikipedia entry on Hilbert’s paradox, we find:


In a hotel with a finite number of rooms, it is clear that once it is full, no
more guests can be accommodated. Now, imagine a hotel with an infinite
number of rooms. One might assume that the same problem will arise
when all the rooms are occupied. However, in an infinite hotel, the
situations “every room is occupied” and “no more guests can be
accommodated” do not turn out to be equivalent. There is a way to solve
the problem: if you move the guest occupying room 1 to room 2, the guest
occupying room 2 to room 3, etc., you can fit the newcomer into room 1.
Unlike a finite hotel, in an infinite hotel, being “full” in the sense that every
room contains a person is not the same as being “full” in the sense that
there is no space for another person. Note that a movement of an infinite
number of guests would constitute a supertask.
It would seem to be possible to make place for an infinite (countable)
number of new clients: just move the person occupying room 1 to room 2,
occupying room 2 to room 4, occupying room 3 to room 6, etc., and all the
odd-numbered new rooms will be free for the new guests. However, this
is where the paradox lies. Even in the previous statement, if an infinite
number of people fill the odd numbered rooms, then what amount is
added to the infinite that was already there? Can one double an infinite?
Also, for example, say the infinite number of new guests do come and fill
all of the odd numbered rooms, and then the infinite number of guests in
the even rooms leave. An infinite has just been subtracted from a still

Page | 217
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

existing infinite, yet an infinite still exists. This is where Hilbert’s Hotel is
paradoxical.
In the Galilean paradox we saw that infinity, taken as a quantity, does not
function properly with respect to mathematical operations, such as squaring.
In this paradox we can see more clearly that infinity does not fit the function
of a quantity with respect to such properties as addition subtraction, or
division; for example, in division by two to get the evens and odds. In a
sense, we can actually see this paradox as a more vividly visual example of
the Galilean paradox. Imagine, for example, that we extend the paradox by
only filling the rooms with labels matching a perfect square. The “number”
of perfect squares are indeed infinite, yet the hotel would seem almost
entirely empty after this infinitely time-consuming procedure, this “super-
task,” of filling the perfect-square numbered rooms.
If we think of this in terms of the one-to-one correspondence used by
Galileo, we can see that by shifting the occupants down by one room, we are
effectively merely shifting the numbers on the rooms by one unit, and hence
shifting the one-to-one correspondence of the room-numbers and occupants
without really changing the nature of the hotel and its infinite, or unbounded
capacity at all. When we allow the occupants to fill up the odd numbered
rooms, we are merely acknowledging, as Galileo did, that the odd numbers
are by themselves infinite, in that they have a one-to-one correspondence
with the Natural numbers and the evens, just as do the perfect squares.

Page | 218
Page | 219
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Great strides toward a nondual rational-empirical, or trans-rational, meta-


view of mathematics were made by Buckminster Fuller (Bucky) in his
exquisitely beautiful Synergetic Geometry with his steadfast emphasis on
starting from experience, rather than the purely rationally-derived
Euclidean “elements” such as extensionless points and lines of zero-width.
Amy C. Edmonson, in her book A Fuller Explanation, relates a vivid example
from Bucky’s childhood:
The teacher stood at the blackboard, made a little dot, and said, “This is a
point; it doesn’t exist.” (“So she wiped that out.”) Then she drew a whole
string of them and called it a “line.” Having no thickness, it couldn’t exist
either. Next she made a raft out of these lines and came up with a “plane.”
“I’m sorry to say it didn’t exist either,” sighs Bucky. She then stacked them
together and got a “cube,” and suddenly that existed. Telling the story,
Bucky scratches his head as if still puzzled seventy years later: “I couldn’t
believe it; how did she get existence out of nonexistence to the fourth
power? So I asked, ‘How old is it’? She said, ‘don’t be naughty.’ ... It was an
absolute ghost cube.” (6-9).
Bucky’s seemingly innocent child-hood reflection conveys a profound
realization, one made by Spinoza around 300 years earlier. It is likely that
this intuition is made by certain “naïve” children all over the world, before it
is programmed out them. There is no existence—relative or absolute—
without the aspect or “attribute” of (volumetric) extension.i Once the forms
of our modern abstract mathematics reach three-dimensional, and
volumetric extension, then suddenly they become sensible and can be
imagined as existing (and aging) in the real world. Bucky’s incredulity at the
sudden existence of “nonexistence to the fourth power” conveys his intuition
of this powerful rational principle.
Rather than build existence from extensionless “nonexistence to the
fourth power” Bucky’s “Operational Mathematics,”ii deals exclusively with
what can be modeled volumetrically, visually and viscerally. (These can be

i
The absolute, recall, enfolds all aspects and attributes, including extension.
ii
In standard mathematics, the term “Operational Mathematics” refers to Laplacian and other
integral transforms.

Page | 220
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

taken, rather playfully, as the 3Vs of modelability.) i So because an


extensionless point could never be seen, touched, tasted, heard, smelled or
otherwise even imagined in percept-form by anyone (it can’t be modeled in
“3V”ii at any conceivable scale) then it cannot exist within Operational
Mathematics, as an item to be operated upon or as an element to construct
anything with, not even a coordinate system. Likewise, since an infinite line
and plane do not have volumetric extension, and cannot be modeled visually
or viscerally then they too cannot exist in Operational Mathematics and the
objectively-real world.iii
This injunction to deal exclusively with the a priori sensible and hence
volumetric (and truly rational) is what Fuller calls “a return to
modelability”iv¥ because it returns mathematics from syntactic abstraction
to a semantic grounding in the realm of the senses, the visualizable,
conceptual, imaginable, modelable and ultimately empirical and causal, in
principle. These extensionless concepts—such as “infinitely small,” or “zero-
dimensional” points—do play a part in the understanding of nondual-
rational, or trans-rational, mathematics (as we will see), but they are not to
be found within mathematical operations as items to be operated upon,
because without being extensive, bounded bodies or magnitudes they
cannot interact, inter-relate or be operated upon and hence they cannot be
symbolized as numbers or magnitudes with de-finite magnitudes.
Again, these are aspects of the infinite, and hence function according to
the rules of the absolute scope in the univocal relations of the Univocity
Framework. The Infinite quality abstracted into the aspects can’t properly
relate amongst themselves, except through their finitized qualities, such as
the various methods of set-generating “countability,” as we will see.v*

The term “operational,” such as in “operationalize,” is used extensively


herein. In general it refers to a syntactic and explicit level of functionality,
rather than to Bucky’s “Operational Mathematics.” Interface Mathematics is,

i
This, however, is not to say that everything in the objectively-real world is tangible, such as energy,
and subtle forms beyond empirical reality, etc, but merely that it is embodiable in the imagination
and also that modelability can translate quantitative and objective (“IT” quadrant) aspects as such,
when the appropriate scales and empirical adjustments or hypotheses are taken into account.
ii
Note, 3V can also stand for the Vision-logic version of 3D: 3-vision-logic-dimensionality….but let us
avoid the natural tendency to call that 3VD. ;-)
iii
You may think of visualizations of infinite planes or points in a computer program, for instance, but
these representations are always measured in terms of pixels and truncated infinities, i.e. discrete
units. There is no possible representation of an infinitely thin anything and this is because the
concept amalgam is an oxymoron.
iv¥
Synergetics 216.03
v
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.

Page | 221
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

however, generally “Operational” in Bucky’s sense of the term, but it is not


properly Operational Mathematics because it does not replace modern
dimensioning systems or geometry with Bucky’s Operational and Synergetic
Geometry. Rather it renders visible the hidden operationality, or
modelability, already enfolded in the embryogenesis of the system of
mathematics itself. Bucky’s Operational Mathematics, and his experiences
and intuitions merely help us see more clearly what we are after in this
work; namely the more general “return to modelability” or the reconnection
of concept with percept, as already delineated by Arnheim.i* When referring
to the visual, visceral and volumetric aspects of Interface Mathematics we
will use the term modelable, rather than operational, or otherwise make it
apparent by capitalizing it as a proper noun, e.g. Operational Mathematics.

Unfortunately, we must forego a fascinating excursion into much of Fuller’s


Synergetic Geometry in which many irrational numbers are unnecessary and
in which all geometrical dimensioning ends in whole number multiples and
relations using four spatial dimensions in order to modelably account for
our four-dimensional constants in physics. The standard XYZ coordinate
system ends at three perpendicular dimensions, so a whole class of
constants is currently beyond the reach of modelability and thus ultimately
impossible to understand. Yet four-dimensionality is absolutely necessary
to quantitatively account for empirical reality. Therefore the scientists,
having come in through the “attic window,” as Bucky says, are missing the
essential tool of modelability and understanding (semantics) because they
are using a dimensioning system (syntax) that does not intrinsically fit
reality. But, rather than delving into Synergetic Geometry, at this point,
instead with our new “Operational” background we will pick up the trail
where we left off-the distinction between infinity (apeiron) and number.

i
* See, Vision-logic Interfaces: Vision-logic and Blind-logic, p124.

Page | 222
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

We have already encountered the polarity of the finite and infinite in the
context of scope and univocity. It is also the more general aspect of the
polarity of infinity and number, which gives us the implicit identity of the
infinite number. The finite and infinite are the polar aspects of boundedness
and unboundedness for the relative and absolute scopes, respectively. And
in terms of pure-relation, they are the quantitative aspects of our polarity of
scope—the polarity and “contra-diction” at the very foundation of
quantitative reasoning itself, because our primitive notions of number
correspond precisely to boundary, as we will see.
The relative scope—and mathematics itself—necessarily deals
fundamentally in boundedness because in order for two event-objects to
inter-relate or even exist, they must have limits and boundaries (whether
gradients or not), excluding or including (or otherwise relating to) the other.i
By definition, however, the absolute scope cannot deal in boundaries, and
this is precisely because boundaries inter-relate—at the very least (and
fundamentally) between the inside and outside of that boundary. Indeed,
boundaries actually are, in a sense, this inter-relation or triune interface
between the within and without. It is in this sense that boundary
necessitates its own transcension in the boundless beyond and within itself.
The one cannot exist without the other.
The absolute scope, then, deals in the generally ineffable aspects of unity
and infinity, and the relative scope deals in the polarities and multiplicities
of the finite.

In esoteric wisdom we have the polarity of the infinite and the finite (or
bounded number) as a simple identity of opposites. The problem is that this

i
An interrelation involving an event/object with itself is an identity, and no real relation at all.
Hence an identity is, in some sense, a function of the absolute scope. The bounded identity
functions as an interface between the relative and absolute scopes because it identifies the infinite
in the finite or bounded individual. Such a bounded identity, as we have seen in the section on the
Univocity Framework, is a horizontal tautology, and if it is unbounded then it is vertical.

Page | 223
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

identity of opposites was not properly fleshed out, and through the LCD of
exoteric representational forces, the pre-modern esoteric polarity became
flattened into a mere duality of opposites: “infinity is not a number.” … but
why, and in what sense is infinity not a number? What about Cantor’s
“infinite numbers”? What about the immanent infinities of the “irrational
numbers”? Neither the exoteric classical duality, nor the esoteric ancient
polarity can satisfactorily explain these questions to the exacting standards
of modern, post-classical mathematics and philosophical logic and reason.
And Cantor’s transfinite arithmetic only touches them as they intersect the
field of mathematics, leaving in its wake a sprawling mess of philosophical
loose ends, as terms radically and unintuitively shift in meaning into their
seeming opposites. A mess for philosophers, to be sure, but it can be entirely
ignored by mathematicians uninterested in the controversies and meanings
of their machinations.
Against this classical duality of opposition between the finite and infinite,
the modern mathematical notions seemed to focus exclusively on the
missing identity, as it was parsed through the similarity of the abstracted set
as category. This is what Deleuze sees as the problem with a set-theory
based ontology. It sees everything in the terms of a similarity of the concept,
namely the abstract set. It reduces everything to a pure or abstract
“belonging” to the mathematical or pure-relational category. As Alain
Badiou writes, “[Deleuze] is challenging a set-theory ontology of elements
and belonging … which weaves out of the vacuum the greatest complexities,
and reduces to pure belonging the most entangled topologies.”
One of the problems with this set-theory ontology is that it generates “a
constant ambivalence between the ‘belonging’ (of an element) and the
‘inclusion’ (of a subset).” In other words, the abstracted categorical set had
lost the meaning and complexity implicit in our holonic logic of sets. And we
have seen these ambivalences and entangled topologies at the very onset of
this set-category, with its categorical blindness to the implicit holonic logic
as it manifested in Russell’s paradox, for example, but it also shows up in the
many paradoxes of set theory not discussed in this volume. And again, it
was only with the abstract, axiomatic re-encoding of the lost truths of the
part-whole (holonic) axiom that the paradoxes were brought into
mathematical reign. This is seen for example, in the fact that axiomatic set
theory has now come into line with mereology and its explicit part-whole
axiom, which set-theory explicitly or exoterically denies. There is, then, an
ambivalence of set-theory to this part-whole axiom, which on its face is
denied, but in its hidden and blind abstract inner-workings, it has
necessarily come to resemble.
Deleuze counters the mathematical notion of the set with the notion of
the “fold,” which he extracts from the Leibnizian monadology. We will find,
however, that the fold is essentially our Spinozan aspect infinite, as it

Page | 224
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

abstracts the immanent infinity of the aspect of locality from the infinite
ONE-ALL. Badiou says, quoting Deleuze’s The Fold:
Leibniz-Deleuze’s thesis is that the point, or element, cannot have the
value of a unit of matter: "The unit of matter, the smallest element of the
labyrinth, is the fold, not the point" (p9).
In this, Deleuze is directly in line with Spinoza and Leibniz, but also in line
with Whitehead’s “point-free geometry,” and our Interface Mathematics.i* It
is the point, conceived as Euclidean element, which generates the labyrinth
of the continuum, recall, and it was only with Leibniz’s abandonment of the
point for the Spinozan aspect infinite (Leibniz’s “termini”), as we will see,ii*
through which he found his Ariadne’s thread. Badiou continues [my
emphasis]:
Leibniz-Deleuze’s ontology apprehends the multiple as a point-subset, that
is, as an extension (an unfold) or a contraction (a fold), with neither atom
nor vacuum. …there have never been but two schemes, or paradigms,
of the Multiple: the mathematic and the organicist, Plato or Aristotle.
Opposing the fold to the set, or Leibniz to Descartes, reanimates the
organicist scheme. Deleuze-Leibniz does not omit remarking that it must
be separated from the mathematic scheme: "in Mathematics, it is
individuation which constitutes a specification; this is not so with physical
things or organic bodies" (p87).
The animal or the number? This is the cross of metaphysics, and the
greatness of Deleuze-Leibniz, metaphysician of the divergent world of
modernity, is to choose without hesitation for the animal. After all, "it is
not only animal psychology, but animal monadology which is essential to
Leibniz’s system" (p146).
The real question underlying this is that of singularity: where and
how does the singular meet up with the concept? What is the paradigm of
such an encounter?
We’ll see this encounter explicitly as it unfolds into the embryogenesis of
mathematics,iii* and as it traces its way through evolutionary unfolding into
the crossroads of the ontic/epistemic and subject/object, in Interface
Epistemology. iv * The encounter takes place through the interface of
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, as well as explicitly on our Vision-Logic Coordinate
System through the interface of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis, in
conjunction with the omni-axis through the Cycle of Unity. But again, this is
getting ahead of our story. Badiou continues [my comments].

i
* See, Boundary and Dimension: (p295), and The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation
(p306).
ii
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270, and Reconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical
Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and the Calculus, p400.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iv
*See, Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch, p541.

Page | 225
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

If Deleuze likes the Stoics, Leibniz, or Whitehead, and if he does not much
like Plato, Descartes, or Hegel, it is because, in the first series, the
principle of individuation [e.g. infinite difference beyond belonging to the
pure similarity or opposition of the concept] occupies a strategic place,
which it is denied in the second. The "Leibnizian revolution" is greeted
with rare stylistic enthusiasm in Deleuze’s supple narration, as the
"wedding of concept and singularity" (p91).
In the shock and integrating interface between the pre-modern
opposite and the post-modern identity, then, we will see emerging
again—but as a cultivated third and triune interface—the ancient
nondual identity of opposites of the finite and infinite. It is this identity
of opposites that finds its germination in the lost truths of modernity,
namely in esoteric rationalism as we find it in Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, also
reflected and refracted through Leibniz’s reactionary monadology. And in
this integration will likewise continue to unfold this “wedding of concept and
singularity.” We have already seen it with the immanent/transcendent
omni- and uni-axes, and we’ll soon see it more explicitly in the concept of
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite and, perhaps at its climax, in the Interface
resolution to Zeno’s paradoxes.

The common, pre-modern, “naïve” mathematical and philosophical


definition of the finite is simply: “bounded or limited in magnitude or spatial
or temporal extent.”i¥ Spinoza, however, gave a more precise definition in
his Ethics: “A thing is called finite after its kind, when it can be limited by
another thing of the same nature; for instance, a body is called finite because
we always conceive another greater body.” Spinoza, then would be saying
that there is something finite about each of Cantor’s infinite numbers or
transfinite sets, precisely because each one can be surpassed by another of
its kind. This, then, gives us a glimpse of the triune interface which is to
come; a sneak peak of just how inextricably interrelated is this polarity
between infinity and bounded-number.
Therefore, as should perhaps be expected, the modern mathematical
definition of the finite, is a bit more convoluted and abstract, as it has been
replaced by notions from modern axiomatic set-theory, purely in the terms
of the similarity and belonging to its bare-bones categorical identities; i.e.
sets. The following definition is from Wikipedia [my comments and
emphases]:
In mathematics, a set is called finite if and only if there is a bijection [one
to one correspondence] between the set and some set of the form {1, 2, ...,
n} [it is in a one-to-one correspondence with a default finite set]... It is a
theorem that a set is finite if and only if there exists no bijection
between the set and any of its proper subsets.


…from onelook.com

Page | 226
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

So the modern definition of a finite set is essentially that it is equal to


(bijection) the default finite set of Natural numbers—naturally, the finite
equals the finite. But the second half of the definition states that the finite is
not equal (no bijection) to any of its proper subsets—i.e., it doesn’t violate
the part-whole axiom. Notice that it doesn’t mention boundaries at all, or
even limitations. Thus, in mathematics, we have Kuhn-lost entirely the
earlier commonsensical notion of the finite simply as bounded, limited or
surpassable by another body or set of like kind. Note also that this definition
is almost a straight-forward recapitulation and negation of Galileo’s paradox
of the infinite. It states essentially that the finite (unlike the infinite, as we
have seen) does not violate the part-whole holarchical relation.
In this sense the pre-modern opposite reflects into the modern identity,
as the finite is defined first in the sameness to the default finite set, and then
in opposition to the sameness or identity of set and subset in the paradox of
the infinite. What we have here is an opposition purely in terms of an
identity, but without the triune integration into an identity of opposites. We
will see the meaning and importance of this very soon.

Similarly the esoteric, or “naïve” definition of infinity (both philosophical


and mathematical), from ancient times up to the late 19th century, was
rather simple and straightforward, and entirely non-paradoxical, of itself.
Infinity was simply the opposite of the finite. It was the unbounded, the
apeiron, absolutely all-encompassing and beyond all conceivable,
inconceivable and possible boundaries, magnitudes or numbers. It merely
lacked any boundary or limit. Such a simple pair of opposites is not too
difficult to understand, in itself. The finite is bounded and the infinite is
unbounded.
The Infinite as the antithesis to the finite, was also the antithesis to
implicit primitive notions of number as boundary. And because boundary,
or the finite, was the implicit pure-relational concept of number, we had the
simple classical dichotomy and duality between infinity and number, which
remains to this day, hiding in the background, waiting to confuse us again
about Cantor’s “infinite numbers.” This classical opposition itself, is the
boundary that Cantor would soon come crashing through with his Galilean
identity of the infinite number. But it had already been ruptured, and was
still bleeding, from the time of Pythagoras and the immanent infinite
numbers of the “irrationals.” But again we’re jumping ahead in our story…
Though the esoteric-naïve definition of infinity was simple and clear, its
exoteric relation to other concepts—namely “number” and the finite—has
been much more problematic, leading to all sorts of paradoxes, some of
which we’ve already seen. This is not because, as we’ll see,i* the naïve

i
* See, The Triune Infinite: Interfacing Emptiness, p268.

Page | 227
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

definition was wrong, per se, but rather because it was incomplete, or
prematurely aborted along with the project of rationalism itself. It was thus
still conceived as a simple duality or dichotomy—an opposition without the
identity in the triune interface which would be capable of unfolding the
complicated and inextricable relations between its two poles—the infinite
and finite. The nondual-rational or transrational concept of the Triune
Infinite—this triune interface between the finite and infinite—had yet to be
differentiated-and-integrated into modern meta-/mathematics, but this is
indeed a function of this work.

Mathematician Dr. Reviel Netz, in a recent NOVA interview, explains this


move from classical to modern conceptions of infinity, demonstrating clearly
that the esoteric understanding of the key rationalists, Spinoza and Leibniz,
is nowhere to be found in modern meta-mathematics [my emphasis]:
Infinity became a really clear and well-defined quantity mathematically in
the late 19th century, which it wasn’t before and which makes it rather
different from what we ordinarily talk about when we talk about infinity,
namely, about something very, very big.
This popularization of the premodern definitions of infinity as “something
very, very big” points to the common (exoteric) pervasive error of thinking of
the Infinite in the merely identical terms of the finite or the set—and thus of
thinking of the absolute in identical terms of the relative. This we can see is
a subtle inversion of the pre-modern conceptions of infinity and bounded
number as merely a duality of opposites, and it occurred with the acceptance
of the Galilean paradox right into the heart of the modern definitions of the
finite and infinite.
In ancient and modern esoteric thought, recall, infinity was not just a
“very, very big” version of the finite. It was never really just a huge,
gargantuan or cosmic “something” at all, but rather merely the boundless
apeiron—the opposite, or simple absence of limit and size—which can be
understood to exist at all sizes and thus none (omni-non). (It is important to
note, however, that “infinite sets” are not to be taken as The Infinite or the
absolute, as we will see, but merely as mathematical aspects or abstractions
of the absolute scope of The Infinite.)
To deal with these pervasive common problems and paradoxes of the
Infinite, the definition of infinity has changed dramatically. In order for
infinity to become mathematically tractable, and the paradoxes to be
“resolved” or rendered moot, it had to be conceived in the terms of the
identity of the category emerging in the new theories of sets. Infinity was
then radically redefined away from the terms of opposition and into the
terms of identity with the finite set, largely through Cantor’s vastly
influential (and still controversial) expansions of set-theory into the
“transfinite.”

Page | 228
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Netz continues:
…the defining property of infinity today is that a set’s cardinality [its
number of elements] is equal to the cardinality of some real subset of that
set.
Netz simplifies this new set-theory definition of infinity as “Something which
is equal [or identical] to some of its parts.” As we should entirely expect, this
definition is naturally the inverse of the modern definition of the finite. But
recall that the conundrum of the Galilean part-whole paradox was exactly
this; that the parts of infinity—such as the set of all squares—are necessarily
infinite as well, and hence the parts are equal or identical to the whole.
Recall also, that this is the unique quality of the universal set, that it violates
the part-whole holonic relation and becomes a paradoxical subset of itself.
The new definition of the infinite, like that of the finite, is essentially a
codification, incorporation and encapsulation of the Galilean part-whole
paradox, rather than its resolution. We have rightly accepted the
paradoxical nature of the infinite, in its identity to the finite, but in
simultaneously discarding its opposition we have yet to understand its
nature. We have yet to tune and triune the paradox into a truly nondual
identity of opposites, and thus into a triune interface of inter-expression.i*
This part-whole violation is merely the result of representational forces,
of thinking of the Infinite in the identical terms of the finite, i.e. in terms of
parts and wholes, and more importantly, sets and subsets and their
abstracted categorical relations of class membership or belonging. The
modern definition of the finite and infinite—still a con-fused dichotomy, not
a polarity—is a result of looking through the representational prism of
axiomatic set-theory and its identical abstract categories. What do we get
when we conceive of the “infinite set” in terms of the identity of its subsets?
The “violation” of the part-whole axiom in the Galilean paradox where a part,
or subset, is identical to the whole infinite set. The main difference now, is
that we aren’t calling it a violation or a paradox. The paradox has not been
solved by this definition, but has now simply become the definition,
subsumed under the identity of the concept or category of the set.

The new definition of infinity is both sensible and senseless. It is sensible to


assume, and operate as if, The Infinite as a part-whole violation is implicitly
non-paradoxical (even if we still have not explicitly solved the paradox).
But—unacknowledged by the identity of the category—it is precisely
because size, magnitude and number are identically opposite to infinity, that
the infinite set and its infinite subsets are identical and of “equal size.”
According to classical wisdom this is simply because they have no size. And
in this simplistic way, the Galilean paradox was long since rendered moot by

i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.

Page | 229
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Galileo himself when he said that magnitude did not apply. Indeed, Galileo
glimpsed this identity of opposites when he discovered that the infinite set
of the integers and its infinite subsets (such as the perfect squares) can be
put in a one-to-one correspondence with each other, thus further
demonstrating their equality. However, Cantor later found that this
correspondence with the Natural set of our counting numbers—a
correspondence which Cantor would naturally label “countability”i—was not
true for all types or sets of infinity, as we will see. And it is this feature with
which Cantor would later assign magnitude to what he discovered as an
infinite set of different “magnitudes” of mathematical infinity.

It is said that Cantor emancipated mathematics from its traditional bondage


to number, releasing it into the domain or “paradise of the infinite,” from
which, Hilbert hoped, we would never be driven. In the traditional dualistic
sense that “infinity is not a number,” this is undeniably the case. Indeed we
will see that Cantor effectively defied Kant’s decree that human reason has
surpassed its bounds when thinking about the infinite, as we find in his
“antinomies of pure reason.” Indeed, the human mind can reason about and,
we will see, understand the infinite, but this understanding simply hasn’t
made its way into philosophy yet (though this is indeed a value of the
present work).ii* To be sure, Cantor showed that not only can we reason
about infinity (at least mathematically), but we can construct an arithmetic
for interrelating its various forms and abstractions. And, as we will see
through Spinoza’s Triune differentiation in Interface Philosophy, the human
mind can understand the infinite in its own terms, in the function of the
imagination as it transmutes, abstracts and opens through reason itself, into
the aperspectival level of vision-logic.
Cantor (with the help of Cauchy, Dedekind and many others) famously
(and some would say infamously) “solved” the paradoxes of the infinite
largely through his concept of denumerability or countability, and the
operationalization of the modern mathematical continuum. Essentially,
Cantor (following Dedekind) circumvented the classical notion of a set as
necessarily relative and finite—a number as boundary—and hence as
adhering to the holonic part-whole axiom.
Infinite sets, as we have seen, are now defined by the paradoxical feature
that they are equal to their subsets, they are “self-nesting”—as Dedekind and
Charles Peirce termed it—while finite sets are merely “nesting,” or
holarchical. This shift, from the sensible and simple notion of infinity as the

i
No pun intended…though allowed…
ii
* See, Paradoxical Postscript and Epitaph: Kan’t and the Antinomies of Pure Reason, p479.

Page | 230
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

opposite of the bounded finite, to the unimaginable, un-sensible identity


between set and subset in the paradoxical violation of the part-whole axiom,
resides at the heart of the meta-mathematical or philosophical controversy
surrounding Cantor’s solution to the paradoxes of the infinite.
Cantor said the infinite set of Natural numbers is “denumerable,” or
“countable” (e.g. 1, 2, 3, 4, ... ∞) and any set that can be put into a one-to-one
correspondence with it, has the same “power,” “cardinality” or “number of
elements,” namely “aleph null.” And aleph null it turns out, is only the first of
the Cantorian orders of the “transfinite,” in the sense, perhaps, that they
transcend the traditional mathematical notion of the infinite as merely
equivalent to the set of Natural numbers and its one-to-one correspondents.
The Natural numbers are now called “countable” even though such an
“infinite set,” it would seem, can never really be fully counted—because n+1
can never be infinite in value. This “countability” should never reach the
infinite itself, even in principle, because with the rejection of the naïve
principle, there is no final “infinitieth” value whatsoever. Each term of the
set is “countable” (and indeed finite), wherever it is found, yes, but the set
itself “as a whole,” according to common-sense, literally is “uncountable”
because there is no final term to be reached.
Countable infinity, then, can only be understood outside of this set-
generating, time-based procedure operating unconsciously and stepwise in
the imagination. It can only be understood outside of time in the abstraction
and idealization that mathematics and vision-logic affords us. When we
make such a move, however, we can again only understand it as boundless.
The countable infinite, then, must be conceived as an a priori existing infinity
of already counted or generated numerals.
This is one of the many semantic controversies and difficulties
surrounding the Cantorian fix; that an infinite set (namely the lowest order)
is “uncountable” and “innumerable” because it has no infinitieth term to be
counted, yet Cantor is now calling it countable simply because of the
stepwise nature of the generation of its boundless set definition. This
simple, trivial, sensible and yet sense-less semantic confusion is indeed
typical of the controversies surrounding Cantor’s fix, and it is our goal herein
to help clear up exactly what is happening behind the confusing terminology,
while retaining and magnifying the extraordinary value of the Cantorian
solution in the context of the nondual identity of opposites, polarity and
triune interface of the infinite and finite.
Essentially, what we will find more explicitly is that the Natural numbers
themselves are defined in a stepwise function of counting, and thus as a
product of counting itself—if only in pure mathematical principle outside of
time. The set of Natural numbers is then intrinsically countable, or perhaps
better, already counted (and perhaps if necessary, only by God).
Cantor then invented some useful tricks (e.g. diagonalization) to
demonstrate that all the subsets and meta-sets that would fall under the

Page | 231
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

problematic paradoxes (e.g. Galileo’s perfect squares and Zeno’s infinitely


divisible rationals (or so it would seem)i) can be placed in a one-to-one
correspondence with the Natural numbers and hence all of them have the
same cardinality and countable status, aleph null.ii

So, what is a cardinality in a sequential set such as the Natural numbers if


not that final number—the “infinitieth” ordinal which is absent and
impossible to define for infinite sets? This, after-all, is the essence of the
rejection of the naïve principle which is central to Cantor’s insight, as well as
to those of Leibniz, as we will see. When dealing with infinite sets, Cantor
had to redefine cardinality as well, away from the naïve principle which
would imply that the cardinality of an infinite set would be the “infinitieth
term.” And this is another key to the controversies surrounding Cantor; the
creation and redefinition of all of these common terms under the identity of
the categorical set.
To understand the countability of the infinite set of Natural numbers,
recall, it must be imagined as one—outside of time—already counted and
created. Infinite sets, then—sharing the identity of having no boundaries
and no outsides—must be compared and contrasted by their intrinsic
differences. They must be compared by their internal structure and depth
and thus ultimately through their methods of generation. This, we can see,
is a Cantorian turn to immanence, as all infinite sets share the same
absolute and incomparable transcendent boundlessness.
Cantor, as opposed to the I/T uni-axis and singular immanent infinities
(singularities) of the irrational numbers, turns to the omni-axis to
differentiate the “powers” between the infinite sets. To make this immanent
or intrinsic comparison between infinite sets, Cantor seized upon the
Galilean application of the one-to-one correspondence as showing that—
seemingly contrary to Galileo—magnitude and quantity do indeed apply to
the intrinsic properties of infinite sets, but these Galilean sets and subsets
are actually of the same size. This notion that a cardinality can be applied to

i
It will indeed be shown that Zeno’s infinite division procedure was not stepwise, not of the order of
the rationals and thus not merely countable, but uncountable. See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning
and Triuning the Paradox, 432, and the subsection, Back to Zeno, p448.
ii
As we will see, however, Karin Verelst demonstrates in great detail that the fundamental structure
for all of Zeno’s paradoxes is an a priori uncountable continuum, thus taking the form of Cantor’s
Continuum Hypothesis itself in the form of a polarity which, as Interface Mathematics will
demonstrate, merely appears to us as a paradox given the implicit status of the fundamental binary
form of the VL-axes underlying conceptual relation itself. See Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 232
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

the infinite by means of a one-to-one correspondence or “bijection” is called


“Hume’s Principle,” after Frege’s use of a quote by Hume.
This, as well, is a controversial move, on the part of Cantor, because it is
by no means unequivocally demonstrated, intuitive or clear that Hume’s
principle is correct. In other words, simply because a one-to-one
correspondence can be made to the countability of the Natural numbers, it is
not given that the concept of cardinality itself, as in a number of elements,
applies to the Natural numbers, let alone to any of its one-to-one
correspondents.

The question must be asked, “Does it ultimately solve, or make sense of the
paradoxes of the infinite to demonstrate a one-to-one correspondence
between an infinite set and its subsets and/or meta-sets, call them
‘denumerable’ and give them all a quantity or ‘cardinality’?” What about the
fact that an “infinite cardinality” or “infinite number” operates in radically
different ways from a finite one? What exactly is the nature of this
difference, and how can we make sense of it? For example, you can add or
subtract any amount whatsoever to an “infinite number” and you will get the
same infinite number. Just what is numerical about that kind of behavior?
This is clearly Hilbert’s Hotel paradox still in action. It hasn’t been explained
by a mere identity in countability, which is indeed still controversial for this
very reason. We still have the same counter-intuitive, oppositional and
paradoxical behavior of “infinite sets” with no real explanation of why. The
opposition of pre-modern naivety is simply obscured—transcended-and-
excluded—by this new mathematical definition under the identity of the set,
which merely incorporates the paradox right into its make-up.
Furthermore, to many it is somewhat confusing to call the infinite and
finite versions of cardinality by same name of “cardinality” or “number”
when they have such radically different properties and behaviors. And it
will be shown herein that the reason “infinite numbers” act so differently is
that they are not really quantities at all, in the traditional sense of numbers
as boundaries, but merely quantitative aspects or abstractions of The
Infinite. (We’ll get into this in much greater detail later in the section on
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite (p273), as well as in the section To Infinity and
Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox (p434).)

The NOVA interview continues:


Netz: So what appears to be a quaint, paradoxical realm — the realm
of infinite magnitude — is actually very practical. It’s something
that allows you to extend operations with numbers to any

Page | 233
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

domain whatsoever. That’s what happened from the 17th


century onward.”
NOVA: How did Georg Cantor’s set theory refine mathematicians’
thinking about infinity?
Netz: Well, the essence of the calculus is that you deal with infinitely
large objects. But you never had to define infinity itself, and you
never had to worry about the nature of infinity, primarily
because you always dealt with the very same kind of infinity —
roughly speaking, the infinity of points making up a line, the
infinity of all the real numbers between, let’s say, 0 and 1. That’s
the type of thing they were worried about in the calculus from
the 17th century to the 19th century.
But they didn’t think about what infinity is, because for one
thing they didn’t think about what a set is. What is a set? And
then what would be the difference between a finite and an
infinite set? This is something that Cantor did in the late 19th
century. Cantor developed the notion of a set, and the notion of
an infinite set, a set that has infinitely many objects.
Then many, many curious things turned up. We found that
the paradoxical properties of infinite sets can actually be used to
define them, and even more striking — and something that is
slightly technical, and for this reason perhaps not something that
I can show you, but you’ll have to take for granted — even more
curious is that the fact that you find that once you have an
infinity, an infinite set, you can create another infinite set that is
bigger than the infinite set you started with. You can have two
infinite sets, one of them being bigger than the other. Actually,
because the operation is recursive, you can take a set and create
a set bigger than itself, so you can have an entire sequence of
infinity. There are infinitely many infinities, stretching all the
way up.
This, of course, gave rise to a fascinating field of operating
with infinite numbers, which, in fact, are richer and more
interesting than finite numbers are. That’s the field opened up by
Cantor.
Indeed, as we will see, the Cantorian fix represents a very important step in
the progress of mathematics as a whole. Cantor has presented mathematics
with valuable tools for working with infinite sets, and he has expanded the
methods and degrees of “chopping up” the mathematical infinite and
operating between their respective quantitative aspects. The issue at hand,
which we will explore in the coming section on tuning and triuning the
paradoxes, i * is precisely what this is a fix for, its ultimate value to

i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.

Page | 234
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

mathematics and its relation to the paradoxes of the infinite—such as Zeno’s


forty or so enigmas.
It is true that Cantor’s transfinite paradise is mathematically coherent
and that it is functional within the system of mathematics itself, but the
meaning behind the operations and labels, i.e. what they actually represent,
has remained obscured. Through the identity of the concept of set as
category, the understanding of the opposition between infinity and bounded
number has become con-fused. It has thus emerged through this abstraction
into conflict with the implicit holonic logic of sets and the philosophical and
common-sense notions of the Infinite, all leading to the current
controversies surrounding Cantor’s work. But we have seen through
mereology that this identity of opposites at work in the implicit holonic logic
of sets has been rebuilt in the purely abstract machinations of the extracted
category. Our task is to bring it into the understanding through the use of
the concept and the imagination.
One issue, as we have seen, and will continue to clarify, is that Cantor is
not dealing with The Infinite absolute, in his infinite sets, but merely with its
quantitative and abstract aspects. Furthermore, as we will see more clearly,i
Cantor himself made the distinction that his use of infinity in mathematics
speaks of a lower order of “abstract” mathematical infinity. It does not refer
to what he called “Absolute Infinity,” as is often assumed. So it is incorrect to
assume that Cantor is even discussing, comparing and contrasting degrees of
The Infinite, or even degrees of infinity itself, but more accurately, degrees
or powers of the different types of abstraction of The Infinite via set-
generation, e.g. countability; what we will come to call “set-generation
aspects” or simply “set-aspects,” which are themselves functions on the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis. Cantor’s project, then, like Zeno’s, is not
incorrect, but simply incomplete, being subsumed now by the identity of the
category.

So now we can systematically say that the countably infinite set of Natural
numbers is numerically identical to its subsets, i.e. “self-nesting,” and we can
give them all a single number or cardinality, and use that number to perform
a kind of arithmetic between them. And through this transfinite arithmetic,
recursively unfolding above us we can “see” an infinite “paradise” of ever
larger and larger infinities. Indeed, not only can we see this (mathematically
speaking), but we can wander through it and perhaps use it for practical
purposes.
Beautiful and functional as this mathematical “vision” may indeed be,
however, it does not give us a vision-logic understanding of the crucial
opposition and interface between the finite and infinite which could explain

i
* See, Cantor’s Three Infinities, p268.

Page | 235
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

why an infinite set is equal to its subsets. This Cantorian liberation and
exodus of mathematics beyond the bondage of number and into the holy-
land of the infinite ultimately serves only the pragmatic needs of exoteric
mathematics to conceive of the infinite in the identical categorical terms of
sets and subsets, in order to move beyond the troubling mathematical
paradoxes in the evolution of their abstract, percept-less operations. The
liberation into the infinite is only partially complete, restricted as it is to
mathematics and its classes of number, and not yet open to the concepts and
identities of philosophy.
Recall that Galileo also demonstrated a paradoxical one-to-one
correspondence between the squares and Natural numbers. This is where
the paradox started, and almost where it is today, as far as human
understanding and philosophy is concerned. The crucial factor for
mathematics was in the Cantorian acceptance of the paradox as simply the
way it must be. Mathematics merely had to believe—to have faith in the
paradox itself, and then to act on this faith. And in the enfolding of this
paradox into its definitions and operations, mathematics itself has become
more systematic and unified in its abstracted rule-based interfaces with the
infinite—blindly encoding, as mereology shows, the previously cast-out
part-whole holonic relation itself. But there has been little progress in the
understanding of why infinite sets behave so paradoxically contrary to
common sense and intuition. Even though we know how to perform the
rituals, we still do not understand the ways and reasons of this new
mathematical God.
In short, only for mathematicians, and essentially only in the language of
mathematics, has the paradox been solved. For the bulk of us still wrestling
with the angel of understanding, we remain stuck in a head-lock with the
same old troubling paradoxes—still con-fused by “self-nesting” violations of
the implicit holonic logic of sets and the relations between the infinite and
finite—as between God and man.
Thus we seek further differentiations and integrations, transcensions and
inclusions. We seek new methods of sensing, intuiting, understanding and
digesting this newly swallowed paradox, leaving its golden Gordian knot to
churn out infinite vistas in the darkness of our bellies. We seek not merely
to swallow the paradox, but to incorporate its hidden truth into our being.
We seek to embody and explore the understanding with our imaginations,
and hence to rid ourselves of the indigestion of this real human controversy.
We seek vision-logic interfaces with which we can resolve and assimilate
this hidden, encapsulated contra-diction.
In order to get there, however, we must traverse a great deal of new
terrain. But when we do, we will indeed have all the functions in place to
truly understand the nature of the finite-infinite polarity underlying all the
paradoxes of the infinite, including the core paradox, which is properly
Zeno’s. We’ll be able to see this polarity between infinity and bounded-

Page | 236
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

number not simply as a pair of opposites—as in the classical dichotomy—


and not merely in terms of the identical relations of the distilled category—
as in modern axiomatic set theory—but in the nondual terms of an identity
of opposites. We’ll resolve not just the polarity, but the triune interface that
provides the inter-expression that gives this identity its opposition and this
opposition its identity. Indeed, we’ll see that this core polarity itself is none
other than the triune interface between our fundamental binary VL-axes of
pure-relation; the quantized, finitized, stepwise and “countable” transitive,
visa-versus the uncountable “through and through” simultaneous “infinite
division equals indivisibility” of immanence in transcendence (yin in yang).i*

As we have seen, the modern definition of the infinite represents a serious


divergence of mathematical reasoning, or meta-mathematics, from coherent
logical, causal and experiential thought, and specifically from the implicit
holonic logic of sets. This is because, rather than solving Galileo’s paradox of
the infinite, it has merely become the definition of the infinite. This
illustrates a common problem in modern and post-modern exoteric thought,
faced as it is with many paradoxes and insoluble problems brought about by
the representational forces of the finite imagination interfacing with the
undifferentiated Infinite (e.g. the two fundamental VL-axes of conceptual
thought and its Spinozan triune interface).
It serves the interests of exoteric, pragmatic, rigorous and logical
thought, to encapsulate and insulate an annoying problem or paradox into a
principle, axiom or fundamental definition in order to make it tractable and
operational and to forget about the problem enfolded within. But at every
turn of history toward this kind of encapsulation of paradox and problem
into axiom and definition, there results a controversy, simply because the
human mind seeks answers on many different fronts (e.g. Wilber’s AQAL
quadrants). Mankind as a whole seeks not merely abstract, mathematical
and syntactic answers, but also to grasp imaginable and visualizable semantic
answers; answers that make sense to the human mind at all levels, from
percept to integrated concept.
This kind of encapsulation of paradox into principle has occurred at
nearly all of our “revolutions” of thought. It happened with Newton’s
encapsulation of the problem of the missing mechanism of gravity into a
mathematical law. It happened with Einstein’s encapsulation of the
problematic Michelson-Morley “null-results” into his a-mechanical and
acausal principle of relativity. And it happened with the problematic wave-
particle paradox (violation of causality) codified directly into the axiomatic

i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.

Page | 237
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

principle of “complementarity” or “wave-particle duality.” And in


mathematics it happened with Dedekind/Cantor’s encapsulation of the
Galilean part-whole violation into the modern definition of finite and infinite
sets. In all of these cases, the solution to a problem or paradox was
substituted by a principle that would again allow progress to be made at the
abstract, operational and quantitative level, in spite of the confusions and
controversies remaining and even magnified at the semantic level of the
senses and the imagination, and hence at the expense of coherent, integral
understanding.
Merely accepting the paradox into the hermetically sealed axiomatic
layer of tacit assumptions—with no explanation of its core polarity
whatsoever—gives the common impression that the problem has been
solved. Indeed this is essentially what is claimed with the Copenhagen
Interpretation which places the blame of paradox and confusion on Nature
herself, at the quantum-level. According to this interpretation, we simply
discovered the surprising “truth” of complementarity and wave-particle
duality and bear no capability nor responsibility to solve the problem any
further. It’s Nature’s problem now. This axiomatization of problem into
principle allows progress on the more pragmatic fronts to continue, while
hiding the semantic problem, its con-fusion and potential solution, under
layers of abstraction, creating more problems for the philosophical attempt
to understand the problem and its potential resolution.
In the case of the quantum, nothing could be further from the truth, that
the ultimate “ground of Truth” had been reached at the “foundational” level
of the senseless and paradoxical quantum. Indeed, there is no empirical
reason to think this is the case whatsoever, because you can’t know a
boundary until you have gone beyond it. The reason is purely practical, to
cement a dogma and quell the chaos of uncertainty itself by encapsulating it
into a fundamental principle. The complexity (“randomness”) surprised us
merely because we were operating on a hidden foundational mindset and
expecting to reach the absolute ground of a-tomic (indivisible) simplicity
and generality. When this was not found, the interpretations based upon it,
namely classical, particle-based and categorical notions of causation, failed.
This foundationalism, however, as we have seen, is a violation of nonduality
and the Univocity Framework. The paradox was simply placed firmly out of
reach at the level of axiomatic assumption, and taken for the ultimate truth
and foundational ground of existence in the metaphysics of scientism. These
“truths” are much easier to take as self-evident if they can be abstracted into
a principle and incorporated into everyday operational usage. Indeed, this
tendency to encapsulate an irritating paradox into a simple principle is so
common and pervasive today, that it will serve our purposes to encapsulate
this understanding into a principle of our own.

Page | 238
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

As an oyster encapsulates an irritation within layers upon layers of its


beautiful iridescent shell, so human beings encapsulate irritating problems
into intricate abstract systems of operation, with layers and layers of
impressive and daunting—and certainly useful—complexity and
abstraction. Indeed, it may be the case that in rigorous systems of thought,
such as science and mathematics, any problem or paradox of sufficient
importance that cannot be solved or removed will eventually become
encapsulated and insulated into a principle, axiom, equation and/or
fundamental definition in order to make it seamlessly tractable,
pragmatically operational, invisible and untouchable by the status quo, in
order that the normal functions of paradigm evolution can continue their
daily grind without calling into question the troubling problems at the very
foundations upon which these workers build.

The Pearl Principle is actually a meta-principle, because it deals with


principles themselves. But this meta-principle is true for the work of many
of our scientific heroes and their “revolutionary” handiwork. Newton, for
instance, couldn’t solve the causation of gravity so he incorporated it into an
operational principle (and an equation) to effectively save us from
constantly confronting the mystery; Einstein, with the help of Minkowski,
Poincaré et. al. couldn’t make sense of the Michelson-Morley null-results so
he codified it into the Principle of Relativity—a violation of common-sense,
to be sure, but it balanced the books; Bohr et al. couldn’t understand the
“wave-particle duality” and the fundamental complexity or “randomness” so
they codified it into the principles of “complementarity” and “uncertainty”
which say that the incomprehensible, “acausal” complexity and paradoxical
duality of quantum theory is intrinsic to Nature herself at the quantum level,
and that sub-atomic understanding is an ultimate impossibility; and Cantor
and friends couldn’t escape the Galilean violation of the part-whole axiom
implicit in the holonic logic of sets when looking at the Infinite through the
lens of Set Theory, so they changed the definition of infinity to incorporate

Page | 239
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

the paradox itself as the definition. In so doing, Cantor appears (but only on
the surface) to have entirely abandoned the esoteric understanding of
infinity as boundless and innumerable, calling it denumerable and bounding
it with a cardinality and number for the sake of operationality.i*
For this encapsulation of ambiguity into axiom; enigma into equation; or
paradox into principle, we give these intensely creative individuals the
highest praise. But one can’t blame us, we seek direct expansion of
pragmatic power, often regardless of whether or not we understand that
power. And we can only bang our head against a wall for so long before we
seek a new direction in the labyrinth. So it is natural to praise the guy who
points us away from the operational dead-end and into a new, more
productive direction, even if, with respect to understanding (and in this case
meta-mathematics), the operational advance is often necessarily backward
and mostly lateral in other domains, causing, in these domains, more
confusion than resolution.

i
* Though, with his own Triune Infinite in mind—which it generally isn’t to mathematicians meta-
mathematicians alike—this provides Cantor with an ambiguous sort of escape route, which we’ll
discover soon in the sub-section on Cantor’s Three Infinities, p268.

Page | 240
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Nonduality can be understood in many ways, as we have seen, but the


Univocity Framework—the fundamental polarity of scope and its
quantitative aspects in the infinite and finite—provide a unique logical and
rational clarity on the subject. From The Lotus Sutra we find, “The concept,
often described in English as ‘nondualism,’ is extremely hard for the mind to
grasp or visualize, since the mind engages constantly in the making of
distinctions and nondualism represents the rejection or transcendence of all
distinctions.”(Watson) And from Bede Griffiths (1997) we find, “Advaita
(nonduality) does not mean ‘one’ in the sense of eliminating all differences.
The differences are present in the one in a mysterious way. They are not
separated anymore, and yet they are there.”
Nonduality is, in part, the recognition that there is no ultimate duality, i.e.
ALL is “not two.” As we have seen,i* this is, because no one part of any
duality can fully contain its own essence, i.e. they are empty of essence and
arise in dependence on other parts. But the mind quickly moves from “ALL is
not two,” to the position that, “ALL is therefore one.” Nonduality says,
however, “ALL is neither two nor one. It is ‘the rejection or transcendence of
all distinctions.’” This provides the mind with an enigmatic launching pad
for a leap of intuition to understand what is meant by “all is nondual,” but it
doesn’t explain what this leap means in explicit logical or rational terms, for
to do so is to speak dualistically, because all terms are terminals of
polarities.
There is a way, however, to use polar terms and distinctions to explicate
what is happening in making this leap of intuition. The ancient non-dualists,
in this case, were simply operating on a common, singular notion of ‘unity,’
rather than making the distinction between the absolute and relative scopes,
and their quantitative aspects in the Infinite and finite modes of unity which
we will explore below. When the non-dualist says that “all is not one,” he is
addressing the student where he generally resides, at the relative scope, the
everyday world of form. He means effectively that, “in the way that all could
be two, all is not one.” In this sense, he is tacitly making the univocal
distinction between the absolute and relative scopes and negating the
relative move from duality to the common notion of unity which sees the
“One” dualistically,ii as a “principle of the same” foundationally underlying

i
* See, for example, What is Nondualism?, p56.
ii
* See, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156.

Page | 241
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

the Many. The absolute and Infinite form of Unity, however, sees the
identity of opposites of the ONE in the ALL; Unity as the identical opposite of
infinite Multiplicity; Emptiness as form, and vice versa; not two, but not
merely one.
As we have seen, duality and finite multiplicity (the Many) operate only
at the relative scope, since as soon as we have differentiation we necessarily
have relation. So when speaking of duality, or “two,” our scope is necessarily
at the relative level. In communicating the concept of the nondual, generally
when we shift to the absolute univocal scope of “ALL is ONE”—the one voice
that can only speak infinite difference—this necessary implicit shift in scope
is not communicated. Since “two” is already finite and bounded (relative
scope), then without the shift being communicated explicitly in the
“nonduality is not two,” the “ONE” would be taken as relative, finite and
bounded as well, the “one,” which is precisely the wrong meaning. This is
pointed to in the following quote from T’ai Chi Chih, “‘Advaita’ in Sanskrit
means ‘Non-Duality.’ This is a difficult concept for most people as we look
about us and see multiple objects.” The proper understanding of an Infinite
Unity is not bound to distinctions, but contains and exfoliates them all.
So, with the preliminary distinction between the absolute and relative
scopes, and the Infinite and finite aspects of unity, the leap of intuition from
bounded and relative notions of unity in the multiplicity of everyday objects,
to the Infinite and univocal “ONE is ALL” in the nondual, becomes more fully
explicated and much more easily replicated or communicated at the
cognitive and logical level.

As we have seen, Infinite Unity is absolute unity, and The Infinitei because
unboundedness, or Emptiness, is the definitional essence of the absolute
scope. This is necessarily the simplest, most fundamental and abstract of all
meta-mathematical unities. Infinite Unity can be readily summoned with the
univocal identity of opposites “ALL is ONE,” a defining feature of the
absolute scope. This is also Phase One in the embryogenesis of the concept.ii
The “ALL is ONE” was the original meaning for the term “Universe” as “one
song”; “a single voice raises the clamour of Being;” that which expresses ALL
of reality and, of necessity, as ONE inter-expressive unity. In the ALL-ONE,
there is nothing left to bound or surpass the totality of existence. ALL is
ONE, in pure principle and by definition. And in accordance with implicit
holonic logic of sets, nothing else can exist apart from the set which includes

i
* first order infinity, see Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270
ii
Note how, at the absolute scope, and in resonance with our principle of absolute reversal, the
identical opposite of ONE is automatically included in the absolute multiplicity of the ALL.

Page | 242
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

everything, i.e. The Infinite Set or the universal set-as-boundless-collection,


as opposed to “one of many” sets and subsets as bounded-collections.
Taken this way, at the absolute scope, there can be no multiple infinite
unities or UNI-verses, without a contradiction in terms, because the ALL, as
absolute scope, includes ALL of every type and instantiation, absolutely.
This is the defining feature of Buckminster Fuller’s intuitive abandonment of
the article “the” when referencing “Universe.” There is only ONE Universe,
and there is nothing other than “Universe,” so no need to make the
distinction between “the Universe” and anything else. Everything is
Universe; ALL is the ONE song; one symphonic, cacophonic clamoring of
Being expressing itself into Becoming.
Furthermore, in accordance with the principle of absolute reversal, and
the omni-non, this ultimate category of the ALL is also the absolute non-
category (and non-identity), because at this ineffable absolute scope it
cannot function categorically to partition (polarize) one concept from any
other. Infinite Unity includes ALL, period, so there can be only ONE. This
simplest of ideas is easily forgotten and the words blurred into new
meanings and confusions.i
It is easy to see here that this infinite and boundless kind of unity, at the
absolute scope, does not correspond to the mathematical concept of a
number, not even the primitive Natural number 1 (or ‘one’), which we will
see as a mathematical abstraction of the finite unity of bounded form, the
relative scope. Infinite Unity, being unbounded and absolute, cannot
participate in relational, and hence mathematical operations. Without
boundaries, it can’t relate. It is ineffable. It cannot be added to, subtracted
from, divided by or multiplied, because by definition it unfolds and enfolds
ALL in existence; there can be nothing to add to everything and nowhere
else to subtract it to. There is nothing else to relate Infinite Unity to and no
outside perspective, operation/operator or implicit hidden set, from which
to withdraw or transfer any arbitrary quantities. The “ONE” is not a number,
it is “inquantate,” because Infinity itself, the boundless ALL, is not a definable
or “boundable” magnitude.ii

Using what we are herein calling “vision-logic equations,” we can break it


down further. Vision-logic equations (VLE) use the symbols and operators
of mathematics to simplify and succinctly display the relations involved at
the vision-logic level of Interface Mathematics. They have slightly different

i
Note that, just as according to Spinoza there are infinite attributes of “God” so too there are
“aspects” of infinite unity abstracted as various infinities of a specific kind. These are the “aspect
infinities,” such as infinite space or infinite time (eternity), abstracting the spatial or temporal aspect
of The Infinite, respectively. We’ll discuss this in more depth in the section, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite,
p270.
ii
This is even true according to Cantor’s own triune categorization of kinds or degrees of infinity.

Page | 243
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

rules, which will be explained as they come up, and are used in a much
looser fashion than mathematical equations. They are used more as quick,
symbolic/visual metaphors, or maps, illustrating relations, rather than
quantitative derivations. This is largely because of their extensive use of
absolute and inquantate infinity,i and its inability to really partake in
quantitative operations—operating, as the VLE often do, between the
relative and absolute scopes.
As we discussed in The Univocity Framework (p155), The ONE-ALL
relation is the identity of opposites and univocity of the absolute and relative
scope, respectively. And as we will see, this is essentially the God/Substance
relation in Spinoza, as well.

The first conceptual operation upon the Infinite Unity of the absolute ONE is
the application of the identity of opposites and the principle of absolute
reversal to find its inverse-identical, in the absolute immanent multiplicity.
Thus we come to the quantitative aspect of Infinite Unity, the ALL. The
absolute ONE, seen relatively and quantitatively, then, is expressed as its
identical-opposite, the ALL, or The Infinite.ii* And in terms of Nondual
Rationalism, the quantitative ALL is expressed by the VLE ratio, ∞/∞.
So breaking it down using the vision-logic equations we have the
following: For our purposes the quantitative aspect of Infinite Unity (the
ALL) can be expressed loosely by the VLE:

ONE = (VLE: Infinite Unity)

The transcendent aspect of the ALL, the common notion of infinity within
absolute Unity, is expressed as:

= iii (VLE: Transcendent Infinity)iv


1

i
This is not to exclude Cantor’s transfinite operations, because, as we will see (See, Cantor’s Three
Infinities, p268), Cantor as well, in his own Triune Infinite, excluded his first order “Absolute Infinite”
from his third order “mathematical infinite,” which he defined as “abstract.”
ii
* This is the first order of infinity in Spinoza’s Triune Infinite. See, Order 1: The Absolute Infinite,
p272.
iii
…or even inversely as 1/0 = ∞ , recalling our reciprocity across the solidus and our see-saw analogy
(see The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual Rationalism (p71), that pushing
up on one side of the see-saw gives the same result as a corresponding weight on the other.
iv
We will come to find this as also expressing Leibniz’s transcendent definition of God, as opposed to
Spinoza’s definition of God, not as the transcendent pole of the immanent-transcendent axis, but as

Page | 244
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

And the immanent aspect of Infinite Unity is expressed as:

1
= immanent “zero” (VLE: Immanent Infinity)

Recall that immanent zero is really the boundless immanent pole of the
immanent-transcendent axis, or the infinite rational zero we encountered
already in The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism (p74). The boundless zero of infinite division is never reached
because it is “infinitely small.” This can also be represented by a single,
abstract and “infinitely precise” location, an ideal point or what we are
calling a Euclidean implicit singularity. In this same sense, with the
inversion occurring across the solidus/vinculum, placing a zero in the
denominator (the immanent position of the ratio) is identical to placing
infinity in the numerator (the transcendent position of the ratio).

In this interrelation between the multiple or quantitative aspects of The


Infinite, i.e. the ALL, we are already necessarily in the scope of the relative in
its quantitative view or aspect of the absolute which it generated in an act of
self-reflection.i* And in the transition through the eye of the uni-axis we
pass through the unit-boundary of the relative, the ‘one’, the uni-axial
interface between the immanent and transcendent aspects of Infinite Unity.
However, because Infinite Unity is not a bounded whole, and therefore does
not have a magnitude, it cannot be divided operationally or mathematically
and thus it cannot be quantitatively halved (or otherwise modified in
quantity). This we have already seen abstractly and incompletely in
Hilbert’s paradox of the hotel. Anywhere on the immanent-transcendent
axis that we place the solidus boundary of the one, we still have infinity on
both sides, and thus—no matter what the scale of the volumetric
solidus/vinculum—it is always exactly in the middle, yet the infinity has not
been quantitatively decreased by half even if you discard one half for the
other.
This division of Unity into polarity (e.g. ∞/∞) is therefore not properly
mathematical or quantitative, but pre-mathematical and pre-quantitative or
meta-paradigmatic; at the vision-logic level of meta-mathematical cognition
(e.g. the VLE). It is merely a percept-integrated conceptual exfoliation of a
possible intrinsic relation, or a way of conceiving the polarity between The

the absolute view of the absolute scope, or simply a transcendent emphasis of the immanent-
transcendent omni-axis and polarity.
i
* See, Polarity and Univocity (p174).

Page | 245
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Infinite and the finite unities. It is this vision-logic, nondual-rational, or


trans-rational polarity within which the mind can cycle. It is also,
essentially, the meta-mathematical abstract rendering of the union between
God and man; the absolute, ineffable Infinite Unity and the relative, effable
finite unity as the solidus-vinculum between infinite immanence and
transcendence.

As we have seen with the Hilbert and Galilean paradoxes, Infinite Unity, or
Infinity (as opposed to the common notion of infinity used, say, in the term
“infinite set,” which is merely an aspect of The Infinite), when operated
upon—divided, multiplied, added to, subtracted from, counted by odds,
evens or perfect squares into its multiple quantitative set-aspects—always
returns infinity. This is the nature of the absolute scope that, even when
conceived in its multiple aspect of the ALL, it cannot properly be operated
upon without leading to paradox or tautologyi*, such as “self-nesting” and
the ONE-is-ALL, respectively. And this is the core principle reconciling the
paradoxes of the infinite—an abstract generality which we will flesh out in
much more detail. We can see this principle as another resonating chord in
our Ariadne’s Cable, from our first chord, the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism; infinite division equals indivisibility.

i
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.

Page | 246
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Explanation: Infinite Unity is the quantitative aspect of the absolute scope, therefore
it cannot participate in the art and science of pure relation (mathematics) except for
the role of the context and field of its other. It is “inquantate,” not quantitative or
measurable. In nondual terms, Infinite Unity is “not one,” in opposition to “Many.”
i
This principle can be stated with a “vision-logic equation” where is taken as a
general operator standing for any operation, or relation, whatsoever:

n or n
* … or zero, the omni-non, given the transitive function of zero as negation. Thus, to
hold, n, in transitive functions such as multiplication, cannot equal zero.

A prime example of the failure to grasp the principle of Infinite Unity and the
modelable nature of Interface Mathematics, is with the use of the “point-
particle” in particle physics. Because the foundation of modern
mathematical reasoning (meta-mathematics) is not fully rational—in that it
does not explicitly recognize the immanent-transcendent axis or its
immanent pole and its rational-zero as the immanent expression of
infinity—physicists do not explicitly conceive of a mathematical point as
itself representing an “infinite quantity.” Because this immanent infinity
(opened up through the function of the mathematical ratio) remains hidden
and “undefined” under the rational-holonic solidus (by the transcendent-
bias of pre-rational representational forces) the scientists were surprised to
find that operations thereupon—in the form of “infinitely-small” point-
particles—returned the answer of infinity when calculating its energy as a
function of distance squared. ii This failure led to the need for the
euphemistic, and now exceedingly necessary and useful, process of

i
* See the coming section: VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-logic Equations, p288.
ii
And as we will soon see, in the holarchical unfolding of the functionality of the higher numbers and
operations the rooting and powering functions come into play when the operations and their
number-functions finally return again to the immanent-transcendent axis. See, The Holarchical
Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.

Page | 247
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

“renormalization”i where observable properties must be plugged back into


the mathematical machinations to remove the infinite results from using
point-particles with intrinsic mathematical singularities in transitive
connection to the (implicitly holarchical and immanent-transcendent)
inverse-square law.

Finite unity, is the identical-opposite of Infinite Unity and the absolute scope.
It is the unity of the relative scope. Mathematically, we will see, it is the unit-
number ‘one’ derived as the vinculum/solidus in the polarity and cycle of
Unity and the VLE ∞/∞. This is the unity of the one vs. the many, the 1 and
the n, as opposed to the univocal tautology or identity of the ONE is ALL.
Finite unity generally corresponds to Spinoza’s modifications and
Leibniz’s monads (and all emergents thereof). Indeed, Leibniz’s principle of
unity is essentially that the whole of any real unity (of which he dealt only
with the finite kind) is greater than the sum of its parts. This is essentially
the principle of emergence where real, unpredictable novelty is generated in
the synergy of the transcendence of immanent complexity into new forms.
Also, Spinoza’s notion of essence applies to finite unities in the sense that
any real finite unity will have a tendency to persist in its own being; an
emergent function of homeostasis or a “strange attractor” maintaining its
emergent form.
In Interface Mathematics, finite unity corresponds to the modelable,
volumetric root number 1, of which all others are relative aggregates,
relations, higher-functions or compounds (we’ll get into this in more depth
later).ii* Having volumetric extension and a boundary, finite unity can enter
into relations with other numbers; it can be added to and subtracted from,
divided and multiplied, odded, evened and squared to make endless and
indefinite operational sets, or definitions for infinite sets.
Finite unities, as relativities and primitive quantities, must have
boundary and magnitude, and in Fuller’s “Operational Mathematics”iii* as

i
From Answers.com: renormalization: In quantum field theory (QFT) and the statistical mechanics of
fields, renormalization refers to a collection of techniques used to construct mathematical
relationships or approximate relationships between observable quantities, when the standard
assumption that the parameters of the theory are finite breaks down (giving the result that many
observables are infinite). Renormalization arose in quantum electrodynamics as a means of making
sense of the infinite results of various calculations and extracting finite answers to properly posed
physical questions. … Some of the problems and phenomena eventually addressed by
renormalization actually appeared earlier in the classical electrodynamics of point particles in the
19th and early 20th century. When calculating the electromagnetic interactions of charged particles
…if the electron is assumed to be a point, the calculated value of this back-reaction diverges,
essentially because of the singularity at the origin in the inverse-square law.
ii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iii
* See, Empirical/Experiential Beginnings: Bucky’s “Operational Mathematics”, p217.

Page | 248
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

well as herein, they must correspond to properties of real, volumetrically


extended modifications.i Therefore each finite unity must have a within and
a without of this boundary, and this is one of the most fundamental of
relative-scope polarities. Finite unity, then, requires “unit-closure” of the
emergent intensive forces into the inter-expressive, yet oppositional forces
of unit-interaction. It is only the generalization and truncation of this
infinite depth of detail which sees the separation thereof, but the forces of
opposition cannot inter-express or come into play without this emergent
unit-closure from the immanent forces of intensity.ii*
Buckminster Fuller’s most famous and misunderstood maxim, arguably,
is “unity is plural and at minimum two.” When properly unpacked into the
imagination, this enigmatic phrase reveals an important yet deceptively
simple duality which opens the way to grasping the fundamental difference
(and polar integration) between infinity and number. This concept is also
essential to Operational Mathematics because it is the essence of finite
volumetric extension and relation and hence is key to sensorial modelability.
“A system, says Bucky, is a ‘conceivable entity’ dividing Universe into two
parts: the inside and the outside of the system.”iii¥
Bucky did not make the distinction between finite and Infinite Unity
(above), rather he was dealing exclusively with the finite, as we will address
below. With this critical distinction taken into account, however, we arrive
at our Principle of Finite Unity as the fundamental tenet of implicit holonic
set theory (see Implicit Holonic Set-Theory and the Part-Whole Axiom, p209):

Figure 12: “Finite Unity is Plural


and at Minimum Two”:
Every surface creates a distinction
between the within and the
without.

i
This also corresponds to Alfred North Whitehead’s “point-free geometry” where the implicit
singularity of the point (in our terms) is exchanged for the relativity of the finite “region,” as
Whitehead calls it..
ii
* For much more detail, see Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.
iii¥
Edmonson 25-8

Page | 249
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Explanation: This principle directly encodes the part -whole relation in the aspect of
holonic sets and invokes the symbiogenesis or emergent coupling of a finite set with its
parent- and sub-sets and vice versa, necessitating that any finite holonic set must be a
subset of a larger set and must also be composed of subsets; Any whole must be a part
of a larger whole and any part must be a whole for smaller parts. This within/without
relation is the holonic polarity implicit in finite, as opposed to infinite, unit y.

In accord with Fuller’s maxim, and indeed with his Synergetic Geometry—
and also for the same basic reasons that Whitehead generated his “point-free
geometry”—the smallest unit in Interface Mathematics is a vanishingly small
volumetric point and finite unity. This Operational, modelable and
empirically-observable spherical point is herein called a “real-point” to
contrast with the unimaginable, unobservable and unmodelable “ideal point”
in standard extensionless and non-volumetric mathematics. The real-point,
the volumetric finite unity (finity) existing at the limits of visibility, is too
small (or far away) for us to see its shape, size or magnitude, so we
approximate it with the simplest, most symmetrical shape we can imagine, a
sphere. This sphere has the intrinsic duality or polarity specified in Fuller’s
maxim and our principle of finite unity. The real point is the infinitely
divisible “anatom,” holon or corpuscle of Interface Mathematics.
The “real point” ideally correlates to the smallest currently observable,
empirically deducible, modelable object or arbitrarily selected scale of
measurement, and like all objects it necessarily has both volumetric
extension and a surface. Therefore all numbers derived from such a real
point (as is the case for the numbers in Interface Mathematics) are
boundaries or limitsi as well. And all higher-level numbers made from
compositions and relations of this finite unit are also necessarily limited in
magnitude because they are multiples or fractions of the unit-number.
The selection of the actual scale for the real-point is fundamentally
arbitrary as it is based in variable utility. Indeed, the impetus of this
volumetric stipulation is to enable a utilitarian correspondence and
resonance—an interface between mathematics and the basic elements of
nondual-rational ontology and empirical reality, such as volumetric

i
As we already discussed, it is the use of ideal non-extended points in physics, the study of physically
extended reality, that causes the problematic infinities euphemistically titled “renormalization.”

Page | 250
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

extension, boundary, relativity and modelability. The unit-number, in the


real physical operations of nondual rational meta-mathematics, is the
selected and generally predefined and standardized unit of measurement,
such as a nanometer, centimeter, kilometer or parsec.
This conclusion of both Operational and Interface Mathematics—that all
numbers (or magnitudes), as relativities, are necessarily a priori volumetric
boundaries—excludes from the relational realm of number (or “identically
opposes”) the quantitative aspects of the absolute scope, such as The Infinite
(absolute boundless) and the ideal mathematical point (the “inverse-
infinite,” or “immanent-zero”i). The Infinite (1st order), in its original form
as the boundless ALL-is-ONE,ii is ultimately not found or reached within the
quantitative operations, operators and unities of mathematics, or even
within the lines, planes, fields and figures, but it is the infinite, absolute,
transcendent and immanent field within and upon which the relative and
indefinite game of mathematics is abstracted and played out.
The Infinite is the absolute univocal context which gives the relative,
differentiated multiplicity of the finite its inter-expressive meaning (and vice
versa) and from which the aspects of infinityiii*—the infinite lines, planes,
volumes and number systems—are abstracted, constructed, transcended
and included in the holarchical unfolding of mathematics itself. The forms of
unity, therefore, mirror in their relation the fundamental polarity of the
Univocity Framework, i.e. that between the absolute and relative scopes.
This is simply because the infinite and finite are merely the quantitative or
mathematical aspects of the fundamental scopes. But even the directional
aspects of infinity (immanent, transitive or transcendent) cannot ultimately
be reached or encapsulated operationally, and thus mathematically. This is
true even though they can be represented and abstracted as “set aspects,”iv*
and their relative, quantitative and generative properties differentiated and
ranked amongst themselves abstractly (and typically in a confused way) as
“cardinalities.”
This exclusion or separation of The Infinite (absolute scope) from
Operational and Interface Mathematics (and the relative scope) may seem
slightly misleading when we think of the immanent infinity within any
number-boundary, but recall our principle (and identity of opposites) of

i
what we were also calling the rational-zero.
ii
Infinity as “boundless” is the form used throughout this work and to which this work presents a
return path without relinquishing the fruits of transfinite mathematics and set theory. It simply
redefines what a set is and how it relates to the categories of the infinite while resolving the
paradoxes that transfinite number theory was attempting to resolve by incorporating the problem
into its new and non-operational definition of “infinite”.
iii
* 2nd order Infinities, see Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270
iv
* See, Galileo, Cantor and the Transfinite, p442

Page | 251
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

immanence in transcendence.i* In the Univocity Framework, both the


immanent and transcendent poles (along with any other infinity) are aspects
of the boundless absolute, The Infinite, or Nagarjunan Emptiness. Number,
on the other hand, conceived as various functions of boundary, is necessarily
dealing within the world of form, the relative scope, not pointing outside
itself to the absolute. To be clear, there is indeed Emptiness or infinity
within all numbers, forms and boundaries, and this Emptiness and infinity is
the source of number and form itself, but this Emptiness or infinity is never
ultimately reached or encapsulated in the symbol-system itself. It is always
critically sub-representational, as Deleuze would say. It is this separation of
the absolute and relative scopes that ensures the functionality of the
Univocity Framework, and the various forms of the univocal concept of
dependent arising.ii*
Furthermore, in line with Interface Epistemology, mathematics, as an
epistemic, exploratory, unfolding function of the properties of quantitative
relation, must also be conceived as an interface gradient (an indefinitely
thick “immanent plane”) between the immanent and transcendent poles on
the immanent/transcendent omni-axis. The simple point here is that
mathematics—conceived as the tools invented and in use by man, not the
mathematical aspects of reality itself (pure relation) discovered by man in
this art and science of pure relation—is, in practice and reality, finite or
indefinite, and therefore a relative subset of The Infinite Absolute.

As we have discussed, volumetric extension is an irreducible aspect of


esoteric and Nondual Rationalism, and it is part of the essence of holarchy
because with no limits to extension, there can be no extended parts that are
not also the wholes of smaller degrees of extension, or smaller parts. For
this reason, and as we will explore in depth, any Operational and modelable
concept of number must also be extended, i.e. no numbersiii (as magnitudes)
are meaningfully represented or derived as infinitely small mathematical
points (those extensionless points are positions, rather than magnitudes).
Therefore, the distinction between infinity and number continues our visual
polarity between the formlessness of Emptiness and the boundedness of
form. The abstraction is given an experiential and sensorial grounding in the

i
* “Immanence equals transcendence (and vice versa),” see Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of
Immanence in Transcendence (Yin in Yang), p95.
ii
* See, From Dependent- to Tetra- Arising: The Conceptual Embryogenesis of AQAL, p560.
iii
It must be noted at the outset that number itself is a fused concept that has already been
differentiated into at least three main branches, cardinal (magnitude or quantity), ordinal (order or
rank), and nominal (a mere label such as #83 on a football jersey). The numbers we will be dealing
with throughout this section are generally the cardinals because they deal with quantity and
therefore mathematics proper. If and when we discuss the others, they will be labeled accordingly.

Page | 252
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

causal-logic of extension and, as we will see, this allows it to retain a


connection with the causality which, through billions of years of evolution,
has informed the innate and powerful imagination of mankind, in its
holarchic navigation between agency and communion.

Figure 13: Orthogonality at the Boundary:


This diagram illustrates the orthogonality between the two polarities infinity/number
and within/without.

A primitive number or magnitude is a boundary or finite unity—represented


in simplest terms by the circle in Figure 13, above—whereas The Infinite is
boundless, beyond all conception, perception, magnitude and number,
corresponding crudelyi to the white background, before any boundary is
drawn. Note that this polarity is not the same as the polarity of the within
and without of the uni-axis upon which this boundary-interface is manifest.
The I/T polarity of the uni-axis is—in the sense provided by this
representation—orthogonal to the polarity of the boundary and the
boundless. The polarity at the boundary divides the infinite into two
portions, the within and the without, while the orthogonal polarity of the
finite and infinite distinguishes infinity as a whole (both within and without
together), from the interface which divides it, and whose immanent

i
… and with a strong transcendent-bias due to the plane of the paper image.

Page | 253
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

substance connects it. This polarity between The Infinite and number
means, however, that even the primitive bounded number one is
intrinsically infinite—an implicit and encapsulated infinite number. As we
will see in detail in the Cycle of Unity, boundary itself comes into being
conceptually from the boundless. A polarity, recall, is not just an opposition,
but also an identity.
This dual polarity and infinity essential to finity forms another tetrad,
which it seems Fuller was not aware of, as it necessitates a fundamental and
inseparable distinction (polarity) between The Infinite and number. This is
a variation and extension of the polarity of the infinite and the finite, as well
as the polarity of its unities, which we already explored.i* This is, rather, the
polarity of the ONE-ALL and the ‘1,’ as the interface of its ONE-one uni-axis.ii*
In Interface Mathematics, once that boundary is drawn (or perceived) a
number can be introduced into consciousness, or the imagination, to
represent, keep track of, and make use of, the bounded object. Numbers
(again as magnitudes) cannot come into being, either causally or
experientially, and have no function without at least tacitly representing, or
being capable of representing, some real, physically-conceived limit—be it
known or unknown.

Note how the image of a boundary on an infinite sheet of paper naturally


imposes the intuition that the interior is bounded while the exterior is not.
In a very real sense (immanent/transcendent), this is an illusion formed by
an objective, transitive or external bias persistent in human psychology. The
exterior is just as bounded by this boundary because its substance (or its
abstracted directions and freedoms) presses up against the walls every bit
as much as does the interior substance. Thus “unity is plural and at
minimum two.” Every boundary generates two bounded bodies, the within
and the without.
But objectively we can see that there is a constant and finite amount of a
specific material (e.g. paper, or a number of atoms or finite unities of a
specific and defined scale) within every boundary, while there may be an
infinite or indefinite amount of the same specific material external to it
(minus the internal portion, removing it from the univocal ONE-ALL).
Therefore, another part of the transcendent-bias must be that given a
constant resolution of units (finite unities), “infinitely more” will fit outside
the boundary than can ever fit within. Therefore, recognition of the I/T
polarity, along with our Cycle of Unity (below), requires the transcension of

i
* See, The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite (p221) and, Unity and Nonduality (p239).
ii
* See The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 254
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

boundary itself, as an arbitrary position on the I/T uni-axis, or omni-/non-


locally on the omni-axis as a transitive plane.
Note that the transcendent-bias is found in the real properties of a
nucleated substrate necessitated in the actual formation of its matter-uniti
because of the real distinction of the “infinite” available “material”
(nucleated substrate or transitive plane) outside the boundary as contrasted
to the finite resources within the boundary.ii This taken into account, the
bias has its reality in the emergent generation of the basic unit or “simplest
body” at whatever of the infinite “root-levels” or transitive planes of
existence we take, and thus even at the “root level” there is substantiality to
the transcendent-bias. Given this understanding and recognition, we can
counter it accordingly to get beyond its default perceptual restrictions.
Also note that this is a self-recurring trans-foundational theme and that
there is necessitated an infinite holarchical “regress” or progress of
nucleation—or form from Emptiness—as turtle rests on turtle rests on
turtle rests on turtle all the way up and all the way down.iii The transitive or
transcendent bias is ever-present in differentiated—if sub-perceptual—
space and time and infinitely, and holarchically self-recurring, as
represented in the uncountable I/T axis.
This “bias” is actually the simple fundamental drive of evolution or
“telos” toward ever further transcendence. Such a bias certainly favors the
survival and autonomy of the individual to live to reproduce its code. So not
only is it a natural and necessary element of the initial formation of any
nucleus and basic-level holon, but it is part of the driving essence of
evolution itself. Thus we can see this essence as it echoes from nucleated
agglomerative substrate into the formation of a higher-level basic nucleus
and on into transcension and inclusion up the ladder of holonic
agglomeration or the pyramid of development, and at higher levels we see
the same initialization process with the stars and galaxies or voids whose
frequencies are beyond our ken.

i
This will be discussed in much greater depth in SpinbitZ: Vol. II
ii
This is in order to satisfy the Venturi pressure difference at the interface of motion or spin which
creates the bit of matter known as the matter unit. This real pressure difference is what causes the
nucleus to condense and differentiate substantially into the basic matter-unit. This is quite literally
and viscerally, the initial “contraction in the face of infinity,” and it represents the initial move from
immanence into the transitive dimensionality as one holon looking out and among many. The
contraction is the basic form of agency, while its chemical bonding harmonics and other
environmental interactions are the initial acts of communion.
iii
This is because it takes a nucleated substrate, with its transitive bias, to generate a Venturi effect
and a higher-level pressurized and differentiated nucleus … again to be explored more thoroughly in
SpinbitZ: Volume II

Page | 255
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

When, in Interface Mathematics, we first operate pre-mathematically upon


the Infinite Unity of the ONE-ALL,i* it is really only upon its abstracted
immanent multiple aspect, the uncountable ALL of infinite multiplicity.ii* In
the embryogenesis of the concept—differentiating-and-integrating,
transcending-and-including from generality to higher and deeper levels of
specificity—this pre-mathematical operation is accomplished first through
breaking the ineffable abstraction of the ONE into the first polarity
represented by the immanent-transcendent omni-axis and the absolute
ONE-ALL.
This ALL-ONE omni-axis, recall,iii* is the omni-uni of extension because it
encapsulates in its concept the entirety of the boundless labyrinth of the
continuum of immanent points, each of which is the implicit singularity and
immanent pole of an I/T uni-axis.iv* Given this, however, it is at the same
time the omni-nonv* of position or locality—as we recall from I/T Omni- and
Uni-axes (p146)—because encapsulating all positions allows no distinction
of one position from any other. The omni-axis is pre-differentiated with
respect to position. Being the pre-differentiated omni-non of position,
however, the omni-axis is also the omni-non of directionality, and

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
iii
* See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
iv
* Figure repeated from I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
v
* See, The Omni-Non: The Binary Logic of the Absolute/Relative Interface, p120.

Page | 256
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

magnitude,i because the aspect of position (and its immanent infinity) is


requisite to define the existence of any real and modelable boundary, finite
unity and primitive (infinite) number ‘1’ of the first mathematical operation
of counting. It is also thus requisite for the compound and much more
complex functions of number as well as its magnitude (scale/amount),
motion (vector) or directional relation to any other existing real magnitude.

Figure 8: Repeated from I/T Interfaces, the Omni -Uni and the Omni-Non.

This gives us an interesting polarity between the aspects of position and


extension (or continuity) when taken at the absolute scope of the omni, or
the ALL—which is the uncountable infinite multiple aspect of the ONE of
Infinite Unity at which both omni- and uni- axes converge. The aspects of
extension and position, when taken at the absolute scope, appear to be
identical opposite of each other. But in quantitative terms, the uni-aspect of

i
In mathematics these correspond roughly to coordinate, vector and scalar, respectively.

Page | 257
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

the uni-axis (the one singularity of the one axis) is finite and the uni-aspect of
the omni-axis (the ONE of ALL uni-axes) is infinite. The quantitative
difference between the uni-aspects of the uni- and omni-axes (i.e. the ‘one’
and the ‘ONE,’ respectively), therefore, presents us with the critical relative-
to-absolute polarity underlying the Cycle of Unity, as we will see. But recall
that this polarity is exactly that of the absolute or infinite aspects of
extension vs. position already embodied in the two poles of the uni-axis; the
ONE and the singularity (See Figure 8, above). Also, recall that we have only
two VL-axes in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System. The Cycle of Unity, then,
is the binary cycle by which the uncountable I/T axis breaks into the
fundamental unit by which to stepwise generate the countable transitive-
axis and to begin the agglomerative embryogenesis of mathematics itself.
Because of this, we can conceive of the uni-axis as the VL-axis (vision-
logic level axis) of the ONE-one, but ‘one’ in both the sense of the one
singularity, as well as being the VL-axis upon which we can define the one-
boundary and vinculum of finite unity. This gives us the distinction between
the VL-axes of the absolute ONE-ALL (omni) and the absolute-relative ONE-
one (uni), and it is critical to note the difference here in terms of scope. The
ONE-ALL, note, is fully contained in the absolute scope (as denoted by the
CAPS), even if viewed through the relative aspect of the multiple to give us
the infinite ALL. The ONE-one and uni-axis, on the other hand, actually gives
us a finite or quantitative aspect in the single position of the one singularity
hiding at its center. It is thus our first relative polarity (as opposed to an
absolute tautology) and conduit from the absolute to the relative scope.
While the omni- and uni- axes converge at the transcendent pole, the
interfaces of each are vastly different, recall. The interface of the omni-axis
is an unbounded volumetric expanse of a specific scale (a transitive plane),
whereas the interface of the uni-axis is the spherical boundary of our finite
unity. The polarity between the two I/T interfaces, therefore, swings us
from the Unity of the absolute, in the ALL-ONE to the unity of the relative in
the unit-interface of the uni-axis. This is the polarity underlying the Cycle of
Unity.
The Cycle of Unity begins with the transition, from the pre-differentiated,
uncountable omni-non of ALL-ONE positions (and thus infinite continuity)
shared by the transcendent poles of both I/T axes, to the infinitely
differentiated ‘one’ singularity of any particular ONE-one uni-axis. Due to
the Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity,i the VLE for Infinite Unity (∞/∞)
is at this point pre-differentiated, and can represent either the omni- or uni-

i
See, Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, p245. “Infinite Unity, or its
unbounded aspects of infinity, when operated upon, always returns infinity. Thus Infinite Unity is, to
coin a term, “inquantate,” not quantitative or immeasurable. In nondual terms, Infinite Unity is ‘not
one.’” Regardless of whether or not the infinity is the Euclidean implicit singularity of the uni-axis,
or the infinite multiple of the omni-axis, infinity is inoperable, quantitatively.

Page | 258
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

I/T axis. But to move from the mutual ALL-ONE in transcendence to our
transitive finite unity, with its one location and bounded magnitude, we
must transition from the omni-non of position (the omni-axis), to its
identical opposite in the omni-uni of position (the uni-axis, with its one
immanent singularity opposite the ONE.)

Figure 14: Univocity Framework for the I/T Axes and Interfaces:
This diagram illustrates the I/T axes and interfaces in the context of the Univocity
Framework.

Recall that in the Univocity Framework, the ONE-ALL of the omni-axis is an


absolute scope polarity, and therefore a univocal tautology,i* where infinite
omni-local immanence is infinite transcendence and the ALL is already
contained in the ONE, and vice versa. In this absolute ineffable tautology we
can oscillate endlessly, moving everywhere at once and thus nowhere …
except for the nondual realization of this identity itself. When, in this
oscillation we next reach the transcendent ONE, however—because the
omni- and uni-axes overlap at the transcendent pole—instead of flipping
back to its identical opposite in the absolute ALL, we can transition toward
the first true (non-tautological and relative) polarity to touch the relative
scope. This is the ONE-one of the uni-axis—where infinite immanence is

i
* See, Exploring the Univocity Framework, 190.

Page | 259
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

infinite transcendence in the sense of a true operational polarity between


the ONE and the one. See Figure 14, above.

Figure 15: Polarity of the Forms in the Cycle of Unity:


This figure represents the polarity between The Infinite and the finite forms of unity, in
the transition from the relative view of Infinite Unity, the ALL, represented by the VLE
/ , to the “one of many” finite unities, identifiable as the holonic, volumetric
vinculum/solidus itself or represented simply by 1, our fundamental and primitive
number as implicit infinity. Infinite Unity, ONE, is non-quantitative, given that it is
unbounded, whereas finite unity is the boundary itself, particularly that between the
immanent and transcendent aspects of Infinite Unity and the I/T uni -axis.

From the transcendent Infinite Unity which both VL-axes share, this pre-
mathematical oscillation transitions us between them—from The Infinite
ONE to a single positional aspect of infinity—the implicit singularity of the
‘one’ of absolute position—but not yet to our finite unity of the first
mathematical boundary and number. On this I/T uni-axis, a “pre-
coordinate” is implicit or emergent as the unit-interface between the
immanent and transcendent aspects of the uni-axis. This boundary breaks
the infinite ALL of the absolute ONE into the relative scope “one of many.”i*
This boundary can be located or derived at any position on any arbitrarily
selected immanent/transcendent uni-axis. See Figure 15, above.

i
* See, Finite Unity: “Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two”, p246.

Page | 260
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

It must be emphasized that the “division” and interface, represented by the


solidus/vinculum of the VLE ∞/∞—in both the ONE-ALL of the omni-axis
and the ONE-one of the uni-axis—is not properly considered a mathematical
operation. These are, rather, pre-mathematical, conceptual operations
symbolized after-the-fact in mathematical terms as indicated by the meta-
mathematical and vision-logic level of the VLE. We speak of division here
only in the sense of the embryogenesis of the concept (EOTC) from ineffable
transcendent-biased Unity into both of these immanent-transcendent
polarities, rather than in the sense of a mathematical ratio which, at a higher
level and function of number, violates the closure property of the finite unity
of the integers and generates a whole new infinite set, as we will see.i*
At this level in the developmental holarchy of mathematics there is yet no
first number or quantitative variability with which to form a differential
ratio. Nor are the a priori immanent-transcendent omni- and uni- axes, their
holonic solidus/vinculum interfaces and the continuum yet limited to the
magnitudes producible/reachable by the higher function of the ratio, with its
Dedekind cuts, etc. There is, at this point in the EOTC of mathematics, only
the pre-differentiated Infinite, absolute boundless, formless, logical
Emptiness or absolute Unity, abstracted into an undifferentiated “multiple
aspect,” the infinite multiplicity and continuity of the ONE-ALL.
As such, none of these pre-mathematical operations has any immediate
bearing on mathematics itself, except insofar as the understanding of
mathematics is concerned, and the effects this meta-mathematical
understanding could have on its evolution. This is simply meta-mathematics,
which is generally considered frivolous to mathematicians unconcerned
with the philosophy of their subject, and likely, in that case, with philosophy
in general. But in my case, this understanding, and in particular the
understanding to come, greatly helped in my own studies of mathematics
and in passing my exams, so it has a clear practical value.

From this pre-differentiated multiple aspect in the ALL we begin the


embryogenesis of operation and number. But only through a “breaking of
symmetry”—from the absolute scope of Infinite Unity, through its aspect in
absolute multiplicity, and ultimately into the relative scope of finite unityii—
can mathematics properiii even begin. And it must begin at square ‘one’;
literally with the finite unity of the primitive number ‘1,’ which itself is an
enfolded implicit infinity, a “bounded infinite” and primitive infinite number

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
We can already see the Triune Infinite in this interface of The Infinite and finite.
iii
Mathematics in the common sense of operations on pre-existing numbers returning differentiated
answers.

Page | 261
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

as pure-relational counterpart to Spinoza’s “simplest body” which we’ll


explore in great depth later.i* In the real-world as empirical correlate, this
manifestation of our primitive finite unity takes place as the emergence of
whatever modification is the bounded object, and set thereof, of the first
primitive mathematical operation of counting. Such manifestation always
takes place in a sub-representational arena, beneath and before the
representation of mathematics itself, and so in the embryogenesis of the
concept of Interface Mathematics as well.
The common tendency to take the immanent pole of this uni-axis—our
familiar “zero-dimensional,” “infinitely small” “mathematical point”—as our
finite unity and first number must be resisted, because unlike our first
“natural” numbers, this point is unbounded, an implicit singularity, and
hence an infinite logical-Emptiness, not a finite, form. It is actually not a
unity at all, but an implicit singularity; a single pole of an unbounded polarity,
and ultimately merely an immanent positional aspect of Infinite Unity.ii*
So we have painstakingly transitioned from the ONE to the ONE-ALL to
the ONE-one and its interface in finite unity. At this point (after manifesting
the ‘one’ of the holonic solidus interface) the necessary pre-differentiated
equality of the pre-mathematical ratio, / —which, in a mathematical
equation (if we were not dealing the pre-mathematical Infinite), would
normally return ‘1’—then returns us back to the pre-quantitative, absolute
and transcendent ONE of Infinite Unity which both the uni- and omni-axes
share, completing the cycle of absolute and relative unities. See Figure 16,
below.

Figure 16: VLE of the Cycle of Unity:


This VLE symbolically represents The Cycle of Unity. Note that the vinculum in the
statement ∞/∞ is a 1, representing the 1 of finite unity as the boundar y on the
immanent/transcendent uni -axis.

To make this more visceral and tangible, and to provide us with useful tools
for the Triune Infinite, The Cycle of Unity can be visualized as an eccentric
orbit; a univocal cometary journey of representation from the dark, vast

i
* See, Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.
ii
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.

Page | 262
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

reaches of Infinite Unity or Emptiness, swiftly past the upper complexities of


“higher mathematics,” hurtling inward to the bright, primitive origin-point
of the relative in mathematical representation; our finite unity and primitive
number ‘1.’ After briefly grazing the surface boundary of this origin of
mathematics, we swing back again, out into the ineffable Emptiness of sub-
representation and pre-mathematics, Infinite Unity and the absolute scope.
See Figure 17, below.

Figure 17: The Orbit of Unity:


This image represents The Cycle of Unity in the image of an eccentric orbit. Towards
the “center of attraction” in the analogy, we approach the boundary between
immanence and transcendence in the solidus/vinculum of the VLE / and moving
outward, toward “outer space,” we approach absolute and Infinite Unity.

Beginning in the outermost regions of the orbit, in the slowness of our


distant position we can afford the time to download some terminology
needed to properly explore our next journey, and for use later in this book.
In astronomy, the apsis of an elliptical orbit denotes the point of greatest or
least distance of a celestial body from its center of orbital attraction. The
periapsis is the closest approach—in this case, the point of originary contact
with mathematics in the representation of the object of counting via our
primitive finite unity, the number ‘one.’ The apoapsis, on the other hand, is
the furthest point—in this case this outermost position from the primal unit-
boundary of mathematics is the return to its identical opposite, the pre-
mathematical, inquantate Infinite Unity of the unbounded ONE-ALL. Along
the way, we must pass through many other regions of complexity necessary
for the journey, but only briefly as we speed inward to the center of our
focus.
At the outer-reaches and apoapsis of our orbit, we are in the domain of
Infinite Unity, the ineffable absolute scope. In its nondual or univocal form

Page | 263
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

this can be written as “ONE is ALL” (i.e. Unity = Multiplicity), and in its
relative and purely immanenti form as the multiple aspect, the ALL. From
the absolute ONE of Infinite Unity, we break from the stalled symmetry of
our orbital apoapsis, falling from the ONE-ALL of infinite complexity toward
the infinite focus and implicit singularity of the first polarity to touch the
relative-scope, the ONE-one and uni-axis. We pass swiftly through the
orbital clouds of higher-mathematics and arrive at the cultivated third of this
first relative polarity giving us the primary boundary needed for our
nondual-rational vision-logic interface understanding of the embryogenesis
of mathematical operations.
Nearing the point of closest approach, from this relative view—
embedded in the representational “orbital dynamics” of the infinite ALL and
its ONE-one uni-axis—the absolute scope of Infinite Unity can be further
abstracted (represented in either its omni- or uni-axis forms) and written by
the VLE statement; ∞/∞. For a brief moment, the periapsis of our orbit is
now distinctly in view. It is the division center of the vinculum/solidus; the
closest point in our orbit to the first meta-mathematical boundary of form
and duality, but the furthest from the nondual identity of immanence in
transcendence (yin in yang); the vastness of logical-Emptiness and Infinite
Unity, respectively. Accelerating us on in the fastest portion of our orbit the
equality of the representative VLE-ratio quickly returns us, in its pre-
mathematical unbounded function, to the ONE of Infinite Unity, flinging us
back into the vast Emptiness from which we came.

The observant reader will be struck by the inadequacy of the orbital analogy.
It is clearly imbued with a transcendent-bias … of all things. This can be
seen in the simple fact that the outer vastness of space represents both
transcendence and immanence whereas the inward direction moves us
toward its VLE division in the solidus/vinculum boundary. We can,
however, turn the unbalanced analogy inside-out, flipping the immanent-
transcendent polarity. Instead of approaching the boundary of the unit-
number from the outside, we can approach it from the infinite depth within
and return to this depth from whence we came on the outbound leg of the
journey.
Combining the two analogies into one, however, provides a more
integrated, balanced and complete view of the unity and distinction of this
most critical immanent-transcendent polarity. The goal in both cases is still
the approach towards the primitive boundary and origin point in Interface

i
…in the sense of “immanence in transcendence.”

Page | 264
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Mathematics, but now we approach it from both directions, simultaneously,


i.e. from both immanence and transcendence.

Figure 18: The Double Orbit of Unity (ant mobius image from M.C. Escher):
This diagram illustrates the mobius -aspect of the Orbit of Unity analogy, in that the
outer leads to the inner, and vice versa. This image is superior to the orbit of unity
because it transcends the transcendent -bias to show the immanence in transcendence
of the ONE-ALL. In this diagram, the 8 represents the ALL which is the relative view of
the ONE. The apoapses of both the immanent and transcendent loops represents the
limits of representation, and the self -crossing represents the location of the unit -
boundary and primitive number 1 of our finite unity between immanence and
transcendence.

To do this, instead of using a circular orbit, we use a figure eight. This figure
is the traditional symbol of infinity, the “lazy eight,” but turned upright;
perhaps to denote the awareness of the transcendent-bias in mathematics
and adopted in the ratio of our VLE. For the sake of convention, but now in
full awareness of the bias, the top loop of our figure-eight, represents
transcendence and the bottom, immanence—as in our VLE ∞/∞, and the
standard positions in the mathematical ratio. The return point of each—
both the top and bottom extremes of the eight—still represents our
apoapsis, the ONE-ALL, respectively, but this time we can see it more clearly

Page | 265
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

as the limits of representation itself. These indefinite limits appear precisely


as we turn for home after tiring of our infinite exploratory journey in both
immanent and transcendent directions simultaneously (e.g. the Planck scale
and the limits of the visible universe). In this sense, the eight itself
represents the limitations of the relative view of the ONE as the ALL, while
the ONE-ALL itself ultimately remains beyond representation. See Figure
18, above.
From the dark, sub-representational vastness of our dual apoapses of
Infinite Unity, we approach—in both immanent and transcendent directions
simultaneously—the central finite boundary and origin-point of Interface
Mathematics. This double motion is denoted by the triangular arrows on the
8-path. Note how this figure can also be seen as our familiar mobius strip,
with the motion, beginning on the outside (transcendence, or yang),
naturally ending up on the inside (immanence, or yin), and vice versa.
Where the two paths cross and immanence becomes transcendence, we
have our unit-boundary, finite unity and primitive (infinite) number 1. This
first boundary in Interface Mathematics occurs precisely where we
arbitrarily determine it to be, and this is generally half-way between the
limits of representation in both immanent and transcendent directions. This
can be seen, in the real world of scientific/empirical mensuration,i in the fact
that the meter—the scale of “man, the measure of all things,”—is almost
exactly half-way between the assumed immanent and transcendent limits of
reality itself, namely the Planck scale and the size of the visible universe,
respectively. From either direction, both immanent and transcendent, the
meter is divided or multiplied (respectively) into deeper layers of unit scales
with their own exponentiating prefixes—deci/deka, centi/hecto, milli/kilo …
and so forth, in both directions, all the way in and out to … yocto/yotta, and
beyond.

Spinoza makes an important clarification to the polarity of the finite and The
Infinite, but he places his emphasis between the Infinite and the imagination
(i.e. representation), which he sees necessarily as finite, given its modal
nature and what we are calling its relative scope in the world of form. ii This
difference, he says in his famous Letter XII on the Infinite, is crucial to
untangling the confusions surrounding the infinite (as we will very soon
see). The Infinite is “that, which can be understood but not imagined” and

i
i.e. measurement.
ii
Technically, the imagination, or representation, is the epistemic level of the world of form, or what
the Hindus/Buddhists call Maya, the real world of real illusion.

Page | 266
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

the finite is “that which can [be understood and] also be imagined.”i¥ This is
the primary scope distinction between absolute and relative—the
fundamental polarity of the Univocity Framework—rendered in terms of the
multiple or quantitative aspects of the imagination, and the limitations of the
forces of representation.
In Spinoza’s view, all images or representations are part of the relative
and finite (or indefinite) imagination. This would then include perception
and conception, while the reality of this necessary representational illusion
of sensation and other forms of the imagination is our qualitative
connection, our interface with, and as, reality (and specifically a finite unity
thereof).ii*
Accordingly, the most primitive form we will explore in the
embryogenesis and holarchical unfolding of Interface Mathematics is the
very first Operational number, form, boundary and finite unity in
contradistinction to The Infinite and its ineffable and inoperable Unity, as
discussed above. This primitive unit-number is necessarily represented by
an image in the imagination or a real object of relative perception, already
designated herein by the appearance of the circular boundary on the white
paper in Figure 13, above (p254), but it is also the real object being counted
in the primitive forms of mathematics from whence we derived the natural
numbers. The Infinite, however, exists beyond, or prior to, any image or
boundary being introduced and thus beyond the imagination. Both the
infinite set of all possible real numbers and a space of infinite extent are
impossible to encapsulate in one’s imagination yet they are quite easy to
understand logically and procedurally. Just imagine endlessly counting by
ones, or multiplying by some recursive, set-generating algorithm, or imagine
an endless expanse of space, a horizon with no boundaries.
This imagination is the indefinite. The interfacing of The Infinite with
the finite forms of time. Through logic and intuition, we must then assume
that it simply goes on “forever” because we can’t get there in our
imaginations. Thus infinity is simple to understand through the rules of logic
and with the help of the imagination, but it is impossible to visualize, imagine
or encapsulate as a totality. The best we get with the imagination is the
indefinite, not the infinite.
Therefore, as the rationalists correctly noted, the abstract understanding,
reason or rationality, coupled with the intuition, can grasp things (at least
relatively so) of a general and symbolic nature extending beyond, or
transcending and including the capabilities of the detailed imagination,
including both objective and subjective forms such as perception. The


Letter XII (B. D. Spinoza)
ii
* See Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” in this book and the
discussion on the Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object,
p528.

Page | 267
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

higher levels of concept, such as logic and reason, can (and should)
transcend and include percept. An understanding of infinity is therefore
always necessarily a conceptual abstraction based on the mnemonic
foundations at the interface of perception/conception, just as every
modification is an abstraction from the infinite itself. But without the
imagination and its foundational perceptions to aid in the process of
transcending itself, there is no understanding of the finite or the infinite.

In light of this analysis, it is odd that Fuller seemed to conceive of “Universe”


as necessarily finite in extent. Fuller took onboard the reigning positivistic
baggage in saying that since the infinite is beyond the senses (and
imagination) and cannot be included in the range of empiricism and
Operational Mathematics, then it also cannot exist in reality (or more
correctly, as reality). However, his principle that “unity is plural and at
minimum two” inherently negates such an absolutistic conclusion (not to
mention the performative contradiction inherent in positivism). As we have
discovered, the “unity” that Fuller is talking about is the finite or bounded
unity. The duality of every finity necessitated by Fuller’s own principle of
mathematical unity negates its own absolute status because, according to
this principle, a fundamental polarity extends omni-directionally within and
without every surface, transcending it in both directions by definition. In
other words, as soon as a boundary is introduced for the extent of Universe,
its magnitude is surpassed by the necessity of an outside in relation to an
inside.
This is perhaps better understood with a simple example; every number
can be doubled, thus every time you think of the infinite as a number you
can, in principle, instantly double it or even add one to it. Conceiving of
number as a boundary, therefore, Fuller’s fundamental polarity necessitates
that there is a beyond to every conceivable limit and thus there can be no
final boundedness to Universal space; and working inwardly from the same
principle, there can be no smallest conceivable volume.
One feasible recourse for Bucky to maintain his finite Universei would be
an appeal to non-Euclidean geometry, but this falls outside his definition of
Operational Mathematics and the stipulation of experiential modelability,
and it also renders his Principle of Operational Unity as problematically and
arbitrarily special case, given that it would not apply to the unity of

i
Unless of course Bucky’s Universe was only dealing with the finite realm of observability, which
would fit with his notion of modelability, but it would necessitate his unrecognizing of the
fundamental distinction between the finite world of mathematics and the Infinite. It would mean
that Bucky did not recognize that the boundless, in principle, cannot be encapsulated in the realm of
the bounded, but vice versa. But then he likely didn’t study Spinoza or Leibniz.

Page | 268
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Universe. The finite unity (boundedness or finity) gives rise to duality and
only the Infinite Unity (boundless ALL and absolute scope) can be truly ONE
and non-dual because it contains and exfoliates all polarity.i
Bucky is correct, however, that infinity does not properly operate within
physics, observation or mathematics. He is right that The Infinite is not to be
found within any finite descriptive (subjective or objective) system, but he
neglects the inverse conclusion (necessitated by his own principle) that all
finite systems or wholes are to be found within, and necessitated upon, a
greater sub-meta-representational system or whole, and ultimately upon the
infinite division equals indivisibility or continuity of the fundamental
Principle of Nondual Rationalism. That nondual continuity as infinite
discontinuity (and vice versa) is the only thing capable of “giving rise” to a
boundless series of possible boundaries in the embryogenesis of the concept
of Universe.

i
This is another route for Spinoza’s “escape” from the mode to arrive at infinite and continuous
substance.

Page | 269
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

According to the evolution and embryogenesis of the concept, polarities


generally differentiate and integrate to triunities, or cultivated thirds. What
then is the cultivated third of the polarity we just explored between The
Infinite and the finite, or more properly between the quantitative aspects of
the absolute and relative scopes? As we will see, the interfacing of the finite
(relative scope) with The Infinite (absolute scope), necessarily results in a
triune organization; the Triune Infinite, first explored in detail, perhaps, by
Spinoza. Due to the simultaneous, nonlinear (and rhizomatic) nature of
these concepts, we have already seen many of the features of the Triune
Infinite in action; sometimes implicitly, and sometimes explicitly, such as the
unfolding “aspects” of The Infinite, which we will flesh out in much more
detail below.
Indeed, it is fascinating to note that many thinkers, for whatever reason,
have independently come to the same general conclusion of three types or
degrees of infinity. These include Giordano Bruno, Spinoza, Hegel and even
Cantor, as well as many others. It is even found in the field of psychology
with H. Wilkinson’s “three infinities in psychoanalysis.”i¥ It was found all
over in medieval texts and even in the hermeneutic wars over the nature of
the holy trinity; e.g. are there three separate and infinite Gods or merely
three aspects of the one infinite God? In most of these cases, it is only the
tripartite nature that these incidences seem to have in common, but there
may be more than co-incidence at work here in this relative interface of the
number three with the absolute scope or the divine.

As mentioned previously, Georg Cantor also had a three-fold categorization


of the infinite, but his system doesn’t quite map exactly to the three degrees
discussed herein, as we will see, and it leaves some critical gaps. Cantor
says, “The actual infinite arises in three contexts: first when it is realized in
the most complete form, in a fully independent otherworldly being, in Deo,
where I call it the Absolute Infinite or simply Absolute; second when it


Wilkinson H. . Psychoanalysis as finite, psychoanalysis as infinite? Psychoanalysis’ religious
potential: International Journal of Psychotherapy, July 2003, vol. 8, no. 2, pp. 147-168(22)

Page | 270
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

occurs in the contingent, created world; third when the mind grasps it in
abstracto as a mathematical magnitude, number or order type.”
Given that, for Cantor, mathematical infinities only occur at the third
level, that of abstraction, or what we would call representation, it is
important to note that none of Cantor’s revolutionary transfinite
mathematics deals at all with our absolute scope, The Infinite or the ONE-
ALL of univocal Emptiness. All of Cantor’s work is strictly at his own third
order of infinity, in abstracto; the realm of the relative scope and the forces
and limitations of representation, with its inability to ultimately or
absolutely encapsulate the absolute scope and its abstracted quantitative
aspects. Recall that this is the critical feature of the Univocity Framework
and the nature of the nondual and Nagarjuna’s Emptiness. This feature
alone, of Cantor’s metaphysical context—if grasped by those mathematicians
and philosophers of mathematics who take issue with Cantor’s work—could
perhaps get us much of the way toward a resolution of the controversies at
the heart of modern “axiomatic” set theory. We’ll explore this in much more
depth later.i*
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite has a slightly different, less transcendental and
less theological mapping. In univocity there is no “fully independent
otherworldly being” because the ALL is the ONE in Substance and its infinite
modifications. But Cantor may be intuiting the absolute/relative scope
polarity as an independent duality, and generally from a transcendent-bias.
In this sense his 1st order can be seen as the absolute ineffable scope of The
Infinite, or the ONE, and his 2nd order can be seen as the relative scope view
of the absolute, or the ALL of infinite multiplicity as it appears in the
“contingent” reality of modification. His 3rd order, however, appears to be
merely a catch-all for all possible representational and quantitative infinities,
namely those of mathematics, which is then where we find the infinite levels
of infinities of his transfinite sets; all merely 3rd order mental abstractions of
“mathematical magnitude, number or order type(s).” So, essentially,
Cantor’s three infinities can be expressed as Absolute, Ontic, and
Mathematical (this last category of mathematical infinities is merely a subset
of the epistemic or representational forms of the infinite (aspects), i.e.
mathematics as the representation (art/science) of pure relation).
We will find a slightly different mapping in Spinoza, and one that is far
more useful for making sense of the polarity of The Infinite and finite, and
the paradoxes that they have inspired. We will find that Cantor’s loose set of
types leaves out several critical distinctions. Indeed, Cantor’s third
distinction is not a distinction in kind or degree of infinity, but merely based
on where it is found—in Cantor’s specialty, Mathematics—and, most
critically, it makes no room for non-mathematical forms of representational

i
* See, Galileo, Cantor and the Transfinite, p442.

Page | 271
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

infinity, such as those found in philosophy and the epistemic modes of


ontology.
Clearly, however, there is a great deal of collective intuition behind this
basic idea of a triunity in the infinite, and the following will flesh it out in
detail demonstrating some of the value behind this vast historical impetus.

In Spinoza’s famous letter to Meyer—his Letter XII on the infinite—we find a


brief outline of three types or degrees of infinity, which Spinoza presents as
the embryonic key to reconciling the common problems (paradoxes etc.) in
philosophical and mathematical conceptions of infinity and the absolute.
Spinoza says, “Everyone regards the question of the infinite as most difficult,
if not insoluble, through not making a distinction” between his three-fold
infinite (below) and his polarity of infinity and the imagination, which we
already discussed in the previous section.i * Spinoza goes on:
If these distinctions, I repeat, had been attended to, inquirers would not
have been overwhelmed with such a vast crowd of difficulties. They
would then clearly have understood, what kind of infinite is indivisible
and possesses no parts; and what kind, on the other hand, may be divided
without involving a contradiction in terms. They would further have
understood, what kind, of infinite may, without solecism [[i.e. error]], be
conceived greater than another infinite, and what kind cannot be so
conceived.
Spinoza goes on to elucidate these distinctions in detail, but, through the
visual polarity of infinity and the imagination and the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System already outlined, we will simplify and clarify these
distinctions and make them visible to the imagination and hence far less
abstract. In the process we will significantly expand them into a vision-logic
interface for the infinite and the finite and fill in many details missing from
Spinoza’s sketch.

It is commonly thought that Leibniz’s own nearly identical Triune Infinite,


was developed independently of Spinoza. But in the Courtier and the
Heretic, Mathew Stewart demonstrates that Leibniz sought out, and secretlyii
copied down Spinoza’s famous letter on the infinite [my emphases].
In April 1676, Leibniz’s interest in Spinoza began to take on the character
of an obsession. … he managed to get his hands on a thirteen year old
letter from Spinoza to his friend Lodewijk Meyer concerning the nature of

i
* See, Spinoza, the Infinite, the Indefinite and the Imagination, p264.
ii
likely out of fear of being associated with the “infamous Jew” and his heretical ideas

Page | 272
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

the infinite and other topics. Leibniz copied out the letter—which
extends for half a dozen pages—then added marginal notes of his own as
lengthy as the original text (p187).
According to Samuel Levy (in his Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually
Infinite Division of Matter), 1676 was the year of Leibniz’s Spinoza studies
and the year he solved his problem of the “labyrinth of the continuum” and
the infinitesimal of the calculus by recognizing “infinitely small” points not
as a priori composing the continuum but as a posteriori “termini” abstracted
from the a priori infinite depth of the continuum.i* These points as termini
are what we will come to see as Spinoza’s 2nd order infinities, and it is likely
that Leibniz drew this inspiration from reading Spinoza’s “thirteen year old”
Letter XII on the infinite, where he made this distinction (used throughout
his Ethics, I will argue) its most clear. And recall again that this is what
Deleuze extracts from Leibniz as the idea of the “fold,” converting his
infinitely divided monadology into an infinitely folded and unified one.ii*
Whether Leibniz invented the Triune Infinite independently thirteen
years later or customized and began to use Spinoza’s Triune Infinite as his
own without attribution—given Spinoza’s heretical and dangerous-to-know
status—is still an open question. Regardless, as with the bulk of Leibniz’s
reaction to his own secret Spinozism, there is much novelty and value that
Leibniz brings to the subject.iii
There is no doubt, however, that Leibniz and Spinoza shared the Triune
Infinite regardless of priority. In the transcript to a 1981 audio-taped
discussion, Deleuze states:
And Leibniz, who was himself a very great mathematician, who had
knowledge of the letter to Meyer, declared that he particularly admired
Spinoza for this geometrical example [which we will explore below]
which showed that Spinoza understood things that even his
contemporaries didn’t understand, said Leibniz.iv¥
And Jim Macdonald says in his paper Spinoza and Leibniz: A strong Affinity:
Leibniz liked Spinoza’s characterization of the three infinities, although he
said he was accustomed to call them by different names. Nevertheless, he
saw Spinoza’s division as pretty much the same as his.

i
* We’ll explore this connection further in the section on the calculus (see Reconnecting the Lost
Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and the Calculus, p400).
ii
* See, The Identity vs. the Opposite: Post-Modern Con-fusion and Pre-modern Naiveté, p221.
iii
Indeed, as we will see (see The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite, p407), Spinoza’s Triune
Infinite led Leibniz to his rejection of the idea that the continuum could be made up of mathematical
points, and hence to his (currently neglected) resolution to the problem of the infinitesimal and the
calculus.
iv ¥
Gilles Deleuze: Cours Vincennes - 20/01/1981 :
<http://www.webdeleuze.com/php/texte.php?cle=191&groupe=Spinoza&langue=2 >

Page | 273
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

And Macdonald continues, quoting Leibniz from his notes, and providing us
with a succinct introduction to the Triune Infinite:
‘I usually say that there are three degrees of infinity. The lowest is, for the
sake of an example, like that of the asymptote of a hyperbola; and this I
usually call the mere infinite. It is greater than any assignable, as can also
be said of all the other degrees. The second is that which is greatest in its
own kind, as for example the greatest of all extended things is the whole
of space, the greatest of all successives is eternity. The third degree of
infinity, and this is the highest degree, is everything, and this kind of
infinite is in God, since he is all one; for in him are contained the
requisites for existing of all the others.’i¥
Note that Leibniz says that all of the degrees of infinity share one thing in
common, they are “greater than any assignable.” This basically means that,
in their respective levels and domains, they are unbounded, as we have
established for the esoteric and nondual understanding of infinity, as the
quantitative aspect of the absolute scope. It is also worth noting that
Leibniz’s own language of “the greatest” seems to imply an actual magnitude
and thus a boundary, the greatest one, as opposed to the boundless. This is,
however, merely a consequence of rendering the infinite in relative terms
such as magnitude.
Leibniz categorized his degrees of infinity from lowest to highest, from
the first to the third degrees, respectively. In light of the embryogenesis of
the concept, however, we will work in the inverse direction, starting with
Infinite Unity as the first order and working into the lower orders in terms of
differentiation into larger numbers and working down into the relative view
of the absolute, from the ONE of Infinite Unity to the ALL of absolute
multiplicity and into the ONE-one of the uni-axis and its finite unity and
implicit, intrinsic singularity.

The 1st order Infinite is “The Absolute,” the ALL is ONE, the “Boundless ALL,”
our absolute scope, Emptiness and Infinite Unity which is not ‘one.’ Spinoza
describes it in his Letter XII as, “…that which must be infinite from its very
nature, or in virtue of its definition.” And Leibniz says, “…the highest degree,
is everything, and this kind of infinite is in God, since he is all one; for in him
are contained the requisites for existing of all the others.” This is the
ineffable absolute; enfolding and unfolding all other possible infinities,
polarities and forms of difference. This is also the “axis of Tao” denoted and
operationalized herein by the second order immanent/transcendent omni-
axis.


Leibniz; Notes; qtd in Macdonald

Page | 274
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Alexander R. Pruss in his paper Can Two Equal Infinity? The Attributes of
God in Spinoza, calls this 1st order Infinite the “Absolute Infinity.” He says,
echoing our principle of Infinite Unity,i “Something infinite in this sense
cannot be broken down into parts.” For the absolute scope to be broken
down into parts or divided, would first require a relation between divisor
and dividend, and barring that, it would require a division of infinite depth.
This “kind of infinite is indivisible,” as Spinoza mentioned, but it is indivisible
precisely because it is infinitely deep or infinitely divided, as Leibniz would
emphasize. The Absolute Infinite is the “infinite division equals
indivisibility” of the fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism. The
Infinite, being Absolute, cannot, by definition, possess internal relations. The
instant such relations exist, we are again at the relative scope.ii
And echoing Spinoza, Pruss continues, “This kind of infinity is only
conceived by the intellect, not the imagination.” The imagination is always
exhausted in a finite amount of time and therefore can only ever reach a
limited, indefinite depth of extension (transitive), division (immanence) or
time.

The Aspect Infinite is the second order infinity and it derives its infinite
nature directly from the first as unfolding aspects, perspectives, infinite
modes of being or mental abstractions from it. The Aspect Infinite mediates
as a cultivated third or a triune-interface between the first and last orders of
infinity, just as Spinoza’s attributes mediate the expression between
Substance and its modes,iii* just as Leibniz’s “pre-established harmony”
mediates between God and the subjective and objective monadsiv and just as
our relative-view ALL mediates between the ONE and the one.v See The
Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attributes and Modifications
(p288), below.

i
“Infinite Unity, or its unbounded aspects of infinity, when operated upon, always returns infinity.”
ii
But again, it is important to note that the absolute and relative scopes are not locations, or scales
of interaction in a relation of reduction, one to the other. They are, rather, the basic conceptual
contexts from which the mind attempts to make sense of the world and itself. Indeed, the absolute
scope only comes into the conceptual field of view when the relative scope attempts to relativize
itself in order to find its context in its identical-opposite. And thus the bounded relative scope must
find its basis and meaning in the boundless absolute scope and the concept comes full-circle to
grasp its genesis in the pre-conceptual, and the finite in the infinite. See “Vertical” Polarity: The
Polarity of Polarity, p175.
iii
* See The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attributes and Modifications, p285.
iv
God and monad together form the “supreme Gonad,” but that is beyond the credulity of this book.
v
And we can also see parallels here between the mediation of Jesus between the ONE God and the
one-many of humanity.

Page | 275
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Leibniz says in his notes, “The second is that which is greatest in its own
kind, as for example the greatest of all extended things is the whole of space,
the greatest of all successives is eternity.” These are the spatial and
temporal (extension and duration) aspects of The Infinite, respectively.
Spinoza distinguishes this type of infinity as, “that which has no limits, not in
virtue of its essence, but in virtue of its cause...” All abstracted aspects or
properties of The Infinite are in this sense also boundless because they apply
to, or are abstracted from, the Absolute Infinite. So each aspect of The
Infinite is infinite or boundless in extent and ultimate amount, not due to its
own “essence”—which is an Empty, finite and relative category or
abstraction—but because each draws its indwelling cause, or is abstracted
from, the Infinite, ineffable source, or true univocal and nondual essence of
the absolute. This very common type of infinity will be broken into sub-
levels for further clarification.
Perhaps because of the effectiveness of mathematical examples for this
type of infinity, Pruss calls it the “Mathematical Infinity.” However, this term
leaves out the whole class of aspects of The Infinite outside the realm of
mathematics. Furthermore it would seem to exclude the mathematical
aspects of the third order of infinity (introduced in a few pages below), and
this flies in the face of Spinoza’s own “geometrical example” of the third
order, as we will see.i Given this, we will loosely side with Cantor and choose
not to categorize the 2nd order as the Mathematical, but as the Aspect
Infinite.

Recall our Cycle of Unity (p257) with the immanent-transcendent omni-axis


beginning as the first pre-mathematical aspect abstracted from Infinite Unity
in the ONE, through the ALL of infinite multiplicity and its ONE-one relative
uni-axis represented by the VLE / , whose solidus/vinculum is the
boundary of the finite unity and primitive unit-number ‘one’ and whose pre-
differentiated, pre-mathematical, vision-logic level ratio-equality brings us
back to the ALL as ONE. See the figures repeated below.

i
This is likely due to the transcendent-bias in only recognizing transcendent forms of infinity in
modern mathematics, and seeing the immanent infinite as merely the undefined or the indefinite.

Page | 276
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Figure 15 and Figure 16 repeated from The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p257

In The Cycle of Unity, recall, we move from the outer-reaches of the orbit, the
apoapsisi of the pre-quantitative Infinite Unity of the ONE, through the
“quantitative aspect” in the infinite multiplicity of the ALL, to the recognition
of “immanence in transcendence”ii* in the pre-mathematical division or
interface of the immanent-transcendent uni-axis and its implicit singularity
into the first boundary and primitive number needed for mathematical
operations.
The second degree of infinity, the Aspect Infinite, arises with the first
(EOTC), pre-quantitative “multiplication through division” of The Infinite
ALL-is-ONE into the first polarity of the immanent and transcendent aspects
in the omni-axis. In this process we move from the sub-representational and
ineffable ONE to the quantitative, yet pre-mathematical aspect of multiplicity
and its inherent omni-non-directional, omni-non-local relativity in the ALL.
From there we move to the omni-directional/locational aspects of the ONE-
one uni-axis and then to the selection/derivation of our unit-scale interface
and finite unity for the beginning of primitive mathematical operations—
namely counting to create the first agglomerative and transitive “natural”

i
“(astronomy) The point in an orbit farthest from the center of attraction.” Answers.com
ii
* See Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of Immanence in Transcendence, p95.

Page | 277
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

numbers, each one of which is an enfolded infinity—a primitive infinite


number—given that each is composed of finite unity which enfolds infinity
within itself. It is this implicit infinity which is broken open with the
Rational numbers and fully with the “irrational” or transrational numbers.i*
In this way, as we will see more clearly in The Holarchical Unfolding of
Number and Operation (p309), the immanent-transcendent omni-axis can be
considered a first phase in the embryogenesis of the concept within the 2nd
order infinity of the Aspect Infinite, since, unlike other aspect infinities, it
maps directly to the first polarity of the ONE-ALL and it is the first aspect
abstracted from The Infinite in The Cycle of Unity and the holarchical
embryogenesis of number and operation. The pre-differentiated I/T omni-
axis, recall, is both omni-directional and omni-local, thus possibly
representationally enfolding and unfolding, and providing a space, for all
other directional and positional aspects of The Infinite in Interface
Mathematics.
In this embryogenesis, the omni-axis is thus prior to the operations and
quantitative functions (including number itself) of mathematics. It is not
derived a posteriori from any function of number, such as the set-generators
which unfold the higher functions/relations of number and its transfinite
orders of infinite sets, but is prior to, and, in this sense, independent of
number. In this way, as representing both The Infinite and Cantor’s
Absolute Infinite (1st order) it is also prior to, and independent of, all of
Cantor’s transfinite orders which, as we will see, work their way up into
function in the holarchical unfolding of mathematics itself.
Note that the omni-non-dimensional I/T omni-axis is also prior to any
concept of dimensionality whatsoever, such as the transitive notions of “flat”
or “curved” Cartesian/Euclidean or non-Euclidean space. It is only
represented visually in terms of straight lines for the sake of simplicity. Note
as well that the concept of curved-space has no meaning without the
identical opposite notion of flat space as a context (nor vice versa,
straightness without curvature). In this nondual sense, one cannot be prior
to the other, and hence the immanent-transcendent omni-axis is neither/and
(non-omni) flat or curved. See Boundary and Dimension (p298) for more
information.
All representations of The Infinite are necessarily aspect infinities—even
the first-phase aspect infinity, the I/T omni-axis—as they draw their infinite
nature as representational aspects from The Infinite. Other aspects include
what we could call the second-phase aspects, e.g. the transitive number-line
when counting by ones, twos, fours, eights, or recursively self-multiplying
into perfect-squares, dividing into the immanent continuity of the rationals,
etc. The abstracted aspects of The Infinite, in these cases would be “square-

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.

Page | 278
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

ness,” “even-ness,” “point-ness,” “line-ness,” “plane-ness,” or “volume-ness”


(extension), etc.
Imagine instead of drawing an infinite line (a clear impossibility) that the
infinite line is simply abstracted into representational reality, bit by bit, from
The Infinite, omni-dimensional continuity which initially contains the
possibility of all lines. The linear aspect of The Infinite appears from the
continuity because we put emphasis on it, and it disappears when we let it
go. Once manifest, we can then assign to its intrinsic nondual or trans-
rational continuity an arbitrary set of numbers based on whatever set-
generating algorithm and relative to whatever transitive scale we choose
(e.g. the mathematical ratio generating the set of the Rationals with their
Dedekind cuts and intrinsic limits).
Other examples of second-phase aspect infinities include the transitive
(directional) axes which unfold, and are enfolded within, the immanent-
transcendent omni- and uni-axes. This would include all mathematical
infinities, such as an infinite line, or Cartesian axes coupled into planes or
grouped into volumes or “higher dimensional” and non-Euclidean multi- or
agglomerative-dimensional representations. The second-phase category
would also tentatively include every one of Cantor’s infinite degrees of the
“transfinite,” as we will see.i*
The sense here is that these mental forms of set-generators, omni-/uni-
directionality, “linearity,” “planarity” and n-dimensionality are abstracted as
singular or grouped directional/positional (relational) aspects from the
concept or reality of the Absolute Infinite, but furthermore, the omni-axis
enfolds and unfolds the uni- and directional- axes, and hence is a more
primitive order in the embryogenesis of the concept of mathematical,
ontological and epistemological infinity.

In this way, as Spinoza notes, we can already see “what kind, of infinite may
… be conceived greater than another infinite, and what kind cannot be so
conceived.” The Absolute Infinite is inquantate,ii or “not one,” as the non-
dualists may put it, and thus (in accord with our Quantitative Principle of
Infinite Unity (p248)) it can’t be quantitatively operated upon to conceive of
any greater infinity. The aspects of infinity, however, spring from, and as,
the interface between The Infinite and the relative realm of representation
and its finite forms and frames of reference, as abstracted aspects of
“contingent” reality, as Cantor put it. Aspect infinities are thus “quantate”
and comparable insofar as their representational aspects and frames of
reference are concerned.

i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
ii
Or non-quantitative…

Page | 279
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This is the key to reconciling (transcending-and-including,


differentiating-and-integrating) the Galilean paradox as well as the
Cantorian fix designed to neutralize it by the Pearl Principle of axiomatic
encapsulation.i* In this sense, the infinity of the Galilean perfect-squares is
derived as the aspect of squaring the wholes whose primitive infinity is
derived from The Infinite as the unbounded or indefinite aspect of counting
finite unities. In a similar way, the higher Cantorian orders of the transfinite
are derived in “higher power,” higher-level set-generating operations, or set-
aspects. These emerge at higher levels in the holarchical embryogenesis of
operation and number, such as at the level of powering and rooting with
Dedekind’s irrational “cuts” into the rational continuum, itself derived by the
lower-level, or more primitive set-generating function of the mathematical
ratio.ii*
Note that the sets and subsets of the number-line appear to the
imagination as different orders of magnitude (‘cardinalities’ or the number
of elements in a set), but the imagination itself is a relative and finite or
indefinite process, as already discussed above,iii* and as emphasized in
Spinoza’s Letter XII. For instance, recall Galileo’s use of the imagination in
showing the apparent difference in magnitude between the wholes and
perfect-squares as visualized for any finite line segment. This idea of
different magnitudes of infinities violates the simple (recall the paradox of
Hilbert’s Hotel), undifferentiated or “naive” concept of infinity as that which
is boundless and unsurpassable.
The resolution to this paradox is to realize that none of these infinite
number sets can have an ultimate number of items (a ‘cardinality,’ in the
familiar, imaginable sense of a finite set) because with every value there are
always larger and larger values attainable and thus all these sets are
fundamentally boundless and infinite. Each infinite-set draws its
boundlessness from The Infinite itself and always in reference to a transitive
scale—e.g. at the “aleph-null” level, that of “countability” or the “one-to-one”
relationship to the numberline.
In an infinite set, cardinality has a critically different meaning than in a
finite set. It does not denote the number of elements, because an infinite set
has no definite, final or actual numberiv of elements. It denotes, rather, a
relation between generative “powers” of set-generation algorithms, as
comparable through the one-to-one correspondence seen with the Galilean

i
* See The Pearl Principle, p235
ii
* We’ll explore this in much greater depth in, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation,
p306.
iii
* See, Spinoza, the Infinite, the Indefinite and the Imagination, p264.
iv
According to the definition of number as boundary, at least.

Page | 280
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

paradox and vindicated through (the controversial) Hume’s Principle.i In


this simple way we can compare the degrees to which these set-aspects
abstract similar or different “powers” of infinity (our quantitative aspect of
the absolute scope) from The Infinite, unbounded Emptiness, Cantor’s
Absolute Infinite or Spinoza’s God/Substance with infinite attributes.

The Bounded Infinite is the third and lowest order of infinity as it deals with
the unbounded within the bounded. Leibniz says in his notes, “The lowest is,
for the sake of an example, like that of the asymptote of a hyperbola; and this
I usually call the mere infinite.” Spinoza describes it as, “…that, of which the
parts cannot be equaled or expressed by any number, though the greatest
and least magnitude of the whole may be known...” Spinoza provides for this
degree of the infinite, his famous geometrical example. Spinoza says [my
emphases]:
As, for instance, in the case of two circles, non-concentric, whereof one
encloses the other, no number can express the inequalities of distance
which exist between the two circles... This conclusion is not based on the
excessive size of the intervening space. However small a portion of it we
take, the inequalities of this small portion will surpass all numerical
expression. Nor, again, is the conclusion based on the fact, as in other
cases, that we do not know the maximum and the minimum of the said
space. It springs simply from the fact, that the nature of the space
between two non-concentric circles cannot be expressed in number.
Therefore, he who would assign a numerical equivalent for the
inequalities in question, would be bound, at the same time, to bring about
that a circle should not be a circle.
The modal infinity is a 2nd order derivative from the Absolute Infinite, and it
unfolds from the confluence of the two main aspect infinities: the I/T
(omnidirectional) and the transitive (uni-directional) derived from our finite
unity as a frame of reference. The modal infinity is the interface between the
immanent and transitive aspects or directionalities, and can thus be seen as
a subset of the 2nd order—as it reaches from the apoapsis of the ALL-ONE
and onto the ONE-one of the I/T uni-axis, passing the periapsis of the finite
unity, to the implicit singularity at its core. On the transitive axis which sees
a line segment or circle as explicitly bounded there is indeed a discernable
outside limit but this limit is not contained within the specified system of
immanent division, which has no conceivable end in sight, so no conceivable
ultimate number can be found for the inner limit. The limits themselves,
being “infinitely precise, are infinitely indefinable. This echoes our Principle

i
Wikipedia: Hume’s Principle: “…the number of Fs is equal to the number of Gs if there is a one-to-
one correspondence (a bijection) between the Fs and the Gs.”

Page | 281
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

of Infinite Determinism, recall, where infinite determinism equals


fundamental (unbounded) indeterminism and the inability to ever
encapsulate the immanent causation into a finite and absolute explanation
or prediction.

As Bucky Fuller says in his Synergetics:


The only infinity humanity has discovered experimentally is that of the
whole-fraction subdivisibility of wholes into parts, as for instance by the
progressive halvings that divide the finitely closed circle into ever
smaller, central-angle-expressed, arc increments (1001.15).
This is the bounded infinite, but these processes themselves are not infinite.
They are indefinite. And the same indefinite—as the interface between the
finite and The Infinite—has been discovered in our operations on the aspect
infinities of the number-line or of unbounded space. We have found only
unbounded dimensions, because beyond every boundary we have always
found more dimension, where we are capable of finding anything at all.
Indeed, a boundary cannot even be found until it is surpassed, exposing the
fundamental polarity of the infinite and finite.
The modal infinite is the order of the fractal, complexity theory and
nonlinear and/or recursive functions, and it is also the home of our familiar
oxymoron, “finite but unbounded,” and our primitive (finite) number as an
enfolded or encapsulated infinite number, in an identity of opposites. Due to
the symmetrical circularity (inverse tautology) of the phrase “finite but
unbounded” it easily could be stated in the reverse, “infinite but bounded”
because what it really means (given our necessary remapping of finite and
infinite to bounded and boundless respectively) is “infinite yet finite” or
“bounded yet unbounded.” The problem here is that the scientists are not
aware of the two aspects of directionality pre-fused and conflated (con-
fused) in the one Infinity. They thus quite easily and unknowingly mix them
together.
The modal infinity, as the interface between the immanent and transitive
directionalities, starts from the transitive and divides inwardly along the
immanent axis. Every successive division is a transitive measure (distance)
toward a deceptively simple “Euclidean point” and implicit singularity of an
immanent/transcendent uni-axis. The modal infinite involves procedures,
such as those of the hyperbola and the infinite continuity in the definition of
the circle or even the line, whereby an explicit number cannot be given for a
quantity, but it is not excluded that a lower and upper transitive bound can
be given. This is because on the transitive axis there is indeed a discernable
outside limit but this limit is not contained within the specified operations of
immanent division and its access to the aspect of infinite continuity in The
Infinite. The ideal mathematical procedure divides the distance between the
inner and outer limits indefinitely with no conceivable end in sight, so no
conceivable ultimate number can be found for the inner limit. It fails to see
Page | 282
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

that the “infinite smallness,” (immanent zero, or the “ideal-point”) which


must characterize this distance is not a distance at all. Distance cannot be
cut finally into non-distance. The limit of the immanent axis cannot be
reached because it is the infinite and unlimited itself.
This example, however, is a mathematically ideal, virtual and indefinite
process—the process of quantifying the continuum. The continuum does not
intrinsically have an infinite number of parts; it has no parts. It is a pre-
differentiated abstraction. As a pattern or modification it can be divided (or
folded, as Deleuze might say, channeling Leibniz) symbolically in the mind or
physically and mechanically an indefinite number of times. This is why
Pruss calls this infinity “Indefiniteness” because it stems from a process in
space and time which can have no final ideal end. Leibniz calls this kind of
infinity the “mere infinite” as a main feature of his “labyrinth of the
continuum.”
Given that human beings are themselves finite unities, it is the modal
infinite with which he has the most contact. Everywhere man looks he finds
the boundlessness of the indefinite, the interface between The Infinite (both
within and without him) and the finite.

It is certainly no coincidence that Spinoza used the example of the circle, the
cross-section of the sphere, in his explanation of the modal infinite. The
sphere itself is the simplest and root-level bounded infinite and infinite
number as the interface of the ONE-one uni-axis and the abstracted aspect of
infinite omni-symmetrical boundedness itself, from the boundlessness
within itself.
Fuller says in his Synergetics, “The Greeks defined the sphere as a surface
outwardly equidistant in all directions from a point. As defined, the Greek
sphere’s surface was an absolute continuum, subdividing all the Universe
outside it from all the Universe inside it; wherefore, the Universe outside
could be dispensed with and the interior eternally conserved” (224.07).
This is why he called the mathematical sphere a perpetual motion machine.
Energy can’t get out or in through an infinitely continuous boundary. And
this is of course exactly the boundary cannot exist, in the sense that stasis
cannot exist and persist without continual flux.
The sphere—in this absolute sense of bounded continuity—is the closest
possible EOTC representation of the omni-non-symmetry of the ONE, in the
omni-symmetry of the one. This is why the ancients intuitively held such a
vaunted place for the sphere, and rightly so. It is the interface of the ONE

Page | 283
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

and the one,i the abstracted essence of man himself in his relation to the
immanence and transcendence of God.

A subset of the Modal Infinite which deserves explicit exploration—vividly


fleshing out the percepts behind this concept—is the ubiquitous fractal. The
fractal is known for its infinite depth of immanent detail. Its “quasi-
continuity” of form in the face of the Emptiness of its infinite depth. At the
heart of the fractal, among many other areas of mathematics, is recursion or
iteration. A fractal equation is deceptively simple. The root equation for
both the Mandelbrot and the Julia sets, for example is: Z = Z2 + C. Iterating
the equation indefinitely for every constant C and feeding that result back
into Z, the results are plotted on the “complex plane” and manifest as an
infinitely complex surface such as the following type of unearthly beauty,
now so familiar to mathematicians, artists, scientists and laymen alike:

i
See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.

Page | 284
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Figure 19: Mandelbrot Fractals:


Top: The whole bounded Mandelbrot set. Bottom: A zoomed -in section (the
boundaries of which are too small to see) of the Mandelbrot set, showing a deep
section of the infinite detail of the “surface.” (source: Wikipedia commons)

Page | 285
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Another illustrative aspect of fractal mathematics is the famous paradox of


the “infinite coastline.” Like the Mandelbrot set, the infinite coastline has
infinite detail in its bounded “surface” structure. We can arbitrarily choose
to measure this coastline, and its infinite depth, by any scale we decree. This
is our familiar implicit selection of a finite unity or interface on the ONE-one
singularity of any immanent-transcendent uni-axis. It is the intersection of
the immanent and transitive aspects of The Infinite. The smaller and smaller
the scale (transitive finite unit or unity) we choose to measure with, the
more and more detail and distance is exposed to our measurement. And so
every time we measure it at a smaller scale, our coastline gets larger and
larger. Given that our axis of scale (the immanent-transcendent axis) is
unlimited, so also is the actual length of our coastline. See Figure 20, below.

Figure 20: The Infinite Coastline:


Copied from Fractals and Education: Helping Liberal Arts Students to See Science by
Michael Frame, in Fractal Horizons by Clifford A. Pickover

Page | 286
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Recall Spinoza’s definition of the finite; “A thing is called finite after its kind,
when it can be limited by another thing of the same nature; for instance, a
body is called finite because we always conceive another greater body.” As
should be clear, we can also take Spinoza’s definition of The Infinite and
finite generally in terms of the polarity of Substance and its Modifications,
respectively, and its Cycle of Unityi*, within which Substance turns around
its modes and vice versa. That which is modified is, in some sense,
necessarily bounded and has magnitude (e.g. size, length width, duration)
relative to other modifications; modification is necessarily in the relative
realm of form in identical opposition to the absolute realm of Emptiness.
Spinoza also had infinite modes in his system, however, to which our
aspect infinities correspond, as aspects at the interface of the finite and The
Infinite. For example, the set of perfect-squares can be conceived as an
infinite or unbounded modification of the mathematical continuum, yet
Cantor discovered that this infinite has the exact same quantitative power
(aleph null) as that of the wholes and the rationals, and is first surpassed
only by the infinity of the irrationals. Thus the infinite modification is, in this
sense of the aspect of power, finite and bounded, and this is precisely due to
its being a modification, or participating in the world of form, identically-
opposed to the world of Emptiness or The Infinite, from which it draws its
boundless aspect in its power of set-generation.
Similarly, when we divide an infinite set or number-line into two parts,
both could still be infinite without paradox, as codified in our quantitative
principle of Infinite Unity.ii* The Aspect Infinite renders the paradox illusory
in the sense that taking directions at the line of division is to take a sub-
aspect of the infinite line. It is to take a sub-aspect of the polarity of the
aspect of linearity, abstracted from The Infinite. Neither of the sections on
either side of the division would be finite in their direction or “kind.”
Therefore, this division of the infinite does not produce limits in their own
kind but draws out polarities and aspects, all of which share in the
boundlessness of The Infinite from which they are abstracted.

i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity.
ii
* See, Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, p245.

Page | 287
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 21: The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attribute and Mode :
In this diagram we can see the structural similarity between the mathematical
ontological and triads in Spinoza: the Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance,
Attribute and Mode.

This relation is key to the structure of Spinoza’s Ethics (See Figure 21,
above). This polar identity of opposites of the finite and infinite is helpful in
reconciling the relation between the mode and its infinite immanence
derived as the finite unity from the ONE-one uni-axis and its implicit
singularity. Take the following quote from Alain Badiou’s Spinoza’s Closed
Ontologyi¥ [[my comments emphases]]:
In the letter of March 1663 to Simon de Vries, Spinoza takes pains to
declare that the word ‘attribute’ does not by itself constitute a naming of
the ‘there is’ [[finite unity]] in any way essentially distinct from the
naming of the latter by substance. Having reiterated the definition of
substance he adds: ‘I understand the same by attribute, except that it is
called attribute in relation to (*respectu*) the intellect, which
attributes such and such a definite nature to substance. [[The attribute is
only finite in the sense that it is in respect to the intellect. It is abstracted
as a special kind of aspect of The Infinite.]] Thus the attribute, as well as
the multiplicity of attributes through which divine infinity is identified, is
a function of the intellect. In the general arrangement of the ‘there is’,
there exists—under the name ‘God’—a singular localization [[implicit
singularity, or aspect of locality, the ‘one’ of the ONE-one uni-axis]], that of
the intellect, upon whose point of view or operations depends thought’s
capacity for rational access to divine infinity, and hence to the ‘there is’ as
such.
It is thus necessary to recognize that the intellect occupies the
position of a fold—to take up the central concept in Deleuze’s philosophy.
Or, using my own terminology, that the intellect is an operation of torsion.
It is localizable of an immanent production of God, but is also required to
uphold the naming of the ‘there is’ as God [[abstracting the identifiable


(Donovan)

Page | 288
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

aspects of/from The Infinite]]. For only the singular operations of the
intellect give meaning to God’s existential singularization [[ALL-ONE]] as
infinite substance.
This infinite immanence and implicit singularity new to the rational—
explored deeply by Leibniz as well, in both metaphysical and mathematical
form (e.g. monads, the calculus and the labyrinth of the continuum)—is the
positive infinity which Deleuze called the secret of the rational. In univocity,
a mode unfolds from infinity, as infinity participates in its own bounded
aspects in the infinite depth of its interfaces (recall the infinite coastline,
above), and Substance turns around its modes, and its modes around
Substance, as Emptiness is Form and Form Emptiness.
It would indeed be a fruitful exercise to undertake an analysis of
Spinoza’s Ethics from this “organizing principle” of the Infinite as the triune-
interface of the “polarity of polarity” in the Univocity Framework.i* In this
sense one could continue to tease out many of the problems of traditional
Spinozist hermeneutics, such as the relation of modes to Substance, and both
to the varied forms of infinity, and The Infinite absolute. One could see that
indeed modes are not other than an interface of infinity, and so on. Some of
this will unfold herein, but much of it will remain beyond the scope of this
work.

i
* See, Polarity and Univocity, p174.

Page | 289
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

As we have seen, the scope parameter is a linguistic device (similar to the


use of scope in computer programming languages) for delineating and
rendering explicit the otherwise implicit absolute and relative scopes. In the
Vision-Logic Coordinate System, we can make the aspect of scope explicit for
delineating the perspectival inhabitation (or absolutization) of the various
axes, levels, positions and poles within the system, making inescapable the
acknowledgement of each of their unique properties and limitations.
The scope parameter has two main divisions: the absolute (ab) and the
relative (rel). From the vision-logic level, each of the triune levels of
infinityi* can be descended into, or “inhabited,” as different levels, or
abstracted aspects of an absolute scope; delineated as ab1, ab2, and ab3, for
the 1st through 3rd degrees of infinity, respectively. The scope for ab1,
however—due to its inclusive identity of opposites in the fundamental
polarity represented by the ONE-ALL and its immanent-transcendent omni-
axis—generates a binary subset of scope parameters; the “charged”
(unbalanced) scopes of the I and the T (the immanent and transcendent)
taken independently and denoted with a + or – sign as a suffix. For example
would denote the immanent pole, or aspect, and the transcendent.
This use of charge in the suffixes above is opposed to the use of prefixes
in the transitive polarity, denoting negative and positive transitive infinities
( and ), such as the positive vs. the negative integers. The suffixes
used in the I/T scope parameters denote the a priori neutrality or (intensive,
rather than oppositional forces) of the positive infinity of the immanent-
transcendent axis. Furthermore, they encode the transcendent-bias a
posteriori, as transcended-and-included transitive suffixes, from which the a
priori I/T polarity is viewed. Again, this is because, as we will see, in the
holarchical unfolding of the operations of mathematics, (called the Onion of
Operations, herein) the positivity and negativity of the transitive axis is
transcended-and-included into the immanent-transcendent axis via the
functions of the mathematical ratio and the rational numbers, which have no
intrinsic positivity and negativity of their own. Taking the immanent as
essentially the “negative view” of the I/T axis, with its negative a posteriori
suffix charge, is an acknowledgement of the necessity of the transcendent-

i
* See Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270, above.

Page | 290
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

bias, as it is encoded also, only this time consciously, into the very structure
of the VCS meta-tags.
Since the scope for the uncountable I/T axis itself, the ab1 scope, includes
both poles, it will be considered “neutral” (intensive) and each of the two
poles taken separately will be considered “charged.” However, since this
isolation of one pole of the axis at the expense of the other can only occur
through an interface—i.e. the interaction between the ONE-one of the I/T
uni-axis, its implicit singularity and the finite unity of the transitive axes—
(as the discussion on the Bounded Infinitei* and The Cycle of Unityii*
suggests) this “charging” or “unbalancing” of the 1st level brings us down to
the 3rd level of the modal infinite and the finite unity, in a full-circle, linking
the top with the bottom through the interacting core aspects (see The Cycle
of the Infinite (p296) below and The Cycle of Unity (p257), above).
The scope of the isolated or emphasized immanent pole will therefore be
given the negativeiii suffix and the scope for the transcendent pole, the
positive. So we now have the ab3+ and ab3- scopes for the transcendent and
immanent scopes respectively, and we can introduce this “charge” into the
VLEs themselves to denote the imbalance between the immanent(-) and
transcendent(+) aspects of the Infinite.
Furthermore, each of the infinities and scopes also has an accompanying
vision-logic equation (VLE), which is a logical, or relational equation for
dealing with the quantitative aspects of the absolute/relative polarity (the
polarity of polarity)iv* from a vision-logic level in the meta-mathematical
framework. Since we are dealing with the absolute scope, and therefore
necessarily with the philosophical and pre-mathematical, rather than the
mathematical notions of infinity, and given that infinity in either case is not a
number, these VLEs are not rigorously mathematical, but rather meta-
mathematical, logical or relational, with their own peculiar logic.v They use
the relational operators of mathematics to quickly and intuitively invoke the
simple conceptual and logical relations between the levels and the VL-axes
of the VCS. They are used more as metaphors, or maps, than quantitative
derivations. This is largely because of their extensive use of infinity, and its
inability to really partake in quantitative operationsvi*—operating as the
VLE often do between the relative and absolute scopes.

i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270, above.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
iii
…due to the transcendent bias statistically emergent and empirically demonstrated in human
thought.
iv
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
v
The subject of operations on the infinite is already controversial for precisely this reason; Infinity is
not a number.
vi
* See, Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, p245.

Page | 291
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The root-level VLE, and the VLE upon which the others are based, is the
equation for the immanent/transcendent omni-axis, and thus for the
Absolute Infinite (ab1) to which it maps.i It is as follows:

ONE

ii
Equation 1: VLE: ab1 — The Infinite: The Root VLE

and expanding this equation we have…

transcendent
ALL ONE
immanent

Equation 2: VLE: ab1 — Expanded Root Equation and VLE: Cycle of Unity

The transitive (uni-directional) axis is implicit (enfolded) in the concept of


the omnidirectional I/T axis and is naturally represented in the root VLE by
the solidus or vinculum,iii exfoliating from and separating the transcendent
from the immanent omnidirectional aspects of the equation in the transitive
plane of the solidus-interface of the omni-axis.iv*

i
As would be expected; The lower levels of the infinite exfoliate from the first and this is echoed in
the relations among the VLEs.
ii
With the transcendent/transitive bias in modern thought this collapses to oo/0 where division by
zero is correctly recognized as undefined, but the denominator is incorrectly recognized as 0 as
opposed to the immanent pole of deep infinity (I/T) denoted as oo-.
iii
Note that division/multiplication is always the operator in these equations. This is because the
ratio is the core of Rationalism and multiplication and division are the two poles of the mediating
operator (cultivated third) between the I/T (powering/rooting) and transitive (arithmetical) axes in
the “Onion of Operations” in, Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.
iv
* See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.

Page | 292
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

The 2nd order mathematical equations are many and varied, such as the “set-
aspects” or set generators of infinite sets and any other equation that
projects, or abstracts finite patterns or aspects from or onto The Absolute
Infinite. Aspect-level VLEs, however, are any VLE that involves the infinite
term with a finite operator. We’ll use as the universal operator to denote
any possible mathematical operation. The defining ab2: VLE is:

(n )=∞

Equation 3: VLE: ab2 — The Aspect Infinite

Recall that prior to this point we were calling the root VLE the equation of
Infinite Unity,i* and that it denoted both the I/T omni- and uni- axes. Now
that we have delineated the a posteriori charge of the immanent and
transcendent operations as they transcend-and-include the transitive,ii we
can also differentiate the uni- from the omni-axis in terms of the VLE, placing
the uni-axis in the aspect level as touching the relative scope in its finite and
singular aspect of position or locality in its implicit singularity. The VLE for
the I/T uni-axis is as follows:

iii
Equation 4: VLE: ab2.1 — The Uni-Axis with Interface at Finite (Bounded) Unity

Due to the complexity of the interactions between the immanent and


transitive axes, and the fact that the Bounded infinite brings the absolute
down fully to the relative level where mathematics (the art and science of
pure relation) thrives, mathematical equations for the Bounded Infinite

i
* See, Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
ii
We’ll explore this in much greater depth in, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation,
p306, but very simply, the first numbers are the wholes and they form the first transitive
numberline. From there we move to the positive and negative transitive charge of the integers and
it is not till the Rationals that we break again into the intensive forces of immanence and
transcendence, transcending-and-including the transitive oppositional charge of the integers.
iii
The ONE-one of the uni-axis, recall, is the transition between the absolute scope of omni-non
locality and the one locality of its implicit singularity, or immanent position aspect. Therefore, we
place this VLE exactly half-way between the

Page | 293
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

come in multifarious well-known forms. These include the asymptote of a


hyperbola, as Leibniz noted, as well as many fractals. The VLE we will use
herein, however, is also found in Deleuze’s The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque.
In our terms, it represents the bounded infinite with an “external limit,” at
(finite) unity or one (we will see why this is important a bit later in the
section on Spinoza and Leibniz as an identity of opposites). Since the triune
infinity is a nested hierarchy, and the Bounded Infinite is a subset of the
aspect infinite, the 3rd order equation is merely a special-case, or recursive,
2nd order equation because it “involves the infinite term with a finite
modifier” and specifically it involves the interface between the two main
aspect infinities of the I/T and the transitive; In this case the VLE represents
the isolated immanent pole of the I/T axis due to this recursive interface.
The VLE for the Bounded Infinite with an external limit at unity (the unlimit
is in the immanent direction) is identical to the VLE for the charged -ab3
scope, the isolated immanent pole of the I/T axis, and it can be written as:

Equation 5: VLE: ab3- — The Bounded-Immanent Infinite

And for balance, we’ll give the reciprocal VLE for the transcendent pole, the
Bounded Infinite with an internal limit at unity, the VLE for the charged ab3+
scope. Note that what is traditionally conceived as the unbounded is actually
bounded in the immanent direction. Thus the transcendent infinite, like the
immanent infinite is bounded and unbalanced, or charged, with a positive or
negative sign in the posterior position, denoting charge as intensity rather
than as transitive opposition.

1
Equation 6: VLE: ab3+ — Transcendent Infinite

For reference and summary, here is the list of the VLEs at their respective
levels of the Triune Infinite:

Page | 294
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

1: ONE
2: (n Ω ∞) = ∞
1
3: and
1

As the levels move down the triune hierarchy, from the absolute through the
relative scope aspects, they get progressively more and more relative (as
aspects) and finite (bounded), since this triunity represents the cultivated
third, or the interface, between the infinite and the finite. This also
corresponds to the move from the trans-trans-bias in the unrecognition of
the rational zero (undefined zero in the denominator) to the recognition, in
the 17th century rationalists, of immanence in the bounded infinite.
The I/T omni-axis is only relative in that, as a vision-logic interface, it
relates to, abstracts, and represents (or points outside itself to), the deeper
quantitative, or “pure-relational” aspect of the ineffable Infinite, with its
fundamental polarity in the ALL-ONE. The Aspect level, on the other hand, is
injected with a finite (relative) operator n (denoting a finite frame of
reference). As we have seen in the Cycle of Unity, however, the bounded
infinity is the interface between the transitive (relative) uni-directional axes
and the Immanent/Transcendent axis. The transcendent—ONE—of the final
bounded infinite then merges through the Cycle of Unity back into the ALL,
completing the Cycle of Infinity.
Though it contains an infinity within itself (and without itself), this
bounded infinite with its implicit singularity can act (and must act) as a
finite transitive root-unit and interact relative to other units. This nucleation
is indeed how the transitive axes exfoliate (emerge) from the immanence
and transcendence of the absolute, though we can clearly see here the
necessary cyclical nature of this non-dual and non-foundational framework
rooted in the rootlessness and implicit singularity represented by the
uncountable I/T axis.i* The Cycle of the Infinite is the move from a priori
I/T omni-non-local/-directional boundlessness, to the uni-axis, its implicit
singularity and finite unit-interface, and through the holarchical unfolding of
number and operation back to function on the I/T axis, making explicit its

i
* This cycle is explored in greater detail in a related aspect called the “Cycle of Identities,” (see The
Binary Cycle of Identities, Axes and Unities, p381) and it is seen in the physical aspect of the model
as well, called Sorce Theory.

Page | 295
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

implicit roots in immanence and transcendence. We’ll see this in another


form in The Binary Cycle of Identities, Axes and Unities (p383). As we will see,
this bounded infinite is the abstract vision-logic description of the Leibnizian
“monad” and the Spinozan “simplest body,”i the joint metaphysical and
meta-mathematical union of the absolute and the relative; the infinite and
the finite. It is also the previously unacknowledged beginning place of
mathematics itself, as it codifies the origin of the number 1 as an implicit
infinite number, enfolded into the primitive natural numbers, whose implicit
infinity will not be broken open until the Rational numbers and fully with
the immanent infinities of the “irrational” numbers.

i
…a specific form of holon, “corpuscle” or anatom whose harmonic maximization of its own implicit
singularity and infinite complexity culminates in extreme self-stabilization, self-focusing integrity and
inertia. See, Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.

Page | 296
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

In Interface Mathematics we are not offering an alternative dimensioning


system in its own right, but instead are presenting a new way to view the
standard dimensional model, using examples from various sources as useful
to understanding dimension and its systems in themselves. Interface
Mathematics can, in this sense, be seen naturally as an interface for
understanding the inter-relations between these dimensioning systems. It is
a “meta-dimensional” or meta-paradigm model for understanding the
relation between dimensioning systems at a more general level. As such, a
sub goal herein is to provide a direct interface between the standard
rectilinear XYZ dimensional model and Fuller’s radial, experiential and equi-
economical vectorial Synergetic Geometry. We will do this without getting
much into its details, and mainly touching only the branching point at its
first dimension; our finite unity and primitive (infinite) number 1—the
origin of counting and mathematical operation itself, as we will see.

As we have seen, beyond the finite representationality of dimensioning


systems, there is real, finite and infinite, sub-representational, a priori
volumetric extension and it is only quantified (differentiated-and-integrated
in the embryogenesis of the concept) a posteriori with the use of dimensions
and systems thereof. Space, conceived as pure volumetric extension prior to
experience, accommodates all possible dimensioning systems (their value is
a function of their utility) and thus if it must be called “-dimensional” then it
is “omni-dimensional.” And by the principle of absolute reversal and the

Page | 297
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

identity of opposites, the omni-dimensional is simultaneously “non-


dimensional,”i* because it hasn’t yet been differentiated into dimensions.
Mathematics or geometry—conceived as a symbolic or syntactic rule-
based approximation of volumetric, omni-non-dimensional extension—must
function through simplification into the bare minimum of dimensions (a
“breaking of symmetry”) required to mathematically
(syntactically/algorithmically) accommodate certain preconceived mental
tasks, e.g. the coordination of abstracted positions, or the interrelation,
comparison and contrast of different lengths and depths—or as Bucky
would have it, for the task of finding the coordinate system that most closely
represents the structural relations in nature, these being based in the radial
and non-parallel functions of sphere-packing and omni-economical, omni-
triangulating systems.
Any number of dimensioning systems are possible, depending only,
perhaps, on utility as a fitness-function. And each one can have a completely
different method of dimensioning and indeed a different number (and
definition) of dimensions themselves.ii When, or if, we ever finally settle
down on a single “all-encompassing” dimensioning system for fundamental
physics and the physical sciencesiii then we will still only know what it takes
for the human mind to dimensionally or parametrically interface with our
current observations and conceptions of reality as required by the current
system of physics and its technological utilization. The math (and the
interpretations of it) will always be that mental interface BETWEEN man
and “God” (the one and the ONE) manifest in the relations of the sensible
Universe.

Buckminster Fuller famously reasoned that the standard XYZ rectilinear


Euclidean/Cartesian coordinate system was a remnant of “flat-earth
thinking”—our transitive as opposed to Immanent/Transcendent axis, with
its spherical coordinates. As Amy Edmonson says, “Early man, finding
himself on a huge flat expanse, assumed that up-and-down and back-and-
forth were the fundamental directions of his universe. Ninety degrees was
the obvious natural angle with which to segment and measure space” (70-3).
As soon as we escape the up-down-left-right perpendicularity of the local
view of the spherical surface of the earth, however—with its mountains and
plains of countless invisible spherical atoms—we find that Universe is

i
* Recall, The Omni-Non: The Binary Logic of the Absolute/Relative Interface, p120.
ii
… as demonstrated so beautifully by Buckminster Fuller’s radically different, exquisitely coherent
and consistent Synergetic Geometry, based on the 4 spatial dimensions inherent in the a priori
volumetric tetrahedron-octahedron isometric vector relation.
iii
Synergetic Geometry seems a good candidate ... eventually.

Page | 298
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

inherently spheroidal and nuclear, not rectilinear. In every direction we


look; inward, outward, sideways and backward, we find new levels of
nuclear, spheroidal and radial structuring; from the algorithmic spacing of
the atmospheric shells of the Earth,i to its core, its atoms, its moon, the
planets, the stars, to the galaxies and their super-clustered hierarchies and
on to the voids. None of these are rectilinear or square. Squares, or cubes
are only found in certain crystals, and even then, far less often then the
hexagon, and tetrahedron. Edmonson continues:
Humankind has had more and more evidence of nature’s radial and
spherical bias throughout history—from the discovery of the shape of
planets to the behavior of radiation and cellular growth. But neither
Copernicus’s spherical earth nor the vast array of biological and physical
phenomena, all suggesting that angles other than ninety degrees would
provide more “natural” or convenient standards, succeeded in reorienting
the perpendicular bias of mathematics.
With its forces of attraction and repulsion, both contracting and expanding
or radiating, the observed universe is far more radial and spherical than
parallel and rectilinear. In fact, rectilinear structuring seems to be a subset
of spherical and radial geometry at its boundary conditions such as the
seeming flatness of the earth we evolved on and from which we began
numbering the cosmos. Because of this, Fuller systematically configured
planar trigonometry as a special-case of spherical trigonometry, in his 4-
dimensional spatial geometry, based on the four axes of the four omni-
symmetrical faces of the tetrahedron as minimal “system” in Universe.
Fuller says in Synergetics:
Synergetics is a priori nuclear; it begins at the center, the center of the
always centrally observing observer. The centrally observing observer
asks progressively, “What goes on around here?” (963.13) … In
synergetics, all experience is identified as, a priori, unalterably four-
dimensional. We do not have to explain how Universe began converting
chaos to a “building block” and there from simplex to complex.ii In
synergetics Universe is eternal. Universe is a complex of omni-
interaccommodative principles. Universe is a priori orderly and
complexedly integral. We do not need imaginary, nonexistent,
inconceivable points, lines, and planes, out of which non-sensible
nothingness to inventively build reality. Reality is a priori Universe. What
we speak of geometrically as having been vaguely identified in early
experience as “specks” or dots or points has no reality. A point in
synergetics is a tetrahedron in its vector-equilibrium, zero-volume state,

i
see Bode's Law and Sorce Theory.
ii
It must be noted that this is in full agreement with the embryogenesis of the concept, in the sense
that Universe is not the same thing as concept. Universe itself is eternal, but the concept-systems of
man indeed do evolve “from simplex to complex,” and this evolution of the concept, not the eternal
(absolute scope: temporal-Emptiness) Universe, is what we are tracing herein.

Page | 299
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

but too small for visible recognition of its conformation. A line is a


tetrahedron of macro altitude and micro base. A plane is a tetrahedron of
macro base and micro altitude. Points are real, conceptual, experienceable
visually and mentally, as are lines and planes (966.12).
Fuller begins with the tetrahedron as the first modelable “system” in
“Universe,” because it is the minimum polyhedron which divides Universe
into a within and a without. “System,” for Fuller, is a priori volumetric and
structural extension. The tetrahedron, however, is generated in Fuller’s
models (and in his “isotropic vector matrix,” See Figure 22, below) from the
relations in a set of four spheres of variable radius, or as points, if that radius
is too small to be seen. And Fuller defines a point as a priori volumetric, a
far-away or tiny “event-star.” The tetrahedron, with its four event-stars, is
the first geometry or structural relation to enclose a volume, because with
any three stars we merely have the plane of a triangle. Add one more star
and we have the tetrahedron, the first event configuration to divide a within
from a without.
Note that with the four stars defined as the corners of a plane in the
rectilinear XYZ model, if there is any misalignment whatsoever (and there
always is such difference, perceptible or not, in real, “contingent” Universe)
then we have a tetrahedron, not a plane. Three event-stars, however, can
never define anything other than a plane; they can never warp into a volume,
without the addition of that fourth event-star. The addition of that fourth
star is the critical pure-relational step into “system” in Fuller’s modelable
and Operational Universe.
Thus the “axis” of “system” itself, in Fuller’s synergetic geometry, is
essentially our ONE-one (“unity is plural and at minimum two”) I/T uni-axis
differentiating the within from the without, with its interface as the omni-
non-symmetric, minimally differentiated sphere. Fuller, however,
fascinatingly sees the fundamental nature of the tetrahedron, and the 720-
degree sum of its angles, in the sphere itself, with his observation that the
operation of closing of any system, from the state of an unfolded plane into
that of a volumetric boundary, involves this same “720 degrees of angular
take-out.” In other words, any system (volumetrically bounded form), from
the skin of an animal to a sphere, can only become closed—from a flat plane
to any volumetric boundary—by removing exactly 720 degrees, those found
in the sums of the angles of the vectors of the tetrahedron, as minimum
system in Universe. This exact angular quantity, for example, is found in the
sum of the angles of the cuts that the taxidermist must make in flattening out
the pelt of an animal from its bounded form to one suitable for a rug on your
living-room floor. Unpeel an orange and the exact amount of “angular take-
out” will equal 720 degrees, says Bucky. The sphere itself, as a closed
system, is thus fundamentally a tetrahedron (or vice versa), in this sense of
its intrinsic 720 degree angular take-out.

Page | 300
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Figure 22: Fuller’s Isotropic Vector Matrix (IVM):


The IVM is the vectorial skeleton of closest sphere packing. The IVM is formed from
the “complementarity” between the tetrahedron and the octahedron, hence the octet
truss. [Image from Buckminster Fuller’s Synergetics.]

While in Synergetics the minimum system is the tetrahedron, Fuller’s


fundamental dimension, however, is not the tetrahedron, but the radial
measurement of the unit-sphere of his “isotropic vector matrix,” or IVM.
Given its omni-symmetrical and hence omni-economical load-bearing
vectorial arrangement, the IVM forms the basis of Fuller’s invention of the
“octet-truss,” a critical element of modern architecture (along with his
innovative geodesic domes). This feature of the isotropic vector matrix, in
turn, is derived from the fact that the IVM is essentially the center-point and
vector skeleton of the most economic form of sphere-packing. The sphere,
therefore, as the locus of every “point” of vectorial radiation and
convergence in the isotropic vector matrix, is central to Fuller’s dimensional
system (See Figure 22, above), as the first dimension itself.

Page | 301
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This radial dimension within each and every sphere of the IVM—and
determining, therefore, the a priori volumetric distance between every
point—recall, is essentially the function of the interface of our “I/T uni-
axis,”i* i.e. to determine the scale or first transitive “plane” or volumetric
field and scale of action, dimension or mensuration. As soon as a boundary
is introduced into the omni-non-dimensional continuum (involving exactly
“one tetrahedron” or 720 degrees of angular take-out), a first dimension, or
infinite polarity and VL-axis (aspect infinity), is already necessarily invoked
as the polarity which gives the triune interface of finite unity its context and
meaning (“(Finite) Unity is plural and at minimum two”). Without this initial
boundary in a priori boundless/formless Emptiness, there is no modelable or
Operational boundary, magnitude, extension, quantity or relation, with
which to dimensionally and modelably interrelate anything with anything
else.

Fuller lays out the dimensional model of Synergetics, saying:


In conventional XYZ coordination, one-dimensionality is identified
geometrically with linear pointal frequency. The linear measure is the
first power, or the edge of the square face of a cube. … In synergetics, the
first-power linear measure is the radius of the sphere.ii
And he says a bit later:
All of the frozen volumetric and superficial area mensuration of the past
has been derived exclusively from the external linear dimensions.

i
* See I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146, and The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
ii
Fuller, Synergetics 963.00 … … and for those interested, I’ll give in this footnote a few quotes
outlining the rest of his dimensional model: (964.01) In conventional XYZ coordination, two-
dimensionality is identified with areal pointal frequency. (964.02) …In synergetics, second powering
represents the rate of system surface growth. (964.30) Shell Accounting: Second power has been
identified uniquely with surface area, and it is still the “surface,” or shell. But what physics shows is
very interesting: there are no continuous shells, there are only energy-event foci and quanta. They
can be considered as points or “little spheres.” The second-power numbers represent the number of
energy packages or points in the outer shell of the system. … (965.01) In a radiational or
gravitational wave system, third powering is synergetically identified with the total point population
involvement of all the successively propagated, successively outward bound in omniradial direction,
wave layers of the system. … (965.02) … as, for instance, total molecular population of a body of
water through which successive waves pass outwardly from a splash-propagated initial circle. As the
circle grows larger, the number of molecules being locally displaced grows exponentially. (965.04)
Perpendicularity (90-degreeness) uniquely characterizes the limit of three- dimensionality.
Equiangularity (60-degreeness) uniquely characterizes the limits of four- dimensional systems.
(966.01) In a radiational or gravitational wave system, fourth powering is identified with the
interpointal domain volumes. (966.02) It is not possible to demonstrate the fourth dimension with
90-degree models. The regular tetrahedron has four unique, omnisymmetrically interacting face
planes—ergo, four unique perpendiculars to the four planes.

Page | 302
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

These “external linear dimensions” are our familiar transitive axes, external
to the immanence within any unitary volumetric scale or frame of reference.
Fuller continues on in the same passage… (and please note that this is
included merely to give a taste of the complexity and beauty of his system,
and its understanding is not needed for the comprehension of Interface
Mathematics to follow)…
Synergetics starts system mensuration at the system center and,
employing omni-60-degree angular coordinates, expresses the omni-
equal, radial and chordal, modular linear subdivisions in “frequency” of
module subdivisioning of those radii and chords, which method of
mensuration exactly accommodates both gravitational (coherence) and
radiational (expansion) calculations. As the length of the vectors
represents given mass-times-velocity, the energy involvements are
inherent in the isotropic vector matrix (963.12).
Interestingly, in Synergetics Fuller also says, “It could be that the concept
conjured up by the mouthed-word sphere itself is scientifically invalid; ergo,
it could be that the word sphere is not only obsolete but to be shunned
because it is meaningless and possibly disastrously misleading to human
thought” (986.235). Fuller means here to distinguish the ideal, absolute
perfection of the platonic Form of the sphere from any real-world
(experiential/empirical) spherical emergent or form. He cautions, correctly,
and always from his experiential basis that we have found no absolute
continuity in nature whatsoever, and thus no perfect sphere. He also makes
the interesting note that such a perfect sphere would be a perpetual motion
machine, with neither input nor output of energy for either entropic (decay)
or syntropic (growth) functions.i
So with Fuller’s caveat on the Platonic sphere, we recognize its use here
as such a Platonic ideal category; an abstracted aspect of The Infinite, and
that a sphere in the real-world is never platonically ideal or infinitely
perfect. Even more, there is never any perfectly detailed frame of reference
from which to measure such a platonic perfection. We have already
“pulverized the categories” with Nondual Rationalism and the Univocity
Framework and need merely to recognize its function and differentiation
here. We fully realize that this ideal sphere belongs in the pure-relational,
abstract world of mathematics and its philosophy, and therefore also that
the sphere is merely the first step in the embryogenesis of the concept from
omni-non-symmetry of the ONE to the first omni-directional symmetry and
minimal modification of the interface of the ONE-one uni-axis…our first
boundary in this EOTC of mathematics as the art and science of pure relation.

i
A fact which would delight Plato, no doubt. And from a trans-foundational and Nondual Rational
frame of reference, this is to be expected as there can be no reduction to any form, including the
formless.

Page | 303
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The sphere is the basic modal infinity as the aspect of bounded omni-
symmetry and absolute bounded continuity.i*

Fuller’s first dimension, therefore, places boundary and volumetric


extension at the root of Operational and Interface Mathematics and it sets
the scale (transitive plane) for our numerical interrelating operations
beginning on the transitive axes (see Fig. 000 below). In Interface
Mathematics as well—and in accord with the embryogenesis of the
concept—nondual-rational dimension springs from the non- of omni-
dimension, or from a priori undifferentiated dimensionality itself. Rather
than starting from one of infinitely many single, differentiated, uni-
directional axes or polarities, we begin with the Infinite Unity of omni-non-
dimensionality, and through a differentiate-and-integrate, transcend-and-
include operation on the immanent-transcendent uni-axis we derive our
first act of dimensioning; the creation of the first “primitive” unit-number
‘one,’ and its corresponding scale of action and mensuration.
Recall our Cycle of Unityii* and its ONE-one triune-interface at the
solidus-vinculum in the vision-logic equation:iii*

ALL = = ONE

…and more visually in the figure below…

i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
iii
* See, VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-logic Equations, p288.

Page | 304
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

Figure 23: Boundary as the First Dimension:


The first dimension in Interface Mathematics springs from omni-non-dimension, or
undifferentiated dimensionality of formless Empti ness itself. Dimension thus begins
with a priori magnitude or scale and is defined as the scale of the selected unit -sphere,
unit-number or “real-point.” This places volumetric extension at the root of
Operational Mathematics and it sets the scale for our interrelating operations with the
generation of the first or “primitive” level of the holarchically unfolding function of
operation and number.

Entirely independently of Fuller, Gerald Lebau recognized number itself as


the first dimension without which systems for co-ordination (inter-relation
and dimensioning) could not exist. In The Orb, Lebau says “The first
dimension, ‘quantity’ is the dimension in which the dimensions are
measured.” He says in What It ALL is and Why [his own comments]:
For such purposes a Cartesian coordinate system of three mutually
perpendicular lines, etc, define a point in this space; a fourth coordinate
independent of the spatial dimensions defines an instant in time; and a
fifth dimension is always implicit.
It is this fifth dimension that provides meaning to the other four. It
has always been present. Indeed, it was probably the first dimension ever
invented. [Dimensions are a tool of measurement. They are abstract
inventions of the human mind. Of themselves, they do not exist in nature.
They are an attribute of metrical kinematics.]
And you can hear Lebau’s call for something akin to Fuller’s percept-based
“conceptuality” or “modelability” when he says:
There is a real and physical objective relation between all things. That
relation is measurable in the dimensions of space and time. The actual
relation is absolutely whatever it may be, but the dimensions are relative
to the rational fiat of the observer.

Page | 305
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Remarkably, Fuller and Lebau have independently converged on many


aspects of their systems. Fuller’s first dimension is the arbitrarily selected
scale of a unit-sphere without which Lebau’s first dimension, number, could
not volumetrically exist because in Operational Mathematics a number-
symbol requires a referent, our “real-point.” Lebau’s and Fuller’s ideas
merge into the primitive and primary concept of number represented as a
minimally complex spherical boundary; a close-up of our finite real-point
and the first operational object and finite unity. Calling the spherical real-
point a “circular” “needle-sharp point,” Lebau says (my emphasis and
[[comments]]):
Let us leave our space-time impossible-point in favor of an even infinitely
small i circular point. A “needlesharp” point. Yes, now we have our
gradient [[and extension]] again (289).
Lebau and Fuller also independently converged, in very different ways, on
the four-dimensionality of mathematical, volumetric “space” (not
Minkowskian 3D space + 1D time, but 4D space). They each began from the
premise of modelability but went entirely separate routes to arrive at the
same basic conception. Lebau considered number as the unacknowledged
root of dimensioning systems, the very first dimension with which all the
others are measured, and Fuller recognized repeatedly that the tetrahedron,
with its four primary axes, is the simplest system “in Universe,” defined as a
priori volumetric and extended.
The physicist’s ignorance of the roots of dimension in number and
ultimately in sub-representational omni-non-dimension, enabled them (and
layman alike) to believe that the specifics of our “standard” dimensioning
system are separate from mathematics and exist independently in the real
world. It is commonly thought that “the universe is inherently three-
dimensional,” but in reality the universe merely has the aspect of dimension
(omni-extension) and it is we humans who break it down arbitrarily into
specific uni-/multi-dimensioning systems. The universe is not inherently
three dimensional, just as it is not inherently twenty-six dimensional. The
Universe is extended and thus omni- and non-dimensional because it
accommodates and allows any and all possible arbitrary dimensioning
systems to function simultaneously depending on utility and function. We
will come to find that it is merely representational relation, as opposed to
Fuller’s structural relation, that is inherently three-dimensional, and thus
unable to coherently and consistently account for the fourth dimension of
the “imaginary numbers” which Fuller’s dimensioning system can.ii*

i
Of course we could take issue with Lebau’s adoption of the standard oxymoron “infinitely small,”
because taken to its infinite extreme “infinitely small” necessarily means “zero-size” (another
unavoidable oxymoron) and thus extensionless, but it is clear that Lebau is stipulating a point with
real extension, “circular” as a sphere represented in two dimensions on paper.
ii
* See, The Imaginary as Vestigial Transitive Axis at the I/T Interface, p348.

Page | 306
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS

It should be clear then that our meta-dimensional beginning in the


immanent-transcendent omni-axis is prior to any concept of dimensionality,
such as the transitive notions of “flat” or “curved” Cartesian/Euclidean or
non-Euclidean space. We should note again as well that the concept of
curved-space has no meaning without the identical opposite notion of flat
space. In this sense, one cannot be prior to the other, and we will now
outline the holarchical and embryological foundations of number and
operation free from any a priori dimensioning system whatsoever, in the
meta-dimensional level of sub-representational vision-logic and the VCS.

Page | 307
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Page | 308
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

As we discovered in the Cycle of Unity, we transition from the ONE-ALL of


the uncountable I/T axis to the ONE-one of the uni-axis and from there we
discover, select or create the boundary-interface between immanence and
transcendence (represented by the VLE ∞/∞) as our finite unity and the
defining scale unfolded as the countable infinite of the “transitive plane” for
our desired operations. The inward infinite terminus and implicit
singularity of this I/T uni-axis and polarity is our old friend the “ideal point”
which we previously kicked out of the finite realm of number and into the
realm of the aspect infinite beyond modelability. He returns here not as the
first primitive number ‘1’—because he lacks a boundary and finite unity and
is only one immanent pole in the uncountable infinity of the omni-axis—but
as the implicit singularity or aspect of relative locality and position upon
which the first volumetric aspect of real dimension, number or magnitude,
can be defined. [Notice here how the word “define” contains the root of
finite. Etymologically it means to assign limits and this is precisely the
procedure here.]

Page | 309
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Before even number itself comes onto the scene in mathematics, the first
boundary in the boundless must itself become manifest in the closure of the
first implicit number 1; the object of the operation of counting … 1+1+1+1+
…. This first operation is Kant’s operator of existence itself, before the
predicate and category of quantity and quality can even arise. This first
operation of “unit-closure,” prior to even counting itself, represents the
formation in the mathematical mind of the primal mathematical identity or
rigid category (“numerically (or absolutely) identical” to any other of its
kind); the number 1, our finite unity as primitive encapsulated infinite
number and bounded or modal infinite. “This one, and that one, and this
other one… and this other-other one … ”—being composed of identical units
(unit-identities), the agglomerative or sequential numbers (cardinals and
ordinals, respectively) all begin to sound alike until we give them sequential
names in order to differentiate…and thus begins counting from a series of
“ones.”
As we recall, in The Cycle of Unity this unit-closure as a conceptual
breaking of the omni-non-symmetry of the formless, ineffable absolute into
the omni-symmetry of bounded relative form (and root Bounded Aspect of
The Infinite), takes place from our singular, relative-scope representation of
logical-Emptiness, the immanent-transcendent uni-axis. Recall from our
Cycle of Unity that this relative unit-identity (or finite unity) is our
interface—through the positional aspect in the uni-axis—with Infinite
Unity—the absolute, tautological identity of the ALL-ONE. So, even the very
first number, the finite unit-identity, is born from a coupling of an identity
and an operation in the differentiation-and-integration of the embryogenesis
of the concept.
This unit-closure is the separation of the absolute identity of the ALL-
ONE of Infinite Unity into its immanent and transcendent poles by the
selection of the first omni-symmetrical interface and boundary of our finite
unity and abstract, ideal sphere as the basic modal infinity. Thus the unit-
identity—our primal relative-identity in the art and science of pure-
relation—is born from the polarization of Infinite Unity, or absolute-identity,
the ALL is ONE, as we have seen in our Cycle of Unity. The sphere is, in this
sense, the closest possible relative representation of the omni-non-
symmetry of the ONE, in the omni-symmetry of the one. This is perhaps why
the ancients held such a high place for the sphere. It is the interface of the

Page | 310
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

ONE and the one, the abstracted essence of man himself in his relation to
God.
There is, then, a critical Heraclitean polarity of identity and operation;
noun and verb; stasis and flux, implicit from the very beginning of this
embryogenesis of the concept of mathematics and number, and we will find
it recurring throughout … and as we have already seen in the Univocity
Framework.i*

From the aspect of the boundless absolute, no number exists. Like Form
emerging from the concept of the formless, number emerges from the
numberless—the finite from the Infinite, and representation from sub-
representation. ii The sole purpose of number is the interrelation of
modifications or differentiations as abstract pure-relational categories in the
relative world of form—specifically between those found at the interface of
the observer and the observed. Thus without modifications and their
perceived boundaries numbers would never evolve, there would be no
distinct “objects” to count and numbers would serve no purpose.
Number is a tool for dimensioning. Operationally, this begins with the
simplest (most symmetric) volumetric geometry, the sphere, as abstractly
representing the first extended or modelable number or distinct physical
magnitude. The primary number ‘1,’ as we saw in The Cycle of Unity,
appears as a boundary between immanence and transcendence, and as the
basic modal infinite.iii From this first volumetric number we have an identity
and a scale to modelably replicate and interrelate all the other numbers, and
this interrelation of predefined unit numbers is the transitive axis (see
Figure 24, below). However, given that each unit-identity is composed itself
of a bounded infinite, then each composite number is a primitive infinite
number, whose infinity is simply encapsulated in the unit-identity itself. The
breaking of this encapsulation of infinity doesn’t occur operationally until
the invention of the ratio, in our holarchical EOTC of number and operation.

i
* See, Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID), p186.
ii
This is not a temporal priority, but a logical one. One cannot conceive of form without something
to be formed, nor the finite without the infinite (see Spinoza). But it must always be understood
that this is a polarity. The Numberless (infinite) turns around number, just as Emptiness turns
around Form, and Substance around its modes.
iii
As Shakespeare’s Hamlet says, “…I could be bounded in a nut-shell, and count myself a king of
infinite space…”

Page | 311
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 24: Transitive and I/T Relations:


The transitive axes deal with inter-unit relations, and thus with countability. The I/T
uni-axis sets the scale for the first unit and the transitive axis deals with initiating the
holarchical levels of inter-unit operations beginning with addition and s ubtraction.
Once a unit is defined and the scale of inter -unit relation is set, agglomerative
complexity can begin. But also see how through agglomeration the size or scale of the
object is increased? This is how the transitive countable infinite maps to the
transcendent pole of the uncountable Immanent/Transcendent axis (see trans-trans-
bias below). Given that each unit-identity is composed itself of a bounded infinite,
then each composite number is a primitive infinite number, whose infinity is simply
encapsulated. The breaking of this encapsulation of infinity doesn’t occur
operationally until the invention of the ratio, in our holarchical EOTC of number and
operation.

Page | 312
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Without “fundamental” units or pure-relational categories in mathematics,i


the complex inter-relations needed for higher level (transcendent)
patterning and systems of rules could not emerge. In the absence of the
agglomeration of solid structural elements—such as the rigid pure-relational
categories of the natural numbers—morphological “excellence,” evolution
and human cognition, could not occur. And hence, without all these there
would be no purpose, and no possible origin for mathematics. Mathematics
is, in a sense, agglomerative dimensioning for agglomerative beings.ii The
transitive axis, then, begins with our first noun-verb, identity-operation
coupling, the linear inter-operation or agglomeration of unit-identities,
otherwise known as counting.

Figure 25: Agglomeration and Transitivity:


Agglomerative relation is the first primitive field of transitivity .

i
… or basic “matter-units” in physical reality (e.g. atoms)
ii
Plato’s descent from the “forms” to “matter” lies buried in this polarity between the elemental
monads and their compounds and emergent representations.

Page | 313
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The transcendent-bias, recall, is the general tendency of the mind (which is


emergent and transcendent already) to favor transcendence (yang) over
immanence (yin) in its implicit functioning. This bias or tendency includes
the failure to acknowledge the transcendent level of initial emergence itself
in the mind (or any other finite unity), and the immanent origin, of thought
or representation—conceiving it, rather, as fundamental or foundational.
The mind begins its search for order and understanding always from this
lofty perch of emergent order and generalized abstraction. The failure to
recognize either 1) this transcendent or emergent level or 2) its generalized
and abstract properties, can generate many false problems in philosophical
or meta-mathematical thought. These include, as we have seen, the
problematic assumption of foundationalism and its “disastrous infinite
regress,” or the missing beginning of eternity.
Recall from the discussion in Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and
the Transcendent-bias, that this peculiarly medieval problem stems from the
failure to recognize the transcendent or emergent nature of thought, matter
and/or time and its implications on the nature of immanent or transitive
causation. It starts from looking inward or backward from the perch of a
priori emergent thought and seeking in this backward way an arbitrarily
imposed ultimate substrate-level or origin event. When the problem of
creation ex nihilo arises from the arbitrarily imposed concept of an ultimate
substrate-level, or when the necessary absence of an origin event in an
infinite temporal chain is realized, a transcendent-biased mind sees a
“disastrous” regress because the expected ultimate substrate or event, which
must begin or ground the transcendence or emergence, cannot be found in
the boundless face of Emptiness. It is the negative view of infinity—which
starts from the tacit level of emergence/transcendence and seeks an
imagined and preconceived origin—that causes the disaster of the regress.

The “trans-bias,” on the other hand, is the combination of the transcendent-


bias and the transitive-bias. This is sometimes called the “trans-trans-bias”
to emphasize this dual mapping, but the terms are ultimately the same. The
trans-bias is the default tendency to think in terms of both transitivity and
transcendence, and to map the one in terms of the other at the expense of
neglected immanence. The countable infinite of the transitive axis tends to
map directly to the transcendent pole of the I/T axis, entirely bypassing the
uncountable immanence within. Any “plane” of transitivity is necessarily
relatively transcendent from the deeper levels of immanence and the
immanent pole of the I/T axis. The trans-bias is a more specific form and
consequence of the objective-bias where much of the functionality of the
subjectivity of the individual is taken up in service of extrinsically directed
activities (conatus) such as perception and social functions (communion).

Page | 314
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Indeed, the algedonici projection-polarity of fear and desire is inherently


externally oriented and projected towards the object of that fear or desire.
Transcendence, growth and evolution, for agglomerated and emergent
beings, must take place through the appropriation of external resources.
And hence, just as in rational mathematics, the immanent infinity of the I/T
axis is hidden as undefined under the cipher on the immanent side of the
solidus or vinculum,ii* so also, in the default scientific materialism of modern
thought, the immanent infinity of the emergent subject is hidden under the
cipher of a demoted “subjectivity” by a reduction to the object in a flatland
materialism.iii
This becomes starkly obvious in the fact that the default transitive axes of
mathematical graphs, the Cartesian coordinate system, maps directly to the
transcendent pole in the one-to-one “identity line” of the default function y =
x (See Figure 26, below), while it entirely bypasses the immanent direction
altogether. Note that there is a hidden ratio here, and that beneath the x of
any integer there is a division by 1. This is the unit-closure of the natural
numbers, the first dimension of number itself in the cycle from Infinite to
finite unity—the ONE to the one—and maintained up through the integers.
Unit-closure is not broken until we get to the rationals—which reveals the
hidden unitary divisor beneath the integers and below—as it breaks closure,
the trans-trans-bias and identity-line mapping, opening up mathematical
operation into the immanent-transcendent axis.

i
Relating to pleasure and pain
ii
* See, The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual Rationalism p71.
iii
This flatland is a tacit function of a proto-rational, trans-biased neo-Cartesianism generated as the
shadow-element of the aborted rationality of modernity. And so the proto-rational Descartes is
enfolded in the “History of Philosophy” as the “father of modernity” or rationalism rather than the
fully rational/modern Spinoza or the mostly rational/modern (and secretly Spinozist) Leibniz.

Page | 315
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 26: The Image of the Trans-Bias in the Cartesian Graph and the Identity Line:
Note how the graph of immanence in the inverse-identity line crosses the unit
boundary in its outward mapping of the immanent/transcendent infinity.

The default space of mathematical graphs is this pre-rational transitive


space of the integer, which includes the transitive bias inherited from the
unit-closure of the Naturals and its agglomerative, expansive, emergent,
transcendentally-directed functions. The immanence opened by the
mathematical ratio is truncated at zero and entirely bypassed, on the way
down the line, into the negative transcendent-transitive direction of the
integers. From the space of the trans-bias—as seen in the pre-rational
function of the identity line—this mapping is perfectly straightforward, a
straight line, but once we begin mapping the immanent space of the rational

Page | 316
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

functions—as seen with the line of the “inverse identity” function—the


intrinsic distortion becomes apparent (as seen in Figure 26, above).
The negative numbers on the graph of the identity line don’t map toward
immanence at all, but merely toward the negative infinity of transitivity and
transcendence (or the macro-scale, in terms of debt rather than payment).
Note how the infinite division of the x in the denominator of the “inverse
identity” function becomes mapped transcendentally or outwardly on the
graph as it moves ever closer to the x-axis. This is the distortion of the
immanent space of the rational in the default trans-biased transitive and
pre-rational space of the Cartesian coordinate system.i The immanence and
continuity of the Rationals is indeed found after-the-fact on the transitive
number-lines, but it is not mapped in terms of its own axis, and only in terms
of the pre-rational transitive axis of the integers. The rationals, recall, are
operating on a fundamentally new axis, the immanent/transcendent, but this
axis is where the unit-identity was generated in the first place. Already we
can see the binary interaction between the two VL-axes in mathematics.
The simplest function, y = x/1, is an identity mapping between the
transitive axes and the transcendent direction, extending transcendence and
transitivity as one, to infinity, while the immanent pole, and the intrinsic
immanent-transcendent axis of the Rationals gets bypassed (See Figure 27
below). Immanence is mapped transitively to transcendence, having no
intrinsic place in the default visual space of mathematical graphs.

Figure 27: Numbering the Infinite:


Note here how the trans-bias of the integers (gray circles) bypasses and ignores the
immanent space of the Rationals (red circles). This is the default integer space of the
pre-rational Cartesian coordinate system and the default space of visualization in
mathematics.

i
And of course this is a function of pragmatism in that it would be extremely difficult to make such
an unbiased graph system, let alone make it the basis of mathematics. This is the real, physical basis
behind the trans-bias, and again the point is merely to acknowledge it and explore its implications
and affects on mathematics and philosophy as a whole.

Page | 317
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This default pre-rational integer-space of the mathematics—and hence the


default “visualization paradigm” for mathematics itself—is perhaps the main
reason that the rational zero is still not officially recognized as the immanent
infinity that it is, but remains “undefined” to this day in mathematics.i The
project of Rationalism, and nondualism, in both mathematics and
philosophy, is unfinished, and this work is illustrating its ancient roots in the
nondual. Recall, for example, this passage from the Tao te Ching;

All things have their backs to the female


and stand facing the male.
When male and female combine,
all things achieve harmony.

Number, in mathematics, is a function of utility, and it requires the ability to


differentiate and map between unit-identities or agglomerations thereof.
The number one, for example, being numerically identical to any other one,
cannot be differentiated from it. And a group of ones, is difficult to
distinguish from a similar group of ones of a slightly different number,
especially as the numbers grow large. Therefore, the first “numbers”
recognized as such in the embryogenesis of mathematics are explicitly
categorical agglomerative-units, already products of the earlier implicit
identity-operation coupling of unit-addition in counting finite unities (or
digits) and labeling them sequentially or stepwise.
This noun-verb, number-operation, coupling of unit-identities with each
other, 1+1+1+1+1… gives us our next holarchical level in the embryogenesis
of the concept of number: the “natural numbers,” 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, … These can
be called the “numerical identities” of mathematics, because, in a very deep
sense, the “natural numbers” are the natural root of our absolutized concept
of number, as abstracted aspects of quantitative relation. They are eternal
absolutized categories. A number 3, for example, is always “numerically
identical,” in its abstract categorical nature, to any other number 3, “from
now until eternity.”
Recall, also, that this hidden quantized agglomeration of unit-identities in
the first mathematical operation of counting is only explicitly revealed with
the breaking of unit-closure in the advent of the mathematical ratio, when it
becomes recognized that beneath every integer (e.g. 3) there is hidden
solidus and unit-identity (e.g. 3/1).

i
The trans-bias, by the way, also shows up as a positive bias on the number line and in additive and
multiplicative operations, as we will see.

Page | 318
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Once the boundary is drawn circumscribing the first-, or unit-magnitude,


the primary “unit-closure” of the “pre-number” ‘1’ can then be added with
other units to form the secondary (or compound) numbers (see Figure 28,
below). This is the beginning of a real, physical, finite (or indefinite)
number-line and it is the beginning of modelable dimensioning. Note that
this Interface-Mathematical number-line is also a three-dimensional
extended shape (albeit generalized into pure relation), therefore it a priori
exists, or can interface with objects existing, in the real, visual and modelable
world of volumetric extension, rather than waiting to exist until zero-
extension has been multiplied to the 3rd power, from an “infinitely thin”
zero-depth plane into a cube. Conversely, the one-dimensional line with
zero-thickness can only exist in the ideal world of abstract mathematics, as a
linear aspect of The Infinite; an aspect infinity.i* And so in Fuller’s terms our
real-line is a priori modelable.ii

Figure 28: The Primitive Numerical Identities:


The first true mathematical numbers are compound numbers, agglomerations of the
pre-number, the unit-identity, 1. These are the “Numerical Identities”.

At this level of abstraction, Interface Mathematics demonstrates its


superiority in modelability and its deep connection with empirical reality.
Conceiving of these transitive axes as agglomerations of unit numbers
reminds us of the logic-fact that each directional axis is arbitrarily chosen
from an infinity of possible others. And similarly, conceiving these unit-
identities as I/T interfaces reminds us of the unbounded possibilities of scale
of each of these units. And keeping all of this visually in mind, when we
come to divisions into the unit sphere (in the rational numbers), we will
remember that we have crossed a primal boundary in the embryogenesis of
mathematics and are working on another VL-axis altogether. Given that the
transitive-axis begins in counting itself, it is natural to see that it pertains to
Cantor’s countable infinity, as it breaks ever deeper into counting the
uncountabilities of the I/T axis.

i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
This is a spatial line, or a vector from the operation of set-generation, as opposed Fuller’s
essentially temporal vectors made from tracing a unit through its motion in space.

Page | 319
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

With the first coupling of unit-identity and operation (the 1 and the
operation of addition), the infinite set of our “numerical identities,” are
formed, as the set-aspect (or set-generator) of counting by ones. This
inherently indefinite operation gives us our first “infinite set,” the natural
numbers.
In mathematics, there is a relation between sets and operations known as
“the closure property.” It states that a set is closed, with respect to an
operation, if those operations, on any of its elements or subsets (our Natural
numbers so far), return only other elements within the set. If an operation
on a set, however, produces a value that does not exist within the set, then
the closure of that set is “violated” by that operation. Given that our set of
Natural numbers is infinite, or unbounded, and that if you add any Natural
number with any other, you merely get a larger natural number, therefore,
with respect to addition the Natural numbers are closed.
Counting is a function of unit-addition, or the addition of unit-identities:
1+1+1+1 … . It is the first stratum of a recursive layering of addition, which
is the first mathematical operation of agglomeration, and it generates its
own infinite set (the Natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, …) with its own closure
property with respect to the first operation of addition (and recursive
addition or multiplication). So we see here that the first number-set, the
naturals, is generated by the first operation, addition, a mathematical form
of unit-agglomeration. We can already see the trans-trans-bias at work with
the first mathematical operation and its generated number-set being a form
of stepwise agglomeration, infinitely increasing scale, mapped to a transitive
number-line. At this point in the EOTC of mathematics we have only this
symbolic agglomeration and the infinite set of Natural numbers it generates.
This simple operation, however, hides an important polarity and a
default directed bias; that of input and output and the trans-bias toward
increasing agglomeration entirely bypassing the immanence within the unit-
closure upon which this whole process is erected. This implicit uni-directed
polarity, as we will see, directly encodes agglomeration as the trans-bias
transcended-and-included in mathematics and the pre-rational Cartesian
graph system, as it maps, by default, the aspect of agglomerative growth in
evolutionary transcendence to the transitivity of the natural-through-
integer, or pre-rational numbers. If we break this primary unit-addition
process down to its visual/visceral real-world experiential elements from
which it evolved in the first place, we can begin to see the simple
input/output polarity in action. [To make it quicker to read, we will often
call the input/output polarity, simply the “iopol,” although we will transition
into it gently, to aid in quick memorization.]

Page | 320
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Figure 29: The Implicit Input/Output Polarity (Iopol) of Addition and Subtraction:
In this figure we can see that addition is a reversed subtraction, in the triune
movement of the unit-identities from the hidden implicit set int o the explicit natural
numbers.

Imagine that there exist two sets of units; one that consists of a single unit,
our selected unit-identity (1), and another which consists of a pile of
undifferentiated unit-identities (See Figure 29, above). The pile is sitting
hidden in the background, and it is our implicit input set from which we will
draw in order to out-put our agglomerating and differentiating number in
the process of unit-addition, or counting, creating, in the process, the set of
natural numbers.
So in order to add a number to our explicit unit in the first place—to
make our first step from the pre-numerical 1 and into the natural
numbers—we must first draw from our implicit set (hidden in the
background of mathematical thought), composed merely of undifferentiated
unit-identities. So we see this simple polarity in the processes of addition
that implies, and even necessitates a hidden subtraction from the
undisclosed, and uncounted set of unit-identities. This is the polarity of
addition and subtraction as a function of the implicit input/output polarity
(iopol). As any unit-identity is counted and added to the set of natural
numbers, it is simultaneously subtracted from the implicit input set. (see
Figure 29, above) This is another aspect of Kant’s operator of existence,
drawing the possible into the light of the actuality of existence before which
any predicates can be assigned.

Page | 321
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

When we reverse the default agglomerative direction (trans-bias) of this


input/output polarity (iopol), and begin recursively taking away from our
agglomerative natural number—taking its component unit-identities out of
the picture and into the hidden implicit set from which they came—
eventually we end up at our initial unit-identity, 1. But there is no logical,
visible or visceral reason why we can’t, as well, place this last unit-identity
into the implicit “erewhon” from whence it came, in effect negating this
number-line itself along with its last primitive unit-identity. So we take this
last unit away and get our first concept of zero as negation, “violating the
closure property” of the Natural numbers with the “new” operation of
subtraction. It is the reversal of the implicit iopol, however, which initiated
the operation of subtraction, which, in turn, led to this violation of our first
set-closure. This will be a recurring theme in the ratcheting, holarchical
expansion of the symbiogenetic function of number and operation.
Interestingly, Bucky Fuller claims, in his historic 42-hour audio/video
session Everything I Know, that it was the invention of the abacus which led
to the cipher, or what we are calling ‘transitive zero.’ We can see this clearly
in Figure 30, below, where the input/output polarity (iopol) itself is directly
instantiated in the physical pole on which the unit-identities (represented by
the “ones” beads) slide. On this now explicit polarity, for addition, the left-
hand set is the (previously-implicit) input set, and the right-hand set is the
agglomerating output set. But when we simply reverse the direction in
which we slide the units, we also reverse the iopol and begin the operation
of subtraction. It is easy to see that transitive zero is naturally formed when
the last of the agglomerated set is finally removed back into the left-hand
implicit input set from whence it came. This transitive zero is naturally
often considered as part of the set of natural numbers, but it wasn’t actually
invented for many hundreds of years after the initial natural numbers, and it
is likely that the simple physical embodiment of the iopol in the bi-
directionality of the abacus rod, naturally led to its invention.
On the transitive axis, therefore, zero represents the negation or absence
of a unit or agglomerative number brought about in the “violation of the
closure property” of the Natural numbers with the advent of the operation of
subtraction in the inversion of the iopol of default (trans-bias) addition.

Page | 322
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Figure 30: The Abacus and the Iopol:


The Abacus as physical instantiation of the input/output polarity. Fuller argues that it
was the invention of the abacus that led directly to the invention of the cipher, our
transitive zero. This is because it operationally instantiated the impl icit input/output
polarity in the bi-directionality of the rod upon which its units moved.

Note that the set of natural numbers, generated by the first operation of
unit-addition, was initially “closed” without zero, and the closure of the set of
Natural numbers is only “violated” with the inversion of the input/output
polarity (iopol) in the second operation, subtraction, which led to zero. Note
also that even though visually, physically and causally you can’t subtract any
more unit-identities from zero as nothingness, the operation of
subtraction—abstracted in the mind into symbolic relations (and on the
abacus rod)—can indeed continue, such as, for example, when we imagine it
as a sort of debt to be repaid when you do get a positive amount of unit-
identities in your explicit set. It can also be visualized on the abacus as
adding more unit-identities to the left-hand, negative set from some other
implicit set. Therefore, not only does the iopol inversion of subtraction open
up to us the important concept of nothingness, the cipher, but it opens up
the physically imaginary, but extremely (and fiscally) useful, realm of
negative numbers.
So, with the inversion of the iopol to reach the identical-opposite of
addition in subtraction, we get the set of whole numbers, with the addition
of zero, and then we get the integers as we bypass the immanence inside of
each unit-identity and move into the transitive operational polarity implicit
in the set-generating aspects of addition and subtraction.

Page | 323
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

It is only when we operationally recognize and reverse the polarity of


input and output that the positive-negative polarity of the transitive axis, in
orthogonal relation to the immanent-transcendent axis, is completed in its
numerical representation in the integers. After breaking the closure of the
Naturals to give us the new digit zero, the use of subtraction beyond the
natural conditions of visual or causal logic, breaks the closure of the whole
numbers to give us the integers, and we have our next function of zero as the
“origin point” on the transitive axis of the emerging transitive Cartesian co-
ordinate system.

As an origin of a number system, zero on the transitive axis is just another


number, but with privileged status as existing in its own unique neutral and
null zone (the “additive identity”) between the positive and negative
directions on the transitive axis. Transitively, zero can be reached as simply
as any other number because it is the negation of number.
This zero-as-negation, is in direct contrast, as we have already seen, with
zero on the Immanent/Transcendent axis, the rational immanent zero, as
inverse infinity, absolutely unreachable and not a number, i.e. “undefined.”
Note also, however, that in The Cycle of Unity this zero is where we started,
the origin, as the immanent pole or implicit singularity of the immanent-
transcendent uni-axis. So, in an oblique sense, the violation of the closure
property of the Naturals brings us full-circle, on the transitive axis, to the
immanent origin of the numberline, from which the transitive axis of the
agglomerative pre-rationals exfoliated in the first place…
But this process of negation in additive iopol reversal is not complete. It
cannot rest at the origin—which is insignificant from the frame of reference
of the transitive axes—hence it passes right on by the implicit singularity of
the rational zero as if it did not exist, because at this point in the EOTC it
lacks the function (the ratio) to access it. The continued “violation” of this
closure property in subtraction, however, brings us past the origin into the
imagined realm of negative numbers, and we have the “oppositional forces”
of quantitative transitivity.

Just like the first finite unity or relative unit-identity was generated by the
noun-verb coupling of a pre-mathematical division or interface of the I/T
uni-axis and its absolute identity in the ONE-ALL (recall our Cycle of Unity),
so we have already seen that the first set of numbers, the naturals, was
generated by the noun-verb, identity-operation coupling of “unit-addition”;
i.e. 1+1+1+1… . This is the first level of addition, implicit in the Natural
numbers themselves as the “first dimension” of number. It is characterized

Page | 324
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

by the implicit unit-closure explicitly revealed only when we get to the


Rationals by the default unitary divisor hidden underneath the implicit
solidus of every pre-rational number (or integer).
When we then move from unit-addition to the addition of the compound
numbers or the “numerical identities,” we are already at the next level of the
unfolding recursive holarchy of the noun-verb coupling of number and
operation; i.e. 3 + 8 = (1+1+1) + (1+1+1+1+1+1+1+1). The integers are
already products of recursive addition, so what we generally call addition is
already the second level holarchical recursion of addition. And as
“numerical-addition” is a recursive, or second-level unit-addition, numerical-
subtraction is a second-level unit-subtraction.
As opposed to the one implicit invariable input-bead of the ones-level of
the abacus and the first level input/output polarity (the one unit added
recursively to the agglomerating whole)—at the second- or numerical-level
of addition, there are two inputs; one implicit and invariable (the unit-
identity), and the other explicit and variable—the infinite set of “numerical
identities,” transcending-and-including the unit-identities. This is the
differentiation-and-integration of function in the EOTC of number and
operation.

Page | 325
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The Immanent/Transcendent axis, we have seen, like all aspect infinities, is


prior to mathematics and operability. Like the imaginary absolutized
categories of the Platonic Forms (or even our natural “numerical identities”
and digits), it is therefore, by definition, ultimately abstract, invisible, un-
modelable and inoperable, in and of itself. It must be accessed, visualized,
mobilized and actualized bit by bit through the real-illusions, forms,
interfaces and operations of the relative scope, beginning with the
operations of transitivity, in the same sense that Substance must manifest
itself—to itself, and through itself—as pure emergent and unpredictable
potential, in actual modification, nucleation, evolutionary agglomeration and
complexification (Emptiness in form).i In the same way, the implicit I/T
axis—which was the implicit origin of the finite unit-identity interface in the
first placeii*—must be accessed and realized through the evolution and
embryogenesis of the noun-verb coupling of number and operation itself, as
we will continue to see evolving with it through its embryogenesis into the
higher-level functions, operations and numerical identities of mathematics.

We have already seen the polarity of multiplication and division in the


structure of the embryogenesis of the concept. Cellular division is this
process whereby multiplication occurs specifically through division.
Similarly, multiplication in mathematics functions on the implicit division of
every single digit or numerical identity by the scale-defining unit-identity
hidden under the implicit solidus. Indeed, that solidus is simply one means
of making explicit this initial set-generating unit-multiplication, in terms of
the division aspect of the unit-multiplication/-division polarity making up
the numerical identities. As such, in a sense, we can and should view every
solidus or vinculum as an inverted multiplication sign, and vice versa. See
Figure 31, Level 1, below.

i
It is my current assumption and discovery that the unconscious accidental conflation between
these two unknown operational axes causes perhaps all of the known paradoxes in ancient and
modern Western meta-/mathematics, as we have already begun to see. We will address many more
of them as we continue to explore this holarchical unfolding of number and operation.
ii
* Recall The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 326
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Figure 31: The Iopol of Multiplication/Division:


In this diagram we can see that division reverses the input/output polarity of
multiplication violating the implicit unit -closure of the hidden immanent denominator
to the infinite variability of the transcendent infinity of the natural number s.

Addition and multiplication in mathematics can be differentiated simply, and


intuitively by the function of recursion. Addition is clearly a small-scale or
local first-level of agglomeration, or the agglomeration of just a few different
or similar numbers together, whereas multiplication is the second level
recursive or automated agglomeration of the same number over and over, a
given number of times. What we generally call multiplication in
mathematics, as we have seen, is recursive numerical-addition…which is
already recursive unit-addition used implicitly to create the numerical
identities or digits themselves. Taken in reverse, in terms of the
input/output polarity, and we have unit-level division and subtractions,
differentiated again simply by the function, or viewpoint of recursion.
Indeed, it is this first order of recursion that ensures that our function of
division maps to merely stepwise operations and thus only to the countable

Page | 327
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

infinity of the transitive-axis, rather than to the uncountable infinity and full
continuity of the Immanent/Transcendent axis.
In this way, our recursive unit-addition in the set-generation of the
Naturals and digits, can also simply be called unit-multiplication, and we can
see that multiplication and iteration already exists implicitly with the set-
generation of the first numbers. This is why the number 1 is the
“multiplicative identity.” It is already implicit as the unit-identity in each of
our digits because, for example, the number 8 is already the unit-identity
iterated or multiplied 8 times. Multiplying by the unit-identity, then, simply
starts again at the beginning of the process that led to the generation of the
digits in the first place.
Multiplication is a pure-relational automated synthesis; one input
iterated according to the value of the second. In this sense, but very loosely,
multiplication can be seen as a doubled addition, acting in two dimensions,
instead of one. See Figure 32, below.

Figure 32: Doubled Addition:


Multiplication as a “doubled” addition moves us into the first quadrant of the pre -
rational Cartesian axis, and transcending -and-including the transitive sign of the
integers, the other quadrants are inhabited.

In the rectilinear Euclidean system, with multiplication we move, in a sense,


from the transitive line into the Cartesian plane, and the y-axis becomes the
axis of multiplication acting upon the x-axis, to create the first planar
quadrant of the Cartesian graph; the upper-right agglomerative/intensive
quadrant. Transcending-and-including the oppositional transitive sign of the
integers in each of the two first dimensions, however, this takes us from the
first quadrant in the default graph of the pre-rational—the purely

Page | 328
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

agglomerative/intensive—into the other three quadrants of the Cartesian


plane. Though, as we will see,i* multiplication can just as easily invoke an
inherently non-Cartesian and non-Euclidean plane, based on the triangle, for
example, as in Fuller’s Synergetic Geometry. This we will see in the simple
fact that a triangular multiplication table is inherently more efficient than a
square one, which also demonstrates, along with other concepts that we’ll
explore, that powering is not inherently “square” in nature, but can be more
economically and optimally seen in “triangling” and “tetrahedroning” as
opposed to “squaring” and “cubing.”

And as we would expect, division is the iopol reversal of multiplication; a


second-level recursion of unit-subtraction and a pure relational analysis.
But there is a crucial difference here with this iopol inversion from
multiplication to division. In multiplication it makes no difference which
number is multiplied by which; multiplication is “commutative.” This is
because in multiplication we are operating in the default agglomerative
(trans-bias) mode with the implicit unit-identity as the transcended-and-
included first-level input, and addition is the “quantized” set-generation
process that fulfills itself, with its full input/output polarity reversal, in
generating the integers.
See Figure 33, below for a simpler way to visualize the commutativity of
multiplication. In the MULTIPLICATION section of the figure, A and B
represent the two orders in which the two input numbers can be arranged.
In spatial terms, the areas drawn out by each are identical and indeed they
can be seen as the same rectangle in a different orientation. It is the
commutativity of multiplication that expresses the agglomerative, oscillatory
reciprocity of the closure property of multiplication with respect to the input
integers, and unit-closure itself.
In division, on the other hand—at the second- or numerical-level—rather
than the unit-identity itself as the standardized default transcended-and-
included agglomerative input, and iopol-reversed as the divisor—the job of
unit-identity has been opened up to the infinite variability of any numerical
identity (the integers, so far) and then iopol reversed as the active “divisor.”
Thus, in division the implicit quantizing, set-generating factor of the pre-
rational numbers has been removed, opening up the omni-non of the
continuum to the mathematical ratio operating on the immanent-
transcendent axis. See Figure 33, below.

i
* See, Four-Dimensionality: Trans-Biased vs. Immanent/Transcendent, p352.

Page | 329
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 33: Multiplication/Division Commutativity and the Breaking of Unit Closure:


MULTIPLICATION: Comparing A and B we can see commutativity as simply a different
orientation of the same resultant rectangular area. DIVISION: In division,
commutativity is absent, because the order of input determines the direction of a
process of unit-scale remapping. The dividend (thin blue lines) retains t he implicit
input scale and the divisor (thick red lines) then remaps itself as a whole to the
dividend and their respective implicit unit -identities are compared. This ratio can be
seen visually by assessing how much of the passive -dividend’s blue squares are present
in one of the active-divisor’s red boundaries.

Because the ratio opens up the implicit input of the enfolded unit-identical
1st level to the infinite variability of the numerical identities (digits), the
ratio begins operation on the VL-axis of scale, the uncountable I/T axis from
which the unit-scale was implicitly defined in the first place. In division, as
we can see in Figure 33 above, commutativity is absent because the order of
input determines the direction of a process of unit-scale remapping (our
expanding/contracting holonic solidus/vinculum, below). The divided
number, the numerator or dividend (thin blue lines), retains the implicit
default input scale and the active frame of reference of the value of the
number itself, and the divisor (thick red lines) then remaps itself as a

Page | 330
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

transcended-and-included whole to the dividend. At this point their


respective implicit unit-identities are compared giving us the function of the
ratio, breaking the closure of the unit-identity itself.
This ratio can be seen visually by assessing how much of the passive-
dividend’s blue squares are present in one of the active-divisor’s red
boundaries. The ratio ultimately compares the different sizes of the
respective scale-defining unit-identities (breaking the implicit identity of
units) of each numerical input, after the initial remapping takes place. If the
divisor and dividend are the same value then the remapping will be no
different than the original implicit input scale of the unit-identity and we are
back at unity; one.
This unit-closure-defying scale-remapping is what makes division non-
commutative, because it is dependent on the direction of the implicit, default
input-scale and explicit expanding/contracting output-scale in its scale-
remapping procedure. Multiplication, on the other hand, involves no unit-
scale remapping procedure (and no possible breaking of unit-closure),
because the unit-scale of 1 (and its pre-numerical closure) is taken
agglomeratively as the transcended-and-included implicit input-unit and not
opened up to the infinite variability of the numerical identities.

As we are beginning to see, the trans-trans-bias inherent in the linearity of


operations, along with our levels of recursion and the input/output polarity,
imparts a fascinating property on the transcending-and-including
embryogenesis of number. At the first- or unit-level of recursion, the
transition from the agglomerative, trans-biased Natural numbers to the
integers—i.e. the violation of the closure property of the naturals—took
place through the inversion of the input-output polarity. At the next level of
recursion, in the transition from the integers to the rationals, we began again
with the agglomerative default of second- or numerical-level recursion in
multiplication and it was again the inversion of the input/output polarity in
division which violated the closure property of the integers—and the unit-
closure shared by all pre-rational numerical identities.
This violation of closure at the transition from the integers to the
Rationals is of such importance in mathematics that it is often called simply
the “violation of the closure property” itself, and this is because it violates
the unit-closure, and pulverizes the fundamental category of mathematics,
the unit-identity (and the agglomerative numerical-identities or the
integers) that began the holarchical embryogenesis of number and operation
in the first place. In so doing it opens up mathematics to the Nagarjunan
logical-Emptiness implicit in the nondual view of rationalism; e.g. there are
different Rational numbers so inconceivably close to each other in value, in
Page | 331
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

comparison to any two integers, that they “appear” identical in all practical
applications, but beneath appearances they have a singular difference. Thus
again we can see a direct correspondence between rationality in
mathematics and rational philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology and
ontology. The rational level in all of them operates on our I/T axis and its
category-pulverizing, re-mapping acategorical imperative, breaking beyond
the rigid distinctions of the numerical identities and opening up to the
infinite difference within.i*
We can see in this iopol reversal, then, a sort of ratcheting, back-and-
forth saw-tooth kind of cycle in our transcending-and-including holarchy
and embryogenesis of identity (number) and operation. Every time we
break the initial agglomerative bias of the transitive mapping of
transcendence,ii* and invert the implicit order of input and output, we move
to the next level of the holarchy.
This implicit polarity and trans-bias of input and output can be seen very
clearly in the asymmetry of the fact that it is easier to multiply than to
divide.iii The Babylonians, for example, compiled tables of division answers
in the form of 1/n for n integers, for the simple reason that division is much
more difficult to do on the fly than multiplication.iv¥ Multiplication/division
is asymmetric with respect to unit-closure. Multiplication recursively and
holarchically builds upon initial unit-closure, and division breaks it open in
the iopol reversal. This polar level of identity and operation exists between
the two ‘orthogonal’ axes—the transitivity of multiplication (with its
recursive expansion of the unit- and numerical-identities) and
immanent/transcendent (with its pulverization of numerical identity into
the intensive forces).
The division of the unit-number into the rational or fractional set,
reminds us that division of the immanent axis, from a unity into a polarity,
the within and without, is the first operation of mathematics in the setting of
the unit-magnitude. Just as in the Triune Infinite, the modal infinity is the
interface between the I/T and transitive axes, so too division and
multiplication function as a map (relational system of application) between
the transitive and I/T axes. Provided that the operational magnitudes are
greater than the unit number and the ratios result in clean integers, the

i
* See, Nondual Rational-Empiricism and the Acategorical Imperative, p62.
ii
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
iii
It may also be seen, in another way, in function offsets, with the asymmetry between the offsets of
input (x) and output (y). For example, take the function x + y = 6; offsets made to the input
parameter, x, such as plugging (x+3) into x, shift the graph in the negative direction—minus 3 units
on the x-axis—whereas those on the y (output) axis, shift it in the positive direction. This asymmetry
is a function of seeing one direction (trans-trans), from implicit input (recall our hidden realm of
input unit-identities used to subtract from in the process of addition) to explicit output, in the
implicit polarity of input and output.
iv¥
Bell, Development of Mathematics, p. 31

Page | 332
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

immanent actions of multiplication and division operate purely in relation to


the transitive, implicitly unit-quantized scale. But once the division ratio
differs from the unit-number or its multiples, it begins to operate in relation
to the infinite immanence (yin) inherent in the operation of division. For
this reason it is important to have the immanent axis in mind when dealing
with multiplication and division.

We find a physical correlation with the following quote from Lebau:


On all macroscopic levels quantity is an absolute dimension. […] For sub-
atomic particles, however, identity begins to intermix. Portions of
material enter into and out of the system designated as “particle.” When
identity begins to be lost, quantity becomes relative. As we shall see, here
is the real indeterminacy in nature.
Similarly, when we divide past unit-identity we break the trans-biased unit-
closure of holarchical recursive agglomeration and enter into infinite
immanence as though we might search to redefine the unit-scale. This
immanent infinity gives rise to the infinities between all finite numbers on
the continuous or rational number-line. It is the land of the undefined
logical-Emptiness that must be mapped in terms of the defined, and thus we
find the Rational numbers and the “Decimal expansions,” operating upon the
new I/T axis yet expanding from either direction in relation to,
transcending-and-including, the transitive axis of integers.

We have already discovered the working elements of the holonic


solidus/vinculum above,i* and also in the section on The “Labyrinth of the
Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual Rationalism (p74). Indeed, it was
instrumental for providing us with the central chord of our Ariadne’s cable,
the Principle of Nondual Rationalism guiding us through Leibniz’s labyrinth.
Recall also, at this point, from the same section, the analogy of the ratio as an
intrinsically balanced seesaw. And recall also that it is the transcendent-bias
implicit in the iopol or distinction of numerator and denominator that
inherently offsets the balance toward transcendence in the numerator—
with its transcended-and-included default unit-scale—and immanence in the
denominator—with its expanding/contracting scale opened up in the iopol
of division, giving us in the end the transcendent-biased definition of the
rational number.

i
* See, Multiplication Through Division, p324.

Page | 333
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

With the implicit first-level input of the unit-identity as divisor now


taken over by the explicit use of any second-level numerical identity or
number, the expanding/contracting solidus or vinculum now represents the
unit boundary of the rational number system, operating upon (abstracting
aspects of) the implicit continuity of the a priori uncountable I/T axis.
Seemingly, this boundary can take any size at all, but due to Dedekind, we
recognize that the Rational numbers do not indeed abstract out this entire
boundless (Emptiness) aspect of immanence and continuity.
To understand very simply the nature of the fraction, so we might see its
limits, and the limits of the rational numbers, visualize the solidus-lever as a
circle. Putting weight on the inside of this boundary, the denominator, pulls
the boundary in the immanent direction, towards contraction or reduction
of intensity, whereas putting weight on the outside, the denominator, pulls it
in the transcendent direction, moving it toward expansion and increase of
intensity due to the transcendent and objective (outward) bias.
Naturally it is intuitive that in this imagined motion the boundary of the
ratio between the two infinities of immanence and transcendence can reach
all points of the continuity within. But given that, for the rational numbers,
only finite unit-multiples can be compared in the ratio, thus ultimately only
finalized jumps can ever be enacted, presenting intrinsic operational limits
(e.g. Dedekind cuts) to the Rational numbers as a whole. The irrational
numbers, on the other hand—opened up through the iopol-reversal of the
next level of roots—deal with the never-ending infinities of immanence
themselves, instead of coming to rest on a final point and number.
This distinction between the infinite and finite nature of irrational vs.
rational numbers, respectively, may be the ultimate difference here in this
respect. Dedekind cuts themselves are not actually gaps in the continuity,
but merely “infinitely small” points where two lines cross (one of which is
the numberline) and a rational number cannot be found there. Is an
“infinitely small” division, a division at all? Not according to our
fundamental principle of Nondual Rationalism which says that infinite
division equals indivisibility. An infinitely small division presents a gap of
zero size, taking out zero amount of continuity. Given that an “infinitely
small” or extensionless point, in Nondual Rationalism, is merely an
“immanent-local” aspect of The Infinite, and given that a Dedekind cut is not,
therefore, a gap in continuity, it may indeed at the same be true that the
rational numberline is indeed continuous—as would be expected given the
infinities on either side of the ratio—but also that the rational numberline is
incomplete with respect to those points that don’t come to rest on a finalized
rational number, but keep going right into the immanent infinity itself, as we
will see.i*

i
* See, The Trans-Rationality of the Irrational Numbers, p365.

Page | 334
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Repeated from Figure 1 (p84): The Expanding/Contracting Holonic Solidus/Vinculum:

Above the unit-solidus—and operating in the transitive-transcendent layers


in the embryogenesis of mathematics—things are just that, solid. We can
add, subtract, multiply and divide in terms of unit amounts, with a bit spilled
over here and there. We can reduce fractions above the unit-solidus to
compound agglomerative numbers, e.g. 2/1 becomes 2*1 = 2, etc. When we

Page | 335
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

break below or between the unit-solidus, however, we abandon the


transitive grid, axis and holarchy of agglomerative number functions and
enter the no-man’s-land of the raw immanent infinite inherent in continuity.
We can see this new VL-axis clearly where we find parentheses in
interval notation, e.g. [16, 8), this is where the transitive breaks into the
immanent aspect of The Infinite and the labyrinth of the continuum.

We can see, then, that the ratio and the expanding/contracting


solidus/vinculum is the mathematical (pure-relational) analog of the
Deleuzian intensive forces. Inherent in this polarity is a positive infinity,
what Deleuze calls the “secret of the rational.” Rational numbers only
inherit a negative sign through transcending-and-including negative integers
with their intrinsic “oppositional forces.”
We can also tell that the rational level works on a new VL-axis by its
inverses. The rational inverse is a reciprocal, flipping across the solidus and
never changing the sign. The additive inverse, on the other hand, always and
merely is a change of sign. These terms and inverses of each level endlessly
“approach” different limits. For the additive it is the negative and positive
axis of the integers, and for the rational it is zero and infinity. The negative
signs that can occur in Rational numbers get there by being transcended-
and-included from the additive layer. Because the negative sign, and
negativity or opposition in general is not native to the I/T axis of the rational
(Deleuze’s positive infinity) its transcension-and-inclusion in the default
pre-rational Cartesian/Euclidean rectilinear geometrical model—which
can’t accommodate more than three dimensions—generates the non-
modelable transitive axis and vestigial 4th dimension of the imaginary
numbers.

With the trans-trans identity and its distinctive identity-line in mind, it is


instructive and valuable to point out the transitive mapping of the intensive
forces in terms of absolute value. When the Rational numbers are mapped
in terms of their intrinsic, agglomerative “positive” value—the intensive
forces transcended-and-included with the unit-closure itself—we find the
distinctive graph of absolute value. See Figure 34, below. Absolute value,
then, in a sense takes us back to the intensive forces and polarity of addition
and the transitive-axis, truncating the negative forces of subtraction, but
only on the multiplicative y-axis opened up with the doubling recursion of
the layer of multiplication in the holarchy and EOTC of mathematics.

Page | 336
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Figure 34: The Image of Absolute Value (or the absolutely valuable image):
The function of absolute value truncates the multiplicative plane into the intensive
forces transcended-and-included tacitly with the unit-identity, and explicitly with the
move into the Rational numbers and the new origin and identity of the multiplicative.

Zero, or the cipher, as we can already see, denotes at least two different
meanings in mathematics. It has an inherently binary nature due to the fact
that there are two fundamental or pre-operational VL-axes underlying
mathematics; the transitive and the immanent-transcendent. But each of the

Page | 337
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

two aspects of zero also corresponds to a different set of numbers generated


with these pre-rational “agglomerative/deglomerative” operations. On the
I/T axis, placed in the immanent position of the ratio (the denominator),
zero inverts to its identical opposite, the transcendent pole of the I/T axis.
This “rational zero” is the infinite immanent pole, the singularity implicit in
any finite unity or being.i*
On the transitive axis, however, zero (transitive zero) is the absence,
negation or non-being of a unit or compound number (through the iopol
inversion), as we have seen. It can be reached simply by subtracting a
number from itself in relation to others. In this way, the immanent and
transcendent (i.e. rational and pre-rational) views of the function of zero
give us Leibniz’s amphibious nature of zero as both the very essence and the
very absence of being.

Figure 35: Immanent Zero:


Immanent zero as the infinite pole of immanence on the immanent -transcendent axis.

Here we can see the difference between the immanent/transcendent and


additive (transitive) identities in light of the differences in transitive and
immanent zero. On the I/T axis, zero is the identical-inverse of infinity. This

i
* Recall The (Binary) Cycle of Unity (p254), and the interface of the I/T uni-axis of the ONE-one.

Page | 338
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

is what we will call “immanent zero.” Neither immanent zero nor


transcendent infinity represent boundaries, or real points, so neither are
numbers, in themselves, though irrational numbers, as bounded infinities,
can directly involve them.

With infinite volumetric extension again inherent and enfolded in the


definition of magnitude and primitive number itself—and thus
accompanying all instantiations or ideas of quantitative value, especially
concerning PHYSICAL parameters—there can be no more “infinitely small”
point-particles to draw us into the labyrinth of the continuum, or into Zeno’s
infinite regress of representational measurement, only to be empirically
“renormalized” later into the finite, volumetric- or extension-derived
physical constants of particle physics. Had this seemingly obvious meta-
mathematical observation been understood by the particle physicists of the
twentieth century, the point-particle mistake, and its extension to the
superstrings extruded therefrom in “zero-thickness,” would have been a no-
brainer. The extensionless point—as the implicit singularity of an
immanent/transcendent uni-axis or as the positional aspect of The Infinite—
can only denote position (a ‘terminus,’ as Leibniz called it), after the fact, not
physical extent or magnitude. Continuity and Infinite Unity is not composed
of immanent infinities, but they are abstracted out of it as positional aspects.
No surprise there, considering our principle of absolute reversal, that the
unwitting input of an immanent infinity (implicit singularity) ends in the
output of transcendent mathematical infinities (explicit singularities).
If that “thing” or property, operated upon as if it were finite or relative, is
tacitly defined in any of its properties as infinite, or absolute—such as an
“infinitely small” point—then an operational error has occurred in the
Univocity Framework at which point the principle of absolute reversal will
come into play. This absolutizing of the relative is a fundamental-level con-
fusion between polar opposites of finite and relative modification vs. the
infinite and omni-local absolute scope. Infinity and immanent zero, as the
limitless limit for division, are such aspects of the absolute scope and by
definition and scope they cannot be surpassed in their kind.
Immanent zero, conceived as a limit, is instantaneously squeezed out of
transitive extension by the categorical realization that “zero-size” is
absolutized into an oxymoron and, like “absolute nothingness,” it is a self-
negating concept. Thus the immanent “zero” behind every infinite division
becomes the abstract inward pole of the infinite immanent axis beyond
transitive extension and numeration. It is the inverse of “infinite in extent”
so we call it the “inverse infinite” or “immanent zero.” And as a pole of an
infinite polarity or VL-axis, it is absolutely un-reachable and boundless.

Page | 339
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

On the immanent axis, there is no absolute “approaching the limit” as


ambiguously undifferentiated in the calculus.i* Such approaches are always,
and only relative to the transitive scale of the default pre-rational,
transcendent-biased Cartesian grid.ii* The curve may appear to get steeper
and closer to the limit, relative to the transitive frame of reference (the
graph), but in parameter-space a simple scale function (operating on the I/T
axis, of course) brings it right back where it started, if desired, no closer and
no further from the non-limit at zero. The “approach” is but a perspectival
illusion, a figment of mathematical imagination (meta-mathematics).
Though this is well known and even intuitive in mathematics—given that it
is not encoded in the modern orthodox mathematical framework, which
currently lacks the I/T axis and Vision-Logic Coordinate System—it is easily
and often forgotten under normal meta-mathematical operations. Its
reiteration here is crucial, however, to the concept of “immanent zero.”

The initial orthogonal distinction between the transitive and I/T axes—and
their respective operations of addition/subtraction and
multiplication/division—perhaps finds its most lucid illustration in the
comparison and contrast between the additive and multiplicative inverses
and their respective identities. This clarity demonstrates the validity of the
assignments of addition/subtraction and multiplication/division to their
respective transitive and immanent/transcendent axes.
At this point there is some potential con-fusion that must be averted with
the different meanings of the term “identity”. Identities, used in conjunction
with the operations—e.g. additive and multiplicative identities—are
effectively nulls with respect to that operation. They are the numbers that
leave no effect on the operation itself, but return the identity of the other
input number; e.g. 3 + 0 = 3 or 3 x 1 = 3. So we have here a distinction
between categorical identities (e.g. the unit and numerical identities) and
operational identities (e.g. the multiplicative and additive identities). The
operational identities return the categorical identities in any operation.
The additive inverse of any number is its negative or inverse-identical
(e.g. x and –x). But the inversion of addition ultimately operates through the
subtraction, from zero (the additive operational-identity and implicit origin
of the transitive-axis), of its numerical-identical (i.e. 3 and 0 - 3). This
inversion process, for the transitive axis, operates symmetrically about

i
* See, Reconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and
the Calculus, p400
ii
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.

Page | 340
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

zero—the additive operational-identity—on the integer number-line.


Similarly, the multiplicative/division inverses operate with respect to the
multiplicative operational-identity, 1, the unit-identity hidden under the
implicit solidus of every integer; i.e. 8/1 inverted to 1/8. In contrast to the
additive inverses, however, the symmetrical and opposite operations of
multiplication/division do not and cannot, of themselves, generate negative
numbers—they are intensive, not oppositional forces.
The rational inverse is a reciprocal, flipping across the solidus and never
changing the transitive sign. The additive inverse, on the other hand, always
and only is a change of sign centered on zero. So we see that the transitive-
axis and its specific operation-layer of addition/subtraction is centered on
zero (the additive operational-identity, or null) and the I/T axis’
multiplication/division (mult/div) layer is centered on one (the
multiplicative operational-identity or null). The origins of each of the
operational VL-axes are centered on their respective operational-
identities, thus we can also call the operational-identities “origin-
identities” to emphasize this relation. And so, we have zero and one as the
origin-identities of the transitive and I/T axes, respectively. (See Figure 36,
below.)

Figure 36: The Map of the Origin-Identities:


The offset origins of the I/T and transitive -axes and their respective operational -
identities of multiplication/division and addition/subtraction. The additive identity
and origin of the transitive-axis is zero and the multiplicative identity and origin of the
I/T axis is one.

Page | 341
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

These terms and inverses of each level not only have different intrinsic
origin points, but they limitlessly “approach” different intrinsic “limits” on
either end of their respective number-line axes. For the additive, the limits
in the unlimited are the negative and positive transitive infinities
(“unboundaries”) of the integers, and for the rational it is immanent-zero
and the positive infinity of transcendence.i
The negative and positive (oppositional) signs that can occur in rational
and multiplicative numbers, as we have seen, get there by being
transcended-and-included from the additive and transitive layer. Because
the negative sign, and negativity, or opposition in general, is not native to the
I/T axis of the rational (again we see the correlation with Deleuze’s intensive
forces of univocity)—but even more critically because the I/T axis itself is
not fully operational in mathematics—the transcension-and-inclusion of the
transitive-axis at the higher level of powers and roots generates the non-
operational, non-modelable and non-conceptual transitive axis of the
imaginary numbers, in the pre-rational context of the Cartesian/Euclidean
rectilinear default geometrical model for numeration, as we will see in more
depth below.

Note that the addition of like signs always results in a number of that same
sign, leading further in the agglomerative direction of either the negative or
positive transitive infinity (e.g. -3 + -3 = -6 and 3 + 3 = 6 ), rather than
deglomeration toward the additive origin-identity at zero from either
oppositional direction. Note as well that with the addition of different signs
it is the number with the greater absolute value that determines the sign of
the result (e.g. 3 + -6 = -3 ).
With multiplication as a recursive addition/subtraction, however, there is
an apparent non-intuitive shift away from this straightforward
agglomerative operation. Unlike addition/subtraction, multiplication of like
signs (whether positive or negative) always leads to a positive number, while
multiplication of unlike signs always leads to a negative. This is not because
multiplication is fundamentally different from addition, but because
multiplication is actually a new emergent layer, operating at the higher
(transcended-and-included) level of recursion, as an automated, or doubled
form of addition/subtraction. For example, take the equation, -3 x -3. In

i
Note that here we again see the overlap of the positive transitive and transcendent infinities in the
default trans-trans bias as seen explicitly in the identity line. See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias,
p312.

Page | 342
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

additive terms we start with zero—the additive operational-identity and


origin—and begin the low-level iteration resulting in … 0 - -3 - -3 - -3. Recall
that subtracting a negative number is the same as adding a positive number,
which would translate to … 0 + 3 + 3 + 3 = 9.
With this shift toward the critical distinction of resultant sign being a
function of likeness vs. opposition—i.e. like signs result in positive answers,
and unlike result in negative—it is difficult to escape the conclusion, once
again, that the rational/multiplicative operational layer is operating now on
the intensive and inter-expressive forces of immanence and its I/T polarity
and axis. Further, the rational layer is, in a sense, oscillating between the
transitive and Immanent/Transcendent axis, as seen in the graphs of this
instability as it manifests in the radical distinction between the axes and
polarities of even and odd integers in the exponents of ascending powers
(See Figure 38, The Trans-Trans Asymmetry and Instability, below, p349).
This seemingly innocuous fact about the second-level of recursion in
multiplication, however—with its identical answers for inversely charged
statements (e.g. -3 x -3 = 9 and 3 x 3 = 9 )—leads to a fascinating critical
instability and ambiguity by the time we get to the next level of recursion in
powers and roots. This ambiguity leads ultimately through the square-root
property and to the phenomenon of “imaginary numbers,” as Descartes
called them. We’ll explore this in more detail below.

Page | 343
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

In the embryogenesis of number and operation, at the level of rooting and


powering, we find yet another transcended-and-included layer of
agglomerative recursion. The difference at this level is simply that powering
has transcended-and-included the iterative-addition function of
multiplication to give us the iterative-multiplication, or (2nd level) iterative-
iterative-addition function of powering. This holarchical level in the art and
science of pure-relation brings us into the domain of physical forces, all of
which are modeled by power/root functions such as the fall-off of forces as a
function of the distance or radius squared. But most importantly, with this
level, the uncountable infinity of the I/T axis has begun to be tapped, with
the iopol reversal into specific roots, for example.
As would be expected, powers are agglomerative, synthetic and
transcending while roots are deglomerative, analytic and immanent or
descending (or “positive” vs. “negative” in trans-biased terms). Both are
meta-functions on the uncountable I/T axis and through their exponent-
notation they reference the origin-identities, VL-axes, rules and polarities of
each of the deeper levels—the unit-solidus origin-identity, axis and I/T
polarity of multiplication/division, as well as the transitive sign-rules and
polarity enfolded at the deeper level of the countable infinities of
addition/subtraction. Indeed, this is what is so distinctive about the
power/root level. It is the first level in which all the previous levels are in
explicit, integrated operation. See Figure 37, below.
Interestingly, this function of the trans-rational operation of powering
and rooting mirrors the function of the “trans-rational” and “integral” level
of development in integral philosophy. This level in integral philosophy is
called “second tier” because it can finally begin to recognize the truths of the
deeper levels, explicitly transcending-and-including them positively, rather
than transcending-and-negating them as with the forces of opposition
characteristic of the pre-rational and pre-integral. At this integral or second-
tier level one can descend and operate at each level at will without negating
the power and function of each. Similarly, in powering and rooting, the
transcended-and-included operations of the previous levels—
addition/subtraction and multiplication/division—manifest explicitly in the

Page | 344
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

nested polarities of the rules of exponents, laying bare to manipulation the


whole transcended-and-included holarchy of identities and operations—but
this only occurs when we get to the level of powers and roots.
In powers and roots, and their exponential notation, the signs of the
transcended-and-included polarities of the exponents ( + and - for addition-
subtraction, and the solidus/vinculum, for mult-div) mediate the polarities
of the next level, for the base. The exponent is, in a sense, an operator,
control or manipulator whose enfolded operational polarities are offset—in
relation to its base—at a higher level in the holarchy of number and
operation; i.e. polarity-inversion operations on the enfolded VL-axes of the
exponent (e.g. transitive-sign and I/T-solidus inversions) ultimately
mediate the operational polarities of the base at the next level up. For
example, changing the transitive sign (+ -) of the exponent, flips the I/T mult-
div polarity of the base across its solidus; e.g. b-x = 1/bx. Similarly, flipping
the exponent across its solidus, inverts the power/root polarity of the base;
x
e.g. b1/x = b (see Figure 37, below).
Therefore, encoded in the operation of the power/root level, for the first
time, is the entire transcended-and-included holarchy of number and
operation, finally made explicit in the sign-rules of exponents. This is our
familiar “ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny,” Haeckel’s “Biogenetic Law,”
which is a natural feature of any transcend-and-include embryogenesis … of
concept or of crocodile.

Page | 345
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 37: The Onion of Operations:


In the exponents of powers and roots the entire transcended -and-included holarchy of
operations is finally made explicitly operational. The input/output polarity of each
transcended-and-included level of operations, in the exponent, acts to med iate the
polarity of the next higher level, for the base. For example changing the transitive sign
of the exponent flips the entire number (and its base) around the unit -solidus, the
origin of the I/T axis and the level of mult -div. So too, changing the position of the
exponent across its own unit -solidus flips the polarity of the next higher transcended -
and-included level of operations for the base, inverting it across the power/root
polarity.

Page | 346
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

The mult/div level is the interface between the transitive add/subtract level
and the immanent/transcendent power/root level. In a sense, while
mult/div held one agglomerative foot (mult) on the trans-trans identity axis
and the other foot (div) slipped into the hidden immanent uncountable
infinity of the I/T axis, not operationalized on the default pre-rational
Cartesian graph, roots and powers operate fully on the I/T axis. This is seen
in the fact that multiplication can modelably operate on the negative
transitive numbers while such operation at the levels of powers and roots
leads to the ambiguity of the square-root property and ultimately to the
unmodelable axis of the “imaginary numbers.” It takes the second-order
recursion of powers and roots to reveal the instability at the heart of the
mult/div level as seen in the numerical-identity and ambiguity between
multiplying numbers of like signs (either positive or negative).i*
Furthermore, this operation of the root/power level upon the I/T axis is
also seen in the graphs of powers and roots in that they can never line up
exactly with the trans-trans identity line (unless their power is strictly that
of the additive/multiplicative levels, i.e. 1), but can only approach it, being
fundamentally non- or trans-linear. In this sense as well, the first power of
the exponent is the representation of the implicit unit-closure transcended-
and-included at the power/root level. The unit-closure is also seen in the
fact that all numbers other than 0 taken to the power 0 are found to be 1.
There is a unique place for both zero and one at the power/root level. This
is the transcension-and-inclusion of the previous origin-identities seen in
the fact that all power and root functions of the form y = xn—which have not
transcended-and-included any transitive x or y off-sets—must pass through
both zero and one (for both x and y), our transitive and I/T origin-identities,
respectively. See Figure 38, below.
The instability between the oppositional forces of the default transitive
and the new intensive forces of the I/T is made manifest with the automated
recursion of multiplication in the power functions. And we can see the
oppositional transitive-axis itself and its integers, standing out in the context
of the rational and its intensive forces in the instability of the powers in
Figure 38, below.

i
* See, The Kernel of the Trans-Trans Asymmetry and Instability at the Crossroads of the Transitive
and I/T Axes, p340.

Page | 347
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 38: The Trans-Trans Instability:


The transitive mapping of the transcendent
generates an inherent asymmetry and
instability in the ascending integer powers.
In terms of integer-powers (curve A), this
instability appears as an oscillation
between the even and odd powers, but on
the rational number-line of powers (curve
B), there is an infinite bias in graphs of
powers toward the intensive forces of pure
agglomeration or absolute value.

Page | 348
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Note that with the powers, and thus with multiplication itself, there is an
effectively infinite favoring of positive, or intensive forces, as opposed to the
negative and oppositional. This is seen in the fact that only with the exact
integer values of the odd powers do we see the recurrence of the transitive
identity line between the positive and negative infinity of the pre-rational.
In even-integer powers (ultimately meaning multiplication by like signs, or
multiples thereof), the trans-trans identity is truncated to the absolute value
of the multiplicative (y) axis and mapped in a mirror image, rather than in
the directionality of the identity axis. On the graph, the curves of the rational
values infinitely approaching the integer powers appear identical. For
example, the graph of x1.99999 appears nearly identical to that of x2.00001 and
since they aren’t integers, they map exclusively in the purely agglomerative
or intensive upper-right quadrant.i
In other words, in a purely random search through the deep infinity of
the space of graphs of powers with rational exponents, it is virtually
infinitely improbable that you will stumble upon one that maps to an integer
power and displays the trans-biased identity axis or directionality between
the upper-right and lower-left quadrants. In this way, curve B in the
diagram below is still infinitely misleading in that the horizontal lines are
infinitely thicker than the actual “infinitely thin” or “zero-dimensional” lines
that they represent.
The reason that non-integer powers of negative x do not show up on the
graph, however, is that they involve a mixture of powers and roots; or
transitive/agglomerative and immanent/transcendent functionality. The
forces of immanence, remember, are forces of intensity, rather than
opposition, and it was the first move onto the I/T axis in the ratio which
pulverized the unit-identity transcended-and-included in the integers,
bringing us intrinsically to the forces of intensity of the rational. So it is
ultimately because the rational number-line is operating on the intensive
axis of immanence and transcendence that rational roots only appear in the
upper-right intensive quadrant.
Take, for example, the value of 2.5 in the exponent. This is actually a
combination of 2 and ½. We have seen that in the exponent the rational
polarity of the solidus is mapped to the next higher operational polarity, the
roots and powers, for the base. And so the rational exponent of ½ is actually
the root 2 of x, or the square root of x. Given the positive-negative ambiguity
of multiplication by like signs (translated at the next higher level in the
onion of operations as “even powers”), and that it can never lead to negative
numbers, then –x is meaningless as a result of an even root … except on the
“imaginary axis,” as we will see below.

i
The Cartesian quadrants are obviously not to be confused with Wilber’s AQAL quadrants.

Page | 349
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

All even powers—which as we have seen lead to a deviation from the


Cartesian graph into what Descartes called “imaginary numbers”—can be
broken down to the square-root, just like even numbers are all multiples of
2. The core of this ambiguity underlying the imaginary axis is the “square-
root property” which states that for any positive number k, if x2 = k then we
must consider both the positive and negative square roots of k in the answer
for x; x k or x k . And this is just the higher root-level
codification of the ambiguity of multiplication by like signs.
Recall that the general shape of the graphs of even powers was the
mirrored axis of absolute value. Absoluting a value is, in a sense, to
disregard the oppositional forces of the transcended-and-included pre-
rational transitive-axis and take it in relation to the rational
Immanent/Transcendent axis with its intensive forces of pure magnitude.
Given that the instability of this ambiguity doesn’t show up until the
multiplicative level (with like signs, positive or negative ending positively),
this negation occurs only with the multiplicative layer and its doubled y-axis
into the Cartesian plane. This multiplicative ambiguity and instability
negates the negative integers of the multiplicative y-axis, putting into limbo
any transcended-and-included transitive (positive/negative) signs
associated with it and causing the dual ambiguity of transitive signs as seen
in the square-root property.

Because the powers and roots have begun to operate fully on the I/T axis,
and because they have fully transcended-and-included the transitive-axis,
there is a necessary interface or transition that must be explored between
the initial oppositional forces and countable infinity of the transitive-axis,
and the intrinsically intensive forces of the I/T axis and its nondual-rational
positive and uncountable infinity.
The branching point of the imaginary axis is the square-root property,
and the deeper-level ambiguity of multiplication by like signs; our kernel of
trans-trans instability. Because it is impossible to derive an even-root of a
negative number—all like-sign multiplication leads to a positive number—
therefore the graphs of even-roots of negative values of x end up in the
undefined land spawned by this oppositional-ambiguity intrinsic to
multiplication itself. In this way, powers, operating exclusively on the
multiplication of like numbers with like signs, can only interface partly with
the transitive-axis and its forces and signs of opposition.

Page | 350
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Even powers are fundamentally indifferent to the oppositional forces


transcended-and-included with the transitive-axis and introduce a
corresponding ambiguity. In order to make that ambiguity tractable into the
space of roots and powers, and because there was a clear need for four-
dimensional modeling and operation in physics and elsewhere—and also,
even more critically because the default pre-rational Cartesian/Euclidean
rectilinear geometrical model employed for our conceptualization of
numeration reaches its limits at three—the 4th (vestigial) rectilinear-
Cartesian axis and dimension of the imaginary numbers was invented.
This occurred through the work of Gerolamo Cardano in the 1500s, but
imaginary numbers were not widely accepted until the late 1700s with the
work of Leonhard Euler and Carl Friedrich Gauss. Descartes, however, in
1637, first called them “imaginary” in the intuitive recognition of their
unconceptual and unmodelable (vestigial) status, with respect to the axioms
and axes of the Euclidean/Cartesian system. The imaginary numbers endow
the limited 3-dimensional rectilinear Cartesian system with an “extra
dimension”—a new “4th dimension” and power much needed in the new
technologies and sciences such as electromagnetism, quantum mechanics,
signal processing, cartography and control theory.

Recall our distinction between transitive and immanent/transcendent axes


and coordinates.i* I/T coordinates, recall, are spherical, being derived
earlier in the EOTC (and The Cycle of Unity) as we move from the omni-non-
directionality of absolute unbounded unity in the ONE, to the omni-
directionality of the bounded interface of the ONE-one I/T uni-axis, and
from this first unit-identity we derive our first agglomerative line, the
essence of the transitive-axis and the starting place and directionality of
primitive mathematics coupled to geometry. In this transition, to put it
simply, we move from the absolute to the relative and from the unbounded
to the bounded. In this sense, in the EOTC, omni-non-linearity comes before
uni-multi-linearity, and thus the sphere comes before the line. The line,
then, is derived as the interrelation of two or more boundaries, and their
respective positions and implicit singularities (Euclidean points).
Transitive coordinates, recall, are points on a line, or on multiple
intersecting lines. This is because the definition of “dimension” in the
default pre-rational Cartesian system is a function of this transitive uni-
multi-linearity, which in turn is a function of the limits of interaction of
transitive lines. Rectilinearity, or perpendicularity is the balancing angle in

i
* See, Coordinates on the Immanent-Transcendent Axis, p142

Page | 351
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

the interaction or interfacing of two transitive-axes or lines. It is the angle of


orthogonality, or independence, between the two axes. These two
rectilinear lines then form an indefinitely extending transitive plane, and the
next interface is the orthogonality and perpendicularity between this plane
and another transitive-axis or line. This then brings us to the limits of linear
orthogonality in the three linear dimensions of the Cartesian system. Being
derived from linearity itself, then, the axiom of perpendicularity implicit in
the orthodox notion of dimension and its explicit Cartesian coordinate
system, is an inherent function of the default (transcended-and-included)
transitivity (and countable infinity) of the primitive level of number and
operation in our nondual-rational embryogenesis of mathematics.
Each of the first three dimensions of the default trans-biased and pre-
rationali* Cartesian system is defined as orthogonal or 90 angular degrees
from the others. And given that this ultimately arbitrary dimensioning
system forms the default conceptioning of dimension itself in orthodox
mathematics, thus our number-system itself is mapped in accordance to this
dimensioning system, in the interface between arithmetic and geometry. In
this particularly pre-rational (transitive-centric) system, then, the “real
numbers” form the full exploration of the Cartesian axes, mapping the
continuum of all rational and irrational numbers. This (ultimately arbitrary)
rectilinearity gives the Cartesian system, and the real numbers which are
mapped to it, a spatial or geometrical limit at three dimensions or axes.
Therefore the imaginary axis, being a 4th dimension to the 3D system, can
only unfold outside of the (pre-rational) axioms of geometrical
perpendicularity mapped to the continuum of the reals, and therefore only
in the imaginary land of abstract, “unreal” symbol manipulations and
machinations, with no intrinsic and consistent geometrical or modelable
correlation to the first three dimensions; i.e. abstract concept divorced from
embodied percept.

Imaginary numbers are defined at Steven Wolfram’s online “MathWorld” as


(my emphasis) “a complex number that has zero real part. An imaginary
number can therefore be written as a real number multiplied by the
‘imaginary unit’ i,” ii¥ equal to the square root of -1. So, with the imaginary
numbers we get a new axis and unit-identity to which all imaginary numbers
are multiplied.

The Wikipedia article on imaginary numbers states (my emphasis):

i
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
ii¥
http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ImaginaryNumber.html

Page | 352
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Geometrically, imaginary numbers are found on the vertical axis of the


complex number plane, allowing them to be presented orthogonal to the
real axis.
This systematic orthogonality is an ad hoc perpendicularity, however,
allowing the mere semblance of geometrical or modelable consistency. In
this visualization, the entire self-consistency of the intrinsic perpendicularity
and geometry of the volumetric space of the continuum of the Reals must
first be abandoned and then artificially collapsed into a line or a plane, and
the implicit axiom of perpendicularity once again brought into play after-the-
fact, and arbitrarily to model the implicit orthogonality of the fourth and
extra axis. See Figure 39 , below [my emphasis].
One way of viewing imaginary numbers is to consider a standard
number line, positively increasing in magnitude to the right, and
negatively increasing in magnitude to the left. At 0 on this x-axis, draw a y-
axis with “positive” direction going up; “positive” imaginary numbers
then “increase” in magnitude upwards, and “negative” imaginary numbers
“decrease” in magnitude downwards. This vertical axis is often called the
“imaginary axis” ….
In this model, multiplication by − 1 corresponds to a rotation of 180
degrees about the origin. Multiplication by i corresponds to a 90-degree
rotation in the “positive” direction (i.e. counter-clockwise), and the
equation i2 = − 1 is interpreted as saying that if we apply 2 90-degree
rotations about the origin, the net result is a single 180-degree rotation.

Page | 353
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 39: Imagining the Imaginary axis:


The orthogonality of the imaginary axis has no intrinsic rectilinear geometrical
relation to the continuum of the reals, and so after the rectilinearity of the
volumetric continuum of the Reals has reached its limits at three dimensions the
perpendicularity of the imaginary axis must be artificially ad hoc added on after the
continuum of the Reals has been collapsed to a line or plane and the axiom of
perpendicularity once again, arbitrarily, brought into play, to give an ad hoc
consistency to the rectilinear system , with its geometrical limits at three dimensions .

(image from Stephen Wolfram’s Mathworld )

This symbolic interface is the imaginary number system, which has no


intrinsically consistent rectilinear metaphor or spatial/volumetric
conceptuality to explain its existence and function at the percept-level, but
must exist because of the need for four-dimensional parameters in scientific
modeling as well as the intrinsic ambiguities and freedoms of the interface
between the transitive and I/T axes. This axis, visualized in this ad hoc
“imaginary” sense, is the vestige of the limits of the transitivity of the default
Cartesian/Euclidean system in its aborted transcension-and-inclusion of the
newly accessed uncountable I/T axis of the mult/div and power/root levels,
and their respective rational and irrational number systems. As Bucky says:
Perpendicularity (90-degreeness) uniquely characterizes the limit of
three-dimensionality. Equiangularity (60-degreeness) uniquely
characterizes the limits of four-dimensional systems.
If we want a four-dimensional geometrical and modelable system, then we
must redefine dimension and orthogonality away from 90-degreeness.


http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ImaginaryAxis.html

Page | 354
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

There is nothing intrinsic to the fourth dimension of the imaginary axis


that says it must orient 90 degrees from the axis of the reals, except that
dimensional orthogonality in the system is already defined in terms of
perpendicularity, which has already reached its limit at three geometrical or
modelable dimensions. Nor, for that matter, is there anything intrinsic to the
numbers themselves that says they must be mapped to a rectilinear system.
The implicit axiom of perpendicularity itself is what excluded coherent and
conceptual four-dimensionality from standard geometrical modeling in the
first place, and it is applied only arbitrarily and after-the-fact in the ad hoc
attempt to self-consistently imagine the imaginary axis in the perpendicular
geometry of the transitive, pre-rationality-based Cartesian system.
In Fuller’s Synergetic Geometry—which
has no initial or default transitive-axis, nor
any implicit axiom of perpendicularity tied
to its notion of dimension, but begins and
ends with transitivity derived and
integrated into the I/T axis—there is no
need for any ad hoc imaginary axis. This is
because the fourth power is entirely
conceptual and modelable based not on
transitive linearity and its 2nd power
interfacing in the implicit axiom of
perpendicularity (two axes crossing in
angular symmetry), but on the limits of
spheres in omni-economical sphere packing, Figure 40: Fuller’s 4-D Logo:
with its primary polyhedron (the Fuller’s early-adopted symbol
tetrahedron, composed of four planes, for his four-dimensional
oriented in four equi-angular lines or geometry.
dimensions from each other) dividing
Universe into the first system—as boundary between the within and
without—giving us simultaneously a priori volumetric extension and the
four omni-symmetric planes and axes of the tetrahedron as the basis for
Fuller’s intrinsically four-dimensional geometrical system.
Because the I/T axis is the primary axis in Fuller’s Synergetic
Geometry—with the first dimension defining the scale of the unit sphere,
unfolding the aspect of extension in the very transition from the absolute
scope to the relative in the Cycle of Unity—his model is intrinsically rational,
based in the axis inherent to the Rational numbers themselves, but
transcending-and-including the pre-rational transitive-axis in the linearity of
each of the omni-symmetrical lines of the tetrahedron, and deriving the
cubic rectilinear grid at a higher level in the system. And because of this
inherent rationality, and the absence or transcendence of the default trans-
biased and pre-rational Cartesian system—cubic grids being derived at a
higher level in the system—there is no problematic transition at the
interface between three and four dimensionality in the system of numbers
Page | 355
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

mapped to Synergetic Geometry. Synergetic Geometry is inherently four-


dimensional and so the “imaginary axis,” with its ad hoc implicit axiom of
perpendicularity, is no longer needed. From this vantage point, the term
“imaginary” is vestigial, so it drops off.
Fuller makes it clear in Synergetics that it is ultimately arbitrary that we
associate the number system with rectilinear geometry and the Cartesian
coordinate system. The most common association comes in, perhaps, at the
level of powers and exponentiation with the notion of 2nd powering as
“squaring” and 3rd powering as “cubing.” For example, a2 is called the square
of a because the area of a square with side-length a is a2, and similarly, a3 is
called the cube, because the volume of a cube with side-length a is a3. But
one of Fuller’s first mathematical discoveries was that the same is true of
triangles and tetrahedra. See Figure 41, below.

Fuller says, in Synergetics [[my comments]]:


[990.02] All scientists as yet say “X squared,” when they encounter the
expression “X2,” and “X cubed,” when they encounter “X3” But the number
of squares enclosed by equimodule-edged subdivisions of large gridded
squares is the same as the number of triangles enclosed by equimodule-
edged subdivisions of large gridded triangles. This remains true
regardless of the grid frequency, except that the triangular grids take up
less space. Thus we may say “triangling” instead of “squaring” and arrive
at identical arithmetic results, but with more economical geometrical and
spatial results.
Corresponding large, symmetrical agglomerations of cubes or
tetrahedra of equimodular subdivisions of their edges or faces
demonstrate the same rate of third-power progression in their
symmetrical growth (1, 8, 27, 64, etc.). This is also true when divided into
small tetrahedral components for each large tetrahedron or in terms of
small cubical components of each large cube. So we may also say
“tetrahedroning” instead of “cubing” with the same arithmetical but more
economical geometrical and spatial results.
We may now say “one to the second power equals one,” and identify
that arithmetic with the triangle as the geometrical unit. Two to the
second power equals four: four triangles. And nine triangles and 16
triangles, and so forth. Nature needs only triangles to identify arithmetical
“powering” for the self-multiplication of numbers. Every square consists
of two triangles. Therefore, “triangling” is twice as efficient as “squaring.”
This is what nature does because the triangle is the only structure [[only
triangles are self-stabilizing, thus their ubiquitous use in structural
engineering]]. If we wish to learn how nature always operates in the most
economical ways, we must give up “squaring” and learn to say
“triangling,” or use the more generalized “powering.”

Page | 356
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

Figure 41: Triangular vs. Rectangular Accounting:


Adapted from Fuller’s Figure 990.01 in his Synergetics.

At this point it is clear that powering or exponentiation—and the system


of number and operation itself—is not intrinsically rectilinear or cubic, and
also that, according to Fuller’s view, rectilinear analogs for 2nd and 3rd
powering are sub-optimal, relative to his Synergetic Geometry. Indeed
William Lauritzen, in his article Nature’s Numbers and in his “gravity-
generated numbers” gives us a triangular multiplication table (adapted in
Figure 42, below) which fully replaces the function of the traditional square
table, but in less space. Lauritzen, a math professor, tells his students, as
would Bucky, that it is inaccurate to say “squaring” for second powering.
Squaring should indeed be reserved for operations in geometry that
intrinsically deal with squares. Powering is not such a case.

Page | 357
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 42: Triangular Multiplication Table:


i
This figure was adapted from William Lauritzen’s “gravity-generated numbers.” To use
this table, merely find the apex of the equilateral triangle between the two numbers
you wish to multiply. One of the advantages of this table is that you need only one
row of digits by which to multiply. Each number is multiplied by another number (or
itself) from the same set.

One of the advantages of this table is that you need only one row of digits by
which to multiply. Each number is multiplied by another number (or itself)
from the same set. Indeed, in this way, it becomes instantly recognizable
that powering is a numerical recursion or tautology of sorts, because you
don’t need two different versions of the same number by which to multiply,

i
Lauritzen’s main row went from 0-9, but I thought the zero row was a bit boring and useless:
0000000000

Page | 358
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

but only that number by itself. And further, this shows that even if
multiplication is a doubling that takes us into the domain of the plane (as
discussed in Multiplication Through Division), then by no means is this plane
inherently square, or rectilinear. Indeed, as we will see, there are very
strong structural reasons to consider that the triangle, not the square, is
inherently planar, mainly because three vertices is the minimum needed for
any plane, and also that the triangle is the only polygon with inherent
structural stability. Another clear and intuitive example of this distinction—
where triangling and tetrahedroning is more fundamental and accurate than
squaring as a geometrical instantiation of the self-multiplication of
numbers—can be seen in the fact that distortions of the squared grid always
produce sub-squares of different shape and unequal area, whereas those of
the triangle grid are always exactly the same shape and always the same size
in relation to the parent shape. See Figure 43, below, also adapted from
Fuller’s own diagram.

Figure 43: Triangular vs. Quadrangular Accounting (Uniformity):


Adapted from Fuller’s Figure 990.01 in his Synergetics. Here we can see that the
triangular grid maintains intra-quantitative integrity in its distortions (its parts and
sub-parts all maintain their original self-identical shapes and power relationships)
whereas the cubic grid, when you move even a single one of its points, disrupts its
internal relationships, its shapes becoming dissimilar and its areas unequal.
Furthermore, unless the displacement of the point is restricted to the plane of the grid,
the grid itself will become non-planar, unlike the triangle framed grid, which can only
and always form a plane.

Fuller says [[my comments and emphases]]:


990.04 There is another very trustworthy characteristic of synergetic
accounting. If we prospectively look at any quadrilateral figure that does
not have equal edges, and if we bisect and interconnect those mid-edges,

Page | 359
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

we always produce four dissimilar quadrangles. But when we bisect and


interconnect the mid-edges of any arbitrary triangle__equilateral,
isosceles, or scalene__four smaller similar and equisized triangles will
always result. There is no way we can either bisect or uniformly subdivide
and then interconnect all the edge division points of any symmetrical or
asymmetrical triangle and not come out with omni-identical triangular
subdivisions. [[Conversely]] There is no way we can uniformly subdivide
and interconnect the edge division points of any asymmetrical
quadrangle (or any other different-edge-length polygons) and produce
omnisimilar polygonal subdivisions. Triangling is not only more
economical; it is always reliable. These characteristics are not
available in quadrangular or orthogonal accounting.
This problem and distinction is well-known in computer-aided geometric or
polygonal modeling, where sculpting in “quads” readily produces inherently
non-planar polygons which can cause problems later on, whereas triangle
polygons always, and can only be planar, no matter what the arrangement of
their vertices are.

Instead of the purely representational implicit axiom of perpendicularity


and the Cartesian coordinate system, which is designed merely to locate and
represent a point in volumetric space, Fuller takes a much more structural
and grounded approach to his conceptuality and representation, solidly
reaching the intrinsic four-dimensionality of structural relation from many
different angles.
For example, if you take three sturdy rods and tie their ends together
securely with a loose bit of rope or elastic, forming a triangle, the structure
will be sturdy and not deform. Do the same with the four rods of a square
and you get a wobbly mess. Build a cube out of those wobbly squares and it
doesn’t get any stronger, but collapses on the floor. You can build a
tetrahedron out of the tied-together triangles, however, and it will stand
strong of its own accord. This is essentially why “the triangle is the only
structure in Universe,” as Bucky would say.
Four dimensionality can be reached purely representationally as well
based on the relations between locations, points or event-stars, as Bucky
called them. The first event-star defines only itself. Add another one and
you get the first relation, the line, or vector. Add a third event star and you
define a plane between them, and no matter where you move each of them,
they can only define that plane. When you add a fourth event-star, however,
it inherently adds the dimension (or axis of freedom) of volume, because if
any one of them is at all out of line with the plane intrinsically defined by
interrelation of the other three, then their relations instantly define a
volume, the tetrahedron, dividing a within from a without. This is the
volume intrinsic to the four points of the tetrahedron, which—as the first

Page | 360
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

structure to enclose an inside from an outside—is “the prime structural


system in Universe”—the simplest closed volumetric form made exclusively
out of the prime structural element; triangles. See Figure 44, below.

Figure 44: 4-D Event-Stars:


The first event-star defines a point, a location. Adding the second event -star defines a
relation, a line between two points. Add the third star and they can but define a
plane, no matter where they are placed. Only with the fourth do we get a volumetric
relation between the points, and if the fourth star is misplaced from the plane of the
other three (which is infinitely probable in the infinite thinness which defines the
plane), then we instantly have a relation of volume. So we see that planarity is
inherently triangular and volumetricity is inherently tetrahedral.

Another example of the intrinsic four-dimensionality of structural relation


involves the closest packing of spheres—our prime non-structural system in
Universe as the first-dimension and aspect interface between immanence
and transcendence—from which all of Synergetic geometry is ultimately
derived. Similar to the above event-star model, but using expanded spheres,
we add them up and see what happens—this time, however, in terms of
degrees of freedom of rotation.
A single sphere floating in space is free to rotate in any direction. Add a
second one touching the first and, like two gears, they must rotate in
tandem, each on the same plane as the other. Add a third touching sphere
and they are constrained to rotate together inward or outward, involuting or
evoluting along a line running through their middle. See Figure 45, below.
But again, when you add that fourth sphere, forming the sphere-packing
version of the tetrahedron, suddenly the touching spheres can no longer
rotate.

Page | 361
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 45: 4-D Event-Spheres:


Adapted from Fig. 411.05, from Synergetics. “Four Spheres Lock as Tetrahedron:”

A: “A single sphere is free to rotate in any direction. ”


B: “Two tangent spheres although free to rotate in any direction must do so
cooperatively.”
C: “Three spheres can rotate cooperatively only about respective axes which
are parallel to the edges of the equilateral triangle defined by joining the
sphere centers, i.e. each sphere rotates toward the center of the tri angle.”
D: “Four spheres lock together. No rotation is possible, making the minimum
stable closest-packed-sphere system: the tetrahedron.”

Another convergence on the inherent four-dimensionality of structural


relation is seen in the investigation of what it takes to restrain one sphere in
space by means of tension strings. Take a sphere floating in space and tie a
string to it. The sphere is constrained to the limits of the string, but it is free
to move anywhere within a larger sphere defined by that constraint as
radius. See, below. Now add a second restraint on the other side of the
sphere and pull taut in the opposite direction. The sphere is now free to
move only in a plane or disc defined by the tautness and limits of those two

Page | 362
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

first constraints. Now add a third constraint, forming a triangle and the
sphere is only free to move in a line through the center of that triangle. Add
one more constraint, a fourth, forming the frame of a tetrahedron, and
suddenly the sphere can’t displace at all.

Figure 46: 4-D Restraints: “Four Vectors of Restraint Define Minimum System ”:
Adapted from Fig. 401.01, of Synergetics. “Investigation of the requirements for a
minimum system.”

A: “One vector of restraint allows ball to define complete sphere…” a volume


B:“Two vectors: a plane…”
C: “Three vectors: a line...”
D: “Four vectors: a point—no displacement…”

So from several different empirical, experiential and modelable methods we


can see that there seems to be an intrinsic four-dimensionality to structural
relation itself, which would give an implicit reasoning for the four-
dimensional accounting discovered by scientists and only tacked on ad hoc
and after-the-fact to the Cartesian rectilinear geometric system as the
imaginary axis. Conversely, the three-dimensionality of the Cartesian
system seems to be merely the simplest number of dimensions required to
locate or represent a position in space, otherwise entirely free from
structural, physical and material considerations altogether. Perhaps, then,

Page | 363
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

as Deleuze might agree, the Cartesian System of representational relation is


a natural outgrowth of an age dominated by representational forces. The
question then, perhaps, becomes one of the value of structural vs.
representational geometrical accounting systems, as applied to our specific
needs.

But there is much more that needs to be added to our meta-paradigmatic


equation. Because Fuller’s system is intrinsically rational (based on the I/T
axis of the rational itself), and because it is based on structural relation and
therefore intrinsically four-dimensional, the interrelations among its parts
and generated geometries end in wholly rational, and often whole numbers,
which is not the case when starting with the cube as unity. Though we don’t
have the time or bandwidth to get fully into the pros and cons of this system,
I’ll quote a few sources on its behalf.

Kirby Urner says in his Synergetics on the Webi¥:


The four-sided tetrahedron is the simplest possible enclosure—which is
why mathematicians call it a “simplex”. … Given the status of the simplex
as “simplest space-enclosing network”, the decision to use its regular
form as a unit of volume makes some sense. As a consequence of this
decision, we obtain whole number volumes for other familiar shapes
(including for the cube). This aesthetically pleasing and streamlining
result provides additional reinforcement for those taking the time to learn
this alternative (yet logical) approach to spatial geometry.

Fuller’s editorial collaborator on Synergetics, Ed Applewhite, describes


Synergetic Geometry thus [[my comments]]:ii¥
Synergetics is Fuller’s name for the geometry he advanced based on the
patterns of energy that he saw in nature.
For him, geometry was a laboratory science with the touch and feel of
physical models—not rules out of a textbook. He started with models of
the closest packing of spheres. From that basic starting point he derived
triangles as the most economical relationship between events.
He did not start with Euclid’s lines in the sand or Descartes’ cubes and
square XYZ-coordinates. Fuller felt that the old classic approaches did not
describe the way nature actually behaves. For instance, Euclid’s lines
were thought to go off to infinity. Fuller says lines are vectors of energy
and he rejected the notion that anything physical could be extended
indefinitely.
Descartes cubes are unstable forms. For Fuller, the world is built of
stable, finite structures. His triangular coordination depends on


Biblio-note.
ii¥
http://bfi.org/node/560

Page | 364
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

tetrahedral models. … Four spheres close pack into a stable tetrahedron:


good. Eight spheres stack into an unstable cube: bad. His geometry hinges
on the tetrahedron, the simplest structural system with insideness and
outsideness: he advances it as the most economical way to measure space
and to account all physical (and metaphysical! [[thought]]) experience.
This is what he calls synergetics: an empirical mathematical system in
which geometry and number mesh without fractions. It gains its validity
not from classic abstractions but from the results of individual physical
experience. His two-volume work “Synergetics” has the subtitle:
Explorations in the Geometry of Thinking.

Amy C. Edmonson says in her A Fuller Explanation [[my comments]]:


Synergetics is the discipline hiding behind Fuller’s fantastic visions of a
sustainable future [[and indeed behind his fantastically successful
architectural innovations of the geodesic dome and octet truss.]]. These
reliable patterns were the source of his unshakable confidence in his
design-science philosophy, which—in short—upholds that innovative
application of the principles governing nature’s behavior can insure
ample life support for all humanity. While many people around the world
have been exposed to Fuller’s ideas and inventions, few have understood
or even been aware of the mathematical principles underlying the elegant
efficiency of structures such as the Octet Truss and geodesic dome.
Happily, these principles are easily accessible once you get into the spirit
of Fuller’s approach: synergetics is a “hands-on” branch of mathematics.
Edmonson continues quoting Fuller:
“The fact that 99 percent of humanity does not understand nature is the
prime reason for humanity’s failure to exercise its option to attain
universally sustainable physical success on this planet. The prime barrier
to humanity’s discovery and comprehension of nature is the obscurity of
the mathematical language of science. Fortunately, however, nature is not
using the strictly imaginary, awkward, and unrealistic coordinate system
adopted by and taught by present-day academic science. (000.125b)”
Nature is instead using the principles embodied in synergetics, which
thus provides the way to eradicate this lethal ignorance. Claiming to have
discovered no less than the mathematical system that describes the
coordination of physical and metaphysical phenomena alike—that is, of
both energy and thought—Fuller was urgent in his insistence that we
study these principles:

Fuller says in Synergetics:


990.05 The increasingly vast, comprehensive, and rational order of
arithmetical, geometrical, and vectorial coordination that we recognize as
synergetics can reduce the dichotomy, the chasm between the sciences
and the humanities, which occurred in the mid-nineteenth century when
science gave up models because the generalized case of exclusively three-
dimensional models did not seem to accommodate the scientists’ energy-

Page | 365
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

experiment discoveries. Now we suddenly find elegant field modelability


and conceptuality returning. We have learned that all local systems are
conceptual. Because science had a fixation on the “square,” the “cube,” and
the 90-degree angle as the exclusive forms of “unity,” most of its constants
are irrational. This is only because they entered nature’s structural
system by the wrong portal. If we use the cube as volumetric unity, the
tetrahedron and octahedron have irrational number volumes.
The “wrong portal”—what he famously called “the attic window”—as we
have discovered, is the transitive-axis and its multiple uni-directional axes
which map the transcendent in terms of the transitive (and the intensive in
terms of the oppositional) and fundamental linearity, entirely skipping over
the immanence within, and the VL-axis intrinsic to the rational numbers.
Fuller’s system, on the other hand, as we have seen, begins mensuration and
dimension on the I/T axis, deriving the cubic and transitive system at a
higher level, fully transcending-and-including it in the process. Because of
this, Fuller’s system manages to escape many of the irrational constants and
unattainable probabilities that plague the standard xyz model and its
“imaginary” uses and adaptations in the sciences.

Fuller continues later in Synergetics [my emphasis]:


Nature would use the tetrahedron as the module of subdivision because
nature has proven to the physicists and the other physical scientists that
she always chooses the most economic realization. Cubes require three
times as much Universe as do tetrahedra to demonstrate volumetric
content of systems because cubic identification with third-powering used
up three times as much volume as is available in Universe. As a result of
cubic mensuration science has had to invent such devices as
“probability” and “imaginary numbers.” Thus “squaring” and “cubing,”
instead of nature’s “triangling” and “tetrahedroning,” account for science’s
using mathematical tools that have no physical-model
demonstrability__ergo, are inherently “unscientific.” (986.067-9)
Fuller points out indeed that as a result of measuring its intrinsically four-
dimensional constants on the basis of a three-dimensional cubic grid, many
of the constants of science ended in irrational and imaginary numbers and
probabilities, instead of the rational and whole number constants derived
time and again in his Synergetic geometry.
Unfortunately, we cannot get more in depth into this fascinating system
of Synergetics, this work serving only in part as a meta-dimensional, meta-
mathematical or meta-paradigmatic interface between Synergetics and the
standard Cartesian system. Furthermore, it may indeed be the case that the
time is still not ripe (and it may never be) for a cultural transition to
Synergetics as a default dimensional/geometric/mensurational paradigm.
Synergetics may indeed be too robust and complex a foundation for the LCD
of humanity, as it now stands, even though Fuller thought (and maybe
correctly) that Synergetics would be perfect for five-year-olds, as Edmonson

Page | 366
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

claims. The point herein is to emphasize the contrast and distinction


between the two; to develop an inter-paradigmatic interface for facilitating a
more evolved discernment.

As might be expected, at this point in the holarchical embryogenesis of


mathematics—just like with the iopol reversal of both the default
agglomerative/transcendent operations (multiplication and addition) to
their new deglomerative/immanent operations (subtraction and division)
which generated a new function and class of number—the integers and
rationals, respectively—with the iopol reversal of the powering function into
the roots comes a new function and class of number, the irrationals. And
just as with the previous iopol-inverted operations, not every operation on
every number will break the closure of the previous number-set into the
new.

The Wikipedia article on irrational numbers states:


Hippasus discovered irrational numbers when trying to represent the
square root of 2 as a fraction (proof below). However Pythagoras believed
in the absoluteness of numbers, and could not accept the existence of
irrational numbers.
Pythagoras was right in the Intuitionist sensei that the irrationals are more
properly functions, rather than numbers. But the Rationals as well are also
generated by functions, and as Kronecker effectively said, are not merely
god-given numbers, but ratios between (transcended-and-included)
integers. But the integers themselves also are created by the function or
operation of subtraction, iopol reversing the iterative set-generating
function of counting by ones; the unit-identity.

i
Intuitionists, following Kronecker, see all numbers greater than the integers as functions.

Page | 367
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The article continues:


[Pythagoras] could not disprove their existence through logic, but his
beliefs would not accept the existence of irrational numbers and so, as
legend had it, he had Hippasus drowned. Theaetetus worked with other
quadratic irrationalities, but it wasn’t until Eudoxus developed a theory of
irrational ratios that Greek mathematicians accepted irrational numbers.
Euclid’s Elements Book 10 is dedicated to classification of irrational
magnitudes.
From earlier in the article we get a definition of irrational numbers as
follows:
…the irrational numbers are precisely those numbers whose expansion in
any given rational base (decimal, binary, etc) never ends and never enters
a periodic pattern. Almost all real numbers are irrational.i¥
So the key difference between the functions of number—and the polarities
and operations that generate them—prior to the power/root level and its
irrational numbers, is that the irrational numbers are operations that never
come to an end; they never rest on a final number. They are immanent
infinities opened by the fact that the power/root level is operating fully on
the Immanent/Transcendent axis and its uncountable infinity.ii
With the square roots of certain numbers, mathematicians have been
able to prove that the decimal expansions never repeat or terminate as the
number gets ever closer and closer approximated in relation to the
numerical identities transcended-and-included in the Rational numbers and
the real number-line. Irrational numbers are unbounded, in this sense, that
on the I/T axis, in the direction of immanence, they never terminate, yet they
are bounded in relation to the transitive number-line, because they are
found within certain limits thereof. Irrational numbers, then, are simply 3rd
order (modal or bounded) infinities, expressed only approximately, in
numerical form. The square root of both 2 and 10 are the common examples
of such irrational numbers.iii
Cantor himself noted that the irrational numbers are more properly
infinities, or “infinite numbers,” with his recognition of their affinity with his
transfinite numbers. As Richard Arthur writes in his article Leibniz and
Cantor on the Actual Infinite, quoting Cantor:


Wikipedia: irrational number: <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Irrational_numbers>
ii
Though it may indeed be the case, as Fuller seems to argue, that the frequency of our encounters
with mathematical irrationality (as well as probability) are a function of having “come in through the
attic window” of the transitive-axis and mapped all of number and reality to the perpendicular limits
thereof. The number pi, is a classic example, for Fuller.
iii
Open Question: What is the significance of the fact that the first two irrational numbers are the
square-roots of 2 and 10? Does it show the limits of a more rational, or immanent/transcendent,
base-nine system underlying the transitive base-ten, as Bucky intimated (e.g. “casting out nines”)?
What has this to do with the symmetrical Scheherazade numbers?

Page | 368
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION

“The transfinite numbers are in a certain sense new irrationalities, and in


my view the best method of defining the finite irrational numbers is quite
similar to, and I might even say in principle the same as, my method of
introducing transfinite numbers. One can say unconditionally: the
transfinite numbers stand or fall with the finite irrational numbers: they
are alike in their innermost nature, since both kinds are definitely
delimited forms or modifications of the actual infinite.”i¥
Indeed, in the nondual-rational view as well, the irrational numbers are
defined in the very same way as Cantor’s transfinites. Their difference is
mainly in their directionality: immanent vs. transcendent. Recall that we
defined the transfinite numbers as aspect infinities, or set-aspects (aspect
infinities abstracted out of The Infinite by set-generating algorithms), and
that the bounded or modal infinite is a specific type of aspect infinite dealing
with the immanent pole of the Immanent/Transcendent axis—an
encapsulated and immanent infinite number. They are immanent infinities
abstracted out of The Infinite as a function of the operation of rooting, with
second-order recursion breaking beyond the bounds of the stepwise
procedures of the countably infinite.

Arthur continues:
Here Cantor alludes to the fact that just as irrationals can be conceived as
limits of infinite sequences of rational numbers, so transfinite numbers
can be conceived as limits of infinite sequences of natural numbers, in
each case added in immediately after the sequence they limit. If one
rejects transfinites, what right has one to allow the extension of the
number system to include irrationals? A reluctance to jettison the theory
of the real line thus explains the widespread acceptance among modern
mathematicians of the Cantorian theory of the infinite.
In Interface Mathematics there is no jettisoning necessary of any of these
operations, but merely a reinterpretation in a more coherent, more evolved,
integral, and rational context. Rational numbers are, more properly,
functions of recursive (non-stepwise) division (rooting) or relation between
integers which, while opening up fully the uncountable infinity of
immanence, still give the finite and final result of a number as boundary or
precise location in the mathematical continuum unreachable by rational or
stepwise operations. Irrational numbers, on the other hand, are the
consequence of higher level functions or relations (i.e. the square-root
function with its “2nd tier” level inversion of the input/output polarity), that
fall between the transcended-and-included transitive limits of the rational
numbers. They are the “Dedekind cuts” in terms of limits of transitive
representation on the real number-line into decimals or binaries, which give
actual infinities (unbounded answers), not final numbers as boundaries.


Cantor, 1887-8

Page | 369
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The fact that the irrational numbers give actual infinite (unbounded) results
demonstrates that the power/root level is operating fully (if not optimally,
coming from the aborted rationality of the default Cartesian system) on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, and has fully opened to the uncountable
immanent infinite neglected by the trans-bias of default agglomerative or
stepwise transcendent operation. Thus, like Cantor’s “transfinite numbers,”
irrational numbers are aspects of the infinite interfacing with the finite
function that generated the number; they are bounded aspect infinities, not
numbers as finite boundaries. As modal aspect infinities, they are bounded
only with respect to the transitive axis, and unbounded in the immanent
direction, identically opposite to Cantor’s transcendently unbounded infinite
numbers. As Deleuze says, in The Fold:
The irrational number implies the descent of a circular arc on the straight
line of rational points, and exposes the latter as a false infinity, a simple
undefinite that includes an infinity of lacunae: that is why the continuous
is a labyrinth that cannot be represented by a straight line.
Thus given that the “secret of the rational” is the positive infinite of the
immanent (as opposed to the regressive disaster of the medieval notion of
the infinite), the “irrational numbers” are “essentially” and deeply rational.
Perhaps undeniably, if we are allowing infinities to be numbers, as we are in
this post-Cantor world, then the “irrational numbers” are more correctly
“trans-rational” or “immanent infinite-numbers”—the mathematical
instances of the bounded or immanent aspects of The Infinite. And so, here
we find yet again a transcendent-bias in that immanent, boundless numbers
are considered non-rational, or “irrational” and transcendent infinite
numbers are naturally just infinite numbers. In other words, there is a ready
place for the transcendent forms of the infinite, but the immanent
manifestations, in this transcendent-biased pre-rational system, have no
place except in the negative (irrational) form. The positive infinity of the
secret of the rational has yet no home in the pre-rational, representational
system.

Page | 370
Page | 371
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Interface Mathematics, as a holarchical embryogenesis of number and


operation (identity and relation, noun and verb), can be viewed in several
different ways. We have already seen the Onion of Operations graphic above
(p347), showing the general holarchy of operations, and this can be modified
to include the two main VL-axes in the VCS and the transition between them
as number and operation move through the trans-bias (yang-bias) and into
the operationalization of immanence (yin) from which the unit-closure
tacitly commenced in the first place (recall our Cycle of Unity).
From the viewpoint of operation, we can trace the movement from the
origin of mathematics—the first boundary from the unbounded, or the ‘one’
from the ‘ONE’—into the transitive axis or plane of addition/subtraction,
then through the transition onto the I/T axis with the mathematical ratio
and its violation of unit-closure, and then fully onto the I/T axis with its
operationalization of the prior polarities in the explicit rules of the
exponents, opening up finally from the trans-bias to the immanent infinities
of the “irrational numbers.” See Figure 47, below.
Note that in the inset of the diagram, we can see that the evolution of
number is, in a sense, overcoming the transcendent bias, in that number only
comes to new function in the direction of immanence, as it breaks closure
with subtraction, then division and then finally with rooting. (Immanence is
the feminine principle, or yin, recall, so naturally we can see that number
itself is “given birth” to or emergent from yin—in critical and necessary
interaction with the dominant and dominating forces of yang.) This is how
the rational levels and beyond function in the context of the trans-biased,
pre-rational transitivity embodied most elegantly in the Cartesian
coordinate system as the default geometry for our conception of number,
leaving the 4th dimension (intrinsic to the rational mensuration of science)
as merely a vestigial, imaginary transitive-axis, stuck ad hoc by an outmoded
implicit axiom of perpendicularity to the collapsed coherency of the pre-
rational geometrical system.

Page | 372
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

Figure 47: The Holarchical Evolution of Number and Operation in the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System:
Following from the main VCS diagram —with transitive-planes visualized as orthogonal
to the I/T axis—addition and subtraction begin on such a transitive -plane.
Multiplication/division begin to transition onto the I/T axis, moving toward parallel
with it, and the power/root level operates fully on the I/T axis. Note the “vestigial”
transitive-axis of the imaginary. In the transitive, pre -rational space of the Cartesian
th
system, the 4 dimension—intrinsic to rational dimensioning itself (see Fuller ’s
Synergetics)—has no geometrical grounding. In Synergetic geometry, with its explicit
grounding in the rational I/T axis, there is no need for this vestigial transitive -
/perpendicular axis, so it drops off. Inset: The evolutionary path of number is outlined
as it moves from the default transitive mapping of transcendence in additive
agglomeration and the naturals, into the successive violations of closure in the
input/output polarity (iopol) inversions of the corresponding levels of agglomerative
recursion. From the naturals, the iopol is inverted (initially toward deglomeration) to
give us the integers and then the iopol of the operation of multiplication is inverted to
give us the rationals, following which the iopol of powering is inverted to give us the
irrational square-roots.

Page | 373
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This same basic evolutionary movement and general form can also be
traced, and more accurately so, as a three-dimensional vector along with the
dimension of time (see Figure 48-A, below); 1) from the undifferentiated
ONE-ALL into the ONE-one I/T uni-axis and then 2) quickly shunting into the
orthogonal laws and rules of transitivity mapped to transcendence (the
trans-trans-bias), and then 3) only through the holarchical embryogenesis of
function and identity (operation and number) moving steadily (emerging
and transcending) toward operation again on the originary I/T axis.
In Nondual Rationalism, recall, there is a shift from the regressive pre-
rational notion of infinity (which sees immanence, yin or Emptiness as a
foundational disaster), to an affirmation of a “deep infinity” (as M.C. Escher
intuits it) or, as Deleuze calls it, a positive infinity as the “secret of the
rational.” The main axis in this core diagram (diagram A) represents this
“positive infinity,” operationalized in the VCS as the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. In the animated version on the SpinbitZ
website (http://www.spinbitz.net/) there are points of light moving in both
immanent and transcendent directions from the central transitive plane,
representing the directions of transcendence and immanence operating
simultaneously in transcendence or evolution. In the static version, this
polar, or bi-directional evolutionary motion is denoted by the spiraling
arrows.
Note that the shape of the spiral isn’t important for the evolution itself,
and is a drastic generalization (largely for aesthetic purposes) in an already
vastly over-simplified linearity. In mathematics, for example, the shape of
the emergent curve would have an underlying quantized saw-tooth wave
pattern, as the number set-closures are successively violated by the
corresponding iopol inversions of the new operations—and number and
operation ratchet themselves into higher and higher functions in tandem, as
we will see below.
In psychological or spiritual development, as well, the shape would have
all sorts of stops and starts, different velocities and directions and various
paths running simultaneously as the diverse lines of intelligence evolve at
different rates, from a range of starting places, through many levels and
plateaus of being.

Page | 374
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

A. B.

Figure 48: SpinbitZ Diagram, Primal Form:


A: In this central diagram in SpinbitZ we see the VCS, as it generally applies to all forms
of vision-logic-level percept-concept in NDR, from philosophy to mathematics to
epistemology. The key elements in this diagram are as follows (see diagram B, for
reference to the VL-axes and planes of the VSC underlying the forms of diagram A).
Following the red line as it moves in both directions orthogonal from the central I/T
axis, we begin in the transitive rules and forces of opposition (e.g. the positive and
negative signs of addition, or the dualisms and platonic absolutized categories of pre -
rational, pre-pulverized philosophy). From there the embryogenesis of the concept
unfolds, moving explicitly in the transitive mappi ng of transcendence, but
simultaneously also (if tacitly, through successive iopol inversions, e.g.) in the
immanent direction toward ever higher, wider and deeper functioning on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis.

This core SpinbitZ diagram, then, basically acknowledges this positive


infinity at the heart of rationalism (opened up in the “violation” of unit-
closure with the mathematical ratio) and shows the nonduality or polarity of
immanence in transcendence. It renders visually and very generally the
realization that evolution itself—including the evolution of mathematics,
science, philosophy, consciousness, art and even spirituality—begins on an
emergent (transcendent) “transitive plane” of existence, oriented by default
in the “orthogonal” direction to this positive infinity and uncountable I/T

Page | 375
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

axis. These transitive planes unfold or emerge from the I/T axis as already
transcendent forms or levels of reality, but forms and operations thereupon
are oriented and configured by default—due to the trans-bias and the
transitive mapping of transcendence—to instantly move away from it,
conceptually, or representationally. The forms and operations are initially
(and very generally) blind to the I/T axis (and immanence in general)
because it is pre-representational and pre-operational and the “fitness
function” of evolution is initially invested in the mapping and
operationalization of transcendence via the transitive forms and forces of
categorical identity and opposition; rudimentary polarization into simplistic
terminals and opposites.
In philosophy, this initial transitivity corresponds to such things as
“essentialism,” dualism or foundationalism—basically superficial and
relative-bound absolutized, categorical thinking. Starting with the unit-
closure of the personal identity and the platonic forms and absolutized
categories, as well the transitive forms of the various foundationalisms and
dualisms, we then move onto the I/T axis with the pulverizing of the closure
of the self-identity of the forms—in the acategorical imperative of the key
rationalists (and the nondualists long before them)—opening up the
Emptiness of the positive infinity of the rational to the univocal unity of the
ONE-ALL and its Immanent/Transcendent axis.
In consciousness, the epistemic (representation) and spirituality, the
transitive corresponds first to egoism (and the Cartesian cogito-interface),
then, moving outward (transitively and transcendently) as the self-boundary
expands, we move simultaneously up the spiral (transcendence). But,
according to the principle of immanence in transcendence and the positive
infinity, as evolution progresses, or as transcendence moves forward, it
begins to turn from the transitive mapping of transcendence and move
closer and closer, full-circle, back to its origin (the integral capacity) on the
I/T axis and hence toward immanence, the “deep infinity,” at the same time.
In meditation itself, the goal is indeed to get closer and closer to this axis
whose temporal aspect, recall, is the “eternal NOW,” Spinoza’s sub specie
aeternitatis, participating in eternity in the instantaneous “intellectual love
of God.” (See Figure 10, repeated below from p191.) This goal is the “flat-
lining” of living in the moment, free from the turbulence of the categorical
forms of memory and anticipation, the illusions of the past and the future,
often absolutized with disastrous effect.

Page | 376
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

Figure 10: Time Tree: Figure repeated from Univocity and the Eternal NOW (p191)

In the evolution of science we see this move toward immanence in


transcendence in the simultaneous expansion of the empirical/theoretical
sphere of the macro and the micro, where curiously we always seem to sit
right in the middle, with meta-galactic voids on one side and “Planck’s
constant” almost exactly equidistantly on the other—in orders of magnitude.

Page | 377
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This path in the physical sphere moves from the unit-closure of atoms, into
the transitive laws of molecular agglomeration, into the higher complexities
of intelligent evolution, into primitive cultures with tool-making from vastly
agglomerated numbers of unit-atoms.
Note also, that only with trans-rationality, in its techno-evolutionary
form, does evolution begin to break the unit-closure of the atom and move
more fully into immanence and transcendence simultaneously in their
explorations and manipulations of the micro and macro cosmos. Beneath
the level of the atom, we have an explosion of more and more “particles,”
which are more like wave resonances, constantly changing form into other
particles and most with very short-lived existences. These particles as
resonances are more properly seen as functions of the forces of intensity,
having not coalesced into singular, nucleated form (finite unities) in
opposition to others. These resonances have no self-consistent, self-
maintaining form and identity of their own (no Leibnizian “principle of
unity” and no Spinozan homeostatic relative essence), but come into being
as fleeting resonances, dissonances and harmonics from very specific
interactions and environments often in the break-down of particles with
real, nucleated, unitary identity, such as the proton or neutron.
The forces of opposition begin only when there is unit-closure into the
emergent, self-stabilizing forms of finite unity. This is when the Spinozistic
homeostatic, strange-attractor notion of “essence” and the Leibnizian
emergent “principle of unity” come into play.

Also, in the animated version of the core SpinbitZ diagram (spinbitz.net),


there are other simultaneously resonating meanings which emerge
depending on your perspective in the 3D space in which it is modeled and
rendered.
From the main point of view—shown in the main animated diagram on
spinbitz.net, and above—if you watch the shape of the spinning curve, you
see that it continuously morphs, oscillating between an S and a Z. The polar
capitalization in the title, SpinbitZ, recall, stands for the interface between
the philosophies of Spinoza and Leibnitz (more commonly called Leibniz),
the two main rationalists in Nondual Rationalism. The symbiotic polarity
found between their work is embodied in SpinbitZ, and in this animation
morphing between the curvilinear S and the rigid pointy Z, denoting the
polarity and triune-integration of their continuous and the discrete aspects
of the absolute, respectively. See Figure 49, below.

Page | 378
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

Figure 49: SpinbitZ <– S-Z –> :


As it rotates, the curve of the animated SpinbitZ diagram morphs, oscillating between
the S and Z, of Spinoza and leibniZ, as seen from the default perspective just above the
central plane.

Furthermore, another, more playful meaning is found in the core SpinbitZ


diagram, but this time based on a different perspective of the same
volumetrically extended (“3D”) form. At the top of the SpinbitZ web page, on
either side, it shows a bottom view of the same spiraling curve as it morphs,
oscillating between a yin-yang sign and an infinity sign or lazy eight (Figure
50-A and -B, respectively). This shows the inherent morphological similarity
between the yin-yang and the lazy eight, symbolizing the polarity
(nonduality) in the positive infinity of Nondual Rationalism between the
absolute and the relative, or between Emptiness and form, essentially.

Figure 50: SpinbitZ Yin-Yeight:


The morphological unity between the yin -
yang and the lazy-eight in the core SpinbitZ
diagram, arising from different rotations of
the same 3D curve from a perspective
closer to the poles than to the central
transitive plane (below, or immanent to
the plane, in this case).

A. B.

Page | 379
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

We can also take a global look at this embryogenesis of mathematics from


the standpoint of number as it unfolds in function from new, recursive levels
of operation, particularly with the input/output polarity reversal of the
default agglomerative operations, addition, multiplication and powering.
See Figure 51, below.
Note that only the first agglomerative operation, addition, opens up a
new function of number (the Naturals and wholes), while every successive
new function of number emerges explicitly only with the iopol inversion of
the new agglomerative operation into deglomerative or immanent function
with the successive breakings of closure, such as that with the integers and
the operation of subtraction, as well as that with the Rationals and the
operation of division. In this sense, the symbiogenetic transcendent
ratcheting of number and operation can be seen as a reaction to the trans-
bias itself, as the mechanism with which it breaks new ground with every
new turn is always toward immanence, ending, finally, with the implicit
immanent singularities of the irrational numbers, breaking into full
immanent infinity itself through the function of rooting.
Recall our repeated inset from Figure 50, above, where the evolutionary
path of number is outlined as it moves from the default transitive mapping
of transcendence in additive agglomeration and the naturals, into the
successive violations of closure in the iopol inversions of the corresponding
levels of agglomerative recursion. An intuition generated with these two
curves in mind should get us closer to a visualization of the actual n-
dimensional structure.
Note also that both the irrationals and imaginaries break out into the
open with the level of roots, as it moves finally and fully onto the
uncountable I/T axis, breaking the bonds of the trans-bias and in the
process—in the default operational context of the extant pre-rational
Cartesian transitive rectilinear grid—the imaginary axis and many of the
prevailing irrational constants of physics and other sciences are seen as the
aftermath of this incomplete interface and transition, not yet fully
operationalizing the I/T axis intrinsic to the level of the rational and the
higher-level functions of number, such as division and rooting. Recall also
that the model of Synergetics was briefly introduced as an example of an
intrinsically rational and four-dimensional model—with a more fully
operationalized and integrated I/T axis—in contrast to the three-
dimensional, pre-rational Cartesian coordinate system. It may well be true
that there are other candidates, but these have yet to be seen by this author.

Page | 380
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

Figure 51: The Saw-tooth Curve of Iopol Inversion


in the Evolution of Number and Operation:
Note how the operations in this map move very
simply into higher and higher forms of recursion in
the transcendent direction (e.g. addition ->
multiplication -> powering), and that—with the
exception of the very first function of unit -
addition, generating the naturals —number is only
broken into new functions (breaking of closure )
with the move toward deglomeration and
immanence in the iopol reversal of the next new
level (e.g. subtraction generating the integers,
division generating the Rationals and rooting
generating the immanent singularities of the
irrationals). Contrast and compare this curve with
the repeated inset from Figure 47 above (p374),
for a more complete intuition as number and
operation work their way out from the d efault,
pre-rational trans-bias.

Page | 381
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Recall, that there are only two VL-axes in the Vision-Logic Coordinate
System. And recall also, from the section The Orthogonality of Inverses and
the Offset Origin-Identities (p341) that the origins and operational-identities
of each of the VL-axes are identical, and thus we call them origin-identities;
i.e. the additive identity is zero precisely because it is the origin (or center)
of the transitive-axis, and similarly, the multiplicative identity is one
precisely because it is the origin (or center) of the I/T axis.
Notice as well that the power/root level has no new origin-identity or
axis of its own, but appears to have simply integrated its use of the previous
two origin-identities and VL-axes. This integration can be seen in the fact
that graphed curves of powers (which have no transitive offsets), always go
through both zero and one. At the power/root level, recall, only the odd
integer powers of x reveal the identity line—the image of the trans-bias in
the transitive mapping of transcendence—as their basis. Also, there is an
infinite favoring of the intensive forces seen in the purely
agglomerative/intensive quadrant of the rational, non-integer powers
(expressible as roots) as well as in the multiplicative/agglomerative
absolute value line (reflecting off the x-axis back into y-positivity) as the
basis of the even integer powers. (Recall Figure 38, above, The Trans-Trans
Instability: p349.)
What then is the relation between these two VL-axes, their countable and
uncountable infinities, their origin-identities and their unities? i The
transitive and immanent/transcendent origin-identities, ‘zero’ and ‘one’
respectively, can be seen as symbiotic or interdependent (polar) functions of
one another in the interplay between the two VL-axes in the continuation of
the Cycle of Unity in the unfolding of mathematics into higher and deeper
levels of operation and number.
The I/T uni-axis (the ONE-one axis),ii* recall, is the pole between
uncountable infinity in its transcendent vs. immanent directions with

i
We’ll explore in great detail the interface and relation between the uncountable and countable
infinities of the two VL-axes in the section on Zeno’s paradoxes. See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning
and Triuning the Paradox, p432, and the subsection, Back to Zeno, p448.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 382
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

respect to a unitary position. In the very “center”i of these two endless omni-
directions is the arbitrarily defined interface and unit-magnitude—the
number ‘one’—the periapsis in our Orbit of Unity,ii* and the origin-identity
of the I/T axis of multiplication and division. In the first phase of this
unfolding of the cycle of origin-identities, the immanent pole of this Infinite
Unity is the origin and operational identity of the countable and stepwise
(agglomerative) transitive-axis as it converts the I/T interface into the finite
unity and primitive number one. This is the interface between the I/T and
transitive VL-axes, as this first boundary from the boundless is then both the
unity (or unit) of the transitive (additive), and the origin and operational-
identity (origin-identity) of the immanent/transcendent (multiplicative).
On the transitive axis, however, once
the unit has been defined for additive
operations, it is the absence of any
unit—our transitive-zero as negation—
which is the identity, thus bringing us
back (even if from a transitive
viewpoint) to the immanent pole of the
I/T axis as origin in the creation (and
inversely as the negation) of the first
unit. The rational zero as immanent-
positional aspect of The Infinite—
through the Principle of Absolute
Reversal, the Principle of Immanence in
Transcendence (yin in yang) and the
identity of opposites—then reflects into
its identical opposite, the ONE, our
Infinite Unity. This returns us full-
circle, dissolving the initial boundary-
division of relative polarity, our finite
unity, back into absolute or Infinite
Unity—dissolving the one (as the
interface of the ONE-one in the Cycle of
Unity) back into the ONE-ALL—and Figure 52: The Binary Cycle of
Origin-Identity and Unity:
dissolving our primitive number-as-
The unity of each axis (I/T and
boundary and dimension back into transitive) is the identity of the
infinite omni-non-dimensional other, and vice versa.
continuity. See Figure 52, right.

i
…every boundary is in the exact center of an infinite axis, whether it be that of the number-line or
that of infinite divisibility and the absolutely indivisible continuum. In the infinite, the “center is
everywhere and *the+ circumference nowhere.”
ii
* See, The Orbit of Unity, p260.

Page | 383
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The multiplicative identity and finite unity, “one,” originates from the
primary VL-axis of dimension and Infinite Unity (the I/T axis) as the first act
of dimensioning, whereas the additive identity “zero” dissolves the
boundaries of the unit-number and fades back into the implicit singularity of
the rational zero, reflecting through the PAR into Infinite Unity, completing
the circle, and triuning (or tuning) the polarity from Unity to finite-unit-
identity to Unity. The Unity of one level is the identity of the next, leading us
one into the other, between the finite and infinite forms of unity and identity.
The cycle is from unity to identity to unity. The unity of one level
becomes transcended-and-included as the identity of the next. But given
that there are only two VL-axes, two origin-identities and two unities, it
cycles in and out, off and on, from the absolute to the relative to the absolute;
from zero, to one and to zero again; and from I/T to transitive to I/T. But,
recall, when it is at zero, through the Principle of Absolute Reversal and
identity of opposites, it is at ONE, so it also cycles from ONE to one to ONE.
Our Cycle of Unity is our cycle of origin-identities, refracting into the prism
of the artifice of pure relation called Mathematics.
The immanent/transcendent and absolute unity is ONE, whose
immanent and operational pole is the rational zero. The transitive identity,
however, is also zero. In this sense, the transitive axis and relative scope
sees the ALL is ONE (in its immanent aspect) as “all is none”: the omni-non.
Within the relative scope of transitivity, the absolute or Infinite Unity is
invisible and inoperable, the cipher, the absence, our common notion of
emptiness, providing the inert identity of the transitive operations of
addition/subtraction. The Unity of the initial Immanent/Transcendent axis
is therefore the operational identity (or null) of the transitive axis which
transcends-and-includes it.
The transitive unity, that is derived in this process of unity-to-identity
conversion, is 1, which will be written as (1) to remind us that it represents a
volumetric, or spheroidal, bounded and finite unity. The rational or
multiplicative identity is also this same (1), which is now transcended-and-
included from the transitive unity as the solidus between the I and T of the
I/T axis. We will represent the rational identity herein as /(1) to remind us
that the transitive-unity (1) is transcended-and-included under the hidden
solidus of all rational and pre-rational numbers. Any numerical imbalance,
balanced on the point of origin, is still that original imbalance.
The immanent/transcendent or rational unity is the I/T axis itself, the
absolute or Infinite Unity, the unreachable ONE-ALL (ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE)
reached by way of the Principle of Absolute Reversal and the identity of
opposites. This Unity, in its transcendent form (inverted across the solidus
in the immanent position), can be represented by the infinity of division by
zero, the rational zero, or /0, which is numerically equal to ∞/1. Transitive
operation begins in converting immanent/transcendent Infinite Unity, ONE-
ALL, ∞/∞, or /0, to the transitive and finite unity, (1). And this coincides

Page | 384
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

with the conversion of the immanent/transcendent-unity ONE—


represented by the rational zero and the immanent pole—to the transitive
identity 0.
The power-/root-level, operating directly on the uncountable
Immanent/Transcendent axis, is “second-tier,” and integral. As such, it has
no new identity of its own, but has integrated both to a new functionality. At
this level the unity doesn’t become the new identity because we haven’t
moved onto a new VL-axis. Rather, the hidden or enfolded unit-identity
comes into a new functionality. The onion of operations comes into full
differentiated-and-integrated view at this 2nd tier. The dis-junctions
between the shifting of VL-axes come into con-junction and the onion of
polarities aligns its inputs and outputs into a new harmony in the full circle
between the uncountable infinity of the I/T axis, the countable infinity of the
transitive, and back again, but always breaking closure against the tide of the
trans-bias to gain its new identities. We’ll see the point of this cycle most
explicitly in the section on Zeno’s paradoxes.i*

We can see here again the primacy of the Immanent/Transcendent axis


(Fuller’s first dimension) and the primacy of radial and nuclear, convergent
and divergent (immanent/transcendent) over parallel (transitive) lines. We
can also see the dependence of the transitive and additive operations upon
the I/T axis as it returns through the cycle to its source. This whole cycle is a
function of the mapping of the immanent through the transitive axes,
breaking into new function against the trans-bias. We come to mathematics
from trans-biased agglomeration, and thus from the outside in. But through
the higher functions of multiplication-by-division, rational numbering, and
power laws, we are led—with each successive iopol inversion and breaking
of closure—back to the neglected source, the immanent-zero, reflecting
through the PAR and identity of opposites to the Infinite Unity of the ONE-
ALL.
Fuller clearly recognized this primacy of the hidden immanent, recall,
when he talks (in his historic 42 hour “thinking out-loud” session,
“Everything I Know”) about mankind having come in to mathematics and
dimensional/geometrical accounting through “the attic window” of cubic-
based geometry and trying to measure the front door based on the
dimensions of this odd little attic window.
We are agglomerative beings, fluid architectures of electro-chemical
reactions at the spherical surface or (I/T uni-axial) interface of a planet.
Thus we are born first into apparent transitivity and from there we find our
way to immanence in its higher resonances, which predated and prefigured
the flat-earth illusion of transitivity. Rectilinearity or perpendicularity is a

i
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 385
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

subset of the spherical, as a surface or interface effect of our spherical,


bounded and finite unity. This is why we so often confuse the immanent and
transitive axes, we always have to come down to the least common multiple
of human understanding, the “we” criterion for justification and collective
“truth.” We start from the outside and work inward. When we get there, in a
sense we have to turn the whole thing inside out to make sense of it.

Open Question: Can this binary cycle and interplay of origin-identities,


unities and VL-axes be seen in the properties of odd and even numbers, with
odds as one-of-a-kind entities and evens composed of identical sub-parts or
halves? We can see this cycle and the role of the odds and evens more
clearly, perhaps, in its interface with the asymmetries of multiplication by
like and unlike signs, the trans-trans instability, and the differences between
odd and even integers.

Page | 386
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

From the transcend-and-include vantage point of the second tier in our


vision-logic interface, we can take a fresh look at the holarchical unfolding of
number and operation through another visual interface, that of the graphs of
functions. This, then, will be the interfacing between two percept-based
interfaces; the graphs of functions and the holarchical model of Interface
Mathematics. In the true, nondual function of an interface, each component
sub-interface will inform or illumine the form and function of the other.
Through the concept of the function, we will take a closer look at our onion
of operations, as it unfolds through the power-root level and into the
exponential/logarithm level. Then we will employ the model of Interface
Mathematics to the understanding of graphs of functions and see how each
informs the other.

As we have seen, the transcend-and-include holarchy (embryogenesis of the


concept) of number and operation (as well as identity, origin and unity)
unfolds as a cycle, mirroring the cycle of integral transcendence, from pre-
operational immanence (or pre-cognitive emergence) into the transitive
mapping of transcendence, and against the current of the trans-bias to
return ultimately to the originary immanence (yin) in balance with
transcendence (yang). At the higher levels, the initial, undisclosed and
unrecognized pre-mathematical VL-axis of freedom (the I/T axis of initial
scale) becomes more and more operationalized in the integration of the
previous transcended-and-included levels. It moves from
immanent/transcendent ALL is ONE—with its nondual, pre-operational,
intensive and inter-expressive forces—to the first operations of transitive
oppositional positive/negative duality (absolutized platonic categories, unit-
identity, numerical identities, etc), and then progressively back to
operationalization of the nondual intensive forces of the rational and
power/root I/T axis with its hidden and implicit immanence.
This conceptual journey also moves from omni-non-dimensional and
uncountable ALL is ONE, through the I/T uni-axis interface (the omni-
symmetrically bounded (spherical) unit-identity) to the uni-/multi-
dimensionality and merely countable infinity of the agglomerative transitive
axis and then—with the breaking of unit-closure—transcending-and-
including into the operations of division/multiplication and finally back

Page | 387
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

home, full-circle, to the integration of the uncountable I/T and countable


transitive axes, but now fully operationalized as the power/root level with
its explicit singularities in the form of “irrational numbers,” and with the
remainder-axis of the imaginary.
In the transcendent direction, mathematical operations transcend and
include their predecessors in a simple self-complexifying holarchical loop of
recursion; taken in reverse, powering is recursive multiplication which is
recursive addition, which is dependent on the recursive agglomeration of
ones to form the set of digits (our mathematical titans) in the first place.
With each level of recursion, however, we find another level of operational
input/output polarity which can be inverted, and each time this occurs this
gives us a new level and function of number, breaking the closure of the
previous set and moving us into a new one, always closer and closer to an
operational return to the pre-operational and neglected immanence of the
I/T axis, against the default current of the trans-bias as seen in the identity-
line. This transcend-and-include motion we have seen simply with the rules
of the exponents where to operate on the base at one level, we use the
operations of the previous level. And with our Saw-tooth Curve of Iopol
Inversion (p381), above, we saw what this looks like in terms of in the
evolution of number and operation ever toward immanence, against the
trans-bias.

As we have seen,i* the juxtaposition of the graphs of the identity-line, y=x/1


and the “inverse-identity-line,” y=1/x, reveals the trans-bias in stark relief
(See Figure 26, repeated below, from p317). The infinity of integers on the
transitive axis contain the hidden or pre-fused division by the transitive unit
or “multiplicative” (rational) operational- and origin-identity. Thus they are
closed through unity, in the immanent direction, i.e. “quantized” into unit
values by the inverse unitary division implicit in the unfolding multiplication
(closure property of the integers, and the numerical identities transcended-
and-included in the naturals). By default, the infinite x-values are in the
transcendent position of the ratio, and the constant rational identity, the
closure-factor, is hidden in the immanent position, in relation to the invisible
solidus. Therefore, the default, implicit, transitive mapping is a one-to-one
function with the transcendent pole of the I/T-axis, and we get the identity
line y=x/1. Take the reciprocal y=1/x, however, the inverse mapping, and the
hidden rational identity comes into relief. This is why, of the twin rational
operations (division and multiplication), only division violates the closure
property of the originary unit-identity, (1), refusing to take us into the

i
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.

Page | 388
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

opposition of the negative transitive numbers, but rather taking us directly


and naturally into the infinite hidden ‘space’ within the unit-identity (the
intensive univocal forces of the positive infinity of the rational) and between
each rung of the transitive/transcendent ladder.

Figure 26: Repeated from The Image of the Trans -trans-bias.

Through transcension-and-inclusion, the transcendent pole, at the level of


the rational, is tied to the transitive unit, the “multiplicative identity” that
makes the identity line possible, and renders the immanence of the root unit
ubiquitously invisible from within its frame of operation. Division, however,
comes from the inverse direction, from the other side of the transitive
agglomerative recursion of multiplication, across the input/output polarity.
Division starts with the output sum as input and works back to find the

Page | 389
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

expanded solidus that fits the recursive ratio. This is how it breaks the
closure of the unit-identity quantizing the integers.i*
In this way division (rationality) includes and vastly transcends the
hitherto transitive, agglomerative and pre-rational functions of addition and
its recursion layer of multiplication. By inverting the quantizing process
across the input/output polarity, and violating closure with the unit
selection in the output rather than a hidden input, division reveals the I/T
axis hidden in the invisible unit-divisor of the integers and upon which the
unit was initially (even if unconsciously or pre-operationally) selected.ii*
And, as we have seen, the asymmetry of the closure property, with the iopol
inversion always breaking closure toward immanence, directly
demonstrates the trans-trans-bias.
It is only natural that the transitive axes were initially mapped to the
transcendent operations encapsulating the trans-trans-bias in the
transcend-and-include holarchy of mathematics. This is, after-all, a natural
objective-bias inherent in sensorial and conceptual operation, and therefore
in mathematical evolution. This image of the trans-bias illuminates why the
trans-cendent and trans-itive collapse into the one-to-one identity of the
common mathematical notion of “the infinite”—mapped as the identity
line—and reveals precisely why the immanent pole of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, represented on the immanent side of the
solidus, gets thrown in the waste-bin of the “undefined” and identified with
the cipher. As we can see on the graph, even the unit-identity itself, the root
trans-unit that got the ball rolling, is invisible from the trans-trans identity
axis and from multiplicative functions, whereas in the inverse-identical
operations of division, and even in the power/root operations, the curves
frame the implicit unit-solidus clearly. From the default trans-trans view,
the immanent pole appears as but an infinitely insignificant spec on the
straight path from one side of (trans-)infinity to the other. The trans-trans
line crosses an infinity of them with every interval, without batting an eye.
However, this infinite insignificance of the immanent axis, marked by a
zero in the “undefined” divisor, is an infinite oversight. The physicists of the
20th century found this out the hard way, stumbling in the dark of pre-
rational meta-mathematics, tacitly assuming the inert nullity of their “point-
particle approximations.” Many still haven’t figured out how and why their
“cipher in the snow”—the implicit singularity of the immanent location-
aspect of The Infinite—manifested its infinite energy, but we have seen,
through the Principle of Absolute Reversal, just how this can happen.

i
* Recall, Phase FOUR: Transitive Interfacing with the I/T Axis, p324.
ii
* Recall, Phase TWO: Unit-closure and the Finite Unit-Identity, p308.

Page | 390
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

There is an apparent asymmetry between input (x) and output (y) in


function offsets, where changes to x shift in the inverse direction from those
on the y (output) axis. For example, the equation y = f(x+3) +3, we see that
x+3 shifts the output a negative 3 units on the x axis. This leaves y = …+3,
which shifts the output, y, a positive 3 units, i.e. on the y axis. This apparent
asymmetry is exactly that, apparent. It is a necessary function of
operationally seeing only one direction (trans-trans), from input to output,
in the implicit iopol of function operations. It is this same implicit polarity
that remains hidden, but still operative, in the initial agglomerative
“onionOp” layers of addition/subtraction and the recursive-addition of
multiplication.

The rational function—operating at a key position in the EOTC or onion of


operations—provides a unique opportunity to explore the onion of
operations in the explicit visual fashion afforded by functions: graphs. And
conversely, the onion of operations allows us to make much more sense of
the terrain of the rational function, generally only known to the abstraction
of symbol-manipulation or calculation. In this interface of the onion of
operations with the rational function we will see that each informs and
reveals the other. This shows up clearly in the procedure for locating the
asymptotes of rational functions—our limits in the unlimited where number
breaks into its originary, pre-operational identical opposite: infinity.
An asymptote is, essentially, a region where the relative curve escapes
into the scope of the absolute, having no final bound. They are “holes” in the
graph of the relative, leading into the absolute. The images of these holes
provide a snapshot of the particulars of the relative function itself
interacting with the polarity of VL-axes, the transitive (mapping the
transcendent in the trans-bias) and the immanent/transcendent.
A rational function is simply one polynomial function divided by another.
There are two types of asymptotes for rational functions; vertical and
horizontal. A vertical asymptote is where the value of the function, or the
value of y, ultimately escapes in the transcendent direction towards positive
and/or negative (transitive as opposed to immanent) infinity. A horizontal
asymptote, on the other hand, is where the hidden immanent pole of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis comes into play, shunting the transitive
mapping of transcendence into the deep-infinity of immanence, as it is
opened up in the function of the ratio.
We can see quickly that any value that brings the denominator—the
immanent position in the rational function—to zero, will give us the pre-

Page | 391
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

rationally undefined infinity in the immanent position of the rational I/T


axis—the rational inverse of zero. Therefore the locations on the graph
where the value of x leads to the cumulative value of zero for the
denominator will result in vertical asymptotes. For example, with the
equation f(x) = 1/x, the vertical asymptote would simply be the vertical line
running through x = 0, or the y axis, because zero in the denominator equates
to infinity for the value of y. We have already encountered this simplest
rational function in the inverse-identity line, see Figure 26, repeated above.
As the values of x approach zero from either side, they extend vertically to
infinity, currently “undefined” in the default pre-rationality of the Cartesian
trans-biased graphing system.
The horizontal asymptotes, however, are much more difficult to find,
especially in more complex rational functions. We will trace out a
modification of the standard set of procedures for locating the horizontal
asymptotes of a rational function. Ultimately the asymptotes are defined by
the ratio of the degree of the polynomial—i.e. the maximum power of any of
its terms—on either side of the solidus of the rational function—because the
maximum power will always overtake any smaller powers on the endless
road to The Infinite. And again, through the “second-tier” integration of the
power/root level, we will find a clarity on the entire holarchy of number and
operation as it unfolds through the lens of the rational function.
To find the horizontal asymptotes of a standard rational function, we can
take n for the degree of the numerator, m for the degree of the denominator
and use the following set of rules. However, we will emphasize our
mnemonic, n for transcendent and m for immanent, for obvious reasons.
And to keep things simple, we will symbolize the degree of the polynomial
with the power of x — x simply stands in for the polynomial itself, to which
we can emphasize its degree.

Page | 392
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

e.g. x¹/x³ — n < m — If the transcendent


degree is less than the immanent, the
horizontal asymptote descends into the
rational-zero of the x-axis. This is called,
herein, an immanent operation because
the immanent side of the ratio ultimately
overpowers the lesser transcendent. The
ends of the curve, representing the over-
riding power of the function, enter into
immanent operation through eventual
over-powering on the immanent side of
the solidus. And, on the trans-biased
Cartesian graph, since immanence (yin) is
“undefined” and invisible, y simply moves
toward zero. This is directly analogous to
the motion toward zero as the Figure 53: Immanent Function:
denominator of a ratio approaches A rational function ending
infinity. Since negative numbers are a (unendingly) in an immanent
function of the transitive axis and operation.
therefore of pre-rational functions, and
zero is the immanent pole of the I/T-axis, the curve forever “approaches” the
non-limit of immanent-zero, rather than crossing into the “imaginary” land
of negative numbers.

e.g. x³/x³ — n = m — If the transcendent


degree is equal to the immanent,
however, the powers drop off, as far as
the asymptote is concerned, and we have
an asymptote defined essentially as the
expanded/contracted solidus of a rational
number. The asymptote then becomes
the ratio of the coefficients of the largest
powers of the polynomials of the
numerator and denominator; the line y =
nc/mc. This operation is ultimately Figure 54: Balanced (Rational)
defined as rational because when the Function:
ultimate powering is balanced across the A rational function ending in a
solidus, at the ends of the curve, (at the rational operation.
unreachable absolute scope) the

Page | 393
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

power/root onionOp shell of the exponents is ultimately negated and we


move one level down to the mult/div, or rational shell, forever
“approaching” a rational number as constant, as opposed to approaching an
over-riding power curve. The asymptote here represents the infinite depth
at the root-unit interface expanded or contracted through the rational
solidus.

e.g. x²/x¹ — n = m+1 — If the


transcendent is exactly one degree
greater than the immanent, then
ultimately—as far as the asymptote or
absolute scope of powers are
concerned—the power of the
denominator is negated leaving one
power of x on the numerator. This leaves
us with the trans-trans identity-line, y = x¹
— often scaled (skewed) or offset by the
particulars of the equation — as the
grand power and asymptote of the
function. The graph of such an equation
is said to have a “slant asymptote” rather Figure 55: Trans-Trans Function:
than a horizontal one. The slope of the A rational function ending with a
slant asymptote is found using division trans-trans operation (mapping the
and dropping the remainder term. The trans-trans identity line of the
operation here is called trans-trans default trans-bias).
because the ends of the graph approach
the transitive mapping of the transcendent pole in y=x/1, the transitive
identity line. Note that the trans-trans operation has exactly one unit of
power, in the transcendent position, showing us clearly its transcendent
bias, as opposed to the rational operations which come about through a
balance of powers across the solidus of the rational function.

Page | 394
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

e.g. x³/x¹ — n > m+1 — If the


transcendent is more than one degree
greater than the immanent, then, it has no
horizontal asymptote. This is called a
transcendent operation because the ends
of the curve have moved into the positive
and/or negative transcendent vertical
directions, approaching no line,
horizontal or vertical as asymptote. And
hence the I/T infinity can be mapped to
the transitive infinite y-axis rather than
approaching a constant within/between
the transitive number-line, the hidden
immanent pole represented by the h-
asymptote.) Figure 56: Transcendent Function:
A rational function ending in a
transcendent operation.
Note that if the ratio, n/m, is greater than
the transitive (root) unit 1, the equation
does not enter into immanent operation and it has no horizontal asymptote,
i.e. the output does not approach the zero of immanent infinity (the
immanent operation) or the immanence between any other y-offset of an
expanded solidus (the rational operation). Instead, the graph moves into the
transcendent direction and increases and/or decreases through mapping the
transcendent to the positive or negative transitive infinity. But if the degree
of n is exactly one greater than m we find the slant asymptote of the identity
line. This one degree offset in the transcendent numerator is another clear
view of our trans-bias, in the transitive mapping of transcendence of the
trans-trans identity line. If the ratio of degrees is balanced, however, the
immanent and transcendent are in harmony and we move onto a new VL-
axis with a new origin-identity and into the intensive forces between the
poles of the rational immanent-zero and the transcendent infinite. The
horizontal asymptote in this case is the ratio of the coefficients of the
degrees, representing the rational expansion or redefinition of the unit-
solidus (breaking the closure of the unit-identity through the iopol inversion
offered by opening up the hidden immanent side of the ratio to input). If,
however, n/m is less than one, the horizontal asymptote is the x-axis and we
move back into undefined hidden immanence, shrinking into the sub-
representational zone of the x-axis itself, an infinite dimension hidden
behind a thick line of pre-rational ink.
Our modern graphs are transitive and trans-biased (yang-biased) in
nature, in the default, pre-rational Cartesian space of modern meta-
mathematics. Because of this, the infinities of the immanent pole (yin)

Page | 395
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

generally take the form of asymptotes or undefinables; the infinite depth


horizontal asymptotes between numbers in unquantized inter-unity
divisions, or the “undefined” vertical asymptotes of the immanent zeros in
the denominator; these zeros being the immanent identity on the immanent
side of the rationally expanded or contracted unit-solidus.

Unfolding in accord with the EOTC, the level of powers has enfolded within it
several different input/output polarities. At least two of these polarities can
be inverted at this level to give us a new function or operation. Recall that
enfolded at the level of multiplication and division is the
immanent/transcendent polarity of the solidus/vinculum. This is the
polarity that—at the offset level of the exponent—is inverted from its
default agglomerative function to give us the function of rooting (See Figure
57, below). We have seen this already in the rules of exponents as
demonstrated in the Onion of Operations, above, where taking the reciprocal
of the exponent (flipping it across the solidus) inverts the operation into
taking the root of the base.
Another iopol open for use at the power/root level, however, unfolds
because the level of powers is the first level of operation explicitly
recognized and operationalized as a function. This explicit operationality is
provided with the role of the exponent, and is the reason that this level is
considered “second-tier,” because it exposes and operationalizes its own
transcended-and-included polarities.
At this level, then, we can differentiate between two types of function; the
power function and the exponential function. Both of these functions use the
same underlying operational form of layered recursion, which we have
already explored at length and which we visualized in the diagram of the
onion of operations (recall Figure 37 above, p347). The power function, we
have already seen, simply takes the input variable x (which we will call the
domain input, to emphasize that x is the input of an entire domain) as the
base, and raises it to the arbitrary single input number n; e.g. x3. The
exponential function, on the other hand, takes the arbitrary input number n
(a single number rather than a domain) as the base, and raises it to the
variable domain-input x; e.g. 3x.

Page | 396
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

Figure 57: Powers, Roots, Exponential and Logarithmic Functions and the
Input/Output Polarity:
The trans-rational or power level has a singular, transcend -and-include, holarchical
structure of inputs and outputs. It is the differential mapping of these input and
output structures to the various aspects of functions, such as the domain -input of the
x, and the single-input n, that allows for the new operations of the logarithmic and
exponential functions. Notice how switching the position of the x and y (input/output
of the function, reversing the direction of the arrows), in the bottom section, converts
between exponential and logarithmic functions, whereas merely taking the reciprocal
of the exponent, in the top section, converts between power and root operations.

Page | 397
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The key difference at this point, then—at this very same level of holarchical
structure, which we can map out visually (see Figure 57, above)—is where
the x, y or n is placed, and this in turn determines the directions and flows of
the various inputs and outputs emerging at this level of the EOTC of number
and operation. Notice how switching the position of the x and y—the
input/output polarity of the function—in the bottom section, converts
between exponential and logarithmic functions (reversing the direction of
the arrows), whereas merely taking the reciprocal of the exponent, in the top
section, converts between power and root operations.

Figure 58: The Onion Offset:


The offset of polarities in the onion of operations. [Adapted from the inset of Figure
37, the Onion of Operations (p347)]

In the power function the x is placed in the transcended-and-included


rational level of the base and in the exponential function it is placed in the
trans-rational level of the exponent, with its offset polarity mapping. And so
the iopol of powers operates at the rational level of the transcended-and-
included solidus, whereas the iopol of the exponential operates at the trans-
rational level of the exponent, and this easily and obviously accounts for the
differences between power-root and exponential curves, where an
exponential/logarithmic, will always overtake a power/root curve.
This new input/output polarity afforded first by explicitly
operationalizing the powers through the use of exponents, and secondly by
treating the power/root level in terms of functions with variable inputs and
outputs which can be swapped around, then allows the inversion of the
function of exponentiation to give us the logarithm. The key difference
between the root and the logarithm, then, is where, in the holarchy, this
iopol inversion takes place.

Page | 398
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER

The two transcended-and-included polarities of the power level, recall, are


the oppositional forces (+|-) of the transitive axis and the intensive forces of
the I/T. The I/T is mapped to the rational polarity of the exponent itself,
toggling by reciprocating it between the power and root operationality
across the square-root line (e.g. 52 becomes 5½, or 2 5 ). And the transitive
+|- polarity on the exponent toggles its base across the rational solidus (e.g.
5-2 = 1/( 52 )).
We can see this very clearly in the rules of logarithms and exponents.
Indeed, expanding logarithmic functions can be seen simply as unpacking
the onion of operations, working in the reverse direction to the
transcension-and-inclusion of number and operation itself and unfolding the
enfolded evolution, mapped to the offset polarities of the exponent.
For example, as we would expect with the operational offset in the onion
of operations (See Figure 58, above), in the power rule — logbMp = p logbM
— we can simply choose to take the exponent (p) out of its trans-rational,
exponential level, and bring it down into its functional equivalent at the
rational level of multiplication or division, as mapped by the offset polarities
of the exponent in the onion of operations. This offset which we are now
deconstructing or “expanding,” recall, we simply traversed with the laws of
exponents, where taking the reciprocal of the power (flipping it across the
implicit unit-solidus (/1) of all rational numbers) inverted the power into its
root.
Similarly, the product and quotient rules — logbMN = logbM + logbN and
logbM/N = logbM - logbN, respectively — traverse the onion-offset of
exponent polarities at the next deeper level of the transitive operations of
addition and subtraction. The product rule can be stated simply: when
logarithms of the same base are multiplied, the base remains the same, and the
exponents can be added. We can see this quite directly using exponents: 35 x
33 = (3x3x3x3x3) x (3x3x3) = 3x3x3x3x3x3x3x3 = 35+3 = 6561 .
The inverse of the product rule, the quotient rule, is similarly illustrative.
It can be stated simply: when logarithms of the same base are divided, the
exponents must be subtracted. So using the logarithm again, we can unpack
the onion still further with the factors, or multiplication within the resultant
equivalence to addition of recursive elements at the level of the exponent.
This allows us to separate the internal (rational) factors of the resultant
through the external (trans-rational) operation of addition or subtraction
offset through the onion of operations. We can then use the iopol inversion
of the logarithm to deconstruct the onion of operations, to replace the
exponents, with their offset polarities and operations, through their
functional equivalents, unpacking the onion through logarithmic expansion.

Page | 399
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Power/root functions operationally revisit both the transitive and rational


identities, zero and one respectively. This is due to the “second-tier”
transcension-and-inclusion of the binary cycle of origin-identities in the
power/root shell, the third level in the onion of operations—from the
additive identity 0, to the implicit multiplicative identity 1, now explicitly
integrated to the unit-identity of the power functions in n0=1 — note that
this expression includes and integrates the binary pair of operational origin-
identities, zero and one. Thus the cycle comes full-circle and the power/root
level makes explicit, or unfolds, what was implicit; from immanent zero, the
transitive identity, to the generation of the transitive unity (1), the rational
identity, finally embodied or unfolded in the unit-identity of the power/root
functions. The exp/log functions operationally embody the whole sequence.
So, unfolded in the exp/log functions we find the entire holarchy manifested,
because the whole thing is recursively transcended-and-included to create
the power/root functions. And so again we find that “ontogeny recapitulates
phylogeny,” a natural feature of transcend-and-include holarchical
evolutions, such as the EOTC. Thus the onion of operations demonstrates
the embryology of the core elements of Interface Mathematics.

Page | 400
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

Leibniz would have nearly completed the opening stages of nondual


mathematical Rationalism and opened the way for Interface Mathematics,
had he further elucidated the understanding of the three infinities he
received when he secretly copied down and studied Spinoza’s infamous
Letter XII on the infinite.i* He had rendered the part-whole paradox of
Galileo moot in his complex and difficult to grasp system of “metaphysical
points,” but he failed to see and implement the new VL-axis of the Rationals
and thus to build a bridge, making visible and visceral the essence of
mathematical rationality. And hence the Zenonian-seed of immanence,ii*
this uncountably “deep-infinity,” this “secret of the rational” was overlooked
and trampled underfoot, laying dormant until perhaps this extended
moment.
This work indeed picks up where Leibniz and Spinoza left off with their
embryonic foundation opening up and operationalizing the immanence of
the Rational. We will see this explicitly in Leibniz’s calculus as the
mathematical expression of his metaphysics of an infinitely divided iii
holarchy of substance as monads, and more subtly in Spinoza’s infinitely
active and modifiediv* Substance as immanent infinity in polar opposition to
his modifications as boundaries; resonating with the Nagarjuna’s nondual
polarity of Emptiness and Form, respectively.

i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
Zeno was really the first to explore immanence rationally and logically, and in its uncountable form.
See, Back to Zeno, p448.
iii
…and via the Principle of Nondual Rationality, indivisible…
iv
* (e.g. folded, using Deleuze’s term to simply unite the two)

Page | 401
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Though its roots extend into both eastern and western antiquity (India and
Greece), the essential elements of the modern calculus emerged from the
exploding progress of algebra and geometry in the 17th century. With the
requisite mathematical pieces finally in place, the birth of the calculus was
imminent. This happened independently through the work of both Leibniz
and Newton, though it is Leibniz who provided the current notation and
terminology (the “science of fluxions” apparently wasn’t catchy enough).
And, as we will see, Leibniz, with the covert help of Spinoza, provided the
embryo of the nondual-rational meta-mathematics to match it and solve its
pre-rational philosophical problems, which naturally persist to this present
day of the aborted and unfinished project of mathematical rationalism.

The calculus was designed for increasing the depth and accuracy of
mathematics in the physical sciences and specifically for dealing with rates
of change between the interacting variables of a continuous curve. The
context of the calculus is this continuity and immanent infinity inherent in all
“points” of the rational number-line. Indeed, the calculus fails when it
encounters a discontinuous function, and the stipulation of continuity is
written into the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus itself, as we will see
below.
This rational continuity, or the “labyrinth of the continuum,” as Leibniz
famously addressed it, also spawned the problematic “infinitesimals,” which
are numbers approaching “infinite smallness”.i The calculus, of both Newton
and Leibniz, relied upon these infinitesimals as the key to mathematically
dealing with the immanent infinity of division by zero (the rational zero)
inherent in its processes.ii

i
…the rational zero and immanent pole of the Immanent/Transcendent axis as seen oxymoronically
through the trans-bias…
ii
Note that the numerical value of division by zero is transcendent not immanent infinity. However,
this is directly because of the immanent infinity of the rational zero. The breaking through of the
unit-closure as the denominator goes below 1 and toward the unreachable rational zero causes the
reciprocal increase to infinity in overall value due to the inherent transcendent-bias of the natural
numbers.

Page | 402
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

For reasons we will explore shortly, the critical role of the infinitesimal
has since been taken over by the less problematic concept of the “limit,” in
the 1800’s, and it is increasingly described more abstractly by functions
today. Behind the facade of these more abstract operations and symbols,
however, the problem of the infinitesimal itself remains.

Naturally, the processes at the core of the calculus form a polarity; the
“derivative” and the “integral,” which is roughly that of analysis vs. synthesis,
respectively. These can also be seen in terms of their motion with respect to
the Immanent/Transcendent axis. The derivative approaches the desired
infinitesimal itself, analytically, immanently, breaking it down through a
process of recursive division. Examples include finding an “instantaneous
velocity,” which is an attempt to “derive” the slope at a point on a velocity
curve to the most precise degree, or smallest scale possible on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. The integral, on the other hand, deals with
the infinitesimal in the opposite direction, synthetically, or transcendently, as
a summation (as Leibniz put it), or an accumulation and integration, of
infinitesimals. Examples here include taking the area under a graph of a
continuously varying function as a summation and integration of
infinitesimal slices. These two processes are indeed the inverse of each
other, as demonstrated explicitly and formally by the Fundamental Theorem
of Calculus which states essentially that if one function is defined as the
integral of another continuous function, then differentiating the new function
returns the function you started with.
It is fascinating to note that this polarity of “derivative and integral” also
goes by the name of “differentiation and integration,” respectively. And, as
we have seen, differentiation and integration are fundamental to the
embryogenesis of the concept. In this case, “differentiation and integration”
are not only implicit in the embryogenesis of the operational concept of the
calculus, but explicitly transcended-and-included in its genetic and
operational make-up, and hence included as well in the formal
operationalization of mathematical rationalism into the body of
mathematics proper. The raw utility of the calculus, with its polarity of core
operations, is therefore an example of the utility of the differentiate-and-
integrate polarity of the embryogenesis of the concept itself.

So far this all sounds well and good. Indeed it is very well and good, as far as
the mathematics of calculus is concerned. The calculus is an extremely
powerful mathematical tool, and it is used routinely and critically in virtually
all scientific and technological fields, from economics to rocket science. And
hence it is even perhaps justifiable (at least pragmatically so) that
Page | 403
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

mathematicians would perhaps write-off and ignore the complaints of


philosophers ever since the inception of the calculus, about problems with
its meaning, especially where the infinitesimal is concerned. Despite these
problems, the extreme utility of the calculus indicates that there is a deep
truth embodied in its operations. And it is the job of philosophy, or meta-
mathematics, to create, discover and integrate that truth into the collective
body of understanding.
The philosophical problems with the calculus stretch all the way back to
its inception and to the concept of the infinitesimal at its core. At the heart
of the calculus is the mathematical ratio taken to its unreachable “limit” in
the unlimited, at the rational zero, or the immanent pole of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis (often offset to the immanence between
higher level intervals or numbers, as we have seen). As we have discussed,
both processes, the derivative and integral, deal directly with the
infinitesimal. But many philosophers after its inception criticized the
calculus for being based on fuzzy ideas and non-rigorous foundations.
George Berkeley, for example, talked of the infinitesimal as “the ghost of
departed quantities.” Those fuzzy ideas, as we have seen throughout this
work, remain at the heart of modern mathematics with its prematurely
aborted rationalism and pre-differentiated, or intrinsic and
unacknowledged, immanent-transcendent axis manifesting as such things as
the ‘undefined’ infinity of division by zero (the rational zero) and even
Zeno’s paradoxes of the infinite. It is this same “undefined” pre-rational
fuzziness that leads to the philosophical problems with the calculus
addressed in this section.
In his paper, “Philosophical Problems with Calculus,” Kelley L. Ross
demonstrates that in the traditional method of taking a derivative—which
involves this infinite division inherent in the calculus— dy/dx would
ultimately represent zero/zero, as the difference, d, reached the unreachable
(infinite) rational zero. And zero/zero, Ross states “is ordinarily a useless or
meaningless relationship in mathematics: zero divided by anything is zero;
and anything divided by zero is often said to be ‘undefined,’ which is a polite
(or wimpy) way of saying ‘infinite.’” Newton and Leibniz, according to Ross,
explain this away by saying that dy/dx were not really zero, but the quantity
they have just before they reach zero. “But, it is objected, there is no quantity
‘just before’ zero. Either there is a finite number ... or there is zero, in which
case dy/dx is either meaningless or indeterminate.’”
The philosophical problem with this definition of the infinitesimal is
obvious in light of the Vision-Logic Coordinate System and the newly
operationalized Immanent/Transcendent axis intrinsic to rationality itself.
There is no “right before reaching,” for any infinity—transitive, transcendent

Page | 404
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

or immanent.i Infinity is not a boundary or a limit and cannot be reached.


This is the limit of the limitless. The use of infinitesimals helped to hide the
immanent infinity threatened to be exposed by the rational zero, and as such
infinitesimals were considered quantities greater than zero—otherwise the
calculations end up at infinity in division by zero—but smaller than any
possible or conceivable number. They are the inexpressible-but-finite
numbers right before “reaching” the unreachableii immanent infinity of the
rational zero. This, in effect, is the pushing of the finite far enough into the
infinite immanence that we merely lose sight of it, at which point we can
safely and, from an operational standpoint, inconsequentially pretend that it
is infinite (in the immanent direction), which is zero. This fuzzy and subtle
oxymoron is Berkeley’s “ghost of departed quantities.” The limit here is one
of conceptual horizons: out of sight, out of mind. The quantity is effectively
zero, but not quite, because that would lead to undefinables in the pre-
rational, transitive Cartesian system.
But a fully integrated, and integral—and indeed post-Cartesian—
rationality, such as Nondual Rationalism, must acknowledge the positive and
uncountable infinity of immanence unfolding with the advent of rationality
and operationalize it into an Immanent/Transcendent axis and polarity.
Only then will the problem of the infinitesimal be resolved, as we will see.

To avoid these conceptual and philosophical problems (rather than solve


them), mathematicians invented the more abstract and distant notion of the
“limit.” This operational concept essentially allows them to ignore the
infinitesimal at the heart of the calculus and leap right over the infinite abyss
of regressive immanence to the external boundary on the number-line which
it unendingly “approaches.” As John Stillwell notes in his Yearning for the
Impossible, The Surprising Truths of Mathematics, iii ¥ “the mainstream
approach to calculus used today...denies the existence of infinitesimals, and
interprets the word ‘infinitesimal’ as a mere figure of speech in statements
that are properly made using limits.” Stillwell goes on to show, that the
avoidance of infinitesimals, due to their philosophical problems, comes “at
the cost of a strange dual notation: Δ for actual differences and d (the ghost
of Leibniz!) for the limits of their quotients and sums.” This is a
cumbersome and ad hoc inconvenience which many mathematicians would

i
This is the classic case of the transcendent-bias because it is much more common to make this
mistake of bounding the unbounded in the immanent than in the transcendent direction; a
mathematical instantiation of foundationalism from the lofty perch of transcendent operations.
ii
… note the constant refrain of this oxymoron…
iii¥
John Stillwell Yearning for the Impossible, The Surprising Truths of Mathematics A.K. Peter, Ltd.,
Wellesley, Massachusetts, 2006], pp.99-100, qtd. in Ross

Page | 405
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

like to get rid of. As Stillwell puts it, “To many this is a compromise solution
which fails to explain why infinitesimals work.”
The problems with the infinitesimal, then, are not just philosophical
anymore, but mathematical, because mathematicians are influenced, and
rightly so, by the clamoring voices of philosophers. In order to temporarily
quiet the mathematical philosophers, the cumbersome dual notation was
invented to distance the calculus from the problematic infinitesimal hidden
within its form and history.
But Stillwell goes on to ask, “Is it possible to define and use genuine
infinitesimals?” There have been mathematical attempts, he shows, such as
Abraham Robinson’s nonstandard analysis, but none of them are “as simple
as the old Leibniz calculus of infinitesimals, and there is a continuing search
for a really natural system that uses infinitesimals in a consistent way.”

Given that philosophy is where the problems of the calculus began, then the
solution to the problem must also be largely philosophical. Recall that the
problematic definition given by Newton and Leibniz, according to academia,
is that the infinitesimal is not really zero, but the quantity just before it
reaches zero. And recall that it is objected that “there is no quantity ‘just
before’ zero,” since we are dealing with an infinite axis. “Either there is a
finite number ... or there is zero, in which case dy/dx is either meaningless or
indeterminate.’” Again, this is the vague and fuzzy “ghost of departed
quantities” criticism by the philosopher George Berkeley, et al, and it indeed
changed the course of the calculus, and arguably (if temporarily) for the
worse.
So how can we use Interface Mathematics and Nondual Rationalism to
give a coherent operational context and definition of the infinitesimal so that
its use could be acknowledged and reinstated to make life easy again for the
mathematician? The essentials of the answer should already be apparent to
most, but we’ll dive in deep and flesh it out in detail.

The understanding of infinitesimals is natural to Nondual Rationalism for


many reasons. I’ll extract three of them here. First of all, infinitesimals
represent immanent values only attainable with the mathematical ratio and
the dissolution of the integer-quantizing closure property in the higher
function of Rational numbers (which occurs mainly through the inversion of
the input/output polarity, as we have seen).i* It is therefore only fitting that
in the age of “rationalism” a method was finally invented for dealing with
these rational qualities and quantities which have puzzled mathematicians

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.

Page | 406
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

and philosophers since antiquity resulting in such vexing problems as Zeno’s


paradox, and the “undefinition” of division by zero. Secondly, the deep or
positive infinity and immanence opened up by the Rational numbers is
embodied in the fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism and the
newly operational Immanent/Transcendent axis. And third, the immanent
zero, forever approached, but never reached by the infinitesimal, is the
mathematical embodiment of Nagarjuna’s Emptiness or sunyata, as we have
seen, as well as the essence of yin, the feminine, dark and mysterious
principle from which transcendent forms emerge.
The solution to the problem of the infinitesimal has therefore been with
us implicitly in the East since at least the 2nd century, and it is inherent in the
explication and operationalization of the Immanent/Transcendent axis
already implicit in the nascent project of Western mathematical and
philosophical Rationalism, such as in core polarity hidden in Zeno’s
paradoxes: and more specifically, in the esoteric understanding of the Triune
Infinite of Spinoza and the mature (informed by the Triune Infinite)
Leibnizian monadology, as we will see.

As Kelley L. Ross states in his Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, “Calculus in the 17th
century was thought to deal with infinitesimal, or almost infinitely small,
quantities. Leibniz, as it happens, has very conveniently provided a
metaphysics to match this. No matter how small the quantity, there is a
monad there.”i¥ Indeed, the infinitesimal (rationally understood) is merely a
monad beyond, or beneath, the immanent horizon of the indefinite
mathematical imagination. ii And further, Leibniz ultimately saw the
infinitesimal—an “infinitely small” point represented mathematically as
zero—as a necessary fiction to operationally bridge the infinite gap of the
series, only “convergent” from a transitive frame of reference on the infinity
of the immanent/rational zero.
In Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually Infinite Division of Matter,iii¥
Samuel Levey explains (my emphases),
Though Leibniz is on occasion prepared to talk of the infinitesimal as “an
infinitely small fraction or one whose denominator is an infinite number”
(GM 4:93), this is not his most considered account of the concept. The
most considered account, rather, is expressed when he writes of the
infinitesimal as an “incomparable magnitude,” a phrase he clarifies thus:
“these incomparable magnitudes . . . are not at all fixed or determined but


( http://www.friesian.com/leibniz.htm)
ii
This intrinsically volumetric aspect is also key to the definition of a point in Buckminster Fuller’s
Synergetic Geometry and it corresponds to Gerald Lebau’s “needle sharp point,” as we have seen.
iii¥
The Philosophical Review, Vol. 107, No. 1 (Jan., 1998), 49-96.

Page | 407
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

can be taken as small as we wish in our geometrical reasoning and so


have the effect of the infinitely small in the rigorous sense.”i¥
Levey goes on:
...it is perfectly clear that by the spring of 1676 Leibniz takes the
infinitesimals of his mathematics to be “fictions.” And in writings of many
years later, he occasionally suggests that he has a positive argument
against the very possibility of infinitesimal quantities.ii¥
So we can see here that Leibniz’s most considered and esoteric view is quite
a bit different from the problematic view of the infinitesimal attributed to
him in exoteric or common accounts of History, including that of Hegel, as
we will see. The infinitesimal, for Leibniz, was not “the quantity [of infinite
division] just before it reaches zero,” but rather a necessary fiction for dealing
with infinite division (immanence) from the default (transitive) frame of
reference (transcended-and-included in the holarchical embryogenesis) of
mathematics. For Leibniz, the “just before it reaches zero” was itself a
perspectival illusion, a necessary fiction to “escape the infinite regress” of
immanence seen from the transcendent perch of the transitive.
This lesser known and more mature Leibnizian view, as we will see, is
essentially what Deleuze calls the “differential point of view of the
infinitesimal calculus,” and it is a critical Leibnizian link in Deleuze’s
alternate lineage of the history of mathematics and philosophy, as opposed
to Hegel’s transcend-and-negate dialectical misrepresentation of both
Spinoza and Leibniz.

Levey goes on to show, however, (which we will see echoed in Deleuze


below) that Leibniz’s change in thought regarding the infinitesimal is
concurrent with his 1676 studies of Spinoza, and specifically his reading of
Spinoza’s famous Letter XII on the infinite (which, recall, Leibniz acquired
secretly in order to maintain his public anti-Spinozistic stance). This letter,
as we have seen, contains Spinoza’s most explicit account of his Triune
Infinite which, along with univocity, is found implicitly throughout his Ethics,
as an “organizing principle.”

Levey says:
In his later analysis of the continuum, Leibniz contends that the labyrinth
arises from confusing the character of matter [namely infinite divisibility]
with that of mathematical or geometrical continua: either supposing


Letter to Varignon, 1702. GM 4:91
ii¥
“GM 3:524, 551”

Page | 408
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

matter to be continuous or supposing continua to be composites of


discrete parts (G 2:282).
… Or, to capture the contrast with “actual parts”: the parts of an ideal
whole are merely possible or potential [a posteriori] parts. And crucially,
it is “because the part is only possible and ideal” that the whole is prior to
the part in the continuum (G 4:491f.).
Note the connection with the aspect infinite as an abstraction from The
Infinite. The whole of The Infinite is logically prior to its abstracted aspects,
such as an immanent local aspect of an extensionless point [my emphasis].
… To see this still more clearly, take this example. “Whenever someone
has conceived duration abstractly, and by confusing it with time has
begun to divide it into parts, he will never be able to understand how an
hour, for example, can pass. For in order for the hour to pass, it will be
necessary for half of it to pass first, and then half of the remainder, and
then half of what remains of this remainder. And if he subtracts half from
the remainder in this way indefinitely, he will never be able to reach the
end of the hour.i Hence many people who have not been in the habit of
distinguishing entia rationis from real things, have dared to declare that
duration is composed of moments. In their desire to avoid Charybdis, they
have run into Scylla.” (A 6.3:279)
Confusion between “entities of reason” and “real things” leads one to
posit discrete parts (such as moments) in what are in fact continuous
wholes (such as duration “conceived abstractly”), and quickly embroils
one in the classical paradoxes of the continuum. One especially
remarkable feature of this early anticipation of Leibniz’s later analysis of
the source of the labyrinth is that the author of the passage just quoted is
Spinoza. Leibniz here is simply recopying an excerpt of the so-called
Letter XII, On the nature of the Infinite, of 1663 ... but the uncanny
resemblance between the excerpt’s apparent import and aspects of
Leibniz’s own later views strongly suggests that those aspects
originate in Leibniz’s 1676 Spinoza studies.
Prior to this encounter with Spinoza’s triune model of infinity, Leibniz had
been entertaining the inherited Euclidean notion that the continuum must
be constructed of elements, i.e. from an “infinite number” of “infinitely
small,” points. But after his 1676 Spinoza studies, Leibniz changed his
stance (pre-echoing Fuller’s own childhood realization of modelability
leading to his Synergetic Geometry), saying now that this construction of an
actual continuum from the “infinitely small,” is impossible, and that a
mathematical point (or an infinitesimal quantity) is merely an abstract
“terminus” in the pre-existing, but still abstract, continuum.

i
This, of course, is a temporal version of Zeno’s paradox, who’s solution also follows from a solution
to the labyrinth of the continuum, and the infinitesimal, which Leibniz found through Spinoza's
Triune Infinite. See, Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 409
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

We know this abstract “terminus” (that never terminates) herein—from


our own studies of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite—as the immanent or positional
(immanent-uni-local) aspect of The Infinite, or operationally as the
immanent pole of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis. And we know the
continuum itself as the omni-non-local and uncountable aspect of
immanence, and operationally as the immanent pole of the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis i *—the ONE as the ALL of infinite
multiplicity. Both of these VL-axes fall under Spinoza’s Triune Infinite as 2nd
order, or Aspect infinities, as we have seen.
The infinite convergent series “converges” towards its bound, but on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis it never actually gets any closer because the
bound is just outside (or transitive to) the (immanent) series. This
convergence only seems to get closer from a particular stationary point of
view, and most importantly, relative to a reference point/frame on the
transitive number-line or grid. Since, as Leibniz shows later on, the series
can have no final term or cardinal, it is always infinitely far away. Implicitly
obvious, yet unacknowledged and unoperationalized in standard
mathematics, convergent series are operating not merely on the transitive
axis where its “bounds” or limits are located and enacted, but on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis.
And here we can see that the con-fusion surrounding the infinitesimal
(even as it pre-echoes in Zeno’s paradoxes)ii* is caused by a conflation of the
pre-fused distinction between the immanent/transcendent and transitive VL-
axes—a distinction which only becomes fully differentiated when the project
of rationalism comes to fruition.

Levey goes on to demonstrate that the Leibnizian “point of view of the


infinitesimal calculus” allowed Leibniz to anticipate some of the
revolutionary insights of modern set theory which arose in the context of an
uncompleted philosophical and mathematical rationality, and hence
emerged into a confused meta-mathematical space of interpretation—thus
ultimately failing to take root. Unfortunately we won’t have time to explore
this fascinating thread further in this volume. For now we’ll simply explore
the Leibnizian anticipation and the Spinozan/Leibnizian keys to the
Deleuzian alternative lineage of History, centered on the calculus and the
positive infinity or immanence of the rational.

i
* See, I/T Omni- and Uni-axes, p145.
ii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.

Page | 410
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

The cardinality of a set is determined by the number of terms within it. In


mathematics, the “naïve principle” states that in an “infinite set” this cardinal
would correspond to the “final” ordinal within it; the “infinitieth” term, or
the “number infinity.” But through his analysis of the infinite convergent
series, catalyzed by his 1676 Spinoza studies, Leibniz comes to reject the
applicability of this principle to an infinite set, because infinity can have no
final “infinitieth” term.
This “singling out and rejecting” of the naïve principle, “a mathematical
principle that runs deep in early modern thought,” Levey states “in effect
anticipates some of the revolutionary insights that will, two hundred years
later, spark the most profound developments in mathematics....” This
indeed, was one of Cantor’s great insights in his revolutionary, yet
systematically misunderstood, Set Theory with its controversial definitions
and transfinite orders of “infinite sets.”

Levey explains:
I have argued that Leibniz’s actual mathematics for calculating the sums
of infinite series encodes a certain conception of the infinite convergent
series, what I call “the mathematical conception,” according to which
there is a terminal element bounding the series at its diminishing end.
That terminal element is supposed to be the infinitieth term in the series,
and is itself an infinitesimal magnitude. We knew already that Leibniz
denies the existence of infinitesimals. We now see also that he denies the
existence of an infinite number. But the mathematical conception
evidently implies the existence of both. Thus, we see more than just a
puzzle about how to make sense of his views of the composition of
matter: Leibniz’s philosophical views about mathematics—his denials of
infinite and infinitesimal numbers—appear to be in conflict with the
commitments of his own mathematical practices. Something has to give if
coherence is to be maintained. In “Infinite Numbers,” a cluster of notes
dated to 10 April 1676, Leibniz confronts these difficulties and submits
the concept of the infinite convergent series and its use in mathematics to
close scrutiny. From this renewed inquiry into mathematics emerges a
stable and subtle philosophy of mathematics and philosophy of the
infinite, and in the process the passage to the later period of his 1676
mathematics is transacted.
In De Quadratura Arithmetica (1676) Leibniz says expressly that we
engage in a certain “fiction” when, in order to find the value of an infinite
quantity, we suppose that it is bounded (133), as in the example of the
last passage “something must be added” to the infinite series in order to
calculate its sum. That “something” does not in fact occur in the series.
The mathematical conception of the infinite series smuggles in a fictional
terminus under its interpretation of the rider ‘etc.’ or ‘to infinity’ that is
inevitably affixed to the expression of the series as “measured” or as
having a sum. Since that series does not in fact contain a last term, the
proposition involving its measured form engages directly (if tacitly) in a
fiction, and so must be said not to be rigorously true. ... Talk of the sum of

Page | 411
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

an infinite series is thus cashed in for rigorously true generalized talk of


the sums of finite series and of the rules for producing them.
Leibniz says, “Whenever it is said that a certain infinite series of
numbers has a sum, I am of the opinion that all that is being said is that
any finite series with the same rule has a sum, and that the error always
diminishes as the series increases, so that it becomes as small as we
would like.”i¥
Levey continues [[my comments]]:
Once the mathematical conception of the infinite series is replaced with
the operationalist one, it becomes possible for all those philosophically
undesirable commitments to be severed from his mathematics.
…Thus, Leibniz’s philosophy of the infinite, places the concept of
infinity safely outside the scope of the concept of number. The infinite can
exist in the realm of mathematics, but not as a single whole; rather, the
infinite provides the framework for mathematics, so to speak, appearing
only as the infinity of mathematical objects but never occurring within
mathematics as a unitary, infinite mathematical object. Likewise for the
world of matter: there can be an actual infinity of matter’s parts, but,
perhaps ironically, those “parts” can never constitute a true whole
[[…because it is the whole from which the parts are abstracted aspects]].
…The mathematical conception of the infinite series has been
dispatched, along with its cadre of problematic notions: the “bounded
infinite,”ii the infinitesimal, the infinite cardinal, and the infinite series
itself, if taken as a genuine whole. All are excised from the rigorously
correct understanding of mathematics, and are retained only in their
appearances, as facets of a practically useful technique towards which an
operationalistiii stance is to be assumed. Having cut the infinite series free
from its imagined undesirable consequences, Leibniz can at last secure
the concept of the infinite convergent numerical series, an unbounded
infinite series consisting entirely of finite terms that can be said to have a
finite sum. And this brings us back to his inquiry into the metaphysics of
matter, for the very point in clarifying and securing that concept of the
infinite series has been to isolate an abstract structure that could serve as
a coherent model for his account of the infinite division of matter. As a
consequence of its circulating through irregular spaces in a plenum, a
portion of matter would have to be divided into an actual infinity of
parts. But these parts could not be “metaphysical points” or minima,
since, as the analysis of the continuum revealed, minima can only be
termini [[abstracted locations or immanent aspects of The Infinite, or
“folds,” as Deleuze would call them]] and never parts of things. Nor is it
correct to suppose that those parts are actual infinitesimals. Rather, it
must somehow be possible for a finite portion of matter to be divided into
an infinity of parts, each of which is divisible and of some finite size. The


A 6.3:503
ii
Note that this is not the same Bounded or Modal Infinite from Spinoza's Triune Infinite.
iii
This is not to be confused with Fuller’s Operational Mathematics.

Page | 412
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

infinite convergent numerical series makes its metaphysical contribution


here by providing precisely such a possibility. A finite portion of matter
might divide into an infinity of finite and divisible parts just as a finite
number might divide into an infinity of finite and divisible numbers. The
moving portion of matter, as it adjusts its shape, divides into an infinity of
smaller parts, each of which is surpassed in smallness by some other part
but none of which is indivisible or infinitesimal. Again, Zeno’s series
makes for a nice example:
After his 1676 Spinoza studies, Leibniz’s mathematics of the infinitesimal is
now in perfect coevolutionary conjunction with his mathematics of the
infinite, as well as his metaphysics of mind and matter. As Levey shows,
Leibniz’s most considered conception of the composition of matter was
essentially the same as the Deleuzian “differential point of view of the
infinitesimal calculus.” Originally, for Leibniz, matter (just as the
continuum) was infinitely divided into extensionless points. But through his
rejection of the “naive principle” of an infinite set (as applied to the
immanent infinity of rationality and the calculus), he comes to the
conclusion that, while matter is infinitely divided, it is not divided into
extensionless points, but each time into finite or bounded ones. Each new
division (a monad) is finite or non-zero in size and thus further divisible into
‘infinitely many’ more such points never converging on an extensionless,
indivisible point to be added up to any cardinality. Just as in our fundamental
principle of Nondual Rationalism, infinite divisibility is endless divisibility, or
indivisibility. It never reaches an end. The ends reached are always the
result of finite divisibility and they end in finite divisions or boundaries,
never infinitely small points.
Naturally, this puts us, both ontologically and mathematically, right in the
middle of an infinite endless holarchy of nested units, or holons, exactly as
postulated in Self-similar Cosmology, Ken Wilber’s Integral Methodological
Pluralism, and the physical model of SpinbitZ which we will explore in
Volume II of this series.

Page | 413
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

As we have seen, the extensionless point—in the context of division and the
ratio—is the rational or immanent zero; the immanent pole of the
immanent/transcendent uni-axis. As such, it can’t be “reached” or bounded
by any number or division. The infinitesimal, in other words—conceived of
as “the number right before reaching zero,” or an “infinitely small”
number—cannot exist. It can only be a convenient fiction. In Spinoza’s
Triune Infinite, as we have seen, the “point” is seen simply as the immanent-
local aspect of The Infinite;i an immanent infinity.
The “limit” in calculus—replacing the problematic “ghost of departed
quantities” (the infinitesimal)—therefore must be seen purely in the
function of operationalizing—i.e. finitizing, bounding or reaching—the new
immanent uncountable infinity of the I/T axis, broken open through the
immanent operations of the ratio and the root functions (as we have seen).
It must be seen simply as a tool or trick for integrating the new I/T axis into
the trans-biased bounding or numerating operations of pre-rational
mathematics transcended-and-included at the trans-rational level of the
calculus.
The limit is the “finitizing” leap across the infinite immanent/regressive
abyss in order to bring the infinite and uncountable I/T sum to a finite and
countable transitive end. This operational leap is philosophically warranted
herein because the immanent/transcendent is a polarity, and, by the identity
of opposites, every regressive immanent value is also progressively
transcendent from deeper values and possible frames of reference, and vice
versa. Indeed, the aperspectival nature of the Vision-Logic Coordinate
System requires us to take on these immanent perspectives so that we can
see the transcendent value in any immanent infinitesimal, a non-zero value
only appearing from above as equivalent to the transitive zero of negation or
the implicit singularity of the immanent zero.
An essential thread of Nondual Rationalism is the overcoming of the
transcendent-bias by the integrating of the immanent, the positive and
progressive or emergent infinity as the secret of the rational. This is the
identity of opposites, of transcendence in immanence (yang in yin in yang
…), embodied and operationalized in the Immanent/Transcendent axis, and

i
And the immanent-omni-non-local aspect of The Infinite is, of course, the immanent pole of the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis.

Page | 414
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

the Principle of Immanence in Transcendence, the 2nd chord in our Ariadne’s


cable out of the labyrinth of the continuum.
The infinitesimal, then, is the essentially-arbitrary (or perspectival), and
effectively-null transitive value required to operationally recognize or map
the transcendent value in the immanence of the limit, allowing the
regressive “abyss” to be a progressive or positive axis, ultimately ending in
integrating the immanent uncountable pole into the fundamentally
transitive and countable operations transcended-and-included in rationality
and the calculus.
Or to put it simply—and to return partially to Leibniz’s own general-level
answer—the infinitesimal is a necessary fiction, an effective or
approximate zero, needed to operationally bridge the infinite gap of
immanence opened up by the mathematical ratio, and to integrate the newly
discovered Immanent/Transcendent axis of rationality into the default
(trans-bias) transitive frame of reference of the pre-rational Cartesian axes.

The question then arises, “If the solution to the problem of the calculus was
ultimately so simple (rather obvious), and already implicit in the Leibnizian
metaphysics, then why was there ever a problem in the first place?”
We have already seen the Leibnizian, philosophical fix to the problem of
the calculus, but without a sociological fix as well, a philosophical solution is
isolated to the individual who invented it. Though Leibniz, in his more
mature reflections, had recognized the impossibility of the infinitesimal, he
failed not only to explicitly recognizei but to operationalize the new VL-axis
upon which mathematical rationalism was operating. To take hold, the
Leibnizian fix requires the explicit, esoteric, or common-place societal
acknowledgment and operationalization of the move, in rationalism and the
calculus, to this new Immanent/Transcendent axis. This explicit
operationalization would manifest in, among other things, putting the
obvious definition of infinity explicitly into the “undefined” rational zero.
Leibniz did not accomplish this step. He did not make explicit, for all to
explore, the existence of this implicit rational VL-axis and the nature of its
holarchical, embryological relation to the body of mathematics as a whole, so
his most considered metaphysical insights, about the rational way to
understand the calculus, did not take root and flourish in the mathematical
and meta-mathematical minds of his contemporaries.
The project of rationalism was still-born, aborted—its developmental
trajectory derailed—due largely to the incompleteness of its operational VL-
axis, but also because of the difficulty of accepting its more esoteric truths
caustic to the pre-rational and mythical-categorical level of development of

i
… along with its embryogenesis of the concept, holarchical structure, origin-identities and offsets,
etc.

Page | 415
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

the power structures in the “enlightenment era” and beyond. This


incomplete rationality allowed the reassertion of reactionary pre-rational
tendencies, the transcendent-biased forces of representation inherent in the
socio-economic LCD basis of post-medieval reality. This pendulum swing
back to the pre-rational, as Mathew Stewart demonstrates in The Courtier
and the Heretic, was even given misdirected force in the explosive reaction
(and transcendent-/representational-bias) inherent in Leibniz’s own
Theistic and Idealistic philosophy, against his own inherent Spinozism,
covert-rationalism and modernism.
Thus rationality has languished through misrepresentation after
misrepresentation, lying dormant, until this torturously extended moment
when Spinoza—dubbed “the prince of philosophers” by Deleuze—is
experiencing a rebirth and radical explosion in scholarship. The tracks of
Rationalism are being reassembled, based on electro-magnetic, nondual
levitation this time, and the train is ready to bullet from the station.

Page | 416
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

In Spinoza’s famous Letter XII on the infinite we are presented with a


“geometrical example” that uses two non-concentric circles to demonstrate
the 3rd order, modal or bounded infinite (See Figure 59, below). Spinoza
says:
As, for instance, in the case of two circles, non-concentric, whereof one
encloses the other, no number can express the inequalities of distance
which exist between the two circles... This conclusion is not based on the
excessive size of the intervening space. However small a portion of it we
take, the inequalities of this small portion will surpass all numerical
expression. Nor, again, is the conclusion based on the fact, as in other
cases, that we do not know the maximum and the minimum of the said
space. It springs simply from the fact, that the nature of the space
between two non-concentric circles cannot be expressed in number.
Therefore, he who would assign a numerical equivalent for the
inequalities in question, would be bound, at the same time, to bring about
that a circle should not be a circle.

In The Science of Logic,i¥ Hegel claims that this example demonstrates the
absence of the differential of the calculus in Spinoza’s thought. This
interpretation of Spinoza as having missed the essence of the calculus—as
opposed to Newton, for example, who “invented” the calculus and who,
according to Hegel, was the one progenitor who properly understood it—
presents Hegel with further opportunity to dismiss Spinoza (and in turn
Leibniz) and as a hapless historical victim of his dialectical progression
toward the apex of philosophical perfection and the completion of History in
Hegel’s own “absolute idealism.”


p251

Page | 417
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The first opportunity to dismiss


Spinoza in the Science of Logic was with
Hegel’s earlier claim that “with Spinoza,
substance and its absolute unity has the
form of an inert unity, i.e. of a unity which
is not self-mediated, of a fixity or rigidity
in which the Notion of the negative unity
of the self, i.e. subjectivity, is still
lacking.” i ¥ Hegel has here neglected
and/or misunderstood the middle-path
third of Spinoza’s attribute polarity; his
symbiogenesis and dependent arising of
subject and object. But at a deeper level, Figure 59: Spinoza’s Geometrical
Hegel has transposed Spinoza’s ineffable Example of the Bounded Infinite:
absolute into the relative scope, his A representation of Spinoza’s
boundless Emptiness into a bounded geometrical example illustrating
object and his Substance into a “rigid” the shrinking into immanence
necessary to realize the
modification. All of this to allow for a
innumerable differences in distance
spurious, transcend-and-negate between the two non-concentric
dialectical critique, based on a lack of circles.
opposites for the opposite of opposites,
the absolute scope.
Spinoza’s univocal Substance, as absolute scope, is ineffable; polar
terminals are inapplicable to it. Rigidity, flexibility, passivity, activity—the
properties of the relative scope; of time and space—do not apply. In this
sense, Substance is both and neither active and passive, subjective and
objective, etc and non-etc. Spinoza says essentially this in his pre-Ethics
work the Short Treatise as we have seen in the Univocity Framework.

In a similar way, as we will see, Hegel transposes the immanence in


Spinoza’s Letter XII example into transitivity—itself present only because
transitivity is transcended-and-included in the higher power relations of the
Rational numbers, acting upon the new Immanent/Transcendent axis. And
hence this transitivity is present in Spinoza’s illustration as he integrates the
new immanent infinity of the modal or bounded infinite into the
transcended-and-included pre-rational transitive-axis of the Cartesian
number-system. In true Hegelian fashion this conveniently allows for a
spurious, transcend-and-negate critique further securing Hegel’s
representation of his absolute idealism at the apex of History.


Science of Logic § 565

Page | 418
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

In a remark in his Science of Logic, Hegel says (my emphasis):


The mathematical example with which he [Spinoza] illustrates the true
infinite is a space between two unequal circles which are not concentric,
one of which lies inside the other without touching it.i¥
This example does not purport to show “the” true infinite, but merely an
aspect of uncountable immanence manifesting in the bounded and lowest
order of the infinite, “…that, of which the parts cannot be equaled or
expressed by any number, though the greatest and least magnitude of the
whole may be known...” (Letter XII) The maximum and minimum distance
between the circles may be known, but no number can express in total the
differences in distance between them.

Hegel continues:
It seems that he thought highly of this figure and of the concept which it
was used to illustrate, making it the motto of his Ethics.
Spinoza’s Ethics deals with the interface between The Infinite and finite, e.g.
between “God” and man, so this is a natural observation, and no doubt a
main reason Deleuze bases his own interpretation of the Ethics on this same
example.
‘Mathematicians conclude’, he says, ‘that the inequalities possible in such
a space are infinite, not from the infinite amount of parts, for its size is
fixed and limited and can assume larger and smaller such spaces, but
because the nature of the fact surpasses every determinateness.’ It is
evident that Spinoza rejects that conception of the infinite which
represents it as an amount or as a series which is not completed, and he
points out that here, in the space of his example, the infinite is not beyond,
but actually present and complete;
This complete infinity is the positive infinity of rationality; the uncountable
immanence opened up with the “violation” of the closure property of the
integers in the countable infinity of the Rational numbers, and the same
immanence explored and operationalized in the calculus. It is indeed “not
beyond,” not transcendent to, “but actually present and [a priori] complete,”
within, immanent to, the boundary of the finite, in which it shares a polar
relationship. That is precisely the point of this example of the bounded
infinite.
…this space is bounded, but it is infinite ‘because the nature of the fact
surpasses every determinateness’, because the determination of
magnitude contained in it cannot at the same time be represented as a
quantum [[a number or boundary]], or in Kant’s words already quoted,
the synthesis cannot be completed to form a (discrete) quantum.


Science of Logic § 566

Page | 419
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

In other words, “no number can express” it, as Spinoza so carefully states.
Hegel continues (my emphasis):
The incommensurability which lies in Spinoza’s example embraces in
general the functions of curved lines and more precisely, leads to the
infinite which mathematics has introduced with such functions, in
general, with the functions of variable magnitudes.i¥
Yes, the curved functions are embraced in this example, but the infinite
space illustrated here is that immanence opened up not merely by functions
of variable magnitude. These curves, as we have seen, can be either
transitive, transcendent or immanent, and they could also be based on
variable integers. But Spinoza’s example specifically illustrates the relation
between two 2nd degree continuous functions, emphasizing, even more
specifically, the immanence opened up in the pulverization of numerical
identity in the mathematical ratio (such as dy/dx), and operationalized by
the Immanent/Transcendent axis. It is this relation of powers in the
mathematical ratio, transcended, included, and fully operationalized in the
power/root functions, that allows for the variable continuity at the
foundations of the calculus, and critically encoded in its fundamental
theorem. The transitive axis of the variable integer, or dis-continuous
functions is included, but radically transcended in the operations of the
Rational numbers. So without recognizing the prefused distinction between
the immanent/transcendent and transitive, this conflation and con-fusion is
understandable.
This infinite is the genuine mathematical qualitative infinite which
Spinoza also had in mind...
This infinite is the bounded 3rd order infinite; merely one type of
“qualitative infinite which Spinoza also had in mind,” but it is centered on
the new axis of immanence opened up to operationality by the ratio, and
represents the full-circle return of the finite to its source, in The Cycle of
Unity and origin-identities (as we have seen).

Curiously, Hegel goes on to say:


The expression ‘variable magnitudes’ is therefore very vague and ill-
chosen for those determinations of magnitude whose interest and
manner of treatment lie in something quite distinct from their mere
variability.ii¥
Yes, and ve vonder who chose it! Not even the term ‘variable’ appears in
Spinoza’s text, and indeed we are dealing with “something quite distinct


§ 567
ii¥
§ 568

Page | 420
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

from ... mere variability” and mere curved functions, in Spinoza’s example.
Maybe what follows can explain it.
...It is, too, only because of a lack of awareness of what constitutes the
peculiar interest of higher analysis and of what has led to the need for and
invention of the differential calculus, that functions of the first degree and
the equation of the straight line are themselves included in the treatment
of this calculus; i¥
These lower degree transitive functions are, of course, transcended-and-
included in the functions of the calculus. However, Spinoza’s example does
not explicitly use the straight line, but points to the difference between two
circles, each of which is a 2nd degree function, and the infinity in question
depends critically on this factor. In other words, there are several
transcended-and-included layers of “relations of power” in Spinoza’s
example; the relation of transitive magnitudes transcended-and-included in
the ratios making possible the continuity of the curves, the relations of ratios
in the 2nd degree functions of the circles, and the relation of offset between
the infinitely continuous circles themselves, illustrating an infinite and
uncountable depth of difference in the distance between them.
...such formalism originates partly, too, in the mistake of imagining that
the intrinsically correct demand for the generalisation of a method has
been fulfilled when the specific determinateness on which the need for the
calculus is based is omitted, as if in this domain we were concerned only
with variable magnitudes. A great deal of formalism would, indeed, have
been avoided if it had been perceived that the calculus is concerned not
with variable magnitudes as such but with relations of powers.
Hegel rightly claims (conveniently opposing his personal Spinoza) that “the
calculus is concerned not with variable magnitudes...but with relations of
powers.” This leaves the erroneous interpretation of calculus—as leading
merely to (or from) the infinite of “variable magnitudes”—falsely projected
onto Spinoza’s example, and it leaves unacknowledged the uncountable
immanence in this example, in the Triune Infinite in general, in Spinoza’s
Letter XII, and indeed pervading his Ethics.
This is where Hegel’s interpretive error lies. He erroneously claims that
Spinoza’s example is not concerned with “relations of powers,” but leads
merely to or from the infinite of the variable function. Indeed, what is the
mathematical ratio if not a relation of powers? And, as we have seen, it is
this relation that breaks open the immanence in Spinoza’s geometrical
example, regardless of the degree of those powers. Without the relations of
magnitudes in the mathematical ratio, there could be no continuously
varying functions, no continuous higher power functions, no infinitesimal,
no limit and no calculus.


§ 569

Page | 421
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This error is the Hegelian transcend-and-negate transposition of the


immanence and continuity of rationality and the uncountable infinity of the
bounded infinite in Spinoza’s geometrical example, into the mere transitivity
of variable functions. But we have seen that the immanence and continuity
of rationality is the key to the calculus, and indeed, it is the same infinity
upon which the power functions operate, as well as the “acategorical
imperative” of Nagarjunan/Deleuzian/Spinozan Emptiness.
It is immanence, and the positive infinity of rationality, as it manifests
from the immanent/transcendent omni-axis of uncountable continuity, that
is the essence of the calculus, and this indeed is founded on the relations of
powers, as is so readily observed in the key relation of the ratio, dy/dx.

Hegel continues:
Although the mathematics of the infinite maintained that these
quantitative determinations are vanishing magnitudes, i.e. magnitudes
which are no longer any particular quantum and yet are not nothing but
are still a determinateness relatively to an other, it seemed perfectly clear
that such an intermediate state, as it was called, between being and
nothing does not exist.i¥
We have already seen that Leibniz—in his more mature, Spinoza-catalyzed
thought—considered this “intermediate state” of the infinitesimal as a
“necessary fiction”—in our terms, an operational bridge between the
immanent and transitive-axes—and he got his key insight from Spinoza’s
Letter XII. Hegel is here reacting to, proliferating, or indeed partially
generating, the exoteric/academic mis-reading of Leibniz discussed above,
where Leibniz says that the infinitesimal is the number “just before
reaching” zero.
What we are to think of this objection and the so-called intermediate
state, has already been indicated above in Remark 4 to the category of
becoming. The unity of being and nothing is, of course, not a state; a state
would be a determination of being and nothing into which these moments
might be supposed to have lapsed only by accident, as it were, into a
diseased condition externally induced through erroneous thinking; on the
contrary, this mean and unity, the vanishing or equally the becoming is
alone their truth.
Indeed, the “unity of being and nothing” is “not a state;” it’s a fiction. The
vanishing act, and the limbo-state itself, is a function of perspective from the
relations between the powers of the transitive and Immanent/Transcendent
axis—or number, and the positive infinity of the rational, respectively. The
truth, as Hegel says—and as the aperspectival Vision-Logic Coordinate
System demands and allows us to see—lies in the limitless becoming of the


§ 573

Page | 422
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

unfolding operations themselves. This is the nature of the interface between


the finite and infinite; it results in indefinite or infinite becoming, depending
on whether we are referring to practice or principle, respectively. And this
is precisely the meaning of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite. The infinitely small
point is merely an aspect of The Infinite. The infinitesimal is a necessary
fiction because this immanent zero can’t be reached by the process of
division—dy/dx—underlying the calculus. Its numerical significance in the
transitive frame of reference of calculation merely falls off beyond a
perspectival threshold, and, for the sake of practicality, we end our chase of
this endless becoming.

Is Spinoza’s example merely an illustration of the infinity of the variable


curve—which, as we have seen, can be either transitive, transcendent or
immanent in its direction—or is it specifically an illustration of the new VL-
axis of the intensive relations of powers found in the ratio dy/dx? The latter
opinion is emphasized by Deleuze in this 1981 lecture at the Cours
Vincennes, transcribed and translated from the French [[my comments and
emphases]].
Here is the figure that Spinoza proposes for our reflection [[recall Figure
59, above, p419]]: two circles of which one is inside the other, but above
all they are not concentric. … Note the greatest and the smallest distance
from one circle to the other. … Spinoza tells us something very
interesting, it seems to me, he tells us: in the case of this double figure,
you can not say that you don’t have a limit or threshold. You have a
threshold, you have a limit. You even have two limits: the outer circle, the
inner circle, or what comes down to the same thing, the greatest distance
from one circle to the other, or the least distance. You have a maximum
and a minimum. And he says: consider the sum, here the Latin text is very
important, the sum of the inequalities of distance. You see: you trace all
the lines, all the segments which go from one circle to the other. You
evidently have an infinity. Spinoza tells us: consider the sum of the
inequalities of distance. … And he says: it is very curious, this infinity
here. … is an infinite sum. The sum of the inequalities of distance is
infinite. … And yet there is a limit. There is a limit since you have the
limit of the big circle and the limit of the small circle. So there is
something infinite and yet it is not unlimited. And he says that it is an odd
infinity, it is a very particular geometrical infinity: it is an infinity that you
can say is infinite even though it is not unlimited. And indeed, the space
encompassed between the two circles is not unlimited, the encompassed
space between the two circles is perfectly limited. I take up exactly the
expression of the letter to Meyer: the sum of the inequalities of distance‚
even though he could have made the same reasoning by taking holding of

Page | 423
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

the simpler case: the sum of unequal distances. Why does he want to sum
up the differences?

For me it is truly a text which is important, because, what does he have in


his head that he doesn’t say? He needs it by virtue of his problem of
essences. Essences are degrees of power, but what is a degree of power?
A degree of power is a difference between a maximum and a
minimum. It is in this way that it is an intensive quantity. A degree of
power is a difference in itself.i¥

According to Simon Duffy in his, The Logic of Expression in Deleuze’s


Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza: A Strategy of Engagement, Deleuze,
takes Hegel to task, and shows that the differential, or relation of powers,
can indeed be seen in the geometrical example from what he calls the
“differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus,” discussed briefly
above.

Duffy writes:
The derivative, from the differential point of view of the infinitesimal
calculus, is the quotient of two differentials, that is, a differential relation,
of the type dy/dx. The differential, dy, is an infinitely small quantity, or
what Deleuze describes as ‘a vanishing quantity’; a quantity smaller than
any given or giveable quantity. Therefore, as a vanishing quantity, dy, in
relation to y, is, strictly speaking, equal to zero. In the same way dx, in
relation to x, is, strictly speaking, equal to zero, that is, dx is the vanishing
quantity of x.
The differential relation can be written as dy/dx = 0/0. “However,” says
Duffy, “although dy is nothing in relation to y, and dx is nothing in relation to
x, dy over dx does not cancel out, that is, dy/dx is not equal to zero.” True,
“there is no relation between two things which do not exist.” However,
Deleuze, like Leibniz, sees the differentials continuing to exist “as vanishing
quantities insofar as they continue to vanish as quantities rather than having
already vanished as quantities.” They aren’t truly zero, but merely vanishing
beyond the horizon of the transitive mathematical imagination.
This is essentially the point of view already expressed by Leibniz, recall,
which he honed through his 1676 encounter with Spinoza’s Letter XII on the
Triune Infinite, and it invokes Hegel’s notion of a relation of powers in action
or Becoming—the difference being that Deleuze sees this becoming in
Spinoza’s geometrical example, in that the numeration or numerical
expression never comes to an ultimate end. The infinitesimal as zero (the
nonexistence of power), is a necessary fiction. Rather, it continues to exist,


Gilles Deleuze, translated transcript from a lecture at the Cours Vincennes dated 20/01/1981.
http://www.webdeleuze.com/php/texte.php?cle=191&groupe=Spinoza&langue=2

Page | 424
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

to vanish, to become smaller and smaller, though we necessarily call it zero,


in order to integrate the new immanence of rationality into the transitive
and transcendent operations of pre- through post-rationality.

Duffy writes:
Instead [of vanishing out of existence], the differential relation itself,
dy/dx, subsists as a relation. ‘What subsists when dy and dx cancel out
under the form of vanishing quantities is the relation dy/dx itself’ …
Despite the fact that its terms vanish, the relation itself is real.
The relation between the powers is still real because this vanishing act is
merely a perspectival illusion; a function of a default, static, numerical frame
of reference; the transitive axis, interfacing with motion beyond the
immanent horizon on the Immanent/Transcendent axis.
It is here [with this subsisting relation in the “differential point of view of
the infinitesimal calculus”] that Deleuze considers seventeenth-century
logic to have made ‘a fundamental leap’, by determining ‘a logic of
relations’.30 He argues that ‘under this form of infinitesimal calculus is
discovered a domain where the relations no longer depend on their
terms’.31
This domain is immanence, the sub-representational, the dark and
mysterious yin. It has been encountered and explored since antiquity
(perhaps most notably with Zeno), but not operationalized and legitimated,
mathematically and metaphysically, until the seventeenth-century, and
perhaps not “fully” until now with the deployment of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System of
Nondual Rationalism and Interface Philosophy.
It is not quite accurate, or complete, however, that “the relations no
longer depend on their terms,” but rather that we no longer need to
represent them as such, because the terms have receded beneath the
mathematical detail of our limited (finite) and transcendent-biased view.
They appear now as zero and we can no longer keep track of the still existing
relation. Yet beyond this immanent horizon, we are forced to take seriously
the immanent forces and the sub-representational field into which the terms
have vanished and in which they must continue to exist, because we know,
intuitively, logically and rationally, that the process of division in dy/dx
cannot finally yield the “infinitely small” and the immanent rational zero—
and this is the core intuition of the “differential point of view of the
infinitesimal calculus.” The space here is one of intensive forces, those
between immanent zero and transcendent infinity, and no longer those
oppositional forces between positive and negative trans-trans infinity.
According to the fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism and the
Law of Absolute Reversal, infinite division [i.e. boundless division] does not
“end” [bound] in the absolutely divided immanent zero, but reverses, at the

Page | 425
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

absolute scope, into its identical-opposite, the indivisible ONE. In other


words, the immanent “terminal” is the identical-opposite of the
transcendent. They are one in the same VL-axis: the twin poles of the
positive infinity of rationality.
To put it in other terms, division is a relation—the relative scope in the
art and science of pure relation—the identical-opposite of the absolute.
There can be no end to division, and hence “infinite division”—without
addressing or acknowledging its identical-opposite (such as in the PNDR)—
is really a conflation of scope, an oxymoron, a “violation” of the Univocity
Framework and nonduality. To say “infinite division,” is (in terms of scope)
to say “absolute relative,” so, as in the PNDR, it rebounds into its identical-
opposite, the indivisible.

Duffy continues:
The concept of the infinitely small as vanishing quantities allows the
determination of relations independently of their terms. ‘The differential
relation presents itself as the subsistence of the relation when the terms
vanish’.32 According to Deleuze, ‘the terms between which the relation
establishes itself are neither determined, nor determinable. Only the
relation between its terms is determined’.33 This is the logic of relations
that Deleuze locates in the infinitesimal calculus of the seventeenth
century, which he then mobilizes in his reading of Spinoza’s Letter XII, and
in his reading of Spinoza’s work as a whole, particularly in relation to the
physics of bodies in the second part of the Ethics.34
This point of view is what allows us to finally “perceive,” legitimate and
operationalize rational immanence and the intensive (non-oppositional and
nondual) forces of the sub-representational. But it is the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and its uncountable infinity that operationally
represents the positive infinity of the rational and the subtle identity of
opposites in Spinoza’s Substance/God (respectively), rendering it the
mathematical representation of the foundationless-foundation, the
boundless Emptiness of Nondual Rationalism.

With this “differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus” now in


place, Duffy is ready to show us Deleuze’s solution to Hegel’s negation of
Spinoza’s use of the differential in his Letter XII.
Deleuze argues that ‘when you have a [differential] relation derived from
a circle, this relation doesn’t involve the circle at all but refers [rather] to
what is called a tangent’.35 A tangent is a line that touches a circle or curve
at one point. The gradient of a tangent indicates the rate of change of the
curve at that point ... or the amount of slope of the curve at that point. ...
The differential relation is thought of as another function which describes,
at each point on an original function, the gradient of the line tangent to
the curve at that point. The value of this ‘gradient’ indicates a specific

Page | 426
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

quality of the original function; its rate of change at that point. The
differential relation therefore indicates the specific qualitative nature of
the original function at the different points of the curve.
This was basic to Spinoza’s point (no pun intended), that there are
numberless (infinite) different “rates of change” in any interval along the
space between the non-concentric circles, but he could have used any
number of different examples of various curves and/or their relations to
illustrate it. He chose circles, in my view, because he wanted to emphasize
the boundedness and uncountable immanence of the 3rd order infinity. The
point is that there are an “infinite number” of immanent differences in
“specific qualitative nature” (in this case expressed as “inequalities of
distance”) to be found in any segment of any continuous, bounded curve.
The image of the two circles just draws out this uncountable immanence of
the Bounded infinite very clearly.

Duffy continues:
... To put it simply, to determine the tangent of a curve at a specified point,
a second point that satisfies the function of the curve is selected, and the
gradient of the line that runs through both of these points is calculated. As
the second point approaches the point of tangency, the gradient of the line
between the two points approaches the gradient of the tangent. The
gradient of the tangent is, therefore, the limit of the gradient of the line
between the two points. Deleuze contends that the maximum and
minimum illustrated in Spinoza’s geometrical example are suggestive of
such limits.
In other words, using points to recursively divide the half-circle arc between
the minimum and maximum distance between the circles (See Figure 60,
below), we can draw a line between them to give us the tangent. As we
move from the outer limit to the inner one, progressively dividing the arc
segment, we endlessly approach the tangency of the minimum point (or we
could work from min to max). At some point, due to the set scale of our
drawing, we can no longer tell the difference between these two angles, or
their respective differences in distance between the two circles, and the
value effectively drops to zero, even though we know that with a true
mathematical curve the division of powers will never end and the tangents
and distances will never be fully equal.
Deleuze is certainly correct that the maximum and minimum in Spinoza’s
example are suggestive of these tangents-as-limits. It seems to me, however,
beside the point to attempt to locate definitively the specific mechanism of
the differential in Spinoza’s example. As we have seen, Leibniz’s solution to
the problem of the calculus, and his mature understanding of the infinite
came to him through his study of Spinoza’s Letter XII, and all we need do, to
further establish the alternate lineage from Spinoza to Leibniz—anticipating,
transcending and including Cantor—is locate the “differential point of view

Page | 427
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

of the infinitesimal calculus” in Spinoza’s example. This is already done,


essentially, but we’ll make it explicit here. But furthermore, we have already
seen the uncountable infinity of the Immanent/Transcendent axis as the
operational axis in his geometrical example, and underlying the positive
infinity of esoteric rationality itself. This is infinity opened up in the
functions of powers in their iopol-reversal into roots, recall, so indeed
Spinoza’s geometrical example demonstrates clearly the relations between
such powers, just as do Zeno’s famed paradoxes, as we will see.
The more clear reference to this
“differential point of view of the
infinitesimal calculus”—a point of view
so critical and pervasive in Nondual
Rationalism itself, as we have already
seen with its Immanent/Transcendent
axis—shows up in Spinoza’s example in
the sentence (my emphases), “However
small a portion of it we take, the
inequalities of this small portion will
surpass all numerical expression.” This
indicates directly that Spinoza is
visualizing these two points on the
continuous curve, giving the infinitely Figure 60: Limits on the
variable size on the Geometrical Example:
Immanent/Transcendent axis between The min and max tangents can be
the two points and between the two seen, Deleuze contends, as the
circles, and essentially saying, before limits of the function, while the
continued division of the arc
Leibniz, that no matter how small the progressively and perpetually
infinitesimal division (differential or moves toward that limit until the
monad) in the “labyrinth of the difference appears equal to zero.
continuum,” there will be an infinity, or This, Deleuze contends, is the
(to put it more accurately) “numberless” illustration of the differential in
Spinoza’s geometrical example.
more divisions within it—it never
reaches the point of zero. And the
inverse, recall, Leibniz found as the solution to the labyrinth of the
continuum, in that the implicit singularity of the immanent zero (the
extensionless point) cannot be found but as an abstraction from the
continuum itself, or, more precisely, as an abstracted immanent-local aspect
of The Infinite. The unity of the continuum is logically prior to the
mathematical point.
Indeed, with his abandonment of the use of these oxymorons and
absolute/relative conflations—“infinite number,” “infinitely small” or
“infinitely large,” to be replaced by the more correct “numberless,” etc.—
Spinoza is subtly enacting the “differential point of view of the infinitesimal
calculus,” in that relative (bounded) functions such as scale, or number, are
identical-opposite to the properties of the absolute scope, namely infinity.
Page | 428
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

The term “numberless,” in the immanent context of division, softly enforces


the differential view of the calculus as it enacts the Univocity Framework by
explicating the understanding that the infinity is not a number which can be
reached or bounded; the boundless is not a boundary, but they form a
critical underlying polarity which is key to both mathematical and
philosophical rationality. This in turn allows us to forestall the collapse of
the infinitesimal into the infinite immanence of the rational zero, and
maintain its positive value as a necessary function of transitive operations.
The main point of connection for this alternate lineage, in my view, is that
the immanent uncountable infinity of the “labyrinth of the continuum”
opened up stepwise and albeit incompletely by the higher level function of
the mathematical ratio, and inherent in any continuous curve or line, is the
essence of mathematical rationality and the calculus. This, Spinoza firmly
grasped, and indeed, in 1676 informed Leibniz of, via his earlier infamous
Letter XII.
So, according to Deleuze, the gradient of the tangent functions as a limit.
When the relation establishes itself between infinitely small terms, it does
not cancel itself out with its terms, but rather tends towards a limit. …
Since the differential relation approaches closer to its limit as the
differentials decrease in size, or approach zero, the limit of the relation is
represented by the relation between the infinitely small. It is in this sense
that the differential relation between the infinitely small refers to
something finite. Or, as Deleuze suggests, it is in the finite itself that there
is the ‘mutual immanence’36 of the relation and the infinitely small.
When Deleuze suggests “it is in the finite itself that there is the ‘mutual
immanence’ of the relation and the infinitely small,” he is referring directly
to the role of the immanent pole of the Immanent/Transcendent axis in the
bounded (3rd order) infinite [my emphasis].
The formula for the problem of the infinite that Deleuze extracts from the
geometrical example of Letter XII, by means of this seventeenth-century
understanding of the infinitesimal calculus, is that ‘something finite
consists of an infinity under a certain relation’.37
The relation is the mathematical ratio which opens the infinity of rational
immanence, and its intensive forces through the violation of the closure
property of the integers, and specifically of the “unit-closure” of the unit-
identity. Through this opening an infinity is indeed revealed or generated
within every boundary, segment, unity or number. That was the simple
point of Spinoza’s example.
Deleuze considers this formula to mark ‘an equilibrium point, for
seventeenth-century thought, between the infinite and the finite, by
means of a new theory of relations’.38 It is the logic of this theory of
relations that provides a starting point for the investigation into the logic
that Deleuze deploys in Expressionism in Philosophy and which can be

Page | 429
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

traced through Difference and Repetition as a part of his project of


constructing a philosophy of difference.
We will not have time to trace out the Deleuzian project in full, but some of
its elements have made their way into this resonant thread.
The Deleuzian solution offered to the problem of the infinite distinguishes
itself from the Hegelian solution insofar as it is not resolved according to
the dialectical logic. Deleuze’s thesis is that the differential cannot be
classified within the dialectical logic, which asserts the opposition of the
infinite and the finite.
As we have seen, in Nondual Rationalism the finite and infinite form a
polarity. Each is meaningless without the other. In Interface Mathematics,
the root of the finite, the unit number one, is formed volumetrically or
intensively on the Immanent/Transcendent axis.
The “opposition of the infinite and the finite” is a purely transitive and
pre-rational view, and in Nondual Rationalism it is critically an identity of
opposites, a polarity directly in line with the Nagarjunan polarity of
Emptiness and form, respectively.
Instead, Deleuze sets up Spinoza’s example of the relation between the
infinite and the finite as a rival metaphysical framework for the resolution
of the problem of the infinite, a rival to that provided by Hegel in the
dialectical logic.
The more explicit and empowered rival is the operationalization of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis in the rational numbers, with the move from
the positive and negative (oppositional) relations of addition and
subtraction, to the relations of intensity in the infinite space opened up
between unity (numerical identity) and immanent zero in the violation of
the closure property by the inversion of the input/output polarity in the
mathematical ratio.
The relation between the infinite and finite can be seen in the Triune
Infinite as the 3rd order infinite, itself an interface between the transitive and
immanent/transcendent axes, becomes the nondual interface between the
infinite and finite. Duffy continues…
Given that the method of integration provides a way of working back from
the differential relation, the problem of integration is, therefore, how to
reverse this process of differentiation. This can be solved by determining
the inverse of the given differential relation according to the inverse
transformation of differentiation. Or, a solution can be determined from
the differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus by considering
integration as a process of summation in the form of a series, according to
which, given the specific qualitative nature of a tangent at a point, the
problem becomes that of finding, not just one other point determinative
of the differential relation, but a sequence of points, all of which together
satisfy, or generate, a curve and therefore a function in the

Page | 430
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS

neighbourhood of the given point of tangency, which therefore functions


as the limit of the function.
Deleuze considers this to be the base of the infinitesimal calculus as
understood or interpreted in the seventeenth century. The formula for
the problem of the infinite that Deleuze extracts from the geometrical
example of Letter XII, by means of this seventeenth-century
understanding of the infinitesimal calculus, is that ‘something finite
consists of an infinity under a certain relation’.37 Deleuze considers this
formula to mark ‘an equilibrium point, for seventeenth-century thought,
between the infinite and the finite, by means of a new theory of
relations’.38 It is the logic of this theory of relations that provides a
starting point for the investigation into the logic that Deleuze deploys in
Expressionism in Philosophy and which can be traced through Difference
and Repetition as a part of his project of constructing a philosophy of
difference.
Duffy writes earlier, “Deleuze actually locates the differential from the
differential point of view of the infinitesimal calculus in the geometrical
example of Spinoza’s Letter XII by implicating Leibniz’s understanding of the
early form of the infinitesimal calculus...” As we have seen, however, even
Leibniz seems to have gotten his own mature, unproblematic, yet esoteric,
understanding of the infinite largely from his 1676 studies of Spinoza’s letter
XII. This, recall, was what enabled him to solve the problem of the
infinitesimal and to abandon the naïve principle, prefiguring Cantor.

Page | 431
Page | 432
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

Page | 433
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

In his book A Brief History of the Paradox, Roy Sorenson writes that
paradoxes are “questions (or in some cases, pseudoquestions) that suspend
us between too many good answers.” A paradox, Sorenson points out, finds
its strange stability in the dynamic equilibrium between two necessary
conclusions from a single question, premise or point of view. “From
engineering, we know that this kind of dynamic equilibrium is most simply
achieved by symmetry. When two boards are propped up against each other
(like this: /\), their equal but opposed forces keep the pair standing.”
To whet our appetite with a simple example, Sorenson asks, “When an
amoeba divides in two, does it go out of existence?” The amoeba has not
perished but merely transformed, so “no” she hasn’t gone out of existence.
Yet she is no longer one individual but two—she has transformed too
much—so “yes” she has gone out of existence. The swinging pendulum of
the answer, of course, depends on the implicit fuzziness or imprecision of
our general category of individual identity—the “it” of which the amoeba
implicitly is … or was … a special case. On the one hand the amoeba has
successfully multiplied its identity by two. So, not only does “it” still exist,
but in twice the quantity. On the other hand, the identity of the amoeba has
been negated in this very act because “to say that the mother amoeba
continues as the pair of daughters conflicts with the idea that organisms are
unified individuals.”i¥ And to satisfy our singular or “unified” idea of
individual identity it is an arbitrary matter to trace the single trajectory of
the mother amoeba’s identity through only one of the daughters she has
become. The mother amoeba was an individual organism, yet, without
perishing, suddenly she is no longer an individual. She has actually divided,
and now each daughter would seem to be merely one half of the “dividual”
that was once the individual mother amoeba. The individual has died to
become the dividual.ii
But what has actually been divided out of existence other than rigidity of
our implicit category of organismic individuality itself? What has been lost
but the applicability of a category generated in the anthropocentric frame of
reference of sexually reproducing beings and then implicitly applied to the
asexually reproducing amoeba? It is the category of organism as indivisible


(Sorenson)
ii
This is close to the inverse-identical to the Borg crisis of identity in assimilation. Instead of a simple
agglomeration, this is a multiplication through division. And for another inverse-identical in the
Leibnizian “problem of sex,” see Monadic Immaculate Conception and the “Problem of Sex”, p683).

Page | 434
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

then, which when implicitly misapplied causes this dichotomy of not quite
right conclusions we perceive as a paradox. The intrinsic precision of the
actuality cannot be reached by the imprecision of the extrinsic boundaries of
the category, and so we oscillate between the two closest approximations:
the mother amoeba has not died so she still exists, yet, in a real sense, she
has gone out of existence.
Paradoxes, then, are errors of intrinsic incompatibility in a
compartmentalized, categorical and dualistic logically descriptive system.
Paradoxes are dualisms. It is not in Nature herself that the dualistic
compartmental incompatibilities of the paradox reside, but only in the
oppositional categories cast upon her from above. From a different vantage
point, then—e.g. from a more detailed system of categories—we will see that
the paradoxes can, and often do indeed disappear. This disappearance can
come not simply by avoidance or turning away, and not necessarily by
“refutation,” but by the very opposite, by explicitly modeling the pivotal
detail inaccessible by the categorical framework rendering and generating
the paradox. Indeed the acategorical perspective of Nondual Rationalism
and Interface Philosophy provides a vantage point from which a new system
or level of categories can be constructed, with the resolution of the paradox
in mind. This is a large function of Interface Philosophy and the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System: to provide the acategorical and aperspectival framework
for such transformations to take shape. But this nondual system was already
built largely to resolve the dualistic paradoxes in a nondual fashion—such as
those of the infinite—as we will continue to see.

A system of categories can be thought of together as a transitive net cast


over a much more detailed and sub-categorical terrain. This is similar to the
artificial lines of nations drawn and redrawn across a continent—sometimes
along the contours of rivers or mountain ranges, but often merely
representing compromises between warring nations or competing states,
rendered as straight lines criss-crossing the territory in a purely ad hoc
geometrical fashion.i
The category, then, serves a transcendent and transitive (trans-biased)
representational function of power over the territory beneath the category—
this territory being namely emergent “meaning” and sub-representation.
Language or syntax in this sense is thus transcendent to and emergent from
semantics or embodied meaning. Yet syntax, in turn, symbiotically
modulates semantics from above, serving as a medium or lens through
which embodied meaning can be manipulated and further elevated. And so
from this already emergent vantage point it often seems as if semantics were

i
… and often times for the very purpose of conquering a region through this division of the collective
power of its people.

Page | 435
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

emergent from syntax, but the fact is that once syntax emerges, they are
symbiotic and co-dependent. They each engender the development of the
other. And it is the attempt of syntax or language and its rigid categories to
represent and modify the fluid contours of deeper semantics and sub-
representation (sub-semantics) that can often lead to the symmetric
opposition between two such rigid categorical conclusions.
In the EOTC, categories and concepts multiply through division, forming
an ever expanding and deepening meshwork of internal categorical
opposition—a sprawling system of polarities operating as opposable
conceptual appendages for grasping various differences in the mind. In the
paradox, however, we have reached the immanent limits of the categories as
they currently exist. We have reached the “limits of minimum (semantic)
ambiguity”—the LOMA, as Gerald Lebau calls it—afforded by the particular
evolutionary state of our system of categories. And if there is no implicit
understanding of the oppositional nature of categories and representation—
in the context of the intensive forces of sub-representation—then a
contradiction is conceived as something to be refuted and rejected from
above, rather than as possibly evoking a deeper truth beyond the
oppositional categories of the particular representational system.
The category representing the organismic individuality of the amoeba,
for example, is like the rigid board in the above image ( /\ ), in contrast to
the underlying continuity, possibility and fluidity of the semantic and sub-
semantic territory which it divides. When mapped to a set of facts which it
doesn’t intrinsically fit—namely the dividual nature of the amoeboid
identity—the category-system equivocates back and forth (yes and no, / and
\), trying to reach the intrinsic detail which its boundaries obscure (/.\).
Thus the category, expressed through the linearity of language and
conceptual thought, takes turns siding against itself, attempting to
triangulate on a detail, made inaccessible by the rigidity of its boundaries.
Like trying to pick up a toothpick while wearing boxing gloves, the system of
categories is too unrefined for the task. In this simplistic case, the
inaccessible detail is the fact that individual identity is not applicable to all
organisms, such as the amoeba, and a new category or distinction of
organismic existence as a divisible identity (“dividual”) is thus needed.

A simple analogy of the paradox emerging from the LOMA (limits of


minimum ambiguity) can be drawn from representational systems in
general. For example, imagine that there exists a representational system
whose categories are rigid line segments of a specific and fixed size, but of
variable position and angle. Everything the system represents, then, must be
essentially polygonal, according to that size and line-segment as unit. The
representational layer, however, is only one half of the whole system,

Page | 436
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

because there must be something for the system to represent. The other half
is a sub-representational foundation which autonomously and
unconsciously generates problems and then feeds the unfolding
consequences and solutions in real time to the representational layer to be
displayed in the form of lines, or collections of lines, such as polygons. As
such, the system is unaware of any of its processes (analogous to thoughts)
as anything other than polygonal. It knows only its polygonal
representations and not the problems and solutions represented from the
deeper sub-representational and subconscious level. This is a polygonal
consciousness which sees the world through a purely polygonal lens.
One day a curious image spontaneously emerges into the display. A
shrinking series of polygons appears—smaller and smaller until finally:
hexagon, pentagon, square, triangle … but then suddenly the display jumps
back to the square, then again to the triangle … square, triangle, square,
triangle… The sub-representational system has converged into a rapid
oscillatory state, flipping the representational layer back and forth between
the triangle and the square. The form appearing in the consciousness of the
system—as the representational answer to the particular sub-
representational problem—seems to be both and neither a square and a
triangle. The shape in consciousness is a duality—a contradiction, a
controversy, a paradox.
But what the representational layer (and the consciousness of the system
itself) doesn’t know is that the sub-representational form being converged
upon is a circle whose diameter is smaller than the line segment. The
system is simply trying to represent the area of this circle. However, this
quantity just happens to be a number exactly between the quantities
representable by the areas of the two smallest possible polygons: the square
and the triangle (See Figure 61, below). The square is too large a polygon to
accurately render the radius and area of the circle, and the triangle is too
small. But the real problem is that the area of the circle happens to lie
exactly in the center between the two, and the system’s only possibility for
coming to rest on the nearest representational state is a sub-
representational rounding function that jumps to the nearest numerical
value. In the extremely rare case of convergence upon a perfect balance
where the sub-representational system ends up in the actual absence of a
nearest representational state—i.e. in perfect dynamic equilibrium or
symmetry between two states where there actually is not any one such
nearest state—the system enters an oscillation between the two nearest
states, in effect averaging its area over time between them.

Page | 437
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Figure 61: The LOMA and the Paradox: A Geometrical Example:


The “limits of minimum ambiguity” (LOMA ) as leading to a paradox or controversy can
be shown through the geometrical example above . In this example, the area of an
unknown circle is being computed by a sub-representational and subconscious system
and then displayed and brought into awareness by a representational layer of
categories made of line segments of a specific size. The explicit and categorical
consciousness of this system then is purely polygonal, unconsciously getting its ever-
changing form and impetus from its deeper sub -representational basis. In this case,
the area of the subconsciously computed circle lies exactly between the two possible
representational or conscious configurations of the square and the triangle. The sub-
conscious system has no mechanism by which to come to rest on one of the
symmetrically opposed representational configurations and thus it begins to oscillate
between them, averaging them over time. The shape in representation is a paradox —a
duality—a square-triangle or a triangle-square—while the computation in the
subconscious is a singular and consistent whole. W e have two competing
consequences or answers, and without knowing or intuiting the sub-representational
shape which they are both attempting to approximate, it may be impossible to know
that both answers are as correct as possible (yet quite incorrect) given the limits of the
representational system itself.

Unfortunately for the system as a whole, it is unaware of the causes of this


oscillatory state, because it cannot see the sub-representational problem,
functions and solution, except through its own polygonal representation.
What is sees is simply an oscillating triangle-square or a square-triangle: a

Page | 438
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

paradox, with a corresponding “principle of complementarity.” In other


words, it can’t see outside its own system of representation: it can’t take an
aperspectival stance in which it could operate with categories of
representation which are not lines of that particular and fixed length.
Even if the system can’t get outside itself, however, if it could instead
“pulverize” its categories into much smaller bits, it could then represent
circles of a smaller size and the system would then see the “paradoxical”
square-triangle for what it is, just a small circle. This is the value, then, of the
acategorical perspective in the context of the Immanent/Transcendent axis:
it allows us to recognize the transitive limits of categories themselves, and
that sometimes their rigidity can converge into a symmetrical oscillation
between two equally valid and ultimately incorrect or limited solutions to a
deeper unknown problem. As in the simplistic case of the amoeba, very
often when using rigid categories to render an explanation, which the
categories were not designed to fit, we end up equivocating on two equally
good (and bad) explanations or conclusions.
The category, then, is like a system of pixels with which we can ever
more accurately represent our world. And the paradox occurs at the limits
of minimum ambiguity—the LOMA—of our categorical system. The nondual
or acategorical perspective, then—tuning and triuning the paradox—would
be the anti-aliasing function between the two closest approximations in the
particular categorical system. The truth of a paradox occurs generally as the
cultivated third between both of the answers (/|\), and the falsity of the
paradox lies in the limits of accuracy of the system of categories themselves,
including both of its paradoxically opposed answers.
This is the simplest “answer” to the paradox, which was honed in the
nondual traditions themselves. Opposites, such as the opposing conclusions
or categories of the paradox, are simply acknowledged as intrinsic elements
of each other. Like yin in yang, and vice versa, they are “identical opposites.”
Nondual traditions embrace the paradox because they know that the
problem is one merely of representation (illusion or Maya), in a dualistic and
oppositional set of categories. The problem sometimes happens then that in
the embrace of the paradox, they can often tend to hold onto it as essential to
reality or nondual philosophy itself. The paradox must be remembered as a
dualistic function of illusion and perspective, and it must be conceived free
from dualistic attachment in order to retain the possibility of seeing it as
one, from a different categorical perspective.
Recall, however, that the forces of opposition are central to the
transitive-axis and to representation itself, whereas sub-representation
deals with the forces of intensity operationalized by the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. As in mathematics, a new set of categories
(identities) is reached immanently, in the breaking of closure of the previous
set, and this occurs in the intrinsic context of the Immanent/Transcendent
axis in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System.

Page | 439
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The artificial modularity, transitive rigidity and compartmentalization of the


category, then, is key to the maintenance of the illusion of the paradox.
Sorenson explains this, naturally, in conjunction with our paradoxes of
sensation, the optical illusions:
After gazing at a waterfall, Aristotle saw the bank of a river apparently
moving—while simultaneously appearing stationary! … Psychologists
think the dissonance [[of optical illusions]] is irresolvable because our
visual systems are compartmentalized. Each mental module contains, as
it were, a little man (a homunculus) who makes rudimentary judgments.

For the sake of speed, the judgments of homunculi are based on a
small number of criteria and a few simple rules for processing the limited
data. There is no time for communication and deliberation.
Consequently, homunculi are dogmatic. They often lock into
disagreement. Illusion is the price that must be paid to evolve
perceptions that can keep up with a dynamic environment. … When all
the good answers to a riddle are the verdicts of a system composed of
homunculi (such as the ones undergirding vision and speech), then the
conflict is not rationally resolvable. …
The paradox might go away because something causes the conflicting
homunculi to stop judging. Some perceptual illusions disappear as we
age. A paradox might also be tolerable because we can hold an irrational
tendency in check (as when a self-controlled air traveler ignores his fear
of falling) or because we come to embrace it (as when a lover embraces
his jealousy). But there is no reasoning with homunculi.
Because our category of organismic existence, for example, and its beginning
and ending points at birth and death, are so tied to the category of the
organism as individual, we have difficulty when that category is pulverized
by the actuality of the organism as dividual—as presented by the amoeba.
How do we make sense of this kind of “individual” who is at the same time
divisible? How can we keep track of the infinitely multiplying trajectory of
this kind of identity … without generating new transitive patterns and
perspectives of categories immune to pulverization by this kind of instance?
This, of course, is the general answer to the paradox. If we want a
resolution to the paradoxical dualism—rather than just a traditional Taoist
embrace and acknowledgement of its status as illusion—then we must
create a new system or deeper layer of categories which exposes and
renders explicit the pivotal detail hidden and inaccessible to the paradox. A
traditional example would be Nagarjuna’s invention of the categories of
Emptiness and Form, which he used to pulverize the dichotomy of the
nihilists and essentialists.
As Einstein once said—the solution to a problem cannot be solved by the
same mind or system of concepts that generated it. The function and motion
of the acategorical imperative, recall, was precisely this: to seek ever more

Page | 440
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

expansions, transcensions-and-inclusions and differentiations-and-


integrations through the immanent pulverization of the categories. Recall
again our recent example with the “pure” categories (identities and
operations) of mathematics, and that it is always with an immanent direction
of operation that the transitive mapping, or rooting of transcendence (trans-
bias) is overcome, leading to a “violation of closure” and a transcension-and-
inclusion into a new set of categories or numerical identities.
But much of the function and results of the acategorical imperative of the
rational has already been transcended-and-included and differentiated-and-
integrated into the Vision-Logic Coordinate System, which then operates as
our meta-perspective from which the problems of the paradoxes will
naturally unravel.

Sorenson states:
Common sense may seem like a seamless, timeless whole. But it really
resembles the earth’s surface; a jigsaw puzzle of giant plates that slowly
collide and rub against each other. The stability of terra firma is the result
of great forces and counterforces. The equilibrium is imperfect; there is
constant underlying tension and, occasionally, sudden slippage.
Paradoxes mark fault lines in our common-sense world. Do these fissures
reach into reason itself?
This final question can simply and effectively be inverted. Can reason itself,
through the acategorical imperative, reach into the categorical fissures of
common-sense—the paradoxes—and find their common-ground in some
kind of deeper level of fluidity and emergence—some nondual form of
rationality that resolves paradoxes naturally?

To a great degree, we will find that paradox traces the very “backbone” of
nondual philosophy. It follows the curves of the “axis of Univocity”—where
the absolute meets the relative scope of logic and rationality—as it winds its
way through the transitive and agglomerative categories of thought itself.
This is why the paradoxes cluster around the interface between the
quantitative aspects of scope—the finite and infinite—as seen so clearly
with the paradoxes of Galileo and Zeno.
We will find, then, that what is central to the resolution of the paradox is
the relation between the transitive-axis—with its forces of representation
and opposition—and the Immanent/Transcendent axis—with its forces of
univocity and intensity. Recall that it is the transitive-axis that is the root of
the identity of the category and thus of singular perspective and its logical
operations. The dissolution of the illusions of perspective—the
pulverization of the categories—then, through the aperspectival Vision-
Logic Coordinate System, itself centered on the Immanent/Transcendent
axis, will be key to the resolutions of the paradoxes of the infinite herein.

Page | 441
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Through the remainder of this section on the paradoxes of the infinite, we


seek a new “plane of consistency,” an aperspectival “immanent plane” within
which the paradoxes readily dissolve. Given that there are hundreds of
paradoxes in existence, we’ll pick and choose only a few that can serve as
models of the Interface Philosophy method of resolution. But we’ve already
glimpsed this “plane of consistency” and methodology in action with our
principles of Nondual Rationalism. We’ve seen, for example, the paradox of
free-will vs. determinism form through the category error between the
relative and absolute scopes. And we’ve seen it dissolve just as readily
through the univocal Principle of Absolute Reversal, giving us the Principle
of Infinite Determinism: “infinite determinism equals indeterminism.”
We’ve seen a similar thing with the problem of continuity and infinite
division, where—according to our Principle of Nondual Rationalism—
infinite division equals indivisibility. But notice again that all of these
paradoxes and problems arise at the interface between the quantitative
aspects of the absolute and relative scope—the infinite and finite,
respectively.
This can also be seen in light of Spinoza’s distinction between the infinite
and the imagination. The imagination imposes its own finite limits (e.g.
perspectives)—the forces of representation—on the infinite, generating the
false infinite of the indefinite. In turn we will also see the maintenance of the
transcendent-bias and its forces of representation as key to the stability and
confusion surrounding many paradoxes, such as Zeno’s. And with the
disintegration of the transcendent-bias through the balancing rational
immanence of positive or deep infinity, comes the rapid dissolution or
integration of Zeno’s carefully propped up oppositions, rendering the
apparent duality into the necessary polarity underlying the whole of
Nondual Rationalism and Interface Mathematics. And we will explore, as
well, the controversies surrounding Cantor’s revolutionary transition
beyond our classical notions of infinity into the “transfinite,” and again our
Vision-Logic Coordinate System will be key to unraveling the problems. We
will find, however, that Cantor’s transfinite illustrates and clearly outlines
the contours of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite—his Bounded or Modal Infinite as
the primitive infinite number—and the global binary structure of the
holarchical embryogenesis of mathematics itself, as we have seen. The
transfinite is fundamentally two-tiered, matching precisely the holarchical
structure of Interface Mathematics, in its binary VL-axes and the transition
of operation thereupon, between the first and second “tiers” of number and
operation.

Page | 442
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

While Cantor’s transfinite arithmetic is not necessarily paradoxical, it is


indeed still controversial, and a controversy is essentially a paradoxical
dichotomy diffused through the social sphere into warring camps, each
spawning from and/or reacting against the same fundamental premise or
point of view, inaccessible by the same categories underlying the
dichotomous representations on both sides of the controversy. The purpose
here, then, is to further explain—tune and triune—the dichotomy and
duality at the core of the Cantorian controversy.

Recall again this quote from Galileo [my emphasis]


So far as I see we can only infer that the totality of all numbers is infinite,
that the number of squares is infinite, and that the number of their roots
is infinite; neither is the number of squares less than the totality of all
numbers, nor the latter greater than the former; and finally the
attributes “equal,” “greater,” and “less,” are not applicable to infinite,
but only to finite, quantities.” — Galileo Galilei, On two New Sciences,
1638
This is the classical, philosophical wisdom that infinities, as boundless,
cannot be compared as bounded magnitudes or numbers, according to the
part-whole axiom implicit in human percept-based thought. But the fact that
we are even talking about “infinities” (plural) tells us that we are not dealing
with the ALL is ONE, the 1st order Absolute Infinite, but only with either 2nd
or 3rd order infinities, Aspect or Modal. It is also clear that the set of all
squares, or all even numbers, is transcendent and unbounded, and at least
by the process of elimination that would leave us with the aspect infinite, for
a quick and easy resolution to the Galilean paradox.
Indeed, it is very easy to see the squares as the “aspect of squaring” the
natural number-line, or the evens as the “aspect of ‘even-ing,’” (the counting
by twos of the infinite set of the Natural numbers), and by the quantitative
principle of Infinite Unity (infinity in operation with anything else equals
infinity) we end up, naturally (pun intended), with infinity. Likewise the
Natural numbers are themselves an aspect of counting, or set-generating by
ones, and are already a 2nd order, or aspect infinite.

Page | 443
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Galileo’s simple unexplained-but-necessary conclusion that infinite


quantities cannot be compared, shines a crucial light on Cantor’s abstract
principle of the infinite hierarchy of transfinite sets. The goal is to give a
vision-logic interface for clearly and simply understanding the necessity of
Galileo’s correct conclusion, as well as the conclusions of Spinoza, Leibniz,
Cantor and others. But also we seek to explain the real meaning behind
Cantor’s pragmatic codification of the paradox into encapsulated symbolic
form in the redefinition of the infinite underlying the “transfinite,” as well as
his resolution to the Galilean paradox.
As we saw in the Pearl Principle,i¥ Cantor had to embrace the paradoxes
of the infinite and codify them into an operational principle, in order to
advance mathematics beyond the conundrum, at least at an operational,
syntactic level. To do this in the language of mathematics—and operating on
his own implicit tri-partite distinction, but without the nondual
understanding that comes from Spinoza’s Triune Infinite—he ultimately had
to treat the infinite set in purely mathematical terms, and so the paradox was
only solved syntactically or operationally, not semantically or sensibly.
Recall that infinity is no longer simply defined as boundless and that “…the
defining property of infinity today is that a set’s cardinality is equal to the
cardinality of some real subset of that set.”ii¥ This, again, is simply a
codification of the truth of the paradox as found by Galileo, et al. It is not a
sensible explanation or resolution of it.
This failure to sensibly or modelably resolve the paradoxes, is why the
controversies remain. They don’t just hang around because some luddites
are resistant to change and want to live in the past. Something was indeed
lost in this paradigm shift—a “Kuhn-loss” of the simple understanding of the
infinite as boundless. And in the shift to modern axiomatic set theory, with
sets as abstracted to the bare-bones of the category, there was a
corresponding loss of the implicit holarchical model of sets underlying the
human imagination, and making sense of the polarity and interface between
the finite and infinite. This fix, while indeed a positive outgrowth for
mathematics, was a transcension-and-negation, not a transcension-and-
inclusion of the truths of philosophy and experiential understanding,
interfacing with the infinite.
The holarchical model of sets implicit in the human mind lost in the
rejection of the part-whole axiom, was to be replaced only with the
abstractions of categories and their rules for relation and inter-
transformation in modern axiomatic set theory. But recall again that it was
this Kuhn-loss in the abstraction to the category itself that engendered the
early paradoxes of set theory, such as Russell’s paradox. And recall also that


See, The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite, p221.
ii¥
Dr. Reviel Netz, NOVA interview

Page | 444
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

much of the modern machinations of axiomatic set theory to reign in these


paradoxes have brought these holarchical truths back in the form of abstract
rules and axioms—thus bringing modern set theory itself back into line with
part-whole axiom which it had earlier rejected, but from a much greater
operational vantage point, i.e. less “naïve.” This is indeed why modern set
theory is now compatible with “mereology,” the study of the relations of
parts to wholes.i*
It is these meta-mathematical controversies, not the mathematics or set-
theory itself, that we aim to fix, offering a new integration of the paradox
with an understanding now afforded us through the differentiation of
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, but in the context of Interface Mathematics we
have installed up to this point. The pre-rational undifferentiated infinite
simply could not (and cannot) accommodate the distinctions being made at
the interface of the infinite and finite, and this resulted in conflations of the
prefused distinctions; con-fusion and paradox. But recall that Cantor as well
had a tri-partite distinction of infinity. His model, however, unlike Spinoza’s,
was far too simplistic and categorical to resolve the paradoxes—its
distinctions having no intrinsic functions and operable definitions such as to
provide for the triune interface of relations amongst themselves needed to
effect an integration.ii*
But Cantor’s “Absolute Infinite,” like Spinoza’s first-order Infinite, is
inoperable; it can’t relate. So Cantor, as we have seeniii*—operating at his
third and lowest level of mathematical, abstract infinity—devised a way to
place a value or cardinality on the counting aspects of the infinite sets by
means of “Hume’s Principle.” The controversy here, recall, surrounds the
assumption that the familiar one-to-one correspondence—used already in
the Galilean paradox between the Natural numbers and “perfect squares”—
can provide a means for assigning or comparing cardinality between infinite
sets. And for the Rationals, Cantor invented a new method of one-to-one
correspondence with the Natural numbers which he called “diagonalization,”
showing that the Rationals as well are of the same cardinality as the Natural
numbers, i.e. they are “countable.”
This “countability,” along with the acceptance of Dedekind’s redefinition
of set—or the blurring, ambiguating encapsulation of the part-whole
violation into the very definition of an infinite set—gave Cantor the means to
further redefine number away from the implicit holonic logic of sets, by
comparing infinite sets themselves as numbers. If, for instance, one set
could not be put into a one-to-one correspondence with the Natural
numbers, or was “uncountable,” it was deemed a higher magnitude or

i
* See, Implicit Holonic Set-Theory and the Part-Whole Axiom, p207.
ii
* See, Cantor’s Three Infinities, p268.
iii
* See, The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite, p221.

Page | 445
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

cardinality. But recall Cantor’s comparison of the “irrational” numbers to his


infinite numbers,i* and that with this new function of number we had
already broken from the classical notion of number as boundary into
numbering aspects of infinity. Naturally Cantor found that the set of Real
numbers, with its “irrationals” and “transcendentals” was “uncountable” and
together considered the next order of infinity, not aleph null, but aleph one.

Recall the binary logic of the VL-axes. In Cantor’s transfinite we can see yet
another manifestation of this dual or polar nature fundamental to
mathematics. The countable infinite is the first level of infinity and all the
higher levels are uncountable. But the countable and the uncountable
correspond directly to operation on the transitive and
immanent/transcendent axes, respectively, in their interfacing throughout
the holarchical embryogenesis of mathematics. Where the function of
number escapes the quantized limits of the transitive, we break into the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and from the oppositional into the purely
intensive forces of infinite depth. And recall this happened explicitly, for
example, with the iopol-inversion of powering, to the function of rooting and
its breaking open to “irrational” or transrational (e.g. transcendental)
numbers. This division between the Rationals and the Reals is precisely the
breaking point between Cantor’s countable and uncountable infinities, and it
is precisely the point where the function of number and operation moves
fully onto the Immanent/Transcendent axis, at the “second tier” level of
powers and roots.ii*

The nondual-rational or trans-rational view of the Triune Infinite—initiated


pre-Cantor by Spinoza and expanded by Leibniz—demonstrates a more
sensible way to understand Cantor’s insights, while keeping all of his
important mathematical and operational advances intact. In this view it is
made explicit that the “cardinality” or magnitude of an infinite set—or an
infinite number—is of a very different type from the cardinality of a finite
set. The difference is that a number—empirically, in its most common and
primitive or fundamental forms—is a boundary (or even a “bounded” or
modal infinite, in the case of the irrational numbers), whereas an aspect
infinite, such as an infinite set is inherently unbounded.
Infinite sets are conceived as algorithmic aspects of set generation (“set
aspects” or “aspect infinities”) abstracted from the ONE absolute Infinity. It
seems they have magnitudes, or we can abstract magnitudes or powers out

i
* See, The Trans-Rationality of the Irrational Numbers, p365.
ii
* See Phase FIVE: The Trans-Rational as Second Tier, p342.

Page | 446
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

from their interactions or interfacings—because we think of them in terms of


magnitudes, i.e. from numerical and operational frames of reference
(algorithms) from which they are generated. But really these set-aspects are
abstractions from the same Absolute Infinite (absolute scope) divided up,
abstracted or interfaced in different algorithmic ways (e.g. “countabilities”).
Cantor’s insight about transfinite orders of infinityi¥ was essentially that
every mathematical and “abstract” infinity or infinite set has within it an
aspect of the finite, in the Spinozist sense that, “in its kind,” it can be
surpassed by another power of infinity, or another infinite set.ii* In this way,
each mathematical infinity also has a finite “kind,” or aspect, which can be
compared with other mathematical infinities. Indeed, as Cantor showed,
each kind or aspect can be superseded by an apparently “infinite number” of
higher-power aspect infinities. This aspect of the finite in every
mathematical infinity is because the 2nd order infinity, the Aspect Infinite, is
derived in the interface between the finite and infinite, in a quantitative
frame of reference such as a set-generating algorithm. An example of such
an algorithm would be the ratio of two integer variables ultimately
generating the infinite set of the rational numbers.iii*
Thinking of The Infinite as absolute and numberless, means that one
cannot operate between absolute (aspect-less and ineffable) infinities (of
which there can be only ONE-ALL); one cannot add, subtract or compare the
magnitudes of The Infinite because The Infinite is not a magnitude, number,
part nor whole and in the EOTC it has not yet interfaced with the finite. As
the abstract identical-opposite of the relative scope—generated, recall, in
the univocal application of polarity to itselfiv*—The Infinite has no internal
conceptual relation or multiplicity which can be abstracted free from the
derivative relation of the aspect infinite or its modal interfaces, which are its
conceptual modalities—its senses. Abstraction into relation is this interface.
What is compared, added and subtracted etc. in the transfinite orders of
axiomatic set theory, are the various abstracted quantitative aspects, the
algorithmic relations, “order types,” and set-generators of The Infinite in
relation to the finite, not The Infinite itself. This, recall, Cantor clearly
outlined in his own three-fold categorization of infinity, by separating his
“Absolute Infinity” from both his second order contingent infinity (or the
infinite in the real world) and from his third order mathematical and
abstract infinity, such as his transfinite orders.


Notes from Spinoza’s Finite Modes: Explained or Explained Away?: 1997 Carl Brock Sides
ii
* See, A Foot in the Door to Paradise: Cantor’s Quick Fix, p228.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iv
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.

Page | 447
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

In Nondual Rationalism and Interface Philosophy, we can retain the original


general definition of infinity as boundless (apeiron), and simply provide it
with a deeper level of detail via our Spinozan triune differentiation. This
allows us to follow Cantor himself in a tripartite distinction, but with even
more explanatory detail. This detail allows us to explain how the triune
differentiation itself is formed in the interface between The Infinite and the
finite. And further we can see how sets are abstracted with aspects of the
finite (set aspects) in their very creation. It is this finite aspect in every
infinite set which is compared and ordered in Cantor’s infinite series of
transfinite sets, not The Infinite itself. We can then apply our quantitative
principle of Infinite Unity: “infinity in any operation returns infinity,” given
by our VLE for Infinite Unity, ∞Ωn = ∞. In the context of sets, then, the
boundless set is equal to its subsets as a natural function of the quantitative
principle of Infinite Unity, as would be expected from the absolute scope in
our Univocity Framework. Because set theory is ultimately concerned with
the unity of the category, then, it abstracts infinity to its most basic
categorical properties in the context of unity, which we have abstracted as
the quantitative principle of Infinite Unity. Given the modern mathematical
reduction to set theory itself, this explains why the mathematical definition
of infinity collapses to the set-theoretic definition which is merely a
holarchical function of our quantitative principle of Infinite Unity, as a pure-
relational abstraction of the ineffability of the absolute scope in our
Univocity Framework.

Page | 448
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

Zeno is reputed to have invented some forty paradoxes. But the myriad
proposed solutions are almost as old as the paradoxes themselves. For
example (and as we shall see in more detail), Aristotle employed the
distinction between actual infinity and potential infinity to attempt a quick
and easy refutation of Zeno’s paradoxes of motion. And, as discussed
previously,i* it is generally assumed that Zeno’s paradoxes were finally and
definitively solved by Cantor’s transfinite arithmetic and the modern
mathematics of the continuum. As explained by Sorenson:
Alfred North Whitehead remarked, “To be refuted in every century after
you have written is the acme of triumph … No one ever touched Zeno
without refuting him, and every century thinks it worth while to refute
him.” (1947, 114) I think this compliment will not be paid by future
centuries. There are still paradoxes involving hypertasks. None of them
overturns the verdict that all of Zeno’s paradoxes were solved by Cantor a
hundred years ago. Cantor’s triumph shows that some important
paradoxes can be solved. We now have answers to Zeno’s riddles that
satisfy the exacting standard set by modern mathematics. Twenty-four
hundred years is a long wait. But remember that the comparison was with
Sisyphus, who labors for eternity.

i
* See, A Foot in the Door to Paradise: Cantor’s Quick Fix, p228.

Page | 449
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Our purpose here is likewise not Sisyphean. We aim not merely to give yet
another purported resolution to the general Zenonian paradox, but to render
the problem and its proposed solutions in the clear light of Interface
Philosophy and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System. Indeed, we will come to
see explicitly why Zeno’s paradoxes hold such an enduring fascination for us,
and why Cantor’s abstract solution works. What we will find, however, is
that far from being an error in itself to be refuted, resolved and corrected,
the duality at the heart of Zeno’s paradoxes is a transitive, categorical
symptom of the fundamental polarity of conceptual relation itself which
Zeno’s pioneering thought experiment deftly tapped into. In the end, Zeno
gives a tantalizing glimpse of the fundamentally polar or nondual nature of
conceptual relation which won’t be operationalized mathematically into the
modern infinitely divisible and indivisible continuum until Cantor and
others in the nineteenth century, and which won’t be fully assimilated into
the social sphere until a truly rational and nondual framework of thought
(e.g. Interface Philosophy and Nondual Rationalism) works its way through
the collective consciousness of mankind. Until then, humanity may continue
to “refute,” rather than to understand the seemingly paradoxical polarity at
the heart of Zeno’s thought experiments, as they inch their way closer and
closer to functionality with Zeno’s “paradoxical,” and ultimately
Parmenidean truth. To understand this truth, then, we must come to
understand Parmenides and the Pre-Socratic context in which it arises.

Between around 600 to 400 B.C.E, the trajectory of “Western” thought


begins to leave its trail as the rudimentary stirrings of “the history of
philosophy.” In his book The Truth About Everything, Matthew Stewart
demonstrates that from these early, “pre-Socratic” fragments a compelling
story of conceptual embryogenesis and evolution can be pieced together
which will echo and recapitulate throughout the rest of the history of
philosophy. Stewart explains:
…it will become apparent that everything that would be said in
philosophy over the subsequent two and a half millennia had already
been said in some way by the Presocratic philosophers. The battles
among the Presocratics over first principles would be relived in an
astonishing variety of forms, but always with the same outcome.
Throughout this embryogenesis can be seen a transformation in the attempt
to define first principles, which themselves were wrested into abstraction
from the anthropomorphic tales of the Near Eastern and Greek gods. From
these early theological yarns and songs the first principle unfolded as a
unitary Chaos, Night or Nothingness—“muck,” as Stewart calls it. From this
muck emerged “elemental figures, i.e. gods, who fight among themselves for
control of the world...” Like the beginnings of mathematics itself, the

Page | 450
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

elemental gods begin in direct opposition and duality, polarized against one
another in countless battles which through subsequent generations
ultimately civilized the dark of Chaos into the dawn of an uneasy and
capricious order of operations.
The first recorded attempt to abstract this originary “muck” into rational
thought as a “first principle” came with Thales and his principle of water,
from which all the other “elements” would arise. Like the battles of the
elemental gods themselves, this water principle was then objected to by
subsequent philosophers, not on the grounds of empirical observation, but
as a matter of self-derived authority and logic. Anaximander, for example,
recognized that in order for a first principle to spawn all the elements it
cannot itself be an element. Thus he chose the boundless itself—the
apeiron—as his first principle. Anaximander reasoned that this apeiron
contained within itself the potential of all the elements, while possessing
none of their individual limits. Mirroring or echoing the implicit EOTC itself,
the Anaximandrian elements are simply separated out of or abstracted from
the unbounded unity of the apeiron. “In effect, by naming a stuff which is not
one of the everyday stuffs we know, Anaximander removed the paradox
involved in describing the whole class of stuffs in terms of one of its
members” (p42).
But history ebbs and flows, from progress to a seeming regress, all the
while gaining new (if hidden) traction in its endless explorations.
Anaximenes, for example, dissatisfied with the ineffability and abstractness
of Anaximander’s apeiron, selected air as his first principle, with the
advantage that he could describe how air could be condensed into fluids and
further into solids, and then liquefied and rarified back into fundamental air.
But at the same time he stepped back into the paradoxes of describing the
class of elements with another member of the same class. Subtle is the way
of nonlinear and massively parallel progress.

Heraclitus was the first philosopher to break from early Ionian first
principles as some kind of muck. In a subtle echo of Anaximander’s apeiron,
Heraclitus exchanged the problem of how stuff can change into other stuff,
with the more abstract idea that change itself was the primordial “stuff.” For
this reason he poetically described his first principle in terms of fire because
it is more of a process of transformation—e.g. from twigs and branches into
smoke and ashes—than a stuff or an element. Through this ceaseless
transformation, however, the ever-changing form of the fire remains. In this
sense, Stewart reasons, Heraclitus, like Pythagoras, successfully and fully
transitions from stuff to form or abstraction as the first principle.
Essentially, Heraclitus selected the nondual and triune interface between
the dual states of any transformation as his primal “stuff.” In this same way,

Page | 451
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

goes the common Heraclitean maxim, “you can’t step into the same river
twice,” because the water in the river is always influxing anew, and the river
itself is constantly in a process of change. It is change. This cultivating third
of change in Heraclitus was formalized into the principle of “logos,” which
can mean anything “from ‘word’ to ‘story’ to ‘account’ to ‘proportion’ or
‘measure.’”
Implicit to Heraclitean logos, we can see, is the essence of the nondual, in
that through it, Heraclitus reasoned, opposites ceaselessly transform into
one another, because in the deepest sense they are one another. This, we
can see, is a pre-echo Parmenides’ Being-now and an echo Anaximander’s
apeiron and it expresses an uncanny resemblance to Nagarjuna’s
pulverization of the categories and Buddhist dependent arising. “In this
synthesis of opposites, by the way, Heraclitus foreshadows for us a feature of
philosophy that will remain with us for the course of this history. The drive
for unity is perhaps the primordial urge of philosophy, and in the end it must
run over all the (merely apparent) oppositions which populate the world”
(p44). The “Heraclitean paradox,” or what we can call a nonduality, Stewart
reasons, “takes us to the bottom [our absolute scope] of the very idea of a
first principle,” which, as we have seen along with Heraclitus, reflects into its
opposite.
A first principle presumably is the form of everything. So what is the form
of everything? Well, it cannot be a particular form, like water or
squareness, for any such particular form would be dissolved into its
opposite through the form of—form. The form of everything, in other
words, is form itself. Everything, Heraclitus tells us, is part of the form of
the world. But to say that form itself is the first principle is to present an
argument in the form of a circle. The very idea that there is such a thing
as a first principle supposes that there is a form of the world. The
premise of the search is its conclusion.
We could end the history of philosophy at this point. In Heraclitus’
inspired hands, philosophy dissolves itself. It falls silent. But in this
Heraclitean world, alas, nothing ever comes to rest. Philosophy will
crystallize again and again, in countless new shapes, throughout the
course of our history.

Breaking the nondual silence of the Heraclitean absolute scope of infinite


difference—with change and nondual inter-transformability itself as the first
principle or logos—Parmenides moves into the contemplation of what a first
principle must look like. Through Parmenides, then, the history of
philosophy transitions into self-reflection—a second-order, recursive
“philosophy of philosophy,” which takes into account the nature—the limits
and possibilities—of the philosophical concept itself. Parmenides, then,
moves philosophy into a rudimentary and implicit post-ontological

Page | 452
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

contemplation of ontology as a development (or embryogenesis) of the


concept, rather than simply of stuff itself. Stewart explains:
From this second-order perspective [Parmenides] rules out many of the
other Presocratic’s attempts, draws his own conclusions about reality,
and articulates the central strategy of much of philosophy to come. … The
decisive move in Parmenides’ thought is to lift philosophy into the new
territory of methodology. The choice he offers us … is between competing
ways or roads. The Greek word is hodos. From this comes the “hod” in
our own word “method.” Parmenides is the first of the Presocratics to
distinguish clearly between first-order investigations into the nature of
things and second-order investigations into what it is possible to
investigate, or between methods and methodology. This move to a
second order is characteristic of philosophy to the present day. What will
later be given the fancy names of ontology, metaphysics, epistemology, and
logic are combined in a single Parmenidean move (p45-7).
This leap moves Parmenides into an aperspectival and primitive integral
stance on philosophy itself—a second tier, of sorts. And in this process
Parmenides recognizes that the Heraclitean infinite difference of the ALL can
only equate to the ONE of “Being” itself.
It is in this sense of emphasis on the unity and identity in the ALL, then,
that Parmenides argues for the ONE of his “Being-now.” He does not argue
against his senses, as is commonly supposed, that there is no difference (e.g.
motion or change), but merely that difference is relative and when taken
absolutely—to the first principles with which the early philosophers were so
concerned—it reflects into its opposite, the ONE of Infinite Unity. For
Parmenides then, ultimately—but only ultimately—there is only the ONE,
and his pupil Zeno will demonstrate this point over and over by equivalence
through the ALL in his many and varied paradoxes of plurality, as we shall
see.

We have already witnessed a bit of a crude echo into the very beginnings of
philosophy. This came with the recapitulation of the ancient theological
transition from muck into elemental gods, in the early philosophies of the
Presocratics, with their muck-like first principles spawning the elements of
the world. Stewart demonstrates quite effectively, however, that this kind of
repetition is ubiquitous throughout the history of philosophy, as the truths
of the previous generations are reduced to the LCD of the next, or simply just
forgotten to be rediscovered anew. To conclude an earlier brief account of
this self-similarity, we take up where we left off with our previous quote
from Stewart [my comments]:

Page | 453
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

… everything that would be said in philosophy over the subsequent two


and a half millennia had already been said in some way by the Presocratic
philosophers. … Parmenides’ leap to the second-order in particular could
be seen as the paradigm for almost all of ancient and modern philosophy.
Aristotelian metaphysics as the study of being qua being would be one
refinement of Parmenides’ project. Descartes’ discourse on method
would be another, as would Kant’s investigations into the conditions of
the possibility of experience. The forthcoming dialectics between reason
and the senses, between divine and human knowledge, were already
mapped out by Heraclitus’ skepticism about the transient world of
ordinary sense experience, not to mention Parmenides’ distinction
between the way of truth and the way of mortals [echoing the Buddhist
doctrine of Two Truths]. The Parmenidean One would merge with
Spinoza’s Substance, and its seedy Anaxagorean response would sprout
again in Leibniz’s pluralistic monadism. Leavened with the Heraclitean
logos-flux, a reinvigorated Anaxagorean Mind, and the Zenoian dialectic,
the One which is Many would return to itself in the form of Hegel’s
Absolute Spirit. The … question of Being would become the first principle
of Heidegger’s philosophy. Heraclitus’ intuitive misanthropic genius, his
attempt to forge new values out of a dead cosmology would express itself
again in Nietzsche. … His faith in a seamless form of the world, one which
could be shown but not said, would be shared by Wittgenstein. The
mysticism of both Eastern and Western philosophy was already laid out
by Pythagoras, Heraclitus and Empedocles. Zeno’s hair-splitting
paradoxes would first drive the Socratic dialectic, and then become the
conceptual clarifications of mid-twentieth century philosophy of language
[as well as logic and mathematics, we might add.]
The list could go on and on. Yet it should not be taken as evidence
that the Presocratics decisively influenced the course of the philosophy
that was to come, or that the subsequent history of philosophy constitutes
some sort of logical development out of these originary problematics. For
most of the rest of the history, it is more likely that the Presocratics were
pretty much forgotten or misinterpreted. Philosophy, as we shall see,
repeats itself blindly. …
The myth of the origin is just another way in which philosophy makes
itself into what it is. Even the Presocratics were referring constantly to a
past, to another beginning in cosmology...
Indeed, we have already seen (and will continue to see) how the exoteric
forces of representation have flattened and misrepresented Spinoza’s
philosophy, only to be renamed and reinvented anew. For example, and as
Will Durant previously mentioned, Hegel flattened Spinoza’s absolute scope
of Substance to a principle of the same, and subsequently re-appropriated
and renamed its lost truths into his own Absolute. And we shall see a similar
thing now with Zeno’s logical demonstrations of the truths of Parmenides, as
it winds itself blindly, through distortion and “refutation” into our modern
Cantorian understanding of infinity and the continuum.

Page | 454
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

Naturally our story must peal off from this self-similar historical trajectory
with Zeno of Elea, as the intellectual heir to the “original” second-order
philosophy of Parmenides. As Stewart said, “Zeno’s hair-splitting paradoxes
would first drive the Socratic dialectic, and then become the conceptual
clarifications of mid-twentieth century philosophy of language.” And, we can
add, Zeno’s paradoxes also forced into the open, critical distinctions in logic
and mathematics, and continue to do so to this day, culminating with the
validation and instantiation of Zeno’s Parmenidean conclusions into the
truths of modern mathematics, as we will indeed see.
As Karin Verelst and Bob Coecke argue—in their paper Early Greek
Thought and Perspectives for the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics:
Preliminaries to an Ontological Approach [my emphasis}:
[Zeno’s paradoxes] stem from what was perceived by classical philosophy
to be the fundamental enigma for thinking about the world: the seemingly
contradictory results that followed from the co-incidence of being and
non-being in the world of change and motion as we experience it, and the
experience of absolute existence here and now. The most clear expression
of both stances can be found, again following classical thought, in the
thinking of Heraclitus of Ephesus and Parmenides of Elea. The problem
put forward by these paradoxes reduces for both Plato and Aristotle to
the possibility of the existence of stable objects as a necessary
condition for knowledge. Hence the primarily ontological nature of the
solutions they proposed: Plato’s Theory of Forms and Aristotle’s
metaphysics and logic. Plato’s and Aristotle’s systems are argued here to
do on the ontological level essentially the same: to introduce stability in
the world by introducing the notion of a separable, stable object, for
which a ‘principle of contradiction’ is valid: an object cannot be and not-
be at the same place at the same time. So it becomes possible to forbid
contradiction on an epistemological level, and thus to guarantee the
certainty of knowledge that seemed to be threatened before.
In the exoteric history of philosophy, then, the paradox and univocal polarity
(the “co-incidence” or interface) between the absolute (the omni-non of
Being and non-Being) and relative scopes (“the world of change and motion
as we experience it”) was naturally prior to the closure and absolute identity
of the concept, as we see in Plato’s Forms and Aristotle’s principle of
contradiction, his metaphysics and his logic. This originary absolute-relative
polarity in the axis mundi of ancient thought, we will see, manifests into the
opposition of the concept through Zeno’s derivative “paradoxes,” and finally,
now, into the unity, polarity and triune interface of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and the Cycle of Unity.
In order for the certainty and rigidity of subsequent philosophical and
“Rational” thought to progress, then, it had to move again from this originary
intensive “muck” of fuzzy nonduality and polarity, into the numerical
identity of the category and the transitive and transcendent (trans-biased
Page | 455
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

and agglomerative) forces of opposition, for example in the principle of


contradiction. For Plato and Aristotle, then, contradiction—literally
“opposing words,” such as an identity of opposites—becomes fundamentally
threatening to ontology itself, and its manifestations must be refuted in
order to be resolved. Whereas before them—such as in Heraclitus and
Parmenides, and generally the whole of early Eastern nondual philosophy—
contradiction was accepted in an essentially nondual and necessary way.
This is why the beginning of exoteric “Western” and “Rational” philosophy is
felt to really start only with the general “refutation” of the Presocratics by
the triumvirate of “Rationality” and Order themselves; Socrates, Plato and
Aristotle i —pushing the “pre-Socratics” into the fuzzy, confused and
“conflicting” twilight zone of our Western proto-philosophical and “pre-
rational” horizons—back into the muck and Chaos from whence they came.
(It is indeed known, however, that Plato himself, towards the end of his
philosophical progression, recognizes a critical problem in his own
philosophy of Forms, in relation to the philosophy of Parmenides.)
Naturally, as should be apparent, this progression mirrors precisely—
though in a much more complex form—the holarchical embryogenesis of
number and operation—the rarified categories of pure relation—from the
originary, pre-operational and implicit Immanent/Transcendent axis,
through the oppositional and dualistic forces of operational representation,
and finally into second-tier integration and operation on the originary
Immanent/Transcendent axis. Rationality itself, then, we can see, begins its
operational, historical and exoteric trajectory in duality with the closure of
the concept, as the categorical object begins in opposition to other such
objects. Differentiating-and-integrating, transcending-and-including,
upward and outward Rationality transcends into higher and higher forms,
approaching closer and closer to the second-tier operationalization of its
hidden and con-fused nondual origins, and ultimately into exoteric
operation on the ONE-ALL of the Immanent/Transcendent axis, the
originary axis-mundi implicit throughout this entire evolution.
We can see this process most strongly indeed with the function of Zeno’s
ubiquitous paradoxes, which, through repeated attempts at refutation in
every subsequent generation, slowly forced into awareness and into
mathematical and now philosophical operationalization the truths at its
core—namely, as we shall see, the triune interface of the two fundamental
VL-axes of conceptual thought, and the fundamental Principle of Nondual
Rationalism (PNDR).
Through the whole of subsequent (post-Socratic) exoteric and uni-logical
philosophy and mathematics, the Immanent/Transcendent axis and polarity

i
But this is not to say that they each don’t have their nondual elements, just that their emphasis
pushed philosophy, and necessarily so, into the forces of opposition and conceptual, trans-biased
agglomeration.

Page | 456
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

underlying Zeno’s “paradoxes” would appear simply as a contradiction, an


“error” needing refutation and resolution. This polarity, then, winded its
way through various interpretations and “refutations,” each of which
injecting non-Zenonian premises in order to collapse the “paradox” into a
workable refutation—but with each resolution, rationality inches its way
closer and closer to truths hidden within.
As Verelst demonstrates in her article Zeno’s Paradoxes. A Cardinal
Problem, virtually all of these so-called “refutations” artificially introduce, in
various guises, the concept of time into Zeno’s instantaneous procedure of
second-order division. This results, as Verelst shows, in the confusion
between potential and actual infinity, first found in Aristotle, but
recapitulated in different forms in all the “refutational strategies up to the
present.” Indeed, when Zeno’s Parmenidean legacy and purpose is made
clear, it will be seen that even Cantor’s “solution” is not so much a refutation
as an acknowledgement that Zeno merely exposed a fundamental property
of conceptual or mathematical “space.” And this resolution merely takes the
form of a codification, operationalization (and ultimately a vindication) of
Zeno’s key findings into our modern notions of the continuum, finally
resolving—but merely operationally, not conceptually, sensibly, or
“philosophically”—the notorious pre-Cantorian problems of the continuum.
Indeed, as Verelst demonstrates in rigorous mathematical detail, the form of
Zeno’s simultaneous “through and through” division mirrors precisely
Cantor’s “Continuum Hypothesis” itself, and the uncountable, second-tier
infinities unreachable by time-ordered or “stepwise” operations such as
“supertasks.”

“Whatever it was that was refuted,” says Verelst, “it was certainly not Zeno.”
Generally what has been “refuted”—along with the exoteric caricatures of
Zeno and Parmenides—are the purely unsubstantiated and absurd views
they never held, such as the simple nonexistence of things and change. In
the common versions of history—what Verelst calls the Received View—it is
said that both Zeno and Parmenides rejected their sense data that
everywhere showed evidence of the plurality of things and change. Yet
every child knows that these comic characters are dead wrong. It is further
claimed that these patently absurd ideas—e.g. no things nor change—were
supported merely through Zeno’s purely logical paradoxes, taken
collectively as reductio ad absurdum (more like a reductio into absurdum, for
the sake of convenient “refutation”) .
From the start, for example, Plato fictionalizes an interaction between
Zeno and Socrates for this very purpose, however consciously or
unconsciously: to make Zeno’s stance appear absurd and make tractable and
possible its subsequent refutation. Plato writes in his Parmenides

Page | 457
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

(demonstrating clearly the scope con-fusion we’ll discuss below) [my


emphases]:
… Is that the purpose of your argument—to maintain against all comers
that there cannot be a many? And do you regard each of your arguments
as proof of this, so that in your view the arguments put forward in your
treatise are just so many proofs that there is not a many? Is that right, or
have I misunderstood you?”
“No,” said Zeno, “you have grasped admirably the whole purpose of
the work.”i¥
That “there is not” nor “cannot be a many?” How many words must this
Zeno character employ in his proof of this miraculous conclusion that there
is but ONE word? Can he not count past ONE… errrr … one? An absurd
character indeed, this “Zeno”—on par with the solipsist who tries to
convince others of his unique and controversial views. Indeed, this Zeno
would be a solipsist, if the many of his peers, and the many details of his
environment simply do not exist. If there is only one, then Zeno must be it!
Why then write those many words, my dear Zeno? To convince those many
people of the truths of your master Parmenides? Sorenson comments:
Many of the mathematicians and physicists who present Zeno’s paradoxes
assure their readers that Zeno is not crazy. They say he is just challenging
us to clarify our ideas. But the above passage from Plato suggests that
Zeno is not interested in prompting us to develop better theories of
familiar phenomena. Zeno contends those phenomena do not exist. When
an atheist asks, “Could God make a stone so big that he himself could not
lift it?” he is not inviting the theist to develop a coherent theory of
omnipotence. The atheist is using the stone paradox to refute the
possibility of God. Zeno is equally destructive. Zeno wants to serve his
teacher Parmenides by exposing the absurdity of all rival positions.
Sorenson continues in same vein, claiming that Zeno himself makes the same
point directly to Socrates. But recall that Plato’s “Zeno,” like his “Socrates,” is
a fictionalized character, serving Plato’s own aims. Further note that Plato
has a direct antagonistic interest in refuting Zeno and Parmenides, in order
to bring categorical stability to philosophy through his theory of the Forms.
Thus his rendition of either character is indeed to be suspect. Sorenson
gives the pulpit again to Plato, where he continues fleshing out his fictional
antagonist Zeno against his protagonist Socrates. “Zeno” says [my
emphases]:
The truth is that these writings were meant as a kind of support to the
arguments of Parmenides against those who try to ridicule him by saying
that if the whole is one, many absurdities and contradictions follow. This
treatise of mine is a reply to those who say that there is a many, and it
pays them back with interest; for it shows that consequences still more


Qtd in (Sorenson).

Page | 458
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

ridiculous follow if what is is a many than if it is a one, if you pursue the


matter far enough.
Plato again radically distorts Parmenides’ view as merely against “those who
say [simply] that there is a many.” But even Plato can’t distort Parmenides
views entirely out of sight. He simply glosses over the distinction that the
Received View also fails to see. The clues here, I have highlighted.
Parmenides, via Zeno, is talking about “the whole,” “what is,” i.e. Being itself.
He is talking about the absolute, not the relative scope of everyday
experience. Parmenides rejects the view that the absolute is a many and not
a ONE, not merely that the many of the relative scope doesn’t exist. Indeed,
“if you pursue the matter far enough,” is precisely the point. Taken to the
absolute scope of first principles, as Zeno shows, the experiential reality of
the many becomes the concept of the ALL which reflects into the ONE of the
Parmenidean “Being-now.”
While Sorenson and Plato may feel that Zeno and Parmenides are merely
being contrary and destructive, mathematicians know first hand the
constructive value in Zeno’s work. Much of the advances in modern
mathematics were indeed formed in response to Zeno’s paradoxes and, as
we will see, they ultimately vindicate it.

Through analyses of the original Greek texts Verelst et al demonstrates


further that the Parmenidean legacy is drastically misunderstood. This
legacy, Verelst shows, is a “phenomenological realism” and nowhere does
Zeno deny the phenomenological or relative reality of plurality and change.
“Zeno’s arguments are not a reductio, if only because the logical prejudice
that something which implies paradoxes cannot ‘really be there’ is itself still
unthinkable, since hypothetical thinking does not yet exist. When one
speaks, one does so not about a possible world, but about this world....”
In other words, it was not the case, in the ancient world, that a paradox
about something necessitated its nonexistence. Indeed, the only first-hand
testimony we have of Zeno’s views is that from Simplicius who had in his
possession Zeno’s book of paradoxes from which he occasionally quoted.
Simplicius states that [my emphases], “In [Zeno’s] book, in which many
arguments are put forward, he shows in each that a man who says that
there is a plurality is stating something contradictory.” Note first how
absurd would be Simplicius’ own statement and first-hand account about the
“many arguments” of Zeno, if he felt they proved the very impossibility of the
many. Secondly, note that in each paradox—presumably including the
paradoxes of motion—Simplicius states that Zeno merely demonstrates that
plurality is paradoxical, not that motion is paradoxical, and certainly not that
the many of things and motion are nonexistent.

Recall that Parmenides was operating at the level of a second-order


philosophy. This is the distinction which is not being taken into account by
Page | 459
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Plato with his fictionalized Zeno, Parmenides and Socrates. The Received
View, then, is a scope con-fusion. At the relative scope of the everyday ontic
and epistemic interface there is no such denial of plurality and motion
whatsoever. But Parmenides and Zeno were primarily concerned with first
principles, and hence with the absolute. And by taking it to the absolute
scope Zeno merely demonstrates that the infinite division of plurality is
logically equivalent to the indivisibility of Unity, and subsequently that logic
and rationality, at its core, is fundamentally polar and nondual—“contra-
dictory” in the face of absolute Unity.
But this is a given, since polarity is the most general function of the world
of conceptual relation, which of necessity includes the world of logic. In his
paradoxes of motion, we will see plurality expressed through the infinite
divisibility of change, and through the same underlying form the
simultaneously infinite division of time is demonstrated to be the equivalent
of the indivisibility of eternity manifesting in the Zenonian instant. Motion,
then, is not so much denied, as demonstrated to be indivisible, continuous
and ultimately ONE eternal and instantaneous Unity—the Parmenidean
Being-now. And this is naturally in conjunction with our PNDR, “infinite
division equals indivisibility,” and its Ariadnean resonance into the chord of
“infinite determinism equals indeterminism” and its eternal-NOW.

It indeed seems to be the case, then, that the Parmenidean legacy (echoing
Anaximander’s apeiron) consists generally of an emphasis on the Unity,
rational harmony or indivisibility aspect of the fundamental identity and
univocal tautology of the ONE-ALL, whereas the Heraclitean (and
Anaxagorean) legacy would emphasize its multiplicity, diversity and
conflicting aspects in the infinite division, difference and change of the ALL.
(Indeed, as we will see, this is the same polarity and triunity of emphasis
underlying the perceived and received view of the dichotomy between
Spinoza and Leibniz, respectively.) In the interface and “shock” between
these two, however, we find the unity in triunity—the nonduality and
resolution to all the resonant dichotomies, dualities, conflicts and
paradoxes—but most importantly, this resolution comes not at the price of a
negating refutation, but with the integrating shift in perspective into a
vision-logic framework whereby the polarity underlying the fundamental
“paradox” of Being itself becomes visible—tuned and triuned—as a singular
omni-axis of thought and conceptual/ontological unfolding—namely the
axis-mundi or I/T axis.
This “atonement” in triunity can perhaps be seen most clearly with our
Cycle of Unity between the Infinite and finite forms of unity—the ALL-ONE
and the “one,” respectively. This, recall, can be seen as an orbit, where the
axis-mundi of the immanent/transcendent ALL-ONE, cycles back through its

Page | 460
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

tautological identity with the ONE-ALL. To enter the orbit and approach the
finite unity of the “one,” however, from the identity in transcendence
between the ONE-ALL omni-axis and the ONE-one uni-axis, recall, the cycle
moves (simultaneously from immanence and transcendence) onto the uni-
axis and toward its bounded interface in the closure of the categorical unit-
identity—the unit of the transitive-axis. Then—through the equality of
immanence and transcendence in the ratio of the ALL (∞/∞)—the
conceptual cycle moves back to the ONE. This, recall, is represented in our
VLE — ONE = ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE — which itself represents the tuning and
triuning binary cycle of emphasis between the Parmenidean unity in the
ONE, and the Heraclitean conflict in the ALL.i* The solidus/vinculum
between the immanent and transcendent infinite in our VLE (∞/∞), recall, is
the very interface of our finite unity, implicit in the ONE-ALL from the
beginning. See Figure 15, repeated below.

Figure 15, Repeated from The (Binary) Cycle of Unity (p257): Polarity of the Forms in
the Cycle of Unity.

Most importantly, however, this Cycle, recall, also reflects through the pure-
relational categories of mathematics into The Binary Cycle of Identities, Axes

i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.

Page | 461
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

and Unities (p383), which acts as the triuning interface between the two
fundamental VL-axes of conceptual relation: the I/T and the transitive.
These binary VL-axes, recall, also represent operational aspects of the
uncountable and countable Cantorian infinities, as we have just seen in the
recent section on Cantor.i* Indeed, we will soon see the interface between
these two VL-axes and their Cantorian infinite aspects as essential to the
understanding—the tuning and triuning—of Zeno’s paradox.

Through con-fusion in the oppositional exoteric forces of representation,


Zeno’s “paradoxes” force into awareness a glimpse of the nondual
foundations of conceptual and categorical thinking itself. It will be shown
that the refutational reaction to Zeno’s thought experiments directly employ
the trans-bias, while conflating the pre-fused distinction between the two
fundamental VL-axes of pure-relational and categorical thinking:
boundedness and extension on the transitive axis and boundless immanence
on the immanent/transcendent axes. Indeed, we will see that these two VL-
axes—and their implicit binary cycle of relation—show up explicitly in both
Zeno’s original logic underlying all of his paradoxes, and in Verelst’s
mathematical demonstration and reconstruction. It is precisely due to the
trans-bias that Zeno reaches the Parmenidean ONE only through
immanence, just as we saw mathematics itself ever and only reaching into
new identities and unities through immanence against the pervasive
agglomerative functions of the trans-bias.
Sorenson echoes the exoteric con-fusion between these two axes when
he states, “… Zeno’s arguments pull infinite rabbits from finite hats.” Indeed,
what Zeno shows is essentially what Cantor and Spinoza show, the existence
of the bounded infinite—or the infinity of the bounded—and the polarity
and identity of opposites between infinity and number; e.g. the infinite
number. The finite is the infinite and the infinite the finite—in the same way
that form is emptiness and emptiness form. This perfectly harmonious
foundationless-foundation is the bottomless hat from which the
mathemagicians (even today) have always pulled “infinite rabbits from finite
hats.”

As Verelst demonstratesii¥—and Simplicius confirms “he shows in each that


a man who says that there is a plurality is stating something contradictory”—
all of Zeno’s paradoxes can be subsumed under one single mathematical
model emulating or distilling the form of his general paradox of plurality

i
* See, The Two-Floors of the Transfinite (p445).
ii¥
(Verelst, Zeno's Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality)

Page | 462
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

(PP). And this model underlying even the paradoxes of motion (PM)
(stadium included) consists of a simultaneous “through and through” infinite
division. This is essentially our immanent/transcendent omni-axis of
infinite omni-local division. Indeed, Verelst demonstrates through linguistic
analyses from the original Zenonian Greek that Zeno nowhere invokes time
for this divisional procedure. Just as our immanent/transcendent omni-axis
exists in the second-order eternal NOW of conceptual pure relation, so too
does Zeno’s infinite “through and through” division also exist sub specie
aeternitatis. And in the paradoxes of motion, the underlying simultaneous
“through and through” division is simply encountered and made manifest,
demonstrating the “infinite division equals indivisibility” of motion through
infinitely divided and thus indivisible extension. It is for this reason, argues
Verelst, that Aristotle’s distinction between potential and actual infinity is
untrue to Zeno’s premises and thus fails to refute him, as modern
mathemagicians, stage-hands and participating audience members all seem
to agree.

The basic Zenonian PP argument can be found in many forms. For example,
Sorenson gives a common exoteric account, following along with the
problematic and con-fused received view of the Parmenidean legacy [my
comments and emphases]:
Some of Zeno’s arguments bolster Parmenides’ [purported] rejection of
anything having size. If an object has a size, then it has parts [e.g. left and
right sides]. This collective is actually a conglomeration of things rather
than a single thing. Therefore, the only genuine individuals must have
no size. But if an object has no size, then it is nothing at all. Go ahead, add
a sizeless object to another object. There is no increase in size. If
thousands of sizeless objects were put together, they would still not add
up to anything. Since sizeless things do not differ from nothing, they are
nothing.
Notice here the implicit assumption that thingness necessarily equates to
individuality. The argument here—presented in exoteric form—is not
ultimately against things having size, but only against “genuine individuals”
or indivisibles (i.e. a-tomoi and absolutized finite unities) having size—and
therefore, ultimately merely for the idea of the infinite ALL-ONE. The
category of “thing” employed by the exoteric caricature of Sorenson’s Zeno
implicitly includes and hides the category of absolute individuality. Zeno is
not merely arguing against the existence of things, but against absolute
things, like a-tomoi. If we “pulverize” the category of “thing” upon the
exoteric ambiguity hidden within it, we can divide it into two categories:
individuals and dividuals (e.g. a-tomoi and holons). Zeno’s argument merely
demonstrates, and purposefully so, the impossibility of the absolute
individual (a-tom), with respect to the concept of size, and thus indirectly for
the implicit holonic logic of sets, with its implicit unity in the ONE-ALL.

Page | 463
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Zeno, recall, was arguing for the infinite and eternal Parmenidean Being-
now, but only at the absolute scope. At the relative scope, things can come
and go. Zeno and Parmenides merely state that ultimately they are ONE.
This hidden argument is very similar to the much more transparent
Buddhist argument against the Eastern equivalent of the a-tomoi. If atoms
have any size whatsoever they will have a boundary and thus they can be
placed next to each other. When placed together there will be one part of
each a-tom that is closer to, or even touching the other. Therefore atoms—
and things of any size whatsoever—are necessarily composed of parts (as
indeed science has shown, where it can). Only infinitely small points can be
free from a boundary and thus free from proximally relational parts. But in
this freedom they are also free from existence. They are mere abstractions
of location—aspect infinities and implicit singularities—with no extension
and no “substance.” Recall again our encounter with these points through
the Principle of Absolute Reversal. This occurred, recall, in the
absolutization of thingness and individuality in modern physics. And this
ended with the reduction of “ultimate particles” to mere points, resulting in
the “Inverse Unified Field”—the ONE-ALL of negation with its nonexistent
“infinitely small” points nonexistently flitting about the nonexistence-
incarnate contradiction of the boundless void.i*
Without the recognition and admission of the category of Parmenidean
“thingness” itself as implicitly enfolding the category of indivisibility (i.e. that
they are talking about first principles and thus the absolute scope),
Parmenides and Zeno can appear to be arguing against mere “thingness”
itself, and thus against the natural and common-sense correlative of the
infinite Heraclitean multiplicity of the ALL. Through their correct arguments
against bounded indivisibles—absolute finite unities—they would seem to
be arguing against relative difference itself—exoterically couched as their
arguments commonly are against mere “things,” such as we find in
Sorenson’s rendition. This is why their paradoxes seem on the surface to
contradict everyday experience, yet ultimately, in the proper nondual
context, they merely reach the founding principle of esoteric and originary
rationalism—not a problematic paradox, but a necessary identity of
opposites; a Heraclitean and Parmenidean polarity where infinite division
equals indivisibility, and vice versa.

A more telling argument can be found in the original source of Simplicius’


account of the “second Paradox of Plurality,” and recall again that Simplicius
himself was quoting and paraphrasing from his own copy of Zeno’s book on
paradoxes. And recall also that he was a student of Zeno, not attempting a
refutation of his own, as was Aristotle. It is for this reason, naturally, that all

i
* See, Chord 3 Example: The Inverse Unified Field, p117.

Page | 464
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

of Aristotle’s antagonistic accounts and renditions of Zeno’s paradoxes are


themselves suspect. If you are attempting to refute a paradox it is all too
convenient, when not quoting the original source, to render it in such a way
as to make the “refutation” more effective and possible. Simplicius writes
[my emphasis]:
For in his proof that, if there is plurality, the same things are both finite
and infinite, Zeno writes the following words: “if they are many, they by
necessity are as many as they are, not more nor less. But if they are as
many as they are, they will be finite [bounded, peperasmena]. But if they
are many, they will be infinite [unbounded, apeiron]. For there will
always be others in between of the beings, and there again others in
between.”
Note that this is known as “the argument from denseness,” and in
mathematics “density” denotes infinitely detailed or divided. Verelst writes
that the contradiction is that “if ‘they are many, they will be both bounded
and unbounded’.” In other words, Zeno, ahead of Cantor, demonstrates the
infinite number, and ahead of Spinoza, the bounded infinite.
Indeed, from these analyses, Verelst, following W. E. Abraham, deduces
from Zeno’s own thought experiment the “Zenonian principle of the
equivalence of the parts and the whole,” and we can see plainly the
equivalence of this Zenonian principle with the modern definition of infinity
itself. Again, it is clear that far from a refutation of Zeno, Cantor actually
presents the mathematical culmination and validation of Zeno’s
Parmenidean program. Verelst continues:
The point is clearly somewhere in the sentence: For there will always be
others in between of the beings, and there again others in between. Even if
not mentioned explicitly, this cannot be other than some kind of divisional
procedure, exactly as we conceive of fractions to mentally break a line. …
It inevitably follows that Zeno had in mind a division which is both
symmetrical and nondirected, i.e. one in which all parts undergo the same
divisional process.
Zeno’s own words, “For there will always be others in between of the
beings…,” specifically denotes an a priori and instantaneous division—an
infinite division merely encountered, not generated through the processes of
time and motion. This is the simultaneous division “through and through,”
underlying any notion of time and motion in all of Zeno’s paradoxes, which
Verelst demonstrates mathematically as equivalent to Cantor’s uncountable
infinite, unreachable by time-ordered stepwise processes, such as a
supertasks.

Page | 465
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This, then, seems to point to the intrinsic difference between algorithmic


description or emulation and real-world complexity, invoking our resonant
chord in the Principle of Infinite Determinism: “infinite determinism equals
indeterminism.” Algorithmic description is merely stepwise and thus cannot
reach and encapsulate the full continuum, whereas real-world simultaneous
“through and through” depth can access or emerge from the full uncountable
infinity of the continuum. This notion, then, would seem to have vast
reaching impacts in much of theoretical science and philosophy, for example
in the philosophy of mind or artificial intelligence. Given that algorithmic or
stepwise complexity can only be countably infinite, there will always be
something missing from any algorithmic emulation of real, massively-
parallel reality. This then shows the truth behind the intuitions of the
armies of philosophers-of-mind who sense that no algorithm can
encapsulate or fully generate and emulate human consciousness. The
solution to the hard problem of consciousness, then, may be a function the
resolution to Zeno’s paradoxes.

Verelst demonstrates this even more effectively through the “first Paradox of
plurality.” She summarizes the argument thus:
Zeno says that a) infinite division leads to an infinite number of final,
indivisible parts which still do have a magnitude, because, b) if they
would not have magnitude, they would not be at all, and so the object of
which they are part would not be at all. And an infinite number of parts
possessing, however small, finite magnitude, would give us an object
infinitely big. But c) given that the division is complete ('throughout'), no
parts with finite magnitude can remain, therefore d) the object
constituted by them will be infinitely small. Thus, upon Zeno’s argument,
a finite thing consisting of a plurality would be either infinitely large or
infinitely small. The subtle variant of the standard interpretation thus
offers us Zeno’s argument as a dilemma.
In other words, by taking finite division to the absolute scope it reflects (via
dilemma) into the two poles of the Immanent/Transcendent axis; the
“infinitely small” and the “infinitely large.” Verelst continues [my
emphases]:
The central point thus is that by being simultaneous (i.e., by occurring in
no lapse of time) the completion by division is at once, cardinal, not

Page | 466
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

stepwise, ordinal. This refers to the arithmetic of “infinity”, developed


towards the end of the nineteenth century by G. Cantor, who proved that
different kinds of infinity exist which he called cardinal and ordinal
infinity. Cardinality (“Zahl”) expresses the total number of elements of a
given set; ordinality (“Anzahl”) concerns the way these elements can be
ordered stepwise. … The infinity of the continuum is uncountable.
… Zeno’s procedure at once generates the uncountable cardinality
of the continuum instead of the merely countable one which would
be attainable when one interprets Zeno’s procedure stepwise. …
But this does not yet suffice to completely solve the riddle, because it
leaves untouched a related problem … : how to construct an extended
object out of parts with no extension whatsoever? Zeno cannot just intend
that his division generates the unextended points composing the
continuous line, for then only the ‘being nothing’-part of his paradox
would remain. Zeno’s divisional procedure generates an infinity of
partitions and a different infinity of parts at once and jointly in any
part independent of its length. The simultaneous and uninterrupted
[apeiron] repetition of partitions is clearly stated by Zeno himself: to say
this once is as good as saying it forever [aei].
Indeed, Verelst carries out this thought experiment mathematically,
rigorously demonstrating the veracity of Zeno’s logic. After a detailed and
rigorous mathematical demonstration, following with an explication in the
formal language of domain theory, she says:
We thus obtain the two kinds of infinity constituting a finite body: an
infinity of extended parts … which would generate when left on its own an
infinitely large body. And an infinity of unextended parts - points - which,
when left on its own, would generate a body with no extension at all. …
Conclusion: Zeno’s divisional procedure can be represented by a binary
tree, a Zenonian semi-lattice in which the nodes represent the megala,
while the micra are given by its paths, in two different infinities, as
follows: [[See Figure 62, below]]
These “two kinds of infinity,” naturally correspond to the interface, in Zeno,
between the two fundamental VL-axes of mathematics itself, corresponding
as well (in any stepwise instantiation) to Cantor’s countable and
uncountable infinities, as we have seen. These are, respectively, our
transitive and I/T axes. The infinity formed of extended parts—the megala
or parts, and represented by the nodes—corresponds to the transitive axis.
And the infinity of the unextended parts—the micra or partitions,
represented by the paths—corresponds to the immanent pole of the I/T
omni-axis. Note as well how the transitive nodes generate the transcendent
infinite, confirming yet again the repeated coincidence and mapping of
transcendence via transitivity, as in our trans-bias.

Page | 467
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

For in two ways it can be said that a distance or a period or any other
continuum is infinite [apeiron], viz., with respect to the partitions or with
respect to the projecting parts [Aristotle, Phys. Z, 2, 263a (24-26)].

For whoever divides the continuum into two halves thereby confers a double
function on the point of division, for he makes it both a beginning and an end
[Phys. Θ 8, 263a (23-25)].

Figure 62: Verelst’s Zenonian Binary Tree and Semi-Lattice:


Copied from (Verelst, Zeno's Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality)

Page | 468
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

We have no first hand account of Zeno’s paradoxes of motion, rather they are
rendered for us by Aristotle, who was simultaneously attempting to refute
them. (For some reason Aristotle did not attempt a refutation of the
underlying and critical PP. Perhaps the PM were easier, given that through
them Aristotle could inject non-Zenonian time, to make his distinction
between potential and actual infinity.) Verelst writes:
Zeno’s famous Paradoxes of Motion are transmitted to us by Aristotle
[Phys., Z 9, 239b], with the comment that they are notoriously difficult to
refute. And indeed attempts to either refute, [or] resolve them have been
at the order of the day up to the present: no one has ever touched Zeno
without refuting him, and every century thinks it worthwhile to refute him.
Let it suffice to say that, however relevant in themselves for future
developments in, say, mathematics, all presumed refutations hinge on
non-Zenonian premises, so that, whatever it was that was refuted, it
was certainly not Zeno.
As stated previously, Verelst demonstrates that all of Zeno’s paradoxes of
motion (PM)—including even the stadium paradox—can be subsumed
under the timeless and instantaneous form of the general paradox of
plurality (PP), rendered into mathematical rigor, above, and explained in her
paper in the formal language of domain theory. Verelst writes [my
emphasis]:
It would moreover be quite strange that Zeno, in order to defend
Parmenides’ stance with respect to the deictical unreality of time [i.e. time
as illusory with respect to the absolute of the Being-now], would
introduce it to make his point. …
… Our analysis of PP thus should be applicable to PM as well. The
reason invariably is that “to move” implies “to count the uncountable”

In other words, the tables have turned on Aristotle. It is the uncountable
infinite of the ignored PP which already exists as the actual infinite
underlying all of the PM. And further, it is divisible movement that takes on
the time-ordered, stepwise function of the potentially infinite, never able to
reach the immanent pole of the actually existing omni-axis within which
motion acts.
Bell puts it like this: Continuity and discreteness are united in the process of
measurement in which the continuous is expressed in terms of separate
units, that is numbers. …

Page | 469
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

This modern view, incidentally, is similar to Leibniz’s analysis of the


continuum from the viewpoint of Spinoza’s earlier and quite prescient
Triune Infinite, where points and boundaries are merely abstracted out as
aspects (termini or folds) of The Infinite. And in Interface Mathematics,
recall, it is the immanence of the continuum that is prior to the first unit
itself in the Cycle of Unity. Verelst continues [my emphasis]…
This is the fundamental point one looses out of sight when one throws
actual infinity out. One assumption implicitly underlying the execution of
Zeno’s procedure—we touched it already before, but here it becomes
particularly relevant—is the onedimensional, horizontal orientation
of the divisional process. This assumption allows Zeno to go over
without any further ado from plurality at rest to plurality in motion.
When one reads the PM-fragments from this angle, the astonishing
coherence of the arguments immediately hits the eye.
From this angle one sees that all of paradoxes of motion (PM) are merely
implications of the general underlying PP structure—the infinite division
and plurality underlying change or motion. Motion, then, merely brings out,
or makes explicit the paradoxical aspects of plurality already demonstrated
in the PP arguments.
Verelst says, “Zeno’s point precisely is to show that, however small the
distance, the number of parts to cross will remain the same,” and this again
illustrates the Zenonian Principle presaging our modern definition of the
infinite as equal to its subsets. It also foreshadows Cantor’s findings that any
segment of the continuum, no matter the size, will have the same cardinality
as any other or as the whole. Verelst continues [my comments]:
Time, being related to distance, is irrelevant in exactly the same way as
the length of our measuring rod was irrelevant. … 'To count the
uncountable' is thus the motion-face of the plurality-coin, which, as the
reader will remember, can be summed up in the slogan 'to consist out of
parts with and without magnitude'. One sees that Aristotle’s choice, far
from being arbitrary, was to pick out exactly those renderings (from an
undoubtedly larger corpus [purportedly some 40 odd paradoxes]) that
develop the paradox step by step, in order to lay bare its many faces, and
to bring out why it is so difficult to resolve. But although the Stagirite
realised the nature of the underlying problem, he apparently did not
believe that Zeno himself did. This—together with the fact that we know
Aristotle’s analysis only from lecture notes taken by his students—
explains methinks their somewhat muddled-up phrasing and sometimes
cumbersome argumentative development.
Verelst then organizes the paradoxes of motion—as received via Aristotle
and now fully subsumed as the many faces of the PP—according to
increasing perplexity.

Page | 470
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

According to Verelst, the Dichotomy or Runner Paradox is the simplest or


least perplexing of the bunch. Aristotle gives us the Received View of the
argument as follows [from Verelst, with my [[comments]] and emphases]:
The first [argument] is the one which declares movement to be
impossible [[or simply contradictory and ultimately polar and nondual]]
because, however near the mobile is to any given point, it will always
have to cover the half, and then the half of that, end so without end before
it gets to the goal. (...) Hence Zeno’s argument makes a false assumption in
asserting that it is impossible to pass over an infinity or to touch one by
one infinitely many in a finite time. For there are two senses in which
length and time and the continuum in general are said to be
unbounded: with respect to partition and with respect to the
extended parts. Therefore it cannot be assumed possible to touch an
infinite quantity of things [i.e., parts] in a finite time, though this can be
assumed for partition, because time itself is infinite in the same way.
The Received View then, is that this paradox demonstrates that “motion
cannot take a start,” but in reality Zeno was demonstrating merely that if we
conceive of motion as ultimately consisting of a stepwise plurality of
infinitely divisible parts, then motion is impossible—stepwise and merely
countable infinity can’t account for the instantaneous uncountable
continuity of Zenonian plurality underlying that motion.
Again, the tables have turned on Aristotle. If we take the rather
commonsensical view that motion is not made of parts, however, then we
are simply siding with Zeno and Parmenides and they (or we) have won.
Motion is ultimately indivisible: one eternal Being-now. In Nondual
Rationalism, however, we know that they are ultimately the same, because
when infinite division is conceived “through and through” outside of time it
is of the order of the mathematical continuum, and then “infinite division
equals indivisibility.”
Verelst notes that Aristotle cleverly injected the notion of time into
Zenonian plurality with the phrase, “Hence Zeno’s argument makes a false
assumption in asserting that it is impossible to pass over an infinity or to
touch one by one infinitely many in a finite time.” Verelst says that Zeno
never mentions time. And it is with the introduction of non-Zenonian time
here that Aristotle generates his false refutation based on potential vs. actual
infinity.

The next paradox in ascending order of perplexity, according to Verelst, is


the Achilles. Aristotle explains it thus:

Page | 471
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The second [argument] is the so-called Achilles. This is that the slowest
runner will never be overtaken by the swiftest, since the pursuer must
first reach the point from which the pursued started, and so the slower
must always be ahead. This argument is essentially the same as that
depending on dichotomy, but differs from it in that the added lengths are
not divided into halves.
Aristotle precisely notes that this argument is essentially the same as the
Dichotomy. However, “The case is slightly more complicated,” Verelst notes,
“by the fact that both the moving body and the goal to attain are themselves
in motion, but the complication is not substantial, as Aristotle points out
himself: it merely implies that the distances to cross will not decrease
symmetrically.” Verelst continues:
The received view presents us Zeno’s argumentation as flawed by an
elementary mathematical error, due to a lack of mathematical
sophistication. In accordance with Aristotle’s distorted rendering of
Zeno’s argument, it is presented as a potentially infinite sequence
decreasing geometrically… the sum of which can very well have a finite
total, because the underlying sequence converges to its finite Cauchy-
limit.
Verelst continues to show that this view has already been challenged by
Vlastos, who, “given his direct acquaintance with the sources of ancient
Greek thought” was “at unease” with this modern interpretation. He then
finds another interpretation that requires a countably infinite number of
steps, a “supertask,” which is generally considered possible in certain
circumstances. Because a supertask is a time-ordered procedure, however,
it is essentially Aristotle’s potential infinite argument in another guise and
with a possible refutation. The false assumption on both of these accounts is
that Zeno’s infinite division is stepwise and thus countable, and thus the
purported resolution via supertask is also a non-starter. Verelst continues:
But although we ever only make finitely many steps, even if we could
make countably many, the stretches to cross would be uncountable in
number. Thus a Zenonian supertask properly speaking would require an
infinity of acts in no time!

“This argument,” says Verelst, “traditionally known as the fourth argument


logically is the third, because it simply combines the former two. What
happens when two measuring rods … pass each other at constant velocity in
opposite directions? So we now not only consider the relation rest/motion,
but motion/motion as well.” To me it is the least compelling of the bunch
because its underlying truths can so readily and easily be con-fused, but
we’ll include it here for reasons of completeness.

Page | 472
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

Sorenson gives a simple, and traditionally distorted account of the


Stadium Paradox as follows:
The final paradox of motion concerns opposite movement of objects in
front of fixed observers in a stadium…[See Figure 63, below].

BEFORE AFTER

A A A A A A A A
B B B B B B B B
C C C C C C C C

Figure 63: Zeno’s Stadium Paradox:


Adapted from fig. 4.4 in Sorenson’s A Brief History of the Paradox.

Let AAAA represent the fans. Let BBBB and CCCC Represent two complex
bodies that move in opposite directions at equal speed until they are
aligned with the fans. Is this convergence possible? After moving, the first
B has moved past two As. Yet the first C has passed four Bs. Therefore, the
first C has moved twice as fast as the first B. This contradicts the opening
assumption that the blocks were moving at equal speeds.

ARISTOTLE’S SOLUTION
I remember having trouble understanding the stadium paradox. Doesn’t
Zeno realize that velocity is relative? BBBB and CCCC are moving equally
fast with respect to AAAA but are moving twice as fast with respect to
each other. Aristotle’s solution to the “paradox” simply draws the
distinction we find so obvious. I thought this was uncharitable to Zeno;
could such a brilliant philosopher be guilty of so obvious an equivocation?
Given that ultimately the same paradox of plurality underlies this paradox as
well, as usual, things are not as simple as they might seem. First of all, the
exoteric Received View doesn’t mention at all the infinite division “through
and through” of the PP underlying this paradox. It simply mentions a
doubling of speed, which is time/distance. Sorenson’s rendition is then
another example of Zeno’s simultaneous through and through division not
only ignored, but also injected with the non-Zenonian premise of time.
Secondly, repeating Verelst from before, “Time, being related to distance, is
irrelevant in exactly the same way as the length of our measuring rod was
irrelevant.” The uncountable infinite Zenonian plurality of each passing
body exists prior to the stepwise and merely countable act of mutual
measurement. “‘To count the uncountable’ is thus the motion-face of the
plurality-coin,” says Verelst. She continues [my emphases]:
The Received View here is that Zeno did not understand the (Galilean)
relativity governing the motions of bodies in inertially moving frames of

Page | 473
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

reference, as in the case of two cars crossing each other with equal speed
on a high way: The unanimous verdict on Zeno is that he was hopelessly
confused about relative velocity in this paradox. But in Zeno’s description,
every part at every moment faces its doubling by division, whether it be
in comparison to a stable measuring rod, or a rod passing by. The
problem arises from the fact that, because of simultaneous through-
and-through division, “to double” here involves a transition from
ordinal to cardinal, from countable to uncountable, from potential to
actual infinity. The infamous “doubling of the times” only takes into
account the potential, stepwise part of the argument. For of course, every
body, while being a continuum, “touches” (counts) the other one
everywhere when it passes (measures). It remains just the same
cardinal problem. Their speed proportional to each other does not
change anything to this fact, analogous to what we saw with the Achilles:
they are at every moment passing each other at infinitely many parts,
which, by facing each other’s unlimited division, count each other’s
uncountability.
Thus, Verelst demonstrates, even Zeno’s Stadium paradox has not been
refuted, given the same paradox of plurality underlying it which even
Aristotle did not attempt to refute. Verelst reminds us, however, “Let us
stress once more that Zeno does not imply that motion does not exist,
only that it is paradoxical.”

The Arrow paradox is traditionally known as the most perplexing of them all
because, writes Verelst, “the only thing that remains is the naked paradox.”
Verelst gives Aristotle’s account of the paradox as follows [my emphases]:
The Third is that just given above, that the flying arrow is at rest. This
conclusion follows from the assumption that time is composed of
instants; for if this is not granted the conclusion cannot be inferred.
We find a more detailed account in Sorenson, however:
The third paradox asks whether a moving arrow is at rest. An arrow is at
rest if it is in a place equal to itself. At any given moment, even a very
speedy arrow cannot be where it is not. Therefore, it must be where it is,
and so in a place equal to itself. So a flying arrow cannot move.
This paradox, says Verelst, “radicalizes the reasoning by combining the first
two arguments pointwise, so that the contradiction plainly arises.” In
“refuting” this “naked paradox,” and because “it does not leave any room for
anything timelike to be smuggled in,” says Verelst, Aristotle has to resort to
the premise of the “parallelism of divisibility of space and time.” This
parallelism states essentially that Zeno forgot to take into account the
division of the time it would take to make the transit, and thus each division

Page | 474
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

of space would proceed correspondingly faster and faster with its


corresponding division of time, such that upon reaching the unreachable
infinite, the transit time itself would be infinite. Sum it all up and you get the
unity of the space-time transit itself, merely divided in concept into an
infinity of parts. In this operation, however, Aristotle introduces into
Zenonian plurality “as an explicit assumption” what he calls ‘time-atoms,’
which are indivisible instants of which the path of the arrow must stepwise
be composed. These time atoms are essentially transitive zeros, which we
already know are unreachable and merely fictitious negations, not
immanent infinities. Aristotle claims that Zeno’s argument is based on the
“assumption that time is composed of instants,” otherwise, he says, “the
conclusion cannot be inferred.” And to this Verelst responds, “after you have
discarded actual infinity, that is.” She continues:
He then rejects these time-atoms, and proposes his potential divisibility
as a more apt solution [Phys., Z 9, 239a(20-24)]. But of course chronons,
like atoms, are non-Zenonian. This is another nice example of
Aristotle’s general neutralizing strategy with respect to Zeno’s
paradoxes: to introduce a seemingly self-evident hypothesis on
Zeno’s behalf, such that his own principle of contradiction can
subsequently be applied successfully.
Again we see the distorting oppositional forces of representation in the
dualistic and early phases of rationality. Verelst continues, illustrating
concisely the interface between our two fundamental VL-axes as they
manifest in Zeno’s two infinities, the mikra and megala, roughly the
immanent pole of the I/T axis (partitions or paths) and an infinitely
decreasing holarchy of extended transitive segments (parts or nodes) [my
comments].
When parts considered are of the megala type, one can still be impressed
by seeing the motion that takes place. [This is because megala, as finite
unities, have boundaries between which the arrow can fly.] When looked
at from the point of view of the mikra the paradox becomes inescapable,
for one cannot see motion over an unextended “distance” in the
unextended now. These parts in effect cannot be further divided, which is
why the atomistic point of view seems to fit in naturally [yet unnaturally,
given that they collapse into naught]. But one then forgets an essential
thing: the arrow is a finite object consisting of megala and mikra, which
nevertheless flies.
The mathematics of the modern continuum has indeed vindicated Zeno. The
continuum is not, as indeed Zeno is precisely saying, composed of instants.
That is the essence of the Parmenidean point of view. The ALL of “what is”—
Being itself—is ONE, not many. Indeed, Aristotle’s “time-atom” is not merely
just a non-Zenonian premise, but an anti-Zenonian premise. It is undeniably
quite telling that Aristotle can only refute Zeno by turning him into his
opposite—an atomist. An unintended self-reductio of sorts, on his own part.
Verelst continues:
Page | 475
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

The last two arguments show that, whether we consider the megala or
the mikra, the paradox remains the same. This is where the reading of the
last two arguments as a dilemma stems from.
Thus we see that the perception of “paradox” itself is a con-fusing function—
a conflation of the prefused distinction—of the hidden polar and triune
interface between these two VL-axes and thus between the countable
stepwise transitive infinity and the uncountable infinity of instantaneous
immanence and transcendence, not merely a result of one or the other.
Verelst continues:
But once the true nature of Zeno’s paradoxes is assimilated, this last
argument reveals itself as the contrary of how it is generally perceived: a
clear an incontestable exposure of the paradoxical nature of motion and
change, and not an incomprehensible enigma.
In other words, Zeno’s thought experiment does not show that motion does
not exist, but merely (exactly as Simplicius indicates) that motion is contra-
dictory, or that it contains a con-fusing polarity which emerges when one
tries to speak and reason about it.
If you let motion, conceived of as covering all systematically smaller
extended parts of a line by counting the uncountable in every single part,
come to an end by mentally letting the extension of the parts decrease to
nought, then division ‘comes to an end’ too, and the only thing that
remains is the naked paradox. This explains why this paradox in the
literature has been considered as the most enigmatic one, while it actually
only sums up Zeno’s conclusion in a concise way.

Contrary to the Received View, the naked Zenonian paradox dissolves


readily away when conceived not simply as a contradiction but as an actual
polarity of diction—a triune interface between two boundless axes
underlying conceptual relation itself, along with all its derivative conceptual
protocols of description and diction. All of these paradoxes, we have seen,
involve the interface between the quantized transitive and the unbounded
immanent/transcendent, and its “infinite division equals indivisibility” of
continuity. Thus they deal exclusively with the immanence of the Bounded
or third order infinity in Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, which itself is a
reactionary function against the transcendent-bias. As we have seen
throughout mathematics and conceptual embryogenesis itself, immanence
breaks the trans-bias to effect a transcendence into new operations and
identities. Likewise, Zeno’s naked paradox radicalizes immanence to break
the transcendent bias of dualistic representation—i.e. diction—shocking us,
generation after generation into various and sundry attempts to refute him.
And all the while, in this very interface—in this refutational dance with Zeno

Page | 476
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

himself—we move closer and closer to operationalizing and vindicating the


polarity and truth hiding at the naked core of his ubiquitous paradox.
The hidden anti-Zenonian premise at the heart of the naked paradox is
that which resides at the heart of the labyrinth of the continuum: continuity
is composed of parts. This is what Zeno time after time refutes. We have
already seeni* that Leibniz found his Ariadne’s thread in his secret Spinoza
studies on the Triune Infinite. His conclusion, recall, was precisely Zeno’s:
points do not compose the continuum. But with Spinoza’s Triune Infinite he
went further, tuning and triuning the Zenonian paradox. Not only do points
not compose the uncountable continuum, but they are merely abstracted
from it as unbounded and unreachable “termini”—what we herein reference
with the various names of: “implicit singularities,” “location aspects,”
Deleuzian/Leibnizian “folds,” or “immanent infinities.” The modern
mathematics and “transfinite arithmetic” of the infinite and the continuum
(transcendence and immanence, respectively) has vindicated both Zeno and
Leibniz, and through them Parmenides, Heraclitus and Spinoza. The
infinitely divisible continuum is indeed the indivisible immanent aspect of
the instantaneous and uncountable immanent/transcendent omni-axis. And
any infinitely-infinite Heraclitean multiplicity of contrasting positional
aspects can be abstracted from its Parmenidean Being-now Unity—be it for
the sake of unbounded increases in calculational precision for its indivisible
trajectories, or simply for a philosophical thought experiment demonstrating
its own intrinsic conflated and con-fused polarities.
Thus the naked paradox dissolves, as every child knows it must. Zeno’s
immovable plurality of instants is merely a con-fused abstraction. An
unreachable aspect of immanence abstracted from Parmenides’ own Being
now. Parmenides and the child have won—and thanks to the countless
man-hours of the myriad regiments of mathematicians, scientists,
philosophers and artists, inspired by Zeno himself into working out the
details of this con-fusion—tuning and triuning the Zenonian interface
itself—we can now say exactly why.

As we saw with our geometrical example of the paradox,ii* it is only by


pulverizing the transcendent-bias and LOMAiii of a system of categorical
dualities, into the acategorical immanence of a new system, that the polarity
underlying the paradox can be tuned and triuned into a conceptual nondual
realization. We have already seen the general framework of the nondual

i
* See, The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite, p407.
ii
* See, Paradox and the LOMA: A Geometrical Example, p435.
iii
“limits of minimum (semantic) ambiguity” — Lebau

Page | 477
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

categories in action in our Nondual Rationalism and Interface philosophy, as


outlined most concisely, perhaps, directly above. The details of this interface
can be cultivated further, however, as we will see, by interfacing the
interface itself with the many faces of the Zenonian plurality as it works its
way through its ramifications with the concept of motion.
The interface of VL-axes, we have seen, underlies the very form of
Zenonian plurality, which itself underlies all of the paradoxes of motion. In
the Bisection paradox, for example, the interface occurs directly in the
symmetrical infinite division of transitive motion as it expresses its own
intrinsic Zenonian plurality. Whereas in the Achilles paradox the interface is
hidden in the ever dwindling yet countably unreachable asymmetrical
difference in time needed to parse the implicit and instantaneous
uncountable continuity of the transitive and finite, yet ever irrelevant
distance between Achilles and the tortoise. In the Arrow paradox, the
infinite division of the motion of the arrow has already occurred and the
interface is naked and self-evident in the pre-given singularity of the
instantaneous point-aspect in space-time.
The con-fusion in all these cases, more precisely, is in the collapse or
false equality between transitive and immanent zero, and thus between
countable and uncountable infinity as it manifests into various conceptual
segments of the continuum. Immanent zero is an implicit singularity. It
cannot be reached because reaching is a transitive stepwise function on this
infinite immanent/transcendent uni-axis. Furthermore, according to our
Principle of Nondual Rationalism and the Principle of Absolute Reversal,
infinite division equals indivisibility or continuity. It is actually the infinite
divisibility of time and space that necessitates that the zero-limit is only
fictitiously reachable by any stepwise process of division, such as that in the
calculus. And taking division to the uncountable absolute scope merely ends
up at the continuity one started with—the one continuous journey itself.
Thus with this move, as noted previously, we merely side with Zeno and
Parmenides.
The continuum, Leibniz concluded, is not formed from points. Rather,
“termini” are abstracted out of it as unbounded immanent aspects of The
Infinite. If space-time points are merely abstracted out of the eternal NOW
of The Infinite, then, the trajectories of the arrow, Achilles and the tortoise
are not composed of zero-points. These “limits at zero” are simply transitive
illusions of perspective between two frames of reference based on the two
fundamental binary axes of pure-relational (mathematical) and
categorical/conceptual thought. Immanent zero can only be “reached,” by
Zeno or anyone, through abstracting its implicit infinity out of the timeless
concept of The Infinite itself.

Gerald Lebau came to essentially the same conclusion of a confusion


between frames of reference, but informed by the context of modern

Page | 478
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

relativistic physics, as well as the con-fused Received View on Zeno [my


comments and emphases]].i¥
Zeno’s arguments were based on formal logic, not experience, which
helped give them a timeless power.

Zeno [according to Aristotle, and contrary to Simplicius] asserted that at
any instant there is no motion. His assertion was correct for any zero
point in time—but time is not a series of zero points [which is exactly
Zeno’s Being-now point]. Time is an organic emergent of being which is
defined by its durational becoming. Literally, there is no absolute point in
time [again, Zeno’s point].
From the perspective of the arrow toward itself, it is always at rest.
From the perspective of any observer who is in a different inertial frame
of reference, the arrow is in motion.
Motion of oneself can only be observed when one steps out of one’s
own frame of reference. Therefore, the bottom line is that a flying arrow is
both at rest and in motion “at the same time”. [This is an abstraction of
the naked paradox itself—i.e. the triune interface—between transitive
time and the immanent/transcendent second-order eternal-NOW of all
times.] The trick here is that time is relative to a given frame of reference,
so that the same arrow simultaneously lives in a near [or uncountable]
infinity of possible frames of time references.
Zeno was right in observing that at any time there is no motion within
each inertial frame of reference. His mistake was in not separating
different inertial frames of reference, a relatively simple procedure. Thus
is Zeno’s paradox resolved. [This is perhaps a fair resolution to the con-
fusion of the paradox, yet not a refutation, given that Zeno was not
denying motion or experiential time itself, just the assumption that it was
composed of a plurality of zero-points or instants.]
Let us now imagine that the arrow is closely flying from one side to
the other of the visual field. Despite this special observer’s confusion, the
arrow “feels itself” to still be in the eternal present, and at rest—because
the arrow “experiences itself” as a whole, rather than as a collection of
parts or linear segments, or even molecules and atoms.
What the arrow essentially “experiences,” the existential human
existentially experiences. ... so too we cannot stop and start an arrow, or a
space ship accelerating through the void. Motion and change are integral
aspects of being; but specific times are fictions we humans impose on the
flow for our understanding and convenience. [A well said conclusion for
the Unity of the Parmenidean Being-now. Aside from this, we give Lebau
the last Zenonian word.]


(G. Lebau)

Page | 479
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Originally, I was planning on devoting an large section to Kant’s “antinomies


of pure reason,” but things have changed dramatically with the recent
Zenonian turn. My plans for Zeno did a complete 180, given that my original
intention was to show, through Interface Philosophy that Zeno’s paradoxes
were errors of reasoning on his part. Indeed, much of what was already
written against Zeno, was simply turned around against those who
misunderstood him. A case in point is the Aristotelian distinction between
actual and potential infinity. It was Zeno who was standing on the ground of
the actual and uncountable infinity and Aristotle et al who failed to reach
him through the actualized stepwise and merely countable potential infinite.
Indeed, I had originally come to the same Aristotelian “refutation” via the
parallelism of time and space, only to first recognize that it was unoriginal
and then that it was simply non-Zenonian and not a refutation or resolution
at all.
To my great surprise, however, the tables were also turned on me.
Zeno’s paradoxes, in the end, far from being refuted, merely demonstrated
and radically bolstered the Interface model itself, rigorously demonstrating
the fundamentality of its own VL-axes, for example, and as we have just seen.
And through the Zenonian turn, the historical trajectory of Nondual
Rationalism found its Western roots, as the EOTC itself was shown to echo,
again and again throughout the history of Western philosophy, as it works
itself out, transitively and transcendentally, toward the immanence in
transcendence of its abandoned, neglected and confused nondual roots.

Given that both Zeno’s and Galileo’s paradoxes have been tuned and triuned
by the modern mathematical continuum and Cantorian transfinite
arithmetic, and into philosophy and common-sense with the understanding
of Interface Philosophy and Nondual Rationalism, it is more than obvious
that, contrary to Kan’t, the human mind can indeed reason about the infinite,
in whatever form it happens to take. Kant’s claim was that human reason
had reached its limits with the concept of infinity as applied cosmologically
or cosmogonically to spatial or temporal aspects. For example, when
attempting to reason about the “beginnings” or extent of the universe. With
the culmination of Interface mathematics in our section on Zeno, however,
with his vindication and codification into the truths of the mathematical

Page | 480
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

continuum and the Cantorian transfinite arithmetic, it is nearly sufficient to


say “enough said.” Case in point. Kan’t was wrong and Can-tor right.

Up until the rise of Christianity in the Dark Ages the universe was
incontrovertibly considered without a beginning or end in space or time.
Exoteric Christianity, with its representational and transcendent forces of
anthropocentrism, however, seized the absolute, called it God, gave it human
powers and limitations, and said “Let there be light.” Thus began the world
of man, but only out of the a priori eternity and infinity of God.
With the operationalization and vindication of Zeno and the binary truths
and axes of the infinite in the modern mathematical continuum, however,
Rationality and Reason have overturned the recent confusion about origins
and put the infinite of eternity back into its originary place. Kant’s
antinomies merely show the limits of the imagination, not of reason, as
Spinoza had already shown in his Letter XII on the infinite. Indeed, given
that mathematics itself operates on Kant’s sanctified “categories of reason,” a
Kantian response must follow and accept the truths of mathematics and its
successes with the infinite and continuous. And to cosmological concerns,
those truths can indeed be applied.
For example, reasoning about the spatio-temporal infinite only becomes
a real problem when we break from the implicit holonic logic of sets—and
from the polarity of the infinite and finite as well as the Univocity
Framework—and impose limits to the absolute, such as an absolute
beginning in Time. Below, Sorenson gives us an account of Kant’s first
antinomy, and note that the proofs in these arguments take the form of
reductios. Kant assumed that each opposing thesis—e.g. that the world had
a beginning, and that it did not—could be proven by the absurdity of the
other. But as we’ll see, the only thesis that is absurd is the thesis that
imposes these absolute limits—or absolute relativities. The infinite itself—
though it can’t fit into the imagination, but can nonetheless be understood in
its percept-based terms—is the only option of the two that makes sense.
Sorenson gives the first half of the antimony as follows:
THESIS
The world has a beginning in time, and is also limited as regards space.

PROOF
If we assume that the world has no beginning in time, then up to every
given moment an eternity has elapsed, and there has passed away an
infinite series of successive states of things. . . .
Kant assumes that this is a logical reductio, but plainly it is no such thing. As
Zeno, Spinoza and Cantor have shown, there is simply nothing illogical about
an infinite number or series of successive states—previous or not. This is
merely the countably infinite, not the Zenonian Being-now. And together,
we have seen, they are merely the interface of the transitive and

Page | 481
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

immanent/transcendent axes. The reductio merely states the temporal


nature of an eternal and infinite universe, relying on the mind-boggling
inability of the reader to fit this spatio-temporal infinity into his imagination.
The logic itself has not been reduced to an absurdity at all, thus the thesis of
a spatio-temporal beginning is unjustified by this failed reductio.
The second half, or antithesis of the antinomy is as follows:
ANTITHESIS
The world has no beginning, and no limits in space; it is infinite as regards
both time and space.

PROOF
For let us assume that it has a beginning. Since the beginning is an
existence which is preceded by a time in which the thing is not, there
must have been a preceding time in which the world was not, i.e. an
empty time. . . .
The logical absurdity is obvious, and thus the reductio vindicates the infinite
antithesis over the failed reductio of the thesis. A spatio-temporal beginning
presupposes the concepts of both space and time. A “beginning to Time” is a
circular concept. A tautology, and a logical, conceptual and imaginative
absurdity. Likewise, a beginning in space presupposes a space in which this
boundary and beginning exists. Thus again, the infinite is merely impossible
to imagine and fully encapsulate (by definition, naturally) as ONE-ALL, while
the notion of ultimate boundary is not only impossible to imagine, but also
illogical, i.e. circular.
To be fair, Kant’s antinomies were discovered in a time prior to the
mathematical resolution of the paradoxes of the infinite, and in the
ignorance of the esoteric rationality of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite. Thus Kant
had very good reasons to side against the powers of reason and with the
paradoxes and con-fusions as being inherently irresolvable.
We have seen otherwise, however, and so we can side with the
capabilities and faculties of man. We have seen that the paradoxes
themselves put a pressure on reason to work themselves out into nondual
recognitions of the fundamental polarity of conceptualization itself. With
Galileo’s paradox, for example, we saw that the polarity of infinity and
number worked itself out through the Cantorian transfinite orders and
arithmetic of the infinite, and into the nondual-rational Triune Infinite. And
through Zeno’s paradoxes the mathematics of the continuum worked itself
into its own ordering of the immanent infinities or singularities of the
irrational and transcendental numbers, and now into philosophical
understanding with the triune interface between the two fundamental VL-
axes of conceptual thought itself.

Page | 482
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX

Page | 483
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS

Page | 484
Page | 485
If mathematics is the art and science of pure relation, then philosophy is the
art and science of the pure concept, which often—and perhaps best—serves
the transcendent or “higher level” purpose of the inter-relation and
integration of the arts and sciences (or knowledge in general). Otherwise
knowledge itself remains fragmented, divided and conquered. This
integration is the function that philosophy has already served throughout
this text, but at the more general level (deeper in the EOTC) of meta-
mathematics, as well as the meta-philosophy and meta-paradigm of the
Vision-Logic Coordinate System and the Univocity Framework.
In this section, however, we delve into the traditional details of
philosophy itself, instead of the areas “outside”, or in the external direction
away from philosophy (such as mathematics) into which philosophy often
strays—offering its integrating perspective by weaving a tapestry of
concepts. The problems we will encounter—with our nondual-rational
integrating perspective and meta-philosophy now intact—are the common
ones which, solved long ago in essence (by the nondual philosophies in
general, for example), seem to persist in philosophy classes, their dualisms
grotesquely exaggerated and caricatured so as to offer eternal resistance and
practice for the budding philosophy student—and perhaps to keep the
professors and philosophy itself employed in the modern academy. These
problems include—the “mind-body problem”; the problem of free-will and
determinism; the nature of knowledge (i.e. epistemology); as well as the
problem of nondually integrating and inter-relating the philosophies of
Spinoza and Leibniz, the two main nondual rationalists.

Page | 486
i
The core analysis in this section was discovered and written long before my encounter with Deleuze
or Wilber. For the original publication of this sub-thesis see
http://home.comcast.net/~anpheon/misc/Spinozas_Attribute_Polarity.pdf. The quote, “the
nucleation of observability” comes from Bucky Fuller’s Synergetics.

Page | 487
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Before we can proceed to integrate the nondual aspects of Spinoza and


Leibniz, in a later section, we must build a coherent and modern image of
Spinoza as a nondual thinker. We have already done so, to some extent, in
the prolegomena, and in this section we’ll just clarify and resolve a deep
problem in the interpretive literature emerging from the pervasive mind-
body dilemma of modern western philosophy.
The deepest rift in the mass of Spinozistic interpretive literature is
centered on the status of the only two attributes which Spinoza identified
out of the “infinite attributes of God”; these two are Thought and Extension
(or roughly mind and matter, respectively). This interpretive rift, I will
argue, is caused partially by the absence of explanatory detail—what is
called the “negative approach”—taken by Spinoza in his definition of the
attributes. The dilemma could be posed, “Are the attributes merely a
function of the knowing mind—a sort of perspectival or epistemic illusion—
as the ‘subjectivists’ assert, or are they part of the very essence of Substance
itself, as the ‘Objectivists’ maintain?” Must we see the Subjectivist and
Objectivist interpretations dualistically as mutually exclusive options? Or
could they both represent essential aspects of a deeper explanation?
As would be expected of any truly nondual approach, the interpretive rift
will be resolved and supplanted through the integrative functions of polarity
in general, and in particular through the nondual-rational, or trans-rational,
framework already presented. In the process, a deeper causal and
morphological explanation of the dual attributes as occurring necessarily at
both the “objective” and “subjective” levels—or more precisely, as we will
find out, at the ontic and epistemic levels (sub-representational and
representational, respectively)—will be put forward.
In Spinoza’s rigorous and crystalline metaphysical and epistemological
scaffolding, starting from the gap in explanatory detail concerning the
attributes, we will progress inward, in the opposite direction of the more
dispersive, abstract/logical tangents of common Spinozistic interpretation.
Instead of mere exegesis, we will generate and explore new territory, filling
in some of the missing structural details to show deeper causal relations
behind Spinoza’s rough sketch of the attributes. This explanation can help to
resolve all sorts of problems in the philosophy of mind, but we will only have
time to focus on a few of them in depth, such as a more satisfactory solution
to the mind-body problem, an elucidation of the “explanatory gap,” and a
comparison between Spinoza’s “neutral monism,” Nondual Rationalism and
Identity Theory.

Page | 488
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

While it marks a radical breakthrough in the mind-body problem in Western


philosophy (or perhaps merely a more detailed throwback to the nondual
approach of the concept of dependent arising and the identity of opposites),
Spinoza’s conception of the attributes itself contains a deeply enigmatic core.
It has been noted by many authors that Spinoza’s system of the attributes
clearly lacks sufficient explanatory detail, and, I contend, it is this lack of
detail which spawned or allowed the false dichotomy—between the
Subjectivist and Objectivist readings—at the core of Spinozistic exegesis.
For example, in The Courtier and the Heretic, Matthew Stewart says:
One could argue that, for example, the division of Substance into the two
attributes of Thought and Extension amounts only to an assertion that
mind and body are the same thing, not an explanation of how the identity
of these two very different kinds of phenomena comes about. In other
words, Spinoza’s theory, when considered as positive doctrine, may
simply be kicking the mind-body problem upstairs, from humankind to
God (p170).
Spinoza, it seems, had the intuition to construct the rigorous logical skeleton
of the answer to the mind-body problem as a function of the two known
attributes of Substance (or aspects of The Infinite), but—due perhaps to the
limited knowledge of his time (or the limits of time on his knowledge)—he
failed to demonstrate how this could causally, relationally or
morphologically come about. Body and mind are one, yes, of nondual
necessity, but how, and in what way can we visualize that they are one?
A related problem in Spinozistic thought, which was pointed out by his
friend Tschirnhaus, is that since Spinoza doesn’t give a demonstration of
what constitutes the causal and morphological nature of an attribute, he
naturally has no explanation for why there are only two of them known. But
to make matters worse, since both of the attributes, in the Subjectivist
account, are interpreted merely or mainly as perspectival functions of the
mind, modern interpretations of Spinoza’s attributes commonly find an
imbalance in the attributes themselves and tend to see the attribute of
Thought as fundamental, or dominant to the attribute of Extension. (This, as
we will see, represents an objective-ontic reductionism, of the
fundamentally neutral “Attribute polarity,” herein.) Stewart explains it thus
(my emphasis):
One may even doubt that these two in fact count as attributes of equal
status. For, if an attribute is, according to Spinoza’s definition, that which
“the intellect perceives as constituting the essence of substance,” then one
might conclude that Extension is perceived through Thought, and so
cannot count as being in the same relation to Substance as Thought.
As we will see, however—when we revisit these problems in the light of the
deeper explanation of Nondual Rationalism that may have been only implicit

Page | 489
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

in Spinoza’s system—this problem is a direct result of the two undisclosed


and undifferentiated conceptual polarities at work here, the polarity of the
ontic/epistemic and the polarity of Thought and Extension (or the within
and the without), and these polarities con-fuse around the pre-differentiated
I/T omni- and uni-axes.i* We will find that this problem can easily and
intuitively be resolved, however, given the right conceptual “orienting
generalizations,” many of which have already been presented and others of
which will follow. Stewart rounds off these problems and gives a final bit of
general perspective on the matter which will help us to progress further
until the problem can be addressed more adequately in the coming sections.
These quibbles do not affect Spinoza’s system in the negative, however, as
a radical break and opposition to the bulk of philosophy up to that point; a
rebellion against the received Platonic doctrineii that the mind is a
“special kind of thing, endowed with free will and immortality, whose
possession grants humankind an exemption from the order of nature.”

The generality of Spinoza’s outline, especially concerning the nature of the


two known attributes, has presented Spinozists with a deep enigma. This
gaping hole within in the logical edifice of Spinoza’s model has resulted in an
explosion of logical interpretations which are often highly abstract,
convoluted and frankly bizarre. In an attempt to reconcile the existing
ambiguities without injecting any new explanatory or metaphysical material
into the mix, each tangent ray of this discursive academic explosion follows a
trajectory distorted and convoluted by the confines of this strictly
hermeneutic space which is already distorted through the ever-changing
lens of history in its reaction against the failed project of rationalism.iii This
is the void left by Spinoza and only skirted around in logical abstraction by
the majority of Spinozists. The view taken herein is that Spinoza did not

i
* See, I/T Omni- and Uni-axes, p145.
ii
It is this platonic inheritance in the medieval system that the last renaissance man, Leibniz (in line
with Descartes), wishes to protect from the onslaught of inevitable modernity initiated by the first
modern philosopher, Spinoza. Descartes may have been the first philosopher employing a modern
method, but his philosophy, like Leibniz's, is an attempt to protect the medieval Theocratic system.
Spinoza, however, is the first of the modern's in both method and message.
iii
Essentially, the project of rationalism failed in part due to the political/theoretical reactions against
the necessary implications of the project in its dethronement and pulverization of the platonic
category of the immortal human soul. Surprisingly, one of the main facilitators of the abortion of
the project of rationality was also one of the progenitors of its key insights, Gottfried Leibniz himself.
In his attempt to subvert his own covert Spinozism in the creation of a “popular religion” which
would unite the catholic and protestant churches, he fostered a transcendent-biased line of
thinking, Idealism, which was itself pre-rational (and indeed pre-postmetaphysical) in many of its key
aspects. This is explicated in great historical detail in Mathew Stewart’s The Courtier and the
Heretic, and is further expanded upon in the section, Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of
Opposites, p659.

Page | 490
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

bring his project far enough to explain the percept-based source of its
resultant conceptual form. For this reason we will take Spinoza’s model as
given—however revealed and/or distorted by the geometric methodology
and the archaic medieval terminology he inherited—and we will shed light
on its epistemological and ontological form through the subsequent
discoveries and inventions in modern and post-modern philosophy and
mathematics, both academic and on the outskirts of orthodoxy, such as the
ideas of Buckminster Fuller and Gilles Deleuze.

Modern Spinozistic exegesis is divided into two main camps, the Objectivists
and the Subjectivists, centered on the problematic, and supposedly
ambiguous, definition of an attribute. As we will see, this division is in turn
generated by a false dichotomy surrounding the interpretation of a central
term in Spinoza’s ultimately inadequate definition of an attribute.
The central definition of an attribute in its original Latin form is “Per
attributum intelligo id, quod intellectus de substantia percipit, tanquam
ejusdem essentiam constituens.”i¥ The most common and natural English
translation of this definition is as follows (my emphases); “the attributes are
that which the intellect perceives of Substance as constituting (tanquam
constituens) its essence.” The term tanquam plays a pivotal role in this
exegetic rift in that it both separates and connects two crucial aspects of the
definition, the epistemic and the ontic. The phrase, “intellect perceives”
represents the epistemic level (perception as a function of knowledge and
representation) and “essence” represents the ontic level, and as we have
seen, ultimately and necessarily Emptiness and Substance.
Perhaps due in part to the pre-rational and transcendent-biasedii*
reactionary restrictions of the historically distorted hermeneutic space
forced upon modern academia by its post-modern Empiricist and Idealist
reaction against metaphysics (or creative ontological conceptualization),
neither side can see, nor invent, a possible way to include both the ontic and
the epistemic aspects of this definition in the final historical interpretation.
Accordingly, the two camps have split precisely at this symbolic conjunction
between the ontic and epistemic aspects, both of which are crucial to
Spinoza’s definition of an attribute. To make matters worse for our modern
academics, Spinoza, being the neutral party that he naturally is—with his
nondual ontic-epistemic polarity implicit in his univocal view of
Substanceiii*—unwittingly armed both sides of the debate by his purposeful
repeated use of both aspects of the definition.


Ethics I, Def. IV. quoted in Francis S. Haserot, Spinoza's Definition of Attribute, (The Philosophical
Review, Vol. 62, No. 4 (Oct., 1953), 499-513.)
ii
* See, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias, p91 and, The Image of the
Trans-Trans-Bias, 312.
iii
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.

Page | 491
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Since the Objectivists take the ontic view that the attributes represent the
essence of Substance, they have the luxury of taking the most common and
natural translation of an attribute, as discussed above, because the “as
constituting” puts a clear link from the attributes to the essence of
Substance—the attributes then become linked to the ontic or sub-
representational level, as constituting the essence of Substance. For the
Objectivists then, the epistemic aspect in Spinoza’s definition, represented
by “the intellect perceives,” becomes a secondary and superfluous (yet
curiously ever-present and bothersome) feature of the definition. The
attributes of both Thought and Extension, according to the Objectivist
interpretation, therefore somehow exist (though they never say how, or in
what form) as part of the essence of Substance, and then merely by
ontological default they extend to the epistemic level providing the support
for the arguments of their epistemically-bound opponents.
The Subjectivists, on the other hand, are at a slight disadvantage, since
they take the less common linguistic interpretation, the view from the
epistemic pole, that the attributes represent merely the ways in which the
essence of Substance can be known. But this linguistic disadvantage is
countered or supplemented by the ubiquity of the scientific/materialist
framework that tends to support this interpretation. The Subjectivist’s
preferred interpretation of this critical passage assigns to the Latin tanquam
the less common meaning of as ifi and the interpretation then becomes “the
attributes are that which the intellect perceives of Substance as if
constituting its essence.”
This emphasis on the illusory “as if” enables the Subjectivists to connect
the attributes to the higher-level intellect and its necessary perceptions (and
perspectival illusions) in direct opposition to connecting the attributes to the
very essence of Substance, the ontic level. The attributes are raised up from
the problematic ontic-level univocity of essence as existence, and into the
abstract, anthropocentric realm of the epistemic, as merely the key ways in
which the essence of Substance (existence) can be known. To the
Subjectivists then, the intellect ascribes attributes to Substance which “in
reality” (ontic) is without them. In the forward to Reflections and Maxims
(edited by Dagobert D. Rune), Albert Einstein—who famously spoke of
himself as a “disciple” of Spinoza—gives a succinct example of a Subjectivist
(scientific/materialist) reading; “Here one finds the majestic concept that
thinking (soul) and extension (naturally conceived world) are only different

i
Think here of the inflection put on this by a modern teenage girl, “as if”, to get my point that this
puts the attributes in the position of being illusory functions, if however necessary, of the limits of
knowledge.

Page | 492
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

forms of appearance resp. conceptual interpretations of the same


substance.” i
As stated previously, Spinoza naturally arms both sides in the debate,
and many other crucial passages in The Ethics consistently (and often
simultaneously) seem to stress both the “Subjectivist” (epistemic) and the
“Objectivist” (ontic) aspects. Take the following passage from The Ethics for
instance, “…substance thinking and substance extended are one and the
same substance, comprehended now through one attribute, now through the
other.”ii¥ It appears quite plainly in this passage that comprehension (a key
epistemic function) plays a central role in determining this duality because
Substance is always comprehended (known) through one or the other
attribute.
It is also quite evident that in order for comprehension to work through
the attributes, they must already exist as prior and essential (ontic) to
comprehension (epistemic)—and indeed prior and essential to “perception,”
as implied in the central definition of the attributes. The duality of the two
known attributes is not only essential and fundamental to conception and
perception, but it clearly has a connection with the essence or eternal nature
of Substance. This is illustrated in the following quote from The Ethics [my
emphases], “Further, by the attributes of God we must understand that
which expresses the essence of the divine substance.”iii¥ Rather than being
merely relegated to the ways in which Substance can be known, the
attributes themselves express the essence of Substance, and the intellect is
formed in such a way as to be inherently able to “perceive” this essence
“through” them, as already existing, even if emergent.
In an attempt to reach what Deleuze would call the “plane of consistency”
in Spinoza’s thought, we must give Spinoza the benefit of the doubt and
assume that he included both the ontic and epistemic (or “Subjectivist” and
“Objectivist”) aspects in the definition of the attributes for the purpose of
conceptual utilization and clarification, rather than accidentally or for the
purpose of confusion. Therefore, if we can find a way to make sense of
Spinoza’s text as it is, that is to be preferred, even if it requires much
conceptual infrastructure or meta-perspective to see it explicitly. The
remainder of this discussion, therefore, will be focused on the ways in which
we can understand, both visually and viscerally (intuitively), how the
intellect, and indeed all modes at all levels of emergence, must be formed in

i
Quoted from Dagobert D. Runes editor with a forward by Albert Einstein, Reflections and Maxims,
(New York, Philosophical Library Inc, 1965). Note that this is essentially an “integral,” or “AQAL” way
of thinking in terms of perspectives as fundamental. Ken Wilber’s AQAL (all quadrants all levels,
lines, etc), however, has two more “quadrants”, which represent the plural aspects of the internal
(mind) and the external (matter) perspectives.
ii¥
Ethics II, Prop VII, note:
iii¥
Ethics I, Prop. 19 Proof.

Page | 493
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

such a way as to perceive the essence of Substance through these two ways,
aspects or attributes.
Given the complexity of the subject matter of the mind, the explanation
will, however, necessarily still be at a general level, and we will see that it is
not necessary for our purposes to dig into the neurobiology of cognitive
functions in order to give an adequate explanation that appears to reach the
plane of consistency in Spinoza’s thought. It is true, however, that those
empirically derived neurobiological explanations have indeed influenced,
are supported by, and are interfaced in this work.

Page | 494
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

As the discussion above suggests, there are two critical aspects of the
definition of an attribute which must be reconciled in the new
interpretation: they are the ontic and the epistemic. The attributes, in
Spinoza’s definition, express the sub-representational essence of Substance
and pre-exist (ontic) the representational intellect which necessarily
perceives this essence through them (epistemic).
Recall that the exegetic division in Spinozistic scholarship is centered on
the subject/object distinction. If we find, however, that in Spinoza’s system
the distinction between the subjective and the objective is a difference in the
fundamental ways in which we can obtain knowledge about the world (as we
will see below)—and as such, this subject/object duality maps squarely onto
the representational domain of epistemology as only an epistemic-level
expression of the much deeper polarity of the attributesi—what then does
this do to the validity of the “Subjectivist” and “Objectivist” labels given to
our exegetic division between the warring camps?
Furthermore, as we will see, this nominal problem is due to the hidden
nature of these dual polarities and the subsequent modern tendency (“flat-
land materialism”) to collapse the objective into the ontic as foundational
and to raise the subjective to the secondary, and at best emergent epistemic.
The other modern tendency (“idealism”) is to react and counteract this
object-reductionism with its opposite replacement in a flat-land subject-
reductionism. This gives us the opposing equations, object = ontic vs. subject
= ontic, which gives us the relational nuclei of the twin poles of this exegetic
rift.
The nondual-rational solution to this problem of foundational imbalance
and tacit-dualismii* will be facilitated, naturally, through use of the VCSiii*
and the Univocity Frameworkiv* as a conceptual reference system for

i
…or as the two upper quadrants in Ken Wilber’s epistemic “AQAL matrix” in his Integral
Methodological Pluralism.
ii
* See, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156).
iii
* See, The Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS), p123.
iv
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF),, p153.

Page | 495
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

understanding and explicitly maintaining the crucial distinction at the


crossroads between these con-fused orthogonal polarities—ontic/epistemic
and subject/object, as well as the univocal absolute/relative—and for
keeping these polarities from collapsing upon themselves, and/or into each
other.i
The VCS, as we have seen, consists, in part, of the two polarities; the
transitive and the immanent-transcendent (I/T) axes. And within the I/T
axis, recall, we have a further distinction between the omni- and uni-axes.
Recall also their interfaces; the interface of the omni-axis, recall, is the
“transitive plane” and the interface of the uni-axis is the sphere—our finite
unity as the simplest (omni-symmetrical) bounded infinity. See Figure 8,
repeated below from p151. We will find that in this new model the ontic-
epistemic interface, being in part a socially constructed or emergent
function, fits the form of a transitive plane, the interface of the omni-axis,
and the objective/subjective interface, at its basis in the individual, fits the
general spheroidal or bounded form of the interface of the uni-axis.
The employment of this system, we will see, makes explicit the precise
distinction and critical interaction between the core polarities con-fused in
this exegetic rift and therefore solves the nominal, categorical and
conceptual confusions surrounding the nature of Spinoza’s attributes and
the relation of mind to body and both to God or Substance (or form to
Emptiness) in general. It is because individual awareness exists as an
interface at the center of this crossroads of polarities, undifferentiated in
earlier thought, that the distinction is so difficult to perceive, and to keep
distinct. We will find that once this is visually and conceptually outlined in
the imagination, however, it becomes rather intuitive to maintain and highly
effective and precise in operation.

i
Ken Wilber’s AQAL matrix, useful as it is at the epistemic level, is not quite adequate here because
it does not explicitly address the ontic/epistemic polarity. This is because it takes as given, at least
on the surface, the modern academic (exoteric) post-modern rejection of any ontic-level claims. For
our purposes, suffice it to say that Wilber’s post-metaphysics relies on a peculiarly medieval notion
of metaphysics as reliant on the “Great chain of Being” (GCB). (This is explained in more detail in the
section Clearing Away the Dust of the Great Chain of Being, p37) Although a common academic
interpretation of Spinoza (fostered by Leibniz and Hegel, for example) is that he offers an essentially
materialistic system. A more informed and perhaps more common view, taken by Bertrand Russell
for example, is that Spinoza’s system is neither a materialism nor an idealism, but rather a neutral
monism. One of the critical criteria for a post-metaphysical model, according to Wilber, is that the
GCB become subverted from its matter-to-mind hierarchy (though it is odd that Wilber doesn’t
address the inversion of this hierarchy in idealism) and these essential distinctions become
epistemic and perspectival, such as the inside vs. the outside points of view. This is precisely the
interpretation of Spinoza herein, and at the general level, it is not an uncommon interpretation.
Note also that this interpretation herein was arrived at long in advance of this author ever
discovering the work of Ken Wilber, and was explicated in the original publication of this article on 7-
31-04

Page | 496
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Figure 8: Omni- Uni- Interfaces: Repeated from I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the
Omni-Non.

One important factor in the categorical and conceptual confusions that we


are addressing is found in a subtle “semantic drift,” or change in the
meanings of some of these terms from the meanings that Spinoza originally
employed. In our scientific age, the current meaning of “objectivity,” or “the
objective world” has become synonymous with the world of physics and
indeed, due to the default scientific materialism, or scientism of our age, it
has become synonymous with reality itself, i.e. the ontic. Thus the objective
is generally taken as fundamental and foundational to the world of thought
(the ‘subjective,’ now demoted to the superficial level of the epistemic), as if

Page | 497
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

one could reduce thought to a few laws and principles, or indeed (and
perhaps the height of absurdity) to “an equation that could fit on a T-shirt.”i
In Spinoza’s time in general, and in his writings, however, the term
‘objective’ referred to the observations of external reality rather than to that
reality itself. Therefore, ‘objectivity’ referred to our knowledge of the
external world and ‘subjectivity’ referred to our knowledge of the internal
world. This distinction between the ontic and the objective (and by
corollary to the subjective) is encoded in the Aristotelian distinction
between actual or formal reality and objective reality, which Spinoza
incorporated wholesale into his terminology via his study of earlier
philosophers, such as Descartes. Indeed, this is made explicit with an
editor’s note from Spinoza’s Ethicsii¥ (265):
Spinoza is here using a scholastic distinction which is also used by
Descartes, (…where Descartes distinguishes between ‘actual’ or ‘formal’
reality and ‘objective reality’). When Spinoza speaks of the ‘formal
essence’ of something, he means the essence of that thing as it is in itself.
On the other hand, to say that something exists ‘objectively in God’s
intellect’ is to say (a) that its existence is mental and (b) that it is
representative of something.
With the Newtonian scientific revolution of the 17th century, however, and
the wild success and ascendancy of pragmatic mathematics, physical
principles and Laws of physics—at the expense of causal or ontological
speculation and explanation, and its roots in scholastic terminology—the
meaning of ‘objective’ slowly became synonymous with the ontic, and came
to refer to the reality itself whose Laws we felt we were uncovering, e.g.
Galileo’s book of Nature written in the language of mathematics.iii
With the “Scientific Revolution”—in which Spinoza’s system was spurned
for Descartes’ and Newton’s respective “mechanistic” dualities—a
corresponding shift in the meanings of these polarizing terms (objective and
subjective) has followed suit. With this ontic shift toward objectivity, the

i
Matthew Stewart, in his book The Truth About Everything notes quite presciently that such a
reduction to man-made and arguably ideal laws discloses a polarity reversal (See, Principle 4: Chord
3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR), p117), in that materialism becomes an idealism when
matter reduces to merely the ideal laws of physics. Indeed we can see this quite clearly in the
operations at the empirical edges of physics where the function of the conscious observer in the
collapse of the wave-function is taken to be the reality itself. Stewart comically calls this problem
“The Schmiderialism Principle” (p. 309) and indeed it is a problem of mistaking descriptive
(epistemic) protocols, subjectivity or objectivity for the formative, ontic or sub-representational
level.
ii¥
Translated by Andrew Boyle with notes by G.H.R. Parkinson (Orion House; USA, 1993)
iii
This shift was also catalyzed by the operationalization of the intrinsic solid bias, the attempt to
search only for the ultimate in terms of particles. This solid-bias, in turn, debilitated the causal
th
reasoning of the physicists of the 20 century when they encountered the vast fluid complexity of
the quantum world with its “zoo” or particles which appear far more like fleeting wave resonances
and vortices than anything solid.

Page | 498
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

delicate neutrality of the Spinozistic relation between the epistemic aspects


of subjectivity and objectivity, in balanced and polar opposition to the formal
reality of the ontic, became unbalanced. This facilitated the problematic
dissolution of Spinoza’s central distinction between the ontic (formal) and
epistemic aspects of his attributes and the epistemic-level duality of the
subjective and objective.i
Therefore, to understand Spinoza’s meaning concerning his attributes
and their relation to objectivity, subjectivity, the ontic and the epistemic, it
will indeed be useful to return to the original neutral meanings of these
terms before the polarizing and unbalanced ontic-objective collapse into
materialism and its reactionary form in idealism. This will indeed help clear
away the errors resulting from the interpretations based on the blurring of
this crucial distinction.

Since the more precise semantic mapping of this Objectivist/Subjectivist


interpretive split is on the ontic/epistemic polarity respectivelyii we will use
the more correct ontic/epistemic distinction throughout the rest of this
discussion, with the new understanding that the object/subject divide
occurs only at the level of representation. The new question at the core of
the problematic exegetic division then becomes; Are the dual attributes
essential to the nature of Being iii (ontic) or are they aspects of a
bifurcation in perception/conception (epistemic) and secondarily
imposed on sub-representational reality (the ontic)?
As we will see, to our advantage this new interpretation puts the
“explanatory gap”—the kernel of the mind-body problem—squarely in the

i
Idealism quickly emerged and constantly re-emerges as a healthy countermeasure to the ontic-
objective reduction thus attempting to balance the imbalance, but it is still a minor reactionary sub-
paradigm on the margins of the default materialism.
ii
It is ironic that the two camps spontaneously divided upon a line which is emergent from the
fundamental division of the attributes themselves. The subjective and the objective are the names
of the two attributes at the level of “excellence” (in complexity) corresponding to that of a cognitive
mode, such as an animal brain/mind. So if the exegetic division occurs between the actual
attributes—at the epistemic level of object and subject—then clearly it is an erroneous mapping
unless one wishes to deny the existence of one or the other attribute. But this may indeed be the
underlying driving factor due to the natural tendency of the human mind for absolutizing inherently
relative knowledge systems or interpretations. This spontaneous division only goes to show the
actual pervasiveness of the fundamental polarity. It exists at all levels of modification, from a-tom
to episteme.
iii
Hegelians may jump at this chance to reaffirm to themselves their favorite interpretive error,
namely that Spinoza’s substance is inert, passive and rigid because, as they suppose, it excludes the
concept of Becoming. This is a common misconception about Spinoza’s substance, but Spinoza
claimed in his Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being, that “since substance is [the cause]
and the origin of all its modes, it may with far greater right be called acting than passive.” Spinoza’s
substance does not equate to the modern physics notion of inert, dead, blind and stupid matter and
it cannot in any sense be passive because it is the root of existence itself.

Page | 499
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

realm of the epistemic, or in representation where explanation indeed


occurs and where it becomes easily dealt with as a natural consequence of
the limits of representation.

Figure 64: Objectivist/Subjectivist Remapping to the Ontic/Epistemic Polarity :


The more precise mapping for the Subjectivist/Objectivist interpretive rift is along the
ontic/epistemic duality. However, this duality is more properly conceived of as a
morphological gradient or ‘polarity’ between the minimal complexity of basic self -
stabilized modification, at the ontic level, and a specific cognitive, representational
type of complexity denoted by Spinoza ’s term “excellence,” at the epistemic level. In
this view, the “Subjectivists” map the attributes to the epistemic level and the
“Objectivists” map them to the ontic level, yet both objectivity and subjectivity exist at
the epistemic level as the emergence —through evolutionary representational
complexification of cognitive holons—of the two attributes.

In concurrence with Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem and with


philosophical “Fallibilism,” the mind-body problem now merely
demonstrates the limits (or fallibility) of all representational systems—
whether subjective, objective, mathematical, linguistic, aural or visual. No
system of explanation and no method of observation can ever be absolutely
complete and infallible because all representational and explanatory
systems are based in the epistemic realm as emergent finite abstractions and
observations. In Spinoza’s system, however, the immanent causation of
Substance is infinite in extent and resolution (i.e. continuous—via our

Page | 500
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Principle of Nondual Rationalism, infinite division equals indivisibility) and


thus cannot be encapsulated by an abstract and finite representation. In this
way, it is only natural that objective accounts can never absolutely explain
the subjective experience (and vice versa), and indeed the need for them to
do so becomes revealed as a simple categorical error between the objective
and subjective modes of knowing.
When placed into relative terms, the two modalities of experiential
knowledge (subjectivity and objectivity) become understood as
symbiotici*—and indeed entirely unthinkable, one without the other—
rather than contradictory and mutually exclusive. In addition, the
interpretation to follow, bridges the exegetic gap by demonstrating visually
and viscerally that the attributes necessarily have both an ontic and an
epistemic nature—exactly as Spinoza’s original text abstractly demands.
Clearly then, to retain this vestigial exegetic Subjectivist/Objectivist
nomenclature would be to suggest that both camps are centered on
epistemic functions—rather than the Objectivists being centered on the
ontic-level essence of Substance—and so the old terms are in connotative
conflict with the interpretive distinction which we are attempting to
illuminate. So to reinforce and clarify the functioning of this interpretive
division we must remap the distinction to a more precise semantic polarity.
We will then be in a position to further explain the exegetic duality as the
two poles (ontic and epistemic) within a morphological gradient of a specific
category of cognitive/representational structural and functional complexity
(Spinoza’s “excellence”),ii rather than the two categories of the epistemic—
the objective and subjective modes of knowing.

A common materialist or Subjectivist interpretation of the attributes is that


they are a sort of “descriptive protocol”iii¥ where an analogy is drawn
between opposing types of description for the same event. Examples of
these descriptive protocols include; reading sheet music vs. reading a vivid
description of the very same music – a chemical spectrograph listing all the
components of a fine wine vs. a wine-taster’s flowery and poetic descriptions

i
* See section 2.5 “Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object”
ii
“For the excellence of ideas, and the actual power of thinking are measured by the excellence of
the object.” Ethics III, General Definition of the Emotions
iii ¥
Darren Staloff, Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition: Lecture 33: Spinoza—
Rationalism and the Reverence for Being, audio CD of a lecture for The Teaching Company
(http://www.teach12.com ). In this lecture Staloff defined Spinoza’s attributes as “descriptive
protocols.”

Page | 501
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

of the same wine – a rigorous objective account of the salient features of a


photographi vs. a subjective impression of how it makes one feel.
Spinoza does indeed seem to support this general descriptive (epistemic)
view and an analogy of a purely nominal distinction was given by Spinoza in
Letter 9 to De Vries. However, as already noted, there is much textual
evidence that the attributes are more fundamental than this purely
epistemic view would imply. Another hint at the incompleteness or
inaccuracy of this view is that the number of descriptive protocols known to
man, is indefinite. If, however, as Spinoza says, there are only two known
attributes, and even in Spinoza’s day the number of known descriptive
protocols was far greater than two, then clearly the “descriptive protocol”
analogy can only point to an important aspect (the epistemic level, or
“Subjectivist” account) and not to the complete understanding of the two
attributes.
A crucial clue is provided by the observation that all the descriptive
protocols fall into two main categoriesii—the subjective and the objective.
For instance; the wine-tasters description is a subjective protocol drawing on
the common pool of qualitative, internal human experiences, whereas the
chemical spectrograph is an objective protocol drawing on quantitative
descriptions or measurements of externally observed reality. Another more
relevant example is the distinction between a “folk-psychology” description
of mental states, which is clearly a subjective account, and those same states
described in the objective, quantitative terms of a functional MRI brain
scan.iii
Clearly then, if the “descriptive protocol” concept is to be useful, we must
take subjectivity and objectivity themselves as the two “fundamental
descriptive protocols” at the root of the epistemic level of the attributes.
However, in accordance with Spinoza’s inclusion of both epistemic and ontic
levels in the definition of an attribute, we must also extend this polarity
down to the ontic level as what will be called the “formative protocols.”iv
Note also that this is in accord with Ken Wilber’s two upper quadrants, the
singular IT and I, corresponding to Extension and Thought, respectively.

i
or even a binary description of a digital photograph, but this seems to be in a specialized category,
that of the constructive protocols, such as DNA. In Golem XIV, Stanislaw Lem calls them “causative
languages.”
ii
And Ken Wilber would argue, quite effectively perhaps, that there are ultimately four; his AQAL
quadrants.
iii
Ken Wilber has mapped out these two “quadrants” sufficiently for our purposes, and we need not
belabor this point. For further demonstration of this distinction, see virtually any of Ken’s books on
his integral model.
iv
A causal explanation of how the formative protocols might function is beyond the scope of this
paper. At the foundation, this Spinozistic interpretation ties into and draws from a new unified
model of physics called “Sorce Theory.” For more information see http://www.anpheon.org .

Page | 502
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Recalling our Principle 8: Chord 6: The Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity


(or The Principle of Holonic Polarity) (p251), “Finite unity is plural, and at
minimum two,” which we adapted from Buckminster Fuller’s own maxim,
we have here the general polarity of the within and the without, as it applies
in the two directions of the representational and the sub-representational
realms, or the epistemic and the ontic, respectively. The interface here,
recall, is the sphere, our interface of the I/T uni-axis forming the boundary of
the finite unity. The polarity of this interface, however, cuts down through
the interface of the ontic/epistemic polarity, which, recall, is essentially a
transitive-plane, given that the ontic and epistemic realms are not centered
on a single location, and thus not located on any given uni-axis, but rather,
effectively omni-local, with the epistemic seen as transcendent or
irreducibly emergent from the ontic.
Within the ontic/epistemic morphological gradient polarity, then, there
is another much more clear-cut division in the orthogonal direction cutting
down through both the epistemic and ontic forms of modification.
Conceptually these two orthogonal divisions (polarities) form a cross where
they meet; a crossroads. Subjectivity and objectivity are at the epistemic
level of the morphological gradient where the modifications become
sufficiently and properly complex for the representation of knowledge
primitives (qualia) and systems thereof (language, science, philosophy, etc.).
But—looking inwardly from the default transcendent perch of internal or
external empiricism—the epistemic polarity fades down into the raw
attributes of Thought and Extension toward the absence of such specific
forms of representational complexity. This absence of representation is
denoted by the term ontic (see Figure 65, below).
This distinction, again, follows the difference between the triune
interfaces of the I/T omni- and uni-axes. The subject/object, or
Thought/Extension interface is the generalized sphere, whereas the ontic-
epistemic triune interface, being a collective of subject/object interfaces
emerging at roughly the same scale of action, is a transitive plane. (Recall
Figure 8, above (repeated from p151).) Once the singular (ONE-one)
cognitive interfaces emerge from the massively complex collective level
below it, a new transitive plane of interacting cognitive units emerges along
with it. This new collective representational level, or transitive plane, is the
epistemic as it emerges irreducibly from the ontic. The gradient between
them is the ontic-epistemic interface, born from the communion of multiple
cognitive, perceptive agents—each one an infinitely detailed interface

Page | 503
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

between infinite immanence (yin) and transcendence (yang) on a uni-axis


interfacing with an internal and external environment, both representational
and sub-representational, in its emergence into view.

Figure 65: Ontic/Epistemic Orthogonal Quadrants:


The attributes give rise to both the “descriptive protocols” (“subjectivity” and
“objectivity”) at the epistemic level (demarcated by a specified degree of
representational complexity), and the “formative protocols” at the ontic level as a
necessary aspect of the essence of Substance in the formation of modes . In this
conceptual schematic, the duality of the attributes is revealed to be orthogonal to the
i
ontic/epistemic duality and they form a cross in the middle.

i
For those informed of Ken Wilber’s Integral Methodological Pluralism, this quadrant map is entirely
orthogonal (a side view) to Ken’s AQAL matrix which would be seen edge on as the line between the
ontic and epistemic quadrants. This is because Ken’s map deals exclusively with epistemic functions
as they fade down into the ontic level. Accordingly, when visualized as extended into 3d space

Page | 504
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

All modification can be understood ultimately as a “breaking of symmetry,” a


conceptual transformation from the omni- of non-localityi into the uni- of a
single locus in contradistinction to its surroundings. Recall at this point our
Cycle of Unity from the apoapsis ONE-ALL of the I/T omni-axis to the
periapsis ONE-one of the uni-axis and its spherical interface of the
generalized finite unity or mode. A finite unity, in the real world of infinite
difference and form, is never a perfect sphere, as Buckminster Fuller made
so clear, because, as Deleuze would also agree, all infinite levels of reality
(transitive planes of existence) are actively modified and thus infinitely
complex in their immanent details (infinite determinism equals
indeterminismii*). If, like the brain, the modification is sufficiently complex
within the morphological space of representational capabilities
(‘excellence’), this locus becomes a consciousiii “point of view.” This gradient
of representational complexity—our singular interface and the crossroads
for our double polarities; ontic-epistemic and Thought/Extension—is
captured in Spinoza’s text, “For the excellence of ideas, and the actual power
of thinking are measured by the excellence of the object.”iv¥

When dealing with the forms of Emptiness at the limits of observability


there are two main “fundamental” or general types of morphologies; they
are the ‘particle’ and the ‘wave,’ both of which are entirely interconvertable
and symbiotic—as modern physics has demonstrated at the quantum level.v
The wave is inherently unstable and non-centering and thus it propagates in
the “attempt” to equilibrate with its surroundings, so to speak. The particle,
on the other hand, is a self-stabilized “nucleus,” actively, continually, and

informed by the categories of the AQAL matrix not shown in this map, a new set of four cubes is
formed for the two “objective and subjective plural” quadrants as they extend from the epistemic
AQAL modalities into the ontic nondual-rational modalities forming a total of eight cubes when
combined. In this extended map of the orthogonal intersection between the nondual-rational ontic-
epistemic polarity and the AQAL singular-plural polarity, only the singular quadrants are visible in
the diagram here, and under consideration in this immediate discussion, except as necessarily
implied in the plurality inherent in the sub-unit architecture and the transitive-plane of the omni-
axis, etc..
i
The omni-local is the identical inverted pole of the non-local. Neither of which are local because a
location requires a field of otherness to give it reference; the omni is negating the local because it is
all-encompassing and thus not located and the non-local is quite obvious as a negation of the local.
ii
* See, Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID), p186.
iii
Consciousness herein is based on the human as exemplar and generally connotes a
representational level of awareness as opposed to a general universal reactivity or within-ness
/immanence.
iv¥
Ethics III, general definition of the emotions.
v
See “The Antipodes of Organization” in the article, Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement.

Page | 505
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

inertially centering upon itself. This structural stabilization, geometrical


localization and nucleation imparts an inherent morphological polarity
which we have already encountered in Buckminster Fuller’s statement, and
our quantitative principle of finite unity, “unity is plural and at minimum
two” (1000.0); a nucleus, or any other emergent volumetric localization,
possesses an inside and an outside with a triune interface dividing (and
indeed connecting) the two. It is the interface that is the source of both the
duality and the unity because it is simultaneously the energetic divider and
the immanent causal (emergent homeostatic) connector.i Furthermore, in
Spinoza’s univocal Substance as infinitely divided (ala Leibniz, as well) and
thus indivisible, all transitive interfaces (dualities and polarities) must be
seen, at a deeper level, as gradients given the proper power of perceptual
resolution.
These most basic of nuclei are what Spinoza calls the “simplest bodies”
and it is no stretch to see that all further self-stabilized agglomerations
(Spinoza’s “composite bodies”) and compounded homeostatic
complexifications of these nuclei (e.g. cells, objects, brains, etc.) must also
possess an interface (e.g. cell-membrane, retina, skin, skull, etc) separating
the outside from the inside for perceptual, regulatory and safe-guarding
purposes. It is also quite well known in the biological sciences that self-
stabilization (e.g. biological homeostasis and/or evolution) is always an
integral and symbiotic interaction between object and environment, via an
interface or variously structured and functional membrane. Since the
observer is always a self-stabilizing homeostatic “organism” we see that the
nuclear quality of all modes and finite unities gives an inherent polarity to
observability itself (see Figure 66, below). As Buckminster Fuller points out,
“All observability is inherently nuclear because the observer is a nucleus”
(1005.32).
This property of emergent homeostasis, recall, is the defining feature of
Spinoza’s concept of modal essence. This same homeostasis, organizational
coherence and emergent unity is also the definition of Leibniz’s “principle of
unity,” which he says all “substances” must possess. And further, this same
list of properties is the defining feature of a holon, in Integral Theory. Such
holons include, a particle, a higher level nucleus, a cell and a human being.
And so we can see a resonance between Spinoza, Leibniz and the Integral
models. It is important to note that only certain types of modes which
possess this homeostatic and fully relative, dependently arising essence can
be considered “holons”. All other modes are merely collections of deeper
modes with no coherence, persistent modal essence and no principle of
unity. Such modes are “heaps,” not holons.

i
This concept of holonic emergence corresponds to Leibniz’s “principle of unity” which serves to
define his conception of substance.

Page | 506
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Figure 66: A Cognitive Modification or Holon:


Human consciousness, i.e. perception/conception and the forms of representation, is
an emergent phenomenon which functions at a specific and limited region of
frequencies (transitive plane) in the continuity ( “infinite divisibility”) of Substance. As
an emergent phenomenon, human -consciousness is herein depicted as a finite 3 -
dimensional gradient interface (an abstract cross -section of a sphere projected into a
representational state-space) between the infinities of micro - and macro-perceptual
irrelevancies. Those vast scales of si ze, with which the perceptual/conceptual
apparatus does not resonate, and thus cannot tune -in, are irrelevant to the organism ’s
cognitive homeostasis functions. It is the finity of this emergent representational
surface (bounded finite unity), between the within and the without, which provides the
analogy for understanding the inherent limits of all systems of representation, i.e.
descriptive protocols, when confronted with an infinite and omni -local causal reality.

The cognitive or representational organism emerges from the sub-


representational medium as a function of evolutionary intelligence
(problem-solving capability) in limited sensorial resonance with an
unlimited, yet infinitely modified (infinite determinism equals
indeterminism) environment. Loosely speaking then, a cognitive mode or
holon has a finite emergent representational “surface”i or interface with two

i
This surface is an abstraction for the emergent nature of consciousness and must not be taken for a
visually distinguishable barrier. It is likely that the actual subject/object interface is indeed quite
distributed in the brain as the “mnemonic primitives” discussed in section 2.5.

Page | 507
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

general “directions” of functionality—within and without, intrinsic and


extrinsic, or roughly immanent and transcendent. At this
cognitive/representational level these directions correspond respectively to
Spinoza’s use of the terms “conception” and “perception” and the epistemic
duality of subjectivity and objectivity, i.e. the descriptive protocols. This
representational interface can even be quasi-located in the membranes and
surfaces corresponding, though not reduced to, the centers of higher
cognitive function, such as the distributed centers of memory and sensory
processing, or the language and planning centers of the cortex.
The polarity of nucleation, with its attendant quantitative principle of
finite unity, is the structural and causal core of the twin attributes,
absolutely fundamental and essential to the formation (ontic) and
representation (epistemic) of all observing and observable finite
modifications or modes. It is a causal necessity that the intellect perceive
the modes of Substance in these two fundamental ways—either viewing its
own cognitive mode or holon (itself) from within (subjectivity) or viewing
other modes (cognitive or not) and their extended interrelations from
without (objectivity).
The perception of the extended field of inter-relating, nucleated, and/or
compounded nuclear agglomerations, is radial and external to the cognitive
(sensorial and mnemonic) interface, whereas the conception of the thoughts
within is internal to that interface. This nucleation structure and duality is
necessitated by the causal nature of the emergence of self-stabilization and
its modal-conjugates and cellular complexifications such as those
architectural monstrosities, the modes of cognition. The inherent nuclear
polarity—the descent in The Cycle of Unity from the ONE-ALL to the ONE-
one uni-axis and spherical interface of the finite unity—is therefore the
ontological core (formative protocols) of the split (explanatory gap)
emerging into the epistemic level, between the descriptive protocols of
subjectivity and objectivity.
In this way the epistemic aspect of the attributes (the descriptive
protocols) find their causal/structural and ontic roots in the symmetry-
breaking, fundamental, formative protocols of modification in generalized
nucleation—and taken together we find the deeper meaning of Spinoza’s
attributes as both an epistemic and an ontic morphological and formative
division inherent in the nature of Substance (or Emptiness) in the formation
and expression of modes (recall Figure 65, above, and see Figure 70,
below—p505 and 525, respectively). And the epistemic understanding of
the nature of this ontic division provides the subsequent intuitive and
visual/visceral union of the mind/brain duality by the “cultivated (and

Page | 508
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

cultivating) third”i of the emergent nuclear, cellular, organismic, or cognitive


interface symbiogenetically arising between them.
Thus the perceived ambiguity in Spinoza’s definition of an attribute—
which appears to suggest both “subjective” and “objective” interpretations
simultaneously—is rendered coherent when their dual ontic/epistemic
nature is exposed as a necessary formative nucleated polarity inherent in
the very nature of active Substance as it is modified (evolved) along a
morphological gradient into an increasingly complex series of ever more
cognitive/representational modes (brains/minds). And simultaneously, the
false dichotomy of the exegetic rift between the Subjectivists and the
Objectivists is rendered visible and defunct when the epistemic and ontic
understanding of an attribute is at once made clear. Without this symbiotic
inside/outside distinction, modes simply cannot self-stabilize, exist and be
perceived or conceived. And a modification with an inside and an outside is
always extended and thus capable of interrelation with other modes in the
field of extension.ii
Despite the duality inherent in the formative protocols of nucleation,
Substance itself always remains univocal and continuous (though not
homogenous) and this continuity (infinite division equals indivisibility) is in
fact key to its formative protocolsiii and the emergent interface separating,
uniting and enabling the nuclear differentiation in the first place. The
definition of polarity as “the possession or manifestation of two opposing
attributes,”iv¥ references this fundamental unity and polarity beneath the
duality of the attributes.

Materialists (or “Subjectivists” in our outmoded Spinozistic nomenclature),


though they sometimes find a deep resonance with Spinoza, nevertheless
often have difficulty with the idea that Spinoza’s attribute of thought
pertains to the ontic level (erroneously assigned to the Objectivist camp in
the objective-ontic shift) and thus to all modes, whether or not they possess
a brain and thus a perceiving intellect. To them this seems to mean that
objects such as trees and rocks are sitting around thinking, like we do.
However, at about this point Spinoza says, “The propositions we have
advanced hitherto have been entirely general, applying not more to men

i
See Michel Serres for discussion on his concept of the “cultivated third”. I have merely emphasized
the ontic, or a priori and active/formative aspect of this polarity-triuning interface, or third.
ii
Thus the modern physics concept of the “zero-dimensional point particle” is a mathematical
abstraction—albeit a perhaps necessary simplification—which has been substituted and confused
for the reality it represents.
iii
See my article, Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement.
iv¥
From http://www.dictionary.com

Page | 509
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

than to other individual things, all of which, though in different degrees, are
animated [animata].”i¥ This “anima” is the immanent active causation within
all things (corresponding to the existential idea that existence, an active
property, precedes individual essenceii*), and as Spinoza says in his Short
Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being, “since substance is [the cause] and
the origin of all its modes, it may with far greater right be called acting than
passive.”iii
Spinoza makes it clear that the attribute of thought is an interior
existence, experience, or point of view whose degree of “excellence” is
dependent upon the degree of “excellence” of the mode doing the existing
perceiving or conceiving. As Spinoza says, “For the excellence of ideas, and
the actual power of thinking are measured by the excellence of the object.”iv¥
This collective degree of excellence is the morphological gradient and
interface between the ontic and epistemic where the modes at the epistemic
level (a somewhat arbitrarily defined level of cognitive complexity
somewhere between the level of the human brain/mind and, say, an
amoeba) would be considered “cognitive modes,” or cognitive holons.v
In Spinoza’s system then, the term for the attribute of “Thought” is
misleading in many respects because it generally connotes to us our own
human intrinsic/subjective and epistemic experience and then seems to
project this connotation onto the fundamental nature of reality. This is
clearly an erroneous reading, however, and this is qualified by Spinoza’s
stipulation of the gradient of “excellence” as interpreted herein.
It is possible that Spinoza used this now problematic term because he
recognized the continuity of the morphological gradient of representational
intelligence (what we might indeed call “thought”) and wished to forestall
the reduction of either mind or matter to the other. And accordingly,
Spinoza extended the attribute of Thought all the way down the infinite,
immanent gradient of excellence (or “depth” as integral theorists would call
it) to objects which we would not ordinarily consider to be thinking at all,
but which nonetheless do indeed have an inner aspect of existence
conceivable only through the attribute of Thought (i.e. from within) in
contradistinction to the outer interrelational aspect perceivable and
conceivable only through the attribute of Extension.


Ethics II, PROP. XIII
ii
* See, Univocity and Essence, p170.
iii
This, recall, directly contradicts Hegel’s main criticism of Spinoza's Substance as rigid. Again,
Substance is Emptiness, the absolute scope. It can no more be called rigid than floppy. Polarities do
not apply.
iv¥
Ethics III, General Definition of the Emotions
v
Note that only certain types of modes would be considered holons. These holons are modes with a
bounded synergetic unity and a homeostasis, where the

Page | 510
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

This is yet another case in which Spinoza seems to have intuited critical
aspects of modern science; this time it is the property that complexity
scientists call “emergence.” With this understanding, Spinoza recognized the
impossibility of ascribing an exact line of demarcation on the gradient
between the morphological instances of the ‘thinking’ and the ‘unthinking’,
the ‘conscious’ and the ‘unconscious’, the ‘intelligent’ and the ‘pre-
intelligent’, or more generally the ‘cognitive’ and the ‘pre-cognitive.’ This is
essentially the view that modern cognitive science has arrived at with its
ideas of the functional nesting of simple mechanisms leading to the gradual
irreducible emergence of higher representational functionality through
synergistic non-linear feedback mechanisms at the boundary between chaos
and order.
Spinoza also makes it clear that the epistemic aspect of the attribute of
Extension is an external point of view from which one conceives or perceives
of the world entirely as if the indwelling essence of reality were exclusively
extended in matter and its inter-relations. This is because outsides and
inter-relations are all we can see when we take things apart and view them
from outside their own immanent causal existence (see Figure 67, below).
The interpretation herein makes it clear how every mode of Substance can
and must be independently conceived under one or the other attribute as
each mode necessarily has an internal and external experience or point of
view from which it can be conceived of and perceived, and—corresponding
to its degree of excellence—from which it can itself, conceive and perceive.

As Matthew Stewart says in The Courtier and Heretic [[my comments]] “The
place to look for the unconscious part of the mind, then, is not in a fictional,
hidden mind, but in the gap between the idea of the body that constitutes the
mind and the body itself” [[i.e. the “explanatory gap”]] (p172). In other
words, the human mind (the “idea of the body” or the idea that the body
has), as epistemic and representational, emerges from the body itself as
ontic, but both stratified ontic and epistemic aspects of attribute-neutral
modality of the body are subject to the vertical bisection of the twin
attributes, Thought and Extension, since holonic nucleation, and the polarity
of the within and without, occurs at all levels of the body, ontic and
epistemic (recall Figure 65, p505).
The dual (within/without) aspect necessarily inherent in the formative
and descriptive (ontic and epistemic) essence of all modification quite
simply accounts for the exact “order and connection” that both the “modes of
thought” and the “modes of extension” adhere to (see Figure 67, below).

Page | 511
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

“The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection
of things”i¥ and simultaneously it explains why the two attributes must
function in parallel isolation from one another; this is because as a
localization you can’t simultaneously be outside the mode, viewing it under
the aspect of Extension, and inside the mode as the intrinsic experience
itself.ii Or more simply put, you can’t be both outside and inside yourself at
the same time.iii However, Spinoza also says, “thinking substance and
extended substance are one and the same substance, comprehended now
under this attribute, now under that. So, too, a mode of extension and the
idea of that mode [[a “mode of thought”]] are one and the same thing,
expressed in two ways.”iv¥ The “idea” of the mode, as a modification of the
attribute of Thought, is this intrinsic existence or the experience of being the
mode itself.
The gap of attribute parallelism at the epistemic level exists because of
the necessary distinction between the two basic modes of
conception/perception—the within and the without—manifesting at the
epistemic level as the fundamental descriptive protocols
(subjective/objective) with their intrinsic limits as an emergent or
transcendent interface. To cross this gap the best one can do is to view both
attributes separately and pseudo-simultaneously (i.e. intermittently shifting
ones attention between the two, time-slices), for example watching a TV
monitor of an active brain scan of the mental states one is in while he
watches his own brain scan. However, the two views—now feeding back
into each other limiting both states simultaneously to an interlocked
existence—are still essentially separate and must be correlated through the
knowledge of what one is watching from the outside vs. how it feels on the
inside.
Ultimately, Spinoza says, “…in the universe nothing is granted, save
substances and their modifications,”v¥ therefore, with only one Substance
(the ONE-ALL of The Infinite or simply Emptiness) in existence, every
modification of an attribute is essentially a modification of Substance,
comprehended and expressed now through one attribute and now through
the other (from within or without), but as we have seen, never both


Ethics I, Prop. VII.
ii
A key is presented here to disabling the homuncular regress by abandoning the notion that the
experience of consciousness necessitates an experiencer. They are one and the same thing but
occasionally the experience includes a feedback function we call “self-consciousness.”
iii
Of course this further depends on the aperture or scope of your definition of self which can be as
flexible as one wants, and can extend beyond Extension to Substance itself thus revealing the
polarity and unity of this duality. It is the control of this aperture that opens the communication
lines between free-will and determinism.
iv¥
Ethics II, Prop. 7

Ethics I, Prop. 6, Proof.

Page | 512
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

simultaneously for any given mode.i This ultimate connection, in the


formative protocols of modification is the unity behind the polarity and
separation, or parallelism, of the attributes.

Figure 67: Attribute parallelism:


All “modes of thought” and “modes of extension” are ultimately modes of Substance
conceived under each attribute respectively because “…in the universe nothing is
granted, save substances and their modifications. ” The real relational unity underlying
the parallel duality exists, therefore, at the ontic level as modifications of Substance.

More specifically, the problem of the attributes is a problem of conflating


and collapsing (con-fusing) the two undifferentiated orthogonal polarities of
the ontic/epistemic and Thought/Extension (or subject/object). These two

i
…unless perhaps one realizes the fundamental symbiotic unity beneath the perceived/conceived
duality of subject and object in the emergence of the sensory/mnemonic interface (see the coming
section, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528).

Page | 513
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

polarities,, recall, are ultimately found on the I/T omni- and uni-axes,
respectively, with their respective interfaces in the transitive-plane and the
spheroidal boundary. There is an ontic aspect to the attributes in the
“formative protocols,” and the attributes exist whether perceived through or
not. As the fundamental polarity of boundary—the duality of finite unity—
the two attributes, existing in the nucleated holonic ontic substrate from
which the epistemic emerges, are naturally prior to emergent and nucleated
perception and conception. And naturally the ontic aspect (the formative
protocols) of this fundamental polarity of bounded form is necessarily
perceived through the a priori “descriptive protocols” of the epistemic.
The mistaken reading of the attributes is the assumption that objectivity
and subjectivity—the twin aspects of cognition, representation and the
epistemic—are both subsumed under the attribute of Thought. The
attribute of Thought, it must be clear, is not the common notion
‘thought.’ Objectivity is the epistemic level of the attribute of Extension
and subjectivity is the epistemic level of the attribute of Thought. The
“crossroads” of the two polarities—the attributes and the ontic/epistemic—
arises at the emergent monadic interface of every
cognitive/representational holon or mode, but the distinction must be kept
from collapsing into a con-fusion between the omni- and uni-axes of the
ontic-epistemic and the subject-object polarities, respectively.

Because the cognitive holon is necessarily a transcendent interface prior


to experience of any kind, empiricism itself is necessarily a transcendent
function. This is the essence of Deleuze’s notion of “transcendental
empiricism.” Beneath the empirical is the sub-empirical; beneath the
representational is the sub-representational; and beneath the epistemic is
the ontic. All of these, however, including the ontic itself (in all its various
names), take place in the relative world of form, as opposed to the ineffable
absolute scope.
Empiricism itself—in its collective or multiple aspect—takes place at a
transitive-plane, between the infinite immanence and transcendence of the
I/T omni-axis. In its individual aspect, it takes place on the transcendent
interface of the cognitive holon itself, between the infinite immanence and
transcendence of the I/T uni-axis. Empiricism is not, it must be noted,
identical with objectivity. This is because observation can take place in both
internal and external directions; both subjective and objective. The science
of psychology is a great example of subjective empiricism in action—with all
its limitations and successes.
This individual interface is the reductive goal of the Cartesian “cogito”; “I
think therefore I am.” But the attempted reduction of relative knowledge to
Page | 514
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

the absolute scope takes us not into the certainty of any of the truths of form
outside the self, but to an absolute certainty of only oneself—the solipsistic
self-absolute because the only thing the self can know absolutely is the
representational interface itself. All else is projection.
Through the principle of absolute reversal, however, of taking the self-
boundary to the absolute, it dissolves its other and fades into the omni-non
of nihilipsism (self-annihilation). If there is no other, there is no self—just as
in the omni-local if there is no distinction between one location and all
others, there is no location referenced at all. Ultimately we come to the
annihilation of the self-distinction and boundary itself with the elimination
of polarity. This is the “cogito of the dissolved self,” roughly.

Page | 515
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Spinoza’s use of the term ‘extension’ comes from a long line of tradition
ending with Descartes who conceived of it as synonymous with volume; a
combination of the measurements of width, height and depth. How does one
measure or perceive volume? As we have seen in the EOTC of number and
operation,i* one begins by identifying a unit of reference for setting the
relative scale of measurement—ideally a highly stable and uniformly
replicable physical object, like a meter-stick—and then one uses this unit to
measure relative distances in terms of multiples or divisions of the unit. The
key point to understand is that these distances are always relative to the
scale of choice, and in turn, this scale must be relative to the organism doing
the measuring. Consequently it is the finite cognitive holon—a form already
transcendent from the Emptiness of immanence—and the limits and range
of its perceptual modifications (sensory systems), which are the ultimate
transcendent referent by which all scales must be set for the purposes of
perceiving and measuring transcendent extension. And it should be clear
that no such finite or indefinite objective process can ever reach the infinite
either in terms of extent or resolution (transitive or immanent,
respectively).ii
Even though Spinoza’s extended Substance is fundamentally continuous
(recall our principle of Nondual Rationalism; infinite division equals
indivisibility), extension—as a relative conceptual, perceptual and metrical
concept—does not descend into the immanent causation or infinite-
divisibility/indivisibilityiii within the continuity. Rather it must remain a
strictly transitive or transcendent (trans-biased) concept based on the set
limit or range of scale centered on the basic unit itself; otherwise every

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
This is why, as Leibniz discovered, neither the multiplicative infinite nor the divisive zero are true
numbers.
iii
At the absolute level these two (infinitely-divided and indivisible) are identical.

Page | 516
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

smallest distance would be conceived/perceived as a compounded infinity


and all sensory propagations would descend into Zeno’s trap of indefinite
division. In such a case their transitive motion would be arrested, shunted
into the infinite immanence within and never to return. An object or wave
in natural uniform motion perfectly illustrates the transitivity of extension
which is always external (emergent and transcendent) to the immanent
continuity within all conceivable “needle-sharp points”i. This exclusion of
the infinities of scale (which are embedded in the concept of continuity), is
the transitivity and transcendence of extension (see Figure 68, below)

Figure 68: Extension and the I/T Axis:


This is the I/T omni-axis illustrating the
transitive-planes of resonance
abstracted from the continuous
spectrum of frequencies. The macro
direction on this VL-axis zooms out and
the micro zooms in to new resonance
scales of extension. In reality all the
scales are spatially superimposed,
coexisting and emergent together, but
they must be separated in this
transitive rendering in order to get a
better understanding of the separation
in perception, measurement and even in
resonant harmonic interaction. This
demonstrates the transitive aspect of
extension as centered on, and
orthogonal to, a common position
(scale) on the I/T omni-axis. The
coordinate of the relevant “plane of
extension” on the I/T-axis is determined
by the scale of the interrelating object
components (units) in resonance with
the interface components (sensory
mechanisms and sub-components) of
the perceiving mode.

Extended observability is always external to the interfaces of both the


observer and the observed and it is always in relation to the vastly limited
sensory scale of the observer. In this sense, the epistemic level of extension
(objectivity) is based on emission or reflection of sensory modifications, such

i
A term borrowed from Gerald Lebau which fits with Bucky Fuller’s “Operational Mathematics” by
adding extension and boundary (and the corresponding nuclear polarity) to every conceivable point,
rendering “infinitely small” ultimately an oxymoron (see SpinbitZ).

Page | 517
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

as acoustic or optical wave-forms. The ontic level of extension, on the other


hand, is based on the reflection of actual bounded forms from each other, as
opposed to their merging. This is because the ontic transitive-plane—the
foundation for agglomerative forms of evolution and complexity—is
dependent on the self-identity of “simplest bodies,” as Spinoza puts it, or
“monads” in Leibniz’s terminology. The attribute of Thought, on the other
hand, is founded on the refraction or self-focusing and self-collecting of
various energies, in both epistemic and ontic forms (subjectivity and self-
reinforcement or homeostasis, respectively).
The external perception/conception of ‘extension’ is objectivity because
sensation must originate in modification at an emergent, and thus finite or
bounded, level. Even when objectivity dissects an object of inquiry, thus
extending its range of observability into the components of this object, it
always does so from the outside of these individualized and exposed
components—and indeed always from outside the original self-stabilized,
integral and emergent organization which it might disrupt in the act of
dissecting observation.
Objectivity can thus never attain the perspective or experience of being
the subjectivity of the object of perception (see Figure 69, below), except
when subject and object are one and the same mode and one perceives the
symbiogenesis of subject and object in the self-focusing sensory/mnemonic
interface itself. This is the essence of the isolation, parallelism and polarity
of the attributes (recall Figure 67, p514) and it gives rise to the
unbridgeable, epistemic, ‘explanatory gap’ between the two protocols of
description—subjectivity and objectivity (or mind and matter)—which finds
its logical unity in the immanent causation of the Substance/Emptiness from
which all bounded forms (including the interface) are emergent.
Conceiving and perceiving through the attribute of Extension is therefore
the transitive outward conceptual (mental/metrical) radiation from a
cognitive interface impinging on the external surfaces of other nuclei or
nuclear-agglomerates (objects, patterns, brains, or cognitive holons) always
within the same scale or region of resonance (e.g. visible light) rather than
transcending infinitely up or down the I/T axis. The singular point of view—
or more precisely, the nuclear interface of observability—is intrinsic to the
concept of extension as it sets the resonant scale of perception.
Throughout the entire visible universe we sense only those events whose
propagated disturbances resonate with our sensory mechanisms. We see
objects, planets, stars and galaxies only because—like our own sensory
mechanisms—within their structuring they contain atoms or molecules
whose electronic shells emit or reflect waves within the narrow band of our
own evolved and technologically augmented sensory receptive frequencies.
This then acts as a filter for the perception of both spatial and temporal
universal patterning relevant to the survival of the organism (recall Figure
68, above, p 518). The universe, therefore, appears far emptier and less

Page | 518
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

orderly and structured than it otherwise would. This is because the


quantized nuclear interfaces—such as the concentric shell-patterning of
planets, stars and galaxiesi—with emitted and reflected frequencies beyond
and beneath the scope of the augmented human spectrum—are entirely
undetectable and invisible to us in our present state.ii

i
This universal self-similar or fractal patterning can be seen on all scales, from the electron shells of
the atom (mapped with Schrödinger’s equation) to the structuring of the stellar systems (mapped
with Bode’s Law). The possible mechanisms for this patterning are explained in Sorce Theory
(www.anpheon.org )
ii
We are constantly expanding our range of perception through technological augmentation. A great
example is the “Terahertz gap” in the spectrum of detectable em-waves between infrared and
microwaves which is just beginning to be opened by technological means offering whole new realms
of observational capabilities such as seeing through walls and enhanced medical imaging. There is
simply no end in sight to the expansion of our perceptual range and no reason (except for current
limitations of “Standard” theory) to suspect an absolute barrier.

Page | 519
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 69: The Cognitive Holon and the Subject/Object Interface with Immanence and
Transcendence:
Perception is a subject/object resonance within a limited domain of frequencies
(transitive plane) on the infinite VL-axis of scale (I/T axis). The white background
without and within each mode corresponds to those frequencies of resonance which
are beyond and below (respectively) the perceptual reach of the cognitive holon, i.e.
beyond the sensorial realm. The black rings denote the self -stabilized homeostatic
integrated emergence of intrinsic, self-focused ‘experience’ (“qualia”) from within the
mode. The larger spheres are the modes of cognition such as a human brain/mind with
its corresponding epistemic duality of objectivity and subjectivity. Note that when the
arrow of extension tries to touch the inner ‘experience’—the inner black rings—of an
outer mode, the best it can do is convert the insides into outsides in exposing the
inside components to an outside view. One may object that we can receive sens ory
data, such as active brain scans, directly from the insides of living brains, but this is
still a view of the inside from outside the mode in question. One cannot ever
experience the within of anything through sensations from without, without
transforming that without into that within. One must be the focal point of the
energies to be the experience of the subjectivity in question.

Page | 520
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Substance, in Nondual Rationalism, is a continuum of “infinite division


equals indivisibility” and “infinite determinism equals indeterminism,” and
thus it is ultimately scale-independent and trans-foundational. This does not
mean, of course, that the aspect or attribute of transitive extension,
orthogonal to the VL-axis of scale, is exclusively an epistemic, sensory,
perceptual or metrical phenomenon. This conclusion would be to neglect the
ontic aspect included in Spinoza’s definition of an attribute. As we will see,
the relevant (sensorially resonant) transitive “plane of extension” i is
meaningfully grounded in an absolute (physical, actual or ontic) position on
the I/T omni-axis, and it is from this emergent or transcendent foundation
that the morphological gradient of “excellence” gets its structural basis.
Substance may be “formless” or emptiness in its logically prior and eternal
absolute scope aspect (Substance is “prior to its modifications”ii¥), but in the
field of time—i.e. in the broken symmetry of actuality/activity or
existence—Substance appears to be entirely inhomogeneous and actively
modified/modifying in self-similar patterns on regular, intermittent and
unlimited scales. This may be the real meaning of quantization as found by
modern physics at the sub-atomic, atomic, planetary, stellar, and galactic
levels and its possible mechanisms are beyond the scope of this book.iii
The nature of actuality appears to be such that at specific recurring
intervals on the I/T omni-axis its modifications become homogenized or
granulated at specific “identical”iv sizes (e.g. interstellar H atoms) to form
levels of unit-patterns, or “matter-unit substrates.”v* These substrates of
interrelating homogenized units (Spinoza’s “simplest bodies” or Leibniz’s

i
Keep in mind that the plane itself is a spatial abstraction from the continuity of the spectrum of
frequencies and thus it really represents a continuous range in a volume of frequencies set by the
cognitive mode itself which in turn is based at the deeper ontic level of the “matter-unit substrate”
or “islands of resonance.”
ii¥
Ethics I, Prop. 1.
iii
Possible mechanisms for this quantization can be found in Sorce Theory, and covered at a general
level in my article Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement. The galactic-scale quantization is seen in
the recent conclusions of the “quantization of redshift” based on observations initially conducted in
the early 1970’s by William G. Tifft, of the University of Arizona. See for example
http://www.ldolphin.org/tifftshift.html This also may cast a deep problem onto the Big Bang
cosmogony which is based on the Doppler interpretation of the Hubble redshift as its sole
mechanism. If—as has been shown in other studies such as the “fingers of God” anomaly—there
are serious problems with the Doppler interpretation of redshift, then there must be another
mechanism other than the fantastical idea of the expansion of the entire Universe, whose extent, for
all we know, may be infinite.
iv
This is the field of “simplest bodies” denoted by Spinoza which evolves into “composite bodies”
along the gradient of “excellence.” Depending on the meta-unit homogeneity (density/pressure
gradients/patterns) of the next substrate level from which they form.
v
* See, Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.

Page | 521
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

“physical monads”), our atoms and their quantized variants i (the ~92
naturally occurring chemical elements), generate resonant levels or planes
of morphological complexity, stability and agglomerative possibility
enabling the architectural complexification necessary for the “spontaneous”
evolution of the cognitive holons. These transitive planes of
stability/possibility (“islands of resonance”) on the I/T omni-axis are then
the “ground” of the morphological gradient of cognitive complexification
towards Spinoza’s cognitive “excellence.”
From the relative simplicity at the level of the homogenized/granulated
matter-unit substrate, to the monstrous architectural complexity of the
cognitive holons—this gradient forms the essence of the ontic/epistemic
polarity; the distinction from which the conceptual/perceptual
(mental/metrical or epistemic) aspect of extension (the fundamental
descriptive protocol) can expand its range of inter-relating, representational
action upon the ontic level in order to create what we call “physical science.”
The immanent scales of these transitive planes are set by the uniformity
of the interrelating and interacting matter-units and their resonant
frequencies. Of necessity—as immanent causal aspects of univocal
Substance—they are perfectly, causally and harmoniously integrated in all
directions on all imaginable and unimaginable omni-relational transitive,
immanent and transcendent axes. It is an infinite causal self-similar
holarchy in which each immanent level enables the quantized existence of
the next transcendent level and vice versa. At the descriptive or perceptual
level, however, these orthogonal ‘planes’ function quite independently as
individual cognitive holons come into or out of sensorial resonance with
them, expanding, contracting or shifting their miniscule range of perception,
through birth, death, technology or evolution.
At our scale of sensory resonance, we observe this homogenized,
interrelational, extensional orthogonality most clearly in the ubiquitous
molecular/atomic matrix of hydrogen (the root atom) that is known to fill
interstellar and intergalactic space.
As highly complex compounded modifications, we are born from and into
this self-similarly modified extensional orthogonality on the chemically and
biologically active surface of a terrestrial nucleus—a planetary biosphere.
This emergent I/T-orthogonality or transitivity inherent in the immanent,
continuous active essence of Substance—in its formative aspect to nucleate
into transitively inter-relating self-similar islands of resonance—is
extension at the ontic level as it causally interrelates the nature of

i
Sorce Theory and quantum physics demonstrates the likelihood that the subatomic particles are
either variants of the simplest atomic nucleus, such as protons and neutrons, or they are relatively
short-lived wave-forms and resonances such as solitons, breathers or other complex and dynamic
morphologies that do not ‘own’ their own material, and thus collectively they form charged fields
rather than composite bodies proper.

Page | 522
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

emergence, modal-complexity (excellence), perception-conception (the


epistemic) and their respective forms of relation (ontic and epistemic). See
Figure 70, below.

Page | 523
Page | 524
Figure 70: Duality Chasm: The Vista of the Expanded
Crossroads:
This chart is a logical extension of Figure 65 (p505), but
renders a more comprehensive view of the ideas given so
far. Note that it includes c onceptual links to the physical
theory upon which this model is based, such as the inclusion
of the single force (“sorce”) and its bifurcation into the
duality of force (all attraction and repulsion) in the
distinction between reflection and refraction. Note also that
there are many open spaces in the tentative listing of
categories and descriptive and formative protocols. Because
of the pervasiveness of these fundamental orthogonal
polarities which are found in almost all known metaphysical
systems, this chart is useful for the organization of many
systems of thought
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Page | 525
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

We have seen that both the descriptive protocols—subjectivity and


objectivity—emerge from the morphological gradient of emergent
“excellence” (with its polarity of formative protocols) into the
representational realm of the epistemic. Thus both subjectivity and
objectivity are finite (or indefinite) systems of relative knowledge about the
relative and infinitely complex, intrinsic or extrinsic world of form,
respectively.
In terms of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, taken as an “organizing principle”
behind the Ethics, the attributes are the aspects of The Infinite (Substance),
as seen from within or from without any particular modification. This
morphological and polar explanation, then, gives a concrete reason why
Spinoza only gave us two of the infinite, or unlimited attributes of God—a
problem which has vexed Spinozists from the beginning.
With the concept of “the nucleation of observability” it has been pointed
out that all systems of knowledge emerge at the sensory/representational
(mnemonic) interface of a cognitive mode, and this emergence is always
transcendent to a deeper level of immanence, on the I/T omni- or uni-axis.
We have also seen this as the simple meaning of Deleuze’s “transcendental
empiricism” in that perception/conception always begins from a plane of
immanence that is already necessarily transcendent or emergent from
deeper immanence. Such an immanent plane, we have also seen, is
necessarily, at the same time, a transitive-plane. Empiricism, therefore,
being derived ultimately from emergent/collective perception, is necessarily
inherently emergent or transcendental, conceived as a transitive plane on
the immanent-transcendent omni-axis, for the collective of empirical data,
and a spherical interface on the uni-axis, for the empirical surface of the
individual.

Page | 526
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Figure 71: The Star of Complexity:


In this diagram we have several interfacing polarities. In the horizontal dimension,
bisecting the left and right sides of the star, we have the polarity of the within and the
without, respectively. From bottom to top we have the inversely overlapping polarities
of complexity—holism vs. reductionism—where, in the upward direction, we move
from whole to greater whole (holism), with the current culmination in the one of
human consciousness, encompassing the simpler wholes of vast quantities of various
simpler holons—atoms, cells, etc. From top to bottom, on the other hand, we have the
polarity of reductionism, where we start with the massive numbers making up the
whole of consciousness and move down toward one single atom. In the two skewed
polarities we find the selection at the ontic level —pointing foundationally to the
immanent pole of the absolute scope —deciding the skew of the epistemic level. If, for
example, the objective is seen as the ontic, then this skews the ontic toward the
attribute of extension, and the subjective suffers a reduction to it as the epistemic.

This finite emergent/transcendent representational surface of the


cognitive/representational mode—emerging from the “infinite-divisibility
equals indivisible” continuum—is a distinction between the infinities of the
within and the without, and naturally this bounded interface shares the
limits of all finite, bounded systems. At the very basis of this fallibilistic

Page | 527
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

view, then, is the common-sense notion that no finite system can encompass
the infinite. In the Univocity Framework, recall, the infinite and the finite
form a fundamental polarity—the polarity of polarity itself, where the
relative scope projects its other, the absolute scope, to give it defining
context.i* The infinite and finite are the quantitative aspects of the absolute
and relative scopes; the core polarity of Substance and its modes.
According to this nondual-rational point of view, then, both the
materialists and the idealists (or the Subjectivists and Objectivists) make a
common mistake. They each fail to understand the proper role of the
subjective and the objective as fundamental descriptive protocols in the
epistemic and relative realm of inherently limited and fallible
representational abstraction. They therefore each take one epistemic
protocol or the other and erroneously project it down to the ontic level,
toward the foundational absolute scope, in exclusion of the other (see Figure
71, above). This unbalanced view is akin to claiming that outsides can exist
without (or prior to) insides or vice versa and that the entire universe is
ultimately composed only of either the outsides or the insides of things.
When understood in this way, these two common views, in their various
forms, become quite nonsensical because they each neglect the fundamental
nondual principle of polarity, violating the Univocity Framework, as we have
seen.
Materialism (or physicalism) is the view that objectivity (modified
Substance as viewed externally through the attribute of Extension) is the
fundamental point of view into which all others must reduce. Even further,
it is the failure to recognize that objectivity is a point of view at all.ii This
failure enables the ontic=objective absolutization of this relative view and
the reduction of its symbiotic opposite. In the minds of the materialists, this
view then becomes inherently infallible in principle (i.e. the finite is
considered infinite or unlimited and the relative is considered absolute) and
the materialist then claims that subjectivity is fundamentally unreal and
therefore encompassable and replaceable by objectivity.
This is the view taken, in one form or another, by many scientists and
philosophers such as Daniel Dennett, for instance, who has gone so far as to
reject the notion (or maybe just an absolute distortion of the term) of ‘qualia’
(the ‘what it’s like’ quality of mental states) entirely as inherently
meaningless and replaceable by mechanical descriptions.iii

i
* See, “Vertical” Polarity: The Polarity of Polarity, p175.
ii
As stated previously, this is because the meaning of “objectivity” has changed from the
representation of external reality to the reality itself, the ontic. Now there is no corresponding word
to denote its prior meaning and to balance the meaning of subjectivity.
iii
Dennett’s view on qualia, however, is quite justified from within the materialist’s paradigm, and
indeed it is useful to break the Cartesian dualistic spell. Dennett places great emphasis on
demonstrating that the common, absolutized and mystified usage of the term qualia renders the

Page | 528
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

In his book The Truth About Everything, Matthew Stewart notes quite
presciently that in materialism, such a reduction to man-made and arguably
ideal laws discloses a polarity reversali* in that materialism becomes an
idealism when matter reduces to merely the ideal laws of physics. Indeed
we can see this quite clearly in the operations at the empirical edges of
physics where the function of the conscious observer and his descriptive
protocols in the collapse of the wave-function is taken to be the reality itself.
Stewart comically calls this problem “The Schmiderialism Principle”ii¥ and
indeed it is a problem of mistaking descriptive (epistemic) protocols,
subjectivity or objectivity for the formative, ontic or sub-representational
level itself.
Similarly, idealism intuitively recognizes that objectivity has forced
something critical out of the picture and so the idealists swing the other
direction and project the intrinsic emergent aspect of modal existence, down
to the absolute level, often rejecting any and all objective external
descriptions, and even science itself in many cases. The idealists too fail to
realize the emergent/transcendental nature of the epistemic mode
(fundamental descriptive protocol) of subjectivity as inherently abstract and
limited—as well as failing to understand the fundamental polarity and
symbiosis of the two fundamental descriptive/representational points of
view.
Both of these views, we can see, ultimately (when taken to their
extremes) collapse into the “cogito of the dissolved self,” the solipsistic
reduction to the ontic-epistemic boundary of individual experience and the

problem in Cartesian dualistic terms, his ‘Cartesian Theatre.’ Essentially Dennett is only denying that
we have subjective experience in order to say that we are the subjective experience which is
ultimately reduced to a “benign user illusion.” The illusion of course, includes the self-diagnostic
feedback function of self-reflexion.
Notice how the rephrasing from “we have subjective experience” to “we are subjective experience”
disables the dualistic, subject/object, internal homuncular projection. His point is that we have let
the common meanings of this problematic word ‘qualia’ disable the functioning of the “intuition
pumps” or “heuristic bridges,” used by the cognitive scientists, thus disabling the relative truths of
cognitive science to work their way through the philosophy of mind. Since the explanatory gap is
fundamentally unbridgeable, intuition or heuristics are then the only means of correlating the
physicalist descriptions with the actual experience we know as ‘qualia.’ This means that if the word
‘qualia’ causes us to misunderstand the nature of the problem, and therefore causes us to fail to
properly use the quite adequate heuristic bridges provided by cognitive science, then the term must
be disabled in favor of a more correctly functioning word in order to render the problem workable.
Perhaps Dennett could have gone the route of saying that we are qualia rather rejecting the word
itself, but this would still not disable the collective connotative basins of attraction into typical and
simplistic Cartesian dualistic notions that the word engenders. It is perhaps indeed more useful to
just abandon a word and start fresh rather than insist that people use it in a new way.
i
* See, Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR), p117.
ii
Matthew Stewart, The Truth About Everything, p. 309

Page | 529
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

absolute reversali* from this solipsism to the identical opposite omni-non of


nihilipsism, when the absolute self dissolves and digests its defining other.

Spinoza’s morphological gradient of ‘excellence,’ along with our cogito


boundary, is the springboard for further reflection into the symbiotic
subject/object polarity of the fundamental protocols emergent at both ontic
and epistemic levels. As previously mentioned, self-stabilization cannot
exist without an environment in which to stabilize; the self is defined by its
interface with its other.
This appears to be true at all levels in the boundless holarchy, from
“fundamental particle” ii to biological cell to animal awareness and to
consciousness. In the genesis of intelligent biological homeostasis,iii the
organism complexifies its inner structure to capture and abstract the
intricacy and the encountered ‘contingencies’ of its environment in order to
optimize its chances of survival through ‘intelligent’ reactions. Or as Deleuze
might say, the organism enfolds the outside into the inside, in the
convolutions of the vinculum of the self-boundary. In this symbiotic
enfolding process the primitive seeds of both subjectivity and objectivity are
born via an interdependent symbiogenesis of an internal and external
environment separating, integrating and manifesting an emerging,
evolving/involving (convoluting ) and enfolding boundary (vinculum).
Subjectivity is dependent on objectivity because the complexity of the
sensed, felt, reacted environment is the catalyst, source and template for its
own ever-complexifying, enfolding interiorization and abstraction into
‘mechanism’ and ‘function,’ through the intrinsic problem-solving
intelligence of evolution. This is what Maturana and Varela call “structural
coupling,” where “...a history of recurrent interactions [leads] to the
structural congruence between two (or more) systems,” (p75) but it is

i
* See, Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR), p117.
ii
In Spinoza’s view, “substance is prior to its modifications,” therefore no particle can be
fundamental in any absolute sense. The absolute fundamental is the ONE, infinite and continuous
substance, i.e. the universe itself—and all else is but multiplication through division—a modification.
However, in a forthcoming integration and interpretation of Leibniz’s concept of the ‘monad’, there
is a sense in which a pattern, in this case nucleation (for instance at the ontic level of “simplest
bodies” or atoms) and its distinctive pattern of quantization (seen in the intra-atomic-electron orbits
and in the structure of the solar system etc,) can be fundamental as the self-similar infinitely
recurring pattern in the cosmos, the “matter-unit (see Sorce Theory). The absolute fundamental
element of nature, however, is the One, infinite substance, i.e. the universe itself or the absolute
scope. All else is but multiplication through division—a modification.
iii
Spinoza calls the tendency or “endeavor” for each composite body towards self-preservation, its
“essence.”

Page | 530
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

important to note that what is coupled is not the environment and the
interior of the organism, but the interior and the exterior of the abstract
interface of perception itself. Objectivity, recall, is not the outside itself (i.e.
the ontic), but the outside view of the epistemic. At the higher levels of
morphological complexity—yet at the very rudiments of the emerging
cognitive mode—this templating or subject/object calibration process
(enfolding) generates what can be called the “mnemonic primitives,” which
are the defining feature of ‘qualia’ as the emergent, primitive-level
subject/object interface (vinculum) itself; the raw percepts transcended-
and-included in the higher forms of concept.
When a child is born into sensorial resonance with the world, it begins an
intensive calibration process between its inherent pattern recognition,
mnemonic and sensory structures and its resonant environment. This
calibration process is the essence of memory, qualia and sensation in one
enfolding interface between the within and the without. This is why the
newborn infant, as it learns to see and interact with the world, generally
forms and retains no memories that make sense as such to the adult, though
they are ‘remembered’ in dismembered or distributive form as the
primitives of the experience of qualia itself throughout conscious life.i The
infant’s root-level mnemonic pattern-recognition medium is still being
formed and it is from this medium (or context) that all subsequent memories
arise as further complexifications. The child’s memories come into focus as
s/he matures because part of that maturing involves the gradual
development of the mnemonic sensory system itself, from the ground up.
At a basic neurological level the senses begin to ‘memorize’ or ‘learn’
(enfold) the abstracted relevant details and differentiations of reality (e.g.
colors) as it resonates and interacts at the sensory-motor interface. It does
this in order to generate distinct and differentiated responses to different
stimuli as the basis for further higher-level, more abstract homeostatic
cognition and interaction. Some of these responses—the mnemonic
primitives—are the learned neuro-sensory patterns and differentiations
(memories) that are reactivated every time the same basic stimulus is
presented, such as the various frequencies of light impinging on the retina.
Subjectivity itself (e.g. qualia), in this primitive form, thus emerges as the
very experience of the cognitive mode, in active/reactive sensory/mnemonic
resonance with its objective environment.

i
Every once in a while, these primitive memories can crop up in strange places, however, such as a
memory I have which I can only attribute to the moment of birth. This memory of a thick squeeze
and release, seems to emerge into my awareness very strongly and only at the still moments of
crisis. In the embryogenesis of the concept, as one would expect, this primitive memory is very
simple and undifferentiated. It is not even localized in space or time, but feels as if it were occurring
throughout my entire body simultaneously, as if it weren’t composed of subcomponents at all. It
squeezes tight my entire, undifferentiated primitive body-“image” and suddenly releases. Perhaps,
indeed, a primitive memory of the contractions or the moment of birth.

Page | 531
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Mnemonic primitives, then, are a function of being embedded in a reality.


They are the “what it is like” to be such an embedded cognitive mode in the
act of perception/conception when this implicit calibration of sensorial
memory becomes reactivated in its various intrinsic and extrinsic ways;
subjective conception or objective perception, respectively.
The mnemonic primitives are the interface between the subjective and
objective because they form the basis and representational foundation of
each, and they are formed in the same embodied enfolding, convoluting,
differentiating-and-integrating symbiogenetic process of the development of
the interface between the within and without. Sensation or objectivity
cannot exist without this subjective calibration and convoluting
differentiation into the intelligent, cognitive, pattern re-cognition functions
of perception. And the mnemonic primitives themselves are the very
medium of more complex memories, as well as all subjective experiencing
such as dreams, emotions, and self-reflection. Therefore, both subjectivity
and objectivity are seen as different sides of the very same enfolded
mnemonic interface and neither could exist without the other. They are
necessarily formed in an entirely symbiotic and integrated process, and so
they are symbiogenetic (see Figure 72, below).
In the complexification through evolutionary intelligence of this
symbiotic subject/object interface into the more abstract representational
forms of awareness and consciousness, more and more layers of abstraction
are added to the pre-existing massive parallelism of the subconscious and
preconscious homeostatic organism. Each new layer of abstraction, while
more complex than the last, generally serves to consolidate and reflexively
integrate the previous, more ‘primitive,’ layer until finally reaching the level
of ‘excellence’ of the human being with its cerebral cortex and unitary
experience or “stream” of consciousness.
The human organism has thus emerged, ultimately, at the level of
abstraction of the linearity of language and the highly focused ‘inner voice of
consciousness’ or ‘the stream of thought.’i This emergent linguistic linearity
enables functionality in the form of complex strings of internal meaning and
external communication (both of which, in the same process at this higher
level, are also symbiogenetic). Through a similar symbiogenetic feedback
process, external communication and internal abstract conceptualization
enables a further degree of rigor and linear complexification in the thoughts
themselves (mnemonic complexes) due to the internal and external
structure of the language in which the thoughts are functionally
‘encapsulated’ and reflexively conjured.

i
Alan Watts calls this “spotlight consciousness” as opposed to the “floodlight sub-consciousness.”

Page | 532
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Figure 72: The Sensory/Mnemonic Interface:


A vastly over-simplified and generalized schematic of the symbiotic relationships
between subjectivity, objectivity, internal and external reality. Objectivity is on the
outside of the mode simply because it includes the external senses and thus mediates
between real or ontic externality and subjectivity. Both subjectivity and objectivity get
their epistemic grounding in the mnemonic primitives as the basis of representation
through enfolding and embodied calibration with external reality via the evolutio nary
development of the senses. Note, however, that this diagram represents the areas in a
linearly circumnuclear fashion, but in reality these areas are distributed throughout
the brain in a highly complex and convoluted patterning, much more like a tree (or a
rain forest) than a sphere. Note also that there are feedback circuits (arrows) in one
form or another from all represented and general areas to all others and that
consciousness plays a key role in both subjectivity and objectivity.

The linearity inherent in language comes at a price, however, because of


its limited scope when confronted with the massive parallelism of its
subconscious processes. This problem is captured in the central paradox of
Artificial Intelligence which states, “systems simple enough to be
understandable are not complicated enough to behave intelligently; and
systems complicated enough to behave intelligently are not simple enough
to be understood.”i¥ This problem is akin to raising oneself up by ones own
bootstraps or trying to fit the area of a circle into its own circumference—or
more appropriately in this case, trying to fit a whole pyramid into its very
tip.


George B. Dyson, Darwin Among the Machines (USA: Addison Wesley, 1997)

Page | 533
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 73: The All-Talking Mouth:


Consciousness can be visualized as the very tip of a vast pyramid of layers and layers of
massively parallel complexity. Each new layer emerges as the abstraction,
simplification, generalization and consolidation of the massive parallelism beneath it
until at the apex of human thought we end up wit h linear, linguistic, abstract
consciousness. This linearity, though very advantageous in the construction and
communication of serially complex and rigorous thought, has its inherent limitations
especially when it tries to encapsulate parallelism of even minimal complexity (just try
to focus on 50 things at once, moving in different directions, and you will find all sorts
of compromises must be made to even begin to approach to that figure). Therefore to
simultaneously understand such complexity —where billions of billions of neurons
(each composed of billions and billions of atoms) are connected by billions more
synapses into densely packed, inconceivably chaotic dendritic thickets —one must rely
on the deeper processes of intuition by letting go of consci ous demands for a perfectly
explicit linear and serial account of the vastly complex, massively parallel and entirely
nonlinear causal foundation from which linear “one-track-mind” consciousness
emerges.

Page | 534
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

As we have seen, the nondual-rational method of understanding the relation


between the attributes (or aspects) of Substance and its modes is necessarily
arranged in a neutral alignment. At the ontic level, neither Extension nor
Thought holds any foundational dominance over the other, in exactly the
same way that neither real outsides nor real insides can be conceived one
without the other. This neutrality is the nondual and relative truth of the
common “neutral monism” interpretation of Spinoza’s system. The key
difference, however, is that the typical monistic approach is commonly
(though not always) a foundationalism, and the nondual-rational approach is
explicitly trans-foundational, given its univocal framework and Vision-Logic
Coordinate System.
Identity Theory, or Reductive Materialism, asserts that mental states are
numerically identical to brain states, in other words they are absolutely one
and the same thing. However, as the name implies, Reductive Materialism
also says that subjective states are “intertheoretically reducible” (absolutely
reducible) to objective, physical or material states. This means that, as the
deeper reality, objective states hold an ontological or foundational primacy
over subjective states, but both are accurate descriptions at their respective
levels of abstraction—ontic vs. epistemic, essentially.
As we have seen, however, in Spinoza’s system both subjectivity and
objectivity are emergent at the epistemic level of the morphological gradient
of ‘excellence’ as the categories of representation, or the fundamental
descriptive protocols. Therefore, as an absolutization of a relative
knowledge system—the epistemic objective at the expense of its inverse
symbiotic partner the epistemic subjective—Identity Theory is thus an
unbalanced view of reality. Indeed, it is a clear example of the objective-
ontic shift, we discussed previously, where the objective has come to be
identified with, or shifted toward the ontic itself, in the context of the
successful scientific-objective relation with technological production and
reality.
According to the interpretation herein, then, Reductive Materialism
essentially says that all insides, though numerically identical to outsides, can
and must be fundamentally reduced to outsides. In these reassigned terms
this conclusion is clearly an absurdity; insides are not outsides and one
cannot exist without (or be intertheoretically reduced to) the other. In
Spinoza’s system there is a strictly separated (and symbiotically conjoined)
parallelism between the two attributes at all levels of the morphological
gradient of excellence; this of course includes the epistemic. The two views
of inside and outside, or subjective and objective are simply not equivalent,
in fact they are symbiotic polar opposites, and therefore it is plain that they
cannot be directly reduced or identified, one to the other.

Page | 535
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Does this mean that Identity Theory and Spinoza’s “neutral monism” or
univocal Nondual Rationalism, share no relation? Spinoza says [my
emphasis], “Thinking substance and extended substance are one and the
same thing, comprehended now through this, now through that, attribute.”
This certainly seems to entail an identity of some kind, especially with the
phrase “one and the same thing,” which is actually used in the definition of
Reductive Materialism given above. If the subjective mind and the objective
brain are not numerically identical, then in what sense are they identical and
in what sense can they be reduced, one to the other?
The key here is found in Spinoza’s use of the term “substance.” In
Spinoza’s neutral monism both subjectivity and objectivity are
representative or epistemic aspects of reality, which is neither mind nor
matter exclusively, but it has balanced aspects of both Thought and
Extension (the within and the without as specifically defined herein). Recall
that all modes conceived under each attribute, e.g. the “modes of extension”
and the “modes of thought,” are fundamentally modes of Substance.
Since the mind and the brain are modes of Substance conceived
(episteme) and only differentiated under the attributes of Thought and
Extension respectively, they are then considered and categorized as modes
of the attributes under which they are currently conceived. Thus—due to
the fundamental non-identity between the attributes—“mind” and “brain”
cannot be numerically identical. An identity must therefore be drawn down
through an attribute-neutral ontic channel to the modification of Substance
itself, inclusive of both of its attributes, i.e. before the epistemic distinction
between the within and the without of the singular mode itself is made (See
Figure 74, below). It is this connection between the epistemic and ontic
symbiogenetic polarities of the singular bounded or nucleated modes of
substance, which provides the parallelism and the “exact order and
connection” between the attributes as both descriptive and formative
protocols.
Neutral Monism—as herein described in the context of Nondual
Rationalism—inherits all of the positive aspects of Identity Theory and yet
seems to escape all of its problems. It is said that one of the benefits of
Identity Theory is its accordance with scientific accounts of the functioning
of the brain. Neutral monism, however, is directly in line with, and accepts
both fundamental descriptive protocols; the objective (cognitive science)
and subjective (folk psychology), and it unifies them at a deeper, univocal
ontological level, through the polarity of bounded form. Thus neutral
monism naturally inherits this same positive scientific aspect because
objectivity is a real perception of real modified Substance.

Page | 536
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

Figure 74: Identity Theory vs. Neutral Monism:


In Identity Theory a numerical equivalence is drawn between mental states and brain
states (“Mind” and “Brain” herein). This is shown in box A. However, Box B shows the
Spinozistic non-identity between subjectivity and objectivity as the emergent epistemic
levels of the attributes as polar opposites. Since the mind and the brain are modes of
Substance conceived (episteme) under the attribute of thought and extension
respectively, then they are considered modes of the attributes. Due to the
fundamental non-identity between the attributes then, mind and brain cannot be
numerically identical and an identity must be drawn through a neutral channel. This is
demonstrated in the “Neutral Monism” panel where the reduction from the two modes
of the attributes is drawn (with the solid lines) down to the mode of Substance (the
“Cognitive Mode”) because “…in the universe nothing is granted, save substances and
their modifications.” The dotted lines indicate functions of the epistemic i.e.
conception and perception and comprehension, whereas the solid lines indicate the
ontic or absolute.

The main problem with Neutral Monism in its current connotations,


however, is that it conjures up a foundationalism; a subject/object,
mind/matter, attribute-neutral immanent/transitive-plane of amorphous
goo, from which complicated modifications somehow emerge. This sounds
rather similar to orthodox accounts of quantum mechanics, actually, as
causation and determinism emerges from the level of “random”
indeterminism existing just below the level of the atom. Neutral Monism as
a foundationalism, as we discussed, would then be a tacit dualism; that of
formlessness and form, the former generating the latter, but not vice versa.i*
A critical problem with Identity Theory, on the other hand, is the so-
called “multiple realizability problem,” the idea that many different brain
states might all cause the same mind state. This problem arises from the

i
* See, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156.

Page | 537
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

absolute nature of the concept of the numerical identity, because if the same
mental state can be achieved in different physical/material instantiations
and functional platforms, then there can be no one-to-one identity. The
problem is that identity theory unwittingly claims an identity between
physical states and mental states at the epistemic level of the objective and
the subjective, rather than at the ontic level of the single mode of substance.
In order for Identity Theory to hold, a weaker, or relative version of the
identity must be maintained, and this weakens the reductive force and
scientific feel of the model, already lacking any morphological or percept-
based description of the identity, and also lacking the reason that its identity
is now merely relative.
Since, however, the attribute-neutrality of neutral monism and Nondual
Rationalism does not place a numerical identity between subjective mental
states and their objective (externally observed) brain-state counterparts, no
such definitional identity problems arise. The mental-states and the brain-
states are fundamentally different states of description at the epistemic level
and they are the relative and limited means to identify or observe states in
the cognitive mode, arising as they do in dependent symbiogenesis of subject
and object at (and as) the mnemonic interface of the cognitive mode. In
Nondual Rationalism, such an absolute attribution of identity between these
relative, limited, and fundamentally (indeed symbiogenetically) opposed
descriptive protocols, is a violation of the Univocity Framework and the
principles of nonduality.
As we will see, however, the main problem with Identity
Theory/Reductive Materialism—and indeed a common problem with
virtually every materialistic, physicalist or Objectivist theory of mind—
stems from its foundationalist nature. The problem is that no strictly
materialist theory can fully (i.e. absolutely) and explicitlyi account for qualia.
This is naturally because the relative world of description can’t encompass
the absolute scope of the infinite difference of the embodied experience of
subjectivity itself. In other words, given the polarity of the attributes, and
the fallibility of the fundamental descriptive protocols occurring at the
relative and emergent level of awareness, qualia are naturally irreducible to
an objective, physicalist description. The explanatory gap simply cannot
ultimately be bridged. Instead, what we get in all of these theories is a
promissory note that eventually science will evolve to the point that such an
explicit account will indeed bridge this gap.ii While certainly such an

i
Note that the ‘explicit’ is the essence of materialism and objectivity.
ii
It is quite unclear how the explanatory gap ever could be bridged, however, except by relying at
some level on an intuition pump or a causative means rather than an explicit objective explanation.
Of course intuition pumps can already bridge the gap, provided one can properly operate the pump,
but this is not at all satisfactory to the absolute aims of the physicalist or idealist programs which
assumes one or the other descriptive protocols as absolute reality itself and thus needs perfectly

Page | 538
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

account will continue to evolve to the point that it feels adequate, it can
never be complete and absolute in any nondual account.
Nondual Rationalism, however, makes no such absolutist claims about
any necessarily finite and relative knowledge system, or about any of the
relative concepts in its own system. The absolute scope, in Nondual
Rationalism, is explicitly open and ineffable. No concept can land there and
retain its own identity. Through the Univocity Framework, Nondual
Rationalism systematically and categorically recognizes that no finite
representational system can encompass the infinite and continuous
immanent causation of Substance and it is therefore a categorical error to
claim that any description ever could or even should be absolute. There can
and need be no numerical identity between any descriptive protocols. The
problem—which is indeed a problem pervasive to philosophy in general—is
one of assigning absolute characteristics to the relative, and it is explicitly
reconciled in the Univocity Framework.

Nondual Rationalism, as stated, recognizes that the explanatory gap will


never be filled because it makes no sense to absolutize a relative descriptive
protocol, especially if they are symbiotic polar opposites. In this same sense,
no amount of detail to the sheet music will ever replace the sensory
experience of the symphony, nor will any hyper-descriptive menu ever
replace the real subjective experience of eating.i
This does not necessarily mean that our knowledge systems, based on
the descriptive protocols, are useless or in any way diminished or limited in
practicality; quite the opposite, in fact. They are indeed useful and entirely
symbiotic and complementary because, as Spinoza says, they express the
essence of Substance, which as we have seen, is infinity and
unboundedeness itself, at the scope of the absolute and ineffable.
This relative knowledge is real and direct knowledge, but with the simple
recognition that knowledge—as a bounded or indefinite manifestation of an
emergent interface—is inherently, mediated, relative, abstract and thus
finite and fundamentally incomplete. This means that the growth of
objective science and subjective potentiality is unlimited, or indefinite, with
no end in sight.

explicit, logical and thus linear accounts of what, as is often the case, is inherently non-linear and
irreducible.
i
Unless of course the menu or the sheet-music can trigger complexly patterned neural responses in
the brain itself and thus the explanatory gap is crossed not by explanation at the epistemic level, but
by causation at the ontic level. This, of course, is not at all the problem in question, but rather a
subversion to the level at which the problem must be addressed.

Page | 539
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

The Spinozistic exegetic rift has been resolved by the recognition that both
the epistemic (Subjectivist) and ontic (Objectivist) readings contain essential
aspects of a deeper morphological gradient. These two warring hermeneutic
camps were also shown to be con-fusing (conflating the pre-fused
distinction between) the two polarities and VL-axes of the ontic-epistemic
and Thought/Extension. These two polarities, recall—the I/T omni-axis of
the ontic-epistemic and the I/T uni-axis of the within and without,
respectively—converge at the cross-roads of the mnemonic interface of the
nucleated observer itself, and this undifferentiated distinction itself is a main
cause of confusion in the literature.
Indeed once the enigmas, ambiguities and nominal confusions of the
traditional exegesis have been explained through the deeper morphological
analysis, Spinoza’s crystalline metaphysical and epistemological structure is
found to be quite robust and indeed resonant with our modern age of
science.i This explanation has been used to elucidate the solution to a few
problems in the philosophy of mind, but we have only scratched the surface
of the possibilities inherent herein.
Nondual Rationalism—with its Vision-Logic Coordinate System,
Univocity Framework, Fullerian “nucleation of observability,” and Deleuzian
“transcendental empiricism”—has been demonstrated as a simple and
powerful resolution to the mind/body problem, and indeed this was a large
part of Spinoza’s original purpose once Descartes burst onto the scene with
his problematic Substance dualism. In this interpretation of Spinoza, the
mind/body problem is solved by logically placing it (the “explanatory gap”)
in the explanatory realm of the epistemic itself where it can naturally be
seen as an incommensurability or non-identity between two symbiogenetic
and fundamentally incomplete polar opposites—the fundamental
“descriptive protocols” of subjectivity and objectivity—morphologically
emergent from the deeper formative protocols of modal nucleation.
Through the topological analogy of “the nucleation of observability” and
the concept of consciousness (the realm of the epistemic) as a finite
emergent interface phenomena (the mnemonic primitives) between the
infinities and perceptual irrelevancies of the within and the without, this
subject/object descriptive discrepancy has been shown as a consequence of
the fallibility of all finite representational systems. The fallibilism,
knowledge-relativity, and Substance neutrality of the nondual-rational
approach are therefore the keys to de-absolutizing and integrating the
skewed materialist and idealist agendas, but this can only be understood and
accepted through the realization of the epistemic and symbiogenetic nature

i
For another excellent example of Spinoza’s surprisingly modern and scientific views, see Looking
For Spinoza, by Antonio Damasio.

Page | 540
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY

of both the subjective and the objective descriptive protocols, in the


orthogonal direction, cutting down through, the polarity of the ontic-
epistemic, with its formative gradient of morphological and representational
excellence.

Page | 541
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Page | 542
Page | 543
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

According to the embryogenesis of the concept,i* differentiation manifests


necessarily at first as polarity, and the interface is the cultivated/cultivating
third in the recognition of the unity and triunity within the terminal and
irresolvable ends of any duality. Recall also that some of these root-level, or
meta-paradigmatic polarities are operationalized in the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System, with its transitive, immanent/transcendent omni-, and
uni- axes—and their respective triune interfaces, such as the transitive-
plane and the platonic sphere, for the omni- and uni-axes, respectively. As
we have just seen in Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity, the omni-, and uni-
interfacesii* each play critical roles as the cultivated thirds at the crossroads
of the ontic/epistemic and subject/object polarities. And, as we have also
seen, the interface of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis (the spheroidal
and bounded “finite unity” and “unit-identity”) is the very beginning of
Mathematics in its holarchical embryogenesis as found in Interface
Mathematics,iii* just as it is the beginning of representation or mimetic
consciousness (roughly the epistemic) itself in the nucleation of
observability. iv * Indeed, Interface Philosophy itself is a “vision-logic
interface” for transferring the framework of a new, nondual way of rational,
trans-rational and even empirical thinking, into various realms of
application.
The metaphor of the interface, however, can be taken to the root of all
these epistemic instances as a budding basic-level model of epistemology
itself, transcending-and-including, and differentiating-and-integrating the
previous and prevailing academic models of epistemology (e.g.
correspondence, foundationalism, coherentism and externalism), as we will
see—making contact and communion where there is now conflict and
controversy. Recall again that it was the relative scope itself, pointing
beyond the real world of relative form, that generated from its own
polarizing stuff, the absolute scope in its attempt to provide its own ultimate
context and meaning in the ineffable other beyond all polarity and effable
form.v*

i
* See, Embryogenesis of the Concept (EOTC), p106.
ii
* See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iv
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
v
* See, Polarity and Univocity, p174.

Page | 544
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Interface Epistemology, therefore, explores the relative interface and


relation between the two fully relative “worlds” of form—the epistemic and
the ontic; representation and sub-representation; the map and the
territory—but it does so in the context of the Univocity Framework which
embodies the essence of the principle of nonduality in the polarity of
polarity,i* keeping open and ineffable the absolute scope, while exploring the
relative world of real form (e.g. Brahma) and the endless possibilities of its
real representations and illusions (e.g. Maya).
Contrary to currently popular notions, in the embryogenesis of the
concept (critical note: this is not an ontological or temporal progression, but
a conceptual or logical one) we cannot move directly from Emptiness or the
absolute scope into representation. Rather we must first pass though the
gradient of sub-representation and proto-representation and then into
mimesis, with the mnemonic primitives and representation. We must pass
from the absolute scope, breaking into the relative in the ontic and then,
transcending-and-including, differentiating-and-integrating into the higher
holonic levels of the epistemic.
But recall from Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity that the interface of the
ontic/epistemic is essentially a “transitive-plane,” occurring as a gradient at
a relatively specific scale, region or coordinate on the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis. And recall also that this volumetric
“plane”ii or interface itself cannot come into being without the units that
make it up on the various scales of its gradient. The main units of this
gradient are the cognitive holons, each one of which is an essentially
spheroidal or roughly omni-symmetrically bounded emergent, sensory-
mnemonic interface on an immanent/transcendent uni-axis. This, recall, is
the interface formed in the symbiogenesis of subject and object; it is the
subject/object interface. And this collusion and collision between omni- and
uni- interfaces—the ontic/epistemic and the subject/object—is the often
con-fusing crossroads where the epistemic and epistemology finds its
emergent roots.
Both representation and meaning (knowledge and understanding) occur,
for the most part, at this sensory-mnemonic, subject/object interface, as it
interfaces with other interfaces—as the subjective and objective interact
with the inter-subjective and the inter-objective—the singular with the
plural—the unit in its relations on its various holonic levels.
But the main unit of the epistemic, this sensory-mnemonic subject-object
interface itself is composed of deeper holons of representation, knowledge
and meaning—as it functionally fades into sub-representation—the smallest

i
* See, Polarity and Univocity, p174.
ii
Recall that a “transitive-plane" is only a plane with respect to the representational linearity of the
omni-directional I/T axis on the main diagram of the VCS. (See Figure 6, p141.) In reality, the
transitive-plane is a scale, or a region between scales, in the unlimited possibilities of scale itself.

Page | 545
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

of which we designated as the “mnemonic primitives.”i* And in the other


direction, the holonic levels of knowledge, meaning and representation
expand into the inter-subjective and inter-objective in “meme complexes”,
“schools” of thought and institutions with their scientific instruments for
vastly deepening, expanding and extending the range of augmented human
perception, understanding and memorialized knowledge—both collective
and individual.
This functional gradient between sub-representation and
representation—between the intra-subjectivity/intra-objectivity of the
mnemonic primitives and the inter-subjectivity/inter-objectivity of
organizations, institutions or “schools” of knowledge—is where Interface
Ontology “enfolds,” and Interface Epistemology “unfolds” in its transcension-
and-inclusion from the ontic to the epistemic. This is the crossroads
between two interfaces—ontic/epistemic (omni-axis) and subject/object
(uni-axis)—expanding into both its intra- (immanent) and inter-
(transcendent and transitive) relational directions. And it is the conflation
of this pre-fusion between these heretofore undisclosed (fused) polarities or
axes and their interfaces—that has caused much of the con-fusion in our
epistemic models. See Figure 75, below (p551).

i
See, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.

Page | 546
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

In the wake of Kant’s “radical ontotomy”—nearly severing the ontic-Body of


Philosophy from its epistemic Head—the task of post-Kantian philosophy
must be one of reintegration of this drastic differentiation. As we have
already discussed,i* but are now better equipped to fully understand, Kant
and Descartes can be seen as similar, if orthogonally opposed, figures in the
History of Philosophy in its transformation into a scientific and respectable
discipline fit for the gleaming halls of the academy. Like Descartes, Kant’s
project was to rescue both Religion and Philosophy from the ravages of the
extreme versions of the other. And like Descartes, his method was to
radically “divide and conquer”—a perhaps necessary, but brutal,
“ontotomy.”
Descartes’ procedure, as stated previously, traced the convoluted folds of
an “inside-out bicameral fissurotomy” between Mind and Brain, severing
precisely along the cogito-interface itself, between the subjective and
objective halves of the epistemic—a tricky operation, to say the least, and by
most accounts a dismal failure. Recall that this Cartesian division is
essentially transitive, as it deals with relations between the within and the
without, but relative to the fixed transitive scale of perception and
conception.
Kant’s incision, on the other hand, followed the outlines of the
anthropocentric level in the ontic-epistemic interface-gradient—the
emergent transitive-plane of representation-level complexity or “excellence”
bisecting the immanent/transcendent omni-axis with its collective landscape
of human, representational cogito-interface units. The post-operative
disaster caused from Kant’s unfortunate incision, recall, was due to the
absence of a distinction between the absolute and relative forms of ontic
knowledge and truth—e.g. the Vedantic “Two Truths doctrine.”
Kant divided the body of Philosophy into two separate worlds, the
“phenomenal” and the “noumenal.” The noumenal world, according to Kant
deals with things as they are “in themselves”—“das ding en sich” (sic)—
absolute and free from relation with other things, including the phenomenal

i
* See, Post-Post-ism-ism: Condition-Critical in the Ontic-Shadow of Post-Kantian Dualism, p40.

Page | 547
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

world. While the phenomenal world (literally “appearances”) deals with the
relative properties seen in the forms of “sensibility,” logic and
representation. And never the twain shall meet.
In his book Foundations: A Manual for the Beginning Student of
Epistemology, academic epistemologist and Kantian, Claude L. Fox writes,
“Distinct from the idea of a thing in itself is the idea of a thing in relation to
other things” (p18). The example Fox gives is of the relation of a father
(himself) to his son, which, he says, is a property predicated to him “not
because of what I am in myself but because of a relationship I bear, to some
other thing.” Kant’s “thing in itself” must then go far beneath the real
relations and effects caused by the real relations a father has with his sons,
such as the memories of the birth, growth, development and all the good and
bad times.
Kant’s “thing in itself,” then, jumps directly from representational
relation, entirely bypasses the real world of sub-representational relation
and reaches into the absolute scope of infinite immanence. Das ding en sich,
then is an independent arising, opposing the relative world of form in
dependence on—interfacing, coupling and changing in accordance with—
other form.i This is in direct opposition to the truths of the nondual
traditions and Spinoza’s real difference, in which the entirety of the world of
form arises in strict inter-dependence in its relations with other form. Kant’s
ding en sich was (or has become) a numerical identity and difference, an
absolutized category free from relation itself, but in absolute opposition to
other categories. And so Kant—or the post-Kantians in his nameii—
bypassed all of ontic sub-representational relation—jumping directly from
the relative world of representation to the absolute of non-relation—and by
default relegating the ontic to the untouchable absolute category of the
“noumenon” while freeing up “phenomenon” for further games with suture
and scalpel.
And so the real world of sub-representational relation—Brahma—was
sunk into the ineffable absolute scope, a lost continent of Philosophy, while
the transcendent world of real illusion—Maya—was elevated and venerated
as a worthy patient. This veneration itself is indeed deserved (though the
operations performed by the doctors of Philosophy may not be). Maya is not

i
When asked in person, Fox stated that Kant’s noumenon is not free from relation, but the thing in
itself is related to all things. This would then be equivalent to the original Aristotelian notion of the
ontos, the One. I then asked him whether Kant made this explicit and the answer was, “No.” It is
well known that Kant himself was unclear about his noumenon/phenomenon distinction, and it is
the post-Kantian reaction which was likely most responsible for the radical ontotomy discussed
herein.
ii
There are indeed Kantians who don’t believe this was Kant’s original intent and that it is the result
of subsequent misinterpretations. Mr. Fox is one of them. This author has not studied Kant’s
original surgical procedure in enough depth to make such a call, but the aftermath is ubiquitous
enough in my contact with run-of-the-mill Kantians and quite readily apparent.

Page | 548
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

only real, but also a real illusion and a real representation. She is more real
than Brahma…but only because she is Brahma, in her roots and in her very
soul. See Figure 75, below.
The task of post-Kantian, post-ontotomy Interface Philosophy, then, has
been to bring the ontic back out of the absolute scope, and to provide an
epistemic interface for exploring this lost continent. And in this process we
will continue to demonstrate that the ontic is not the ineffable, untouchable
Absolute, but fully within the relative and effable world of form embraced in
the very interface of Maya and Brahma. And indeed, this interface of Maya
coming to know Brahma grows ever larger as more and more unknown
territory is uncovered daily and become known. But more to the point, in
our relative freedom to explore the lost ontic continent of Brahma in
epistemic union with Maya, we will then be equipped to explore the lofty
heights to which only Maya can lift us.

Page | 549
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 75: Double-Crossing Dualisms:


The orthogonal intersection of the Cartesian transitive duality between subject and
object and the Kantian immanent/transcendent duality between ontic and epistemic is
precisely our crossroads of interfaces, the very core of the epistemic at the cogito -
interface itself.

Page | 550
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

In Aristotle’s works, ontology was the study of “Being,” the “ontos,” the One
whereas “epistemology” was the study of “knowing,” “episteme.” This sets
up a polarity from the outset between the One and the Many. The ontic is
the One whereas the epistemic starts in the division of the One into the
various ways and means by which it can be broken down and analyzed. We
have already seen this indefinite analytical epistemic process of
differentiate-and-integrate in the EOTC, and in the fact that representation
itself first breaks into structure and form with the nucleation of
observability, and the opposition of self and other—subject vs. object—that
this brings.
When pointing to the ontic from its identical opposite in the epistemic,
then, we must be aware that we are recognizing the unity in diversity, and
ultimately, at the absolute scope, the ONE-ALL tautology and
Unity=Multiplicity of Univocity. It is in the ontic where the symbiogenesis of
subject and object occurs, recall, and it is in the ontic where we recognize the
nature of the epistemic as real in itself—i.e. as transcended-and-included
from the real, or from the ontic.

Recall from our section Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity
(p178) the intrinsic polarity between the ontic/epistemic and between
ontology/epistemology (see Figure 76, below). Ontology is inherently
epistemic (a form of knowledge), and epistemology is inherently ontic (a
form of the real). At the risk of further confusion, the first polarity of terms,
the “ontic/epistemic” can be applied to itself and to the second polarity of
terms, “ontology/epistemology,” to gain a bit of verbal clarity in our
discussion (if this tricky self-referential analysis provides more confusion
than clarity, then by all means skip it).

Page | 551
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 76: -ic Versus -ology:


There is an –ic to every –ology, in the sense that the epistemic transcends -and-
includes the ontic—i.e. all knowledge is fundamentally real, in itself regardless of
whether the reality is more illusory than explanatory, more confusing than
illuminating. “Ology” is the world of knowledge, while “ic” is the world of real form
and properties.

The ontic/epistemic pair can be seen as the ontic aspect of the general
polarity of representation/sub-representation, and the
ontology/epistemology pair can be seen as the epistemic aspect. The words
point out the real vs. representational aspects of their general referents
respectively.
This is easy to spot and to remember in the fact that “ology” itself refers
to a field of study, or knowledge, the real world of the epistemic, and that the
“ic” points out a real aspect or feature of reality. So when discussing the
knowledge or epistemic fields themselves we say ont-ology or epistem-ology,
and when discussing their real-world (or ontic aspects) we say ont-ic and
epistem-ic. In this sense, ontology studies the real ontic, and epistemology
studies the real epistemic as transcended-and-included from the ontic. This
will make much more sense shortly when we explore in more detail the
holarchical nature of the epistemic, transcending-and-including the ontic.

Page | 552
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Clearly, the real map of an epistemic model is necessarily a subset and


abstraction of the real territory in which it was made—just as in Hindu and
Buddhist philosophy Maya is a subset, or meta-set of Brahma, the illusion is
a meta-set of the reality (or higher-level form in a smaller domain, i.e.
greater “depth” with less “span,” as in Integral Philosophy). And without the
reality of the set and meta-set relation between the territory and the map,
respectively—i.e. without the relative forms, energies and “materials” of the
territory—the map itself could not come into existence. So it is with
knowledge. Without the ontological reality of its own being, as well as the
reality of that with which it interfaces and purports to be knowledge of,
knowledge itself cannot come into being and can have no meaning.
As Fox i puts it, “All theories of knowledge contain concepts and
judgments about the nature of the Universe in attempting to describe the
nature of the known. These concepts are in fact ontological concepts which
themselves determine much of what may or may not logically be claimed
about the knower and the means of knowing. … In examining a theory of
knowledge therefore, it is important to identify those basic ontological
concepts which constitute part of the foundation of that theory” (p4). The
knower is a meta-set of reality, after all, and without attempting a relative
knowledge of reality and its knowers, it is impossible to address the
limitations of the knower and his/her knowledge about the known.
From the above, we can perceive already a triune nature to the study of
epistemology. And as we have seen, triunity is generally the interface or
cultivating/cultivated third between the two terminals of a polarity. As Fox
puts it [my insertions], “All theories of knowledge may be thought of in
terms of what they have to say about the three basic dimensions in the
phenomenon of knowledge: [1] the knower, [2] the means of knowing, and
[3] the known.” These three distinctions of knowledge, put in other words,
are generally [1] the epistemic knower (e.g. subject), [3] the ontic known
(e.g. object), and [2] the interface between them—i.e. the means of
knowledge itself between subject and object and between epistemic and

i
Another interesting historical side-note on Mr. Fox: In an inconceivably fortunate set of events, as I
was given two days to vacate my apartment in Superior Colorado, I decided I needed a move into
the mountains, and the very first and only place I looked at was a basement studio apartment above
Boulder, Colorado. After I moved in I finally met the owner and tenant of the house and we had a
little discussion over tea about the rental situation. It just so happened that my new landlord was a
retired philosophy professor specializing in epistemology. Indeed, Mr. Fox’s views were unorthodox
in exactly the same way as my own, stressing the ontic-epistemic polarity and the ontic foundations
of the epistemic in the precise way I just happened to need for the very section of this work that I
happened to be writing at that very moment in time—this one. The odds of the first and only
apartment I looked at just happening to be co-occupied by with a retired philosophy professor are
themselves very low, but the odds shrink dramatically with the fact that he happened to be
unorthodox in exactly the same way that I just happened to need at that very precise moment in the
progress of this work. As Gerald Lebau says, “God said look for me in coincidences.”

Page | 553
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

ontic (recall the mnemonic interface as the crossroads between these two
polarities).i
Fox continues, “These distinctions are indispensable for avoiding
confusion, especially, for example, when we consider the object of
knowledge to be the knowing subject itself; that is to say, when the knower
is considered as the known.” In other words, when we consider the real and
relative formal or ontic nature of the epistemic subject (i.e. as an “object”) in
order to ascertain the limitations and powers with respect to the knowledge
which that subject-as-object can attain, then we must be clear that we are
addressing the ontic (relative not absolute) nature of the epistemic in the
real and relative formal properties and limitations of the knower itself.
And again, it must also remain clear that ontic does not equate to
objective, though ontic objects (e.g. rocks), as opposed to epistemic objects
(e.g. thinking beings) are easiest to identify and understand. As discussed in
Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and the Nucleation of Observability, objectivity is
merely the outside view of the epistemic; i.e. knowledge gained about the
external world, and there is a natural tendency to collapse the objective into
the ontic which must be avoided—e.g. when subjects become seen as
objects.
Often in epistemology it is the ontic nature of the epistemic subject that is
the object in question, so there is always a danger of an unrecognized
feedback loop and circularity. And if the ontic, epistemic, subject and object
polarities and their respective VL-axes, interfaces and distinctions are not
maintained in clarity, this can easily trip up and con-fuse the user.
Fox continues, “In the most general terms then, according to the three
basic dimensions of the phenomenon of knowledge as mentioned above, the
basic questions of epistemology will always be derivatives of the three
questions: What is the nature of the knower?, What is the nature of the
means of knowing?, and What is the nature of the known?” Questions
probing “the nature” of these three “dimensions,” as should be clear, are
ontological questions, as they attempt to address (relatively) the formal
reality of the three basic dimensions of the epistemic, and the powers and
limitations thereof (see Figure 77, below).

i
There is, of course, a clear conflation at this point between the object/subject and ontic/epistemic
polarities and their respective uni- and omni-axes which will be cleared up as we proceed.

Page | 554
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Figure 77: The EOTC of the Triune Dimensions of the Epistemic /Subject at the
Crossroads of the Ontic/Object:
Notice here that the crossroads between subject/object and ontic/epistemic is clearly
defined in the space where the “means of knowing” between subject and object is
inquired of as to its ontic nature.

We can see here already, in the basic fundamentals of epistemology, the


crossroads of the ontic/epistemic and subject/object. This is very clearly
seen on graph of Figure 77, above, where the two interfaces intersect at the
“means” of knowing and the “nature of.” This is the ontic nature of the ontic-
epistemic and subject-object crossroads and interface.
It must be clear that the subject-object is a transitive distinction,
however. The subject-object interface—as the very unit of the transitive-
plane of the orthogonal ontic-epistemic interface—is a spherical or omni-
symmetrically bounded interface on the I/T uni-axis. Nondual hence it is the
very beginning of transitive epistemic functioning as it relates everything
else to its unit-scale of operations. This we found so clearly in the pure-
relational genesis in Interface Mathematics from the unit-identity into the

Page | 555
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

transitivity of the number-line. And we saw it as well in Spinoza’s Attribute


Polarity, above.
Once a unit is formed on the I/T uni-axis—in The Cycle of Unity, recall,
from the ONE-ALL of the omni-axis to the ONE-one of the uni-axis—inter-
unit relations can then begin, and these relations are the very beginning of
opposition and transitive functioning. The polarity of the within and the
without, in these cases of inter-unit relations—after the unit is formed—
begins functioning in linear, me vs. you, terms, in opposition and therefore in
transitivity.
And so this is why the subject-object polarity, once formed, is conceived
generally as a transitivity, rather than an immanence and transcendence.
After-all, in the act of perception itself the object does not transcend the
subject, but exists first of all in opposition to the subject. Opposition, recall,
is a key element of transitivity as opposed to the “intensive forces” of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and sub-representation.i

Fox continues [my emphasis], “As should be clear from the preceding, those
ontological concepts which are instrumental in describing the nature of the
known are in that regard epistemological concepts. In this overlap can be
seen the reason for saying that ontology and epistemology may be said to be
distinct but not separate.” Recall at this point our basic definition of
conceptual nonduality and polarity as “distinct but not separate.” Fox is
here pointing simply and clearly—if unconsciously—to the fundamental
polarity and holarchy between the ontic and its real meta-set, the epistemic
(the territory and the map), as they unfold into the triune nature of the
knower, the known and the interface and means of knowing.
In this overlapping sense, because the epistemic is not only real, but also
(meta) an emergent representation, it is a higher or transcendent level of
reality, or as Ken Wilber would say, it is “deeper” or has more depth of form,
complexity or reality to it. Yet the epistemic is a sub-set in the sense that it
has a smaller domain, because only a small percentage of ontic modes or
holons will deepen into the epistemic or into representational capabilities.
This is what we see, in integral theory, in the maxim that with increasing
depth comes a decreasing span. The higher and deeper (the more layers of
depth) the form of transcendence the more rare it becomes.ii* In this same
sense, Maya or the illusion is a deeper reality than mere Brahma, the plain
old reality—it goes beyond, or meta, but only in the transcension-and-
inclusion of the ontic in those most rare holons capable of representation.

i
… until that process is turned on itself, for example, in transformative practices like meditation and
shadow-work in psychotherapy, and then only very slowly. This is how transitivity is mapped to
transcendence.
ii
* We’ll discuss this in much more “depth” in the section, Depth vs. Span: Further Untangling the
Trans-Trans-Bias, p573.

Page | 556
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

So, at this point we have the triunity of the knower, the interface of knowing,
and the known; roughly the epistemic subject, the subject/object interface
and the epistemic object—and this triune structure, recall from Figure 77
above (p556), is emergent across the polarity and triunity of the
ontic/epistemic and its interface in the probing of the “nature of” the
elements of this fundamental epistemic triunity. But there is another
“indispensable” triune (holarchical and emergent) set of relations which Fox
wants the beginning student of epistemology to be aware of, and which, Fox
says, “Aristotle reminds us to employ whenever we are doing philosophy…”
(p5). Aristotle calls this triune structure the “three levels of being” and they
are, as Fox states: “reality, meaning and language, or respectively reality
itself, our mental representation of reality and our linguistic symbolization
of those representations.”
This triune Aristotelian distinction, in a sense, collapses or ignores the
interface and polarity between the ontic and epistemic, but it expands or
differentiates the epistemic into a distinction between semantics (meaning)
and language (roughly syntax in addition to meaning). As we have stressed
previously,i* and will explain more fully below, semantics, meaning or
“intentionality” is emergent in the symbiogenesis of subject and object. In
the very process of emergent, representational embodiment itself,
meaning unfolds in layers of accretion, transcension-and-inclusion.
Syntax or language, then, is a later invention of creatures whose
foundational semantics is already emergently embodied in its mnemonic
primitives and higher-level representational and mimetic structures—such
as hunting strategies or avoidance routines. This later invention of language
then serves to rigorously tease out, complexify and communicate higher and
higher forms of meaning, transcended-and-included from embodiment itself
and expanded through the subsequent embodiment of invented language.

As the attentive reader can see, in our EOTC of the epistemic categories, we
now have a fourth and even a fifth level differentiated-and-integrated into
our original triune holarchy; the epistemic subject, the subject/object
interface and the epistemic object. So now we have the fivefold delineation
of epistemology; (1) the ontic, (2) the ontic/epistemic interface gradient, (3)
meaning, (4) the meaning/language interface gradient, and (5) language.
See Figure 78, below.

i
* See, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.

Page | 557
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 78: Embryogenesis of the Epistemic Categories:


In the embryogenesis of the concept of the epistemic, we can already see an intense
complexification and level of detail unfolding into Int erface Epistemology. The
Absolute scope breaks into the relative scope and then into the ontic/epistemic
(Brahma/Maya) holarchy/polarity. From there we expand the category of the
ontic/epistemic interface and break it into the vast gradient of the intra-
objective/intra-subjective sensory-mnemonic primitives, and complexes. Via Aristotle ,
we have also expanded the category of the epistemic into meaning and language and
into the inter-objective/inter-subjective meme-complexes, such as schools of thought,
where language and meaning unfold each other into ever higher and higher levels of
complexity.

The Absolute scope breaks into the relative scope and then into the
ontic/epistemic (Brahma/Maya) holarchy/polarity. From there we expand
the category of the ontic/epistemic interface gradient and break it into the
intra-objective/intra-subjective sensory-mnemonic primitives, and
complexes. Via Aristotle, we have also expanded the category of the
epistemic first into meaning and then into higher level language and into the
inter-objective/inter-subjective meme-complexes, such as schools of
thought, where language and meaning unfold each other into ever higher
and higher levels of complexity.

Page | 558
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Other models, such as Ken Wilber’s Integral Methodological Pluralism (IMP),


are much more fully developed than Interface Epistemology, as higher-level
epistemic models of cognitive and “spiritual” development as well as in the
general and abstract integration of all forms of knowledge into a single
whole. But, as in the case of IMP, they have tended (at least in the past) to
tow the postmodern party line that ontological models and ontic truth
claims are simply to be avoided and neglected, as if they all necessitated an
absolute, instead of merely a relative form of truth. As mentioned
previously, this “mean green meme,” as the integralists call it, has razed to
the ground the critical and essential polarity and holarchy between the
epistemic and the ontic; the map and the territory, causing various
“performative contradictions” as the models inevitably attempt to plumb the
ontological depths of their own epistemic details (e.g. an infinite holarchy of
perspectives) without being able to admit of their so doing.
Ken Wilber’s stance on this appears to be rapidly changing, however, as
he is now beginning to explore, what he is calling “post-ontology.” He is
doing this now with the full recognition that post-ontology is indeed a form
of ontology, and that he is using the “post-post-ism-ism” to get beyond the
radar of ontically-timid (“green-meme”) “post-post-modern” academia.i¥
Despite the unfortunate need for post-post-ism subterfuge in exoteric
academia, this is a good sign that the academic world is waking up from the
pipe-dream of the unreal, or the “aperspectival nightmare” of the “floating
signifier,” the mirrored hall of “infinite representation,” an endless series of
representational contexts with no sub-representational reality in which to
give it identically-opposite context or meaning.
Because models that ultimately deny ontology and relative ontic truth
claims have no legitimate pathways to their ontic roots, they cannot so easily
build an explicit and coherent foundation for a true model of epistemology.
Thankfully, Integral Methodological Pluralism appears to be moving out of
this last, deepest and greatest post-modern kosmic rut.
IMP is an epistemic (and, to a small and necessary extent, an ontic)
model—a model of forms generally within the epistemic (e.g. the AQAL
quadrants as real perspectives on holons). It outlines in great detail the basic


This was disclosed in a recent public ISC call—May 12, 2007—in which I participated with Wilber.

Page | 559
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

higher-level structures of knowledge, such as the All Quadrants All Levels


(and states, types and lines) of “AQAL” metatheory into which the various
fields of knowledge (e.g. methodologies, isms and paradigms) can be
organized and integrated into a larger whole (see Figure 79, below, for the
standard AQAL quadrant diagram).
These quadrants are the within (I), the without (IT) and the plural forms
of these, the inter-subjective (WE) and the inter-objective (ITS), as well as
the various lines and levels of intelligence and consciousness, (see Figure 80,
below, p562.) But, as is well known among integral theorists, IMP is not yet
a model of epistemology proper. This is primarily, however, because it does
not outline the fundamental relation between the ontic and epistemic and its
interface with subject and object, and hence cannot yet probe the sub-
representational nature of
representation. It cannot probe the
nature of the three dimensions of
the epistemic; the knowing subject,
the interface and the known object.
Indeed, it is well-known among
integral theorists that IMP is
lacking a model that can place into
an integral, transcend-and-include
holarchical arrangement—if such
an arrangement exists (and we will
find that it does)—the various
competing models of epistemology,
in order to integrate the various
differentiations, innovations and Figure 79: The AQAL Quadrants of
Integral Meta-Theory:
relative truths of those models. The standard AQAL diagram adapted from
To that end and others, Interface various Integral books, illustrating the
Philosophy can itself be used to four quadrants corresponding to the basic
great effect as a “post-ontological” pronouns of speech.
foundation for a truly Integral
model of epistemology; an interface between, for example, the largely
epistemic Integral Methodological Pluralism and a nondual and explicitly
detailed trans-rational model of ontology (or “post-ontology”), such as
Nondual Rational-Empiricism (herein) and Interface Philosophy, with its
Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS) and Univocity Framework (UF).

Page | 560
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Figure 80: The Expanded AQAL Map:


In AQAL metatheory, the four quadrants are used to categorize all forms of knowledge.
This disallows any one form of knowledge or methodology from absolutizing itself at
the expense of any others. This then serves a complimentary function to that of the
Univocity Framework. In this diagram we see the I/T axis itself implicit in the outwar d
dimension (the transcendent bias) toward higher forms of evolution (“transcension -
and-inclusion”, as Wilber calls it).

Page | 561
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

As discussed,i* Spinoza’s Substance as expressive existence can be seen as


analogous to Nagarjuna’s “Emptiness,”ii* as well as directly encoding the
principle of “dependent arising” (or alternately the Taoist notion of the
identity of opposites) in his notion of “real difference” and in his attribute
parallelism and polarity.iii* Note also that this dependent arising and
attribute-parallelism, is virtually identical in function to the singular half of
the “tetra-arising” in the AQAL model—albeit AQAL is a bit more evolved at
the higher level of the epistemic (while forsaking the depth at the ontic) in
that it explicates the implicit plural aspect of the attributes and integrates
the great bulk of the transformative truths and practices of the Great
Wisdom Traditions of the East and West.iv
So we can see here an embryogenesis of the concept of dependent
arising. The Buddhist notion of dependent arising was a more general
precursor to Spinoza’s more specific notion of “double arising” (to coin a
phrase), which was a more general precursor to Wilber’s more specific and
operationally-inclusive “tetra-arising.” So, from the Buddhist “dependent
arising,” through Spinoza’s dependent “double arising” (polarity and “real
difference”) to Wilber’s dependent “tetra-arising,” we see a pattern emerging
of the embryogenesis of the concept, through a differentiate-and-integrate,
transcend-and-include process.
Spinoza’s system, then was already AQAL compliant, though not AQAL
explicit, and in this sense (and others, as we have seen) also already “post-
metaphysical,” because the dependency of the arising of mind and matter
(Thought and Extension) precludes any absolutism of matter over mind as
required by the medieval metaphysics of the Great Chain of Being—at the
same time that Spinoza’s concept of real difference precluded any pre-
existing absolute Platonic form or self-identity. Spinoza merely needed to
make explicit the two remaining quadrants of plurality (already implicit in
the plural pronouns, we and its) to bring it up to speed with the basics of
Wilber’s more epistemically explicit tetra-arising model.

i
* See, for example, The Tao of Rationalism: Pulverizing the Categories (p56), Spinoza’s Univocity
(p158) and Spinoza: A Nondual Sketch (p664)
ii
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153, for more detailed information.
iii
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
iv
To this integrative purpose, then, we flesh out the alternative lineage of Western Nondual
iv
Rationalism, from Heraclitus to Parmenides and Zeno —going underground with the exoteric
rationality of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle (for example in the principle of contradiction and platonic
absolutized categories)—emerging with the stoics perhaps and the Neo-Platonists—and meeting up
with Deleuze at Spinoza.

Page | 562
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

But the point of transcension-and-inclusion in the EOTC is that the initial


concept be retained in the embryogenesis or ontogeny of the more evolved
and detailed version. And in this case, the general concept of “dependent
arising” (or the Taoist “identity of opposites” and the Spinozan notion of
“real difference” in opposition to “numerical difference”) has a power and
flexibility of application that neither “double” or “tetra-arising” possess, even
though they can be seen as differentiations, or specializations of it. There is
always something both lost and gained in specialization.
This is not to say that this embryogenesis occurred in a direct
evolutionary lineage, because it is doubtful that Spinoza studied the concept
of “dependent arising” (though his notion of “real difference” directly
embodied it) and it is even more doubtful that Wilber studied, or was aware
of, the dependent arising aspect of Spinoza’s “real difference” and attribute
polarity. It is perhaps an open question as to whether Wilber explicitly
recognizes or acknowledges the functional similarity between the Buddhist
dependent arising and his own tetra-arising, though it is doubtless an
important contributor to the development of his AQAL quadrants.
But the more general (and in a sense more flexible and powerful)
“dependent arising” and “real difference” lacked the detail and distinction
needed to fully solve the Cartesian dilemma, just as Spinoza’s attribute
polarity lacks the detail needed to explicitly integrate and organize the four
main aspects of human knowledgei that Wilber’s AQAL model explicates.
And this is the defining feature of the notion of “2nd tier” at the “integral
level of consciousness,” i.e. that we can jump between any of these levels we
wish, in the entire known sequence of development, in order to deal with
things at that level. When dealing with general duality, the notion of
“dependent arising,” “real difference” or even the Taoist “identity of
opposites,” is more powerful because it is not restrained in its applicability
by the later imposed categorical distinctions of Inside, Outside, Unity and
Plurality. And when dealing with Mind/Matter dualism, the Spinozan
“attribute polarity” is a simpler, yet more deeply engaged and direct solution
to the problem than tetra-arising.

AQAL metatheory can be seen as a complimentary epistemic-level function


or framework to that of the deeper-level (more immanent), ontological
Univocity Framework and Interface Philosophy in general. In AQAL
metatheory the four quadrants are used to categorize all forms of
knowledge. This disallows any one form of knowledge or methodology from
absolutizing itself at the expense of any others. This then serves a similar

i
… and now the eight primordial perspectives and their respective methodologies.

Page | 563
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

and complimentary function to that of the Univocity Framework, as well as


the concept of dependent arising and Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity, as we saw
with our “Star of Complexity” diagram (recall Figure 71, p528).
This is one of the great values of AQAL metatheory and Integral
Methodological Pluralism. Like Interface Philosophy, and much more
powerfully in conjunction with it, Integral Methodological Pluralism is a
great tool for inter-paradigm research, in that it uproots the users from their
paradigm-bindings and forces them into a meta-paradigm space where new
rules of engagement necessarily apply, such as those outlined by Thomas
Kuhn (e.g. paradigm incommensurability). This meta-paradigm stance, and
its rules of engagement, is absolutely necessary for the progress of science in
its inter-departmental and interparadigm relations, but it is largely beyond
the scope of this book and will be explored in much more depth in SpinbitZ
Volume II.
Given the four quadrants—I, IT, WE and ITS—AQAL theory has mapped
their respective “quadrant absolutisms” and brutal or crude reductionisms
as formalized into various philosophical systems. They are, respectively, the
extreme versions of: Idealism (I), Materialism (IT), Postmodernism (WE)
and Systems Theory (ITS). These extreme versions make the claim that their
respective truths are absolutely fundamental to those of any other system.
For example extreme Idealism (I) makes the claim that “Mind is THE reality”,
extreme Materialism (IT) claims that “Matter is THE reality”, extreme
Systems Theory claims that “The cosmic web of life is THE reality” and
extreme Postmodernism claims that “Culturally constructed meaning is THE
reality,” (see Figure 81, below). AQAL metatheory softly enforces the
integration of all these views, molding them into their moderate and
relational forms, where the difference becomes one of focus or degree,
rather than one of absolute kinds or categories.

Page | 564
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Figure 81: Quadrant Absolutisms in AQAL Meta-Theory:


This diagram illustrates one of the key values of AQAL metatheory, that it allows us to
see explicitly the various exoteric absolutisms and thus to dynamically avoid and/or
correct them.

Because AQAL metatheory and the Integral OS are such a powerful,


explicative and integrative force at the higher levels of the epistemic, it is
then to a great advantage for both models to unfold an interface between
them. How then do the AQAL quadrants, levels and lines fit to the VCS and
Univocity Framework?
Recall that the ontic/epistemic polarity is a holarchy and it can be
mapped to the immanent/transcendent omni-axis, whose interface is a
region on a gradient of complexity between pre-mimetic or automatic levels
of reflex, into mimetic levels of representational planning or “forethought,”
which occurs most clearly with the integration of the senses in the higher
organisms. Note also that the levels of awareness in AQAL map directly to

Page | 565
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

this ontic-epistemic interface and become more and more relevant as we


move higher and higher into the epistemic with the mapping of the
actualization and potential of human consciousness. The levels of awareness
are where the AQAL model has mapped this ontic/epistemic interface
gradient, to great degree, and it overlaps precisely, but generally with
Spinoza’s gradient of “excellence” we discovered in Spinoza’s Attribute
Polarity. Even though we can view all holons through the AQAL lens to see
their “quadrivia,” or tetra-arising aspects, the lines, states and types of AQAL
theory are relevant only to the epistemic level of the awareness of cognitive
holons, such as human beings. We wouldn’t use these categories—e.g. “the
artistic line of development” or the state of “dreaming”—to much effect, say,
on atoms or “quarks.” Indeed, the power of the AQAL map, as we have seen,
is in the integration of knowledge systems, and in this power—by far its main
focus—it is a fully and powerfully epistemic model.

Although there is the polarity, in AQAL meta-theory, of the immanent and


transcendent (for example in the very process of transcension-and-inclusion
and in the laws of holons, as well as in the aspect of transcension-and-
inclusion implicit in the outward expansion in the expanded AQAL map
above (See Figure 80 above, p562)), there is no explicit I/T axis in the model.
The AQAL quadrants deal explicitly with the transitive delineations between
the perspectival directions of the within and the without (i.e. subjective and
objective) and their plural inter-relations. We find the same transitivity in
our own distinction between subject and object, despite the fact that the I/T
uni-axis and its subject/object interface maps also to the within and without.
Recall the trans-bias in the mapping of transcendence with the external
means of transitivity. The outside view is only transcendent if it transcends
up the holarchy.
It is very important to maintain the clarity here in the way the
within/without polarity is mapped; transitive vs. immanent/transcendent.
The distinction between subject and object—as found between the I and IT
quadrants—amounts to a linear or oppositional (and integrative) quality of
mapping. The I/IT quadrant distinction does not explicitly take into account
the immanence, emergence and transcendence in the move from the within
to the without as found on the omni-axis (and in the laws of holons, etc), and
as such it is a purely transitive categorical relation, polarity and axis, even
though such transcension and/or inclusion may indeed be implicit. The
same is true of the singular and plural. There is no necessary transcension
in the move from singular to plural (e.g. from holons to heaps), or vice versa,
in AQAL theory. And so both axes, the within/without and the
singular/plural, are purely transitive in nature.
But this transitive map is a transitive-plane, occuring on an implicit VL-
axis of immanence and transcendence, with its laws of holonic transcension-
and-inclusion already made explicit in the model. Indeed the AQAL map

Page | 566
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

itself exists to make this transitive opposition explicit for the sake of
integration, and thus transcension-and-inclusion up the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. So, in AQAL metatheory there exists the very
same polarity between the I/T axis and the transitive-planes—as there
indeed does in any model dealing with the truths of evolution—though this
distinction remains, to a large degree, implicit.
The AQAL map, therefore,
consists of a transitive-plane,
projected from the transcendent
level of the epistemic, “down” into
“lower and lower” immanent
transitive-planes, as well as “up”
into “higher and higher”
transcendent ones (see Figure 80,
p562, above). The AQAL map
projects from the epistemic simply
because, in relational reality (in the
ontic) there is no such distinction
between these relations—in reality
they are already integrated and in
need of none of our maps. They
tetra-arise together, not apart. It is Figure 82: The I/T AQAL Grid: The
only because finite unity begins in Quadrants as a Transitive-Plane on the
representational or operational I/T axis:
opposition and relation to other Because the AQAL quadrants deal with
finite or bounded unities that it oppositional relations, rather than with
unfolds initially onto the relations of transcension and immanence
(included in other aspects of the model,
oppositional transitive-axis, and this such as the laws of holons) the quadrants
is the very reason that opposition, at (at whatever level they are projected to)
the higher (e.g. “second-tier”) levels can be placed on a transitive-plane, with
of consciousness must make maps respect to the Immanent/Transcendent
to integrate at the epistemic level axis.
that which was never disintegrated
at the ontic.
Indeed, this is an explicit feature of the AQAL model in the dictum that
the quadrants “tetra-arise” and that ultimately there is never one without
the other three. The AQAL quadrants explicitly form merely a map of
important distinctions to be made at the epistemic level, of intrinsically
integrated or inseparable features of relational reality—the ontic level (See
Figure 82, above).

So, in the integration of AQAL metatheory with Interface Philosophy, we


can say that any epistemic mapping of an Immanent/Transcendent axis
and coordinate into a transitive-plane of relation must include the four

Page | 567
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

quadrants if it hopes to be all-inclusive and “integrally informed” of the


fundamental perspectives of human (and perhaps indeed nonhuman)
awareness. To be sure, we can simply imagine that in the exfoliation of any
transitive-plane from any Immanent/Transcendent axis, the AQAL map is
implicit, and can be made explicit in order that one quadrant not be
neglected or reduced out of the picture for the sake of any of the others (see
Identifying Quadrant Absolutisms, above).
In ontological terms, this simply means that there can be no field of
relation (transitivity) without units to inter-relate. Indeed, “relation”
implies the plurality of units, and “units” implies the singularity of the unit.
And as we have already seen in the Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity—
“Finite unity is plural and at minimum two”—there is no bounded form
without the polarity of within and without, and, most importantly for our
purposes, the interface between them. And most importantly, the quadrant
lines-of-division themselves will herein be treated as triune-interfaces
between the useful AQAL categories which can otherwise easily devolve into
simplistic categorical dualisms if not treated carefully. But we will see that
these interfaces themselves have fascinating properties and complexities,
transforming the absolutisms in one quadrant, for example—through the
Principle of Absolute Reversal—directly into the identical opposite of the
other.i*
And so the principles and features of Interface Philosophy already
implicitly generate the features made explicit by the AQAL quadrants—
giving them further intrinsic explanatory detail. The lines, levels and states,
however, are new with the AQAL model (or newly integrated, at least), and
they generally apply only to the epistemic levels of reality.
In the interface between Interface Philosophy and AQAL metatheory,
then, the categorical lines between the AQAL quadrants will not simply be
treated dualistically and categorically, but rather more fluidly, as triune
interfaces. Indeed, we will find that the quadrant- or AQAL-interfaces—
when absolutized, giving rise to the Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR)—
will act as tunnels or conduits between each other, becoming rather more
like real interfaces, than merely illusory categorical distinctions.

In Wilber’s subsequent work in IMP, he has since divided each of the


quadrants into an internal and an external “perspective”—breaking the four
quadrants into “eight primordial perspectives,” and their respective
academic methodologies. Though we won’t have time to go into these in the

i
* See, Quadrant Interfaces and PAR-Tunnels: Cogitism, Formalism and Other Theories of Knowledge,
p631.

Page | 568
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

detail they deserve, I include Figure 83 (see below) merely for interest, and
to show perhaps a glimpse of the power of Wilber’s model.
“The idea is simple enough,” says Wilber:
Start with any phenomenon (or holon) in any of the quadrants—for
example, the experience of an ‘I’ in the UL [upper left] quadrant. That ‘I’
can be looked at from the inside or the outside. I can experience my own
‘I’ from the inside, in this moment… But I can also approach this ‘I’ from the
outside, in a stance of an ‘objective’ or ‘scientific’ observer. I can do so in
my own awareness (when I try to be ‘objective’ about myself or try to ‘see
myself as others see me’), and I can also attempt to do this with other ‘I’s’
as well, attempting to be scientific in my study of how other people
experience their ‘I.’ The most famous of these scientific approaches to I-
consciousness have included systems theory and structuralism (p35-6).
Wilber goes on to outline this new within/without perspectival polarity with
respect to each of his quadrants.
This additional polarity and distinction to the quadrant map as a whole
may indeed be indicative of the importance of the implicit
immanent/transcendent uni-axis with its finite unity (e.g. the holon) and its
within/without polarity (recall our Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity
(p251)). Though it still seems to be the case that Wilber’s distinction is of a
more linear, oppositional, and therefore transitive nature. Regardless, we
can notice a very clear difference here, between the two axes in Wilber’s
model, given that the quantitative or plural axis has not been reiterated, self-
reflexively, in this fashion.
Because the “primordial perspectives” themselves are generated in a
recursive “fissioning” across the holonic polarity of finite unity, there
appears, then, to be—shall we say—an “integral” aspect of finite unity and
boundedness to perspective itself in IMP. In other words, in integral terms,
there is, necessarily, a fundamentally holonic nature to perspective.
Perspectives, we can say, at minimum come in twos. This obviously is a
corollary to our Fullerian Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity. So it is
interesting to note that the very core of Wilber’s move into “post-
metaphysics” is the replacement of “perceptions” with “perspectives,” which
conveniently and simplistically gets rid of the problem of correspondence in
epistemology, and its metaphysics of the “myth of the given.” Wilber makes
the very accurate claim that we cannot have perceptions without first having
a perspective. Indeed, however, he often makes the seemingly absolutist
conclusion that “All is perspective.”
This claim, in Integral Post-metaphysics, that perspectives replace
perceptions, and especially the claim that “All is perspective” must be
tempered with the recognition of the ontically-timid nature of the academic
climate into which Wilber is projecting his new model. Given this, it is
natural for Wilber to often conveniently drop the corollary that “All is
holonic,” because it is the holons that ontically embody the perspectives.

Page | 569
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

There can be no such thing, especially in Integral theory, as a disembodied


perspective. That would be an “I” without an “IT”—absolutely unthinkable
in AQAL.
So naturally Wilber also makes the claim that [his emphasis] “all
perspectives are embedded in bodies and in cultures”—the singular and the
plural, naturally.i¥ Given the fact that the “primordial” basis of perspective in
IMP fissions from four into eight across the “unity is plural and at minimum
two” boundary-polarity of our holonic Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity,
it is clear to see why embodiment and boundary itself is already fundamental
to perspective. In this sense it is very misleading to occasionally make the
simple epistemic-bound claim that “All is perspective” without qualifying it
with the ontic-corollary that “All is also holonic,” because the “primordial
perspectives” themselves turn on the boundary of finite unity itself. And of
course the “All” in both of these conjunctive cases is the ALL and infinite
multiplicity of the relative scope.

The question that must be asked is whether it is really meaningful to claim


that—for example—an atom has or holds a perspective. To what sense is a
perspective itself dependent on representation? This is largely a function of
definitions—semantics—and fully dependent on the details of the model in
question. To my knowledge, Wilber is using the term “perspective” very
loosely. It gets him out of the absolutist binds of correspondence between
the myth and the given and into the relative connections of perspectivism.
But a disembodied perspectivism, as Wilber knows, is an aperspectival
nightmare. An atom may not be able to represent to himself or view the
“point of view” at which he sits, but he does indeed embody such a vantage
point from which the world could be viewed, for example, inter-sub-
subjectively. This is indeed similar—as we saw in Spinoza’s Attribute
Polarity—to the holding of such an intrinsic or embodied point of view apart
from its opposite external point of view—the parallelism of Thought vs.
Extension—in order not to collapse insides to outsides, as is the tendency,
especially in this scientific age of radically empowered objectivity.

The difference between the claim—All is perspective—taken without its


bounded or holonic corollary, and the claim taken with it—as a corollary and
polarity as seen in our Cycle of Unity—is similar to the difference between a
point-based geometry (e.g. all is a “point of view”) and a “point-free
geometry” (e.g. “All is an infinite holarchy each holon of which embodies a
possible perspective or point of view”) such as that outlined in Interface
Mathematics. When we take points—of view or of anything else—as
fundamental to volumetrically extended and bounded embodiment itself, we


(Wilber, Integral Spirituality) p. 43

Page | 570
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

are perhaps taking a representational and an inherently Euclidean, and even


perhaps a Cartesian stance. The difference, recall, was outlined very clearly
in Interface Mathematics, and especially in the section, The Holarchical
Unfolding of Number and Operation (p309) and the subsection Structural vs.
Representational Relation (p361).
There is a sense in which the extensionless and abstracted immanent
infinity of the mathematical point—as “implicit singularity,” as opposed to a
Euclidean “building block”i—is fundamental to its bounded form, but this is
only in the epistemic sense of the EOTC from the absolute scope of the ALL-
ONE (omni-axis) to the ONE-one (uni-axis) in our Cycle of Unity (ALL = ∞/∞
= ONE). This is a fundamentally non-Euclidean move, recall, as it puts the
first dimension on the I/T axis itself (in conjunction with Fuller’s Synergetic
Geometry), rather than in linearity and transitivity. It is from the I/T axis
that the initial scale for linear dimensioning is generated in the same
movement in which the unit is generated for linear inter-unit relations. And
it is with this move that volumetric extension comes in at the very beginning
of dimensionality.
So, the danger with these statements which seem to imply the absolute
fundamentality of epistemic points of view or perspectives without making
clear the acknowledgment of the ontic-level embodiment in holons and
bounded form—and indeed the interface and holonic gradient of emergence
necessary for representational embodiment itself—is that IMP can seem to
collapse to an epistemic absolutism. The hope, therefore, is that IMP will
clarify this ambiguity in the explication of the ontic-epistemic polarity, in its
exploration of “post-ontology” with the corollary that “All is holonic.”

i
As truly odd and senseless as an extensionless building block may sound, given that it breaks down
into the labyrinth of the continuum.

Page | 571
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 83: The “Eight Primordial Perspectives” and their Methodologies:


This diagram, abstracted from (Wilber, Integral Spirituality) , shows the “eight
primordial perspectives generated from a recursive fissioning across the pol arity of
finite unity itself, which is abstracted as Wilber ’s interior/exterior transitive axis.

In his book Out of Control, Kevin Kelly writes:


A contemplative swarm thought: The Atom is the icon of 20th century
science.

The popular symbol of the Atom is stark: a black dot encircled by the
hairline orbits of several other dots. The Atom whirls alone, the epitome
of singleness. It is the metaphor for individuality: atomic. It is the

Page | 572
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

irreducible seat of strength. The Atom stands for power and knowledge
and certainty. It is as dependable as a circle, as regular as round.

The internal circles of the Atom mirror the cosmos, at once a law-abiding
nucleus of energy, and at the same time the concentric heavenly spheres
spinning in the galaxy. In the center is the animus, the It, the life force,
holding all to their appropriate whirling stations. The symbolic Atoms’
sure orbits and definite interstices represent the understanding of the
universe made known. The Atom conveys the naked power of simplicity.
The original ancient Greek Atom was foundationalist and absolutized
bounded form. The Atom (a-tomos) was the “uncuttable,” indivisible rival
and antithesis of the infinitely divisible “corpuscle” of eighteenth-century
“Natural Philosophy.” The Atom, and Newton won out over the corpuscular
folks like Leibniz and Boyle. Atomic simplicity was far easier to deal with for
the exoteric LCD of humanity. But the victory of the Atom was short-lived.
Indeed, the Atom of the 20th century is no longer the indivisible entity of
Leucippus, Democritus, Gassendi and Newton. Without anyone noticing it,
the Atom was transformed into its rival, the corpuscle—the an-atom.
The corpuscle, or the anatom, is infinitely divisible. It has anatomy. It
ontologically embodies the modal half of the fundamental principle of
Nondual Rationalism.
The Holon, on the other hand, is the conceptual and abstract form of the
infinite divisibility of the corpuscular anatom—and it is directly opposed to
the Atomic concept of the absolutized and foundational Planck scale in
modern physics. This infinite divisibility is encoded into its very definition
as a part-whole, or equally as a whole-part—i.e. a whole that is always part
of a larger holon, and a whole whose parts are always made from smaller
holons. The very definition of a holon, then, necessitates that there can be
no end to the holarchy, because (in the immanent direction) this would
entail that a holon is either made of foundational non-holons (the ancient
Greek A-tomoi) or (in the transcendent direction) that the last holon is not a
part of a larger holon, and thus not a holon either, but some kind of inside-
out Atom, e.g. a transcendent God. These two forms absolutize our two
vision-logic equations: ∞/1 and 1/∞, respectively, corresponding to
immanent and transcendent bounded form.

Kelly continues:
Another Zen thought: The Atom is the past. The symbol of science for the
next century is the dynamical Net.

The Net icon has no center — it is a bunch of dots connected to other dots
— a cobweb of arrows pouring into each other, squirming together like a
nest of snakes, the restless image fading at indeterminate edges. The Net
is the archetype — always the same picture — displayed to represent all
circuits, all intelligence, all interdependence, all things economic and

Page | 573
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

social and ecological, all communications, all democracy, all groups, all
large systems. The icon is slippery, ensnaring the unwary in its paradox of
no beginning, no end, no center. Or, all beginning, all end, pure center. It is
related to the Knot. Buried in its apparent disorder is a winding truth.
Unraveling it requires heroism.
This use of the dynamical Network as “the symbol of science for the next
century” is similar to Deleuze and Guattari’s championing of the concept of
the rhizome. In The Deleuze Dictionary we find:
…the rhizome is a concept that ‘maps’ a process of networked, relational
and transversal thought, and a way of being without ‘tracing’ the
construction of that map as a fixed entity. Ordered lineages of bodies and
ideas that trace their originary and individual bases are considered as
forms of ‘arborescent thought’, and this metaphor of a tree-like structure
that orders epistemologies and forms historical frames and homogenous
schemata, is invoked by Deleuze as everything that rhizomatic thought is
not.
Where Deleuze and Guattari conceive of the tree (“arborescent thought”) as
opposite to the rhizome, we can see the simple difference between these two
forms in the idea of lineage. The tree traces everything back to the
individual unit, the trunk from which the roots and the branches diverge.
This, they say, is the focal point of power. By forcing everything into
patterns of “arborescent thought” power becomes centralized and controlled
through the trunk. The roots of the tree can be seen as the past or the
immanent line of emergent descent (if looking regressively from the
transcendent trunk) or ascent into the trunk, while the branches can be seen
as the future or the transcendent line of emergent ascent away from the
trunk.
The trunk of the tree, then, is roughly analogous to the holon—analyzed
into its own spatial and/or temporal networks. What we can see in the
infinite holarchy, however, is the combination of the rhizome and the tree.
In the holarchy we can find both. Trees are found by tracing both immanent
and transcendent lineages (lines of flight) to a single holon, and rhizomes are
found by tracing them through large groups or collections of holons.
A holon, however, is always composed of an infinite number of deeper
holons—indeed an infinite holarchy or a rhizomatic network of holons—
whereas the trunk of a tree is not composed of an infinite number of trunks
of trees. The trunk and strictly “arborescent thought”, therefore, is much
more akin to the Greek Atom and/or “Atomic thought”—which is a variant of
our friend “categorical absolutism”—whereas both the holon and the
holarchy contain and remain free from the restraints of both and embrace
the fundamental principle of Nondual Rationalism.
The holon/corpuscle/anatom and the holarchy/network/rhizome, then,
correspond in the pure-relational terms of immanence and transcendence to
the I/T uni-axis and the omni-axis, respectively. The holon embodies

Page | 574
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

singularity, and the holarchy embodies multiplicity; And each is enfolded in


the concept of the other. And these two emphases of thought naturally
correspond to the singular and plural quadrants of AQAL.

There is a possible bit of confusion, at this point, which must be averted in


order for Interface Philosophy to merge smoothly with AQAL metatheory.
For the most part we have been using the notion of transcendence to denote
holarchical scale on an infinite Immanent/Transcendent axis, but its more
precise meaning, as we have also seen, comes with the holarchical idea of
transcend-and-include, which we have been using throughout this text (for
example in the pervasive EOTC). We have discussed at length the tendency
for the transcendent to collapse or map directly to the transitive, and indeed
the need to untangle this collapse. And so through the use of the concepts of
“depth” and “span,” which come to us from Integral Theory, we will attempt
to further preclude this otherwise imminent collapse.
Depth, in Integral Theory,
can be very simply mapped to
the Immanent/Transcendent
axis as we have come to know it
through the notion of holarchy.
The depth of an individual
holon is the number of holonic
levels—or the degree of
transcend-and-include
complexity—which the holon
has incorporated into its
functional and structural make-
up. For example, the depth of
an atom is less than the depth Figure 84: Simple Depth Vs. Span:
of a cell which is less than the This simple diagram (though obviously not to
depth of a human being. The scale) captures the dimension of scale
involved in transcension-and-inclusion from
depth of each holon gets
tiny atom to human, but in so doing it loses
greater than the last holon the aspect of diminishing span with increasing
precisely because it transcends- depth.
and-includes it into ever greater
levels of transcendence (see
Figure 84, above, right). In this sense of a gradient of complexity, depth is
very much akin to Spinoza’s notion of “excellence,” from the “simplest
bodies” to the boundless complexity of God, the transcendent emphasis of
the immanent/transcendent omni-axis.

Page | 575
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Span, on the other hand, is the number of holons of or at a specific depth,


or at a given level of the holarchy. For example, it takes billions of atoms to
make a single cell, and it takes billions of cells to make a single human being.
For this reason, in any given region of space, there will be far more cells than
humans and far more atoms than cells. And so we can say that atoms have
greater span than cells, and that cells have greater span than humans. See
Figure 85, below.
And so we can see a general pattern in the holarchy that with greater
depth comes less span. We can see this also in the fact that not all collections
of atoms will transcend their agglomerative molecular nature to become
cells, and not all groups of cells will transcend to become humans. There
are, then, even less humans than atoms or cells…and far less than would be
assumed by merely accounting for their constituent holonic numbers. So we
can see that transcendence—in this sense of depth and span—takes on the
“spiky” nature we’d expect from an exponential or logarithmic decrease in
spatiotemporal frequency—the increased rarity—of the higher evolved
kinds of beings. See Figure 85, below.

Figure 85: Holonic Depth vs. Span:


In Integral Theory, depth is defined as the number of levels of the holarchy a given
holon has transcended-and-included. Span, on the other hand, is the number of holons
generally found at a given depth (in an average zone i n the cosmos, as far as such an
average can be estimated).

This relation of increasing separation between higher and higher evolved


beings may indeed help to account for the problem of the silentium universi,
and should be factored into the Drake equation. This, of course, may also be
Page | 576
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

countered with an unknown relation in which it is likely that these higher


level beings may begin to technologically transcend these limits altogether,
and indeed reach a much greater span both perceptually and conceptually,
and perhaps even physically (as would be expected of AQAL theory and
general dependent arising), in some as-yet-unknown form of transcendence
and connection.
Indeed, as we have already discussed at length, with the increase in
transcendence comes a corresponding expansion into immanence—though
the causal relation is very often the other way around.i* This, recall, is
embodied in The Core SpinbitZ Diagram (p376), and animated on the
SpinbitZ website. We also saw, for example, that in the holarchical growth
of mathematics it was always with a move toward operational immanence
(e.g. subtraction, division and rooting) that the “breaking of the closure
property” of the current set of numbers caused a transcendence to a new,
more inclusive set. This is most easily seen with the move to Rational
numbers in the operation of division, or the move toward the infinite
immanence of so-called “irrational” numbers—which operate fully on the
VL-axis of the rational, and so are far from being “irrational,” in the esoteric
and nondual sense of rationality.
Given the close mapping between the “pure-relational” aspects of
mathematics with the field of real relation itself, it is indeed plausible that
with an increasing level of technological proficiency at the increasing levels
of immanence (micro-, nano-, femto-, etc), will come a “quantum”
breakthrough in a form of transcendence that we simply cannot fathom (e.g.
“The Technological Singularity”). This principle that with increasing
technological immanence comes increasing transcendence,ii may indeed,
therefore, entirely compensate or overtake the principle of decreased span
with increasing depth.

While it may be immediately clear that span is a transitive type of concept, it


must also be clarified that the operational axis of span is not the transitive-
axis directly. Span is essentially a quantitative concept (i.e. the number of
holons at a given depth), whereas transitivity is a geometrical concept. But
specifically, transitivity is a linear or uni-/multi-directional concept (as
opposed to the Immanent/Transcendent axis which is omni-directional),
while span is a number, involved in a purely quantitative relation specifically
inter-relating quantities of holons at different levels of depth.iii*

i
* Recall the Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of Immanence in Transcendence (Yin in Yang), p95.
ii
This is an expanding corollary to our Principle of Immanence in Transcendence.
iii
* Please refer to, The Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS), p123, for any confusion that will
inevitably crop up for those who haven’t read the sections basic to these concepts.

Page | 577
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

This is why span, in relation to depth, generally corresponds in the


opposite direction to scale or transcendence, whereas, as we have seen,
transitivity and transcendence generally tend to overlap, conflate and con-
fuse and otherwise positively reinforce one another (compare Figure 84 and
Figure 85 above). For example, it is clear that a cell has far a greater scale
than an atom and that a human has a far greater scale than a cell, while each
has less span than these constituents. In this sense, span is an inverse and
quantitative relation to transitivity and transcendence, though slightly
indirectly.

It is also important to clarify that holonic or holarchic transcendence does


not always equate to scale or size, though very often it is indeed the case. A
counter-example of the correlation can be seen in the fact that a dinosaur
has a greater size than a human, while a human—with its transcension-and-
inclusion of the reptilian brain into the mammalian triune brain—has
greater depth and transcendence. See Figure 86, below.
There is a simple way to understand the difference, however, when we
think of transcendence solely in terms of a single holonic (arborescent) line
of development (or flight) as opposed to interrelating the complexity of two
or more lines (moving into rhizomatic relations). For example, in the line of
development from atom, to cell, and to human—where each level physically
transcends-and-includes the holons of the previous levels—we can apply the
restrictions of boundary and scale very simply at each level. In this sense, a
holon cannot physically transcend-and-include a holon of greater size than
itself. So in this single transcend-and-include line—a holonic line—there is
indeed a necessary movement up in scale as we move toward transcension.
Though it is also the case that the scales and depths between two different
holonic lines or types may not indeed match up.
As the perceptive reader will note, however, there are two different kinds
of transcension-and-inclusion being used here. The transcension-and-
inclusion of the reptilian brain into the triune-brain of the human is not the
same kind of transcension-and-inclusion as that of the atom into the cell, for
example. This is seen in the fact that while there are indeed billions of whole
atoms intact and included in the cell and there are billions of cells intact and
included in the reptile, there are certainly not billions, or even a single
reptile transcended-and-included in the human being. In a very real sense,
however, there is one reptilian brain transcended-and-included in the
human brain, but the brain is a part of the dinosaur or human holon, not a
whole or a holon in its own right.

Page | 578
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Figure 86: Depth vs. Size:


Depth in a single holarchical line of development does indeed roughly correspond to
size or scale, but depth as a relation between two lines often does not. In this diagram
I have also indicated the two distinct types of transcension -and-inclusion, holarchic
(intra-unit) and holonic (inter-unit). This distinction can be seen in the fact that
brains, or parts thereof, are not holons in their own right. G iven the fact that they
can’t persist outside and apart from the body, therefore, their transcension-and-
inclusion may be holarchic, but it is not holonic.

The first kind of transcension-and-inclusion, from atoms to cells to


organisms is a kind of holonic or arborescent relation—where the complete
units (part-wholes or holons) of one level form together to give the collective
emergent properties of the next complete unit or holon and everything is
traced to the individual holon(s). The second type of transcension-and-
inclusion, on the other hand, from reptilian to human triune brain, is
rhizomatic or holarchic. It is a fractional and functional incorporation of a
vast collection of holons (neurons) as a single part (a body-part, not a holon;
such as the reptilian brain) enfolded into a larger part (the triune brain).
The difference can be divided, then, on two lines or polarities: the collective
emergence and unity of the holonic vs. the fractional multiplicity of the

Page | 579
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

holarchic. A brain is not a holon, but a sub-holon or a holarchy—a part, not a


part-whole—because it can’t maintain its unity outside or apart from the
body itself.i

So, we can see these two types of transcension-and-inclusion as holonic vs.


holarchic, or anatomic vs. rhizomatic. And naturally we can see this
distinction as occurring roughly between the I/T uni- vs. the omni-axis,
respectively. The holarchical transcension-and-inclusion, need not resolve
to holons (anatomoi) themselves, but traces its lines to whole collections or
expanses of networked holons composing only a part of a larger holon—
such as collections of neurons composing the reptilian brain—whereas
holonic transcension-and-inclusion traces its lines of flight explicitly from
holon to holon via collections and their emergent properties into new holons.
This holonic transcension-and-inclusion traces ultimately to the uni-axis of
the individual, from the implicit singularities of immanence to unbounded
transcendence. Holarchic transcension-and-inclusion, however, takes place
only on the I/T omni-axis, because it doesn’t trace its lines to a single holon,
but only to collections of sub-holons forming a part of the main holon.
In these terms, then, the transcension-and-inclusion of single humans (I)
into a collective WE is holarchical rather than holonic, because it doesn’t
resolve to a proper unity. And this explains why the WE has a very different
nature than the I. This difference in nature turns on the aspect of the unity
of intrinsic experience which all holons explicitly share at some level, but
which a group of humans perhaps only rarely experiences given the
differences in outward appearance and functionality and that we can’t know
this explicitly or empirically. The individual holon, such as the human, can
indeed empirically and explicitly sense this unity because, as the unity itself,
he experiences and senses it directly and unmediated. Only for others is your
own experience subjective, implicit and non-empirical.

As we have seen, there is a general acceptance of holarchy as necessitating a


boundless or infinite depth in both immanent and transcendent directions.
As we might expect from the previous (pre-rational) attempts to
quantitatively deal with the infinite in terms of the finite, however, this
infinite notion of depth can be a bit confusing with respect to finite
individual holons. Indeed, this general underpinning of infinite holarchical

i
This is not the same dependency, however, as the human on its social structure or environment,
simply because while the social sphere or the environment can exist without a particular human, the
human can’t exist without its brain. Furthermore, a brain does not possess the properties of holons,
such as agency and communion. Without the body, the brain has no function of homeostasis and it
quickly dies.

Page | 580
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

depth wreaks havoc on the notion of individual holonic depth, because


(given our Quantitative principle of Infinite Unity) in an infinite holarchy all
holons would necessarily have an equally “infinite number” of holons
transcended-and-included within them, and hence an equally infinite depth.
In this way the depth of one holon therefore can have no differential
meaning with respect to another. This, then, razes to the ground any
difference in depth and therefore any hierarchical notion of holarchy and
depth as anything but a purely epistemic (imaginary) and metrical function.
The quick answer is that we have taken the relative concept of depth to
the absolute scope of the infinite, and that depth can only remain relative.
But this ignores the necessity of a holarchy of infinite depth. The depth of
the holarchy is necessarily infinite by the very definition of a holon, even if
the depth of a holon can only be quantified relatively. Holons, then, must
have real depth relative to some kind of deeper, emergent and real limit or
metric on the Immanent/Transcendent axis. But the difficulty is how
precisely to deal with that real metric while acknowledging the infinite
depth of the holarchy itself. How indeed does that relative metric and its
limits show up in relative reality in order for depth to have any real or ontic
meaning? And how does this finite notion of depth relate to the infinite
depth of the holarchy itself?
A quick answer can be seen by simply relating one holon to the holons it
has transcended-and-included. This holon is obviously of a greater depth
than the holons it transcended-and-included, and we can do the same
relative procedure for each holon in the holarchy. The analogy here is the
number-line. Two is greater than one which is greater than zero which is
greater than negative one, even though each of them has an infinite number
of integers preceding it.
While inter-unit relation is valid and useful, it is only useful for relating
holons of similar lineages. If we have one holon composed of different types
of holons—a different line of symbols—than another, then how do we relate
the depth between them without a common metric? Another problem with
this method is that it neglects the big picture of transcendence itself, which
is the obvious empirical gradient of complexity manifest in holarchical
evolution. Indeed, the real difference from two to one to zero is the gradient
of increasing value or magnitude it embodies. This quick fix is an essentially
“ordinal,” rather than a “cardinal” solution. When we go past zero, in this
quick fix, into the negative numbers, we are saying that there is a negative,
indeed an infinitely negative form of depth. Often times in real-world
problems the negative numbers must be cast out as meaningless, and indeed
this is another case. There is no negative form of depth. The quick solution
to save this view would be to start with infinity and count backwards, but
infinity is not a bound and not a number. It is not found on the numberline
at all, but is its boundless context.

Page | 581
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Another quick fix is to cast out the negativity problem of depth by


jumping on the Immanent/Transcendent axis of the rational numbers,
decreasing not into negativity, but into infinite immanence. But if depth
doesn’t relate to some actual metric of complexity in the holarchy itself, like
a common ground of simplicity relative to all holons of a certain level, at
least of a specific locale, then the gradient itself, necessary to the very notion
of transcension-and-inclusion, would necessitate that holons get ever
simpler and simpler as they go back into the infinite immanence of the
holarchy.
Ultimately, then, holons in this simple notion of emergent complexity,
would be infinitely simple, because there would always be an infinite depth
above them to count back from. Perhaps some version of this chain of
reasoning is the very genesis of the concept of the mathematical point. But
recall that there can be no reaching of the infinite, in any of its aspects,
simplicity, complexity or whatever. This infinite holonic simplicity seems,
on its face, absurd. Surely there is some emergent form of a limit to
simplicity. After-all, the properties of any holon must surely have a
minimum amount of complexity in order to count as holons, and indeed to
even exist.
So this purely relative metric of depth either ends in the problem of
negativity or the problem of infinite simplicity, both of which render the
“cardinal” meaning of the gradient meaningless and devolving into
essentially “ordinal” solutions with no real value or magnitude for depth—a
mere ordering by number, devaluing the real magnitude of increasing
complexity itself.

Perhaps the only self-consistent way out of this dilemma of a “flatland” of


infinite depth is to “finitize” or quantize the notion of depth for each holon in
relation to some real metric in the holarchy itself, giving a real, not purely
relative, scale or referent for holonic depth. This would be similar to the
transitive unit providing the scale for inter-unit operations in Interface
Mathematics: there has to be a real, if always emergent and relative, ground
for the gradient of complexity to begin. This would mean that holonic
complexity reaches a minimum at recursive self-similar levels (transitive-
planes) in the holarchy, at which all holons are effectively equal at a depth or
complexity of one.
The complexity from the infinite holarchical depth, at these “minimally
complex” levels, however, cannot not just disappear on a whim, but is then
necessarily “enfolded” within the ground-level holons, so their unit-
differences and interactions and are minimally complex, not absolutely
simple. This is not absolute-zero complexity, but minimal and enfolded
complexity—involution—where the inter-unit differences and relations

Page | 582
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

become enfolded and homogenized to the bare minimum. This involution of


complexity in the holarchy itself, then, provides the ground for the evolution
and real relation of actual holons. Depth is then simply a relative and ordinal
measure between holons themselves, but between holons and their real
place in the real depth-metric of the holarchy in terms of the involution and
evolution of holarchical complexity.

Indeed, the most consistent way to understand this periodic quantization of


holarchical involution and evolution is that the enfoldment of infinite
holarchic complexity itself maintains the extreme unit integrity of the
simplest holons or units, as the energies maximally emergent at the focal
point of the unit become internally refracted and reflected toward harmonic
self-reinforcement and self-stabilization (e.g. inertia).i In this sense we
have another true polarity: Holons of MINIMAL outward or inter-unit
complexity occur precisely at the focal point of MAXIMAL complexity,
where they can finally harness the complexity of the infinite holarchy
into their own self-stabilization and inertial integrity. Simplest bodies,
then, are simplest precisely because they are internally the most
complex and self-organized. In this sense, evolution itself leads directly to
involution at the next level. Indeed, evolution and involution are the two
sides of the same coin, because it is increasing complexity itself—
evolution—that allows involution to proceed toward the self-centering, self-
harmonizing, self-focusing of its ever higher ground-levels of simplest
bodies. Evolution, then, is involution seen in reverse. And we can see this
as a harmonic corollary to our Principle of Immanence in
Transcendence. Just as immanence is transcendence if seen from
“beneath,” so too involution is evolution if seen from within its unfolding
process.
A simple way to visualize this process is to conceive of the polarity of
involution and evolution in terms of a torus whose outside is turning inside
and whose inside is turning outside (See Figure 87, below), like a dipole
magnetic field. Imagine that the torus is resting upon the axis that runs
through its center. In order for the torus to move up the arrow it must
continually turn itself inside out, rolling up the torus in the omni-directions
of its intrinsic planarity. In the same way, as evolution progresses, it gets
more and more complex, enfolding the outward complexity inward to the
point that this complexity emerges into new properties which begin to allow
the units or holons to attain the maximally self-harmonized, self-stabilized
and self-focused structure of “simplest bodies” whose maximal inward
complexity manifests as a minimal outward complexity with which this
process begins anew from this newly emergent “ground-level.”

i
This process is explained in explicit and exquisite causal detail in Sorce Theory.

Page | 583
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 87: Involution is Evolution Seen in Reverse:


Involution and evolution are part of the same process, but depending from which side
of the process the viewer is placed, he will see either involution or evolution. In order
for the torus to move up the axis running through its center, it must involute and
evolute itself, rolling up the axis in the omni -directions of its intrinsic planarity.

Page | 584
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

The preceding section perhaps explains our popular fascination with the
idea of the “black hole.” Indeed, the simplest holon is the point where the
maximal energies enfold and self-reinforce in such a way as to “encapsulate”
or hold them within its body—a holding pattern limiting its outward
complexity to an apparent inter-unit self-similarity and homogeneity. But
the simplest bodies are not black holes. They don’t suck in everything
around them based on a runaway concept of abstracted gravity.i They
merely have the power to harness their own intrinsic energies and those
around them, with a minimum of loss to outward complexity. There is
indeed a degree of outward complexity displayed. It’s just the minimum
level.
Perhaps also, it is this innate idea of the focal point of complexity
emerging into maximal simplicity that forms the locus of our attractor for
meditative transformational practices. This move is accomplished, however,
only through an analogous sort of inter-harmonizing of internal energies to
attain a self-reinforcing and self-stabilizing form of “psychic inertia” that
only the focal point of maximal and maximized energies can provide.
In meditation, for example, the generally trans-biased (transitive and
transcendent) focus is instead centered within. But representation can’t
simply enter the implicit singularity of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis
of its bounded form. Rather—through a relaxation simultaneously into
transcendence—it enters the immanent multiplicity of the boundary itself
(e.g. from mnemonic complexes to primitives in the sensory-mnemonic
interface) until the limits of this process are reached and the
representational and experiential detail is so fine (and simultaneously vast)
as to appear continuous and empty, due to the perspectival limits of
representation itself.
Indeed, relative to everyday experience this experience is Emptiness, but
it is not the Emptiness we conceive of logically and rationally at the absolute
scope as infinite or limitless depth in itself. Experience itself is bounded and

i
Indeed, we can recognize that Einstein himself felt that his concept of gravity was only one half of
an abstract polarity, which, by itself leads the universe to implosion. Thus he invented his opposing
concept of the cosmological constant. This concept was disparaged with the arising of the
popularity of the Big Bang Theory, but oddly enough, the constant was revived under a the guise of
“inflation” in order to save the Big Bang model itself from collapse.

Page | 585
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

enabled by its form; indeed Emptiness is Form and Form Emptiness. The I
cannot escape the IT, in AQAL parlance. So, even though the holarchy itself
is infinitely deep, it is the brain that is doing the representation, and
representation is possessed of a relative and finite depth, as it merges into
the infinite depth of sub-representation. What is meant, then, by
experiential Emptiness, must simply be “the experience of non-experience,”
or the non-experience within experience. This is sometimes called the
“witness” or the fundamental perspective or ground of being necessary for
experience itself. It is the approach and realization thereof to the identical
opposite and sub-representational context of experience itself. In this sense,
if the approach is successful, Emptiness can’t “feel like” anything at all.
This immanent process of approaching representational continuity,
immanence or Emptiness, provides the practitioner with the chance to
decouple his higher-level internal-external (subject-object) mappings and
differences and move closer and closer to a ground of maximal simplicity
and unity. And—as analogous to the role of immanence in the
transcendence of operation and numberi where it was always through
immanence that the breaking of closure was accomplished and the
transcendence into the next set of numbers was reached—it is through this
immanence that transcendence is accomplished, and perhaps vice versa.

So the meditator is approaching the “ground of being” in many senses. He is


approaching the ground of holonic simplicity itself (minimal depth), in
minimizing the complexity of his thoughts—breaking them down or
“pulverizing” them from mnemonic complexes to primitives—while at the
same time approaching a general self-similarity (or roughly analogous
“psychic” form) to the actual internal structure of the simplest holons with
their maximization of the internally inter-harmonizing patterns of infinite
energy at the emergent focal point at the interface (vinculum) of awareness
itself, of the implicit singularity of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis. It is
this implicit singularity (or an “infinite number” of them) at the heart of his
bounded being—reflecting through the Principle of Absolute Reversal into
the transcendent—which he later acknowledges and analogizes as he
approaches the immanent limits of his own experiential form and boundary:
his sub-mnemonic interface.
A finite unity cannot experience the absolute scope of the infinite because
experience itself is relational and relative. Or, put another way, one must
experience the absolute through the relative; one must experience the infinite
through the finite, which results in the boundlessness of the indefinite, or in
the nondual resting in the infinite and finite as one. Similarly, one may
experience the timelessness of eternity (sub specie aeternitatis), but only

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.

Page | 586
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

through the forms of time. Indeed, the one without the other is a duality, not
a nonduality or polarity. In this way, it is only through logic, rationality or
trans-rational and trans-logical intuition that we can recognize what these
relative experiences point to in their own identical opposite of the
unreachable Absolute Infinite and Emptiness, or even vastly beyond the sub-
and meta-representational reaches of experience. And this is indeed why
the cognitive line is so important to development. We may experience
emptiness all the time, but without cognitive models for what is being
experienced and how to recognize its signs, we have no tools for maximizing
or controlling its unfolding.
The basic relation in experience is that between subject and object.
Through meditation one may indeed break down to the cogito of the
dissolved self, but to retain experience through it one must relate the
experience to memory and indeed pull it back through the mnemonic
primitives themselves. In these states one breaks down the mnemonic
complexes to their primitives and approaches the nondual state of the
symbiogenesis of subject and object. This is a state of pre-differentiation
between self and other and a state prior to the learning and functioning of
the senses, so it approaches ineffability, in itself. But all states are relative
whether nondual or not, because form is emptiness and emptiness form.
This will make much more sense when we revisit the concept of scope,
below and see that ultimately, or merely ontically, they are inseparable.i*

With this loose speculation, however, it is important to note that the self-
similarity between the ground-level of simplest bodies and the interstitial
level of the human being is clearly and observationally inexact—a loose
analogy and real-world echo distorted through the chambers and
stratifications of complexity itself between its recursive isomorphisms.
Indeed, as we’ll see below, man sits virtually halfway between his upper and
lower simplest levels in a state meso-complexity. His form, then, cannot be
identical to that of the simplest body (e.g. the atom), but it can be a self-
similar echo of many of its patterns and relations. We see this effect in the
self-similar forms of both mathematical and real-world fractals, where
between specific levels of self-similarity we see only “distorted” similarities
to the main pattern. And it is this self-similarity in nature that reinforces the
notion that man, as a self-similar echo of nature, can understand and
experience that nature itself. In other words, if nature is wholly self-similar,
as it indeed appears to be, then the epistemic is a self-similar echo of the
ontic, and thus, in this sense, “corresponds” to it.

i
* See, Defining the Scope of Scope, p592.

Page | 587
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

From this recurrent unitizing, homogenizing ground of complexity enfolded


into simplest holons, (e.g. “atoms”) complexity and depth then finds a
foundation to unfold again. In this emergence from a recurrent ground-
level, holons find their ontically real referent for relative differences of
holonic depth and complexity at the higher levels of evolutionary holonic
and holarchic transcension-and-inclusion.
This notion of enfolded and minimal complexity is deeply concurrent
with Spinoza’s notion of “simplest bodies.” Nowhere does Spinoza equate
his “simplest bodies” with a “smallest” scale. Precisely the opposite. There
is no smallest scale of modification in Spinoza because Substance is
fundamentally indivisible. And, as we have seen in our fundamental
Principle of Nondual Rationalism,i* this indivisibility is the identical opposite
corollary of infinite divisibility. Rather, Spinoza calls these bodies “simplest”
in a deliberate contrast to the other end of the polarity in complexity or
“excellence.”
Indeed, Spinoza’s implicit use of the notion of an unbounded
Immanent/Transcendent axis, in conjunction with his stipulation of the
necessity of the notion of a “simplest body,” would seem to have implicitly
beat us to the conclusion of this need for levels of minimum or enfolded
complexity with which to begin unfolding the gradient of complexity or
“excellence.” Perhaps in some sense, Spinoza indeed intuited that these
boundless levels of complexity enfolded into “simplest bodies” would
quantize and finitize the quantitative relation of depth, giving it a scale from
which it can begin relation and sparing it from the equalizing dilemma of a
holarchy of infinite immanence. Or perhaps Spinoza, like the Great Chain of
Being theorists before him, just recognized the necessity of the gradient and
followed it back to its necessary “foundational” elements, in the intuited
understanding that this distance and difference could not be infinite.

While this rational or logical necessity of the “simplest body” is important to


consider in its various relative possibilities, it is also important to consider
whether it is backed up by any scientific and empirical data. Indeed, the
recent findings of the “fractal” or “self-similar” models of cosmology have
already determined an empirically-derived, quantized, self-similar and
recurring relation between levels of complexity or what we call holonic
depth.
The Self-Similar Cosmological Model of Rob Oldershaw, for example,
forms a rigorous empirical and mathematical basis upon which to anchor

i
* See Principle 1: Chord 1: The Fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism (PNDR) (p84), which
states that “infinite division equals indivisibility.”

Page | 588
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

and justify these quantized unit-levels of “simplest bodies” and enfolded


complexity.
Giving a context for his model, Oldershaw says:
In the new theory there is no stipulation that nature’s hierarchy is limited
to the scales that we have defined; this assumption, in fact, would have an
anthropocentric bias which physicists have sought to avoid since the time
of Copernicus. It is quite possible that the hierarchy extends beyond the
galactic scale and that galaxies are the component building blocks on a
larger ‘meta-galactic’ scale.
Aside from the readily demonstrablei structural self-similarities between the
levels of the atom and the star—such as the exact same geometrical relation
found between the orbital spacings in both Schrödinger’s atomic-, and
Bode’s planetary-laws—Oldershaw has found a deep underlying
quantitative similarity between various aspects of these recurring levels or
scales (atomic, stellar and galactic) through a self-similar scaling equation
that inter-relates them. This equation shows, for example, that the relations
between the numbers or frequencies of the elements compared to the
numbers or frequencies of the different kinds of stars, is virtually identical,
and inter-transformable via the scaling equation. The number of Hydrogen
atoms compared to the number of other elements, for example, occurs in
precisely the same relation or ratio as the number of M-dwarf stars
compared to the other types of stars. Oldershaw has also demonstrated
structural relations between excited stars (e.g. “planetary nebulae”) and
excited atoms (e.g. Rydgerg atoms). He has extended his analyses as well to
the galactic level, but, due to the vast time-scales involved, the frequency of
the data points is scarce, making it difficult to refine a precise quantitative
relation at the galactic and higher levels.
In conjunction with Oldershaw, various other models concurrently
demonstrate with vivid clarity the pictorial self-similar relations occurring
at these intermittent levels. It is indeed impossible to ignore the sheer
quantity of this empirical, observational data that shows clear structural
relations between these levels in the cosmos. And so we can use this data to
empirically buttress the rational necessity of this quantization and periodic
enfoldment of individual holonic depth.

These models show that at specific scales (recurring transitive-planes or


“ground levels” as we’ll call them) there is a sort of “reset” in holonic
complexity that occurs. According to the general quantitative relation as
discovered by Rob Oldershaw,ii¥ this occurs at around every twenty orders

i
See Oldershaw < http://www.amherst.edu/~rloldershaw/menu.html>.
ii¥
(Oldershaw)

Page | 589
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

of magnitude (in meters), from the Planck level, to the atom, to the M-dwarf
stars, to galaxies or voids and very likely beyond.
We’ll get into the physics and causation of this empirical relation in
Volume II (and I explore it in depth in my article Sorce Theory: Unlocking the
Basement), but suffice it to say that the effective continuity of the emergent
levels imparts a critical set of emergent qualities or quantifiable properties
(e.g. superfluidity, with an effectively zero friction and viscosity) which
allows the next ground-level of units or “simplest bodies” to enfold the
infinite complexity beneath it into self-stabilizing, self-harmonizing and self-
centering inertial integrity, emerging into what appear on the surface as a
level of homogenized and simplest bodies (see this note for more details).i

i
Sorce Theory, gives us a simple way to causally understand one of the properties that can lead to
such a real, emergent, self-similar relation. Beneath the unit-level or “ground-level” of the atomic
nucleus (the proton) we have an effective subatomic continuity (a quasi-continuity) that doesn’t see
its deeper unit-level until another whopping twenty orders of magnitude in meters—the Planck level
(the same distance on the Immanent/Transcendent axis between an atom and a star). Accordingly,
the actual properties of matter shift dramatically between the atomic (unit) and subatomic (sub-
unit) levels, and this is precisely why the physicists of the early twentieth century were so utterly
befuddled when their “classical” meso-scale and particle-based expectations were shattered by the
entirely new properties of the sub-atomic quasi-continuous level—themselves emergent from a
much deeper level.
The intermediate holons between the Planck and atomic scales are highly unstable, as physics
has discovered, whereas the proton (atomic nucleus) is extremely stable (the neutron is also
unstable and decays into the proton). It is this aspect of extreme or maximal stability—among other
things such as maximal unit simplicity (minimal complexity)—which qualifies a level as a ground-
level of “simplest bodies.” We find such levels at the scale of the Planck unit (the Planck scale), the
proton, the M-dwarf stars and likely at the level of galaxies or voids. The larger and larger we get,
however, the more sparse and indirect the data, so it is difficult to determine the precise unit-levels
at those scales. This is mainly because of temporal dilation at larger scales in that we see fewer and
fewer complete events and thus we have far fewer points of data to correlate into an empirical
relation. … This shift between levels and their qualities can be seen most clearly in the emergent or
transcendent direction, as opposed to the regressive or immanent. As we zoom out in scale from
the size of the atomic nucleus, for example, the discreteness of the atomic level recedes from view
and rather quickly begins to appear continuous. Even by the time we get to the human level (the
meter), exactly half-way between the upper and lower levels (atomic and stellar), we have what
appears as an effective continuity. Water, for example, appears quite continuously fluid. Despite
this apparent continuity at this mid-level, however, water has a specific and tangible discrete aspect
in its quality of viscosity. As you get to smaller and smaller scales, for example, there is a rise in
surface tension and viscosity such that water at those levels tends to quantize into droplets of a
similar size. This is called “atomization,” naturally.
These are thermo-inertial and chemical properties directly emergent from the inertial properties
of the unit-level of the atom, but properties which effectively disappear at the subatomic level. And
again in the transcendent direction, by the time we get to another twenty orders of magnitude
larger, according to this model, at the level of the M-dwarf stars this apparent continuity has
drastically changed, transcending its atomic discreteness through this shear quantity of its intrinsic
qualities and its emergent effects. At this point a new set of continuous and superfluid properties
has emerged. This shift to superfluidity at the stellar level (as also seen at the sub-atomic or sub-
inertial level) can be seen in the shift in astrophysics to modeling cosmic scale objects, such as black-
holes, for example, on superfluid dynamics (see the work of Volovik, for example).
Indeed, as seen in studies of superfluidity, this zero friction/viscosity aspect allows superfluids to
achieve remarkable things, such as forming metastable vortices that interact as discrete units,

Page | 590
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

In this self-similarly quantized sense, then, the depth of an individual holon


must be measured only with respect to the transitive-plane or ground-level
corresponding to its “simplest bodies.” For us—according to the empirical
scaling relation of Self-Similar Cosmology—this simplest holon is the atom
(or, more correctly, the corpuscular anatom). For any possible entities
beneath the scale of the atom, it is the Planck unit, and for any holons
smaller than the Planck scale (in direct opposition to the modern exoteric
Atomic and foundational notion of the Planck scale), it is the next smaller
simplest body, perhaps ad infinitum. The anatomic units at these ground
levels are perhaps equally “simple,” as they constitute a recurring self-similar
pattern of minimal or enfolded complexity on the Immanent/Transcendent
axis—and again, according to the clear empirical self-similar relation.
Once this ground level of basic building blocks is set up, evolution and
structural relation can begin to transform the simplest bodies into holonic
layers of greater and greater structural complexity and depth. Without
these first and simplest bodies and their respective ground-levels, there can
be no structural complexification into greater holonic depth.
Recalling our two forms of transcension-and-inclusion—holonic and
holarchic, as roughly bifurcating on the distinction between the I/T uni- and
omni-axes, respectively—we can see a very clear distinction between two
types of depth. Holonic depth is individual depth as measured with respect
to the “ground level” of enfolded and minimal complexity transcended-and-
included in the individual holon as the bounded interface on its own I/T uni-
axis. Holonic depth, then, is arboreal, a network of holons always funneling
through a single trunk of a holonic focal point. Holarchic depth, on the other
hand, is depth with respect to the infinite distributed multiplicity of the
holarchy itself, or the networks of parts thereof. Holarchic depth then is
rhizomatic, it resembles networks of connected roots, like grasses or
neurons, irrespective of any single localized holonic development or holon.
It need only resolve to distributed collections of holons forming parts of
larger holons or to the omni-/non-locality of the infinite holarchy—the ONE-
ALL of infinite multiplicity itself. And so, while the holarchical depth of any
holon may indeed be infinite, the holonic depth is not.
This ever-present polarity of depth allows us to differentiate and inter-
relate the depth between holons, while at the same time it accounts for the
empirical evidence of boundless depth manifesting as the inherent
indeterminism or unpredictability of any event. (Recall our Principle of
Infinite Determinism.)

similar to atoms. In Sorce Theory, it is shown how the subatomic Planck-level superfluid can indeed
form the atoms as metastable vortices with their harmonically quantized interior energy shells.

Page | 591
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 88: Holonic and Holarchic Depth:


In an infinite holarchy—as presupposed by AQAL metatheory for example—in order to
escape the conundrum of an equally infinite depth to ALL holons, depth itself must be
“finitized” or quantized, in some sense, to recurring scales of “minimum” or enfolded
complexity. The units of these “ground-levels” correspond to Spinoza’s “simplest
bodies” and they are reinforced by the empirical findings in the emerging Fractal and
Self-Similar Cosmologies, such as the empirical scaling relation discovered by Rob
Oldershaw. Furthermore, in conjunction with the distinction between holonic and
holarchic transcension-and-inclusion, we can make the distinction between holonic and
holarchic depth. While an individual holon may have a finite holonic depth—quantized
by the recurring scales of enfolded complexity —it can, at the same time, possess an
infinite holarchical depth. Via the Principle of Infinite Determinism, this polarity of
depth accounts for the necessarily indeterminate “fundamental” complexity of holons
of a finite holonic depth.

Page | 592
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

And so, depth is indeed measured on the Immanent/Transcendent axis, but


it is differentiated into holonic and holarchic depth, corresponding to the
differentiation of the I/T axis into the uni- and omni-axes, respectively.
Holonic depth is individual depth, quantized and measured specifically with
respect to the recurring “ground-levels” of “simplest bodies.” This
quantization of holonic depth removes the conundrum of an equality of
“infinite depth” that would otherwise render the differential depth of
individual holons meaningless. At the same time, the polarity between
holarchical and holonic (or rhizomatic and arboreal) depth explains—via the
Principle of Infinite Determinism i and its boundless levels of causal
complexity—how the truncation, quantization or enfoldment of individual
complexity itself can manifest the infinite depth of holarchic complexity into
observations of fundamental indeterminacy or unpredictability. See Figure
88, above.
Span as well, we found, does not correspond to scale or to the transitive-
axis but is merely a quantitative relation between levels of holonic depth. In
this sense that the higher levels of holonic evolution and transcendence get
more and more rare as they ascend, span is essentially an inverse relation to
holonic depth.

i
“Infinite determinism equals indeterminism.”

Page | 593
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

This section—as it continues to break down the traditional dichotomies of


self vs. other, rational vs. empirical, subject vs. object, ontic vs. epistemic etc.
via the cultivated/cultivating third of the various triune interfaces—plumbs
the nature (ontic) of the knower (epistemic), from the depths of evolution to
the structure of the cell; from the evolution of sensation to the general
structure of the sensory system, but in the context of the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System and Univocity Framework. The theories of knowledge
acquisition, we will find, can be ordered and harmonized according to the
EOTC and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System in the Interface model of
epistemology.

The absolute and relative scopes, recall, are purely epistemic functions. They
are the two nodes of conceptual context in the fundamental distinction and
polarity in the Interface model of Epistemology, as already used extensively
throughout this work. This is not to say that there is no absolute and
relative world, however, but to say that it is only in the oppositional realm of
the epistemic, the realm of scope itself with its embryogenesis of the
concept, that such an oppositional distinction necessarily exists.
Recall again how the absolute scope was generated in the attempt by the
relative scope to find its ultimate context-defining other. The absolute scope
then is reserved in opposition to relation, but with the understanding that
this opposition is merely a way of looking at things—a scope. And in a true
polarity, the absolute and relative scopes are distinct but not ultimately
separate. The absolute scope is The Absolute conceived initially apart from
the relative—Emptiness conceived apart from Form—for the sake of making
the initial distinction apparent and breaking the bonds of absolutism in
order to effect their consistent integration. This is in the same way that
Spinoza’s attributes are conceived as apart and parallel, with the
understanding that there is ultimately only Substance and its modes as

Page | 594
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

conceived through one or the other attribute. And this is also in the same
sense that the AQAL quadrants are seen as apart (e.g. scopes) but understood
as fundamentally integral (tetra-arising) and ultimately never separated in
the first place (ontic). The initial differentiation ensures the proper
integration. This, recall, is a fundamental function of the EOTC.
Recall again how the absolute scope reserves the space for The Absolute
itself free from conceptualization. This is because the quantitative aspect of
The Absolute is The Infinite and the concept itself is always a bound. When
The Absolute is conceived in terms of a concept, the unlimited is conceived
as a limit. In the EOTC, however, such a differentiation must eventually be
resolved to an integration—an organization must always resolve to an
organism. And so in the ontic—the sub-representational—the absolute is
understood as infinite difference and relation in itself—the ALL-ONE. So
ultimately The Absolute is not other than the relative, but merely the infinite
or Emptiness aspect of the relative world of Form (Spinoza’s Absolute
Infinity)—or vice versa, the relative is merely the finite or bounded and
differentiated aspect (the Form) of The Infinite Absolute, or Emptiness.
Taking these linear logical limitations in parallel, together, we can perhaps
approach the true polarity beyond the limitations of our language. The
absolute is the relative is the absolute. Unity is Multiplicity.

ONE = ∞/∞ = ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE

Scope is merely an epistemic tool used to untangle the constant con-fusions


between absolute and relative modes of thought in both ontology and
epistemology, as each symbiogenetically engage in the unfolding and
evolution of the other. The tool itself must not be tripped over in the
emphasis of its distinction over its inseparability. Once the epistemic or
representational distinction is made, it is crucial to integrate it back into the
ontic realization that the absolute and relative are ONE world with two
representational stances, “positions” or scopes from which it can be viewed.
The crucial difference between the relative and absolute scopes is in their
quantitative aspects, the finite and the infinite, respectively. It is critical, at
this point, to understand that knowledge itself is a finite or indefinite “field”
of form, and is thus always, of necessity, relational and relative, even if
rigorously proven by empirical or logical means, and even if inseparable
from the infinite context in which it exists. This is to say that knowledge—
being ontically inseparable from the absolute—is, in a sense, fundamentally
infinite, or unbounded. And, as we have seen, the finite, interfacing, in its
finite way, with its own infinity, gives us the indefinite.
Knowledge expands indefinitely, in all possible directions—immanent,
transcendent and transitive—and hence it is always incomplete. This we
can see as a corollary or resonant chord to our Principle of Infinite
Determinism: “Infinite determinism equals indeterminism.” Because

Page | 595
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

knowledge is founded on The Infinite (Emptiness), it is always indefinite


and incomplete.
When knowledge attempts to absolutize itself, it is attempting define
itself in infinite terms—a contradiction in terms, given the root of “define” in
the attempt to determine its fine, or boundary. It is the attempt itself—in the
expansion—in which we can see that knowledge, at any given point in time,
is inherently limited, even (or especially) in the trans-foundational context of
the unlimited. Knowledge, in these cases, is attempting to identify itself with
its engendering other and context, and, not understanding or differentiating
this, con-fusing the two in the process. And in this absolutization, as we will
see, knowledge naturally annihilates itself into the ineffable absolute, after
passing through the solipsism of its own sensory-mnemonic interface.

This rejection of any purely absolute (infinite or complete) knowledge may


be objected to, for example, by pointing out the logical contradictions of the
statement “There are no absolutes,”i¥ for to say such a thing is to negate its
own meaning as an absolute statement.
This, however, is not an example of a successful absolute statement, but
an example of a failure. The reason it fails, as should be clear, is largely
because it is self-referential and circular; it is actually a logical mobius strip,
twisting in on itself and deconstructing its own foundational tail. It is an
absolute statement against absolute statements—a line of logic and relation
turned against its primary concept, a self-deconstructing relation merely
pointing to the absolute. The fact that we can’t even seem to make a
successful absolute statement against absolutes tells us more about the
necessarily relative and limited nature of statements themselves than about
the nature of the absolute scope. The absolute scope, being the engendered
other, simply has no place within the relative world of statements,
knowledge, truths and forms—and relative concepts have no place in the
absolute scope. That is the entire point of the distinction. The absolute
scope, recall, is the self-engendered other of the relative scope, in its
(successful) attempt to find its ultimate context.
Because, in the interface model, the absolute scope has been placed fully
“outside” the real world of form—as merely an epistemic scope and
oppositional/representational context—the constant confusion between the
ontic and the absolute is no longer possible when the system is properly
embodied. The ontic, being infinite difference itself—the integrated ONE-
ALL—is fully, or infinitely relational. It is the pre-scope fusion of the
absolute and relative scopes.ii


(Fox, Foundations: A Manual for the Beginning Student of Epistemology)
ii
And moreover, confusion itself is a fully relative phenomenon. If confusion thinks it is dealing with
the absolute scope it is fundamentally mistaken. The absolute scope cannot, by oppositional
definition, partake in the relation of any contrariwise fusion.

Page | 596
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

But further, and very importantly, to say that “reality is relative” is no longer
to say that it is dependent only on the observer, but precisely the opposite.
The real is simply relational, and infinitely so. It is not fundamentally
representational or purely subjective: Truth is not relative in this purely
subjective sense. The subjective, recall, is the epistemic level of the within—
the representational level of the “I” quadrant, in AQAL theory. An atom, for
example, does not make a “purely aesthetic” judgment call (as if aesthetics
were purely subjective either) as to which atom it will conjugate a chemical
bond with. It does so based on its own intrinsic relations in its active
interfacing with the intrinsic relations of the other atoms it is “courting.” If
there is a harmonic fit it snaps into place and the bond tightens into a
greater, synergistic harmonic interface, the two now greater than the sum of
their parts.
Often times the relation of the real is between the real observer and the
real observed, in which case the triune interface between them is indeed
dependent on its polar terms, but in all cases the relative is fully real. In
Interface Epistemology, knowledge is no longer cut off from the reality
which, through its various relations and interfaces, brings it into being;
representation is no longer cut off from the field of sub-representation; and
transcendence and transitivity are no longer cut off (through the trans-bias)
from immanence. The interface which differentiates and unites them in
“real difference” is key to Interface Epistemology. This infinite difference of
immanence in the triune interface itself, as Deleuze says, affirms “the truth
of relativity”—the truth of the relation of “real difference” itself—as opposed
to “the relativity of truth.”
As Deleuze says in Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, “In short, what is
expressed everywhere intervenes as a third term that transforms dualities.
Beyond real causality, beyond ideal representation, what is expressed is
discovered as a third term that makes distinctions infinitely more real and
identity infinitely better thought. What is expressed is sense: deeper than
the relation of causality, deeper than the relation of representation.” This
“sense,” as we will shortly see, is the enfolding of meaning in the immanence
and embodiment in the evolution, embryogenesis and development of every
individual—each of which is a confluence of singularities of infinite
difference, interfacing within the unbounded confluence of external
singularities; Bounded Infinities boundlessly interfacing Bounded Infinities.

In Interface Philosophy, as we have seen, the sensory-mnemonic interface is


the very root of the epistemic and the empiric. This is the ultimate

Page | 597
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

destination of Deleuze’s cogito of the dissolved self, where the Cartesian


absolutization of representation breaks down to sensorial solipsism—and
“nihilipsism” (self annihilation) with the eradication of the self/other
distinction—and a breakdown of the project of absolute knowledge itself to
the truth of relativity. When relative knowledge seeks its absolute root, it
contracts to the immanence of the cogito, dissolving the self-other
distinction in the process, thus reversing the root-level emergence of the self
at the beginning of The Cycle of Unity.
This is how Bishop Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism ultimately collapses
into solipsism when made self-consistent and the subjective is taken to the
standards of absolute knowledge forced on the objective. This is how
Berkeley’s strangely anti-objective world-view can be lumped into the
category of Empiricism. It contracts to the cogito-interface itself, which is
the radical sensory-mnemonic root of the empirical; the same root to which
Lock and Hume are said, in a round-about way, to contract.
Indeed Berkeley and Descartes—as radical Empiricist and Rationalist—
can be seen, in a sense, as identical opposites united by a common
“Cogitism”; each—facing the specter of radical skepticism—dramatically
collapsing and dissolving into the cogito, and each calling upon an analytical
(or definitional) faith in God to restore absolute knowledge of the self-
defining other. Descartes, having affirmed for himself the personal-
subjective of the cogito ergo sum (I think therefore I am), called upon the
absolute to affirm the absolutely unseen forms of the outside world of the
objective and inter-subjective—and Berkeley, after affirming the immediacy
of the sensory interface in his esse est percipi, (to be is to be perceived) called
upon a faith in God (with a series of notoriously bad arguments) to be the
ultimate unperceived perceiver and mediator of the same objective and
inter-subjective world.

Interface Epistemology, on the other hand, recognizes and affirms the reality
of relation. This “truth of relativity” extends, therefore, to the forms of
knowledge—both objective and subjective, both mediated and immediate.
And critically, Interface Epistemology recognizes and affirms the relative
subject/object polarity and bounded sensory-mnemonic interface of the
individual itself as the very root of knowledge at the crossroads of the
orthogonal polarity of the ontic/epistemic (sub-
representation/representation). It is this cogito-root into which both
models collapse into a common epistemic-bound Cogitism.
As the Bodhidharma says, “The mind and the world are opposites, and
vision arises where they meet.” If we contract the representational world
down to the absolute knowledge of the raw sensory-mnemonic interface—
but before even the projective, pattern-recognition properties of the
mnemonic primitives and “qualia” arise—the world and the mind disappear
into the solipsistic and nihilipsistic cogito of the dissolved self.

Page | 598
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

This, recall, is the return journey in The Cycle of Unity, where the
recognition of the interface represented by the vinculum of the vision-logic
equation for the ALL — ∞/∞ — the ‘one’ boundary of finite unity on the I/T
uni-axis, along with the recognition of the unity of the ratio of immanent and
transcendent infinity (∞/∞ = ONE), returns us to the boundless ONE of
Infinite Unity, the ineffable absolute scope. This Cycle of Unity is expressed
in the vision-logic equation: ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE — as the swerving deviation
from the univocal tautology of the ONE-ALL, into the relative realm of the
bounded individual—the one and its vinculum interface—simultaneously
from both omni-directions, the infinite within of the implicit singularity and
the explicit infinity of the transcendent ONE.i* The individual cogito of the
evolved- and involved-; the unfolded- and enfolded-self is the
vinculum/interface between this infinite immanence and transcendence—
between the dark and mysterious subjectivity of yin, and the bright and
obvious objective-power of yang.

Mystic scientist and Jesuit priest Pierre Teilhard de Chardin wrote:ii¥


Is evolution a theory, a system, or a hypothesis? It is much more—it is a
general postulate to which all theories, all hypotheses, all systems must
henceforth bow and which they must satisfy in order to be thinkable and
true. Evolution is a light which illuminates all facts, a trajectory which all
lines of thought must follow—this is what evolution is.
Because evolution—in its “deep” and sub-representational form—is the very
process by which representational systems come into being, we must dig
into the very roots of this alien intelligence to truly understand the nature of
the epistemic and its triunity of: knowledge, the interface or means of
knowing, and indeed the knower, who is himself the problem-child of
evolution.
So, what is evolution? Perhaps we can start by defining what evolution is
not. Evolution is not “survival of the fittest.” That wasn’t even Darwin’s own
catch-phrase for his “natural selection.” Indeed, Darwin didn’t like the
phrase or the catch.iii So is evolution, then, defined merely by Darwin’s
proposed mechanism of natural selection? Not according to modern
“postdarwinian” evolutionary theorists, and perhaps not even according to
Darwin himself who also stressed sexual selection. As Kevin Kelly writes in
his book Out of Control:

i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
ii¥
Quoted from Kelly’s Out of Control.
iii
The phrase was invented by Herbert Spencer for his spin-off of evolution called “Social
Darwinism”.

Page | 599
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

What the postdarwinians have shown is that there is no such thing as


monolithic evolution run by one-dimensional natural selection. It would
be more fitting to say that evolution is plural and deep. Deep evolution is
an aggregate of many kinds of evolutions; it is a multifaced god, a creator
with many arms, working by many methods, of which natural selection of
variation is perhaps the most universal factor. An uncharted variety of
evolutions make up deep evolution, just as our minds comprise a society
of dimwitted agents and a variety of types of thinking. Various evolutions
proceed at different scales, at different tempos, in different styles.
Furthermore, this blend of evolutions changes over time. Certain types of
evolution were important in early protolife; some are more emphasized
now, four billion years later. One variety (natural selection) will be
ubiquitous throughout the plurality, while others will be rare and
specialized in their roles. Deep, pluralistic evolution, like intelligence, is
an emergent property of a community of dynamics.
For decades we’ve known of many other “evolutions” far more capable than
mere natural selection. Darwin himself wrote extensively on the much more
powerful sexual selection. Why then is evolution, in the mainstream of
modern culture, always defined by natural selection? Modern culture—even
academic culture, much of the time—is stuck in the evolutionary “kosmic
rut” of the “survival of the fittest,” and this rut tinges evolution with a
negative “red in tooth and claw” brutality and stupidity.
After decades of research going far beyond natural selection, to say the
word “evolution” is still to utter “survival of the fittest.” So, if we can’t mean
modern evolution when we say “evolution,” but are stuck in an 1800’s era
kosmic rut, then we must force a new definition by introducing a new term.
Enter Kevin Kelly’s “deep evolution,” where we are required to double-take,
make the distinction and flesh it out with the depth that can finally begin to
approximate the inhuman, vastly distributed and deep intelligence of
Nature. Deep, vast and sprawling evolution, we will find, is deep
intelligence—an alien immanent power of creation breaking the bonds
of the transcendent-bias that would seek to define all of creation in the
strictly anthropocentric terms of monological, representational, one-
track humanoid intelligence.

“I believe there is a mathematics of life,” says Kelly, and natural selection is


only the “additive function.”
But to fully explain the origin of life, the remarkable trend toward
complexity, and the invention of intelligence requires more than addition.
It needs a rich mathematics of complex functions built upon each other; it
needs deeper evolution. Natural selection alone is not enough, not by
miles. It must be alloyed with more creative, generative processes to
accomplish much. It must have more to naturally select from.
And through interviews, experiments and interfaces with cutting edge
evolutionary biologists, computer scientists, engineers, video-game

Page | 600
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

designers, philosophers, futurists, mathematicians, ecologists, physicists,


complexity scientists and cyberneticists, Kelly spends the bulk of Out of
Control showing us a vast range of parallel “evolutions” each of which—
virtually unknown to the outside world—is far more powerful than the
ground-level additive function of natural selection, or “shallow evolution.”
Of these “many arms” of this out-of-control “multifaced god” of evolution,
we’ll only have the time to explore the prestidigitated fugues of sexual
selection in the shallow ground-base of natural selection. This will, however,
demonstrate quite amply that deep evolution is far more intelligent and
interesting a composer than the mere rhythm-section of natural selection
would imply.

As P. D. Ouspensky wrote:
But we do not realize, do not see the presence of intelligence in the
phenomena and laws of nature. This happens because we always study
not the whole but a part, and we do not see the whole we wish to study.
But studying the little finger of a man we cannot see the intelligence of the
man. The same refers to nature. We always study the little finger of
nature. If we realize this and understand that EVERY LIFE IS THE
MANIFESTATION OF A PART OF SOME WHOLE, Only then a possibility
opens of knowing that whole. In order to know the intelligence of a given
whole, one should understand the character of that whole, and its
functions.
This core idea of evolution as a form of intelligence can be found in a long
line of eminent thinkers, from Erasmus Darwin to Samuel Butler to P. D.
Ouspensky to Alan Watts to Kevin Kelly to George Dyson—not to mention
the eastern thinkers and the countless engineers working in the trenches
with the alien distributed-intelligence of evolution first-hand to help evolve
solutions to problems unthinkable by single-track human intelligence.
Unfortunately we’ll only have time to skim a small portion of these
fascinating details.

In the human form of cognition we have an inextricably intertwined mesh of


functions. We call them, for example: consciousness, intelligence, and
wisdom. When we seek to distill these categories and functions separate
from one another, we seek their most general form. For our concerns here,
then, what is the most general and widely applicable definition of
intelligence? Perhaps intelligence can be most simply defined as the power
of “problem solving.” This is the most general function and indeed the goal
of most IQ tests, after-all. IQ tests, for example, don’t check directly for
wisdom, nor consciousness, though these can indeed feed into the resulting
IQ score. How well you can solve the problems of the IQ test—not how

Page | 601
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

conscious or how wise you are—indeed determines the power (or quotient)
of your intelligence. But it can be seen that intelligence is a form of
consciousness or wisdom, or that wisdom or consciousness is a form of
intelligence, depending only on your preference and the way your intrinsic
system of categories is already set up.
If we de-couple the ‘problem’ from its anthropocentric roots, however,
the flexibility of its definition can be extended to the more general field of
biology, and even to evolution. “Living organisms” says computer-scientist
John Holland, “are consummate problem solvers. They exhibit a versatility
that puts the best computer programs to shame.”i¥
Naturally, problem and solution form a polarity, and a problem-solver is
a solution in its own right. Indeed, sometimes problems, in another sphere,
can only be seen in light of their solutions. But where there is a solution,
there was a problem … and where there is a problem-solver there is a form
and power of intelligence—some kind of an “intelligent designer,” or
“composer,” if you will.
The question, of course, is whether this prodigious composer of profound
and preposterous proteinaceous fugues is humanoid, reptilian, vegetative,
mineral or an entirely different form altogether: perhaps an amalgam or
even an abstract principle… What kind of intelligence must it be? … and just
how intelligent, given the vast, “geological” resources of time, energy and
matter at its disposal?
The solutions to the problems hidden in the depths of evolution are the
myriad “life-forms” scattered throughout the history of life on this planet—
perhaps %99 of which are already extinct (which tells us that the death of
organisms hasn’t yet been on the list of problems for evolution to solve). We
organisms—intelligent solutions in our own right, if sometimes a bit
quirky—are the problem-children of evolution.
Evolution, the mother of invention, has the general problem of getting its
children to replicate its code. But it has another problem. Every time it
thinks it has solved a problem—firing off an organism capable of replicating
its newly invented code—the environment into which the problem-children
are injected has changed and they often can’t seem to adjust. And so the
code they would replicate dies out. Evolution, then, must continually find
new solutions to its new problems which are, by now, vastly multiplying out
of hand.

But vast multiplicity and parallelism is evolution’s strong suit. Its


exponentially-replicating problem-children are its very solutions. Indeed,


Quoted in Kelly, Out of Control

Page | 602
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

this is what gives evolution its inhuman power of creation. It multiplies its
code in billions of billions of variations at once, and those that survive to
reproduce are already successful while the rest, unneeded, are forgotten.
Evolution is a “differential reproductive success”—a shotgun creationism;
the madness of a method exploding into a billion-billion sub-processes, each
one a new trajectory tunneling into the dark space of biological possibility.
Kelly writes:
Parallelism is one of the ways around the inherent stupidity and
blindness of random mutations. It is the great irony of life that a mindless
act repeated in sequence can only lead to greater depths of absurdity,
while a mindless act performed in parallel by a swarm of individuals can,
under the proper conditions, lead to all that we find interesting.
This is indeed why engineering is increasingly turning to “evolutionary
algorithms” as an interface between the limits of single-minded human
engineers and the alien, distributed, vastly-parallel intelligence of deep
evolution. The novel solutions emerging from this computational interface
of simulated evolution tend to be far beyond the capabilities of humans to
engineer, let alone even to understand. Kelly writes:
What humans can’t engineer, evolution can. [Tom] Ray puts it nicely as he
shows off a monitor with traces of the 22s propagating in his soup: “It
seems utterly preposterous to think that you could randomly alter a
computer program and get something better than what you carefully
crafted by hand, but here’s living proof.” It suddenly dawns on the
observer that there is no end to the creativity that these mindless hackers
can come up with.
Evolution is indeed a form of distributed intelligence and creativity quite
alien to the single-minded approach of human consciousness.i At best, we
can sit atop and harness the vast parallelism of our brain-cells in an intuited
spark which seems to come from nowhere, but it is difficult for us to grasp
the raw power—and the products—of this alien intelligence which brought
us into being, and whose unconscious goals and desires still course through
our own veins.

While evolution is increasingly an interface for engineering, the inverse is


also true. Engineered or simulated evolution is increasingly an interface for
understanding and expanding evolution, as the two intelligences feed back
into each other at ever higher levels of sophistication. Kelly continues:
Perhaps the most astounding thing about Tom Ray’s electrically powered
evolution machine is that it created sex. Nobody told it about sex, but it
found it nonetheless. In an experiment to see what would happen if he

i
For a brilliant and fun exploration of the intelligence of evolution see George Dyson’s book Darwin
Among the Machines.

Page | 603
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

turned the mutation function off, Ray let the soup run without deliberate
error. He was flabbergasted to discover that even without programmed
mutation, evolution pushed forward.
The fact that evolution—after inventing its own sex games—pushes forward
even in the absence of random mutations, empirically informs evolutionary
biologists that sex is a powerful addition to the arsenal of deep evolution.
To scientists, the most exhilarating news to come out of Ray’s artificial
evolution machine is that his small worlds display what seems to be
punctuated equilibrium. For relatively long periods of time, the ratio of
populations remain in a steady tango of give and take with only the
occasional extinction or birth of a new species. Then, in a relative blink,
this equilibrium is punctuated by a rapid burst of roiling change with
many newcomers and eclipsing of the old. For a short period change is
rampant. Then things sort out and stasis and equilibrium reigns again.

As Tom Ray witnessed first-hand, evolution evolves, and to even greater


depth with the invention of sex. Like Ray, John Holland too has
experimented with computer sex: rather, he invented it. Instead of waiting
for them to discover it themselves, Holland plugged sex into his genetic
algorithms (GAs) from the start. Kelly writes:
In real natural life, sex is a much more important source of variation than
mutations. Sex, at the conceptual level, is genetic recombination -- a few
genes from Dad and a few genes from Mom combined into a new genome
for Junior. …
Mating rather than mutating was discovered by theoretical biologists
in the early 1960s to make a more robust computer evolution -- one that
birthed a higher ratio of sensible entities. But sexual mating alone was too
restrictive in what it could come up with. In the mid-1960s Holland
devised his GAs; these relied chiefly on mating and secondarily on
mutation as a background instigator. With sex and mutation combined,
the system was both flexible and wide.
In deep evolution, sex and mutation work hand in hand. The sprawling
randomness of mutation allows sex to escape its kosmic ruts—jumping
dead-end routines into new kosmic grooves—while sex rapidly optimizes
these new shotgun trajectories and functions by feeding back its intelligent
selection into the mix. Kelly writes:
In Holland’s scheme, the highest performing bits of code anywhere on the
landscape mate with each other. Since high performance increases the
assigned rate of mating in that area, this focuses the attention of the
genetic algorithm system on the most promising areas in the overall
landscape. It also diverts computational cycles away from unpromising
areas. Thus parallelism sweeps a large net over the problem landscape

Page | 604
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

while reducing the number of code strings that need manipulating to


locate the peaks.
This function whereby the highest-performing algorithms mate at an
increasing rate, mimics the function of sexual selection. In real life it is often
the most “successful” organisms—such as the dominant male of a
population—that get the most chances to mate. This massive multiplicity
and parallelism, optimized by sexual selection and gene-combination, can
find solutions to vastly complex problems that humans can’t even define,
locate or properly understand.
The evolutionary approach, Holland wrote, “eliminates one of the greatest
hurdles in software design: specifying in advance all the features of a
problem.” Anywhere you have many conflicting, interlinked variables and
a broadly defined goal where the solutions may be myriad, evolution is
the answer.
Just as evolution deals in populations of individuals, genetic
algorithms mimic nature by evolving huge churning populations of code,
all processing and mutating at once. GAs are swarms of slightly different
strategies trying to simultaneously hill-climb over a rugged landscape.
Because a multitude of code strings “climb” in parallel, the population
visits many regions of the landscape concurrently. This ensures it won’t
miss the Big Peak.
Implicit parallelism is the magic by which evolutionary processes
guarantee you climb not just any peak but the tallest peak. How do you
locate the global optima? By testing bits of the entire landscape at once.
How do you optimally balance a thousand counteracting variables in a
complex problem? By sampling a thousand combinations at once. How do
you develop an organism that can survive harsh conditions? By running a
thousand slightly varied individuals at once.

In the evolution of life on this planet there is a tell-tale sign of the power of
an evolutionary function: The faster the pace of change the greater the
power (or intelligence) of the function behind it. For the first few billion
years of evolution—based perhaps mainly on the function of cellular
division and random mutation—the history of change moved at a snail’s
pace. It hardly budged from one point in time to the next…and it left a slimy
trail.
Then, at only around 500 million years ago—perhaps already 4 billion
years into this languishing, monotonous, barely-intelligent cycle—occurred
a biological “Big-Bang” (pardon the pun). This is the “Cambrian explosion”
where, in the geological blip of perhaps merely 10 million years, all the body
plans of the subsequent biological eras were evolved. So, after four billion
years, evolution suddenly picked up its pace, exploding from single-cells into
the sprawling possibilities of multi-celled organisms and body-plans.

Page | 605
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

What changed? Kelly, tells us that the Cambrian explosion occurred just
after the invention of sexual reproduction, perhaps about the time it takes
for real-world eukaryotic sex to work its hill-climbing magic on dull
mutation. It took about 500 million years to reach the knee of the
exponential curve, but when it did — POW! — this magic finally exploded
from single-celled organisms into myriad modes of multicellular monsters,
injecting their own exponentially increasing intelligence into the exploration
of this vastly unfolding space of multi-cellular possibilities.i A fantastic
menagerie of forms of intelligence was now at the disposal of natural
selection and deep evolution.
In sex, recall (if your lucky), rather than merely going off in a corner and
replicating by yourself—actually dividing yourself in half—there is an
interfacing or union of two organisms to create a third. But recall from your
fortunate and romantic courtship all the energy of intelligence (both
conscious and unconscious) that went into the endless quest, the
intermittent battles and the final decision of with whom to mate—you
weren’t prepared to mate with just anybody, right? The same is true, but at a
smaller scale with the early organisms who first began to experiment with
sex.
Sexual reproduction opens a space for sexual selection, and sexual
selection harnesses the intrinsic intelligence of the organism in solving the
problem of with whom to interface. Sex itself is a medium for intelligent
design, much more powerful than mere random mutation, and we can see its
effects directly in the often bizarre sexual dimorphisms of its unwitting
participants…which includes us. Every time we have sex, we are
participating in the higher-level intelligence of evolution, because we have
injected our own intelligence into this program and passion for selective
bonding and breeding. Sexual selection, then, is a feedback “mechanism”
magnifying the intelligence of natural selection and the other mechanisms of
pre-sexual evolution.
If natural selection is the “additive function” in the mathematics of life,
then sexual selection is its “recursive function.”

Deep evolution is a form of intelligent design—a shotgun creationism.


And this recognition of evolution itself as an “intelligent designer” is the
nondual “judo move” in the “Evolution vs. Intelligent Design” debate.
Transcendent-biased—top-down—Creationism has no sole claim to

i
The Cambrian explosion occurred around 500 million years after the invention of sex. Because the
intelligence power of sexual selection is indeed dependent on the intelligence power of its
participants, then one would expect that its power would increase exponentially as it starts feeding
back into itself its new powers. It then perhaps took around 500 million years to reach the bend of
the knee of this curve.

Page | 606
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

“intelligent design,” when Intelligence can be explained from the bottom-


up—from the immanence, emergence and vast multiplicity of a problem-
solving capability alien to our transcendent-biased single-track exoteric
forms of consciousness. Evolutionary intelligence ramps up in IQ from the
additive function of mutation and “the survival of the fittest” into the
recursive function of sexual selection and “the survival of the sexiest,” to put
it crudely, where the intelligence of the organism is injected back into the
intelligence of evolution. And this feedback process gets stronger and
stronger the more and more intelligent the organism feeding back into the
process that brought it into being.

Through the mouthpiece of “Golem XIV,” a fictional, super-intelligent,


government-owned, war-computer turned philosopher—Stanislaw Lem, in
his book Imaginary Magnitudes, pronounces, “You will come to know that
the code [DNA] is a member of the technolinguistic family, the causative
languages that make the word into all possible flesh … “ DNA is a code that
translates directly, causally, or emergently into the “technology” of the
organism, rather than into or through the representational level of
semantics or meaning. The “meaning” of the causative language is the
artifact (or organism) which it generates, just like the meaning of the source
code is the program or application which boots up into memory. As Golem
proclaims, “THE MEANING OF THE TRANSMITTER IS THE TRANSMISSION.”i
Golem XIV declares that life emerged through the “negative gradient” of a
causative language which imperfectly replicates itself through its creations.
“IN EVOLUTION, A NEGATIVE GRADIENT OPERATES IN THE PERFECTING
OF STRUCTURAL SOLUTIONS.” It is negative, in Golem XIV’s mind, not only
because of its imperfect replication, but also because evolution “cares” not
for its creations, and only for the code. Another negative aspect is that life
moves from feeding on the “pure” energy of the star (photosynthesis), and

i
Indeed, as we’d expect from a true polarity, though Lem’s meaning is clearly intended as “The
meaning of the organism is the code,” it’s hard to really or ultimately pin down which is the
transmitter and which the transmission; the organism or the code. Does evolution transmit its
meaning into its organisms as code, or does the organism transmit its deepest meaning through
reproduction of the code? Of course this breaks down into “mere” semantics…

Page | 607
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

begins feeding on itself—cannibalizing in ever wider cycles of recursion—i.e.


the “food chain”.
Because evolution “cares” only for its code, it did not attempt to solve the
problem of organismic death. But then again, evolution proceeds in waves
transcending-and-including each other into higher and higher powers, from
mutation to sexual reproduction and into culture and beyond—creating ever
more intelligent and powerful creations along the way. Evolution has now
entered its phase of “auto-evolution,” as Lem terms it—evolution self-put to
the task of deliberately evolving itself. Mankind, now taking control of
evolution, has its own newly emergent problems and goals, and the
predicament of “natural death” or senescence is indeed being unraveled as
we speak.
As we have seen, it was this imperfect replication itself—this mutability—
which was the initial creative, learning and intelligent function of the code.
A perfect linguistic replication can never make mistakes and can never learn.
It can never create or solve problems, but can merely recapitulate itself to
eternity. In this “negative gradient”—from a sterile, immutable Eden into
the fecund Earth of continual creation—evolutionary intelligence has
“fallen.”
But critically, for our purposes DNA is a causative mnemonics; a living,
breathing, replicating language of memory. This “imperfect” memory
allowed the first level of geologically slow creativity and intelligence to
emerge. Sexual reproduction and selection, on the other hand, can’t so easily
be seen as merely a failed causative and replicative language, but rather a
successful collaboration between two organisms to bring about a new one.
But not only that. It is a collaboration and a communication between
organisms and their code. An intelligent cultivating third, interfacing
between two of its own intelligences, injecting their combined intelligence
back into the evolutionary stream of creation which engendered their
communicative dance in the first place.

Stepping back to look at the whole of life on Earth, we see it evolving within
the thin interface and atmosphere of the planet. We know that life
penetrates or emerges from this interface at depths and heights which to us
are difficult to imagine, but in relation to the earth, life is concentrated
within a thin film of atmosphere, hydrosphere and lithosphere, whose depth
may be rightly compared to the thickness of the skin of an apple.i Indeed, we
can again see the interface as key when we reflect that this living cosmic
membrane occurs precisely at the boundary between the “order” of the

i
… or with the “deep hot biosphere” perhaps the depth of an orange peel. (see Thomas Gold)

Page | 608
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

frigid reaches of interstellar space and the “chaos” of the molten core of the
earth, both of which are hostile to life, yet at their enfolding and unfolding
interface, life flourishes. Life itself is a cultivated/cultivating third, on this
“third rock from the sun.” i
Stepping back yet again, we see life emerging at another interface, the
“sweet spot” or “habitable zone” of the temperature gradient of the
planetary orbit of the earth, just close enough to the sun for life to evolve
through the benefit of photosynthesis, and just far enough away for those
life-forms to avoid burning up.

So the relative interface of experience, memory and knowledge can be seen


in the visceral and vivid terms of the evolution of life itself as it begins to
encode the results of its interactions—its “experiences”—into the embodied
genetic code and memory of its organisms. These “genetic memories”—
through the causative language of DNA, and protein expression—recall and
recount only those successes in the game of life. But these genetic
recollections, causatively expressed into cycles of living replicating
organisms, are the very rudiments of our mnemonic primitives. They
are the genetic-mnemonic primitives where the memory of the chain of
successes of evolution is directly or causally encoded into the organism at
the very beginnings of the emergence of knowledge, intelligence, rationality,
and experience (empiricism)—long before representation has dreamed
itself into unfolding.
Through natural and sexual selection, the story of life is ever told anew
by its victors, but it is told directly and immediately in the causative
language of DNA. This causative language, now injecting its selections back
into the deep evolutionary stream of creation, is part of the feedback or
“sensation” of “what works” in the game of life—and by absence of a vote,
what doesn’t. Without this additive function of natural selection and the
recursive function of sexual selection there is no “sensation” or feedback of
any gradient into greater and greater function and intelligence, and thus no
evolution.

And naturally, we can see this purely positive reinforcement of the living
story of evolution—told only by its victors—as a form of the familiar
Deleuzian intensive forces, arising from the immanent, sub-representational
level of the causative language of evolution. The intelligence of evolution

i
It is, of course, just a coincidence that the earth is the “third rock” or node from the sun. Indeed, it
is very likely only the third visible node from the sun. Let us not break down into numerology, but
remain in the power and embrace of logic and causation.

Page | 609
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

itself functions on the intensive forces of this purely positive feedback. The
intensive forces of the “additive” and recursive functions of natural and
sexual selection—informing and re-injecting evolution only with its
successes—is the very rudiments of evolutionary sensation, and it is
naturally coupled with the rudiments of memory in the genetic code. As this
ever renewing tale is directly “memorized” (encoded) and expressed in the
causative language of DNA, it echoes, recapitulates and unfolds into the very
embryogenesis of its creations.

Strangely, but as we may by now expect, the new direction in cellular biology
directly supports an Interface Philosophy or Epistemology of emergent
intelligence, creativity and knowledge. Cellular biology is indeed moving
away from the idea that the cellular nucleus is the driving intelligence or
“brain” of the cell, and toward the notion that the intelligence is actually
found in the outer cellular membrane itself; the interface where primitive
sensation and its encoded reactions (rudimentary genetic-mnemonic
primitives) takes place.
This new idea is reinforced by numerous experiments that show that a
cell can live a virtually normal, active and reactive existence long after its
nucleus has been removed. In this new direction in biological science, the
nucleus of the cell now mainly serves the function of reproduction—doing
the “dirty work” of the slower and distributed intelligence of evolution. The
nucleus, in short, is not the brain of the cell, but its gonad—its genetic or
long-term memory—and these experiments have basically created a bunch
of cellular eunuchs.i
So there a shift in biology to the idea of the interface as the driving
intelligence of primitive life-forms; the code or genetic memory remains
safely tucked away in the core—in the gonads—while the cutting edge of
intelligence and active memory unfolds, enfolds, acts and reacts largely at
the interface between the within and without of the cell. As Bruce Lipton
states, in his article Fractal Evolution, ii ¥ “The membrane boundary
enveloping each biological cell comprises the structural basis of a biological
processor system…. As a processor, the cell’s membrane receptors scan the
environment for signals. … the specificity of reception that is characteristic
for each receptor … enables it to distinguish its complementary signal out of
all the jumbled ambient noise.”

i
… or else—if we have unintentionally reversed this polarity—perhaps our own gonads are the
proper brains of us “higher” forms of life. Gonads are “deep brains” or the brains (or perhaps
merely the nerve cells) transcended-and-included in the vast, slow and alien distributed intelligence
of evolution.
ii¥
(Lipton PhD.)

Page | 610
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

“The profound point of this discourse,” Lipton continues, is that


“...biological awareness is a measurable property, and is directly correlated
with the surface area of the cell’s membrane.” Indeed, Lipton demonstrates
that cells even have the capability to learn and acquire new senses. He says:
… each bacterium is also capable of learning about six additional
environmental “signals.” For example, a bacterium may acquire the
ability to resist an antibiotic introduced into the environment. It does this
by creating a surface receptor that binds and inhibits the molecules of the
antibiotic. The new receptor is fundamentally the equivalent of a protein
“antibody” that our immune cells create to neutralize an invasive antigen.
The creation of a new receptor, by definition, implies that there must be a
new gene created to remember the amino acid code for that protein. In
bacteria, these “new” memory genes are present as tiny circles of DNA
called plasmids. The plasmids are not physically attached to cell’s
heredity-providing chromosome and float freely in the cytoplasm.
Bacteria are capable of creating an average of about six different plasmids,
each derived from a unique learning ‘experience.’ The limitation on the
number of plasmids the cell possesses is not due to an inability to make
DNA. For the bacterium can make thousands of copies of any of the
individual plasmids it possesses. The limitations must be related to the
fact that each “new” protein perception complex requires a unit of surface
area to express its functions. The inability to expand its membrane (i.e.,
surface area) limits the bacterium’s ability to acquire new perceptions
(awareness).
There is indeed a clear coupling here between the membrane, and cellular
awareness and intelligence, or the cell’s ability to recognize and solve
problems such as those pertaining to survival and replication of its central
code.
Lipton also shows that the limitations of the individual learning
capabilities of a single organism (based on the limiting surface area of its
membrane) lead to collective learning behavior among groups of bacteria.
This sharing and pooling of knowledge resources is arguably an early form
of culture.
The more awareness the greater the ability to survive. Limitations upon
individuals increasing their awareness, led to bacteria living in loosely
knit communities. If an individual bacterium can “learn” six facts about
the environment, than a hundred bacteria are collectively capable of
being aware of 600 facts. Bacteria developed mechanisms to transfer
copies of their plasmids to other bacteria in the community. By
transferring copies of their “learned” DNA, they share their “awareness”
with the community. Bacteria can transfer a plasmid to another
individual. The recipient bacterium can use the donated plasmids
“awareness” during its life, but generally can not pass copies of the
plasmid on to its daughter cell progeny.
Indeed, Lipton shows that it is through this communication that organized
groups of cells began to create communities with differentiated functions.

Page | 611
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

These new organizations naturally create a new membrane, a “bio-film


matrix” around the community as a whole in order to control the internal
environment in opposition to the external, and to expand the differentiation,
sensation and awareness capabilities of the membrane. This creates a
second order of homeostatic function and a second order of organism. As
Lipton states, “It was the origin of multicellular organisms that represented
an alternative way to expand the membrane surface area (i.e., awareness
potential) beyond the limitations of the single cell.” Lipton goes on:
Consider that surface area relationship in regard to vertebrate brain
evolution. First vertebrate brains are small, smooth spheres. As one
ascends the evolutionary ladder, the brains become larger and more
surface area is subsequently derived from infoldings of the brains surface
that produce the characteristic sulci (grooves) and gyri (folds) of more
advanced brains. Interestingly, when considering awareness in terms of
brain surface, humans are in second place since porpoise and dolphin
brains have a larger surface area.

Even further, in the embryogenesis of the “higher” forms of life, it is the


interface—the “ectoderm,” or outer-layer of the growing embryo—which
transforms into the nervous system, the sensory organs and the brain. So,
given Haeckel’s law that ontogeny recapitulates phylogeny,i there seems to
be good empirical evidence of cognition (intelligence, consciousness and
representation) as emergent at or from the interface—from primitive, pre-
representational life to its higher and higher sentient forms. And recall that
Haeckel’s law is a natural feature of any transcend-and-include holarchical
emergence, such as the “embryogenesis of the concept.” The holonic
interface, then, is fundamental not only to perspective, but also to
perception, intelligence and consciousness itself.

In the nondual traditions, such as ancient Taoism and Buddhism, touch is


considered the fundamental sense; the direct and directional, soft and
forceful, pressurized interface of awareness between self and other (singular
and plural). This sense of touch can be found at the very root of the “tree” of
life in perhaps all single-celled organisms. These “mechano-sensing”
organisms exhibit what is called mechanotaxis, where they are observed to
respond and move (taxi) in reaction to the changes in pressure, rigidity or
solidity in their environment.

i
…i.e. the entire evolutionary chain of development leading to the specific individual is echoed in its
very own embryogenesis…

Page | 612
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

In the evolutionary embryogenesis of sensation, as would be expected,


we can see a differentiation and integration of this rudimentary sense of
touch into the higher levels of complexity required of the higher senses.
Taste, for example, can be seen as a modification of touch (though this may
have occurred the other way around, or simultaneously) in the immanent
direction, toward the encoding of the distinctions between the effects of
different molecules as they touch the various receptors on the cellular
membranes of single-celled organisms (or specialized receptor cells in
multicellular ones). Taste is merely touch at the molecular level.
The receptors on the generations of cellular membranes “learn” through
the “intelligent design” of evolution how to detect which molecules will do
them good and which will do them harm. Through the emergent intelligence
of evolution, the fruits of these interactions are encoded and “memorized” in
the genetic code of the cell which originates its individual structure and
which it passes down to its offspring. In cellular differentiation and
individual cellular development, this code interfaces with the particularities
of the inter-cellular molecular medium and “expresses” itself into proteins
which encode its membrane with the intelligence to know, and, in a sense,
remember which molecules will be beneficial to let into its interior and
which ones will be harmful and should be excluded. In different chemical
environments, different genes and proteins are expressed (genetic nature in
symbiosis with protein expression and environmental nurture) and we end
up with different types of cells with different intelligent-sensory membrane
functions, actively including and excluding different molecular milieu.
Through the unfolding wisdom of evolution, this rudimentary sensory-
intelligence and genetic memory of the cellular interface gets more and more
complex to the point that the cell now can “detect” and move in response to
chemical gradients across its surface as a whole. This is chemotaxis, a
sensory-effector reflex function common to a great number of species of
cells. In essence, the cellular membrane at this level is, among other things, a
great and simple spheroidal tongue or nose, tasting or smelling its
environment and moving toward the “tasty” and away from the “smelly.”
As cells band together, they begin to encode, communicate and express
functions in the context of a higher organism, and the intelligent functions
move, generally, to the periphery of this collection as the possibilities for
awareness have expanded.i We see this in the fact that the cells of the
ectoderm of the embryo differentiate into the nervous system and brain of
the higher forms of life. And this is indeed to be expected, given that it is the
surface at which the reaction and interaction of intelligence is generally
needed.

i
It takes a mere chemical gradient in the embryonic medium to differentiate the zygote into a front
and back, given the expressivity of the genetic code in response to the environment, though there is
much more complexity involved in this interaction.

Page | 613
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

As we move into more and more complex life-forms with ever more
complex sensory-effector appendages, it is a straight-forward matter to
differentiate the sense of touch into its higher forms, such as the refinements
and distinctions between smell and taste. These newly evolved and
specialized appendages allow the further evolution of the active (sensor-
effector) participation of the organism in sensory-mnemonic interaction
with its environment, such as the function of the highly-sensate hand in the
evolution of man, the tool-maker. In the higher organisms, these
rudimentary functions become more and more localized into highly evolved
appendages; differentiating islands of skin and muscle enfolding and
unfolding the sensory-mnemonic, sensor-effector active intelligence of
evolution.i
In this way, the sense of taste is differentiated from the global ambient
chemo-sensation of smell. Smell, and the appendage of the nose, seems to be
the islanded and evolved variant of this basic sensation of ambient chemical
signatures, while the tongue becomes a more active and controlled
appendage for direct chemo-sensation and tactile manipulation, not of the
ambient fluid or air, but actively directed toward differentiating, interfacing
and sometimes manipulating the chemical and mechanical properties of
various surfaces.
Hearing, as well, is a direct differentiation of the mechano-sensation
found at the most rudimentary cellular levels. At the advanced levels of the
pattern recognition in higher organisms, the detection of types of
repetitions, or frequencies become encoded and memorized in the genes and
expressed in the intricacies of the organs of sound. These organs transcend-
and-include cells that—like the single-celled organism—react to direct
mechanical stimulation. These cells, however, are now highly specialized,
reacting in a highly specific electro-chemical fashion, and the mechanical
stimulus is now highly amplified by the surrounding structure of the

i
On a side note, this active intelligence of evolution, which requires no forethought, but acts in such
a way as to solve problems difficult, if not impossible, in any other fashion, is the rudimentary
embodiment of the principle of non-action found in ancient Taoism. The indwelling intelligence of
evolution, of the body, is the Tao, “the way,” in its yin, feminine or immanent aspect, transcended-
and-included in the higher, more transcendent forms of life, intelligence, knowledge and
consciousness. An explicit goal of Taoism, as we have seen, is to get beyond the intrinsic
transcendent- or yang-bias (“all things have their back to the yin…”) and tap into the immanence
and wisdom of yin.
We can transpose this goal directly into the operationalization of yin as it is expressed in the
immanent biological intelligence of evolution itself in everyday action, and to let thoughts arise in
the context of this deeper and wider intelligent function; the “wisdom” of evolution, spanning
geological ages and the globe itself. The Tao is in opposition, in a representational sense, to the
transcend-and-negate attitude that excludes bodily intelligence and intuitive action; and in parallel,
it is in opposition to the use of concept in such a way that excludes or negates the percepts and
intuitions which brought it, often unconsciously and symbiogenetically (rather than foundationally
or reductionistically), into being.

Page | 614
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

acoustic organs. But the basic sense of touch clearly still exists at the very
root of the specialized sensation of hearing in higher organisms.
Sight too can be seen as a modification of touch, with specific pigments in
specialized cells absorbing and reacting to the effects of being touched or
impacted by certain frequencies of light waves (or “photons”) emitted or
reflected by other surfaces. These cells are now highly specialized and
arranged in organized arrays, with long specialized appendages called axons,
collectively transmitting their massively parallel messages into optic nerves
winding directly into the specialized optic regions of the brain.
But, once again, touch is at the very root of the sensation. Indeed, the
sense of sight can be seen as the extended interface of touch, whose critical
distance and simultaneous detail (to near quantum levels) is afforded and
mediated by the great speed and fidelity of light waves, emitted, reflected or
refracted through the surfaces and membranes of other creatures or
structures in the environment. Without that touch of the “photon” with the
pigment—and the intelligent sensory-mnemonic interface it affords—there
would be no sight.

To further plumb the depths of the nature of the “knower” or the self, we can
tease apart the evolution of self-hood in terms of a critical polarity at the
very heart of embodiment and active intelligence itself: that between sensor
and effector (e.g. sensory and motor neurons). The self, as a homeostatic
function of active evolutionary intelligence, can naturally be seen to evolve
from the cellular interface as well, and we’ll see that as the self interface
emerges, complexifies and “thickens up,” this sensor-effector polarity
spreads, differentiates, integrates and complexifies as well, indeed, as two
aspects in the very same process.
The evolutionary self expands as an “aperture,” in a sense, actively taking
in, processing and reacting to larger and larger amounts of information. But
even as this bounded interface gets larger in scale—from the radius of a
cellular membrane to the extended radius of the limits of the human senses,
skin and brain—much more to the point it expands in thickness and
complexity. It’s not so much like an expanding balloon, but an expanding
spongy and convoluted surface getting thicker and thicker as it unfolds into
more and more complexity needed to process and integrate ever more
information—much more information than can be accommodated by the
merely mechanical reflexes seen with the thin cellular membrane.
It is critical, however, to understand this sensor-effector polarity not
simply in terms of the I/T uni-axis and its spheroidal/bounded interface,
because neither sensor nor effector exists solely on one or the other side of
the interface-boundary of the organism. It’s a much more complex and
abstract polarity. Rather than a simple spatial polarity, sensor/effector is a

Page | 615
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

polarity of function, similar to our input/output polarity in Interface


Mathematics.i And like a true polarity, there is no sensation without
actuation or manipulation. Indeed, the entire reason for being of sensation
is to effect changes in the organism and/or environment to maintain
homeostasis and continued organismic growth. Indeed this coupled
behavior is exactly how we can tell that the early single-celled organisms
“sense” anything at all:ii they move directly in response to it (e.g. chemo- and
mechano-taxis).
And so we can see in the very rudiments of cellular evolution the
interfacing between “behaviorism” and the “subjectivity” which the extreme
versions absolutely ruled out. Without sensation—which emerges at the
higher levels into the more complex forms of representation—there can be
no intelligence to effect and inform complex behavior. And indeed, without
the possibility and actuality of early reflex forms of behavior coupled to
sensation, there would be no reason and feedback mechanism for sensation
to evolve. As might be quickly intuited, this is a corollary to our
symbiogenesis of subject and object.
At the level of the single-celled organism (and indeed even as that
organism is enfolded into a multicellular function in the higher organisms),
this coupling between sensor and effector is much tighter and it amounts to
a nearly machinic reflex. As Bruce Lipton states, “… in the membrane
processor, the BITs are represented by receptor/effector complexes.” The
intelligence of a cell is directly encoded from sensor to effector in extremely
direct reflexes. This occurs, as we have seen, mainly in the cellular
membrane or interface. As we move into more and more complex
organisms the interface itself gets more and more complex to the point
that—with the multi-celled organisms, where entire cells are specialized
into sensors vs. effectors (sensory vs. motor neurons)—there appear whole
networks of cells between them, modulating and complexifying this input-
output response.

i
…and so we might have called this sensor-effector polarity the “sepol,” had this polarity played a
more ubiquitous role in this section. Indeed, that’s the shorthand used in writing this work, but the
word-processor automatically replaces “sepol" with “sensor-effector polarity” so it not encumber
the user with infrequently used new vocabulary.
ii
…insofar as we can stretch our definition of sensation to this rudimentary level…

Page | 616
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Figure 89: The Self-Aperture and Sensor-Effector Polarity:


The “thickness” or complexity of the self-system boundary on the
immanent/transcendent uni-axis can be seen as directly coupled to the sensor -effector
polarity in that the more complex the chains of sensation and effectuation the more
and more information and complexity the self can take in, process and output to
survival or creative endeavors.

So we can see the interface of organismic intelligence and awareness itself


evolving, expanding and thickening, from the most primitive level of a direct
sensor-effector coupling in the cellular membrane—where the sensors are
directly coupled as reflexes to the effectors, opening up ion channels or
moving the cytoskeleton, for example—to the vastly complex processing
that in the higher animals can be diverted into layers of memory and
representation, often circumventing the global-level sensor-effector
networks (reflexes) themselves, and diverting this energy into far less
obvious and tangible processes like emotions, thoughts, plans, theories, and
externally or empirically manifesting only as effects like galvanic skin
response and dilation of the pupils. (See Figure 89, above.)
But we can see these vastly complex sensor-effector networks
themselves being composed of smaller-scale sensor-effector polarities. The
neuron itself is a sensor-effector polarity. The dendrites are the specialized
senses (some specializing for different neurotransmitters or patterns of
stimulation, for example) and the axon is the specialized effector,
responding to the sensed stimulus by effecting an electrical-chemical
response to its neighbors. In this way, the inner processing of the brain is

Page | 617
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

filled with micro-senses made of self-similar networks of sensor-effector


polarities that only emerge at a much higher level into the often vague
sensations of feelings, memories or very clear conscious thoughts or
directives. Consciousness, then, is an internal “meta-sense,” integrating the
variously differentiated micro-senses, both internally and externally
coupled.
This is the evolution of representation as a direct function of the self-
similar embodiment found in this most primitive of couplings between
sensor and effector.

From the genetic rudiments of the sensory-mnemonic primitives, we can


trace a lineage from the encoded and memorized sensor-effector pattern-
recognition functions of the cellular membrane—the rudimentary sensory-
mnemonic interface—to the symbiogenesis of subject and object at the level
of representation. And, with the collectivization of the cells into the higher
organisms, we can trace the recapitulation of the phylogeny—or the
evolutionary sequence of the organism—in its ontogeny or embryogenesis
as it replays the evolutionary transformation of the sensory-mnemonic
cellular membrane into the ectoderm and outer-membrane of the embryo,
as the membrane now takes on the transcended-and-included life of the
nervous system and brain of the organism.
This whole sequence of evolutionary embodiment and interplay between
sensation, memory and active effectuation—from the causative language of
genetics into the mnemonic primitives of representation—is the starting
point which must be transcended-and-included, in its entirety, if we are to
understand the origination and embodiment of meaning or intentionality
itself.
In this pre-rational world of modern academia, the transcendent- and
representational-bias is rampant. We conscious beings naturally begin in
this transcendent place of representation, having evolved from such a depth
and into such great heights. It is only natural, therefore, that the beginning
stages of knowledge and conceptualization will project into concept the
transcendence that it, and we, have come to embody. Indeed this projection
stems from the very nature of pattern recognition in the mnemonic
primitives themselves. Conceptualization and psychological projection is a
transcended-and-included extension of the pattern-recognition game which
began with the mnemonic primitives (and the genetic mnemonics before it),
encoding sensory memories and re-activating them in the very act of
perception, differentiating our experience into the blooming and buzzing of
consciousness itself.

Page | 618
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

This primitive pattern-recognition game is the very context and


background of the infant, transcended-and-included into the ubiquitous
background of the consciousness of the individual. It is the vastly-parallel
“what-it-is-like” quality (“qualia”) of embodied experience itself, which
cannot be fully transmitted by the impoverished and highly simplified
generalizations of the higher forms of conceptual (mimetic or
representational) language. Embodiment in the development process—
which transcends-and-includes the whole intelligent complex of evolution
itself in the genetic primitives and causal-language of the physical organism
and its instincts, and in the mnemonic primitives of the learned sensory
interfaces—is the very core of meaning and “intentionality,” as it gets
abstracted and encoded into the higher and higher mimetic and
representational forms of transmission in our language.

The attendant reader will have noticed, by now, a bit of ambiguity


surrounding the ideas (“concepts”) of percept and concept. This is because
concept is often defined (usually tacitly) at a higher level of complexity than
percept. And it is defined at a higher level, generally, because the powers
and complexity of our conceptual faculties (e.g. the cerebral cortex), for the
most part, have outstripped the powers and complexity of our inherent
perceptual faculties (e.g. our eyes)—although we have now radically evolved
our perceptual faculties through the techno-evolution of such “paradigms”i
as the micro-scope and the telescope, as well as our extension into the outer
and inner reaches of the various spectrums of sight and sound—i.e. into
infra-red and ultraviolet as well as infrasound and ultrasound, respectively.
As we have seen, however, in the section on “the symbiogenesis of
subject and object,” (p531) the division between percept and concept can—
and very often is—most simply understood as the externally and internally
directed faculties of the imagination, respectively. Indeed, we will find that
concept and percept unfold and enfold, at all levels of human development,
in a perfect symbiogenesis: each one informs and engenders the
development of the other. They emerge in a “structural coupling,” as
Maturana and Varela put it. But as concept begins to rise above its
symbiogenetic grounding and coupling in percept we can make a
preliminary distinction between the more primitive and these higher-level
concepts. This distinction, then, would be based on the “point” of the
gradient at which the complexity of concept outstrips or transcends that of

i
According to Ken Wilber, in the original Khunian sense, the term “paradigm” referred to any
scientific instrument that allowed the observation of new realms of empirical fact. In this sense,
perception itself—in each of its various modes—is a paradigm.

Page | 619
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

its coupled percept. As a start, we could call them percept-concepts vs.


abstract concepts.
The concept of time, for example, seems fundamentally inherent in
human consciousness, but in its embryogenesis there is no point at which we
can de-couple the concept of time from the perception of duration, and even
deeper into the experience of evolutionary intelligence with the forms of
duration.

We have already seen the symbiogenesis of the rational and the empirical in
the pure-relational and categorical context of the holarchical unfolding and
embryogenesis of mathematics. i * This symbiogenesis unfolds in the
coupling between the empirically-derived geometry of the numerical
identities as boundaries, with their unfolding into the logic and rationality of
the noun-verb, identity-operations of arithmetic. We also saw a glimpse of
how this coupling between empirically-derived geometry and abstractly
rational arithmetic can be maintained even up to the fourth dimension, in a
direct correlation, without any compromise of the foundational axioms of
dimension. This is because with a move to an a priori operationalization of
the Immanent/Transcendent axis, for example in Fuller’s Synergetic
Geometry, we move away from rectilinearity and into radial and convergent
equiangularity with its dimensional limits not at three, but at four,
corresponding to the four perpendiculars (normals) from the faces of the
tetrahedron. And therefore the fourth dimension of the axis of the
imaginary numbers can be mapped in a purely modelable and consistent
manner.ii*
But with these various symbiogeneses or structural couplings in
evolutionary and organismic embodiment—subject and object, intelligence
(rationality) and experience (mnemonics), percept and concept, sensor and
effector, etc and etc—we can see the simple resolution to the nature vs.
nurture debate rattling at the very core of the distinction and duality
between the so-called “Rationalists” and “Empiricists.” Is the mind by nature
possessed of “innate knowledge” and rationality or does all knowledge come
from experience, or from nurture?
The answer, we can see, is yes, and yes. We have seen the innate
knowledge, intelligence and rationality of the organism in the knowledge
contained in its very own DNA, and we have seen how this knowledge itself
gets encoded into the causative language of proteins by the very experience
of the organism itself, interacting with its environment and injecting its

i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
* See, The Imaginary as Vestigial Transitive Axis at the I/T Interface, p348.

Page | 620
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

intelligence back into the stream of deep evolution itself through sexual and
natural selection. This coupling of experience and intelligence in evolution
itself is ultimately expressed in the highly rational and intelligent instincts of
its organisms even before birth and before the coupling of experience and
intelligence in the construction of the sensory-mnemonic interface in the
symbiogenesis of subject and object. The experiences and interactions of
evolutionary trials (genotypes) that prove fruitful get passed on—the story
told by the victors—and this feeds back into the code—as a rudimentary
“sensation”—reinforcing the positive effects and successes of the various
forms of directed and undirected mutation while ignoring the negative
effects.
There is no evolution of problem-solving intelligence and solution-
encoded rationality without experience to drive it into higher levels of
solutions encoded ultimately into the generalized principles at the corner-
stone of human levels of rationality. From the very beginning, rationality
and experience go hand in hand; they are symbiogenetic.
Leaving the cumulatively successful evolutionary sequence (phylogeny)
and taking residence in the development of a single human individual
(ontogeny), the symbiogenetic rudiments of both empiricism and
rationalism can be seen in the functions of sensation as it gets encoded into
memory (experience, empiricism) and intelligence (rationality) in the
cognitive and intelligent pattern-recognition and differentiating functions of
the mnemonic primitives, and primitive sensation. Indeed, the
symbiogenesis of Rationalism and Empiricism is a direct corollary of the
symbiogenesis of subject and object, in that the intelligent functions of
sensation necessitate the experience of the objective world in order to
encode the differentiations of sensation into the increasing rationality of its
cognitive functions.
These newer functions, in turn, allow the developing organism to
experience higher and higher forms of sensation, enfolded into higher and
higher forms of intelligence and rationality, and enfolded into higher and
more complex memories, until these memories begin to reach the level of
the percept-concept and into abstract concepts and can be encoded and
retrieved in language by the highly developed adult. Prior to this point, the
memories are of such a primitive nature that they only appear as the very
background of embodied meaning itself, such as qualia or the what-it-is-like
quality of sensation, encoded and transmitted abstractly via our mimetic and
representational language.

As we can see, there is no ultimate defining line before which experience and
sensation did not exist. On closer inspection, that line—the ontic-epistemic
Page | 621
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

interface itself—turns out to be a vast gradient of immense multiplicity in


both space and time, indeed spanning geological eras and vistas. Therefore,
we must note that the Kantian a priori/a posteriori (the before/after of
experience) is a purely anthropocentric distinction. i For Kant, the
ontic/epistemic line bisecting the interface-gradient, was clearly drawn at
the human level of experience and representation, and naturally so—he was
dealing with philosophers; trying to find a middle-way between the unruly
skeptics and dogmatists while keeping an absolute space clear for
transcendent-biased morality, as opposed to a natural and immanent ethics
as we find in Spinoza. To these aims, Kant seized the whole of sub-
representational relation—the ontic noumenon—for his safeguarding of
pre-rational moral truths in the face of rampant deconstructive skepticism
and moral relativism.
In Kant’s “Transcendental Aesthetic” there is an attempt to determine the
“a priori forms of sensibility”—“the a priori conditions of the possibility of
intuition”ii¥ through which all intuition must emerge as the substance and
medium to be shaped and explored by the higher-level percepts and
concepts. The a priori forms of sensibility, then, are the aspects or
structures of knowledge—e.g. the instincts—with which we (humans) are
born and which shape and guide, or inform all our sensations. They are the
“innate knowledge” we inherited from evolution itself as part of the solution
to the problem of survival and reproduction that we are.
But, as we have seen, evolution proceeds through a symbiogenesis of
intelligence (rationality) and experience in a feedback processes that can
itself be seen as a primitive form of sensation—detecting, remembering and
effecting the gradient of success and increasing functional complexity
through the positive tales told only by its victors. And further, through
sexual selection, the very sensations of evolution’s most primitive creatures
feed back into the code their own “genetic” forms of sensation, intelligence
and experience through their own successes in the game of life. Evolution
proceeds through these various levels of feedback and sensation from its
most primitive forms into its most complex, and it is this symbiogenesis or
structural coupling between evolutionary and primitive sensation
interfacing with the forms of relation itself that informs the forms of
sensibility at the towering temporary plateaus (and tiny pimples) of human
representation. The “forms of sensibility,” then are informed by a
symbiogenesis or a structural coupling with the sensations of form, from
the very beginnings of the evolutionary process.

i
…so much for the “Copernican revolution”…
ii¥
(Stewart, The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy with Illustrations)

Page | 622
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

And Kant seems at first to agree, in the Introduction to The Critique of Pure
Reason:
It is beyond a doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience, for by
what should our faculties be roused to act if not by objects that affect our
senses, and thus partly of themselves produce impressions, partly again
bring the understanding itself into movement in order to compare these,
to join or disjoin them, and in this manner work up such crude material of
the intimations of sense into a cognition or recognition of objects, which is
named experience. So far as time is concerned then, no cognition of ours
precedes experience, and with experience all our knowledge begins. …
But, Kant draws the line of this dualistic chicken-and-egg problem at the
categorical and “transcendental” ontic eggs buried in the human
understanding. He continues…
Though all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that
therefore it all derives from experience. For it is just possible that
experience is itself a compound. It is just possible, that is, that there is
experience besides what is due to the impression of sense, something in
addition that comes from our faculties themselves, when merely acting
because of impression, and in that case it would take long practice, it may
be, to enable us to distinguish the latter and separate it from the former.
The gradation of “sense,” for Kant, clearly ends at the level of human
complexity in the holarchy which makes up the human form itself. But
indeed “there is experience besides what is due to the impression of
[anthropocentric] sense, something in addition that comes from our faculties
themselves,” for in these a priori eggs of sensibility, we have seen, incubates
a deep evolutionary gradient of interaction between more primitive forms of
sensation and sensations of form, i.e. between experience and rationality.
He continues…
Can there really be such component part of knowledge as is independent
of experience, and indeed of any impression of sense whatever? Such
component part of knowledge, did it exist, was alone to be truly a priori,
and it would evidently stand in contradistinction to what other
component part of knowledge is called empirical, the latter, namely
having its source only a posteriori, or in experience. … The expression a
priori, at the same time is not precise enough to designate the entire sense
of the preceding question, for of many a mere empirical fact we say that
we know it a priori simply because we do not derive it directly from
experience, but from a general rule, and this even notwithstanding that
the rule itself may be so derived. For example, we say of a man that shall
have undermined his house, he might have known a priori that it would
fall in. He had no occasion to wait for the experience of the actual event.
Nevertheless he could not have known this absolutely a priori, for that
bodies are heavy and consequently fall when their supports are
withdrawn, this at least he must have known by experience.

Page | 623
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Kant supposed that the categories of the understanding were absolute. They
were free from relation, in the sense that, whatever the circumstances, they
were absolutely universal and fundamental to any human perception and
conception whatsoever. We can indeed see why, and in what sense they are
“absolute” and universal. They are interfacing, from the ground up with the
reality that they are and with that which surrounds them. It is the reality of
relation itself which forms and informs the forms of sensibility, and which
grounds them in an inevitable universality…in this neck of the universe, that
is.

Of the forms of sensibility Kant identifies only two: space and time. As
Matthew Stewart explains [my emphasis], “…they are features of our mode
of knowing, rather than, as common sense would have it, features of the
world.”i¥ This separation between the forms of sensibility (representation),
such as space and time, from the forms of sub-representation, is part of the
radical ontotomy performed by Dr. Kant in order to sanction science and
religion from the extreme versions of each other. This is not a transcend-
and-include differentiation, from reality into its real illusions. If it were, the
noumenal and the phenomenal would have space and time in common, at
least in some form. As Kant says, “Time has no objective reality. It is not an
accident, not a substance and not a relation. It is a purely subjective
condition, necessary because of the nature of the human mind which
coordinates all our sensibilities by a certain law, and is a pure intuition. We
coordinate substances and accidents alike according to simultaneity and
succession only through the concept of time.”ii¥ In other words, though Kant
is not stating it explicitly, the faculty of time coordinates the real “temporal”
relations it receives at its active sensory interfaces, such as real simultaneity
and real succession. Kant simply chooses not to call this real temporal
relation, in both the senses and the objects and relations which it senses, by
the distinct name of time. We can see this radical transcend-and-negate
division as well in Kant’s Transcendental Logic with the sequestering of
causation itself into the phenomenal world alone.
With our ontic/epistemic polarity there is a clear sense into which this
kind of differentiation resonates into a reconstructive bit of surgery. Time
and Space (and causation) are aspects of relation abstracted out of the One—
the ontos—into the forms of representation or sensibility, through the
interface between the ontic and epistemic in the evolutionary symbiogenesis
between the forms of sensibility and the sensation of form.iii* In other
words, it’s not as if there were nothing “resembling” time and space in real


(Stewart, The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy with Illustrations)
ii¥
Collected Works, Volume II
iii
* See, The Gyth of the Miven, p42.

Page | 624
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

relation, but rather that in the ontos there is no real distinction between
them. In acategorical reality time and space are One. The resemblance itself
emerges and differentiates into the epistemic in the interface-gradient with
the ontic. time and space, as separate faculties of knowledge, are abstracted
out of the One of real relation and its infinity of multiplicity and activity.
As we have discussed at length, mathematics (including geometry) is the
art and science of pure-relation.i And this is why geometry and arithmetic
are composed of “synthetic a priori judgments.”ii Relation itself—in its
various inter-relational interfaces and couplings of increasing sensation,
experience and intelligence—informs the forms of sensibility, which
themselves inform the intuitive-substance manifesting into the whole of
generalized categorical and conceptual mathematics. Geometry is simply its
most sensate and explicit form, but all of mathematics draws from this deep
evolutionary reservoir of sensation and experience with the most primitive
forms of relation.
Interestingly, Kant claims that Arithmetic is a function of the category of
time and Geometry is a function (naturally) of the category of space. With
the Einsteinian revolution, however, even this absolute categorical
distinction is rendered moot. And as we have seen, there is no operation
without identity and no identity without operation. Thus there is no spatial
noun without a temporal verb and vice versa. In Interface Philosophy and
Mathematics, they are structurally coupled or symbiogenetic polar
relations.iii*

i
In other words, the mathematics approaches the most primitive and general forms of relation at its
very foundations and forms this generalized artifice into a creative science.
ii
A “synthetic a priori judgment” is a judgment that reveals new facts (synthetic) about the world
prior to having experienced them (a priori). The boundary of experience here is the boundary of
human representation. As we have seen, however, this boundary is a gradient, and pre-human
experience, in a structural coupling, actually informs the forms of sensibility that lead to the human
level of representation.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.

Page | 625
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

In the evolution of models of perception, in conjunction with individual


development, we can naturally discern an embryogenesis of the concept,
where the implicit interface of perception itself gets progressively more and
more explicit , differentiated—and one would hope, integrated.

The unity stage in this development is the primitive state of raw sensation.
This is the state to which the absolute demands of the cogito breaks down,
because all higher forms, which include a self-other distinction and
recognition, necessarily reach into the higher and higher complexities where
percept graduates—through simple projective pattern-recognition into
abstract concept. It is this projection itself—of the various depths of
pattern-recognition and sensor-effector couplings in the mnemonic
simplexes and complexes—that the cogito breaks down to the absolute
knowledge of no projection and no cognate self-other distinction at all.
This first or unity stage of representation then is an undifferentiated raw
awareness. This is the stage of the simple innate consciousness of an infant,
undifferentiated in his/her understanding from his environment. The world
revolves around this infant, and he can’t even make the distinction between
his own self and his surroundings.

The polarity phase in this embryogenesis—when the senses have become


informed and embodied with the mnemonic primitives—is the first actual
model of perception; “naïve realism.” This is a naïvely reflexive, yet highly
effective, level of perception free from the interference of concept and self-
consciousness. It represents a tacit subject/object polarity as a simple
duality and a naïvely absolute or uncritical correspondence between these
real poles of representation. The idea of naïve realism is that the observer
just simply observes or perceives the objects in question. There is no
question as to the depth or degree of reality to which the perception
occurs—and thus no absolutist skepticism that the “ultimate nature,” or the
“thing in itself” is not being reached—but merely the recognition that

Page | 626
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

perception between subject and object is really taking place. This is a simple
and tacit acknowledgement of the subject/object interface itself, prior to
triuning and making any further conceptual and conscious refinements to
the polarity, and prior to its breakdowns and con-fusions.
This tacit belief underlying naïve realism—naïve as it may indeed be—is
empirically justified, in the relative world of form, by the billions of years of
evolution which brought it about, making it worthy of its own cliché; “seeing
is believing.” The evolutionarily-informed effectiveness of this largely
subconscious and autonomous model, operating throughout the less-than-
humanly-conscious animal kingdom, is the relative truth underlying
correspondence theories of knowledge. There is a correspondence, in a
sense, but rather than dualistically absolutizing the terms of the
correspondence itself, the interface model recognizes the relativity in the
triune interface of perception itself in the symbiogenesis of subject and
object.

Naïve realism has been generally derided in philosophy, but the one main
criticism seems to hold no water. This criticism, “the argument from
conflicting appearances,” states that because the same object may appear
differently to different people, or even to the same person at different times,
therefore the properties in question cannot be contained or expressed in the
object itself, but only in the perceiver of those properties. For example, an
apple may appear red in the daytime, but at dusk a shade of grey. Thus, the
apple cannot really (or intrinsically) possess the property of redness, but
that property must hold only in the perceptual apparatus of the observer.
This problem of conflicting appearances is easily dismissed,i however, as
no problem at all, because to say that something cannot intrinsically possess
a property if it appears different under different conditions is logically
equivalent to the claim that something cannot really possess a property
unless it always appears to possess that property. If this were true, we
would have to conclude that a stick placed halfway in water was no longer
straight, but actually was bent, as it appears to be.
In such a case, the real polarity and distinction between reality and
illusion (between the territory and the map and between the ontic and the
epistemic) breaks down. It is this critical and indispensable polarity of the
real illusion and the illusory reality, that the interface model affirms. In this
model, the illusion itself is a function of the perspectival interface between
subject and object. Color itself is a function of this symbiogenetic interface,
as it has taken place billions of years of evolution to unfold. The triune
neural-model of color in the primate retina itself is a function of the coupling

i
…for example, see Myles Burnyeat’s article Conflicting Appearances

Page | 627
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

of genetic mnemonics in the intelligent unfolding of evolution into its


intelligent creatures.
At the level of the organism, we have seen, this takes place with the
embodiment (enfoldment) of the mnemonic primitives in the symbiogenesis
of subject and object where it is only through interaction with the
environment that the senses can learn to remember and refine the sense of
qualia into the higher differentiations of sensation.i*

The truth of naïve realism is in its implicit coupling of subject and object,
directly intuiting the symbiogenesis of subject and object itself. The falsity
of naïve realism is merely in its naiveté . It is simply incomplete.

This triune interface implicit in the polarity of naïve realism was explored a
bit further by Thomas Reid, in his refinement of this model, now called
“direct realism.” This idea acknowledges the inadequacy of naïve realism
and directly recognizes the interface or “veil of perception” as being
somehow, and in some sense, transparent to the objects in question. In this
sense, direct realism acknowledges the fact of representation or the “benign
user-illusion, as Daniel Dennett calls it, but claims that through a “set of data
transfers” the illusion is part of the mediation of direct sensation itself. This
sense of transparency, can perhaps be likened to the transparency one
senses in the use of the screen of a video camera. In this analogy, however,
the sensory apparatus is conveniently brought into the exterior and we can
see both the illusion and the reality as well as their actual or causal
correspondence.
Reacting to this simple polar naiveté, however, and further refining and
focusing on the reality of the veil of perception, to the point of its blinding
opacity, we come to the next stage: “indirect realism.” At this phase we come
to recognize and emphasize the role of imagination, representation and
illusion in the construction of sensation. At this point, we are so focused on
the interface of perception itself, that we cannot see it as the medium of
relation through which perception necessarily takes place. There is no
possible perception without mediation. Indeed, this is what perception
inherently is; the mediation and interface between subject and object.
Indirect realism, however, looks for unmediated and absolutely direct
sensation. The idea of indirect realism is that we can directly and
immediately sense only the interface of perception itself, occurring

i
* See, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.

Page | 628
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

somewhere in the brain, and therefore not the object at all…at least as far as
we know absolutely. The interface then becomes not just a veil, but a final
curtain… but we can see this problem very simply as a function of
absolutizing the relative world of reality and its mappings. It’s a simple con-
fusion of the relative and absolute scopes.
This con-fusion presents another obvious problem. If we can sense only
the sense-data themselves, and this is occurring somewhere in the brain,
then in what way do we sense this sense-data? Is there yet another observer
inside the brain blinded by another final curtain of sensation ad infinitum?
Clearly, pushing the zone of sensation into the brain does not solve the
problem. It merely changes its location, breaking it into the infinite chain of
cause-and-effect relation that it is, in its con-fused search for absolute
relation and unmediated mediation between subject and object.

In both of these models, direct and indirect realism, we now have the
problematic triune interface of the self, the representation and the reality
(corollaries of our fundamental epistemic triunity of the knower, the means
of knowing and the known) and where and how in this continuum of
infinitely divisible multiplicity and relation to draw the dividing line. Direct
realism chooses to draw the line between the subject and object themselves,
and at the interface of the senses, but it draws this line loosely, maintaining
the connection of the interface of perception itself. Indirect realism, on the
other hand, correctly transcends the naiveté of direct realism in identifying
that there is a deeper level of sensation and representation occurring in the
brain, and in making this distinction clear it locates a more solid and
dividing line somewhere in the “Cartesian theater” of gray matter. The
interface model, on the other hand, sees both models as illuminating and
emphasizing different zones in a single, continuous, yet differentiated
interface.

The above models are considered “realist” models because they assume the
real existence of a world outside of our senses. There are, odd as it might
seem, “anti-realist” models of perception. In fact we have already
encountered both of them in the break-down of our cogito. These are Bishop
Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism, and the deep Skepticism seen in Descartes’
cogito. Indeed, they both begin with an absolute criterion for truth, the
contracted cogito, which is the Skeptic’s prime directive. Only after shucking
off the real world through the initial criterion of absolute knowledge, do
both of these models fudge their criterion and bring in the faith-factor of God
through various bad arguments. If we hold both of these models self-

Page | 629
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

consistent, however, as we have seen they both break down into the cogito
of the dissolved self.

The Interface model of perception, as should already be more than clear,


recognizes the relative truths of the previous models and also recognizes
that they all point to the triunity of the subject/object interface itself as it
occurs at the crossroads of the ontic-epistemic interface-gradient of
increasing representational functionality. We have seen this model
throughout the previous section, in the evolutionary embodiment and
various triune interfaces of knowledge, intelligence, memory, and sensation,
as well as in the symbiogenesis of subject and object in Spinoza’s Attribute
Polarity (p531).

Page | 630
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

The academic view of Rationalism as a model of knowledge acquisition says


that knowledge is primarily a function of a priori processes or is innate; i.e.
not derived from experience. This is directly contrasted in academia with
Empiricism which says that knowledge is primarily a function of a posteriori
processes or is necessarily derived from, and after experience.
Constructivism, on the other hand, says that all knowledge is a function of
social convention, i.e. a social construction.
As we have seen in the embodiment of meaning and sensation in deep-
evolution, however, experience, knowledge, rationality and intelligence are
co-evolutionary or symbiogenetic: they necessarily evolve and emerge
together. This means that neither academic Rationalism nor academic
Empiricism, as exclusionary of the other, can be correct. And indeed, we
have already seen that the esoteric Nondual Rationalism of Spinoza, for
example, was both rational and empirical in emphasis, and we saw Spinoza
as playing a key role to both movements of modern philosophy.i*
Recall also, for example, our discussion on the mnemonic primitives
(p531) where implicit in the development process itself, experience and
primitive reason emerge hand-in-hand as they symbiogenetically construct
the mnemonic interface (the intelligence and rationality of perception itself)
between subject and object, and between inter-subject and inter-object.
There is no perception or conception without prior experience to build the
mnemonic primitives and “qualia” of sensation, all of which is further
dependent on the symbiogenetic interface of evolutionary experience and
intelligence (primitive rationality) in the billions of years of evolution
sensory-mnemonically encoded into the instincts and reflexes—and indeed
unfolding in the very embryogenesis and temporal trajectory—of the
cognitive or pre-cognitive organism.
Recall also, however, the orthogonal ontic/epistemic polarity on the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis, as opposed to the transitive distinction
of the subject/object polarity. The epistemic emerges on the

i
* See, The Tao of Rationalism: Pulverizing the Categories, p56.

Page | 631
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

immanent/transcendent omni-axis as a fundamentally social interface or


transitive “plane” in the higher level conceptual construction of the cognitive
holons. In the symbiogenesis of subject and object, recall, society also plays
an ever larger and larger role as the child grows up. This starts even before
the child exits the womb with the mother’s and father’s voices penetrating
the amniotic membrane and fluid. When the child is born, the parents
immediately begin feeding back to the child either positive or negative
reinforcement according to their instinctual and learned macro and micro
societal norms.
In other words, as we’d expect in AQAL metatheory, there is no
neglecting the “WE” or social quadrant in the emergence of knowledge itself.
From societies of single-celled organisms and their primitive culture of
sharing plasmids, as well as feeding this collective experience back into the
gene pool and into societies of humans feeding their learned wisdom into
the meme-pool, the plural aspect of holonic and holarchic development
cannot be neglected. The collective depth of both gene- and meme-pools of
learned genetic and mimetic intelligence and experience is where the infant
immediately begins to swim. Indeed, plurality, as we’ve seen, is implicit in
the concept of relation itself and in our Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity
“… is plural and at minimum two.”
When we take into account the sensory-mnemonic interface of subject
and object at the crossroads of the ontic/epistemic on the multiplistic omni-
axis and recall the function of this interface as a “fundamental” unit on the
transitive-plane of the epistemic as it emerges from the ontic, then we see
the epistemic itself as an intrinsically (though not reductionistically) social
construction. And with the forces of social convention playing a clear role in
shaping the higher levels of conceptualization, knowledge justification and
acquisition, we have already transcended-and-included the academic model
of Constructivism, while giving it a deep-evolutionary rational and empirical
basis of co-embodiment to escape absolutization into a purely social or inter-
subjective phenomenon.
Indeed in AQAL metatheory, Constructivism is found almost exclusively
in the “WE” quadrant of the Epistemic, while Rationalism would be found in
the “I” quadrant and Empiricism in the “IT” quadrant. Rationalism
recognizes the truths of the innate, subjective and intrinsic “I” knowledge of
logic and rationality encoded in the experience of evolution, while
Empiricism recognizes the truths of perception, objective experience or “IT”
knowledge. And Constructivism recognizes the interior truths of the social
or plural aspect in the “WE” quadrant. All of them are equally valid, but each
of them is incomplete in its academic, exoteric, absolutistic, simplistic and
exclusionary (dualistic) form. The “I”, “WE” and “IT” of Rationalism,
Constructivism and Empiricism, therefore, are symbiogenetic and “tetra-
arising” in the emergence of the epistemic from the ontic. See Figure 90,
below.

Page | 632
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Because of the trans-bias toward externality in the transitive mapping of


transcendence, Empiricism tends primarily to arise in the “IT” quadrant,
with a focus on perception and objective experience, rather than directed
toward the internal, subjective perceptions and empiricism of conception.
However, as we have seen with the case of Bishop Berkeley, extreme
Empiricists can easily flip to the other side of the singular-quadrant cogito-
interface into an Idealistic version.i This happens, as we have also seen,
through the absolutization and contraction to the sensory-mnemonic cogito-
interface (a “Cogitism”) between subject and object. The cogito-interface is
actually represented by the line between the “I” and “IT” quadrants, and can
be called a quadrant-interface.
This flipping or tunneling across the singular quadrant-interface is a
clear example of the Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR) in action. Indeed
we will see this phenomenon so frequently below that a common term is
needed to reference it. That which interconverts the absolutized variants
into their opposites—such as Cogitism—can then be called a PAR-Tunnel.
See Figure 90, below.
Also, as we might expect, many Rationalists (“I”) tend to simultaneously
be Materialists (“IT”), as opposed to Idealists (“I”), but the cross-over here is
not nearly as explicit because it tends to traverse at the deeper, immanent
and implicit absolutization of ontic-level form—a “Formalism” as Fox terms
it—central to both logic and experience, for example in the idealized laws of
Science (see below). The absolutism of the cogito (a Cogitism), however, can
be seen as an epistemic-level version of an ontic Formalism, given that the
cogito-interface is the emergent root form of the epistemic.

Other theories of knowledge include Idealism, Realism, Phenomenalism, and


Pragmatism, and can quite easily be ordered on the AQAL grid of quadrant-
interfaces. Epistemological Idealism, as we have seen, holds that the
primary constituents of reality are ideas, such as Plato’s Forms. Naturally,
then, Idealism fits into the “I” quadrant as it stresses the objects of subjective
experience, the ideas. However, through the absolutization of the Form in a
mathematical and physical Formalism one can also very easily pass through
the infinite immanence of the PAR and end up in the outside quadrant,
stressing the objective experience of form.

i
… and indeed there is a subjective form of scientific empiricism as well, such as in psychology.

Page | 633
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

The absolutization of the forms of experience, like the cogito-interface


between subject and object, is a PAR-Tunnel directly linking Materialism-
Empiricism and Idealism, but at the ontic, rather than at the epistemic level.
(See Figure 90, below.) This Formalism is seen in the common stressing of
the ideas that represent the forms of the ontic—such as the mathematical
laws and formalisms of fundamental physics. This emphasis on
mathematical laws of physics is often taken to the extreme of an Idealistic
Mathematicism or Neo-Pythagoreanism and Scientism so common with
today’s mathematical physicists, whose particle-biased and categorical
model of causation was pulverized through their encounter with the super-
fluidity and “wave-nature” of the sub-atomic world. Mathematics, Galileo
said, is the very language of Nature, and this is the attitude of the Empiricist-
Materialist-Idealist.
This, perhaps, can best be seen from the other, or formless side of the
PAR-Tunnel of Formalism. Many Idealists, opposing the absolutization of
Form in the mathematical laws of physics, take a formless absolutism which
leads directly to the isomorphic formlessness of “substance.” But
Materialists as well, stress the underlying formless “substance” giving rise to
the forms of matter.
So, through both formed and formless versions of Formalism, a PAR-
Tunnel is found leading through the immanence of the I/IT interface to its
identical opposite. In both varieties of Formalism, the extreme versions of
Materialism and Idealism tend to share an underlying isomorphism. This is
essentially what Matthew Stewart comically calls the “Schmiderialism
Principle,”i¥
Materialism and Idealism are two aspects of the same thing:
schmiderialism.

Proof. … Materialism putatively claims that everything, including


consciousness, reduces to matter and material laws or forces. But insofar
as matter has definite properties, such as those assumed in “forces” or
“laws,” it is ideal. Indeed, materialism permits the interpretation of the
world on strictly ideal terms, as the activity of those ideas which are taken
to stand for matter. So materialism is a form of idealism. Idealism, on the
other hand, supposes that all the world, including matter reduces to
something ideal. But if what exists is and can only be ideal, is given
immediately and has no possibility of being other than itself, then it is not
ideal but material. So idealism is a form of materialism.

Scholium. Now, next time you pass a couple of philosophers arguing


about the virtues of idealism and materialism, roll down the window and
tell them to try chewing on the grass instead.


Matthew Stewart, The Truth About Everything, p. 309.

Page | 634
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

As in realistic theories of perception (e.g. direct realism), epistemological


Realism holds a correspondence between the real and the known. The
objects of knowledge, for the realist, are themselves real—which is to say
that they exist in themselves apart from the knower. This is directly
opposed to epistemological Idealism which holds that the objects of
knowledge do not exist separately from the mind, but are themselves “mind
stuff.” But like the Idealist, the Realist can really know the real. And so, as
we saw in Stewart’s Schmiderialism Principle, Realism, like Materialism,
passes through the PAR-Tunnel into Idealism—and vice versa—through the
acceptance of the given material of the real. Stewart wrote, recall [my
emphasis], “… if what exists is and can only be ideal, is given immediately
and has no possibility of being other than itself, then it is not ideal but
material. So idealism is a form of materialism.” The realist as well takes
what exists as “given immediately” with “no possibility of being other than
itself,” and so this Schmiderialism-Tunnel applies to it as well, as Realism is a
looser and more naïve form of Materialism.
Epistemological Phenomenalism, on the other hand, is closely related to
epistemological Idealism in its emphasis on the subjective dimension of the
epistemic. Contrary to Idealism, however, in Phenomenalism the known is
intentionally given by consciousness in the very activity of being conscious.
The Phenominalist, then, comes closer to approaching the truth of relativity
in the interface in that he recognizes the activity of the mind itself and its
perspectives as essential for the formation of knowledge in relation to its
objects. He doesn’t project this activity or its forms into the absolute outside
of consciousness, or take these ideal forms as a given material for
representation, but he also doesn’t explicitly recognize the interface of
interaction itself as the expanding locus of knowledge.
And finally, epistemological Pragmatism (similar to Utilitarianism) claims
that knowledge is a function of societal utility. If an idea or truth makes no
positive difference for social utility, in either practice or theory, then that
idea or truth is meaningless and untrue by this pragmatic and utilitarian
criterion. As John Dewey said, “Truth is what works.” Naturally, with its
emphasis on inter-subjective meaning in social pragmatics, Pragmatism fits
generally into the “WE” (or perhaps also the “ITS”) quadrant on the AQAL
grid.

Page | 635
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Figure 90: AQAL Grid of Quadrant Interfaces with Knowledge-Acquisition Theories:


The various theories of knowledge acquisition can be simplistically ordered according
to the AQAL grid, but notice that through the interface between the “I” and “IT”
quadrants the models can easily flip betwee n their opposing variants. This occurs
through the Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR) in the absolutization of various
aspects of experience/rationality. The PAR-Tunnel between Rationalism and
Empiricism, for example, is in the senso ry-mnemonic symbiogenesis of subject and
object at the cogito-interface—the root of the epistemic. The epistemic -level cogito
also serves as the PAR-Tunnel between Empiricism and Idealism. The absolutization of
Form in Formalism, on the other hand, serves at the ontic -level as the PAR-Tunnel for
Materialism and Idealism, in both its Formless and Form versions. Essentially Cogitism
(the absolutization of the cogito) is an epistemic -level Formalism.

According to Plato, Knowledge is the intersection between truth and belief.


In other words, whatever is believed and also happens to be true is
considered knowledge. For most of philosophical history, knowledge was
taken to mean belief that was true and justified as such; knowledge as
“justified true belief.” Nondual Interface philosophy, however, recognizes the
naiveté of this implicit absolutism. It recognizes that within the notion of

Page | 636
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

“justified true belief” lies a hidden polarity, triune interface and a


corresponding set of con-fusions.
This polarity within truth—called “The Two Truths Doctrine” in Vedanta
Hinduism—recognizes truth as separated into its absolute and relative
scopes. Relative truth can be known, used, abused and confused, whereas
absolute truth (or Truth) is fundamentally ineffable and unreachable. This is
a direct function of the quantitative aspects of the relative and absolute
scopes. Absolute Truth is unreachable by the finite forms of relation
essentially because it is infinitely deep. Relative truth is simply the finite or
indefinite (and always incomplete) portion of the Absolute that relative
beings can accumulate and grasp. There is no conceptual separation
between the absolute and relative scopes except insofar as their aspects are
concerned.
And so we can see immediately that the resulting interface between
infinite Truth and finite knowledge can only be the indefinite function of a
regress of truth into the infinity and Truth of Emptiness. This function of
chasing the relative justification of knowledge into the infinity of absolute
Truth leads inevitably, then, to the “regress problem.” In other words, if we
ask for the justification of every belief to affirm its status as knowledge, then
we will never come to an end of this chain of relation. Indeed, if every belief
requires justification then there can be no end to the chain at all. It must be
infinite in itself. But if we necessitate an infinitely deep chain of justification
for truth, we have forced a search for absolute Truth, given that the infinite
is the quantitative aspect of the absolute scope. If we don’t recognize this
distinction in the process, and then come to the conclusion that “truth” is not
possible because the end of the chain cannot be reached and indeed cannot
exist, then we have performed a scope con-fusion. The search for Truth is
not the search for truth. It is the fruitless and confused for absolutes in the
land of the relative. This is the core of the skeptics error in absolutizing the
truth of relativity.
Perhaps the only self-consistent way to break the con-fusion is to
differentiate the pre-fused and conflated scopes of truth. There is no
possibly complete and absolute justification of the knowledge of absolute
Truth. Justification itself is a relative function and can only interface with
relative truths, not the ONE-ALL of absolute Truth. Every self-consistent
system of truths—interfacing with the emptiness of infinite possibility—is
based on axioms and hypotheses which themselves cannot be proven, and
this is a natural corollary of Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem—from the
rarified mathematical world of pure-relation to the real world of ontic and
epistemic relation; the real and the real-illusion, Brahma and Maya.

Page | 637
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

The “infinitists,” like the nondualists, are not bothered by an infinite regress
of truth and justification. In this regard, like the esoteric “Grand rationalists”
they see a positive aspect to infinity. Infinitists, however, argue that it is
indeed possible for an infinite chain of justified true belief to exist, at least in
potential. This would mean that it is possible, given the resources, that a
justification could be found for each belief in an infinite chain. But,
ultimately this would be to say that the finite could reach the infinite, which
on its face, and by definition, is absurd. In other words, while each single
link in the chain could, in principle, be justified, it is a logical contradiction to
suppose that one could ever get the resources—even in principle, in an
infinite universe—for the justification of the entire infinite chain. The finite,
in any form, simply cannot overtake the infinite. The act of overtaking,
increasing in magnitude, lies squarely in the finite and indefinite realm of
magnitude and boundary itself. The infinite, as we have seen, is not a
boundary or magnitude. It can’t be reached. There is no ∞ - 1. The very
premise of the infinitist argument is contradictory; a hopeless scope-
confusion. In an infinite chain of belief, there will be no final justification.
The truth of the infinitist’s position, however, is in the acceptance of the
open-ended or boundless aspect of justification in the face of absolute
Truth—the relative scope interfacing with the absolute scope. Where it
went wrong is in the assumption that the potential of a finite process could
equal the actuality of an infinite reality. This is a clear con-fusion between
the quantitative aspects of scope.

In the search for truth in relative knowledge there is a constant vacillation


between the relative and absolute scopes of truth. Skepticism, for example,
assumes that all knowledge must be absolute to count as knowledge at all.
The Skeptic argues that because there is no possible end to the chain of
relative belief and justification, then there can be no knowledge whatsoever.
The Skeptic is blind to relative truth and its vast holarchical networks of

Page | 638
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

justificatory relation precisely because he has absolutized its relativity. The


truth of the Skeptic’s position is in the acategorical imperative of rationality
which he employs, but the Skeptic has taken this relative truth to its infinite
ends (the absolute scope). He has elevated the relative practice to an
absolute category and criterion of justification. This con-fusion is a clear
performative contradiction. Relative truth proceeds and develops through
the acategorical imperative. It is not ultimately destroyed by it. The only
thing that is destroyed by the acategorical imperative is the dogmatist’s
illusion that truth must be absolute.
Naiveté is the other end of this extreme. The Naivetist, then, would
accept (at least some) relative truth claims as absolute Truth on their very
face, without requiring of them any form of justification. This easy model
can be seen functioning implicitly in the vast majority of humanity. It is,
after-all, the foundation of dogma in the absolutization of belief. The
Naivetist’s usual justification follows the law of averages. To put it harshly,
it is a “herd mentality,” or as the Integralists call it, a “mythic-membership”
level of development. But such a naïve mentality has its justification in the
knowledge imparted to us from evolution. The law of averages generally
works for survival into reproduction.

The middle-path between these two views is naturally the univocal


realization of the truth of relativity. This is not to be confused with an
absolutized relativity, or the scope con-fusion of the “relativity of Truth.”
Not ALL beliefs are created or justified equally. In fact most aren’t. The
most robust and valid beliefs have a variety of different complimentary
methods of justification at their disposal, cumulating in a relative feel, or a
probability of their being correct or incorrect. These would include: an
appeal to parsimony or simplicity of explanation for the widest variety of
facts (Ockham’s Razor), an appeal to empirical evidence or inductive
reasoning, an appeal to a foundation of logical coherence or consistency
(deductive reasoning).
The value in naiveté is in its child-like freedom from the preconceptual
tyranny of the transcendent category. The goal of this middle-path between
skepticism and naiveté is to use the acategorical imperative of the truth of
relativity to break down preconceptions and pulverize the categories in
order to effect the naïve state before the categories were implanted. But one
must do this while, at the same time, retaining the relative truths gained by
the relations of the categories. The category boundaries must, in effect, be
transformed into fluid, reconfigurable interfaces. This is much more difficult
even than it seems, because many of our deepest and most influential
categories were also the earliest planted. They are ubiquitous and indeed
the very context of thought itself. We can’t see them because we see through
them. They form our very eyes, both literally and metaphorically.

Page | 639
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Correspondence theories would extend a naïve or direct realist theory of


perception into a model of knowledge and truth. Correspondence models,
then, assume truth to be a one-to-one mapping of an idea and its object, and
this mapping is implicitly absolute and singular, or linear. There is only one
correct mapping, “one Truth,” and if the correspondence is right, then that
Truth can be known. The problem, then, with correspondence models is that
their uni-linearity cannot accommodate any form of relativism or
perspectivism. They break down when confronting their own linear and
relative limits in the vast multiplicity of perspectives on relative truth.
In a sense, the correspondence models can be seen as the identical
opposite of skepticism. Both models con-fuse the univocal polarity of the
relative and absolute scopes of truth, but each model comes down on the
other side of this con-fusion. Skepticism unwittingly deconstructs relative
truth by the criterion for absolute Truth, whereas, in their naiveté
correspondence theories elevate their own constructed relative truth to a
default status of absolute Truth.

In her article “Force Relations,” Beth Metcalf says:


[In correspondence theories] There is merely an external relation of idea
and object. It gives us no formal or material definition of truth, but only
“extrinsic designation”.
The problem of correspondence theories, then, can also be seen in terms of
AQAL metatheory, as a quadrant absolutism of the “IT”, or external
quadrant. The correspondence, however, is not only between idea and
object, but also between epistemic and ontic. As we have seen, the
ontic/epistemic polarity occurs on the immanent/transcendent omni-axis,
which runs orthogonal through the transitive-plane of the AQAL grid. The
AQAL grid, therefore, by itself is inadequate to map this extrinsic relation.
Using the I/T-augmented AQAL grid, however, the relation becomes
apparent as a diagonal, rather than a purely horizontal or vertical (transitive
or I/T) relation. It is indeed this hidden diagonality in the tacit
correspondences in science that gives rise to the common con-fusion
between the objective and the ontic. See Figure 91, below.
So, with the I/T AQAL mapping in mind, it is apparent that the main
problem with correspondence theories is that they absolutize a purely
external relation between epistemic-level idea and its ontic-level object and
so they don’t allow the emergence of the multiplicity of perspectives
acknowledged at the higher levels of knowledge models—from pluralism to
integralism and beyond—and embodied in the plural quadrants. This one-
to-one external mapping to absolute undifferentiated Truth makes
correspondence models unable to adapt and integrate new perspectives and
unable to transcend-and-include into higher levels of growth. But
Page | 640
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

furthermore, correspondence models don’t explicitly recognize the interface


of perception at the ontic level transcended-and-included into the epistemic.
This is why the ideate (the object at the epistemic level), in correspondence
theories, is islanded with no interface to the idea, and also why the idea at
the ontic level—the subject—has no interface with its object

Figure 91: Correspondence on the I/T-AQAL Grid and its Missing Interfaces:
With the help of the I/T axis, we can see that the correspondence relation between
idea and object is not merely horizontal (or transitive) but also vertical
(immanent/transcendent), which together gives a diagonal relation. It is this diagonal
relation in the tacit correspondences of science that gives rise to the con -fusion
between the ontic and objective. But we can also see that the correspondence view
has no interfaces between subject/idea, subject/object, idea/ideate an d ideate/object.

The value of correspondence theories is in their naïve and implicit


acceptance and use of analogy. In the words of H. P. Blavatsky from The
Secret Doctrine, “Analogy is the guiding law in Nature, the only true Ariadne’s
thread that can lead us, through the inextricable paths of her domain, toward
her primal and final mysteries” (2:153). Analogy, in correspondence
theories, occurs through the subject-object interface at the crossroads of the
orthogonal ontic-epistemic interface gradient. It is the analogous and
relative correspondence between the representation and the reality.
Analogy itself is fundamental to representational awareness. It is the higher,

Page | 641
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

conceptual level of pattern-recognition and -projection. The very reason


that analogy works so well as to be the “guiding law of nature” is because
there is indeed a relational and relative correspondence between subject and
object in the interface, and indeed a self-similarity in Nature not only
between its sub-representational forms, but between representation and
sub-representation. In other words, in a self-similar Kosmos, it is no
surprise that the forms of reality should find their echoes in the forms and
interfaces of its real illusions and representations.

Alain Badiou writes, “One of Deleuze’s strong points is to have thought with
Leibniz an objectless knowledge. The ruin of the category of the object is a
major success of philosophic modernity…” (p67). The object is “ruined” by a
transcension-and-inclusion, or an enfoldment into the subject/object
interface and polarity itself. In The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze
takes Leibniz’s seemingly discontinuous stipulation of an infinitely divided
universe and translates it across the implicit Principle of Absolute Reversal
and into the interpretation of infinite division as an infinite continuity of
folds within folds within folds ad infinitum. In Leibniz’s universe, according
to Deleuze, reality is infinitely folded, infinitely modified, and through the
Principle of Nondual Rationalism, we can see the identity here with
Spinoza’s universe.
The subject/object interface, what Deleuze calls the vinculum, is likewise
composed of infinite folds. And this vinculum, composed of folds of folds
within folds and folds..., offers a perfect symbol for the mnemonic interface,
and is actually seen in the folds of the neocortex. From single- to multi-
cellular organisms, the interface of awareness itself, as we saw in Interface
Biology (p612), maximizes its power of intelligence and perception by
maximizing its surface area. At the higher levels of this transition it begins
to maximize its surface area by convoluting into pleats called sulci and gyri,
in order to give maximum space for mapping and expanding the collective
and vastly parallel sensory/mnemonic interface.
The outer pleats of the interface fold inward and the inner outward,
involution becomes evolution and vice becomes versa. Thus subjectivity and
objectivity become intrinsically enmeshed in the labyrinthine folds and
internal sensor-effector lattice-works, remappings and holarchies—the
cultivating third and symbiogenesis of subject and object in the
sensory/mnemonic interface and the higher levels of representation. No
longer can the object of perception exist without this deep interface and
identity in the subject, because both exist also within the interface of
representation itself, as the inner cleaves from the outer at all levels in the
infinite holarchy. As Deleuze says, “[the fold] also passes between mind and
body, but after having already passed between the inorganic and the organic

Page | 642
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

for the bodies…” The fold, then is also the metaphor for the cultivating third
between the inorganic and the organic, or between life and death. Deleuze
makes a point of Leibniz’s idea that the “machine” is not mechanical enough
to be alive. Living organisms are composed of infinite holarchies of deep
complexity—machines made of machines made of machines—whereas
“artificial” machines are made of bulk materials, vast crystals roughly hewn
into behemoth gear-works, clanking and grinding around in the comparative
inter-galactic space between. We’ve just begun to tap the depths of this
Leibnizian complexity with the electron and molecular bio-machines.
Through infinite multiplicity the categories of both life/death and
subject/object become pulverized as well and the truth of the relativity
between them is revealed. Deleuze continues, “It is an extremely sinuous
fold, a zigzag, a primitive unlocalizable link” (p162). We saw it already zig-
zaging its way through the complexities of evolution in the symbiogenesis of
rationality and experience in the sensory feedback functions and intelligence
of deep evolution as it encoded experience and intelligence (“innate ideas”
and rationality) into the convoluted folds of its creations. The category of
the object in opposition to the subject has become pulverized and
reassembled at all levels along with the subject into the interface, the
cultivating third in the truth of relativity, free from the singular and linear
correspondence with an implicitly absolute Truth.
It is only when correspondence and analogy are used without a univocal
grounding in the Two Truths and real difference (dependent and relative
arising) that the one-to-one mapping between relative knowledge and
absolute Truth takes place, negating the truth of relativity and its infinite
reality of truths. As Deleuze says in The Fold, “This is not a variation of the
truth from subject to subject, but the condition under which the truth of a
variation appears to the subject” (p27). Truth itself unfolds into variation in
the reality and infinite multiplicity of relation. Badiou says, echoing Deleuze
and pre-echoing Wilber’s IMP, the subject becomes “the point (of view) from
which there is a truth, a function of truth. Not the source, or the constituent,
or the guarantee of truth, but the point of view from which the truth is.
Interiority is above all the occupation of such a point (of view)” (p62).

As we have seen throughout this text, Foundationalists, like many others, see
the necessary infinite depth of justificatory relation as a regressive disaster.
Despite the fact that Foundationalism is most commonly associated with the
traditional exoteric view of Rationalism, this negative, regressive view of the
infinite, we have seen, is the very antithesis of the positive infinity of the
“secret of Grand Rationalism,” as Merleau-Ponty put it. Indeed, as we have
also seen, in opposition to the positive infinity, it is the pre-rational and
medieval transcendent-bias that leads to the view of the infinite as

Page | 643
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

regressive, always in search for a transcendent origin point or ground and


bound of justification in infinite immanence.i*
Foundationalists respond to the regress problem by claiming that some
foundational beliefs do not require justification. As we can see in Figure 92
below, Foundationalism seeks justification generally in a hierarchical
orientation to the Immanent/Transcendent axis, from simplest axioms to
complex conclusions. It is this immanent, yet transcendent foundational
axiomatic layer or transitive-plane upon which Foundationalists build their
rigorous pyramidal structures. And it is this rigor that gives them their
power.
Indeed, as should be clear from our discussion in the section Trip-Reset:
“Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos (p588), the foundational
pyramid from its “simplest axioms” to the higher complexities of its
conclusions, is roughly isomorphic to certain aspects of reality, namely the
reality of agglomerative and evolutionary holonic and holarchic complexity,
from “simplest bodies” to the more complex forms and outcomes of
evolution. This, then, taken relatively, is one of the truths or strengths of
Foundationalism.
And naturally where Foundationalism breaks down is in its rigid ties to
its axioms as absolute, as if they ultimately could not benefit from
justification and were not always open to further analytical depth, as directly
analogous to the necessity of the infinite holarchy and Emptiness. Simplest
axioms, like simplest bodies, are not absolutely pure and perfectly
independent in their simplicity, but always exist as an outcome of deeper-
level processes in a deeper-level context. Because of the truth of relativity,
the context itself is always open to its own forms and particulars of change,
leaving the axioms as well open to the endless need for relative revision.
The escape from the regress of justification into axiom can be based on many
things, such as an appeal to the notion that some ideas are “self-justifying” or
obviously true, or it can be based on an appeal to empirical evidence or
simply to the lack of opposing evidence. The main criticism of
Foundationalism, naturally, is precisely its appeal to the arbitrary,
“subjective” or unjustified acceptance of certain beliefs.
Esoteric and nondual philosophies, such as Nondual Rationalism and
Interface Philosophy, take the Immanent/Transcendent axis itself as the
foundation and are therefore rootless-root...isms, or Foundationless-
Foundationalisms, insofar as they are foundationalisms at all. All axioms, in
such a philosophy would be open to further analysis as necessitated by the
acategorical imperative at their very core.

i
* See, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias p91.

Page | 644
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Figure 92: The Foundational Pyramid:


In this diagram we can see that the primary general axis of Foundational models is the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. At the root level is the axiom, needing no justification
whatsoever, and the “self-evident” truths of the axioms together feed into th e truths
or beliefs at the higher levels of the pyramid.

The value in Foundationalist models which must be retained in any integral-


level metatheory tends to be their logical axiomatic rigor, which can closely
approximate both immanent and transitive forms of causation, especially as
roughly isomorphic to the forms of the pyramids of complexity found in
evolution, as we discussed.

As we have seen, the appeal to a foundational axiomatic layer is not so much


the problem with Foundationalism, simply because infinite immanence is
unreachable and we must begin somewhere relevant to the human condition
in relativity. The problem with Foundationalism is its transcendent-biased,

Page | 645
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

negative view of infinite immanence or logical Emptiness as a regressive


disaster.
Foundationalism is based on an anthropocentric, top-down view of
reality that seeks to find or impose order or origin from without. This
transcendent-biased mindset spawns many subtle versions of the
“disastrous regress,” such as the idea that randomness cannot equal an
unknown order of an intrinsic and infinite depth. This “transcendental-
determinism,” as we could call it, leads directly to the problem of the
freedom of the will, as we will see.
With the recognition of immanence in transcendence enfolded in the
Principle of Infinite Determinism—which says (recall) that “Infinite
determinism equals Indeterminism” i *—the problem is simply resolved
(though this won’t be dealt with in depth until SpinbitZ Volume II). The
infinite depth of determinism is only seen to negate free-will in its
absolutization, indeed as all concepts-as-relativities are negated or inverted
when taken to the absolute scope. Through the Principle of Absolute
Reversal, naturally, taking the relative freedom of the individual in
dependent arising, to its absolute regressive ends in seeking absolute
independence, reverses it into absolute unfreedom. “Not only are we
determined, but we are infinitely determined!” This, indeed, is a perfect
example of the PAR in action.
There is a curious reversal of the power of determinism in the regressive,
transcendent view. This view places the infinity of immanent causation
outside the ownership of the transcendent individual, rather than grasping
this infinite depth of causation as the emergent unbounded essence of the
individual himself. When determinism is seen transcendently it is nearly
always seen externally, e.g. the hand of God. Transcendence naturally maps
to the transitive in the trans-bias. This is because our most obvious sensors,
effectors and manipulators are located and directed on the outside and
outwardly from our cognitive interfaces. This transcendental, top-down
determinism is seen when we effect a change in our environment, such as
when we place a stick in the path of a bug. The bug can’t readily be seen to
have caused the action and so he is passive with respect to it. But likewise,
we can hardly be aware of the infinite chain of immanent causation that led
to our own desire to do so.
The infinity of immanent determination, however, given that it is found
within the individual can just as easily be seen as self-determination. “I am
determined! … and infinitely so!” This is a vast switch in power, taking
ownership for one’s own infinite immanence and purpose. A much simpler
view than seeing this immanence as somehow other—owned, perhaps, by a
transcendental God as the warden of some perfect prison where absolute

i
* See, Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID), p186.

Page | 646
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

compliance is achieved through the implanting of alien and artificial


clockwork mechanisms into the very soul of its inmates.
This points to another problem with transcendental determinism—
where causation is bound in the transcendent transitivity and mechanism of
the concept. Determinism in its transcendent, top-down form becomes
indistinguishable from pre-determinism and fatalism. We can see this very
clearly in the exoteric transmutation of Leibniz’s inherent Spinozism
through the “popular religion” of the Leibnizian transcendent God. When
Spinoza’s balanced nonduality of immanence and transcendence is distorted
through the transcendent hands of the Leibnizian God, determinism for each
monad becomes mechanized into an infinite chain of causes and effects pre-
existing and absolutely pre-determining every action of the monad, in a “pre-
established harmony.” This tireless grip of the dead hand of fate, this
mechanical past which pre-determines every move of the future,
mechanically encoded into the very soul of the monad, is directly opposite to
the Spinozan eternal NOW of sub specie aeternitatis. In the eternal NOW the
past does not exist except for its effects transcended-and-included into the
NOW, whose infinite determinism brings forth an emergent novelty of
indeterminism with every moment.i*
But recall that it was the fusion of Leibniz’s infinitely divided substance
as monads with Spinoza’s indivisible Substance that led to the Principle of
Nondual Rationalism in the first place. Indeed, when Leibniz forgets about
his exoteric goals for a popular religion, he regains a self-consistency which
is virtually identical to the Spinozan system which he exoterically
repudiates. And his reactionary distortion of Spinoza into exoteric form
reveals some interesting and useful tricks and tools to add the collection. As
the Theosophists say, it is the “shock of the two,” Leibniz and Spinoza, that
leads to the truths of the esoteric system. This will be further explored in
the coming section Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of Opposites (p663).
If we take a progressive view of infinite determinism, we see this infinite
depth of complexity itself as the very foundationless-foundation of the
individual, giving rise to relative freedom in relation to other individuals.
Without causation and the inter-expressivity of the truth of relativity there
could be no platform for the emergence of individual freedom. Indeed, it is
the regressive, top-down view of transcendental-determinism that is blind
to the progressive aspects of infinite depth in giving rise to emergence and
true novelty. It is this novelty in emergence, in its infinite levels, that is the
platform for true freedom at the only scope at which the concept of freedom
makes any sense—the relative. As Matthew Stewart notes, “Spinoza
supposes that the opposite of freedom is not necessity, but compulsion or
constraint." ii These are external, or transitive, causes on the individual.

i
* See, Univocity and the Eternal NOW, p187.
ii
Stewart, Courtier, p161

Page | 647
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

One’s own immanent infinitely necessary nature is therefore the source of


freedom, rather than the cause of unfreedom.

Absolute freedom, like absolute-anything, is absolutely senseless. Indeed,


this is the Freedom of Spinoza’s God as absolute-scope immanence in
transcendence; free from the needs and relations of the senses and the
internal sensor-effector (algedonic) complexes in the passions. In this
absolute sense of independence only the tautology and identity of the ONE-
ALL can be Free. But man, as relative freedom, can approach this Freedom
asymptotically by the recognition and embodiment of his own infinite
determination, in the dependent “essence” of his very soul with which he has
an inter-expressive relation with all other beings.
This is the goal of Spinoza’s theory of the emotions, as it uses the higher-
level passions to overcome the lower ones, allowing self-determined activity
and order to unfold and harmonize into the infinite depth of determination
itself as it manifests in the emergent layers of the passions. This view, as a
“psycho-active map,” then—as the very reason Spinoza developed it and
used himself successfully as its pilot and test-case—starts to calm the
infinite layers of emergent determination expressing through the passions,
allowing them to inter-harmonize beyond mere reactivity and passivity. It
allows them to realize and actualize the infinite activity that they ultimately
are.

In opposition to foundational theories, Coherentism responds to the regress


problem by rejecting the assumption that the regress must proceed
according to a pattern of linear justification, generally from foundational
immanence and simplicity to transcendent complexity. In opposition to
correspondence theories as well, Coherentism rejects the idea that truth
must be justified in a correspondence with its object. Originally coherentist
models were composed of circular chains of reasoning. And this circularity
was broadly repudiated, for being … well … circular. But circularity itself
cannot be the problem when systems in the real world can, and often are,
circular. Take the phenomena of dynamic feedback, auto-catalysis,
structural coupling and symbiogenesis. In all of these cases, each node in the
chain supports the emergence of the other in a circle of mutual relations, and
one cannot be seen to logically precede the other.
Indeed, every-bit as much as linearity, circularity as a form of non-
linearity, may be intrinsic to the nature of causality. And the acceptance and
careful use of a degree of circularity in coherentist models, may itself be a

Page | 648
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

particular advantage which has yet to be fully explicated and exploited. This
may be the province of parallel functions in computational simulations,
however, rather than logic. A logical circuitry as opposed to a circular logic.
Furthermore, this circularity in coherence models and in reality itself tends
to be in a transitive-plane, while supported by webs of immanent complexity
(cultivating thirds) giving rise to an emergence of properties. It may simply
be that linear forms of logical circularity are invalid, while parallel, trans-
logical and non-linear forms of circularity and circuitry have yet to be
discovered and utilized.

But aside from this generally repudiated and vacuous logical circularity,
most coherentists now hold that an individual belief is justified mainly by
the way it fits or coheres with the rest of the belief system of which it is a
part. Coherentism, then, generally takes place in transitive interrelations of
justification between its component beliefs. None of the beliefs are
foundational and each belief helps to justify the rest in the synergetic
consistency and coherence of the whole. This theory, consisting mainly of
transitive relations of beliefs, naturally has the advantage of avoiding the
problem of the infinite regress, without the need to claim special, arbitrary
foundational status for some particular types of beliefs. See Figure 93,
below.

Figure 93: Coherentist Raft Over the Abyss:


In this diagram we can see that the primary axis of Coherentism is the transitive -axis.

Page | 649
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Indeed, coherentist models function largely as a transitive -plane, floating above the
abyss of immanence and transcendence. This is why they are generally conceived with
the metaphor of the raft.

The main problem with Coherentist models in rejection of correspondence


and foundational methodologies, is that a system can be coherent while also
being wrong. And so coherentists may build a vastly beautiful and
intrinsically coherent model and have no assurance that this model
corresponds to anything in reality…other than itself.

Metcalf continues…
On the other hand, perhaps we may try to reach truth as an internal
relation of the concept by using a definition of internal coherence. But this
gives us only representative content, and its form is that of psychological
consciousness.
So, while Correspondence models possessed merely extrinsic or external
relations, Coherentist models possess merely internal relations. Coherence
is essentially a dualistic reaction against correspondence, so naturally it flips
across the quadrant interface from the external to the internal. Coherence
models, however, intrinsically allow the pluralism of multiple perspectives
and truths, and as such fit on the AQAL grid in the “WE” quadrant, as
systems of relations forming a collective whose internal quality is greater
than the sum of its parts.
The usefulness or truth of Coherentist models which must be retained in
an integral model is in their use of coherence, internal consistency and
rigorous interconnectivity as a marker for success. This same kind of truth
characterizes the nature of the objects of consciousness themselves.

Faced with these two opposing models and their intrinsic relative truths,
Susan Haack, in the integral spirit, mashed them together to create
“Foundherentism.” With the “analogy of the crossword puzzle,” and in light
of the Vision-Logic Coordinate System, we can see that Foundherentism
combines the immanent/transcendent justificatory chains and networks of
Foundationalism with the transitive chains and networks of Coherentism.
See Figure 94, below.
Perhaps a better analogy for Foundherentism, however, would be the
idea of a pyramid, each layer of which would be composed of coherent rafts,
and extending the criterion and function of coherence on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, each component belief in each raft would
interlink, in both immanent and transcendent directions, and cohere with
those beliefs in its surroundings. Inherent in this metaphor, then, would
Page | 650
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

already be the “crossword puzzle analogy,” though the structure would


retain the relative truths in the Foundationalist model in building from
simplicity to complexity as found in the evolution of systems themselves
which these models may wish to represent. In some instances, however, the
pyramid model may be too limiting, so the crossword-puzzle analogy may be

Figure 94: Foundherentism and the “Analogy of the Crossword Puzzle”:


Here we can see that Foundherentism combines both the transitive and
Immanent/Transcendent axis unique to both Coherentism and Foundationalism which
it combines. This results in the “crossword puzzle” analogy.

more flexible because it is not constrained to a global morphology.

Foundherentism is naturally a useful step toward integration along the way,


but because it has neglected to include the truths of correspondence models,
namely the relative use of analogy, it appears to be lacking. Also,
Foundherentism lacks the truths of the more recent models, Internalism
and Externalism, as we will see.

Page | 651
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

For thousands of years philosophers have operated on the idea that


“knowledge is justified true belief,” and in just a few pages, Edmund Gettier,
in 1963, shattered the certainty and justification of this belief. Gettier
demonstrated that there are indeed situations in which one’s belief may be
justified and true, and yet fail to count as knowledge. In his demonstration,
Gettier proposed two thought experiments, now known as “Gettier cases.”
In the first case, Smith and Jones have just applied for the same job and are
awaiting their results. Both men have ten coins in their pockets. Smith has
very good reasons to believe that Jones will get the job and he also correctly
believes that Jones has ten coins in his pocket (he counted them a few
minutes ago). Smith then forms a proposition of belief that, “The man who
will get the job has ten coins in his pocket.” But Smith is unaware that he
himself has ten coins in his pocket. It turns out, however, that Smith, not
Jones, will get the job.
While Smith has a justified true belief that “The man with ten coins in his
pocket will get the job,” according to Gettier, Smith does not have knowledge,
because Smith’s true proposition of belief is in reference to a different set of
facts, that Jones, not Smith himself, will get the job. According to Gettier,
Smith then has a justified true belief, but no real knowledge. This is simply
because knowledge is tied to particulars of fact, while beliefs are tied to
mere propositions.
Gettier’s case is plainly exploiting the relativity of ALL propositions, as
well as the interface between language and reality, or propositions and facts.
ALL language is interpreted, inherently ambiguous and relative. The
interface model, with its Univocity Framework, entirely expects that no
belief can be absolute and no statement free from relativity in its
transcended-and-included correspondence, because beliefs are part of the
relative world of form, and thus always fallible.

There are two other, simpler related examples which preceded Gettier’s
accounts, however. The first case, by Meinong, posits a situation in which S
has an auditory hallucination of the sound of a harp. This, supposedly,
justifies S’s belief that a harp is playing. And, lo and behold, a harp just
happens to be playing … but it is the one not heard by S. Only the
hallucinatory harp is heard by S. So S has a justified true belief that a harp is
playing. But does she have knowledge?
The second case, by Russell, imagines that a clock has stopped, say at
12:00. S looks at the clock and forms a belief that it is now 12:00. We will
suppose, for the sake of the story, that this belief is justified by the face of the

Page | 652
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

clock. And indeed, at that very moment it just happens to be 12:00. But does
S actually know that it is now 12:00?
The first case seems rather straightforwardly the case of a belief
randomly connected to an actuality. It is truly a mere coincidence that there
happens to be a harp playing at the very moment that S hears a harp, and she
has no other reason than her hallucination to believe in the harp. And so it
seems clear that S wouldn’t be justified in her belief. In the second account,
however, there would be many reasons to take the word of the clock at face
value. The sun, for example, should be just overhead, as would be expected
of 12:00 noon. And S’s internal clock may be adding to S’s justification as a
visceral and emergent reason for her belief that it is twelve o’clock.
Regardless, from cases like these we can conclude that perhaps all
accounts of justification share a common fallibilism, given that knowledge is
always taken at the absolute scope. What one is justified in believing does
not necessarily determine the absolute truth-value of what is believed, and
thus there can be no such thing as absolute knowledge. Because of this, one
can have a justified belief that is false, and fails to be knowledge. Yet one can
also have a justified belief that is true, but in a way that is disconnected from
the justification itself. What each of these cases demonstrate is that
justification is always mediated by a series of relations—between words,
referents, statements and facts—and there are many cases in which cross-
talk and confusion between these levels can occur, making it appear that one
has knowledge, or that one does not, when the reverse is true. Such is the
way of the true relations of real knowledge.

Internalism about justification is the idea that everything necessary to give


justification for a belief is immediately available in consciousness.
Internalism takes a pragmatic approach in suggesting that justification for
beliefs cannot depend on truths unknown and unknowable to the observer.
For example, when we imagine subjects completely cut off from their
surroundings (thanks to an evil demon, perhaps, or similar to the
disconnects in the Gettier cases above) should we suppose that they cease to
be rational in assuming that things are as they appear? What about the
Gettier cases mentioned above? Is S justified in believing that there is a harp
playing or that it is 12:00? Should we consider it knowledge?
When we apply the Two Truths Doctrine this internalist view becomes
very sensible. Given that we are always limited to what we know and can
know, we can only deal in relative truths, not Truths. There is no truth, in
the reality of relativity, that can be known absolutely, and in this sense there
will always be something outside of our awareness that may either offer
more justification for the truth or instantly render it false. Given that we

Page | 653
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

cannot know all factors in any case, we must deal with what we can know,
i.e., with what is “internal” to consciousness.
On the other side of the token, when we seek to asymptotically approach
absolute Truth—as we do in science—it is clear that there will always be
facts outside of awareness that may eventually change the status of the
belief. As a rational observer, it is indeed necessary that we recognize this
fact and seek to transform those external facts into internal ones. This, then
seems to point directly to an interface with Externalism.

Externalism, as should already be clear, is the view that there are facts
outside the immediate consciousness that affect, should affect or that will
affect the status of the belief as knowledge. Externalists deny that one can
always have this internal sort of access to the factors that can justify one’s
beliefs.
Clearly this entire debate hinges on ones personal tastes and definitions
for justification. What is of value for the Externalist position is that it is
analogous to Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem. The “pure-relational”
acategorical imperative of Gödel’s Theorem naturally should open our
limited categories, sets and contexts of truth and justification to what is
external to them. This recognition, then, opens the way to an
acknowledgement of the Interface itself, always expanding in the conversion
of external justifications into internal truths.

Externalists, as we can see, embody a Gödelian or an unbounded view of


justification. A crucial point, however, is that this externality can be
misleading in that we are talking about an externality to the emergent
interface of awareness, the individual consciousness, rather than an
externality to the individual organism, so, given that some justification
external to consciousness, can actually be internal to the organism, then we
need to distinguish between these two types of individuality and their
respective forms of externality. The ontic/epistemic, recall, is actually
orthogonal to the subject/object boundary of the organism. And something
epistemically external to the individual consciousness or the epistemic
representation can at the same time be internal to the individual organism,
e.g. the subconscious. Accordingly, there also needs to be a distinction
between epistemic externality (i.e. the ontic) on the I/T omni-axis, and
organismic externality (i.e. objectivity, or externality within the epistemic)
on the transitive axis of subject/object.
Epistemic externality is external to both the subjective and objective
forms of knowledge and therefore cuts orthogonally or horizontally through

Page | 654
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

the boundaries of the organismic or subjective individuality. In other words,


epistemic externality, as merely the ontic, can be both internal and external
to the boundary of the organism, so long is it is external to the interface of
representation and awareness itself. Subjective externality on the other
hand, is external because it lies outside the boundaries of the organism in
“objective reality” which generally can be either known (epistemic and
properly objective) or unknown (and properly merely ontic).
Indeed the conflation of this common prefusion (of the crucial distinction
between the orthogonal polarities of ontic/epistemic vs. subject/object)
could be the main source of the crosstalk and con-fusion leading to the
controversy between internalist and externalist models. It may very well be,
for example, that the internalists intuitively sense that much of what counts
for being external to the individual awareness is actually internal to the
individual himself, and accidentally ascribe internality to the individual to
internality of awareness.

As may be clear from interfacing with it already, Interface Epistemology is


essentially a form of fallibilism. It is, however, informed with the vision-
logic interfaces of the VCS, the Univocity Framework and the Two Truths
Doctrine, as well as the knowledge of evolution in its effects as a cultivating
third for the dualisms that plague the academic models of epistemology, and
in light of Interface Mathematics as a rarified and simplified form of the
EOTC, which can be used loosely as an exemplar for the embryogenesis of
concepts in general. We have already seen all of this in action throughout
this section on Interface Epistemology.
Accordingly, the Interface model of truth and justification must
transcend-and-include the truths of foundationalist, coherentist, internalist
and externalist distinctions, as well as addressing the four quadrants and
interfaces of the “AQAL” matrix (the I, WE, IT, and ITS, domains) and their
respective criteria of truth and justification, where need be. However, as
already discussed, Ken Wilber, et al, has already extensively addressed the
AQAL model in the context of integrating the forms of knowledge, and our
purpose here is much narrower in that we seek merely the aspects of this
model as it applies to the integration of epistemological models of
justification of truth and knowledge—the interface between the ontic and

Page | 655
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

epistemic—because it is in the area of ontology and rationality where the


post-postmodern shadow-element resides.
Because humans as finite and relative expressions in the infinite can
only deal in relative and open-ended (third order infinite) truths, the truths
of all epistemological models, as we have seen, must be found in their de-
absolutized forms. Indeed the problems of interrelation between these
models can all be demonstrated as functions of this absolutistic, categorical
and oppositional tendency manifesting throughout the history of
philosophy, as we have seen. But it is this opposition and constant warfare
of differentiation that allows progress in the first place, but perhaps up to a
certain level where to progress further and faster, some integration can go a
long way. This problem of absolutization of philosophical differentiations, as
Matthew Stewart demonstrates in The Truth about Everything, is the
constant attempt to find what he calls, “the Holy Grail of philosophy,” or the
“free lunch,” which is the assumption that one’s chosen model, truth, axiom,
method or whatever, can result in an encapsulated and complete system,
and/or absolute knowledge or foundations.
Contrary to what it might seem, this “mysticism in philosophy” is the
very antithesis of the nondual, or “great wisdom tradition” approach as
embodied in the nondual-rational and transrational philosophies (contra
Descartes) and the so-called ‘‘mystical” philosophies such as Buddhism and
Taoism. The Eastern traditions can be every bit as rational and transrational
as their Western counterparts, as shown throughout this work. The
absolutist and the nondual stances are as opposed as the bounded (finite) is
to the unbounded (infinite), and in precisely the same way. The absolutist
form of mysticism, or dogmatism, is a function of the “forces of
representation,” the “all too human” drive to get rid of uncertainty,
incompleteness, and the fear of the unknown by projecting the finite and the
known into the infinite and the absolute; i.e. the “will to (knowledge is)
power.” It is the rare (or nonexistent) philosopher or student who can avoid
this trap entirely, and perhaps the more a philosopher engages in it, the
larger an audience he has. This absolutist, encapsulating, finitizing (e.g.
foundational) tendency (trans-bias) is therefore more of an exoteric, than an
esoteric function; more religious than philosophical. The two together form
the polarity of the exoteric and esoteric as the individual forms his new ideas
and they are constantly trampled down into the LCD of the academy, only to
be dusted off and re-invigorated by other individuals, ad infinitum.

This brings us to the task at hand of briefly sketching out the integration of
the epistemological models so far in light of the preceding context. Given the
holarchic emergence of the epistemic from the ontic, and the reduction of
span with increased holarchic depth, the epistemic is therefore necessarily

Page | 656
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

an emergent subset of the ontic. This is the first interface we encountered,


that between the ontic and epistemic, but recall as well that this interface is
the cultivating third and a transitive-plane on the immanent/transcendent
omni-axis, and that units composing this plane are the cogito- or subject-
object sensory-mnemonic interfaces themselves—i.e. living human beings
and their interfaces of direct awareness. This, recall, was the crossroads of
the I/T omni- and uni-axes at the transitivity of the subject-object functions.
This notion of knowledge as occurring at a finite interface, then, means
that knowledge itself is necessarily limited and hence relative, and further
that an individual cannot be entirely aware of all the justifications of his/her
beliefs, because an emergent cannot be reduced to its antecedents. Thus an
“externalist” model of some sort is required, but given that “externalism”
transcends-and-includes internal modes of justification, and only adds to it
the possibility of sources of justification external to awareness, i.e.
unconscious, this poses no problem at all for an integral approach based on
the emergence of the epistemic from the ontic.
The truths of the correspondence models, recall, were the truths of
analogy between the ontic and epistemic, and indeed through their very
interface and unity. But as we have also seen, the absolutization of this truth
breaks down into a single, linear and absolute form of Truth, which is
inconsistent with the truths of relativity emergent from every perspective in
real relation and its ONE-ALL (∞/∞) of infinite difference.
The truths of foundationalism, on the other hand, are its gradient-
networks/pyramids of complexity, as well as its logical rigor. At the same
time the truths of coherentism are its use of logical circuitry (as opposed to
circular logic) as well as its criterion of holistic or synergistic internal
coherence. And, as we have already started to see, each layer of the
foundationalist pyramid can be considered or constructed as a cellular kind
of coherentist raft (formed in a transitive and immanent/transcendent
embryogenesis of the concept), where the symbiogenetic, other-enabling
qualities of the concepts differentiating-and-integrating amongst
themselves, as well as the holarchic emergence of this layer from the next
deeper one and into the one above it, gives the layer its intrinsically
coherent criterion of epistemic success, i.e. justification. Such a coherentist
criterion, however, even if it contains the foundational holarchical thrust, is
purely an internalist, or subjective-bound criterion. If we apply to this the
symbiogenesis of subject and object, and by corollary the symbiogenesis of
empiricism and rationalism, however, and demand that all concepts must
correspond to objectively derived notions of causation, or at least to
empirical data patterns, then we have informed our recursive
foundationalist/coherentist model with an externalist and empirical aspect,
with their respective methodologies of justification and truth generation.
We can break these aspects down in terms of our VCS, with its I/T and
transitive axes corresponding respectively to depth vs. span, and the

Page | 657
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

foundationalist vs. coherentist truths. The coherentist model possesses an


inter-conceptual fitness function corresponding to transitive interactions
and span, whereas, the foundationalist model possesses a trans- and intra-
conceptual fitness function which seeks fitness hierarchically or
holarchically both inward and outward. In its de-absolutized, and indeed
ultimately foundationless form, this is a holarchical function, and operates
along the I/T axis.
In this recursive-holarchical Interface model, we start from the broad
base of a few assumptions gathered from observed properties of the world
that upon deeper inspection are found to be causally explicable and
symbiogenetic rather than abstractly symbolic and self-contained
unquestionable axioms (such as we find in modern mathematical physics).
We then differentiate those assumptions and integrate them into a new layer
of complexity, gathering more and more polymorphic and explanatory
power as we progress through an evolutionary feedback process between
the subjective logical/linguistic modeling functions and the empirical results
from objective reality (the subject/object interface).
In this view, then, after the ruin of the category of the object in its
symbiogenesis with the subject, the de-absolutized truths of
correspondence, coherentism and foundationalism are entirely compatible
and indeed symbiogenetic as they express, among other things, the two basic
orthogonal and directional tendencies in human conceptualization; the
holarchic (immanent/transcendent) and the transitive, oppositional and
agglomerative, and given the necessary symbiogenesis of subject and object,
this naturally encapsulates the truths of external epistemic models as well.

All of these crucial terms that we associate with epistemic models are to be
given a relative scope (i.e. limited in certainty as opposed to fundamentally
or absolutely ungrounded), but always in polar relation to the absolute
scope in the Univocity Framework. They will be defined here.
Ontic: The ontic is the relative world of form underlying
representation, and from which it emerges through an interface
into the epistemic. It is therefore also called sub-representation.
The ontic, as the real world of real relation, is the equivalent of
Brahma, in Hinduism.
Epistemic: The Epistemic is the relative world of real representation,
or the real world of representational relation, i.e. knowledge.
Maya, the real illusion. It is emergent as an interface or
transitive-plane and its units are the individual cogito-, sensory-
mnemonic or subject/object interfaces emergent in the
symbiogenesis of subject and object.

Page | 658
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH

Belief: Belief is the acceptance of a proposition likely to be true, based


on many and varied complimentary and synergistic
methodologies and criteria, in their nondual and relative forms.
These criteria for justification would include: rational truths of
logic; empirical truths of evidence as well as Ockham’s Razor;
coherentist “rafts” of transitive consistency and logical circuitry;
foundational logical rigor and pyramidal
immanent/transcendent gradient-networks of complexity; and
relative correspondence analogies.
Truth: The truth model here transcends-and-includes an absolutist
and singular correspondence theory as merely a probabilistic
fitness function. It recognizes that truth emerges at the very
interface of relation between subject and object at the
orthogonal ontic/epistemic interface. Interface Epistemology
recognizes the chain of relations between the proposition of
belief and the facts of knowledge that can easily get crosswired
as in the Gettier cases. The correspondence theory in this model
is infused with the univocal doctrine of Two Truths;
corresponding to the absolute and relative scopes. Truth and
knowledge are only applicable to the world of form, the relative
scope, while the absolute scope is reserved for Emptiness and the
ineffable, serving to pulverize the categories of Truth, keeping
them always open to further growth. The ontic, however, can
now be seen as the interface, the cultivating third, between the
relative and absolute scopes in the sense that the ontic is the One,
undifferentiated reality. It is actual reality, irrespective of who
or what views it and divides it into scopes. It is thus, in this sense,
as Kant intuited, less relational and more absolute, or more
intrinsic and immanent, than transcendent representation. It
lacks the relations of the epistemic which can get cross-wired
into con-fusions, etc. Thus the ontic is at the same time, less real,
in the sense that it has less complexity and depth—less
relation—while naturally having far greater span. The
correspondence of knowledge is a relative interface between
epistemic belief and ontic truth, which is just a way of making
the implicit ontic/epistemic polarity in operation behind the
word “truth” explicit in order to avoid equivocation.
Knowledge: Knowledge is justified and assumed-true belief. It is
always relative, provisional and fallible, because it is always a
real emergent in the world of relation and form. Because the
distinction between the ontic and epistemic is a polarity, the root
of relative knowledge reaches down to, or emerges from, the
immanent infinity of the absolute (the I/T omni-axis), through
the interface of the sub-representational world of form. This
absolute root of knowledge is the crossroads between the

Page | 659
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

fundamental polarities of the ontic/epistemic and the


subject/object (See “Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity”). This
intersection at the interface of “pure” awareness is the “cogito of
the dissolved self,” the “Cogitism” and solipsism that all radical
foundationalisms, or any other absolute criterion of knowledge,
falls into. This interface between the absolute and the relative
forms of knowledge/experience is also that which is experienced
consciously by practiced meditators. The self emerges in the
other direction from this dissolution, into sensory-mnemonic
complexification and projection, and all knowledge beyond this
absolute solipsistic core of ‘‘I think therefore I am” is relative to
it. Therefore any extrapolation beyond solipsism of the severely
limited form of the irreducible NOW of brute sensation is relative
and subject to fallibility.
Justification: a belief is justified relatively only, and the level of this
relative justification is an emergent function integrated from the
various models of epistemic justification: from correspondence
theories, the use of analogy and the recognition of ontic-
epistemic self-similarity; from foundationalism a holarchical
logical rigor; from coherentism a criterion of interdependent and
emergent/holistic coherence; and from externalist models, an
implicit acknowledgement that the Self and its knowledge is
formed at the subject/object interface and therefore the
justification of knowledge can, and indeed must, come from
internal and external sources.

Page | 660
Figure 95: Leibnoza Von Spinbitz—The Only Surviving Portrait

Page | 661
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Despite their tantalizing similarities, it has long been thought that the
philosophies of Spinoza and Leibniz are fundamentally incompatible and
even purely and irreconcilably opposed. Spinoza—a self-sufficient heretic,
branded atheist, and Nietzsche’s “predecessor”i—conceived of the absolute
as a single “Substance,” continuous and indivisible; whereas Leibniz—a
foppish courtier and tireless champion of the Christian pre-rational,
anthropomorphic religion and its Theocracy—put forth a notion of the
absolute as infinitely divided into innumerable simplest substances called
“monads.” But most importantly, Leibniz’s system possesses a profound
inner tension between an absolute exteriority, the pre-rational
transcendent-biased God, and the ultimate interiority, the “monad,” whereas
Spinoza’s system is a harmonious whole where God, Nature and ALL its
modifications are essentially ONE, but seen in different ways, as we have
seen, in Spinoza’s polarity of attributes.
Despite these seemingly opposite foundations, conceptions and
personalities, however, Spinoza and Leibniz agree on many important
points, such as an overriding unity that pervades both systems, and beyond
their differences, they stand together in direct opposition to the proto-
rationality of the Cartesian dualism, the ghost and the machine, popular in
their own time, and now ubiquitous and unseen in ours.
While great disparities appear to exist between their systems, especially
at the absolute level, it will be demonstrated herein that these differences
are largely nominal and superficial, subsisting mainly at the level of words
and their different syntactic mappings through opposite conceptual
emphases. Unfortunately, these superficial differences have been
exaggerated through the years from surface-level readings, over-
simplifications and procrustean historical categorizations. Great strides
have been made toward reconciliation, for example, with the work of Gilles
Deleuze and Matthew Stewart, in tracing out the roots of the traditional
misconceptions surrounding these two philosophers.
As Stewart writes in The Courtier and the Heretic:
… even in the days of their first exchange, there was already at least a hint
of the possibility that, far from being pure contraries, Leibniz and Spinoza
were two very different faces of the same philosophical coin, always
looking in opposite directions as they spin through the air, yet always
landing in the same place (p116).
While representing the two faces of the coin of modernity—the active and
the reactive—Spinoza and Leibniz, respectively, have never been properly
reconciled within the single underlying anti-Cartesian,ii and nascent trans-

i
As proclaimed by Nietzsche himself in his notes on Spinoza.
ii
…though indeed this anti-Cartesianism is not absolute. There are a few things from Descartes that
get included in the trans-rational system that traces its Deleuzian lineage through Leibniz and
Spinoza.

Page | 662
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

rational system that they both explored and inhabited from their different
vantage points.
In accord with the Taoist principle of the “identity of opposites,” and
through the use of our Vision-Logic Coordinate System and Univocity
Framework, a reconciliation will be presented which will avoid the complete
“collapse” of the Leibnizian tension into Spinozistic release, as so many
commentators have predicted. Instead, while some purely reactionary, and
correspondingly absurd layers of the Leibnizian system will be expelled as
the differences shrink, we will find that the metaphysical foundations of the
philosophies of Spinoza and Leibniz are fundamentally compatible, and even
represent a symbiotic, and perhaps symbiogenetic, polarity of opposite
tensions, methods and perspectives for addressing a common intuitive
unfolding essence of rationality, a similar “plane of immanence,” as Deleuze
might say. As Leibniz sheds layers of unnecessary assumptions built to
serve his theocratic/exoteric patrons and his own intrinsic reaction against
modernity, Spinoza gains new layers of detail gleaned by Leibniz through his
effort to overcome his own Spinozistic attraction and collapse. In other
words, we will find that as Leibniz loses his own pre-rational layers of
complexity, Spinoza loses his inherent ambiguity as he gains in Leibniz’s
additional transrational complexity, in perhaps a balanced and reciprocal
fashion.

For this integration, we will finally make heavy use of the full set of our VCS-
meta-tags (scope parameters and vision-logic equations or VLE) outlined in
Interface Mathematics. See VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-
logic Equations (p291) for the full explanation, but for our purposes we will
summarize them quickly below. Recall that the VLE essentially trace out the
Triune Infinite as it abstracts the absolute scope through the three degrees
of infinity, with the scope-parameters from “ab1,” to “ab2,” to “ab3.” The last
degree (ab3, the Bounded Infinite), recall, completes the Cycle of Infinity,
reconciling the trans-bias with the immanence of the Bounded Infinite.
Recall also the use of “charge,” or the positive and negative signs. Because
the forces of opposition are intrinsic to the transitive-axis, the sign is used as
a prefix, to denote positive or negative forms of transitive infinity (e.g. -∞ or
+∞). The I/T axis, however, operates on the intensive forces, transcending-
and-including the transitive oppositional charge as secondary, not intrinsic
to its own polarity. Thus the charge of the I/T axis is found as a suffix, rather
than a prefix, denoting the two intensive poles of the bounded infinite:
immanent vs. transcendent (e.g. ∞- or ∞+). With this again in mind, the VLE
can be summarized and recapped below. Recall also our use of as the
universal operator, denoting any operation whatsoever. This is used, recall,

Page | 663
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

to demonstrate our Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, where any


operation to The Infinite returns the quantitative value of infinity.

ONE

i
VLE: ab1 — The Infinite: The Root VLE

and expanding this equation we have…

transcendent
ALL ONE
immanent

VLE: ab1 — Expanded Root Equation and VLE: Cycle of Unity

(n )=∞

VLE: ab2 — The Aspect Infinite

ii
VLE: ab2.1 — The Uni-Axis with Interface at Finite (Bounded) Unity

i
With the transcendent/transitive bias in modern thought this collapses to oo/0 where division by
zero is correctly recognized as undefined, but the denominator is incorrectly recognized as 0 as
opposed to the immanent pole of deep infinity (I/T) denoted as oo-.
ii
The ONE-one of the uni-axis, recall, is the transition between the absolute scope of omni-non
locality and the one locality of its implicit singularity, or immanent position aspect. Therefore, we
place this VLE exactly half-way between the

Page | 664
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

VLE: ab3- — The Bounded-Immanent Infinite

1
VLE: ab3+ — Transcendent Infinite

Page | 665
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

As might be expected, the embryogenesis of the concept can be used to


provide much needed clarity in the understanding of Spinoza’s system.
Using this schema, we can see Spinoza’s system as a whole, from far away,
and zoom in quickly to get a feel for the general functioning of this model at
all levels of the EOTC. But, as might not be expected, Spinoza’s Ethics seems
to follow this schema quite well. Indeed, right at the beginning of Spinoza’s
Ethics we naturally commence to eff the ineffable—to break from the
absolute to the relative scope—in the outline of the fundamental polarity
between Substance and modification.

Substance, in Spinoza (as we have seen), is defined essentially in the “escape”


from modal, finite, dependent and relative thinking. It is defined in the
move from Form, relation and dependence—not into the formless or
amorphous, because that’s just another type of Form—but into the ineffable,
and absolutely infinite immanence of Substance. So, Substance is defined in
an escape of the infinite regress of immanent causation and logical/causal
dependency to the “independent” ALL-is-ONE tautology or identity of the
absolute scope: Substance being merely its immanent aspect. So, in Spinoza
we have this fundamental polarity between Substance and modification, The
Infinite and the finite, the boundless and the bounded, and the absolute and
relative scopes, essentially.
As a concept—this polarity, however, can be seen essentially as a
functional equivalent to the Nagarjunan polarity of Emptiness and Form.
Modification, in Spinoza, is clearly a direct analog to Form in Nagarjuna. But
Substance, on the other hand—in its common connotation as a foundational
stuff—would seem to be the opposite of Emptiness. As we have seen,
however, Spinoza’s Substance is not a foundational stuff. It is reached only
in the escape from the search for foundations, all of which would be modal,
as “transitive planes.” Substance is then the positive or fullness aspect of
Emptiness, in its immanent direction, which points (through the Principles

Page | 666
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

of Absolute Reversal and Immanence in Transcendence) to the


groundlessness of Emptiness and the absolute scope.
So, basically Nagarjuna sets up his Emptiness as the “bottomless pit of
individual identity and essence,” to pulverize the categories of absolute self-
identity and to explain the transformation and relation between and among
forms in a dependent arising. In an analogous way, Spinoza enforces his
concept of “real” indivisible and immanently enabled (polar, nondual and
triune) difference in opposition to numerical (representational, divisible and
dual) difference. This new theory of difference, reaching into the absolute
itself to make Substance turn on its modes, says Deleuze, is the very key
through which Spinoza turns all of Descartes’ axioms against him, converting
his dualism into a nondualism.
Spinoza also defines the absolute scope of essence as the absolute
existence of infinite Substance; the ALL-is-ONE essence which all modes
share in their dependent arising. So, Substance and modification unfold in
the Ethics in this fundamentally polar arrangement, which is virtually
identical in conceptual form and function to the Nagarjunan polarity of
Emptiness and Form in its pulverizing of the absolute categories of self-
identity and independent Form.
We can see this equivalence very clearly in Spinoza’s definition of modal
essence. Spinoza defines modal essence, as we have seen, as the tendency
through which a modification “persists in its own being.” And this is
essentially our modern definition of “emergent homeostasis.” So, at the
relative scope of modification and dependent arising, in Spinoza, the essence
and self-identity of Form is defined in strictly emergent and dependent
terms, in contradistinction to the platonic notion of pre-given independent
Forms preceding the existence of their instantiations. The only independent
concept in Spinoza is the absolute scope of Substance itself, which, even as
Deleuze shows, “turns around,” or is inseparable from, its modes. This again
reinforces the dependent arising of the relative world of Form or
modification identically opposed to Emptiness and Substance.

When we get to the triune level, in Spinoza’s “embryogenesis of the concept,”


we find Spinoza’s attributes. The attributes, then, function in part as the
interface or mediation between Emptiness and Form, or between Substance
and modification. In the pure relational terms of the Triune Infinite, the
attributes are specific aspects or Aspect Infinities of The Infinite. But the
attributes, recall, are defined, by Spinoza as “that which the intellect
perceives of Substance as constituting its essence.” So, we have this
essentially perspectival aspect of the attributes in perception, but it is the
perception of the essence of Substance through modification into cognitive
modes or holons. So the two attributes can be seen as the two perspectives

Page | 667
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

fundamental to perception and conception itself, and indeed fundamental to


modification.
Deleuze, shows, however, that Spinoza inverted the medieval concept of
the attributes from being attributed to Substance transcendently—from
above or from God—to the notion of the attributes as being actively
attributive or expressive of the essence of Substance into (interfacing with)
the essence of modification in cognitive holons. The attributes are no longer
mere propria, or “divine names,” but the forms or channels through which
God, in its immanent aspect (Substance) actively and directly “speaks”
through the perception and conception of modifications. This is the “logic of
expression” which Deleuze identifies in Spinoza, but the meaning of the
expression is found in the interface between God as Substance and man as
modification or manifestation of God/Substance. The meaning of the
attributes is not to be found in the absence of this relation, because it is only
the attributes which are expressive in this way in Deleuze, and, as we have
seen, there is a fundamental ontic-epistemic and subject-object polarity in
the attributes. The attributive meaning of the expression, then, occurs at the
crossroads of these two polarities, which, as we have seen, are found on the
I/T omni- and uni-axes, respectively. This crossroads, recall, occurs at the
subject/object “mnemonic interface.”

Though both Spinoza and Leibniz employ the word “substance,” as we will
see much more clearly, its meaning in their respective systems is far from
coinciding with each other and with the more common (e.g. Lockean)
connotations of the term as an underlying “substrate” of material. Spinoza’s
Substance, we have seen in the Univocity Framework and the nondual
sketch above, is essentially a Nagarjunan Emptiness, rather than a plane of
immanence or self-existing substrate. As we have seen, all immanent planes
are transitive, and relational, and hence modified. Spinoza’s Substance, we
have seen, is derived in a univocal polarity between the absolute and relative
scopes. Substance reaches into the absolute scope as ultimately an
immanent emphasis—unfolding an infinity of attributes—on our
Immanent/Transcendent axis, in identical opposition with the transcendent
emphasis of God—enfolding all infinite attributes. With the interface of the
attributes, we can then see Spinoza’s polarity between Substance and God as
a function of involution and evolution. Substance unfolds the attributes in
its immanent Becoming, and God enfolds them into transcendent Being.
Spinoza’s Substance, inversely identical to his notion of God, is thus
infinitely immanent and infinitely transcendent since it is merely an
emphasis on the axis itself (“there is only substance” = ALL is ONE) and we
can adopt for it the Root VLE and scope for the I/T axis, with its neutral or
uncharged scope ab1:

Page | 668
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

ONE

So Spinoza’s Substance will be denoted as “Substance: ab1” and his God,


“God: ab1,” and since they are identical at this level (a univocal tautology or
identity), we can collapse them into “Substance-God: ab1,” which is
represented by the I/T axis, or axis-mundi we have already seen in
Parmenides and Zeno.

Page | 669
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

In The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze sees in Leibniz a fundamental
“chiaroscuro” (a term borrowed from the visual arts in which there is a
dramatic swing between positive and negative, light and dark, such as we
find in Rembrandt). Deleuze states, “in the same way the clear plunges into
the obscure and never ceases plunging into it; it is chiaroscuro by nature,
development of the obscure, it is more or less clear as revealed by the
sensible.”i¥ In The Courtier and the Heretic, on the other hand, Matthew
Stewart demonstrates Leibniz's philosophy as a “reactionary” form of
modernism, and the powerful precursor to reactionary modernism to this
day. Stewart writes:
We live in an age defined by its reaction to Spinoza and to all that he
recorded in his philosophy. And there is no more compelling expression
of this reaction than the philosophy Leibniz developed in the long years
after his return from Holland (p16).
In this first section we will bring to light those many aspects of this
reactionary chiaroscuro that result from a philosophy of pure reaction, with
Leibniz’s attempt to forge a “popular religion” by pulling the critical features
of pre-rational religion through the labyrinthine Zenonian interiors of
rationality itself. The result of this bizarre attempt is this vastly beautiful
and fantastically baroque cathedral of philosophical curiosities that
characterizes Leibniz's philosophy to this day—this infinite origami and
Indra’s net of endless monads within monads, “windowless,” “pregnant with
the future, and each with a magic mirror on its interior wall—this
transcendent God as “prime chooser” among a bottomless pyramid of
suspended worlds from which ours is the apex and “best of all possible.”
Much of this, we will find problematic—obsolete curiosities and museum
pieces in the halls of philosophy. This is due to Leibniz's indiscriminate
mixture of pre-rational (mythic) and rational elements into a pseudo-
rational whole. Much of this popular caricature of the mythic elements of
Leibniz, therefore, will be jettisoned, as we reach the core elements of
rationality which both Leibniz and Spinoza explored. But what remains in


Quoted from The Fold, in Badiou.

Page | 670
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

the after-math of the reaction will be nonetheless breathtaking, and indeed


every bit as Baroque.

As we have seen, rationality itself has a certain intrinsic structure, with its
own fundamental conceptual axis, implicit nondual principles and distinct
tendencies. And it has been demonstrated herein that the Rational, when
taken to its ends, unfolds the intensive truths of the nondual, not the
oppositional truths of duality. We’ve seen this explicitly and unequivocally
with the truths and intensive forces of Rational mathematics, and also with
the rational acategorical imperative found in both Spinozai and Nagarjuna.
And we’ve also seen it with the inevitable unfolding of the fundamental
Principle of Nondual Rationalism in Zeno and Parmenides. However, as we
have also seen, for the most part Descartes merely honed the expository
style, and its nascent Principle of Sufficient Reason, appropriate to this age of
reason. He did not fully explicate the truths of the Rational, nor should he be
considered its exemplar or father, but as a transitionary and largely proto-
rational figure.
It was Spinoza, in his early study of Descartes, who rendered the
Cartesian philosophy in the “geometric style” of early mathematical forms of
rationality, namely from the 4th century B.C.E. and Euclid’s geometry. This,
then, can be seen as the culmination of the rational style of philosophy, as it
expresses the largely proto-rational Cartesian philosophy in the rationality
and syntax of mathematical formal systems. Rationality itself, then, must not
be confused with its style of exposition, which is merely the perfection of the
use of reason itself. With Spinoza's Ethics, the rational style and its use of
reason becomes married with a truly rational—and thus nondual—
philosophy. An apex which rational philosophy has yet to surpass, perhaps.
So “Rationalism,” in the Cartesian and common sense, is largely
synonymous with the intellectual rigor of a geometrical style and its
emphasis on reason. But the tool of Cartesian rationality, again, did not
reach the truths and understanding ultimately accessible through its
properly self-consistent use, to reach its full potential.
Spinoza, on the other hand, was the first to take this tool into its depths,
and really map out the philosophical territory and paradigm of the Rational
in detail, and in the modern, rational style so finely polished by Descartes.
And as we shall see, Leibniz then came along afterword, explored this same
rational territory, and expanded it greatly into its mathematical sphere with
the help of Spinoza's map. Leibniz, however, employed a radically different

i
This is seen in Spinoza's fundamental anti-Platonism, recall.

Page | 671
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

intrinsic agenda for the development of his reactionary interpretation, as we


will see.
It is often thought that the fantastic and sometimes absurd doctrines of
Leibniz—the “third Cartesian”—represent the culmination of the rationalist
and Cartesian paradigm—from Descartes through Spinoza and ultimately to
Leibniz—into a self-reductio ad absurdum. We have already seen in detail,
however, how and why Spinoza was—and considered himself to be—anti-
Cartesian. Descartes, as demonstrated by Spinoza, was seriously confused.
Leibniz too considered Descartes confused and himself profoundly anti-
Cartesian.i And, as we shall see, it is only Leibniz's recoil in the face of a full,
and indeed a nondual Rationalism and modernity—as we find at least
implicitly in Spinoza—that forced him into such an odd, fantastic and
fascinatingly modern, yet anti-modern position. This intrinsic recoil itself
impelled Leibniz—against his esoteric sympathies and resonances with
Spinoza, and against his own rational logic—into a subtle, yet critical
exoteric collapse into similarities with the proto-rationality of Descartes.
Stewart writes:
[Leibniz's] work represents a species of modern thought best described
as “reactive,” inasmuch as it involves a characteristically modern
repudiation of modernity in the name of values that are imagined to have
been realized better in, among other places, the medieval world (p328).
So we can see the Leibnizian reaction as an injection into the modernity of
rationality, the truths of the pre-rational and mythic era of the medieval,
culminating with the proto-rational exposition of Descartes. These
Leibnizian Cartesianisms begin with a return to a plurality of substances and
end in a mind-body dualism and mythic-level Theology and Theocracy.
Leibniz needed this plurality of substances to reassign the pre-rational
categorical absolutism of individual immortality to the human soul, rescuing
it from the ONE-ALL identity in the esoteric anima-mundi of Spinoza. Given,
however, that the key notion of substance, even in Leibniz, is absolute
independence—and that the only absolute independence in a truly Nondual
Rationalism is the univocal tautology of the ONE-ALL, itself taken abstractly
and epistemically as absolute scope—this then illuminates the
fundamentally dualistic stance which Leibniz had taken, with each substance
absolutely independent of all the infinite others, and all of them somehow
independent of God their creator, and vice versa. This is why Leibnizian
monads have “no windows,” and can only “interact” with other monads
through the equivalent of “magic mirrors” in a perfectly pre-established, and
predetermined “harmony,” as we will see. If they did have windows or
causal connections of perception, then other substances or modifications
would determine a monad’s essence, and vice versa, through a causal

i
…but then again he considered himself profoundly anti-Spinozan as well…

Page | 672
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

interaction. In this case individual immortality, and God himself, would


collapse into the nondual and esoteric ONE-ALL of the anima-mundi.
Substances, thus dependently arising with one another, would cease to be
substances—plurality, as in Zeno, would collapse into the Parmenidean
Unity of the Being-now, and would have to be extracted as Spinozan aspects
of The Infinite.
This brief excursion into the monadology immediately raises many
problems, as we will see. The obvious one is the absurdity of perception in
the Leibnizian system. When monads—you and I—can have no real causal
perceptual interface with each other, but our interactions were prescripted
an eternity ago by our creator—timed, like two independent clocks, to an
infinite harmonious perfection—what then can Leibniz mean by
“perception”? Another problem leading directly toward tension and collapse
into the rational ONE-ALL, is the incongruence of a Theological creation with
the idea of substance. How can monads be substances given their obvious
dependence on God when he chooses to flash them into existence, setting up
their eternal and infinitely coordinated scripts of action, on which they again
are dependent? We’ll get to these problems in detail and in due time.
This dualism of absolutized categories is the Cartesianism inherent in
Leibniz, as it is inherent in the mythic level of the pre-rational, extending all
the way down to the dualisms of Plato and Aristotle. God himself, in such a
system, is a substance distinct and apart from the univocal ONE-ALL of the
Rational and its implicit acategorical imperative. And when this pre-rational
dualism is then mixed on equal footing with the truths of the Rational—such
as the immanence of the continuum—the logical absurdities (irrationalities)
inherent in dualism become magnified to the infinity at the heart of the
Rational. This rationalist recoil, accompanied by a reinjection and
integration of pre-rational and medieval Augustinian Theology and
Theocracy, reveals the absurdity not of the Rational taken to its logical
conclusion, but of the conflation and con-fusion that occurs when the truths
of the Rational are indiscriminately mixed together with the truths of the
pre-rational. This, then, points to the value of the Integral model and of
Wilber’s notion of the “pre/trans fallacy,” which demonstrates that the
attempt to mix the levels of development together, as if on equal footing and
with identical criterion of judgment, can only lead to con-fusion. This model
and its integral level of development, recognizes the truths and differences
between the levels, on their own terms and at their own levels of development.

In order to understand this Leibnizian recoil against the radical


modernity and full-blown Nondual Rationalism implicit in Spinoza, we must
first understand its historical context. Spinoza, in the half century following
his death, was an infamous and widely vilified man, and yet he was vastly

Page | 673
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

influential at a deep and hidden level. As Philip Clayton writes in his The
Problem of God in Modern Thought:
…one has to recall that the term Spinozism represented to the late
seventeenth century—and especially to a thinker who was by nature a
mediator and who thus worried about the orthodox appearance of his
thought—a dangerous and pernicious heresy. Like the term murder, its
use implied immediately that one had done something wrong. Yet like
other heresies in the history of thought, it also exercised a seductive
attraction on metaphysicians of the period (and not just then!). One must
finally agree with Catherine Wilson: “Spinoza was, in a sense, Leibniz’s
ghost. He was what Leibniz was afraid of being and saw himself as
dangerously capable of becoming; the [Spinozan] doctrine that God was in
some way related to creatures as a whole to its parts, not as an extra item,
was one which obsessed him.
And as Matthew Stewart writes in The Courtier and the Heretic:
Justice is no more assured in the history of thought than it is in the rest of
human experience. In the crucial half century after his death—the
crucible of modernity—Spinoza was arguably the most important
philosopher in the world. Yet his influence was mostly negative and
almost always unacknowledged. The incalculable impact he had on
Leibniz is only one example, albeit the finest, of the immense but nearly
invisible power Spinoza wielded over his contemporaries (p307).
Spinoza’s philosophy deeply unfolded the hidden nondual truths of the
Rational, as we have seen. It was thus the very antithesis of the pre-rational,
exoteric, transcendent-biased and oppositional forces of representation,
entrenched in the power structures of his day. Like a hot cinder on a cold
block of butter, this radically new philosophy—at once both repugnant and
irresistible—passed into the representational power structures and
ideologies which it opposed, and from generation to generation left its
cryptic trail only in the distortions surrounding it; i.e. the obscuring defenses
built up against it. Precisely because Spinoza was so vehemently vilified, the
cultural lens surrounding his philosophy became radically distorted, with
numerous defects persisting to this day.

Leibniz’s obsessed and repulsed reaction from the pre-rational “City of God”
was simply one of the first, strongest and most compelling of these many
distorting interpretations. But Leibniz wasn’t just reacting externally or
transitively to Spinoza. As is shown in various accounts, Leibniz possessed a
profound inner tension secretly both towards, and publically against what
many scholars see as his own intrinsic “heretical” Spinozism. Indeed, in
seeming accordance with his own principle of activity—which states that a
body cannot react to a force without an interior active resonance of

Page | 674
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

“perception” within that body and to that force—in the vastly complicated
interior folds of the vinculum of the monad of Leibniz himself, a Spinozan
logic unfolded in secret as a function of his own intrinsically rational
principles. It was this inner Spinozan resonance that allowed Leibniz his
outward Spinozan dissonance.
Bertrand Russell writes, “… Leibniz fell into Spinozism whenever he
allowed himself to be logical; in his published works, accordingly, he took
care to be illogical.” Indeed, Russell felt that Leibniz had two distinct
philosophies. The inner one, akin to the brazen heresies of Spinoza, and the
outer one, cowed and contorted in accord with the orthodoxy of his times.
For this reason, Russell considered Leibniz a great logician, but a scoundrel
of sorts who lacked the conviction or courage of his own true philosophy.
It is difficult, however, for us to comprehend the danger of the times for a
free thinker challenging the status-quo and its political power structures.
Spinoza had put his life on the line with the publication of works such as the
Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, and nearly paid for it with an attempted
assassination—the knife in the dark leaving its open wound only in the
threads of Spinoza’s overcoat. After this, Spinoza adopted the thorny signet
ring of Caute, or “Caution,” as the seal for all his correspondences.
Given these dangerous conditions for thought, and given Leibniz’s
profession as a court barrister within the very bowels of the pre-rational
power structure itself, one can quickly see what devastating consequences
would follow such a courage for a man such as Leibniz. It’s impossible to
understand the effects this had on the inner Leibniz. And perhaps we can be
grateful for Leibniz’s shrewdness in hiding his inner conflicts from those
who would never understand them. Without this subterfuge, perhaps, we’d
have none of the profound truths and tools Leibniz invented along with his
fascinating and fantastically Baroque philosophical reaction.
Matthew Stewart notes that along with this inner Leibnizian Spinozism
coincided a profound inner reaction against Spinoza as well. Stewart writes:
It is too simple by an order of magnitude to say either that Leibniz was a
Spinozist, with Stein, or that he was never a Spinozist, with Freidman.
The truth is that before he knew anything about Spinoza, Leibniz was
against Spinoza; and yet, at the same time, he also had a Spinozistic side.
The encounter with Spinoza was crucial to his philosophical development
because it forced him to confront this division within his own thought.
Spinoza presented him with a problem he devoted his philosophical
labors to solving, namely, how to suppress the dangerous Spinozist within
himself. Absent the dalliance with Spinoza, Leibniz would have remained
a conservative thinker; but he would not have been an essentially modern
one, and his philosophy would not have originated the reactive form of
modernity. To make a long story even more complicated: It is quite
plausible to say that, before, after, and during their encounter, Leibniz
was deeply anti-Spinozistic, superficially anti-Spinozistic, and deeply

Page | 675
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Spinozistic, all at the same time. The only thing that cannot be said, in my
view, is that for Leibniz Spinoza did not matter (p331).
As we will see, and as Stewart aptly demonstrates, at nearly every turn,
Leibniz’s privately expressed Spinozistic logic impelled him toward this
radical rationality already embodied in heretical Spinozism. And in every
instance, his inner and outer anti-Spinozist and anti-modernist compelled
him to invent a fantastic metaphysical contrivance to counteract this
dangerous and heretical Spinozism. It is indeed because his inner rational
truths are so strong and deep, that his reaction against them is so fabulous
and informative.
Through detailed studies of Leibniz’s private correspondence, Stewart
shows that this Spinozism was implicit in Leibniz from his secret readings of
Spinoza’s work long before their meeting in the Hague. During this time, for
example, while Leibniz was reading Spinoza’s Tractatus, he would write of
the book to his contemporaries and patrons that it was “terrifying,”
“monstrous,” and “intolerably impudent,” even feigning ignorance of the
name of its author, while simultaneously writing favorably of it in his notes
and penning a clandestine letter to Spinoza in praise of his work, in order
eventually to secure a secret meeting with him.
In the year 1676, recall, Leibniz began his Spinoza studies. Indeed,
Stewart writes, “Leibniz’s interest in Spinoza began to take on the character
of an obsession,” where he would attempt to secure any and all of Spinoza’s
writings he could possibly get his hands on (p187). And it was this
obsession, recall, through which Leibniz found his Ariadne’s thread out of
the labyrinth of the continuum, as well as his solution to the problem of the
calculus, after locating and copying out Spinoza’s Letter XII on the infinite.i*
During this year as well, Leibniz had a lengthy discussion with his friend
Tschirnhaus in which the contents of Spinoza’s “secret philosophy”—the
Ethics—were spelled out. The influence of this discussion is seen in blatant
Spinozisms in Leibniz’s notes of the time. At this point for Leibniz, as for
Spinoza, God and Nature are ONE. But later on, near the point of their
meeting, Leibniz “suddenly recants” his unwitting “collapse” (or advance)
into Spinozism saying:
“God is not something metaphysical…so that it would be the same if you
were to say that God is nature…. Rather, God is a certain substance, a
person, a mind.” (p184)
Leibniz then sets himself the task: “It must be shown that God is a person,
i.e., an intelligent substance.”ii¥ As we have seen,iii* on a ferry boat just prior

i
* See, The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite, p407.
ii¥
VI.iii.518; DSR, p. 26
iii
* See, The Exoteric Face of Esoteric Rationalism, p67.

Page | 676
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

to his meeting with Spinoza, Leibniz reveals the original difference between
he and Spinoza, saying [my emphasis]:
“A metaphysics should be written with accurate definitions and
demonstrations. But nothing should be demonstrated in it apart from
that which does not clash too much with received opinions. For in
that way this metaphysics can be accepted; and once it has been
approved then, if people examine it more deeply later, they themselves
will draw the necessary consequences. …” (p187)
“At this point,” writes Stewart, “Leibniz was a Spinozist and he knew it.”
His strategy would be to conceal his true views wherever they offended
the orthodox, to cite great men such as Plato and Parmenides as a
diversion, and, in general, to work for the day when Spinozism might
emerge out from under the false accusations of heresy and claim its
rightful place in the sun. In the meantime…Leibniz would censor
himself…of…thoughts that the world was not ready to receive (p187).
We can see here that Leibniz and Spinoza had drastically different strategies
for interfacing their esoteric philosophies with the exoteric public. Leibniz’s
public interest was, as he himself admitted, in establishing a “popular
religion” and theocracy, a “City of God.” And after this fateful meeting in the
Hague, as Stewart shows, and as we will see, Leibniz willfully converts his
esoteric Spinozism into exoteric contortions largely because the truths of
Spinoza’s radical modernism are incompatible with, and intolerable to the
masses, let alone even to himself.
This is the original function of his monadology; to explode the truths of
esoteric modernity and rationality into the exoteric trappings of a
transcendent, anthropomorphic and pre-rational God, in a tensile and polar
arrangement to the immortality of the individual soul. In this reaction,
Leibniz fractured Spinoza’s ONE=ALL of God/Substance into an ALL of
infinitely many monads (ones), but only in order to separate the ONE of God
out of the identity of the equation and into a transitive and causal relation of
dependency with it, as we will see. Indeed, as we have already glimpsed, in
doing so he placed the omni of the ONE outside of the reach of logic and
rationality, where we will see it collapses into the non of a mythic vacuum of
logic.
On the surface, Leibniz essentially reverted the Parmenidean and
esoteric rational ONE to the pre-rational, mythic and exoteric Christian God
of pure transcendence. All of Leibniz’s reactions against his own Spinozism,
then, can be traced to the single idea that God is not immanent, but only and
purely transcendent … and we’ll see what happens when transcendence is
absolutized or “purified” without its identity with immanence.

Page | 677
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

The rejection of Spinoza’s God as Nature—the ONE as the ALL, and the
anima mundi of the omni-axis—becomes the first principle of Leibniz’s
mature philosophy. Leibniz rejected Spinoza’s God essentially because it has
no will nor intellect in order to be “good” and deserving of the name of
“God.” And with this Spinozan identification of the ONE and the ALL, exoteric
and top-down morality can have no basis. This first principle of Leibniz’s
philosophy, we can see, is essentially that God is not immanent, and we’ll see
this echo throughout the rest of the Leibnizian reaction, building a profound
tension between the immanence of man and the transcendence of God, or
1/∞ vs. ∞/1, respectively.

Leibniz asks the critical question that can be asked of Spinozism. Can
Spinoza’s God be properly considered “God” at all if it is merely Nature?
Stewart writes:
According to Spinoza, God or Nature causes the things of the world in the
same way that the nature of coffee causes it to be black. But we do not
usually say that the nature of coffee is divine, so why should we say that
Nature is divine? Leibniz’s position here might be stated this way: what is
divine must be in some way beyond or before what is natural, or else it is
not divine at all (p236).
This implies a false analogy, however, because the nature of coffee, as
opposed to the nature of anything else, say tea, is just a deeper level of
modification (an immanent plane of transitive causation), rather than
corresponding to Spinoza’s implicit definition of Substance as an immanent
emphasis on the I/T axis. In other words, what we would call nature, even
as in “the nature of the physical world,” is not what Spinoza would call
Nature as Substance at all. Rather it would generally pass for nothing more
than the modifications known as the biosphere—or perhaps the
“physiosphere,” objectivity, or a plane of immanent transitivity. All of these,
as we have seen, are merely subsets of modification or form.
Spinoza’s Substance—like Nagarjuna’s Emptiness—is the identical
opposite of “form” and of modification. God as Nature, then, would simply
denote the ONE as enfolding the ALL, and hence God, in Spinoza, is seen as
intrinsically animate, as it enfolds and unfolds nature herself. This is,
however, one of the main distorted criticisms of Spinoza we see in Leibniz,
and echoed into Hegel: that Spinoza’s Substance is “rigid” or inanimate. And
this animate immanence and ALL in his own infinitely divided or folded

Page | 678
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

substance(s) is exactly what Leibniz uses to counter his distorted caricature


of Spinoza.i

Stewart continues [my comments]:


In arguing that God must be good, Leibniz puts his finger on a related
paradox in Spinoza’s thinking. To say that nature is divine is in some way
to judge the world—usually, to imply that the world as a whole is good. ...
Spinoza himself says that the world is “perfect.” But according to
Spinoza’s own logic, the totality of things lies beyond all human judgment
[precisely because it is perfect]. It is neither good nor bad. Now, says
Leibniz, if Spinoza cannot say that the world is good, he certainly cannot
say that it is perfect, except in the most abstract sense meaning ‘complete’
or ‘all that there is.’ He cannot judge or ‘affirm’ the world in the way one
must if one says that it is divine. Therefore, he has no license to give
Nature the name of God, as he claims to do.
Spinoza’s notion of perfection transcends the limits of anthropocentrism,
however, and is indeed a boundless totality of immanent, transcendent and
transitive causation. His affirmation of this absolute perfection is similar to
the Buddha’s or to Nietzsche’s affirmation of reality—an affirmation beyond
the anthropic limitations of Good and Evil and beyond the passions. Spinoza
calls it God because he finds this realization of boundless, all-encompassing
immanence and transcendence far more majestic and awe-inspiring than an
anthropic and limited God with jealousies, desires, and a need for a will to
get or do what it lacks. There is a raw aesthetic experiential judgment in the
face of the mystery of The Infinite, and the label of “God” is the only thing
that comes close to invoking the feelings and intuitions of this immensity.
Indeed, God is the only name that will correspond with the “intellectual love”
Spinoza consciously projects onto and into that infinite perfection through
his identity of the ONE-ALL.

After Leibniz’s encounter with Spinoza in the Hague, says Stewart


“Something went wrong.” Leibniz writes:
“If all possibles were to exist, there would be no need of a reason for
existing, and mere possibility would be enough. So there would not be a
God, except insofar as he is possible. But a God of the kind in which the
pious believe would not be possible, if the opinion of those who believe
that all possibles exist were true” (p207-8).

i
Recall also that Spinoza mentions explicitly in his Short Treatise that God is anything but passive
and therefore can only be seen as active.

Page | 679
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

In other words, if Spinoza is correct then the orthodox God of “the pious” is
impossible because he doesn’t choose to create the world, or to interact with
it, but rather it merely ‘emanates’ from his nature. Leibniz continues, “If all
things emanate of necessity from the divine nature, then all possible things
exist, with equal ease unfortunately for the good and the bad. Therefore
moral philosophy is destroyed.” According to Leibniz, this Spinozan idea
that “matter assumes all forms possible successively” is “the proton pseudos
[first lie] and foundation of the atheistic philosophy”(p224).
However, it would seem impossible to argue that the possible has not
been, and is not now equal to the actual, in some sphere in this inconceivably
infinite and eternal universe. For if a thing is possible, and there are infinite
chances (times and places) for this possibility to become actual, then the
likelihood of its not actualizing reduces to zero. Stated another way, an
event with any possibility whatsoever will have a finite probability greater
than zero, and this number—even the smallest conceivable number—
multiplied by infinity is … infinity. We’ve seen this in the paradoxes of the
infinite, as well as encoded in our Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity,
represented in our VLE: ab2.
Assuming Leibniz is right, however, if an event is possible, yet never has
been nor will be actual, what can this possibility mean? Leibniz has a ready
answer for just that question, as we will see.

Leibniz offers a rare confession about his precarious position with respect to
the Spinozan actual-possible. He says:
“When I considered that nothing occurs by chance ... and that nothing
exists unless certain conditions are fulfilled from all of which together its
existence at once follows, I found myself very close to the opinions of
those who hold everything to be absolutely necessary [i.e. Spinoza]... But I
was pulled back from this precipice by considering those possible things
which neither are nor will be nor have been” (p220-1).
Twenty-five years later Leibniz would admit that he had once “leaned to the
side of the Spinozists” and that “these new lights have healed me, and since
that time I have sometimes taken the name of Theophile.”
Leibniz’s Theophilic answer to Spinoza’s God of “immanence in
transcendence” is what would appear to be a purely transcendent God,
outside of all space and time. Stewart writes:
...Leibniz provides a more vivid representation of this idea of God. In the
final pages of his Theodicy, a character named Theodorus (Leibniz’s alter
ego in this instance) falls asleep in a temple and begins to dream. In his
reverie he visits “a palace of unimaginable splendor and prodigious
size”—an edifice that, as it happens, belongs to God. The halls in the
palace represent possible worlds. As Theodorus wanders through this

Page | 680
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

magnificent construction, he tours a variety of worlds in which things


happened very differently than in our own: worlds in which Adam did not
eat the apple, for instance, and worlds in which Judas kept his mouth shut.

“The halls rose in a pyramid, becoming even more beautiful as one mounted
toward the apex, and representing more beautiful worlds. Finally they
reached the highest one which completed the pyramid, and which was the
most beautiful of all: ... for the pyramid had an apex, but no base; it went on
increasing to infinity. That is ... because amongst an endless number of
possible worlds there is the best of all, else God would not have determined
to create any” (p237).
The central feature of Leibniz’s mature philosophy, Stewart notes, is “his
representation of God’s choice in terms of possible worlds—as opposed to
possible things.” This, then, is Leibniz's infamous “principle of the best.”
This marks what Leibniz believed was one of his decisive breakthroughs
in the ten years after his journey to The Hague. (p238).
Prior to this time, however, Leibniz found it difficult to conceive of merely
possible things. This is because his Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR)—
essentially that all things must have a logical reason for existing—demands
that no-thing be ultimately accidental or random. All things in Leibniz’s
infinitely interconnected and rationalistic world are ultimately pre-
determined, and actual, not merely possible [my comments].
“Because of the interconnection of things,” he acknowledges at the time of
his Discourse, “the universe with all its parts would be wholly different
from the commencement if the least thing in it happened otherwise than
it had.” [Note that this is an anticipation of the “butterfly effect” in
modern complexity science.] By raising God’s choice to the level of
possible worlds, however, Leibniz can have his Principle of Sufficient
Reason and eat it, too, in a sense: that is, he can grant that all things within
our world are linked together in a necessary way while still maintaining
that the world as a whole does not necessarily have to be the way that it
is. “The reasons for the world,” he says, “lie in something extramundane”
(p238).
Leibniz then, in accord with his PSR, maintains the Spinozan equation
between the possible and actual, but isolates and encapsulates this
problematic equation into his bounded conception of worlds, leaving God’s
“extramundane” world of worlds free from logic and free from the Spinozist
and rationalist constraints implicit in the fundamental Leibnizian PSR. One
then wonders how indeed this world of worlds has spontaneously self-
ordered into this bottomless pyramid of ever more perfect worlds, without
an infinitely perfect and interconnected logic of its own to accomplish such a
supertask, leaving this good God the no-brainer of merely plucking the top-
most ripe, yet merely possible world for “actualization” into this “best of all
possible worlds.”

Page | 681
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Leibniz also rejects the Spinozan notion of modal impermanence and


personal mortality. Stewart notes, “If the mind is the idea of the body, he
reasons, then it must perish with the body; and this contradicts the doctrine
of personal immortality.” Clearly Leibniz is recoiling in the face of the
nondual truths of modernity and rationality; reactively clinging to an
absolutized category, a pre-rational self-identity and permanence which
Spinoza, like Nagarjuna, would pulverize in their quest to maintain
authenticity in reason.
Even more than he [Leibniz] wants to convince us that God is good, he
wants to convince us that we are the most special beings in nature. In the
entire universe, he says, there is nothing more real or more permanent or
more worthy of love than the individual human soul (p241).
This reactionary reinstatement of individual permanence was the whole
function of the designation of the monad as an independent substance and
its assignment to the human soul. Barring their problems of dependency on
God, if souls are substances, as we indeed also find in Descartes, then they
are independent of the body and its modifications and deconstructions.
They are thus immortal. This view, however, “that we are the most special
beings in nature” is resonant with the integrally and holarchically
interpreted Spinoza in that the human monad possesses more depth (though
necessarily less span)i* and therefore, in a sense, enfolds and unfolds more
reality than the rest of the natural world (at least on earth). Man has
transcended-and-included nature, or the physio- and bio-sphere, and is at
the apex of his awareness of individual awareness itself.
... The human being is the new God, he announces: Each of us is “a small
divinity and eminently a universe: God in ectype and the universe in
prototype.” This is the idea that defines Leibniz’s philosophy, and that
explains the enormous, if often unacknowledged, influence that his
thought has wielded in the past three centuries of human history (p241).
This too, is generally resonant with a properly interpreted Spinoza. But, as
Stewart shows, in its absolutized form in the monadic substance, the
Leibnizian theory of immortality has met its match in modernity.
Leibniz takes issue with Spinoza’s emergent modal view of the human
mind on the correct grounds that all finite modes are dependent, and
therefore also finite in time, “merely a chaff blowing in the silent winds of
nature.” So Leibniz must postulate a world prior to the “material” world,
made of eternal mind-monads, e.g. you and me.

i
* See, Depth vs. Span: Further Untangling the Trans-Trans-Bias, p573.

Page | 682
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

As we have already glimpsed, however, Spinoza’s concept of real


difference goes far beyond the mere materiality of extension and reaches
into the absolute. Real difference explicitly demonstrates—as does Zeno,
effectively—that any view of substance as plurality is logically inconsistent.
This is because in order for two things to really differ, they must inter-
express this difference in an immanent and inter-dependent similarity—a
dependent arising and identity of opposites. This logical inconsistency in
Leibniz is seen with the contradiction of monads as substances in
dependence on God for their creation and their very definition, insofar as
actualizing the best of possible worlds is a creation act at all. And if it isn’t,
then Leibniz’s God deserves the name even less than does Spinoza's, given
that he is beholden to the laws and decrees of this world of all possible
worlds in which he has found himself; a world of worlds properly already
identified, through the univocal concept of real difference, as Spinoza's God.

In his notes, Leibniz explicitly rejects Spinoza’s definition of Substance as


that which is “in itself” and “conceived through itself.” He says now that a
substance is indeed “in itself,” but not “conceived through itself.” Rather,
Leibniz proclaims, it can only be “conceived through God” (p243). Leibniz
gives extensive quasi-mathematical argumentation that the number of
substance/monads must be infinite due to the labyrinth of the continuum
and the infinite divisibility of extension. He seized “monads” from the Greek
word for “unity” first used by Giordano Bruno.
This is Leibniz’s quasi-logical justification of the radical shift in the
definition of substance from absolute independence to dependence on the
absolute. In Spinoza, God is Substance precisely because substance has
always been defined explicitly as independent, and the only “thing” that can
be rationally conceived as independent is the boundless and tautological
ONE-ALL itself. Leibnizian immanently bounded substances (1/∞),
however, with their shift to the relativity of forms, has not enfolded its
opposite, but merely adopted its properties illegitimately and illogically, in a
dependence on a transcendently bounded God (∞/1). It thus cannot be
equated with Spinozan Substance, but more properly with absolutized and
eternalized modifications, akin to Plato’s forms. In essence, Leibnizian
substance is an arbitrary mixture of the traditional definition of substance as
independent, with the one exception for a dependency on a medieval, pre-
rational and mythic-level God, all of which making for a bizarre confusion
and tension.
Leibniz’s monads are a finitized extension of an infinite God—but
ultimately a con-fusion between the independent and inoperable properties
of the absolute, with the necessary dependencies, boundaries and operations
of the relative. Rather than a univocal and nondual integration as we find in

Page | 683
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

the ONE-ALL, in the Leibnizian dichotomy of God and the monads—the


charged bounded forms of the infinite, ∞/1 vs. 1/∞—we find a profound
tension as the absolute is illegitimately and illogically extended into the
relative to impart its tautological and absolute property of permanence on
the relativities of form.
To accomplish this, Leibniz tacitly shifts his definition of unity from the
Spinozan absolute scope Infinite Unity—in the identity of God and Substance
on the I/T axis—to a finite unity. With this shift from Infinite to finite unity
comes a corresponding “principle of unity” directly in accord with Spinoza’s
definition of finite essence. Recall that the definition of finite essence in
Spinoza is essentially a function of homeostasis, a strange attractor of
implicit potential, of sorts. The complimentary Leibnizian principle of
(finite) unity, likewise, has a complexity-science feel, as essentially a
principle of emergence. Leibnizian unity and substance is defined ultimately
as a whole greater than the sum of its parts, i.e. not merely an aggregate, but
whole unto itself; not merely an organization but an organism; not a heap,
but a holon. However, since the only dependency allowed them by Leibniz is
that upon God their creator (or conceiver … or flip switcher … or dupe of The
Infinite), monads cannot emerge in a dependent arising with other monads,
and thus, as we have seen, they can have no “windows,” or real perceptions.
They can only “interact” through magic mirrors in a purely pre-established
“harmony” of routines. Thus we have the con-fusion of emergence and
eternity in the absolutized relativities of the Leibnizian monads.

Monads are eternal ... with the exception that, in order to cleave a
transcendent, and indeed transitive, space for God with a bit of smoke and
mirrors, they can be created or destroyed with an attendant flash, all
supposedly outside of time, and outside of the core Leibnizian principles,
such as the principle of activity, and sufficient reason. Instead of windows,
eternal monads flash into existence complete with “mirrors,” which can
miraculously show their monads the entire universe and their place within
it, all somehow without any real conduit or interface to the outside. This is
because, recall, being substances, monads can’t arise with any external
dependencies whatsoever. Indeed, one must ask why a mirror is any less a
function of causal interaction than a lens, except merely that it breaks the
line of the light into reflected and redirected segments, rather than merely
bending it, thus interrupting our simple linear correlation with the
perception to its object. I suppose this is like questioning the logic of a good
fantasy or science fiction book, however, which, of course, spoils the effect.

Page | 684
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

So we allow Leibniz his “magic mirror on the wall,” and in the interior folds
and vinculum of his infinite eternal monads.
By means of these 'mirrors' of consciousness, each monad replicates the
entire universe of monads within itself; and so each monad is a “universe
in prototype.” Leibniz refers to this strange vision of worlds within
worlds as “the principle of macrocosm and microcosm”—meaning that
the microcosm contains or replicates the macrocosm all the way down to
the infinitely small. He expresses the same notion in his claim that the
ancient doctrine that “All is One” must now be supplemented with the
equally important corollary that “One is All” (p245).
We have already discussed the con-fusion here in the context of the
univocity framework.i* Essentially, recall, Leibniz has tacitly equivocated
from the absolute scope of the 1st order Absolute Infinity—taken in the
ancient “All is One,” (our balanced VLE ∞/∞)—to the relative scope of the
monad at the level of the 3rd order infinite, or bounded infinite (our charged
VLE 1/∞). The ALL-ONE was already the ONE-ALL, but the Leibnizian “One
is All” shifts through the Cycle of unity to the interface of the uni-axis, and to
the one of many. The “principle of macrocosm and microcosm” is thus not
quite the logical corollary, of the ONE-ALL, which is why the mirrors
themselves are “tarnished” by the finite variable, n. Stewart says the mirrors
are “splotchy,” and Badiou says, “Deleuze’s subject, the subject-as-fold, has
its numeric formula 1/oo, which is the formula for the monad, even if its
clear part is 1/n (Fold p. 178).” Thus the “All”—reflected in the clear part of
the splotchy mirror of the monad—in Leibniz’s “principle of macrocosm and
microcosm”—is not the ALL of the ancient ONE-ALL, but merely the Many of
the One and the Many.
These splotchy magic mirrors (or pre-established virtual reality
simulators), give an imprecise view of reality, and it is this imperfection of
window-less “perception” (in a prescripted harmony) that gives distinction
and individuality to each monad. Furthermore, according to Leibniz, it is
this same lack of perfect knowledge or virtual-perception which imparts the
gift of free-will on the monad. A strange freedom indeed being the “gift” of
absolute perceptual isolation and relative imperfections in the magic mirror
of each monad, a bunch of splotches merely obscuring the fact of a purely
pre-scripted and pre-determined existence.

Contained within any eternal monad is its entire pre-scripted history—


which (thank God for those splotchy mirrors) it is unaware of, thus allowing

i
* See, The Univocity Framework In Action: Leibniz and the “Principle of Macrocosm and
Microcosm”, p195.

Page | 685
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

it a “freedom” of the will. As Leibniz says, monads are “pregnant with the
future.” Individual monads, such as the Leibniz monad, “begin” as seeds,
floating around for eternity like particles of dust or atoms, agglomerating
into a larger entity here, dissolving again there. Thus, according to Leibniz,
monads can grow and develop, and they can also disintegrate and devolve.
This conception—as pleasing as it may sound to float around for a near
eternity as a speck of dusti—posed a vexing problem for Leibniz’s followers.
Which one of your parents, mom or dad, contained your monad—you—as a
seed? This was known as the “problem of sex,” and we can see it as
essentially the inversion of the paradox of the amoeba.ii*
Ultimately, again the problem comes down to the indivisibility of the
category of the individual, except this time the division occurs in reverse,
with the process of sex merging, in a sense, the identity of two “individuals.”
If an indivisible monad is the essence of your individual identity, and you are
created in the merger of two individuals, then indeed it must be asked which
parent’s gonad housed your monad—your mom’s or your dad’s? “…And
why do you look like a mixture of them both?”

The problems with Leibniz's “principle of the best,” seem to multiply to


infinity with each of the auto-generating worlds in his world of all possible
worlds. The most superficial, yet entertaining of these worlds of all possible
problems is best exemplified by Voltaire’s parody of Leibniz in his Candide.
The essence of the Leibnizian philosophy is portrayed in Candide by the
character of Dr. Pangloss—literally a gloss over the ALL… and/or (perhaps
no less apt) a loss or numbness to pangs. Voltaire writes:
Master Pangloss taught the metaphysico-theologo-cosmolonigology. He
could prove to admiration that there is no effect without a cause; and, that
in this best of all possible worlds, the Baron's castle was the most
magnificent of all castles, and My Lady the best of all possible baronesses.
“It is demonstrable,” said he, “that things cannot be otherwise than as
they are; for as all things have been created for some end, they must
necessarily be created for the best end. Observe, for instance, the nose is
formed for spectacles, therefore we wear spectacles. The legs are visibly
designed for stockings, accordingly we wear stockings. Stones were made
to be hewn and to construct castles, therefore My Lord has a magnificent
castle; for the greatest baron in the province ought to be the best lodged.
Swine were intended to be eaten, therefore we eat pork all the year

i
* See, Immortality…as a “Speck of Dust”?, p694).
ii
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.

Page | 686
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

round: and they, who assert that everything is right, do not express
themselves correctly; they should say that everything is best.
According to Leibniz, bear in mind, the Spinozan equation of the possible
with the actual is “the proton pseudos” or first lie of “the atheistic
philosophy.” Recall also our mathematical demonstration that, in an infinite
universe any finite possibility whatsoever would have an infinite chance of
being actualized, putting its probability of occurrence exactly at one—
somewhere and somewhen in this infinitely infinite universe of universes.
We then gave Leibniz the benefit of the mathematical doubt, granting the
good doctor the claim that “OK, all possibles are not all actuals.” The Von of
all possible Leibniz’s then exclaims, “Oh contraire! In this best of all worlds,
governed by this best of all principles, and hence with amply sufficient
reason, all possibles are indeeeeed actual!!” “But!,” proclaims the doctor,
“This best of all worlds is not the only one possible!!!”
Dr. Von Leibniz then reveals that an infinite number of possible worlds
actually exist and yet will never exist actually. And in each of these possible
worlds there actually exist an infinite number of possibles which also will
never exist … actually. “This is because,” beams the good doctor, “there is
actually a world of all possible worlds, within which, self-assembled into a
bottomless pyramid of worlds of lesser and lesser possible perfection, there
actually sits atop, for all eternity, an apex!” This actual possible, it turns out,
is actually the best of all possible worlds, and possibly the best of all actual
worlds.
“God!,” explodes the doctor, “Being ‘good,’ as he is by nature, need select
only this ‘best of the best,’ in order to retain his title as… God.” And thus he
does . . . effectively consigning the rest of all possible worlds, and the rest of
all unfortunately impossibly-possible inhabitants, to the actual dustbin of
the incompossible, in this pyramid and world of infinitely actual possibles,
yet only one possibly actual world.
We then ask again, “Pray tell, Dr. Von, what possibly can be the meaning
of ‘possibility’ in this actual world of infinite possibly impossible worlds, and
their actually possibly impossible inhabitants in this best—and indeed in the
rest—of all possibly impossible worlds?!”

The problem rising to the surface in this infinite Leibnizian game seems to
be a contradiction of Leibniz's own Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR). In
constructing his world of all worlds, in which Leibniz can have his PSR and
eat it too, Leibniz has cleaved the world of causal and logical integrity off
into a purely arbitrary “fantasy world of all worlds.” In this fantasy land,
outside of space and time, apparently anything can happen. It thus fulfills
Leibniz's need of displacing the PSR and once again offering God a “moral”
choice in order to demonstrate to us his “goodness.” And so, by fiat and
royal decree, it becomes an actual world of mere possibles, already
actualized into a pyramid of mere possibles, timelessly awaiting an eternity

Page | 687
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

for a “good God” to choose to actualize the only one of these actually existing
mere possibles which is the best. In this world of all possible worlds Leibniz
is God. It is by his fiat that the PSR is suspended, and by his decree that this
world has actualized into its pyramid of worlds etc, etc, etc….
Perhaps the only appropriate question to ask is one of aesthetics. Does
this Baroque fantasy appeal to us enough that we can will ourselves into a
belief and faith in it? I am not sure, actually, if any of the infinitely possible
possibles (or merely any of the actuals) has ever really believed in it, or
thought it really even possible, including Leibniz himself—one of the most
eminently logical of all actual thinkers in this actual world of pure actuals.

Perhaps just for fun, we’ll outline these problems more detail, below:

Leibniz contradicts his own fundamental PSR by surreptitiously dividing


reality into (1) God’s extramundane world of all possible worlds which is
exempt from (or deficient of) the causal, spatial, temporal and logical
connection (or integrity) embodied in the PSR, and (2) our “perfect” PSR
world in which there are no real possibilities whatsoever because
everything is already connected and contained in God’s original “choice” of
the best world for us. This choice, recall, supposedly proves or guarantees
that God is “good” and therefore worthy of the name, yet it would seem to
have entirely removed our immanent free-will into the transitivity of the
infinite list of predetermined actions God has written into our nature in the
supposed act of independently-dependent creation of our eternal monadic
existence, with the mere flip of the switch to actualize this pre-determined
best of all possible worlds.
The obvious problem with this scenario is that possibility, like
probability, is a function of space and time. It makes no sense whatsoever
when displaced into a senseless world without space and time. In other
words, the aspects of the relative world, such as possibility and choice, cease
to relate when surreptitiously displaced into the absolute. In the absolute,
recall time becomes the eternal-NOW. Possibility in such an inoperable and
ineffable wonderland instantaneously becomes multiplied to infinity and/or
divided to naught. In such a timeless world too, there can be no choice,
because again, choice demands time. To be meaningful in any sense, choice
demands deliberation, contemplation, all of which presuppose time, space
and causation ala the PSR. And indeed choice demands limitation of the
knowledge of the outcome and the possibility of error, otherwise with
perfect knowledge of all effects, there is no possibility of error and no real
choice. The choice for a true God, is a no-brainer, a flip of a switch that any
“good” computer could make.
And from a Spinozist standpoint of real difference—in which differences
can only realize if they share a common inter-expressivity or dependent

Page | 688
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

arising through which to inter-oppose—how can these two fundamentally


different worlds causally interface without some deeper immanent causal
unity between them, such as a deeper substance or a deeper PSR? Is not this
cleavage of the world of all worlds, from our merely perfect world, the
Cartesian mind-body problem in a different and more absurd dress? Does
God “choose” and actualize this world through his morally divine pineal
vortex?

Furthermore, if within each world everything is wholly interconnected such


that, as Leibniz says, “the universe with all its parts would be wholly different
from the commencement if the least thing in it happened otherwise than it
had” then our existence is wholly incompossible with any other world. In
other words, God had no other choice for us but to actualize this universe in
which all its parts (such as ourselves) are wholly and only compossiblei
therein. Therefore, pushing free-will and choice into the extramundane
world of God does not grant God goodwill toward us, because there is no
other or lesser world to be chosen for us with which we are compossible.
Therefore the PSR, by its very nature, still governs God’s choices with
respect to us because it demands that there is only one world with which
mankind, as it is—i.e. the individuals such as ourselves for which this
beneficent choice is supposedly made—is compossible. Thus Leibniz’s
statements about possible worlds where Adam ate the fruit and Judas kept
his mouth shut are inconsistent with his PSR and principles of
interconnection, and indeed inconsistent with Leibniz's above statement. As
such, God could not have chosen differently with respect to these individuals
because they are only compossible within this one world.

As Stewart mentions, if God, through this one choice, is to demonstrate his


nature as infinitely good and perfect, then he has only one choice, and that is
clearly and necessarily the actual apex. So God’s “choice” is a no-brainer for
him, indeed a necessity stemming from his very nature, and it has no bearing
on a beneficial outcome for mankind but merely amounts to a role as the
automatic cause of the inevitability of man’s actualization and existence as
already ordered and implicit in this only possible world of all actually
impossible worlds. Stewart distills the argument as follows:
How do we know that this is the best of all possible worlds? It cannot be
because we observe it to be so—for, to sift through all possible worlds
and rank them according to their merits requires the kind of omniscience

i
Compossible means “compatibly possible,” essentially, such that a compossibility takes into
account the inter-expressive compatibility of its intrinsic terms.

Page | 689
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

that only God has. It must therefore be because the choice of the best of
all possible worlds follows from God’s nature. In other words, God
chooses the best of all possible worlds because it is in his nature to be
good. God could not do otherwise because if he did so he would not be
good, and therefore he would not be God (p281).
To deal with this problem, Leibniz labors to divide necessity into moral and
metaphysical (causal) varieties. Since God exists in an extramundane and
indeed a “meta-metaphysical” space, Leibniz can then decree that the laws of
this divine world of worlds are purely moral. God is thus exempt from
metaphysical necessity and rather “chooses” the best world out of purely
moral necessity.
However, since Leibniz declares God “good” merely because he decides
to actualize our world, which just happens to be the best and only world in
which we are compossible, then what about the disservice God does to those
inhabitants of the rest of all possible worlds by choosing our world to
actualize and not theirs? Is not God evil in their eyes, and rightly so, since he
effectively condemns the inhabitants of these slightly and ever lesser worlds
to an existence of nonexistence in this extramundane pyramidal necropolis
of worlds?!? Does not this “moral necessity” of choosing only one world thus
generate a moral “evil” along with its moral “good”? And is not this moral
evil infinitely worse, given that there are infinitely many more less-perfect
worlds which will go unactualized by this choice?
This cleaving of moral from metaphysical necessity, like Leibniz's
cleaving of the “world of worlds” from our world governed by logic and
sufficient reason, is purely arbitrary and leads to patently absurd
consequences. In the end it serves only to justify Leibniz's fantasy wherein
the rational and the pre-rational can mingle together on equal, and
ultimately transitive ground. The distinction, naturally, by no means
convinced everybody. Samuel Clarke, in his exchange with Leibniz, argues
that “necessity, in philosophical questions, always signifies absolute
necessity.” Necessity, after-all, is necessity, be it moral or metaphysical.
Arthur Lovejoy wrote, “The distinction Leibniz here attempts to setup is
manifestly without logical substance; the fact is so apparent that it is
impossible to believe that a thinker of his powers can have been altogether
unaware of it himself.”
Indeed, it is increasingly difficult to imagine that even Leibniz himself
could take much of this seriously, and there is ample reason to suggest he
didn’t, as shown by Stewart. Leibniz was a court barrister, in the end, and he
made a living of convincing others of beliefs that he never held. And in
accord with his admitted purpose on that ferry boat to his meeting with
Spinoza, Leibniz's universe seems to have been merely a toy world, a
fantastic metaphysical contrivance meant not ultimately for him, but for the
masses. It was conceived as a popular religion, and Leibniz was not to be
one of its followers, but its founder.

Page | 690
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

Spinoza considered and rejected the transcendent and separated (i.e.


Leibnizian) God, as did the majority of theologians, apparently. He said:
“He who affirms that God could have refrained from creating the world is
declaring in an indirect way that it was made by chance, since it
proceeded from an act of will which might not have been. Since this belief
and this view is quite absurd, it is commonly and unanimously admitted
that God’s will is eternal and has never been indifferent” (p281).
According to Spinoza, Stewart claims, “Leibniz’s God… is not a free agent, but
rather is beholden to some preconceived idea about the good...” (p282).
God’s decision, then, separated into transcendence, is wholly transitive and
wholly compulsory, as the forces of opposition and separation are a function
of the transitive-axis. Indeed, it is these forces which determine the aspects
of chance and arbitrariness in God’s choice, as intuited and rejected by
Spinoza and the majority of theologians. The good to which any God of
reason and rationality must “aim,” can only be internal, not external to its
nature. This is reflected in the Immanent/Transcendent axis of the Rational
itself, which enfolds and unfolds the transitive-axis into the ONE-ALL.
Stewart notes:
Spinoza’s God creates the world in the same way that an essence creates
its properties—that is, in the same way that the nature of a circle makes it
round. It is in the world (just as the world is in it) and therefore cannot
conceivably be associated with any other world or with no world at all. A
transcendent God, on the other hand, is the “transitive” cause of things.
He creates the world in the same way that a watchmaker makes a watch
(p239-40).
“In sum,” says Stewart, “Spinoza believes in an ‘immanent’ God; Leibniz
argues for a ‘transcendent’ one” (p239). This may be true on the surface, but
the crucial difference is that since Leibniz’s God exists due to a forced
dualism between the mundane world with its metaphysical necessity and
the extramundane world with its moral necessity, therefore Leibniz’s God,
although it exists in the transcendent direction to his subjects, is a
thoroughly transitive and finite God who is merely the transitive and
automatic cause, and not even the creator of this world. If God must make a
choice between possibilities that he didn't create, can't control and doesn't
encompass and embody, then this God is transitively bounded by its other,
the world of worlds itself, which is transcendent even to this God. Leibniz's
pre-rational God is thus not fully transcendent, and is not even infinite, but a
mere finite modality dependent on the extramundane world from which the
moral necessity and possible worlds he is compelled to choose from emerge.
The transitivity and hence pre-rationality of the Leibnizian God is also
evident in the fact that Leibniz employed transitive (temporal) causation in
his cosmological argument. Spinoza, on the other hand, employed immanent
causation in his demonstrations of God as entirely limitless and
Page | 691
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

independent. Therefore, as Deleuze also demonstrates, Spinoza’s God, being


wholly immanent for all of transcendent reality, is also wholly transcendent.
Indeed, Spinoza's God is the enfolding and transcendent emphasis on the I/T
axis. It’s not mere or pure immanence, but immanence as it reflects into
transcendence. The intrinsic polarity and nonduality of the I/T axis
naturally and implicitly reflects through the PAR into Spinoza's nondual
awareness, as he intuitively recognizes the identity of the transcendence of
God with the immanence of Substance. This is why his God/Substance can
be denoted by the statement, ∞/∞, and this is why Spinoza’s
immanent/transcendent God transcends-and-includes any purely
transcendent and thus purely transitive God.
Thus we can see that any attempt to take pure transcendence to the
absolute scope as God—actuating the pre-rational transcendent bias—
without including its identical opposite in immanence, merely ends in pure
transitivity. In this way, pure transcendence reflects through the Principle of
Absolute Reversal into transitivity, thus revealing the transitive mapping of
transcendence itself, in the trans-bias. But any transitive-plane is immanent
to higher levels of transcendence, as we see with Leibniz's God embedded in
the world of worlds which he did not create and which he cannot control. In
this transcendent world beyond God, he merely selects the best from the
apex of the pyramidal necropolis of suspended worlds.

We can see here yet another resonant chord in our Ariadne’s cable.

Page | 692
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

Explanation: This principle is a direct function of the transcendent bias and the
Univocity Framework. As the pre-rational forces of representation seek to mono -polize
the absolute scope with its transcendent pole, pure transcendence reflects through the
Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR) into its implicit other, pure transitivity, because in
order to escape immanence, transcendence must conceive of itself outside of Being, as
we see with Leibniz’s inconsistent attempt to escape his own principle of Sufficient
Reason and causality. Thus pure transcendence implicitly cleaves for itself an absolute
and absurd dualism between itself and the ONE -ALL of the PSR. And (this absurdity
aside) in order for pure transcendence to effect anything from its “outside” position, it
must do so transitively, because immanence is not an option, and simply because it is
on the outside. The world then becomes the absolute object of the absolute subject,
and as we have seen, the subject -object polarity and causation is a transitive function.
Given the duality, however, Leibniz unwittingly falls yet again into the Cartesian
dilemma. Without an “immanent plane” there is no univocity and no real difference or
inter-expressivity between God and the worlds. A transitive-plane is always immanent
to higher levels of transcendence, as we see with Leibniz's God embedded within a
world of worlds which he did not create and which he cannot control, but merely
selects transitively from the static, p re-determined apex of its pyramidal necropolis.

And to conclude these arguments on the possible vs. the actual, we can sum
it up with yet another principle, echoing the anima-mundi itself as it reflects
into Spinoza’s principle that the totality of possibility in an infinite world
equals the totality of actuality, or that all possibles, given infinite space and
time, will be actual. This is also a reinstatement of the PSR and a limitation
or identification of the world of all possible worlds to an affirmation of this
world of immanence in transcendence and the ONE-ALL.

Page | 693
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

Explanation: In an absolutely infinite and eternal universe any finite, non-zero true
possibility whatsoever would have an infinite chance of being actualized, putting its
probability of occurrence exactly at one —somewhere and somewhen in this infinitely
infinite universe of universes.

Because a monad is a substance, as we have seen, and hence entirely self-


contained and independently arising, its complete future and history are
written into its very essence in the act of creation, or in the auto-generation
in the world of all possible worlds from which God must merely select. The
“complete” concept of a substance, Leibniz says, “must contain all the
predicates that ever have been and ever will be true of it.”i¥
Leibniz's pre-established “harmony” is thus a transcendental
determinism,ii* and via our principle of pure transcendence, a purely
transitive fatalism and Theocratic tyranny. Leibniz had presciently critiqued
the old doctrine of extension (and matter) as a function of the imagination—
in accord with the Deleuzian univocal account of Spinozan extension as a
aspect of the interface of expression between God and man. His view of
spatial and temporal extension as purely relative, anticipated both Kant and
Einstein, in different ways. But Leibniz's transcendental determinism
surreptitiously thwarts his view of extension by unequivocally re-imposing
absolute, and indeed linear time which he, along with Spinoza had rejected
as a consequence of the unfolding principles of rationality. The pre-
established absolute “harmony” between the actions of monads can be none
other than an absolute time, imposed artificially from the Leibnizian mixture
or the pre-rational with the Rational. Only God, in his necropolis of worlds,
can be said (by pure mythic fiat), to exist in a world of relative time, if time at
all could be consistently reimposed into the world of worlds without
bringing with it the PSR.


qtd. in Courtier p245
ii
* See, Transcendental Determinism and the Captive Will, p643.

Page | 694
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

This transcendental determinism, then, as a pure transitivity, is another


example of the con-fusion and indiscriminant mixing of Rational and pre-
rational truths. Indeed, Leibniz “transcends” freedom of the will into the
purely pre-rational transitivity of a transcendental fatalism. Leibniz himself
says, for monads “everything [is] settled in advance,” and “God’s decree [to
actualize the best of all possible worlds] is immutable.” Stewart notes:
Arnaud—oddly echoing Spinoza—accuses Leibniz of propounding a view
“more than fatalistic.” “Once God has chosen,” Leibniz acknowledges,
once again adding fuel to the fire, “one must grant that everything is
included in his choice, and that nothing can be changed" (p284-5).
Leibniz then admits, as we have already seen in the context of the splotchy
mirrors, that it is the Monad’s “ignorance” of its own nature that requires it
to act and think as if it were free. Stewart continues:
The best reason to think that Leibniz’s argument in favor of free will is as
bad as it sounds is that it is indistinguishable from Spinoza’s argument
against free will. This surprising coincidence is evident in a moment
when Leibniz lets down his guard and speaks frankly. The will, he says,
“has its causes, but since we are ignorant of them and they are oft-hidden,
we believe ourselves independent. It is this chimera of imaginary
independence which revolts us against the consideration of determinism,
and which brings us to believe that there are difficulties where there are
none.”
Leibniz here admits that a monad is not independent, and merely believes
itself so, and along with this, Leibniz should then admit that it can hardly be
counted as a substance at all. Spinoza's Substance, on the other hand, is
fundamentally independent simply because it is the ONE-ALL, and there is
nothing other than the absolute scope to be dependent upon. Stewart
continues, commenting on the above quote from Leibniz:
These words could have simply been lifted out of the Ethics, where
Spinoza writes that “men believe they are free...because they are
conscious of their volitions and desires, yet ignorant of the causes that
have determined them to desire and will.” Leibniz was—and, at least in
the privacy of his personal notebooks, understood himself to be—a
determinist.
The freedom Spinoza discusses that men imagine themselves to posses is
freedom at the absolute scope, i.e. freedom from the immanent causation
about which they are ignorant. Spinoza counters this con-fused freedom
with the understanding that a mode only experiences real or absolute
freedom in the relative context of its own immanent causation which is
ultimately the freedom of Substance itself. It is this relative notion of
freedom which Spinoza shares with Taoism. Freedom, for Spinoza, involves
“going with the flow,” and releasing ourselves from the bondage of transitive
and external causes. The Tao te Ching states, recall, that “All things have
their backs to the female and stand facing the male. When male and female

Page | 695
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

combine, all things achieve harmony.” For Spinoza, as for the Tao, a goal is
the overcoming of the transcendent or yang bias and its mapping to the
oppositional forces of transitivity, and this goal is distinctly a function of the
Rational, as we have seen in both its mathematical and philosophical
aspects.
For Spinoza, immanent causation (yin) is not a restriction of human or
relative freedom, but its implicit and invisible emergent foundation. The
immanent causation of the individual is included in the maximizing
definition of his own freedom. For this reason Spinoza’s determinism of
mind can be mapped into the “infinite determinism equals indeterminism”
of the body, but critically not reduced to it. Leibniz’s determinism, on the
other hand, is logically contained in the moment of creation of each monad
and in its pre-scripted transitive list of actions. Stewart writes [my
emphasis]:
According to the doctrine of pre-established harmony, mind and body
move in parallel only because God has seen fit to harmonize the pre-
determined activities of independent mind- and body-substances...
(p286).
Bear in mind that Spinoza’s philosophy of mind and body—his theory of the
attributes—is generally also conceived as a parallelism. But just as Spinoza’s
parallelism is an illusion of transitive perspective—as we have seen with the
immanent interface in the symbiogenesis of subject and object—so his pre-
determinism is an illusion. There is no time-line in univocal existence, but
only the eternal-NOW, the Parmenidean Being-now of Spinoza’s sub specie
aeternitatis. And as in Heraclitus, there is nothing but change itself,
changing, Being, Becoming for all eternity. And in the understanding of this
in the now itself we can thus participate in the eternal. This is Spinoza’s
notion of immortality as it transcends the limits of personal identity and
recognizes that eternity is not a function of life. Thus immortality has
nothing to do with duration but is a scope con-fusion projected onto the
aspects of mortality.

As we have seen, Spinoza and Leibniz have very different ideas about
immortality. But through their respective accounts of virtue, these
differences and their consequences begin to come into the light. For Leibniz,
virtue is correspondingly pre-rational, transitive, and transcendent; a virtue
which lies ultimately outside and beyond oneself. Leibniz thus seeks virtue
in the acknowledgement or praise of others. It is thus because virtue goes
unrewarded in this lifetime that Leibniz seeks salvation in the immortality of
the individual. Spinoza, as advocate of existential honesty and humility, on
the other hand, accepts individual mortality and seeks virtue as its own
reward. He thus does not require personal immortality. Stewart writes:

Page | 696
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

[Spinoza and Leibniz] in fact represent a pair of radically different


philosophical personality types that have always been part of the human
experience. Spinoza speaks for those who believe that happiness and
virtue are possible with nothing more than what we have in our hands.
Leibniz stands for those convinced that happiness and virtue depend on
something that lies beyond. Spinoza councils calm attention to our own
deepest good. Leibniz expresses that irrepressible longing to see our
good works reflected back to us in the praise of others. Spinoza affirms
the totality of things such as it is. Leibniz is that part of us that ceaselessly
strives to make us into something more than what we are (p312).
We can see here a simple polarity of direction, to be sure. Spinoza seeks to
liberate the immanence within, whereas Leibniz seeks to escape into
transcendence. The two together represent a balanced view, which is
actually expressed most coherently in Spinoza's use of immanence, in his
theory of the emotions, to manifest transcendence toward the intellectual
love of God or blessedness. We have also seen this turn to immanence
generating the transcendence in mathematics through the breaking of
closure into a new set of numbers, recall.

Recall how Leibniz's drive for individual immortality is the sole impetus of
his ascription of the absolute properties of substance to the relativity of the
monad. And how this con-fusion generates the tension between the monads
and God their creator, and recall how this God of pure transcendence thus
collapses with his possible worlds into a pure fatalistic transitivity,
immanent to a higher transcendence which is equivalent to Spinoza’s God.
We’ve also seen how this forced individual immortality imposes upon the
monad an absolute dependence on God, as their free will becomes solely a
function of the obscurance of their splotchy mirrors, limiting their ability to
see their own fatalistic, infinitely detailed and pre-determined life-scripts.
There is another problem that comes with this pre-rational wish for
personal immortality, however. Given that Leibniz is committed to a
dualistic form of parallelism, “…Leibniz is forced to acknowledge that even in
its before- and after-lives, the mind-monad remains tied to some parallel
manifestation of body-monads” (p287). When a body dies, then, it begins to
disintegrate back down the levels of the Great Chain of Being, from human,
to animal and ultimately to mineral forms of awareness. The mind-monad
then wafts around the universe as a speck of dust, for what easily could seem
a near eternity before it finally might get incorporated into a more
transcendent monad, such as another human. The question then arises, why
would this one of billions of specks of dust have any more claim to the
singular mind-monad position of its human host than any of the others that
are likely caught in the mix?
Another related question is posed by Stewart:

Page | 697
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

… why not ascribe to this outside infinity of [physical] monads all of the
attributes we use to define our identities... ? (p287)
In other words, if the mind monad gets its properties and levels of
awareness from its aggregation with the physical monads, then why do we
need the mind monads at all. Why not say, as does Spinoza, that matter
itself, as modifications of Substance, possesses the power or attribute of
thought as a simple function of interiority, and this power is simply
magnified or unfolded in emergence into higher forms of complexity or
“excellence,” which is the individual identity itself in its interior aspect?
What does the speck of dust mind-monad really add to the picture of the full-
scale complexity of the body monad except for merely something to attach
the immortality category itself to? And is this immortality as a speck of dust
really worth the trouble of this Cartesian-esque parallelism? Stewart notes
[my comments]
Instead of preserving the sanctity of the [absolute] individual, Leibniz
may be inadvertently engaged in a deconstruction of individuality itself—
which, of course, is exactly what Spinoza accomplishes in his system
(p287).
Of course in this deconstruction of individual immortality one recognizes
oneself in reverse as a divine construction from God or Substance itself, in
sub specie aeternitatis.

With the doctrine of pre-established harmony, Leibniz exchanges the


impossibility of Descartes’ mind-body interaction with the vastly improbable
pre-established harmony of an infinity of non-interacting physical and
mental monads.i The vast perfection of the craftsmanship necessary for the
theory of the eternal synchronization of the infinite monads, however,
Leibniz surprisingly takes as another proof of God; a variation on the
“argument from design.” The surprise is that this “proof” is based not on
observation, but on mere fantastic speculation, and that generally, ala
Ockham’s Razor, the improbability and difficulty of a speculation would be
taken as a strong indicator of its falsehood, not its truth. Stewart notes,
however, that “Spinoza, Hume, Kant and many other philosophers have long
since pointed out that the logic of the [general] argument is hardly
compelling: it establishes a probability, not a certainty; and the probability
of an event that is absolutely unique is in any case undefinable [at best]”
(p249-50).

i
This linear and even algorithmically coordinated unfolding of infinite parallel histories is in direct
contradiction, however, with the modern empirical concept of nonlinearity and emergence which
otherwise would justify Leibniz's prescient principle of unity.

Page | 698
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

Perhaps for this reason, among many possible others, Leibniz’s


metaphysics struck Bertrand Russell as “a fascinating fairy tale, coherent,
perhaps, but wholly arbitrary.”i¥ Hegel, however, claimed that “Leibniz’s
philosophy appears like a string of arbitrary assertions, which follow one
another like a metaphysical romance. It is only when we see what he wished
thereby to avoid that we learn to appreciate its value.”ii¥
Indeed, as Stewart notes [my comments]:
There is in fact a single thread that may lead one safely through the
labyrinth of the monadology. The astonishing and bizarre features of the
monads—the windowlessness, the pregnancies, the splotchy mirrors, the
infinite replications of the infinite universe, and the pre-established
harmony—all follow with admirable logical rigor from the premise that
substantiality [i.e., absolute independence] is a quality of individual
minds, and not of [Nature] as a whole. What Leibniz is for is often difficult
to grasp; but what he is against fits neatly into one word: Spinoza.iii

The Leibnizian system, we have seen, is a function of a profound tension


between God and the monads; i.e. the bounded forms of infinity,
transcendent vs. immanent, respectively. As we have also seen, upon closer
inspection these distinctions seem to vanish in a puff of illogic. As noted by
many commentators, Leibniz seems to collapse either into Spinoza or into
Atheism, when forced to a greater logical, and indeed a rational rigor.
This is seen clearly in the principle of the best. The choice God has to
make in this world of worlds seems to come back to the question of why this
world and not another, like a choice of entrées on a menu. But in fact the
choice is much more fundamental as it entails the actualization of the world
itself from nothing, ex nihilo i.e. a relativity from the absolute scope of the
omni-non. But even Leibniz could not imagine his transcendent God without
putting him in an actualized world in which the choice is already laid out for
him ontologically and transitively at the ready-made apex of his pyramid.
Stewart writes:
If we say that this higher world is God’s creation, too, then we seem to
acknowledge that there is only one possible world from which God may
choose—namely, this higher world—and all the so-called possible worlds
aren’t really “worlds” at all, but merely features of the one true world


Courtier, p251-2
ii¥
Courtier, p252
iii
By Hegel’s time, and largely due to the Leibnizian reaction itself, the historical reading of Spinoza’s
philosophy had thoroughly collapsed into the objective-ontic flat-land of materialism (or slightly
better, the “eco-philosophy” of the romantics) the “rigidity” and lifelessness of which both Leibniz
and Hegel falsely projected onto an already distorted Spinozism.

Page | 699
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

created by God, like the blocks of a pyramid. At the end of that road lies
Spinozism. If we say that this higher world has always been there and has
always been the way it is, on the other hand, then we make God one of its
creatures and we subject God to its rules, and he acts unfreely—i.e.,
according to its nature and not his own. In a sense, God is no longer God,
but just a logical operator within the scheme of some pre-existing nature.
At the end of that road lies atheism—or, one could say, a form of
Spinozism without Spinoza’s belief in the divinity of nature (p 283-4).
One problem, as we have seen, is the presumption that monads can be
absolutized into substances, as absolutely independent entities. We’ve seen
how this reverts into its opposite, forcing monads into an absolute
dependence on God in a fatalistic master and servant, or perhaps
programmer and program, relationship. The inverse problem is that Leibniz
has erected his God purely transitively, as an injection of the transcendent
bias of pre-rationality into the logical rigor and immanence of an unfolding
Spinozist rationality. In this rational light, recall, this pure transcendence
collapses into pure transitivity and thus Leibniz’s world is left Godless,
bereft of the divinity that Spinoza ascribes to the ONE-ALL of
God/Substance. Stewart notes [my emphases]:
All of the suggestions that Leibniz is some sort of Spinozist can be mapped
into the claim that monads are not true substances, as Leibniz maintains,
but rather something more like modes of a single Substance. Leibniz
himself acknowledges the centrality of the matter when he says that
Spinoza would be right, if there were no monads. All of the challenges to
the substantiality of the monads in turn come down to a question about
the relation between monads and God.
In his metaphysical system, Leibniz strives to maintain a delicate
balance between God and the monads. For example, he avers that
monads are eternal and indestructible—as indeed substances must be—
but then turns around and allows that God can create them and annihilate
them all in a flash. He grants monads freedom in their own eyes—which
is as it should be for all substances—but then seems to take away their
freedom in God’s eyes. These and other tensions in the City of God come
to a head in the simple question: is God a monad?
It would seem a straightforward question, the sort to which the great
monadologist would have a ready answer. Yet Leibniz is surprisingly
cagey on the subject. His best hint comes in the phrase that God is the
“Monad of monads.” One would have thought that, after three centuries of
effort, the Leibniz scholars would have come to a consensus on just what
Leibniz means by “the monad of monads.” But such is not the case. Some
argue that God must be a monad, others that he cannot be. In fact
there is no answer that works within the Leibnizian System (p288-9).
So let’s look at these two options.

Page | 700
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

If we say that God is not a monad we can understand the postulate that God
flashes the monads into existence and then must exist before them. The
monads, however, then get their properties from God, including an infinite
pre-determined script controlling (or “harmonizing”) their entire lives.
Hegel says, “There is a contradiction present. If the monad of monads, God,
is the absolute substance, and individual monads are created through his
will, their substantiality comes to an end.” i ¥ Monads, then, are not
independent. However, they are not merely dependent either, but infinitely
dependent on God to mediate their interactions with other monads. In this
sense, monads seem merely to be extensions, appendages or unwitting
agents of God, at best. And Since God alone is independent—barring of
course his collapse into transitivity and thus dependence on the world of
worlds which auto-arranges into his pre-defined choice—“he” alone can be
Substance, and we are again at Spinozism. As Stewart notes, “If God is not a
monad, in short, then Leibniz is a Spinozist” (p289).

If we say, on the other hand, that God is a monad, then by definition he


cannot interact with other monads, for otherwise he would determine their
essence and they his. And if he cannot interact with them, then certainly he
cannot create them. As a monad, he can only interact with other monads in a
virtual, not an actual way, and thus through a pre-established harmony. As a
monad, however, he cannot be the creator of the pre-established harmony,
but his mediation with other monads must be accomplished through the
“harmonizing” (totalitarian) omnipotence of a greater God. “And whatever it
is that God does—if there is anything at all left for him to do—all of it follows
with absolute, logical necessity from his monadic essence. ... Indeed, given
the lemma that to choose one monad is to choose its entire universe, it
follows that once God exists, then the universe such as it is exists with
rigorous necessity” (p289).
In Leibniz’s transcendental determinism God as a monad is not free, he
has no choice of the “best of all possible worlds.” “In short, if God is a monad,
he isn't God at all; he’s just another one of us. Russell alludes to this
eventuality when he remarks that Leibniz’s monadism should have impelled
him to an even greater heresy than Spinozism. To put it crudely: if God is a
monad, Leibniz is an atheist” (p290).
Stewart notes:
Perhaps the best way to summarize Leibniz’s problematically self-
subverting position is to say that he was a Spinozist who did not believe
in Spinoza’s God. One logical outcome of such a position, of course, is


Courtier, p289

Page | 701
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

precisely that to which Leibniz tended whenever he attempted to


distinguish himself from Spinoza: namely that there is no God at all. The
author of the system of pre-established harmony spent a lifetime
branding the author of the Ethics an atheist; but it was Leibniz who sailed
much closer to the winds of unbelief (p292).

The problem, Stewart notes, is that there is no way an observer could tell the
difference between a Leibnizian and a Spinozan world. Indeed Leibniz’s
critics accuse him of plagiarism over and over on this point. But Leibniz
insists that his form of parallelism is different in that it occurs by the will of
God. This is a moral, rather than a metaphysical necessity, he insists. God
could have chosen to make a “disharmonious” universe, claims Leibniz, but
he didn’t, because he is good. And thus “the pious” have something in which
to believe—which incidentally never seemed to have included Leibniz given
that he loathed church and never appeared to have worshiped on his own.
But, Stewart asks, is a “disharmonious” universe even metaphysically
possible, as Leibniz indeed implies?
According to Leibniz’s principle that One is All, each individual monad
entails the entire existing universe of monads, in the sense that its
internal “mirror” replicates the activities of all other monads, no matter
how many or how far.
A monad is intrinsically tied to the universe of all other monads. Choose one
monad, says Stewart, and you choose the entire universe.
In a disharmonious universe, however, the “universe” within each monad
would have nothing to do with the “universe” outside. … Choose two or
more monads, in other words, and you choose two or more universes that
have nothing to do with one another. ... But if disharmonious monads do
not belong to the same universe, then a disharmonious universe is not
possible. And if a disharmonious universe is not possible, then Leibniz’s
God has only harmonious possible universes to choose from, which is to
say that in all possible universes mind and body are harmonious, which is
to say that the parallelism of mind and body exhibits just as much logical
necessity in Leibniz’s world as it does in Spinoza’s (p 287).

In Leibniz’s transcendental fatalism, “everything a monad ever does is


contained its concept,” and God’s decision to “create” the world is
“immutable.” Therefore, notes Stewart, “it would seem pointless to pray to
[Leibniz's God], just as it is pointless to pray to Spinoza’s God in hopes of
some alternative outcome of events” (p290). Indeed, for this reason, the
same orthodox antagonists of Spinoza, also attack Leibniz on this count. As
Page | 702
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

Stewart notes, “Russell goes so far as to accuse Leibniz of ‘discreditable


subterfuges’ in his efforts to conceal the fact that all sin for him is ‘original
sin’ in the inherent finitude of every created monad” (p290).
“Leibniz attempts to finesse the issue” through the unclear concept of the
“presumptive will” of God. Leibniz is effectively saying that monads can
guide their efforts by presuming to know God’s will, and acting in its accord.
This of course, presumes that their lives were not already scripted eons ago
by God himself. This action upon a presumption of God’s will thus depends
on their ignorance of this unfortunate fatalistic fact, and all of their
“corrections” to their course were prescripted in the infinite minutia of the
course itself in the very act of creation! What then can a “presumptive will”
accomplish in such a fatalistic scenario? Absent this transitive and
transcendent determinism, however, Spinozists immediately recognize this
“presumptive will” as a “metaphorical way of alluding to the realization of
our own essential and inherently finite natures...” along with the realization
of the infinite immanence of God within as the absolute source of our
relative and dependently arising freedom—our “conatus.” And “this
maximization of the individual conatus, of course, is precisely the path
Spinoza proposes to take in the Ethics” (p291). Note, however, that in the
linear and transitive take-over of this immanent determinism—where
infinite determinism equals indeterminism” in the eternal-NOW of sub specie
aeternitatis—the reduction of time to a pre-determined line has entirely
negated the function of the “presumptive will.”
Leibniz explains his idea thus, “Pleasure is nothing but the feeling of an
increase in perfection.”
But these words could easily have been lifted from Spinoza’s Ethics. The
more active a monad is—which is to say, the more it realizes its own
nature, as opposed to submitting passively to the domination of other
monads—the happier it is. “We will be happier the clearer our
comprehension of things and the more we act in accordance with our
proper nature, namely reason,” Leibniz clarifies. “Only to the extent that
our reasonings are correct are we free and exempt from the passions
which are impressed upon us by surrounding bodies.” It is passages like
this one—which again could simply have been cribbed from the Ethics—
that lead Russell to suggest that, in his ethical philosophy, “Leibniz no
longer shows great originality, but tends, with slight alterations of
phraseology, to adopt (without acknowledgment) the views of the decried
Spinoza” (p291).

Stewart sums up the reactionary Leibniz succinctly and eloquently in the


following passage:
In their reports on their travels into the very heart of things, Leibniz and
Spinoza seem at first glance to describe radically different universes. One

Page | 703
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

discovers a numberless horde of animated substances, the other a


singular mass of undifferentiated substance; one finds souls that never
die, the other no souls at all; one sees a world in which everything
happens for a reason, the other a world in which everything just happens.
Yet when we look for observable effects and practical consequences
that might serve to distinguish the two worlds in question, the
discrepancies seem to evaporate upon inspection. The world according to
Leibniz is a reasonable one; it is a law-abiding, all-determining cosmos
that is the proper subject of scientific investigation, a world
unencumbered with inscrutable deities, where the individual remains for
all practical purposes at the mercy of external forces, and in which we
have the responsibility to seek happiness by realizing ourselves. The
world Leibniz describes, in brief, is the one first properly observed by
Spinoza.
Ultimately the differences between the two philosophers have to do
not with the nature of the world as each sees it, but with the meaning or
value each ascribes to it. Spinoza identifies the law-abiding, all-
determining nature that serves as the object of scientific investigation
with God. Leibniz does not. Indeed, Leibniz’s philosophy is at its clearest
and most sincere in the negative. Its founding principle remains: Nature
is not God; that is to say, a Being that makes no choices and cannot be
called good does not deserve the name of God. The monads exist for no
other purpose than to make this negation, which remains standing even
as the rest of Leibniz’s philosophy collapses into something
observationally indistinguishable from Spinozism.
In this there is revealed something essential about the nature of
Leibniz’s philosophy and its peculiar relationship with that of Spinoza. …
Leibniz’s avowed proof of the immateriality of the mind is really just an
argument that Spinoza’s materialism does not rule out the possibility of
an undetectable spiritual force behind all apparently mechanical actions;
his proof of the pre-established harmony is really just an argument that
the parallelism Spinoza observes can never be definitively shown to be
the result of an identity, rather than mere coincidence; his proof that the
world has a designer is just an argument that Spinoza fails to prove
absolutely that there is none; and his proof of the existence of a
transcendent God is really just an argument that an immanent God is not
a God. … In the final analysis, he does not leave us with a set of positive
doctrines, but with a series of negations. His work amounts to a
deconstruction of modern philosophy in general and of Spinozism in
particular. It is defined by—and cannot exist without—that to which it is
opposed. It is, in essence, a reactive philosophy.
That being said, we now turn from the pre-rational con-fusions in the
Leibnizian attempt to forge a popular religion, to the positive elements of an
actual philosophy. In this we will find a new lens on the underlying terrain
of the Rational, a view largely only implicit in Spinoza, and in every case,
ultimately not opposed to him.

Page | 704
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

Leibniz was undoubtedly one of the greatest of “universal geniuses.” That


much can’t be denied. Indeed, he is near the top of the list of prolific writers,
such that no one person seems capable of really mastering his sprawling and
penetrating thought, let alone his often self-contradictory philosophy. The
problem is that as an “omnimaniac”i¥ his mind was all over the place,
jumping from new idea to new idea. And naturally, with such a scattered
focus, most of his brilliant ideas came to naught. Of the few possibilities that
found their way through his labyrinthine mind into this best of all actual
worlds, these rank among the greatest inventions known.
Along with Spinoza, he prefigured many of the fields of modern thought
such as:
1. complexity science:
a. Leibniz: emergent principle of unity, “active matter,” and
butterfly effect
b. Spinoza: homeostatic/strange-attractor definition of finite
essence
2. evolutionary biology:
a. Leibniz: claims that organisms evolve and predicts the
existence of microscopic animals
b. Spinoza: notion of the powers of the body and the gradient
of “excellence”
3. cognitive science:
a. Leibniz: idea of “little perceptions”
b. Spinozan: question, “what can a body do?” and theory of
mind and emotions

Leibniz, however, also made important contributions to computer science


and mathematics, such as the invention of the first computer, binary
numbers, and the calculus, including its modern notation.
In philosophy too Leibniz is a vastly influential figure. We’ve already
seen this in the philosophy of mathematics, and as Professor Darren Staloff
notes:
…in many ways [Leibniz is] a precursor to important subsequent
developments in the history of philosophy. His views on history as being
the emergence of a moral world within the natural world, of history being
progressive, prefigure the sort of thinking we find in Vico, in Kant, in
Herder, in Hegel, in Marx and other substantive thinkers on history in late
eighteenth and especially nineteenth century. As we’ll see, his views


Stewart, Courtier

Page | 705
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

about the relativity of space and time, not only prefigure developments in
twentieth-century physics, but his view that they’re mentally constructed,
prefigures the Kantian distinction between the noumenal and
phenomenal. And finally his critique of extension, and with it an implied
critique of the notion of matter, and his role of God as a sort of universal
switchboard between monads, certainly prefigures and presupposes the
development of classic Idealism, both in Berkeley and the English
tradition, and in classic German Idealism of the late eighteenth and early
nineteenth century. i¥
As we have seen, however, many of the specific mythic ideas in his
monadology collapse in the light of logic and reason. They are simply
revealed as by-products of his attempt to forge a popular religion by pulling
critical mythic ideas through the labyrinthine cusp of Rationalism, as it was
emerging in Spinoza. Together they end up being merely one of many
bizarre and obsolete projects of Leibniz's omnimaniacal mind—a brilliant
but futile attempt to inject critical pre-rational elements into an essentially
Spinozist rationality in order to found a religion. These incompatible
notions, then simply get shucked off with our emphasis on rational-level
philosophy rather than pre-rational and mythic-level religion. What remains
is largely the bare and tensile differences of emphases on an underlying
rationality—the same emergent territory explored by Spinoza, but seen in a
new critical light and with a new emphasis in Leibniz.
These obsolete mythic notions include; (1) the anthropomorphic God of
pure transcendence, (2) the tyranny of monadic existence under the
absolutism of substantial stasis, e.g. (2a) windowlessness, (2b)
independence=fatalistic dependence, (2c) the need for a monadic “magic
mirror,” as well as (3) the world of all possible worlds and (3a) its fiat
suspension of the PSR and the principle of activity, (4) the “creation” event,
and (5) the principle of the best.
With all of this reactionary con-fusion swept aside, we can now focus on
the core positive elements and results of this reactive philosophy, as it
carves new grooves and makes new folds in the body of Rationalism first
represented by Spinoza. As we have seen, in order to inject his pre-rational
elements, Leibniz created a profound tension ultimately between our two
forms of unity: the finite unity of his monads and the Infinite Unity of his
transcendent God—the one and the ONE, respectively. We have already seen
how to tune and triune this tensile polarity in the Cycle of Unity, and as it
manifests in the triune interface between the binary VL-axes of conceptual
relation, as well as in the resolution to the paradoxes of the infinite.
In Leibniz, however, the tensile relation remains, and this relation is
critical to the chiaroscuro and mannerist style of his system, with its truths


(Staloff, Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition: Lecture 12: The Philosophy of G.W.
Leibniz: Audio CD Lecture: The Teaching Company.)

Page | 706
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

of emphasis. Along with this tension, then, the monad itself must remain,
freed from the tyranny of the absolute stasis and independence of
substantial aspects. This then marks a shift in emphasis from the Spinozan
Infinite Unity of Substance as God, or ALL as ONE, to the almost Zenonian
inversion of ONE as ALL. Leibniz, recall, demonstrated mathematically that
substance taken as plurality shifts from infinite Unity to the infinity of the
ALL and the Zenonian labyrinth of the continuum. With the substantial
tyranny of absolute independence removed from the monad, what we find is
a fleshed-out holarchy of monads within monads—an inverted “indivisibility
equals infinite divisibility” of folds within folds—each with a principle of
“unity as emergence,” now freed from eternity and numerical identity to
really emerge in an infinitely inter-expressive arising.
This, then, is the core value of the Leibnizian addition to Nondual
Rationality: the integration of the Spinozan principle of Infinite Unity with
the Leibnizian emergent principle of finite unity—the ONE with the one.
Deleuze sees this critical Leibnizian move as a “new relation between the
one and the multiple,”i¥ and in Interface Philosophy, we can pull this through
the triune interface and cultivated third of Spinoza’s three infinities and into
the Cycle of Unity, from ONE to ALL and into the ONE-one uni-axis and its
monadic interface, and then back through the equality into the ALL-ONE—
the cycle recall is—ONE = ALL = ∞/∞ = ALL = ONE.
The Leibnizian injection of the monadology can be seen as explicating the
Spinozan system in the positive, because it begins to flesh out the
holonic/monadic interface, the infinitely folded vinculum and the emergent
source of finite unity, and with it the uni-axial triune interface—the
cognitive holon—in the polarity of the two attributes. It begins to integrate
and interface our finite (relative) unity with Infinite (absolute) Unity, and
thus places the emphasis on the Zenonian/Heraclitean instantaneously
active ALL, pulling away from the eternally timeless Parmenidean/Spinozan
emphasis on the ONE. This is the move from the calm serenity of the ONE
into the wild, labyrinthine, immanent, organic, Baroque folds of the
monadology. And this is how “the clear plunges into the obscure and never
ceases plunging into it.”ii¥
From this new emphasis on the one, and with the monadic equation of
the bounded infinite with an external limit at 1, i.e. 1/∞ , we find that “The
human being is the new God,”iii ¥ and that each of us is “a small divinity and
eminently a universe: God in ectype and the universe in prototype.”iv¥ As
Stewart explains, “This is the idea that defines Leibniz’s philosophy, and that


(Badiou p. 173)
ii¥
Quoted from The Fold, in Badiou.
iii¥
Stewart, Courtier, p241
iv¥
Leibniz, qtd. in Courtier, p241

Page | 707
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

explains the enormous, if often unacknowledged, influence that his thought


has wielded in the past three centuries of human history.” What Leibniz has
done is bring to the metaphysical table that which is implicit in Spinoza's
Triune Infinite as its logic implicitly permeates the whole of the Ethics. The
bounded or modal infinite thus becomes representative of the human
singularity and its “infinite determinism equals indeterminism.” And with
the substantial shackles of absolute independence now removed from the
monad, this active determinism can shed its reactive pre-rational,
transcendental and fatalist restraints.

As we have seen, Deleuze finds in Leibniz a countering of the mathematical


with what he calls the animal. This is the principle of activity that Leibniz,
perhaps unwittingly, abstracts from its hiding in the calm of Spinoza's ALL as
ONE. In the Leibnizian appropriation of the Spinozan Triune Infinite, recall,
Leibniz extracts the aspect infinite as his Ariadne’s thread out of the
labyrinth of the continuum—his points as “termini.” This aspect infinite
Deleuze then finds as the concept of the fold. Badiou explains:
The fold is first of all an antiextensional concept of the multiple, a repre-
sentation of the multiple as a labyrinthine complexity, directly qualitative
and irreducible to any elementary composition whatever.
The critical shift in Spinoza, which makes its way through Leibniz and into
Deleuze—and independently through Zeno and then axiomatically through
Cantor—is this shift away from the Euclidean notion of the continuum as
constructed from extensional “elements,” such as points and lines. In
Spinoza's Aspect Infinite, the point is abstracted out of The Infinite as an
aspect of position and an implicit singularity. Likewise, the line is a
secondary abstraction of distance, and always a transitive aspect in relation
to the singularity of the Immanent/Transcendent axis. This is also the
interface to Leibniz's relativization of space-time through his critique of
extension. In the same way, Deleuze sees the effects of the Aspect Infinite in
Leibniz as the continuum becomes possessed of the aspect of infinite folds.
Badiou continues:
The fold is yet again an antidialectic concept of the event, or of singularity.
It is an operator that permits thought and individuation to “level” each
other.
This, we have seen, with the “intensive forces” of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. Individuation, recall, is the primal closure of
the unit of number, or the unit of matter—the category. From this closure of
intensive forces comes the deflection into duality and the forces of

Page | 708
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

opposition, as we see in the move from the unit-identity (1) into the
oppositional transitive forces of addition and subtraction.i And thus it is
with the Hegelian dialectic. Univocity breaks the absolute dominance of the
dualistic forces of the dialectic—it pulverizes the categories and opens up
the triune interfaces in the inter-expressive forces of intensity closed off and
forgotten in the origination of duality.
And in the sphere of set theory, as we have seen, the “animality” or
“organicity” of the fold is opposed to the “mathematicity” of the set, and its
identity and similarity of “pure belonging.”ii It was this “pure” or abstracted
aspect of “elements” and “belonging,” recall, that generated the naïve
paradoxes of set theory to begin with. An abstraction from the percept-logic
of the implicit holonic theory of sets, which, recall, was blindly reinstated
through “axiomatic set theory,” as reflected in its congruence with
mereology. Badiou continues:
The fold is finally an anti-Cartesian (or anti-Lacanian) concept of the
subject, a “communicating” figure of absolute interiority, equivalent to the
world, of which it is a point of view. Or again: the fold allows us to
conceive of an enunciation without “enouncement,” or of knowledge
without an object. The world as such will no longer be the fantasy of the
All, but the pertinent hallucination of the inside as pure outside.
Thus we see the fold as the vinculum of the monad, as we have seen it in the
symbiogenesis of subject and object, and the “ruin of the object.”iii With the
fold, then, as with the symbiogenesis of subject and object, the inside is
folded into the outside and the outside inside. The fold is thus the thick
mobius texturology of subjectivity as objectivity, the recognition of the
“hallucination of the inside as pure outside” as a triune interface between
subject and object, ruining the duality and opposition of the twain, and
elevating the hallucinating interface to the status of direct knowledge.
Badiou continues:
This vision of the world as an intricate, folded, and inseparable totality
such that any distinction is simply a local operation, this “modern” convic-
tion that the multiple cannot even be discerned as multiple, but only “acti-
vated” as fold, this culture of the divergence (in the serial sense), which
compossibilizes the most radical heterogeneities, this “opening” without
counterpart (“a world of captures rather than enclosures” [p. 111]): all
this is what founds Deleuze's fraternal and profound relationship to
Leibniz. The multiple as a large animal made up of animals, the organic
respiration inherent to one’s own organicity, the multiple as living tissue,
which folds as if under the effect of its organic expandings and

i
See, Phase TWO: Unit-closure and the Finite Unit-Identity (p308) and, Phase THREE: The Transitive-
axis and Agglomeration (p311).
ii
See, The Identity vs. the Opposite: Post-Modern Con-fusion and Pre-modern Naiveté (p221).
iii
See, The Fold and “Ruin” of the Object (p640).

Page | 709
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

contractings, in perfect contradiction with the Cartesian concept of


extension as punctual and regulated by the shock: Deleuze’s philosophy is
the capture of a life that is both total and divergent. No wonder he pays
tribute to Leibniz, who upholds, more than any other philosopher, “the
assertion of one sole and same world, and of the infinite difference and
variety found in this world” (p. 78). No wonder he defends this audacity,
“baroque” par excellence: “a texturology which is evidence of a
generalized organicism, or of the presence of organisms everywhere” (p.
155).
In fact, there have never been but two schemes, or paradigms, of the
Multiple: the mathematic and the organicist, Plato or Aristotle. Opposing
the fold to the set, or Leibniz to Descartes, reanimates the organicist
scheme. Deleuze-Leibniz does not omit remarking that it must be
separated from the mathematic scheme: “in Mathematics, it is
individuation which constitutes a specification; this is not so with physical
things or organic bodies” (p. 87).
The animal or the number? This is the cross of metaphysics, and the
greatness of Deleuze-Leibniz, metaphysician of the divergent world of
modernity, is to choose without hesitation for the animal. After all, “it is
not only animal psychology, but animal monadology which is essential to
Leibniz’s system” (p. 146).
In the end, says Deleuze, "We remain Leibnizian."i

Thus we can see that Leibniz’s notion of “substance” is quite different from
that of Spinoza, and effectively illegitimate except insofar as his principle of
unity is concerned. Both in his absolute substantiation of the monad, and in
his inclusion of God as pure transcendence, Leibniz employed a pre-rational
methodology, an operation on the transitive axis, rather than the rational
methodology of the I/T axis intersected into mathematical/philosophical
thought with the continuity of the rational numberline. This transitive and
pre-rational operation resulted in the split and tension between God and the
monad, which drives the dazzling baroque machine of his entire system into
such exquisite and often absurd heights. It is this “tension in the City of
God”ii that Leibniz was in danger of collapsing had he taken up the intrinsic
heretical Spinozism and brute modernity and rationalism that he was drawn
to. But we are demonstrating how indeed Leibniz and Spinoza can coalesce
in opposition from the same underlying elements of rationality—and thus
how they can both coexist in harmony on the same “plane of immanence,” or
more properly, in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System.

i
(Fold, p189)
ii
Stewart, Courtier

Page | 710
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

The use of the pre-rational transitive axis in his cosmological argument


might explain why Leibniz ended up (through the trans-bias) with an
externalized pre-rational God—yet more likely, his preconception of a pre-
rational God for his “popular religion” explains his use of the transitive axis
and its absolutization into pure transcendence—transitively pushing God
outside the monadic anima-mundi of the ONE-ALL, rather than immanent,
transcendent and identical to it at once, as we find in Spinoza. Conversely,
Leibniz’s logical portrait of the monad is derived immanently, in emergent
harmony with his calculus, which infused in his thinking the essence of the
rational philosophy. This transitive (pre-rational), vs. immanent (rational)
dichotomy is the source of the vital tension, the highly charged polarity,
mannerism or chiaroscuro, in the Leibnizian system.
In The Fold, Deleuze renders the monad as a third order infinity. In fact
the core expression in this VLE was already given by Deleuze in reference to
the monad 1/∞, and he gives the corresponding expression of the Leibnizian
God as ∞/1, the VLE of transcendence—which Leibniz needlessly
absolutized into pure transitivity, as that which stands outside of the flow of
time, pre-establishes, tyrannizes and fatalizes its harmony. With the off-
shucking of the Leibnizian pre-rationalisms, Leibniz’s substance as
“renormalized” monad therefore becomes “substance: ab3-”, and his God
becomes “God: ab3+,” or ∞- vs. ∞+ respectively, each of which are “charged”
in opposition to the other, giving the Leibnizian system its unique intrinsic
tension, seen together as: ∞/1 vs. 1/∞.

Page | 711
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

With his “principle of unity” as a function of holonic emergence from an


infinite immanence of folds, or “pleats of matter,” Leibniz incorporated only
the immanent (charged) pole of the I/T axis into his definition of
“substance.” This was the monad as emergent “surface” (or vinculum)
surrounding his “metaphysical point,” equivalent to our interface on the
immanent/transcendent uni-axis. Spinoza, on the other hand, took the
omni-axis itself, in its unfolding and manifesting aspect of immanence—the
ALL—as his Substance. His God then becomes the enfolding aspect of
transcendence, the ONE. And together they are the ONE-ALL, as Substance
becomes identified with God and God Substance. Thus, we have seen,
Spinoza explicitly reaches an essentially nondual Rationalism, both infinitely
immanent and transcendent, and which unfolds and enfolds the infinite
pluralism of Leibnizian monads—as the ONE to the ALL and vice versa.
Spinoza, however, failed to differentiate precisely the monads from the
modes, and the heaps from the holons. However, as we have seen, with his
“simplest bodies,” we find a critical ground-level holon not differentiated in
Leibniz, thus solving the problem of infinite holarchical depth.i And with the
Spinozan definition of finite essence as homeostasis we also find a defining
feature of the monad complimentary to the emergent principle of finite unity
in Leibniz. Taken together we have a surprisingly modern, nondual and
holarchical system of emergent homeostasis and fundamental organicity.
Leibniz does attempt come back to the immanence in transcendence
through his holarchy of monads and the idea of God as the “monad of
monads,” but this view collapses in light of the bounded scope of the monad.
God, we saw, cannot be a monad. Necessarily, and as the VLE intimate, the
boundary for his God must then attract to the inverted boundary of the
monad, with the limit at unity on the inside and the infinite on the outside:
∞/1. With deified man as the source monad for this entire anthropocentric
system, this God as the “monad of monads,” simply becomes his inverted and
perfected mirror image. This cosmic tension, this tacit identity of opposites
between man and God, perhaps explains why Leibniz was attracted to the
anthropomorphic conception of the pre-rational Christian God, whereas
Spinoza was inexorably drawn to its trans-rational Nietzschean, Heraclitean
and Parmenidean dissolution.

i
See, The Problem of the Infinite Holarchy (p578).

Page | 712
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

This then brings Leibniz squarely in accord with Spinoza at the absolute
level, but with the benefit of integrating, rather than negating the differences
that make these systems unique. Through the use of the scope parameter,
we can see that Leibniz is taking the pluralistic, or ab3 view of the absolute
I/T axis and polarizing, charging, and unbalancing its binary components
into his crucial tension between the pre-rational transcendent/transitive
God and the rational/immanent/intensive monad, and hence between God
and man. This I/T polarizing view is the inverse identical to the I/T unifying
view adopted by Spinoza, and the symbiotic and harmonic tension—the
“shock” between the two methodologies as explicated in SpinbitZ—brings a
“New Harmony” a cultivated third, transcending and including, retaining, not
draining, the elements and details spawned from each.
So, in dramatic conclusion, to reach Leibniz = Spinoza, we end with a
measly formula. We simply (and anticlimactically) multiply,i reintegrateii
and re-equilibrate, the two charged (bounded) poles of the Leibnizian
system (see below):

i
…since multiplication is the inverse operation of division and since it is the cultivated third
(interface) in the onion of operations between the I/T infinite and the transitive infinite…
ii
many have used the term “collapse” here, in reference to impending resolution of Leibniz’s
harmonically self-contradictory system, into the non-contradictory harmony of the Spinozan system.

Page | 713
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM

(Leibniz = Spinoza)

or

(God: +ab3)(monad: -ab3) = (Substance-God: ab1)

or

(transcendent)(immanent) = Absolute Infinite

or

1
ALL ONE
1

or

and finally…

Page | 714
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES

Page | 715
I would like to give a special thanks to Juan Calsiano for helping me to find
my way out of this dark labyrinth. Without his constant help and feedback
this book would not have been possible. And Robert Kernodle’s deeply
embodied dance with the human language, as well, was a constant source of
feedback and inspiration. And also Gerald Lebau, for his brilliant
demonstration of the raw power of the imagination to effect an exquisitely
beautiful causal understanding of the fundamentals of nature—and through
his patience in leading me up the treacherous paths to the other side of the
mountain—I cannot begin to thank him enough. But it was through my
mother’s wisdom and her understanding of the value of the arts for the
development of a young child—and in her own patience and constant
support, that the very foundations of my being were constructed. She was,
and is, a true renaissance woman. And I’d like to also thank my wife Liz, and
my son Grey for patiently and lovingly enduring this difficulty of an absent-
minded and absent-bodied father… I’m finally coming home …

Page | 716
Figure 1: The Holonic Solidus: .................................................................................................84
Figure 2: Space in the Process of Infinite Division by Spheres: .................................................89
Figure 3: Embryogenesis of the Concept: .............................................................................. 109
Figure 4: The Yin-Yang of Emptiness and Form: ..................................................................... 117
Figure 5: Polarity: ................................................................................................................. 118
Figure 6: The Main VCS Diagram: .......................................................................................... 143
Figure 7: The Nuclear VCS Diagram With Coordinates: .......................................................... 145
Figure 8: The Omni and Uni Axes and Interfaces: .................................................................. 151
Figure 9: Ontic-Epistemic Polarity: ........................................................................................ 179
Figure 10: The Tree of Singular Time: .................................................................................... 191
Figure 11: The Univocity Framework Template: .................................................................... 194
Figure 12: “Finite Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two”: ....................................................... 250
Figure 13: Orthogonality at the Boundary: ............................................................................ 254
Figure 14: Univocity Framework for the I/T Axes and Interfaces: ........................................... 260
Figure 15: Polarity of the Forms in the Cycle of Unity: ........................................................... 261
Figure 16: VLE of the Cycle of Unity: ...................................................................................... 263
Figure 17: The Orbit of Unity: ............................................................................................... 264
Figure 18: The Double Orbit of Unity (ant mobius image from M.C. Escher): .......................... 266
Figure 19: Mandelbrot Fractals: ............................................................................................ 286
Figure 20: The Infinite Coastline:........................................................................................... 287
Figure 21: The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attribute and Mode: .................... 289
Figure 22: Fuller’s Isotropic Vector Matrix (IVM): .................................................................. 302
Figure 23: Boundary as the First Dimension: ......................................................................... 306
Figure 24: Transitive and I/T Relations: ................................................................................. 313
Figure 25: Agglomeration and Transitivity: ............................................................................ 314
Figure 26: The Image of the Trans-Bias in the Cartesian Graph and the Identity Line:............. 317
Figure 27: Numbering the Infinite: ........................................................................................ 319
Figure 28: The Primitive Numerical Identities: ....................................................................... 320
Figure 29: The Implicit Input/Output Polarity (Iopol) of Addition and Subtraction: ................ 322
Figure 30: The Abacus and the Iopol: .................................................................................... 324
Figure 31: The Iopol of Multiplication/Division: .................................................................... 328
Figure 32: Doubled Addition: ................................................................................................ 329
Figure 33: Multiplication/Division Commutativity and the Breaking of Unit Closure: ............. 331
Figure 34: The Image of Absolute Value (or the absolutely valuable image): .......................... 338

Page | 717
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Figure 35: Immanent Zero: ................................................................................................... 339


Figure 36: The Map of the Origin-Identities: ......................................................................... 342
Figure 37: The Onion of Operations: ..................................................................................... 347
Figure 38: The Trans-Trans Instability: .................................................................................. 349
Figure 39: Imagining the Imaginary axis: .............................................................................. 355
Figure 40: Fuller’s 4-D Logo: ................................................................................................. 356
Figure 41: Triangular vs. Rectangular Accounting: ................................................................ 358
Figure 42: Triangular Multiplication Table: ........................................................................... 359
Figure 43: Triangular vs. Quadrangular Accounting (Uniformity): .......................................... 360
Figure 44: 4-D Event-Stars: ................................................................................................... 362
Figure 45: 4-D Event-Spheres: .............................................................................................. 363
Figure 46: 4-D Restraints: “Four Vectors of Restraint Define Minimum System”:................... 364
Figure 47: The Holarchical Evolution of Number and Operation in the Vision-Logic Coordinate
System: ............................................................................................................................... 374
Figure 48: SpinbitZ Diagram, Primal Form: ........................................................................... 376
Figure 49: SpinbitZ <– S-Z –> :............................................................................................... 380
Figure 50: SpinbitZ Yin-Yeight: ............................................................................................. 380
Figure 51: The Saw-tooth Curve of Iopol Inversion in the Evolution of Number and Operation:
............................................................................................................................................ 382
Figure 52: The Binary Cycle of Origin-Identity and Unity: ...................................................... 384
Figure 53: Immanent Function: ............................................................................................ 394
Figure 54: Balanced (Rational) Function: .............................................................................. 394
Figure 55: Trans-Trans Function: .......................................................................................... 395
Figure 56: Transcendent Function: ....................................................................................... 396
Figure 57: Powers, Roots, Exponential and Logarithmic Functions and the Input/Output
Polarity:............................................................................................................................... 398
Figure 58: The Onion Offset: ................................................................................................ 399
Figure 59: Spinoza’s Geometrical Example of the Bounded Infinite: ...................................... 419
Figure 60: Limits on the Geometrical Example: ..................................................................... 429
Figure 61: The LOMA and the Paradox: A Geometrical Example: ........................................... 439
Figure 62: Verelst’s Zenonian Binary Tree and Semi-Lattice: ................................................. 469
Figure 63: Zeno’s Stadium Paradox: ..................................................................................... 474
Figure 64: Objectivist/Subjectivist Remapping to the Ontic/Epistemic Polarity: .................... 501
Figure 65: Ontic/Epistemic Orthogonal Quadrants: .............................................................. 505
Figure 66: A Cognitive Modification or Holon: ...................................................................... 508
Figure 67: Attribute parallelism:........................................................................................... 514
Figure 68: Extension and the I/T Axis: .................................................................................. 518
Figure 69: The Cognitive Holon and the Subject/Object Interface with Immanence and
Transcendence: ................................................................................................................... 521
Figure 70: Duality Chasm: The Vista of the Expanded Crossroads: ......................................... 525
Figure 71: The Star of Complexity: ........................................................................................ 528
Figure 72: The Sensory/Mnemonic Interface: ....................................................................... 534
Figure 73: The All-Talking Mouth: ........................................................................................ 535
Figure 74: Identity Theory vs. Neutral Monism: .................................................................... 538
Figure 75: Double-Crossing Dualisms: ................................................................................... 551
Figure 76: -ic Versus -ology: ................................................................................................. 553
Figure 77: The EOTC of the Triune Dimensions of the Epistemic/Subject at the Crossroads of the
Ontic/Object:....................................................................................................................... 556
Figure 78: Embryogenesis of the Epistemic Categories:......................................................... 559
Figure 79: The AQAL Quadrants of Integral Meta-Theory:..................................................... 561
Figure 80: The Expanded AQAL Map:.................................................................................... 562
Figure 81: Quadrant Absolutisms in AQAL Meta-Theory: ...................................................... 566
Figure 82: The I/T AQAL Grid: The Quadrants as a Transitive-Plane on the I/T axis: ............... 568
Figure 83: The “Eight Primordial Perspectives” and their Methodologies: ............................. 573
Figure 84: Simple Depth Vs. Span: ........................................................................................ 576
Figure 85: Holonic Depth vs. Span: ....................................................................................... 577
Figure 86: Depth vs. Size: ..................................................................................................... 580

Page | 718
TABLES AND LISTS

Figure 87: Involution is Evolution Seen in Reverse: ................................................................ 585


Figure 88: Holonic and Holarchic Depth: ............................................................................... 594
Figure 89: The Self-Aperture and Sensor-Effector Polarity: .................................................... 619
Figure 90: AQAL Grid of Quadrant Interfaces with Knowledge-Acquisition Theories: ............. 638
Figure 91: Correspondence on the I/T-AQAL Grid and its Missing Interfaces: ......................... 643
Figure 92: The Foundational Pyramid: ................................................................................... 647
Figure 93: Coherentist Raft Over the Abyss: .......................................................................... 651
Figure 94: Foundherentism and the “Analogy of the Crossword Puzzle”: ............................... 653
Figure 95: Leibnoza Von Spinbitz—The Only Surviving Portrait .............................................. 663

Equation 1: VLE: ab1 — The Infinite: The Root VLE ................................................................ 293
Equation 2: VLE: ab1 — Expanded Root Equation and VLE: Cycle of Unity .............................. 293
Equation 3: VLE: ab2 — The Aspect Infinite ........................................................................... 294
Equation 4: VLE: ab2.1 — The Uni-Axis with Interface at Finite (Bounded) Unity ................... 294
Equation 5: VLE: ab3- — The Bounded-Immanent Infinite ..................................................... 295
Equation 6: VLE: ab3+ — Transcendent Infinite ..................................................................... 295

Principle 1: Chord 1: The Fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism (PNDR) ....................87


Principle 2: The Un-Principle of Principles: ..............................................................................88
Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of Immanence in Transcendence (Yin in Yang) ....................98
Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR) .............................................. 119
Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID) ........................................... 188
Principle 6: The Pearl Principle of Axiomatic Encapsulation ................................................... 240
Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity ........................................... 248
Principle 8: Chord 6: The Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity (or The Principle of Holonic
Polarity) ............................................................................................................................... 251
Principle 9: Chord 7: The Principle of Pure Transcendence as Transitivity .............................. 695
Principle 10: Chord 8: The Principle of Infinite Possibility (or the Principle of the Proton
Pseudos) .............................................................................................................................. 696

Page | 719
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

(1997), Bede Griffiths.


Badiou, Alain. "Gilles Deleuze, The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque." Gilles
Deleuze and the Theater of Philosophy. Ed. Constantin V. Boundas and
Dorothy Olkowski. New York: Routledge, 1994. 51-69.
Blavatsky, Helena Petrovna. The Secret Doctrine (Reprint edition). Theosophical
University PR, 1999.
Clayton, Philip. The Problem of God in Modern Thought. Wm. B. Eerdmans
Publishing, 2000.
—. The Problem of God in Modern Thought. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing, 2000.
Cooper, David E. Metaphysics. Blackwell Publishing, 2000.
Damasio, Antonio. "Looking for Spinoza." n.d.
Deleuze, Gilles and Felix Guattari. What is Philosophy? Columbia University
Press, 1996.
Deleuze, Gilles. Difference and Repetition. n.d.
—. Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza. Brooklyn: Zone Books, 2005.
—. Spinoza: Practical Philosophy. San Francisco: City Lights Books, 1988.
—. The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque. Mineapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, 2001.
—. The Logic of Sense. n.d.
Dennett, Daniel. Consciousness Explained. n.d.
—. Darwin's Dangerous Idea. n.d.
Donovan, Thom. “Thought's Torsion” on the blog “Wild Horses Of Fire: what
wings raised to the second power...”.
<http://whof.blogspot.com/2007/01/thoughts-torsion.html>.

Page | 720
BIBLIOGRAPHY

Duffy, Simon. "The Logic of Expression in Deleuze’s Expressionism in Philosophy:


Spinoza: A Strategy of Engagement." International Journal of Philosophical
Studies (n.d.): 47-60.
Durant, Will. The Story of Philosophy. n.d.
Dyson, George B. Darwin Among the Machines. Addison Wesley, 1997.
Edmonson, Amy C. A Fuller Explanation. 1987.
Einstein, Albert. "Forward. Reflections and Maxims." Runes, Dagobert D.
Reflections and Maxims. New York: Philosophical Library Inc, 1965.
Fox, Claude L. Ph.D. Foundations: A Manual for the Beginning Student of
Epistemology. Lanham: University Press of America, 1999.
—. "personal correspondence."
Frame, Michael. "Fractals and Education: Helping Liberal Arts Students to See
Science." Pickover, Clifford A. Fractal Horizons. n.d.
Fuller, Buckminster. No More Second-Hand God. n.d.
Fuller, R. Buckminster. Synergetics: Explorations in the Geometry of Thinking.
Macmillan Publishing Co. Inc., 1975, 1979.
Goetschel, Willi. Spinoza’s Modernity: Mendelssohn, Lessing, and Heine. n.d.
Greene, Richard. "Lecture Notes on Epistemology: Weber State University."
Ogden, 2005.
Haserot, Francis S. "Spinoza’s Definition of Attribute." The Philosophical Review
62 (1953): 499-513.
Hegel, G. W. F. Hegel’s Science of Logic. London: George Allen & Unwin, 1969.
Hypothesis, The Continuum. "McGough, Nancy."
<http://www.ii.com/math/ch/#overview>.
Kant, Immanuel. The Critique of Pure Reason, 2nd Edition. 1787.
Kelly, Kevin. Out of Control: The New Biology of Machines, Social Systems, and
the Economic World.
Lauritzen, William. "Nature's Numbers." 1994. 27 May 2007
<http://www.earth360.com/articles/naturesnumbers.html>.
Lebau, Gerald I. The Nature of Matter and Energy. Self-published (1965) web-
published as "The Orb" (2003 anpheon.org), 1965.
Lebau, Gerald. "personal correspondence."
Leibniz, Gottfried Wilhelm. De Quadratura Arithmetica. 1676.
—. Discourse on Metaphysics and the Monadology. Prometheus Books, 1992.
—. "Letter to de Volder."
Lem, Stanislaw. Imaginary Magnitudes. n.d.
—. Summa Technologia. n.d.
Levey, Samuel. "Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually Infinite Division of
Matter." The Philosophical Review 107 (1998): 49-96.

Page | 721
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Lipton PhD., Bruce. "Fractal Evolution." 2006-7. brucelipton.com.


Lynds, Peter. "Time and Classical and Quantum Mechanics: Indeterminacy vs.
Discontinuity." (n.d.).
—. "Time and Classical and Quantum Mechanics: Indeterminacy vs.
Discontinuity." (n.d.).
Macdonald, Jim. "Spinoza and Leibniz: Strong Affinity on the Nature of Infinity."
Washington, DC: Presented to Washington, DC, Spinoza Club, 3 September
2002.
Marks, John. Gilles Deleuze: Vitalism and Multiplicity. London: Pluto Press, 1998.
Maturana, Humberto. and Francisco Varela. The Tree of Knowledge: The
Biological Roots of Human Understanding. Boston: Shambhala, 1987.
May, Todd. "Difference and Unity in Gilles Deleuze." Marks, John. Gilles Deleuze
and the Theater of Philosophy. n.d.
Metcalf, Beth. 26 July 2007
<http://users.rcn.com/bmetcalf.ma.ultranet/index.htm>.
Montag, Warren and Ted Stolze, The New Spinoza. Minneapolis : University of
Minnesota Press, 1997.
Negri, Antonio. The Savage Anomaly. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota
Press, n.d.
Netz, Dr. Reviel. Interview. NOVA.
Oldershaw, Rob. Fractal Cosmology. 26 July 2007
<www.amherst.edu/~rloldershaw/menu.html >.
Opdenberg, H. R. "Universe of Infinite Variety." Theosophy. 8 July 2006
<http://www.theosophy-nw.org/theosnw/science/sc-opden.htm>.
Ouspensky, P. D. Tertium Organum: The Third Canon of Thought, A Key to the
Enigmas of the World. n.d.
Pratt, Vernon. "One for Leibniz." SORITES (1996): 10-20.
Pruss, Alexander R. "Can Two Equal Infinity? The Attributes of God in Spinoza."
2002/2004.
<http://www.georgetown.edu/faculty/ap85/papers/TwoInfinity.html>.
Russell, Bertrand. "The Philosophical Importance of Mathematical Logic." (n.d.).
Sorenson, Roy. A Brief History of the Paradox: Philosophy and the Labyrinths of
the Mind. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.
Spinoza, Baruch. Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being. New York:
Philosophical Library, Inc., 1958.
Spinoza, Benedict De. Ethics; On the improvement of the Understanding;
Correspondence. New York: Dover, 1955.
Staloff, Darren. Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition: Lecture 12:
The Philosophy of G.W. Leibniz: Audio CD Lecture: The Teaching Company.
n.d.

Page | 722
BIBLIOGRAPHY

—. Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition: Lecture 33: Spinoza—


Rationalism and the Reverence for Being: Audio CD Lecture: The Teaching
Company.
Stewart, Matthew. The Courtier and the Heretic: Leibniz, Spinoza, and the Fate
of God in the Modern World. New York: Norton, 2006.
—. The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy with
Illustrations. New York: Prometheus Books, 1997.
Stillwell, John. Yearning for the Impossible, The Surprising Truths of
Mathematics . Wellesley, Massachusetts: A.K. Peter, Ltd. , 2006.
Surin, Kenneth. "Spinoza, Baruch." Parr, Adrian. The Deleuze Dictionary. Ed.
Adrian Parr. New York: Columbia University Press, 2005. 260-2.
The Lotus Sutra.
Verelst, Karin and Bob Coecke. "Early Greek Thought and Perspectives for the
Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics: Preliminaries to an Ontological
Approach." CLEA-FUND, Free University of Brussels (n.d.).
Verelst, Karin. "Some remarks on the relation between the microcosmical and
macrocosmical." CLEA, Free University of Brussels (n.d.).
—. "Zeno's Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality." FUND-CLEA
Vrije Universiteit Brussel (n.d.).
Voltaire. Candide. n.d.
Watson, Burton, trans. The Lotus Sutra. n.d.
Watts, Alan W. The Joyous Cosmology. New York: Pantheon, 1962.
—. The Two Hands of God. n.d.
Wilber, Ken. A Brief History of Everything. Boston: Shambhala Publications,
1996.
—. Integral Spirituality. Boston: Integral Books, 2006.

Page | 723
Absolute Infinite, 39, 243, 269, 273, Aristotle, 28, 171, 174, 224, 440, 449,
274, 275, 277, 278, 280, 291, 292, 455, 456, 457, 463, 464, 468, 469,
443, 445, 447, 584, 713 470, 471, 472, 473, 474, 475, 479,
acategorical imperative, 45, 49, 52, 66, 480, 550, 556, 557, 561, 672, 709
67, 188, 331, 375, 422, 440, 441, Arnheim, Rudolph, 22, 25, 125, 126,
638, 643, 653, 670, 672 127, 128, 129, 131, 220
advaita, 57 Aspect Infinite, 137, 191, 274, 275, 276,
aleph null, 87, 230, 231, 286, 446 277, 286, 292, 447, 663, 707
anatom, 209, 249, 295, 572, 573, 590 asymptote, 273, 280, 293, 391, 392,
Anaxagoras, 29 393, 394, 395
Anaximander, 451, 452, 460 a-tomos, 572
Anaximenes, 451 axis of univocity, 195
animality, 708 Badiou, Alain, 223, 224, 287, 641, 642,
apeiron, 72, 74, 76, 78, 79, 111, 162, 669, 684, 706, 707, 708
221, 226, 227, 448, 451, 452, 460, baroque, 669, 709
465, 467, 468 Berkeley, George, 47, 404, 405, 406,
apoapsis, 262, 264, 276, 280, 505 597, 628, 632, 705
Applewhite, Ed, 363 bijection, 225, 226, 232, 280
AQAL, 107, 163, 236, 251, 348, 493, biology, 601, 609, 704
495, 496, 502, 504, 558, 559, 560, blind-logic, 128, 205
561, 562, 563, 564, 565, 566, 567, Bodhidharma, 46, 542, 597
569, 574, 576, 584, 591, 594, 596, breaking of closure, 381, 385, 439, 584,
631, 632, 634, 635, 639, 640, 649, 696
654 Bucephalus, 174
AQAL metatheory, 560, 562, 563, 564, calculus, 30, 37, 72, 73, 78, 79, 89, 99,
566, 567, 574, 591, 631, 639 140, 203, 233, 272, 288, 339, 401,
arborescent, 573, 577, 578 402, 403, 404, 405, 406, 408, 410,
Ariadne, 73, 84, 95, 118, 121, 224, 245, 413, 414, 415, 417, 419, 420, 421,
332, 415, 477, 640, 675, 691, 707 422, 423, 424, 425, 426, 427, 428,
429, 430, 431, 478, 675, 704, 710

Page | 724
INDEX

infinitesimals, 406 503, 505, 514, 543, 544, 545, 549,


nonstandard analysis, 406 553, 554, 597, 629, 631, 640, 656,
solution to the problem of, 415 658, 667
Candide, 685 cultivated third, 39, 108, 148, 149, 167,
Cantor, Georg, 87, 136, 203, 214, 217, 181, 225, 263, 269, 274, 291, 294,
223, 226, 229, 233, 235, 238, 275, 439, 509, 543, 552, 706, 712
278, 286 cultivating third, 28, 167, 169, 170, 175,
calculus, 427 177, 191, 194, 452, 543, 593, 607,
cardinality, 470 608, 641, 642, 648, 654, 656, 658
controversies of, 442, 443 Cycle of Unity, 122, 148, 149, 151, 198,
controversies, solution, 448 200, 224, 253, 257, 259, 261, 262,
countable and uncountable, 446 275, 276, 277, 286, 290, 291, 294,
culmination of rationality, 707 301, 303, 308, 309, 310, 323, 325,
irrational numbers, 367 337, 350, 354, 371, 382, 383, 384,
irrational numbers as infinite 420, 455, 460, 461, 470, 505, 508,
numbers, 367 555, 569, 570, 597, 598, 663, 705,
Leibniz, echoes of, 411 706
three infinities, 269 Damasio, Antonio, 35, 64, 67, 125, 539
transfinite, 467 deep evolution, 50, 599, 600, 602, 603,
transfinite numbers, 367 605, 608, 620, 622, 624, 642
Zeno, prefigured by, 465 deep infinity, 72, 98, 99, 131, 156, 159,
Zeno’s paradox, 449 161, 168, 172, 184, 186, 291, 348,
Chardin, Pierre Tielhard de, 598 373, 375, 442, 663
chemotaxis, 612 deictical, 469
chiaroscuro, 29, 71, 669, 705, 710 Deleuze, Gilles
cogito, 62, 375, 514, 515, 528, 529, acategorical imperative, 66
546, 549, 584, 597, 598, 625, 628, alternative lineage of history, 33, 59
632, 633, 635, 656, 657, 659 alternative Spinoza, 92
coherentism, 96, 162, 543, 656, 657, and chiaroscuro, 71
659 animality, 707
commutativity, 328, 329 anti-Hegel, 180
compossible, 688, 689 calculus, differential point of view
con-fusion of, 408, 423
definition of, 123 cogito of the dissolved self, 597
Corpus Hermeticum, 141 Descartes, 89
cosmogonic, 149 fold, 224, 288, 293, 412, 529, 641
countability, 220, 229, 230, 231, 232, intensive forces, 170
234, 279, 311, 445 irrational numbers, 369
countable, 87, 88, 136, 138, 217, 230, joy, 22
231, 236, 257, 308, 311, 313, 318, Leibniz and chiaroscuro, 669, 706
326, 343, 349, 351, 382, 383, 385, Leibniz, fraternal relationship with,
387, 414, 415, 419, 445, 446, 462, 709
467, 471, 472, 473, 474, 476, 478, logic of expression, 97
480 monad formula, 684
crossroads of the ontic-epistemic and numerical distinction, 168
subject-object, 28, 41, 224, 496, ONE-ALL, 165

Page | 725
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

organicity, 529, 707 Einstein, Albert, 40, 44, 64, 119, 124,
philosophy, definition of, 134 127, 189, 196, 208, 236, 238, 440,
plane of immanence, 131 492, 493, 584, 693
rationalism, secret of, 27 embryogenesis of the concept, 25, 27,
rhizome, 573 28, 50, 58, 94, 108, 109, 110, 111,
set-theory, 223 114, 136, 163, 206, 241, 255, 260,
Spinoza, 416 261, 268, 269, 273, 277, 278, 296,
Spinoza and Leibniz, 661 298, 302, 303, 309, 310, 317, 325,
Spinoza as anti-Descartes, 52 374, 387, 403, 415, 530, 543, 544,
Spinoza, Ethics and univocity, 419 557, 561, 593, 611, 625, 656, 665,
transcendental empiricism, 514 666
truth of relativity, 596 entheogen, 130
univocity, 155 erewhon, 152, 158, 321
univocity as organizing principle of ergodic, 152
Spinoza's Ethics, 39 Escher, M.C., 25, 72, 98, 113, 116, 117,
denumerability, 229 143, 203, 264, 373, 449
dependent arising, 33, 40, 50, 52, 59, eternalism, 58, 59
69, 86, 93, 98, 101, 102, 107, 157, Euclidean, 44, 146, 147, 148, 150, 218,
163, 168, 169, 191, 196, 197, 198, 224, 244, 257, 267, 277, 278, 281,
251, 418, 452, 489, 561, 562, 563, 297, 306, 327, 335, 341, 350, 353,
576, 645, 666, 682, 683, 688 409, 570, 707
Descartes, Rene Eudoxus, 367
as pre-rationalist, 61 extensionless, 74, 85, 120, 147, 218,
as proto-rationalist, 670 219, 220, 249, 251, 305, 333, 338,
as proto-rationalistist, 61, 89 409, 413, 414, 428, 570
cogito, 597 externalism, 543, 656
dualism, 539 fallibilism, 539, 652, 654
imaginary numbers, 349 fatalism, 90, 646, 693, 694, 701
pre-Socratics, 454 fissurotomy, 41, 546
reconciler of science and religion, 41 force, 39, 170, 187, 416, 462, 523, 537,
Spinoza, anti, 40, 52 564, 572, 599, 673, 703
descriptive protocols, 40, 174, 501, formative protocols, 174, 502, 504,
502, 504, 507, 508, 512, 514, 525, 508, 509, 513, 514, 523, 525, 535,
527, 528, 534, 535, 537, 538, 539, 539
540 foundationalism, 92, 96, 97, 98, 100,
deterritorialize, 34 103, 120, 156, 157, 160, 162, 179,
diagonalization, 230, 445 237, 313, 375, 405, 534, 536, 543,
dimethyltryptamine, 130 656, 657, 659
dividual, 434, 436, 440 foundationlessness, 103
dogma, 43, 45, 49, 50, 237, 638 four-dimensionality, 221, 305, 354,
Duffy, Simon, 34, 35, 36, 37, 38, 424, 359, 360, 361, 362
425, 426, 427, 430, 431 Fox, Claude L., 547, 552, 553, 555, 556,
effector, 612, 613, 614, 615, 616, 617, 632
619, 625, 641, 647 freedom, 684
free-will, 7, 65, 152, 164, 442, 486, 512,
645, 684, 687, 688

Page | 726
INDEX

Frege, Gottlob, 213, 232 Haserot, 491


Fuller, R. Buckminster Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich, 36, 38,
"attic window", 33 46, 47, 79, 160, 161, 164, 168, 169,
"multiplication through division", 79 171, 173, 175, 179, 180, 181, 182,
"nucleation of observability", 503 183, 225, 269, 408, 417, 418, 419,
"unity is plural and at minimum 420, 421, 422, 424, 426, 430, 454,
two", 196 496, 510, 677, 698, 700, 704
anti-specialization, 23 Spinoza, misinterpretation of, 160
conceptuality, 129 Heraclitus, 28, 29, 58, 141, 156, 173,
Einstein, 189 451, 452, 454, 455, 456, 477, 561,
finite absolutism, 267 695
first dimension, 305 holarchy, 42, 43, 48, 77, 108, 123, 126,
four dimensionality, 354 140, 158, 168, 175, 176, 194, 205,
holarchy, 137 209, 210, 212, 213, 251, 260, 324,
Isotropic Vector Matrix, 300 331, 335, 344, 345, 371, 387, 390,
language as the first industry, 48 392, 398, 400, 401, 413, 475, 522,
modelability, 206 529, 555, 556, 557, 558, 564, 565,
multiplication through division, 328 569, 572, 573, 574, 575, 579, 580,
nuclear geometry, 33 581, 582, 584, 587, 590, 591, 622,
omni-directional halo, 141 641, 643, 706, 711
Operational Mathematics, 247 Hollingdale, 37
point-free geometry, 137 holon, 94, 108, 140, 163, 177, 205, 209,
real point, 137 212, 249, 254, 295, 506, 507, 508,
sphere, 302 514, 516, 520, 568, 569, 572, 573,
Synergetic Geometry, 137, 218, 296 574, 575, 577, 578, 579, 580, 581,
dimensions, 300 584, 590, 591, 683, 706, 711
Synergetic Geometry as structural homunculus, 440
relation, 354 Hume, David, 35, 42, 43, 47, 66, 232,
tetrahedron, 299 280, 445, 597, 697
volumetricity, 137 hylomorphism, 174
function, 387 I/T axis. See Immanent/Transcendent
fundamental question, 177 axis
Galilei, Galileo, 28, 214, 215, 216, 217, identity theory, 537
218, 226, 229, 231, 235, 236, 279, idiographic theories, 187, 188
401, 441, 443, 444, 480, 482, 498, imaginary number, 305, 335, 341, 342,
633 346, 349, 350, 351, 352, 353, 365,
Gassendi, Pierre, 572 619
Gerolamo, 350 immanent determinism, 185
Gettier, Edmund, 651, 652, 658 Immanent/Transcendent axis
Gödel, Kurt, 500, 636, 653 definition of, 143
Great Chain of Being, 38, 39, 48, 496, impermanence, 681
561, 587, 696 incompossible, 686, 688
Guattari, Felix, 22, 131, 573 indiscernables, 183
gyri, 611, 641 inertia, 295, 582, 584
Haack, Susan, 649
Habermas, Jürgen, 36

Page | 727
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

infinite regress, 39, 92, 98, 99, 100, anti-Cartesian, 60, 86, 89
103, 211, 313, 338, 408, 637, 648, anti-Spinozism, 69, 196
665 as anti-Spinozist, 672
infinitieth term, 230, 231, 411 as atheist, 699
input/output polarity as exoteric rationalist, 68
definition of, 319 as pre-rationalist, 669
Integralism, 36 as rationalist, 47
intelligent design, 601, 605, 612 as reactionary modernist, 669, 675,
intensive forces, 170 677
intepretation, 156 as Spinoza plagiarist, 68
interaccommodative, 298 as Spinozist, 69, 673, 699
interparadigm, 563 binary logic, 122
intertheoretical reduction, 160 calculus, 401, 403
involution, 117, 141, 581, 582, 583, Candide, 685
641, 667 Cantor, 410, 446
iopol. See input/output polarity chiaroscuro, 29, 669, 699
irrational number, 137, 220, 223, 231, complexity, 642, 704
333, 338, 351, 353, 365, 366, 367, compossibility, 688
368, 369, 371, 379, 388, 446 continuum, 148
Kant, Immanuel contra Spinoza, 676
antinomies, 480 corpuscularianism, 572
contra Cantor, 229 creation event, 197
dualism, 41, 546 Deleuzian alternative lineage, 38,
epistemic reductionism, 180 156
forms of sensibility, 621 determinism, 693
Great Chain of Being, 40 disharmonious universe, 701
misinterpretations by, 34, 38 emergence, 377
ontic-shadow, 41, 546 emotion, 63
radical ontotomy, 41, 546 eternal now, 195, 377
Khun, Thomas, 618 exoteric agenda, 675
koan, 86 extension, critique, 693
kosmos, 24 fatalism, 646, 693
Kronecker, Leopold, 312, 366 fold, the, 223, 641, 707
Laplacian, 219 freedom, 646
Lauritzen, William, 356, 357 God, 677, 699
Lebau, Gerald I., 5, 6, 30, 32, 86, 103, God, "presumptive will of", 701
109, 132, 205, 304, 305, 332, 407, Hegel, 417
436, 477, 478, 479, 517, 552, 715 Heraclitus, 29
Leibniz, Gottfried, 518 honesty, 70
"active space" and the arrow of human as divine, 681
time, 183 hyper-essentialism, 172
"City of God", 675 immanent determinism, 186
"magic mirrors", 684 immortality, 681, 695
alternative interpretation, 47 Indra's net, 197
Anaxagoras, 29 infinite, 99
animality, 707 infinite baroque machine, 642

Page | 728
INDEX

infinite convergent series, 410 solution to the problem of the


infinite divisibility, 86 calculus, 415
infinite divisibility of matter, 224 Spinoza, fusion with, 28, 661, 702
Infinite, Absolute, 273 Spinoza, misinterpretation of, 160
Infinite, actual, 99, 367 Spinoza, misrepresentation of, 678
Infinite, Aspect, 274 Spinoza, obsession with, 675
Infinite, Modal, 280 Spinoza, plagiarist of, 702
infinitesimals, 402, 408 Spinoza, secret studies of, 272, 411,
influence on modernity, 704 413
Integral philosophy, 506 Spinozism, 673
labyrinth of the continuum, 74, 402 substance, 667, 682
Leibnizian dilemma, 698 termini, 224
matter as infinitely divided, 407, 506 the principle of the best, 680
metaphysical necessity, 689 Theophile, 679
metaphysics, improbability of, 698 Theosophy, 28, 60
metaphysics, obsolete pre- transcendental determinism, 646,
rationalisms, 705 693
modern mathematics, anticipations transfinite, 446
of, 410, 470 transitivity of, 690
monad, 295, 518, 682, 699 Triune Infinite, 271, 402
monadology, 196, 682, 683 univocity violation, 199
monism vs. monadology, 158 virtue, 695
moral necessity, 689 world of all possible worlds, 682
Nature, 677 Zeno, 477
omnimaniac, 704 zero, "amphibian between being
organicity, 708 and non-being", 337
point, 224 Lem, Stanislaw, 5, 130, 502, 584, 606,
popular religion, 675 607
possibility, 678 Levey, Samuel, 148, 407, 408, 410, 411,
possible worlds, 680 412, 413
pre-established harmony, 693 Lightyear, Buzz, 443
pre-Socratics, 454, 460 Locke, John, 35, 47, 64, 65
principle of macrocosm and LOMA, 436, 438, 439, 477
microcosm, 196, 684 definition of, 436
principle of sufficient reason, 680, Macherey, Pierre, 34, 36
686 machinic, 615
principle of the best, 685 Madhyamaka Buddhism, 31, 58, 156
principle of the best, problems of, mannerism, 710
685 mathemagicians, 462, 463
principle of unity, 247, 377, 506, 683 Matta, Roberto, 129
problem of sex, 685 Maturana, Humberto, 529, 618
rationalism, 671 mechanotaxis, 611
reactive modernist, 52 meditation, 57, 375, 555, 584
relativity of space and time, 693 megala, 467, 475, 476
salvation, 701 Meinong, Alexius, 651
science, 704

Page | 729
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

mensuration, 265, 301, 302, 303, 365, naïve realism, 625, 626, 627
371 natural number, 87, 169, 266, 295, 312,
mereology, 211, 213, 223, 234, 235, 314, 317, 319, 320, 321, 322, 326,
445, 708 368, 402, 443
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 39, 642 Negri, Antoni, 36
metaphysical necessity, 689, 690, 701 neocortex, 641
metaphysico-theologo- Netz, Reviel, 227, 228, 232, 233, 444
cosmolonigology, 685 neutral monism, 534
metastable, 589 Nietzsche, Freidrich, 37, 156, 160, 169,
mind-body problem, 62, 486, 488, 489, 173, 179, 187, 454, 661, 678
499, 500, 688 nihilipsism, 515, 529, 597
Minkowski, Herman, 238 nomothetic, 187, 188
mnemonic interface, 189, 513, 518, nondualism, 37, 57, 58, 61, 66, 158,
531, 537, 539, 544, 553, 584, 595, 171, 183, 186, 191, 240, 317, 666
596, 597, 614, 617, 620, 630, 631, nonduality, 27, 33, 50, 52, 57, 58, 65,
641, 656, 667 77, 90, 112, 155, 165, 169, 171, 173,
mnemonic primitives 176, 180, 191, 192, 237, 240, 241,
definition of, 529 374, 378, 426, 452, 455, 460, 537,
mobius, 116, 264, 265, 595, 708 544, 555, 584, 646, 691
Modal Infinite, 282, 283, 412, 442 noumena, 42
monad, 29, 196, 197, 198, 199, 200, numerical distinction, 52, 167, 168, 180
274, 295, 407, 413, 428, 529, 646, numerical identity, 74, 80, 171, 173,
660, 661, 671, 674, 681, 684, 685, 325, 328, 331, 333, 420, 430, 455,
693, 694, 695, 696, 697, 699, 700, 537, 538, 547, 706
701, 702, 706, 707, 708, 709, 710, objective-ontic shift, 160, 509, 534
711, 712, 713 observability, 267, 487, 505, 506, 517,
monadology, 69, 71, 72, 89, 158, 196, 518, 525, 539, 543, 550
223, 224, 225, 272, 407, 672, 676, occasionalism, 90
698, 705, 706, 709 Oldershaw, Rob, 99, 205, 587, 588, 591
monism, 36, 158, 159, 165, 167, 171, omni-axis
173, 488, 496, 534, 535, 537 definition of, 146
monological, 133, 599 omnidimensional, 139
Montag, 34 omnidirectional, 139, 141, 145, 146,
moral necessity, 689, 690 280, 291
multiplicity, 7, 29, 59, 96, 107, 108, omnilocal, 147
109, 111, 149, 156, 160, 165, 166, omnimaniacal, 705
189, 196, 241, 243, 250, 255, 260, omni-non, 122, 123, 148, 149, 151, 188,
270, 273, 275, 276, 287, 410, 447, 212, 227, 242, 246, 255, 257, 276,
460, 464, 477, 569, 574, 578, 584, 277, 282, 292, 294, 297, 299, 301,
590, 601, 604, 606, 621, 624, 628, 302, 303, 304, 305, 309, 328, 350,
639, 642 383, 384, 387, 410, 414, 455, 515,
myth of the given, 43, 45, 568 529, 663, 698
Nagarjuna, 33, 36, 37, 39, 50, 58, 59, omniradial, 301
66, 67, 80, 98, 169, 270, 401, 407, omnisimilar, 359
440, 452, 561, 665, 666, 670, 677, omni-uni, 151, 255, 258
681 oneironaut, 139

Page | 730
INDEX

onion of operations, 348, 385, 387, 460, 561, 632, 635, 672, 676, 682,
391, 396, 398, 399, 400, 712 709
ontic-epistemic polarity, 178, 491, 505, Poincaré, Henri, 206, 238
552, 570 positive infinity, 27, 39, 46, 50, 80, 82,
ontogeny, 125, 344, 400, 562, 611, 617, 83, 89, 93, 99, 103, 122, 156, 162,
620 182, 184, 288, 289, 335, 341, 369,
ontologies, 30, 99, 100 373, 374, 375, 378, 389, 407, 410,
ontos, 547, 550, 623 419, 422, 426, 428, 642
ontotomy, 41, 42, 49, 546, 547, 548, postdarwinian, 598
623 postformal, 133
Opdenberg, H.R., 660 post-ontology, 48, 49, 558, 559, 570
ordinality, 467 pragmatism, 316
organicism, 709 pre-established harmony, 90, 274, 646,
organicity, 708, 711 695, 697, 698, 700, 701, 703
origin-identity, 122, 341, 343, 382, 383, Presocratic, 450, 453, 454
388, 395 Prigogine, Ilya, 184, 186
orthogonality, 136, 142, 252, 351, 352, Procrustes, 39
353, 354, 522 propria, 667
Ouspensky, P.D., 125, 433, 600 protolife, 599
Pangloss, 685 proto-rational, 89, 140, 314, 661, 670,
Parmenides, 28, 29, 69, 70, 88, 450, 671
452, 453, 454, 455, 456, 457, 458, Pruss, Alexander, 274, 275, 282
459, 463, 464, 469, 471, 477, 478, Pythagoreanism, 633
561, 668, 670, 676 quadrant interface, 649
misrepresentations, 457 qualia, 503, 520, 527, 528, 530, 537,
PAR-Tunnel, 632, 633, 634, 635 597, 618, 620, 627, 630
Pearl Principle, 238, 279, 444 Rado, Steven, 205
percipi, 597 Rational number, 73, 74, 75, 76, 79, 80,
performative contradiction, 181, 205, 82, 83, 84, 87, 88, 89, 122, 152, 277,
267, 558, 638 295, 330, 332, 333, 335, 336, 354,
periapsis, 262, 263, 280, 383, 505 367, 368, 406, 418, 419, 420, 576
perspectival, 45, 289, 339, 408, 415, Rationals, 74, 79, 80, 83, 278, 292, 316,
423, 425, 488, 489, 492, 496, 565, 324, 330, 366, 379, 381, 401, 445,
568, 584, 626, 666 446
perspectivism, 569, 639 Real number, 446
phenomenae, 57 realism, 459, 625, 626, 627, 628, 634
phylogeny, 125, 344, 400, 611, 617, 620 rectilinearity, 351, 353, 619
physicalism, 527 redshift, 521
physiosphere, 677 rhizome, 573
Pickover, Clifford, 87, 285 Sagredo, 216
plane of immanence, 128, 131, 132, salvation, 695
134, 156, 160, 162, 167, 169, 170, Salviati, 215, 216
172, 182, 184, 191, 525, 662, 667, scalactic, 140
709 scalaxis, 140
Plato, 28, 59, 69, 70, 174, 224, 225, schmiderialism, 633
302, 312, 455, 456, 457, 458, 459, Scotus, Duns, 38, 156

Page | 731
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

second tier, 343, 387, 446, 453 Cartesianism, 38


self-similarity, 142, 207, 453, 584, 641, contra Leibniz, 676, 677, 694, 698
659 crossroads, 490, 543
sensor-effector polarity, 614, 615, 616 Deleuzian alternative lineage, 156,
Sephiroth, 141 424
Serres, Michele, 108, 509 dependent arising, 40, 52, 168, 561,
sex, 109, 434, 602, 603, 605, 685 666
silentium universi, 575 Descartes, 670
simplest bodies, 506, 518, 521, 529, determinism, 646
574, 582, 584, 587, 588, 589, 590, differential point of view of the
591, 592, 643, 711 infinitesimal calculus, 428
Simplicius, 459, 462, 464, 476, 479 dogma, 50
Skepticism, 628, 637, 639 Einstein, 492
Socrates, 28, 456, 457, 458, 460, 561 emergence, 511, 534
solidus, 74, 79, 82, 122, 199, 243, 244, emotions, 63, 647
245, 246, 247, 259, 260, 261, 262, empiricism, 64, 65, 92
263, 275, 291, 303, 314, 317, 324, essence, 58, 173
325, 329, 332, 333, 334, 335, 340, essence and Leibniz's principle of
343, 344, 345, 348, 384, 388, 390, unity, 506
392, 393, 394, 395, 396, 398, 399, eternal now, 646
461 Ethics, 98
sorce, 170, 523 excellence, 500, 529
spaceless, 46 existentialism, 666
Spinoza, Baruch experience, 64
"depth", 574 extension, 521
"Leibniz's ghost", 673 finite (definition), 225
acategorical imperative, 63 finite unity, 247
active Substance, 168 fold, the, 223, 641, 707
alternative interpretation of, 34, 96, freedom, 647, 694, 701
671 Galilean paradox, 214
and the Great Chain of Being, 38 geometrical example, 418, 422
anti-Cartesian, 52, 60, 86, 89, 168 God, 678, 682
anti-Hegel, 179, 181 Hegel's misrepresentation, 417
anti-Plato, 174 heresy, 672
AQAL, 565 identity theory, 534
Aristotle, 174 imagination, 265, 442
as empiricist, 35, 65 immanent determinism, 185
as enlightened, 52 immortality, 695
as existentialist, 173 infinite determinism equals
as modernist, 62, 67 indeterminism, 185
as non-Rationalist, 44 infinite divisibility, 86
attempted assasination of, 674 infinite modes, 286
attribute (definition), 491 Infinite, Absolute, 274
attributes, 488 Infinite, Aspect, 274, 707
calculus, 402, 407, 408, 420, 423 Infinite, Modal, 280
Cantor, 444, 481 infinity, 122, 448

Page | 732
INDEX

influence on modernity, 704 substance as immanence, 179


Integral philosophy, 506 Theosophy, 32, 60
interpretive rift, 490 Tractatus, 675
intuition, 68 transcendent bias, 695
Kant, 621 transcendental injunction, 53
Leibniz, 68, 196 transfinite, 446
Leibniz, fusion with, 28, 29, 661, 702 transrationalist, 67
Leibniz's Spinozism, 674 Triune Infinite, 72, 98, 224, 229, 269,
Letter XII, 148, 271 408
Locke, 65 Triune Infinite in the Ethics, 287
meditation, 375 univocity, 39, 59, 159, 172
mind-body problem, 62, 525 villified, 672
mnemonic primitives, 534 virtue, 695
modern mathematics, anticipations Zeno, 462, 465, 476, 481
of, 470 Staloff, Darren, 40, 501, 704
mortality, 681 Stewart, Matthew, 35, 36, 43, 47, 52,
multiplicity, 164 60, 61, 62, 64, 65, 66, 67, 68, 69, 70,
Nagarjuna, 180 92, 161, 164, 165, 185, 196, 197,
Nature, 677 198, 271, 416, 450, 451, 452, 453,
neutral monism, 534, 535 455, 489, 490, 498, 511, 528, 623,
nondualism, 169, 172 633, 634, 646, 655, 661, 669, 671,
nonduality, 665 673, 674, 675, 676, 677, 678, 679,
objective-ontic shift, 498 680, 681, 684, 688, 689, 690, 694,
omni-axis, 149 695, 696, 697, 698, 699, 700, 701,
on Cantor, 225 702, 704, 706, 709
ontic/epistemic polarity, 534 sub specie aeternitatis, 88, 189, 196,
ontological proof, 50 375, 463, 584, 646, 695, 697, 702
parallelism, 511, 534, 535 subdivisibility, 281
Parmenides, 672 subject-object polarity, 555, 667, 692
point, 414 sulci, 611, 641
positive infinity, 103 sunyata, 59, 80, 407
possibility, 678 superfluid, 589, 590
post-metaphysics, 49 supertask, 217, 472, 680
pre-Socratics, 454 Surin, Kenneth, 36
rationalism, 60, 670 symbiogenesis of subject and object,
real difference, 168, 547 66, 86, 93, 94, 194, 196, 518, 537,
recieved view, 33 544, 550, 556, 584, 615, 617, 618,
relativity of space and time, 693 620, 626, 627, 629, 631, 635, 641,
salvation, 701 656, 657, 695, 708
science, 704 symptomatology, 187, 188
scope, 593 synaesthetic, 130
simplest bodies, 506, 521, 587, 591 Synergetic Geometry, 32, 137, 218,
simplest body, 261, 295 220, 249, 296, 297, 328, 354, 356,
sub specie aeternitatis, 88, 189 363, 407, 409, 570, 619
substance, 97 Synergetics
substance as active, 180, 183 dimensions, 300

Page | 733
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I

Tao, 3, 56, 58, 60, 72, 76, 92, 95, 107, uncountability, 138, 474
136, 137, 161, 162, 176, 182, 273, uncountable, 87, 88, 136, 146, 152,
317, 613, 694 158, 172, 230, 231, 236, 254, 255,
Tao Te Ching, 3, 56, 58, 60, 76, 92, 107 256, 257, 290, 294, 308, 311, 313,
technolinguistic, 606 327, 329, 333, 343, 346, 349, 353,
telos, 254 367, 368, 369, 374, 379, 382, 385,
teraform, 24 387, 401, 405, 410, 414, 415, 419,
tetrahedron, 297, 298, 299, 300, 301, 421, 422, 426, 427, 428, 429, 445,
305, 354, 355, 359, 360, 361, 362, 446, 457, 462, 465, 466, 467, 469,
363, 364, 365, 619 470, 471, 472, 473, 474, 476, 477,
texturology, 708, 709 478, 479, 480
Theaetetus, 367 uncuttable, 119, 572
Theodorus, 679 uni-axis
Theophile, 679 definition of, 146
Theosophy, 28 unit-closure, 123, 170, 248, 309, 314,
thinkability, 141 315, 317, 318, 319, 324, 326, 328,
trans-bias 330, 331, 332, 335, 346, 371, 374,
definition of, 93 375, 377, 387, 402, 429
transcendental determinism, 646, 693, unit-identity, 170, 309, 310, 311, 316,
694, 700 317, 318, 319, 320, 321, 322, 323,
transcendental number, 74, 75, 140, 324, 325, 327, 328, 330, 332, 333,
482 336, 340, 348, 350, 351, 366, 384,
transfinite, 88, 203, 211, 214, 216, 223, 385, 387, 388, 390, 395, 400, 429,
225, 227, 230, 234, 243, 250, 270, 461, 543, 554, 708
277, 278, 279, 367, 368, 369, 411, univocity, 27, 36, 39, 60, 72, 89, 97,
442, 443, 444, 446, 447, 448, 449, 155, 156, 157, 159, 163, 165, 166,
477, 480, 482 172, 175, 176, 177, 178, 180, 182,
transitive axis 183, 184, 186, 188, 191, 192, 193,
definition of, 138 194, 195, 196, 198, 200, 222, 243,
trans-rational, 27, 30, 31, 46, 51, 66, 270, 288, 341, 408, 441, 492, 684,
67, 73, 74, 93, 98, 106, 140, 147, 692
204, 218, 220, 245, 278, 343, 369, Univocity
377, 397, 398, 399, 414, 446, 488, as organizing principle of Spinoza's
543, 559, 584, 661, 662, 711 Ethics, 39
triangle, 299, 328, 355, 357, 358, 359, Urner, Kirby, 363
361, 362, 437, 438, 439 vector, 151, 256, 297, 298, 299, 300,
Triune Infinite, 30, 72, 98, 137, 148, 302, 318, 359, 362, 373
149, 163, 166, 189, 224, 225, 227, Vedantic, 42, 546
232, 239, 241, 242, 243, 250, 260, Venturi, 254
261, 269, 270, 271, 272, 273, 286, Verelst, Karin, 88, 141, 146, 231, 455,
287, 289, 290, 293, 303, 318, 331, 457, 459, 462, 465, 466, 467, 469,
401, 407, 408, 409, 410, 412, 414, 470, 471, 472, 473, 474, 475, 476
421, 423, 424, 430, 442, 444, 445, virtuality, 169
446, 470, 476, 477, 482, 525, 662, vision-logic equation, 199, 204, 242,
666, 675, 707 243, 246, 290, 303, 572, 598, 662
Tschirnhaus, 68, 69, 489, 675 definition of, 289

Page | 734
INDEX

vision-logic interface, 26, 27, 28, 129, fundamental physics, 118


159, 235, 263, 271, 294, 387, 444, immanence, 75
543, 654 immanent/transcendent axis, 143
VL-axis infinite division equals indivisibility,
definition, 136 88
VLE. See vision-logic equation misrepresentations, 457
Volovik, 589 nonduality, 462
Voltaire, 685 non-Zenonian premises, 463
Wilber, Ken, 30, 32, 33, 34, 38, 39, 48, non-Zenonian time, 463
52, 53, 54, 61, 103, 107, 115, 123, paradoxes, 28, 234
133, 134, 149, 156, 163, 204, 209, "as the door to all wonders", 28
236, 348, 413, 487, 493, 495, 496, Achilles, 472
502, 504, 555, 558, 560, 561, 562, Arrow (the naked paradox), 474
567, 568, 569, 571, 618, 642, 654, Dichotomy, 471
672 of motion, 449
windowless, 71, 196, 197, 199, 669 of motion, 469
Zahl, 467 of plurality, 449
Zeno plurality, the core paradox, 455
"simultaneous division through and Stadium, 472
through", 462 tuned and triuned (resolved), 476
"Zenonian semi-lattice", 88, 467 uncountably infinite, 462
and the fundamental principle of refutational attempts, 449
nondual rationalism, 84 scope con-fusion, 457
calculus, implicit seed, 401 Simplicius' first-hand accounts, 459
Cantor, 225 the fold, 707
demonstrating the ONE-ALL of Zermelo-Fraenkel, 213
Parmenides, 453 Zinacantan, 141

Page | 735

You might also like