Morrison Spin BitzV1
Morrison Spin BitzV1
999…
See www.spinbitz.net for more info.
Copyright © 2007 by Joel David Morrison. All
rights reserved. No part of this book may be
reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or
transmitted, in any form or by any means
without prior written permission from the
author or his estate.
Page | 3
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
This is a highly collaborative work, drawing, often unconsciously, on many
sources both known and unknown and working at many levels, across many
disciplines spanning nearly the whole spectrum of human knowledge and
ideas. The net is cast wide, but as such it cannot possibly hit all relevant
points in-between, and it also cannot penetrate with equal depth into all its
points of contact. The vast depth and complexity of these systems of human
thought makes the construction of the linear linguistic interface between
them seem like (in the words of Stanislaw Lem) “giving birth to a leviathan
through the eye of a needle—which turns out to be possible, if the leviathan
is sufficiently reduced. But then the leviathan looks like a flea. Such are my
problems when I try to adapt [this emergent system of living concepts] to …
language.”i
Writing such a book is like skinning an 11-headed dragon into one long
and thin strip of leathery scales. How can one retain the iridescent living
beauty and patterning of the scales? Or the elegant curvature and
serpentine motions of the intertwining necks? Or the form of the
musculature in the legs, torso and arms? … To strip away the metaphor, how
can one retain the emergent structure and inter-connective synergetic
harmony of the simultaneous actions of hundreds of billions of nerve-cells
and electro-chemical gradients as they emerge into the higher-level thought-
patterns that make up this living system of concepts if one reduces it to a
single, long line of alpha-numeric text which the reader must transcode and
attempt to bring to life, bit by tiny bit? Can I effectively convey the broad
simultaneous network of interconnected ideas after it is run through the
spaghetti machine of human language? This question, at the interface of
i
(Lem, Imaginary Magnitudes, Golem XIV), oooh such grandiosity to take the perspective of Golem
XIV, but its resonance to our human nature provides such a clear line of departure, illustrating the
holarchical nature between deep embodied semantics and higher-level syntax.
Page | 5
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
As Gerald Lebau so eloquently stated in the preface to his 1965 work, The
Nature of Matter and Energy:
All in all, this is a highly interconnected and interdependent set of
concepts. No one part can be fully understood until all of it has been
finished. The reader’s patient indulgence is urgently requested. The major
intellectual effort required to complete the book should be most
adequately rewarding.
Ultimately, we have to progress linearly in unfolding this complex nonlinear
system, so our communication depends critically on the patience of the
reader to allow the nonlinear intuition of critical underlying concepts and
contexts—that have not yet been given their time on the stage—to naturally
and fully emerge. As Deleuze might say, the reader must allow the “plane of
consistency” in the text to fully arise, lest a premature criticism enforce a
false reading in this highly inadequate linear method of communication.
To this end I have attempted to give as much nonlinearity as possible to
the construction. I have supplied many visual diagrams, and I have tried to
format the book hierarchically by subject, and sequentially by generality—
from the general to the specific—and have given cross-references (and
hyperlinks for the ebook format) where possible (see the back of the book
for formatting specifics). The book should unfold adequately for most
readers in the sequential format, but it can also be approached nonlinearly
by subject—jumping to new subjects or levels of generality/specificity as
needed, in order to explore, or give context to the current position on the
chosen nonlinear trajectory.
My only wish is that this book be enjoyed, because only if it is enjoyed will it
be understood. Let the dialogue unfold as you, the creative reader, see fit. If
it is not fun following a sequential format, then by all means skip around.
Hopefully the formatting and style of the book will be adequately
accommodating.
Page | 6
…
stone-walled into compartments
form is stolen from potential
like the exoskeleton of a new insect
liberating protoplasm to wander
into the labyrinthine tomb of its own hardening limbs.
Page | 7
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
interfaces. And through us, these living monoliths grope and crash their way,
ever onward, inward and upward, to a deeper, vaster, higher, more coherent,
comprehensive and organic coalescence.
Slowly drifting and converging through the infinite “space of
possibilities,” the rigid and cracked empirical, logical and mathematical
exteriors of the pragmatic, exoteric and quantitative systems move toward
integration with the expanding soft and supple center of ancient esoteric
wisdom—the common, unmoved, yet ever-yielding core of singular
“metaphysical” understanding manifesting throughout all cultures of man
and intrinsic to his deepest intuitions. This ubiquitous, esoteric wisdom is
only divided and conquered—flattened into layers and layers trampled
under foot with each successive generation—by the fossilization of
differences in the superficial details of the rigid and arbitrary categories of
man’s symbol-systems. It is merely the institutionalization of the different
arbitrary mappings—to the same living and breathing core—that stands
between them.
…Being is univocal.
i
— Gilles Deleuze, Difference & Repetition
Page | 8
A NOTE TO THE READER...........................................................................................5
PRELUDE: SPELL-BINDING ........................................................................................7
CONTENTS (QUICK).................................................................................................9
CONTENTS (FULL) .................................................................................................10
FORMATTING NOTES .............................................................................................20
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY .....................................23
PROLEGOMENA: NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM .........58
PART ONE: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY..................... 106
THE INTERFACE BETWEEN INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL RATIONALISM ...........107
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT (EOTC) .............................................................108
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM (VCS).......................................................125
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEWORK (UF) ........................................................................155
PART TWO: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS ...................................................... 202
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION ........................................204
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION ....................................309
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE SECOND TIER ................372
RECONNECTING THE LOST THREAD OF MATHEMATICAL RATIONALISM: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ,
IMMANENCE AND THE CALCULUS ...........................................................................402
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX ...............................434
PART THREE: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL RATIONAL-EMPIRICISM ... 486
PHILOSOPHY: THE INTEGRATING ART OF THE CONCEPT ..............................................487
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY AND “THE NUCLEATION OF OBSERVABILITY” ................488
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH .................................................544
LEIBNOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES ...............................................663
TABLES AND LISTS ....................................................................................... 719
BIBLIOGRAPHY ........................................................................................... 722
INDEX ....................................................................................................... 726
Page | 9
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 10
CONTENTS
Page | 12
CONTENTS
Page | 13
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 14
CONTENTS
Leibniz, Spinoza, the Triune Infinite and the Calculus ........... 403
The Inception of the Calculus ............................................................................ 403
The “Ghost of Departed Quantities” and the Problem with the Infinitesimal .. 404
Fixing “The Limit” of the Unlimited ................................................................... 406
The Hidden Leibnizian Thread ........................................................................... 407
The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite...................................................... 409
Leibnizian Pre-Echoes of Cantor........................................................................ 411
The Nondual-Rational Interface Solution .............................. 415
Reconnecting to the Deleuzian Alternative Lineage ............. 418
Hegel’s Calculus of Misrepresentation .............................................................. 418
Deleuze and the “Differential Point of View of the Infinitesimal Calculus” ...... 424
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
.............................................................................. 434
The Acategorical Perspective and the LOMA ........................ 435
Paradox and the LOMA: A Geometrical Example .............................................. 437
Paradox as Transitive Illusion of Perspective .................................................... 441
Galileo, Cantor and the Transfinite ....................................... 444
The Two-Floors of the Transfinite ..................................................................... 447
Summary: The Nondual/Interface Definition and Resolution of the Nature of
Infinity ............................................................................................................... 449
Back to Zeno .......................................................................... 450
Swirling in the Presocratic Soup ........................................................................ 451
From Muck Into Form ................................................................................... 452
Parmenides and Second-Order Philosophy ................................................... 453
Corso and Recorso: Self-Similarity in the History of Philosophy ................... 454
Plurality is Unity: Zeno’s Core Paradox ............................................................. 456
Post-Socratic Scope Con-Fusion .................................................................... 458
Parmenides, Heraclitus, and the Cycle of Unity and VL-Axes ....................... 461
Simultaneous Division “Through and Through” ................................................ 463
Aside: Countable and Uncountable, Linear vs. Parallel and the “Hard
Problem” of Consciousness........................................................................... 467
Zenonian Plurality and the Binary Interface of the VL-Axes .............................. 467
The Paradoxes of Motion and the Many Faces of Plurality ............................... 470
The Dichotomy: “Motion Cannot Take a Start” ............................................ 472
The Achilles: “Motion Cannot Come to its End” ........................................... 472
The Stadium: “The First Two Arguments Combined for Extended Bodies” ... 473
The Naked Paradox (The Arrow): “Motion is Self-Contradictory” ................ 475
Tuning and Triuning the Naked Zenonian Interface .......................................... 477
Further Cultivating the Zenonian Third ............................................................. 478
Paradoxical Postscript and Epitaph: Kan’t and the Antinomies
of Pure Reason ...................................................................... 481
Page | 15
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 16
CONTENTS
Page | 17
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 18
CONTENTS
Page | 19
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Footnotes
In order to help the reader remain undistracted by the many notes and
references, and to increase the reader’s own control of the flow of such a
complicated experience, I have differentiated the notes into three types
(naturally), with their own simple hierarchical order of operations (see
below), and placed them at the foot for easy access. The reader will very
quickly become accustomed to the symbology and easily and unconsciously
become aware of which notes to entirely ignore and which to possibly
explore, according to his purposes.
1. Subject-Tangent (i): This is the default; just a regular note, a tangent
of thought, or a curiosity leading perhaps nowhere in particular… It
will have no specific symbol other than the roman numeral they all
share in common, such as.i
2. Subject-Link (*): This note signifies a subject reference, or a hyperlink
(for the ebook) for splitting off into a related but different subject
trajectory in the book. This note will be followed by an asterisk, as
such,ii* and the note itself will contain only a reference or hyperlink to a
different section of the book, along with perhaps a bibliographic
reference.
3. Bibliographic Note (¥): This is simply a bibliographic reference, for
those tracing back to original sources. It will be followed by a ¥, as
such.iii¥ Page numbers, where available, will be included with the
“quote,” such as (p66).
i
e.g. Bucky Fuller mentions that Roman numerals were generated from the common numbering
system of notches or slashes, where larger bundles of slashes, say of five, are marked with a slash
through them so as to be counted by fives. This new symbol of the slash then evolved, for example,
into the symbol ‘V’.
ii
* e.g. See this page.
iii¥
e.g. (Ouspensky) p. 56
Page | 20
Order of Footnote Operations: These types are arranged in order of
importance to the reader in controlling the nonlinear flow of his/her
experience. As such, the bibliographic note takes lowest priority, and the
quick subject-tangent the highest. Where any of these are combined, they
will be subsumed under their next higher order. For example, in any
instance of combination with a subject-tangent, the note will be subsumed
under this default subject-tangent referent, e.g. i . If the reader has further
interest in the subject-tangent, for example, he may also find a subject-link
and/or bibliographic note. But where the subject-link and bibliographic
note are combined, the referent of the subject-link (*) will be used. And only
where the bibliographic note stands on its own, will we find its referent, ¥.
Page | 21
Page | 22
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
Page | 23
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
i
Fuller was twice expelled from Harvard
ii
…though, at one point, it embraced and took over the difficult job of the camera, so it’s not merely
the rigor that it recoiled against, but rather the level of generality, perhaps.
Page | 24
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
arbitrary and even contradictory. I always want to ask WHY? And to see in
my mind’s-eye what is happening to lead to such a rule or habit.
Toward these ends and driven by these unconscious goals and
propensities for pleasure and vision in understanding, this meta-
mathematical system (Interface Mathematics) emerged; unfolding slowly,
yet spontaneously and intuitively. Rather than doing much of the homework
in my college algebra classes—which was designed to drill in the seemingly
arbitrary rule-systems and abstract concepts that otherwise have no
conceptual grounding—I would instead tease out the details of this new
system as they emerged from interfacing the new rules with the embryonic
meta-mathematical form already breathing itself to life in my mind.
Surprisingly, as I became more and more capable of visualizing, or
internally sensing the interactions and relations within the emerging
organism of this system, the whole of fundamental mathematics, with its
abstract and seemingly arbitrary principles, began to make intuitive and
visceral sense. It began to speak to me; no longer in riddles, but in pictures
and clear, sensible structures that mirrored my view of the kosmosi itself—
holarchical, boundless, endlessly unfolding. ii Mathematics no longer seemed
abstract and arbitrary, like random bits of code needing strings of
meaningless mnemonics to tie them down to a rigid and brittle chunk of
habitual finger-memory.
Ultimately, as it developed, I had to do less and less of the rote
memorization in the homework in order to pass my tests. And new ideas
presented in the class just seemed to illuminate, resonate and reinforce
hidden places already present in the system. The algebra class began to get
very exciting as I would continue to tease out how the mathematics naturally
unfolded in the vision.iii
i
Kosmos is the ancient Greek term not merely for the physical or objective universe (the cosmos)
but for ALL of reality, putting the subjective, and other spheres, on equal (neutral, nondual) footing.
ii
Holarchical means; wholes made of deeper parts, which are wholes made of deeper parts, which
are wholes made of deeper parts, and so on…
iii
In retrospect, I suppose it would have had the same “intellectual mustiness” which Fuller spoke of
when discovering some of his many generalized principles, laying dormant for an eternity to be
uncovered…if it hadn’t been overwhelmed by the feelings of sneaking into the graveyard of
respectable philosophy and digging the jewels off the dead fingers of my heroes, Spinoza and
Leibniz, and trying to get the crypt-keepers to trade it in for gold; rather than being content to stare
at the mausoleum frontispieces. No, this has an earthier feel, and the jewels have unexpectedly
turned to seed…readied to teraform the largely forbidden and deserted planet of esoteric
rationality.
Page | 25
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
But all of this was only made possible from a training in the visual arts. As
Rudolph Arnheim says in his book, Visual Thinking, “the arts are the most
powerful means of strengthening the perceptual component without which
productive thinking is impossible in any field of endeavor” (p3). Having
started my life as a visual artist, I gradually discovered that my artistic
expressions were becoming more and more philosophical as time
progressed. I would often notice that in the back of my mind, as I lay
thinking, an unconscious and intricate visual form was taking shape in my
visual field; line by line, curving and collecting into shape after shape,
unconsciously informing and solidifying the conceptual construction. Finally
the philosophy began to rise above, transcending-and-including this ever-
present and often unconscious visual art-form.
The same sort of process must have occurred, in some form, with M.C.
Escher, when he wrote in an essay entitled Approaches to Infinity:
However, it may happen that someday someone will feel a specific and
conscious longing ripening within him to approach infinity as purely and
as closely as possible by means of his representations. This may happen
i
* See the section Embryogenesis of the Concept (EOTC), p106.
ii
As Deleuze calls it.
Page | 26
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
The diagrams used in this construction are therefore found throughout this
work as they will help the reader to process the abstract linear verbiage
through the deeper, nonlinear and vastly parallel sensory functions that all
humans possess. It is ultimately through the senses, transcended-and-
included in higher, more abstract, cognition, that the sense of the text is truly,
integrally, embodied.
This is the general goal of SpinbitZ; to make sense of abstract thought
through the employment of the human interface of sensation; to empower
the conceptual imagination through images. Philosophy as the integrating
art of the concept; a philosophy of vision-logic interfaces—and hence an
Interface Philosophy.
Page | 27
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
Page | 28
OVERVIEW
Page | 29
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
i
When referring to Spinoza’s “substance” herein, we will capitalize it to make the distinction to the
common philosophical term and to distance ourselves from its foundationalist baggage.
ii¥
http://www.answers.com/Gottfried%20Leibniz
Page | 30
OVERVIEW
Page | 31
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
i
As Deleuze calls it, and as we will explore later.
Page | 32
This project emerged into consciousness as a spiraling visual interpretive
fusion of the systems of Spinoza and Leibniz. The systematic fusion began to
occur even before I learned of the recognition in esoteric philosophy of the
possibilities of this fusion for the emergence of “the truths of the archaic
doctrine.” This process was catalyzed through contact with many different
sources in science, art and philosophy, but most distinctly the work of R.
Buckminster Fuller (Bucky) and his absolutely beautiful Synergetic
Geometry,i* and Gerald I. Lebau with his work on a qualitative and causal
understanding of fundamental physics.ii
During my exploration and creation process I stumbled upon the work of
others, such as Gilles Deleuze and Ken Wilber, whose conceptual schemes
were deeply resonant, and in some places virtually identical to my own—
beneath the arbitrary and ultimately minor differences in word choices and
category lines. I have since gone back and infused their additional insights
into my own, allowing for further (if always unfinished) creative synthesis
and resonance, ever fueling this soft, organic explosion.
i
* See Part Two: Interface Philosophy (p200), and Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and the Nucleation of
Observability (p486) in this volume.
ii
Sorce Theory is a new theory of matter and energy based on an explicitly causal and unified
metaphysics matching in its general form the holarchical terrain explored (through its catalytic help)
in this book. See www.anpheon.org and the section Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement in
SpinbitZ: Volume II.
Page | 33
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
i
…minus the inherited Leibnizian-Kantian-Hegelian shadow-element from academia, as well as the
explicit grounding in the nondual framework of Univocity, which we will explore in much greater
depth later on.
Page | 34
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM
i
I have had several discussions with Wilber on this issue, and he continues to state that Spinoza is a
“dedicated Cartesian.” When challenged on this issue, however, he did not attempt to back up his
claim, so the appearance is that he got it from a second-hand source, without the context.
ii
¥ Pierre Macherey, ‘The Encounter with Spinoza’, trans. Martin Joughin, in Martin Patton (ed.)
Deleuze: A Critical Reader (Oxford: Blackwell, 1996), p.142. This is one of the questions central to
Macherey’s problematization of Deleuze’s reading of Spinoza in the ‘The Encounter with Spinoza’.
iii
¥ Ibid., p. 148.
iv
¥Warren Montag and Ted Stolze (trans. and eds), The New Spinoza (Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 1997), p. x.
Page | 35
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
Deleuze and many other thinkers have done, and even more now are
continuing to do. And this ever-renewed examination is critical, if indeed
Spinoza’s message was ahead of the times into which it was initially
injected—an era which cast its interpretive, enlightening and ultimately
obscuring forms upon it in the “History of Philosophy.” If Spinoza’s message
is for the future, then the future—perhaps indeed our “now”—must be freed
of the interpretations of the past in order to understand Spinoza’s message.
Duffy writes:
According to this conception of the history of philosophy, one way to
understand the ‘importance’ or ‘influence’ of the different figures in the
history of philosophy on contemporary thought would be to determine
‘the citations, the references, and the borrowings (acknowledged and
unacknowledged) that bind contemporary thought to the texts of’ these
figures, which would thus put each of them ‘in the position of a
predecessor or forebear whose thought “anticipated” the concerns’ of
contemporary thought.
Many thinkers have done just this with respect to Spinoza, exhuming the
influences of Spinoza’s thought in various contexts in the sciences, in history,
the humanities, and in philosophy, to name a few. For example, Matthew
Stewart, in The Courtier and the Heretic, examines Spinoza and Leibniz in a
very fresh and unbiased light, demonstrating that Spinoza’s philosophy was
directly influential to the empirical philosophy of John Locke, and that
Spinoza is not the “rationalist” that is generally claimed of him. Stewart
deftly shows that Spinoza is very much a forebear to radical empiricism,
such as that espoused by David Hume (we will explore this connection in
greater depth later on). Indeed, Deleuze himself sees Hume as a critical link,
and kindred spirit, in his alternative chain of history, with Hume following in
the path (if unconsciously through the work of Leibniz and Locke) laid out
by Spinoza.i
i
Another thinker demonstrating the influences and resonances from Spinoza's work is the modern
neuroscientist, Antonio Damasio, whose book, Looking for Spinoza: Joy, Sorrow, and the Feeling
Brain, demonstrates that Spinoza's philosophy can serve as a general basis for contemporary
explorations into the neurobiology of the emotions.
Page | 36
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM
And so we can see that the interpretation of Spinoza has changed radically
through the years, depending on the historical context in which it is
addressed. It is therefore anything but pre-given and static.
Indeed, in the last few decades there has been an explosion in Spinoza
scholarship. As Kenneth Surin states in his entry on Baruch Spinoza in The
Deleuze Dictionary;
In the last few decades the writings of Louis Althusser, Etienne Balibar,
Pierre Macherey, Antonio Negri, Deleuze and others, have marked a
resurgence of interest in the thought of Baruch Spinoza, in which
Spinoza’s … ontology has been used as a framework for constructing a
matrix of thought and practice not regimented by the axioms of Platonic
metaphysics, the epistemology of Rene Descartes, and the transcendental
rationalism of Immanuel Kant and Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel.
Titles like, The New Spinoza, i ¥ Spinoza’s Modernity, ii ¥ and The Savage
Anomaly: The Power of Spinoza’s Metaphysics and Politics,iii¥ are merely the
cusp of this evolving hermeneutic. And this trend readily seems to follow
the gradient of history, from Theism, to Secularism and to the new surge of
Integralism, and the resurging interest in ancient Nondualism. This
integration is occurring between many dualities across the sphere of
knowledge, but in Spinoza studies it is specifically occurring between
“eastern” and “western” interpretations and between and beyond his
intrinsic “rationalism” and “empiricism.”
The Spinoza hermeneutic follows a gradient from reactionary theism—
seeing the “god intoxicated man” as an atheist and heretic—to romantic
pantheism, to scientific-materialist monism, and now, at the interface
between the 20th and 21st centuries, we have the philosopher of univocity
and infinite difference (in Deleuze), the radical modernist and rational-
empiricist in Matthew Stewart, and—reinterpreting and integrating them
all—we find Spinoza, the nondual trans-Rational empiricist herein.
i
¥ (Montag and Stolze)
ii
¥ (Goetschel)
iii
¥ (Negri)
iv
It was Jürgen Habermas who explained how power necessarily distorts the channels of
communication.
Page | 37
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
outline of the Deleuzian project (and please note that it is clearly nondual in
purpose):
The task of modern philosophy is to overcome the alternatives [:]
temporal / nontemporal, historical / eternal and particular / universal.
Following Nietzsche we discover, as more profound than time and
eternity, the untimely: philosophy is neither a philosophy of history, nor a
philosophy of the eternal, but untimely, always and only untimely — that
is to say, “acting counter to our time and thereby acting on our time and,
let us hope, for the benefit of a time to come.”i¥
Indeed, Deleuze’s “task” he set for Philosophy echoes the task that Nagarjuna
set for himself, in his “philosophy of the middle-path,” which was to
overcome the dominating philosophical dichotomy of his time, to pulverize
the categories dividing the “eternalists” and the “nihilists.”
i
¥ From Duffy’s notes, “DR, xxii. The Nietzsche citation is quoted by Deleuze from: Friedrich
Nietzsche, ‘On the Uses and Disadvantages of History for Life’, Untimely Meditations, trans. R. J.
Hollingdale (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1983), p. 60.”
ii
¥ Quotes from, Difference and Repetition, p. 184., qtd. In Duffy
iii
* See Reconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and
the Calculus, p400.
Page | 38
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM
i
* see, The Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS), p123
ii
Expressed through the “cultivated third” of the attributes, seen herein as specialized functions of
the nondual concept of “dependent origination.”
Page | 40
UNCOVERING THE PROJECT OF ESOTERIC RATIONALISM
(also like Wilber’s holons) they are not eternal, pre-given and Platonic.
Rather, modes are always relative forms emergent within time and their
ultimate essence is never their own, but shared univocally and inter-
expressively with all other modes of the univocal Substance. The individual
essence of any Spinozan mode, as we will see, does not precede its existence,
but is a function of its emergent homeostatic nature to “persist in its own
being.”i* Forms—or modes, in Spinoza—participate in eternity only insofar
as they recognize and embody the understanding of their ineffable and
boundless source in (Nagarjunan/Spinozan/Deleuzian) logical-Emptiness.
This concept of “real difference”—as opposed to numerical difference—in
Spinoza, gives all forms and modes a necessary dependent arising, in direct
opposition to the Cartesian system rampant with numerical or absolute
distinctions, such as his duality of substances. Indeed, it is this Spinozan
concept of difference as a dependent arising that turns all of Descartes’
axioms against him, turning his Dualism into a nondual Rationalism.
There is, then, in Spinoza, no Great Chain from matter, to mind, to the
various forms and gradations of spirit. Indeed, this is the entire purpose of
Spinoza’s polarity of “attributes,” Thought and Extension (mind and matter,
within and without, or “I” and “IT,” respectively), which apply to all finite
and emergent forms at any level of “excellence.” This notion of the attributes
as expressing the essence of infinite Substance in the distinction between
fundamental perspectives—generally the within and without—is a very
common interpretation among Spinoza scholars and enthusiasts. It can be
found everywhere from Albert Einstein, to Darren Staloff,ii to Will Durant.
Spinoza does not collapse Thought to Extension, nor mind to matter, but
maintains a critical parallelism and polarity. Indeed, this polarity—or
identity of opposites—of the attributes, and this concept of real difference
enforcing a dependent arising of all form, is precisely how Spinoza converted
the Cartesian dual rationalism (and largely a pre-rationalism, as we will see)
into a fundamentally Nondual Rationalism.
And hence, the lumping, by Lovejoy, of all pre-Kantian ontology into the
term “metaphysics”—disparaged and devolved from the revolutionary
insights of the key esoteric rationalist and modernist, Spinoza, to an
absolutized categorical mythology, straight from the dark ages—is indeed a
procrustean bed which served more to give power to the reactionary critics
of radical modernity and Rationalism (the Idealists and post-modernists)
than to accurately interpret the key rationalists on their own terms, and
from their own plane of consistency.
i
* See Univocity and Essence, p170.
ii
Staloff calls the attributes the “descriptive protocols,” as we will explore both the descriptive and
the formative aspects of the attributes more deeply in the section Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and
the Nucleation of Observability, p486
Page | 41
Post-post-ism-ism is a “critical” condition running rampant through the
body of post-post-modern Philosophy. It’s Kant’s fault … or the fault-line of
those who interpreted and transformed his critical philosophy into a
respectable profession fit for the LCDi of exoteric academia. Kant, like
Descartes, set himself the task of reconciling science and religion, and
protecting each from the other—“Am I going to have to separate you two?”
And like Descartes, Kant’s procedure was a radical division, a dich-otmy
between two zones of the Philosophical body. Both Kant and Descartes had
the best of intentions, but you know what they say about the road to Hell…
Descartes’ project merely ended up in an inside-out bicameral
fissurotomyii between the mind and the brain. No problem, we’ve just about
recovered … finding little tricks to get the two halves to (feebly) interact
again. Kant, however, accidentally ended up nearly severing the
Philosophical body from its head.iii Beyond the poetry of this metaphor, we
will come to find that the very core of the epistemic emerges at the
crossroads of these actually orthogonal dualities—cultivated into their
respective polarities and triune-interfaces.
i
Lowest common denominator…
ii
The transitive (horizontal) severing of the subject/object polarity, as we will come to understand
shortly.
iii
The severing of the ontic from the epistemic on the orthogonal or vertical immanent/transcendent
omni-axis, as we will see. This is the crossroads of the subject/object and ontic/epistemic polarities,
on the transitive- and immanent/transcendent omni-axes, respectively.
Page | 42
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
The problem, we will explore near the end of this book, is that the ontic was
early on con-fused with The Absolute. Kant split the ontic and epistemic into
the illusory phenomena and the untouchable noumena. And hence forth,
making an ontic claim was equated with making claims about the ineffable
Absolute, or making absolute (dogmatic) claims in general—a waste of time
and a serious symptom of dementia.
The solution to this aspect of the post-Kantian mishap, we will find, is
simple, once the Vedantic doctrine of the Two Truths is allowed as a
distinction between the relative and absolute scopes—allowing the ontic to
regain its healthy esoteric capacity as the real and relative world of sub-
representational form it always was (Brahma), and the epistemic to be the
real illusion (Maya) it still wants to be.i* It was this holarchy between
relative-reality and real-illusion that Kant’s radical ontotomy, perhaps
accidentally, rendered asunder. And ontology and its rational and
transrational truths have been languishing in the obscurity this post-
modern, ontic-shadow ever since.ii*
i
* See the section, Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch, p541.
ii
* For the continuation of this metaphor, see the section, Condition Still Critical: Waking Up from
the Post-Op Nightmare of the Kantian Radical Ontotomy, p545.
Page | 43
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
limits of reason itself. Through logic and rationality he plumbed the very
nature—the reality beneath the experience—of the thinking and knowing,
rational mind. He was exploring the ontology of rationality or “pure reason,”
and what he found was knowledge prior to experience, i.e. innate knowledge
in the form of what he considered absolute categories, actually a
metaphysics upon which to firmly ground the relative certainties of science.
The forms or categories of reason (logic and sensibility or intuition)
were, for Kant, transcendental or a priori, meaning they exist and find their
justification for existence before or prior to experience (this is more
precisely immanent rather than transcendent, as we will see, however).
Experience itself, Kant argued, cannot exist without these ontic categories of
the epistemic.
As is commonly acknowledged even in academia, Kant was turning
metaphysics into a science. For Kant, Metaphysics in the bad or unscientific
sense, was reasoning or simple belief beyond the means or categories of
understanding, not beyond experience itself. This bad metaphysics is dogma,
not rationality and surely not ontology, given that Kant himself deduced his
own fundamental categories ontologically and as ontic forms at the very
nature of the knower himself. (To be sure, it is only because the ontic and
epistemic form a polarity and indeed a holarchy that to practice fundamental
epistemology—e.g. seeking the nature of the knower—is to practice a form
of ontology.)
Page | 44
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
the reverse, so Kant supposedly proved that the object of knowledge must
conform to the subject’s faculties of knowledge, and not the reverse.
… These stories about Kant are myths. The Kantian philosophy is not a
real turning point in the history of philosophy. It is a continuation of the
project of which the metaphysics he criticizes is merely one possible
expression. … Most of his philosophy can be understood as a reenactment
of what I have grandly called the dialectic of empiricism, which is itself an
instance of the search for the Holy Grail of Philosophy. To be sure, Kant
had a huge influence on subsequent philosophers, especially on the breed
who would become the professionals of the modern university. But this
just means that his name is useful as a collection point for a host of beliefs
and reconstructions, mostly based on misunderstandings.
This may indeed be somewhat of an exaggeration, but there are certain
truths in this account as well. Indeed, we will find Kant’s dichotomy
between the Rationalists and Empiricists entirely ill-fitting, when it comes to
Spinoza, and thus all the arguments against Spinoza via his status as
“Rationalist” will be found suspect as well.
The limits Kant imposed on experience were themselves purely
anthropocentric, and in this sense decidedly anti-Copernican. Copernicus
removed Man and his earth from the center of the Cosmos, whereas Kant
placed Man and his faculties back into the center of Philosophy, where he
had been with the sophists before him, for example. Kant’s exemplar was
also the Newtonian revolution, of which he was a champion. But it was the
Einsteinian upheaval after him which—while simultaneously refuting his a
priori absolute of Euclidean space and Newtonian physics—demonstrated
that all bodies, such as the earth, are indeed the center of their own warped
spaces, just as man is the center of Kant’s universe. Unlike Kant, however,
Einstein showed that the objects of physics and their warped fields are One.
The objects do not simply generate their fields, anymore than the fields
generate their objects. They arise together. In Einstein’s universe, an object
of matter is a congealed field, tied into self-stabilizing knots of energy. This
is similar to the principle of complementarity in quantum physics. Particles
no more can be reduced to waves than waves to particles. They co-evolve
and co-create one another in the very same act. And in this same self-
aggrandizing sense, after the “Einsteinian Revolution” of Interface
Philosophy, subject and object (or given-myth and mythic-given),
necessarily arise together, in a structural coupling or symbiogenesis, of
sorts, as we’ll see.
In effect, Kant created a metaphysics of experience, with his metaphysical
and ontological a priori (immanent) and “transcendental” categories of
experience. This metaphysics itself is often used—post-Kan’t (sic)—to deny
pre-Kan’tian metaphysics based on the assumption that these earlier
systems necessarily go beyond the categories of experience and thus cannot
be verifiable and scientific. Kant, however, outlined an entire set of
Page | 45
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
Page | 46
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
i¥
… from Daniel Dennett
ii¥
Qtd in Will Durant, The Story of Philosophy.(Durant)
iii
* See I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
Page | 47
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
Page | 48
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
Along with tacitly following Arthur Lovejoy in lumping most, if not all of pre-
Kantian metaphysics with the Great Chain of Being, Ken Wilber defines
‘metaphysics,’ “in the bad sense” also as a postulation of ontological entities
which cannot be empirically proven by science. Ironically, this would place
much of science (and its hidden Foundational metaphysics)—such as
“[insert your Ultimate Fundamental Object here] Theory,” and Cosmology—
in the category of “bad metaphysics” or bad ontology. They all do indeed
make fundamentally unjustifiable and unproven claims about the very
nature of reality.i
This problem, to me, is part of a subtly imprecise, reactive and ontic-shy,
inherited definition of post-metaphysics, in this post-Kantian era of rampant
post-post-ism-ism. There are clear and restrictive limits on empirical reality
that science and logic must at least attempt to move beyond. Indeed, science
does this all the time, and of necessity, as does Integral Post-Metaphysics
with its logical necessity of an infinitely deep holarchy of ontically real
holons.
Language, Buckminster Fuller tells us, was the first industry. It is based
on the collective technology and invention of the word. Likewise all
“language games” are forms of technology. ii And as we would expect from
the dialectic of progress, any technology that can be used, can also be
abused. The technology of metaphysics is no exception. Metaphysics is
abused, as Kant noted, in the taking of dogmatic stances, in postulating
ABSOLUTELY the existence (not necessarily the existence of the absolute) of
entities that cannot be proven. And more to the point, bad metaphysics is
the absolute belief in these entities despite its detriment to the rationality
and well-being of the user.
Post-metaphysics, and post-ontology, if it is to emulate the objectivity of
science, cannot be fundamentally opposed to merely postulating ontically-
real entities that cannot be proven empirically, because this is a necessary
function of science and philosophy at the limits of the augmented senses—in
the zone of pure-reason. Again, Kant himself identified the forms of logic
and the forms of sensibility as the forms of understanding itself necessary to
understanding anything. Mere hypothesis is not a belief system in itself, and
if we restrict ourselves to the merely empirical, then we end up with a
variant of logical positivism that no longer dares to wonder about what lies
i
Indeed, there is a rampant Foundational metaphysics hidden under much of Science, despite the
fact that Foundational truth-claims—a main feature of medieval Philosophy and Theology—have
been demonstrated extremely problematic and indeed illegitimate during the last century of
Philosophical progress.
ii
… or “life-forms” as Wittgenstein called them.
Page | 49
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
beyond the provincial pale of the augmented senses. A sad and safe little
representational world would that be.
Page | 50
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
thread to the positive infinity and secret of Rationalism. And, as we will see,
the Vision-Logic Coordinate System and the Univocity Framework, form a
meta-metaphysical framework within which metaphysics can find no
foundational ground with which to dogmatize and ism-ize itself.
For example, while it may indeed be true that Spinoza believed in his system
as ultimately True, it may also be true that in his age of rampant dogma, a
deep faith in one’s own way out of dogma was essential to his emotional,
intellectual and even to his physical growth and survival. It is also the case,
however, and critically so, that nothing in Spinoza’s philosophy depends on
any absolute belief whatsoever; as Deleuze says, even Spinoza’s ontological
proofs are “not hypothetical, but genetic.”i¥ Spinoza’s ontological proofs do
not attempt to prove a transcendent God, as do Leibniz’s. They show how
the relative concept, interfacing with the absolute, is properly, logically,
consistently, rationally and non-dually generated.ii Spinoza’s philosophy
does not rely on the belief in the properties of an existing entity. It merely
shows how to consistently and non-dually define it. Indeed, as we will see,
Spinoza renders the truths of the nondual traditions into the logic of
rationality. The positive infinity and secret of rationalism is the logical
equivalent of Nagarjuna’s Emptiness, while Spinoza’s concept of real
difference is the logical equivalent of dependent arising. Spinoza shows how
and why the truths of nonduality are entirely compatible with the truths of
rationality, and indeed how and why they are unavoidable and unassailable
for any logical and rational mind.iii*
Indeed, it will be shown herein how and why the positive infinity of the
rational does not give rise to antinomies, as Kant thought, but that the
necessities of logic and relation demand the existence of the infinite.
Regardless of whether the infinite can fit into the finite or indefinite
imagination of man, it can very simply fit into his logical and rational
understanding, itself informed in deep evolutionary symbiogenesis with
experience, intelligence and memory. To be sure, only through affirming and
incorporating the necessity, in the rational, for the infinite can the nondual
synthesis between the relative and the absolute be truly accomplished. Just
as only through incorporating the necessity of Emptiness in form, at some
level or zone, can the nondual begin to present itself.
Spinoza demonstrated that there is a valid way to generate and conceive
the nondual absolute in the crystalline rigor that the geometrical method of
the Ethics helped to provide. More than he believed in his absolute
i¥
Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, p79
ii
We’ll see this more explicitly through our “embryogenesis of the concept” in the section Spinoza: A
Nondual Sketch, p664.
iii
* See Spinoza: A Nondual Sketch, p664.
Page | 51
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
Page | 52
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
After getting to know Ken Wilber—working directly with him at his Integral
Institute for the past two years—I dearly love and greatly admire the man.
But he is, after-all, a man. And when the exalted authority of one man stands
in the way of the emergence of pragmatic and logical truths in another, less
known sphere, this authority must be questioned. It is in this healthy and
loving way that I attempt to inform the exoteric Received View of Spinoza in
Wilber’s work with my studies in esoteric rationalism .
In a recent encounteri¥ with Ken, he made the claim that Spinoza’s
philosophy could not be post-metaphysical because Spinoza himself was not
enlightened. But Wilber also makes the claim that Spinoza was “by his own
admission a dedicated Cartesian.” Indeed, Spinoza wrote an early book on
Descartes, within the confines of which he remained true to the Cartesian
system, but only in order to render it and study it correctly. It is this early
dedication to which Spinoza spoke, and to which Ken alluded. In Spinoza’s
mature work, as noted by most Spinozists, he went radically beyond
Cartesianism.
I challenged Wilber on this claim, stating that the majority of Spinozists
would disagree with the assumption that Spinoza could be classified as a
dedicated Cartesian. He then promptly retracted it, with the off-hand
comment that it was irrelevant to his points. On the contrary, it is precisely
relevant. The fact that Wilber could not defend his own claim shows that he
adopted the maxim second-hand, and perhaps has lost the context. Anyone
who really knows Spinoza’s philosophy—i.e. from studying him in depth, not
just in passing on the way to a vast meta-theory of everything (and
everyone)ii—knows that Spinoza was profoundly anti-Cartesian. This is why
the Theosophists consider that Spinoza’s philosophy, when reconciled with
Leibniz’s (reactive interpretation), would reveal the “spirit of esoteric
philosophy” in opposition to the philosophy of Descartes.
Again, the esoteric understanding of Spinoza is profoundly anti-, or trans-
Cartesian. Indeed, as Deleuze states in Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza,
[my emphasis] “…there is no Cartesian axiom [in Spinoza]…that does not
take on a new meaning, hostile to Cartesianism, on the basis of the new
theory of distinctions. The theory has as its fundamental principle the
qualitative status of real distinction. Detached from all numerical
distinction, real distinction is carried into the absolute, and becomes capable
of expressing difference within Being, so bringing about the restructuring of
i¥
ISC call, May 12, 2007
ii
Wilber’s limitations here are to be expected of a human being, rather than a god. His net was cast
wide and his focus was on the eastern forms of nonduality, not on “Rationalists,” such as Spinoza.
Page | 53
INTRODUCTION: REAWAKENING THE EMBRYO OF RATIONALITY
other distinctions.”i¥
The Spinozan theory of distinctions, as we will see, transforms the
dualistic independent arisings in Descartes, ultimately into dependent
arisings. This dependent arising is one of the key elements of nondual
philosophy, and it is a necessary outcome of the acategorical imperative of
esoteric rationalism itself, as we will see.
Given that Ken Wilber has not found the plane of consistency in Spinoza’s
philosophy—following his claims that Spinoza is a “dedicated Cartesian,”
which he cannot back up—then it is clear that Wilber has not properly
followed the injunctions of the Spinozan paradigm.ii This assertion, then,
that Spinoza was not enlightened, is a clear and uncharacteristic example of
metaphysics in the bad sense. It is a truth claim about the nature (ontic) of
Spinoza’s mind that not only cannot ultimately or absolutely be verified, but
one whose relative merits Wilber himself has not attempted to validate with
the relative truth claims available to him, namely reading Spinoza to the
point of understanding, or even reading the main Spinozists, rather than
merely his critics. In order to assert that Spinoza was not enlightened one
must first understand Spinoza, and when one understands Spinoza, one sees
that he was anything but a “dedicated Cartesian.” As Matthew Stewart
noted, Spinoza considered Descartes to be seriously confused, as any
nondualist to any dualist.
As we will see, there are many thinkers who have found enlightenment
through Spinoza’s philosophy and who feel indeed that Spinoza was
enlightened himself. These are thinkers who have studied Spinoza in depth,
i.e. thinkers who have followed the injunctions of the Spinozan paradigm,
such as Arthur Schopenhauer, the Theosophists, and many others in both
eastern and western nondual systems.
i¥
Deleuze, Expressionism in Philosophy, p. 38
ii
A paradigm is a function of technology, and a philosophical system itself is a technology; an
invention based on the industry of language.
Page | 54
POST-POST-ISM-ISM: CONDITION CRITICAL IN THE K’ONTIC SHADOW
Page | 55
Page | 56
Page | 57
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i¥
Wikipedia: nondualism
Page | 58
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
Page | 59
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
This polarity between the absolute and relative also gives rise to the Two
Truths Doctrine of Buddhism, a foundational element in Nondual Rational
Epistemology, or Interface Theory.i* This, we will find, is foundational also
to the notion of Univocity,ii* which Deleuze sees as the key element in his
interpretation of Spinoza, and this will be operationalized as the polarity of
absolute and relative scopes.
Toward the goal of laying out a middle-path between these extremes of
relative nihilism and absolute eternalism (or essentialism), Nagarjuna
developed a concept he called sunyata, or Emptiness, which essentially
means that all manifestations of existence, what we might call objects or
modifications, are empty of their own self-contained essence (i.e. they are
empty of the metaphysical essences which Plato called forms or ideas).
Nagarjuna, like Deleuze, basically implores us to think acategorically, and he
even titled one of his later books, Pulverizing the Categories. Indeed, this
common categorical, or essentialist thinking, is the “essence” (pardon the
term) of the “forces of representation” which, Deleuze argues, have distorted
the reading and interpretation of philosophy (mainly Spinoza and Leibniz,
herein) throughout History via an essentialist and idealist (Platonic) lens.
(This will be explored later through the explication of the concept of the
transcendent-bias.)
This Nagarjunan (and Deleuzian) pulverizing of the categories is effected
through what is called dependent origination, or dependent arising, in the
sense that the essence of an object or phenomenon is not self-contained, but
is fundamentally dependent on the context in which it emerges or arises.
And specifically, all opposites are dependent on each other for their identity
in the very process of origination. In Taoism, this idea is called the identity
of opposites, and it is a key concept throughout this work.
i
* See, Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch , p541.
ii
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
iii
As we will see in Unity and Nonduality (p239), this ONE is not to say that there could be TWO.
Infinite or absolute unity is not numerical, because it is not relational. There is a very important
difference between infinite and finite forms of unity, or the forms of unity from the absolute and
relative scopes, respectively.
Page | 60
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
Emptiness is not other than Form, that which is Form is not other than
Emptiness.” This is the identity of opposites (polarity, not duality) of
Emptiness and Form, or The Boundless and Boundary, or The Infinite and
the Finite, or The Absolute and the Relative. These are all different polarities
expressing (at least herein) the same basic meaning.
As Matthew Stewart says in his The Courtier and the Heretic (my emphases):
In the most widely accepted versions of the history of philosophy, Spinoza
and Leibniz are understood to represent a speculative metaphysical
program that long ago succumbed to academic progress. In fact, talking a
broader view of events, it is clear that the two greatest philosophers of
the seventeenth century remain unsurpassed, and should perhaps be
considered the twin founders of modern thought. We live in an age
defined by its reaction to Spinoza and to all that he recorded in his
philosophy. And there is no more compelling expression of this reaction
than the philosophy Leibniz developed in the long years after his return
from Holland (p16).
And see this quote from Madame Blavatsky, in her The Secret Doctrine
(again, my emphases):
It may be correctly stated that were Leibnitz’ and Spinoza’s systems
reconciled, the essence and Spirit of esoteric philosophy would be
made to appear. From the shock of the two—as opposed to the
Cartesian system—emerge the truths of the Archaic doctrine.
In contrast to the above emphases on Spinoza and Leibniz as “the twin
founders of modern thought,” or as expressing “the essence and Spirit of
esoteric philosophy,” “as opposed to the Cartesian system,” Rene Descartes
is long considered by academia the father, and indeed the epitome, of
philosophic modernism and Rationalism. Yet curiously, both Leibniz and
Spinoza vehemently, rigorously and indeed brilliantly disagreed with
Descartes at the most fundamental of levels, while at the same time forming
systems which (as we will explore herein) are curiously resonant and
Page | 61
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i
A key interpretive error we will correct herein, with the help of Deleuze.
ii
According to Ken Wilber’s brief encounter with Spinozistic history.
iii
See Mathew Stewart’s The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy.
iv
This is not to be considered a definitive account of the fundamental irrationality of the Cartesian
system. For that, consult virtually any modern professor of philosophy. And this is not to say that
Descartes does not have his truths as well, but simply that they are compromised by irrationality of
his metaphysics, and his desire to secure absolute certainty, at whatever cost.
Page | 62
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
As Stewart says:
In the most widely accepted narratives of the history of thought,
Descartes’ so-called dualism is often taken to represent a fundamental
revolution in ideas and the starting point of modern philosophy. In style
and method Cartesian philosophy did indeed mark an important, hugely
influential breakthrough in European letters; but in substance his work is
perhaps better understood as an attempt to conserve the old truths in the
face of new threats. His dualism was in essence an armistice of sorts
between the established religion and the emerging science of his time. By
isolating the mind from the physical world, the philosopher ensured that
many of the central doctrines of orthodoxy—immortality of the soul, the
freedom of the will, and, in general, the “special” status of humankind—
were rendered immune to any possible contravention by scientific
investigation of the physical world. Conversely, the complete self-
sufficiency of the machine-like material world guaranteed that physical
science could proceed without fear of contradiction from revealed
religion. … For men such as Descartes, Malebranche, and Leibniz, solving
the mind-body problem was vital to preserving the theological and
political order inherited from the Middle Ages and, more generally, to
protecting the human self-esteem in the face of an increasingly truculent
universe. For Spinoza, it was a means of destroying that same order and
discovering a new foundation for human worth.
Spinoza’s answer to the mind-body problem marks a radical break in
the history of thought—the kind that happens only every millennium or
two (p164).
What then is Cartesian in Nondual Rationalism given that Descartes’
metaphysical dualism is so clearly and obviously irrational, or pre-rational
and pre-modern? What specifically did Spinoza or Leibniz inherit, or even
pass over, from Descartes, that we may find useful in outlining and
expanding Nondual Rationalism? Many things, such as his focus on the
direct interface of experience in the cogito—a key element and limit
(relative boundary) of Nondual Rational Epistemology—and some general
elements of his system of physics, such as the focus on vortices (spin) in the
formation of the solar system (a spinning bit)—both of which will be
explored in Volume II—but mainly what was emulated in Descartes was his
geometric style of rigorous explication.
Descartes geometric style, while still being very readable and personable,
was definitively rational. Both Spinoza and Leibniz admired and expanded
on this style, and particularly the use of rigor and logic which Descartes
inherited from earlier mathematical treatises, such as Euclid’s Elements.
Spinoza inherited and perfected this style to demolish Descartes’ inherent
irrationalism, the key tenets of dualism, to replace them with a
fundamentally nondual metaphysical system wherein mind and body are
mere attributes or ways of perceiving, conceiving and expressing “the
essence of Substance,” which is ultimately infinite and unbounded existence
Page | 63
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
itself (in line with the existentialists, but opposed to academic accounts of
Spinozism and Rationalism).
Page | 64
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
As Matthew Stewart says (and note here the specific nondual emphasis):
The endpoint of Spinoza’s philosophy—the intellectual love of God, or
blessedness—transfigures all that precedes it. … It is the union of the
individual and the cosmos, of freedom and necessity, of activity and
passivity, of mind and body, of self-interest and charity, of virtue and
knowledge, and of happiness and virtue (p177).
Does Spinoza or Leibniz reject or spurn experience, or stress reason at the
expense of experience? Not so at all. Indeed, Spinoza was a great fan of
scientific and empirical methodologies, and none of his rationalizations
contradict, or occlude empirical data (and he would likely not allow them to,
if he found out they did). Rather, they are born from it and help to organize
it. Indeed, as Antonio Damasio has shown, Spinoza’s psychology of the
emotions has held up extremely well and even today can provide insights to
neuroscientists, such as himself (see his book Looking for Spinoza).
Spinoza’s metaphysics, as well, was, and still is, attractive to many
empirically centered scientists, such as Albert Einstein, who called himself a
“disciple” of Spinoza.
Indeed, Spinoza can even be seen as a progenitor of empiricism for many
reasons. Firstly, Spinoza’s philosophy was directly influential to John Locke,
as Locke purchased and studied all of Spinoza’s work in depth, during his
exile in Holland. Leibniz himself, as Matthew Stewart goes on to show, drew
many parallels between Locke’s empiricism and heretical Spinozism, such as
Spinoza’s rejection of the notion that the body was known empirically to the
degree that we can say that the higher functions of cognition, such as
consciousness, could not arise with it in its increasing complexity.
Spinoza asks, “What can a body do?” He says (my emphases):
Nobody as yet has learned from experience what the body can and cannot
do ... solely from the laws of its nature insofar as it is considered
corporeal. For nobody as yet knows [again, clearly from experience] the
structure of the body so accurately as to explain all its functions, not to
mention that in the animal world we find much that surpasses human
sagacity, and the sleepwalkers do many things in their sleep that they
would not dare when awake ... [the human body] surpasses in ingenuity
all the constructions of human skill.
i
intelligent evolution, as it were…
Page | 65
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486).
ii
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486).
Page | 66
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
the natural artifacts of man, such as the scriptures. Spinoza writes [my
emphases]:
I hold that the method of interpreting Scripture is no different from the
method of interpreting Nature, and is in fact in complete accord with it.
For the method of interpreting Nature consists essentially in composing a
detailed study of Nature from which, as being the source of our assured
data, we can deduce the definitions of the things of Nature.i¥
Matthew Stewart continues, noting the similarity between Spinoza’s position
and that of David Hume, who is generally considered by academia, the arch-
empiricist. He begins with a quote from Spinoza himself [my emphases]:
“the human mind … has not an adequate but only a confused and
fragmentary knowledge of itself, of its own body, and of external bodies.”
That is to say, in Spinoza’s world, our knowledge of ourselves, just like
our knowledge of particular things in general, is mediated through the
body itself, and is therefore always imperfect or fallible and open to
revision. Thus, minds are every bit as complex and multifarious as the
bodies of which they are the ideas. (It is worth noting that Spinoza’s
position is quite close to that which the historians of philosophy
ascribe to the radical empiricists, such as David Hume, and not at all
consistent with the “rationalism” with which he is often incorrectly
identified) (p172).
Again we see the tight procrustean bed of academic/exoteric “rationalism”
projecting its ill-fitting categorical boundaries into wounds on the sprawling
esoteric body of Spinoza’s philosophy, and again we invoke the ghost of
Deleuze and Nagarjuna to implore the reader to pulverize the categories
inherited from the past. Again we incant the acategorical imperative of
nondualism and invite the reader to look outside the academic box of
rationalism to explore Spinoza’s philosophy anew; to see it beyond
“rationalism” and even as a trans-rationalism, in this sense as beyond the
common stifling restrictions of the term.
As I will show in the chapter on the symbiogenesis of subject and objectii*
and in the section The Symbiogenesis of the Rational and Empirical, this
intimate connection between rationalism and empiricism is emergent in the
very process of the development of consciousness as a function of what we
will call the “mnemonic primitives,” wherein the brain, and its rational (or
irrational) concepts cannot even begin to grow (and cannot continue to
exist) without external sensory stimulation. There is a direct coupling
between percept and concept—between experience and rationalization—
encoded at all levels, from the most primitive rudiments of ‘mental’
evolution and individual development at the level of cellular ‘sensation’ and
i¥
TTP, chap. 7, G III.98/S 87
ii
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
Page | 67
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
Page | 68
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
So we have seen that Spinoza is not against the emotions, he does not
consider them irrational and does not seek to supplant them with pure
reason. He also does not spurn the faculties of experience, which he calls the
“first kind of knowledge.” In fact experience is critical to inform rationality,
in Spinoza. But what about intuition? Indeed, Spinoza’s view can hardly be
seen as against intuition when he considers intuition the highest form of
understanding, the bleeding edge of the intellect. It is intuition, or “the third
kind of knowledge,” that enables us to know God in the way that affords us
with “the intellectual love of God.” So we see that the circle is completed
with the recognition that intuition is the highest form of knowledge which
allows the emotions to elevate us to the intellectual love of God.
i
This is a simplistic view of the matter, of course, and the full picture of Leibniz’s Spinozism will be
explored here: Leibniz: A Reactionary Chiaroscuro, p668.
ii
And contrary to modern assumptions, Spinoza's “Nature” is not merely the physical or material
world, but the whole of Reality.
iii¥
Leibniz: A VI.iii.518; DSR, p. 26.
Page | 69
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
On a ferry, in his journey to his first and only face-to-face meeting with
Spinoza, Leibniz pens a draft of an argument that he would soon make
directly to Spinoza. In this argument, titled ‘That a Most Perfect Being
Exists,’ Leibniz proves, through his own Principle of Sufficient Reason, that
Spinoza’s God is possible and indeed logically and rationally necessary,
indeed unavoidable, given this core principle of Leibniz’s entire philosophy
(p191).
In the argument, Leibniz “duplicates in abbreviated fashion the first
crucial propositions in Spinoza’s Ethics: Substances are radically distinct and
can be understood one without another; but all things in the world are
understood through the unique and ultimate reason for all things; therefore,
there cannot be two or more substances in the world; therefore, there is only
one substance, and all things are modes of this one substance” (p192). Thus
Leibniz begins with his “irrevocable commitment to the Principle of
Sufficient Reason—that for every thing there must be a reason—and ends in
a declaration of belief in the core doctrines of Spinoza” (p192). Leibniz then
makes a clearly deliberate false attribution of the argument to “Plato in the
Parmenides”i¥ rather than to the obvious owner, “Spinoza in the Ethics.”
i¥
A VI.iii.573.
Page | 70
THE TAO OF RATIONALISM: PULVERIZING THE CATEGORIES
Page | 71
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
For now, then, and until we get to the section wherein we draw out the
identity of opposites between them, we can think of Leibniz as essentially a
covert-Spinozist in self-reflexion and reaction, and hence a covert trans-
“rationalist,” with a bizarre mix of pre-rationalisms and irrationalisms
thrown in the mix, for good exoteric measure—though this is not to
underestimate the beauty of his logical insights and monadology formed in
reaction to his own Spinozism.
i
* See, Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of Opposites, p659.
Page | 72
This work presents a new view of Rationalism that integrates the key
philosophical and mathematical insights of the rationalists. These include;
mathematical rationalism and the basic properties of rational numbers,
Leibniz’s calculus as the mathematical aspect of his infinite monadology,
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite,i* and Deleuze’s Spinozistic notion of univocity, as
the operational framework for his trans-foundational metaphysics. These
key insights will unfold within a nondual framework implicit in the ideas of
the rationalists themselves, as we have already started to see.
A key aspect of Nondual Rationalism, as discussed above, is the
Nagarjunan polarity of Emptiness and Form, as well as the notion of the
identity of opposites.ii How can we understand this polarity of Emptiness
and Form in a convergent understanding of mathematical and philosophical
rationalism? And what is the identity of opposites in this context?
In nondual mathematical rationalism (Interface Mathematics), the
polarity of Emptiness and Form, or absolute and relative, can be translated
rather simply as the polarity of infinity and number.iii* ‘Infinity,’ in this
sense is taken from the ancient Greek apeiron as boundlessness, which
“derives from the archaic a-peirar … a rope, knot or bond, i.e., something that
has to be put around or upon something else from the outside, not just an
end or a limit which is intrinsic to it.”iv¥ In Interface Mathematics and
i
* See Spinoza’s famous letter on the infinite.
ii
It may be objected outright that the nondual is fundamentally ineffable and hence, “The tao that
can be told is not the eternal Tao.” The Tao that is spoken and described throughout this work is the
Tao as it manifests only in the relative world (the relative scope). This framework of Nondual
Rationalism actually makes the statement, and holds open the space, that the absolute, which
includes all forms of boundlessness such as the boundless time of “eternity,” is indeed ineffable
precisely because it is not relative and relational, but its identical opposite.
iii
* See The Polarity of Infinity and (Primitive) Number, p250.
iv¥
(Verelst, Zeno's Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality)
Page | 73
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
Note that all of this will be expanded in much greater detail in the
section, on Interface Mathematics. We will explore just enough basic
mathematics here to give us a thread for tracing the essence of Nondual
Rationalism as we proceed through this labyrinth. Note also, that the level of
mathematics explored herein, while meta-mathematically, or philosophically
advanced, covers mainly the basics, or fundamentals of mathematics itself,
though we do get into the philosophy of the calculus and Set Theory, later
on. So from a mathematical point of view, this is largely elementary stuff;
addition, subtraction, fractions, etc. Philosophically and meta-
mathematically, however, it breaks open into a new way of understanding
and organizing these fundamentals in resonance with nondual-rational and
trans-rational Interface Philosophy and Mathematics, helping to provide a
fundamental and much needed cohesion between physics and mathematics.
Page | 74
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
i
It is now known that the Rational numbers in themselves do not completely compose the
continuum of “the real numbers”, because of the existence of irrational and transcendental
numbers, or “Dedekind cuts” in the rational continuum. But it is the “violation of the closure
property,” in the inversion of the input-output polarity (See Recursion, Iopol, Violation of Closure
and the Acategorical Imperative, p329), initiated in the mathematical ratio that first makes contact
with the continuum and opens the higher level functions of number to this immanent infinity of the
“immanent-transcendent axis,” which the “trans-rational” numbers enfold into. We will see,
however, that because Dedekind’s cuts are “infinitely thin”, the continuity of the Rationals is not
broken, but rather simply not complete. If this seems a conundrum, it will make sense later, for
example, once the concept of an aspect infinity is understood (See The Triune Infinite: Interfacing
Emptiness, p268).
Page | 75
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i
This is the “violation of the closure property,” which we will explore in much greater detail later.
ii
We will discuss Zeno’s paradoxes in much greater detail later throughout the book, but specifically
in the section on the paradoxes of the infinite. See, Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.
iii
Note that we could call the transcendent direction “ascendant”, in order to ward off the possible
confusion with the transcendental numbers, which are certainly not to be confused with the
rational. But immanence and transcendence are key to the main axis of the framework of Nondual
Rationalism, as we will see, and they are key to the meaning of the mathematical ratio. We will
reserve the term “ascendance” for additive increases, while the multiplicative transcends and
includes addition through its recursivity. This will be discussed in greater detail in the section on,
Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.
Page | 76
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
i
This is the input/output polarity (iopol), we will explore in Interface Mathematics.
ii
Tao Te Ching, verse 42, by Lao-tzu, from a translation by S. Mitchell, states: “All things have their
backs to the female and stand facing the male. When male and female combine, all things achieve
harmony.”
iii
Note that while the transcendent number (numerator) may hold the active or default frame of
reference, the immanent number (denominator) is the active divisor to the divided, or dividend of
the numerator.
Page | 77
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
transcendent active
transcendent bias
immanent passive
and…
increase
increase transcendent bias
decrease
not…
decrease
increase immanent bias
increase
i
We’ll see this as the “trans-trans-bias,” where ascendancy equates to the transitive, and the
transitive/transcendent mapping will be explicitly demonstrated through graphing basic functions.
Page | 78
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
To approach this thread more clearly, let’s see what happens when the value
in the denominator dips below the unit-value of the integers, the
fundamental categorical numerical-identity 1, without reaching or crossing
zero. Let us do this through the rational process of division, recursively
dividing the immanent value by 5:
1 1 1 1
1, 5, 25 , 125 , …
1 0.2 0.04 0.008
1 1
244140625_, … | … undefined_ .
0.00000000 4096 0
The value of the whole ratio, or the rational number, begins in balance, at 1,
and (as the voice of the screaming kid reveals his glee at being lifted into the
air) increases to 5, 25, 125, and … 244140625. The increase in overall value
continues toward infinity to the point that when, and only when, we finally
get tired of making distinctions that are too small to be relatively meaningful
and we then reach over the infinite abyss …|… and artificially plug in 0
(because we can’t reach 0 through division), the equation becomes
undefined.
Why, when we increase toward infinity (apeiron) as we indefinitely
“approach” zero through division of the denominator, do we not actually
“reach” infinity when we finally skip the immanent infinity, represented here
in decimals, and plug in zero? Were we increasing toward the undefined all
i
* See, Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200
ii
Specifically, in the violation of the “closure property” which we will discuss in great detail in
Interface Mathematics
Page | 79
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i
To illustrate the inherent finity in this analogy for the “groundless” infinite.
ii
As Hegel claims is the essence of the calculus, which we will come to in the section on the calculus.
Page | 80
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
The infinity and “essence” of Nondual Rationalism must then be, at least in
part, this infinite divisibility that exists between and within all integer unit-
values, hidden by the cipher and dividing toward ever smaller and smaller
quantities indefinitely and unboundedly. On this immanent axis, of the
Rationals, there is no final level of value; no final numerical form to reduce
Emptiness to, or vice versa, and no reachable limit at immanent zero. Hence
immanent, rational, “undefined” zero is actually unlimited, unbounded and
infinite Emptiness. This infinite divisibility, infinite depth or immanent
infinity, is the unbounded Emptiness of mathematical rationalism which we
will take as a key property and root operational axis (positive infinity) of
Nondual Rationalism itself, both mathematical and philosophical. And
indeed, this unboundedness in the rational zero is encoded in Nagarjuna’s
definition of Emptiness.
From the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, we find [my emphases]:
Nagarjuna saw in the concept sunya, a concept which connoted in the
early Pali Buddhist literature the lack of a stable, inherent existence in
persons, but which since the third century BCE had also denoted the
newly formulated number “zero,” the interpretive key to the heart of
Buddhist teaching, and the undoing of all the metaphysical schools of
philosophy which were at the time flourishing around him. Indeed,
Nagarjuna’s philosophy can be seen as an attempt to deconstruct all
systems of thought which analyzed the world in terms of fixed
substances and essences. Things in fact lack essence, according to
Nagarjuna, they have no fixed nature, and indeed it is only because of this
lack of essential, immutable being that change is possible, that one thing
can transform into another. Each thing can only have its existence
through its lack (sunyata) of inherent, eternal essence. With this new
concept of “emptiness,” “voidness,” “lack” of essence, “zeroness,” this
somewhat unlikely prodigy was to help mold the vocabulary and
character of Buddhist thought forever.
Unlike the Natural numbers or the integers, the Rational numbers are
composed in a function of relation—a polarity of two numbers, each playing
on the other defining the value in a global symbiosis for the rational number
itself—and hence they possess no intrinsic immutable essence or
numerical identity of their own. The integers, on the other hand, are
categorically “closed,” self-defined, numerical identities, in a sense; they
have a unit “closure property” that is “violated” and pulverized in the
function of division itself. Each integer can only mean one thing and have
one identity separated from all others and categorically identical to any
integers of the same value. The Rationals, however, can be formed in an
Page | 81
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
infinite number of ratios. The number 2, for example, can be written as 2/1,
4/2, 16/8 or 3446/1723, and it is “infinitely close”i to its “nearest neighbor,”
which naturally cannot even be defined, because it has no nearest neighbor,
but infinitely many of them. Indeed, the relationship itself, is endlessly
mutable, forming a continuum of possible states in between. (See Figure 1,
below)
i
To invoke the labyrinth before an explanation is at hand.
Page | 82
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
Page | 83
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
So we can see here a precise break between the infinity of Rationalism and
that of pre-rationalism. The pre-rational (transitive or regressive) infinity
passes from one side of infinity to the other, right through the integer-zero
as merely the absence of another self-defined integer on its way from the
positive to the negative transitive values. In contradistinction to this
positive/negative opposition, the mathematical ratio, of itself, can’t even
produce negative numbers, but rather merely an infinity of positive
intensities on either side of “unity” (one), approaching, but never reaching
immanent zero or transcendent infinity. The Rationals are operating on a
new axis,i* and this is why the pre-rational (transitive) axis of infinity does
not know what to do with this new role for the cipher as an immanent
infinity once the mathematical ratio introduces the “violation” or
“pulverization” of the “closure property” of the fundamental unit underlying
the pre-rational integers.
Mathematical ratios, and hence rational numbers, have no intrinsically
negative values. Try as we might, but they can’t be reached by either
multiplication or division.ii* And hence the “negative infinity” of the
Rationals (to entertain the transcendent-bias further) is in the immanent
direction, and on the positive side of the integer-axis, ever toward the
“unlimit” of zero.iii The rational zero as infinity, then, will remain undefined
until the transcendent bias is lifted and we can explicitly and operationally
see the infinite axis, and indeed the infinite interminable pole “terminating”
at the immanent zero, the inward pole of the positive infinity of the
Rationals.
The idea that negative numbers and the negative infinity—as well as the
positive and negative transcendent polarity itself (toward increasing
positive or negative values on either side of the infinite integer number-
line)—are in this sense pre-rational, is further supported by the observation
that the ratio is indifferent to the placement of the pre-rational negative sign.
You can put it in the numerator or the denominator or on the rational
number as a whole and you get the same negative rational number. The
negative infinity of the integers, which would oppose the positive infinity
found in both of them, is simply not the negative infinity of the Rationals. It
is this infinite divisibility and depth, this positive immanent infinity between
the integer-unit one and its non-limit at the rational (infinite) zero, that fills
the role of the “negative” on the immanent axis (which as a whole is positive,
i
* See, The Orthogonality of Inverses and the Offset Origin-Identities, p338.
ii
* See, The Kernel of the Trans-Trans Asymmetry and Instability at the Crossroads of the Transitive
and I/T Axes, p340.
iii
The rational numbers, then, are intrinsically “intensive,” as Deleuze speaks of the “forces” of the
sub-representational. Rational numbers, as we will see, are the mathematical equivalent of the
forces of immanence and sub-representation.
Page | 84
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
And now we close upon our Ariadne’s thread, the central principle of
Nondual Rationalism that will guide us, and indeed pull us, through the rest
of the labyrinth as it gets clearer and clearer what this thread really consists
of and the forms, strands or chords it morphs or resonates into, pulling
them, as well, from the deep-infinity of Emptiness. Indeed, this will be
merely one strand of what will become an “Ariadne’s Cable,” getting stronger
and stronger as it ties Nondual Rationalism directly to the senses and hence
to sensibility and the roots of understanding.
i
* See, The Polarity of Zero: The Amphibian of the Transitive and Immanent, p335.
Page | 85
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
matter how close they may seem, the gap is filled with yet another infinity of
indivisible points. The continuum is therefore—by the same infinite
principle—fundamentally indivisible precisely because it is infinitely divided,
leaving no gaps. Division, as it traverses the immanent axis toward its ever
unreachable “limit at zero,” endlessly approaches an “infinitely small point,”
and hence an absolute division is merely one of an “infinite number” of
extensionless and unreachable position, abstracted out of the labyrinth of the
continuum.i
If this seems paradoxical, don’t worry, it will make much more sense
when the framework of Nondual Rationalism is in place. Indeed, it would be
entirely suspect if it were not seemingly paradoxical and difficult to grasp
when dealing with the infinite and the nondual.
And so we can state our principle of Nondual Rationalism as the
following identity of opposites:ii
i
This is Leibniz’s notion of a mathematical point as a “terminus,” not a real entity. It is merely a
direction of unbounded division, the pole of an Immanent/Transcendent axis.
ii
And our “principle of principles” could state that a principle is merely a tool. A man-made habitual
element of a system of thought whose repeated use will prove beneficial when implemented in his
entirely fictional construction.
iii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 86
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
Explanation: The principles used throughout this text are not conceived or used as
fundamental truths about reality, i.e. Laws of Nature, but merely as pithy and
distilled rudimentary or fundamental elements of the system itself. Sometimes they
are used as rigidified building-blocks—or as Gerald Lebau would say, as “needles” to
the softer, more intuitive semantic “noodles”—and sometimes they are used as
resonant keys to unlocking paradoxes and conundrums of the evolving text. Indeed,
the Fundamental Principle of Nondualism itself is the key to unfolding its resonant
chords, the other principles in this unfolding system.
Page | 87
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
Cauchy and Cantor, et al shows, however, that the Rational numbers do not
exhaust the full order of the continuum. The rational numbers, Cantor
showed, are of the exact same order of infinity (aleph null) as the natural
numbers. And the natural numbers, Cantor said, are “countable” or
“denumerable,” while the continuum itself (the continuum of “real
numbers”) is uncountable.
Page | 88
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
gaps nonetheless given that the immanent infinities of these Dedekind cuts
and infinite “irrational” numbers cannot be reached by the function of the
ratio. Thus when you undertake a time-ordered process of division carried
to infinity, not all points on the continuum will be reached, just like the
Rational numbers can’t reach the “irrationals” or transcendentals. What is
left over from this stepwise division process, then, is called “Cantor dust,”
which is essentially the difference between the countable and uncountable,
or first and second transfinite orders of the infinite (and between the
transitive and immanent/transcendent VL-axes, as we will see).
Thus we will find that the fundamental principle of Nondual Rationalism was
introduced at the very beginnings of rationality itself, but it was originally
conceived as a “contradiction” or “paradox.” And ever since the Aristotelian
introduction of the principle of contradiction—inaugurating the exoteric and
dualistic form of rationality to come—dualistic rationality could not codify
and operationalize the nondual reality (polarity) underlying the very
inception of rationality itself. And so it was conceived as an anomaly to be
refuted. Indeed, Verelst shows that every attempt at refutation since has
i
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 89
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
It must be clarified and/or reiterated at this point why we are taking the
unorthodox position that Descartes is a proto-rational thinker, as opposed to
a fully rational one. There are several reasons.
i
* See To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
ii
Deleuze claims, in Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, that the critical distinction between the
“post-Cartesianism” in Spinoza and Leibniz, and Cartesianism itself, is that Descartes does not
address the idea of expression, which both Spinoza and Leibniz take up with a passion in their own
ways. In Spinoza, this expressionism works its way through the univocity of immanence and through
Leibniz it works through an equivocity, due to his own transcendent-bias. Indeed, their respective
uses of expression, univocal vs. equivocal, constitutes, for Deleuze, the prime distinction between
Spinoza and Leibniz.
Page | 90
LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM AND THE PRINCIPLE OF NDR
Page | 91
Page | 92
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS
i
We will discuss foundationalism in much greater depth later. See Foundationalism: Crystalline
Pyramids In Emptiness, p641.
Page | 93
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i
* See the section in Spinoza's Attribute Polarity Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the
Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
ii
* See The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
Page | 94
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS
i
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
ii
…and number, as we will see.
iii
See Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement in SpinbitZ: Volume II
Page | 95
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
Page | 96
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS
While it is true that Spinoza rendered his system in the geometrical style of
Euclid and Descartes—with a foundation of axioms, propositions and
definitions—the system of concepts itself can take many different types of
rendering. Deleuze’s interpretation of Spinoza demonstrates that, contrary
i
We will discuss both foundationalism and coherentism in much greater depth later. See Trans-
Folding Models of Knowledge and Truth, p629.
Page | 97
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
to the rigid logical, axiomatic structure into which Spinoza rendered his own
system, this same system can also be rendered in a way that is
fundamentally different, and indeed non-foundationalist. Interface
Philosophy take this further and gives Deleuze’s rendering according to his
“logic of expression” a more accessible and explicit depiction in Interface
Epistemology. This will mainly be taken up SpinbitZ: Volume II, but it has
already, and will continue to inform and be worked out in the context of this
work, given the interdependency of ontology and epistemology themselves.
For now a few comments on foundationalism will suffice to set the desired
context of this concept (in relation to the pre-rational regressive infinity, and
the transcendent-bias) for the rest of this volume.
In Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, Deleuze shows that, contrary to
the common academic conception, Spinoza’s system does not begin or rest
on the concept of God or Substance, and therefore it is not necessarily a
logical or ontological foundationalism. In the appendix to the book, Deleuze
gives a schematic breakdown of the Ethics according to his logic of
expression. He states, “These eight propositions [the first ones in the Ethics,
1-8] are not hypothetical but categorical; it is thus false that the Ethics
‘begins’ with God.” He goes on, “Only here [in the propositions 9-14] do we
reach the idea of God as absolutely infinite substance” (p 337).
Indeed, according to the interpretation herein, Spinoza does not begin
logically, or even sequentially with a definition of God or Substance from
which all else follows, and upon which all else logically rests. Rather,
logically, he begins in the middle, with a critical definition of the finite in its
own kind, as that which is limited or surpassed by another modification of
the same kind. It is The Infinite (The Absolute), or Substance/God, which
hinges or turns on this definition of the finite, the mode, or the relative, as
that which is not limited by anything else.
Spinoza ultimately sets up a polarity, defining the infinite or
Substance/God (our absolute scope) as the identical-opposite of the finite
(our relative scope), i.e. that concept which is unlimited, independent and
unsurpassed by another deeper cause because it was explicitly defined as
the identical-opposite, the context of Emptiness, for the relative scope itself.
Indeed, Deleuze also shows how, with univocity, substance “turns around
the modes,” giving what we are demonstrating herein as a true polarity
(between the absolute and relative scopes, essentially, similar to Nagarjunan
Emptiness and form). Unfortunately, we will not have the time herein to go
much beyond this superficial rendering of Deleuze’s expressionist reading,
though it is resonant throughout, beneath the differences in terminology.
The reaching of substance, in Spinoza, is ultimately attained only in the
abandonment of the immanent representational regress of finite causes,
logical/causal dependency and relativity (the relative scope), to a positive
acknowledgement of the infinite depth of dependent existence itself (the
absolute scope) as the identical-opposite of the finite, or the mode (the
Page | 98
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS
i
a phrase borrowed from M.C. Escher
Page | 99
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
The last century of ontology and epistemology, coupled with the discoveries
of quantum and complexity science, has rendered moot the lingering,
peculiarly medieval, fear of the infinite regress and thrown it into positive
relief. Instead of viewing the problem from the negative point of view of
looking backward or inward to find an origin in space, scale or time, and
fretting when these hypothetical beginnings can’t be found, the problem is
turned on its head. If there are no origins to begin with—in other words, if,
contrary to our tacit predispositions, the universe is eternal and infinite (as
conceived in Buddhist nondual schools of cosmology), in both depth and
i
See Rob Oldershaw’s Self-Similar Cosmological Model, for instance.
Page | 100
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS
span, then the search for an origin is itself a false problem engendered by the
false premise that such an ultimate beginning or ultimate foundation
necessarily exists. The problem of the regress itself is seen to be merely a
projection of a regressive, point of view on the infinite or the unbounded
nature of reality.
This regress, however always occurs from the transcendent perch of the
emergent mind and its generalized, a posteriori, categories of representation.
This is why the transcendent-bias, the infinite regress and foundationalism
always go hand in hand. Falling from the transcendent perch of the mind,
and into the infinite abyss, the transcendent-biased mind can’t see its
regress for what it is. It fails to recognize that it started from transcendence
and emergence in the first place, ignorant of the depth (infinite or not) of its
causes, and that the forces of immanence play a role in its very formation. It
also fails to recognize, therefore, that it is going backward in time and
causation to look for an immanent cause after the fact, and that any ultimate
cause or immanent substrate, will also be transcendent from the deeper
levels on the immanent-transcendent axis. The transcendent-bias then
reappears in the very attempt at absolutization of this immanently located
transcendent plane. The bias then encounters itself and its own necessary
failure in absolutizing the relativity of planes or forms in the Emptiness and
boundlessness of the immanent-transcendent axis.
Page | 101
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
Each absolutized view has a damning criticism of the other, each opening
the other to yet another dependent arising, and identity of opposites. The
bundle-view critique of the substance-view can be explained thus;
properties and modifications could not inhere in substance if it had no
inherence properties in the first place. In other words, if substance had no
properties to begin with, such as the property of modifiability, then how
could it ever be modified into patterns, modes, objects and higher-level
properties, in the second-place? Doesn’t modifiability presuppose
properties that can be modified, at the very least generalizable as the
property of modifiability or inherence itself? Isn’t substance, therefore, at
the very least, necessarily pre-modified with the property of modifiability—
whatever that must entail? Conversely, is it really any better to take the
view that there is no substance to reality and that it is all merely bundles of
properties ultimately inhering in … absolute nothingness?
With this dichotomy of opposing and equally bizarre paradoxes in mind,
it is clear that each contains a truth in its critique of the other, as well as a
relative truth in its basic concepts. Therefore, as is usual with controversies
that rage for centuries with brilliant proponents for each side, the truth is
likely somewhere in the middle. This is specifically true in the case of heated
intellectual controversies over competing models each of which has a broad
base of adherents all recognizing some validity to their preferred model.i
A case in point is the “nature v. nurture” debate in which it is now
understood that both sides were correct and that nature and nurture both
play key, indeed symbiogenetic roles in the development of the individual. It
is clear therefore, and we have many historical precedents to spur us on, and
an integral model (Integral Methodological Pluralism) to pull us forward,
into the view that some integration of this useful differentiation between
substance and bundle views is in order.
But what can a “substance-bundle view of substance” look like (to
temporarily retain the cumbersome nomenclature)? And for the logical
aspect, what would an axiomless-axiom look like? A useful clue for resolving
the “substance-bundle” dichotomy can be found in the identity of opposites
and in our Principle of Nondual Rationalism: Infinite divisibility equals
indivisibility.
In nondual philosophies all dichotomies and opposites are symbiogenetic
(to use a more modern and precise vocabulary) or “other-engendering and
other-necessitating.” In other words, neither substance nor its modifications
can exist one without the other. Neither substance nor its bundles
(properties formed from low-level modifications) are foundational, but both
must exist at every conceivable level whether the substance appears
i
Indeed we will come to see this historical pattern of conceptual differentiation, which generates a
highly polarized false-dichotomy, which in turn must finally be integrated into a symbiotic (and
symbiogenetic) conceptual polarity, or indeed a complimentary set of practical axes, or praxes.
Page | 102
FOUNDATIONALISM, THE INFINITE REGRESS AND THE TRANSCENDENT BIAS
i
This treatment, of course, is only meant to be suggestive of the solution, and in order to rigorously
counter the many objections from academia regarding this clearly “easy fix” for a problem that has
been raging for centuries, I would have to fully explicate the implications and intrinsic connections.
This I plan to do in SpinbitZ, but for now, the suggestion indeed may be all that is needed for some
to grasp the usefulness of the solution and begin to employ it.
Page | 103
NONDUAL RATIONALISM AND THE LABYRINTH OF THE CONTINUUM
i
Note that this “amorphous aspect” is also the definition of the “ether” in Gerald Lebau’s Sorce
Theory
Page | 104
Page | 105
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Nondual Rationalism—as we have seen and will see in much greater detail—
in contrast to modern exoteric rationalism, is already a trans-rationalism.
The esoteric project of rationalism in this book is now in a healthy state of
completion (though, at this page it has yet to unfold in its entirety). And so,
as we will see, through the use of the higher-level—trans-rational and
vision-logic level—Interface Philosophy, the mathematical and philosophical
elements of Nondual Rationalism will unfold in perfect harmony and
operation upon the axis inherent to the rational itself, the
Immanent/Transcendent axis at the core of the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism. Thus, a Nondual Rationalism naturally forms the transcended-
and-included “foundation” for a nondual philosophy, and in this case it forms
the base of trans-rational Interface Philosophy.
In the embryogenesis of this work, these two philosophies unfolded in a
tight symbiogenesis, the interfaces forming a higher-level scaffolding and
perspective from which to see the resolutions to the deeper dualities and
paradoxes. At this point in the game, we have yet to see much of this unfold,
but it will become readily apparent as we progress.
Page | 106
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
i
See the work of Ken Wilber, for an overview.
ii
See From Dependent- to Tetra- Arising: The Conceptual Embryogenesis of AQAL, p560).
Page | 107
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
distinction. Only when we recognize from a higher level that the distinction
itself is important, not any side over the other, can we move forward. And in
this way the original conceptual distinction and differentiation, the new
functional polarity, is integrated into a higher level of functioning as we
move from simplicity to complexity in the embryogenesis of the concept.
A. B.
i¥
“cultivated third”: a term borrowed from Michel Serres
Page | 108
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
the compartments are given focus and manifest a new integrating level of
further differentiation. Or it could be that the new holons from the first
division, undergo a similar process of differentiation themselves, a holonic
mitosis, and the process repeats.
These two methods, analogous to sex, in the first instance, and mitosis in
the second, would likely be intermixed throughout the developing organism,
depending on the specific natures of the conceptual holons and their
interfaces and relations between other holons. In any case, the previous,
more general conceptual level of description is transcended-and-included by
a more specific and detailed version of itself. Unity differentiates into
polarity which integrates through triunity which differentiates further into
multiplicity, “the ten thousand things” and so on.
The critical point is that ideally, this history would be recorded, or
reconstructed, so that one can see the whole from the outside (the level of
vision-logic, which we will explore shortly) and travel up and down between
levels of description, from general unity to specific multiplicity, because this
orienting and zeroing-in general-to-specific, transcend-and-include
holarchical historical procedure ensures that the ONE is included in
differentiation to the MANY just as the MANY is transcended and integrated
back into the ONE.
With this ideal embryogenesis of the concept in mind, the delineation of this
conceptual scheme will hopefully unfold in the most natural progression as
it works itself out through the basement level tombs of the pyramid of
complexity.
i¥
From Gerald Lebau
Page | 109
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Page | 110
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
i
* See, Unity and Nonduality, p239.
Page | 111
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Page | 112
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
Alan Watts explained the concept of polarity very simply when he said, “The
axis of opposites is the perception of polarity. The difference between them
is explicit, but the unity is implicit.” We speak (explicate) in terms
(terminals) to make things nice and simple, black and white, but we know
that between black and white there is always at least a little grey on the
edges of vision.i
Mankind breaks into consciousness through the use of sensory, and then
conceptual contrasts: light-dark, hot-cold, sharp-dull, loud-quiet, and so on.
This is the defining feature of the relative scope: one sensation or concept in
relation to the other.
i
…or if one is lucky, always in the center of it.
Page | 113
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Polarity is one of the most, simple, pervasive, powerful and critical concepts
to become aware of. It can be seen virtually everywhere in thought and
nature at the most rudimentary and fundamental levels. Observation itself
functions on polarity in multiple ways. The nerve cell either fires or not and
all perception is, at the basis, contrast dependent. Perception breaks into
subtleties as it matures, certainly, similar in this way to the embryogenesis
of the concept, but in the beginning it is fundamentally polar, and retains a
strong element of polarity throughout its course.
We cannot function without differences and extremes. In thought and
language, pairs of opposites are ubiquitous. And for pinning down a
distinction they are as indispensable as an opposable thumb. As powerful as
they are, however, they can easily be abused through ignorant and/or
dishonest manipulation, such as in a bait and switch, or in the very common
rhetorical and political divide-and-conquer devise of the false-dilemma.
Page | 114
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
Page | 115
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
The phrase, “the walls of a box are what the inside and the outside have in
common,” brings us to the triunity in polarity. In the following diagram I
have emphasized the triuning Emptiness of polarity in the ancient Chinese
Yin/Yang (see, Figure 4, below), showing the walls of the box of this ancient
“Diagram of the Supreme Ultimate.”i¥
Between all poles there is an interface and beneath all interactions there is
deeper ground of Being. This triunity can be seen in the “lazy eight” infinity
symbol below, where each lobe is formed from the continuation of the curve
of the other and both are unified through the one curve passing between
them, (see Figure 5, below).
The Escher drawing with the infinity sign presented as a mobius strip
shows more clearly the duality of finite unity, and inversely, the unity of
finite duality.ii* The single circular strip can be twisted in such a way that
the distinction between the inside and outside dissolves, revealing it for the
relative division that it always was.
i¥
<http://www.hartford-hwp.com/archives/55/069.html>
ii
* See Finite Unity: “Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two”, p246.
Page | 116
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
A.
B.
C.
Figure 5: Polarity:
A) The infinity sign. B) Escher Drawing “Mobius Strip II.” C) The lower half of a
diagram from Buckminster Fuller’s Synergetics, originally illustrating the polar concept
of involution and evolution.
from this analysis of polarity and the identity of opposites, we can draw
another thread from a resonance with our original Principle of Nondual
Rationalism, to entwine in our Ariadne’s Cable, leading us out of
(transcending-and-including) the labyrinth of the continuum.
Explanation: Given the identity of opposites, any term (or terminal of a polarity) whose
identical-opposite is neglected when taken to the absolute scope , will rebound, reflect
or refract into its identical-opposite. This is because the absolute scope is ineffable
and the very opposite of relation. Terms, concepts and other relations, have no
function at the absolute scope, and the identity of opposites always re veals itself when
taken to extremes.
We have already seen the PAR in action in Chord 1, the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism, “Infinite Division Equals Indivisibility,” because the concept of
divisibility (neglecting to include its identical-opposite of indivisibility),
when taken at the absolute scope (whose quantitative property is infinity),
“necessitates that there can be no fundamental or absolute division because
there will always be a deeper level of divisibility, and hence, infinite
divisibility necessitates that the absolute is fundamentally indivisible.” In
this way, divisibility, taken to its absolute scope, becomes indivisibility,
enacting our Principle of Absolute Reversal, because infinity is boundless.
See the example below which will help make sense of both the Principle of
Nondual Rationalism and the Principle of Absolute Reversal, and note also
how it resonates with our Principle of Immanence in Transcendence.
Page | 118
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
i
Most rational physicists have come to understand that space, or the vacuum, is not void but rather
teeming with an abstraction called “energy” which simply means “the ability to do work.” But since
Einstein's initial and self-confessed premature reaction was to throw away the term (a)ether as
denoting the substantial aspect of the vacuum, now the term is anathema and we must speak in
abstractions like “energy”.
Page | 119
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
(taking form, solidity and indivisibility to the absolute scope) has been cut so
much by the intervening nothingness (in the minds of the physicists) that
the original Greek a-tomoi are now extensionless points existing in a sea of
nothingness. This is the “infinite smallness” of the mathematical point, the
absolutized relativity of somethingness and form down to the absolute
immanent size of nothingness. Having no extension, they are, fundamentally
uncuttable. They take up no space and have no diameter to halve.
So we already see that Form, when taken to the absolute scope, the
infinity of infinite smallness, becomes the non-form of Emptiness. And we
can see that this is a resonance of our Principle of Nondual Rationalism, that
the infinite divisibility in the foundational search for the “fundamental
particle,” the inverse-ultimate form, has ended in the non-particle, the non-
form of the mathematical point—the implicit singularity of Emptiness.
In other words, since the size of these point particles is zero, this
nothingness of “empty space” is effectively divided by merely another
sizeless nothingness—the idea of form which has lost its size and extension,
and indeed its existence in either the imagination or reality. The
absolutized somethingness of physics is dually-described yet
ultimately a single infinite nothingness. Taking somethingness and Form
to the absolute scope has rebounded, reflected or refracted through the
ineffable absolute to return its identical-opposite, Emptiness. And, as a
corollary, a solid has reflected off the absolute in the form of a fluid: The
Inverse Unified Field.
It is quite an interesting time in history that modern Physics has reached the
EXACT inverse of the truth necessitated by the metaphysics of causality and
esoteric science. By abandoning rational philosophy, with its irreducible
nondual aspect of extension, the physicists have “somehow” (ad hoc and
acausally) reached the simple axiomatic level of the Inverse Unified Field, or
a “unified nothingness,” which is now only describable by similarly causally-
empty and abstract entities such as “space-time,” “extra-dimensions,”
“probabilities,” “randomness,” and “uncertainty,” because nothingness—
whether pseudo-extended as an existing nonexistence, a void, or non-
extended as a point-particle—does not, and cannot ‘possess’ real properties
or causality. This logically-derived unity (inverted or not) is ironically quite
an accomplishment and a testament to the self-correcting power of
empirical mathematics, driven by a medieval foundationalism, and operating
on blind (acausal) quantitative logic in the face of human misconception and
misinterpretation.i
i
The unconscious metaphysical inversion of substance into its opposite, the void, with its
incompatibilities and nonfunctional paradoxes shows directly that physics is incorrect at the very
core of its reductionist paradigm, the solid-/particle-bias. When the model finally becomes too top-
heavy, with its umpteen-dimensional, semantically void, space-time knots leading to ultimate
Page | 120
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
The above interface with the Principle of Absolute Reversal and the absolute
and relative aspects of locality, provides a nice illustration of a recurring
aspect of the interface between the absolute and relative scopes. Generally it
incomprehensibility, then the whole thing will flip right-side up again in the true nature of a
scientific REVOLUTION. See SpinbitZ: Volume II.
i
* See Principle 1: Chord 1: The Fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism (PNDR), p84.
Page | 121
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
is the case that when a relative concept is taken to the absolute scope of the
ALL-ONE or omni, its meaning is effectively negated. This can be readily
seen with the relative concept of number taken to the quantitative or
multiple aspect of the absolute scope, i.e. infinity. This generally results in
the common subtle oxymoron “infinitely many,” or an infinite number.
Spinoza intuitively recognized the common con-fusion of this intrinsic
polarity and preferred the term “numberless” rather than an infinite number
or infinitely many. Infinity, in this sense, is therefore the dissolution of the
boundary of number itself. It is the logical Emptiness of the relative world of
quantitative form. And so taking number to the omni of infinity turns it into
the non of the numberless or boundless.
The omni-non is the binary logic aspect of the interface of the absolute
and relative. This common absolute-inversion from the ONE-ALL to the non,
is the intuitive source and inspiration, I believe, of Leibniz’s cosmic
fascination with binary logic, leading to the invention of our modern
computational infrastructure.
Laplace wrote:
Leibniz saw in his binary arithmetic the image of Creation. ... He imagined
the Unity represented God, and Zero the void; that the Supreme Being
drew all beings from the void, just as unity and zero express all numbers
in his system of numeration. This conception was so pleasing to Leibniz
that he communicated it to the Jesuit, Grimaldi, president of the Chinese
tribunal for mathematics, in the hope that this emblem of creation would
convert the Emperor of China, who was very fond of the sciences ...
This polarity (which he saw in the emblem of polarity itself, the yin-yang
symbol) between Unity and the void is that between the fullness and
emptiness conceptions of the absolute; in nondual philosophy it is generally
held that Emptiness is fullness and vice versa, as one. The void, Leibniz
speaks of, however, is the immanent infinity of the rational zero, not the pre-
rational concept of zero as negation, or immanence as regression.i* Indeed,
the axis of the Rational numbers as well as the positive infinity of
philosophical rationality, as we will see, has an implicit binary form, toggling
between the origin-identity at one and the immanent infinity at zero. His
idea, therefore, that “the Supreme Being drew all beings from the void” is
echoed in our Cycle of Unity, where the 1 of finite unity is the interface
(solidus/vinculum) of the I/T uni-axis of the ONE-one. (This will make sense
only after absorbing the context of the appropriate section,ii* or upon
reading this the second time. Such are the compromises imposed from the
linearity of language.) Furthermore, this is the creation of the first unit-
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 122
EMBRYOGENESIS OF THE CONCEPT
Page | 123
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Page | 124
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
See Arnheim’s Visual Thinking, for example.
ii
Transcension-and-inclusion can also be seen as implicit in Haeckel’s “biogenetic law,” “ontogeny
recapitulates phylogeny,” which says that the ontogeny, or embryogenesis of an individual
organism, recapitulates, or transcends-and-includes, its phylogeny, or its entire evolutionary history.
iii
emotions being an inner form of sensation, as described by the neuroscientist Antonio Damasio
Page | 125
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
…even if diffused over many instances into a vague generality…
ii
Which would be a rather “green-meme,” or holarchy-demolishing interpretation.
Page | 126
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
There is a bit of ambiguity, however, regarding the distinction between percept and concept which
will be cleared up in the section, Percept and Concept, p617.
ii
The audio sense does, perhaps, a better job of this in the temporal, and emotive realms, but lacks
the resolution in the spatio-temporal.
Page | 127
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
spectrum of the arts. Vision at this level, in a sense, simply means “percept,”
and so, accurately speaking, we might call this a “Percept-Logic Coordinate
System,” though this would lose the unique network connotations that
vision-logic has come to embody.
Vision-logic, therefore—with its integrated concept-percepts—becomes
opposed to “blind-logic,” where “concept is divorced from percept, and
thought moves among [mere] abstractions.” Blind-logic has a limited,
hollowed out, semantic foundation and so it lacks the groundi or medium
within which to move, so to speak. Unable to find a ground within which to
find subtle reconfigurations and variations, it is stuck in a single perspective.
It can’t, therefore, find new modes of “seeing” the whole. Blind-logic
generally lacks the ability to lift itself out of the rooted perspective of mere
words, syntax; it cannot escape the “word-binding” so common to abstract,
sophistic, logic (e.g. lawyer talk) which can “prove” the “truth” of even the
most obvious of absurd conclusions; thought, such as this, easily becomes
“spell-bound” to its surface-level machinations, as does its unwitting
audience.
~~
i
An instance of the Deleuzian “plane of immanence.”
Page | 128
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
Page | 129
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
ii
See S. Lem’s Imaginary Magnitude, for a fantastic discussion on the possibility of “meta-
languages,” complete with a diagram of a future evolutionary-linguistic scenario.
iii
DMT, or dimethyltryptamine, is classified as an “entheogen,” similar to other drugs that induce
“religious” or mystical visions of a unity (or vast plurality) with God or the cosmos.
Page | 130
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
…not to suggest an actual genealogy of the conception itself from Deleuze’s plane of immanence,
but merely a conceptual unfolding for this current explication.
Page | 131
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Though of course it is obvious from the above quote that the plane of
immanence is not really a “plane” at all, but something much more alive and
complex, a “fractal…abstract machine” with “assemblages” and “working
parts,” an embryogenesis, prior to the concept, sub-representation, if you
will. In this sense the VCS is, or includes, the plane of immanence, though as
a service to the concept itself, we abandon the term “plane” in general, and
delineate the working parts, the “anatomy, physiology and embryology,”i of
this abstract machine in more dimensions than a “plane” will connotatively
allow.
i
To quote the first part of Gerald Lebau’s acronym, ANPHEON, “the anatomy, physiology and
embryology of Nature”.
Page | 132
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
This is similar to Phillip K. Dick’s conception of God, getting lost in his own creation…and it is
ironically similar to the role of the author, as I am right now lost inside this creation as I create it.
Page | 133
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
perception as a whole in the mind, with the capacity to descend and ascend
at will to see the whole object/system from various vantage points in a
higher-dimensional space. The VCS serves the function of visualizing and
coordinating conceptual relationships (networks) free from a singular
rooted perspective, and at the vision-logic, or integral-aperspectival level of
cognition which, as Ken Wilber states in his A Brief History of Everything,
“synthesizes, integrates, and sees networks” between otherwise opposing
systems, rather than being rooted defensively and offensively within any of
them.
This may seem a daunting and unrealistic task, but it is actually quite
simple, taken step by step. And, with the help of language, we will bootstrap
this conceptual and inter-dimensional space from the 2D frame of this paper
(or computer screen). The flat diagrams and linear text will suggest to the
mind the intuitive, non-linear and aperspectival forms, the plane of
immanence, from which they were derived. These emergent (non-platonic)
forms are to be used loosely, intuitively and organically, as orienting
generalizations from the aperspectival vision-logic level of cognition.
It must be pointed out again, at this point, that in harmony with the
Deleuzean definition of philosophy as an essentially creative act, this system
itself is purely imaginary, and indeed a synthetic and even an aesthetic
creation; a toy demi-mythology; Philosophy as the art and play of the
concept. This system does not claim existence for itself outside the mind or
the paper. As in Buddhism, in this demi-mythology of an imagined world of
ordinary concepts, an enlightened man is more powerful than any of its
would-be gods, and one must always be on the look out for any enslavement
by these concept-gods (platonic forms), as well as ways to transcend them
(negating if necessary, but including if possible).
The system is not conceived as a ‘pure’ platonic form preexisting all
human thought and action that must descend into impure materiality. But it
does indeed map—in the general and abstract way of all maps—a deeper
and vastly more complex emergent territory beyond itself; A dynamic reality
of conceptual attractors, dimensions, drives and motions, pushing and
pulling the mind in these abstract intuited directions which are only mapped
a posteriori, and even empirically, to the artificial geometries (points,
boundaries, axes and planes) and concepts of the system.i These basic
emergent directionalities of thought, can be found in virtually all
i
This is the essence of Deleuze’s conception of Empiricism, an intensely creative and conceptual
endeavor coupled always and ultimately with immanent and causal explanations of emergent and
sensate reality. That is why he considered Spinoza one of the key empiricists, as opposed to
Descartes who imposed his system from the outside, from the limitations of his own mind, rather
than recognizing the limits of the mind to grasp the immanent capabilities of matter to be at one
with mind as aspects, or attributes, of a single immanent causal reality.
Page | 134
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
* See the section on Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.
Page | 135
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
In the embryogenesis of the concept, the ineffable absolute breaks into the
relation of cognitive operation i first in the polarity of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and then in the orthogonal transitive axes. In
this vision-logic meta-system, then, we have only two main “axes,” “vision-
logic axes” or “VL-axes” which are conceptual forms of directionality as a
pre-operational context for the operations of mathematics itself. Because we
have only two VL-axes in mathematics there is an underlying binary form to
mathematics, and it manifests into various cycles between zero and one, as
we will see. These VL-axes are the immanent/transcendent (I/T) and the
transitive, and, as we will see, they correspond roughly to Cantor’s
uncountable and countable infinities.ii* Unlike the axes of the Cartesian
system, the orthogonality between these VL-axes is not really perpendicular,
and the VL-axes are merely forms or concepts of directionality, of motion,
and not necessarily linear, as we will see. They are often, however,
necessarily represented merely “on paper” as linear and perpendicular axes,
such as in the main diagram of the VCS which we will encounter below, and
doing so can be very beneficial, so long as their real nonlinear and non-
rectilinear nature is kept in mind. So the term ‘VL-axis’ can function by
operationalizing a polarity, and invoking the diagram and the differentiating
orthogonality represented therein, rather than forcing the mind to conceive
of each of these directional concepts as uni-directional and perpendicular
linearities. Viewing them as single linear axes would collapse the system to
the merely transitive, as we will see.
i
A conceptual “symmetry breaking”
ii
* See To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox (p432) and its subsections Galileo,
Cantor and the Transfinite (p442), and Back to Zeno (p448).
Page | 136
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i nd
This is the essence of the concept of the “Aspect Infinite,” which is the 2 order infinite, found in
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
True to the Tao, the omni (infinite) is singular and the singular is omni (infinite) — ALL is ONE.
Page | 137
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
These are the two main elements of the transitive: its uni-linearity and
its quantized, or discrete nature. Each of the two main elements, uni-
linearity and quantization, alone, is enough to denote the transitive quality.
The transitive axis only gets into continuity when it begins to move into
operation on the immanent-transcendent axis, such as in the real number
line, as we have seen with the labyrinth of the continuum opened up first in
the rational numbers. But it is critical to note that any line is transitive, even
if it has elements within it derived from immanent-transcendent operations.
The Cartesian axes, then, even though they can represent the rational
numbers, are intrinsically transitive-axes, because they are a composite of
linear dimensions.
i
Or “numberless,” as Spinoza might say, to avoid the oxymoronic pitfalls that befall us when thinking
of the infinite in terms of a number, or the finite.
Page | 138
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
…invoking the Principle of Absolute Reversal to invoke the identical opposite, omni=non.
ii
Interestingly, this was also the period in my life when I was experimenting with the interface
between tedium and excitement, or repetition and difference in music.
iii
“Oneirology is the scientific study of dreams. The term comes from the Greek oneiro which means
dream.” An oneironaut, then, is a creative practitioner, or explorer of dreams.
Page | 139
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
the holon, the “part-whole,” which had been invented decades earlier by
Arthur Koestler, but about which I was ignorant. This simple idea—that
every unit is a collapsible and expandable scale, the very environment of
deeper, “collapsed” units, (or every part is a whole) and its corollary that
every scale is collapsible to, or expandable from, a unit (or every whole is a
part)—necessitates an “endless holarchy” of collapsible/expandable unit-
scales.
When reading over my old notes, I found it fascinating that this transition
from the transitive “ticker-line” to the immanent-transcendent holonic axis,
or the “scalaxis,”i as I originally called it, was directly enacted, and indeed
discovered in this simple little dream. In retrospect, it seems but a vivid
reenactment of Zeno’s hypnotic brand of toys—which themselves break into
the fundamental binary VL-axes of conceptual relation—but used as a seed
for my wanderings in the conceptual space of the new biological genome. I
include it here for a nice little diversion into dreamland, perhaps providing a
self-similar historical echo, and a convenient segue; an intuitive bridge from
the transitive to the immanent-transcendent dimensions in an infinite
holarchy of unit-scales.ii
i
With the adjective form, ‘scalactic’ having a nice sci-fi ring to it.
ii
One of the motivations for using the term immanent-transcendent axis, rather than ‘scalaxis,’ is
that operationalizing the idea of ‘transcendence’ as a common, and fundamental aspect of reality,
will help bring it “down to earth”, so to speak, and help reconcile the transcendent-bias, and
immanent-transcendent dualism infecting pre-rational modernity (and post-post whatever).
iii
…and here we find yet again a transcendent-bias in that immanent boundless numbers are
“irrational” and transcendental numbers are merely transcendental.
iv
And here we see the age-old dichotomy between the continuous and the discrete embodied as the
distinction between the two conceptual directionalities in the VCS.
Page | 140
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
* See, Evolution is Involution Seen in Reverse, p580.
ii
Notice the modal-centric emphasis on locality, as in the center is everywhere. The law of absolute
reversal requires that this polarity be switched to operationalize its inverse. It then becomes “God is
an intelligible sphere whose center is nowhere and whose circumference everywhere.” It works
from either an inward or an outward perspective.
Page | 141
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
In the figure above, the I/T axis is drawn, unfortunately but necessarily, as a
linear, unidirectional, “axis” rather than an omni-directional expansion or
contraction. The transcendent “direction” on this axis zooms outward from
any “position” (fixed volumetric scale) on the I/T axis and the immanent
“direction” zooms inward. The familiar 3-dimensions, xyz and all infinite
uni-directions in-between, have been collapsed—for the sake of higher-level,
aperspectival, visualization—into the transitive plane fixed upon the central
I/T axis. Also note that the orthogonality between these VL-axes is
represented by perpendicularity, which is also entirely misleading.
Perpendicularity is simply the easiest and most direct way to visualize
orthogonality. The orthogonality between these two VL-axes, however, is
best understood as a scale invariance between transitive relations. In other
words, in a system of transitive relations, such as any mathematical
geometry (or self-similarity), if you change the scale itself (changing
coordinates on the I/T axis) the pattern of relations will always remain the
same.
The crucial function of this diagram is to demonstrate the relation
between transitive planes as fixed with respect to specific positions on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, and that these “positions” correlate in this
higher-dimensional interface, not to position itself, but to size or scale. But it
Page | 142
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
The most crucial distinction between the I/T axis and the transitive
polarities is that the I/T axis deals exclusively with a priori volumetric
omni-directionality, inward-and-outward, and the transitive axes are
exclusively unidirectional abstractions, such as the 3 uni-directions
that make up Cartesian coordinate space.
A quick look at coordinates on the I/T and transitive axes will help make the
distinction clear. To aid in representation, we can use an enclosing surface, a
sphere (see Figure 7, below), representing or embodying the particular
volumetric scale. This sphere is a coordinate, on the I/T axis; a fixed scale
which is inherent to (unfolding as) the particular transitive axes,
i
It is clear, however, that an infinitely small distance, were it not a contradiction in terms, would
take zero time to cross, which we will explore in greater detail in Interface Mathematics.
Page | 143
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
represented as a plane on the main VCS diagram (above).i And so even the
rational and continuous numberline, such as that drawn on a Cartesian
graph (or any of the single lines passing through the infinity within the I/T
axis below), is, in a sense, merely a uni-directional, or transitive, cross-
section or rendering of the spherical/omni-directional I/T axis.
i
…and as we will see, the sphere is the most general representation of number, in identical
opposition to this same immanent-transcendent axis (the identical opposite of number), The
Infinite.
Page | 144
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
Note that we are not concerned here with the use of transitive axes to represent non-spatial, or
non-physical aspects, at this point, except for the representational use of the transitive-axis to stand
for the immanent-transcendent axis in the main Vision-Logic Coordinate System diagram (two
figures above).
ii
* See, for example, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
iii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 145
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
* Recall Figure 7: The Nuclear VCS Diagram With Coordinates:, p144.
ii
* See, The Nondual-Rational and Empirical Embryogenesis of Mathematics, p217.
iii
It is also the polarity of Spinoza’s Substance/God, with omnilocal immanence-in-transcendence
equating to Substance, and omni-local transcendence-in-immanence equating to “God.” This last
point takes us far afield, but see Leibnoza Von Spinbitz (p659), to jump the line and explore further.
iv
We are not here using the term ‘singularity’ in its strictly mathematical and operational sense.
Rather, we use the term to highlight the infinity hidden in the “infinitely small” Euclidean point.
Indeed, this implicit infinity is the very source of the immanent infinities (mathematical singularities)
found when physicists of the early twentieth century tried to calculate the energy of an electron—
represented as such a point—as an inverse-squared function of the distance to its center and its
non-existent terminating surface.
Page | 146
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
i
* See Exploring the Univocity Framework, p190.
ii
* This is another aspect of the trans-trans-bias. See The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
iii
As Samuel Levey termed it in his article “Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually Infinite Division
of Matter.”
iv
* For further information, see, for example, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite (p270) and Reconnecting the
Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and the
CalculusReconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence
and the Calculus (p400).
v
* See the related discussion on The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 147
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
position is also its non, as we would expect with the Principle of Absolute
Reversal and the univocal aspects of the absolute scope.i*
The omni-axis is the IT axis whose locality aspect is “seen” (or unseen) at
the absolute scope, through the “eye” of Infinite Unityii* to give us omni-non-
locality.iii Poetically speaking, in the omni-axis, the pupil of the eye of
locality and its boundary is fully and entirely opened, so that the eye itself—
and its limiting/enabling differentiated, boundaries, positions and
perspectives—has actually disappeared in the complete omni-directional
opening of its boundary. This, in part, is the continuity aspect of The Infinite.
The omni-axis is the VCS representation of the ‘ONE-ALL’ tautology and
identity of univocal multiplicity, whereas the uni-axis is merely the locus of
the ‘one’ of “finite unity;” i.e. the immanent singularity and its boundary,
respectively.iv* This distinction between the absolute unbounded ‘ONE’ and
the relative ‘one’ of boundary will be explained in much more detail in the
section on Unity and Nonduality. But it is important to note that both the
uni and omni forms of the immanent-transcendent axis—as all VL-axes of
the Vision-Logic Coordinate System—are mere abstracted aspects of “The
Infinite,” as we will see in the section on Spinoza’s Triune Infinite.v
Recalling the two previous diagrams of the immanent-transcendent axis,
we can simplify, modify and compare them, side by side, to differentiate-
and-integrate the omni- and uni- axes (See Figure 8, below). The interface or
cultivated third of the immanent/transcendent polarity in its omni-non-local
aspect (i.e. the omni-axis), is a transitive “plane,” (see side A of Figure 8,
below). Recall, however, that the image of the plane is a mere convenience,
both of speech and of imagination. For the sake of higher-level,
aperspectival, visualization and simplification of the omni as a uni-
directional axis, the familiar 3-dimensions—xyz and all infinite uni-
directions in-between—have been collapsed into the “transitive” planes
fixed upon the central I/T “axis.” Such transitive planes—“planes of
existence” or “levels of reality” as they are often called in cosmogonic
textsvi—in the real world correspond to the emergent/transcendent, yet
relatively fixed scales (or “Kosmic grooves”) of nature, such as the “Planck
i
* See Exploring the Univocity Framework, p190.
ii
* See Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
iii
… incorporating in the omni-non the identical opposite necessary at the absolute scope…
iv
* See Unity and Nonduality (p239), and The (Binary) Cycle of Unity (p254).
v
The I/T omni-axis is, mathematically-speaking, non-operational, due to its taking on of the
properties of the absolute scope in its omni-/non-locality. In other words, in order to operate
mathematically, one position (ideal point and immanent pole of an I/T axis) from the infinite must
be abstracted and selected so as to construct the first number in Operational Mathematics, the
volumetric boundary (a real-point). We’ll explore this in much more detail later. See for example
Empirical/Experiential Beginnings: Bucky’s “Operational Mathematics” (p217), The (Binary) Cycle of
Unity (p254) and The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation (p306).
vi
See, for example, The Secret Doctrine, by H.P. Blavatsky or Ken Wilber’s Integral model.
Page | 148
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
scale,” the level of atoms and the level of cells. The “transitive plane,”
therefore, is actually a planar cross-section of an infinite volume or extension
whose vastness is defined relatively and transitively to a specified scale
(coordinate on the I/T axis) of a priori volumetric spherical units. Each one
of these nested (holonic) units, however, is the spherical and omni-
directional I/T interface of a single uni-axis.
Page | 149
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
A. B.
Page | 150
THE VISION-LOGIC COORDINATE SYSTEM
At this point an interesting relation has begun to appear between the ALL-
ONE, the omni-non and the aspects of position and extension (or continuity).
The omni-non of position, recall, is the ALL-ONE, or the “omni-uni” of
extension (the omni-axis), and the omni-non of extension is the omni-uni of
position (a single uni-axis between the ALL-ONE and the singularity). This
gives us an interesting polarity between the aspects of position and
extension (or continuity) when taken at the absolute scope of the omni, or
the ALL—which is the infinite multiple aspect of the ONE of Infinite Unity at
which both omni and uni axes converge.i* The aspects of extension and
position, when taken at the absolute scope, appear to be identical opposite of
each other, in this sense. But in quantitative terms, the uni-aspect of the uni-
axis (the one singularity) is finite and the uni-aspect of the omni-axis (the
ONE of ALL uni-axes) is infinite. The quantitative difference between the
uni-aspects of the uni- and omni-axes (i.e. the ‘one’ and the ‘ONE,’
respectively), therefore, presents us with the critical polarity underlying the
Cycle of Unity, as we will see.
While the omni- and uni- axes converge at the transcendent pole, the
interfaces of each are vastly different. The interface of the uni-axis, as we
have seen, is an arbitrarily defined mathematical, or real-world emergent,
spherical/spheroidal boundary, whereas the interface of the omni-axis is an
infinite expanse of a mathematical/metrical or physical substrate; e.g. a
cubic grid or an “isotropic vector matrix” of imaginary or real metric units or
a relatively uniform volumetric expanse of real atoms; a “level of reality,” or
a “plane of existence.” The polarity between the I/T interfaces, therefore,
swings us from the unity of the relative (finite unity) in the unit-interface of
the uni-axis, to the unity of the absolute (Infinite Unity), in the ALL-ONE.
This is key, as we will see, in the Cycle of Unity.
i
* See Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
Page | 151
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
The tendency when we delineate all of this stuff and break it down into its
subcomponents, with infinite levels of transitive planes exfoliating from an
immanent-transcendent axis (itself composed of two types), is to forget to
put it back together. The immanent-transcendent and transitive axes
ultimately form an orthogonal polarity, a conceptual symbiosis. The first
unit, the number 1, emerges from the uncountable I/T axis as the decided
unit-boundary, the chosen scale of measurement, allowing the transitive
operations of addition and subtraction (and in physical reality,
agglomeration and evolution) to begin. Then, with the operations of
division, the immanent-transcendent axis is again invoked or awakened as
the mathematical ratio dissolves or “violates” the “closure property” and
opens up the immanent pole of the Rational numbers (all of which we will
discuss in detail in Interface Mathematics).
Furthermore, these infinite levels abstracted and represented on the
immanent-transcendent axis, do not necessarily exist somewhere else, in the
erewhon of “mere mathematics,” or in different worlds, but, as SpinbitZ:
volume II will explore in depth, they emerge into every scale as the very
forms of the relative, such as the “ergodic” and fractal complexities of nature
(see Saturn’s rings, for instance that manifest the infinite complexity in its
energy fields, as an instance-definition of ergodic).
With this conceptual framework in mind, our task ahead will be much
simpler because we have made explicit the many implicit, “pre-fused”
differentiations that so often conflate and “con-fuse” these absolute-level
discussions, manifesting in the various paradoxes of the infinite, and of free-
will vs. determinism, for example. We can now cast aside the shells so often
unwittingly employed in the game of philosophy and, perhaps for the first
time, begin to move these symbols around freely, on our conceptual game-
board, in the light of reason.
Page | 152
Page | 153
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Page | 154
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
Univocity is explained by Deleuze as “the idea that all events are compatible;
they are ‘inter-expressive’. Being has one voice but can only express
differences.” And Todd May says, “What univocity implies is not that
everything is the same, or that there is a principle of the same underlying
everything, but, instead, precisely the opposite. With univocity comes
difference, difference for the first time taken seriously in itself.”i¥
Univocity means that every expression of existence is different in a
fundamental sense from every other. And yet the unity aspect of the concept
signifies that these differences are fundamentally causally intercompatable,
or ‘inter-expressive.’ This is the identity of opposites of difference and
similarity, because indeed without this inter-expression or inter-relation,
differences could not interface or relate in order to really differ. And thus,
with univocity, difference (or relativity) is “taken seriously in itself” and
given a framework for actualization and understanding.ii It is this basic, or
“fundamental,” framework, expanded and operationalized herein, upon
i¥
(May)
ii
Actualization and understanding are ontic and epistemic respectively. See the section below,
Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity, p176.
Page | 155
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
which any healthy and “holistic,” or integral rationality must be built (in
some form or other), and we have already seen it as the implicit essence of
ancient and esoteric nondual/perennial philosophy,i such as Taoism, Advaita
Vedanta Hinduism, Madhyamaka Buddhism. It is also seen in the West in
some forms and levels of Christianity, Neo-Platonism, esoteric Spinozism,
and in some of the pre-Socratics, such as Heraclitus.
This fundamental “causal” or “expressive” intercompatability of
univocity, giving meaning and truth to relativity (instead of relativity to
Truth), is what Deleuze sees as the core of rational/empirical philosophy as
it winds its way through western History from the Stoics to Duns Scotus to
Spinoza to Leibniz to Nietzsche to Bergson, through Deleuze and beyond.
This univocal relativity, or multiplicity, is the defining essence of Spinoza’s
Substance,ii for instance, as opposed to its common academic intepretation
as a “principle of the same,” or a foundational material substrate, underlying
and unifying everything. And as we have discussed, the re-emerging esoteric
understanding of Spinozism, catalyzed by Deleuze and others, is essentially
nondual and non-foundational.
Nondual Rationalism takes it further, at least explicitly, and shows that
the more coherent understanding of Spinoza’s Substance is ultimately based
not on any foundational “transitive-plane” (substrate) immanent to
observed reality (e.g. Deleuze’s plane of immanence), but rather on the
positive, a priori, and non-regressive notion of deep infinity, which we have
operationalized in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System as the immanent pole
or emphasis of the Immanent/Transcendent axis. It is the identification of
Spinoza’s Substance with the notion of positive infinity in Deleuze, and with
the immanent pole of the immanent/transcendent “axis” herein, that brings
rationalism out of its modern academic exoteric misinterpretation as a
foundationalist formless-absolutism or even a materialism or scientism (or
“eco-philosophy,” as Ken Wilber might put it), and into a nondual,
“foundationless-foundationalism” or a “rootless-rootism,” that re-opens and
re-animates the project of rationalism and sets it on its feet again.
In true rationalism, unshadowed by the reactionary misinterpretations
and pre-rational tendencies (e.g. the transcendent-bias, or the “forces of
representation”), of post-/modernity, the one foundational principle (or
i
Aldous Huxley defines it as “the metaphysic that recognizes a divine Reality substantial to the world
of things and lives and minds; the psychology that finds in the soul something similar to, or even
identical with, divine Reality; the ethic that places man's final end in the knowledge of the immanent
and transcendent Ground of all being; the thing is immemorial and universal. Rudiments of the
perennial philosophy may be found among the traditional lore of primitive peoples in every region
of the world, and in its fully developed forms it has a place in every one of the higher religions” (The
Perennial Philosophy, p. vii).
ii
Throughout this work, I will be using “Substance” rather than “substance,” capitalizing the S to
denote an absolute scope. This can serve as a reminder that we are not talking about a foundational
substrate, but rather the I/T axis itself, if mainly an immanent emphasis.
Page | 156
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
(((or artificially inseminated)))
ii
* See also the section Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity, p176.
iii
* See the previous section Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind, p112.
iv¥
Logic of Sense, 177 qtd in Widder’s Genealogies of Difference by Beth Metcalf
Page | 157
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
The idea in nanotechnology that a single self-replicating “nano-bot” could replicate itself at an
exponential rate, and take over the earth with the monotonous similarity of its ceaseless repetition.
ii
…which self-recursively generated the absolute scope in the first place. See the coming section on
Polarity and Univocity, p174.
iii
Given that the absolute scope is defined by its absence or opposition to relativity, it makes no
sense to think of it in terms of space or location. The absolute scope can't be colonized period, and
it is not a place outside the relative world. It is merely the relative world attempted to be “seen”
from an infinite perspective, and this is already a “contradiction in terms”, which, we have seen, is a
natural property of the absolute scope. See also the section, Part Two: Interface Mathematics
(p200) and Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486) which explain
how a point of view is the identical opposite of the Infinite.
Page | 158
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
Polarities completely within the relative scope, however, can be vertical or horizontal, because the
relative scope is the home of polarity. These vertical polarities include any holarchical emergent,
such as the ontic/epistemic polarity, though a vertical, or holarchical polarity has a necessary
transcend-and-include asymmetry to it, characteristic of holarchies in general, and this is the actual
or ontic source of the transcendent-bias itself.
ii
* See Polarity and Univocity (p174), below.
iii¥
Translation by Yirmiyahu Yovel
Page | 159
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
* See the section, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias (p91).
ii
A flatland straw-man generated in reaction to modernity and rationality mainly by its theocratic
critics, Leibniz and Hegel, both of whom were idealists.
iii
And Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486) points out the
objective-ontic shift that renders Spinozism into a materialism.
iv
Spinoza’s modern, homeostatic, complexity-science, strange-attractor conception of “essence” as
“The endeavour, wherewith everything endeavours to persist in its own being…” from the Ethics,
Part III VII. This, as we will see in Univocity and Essence (p170), is a “reciprocal” or polar notion of
essence that does not precede existence, but is symbiogenetic with it.
Page | 160
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
appropriated for his “Absolute Reason.” But he was honest enough when
he said, “To be a philosopher one must first be a Spinozist.”
A major difficulty for modern philosophy students is that Spinoza inherited a
lexicon “stuffed with medieval barbarisms such as ‘substance’ and
‘attributes,’” i ¥ which was custom evolved for developing pre-rational
foundationalisms. But nowhere does Spinoza ever say that his Substance
exists at any single or particular level, immanent or transcendent to its
modifications, or that Substance, at any level, can exist without being actively
formed or modifiedii or that Substance is equated with matter. Quite the
contrary, Spinoza makes it clear that Substance is the rootless-root of
existence; activity itself, but only in the sense that—as the absolute scope
and axis of Tao—it enfolds and unfolds all polarities, including flux/stasis,
and hence it can’t be acted upon, set in motion or stabilized, by anything
else, because as the absolute, there isn’t anything else. Spinoza says in his
precursor to the Ethics—essentially a rough draft called the Short Treatise on
God, Man and his Well-being, iii —“God, it is said, inasmuch as he is a
supremely perfect being, cannot be passive.” And indeed, Nondual
Rationalism shows the precise reason that mono-poles (terms) such as
‘passive’ and ‘active’ simply have no function or power at the absolute scope
allowing us to more closely reach the plane of consistency in Spinoza’s
thought. Hence Hegel’s claim that Spinoza’s Substance was too rigid, too
passive, or too positive, is based on a category error; a failure to understand
Spinoza’s Substance univocally (see also Univocity and Polarity, p176). It is
i¥
Mathew Stewart, The Courtier and the Heretic, p179
ii
Spinoza says that substance can be conceived of axiomatically or logically without modifications,
but this establishes the relationship of immanent-causal, and logical dependency between eternal
Substance and its temporal modifications (i.e. between the absolute and relative scopes); a
dependency enforced by the geometric logic of the exposition, not the univocal framework itself.
Indeed the Univocity Framework takes a reciprocal, polar or nondual approach to the Substance-
modification relation, and with Deleuze, takes Substance to “turn around its modes” just as
Emptiness turns around form, and vice versa, on both counts.
The relation does not specify an actual duality or that substance can exist without its expressions in
modifications. Indeed, existence is expression. Substance is “logically prior” not temporally, given
the axiomatic geometric framework through which Spinoza chose to represent his model.
Furthermore, Spinoza says that the intellect conceives and perceives the essence of Substance
through the attributes, but what is it that the intellect ultimately conceives and perceives?
Modifications. Through the attributes they appear as modifications of Thought or Extension
(internal vs. external, respectively), but Spinoza tells us that the only thing that really exists is
Substance (deep infinity) and its modifications. Therefore, in a sense, modification itself is part of
the essence of Substance, and vice versa. Indeed, “active modification” seems to be a descriptor for
existence itself, which Spinoza says “pertains to the essence of Substance.” And this notion of an
essential polarity between Substance and its modifications, brings us right back to the polarity of
Emptiness and form. Emptiness (also called Fullness) is the infinite depth of Substance, Leibniz's
labyrinth of the continuum, and our principle of nondual rationality as infinite divisibility =
indivisibility, and form is the necessary inclusion of modification in the unbounded levels of active
existence.
iii
also called the “The Book of God.”
Page | 161
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
entirely likely that Hegel confused the rigidity of the geometric style, or the
“presentation layer” of The Ethics with its actual content.
Substance is eternal, or eternity itself,i not because it is static and
immovable, but because it is existence itself taken at the ineffable scope of
the Absolute, which enfolds and unfolds all polarities, including flux/stasis.
There is simply nothing beyond the absolute scope of “ALL is ONE,” by
definition, to act on (or stabilize) Substance, because the absolute scope was
generated from the application of polarity to itself in order give it dynamic
context and meaning in its identical-opposite.
i
Because Substance is at the absolute scope, saying “Substance is 'eternal'” necessitates that we
simultaneously mean the identical opposite, that substance is infinitely and irreducibly
instantaneous. And hence the fully univocal statement about the temporal aspect of Substance
would be “Substance is instantaneous and ‘eternal’“ or the “eternal NOW,” as it is commonly
phrased. Univocity as Deep Infinity: Prigogine and Leibniz (p182), and Univocity and the Eternal
NOW (p187).
ii
Substance can be considered merely an immanent emphasis on the Immanent/Transcendent axis
of which God is its identical opposite transcendent emphasis, and more identical than opposite, in
this case.
iii
* See Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch, p541.
Page | 162
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* See the section Univocity and Essence (p170) below, to see how Spinoza's use of “essence” is
thoroughly modern and indeed contrary to the modern notion of “essentialism.”
ii
This parallelism exactly mirrors the “tetra-arising” of the two singular quadrants, 'I' and 'IT'
(within/without respectively), in Ken Wilber's AQAL matrix. And, according to Wilber, this is one of
the key features of any “Integral post-metaphysics,” the other being an emergent and non-
foundational (i.e. nondual) ontology.
iii
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
iv
* See Identifying Quadrant Absolutisms, p561.
v
Indeed, as we will see, Spinoza’s Ethics can be shown to operate fundamentally on his notion of the
Triune Infinite, even though he only explicitly mentions this triunity in his famous letter on the
Infinite. See the section on Interface Mathematics and Nondual Rationalism, below.
Page | 163
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i¥
Deleuze, Negotiations
ii
* see my article, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” (p486), now
expanded as a chapter in this volume.
iii
through Spinoza's critics, Leibniz and Hegel, et al.
iv
See The Courtier and Heretic by Matthew Stewart
Page | 164
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
Vedanta. For example, Schopenhauer said about Bruno and Spinoza, “The
banks of the Ganges were their true spiritual home; there they would have
led a peaceful and honored life among men of like mind.”
Nondual Rationalism reconciles and integrates the two independent
unorthodox accounts of Spinozism, the Eastern and Western esoteric
readings, by recognizing and explicating the realization that Univocity is
nonduality, and thus the East and West meet in Spinoza/Deleuze. These two
unorthodox accounts, along with others such as the insights from Matthew
Stewart, together represent a much stronger front to the slights of orthodox,
exoteric, flatland, lowest-common-denominator (LCD) appropriations by
“traditional Representational forces.”
Opposed to the foundational One/Many monism (and tacit dualism),
where the Many are reconciled and unified by the distant (immanent or
transcendent) One, Deleuze recognizes instead the identity of “ONE is ALL”
as invoking the a priori infinite multiplicity of univocity. This can be stated
as the identical-opposite,i “Unity is Multiplicity,”ii meaning that there is no
separation or distance between Unity and Multiplicity or between ONE and
ALL. They are one and the same, an inverse identity, or an identical-
opposite, and this is operationalized directly in the I/T omni-axis, with its
absolute poles in the ONE of transcendence and the ALL of omni-local
immanence. As Metcalf notes, “Univocity is not opposed to multiplicity.
Univocity is not to be confused with the one opposed to the multiple. Rather,
Univocity IS multiplicity,”iii¥ just as the absolute scope is the relative scope,
in its other-engendering context. The appearance of separation itself is
merely one of epistemic scope; absolute vs. relative, and it is the principle of
Univocity which mediates as a triune interface between the polarity of
scopes.
With this identical-opposite we can easily recognize the “ONE is ALL” as a
function of the absolute scope, because, as we will see in much more detail,
the absolute scope can only be addressed by such inverse-identities or
tautologies.iv It cannot be adequately addressed (not mono-polized) by
conceptual mono-poles (i.e. concepts, or terms). This is because the absolute
scope enfolds and unfolds, or gives context to, ALL relativity, polarity,
boundary, difference and distinction. And hence, as in the nondual
i
…commonly confused for a “paradox” or “oxymoron”
ii
Note that both terms of the polarity are in the absolute scope. See the discussion in Polarity and
Univocity (p174) for details.
iii¥
Metcalf, Bergson and Univocity
iv
This brings us to Wittgenstein’s notion of a tautology as the only possible “atom” of logic (ruling
out axioms). As would be expected of the absolute scope, these logic atoms are devoid of factual
content and there can be no natural ordering of these tautologies, i.e. they cannot be related one to
another because they are at the absolute scope.
Page | 165
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
The ALL is The Infinite or 1st order infinite, see the forthcoming section, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite
(p270).
ii
* See, Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
iii
* See Spinoza’s Triune Infinite (p270) for a discussion on “aspect infinities”.
iv
This is another example of the principle of “absolute reversal” in which, any concept, taken at the
absolute scope, ends up at its identical opposite. See, Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute
Reversal (PAR), p117.
v
* … as we have already discussed in the section, Spinoza’s Univocity, p158.
vi
See, Univocity as Multiplicity, p163.
vii
* See Substance and Bundle Views of Substance (p99).
Page | 166
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* See Substance and Bundle Views of Substance (p99).
ii
…as opposed to the “cultivated third” of transcendent and/or a posteriori unification.
Page | 167
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
opposition and union with its transcendent aspect, God. The dependency of
Substance occurs not in the transitive direction, as in the dependent arising
and “real difference” of the modes, but in the polarity and logical relation
between Substance and its expression in and as modification. Because
Substance/God is the absolute scope, maintaining the logical Emptiness of
the form of modification in dependent arising, it can’t be conceived as
dependent in any relational or transitive way, but only as the ONE-ALL
tautology itself. This is precisely why Spinoza says it can’t be conceived as
passive. It is activity itself, in identical opposition to its forms in passivity
which it enfolds.
As opposed to the forces of representation, Univocity does not unify
distinction after the fact, but provides the real and relative ground of infinite
variability, and infinite difference itself, which allows for, and indeed
necessitates, the emergence of real difference, Spinoza’s version of
dependent arising. “When there is no numerical distinction of individuals,
there can finally be real distinction.”i¥ Note that Deleuze does not give a
causal/visual reason for this necessary difference in every mode, but herein
it is very simply understood with deep infinity, the Immanent/Transcendent
axis and the infinite holarchy of relative form and modification.
i¥
Metcalf, Deleuze Versus Hegel
Page | 168
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
As we have seen (and as we will see in more detail in the next section,
Univocity and Polarity), Deleuze/Spinoza’s Univocity is essentially an
operationalization of the Taoist identity of opposites, polarity or nonduality
and Nagarjuna’s polarity of Emptiness and Form. This means that all
dualistic notions, such as Hegel’s dialectic, are Ultimately inadequate, i.e.
meaningless at the absolute scope. This is why his criticism of Spinoza’s
Substance (which we are taking as the absolute scope) for neglecting the
negative or oppositional element of the dialectic, entirely missed its mark.
And indeed, Spinoza’s absolute is only positive in the sense that it is no
longer negative, disastrously regressive, oppositional and relative. It is the
positive infinite in that it affirmatively “exists” a priori, or more properly, it is
existence itself, along with all other relative terms and oppositions enfolded
as ALL is ONE.i
In What is Univocity?, Metcalf says, “…with Univocity, representation is
temporary surface effect. Univocity always keeps the representational plane
of transcendence open to the sub-representative plane of immanence.” And
as Deleuze points out in Difference and Repetition,ii¥ “Forms of the negative
do indeed appear in actual terms and real relations, but only in so far as
these are cut off from the virtuality [immanence] which they actualize, and
from the movement of their actualization.” In other words, forces of
opposition and negation are “temporary surface effects,” and occur only in
transitive representational ignorance of the immanent forces (the inter-
expressive cultivating thirds) that allow for the emergence of real and
i
And we will find, as we have already briefly seen, that the rational numbers, with their “violation of
the closure property” of the integers and natural numbers, also operate no longer on the
positive/negative opposition of the integers, but on the “intensive forces” of the infinite space
between “immanent-zero” and one, the sub-representational realm beneath the numerical
identities of the Natural numbers and the transitive integers.
ii¥
p207, qtd in Metcalf.
Page | 169
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
relative polarity and difference in the first place. And as we will see in much
more detail in SpinbitZ: Volume II,i* even forces of immanence in physics are
always transcendent or emergent when conceived or perceived at any
particular scale, level or “plane,” i.e. at the relative scope.
Deleuze describes forces of Univocity as intensive, as relative and inter-
expressive degrees of sub-representational power emergent from the
infinite difference which monads can enfold as a singularity.ii And, as
Metcalf says in her article Force Relations, “There is no opposition to other
degrees since they are all singular. Each is positive, singular intensity.”
Clearly, however, there is relation and polarity at this level of univocal
forces, but this is exactly the point. The forces of Univocity are the
modifications and relations on the relative plane of immanence, the
cultivating third which allows opposition to emerge and which allows its
poles to really inter-relate and inter-oppose.
Metcalf continues, “All intensive forces fit together without opposition or
lack, because they are singular degrees of real distinction, ontologically one.”
This brings us to a fascinating correlation with a cutting edge model of
fundamental physics, called Sorce Theory,iii which we will explore in much
greater depth in the SpinbitZ: Volume II.iv Similar to Deleuze’s forces of
Univocity, Sorce Theory’s “singular” force (sorce) of pressure, emerges into
opposition (negativity) only through positive differences in relation, i.e.
polarity. This polarity is the distinguishing feature of the forces of electro-
magnetism, and we will examine in SpinbitZ: Volume II how the polar and
indeed univocal forces of electro-magnetism are immanent, or fundamental
to those seemingly monistic forces such as the extremely weak force of
gravity.v
“However,” Metcalf continues, “Univocity includes both a plane of
transcendence and a plane of immanence. Now, the plane of transcendence
is not cut off from its source. With Univocity, representation is actualized in
really distinct worlds that remain open to all the singular forces of intensity.”
Perhaps contrary to Deleuze, it is not quite so simple a matter as to merely
switch dualistically between intensive and oppositional forces when moving
between these two levels. And, as we should by now expect, this is yet
another polarity, because the intensive and oppositional (which are also the
continuous-inhomogeneous, and discrete) are symbiogenetic and
i
* see Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement .
ii
Just as the unit-identity in Interface Mathematics enfolds the infinity of the immanent pole within
it (which the ratio breaks open again in its “violation” of “unit-closure”) as it is first selected from the
immanent-transcendent axis as the defining scale in the operational interface between mathematics
and reality.
iii
Sorce Theory is a purely causal unified field theory. See www.anpheon.org .
iv
Which currently exists in the unpublished paper titled, Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement
v 40
electro-magnetism is around 10 times stronger than gravity
Page | 170
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* …or cognitive nucleation, see Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”,
p486.
ii
at least where it interfaced with Hegel’s failed attempt to find the “plane of consistency” in
Spinoza’s thought.
iii
if problematically, as we will see below.
iv¥
Wikipedia: essentialism
Page | 171
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i¥
Beth Metcalf, The Immanence of Univocity
ii¥
Deleuze, A Thousand Plateaus p.254, qtd in Metcalf, The Immanence of Univocity
iii
* See Univocity as Deep Infinity: Prigogine and Leibniz (p182) below.
iv
* See Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486
v¥
Deleuze, Spinoza Practical Philosophy
vi¥
Ethics, Part III VII. “The endeavour, wherewith everything endeavours to persist in its own being,
is nothing else but the actual essence of the thing in question.”
Page | 172
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* See Spinoza’s Univocity, p158.
ii¥
Will Durant, The Story of Philosophy
Page | 173
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i ¥
Also called the “Short Treatise on God, Man, and His Well-Being,” see:
http://www.yesselman.com/ShortTreatise.htm)Spinoza
ii
Or the sub-representational vs. the representational, respectively.
Page | 174
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
Note that we can have no absolute truths of the sub-representational, or any level, nor are our
concepts themselves, including the concept of sub-representation (ontic), subrepresentational.
They merely point to sub-representation to break out of the forces of closed Representation which I
show possess a transcendent bias which in turn forces a foundationalist reading of Spinoza as an
essentialist and this in turn forces an idealist, or epistemic-absolutist counter-reaction, the
beginnings of which we see in the Leibniz/Kant/Hegel hermeneutic trajectory. It is this historical
trajectory, appropriated into orthodoxy as a representational reaction to the incomplete project of
rational-empiricism (or modernity) itself, that Deleuze rejects as a distortion of Spinoza's Univocity.
ii¥
Deleuze, Logic of Sense, p177. Quoted in Metcalf.
Page | 175
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
* See, Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity (p176), below.
ii
* See the previous section, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156.
Page | 176
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
within, but between the transitive/relative and the infinite immanence and
transcendence of the immanent-transcendent omni-axis itself. It is the
polarity between polarity-transitivity-relativity and the ineffable tautology
of the ONE-ALL.
Page | 177
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
polarity, respectively, and they are both purely (and infinitely) relational.i
Before univocity can “reach” the unreachable absolute in the immanent
direction, then, it must first orient in the relative vertical polarity of the
ontic/epistemic.ii
Through the identity of opposites in the ontic and epistemic we can see also
that ontology is epistemic and epistemology is ontic. In other words,
speculation about the nature of reality is necessarily representational, and
representation is necessarily real. Or even simpler, the map of the territory
is a feature of the territory itself.
The commonplace representational conflation between the map and the
territory is perhaps a main cause of our tendency to think that ontology (the
study of reality) is the study of the absolute scope, and to cast out relative
truths about relative reality when we merely want to proactively eliminate
its absolute truth claims (absolutist ontology). See Figure 9, below.
i
…or taken to its limitless limit, the absolute/relative polarity.
ii
The dialectic must demand that even the dialectic has its opposition, otherwise it is an
absolutization of the relative operation of the dialectic itself. The trick is to shift from the relative
scope, with its infinite holonic and operational transcension and immanence, to the absolute scope
with its “ALL is ONE,” nondual unity, enfolding and unfolding all polarity and relativity.
Page | 178
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
A violation of this framework, recall, results in a reductionism, absolutism or foundationalism.
ii¥
Science of Logic § 565
iii
* See Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
Page | 179
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
…recall that the absolute scope enfolds and unfolds all polarities
ii¥
http://users.rcn.com/bmetcalf.ma.ultranet/index.htm
Page | 180
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
mapping to difference and unity, respectively, but also vice versa, at the
absolute scope (given the PAR).
This “infinite representation,” as Deleuze calls Hegel’s use of the dialectic,
is part of Hegel’s “absolute idealism.” The problem, as Deleuze sees it, is not
idealism, per se, but that Hegel has absolutized and closed off the level of
Representation and self-consciousness, and further that he has done so in a
negative way as pure opposition. Deleuze sees Representation and the
forces of opposition always as transcendental, meaning that it is essentially
emergent from deeper levels of reality. In other words, it is always
dependent and relative, not absolute and independent. The opposition of
the absolute scope can only reflect back to the relative scope. But there is
opposition of Substance, as the immanent aspect of the absolute scope, in the
transcendent aspect of God, in the identity and tautology of the ONE-ALL.
i
Perhaps only insofar as his mis-mapped and mis-targeted criticism of Spinoza is concerned.
Page | 181
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Page | 182
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
Univocity can be understood much more clearly in its relation to deep (or
positive) infinity. This is illuminated from the other direction by Leibniz—
from the point of view of identity or similarity rather than difference—in his
principle of the “identity of indiscernables.” This is the idea that two things
with absolutely the same properties are in actuality necessarily the same
thing. The idea is that, at the very least, a mere difference of position in
space of two otherwise identical entities (were this identicality otherwise
possible) will manifest differences in expression, because every position in
“space” is necessarily different from every other. According to Leibniz (and
contra Descartes and Newton) the concept of space or extension, as an
abstract, isometric (and perhaps platonic) Emptiness—principle of the
same—imparting no real, active/causal or physical difference on objects or
expressions located differently within it, is a superficial and misleading
generalization, if taken absolutely. Space itself, according to this view, is
composed of, or has the property of, infinite depth of real difference, infinite
activity (anima) and infinite modification, very similar, in this sense, to the
active properties of the modern “quantum vacuum,” with it’s “zero point
energy.” And therefore any particular region of space will impart its own
unique properties, stemming from this infinite depth of active detail, upon
objects located within it.
And even before Leibniz, Spinoza conceived of extension as an attribute
of infinitely active Substance, i.e. the essence of Substance conceived and/or
perceived from the outside.i In Deleuze’s view of Spinoza, and similar to my
i
* See Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
Page | 183
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
As Deleuze called it.
ii
And as will be discussed in greater detail in the section Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of
Opposites, p659.
iii
…although a modal substrate is perhaps not quite what Deleuze meant with his “plane of
immanence.”
iv
* Recall the transcendent-bias and the pre-rational, negative/regressive infinity discussed in the
section, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias, p91.
v
…though Leibniz consciously dissolves the absolute distinction between space and matter.
vi
Space and matter, then, as should be expected, present no real dichotomy in Nondual Rationalism,
but merely a polarity based on solidity or tangibility of existence at the interface with our senses.
This is why open air, which we now know is full of “stuff” is generally considered a space. The
concept of “outer-space” is a new one to make a more refined distinction between a new kind of
space that is too intangible to be detected directly, such as with wind, by our senses.
vii
Recall our Principle of Nondual Rationalism, infinite division equals indivisibility, and how this
would naturally seem to lead to a “unified” view of reality.
Page | 184
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* See Transcendental Determinism and the Captive Will (p643), for a discussion of Transcendental
Determinism and the problem of the freedom of the will, which it causes..
ii
Recall our principle of absolute reversal…lasrever etulosba fo elpicnirp ruo llaceR
Page | 185
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
reduce all phenomena to a finite set of intelligible causes, and all things
must appear to us to be at some level radically free. (In this sense,
incidentally, he should count as a radical empiricist.)
This fundamental inability of Representation to reach or encapsulate the
deep infinity of Nature, i.e. to bound the unbounded, is a simple function of
the polarity of the finite and infinite, or the relative and absolute scopes,
respectively, as we have discussed. Any process that has a beginning or an
end, is necessarily relative, and therefore finite or bounded, even if
indefinite, with bounds yet-te-be-determined.i* The simple point is that just
as the finite cannot overtake the infinite (you can’t count to infinity),ii so the
relative scope cannot encompass or equal the absolute scope in its
immanent or transcendent aspects (this is an explicit function of the
univocity-framework and the different properties of horizontal vs. vertical
polarities at the absolute vs. relative scopes, as we will see).
In this way, unbounded or “infinite determinism”—determinism at the
absolute scope of deep infinity—is identical to indeterminism, in that it
necessitates the inability to absolutely know the (infinitely detailed) causes
of any event/object. As such, it is logically, rationally and empirically
impossible to predict or determine absolutely, the outcome of any process
and to put the ultimate causes into a finite set of intelligible laws, such as
those of thermodynamics. In this sense, Spinoza, in the 17th century, had
already solved the “arrow of time” problem, implicitly, in his radical
(absolute scope) “determinism.” It just took exoteric science 300 years to
catch up. Indeed, Spinoza’s modes, as seen through the attribute of
Extension, are already composed of Prigogine’s 300 year-old active matter,
and they already existed in Leibniz’s decades-old active space, i.e. Extension
itself.
The identity of opposites (with its implicit Principle of Absolute
Reversal), and the Univocity Framework, necessitate that, at the absolute
scope, infinite determinism and indeterminism are merely two ways of
stating the same thing. This is because, as we have seen, at the absolute
scope of the modifier ‘infinite,’ all polarities are enfolded as one. In other
words, the concept of determinism itself (as all concepts) is relative and it
has no ultimate (absolute scope) meaning apart from its (identical) opposite.
Therefore, we come to another resonating chord from our Principle of
Nondual Rationalism, which itself reverberates from the ancient principles
of nondualism, such as the identity of opposites. As will be explicated
further through the Univocity Framework, this univocal essence of deep-
i
* … i.e. a third order infinity (see Order 3: The Modal (or Bounded) Infinite:, p279).
ii
Note that even children are operationally aware, at some level, of the absolute scope, when they
jump out of the modal and relative games of magnitude invoking the modifier of, “I’m infinity!”.
Page | 186
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
Explanation: Given the identity of opposites and the Principle of Absolute Reversal,
determinism, when taken to its absolute scope, rebounds or reflects of f the ineffable
absolute into its identical-opposite. An infinitely deep determinism necessitates the
inability to absolutely and completely determine, from any level or region of levels, the
outcome of any event/object; Emptiness precludes the self-identity of the forms of
time.
i
…which we could denote with the simple hyphenated variant, in-determinism…
Page | 187
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
It may indeed be the case, given the transcendent bias, that the
nomothetic explanation exclusively is imposed on the immanent world of
the quantum because we expect things to get ultimately and categorically
simple in our post-medieval and foundationalist scientific mind-set. Without
recognizing the infinite difference of immanence (Leibnizian/Prigoginian
active-space/matter), we can’t see deviations from these categories and laws
for what they are; emergent properties from immanent complexity. And so
we assume that conceptual randomness, opposing our simplified categories,
rules in this domain, rather than recognizing the limits of the nomothetic
explanation and the need for the idiographic.
This is a classic example of the transcendent-bias in action. Given the
Principle of Infinite Determinism, above, the resolution to the conundrum is
simple. Embrace the immanence of univocity and there is no need to discard
the idea of causation or determinism when our categories and laws give way
to the idiosyncrasies of the individual object-event. The call for randomness,
in every case, can be seen as the conflict and break-down of the nomothetic
categories in the entropic face of infinite difference and idiosyncrasy.
Randomness, then, calls for the idiographic methodology, in a univocal
polarity of explanatory function between the nomothetic use of the principle
of the same and the idiographic use of the principle of infinite difference.
Indeed, the laws were formed as general cases from a symptomatology in
the first place. In our foundationalist mind-set we simply expected them to
govern absolutized categories, with absolutized laws, rather than real idio-
singularities of infinite difference in interactions of infinite detail.
The Univocity Framework, therefore, opens the way beyond the closed
oppositional forces of the categories of Representation, to a recognition of
the need for an evolutionary history—a symptomatology—for each
individual “particle,” in order to get a full account of the infinite determinism
equals indeterminism of any single event-object, and indeed to account for
the “arrow of time,” in the eternal NOW. No two events are alike or
ultimately predictable, not because there are no determining factors
involved (i.e. randomness), but because there are infinitely many.i And again
we can see here the polarity of the omni-non between the categorical forces
of Representation and the acategorical imperative in the Univocity
Framework.
i
…this is another instance of the omni-non...
Page | 188
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
the quantitative aspecti* of the ALL in the ONE. This omni-axis, when
applied to the absolute scope of the aspect of duration or time, translates
into the identity of opposites commonly called “the eternal NOW,” or simply
Eternity = NOW. This is also implicit in Spinoza’s sub specie aeternitatis, and
Spinoza’s concept of immortality in the participation of eternity in the
instant.
Deleuze explains this through a Stoic lens; “Univocity is the pure empty
form of time (Aion). Sense is on the plane of Aion,ii* that pure instant which
divides every present into both future and past directions at once.”iii¥
Eternity is the infinite transcendent pole (or directionality), of the absolute-
scope of the temporal axis. And the “infinitely small” or sizeless irreducible
instant, the NOW, is the absolute-scope of its immanent pole. Neither
absolute pole—the eternal or the NOW—is reachable through any transitive,
linear or finite (relative) means, such as multiplication or division into ever
larger or smaller intervals of time, represented to the mind as either
memory or anticipation. In principle, any interval, in space, time, or
whatever, can be divided or multiplied further. This means ultimately that
the linearity of time, i.e. the existence of a ‘‘time-line” consisting of moments,
one after another, from the past to the future, is a purely relative and
sometimes representational function. Neither the past, the future or the
‘‘time-line” itself, exist at the absolute (and sub-representational) scope. In
the immanence of the eternal-NOW, there is no absolutely and
transcendently predetermined future waiting for a “near eternity” to become
the past. There is no inescapable predetermined chain of events or tireless
iron grip of the dead hand of fate. At the absolute scope there is only the
single irreducible and unreachable, yet ever-present and inescapable, NOW
of existence, “nowing”iv in infinite difference and irreducible multiplicity for
all eternity.v See, below.
As Bucky Fuller says in his Synergetics:
The norm of Einstein is absolute speed instead of at rest. “At rest” was
what we called instantaneous in our innocence of yesterday. We evolute
toward ever lesser brain comprehension lags—ergo, toward ever
diminishing error; ergo, ever diminishing misunderstandings; ergo, ever
diminishing fear, and its brain-lagging painful errors of objectivity;
wherefore we approach eternal instantaneity of absolute and total
comprehension. The eternal instantaneity of no lag at all (529.31).
i
* See the section on the Triune Infinite and specifically the “Aspect Infinities.”
ii
* The “mnemonic interface” discussed in Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of
Observability”, p486).
iii¥
Logic of Sense, qtd in Metcalf
iv
And “wowing,” as Bucky Fuller would say.
v
We can see here implicitly enfolded the opposite-identity of the noun-verb polarity which is a
version of the deeper stasis-flux polarity.
Page | 189
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
Page | 190
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* See the Order 2: The Aspect Infinite, p273.
Page | 191
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
Thus Univocity actually enforces or enacts (operationalizes) the message of nonduality, and this is
why it is the most effective core of any “Integral Operating System.”
Page | 192
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
A. B. C.
i
It is interesting to note the similarity of this diagram to an earlier dream of mine. In this dream, a
dark bony woman was constructing and speaking a sign language with triangles and a pendulum
form in the middle out of her many long bony fingers.
Page | 193
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
orient the relative and absolute scopes and to denote the vertical direction
in the framework. In the relative scope, the I/T axis is aligned with the
univocity axis, but again, both immanent and transcendent directions point
(in their infinite aspects) to the absolute scope. This is because they deal
with the omni/non polarity of the aspect of locality, rather than the
transitive left-right types of polarities.
This aspect of the immanent-transcendent axis, where each pole points
to the absolute scope, is contrary to the diagram which necessarily has to
show one pole closer to the absolute scope than the other. In this case, it
shows the immanent direction as pointing toward, or emerging from, the
absolute scope. This is because we are counteracting the transcendent-bias
and focusing on the ontic as the emergent triune-interface between the
relative and absolute scopes. The point is that the epistemic is an emergent
subset of the real-world of form, the ontic, but it is also true that the ontic is
both immanent and transcendent to the interface of representation, or the
epistemic. So in this sense, the epistemic can be seen as the triune interface
between the immanent and transcendent aspects of the ontic.i*
Circles in the above univocity diagram denote modifications, or modes,
while lines denote emergence or directionalities of thought. Solid lines (and
solid circles) denote real, or ontic, directions (emergence or an actual
identity) while dotted lines denote representational lines. The principle of
Absolute Reversal (and the identity of absolutized opposites) is denoted by
the triangular line that reflects off the boundary of the absolute scope, since
relativities make no sense and have no function in the absolute scope.
The two examples (A, C) illustrate the two main kinds of polarity,
absolute and relative, respectively. The absolute polarity, seen in the
absolute scope level of example A, illustrates the seemingly “paradoxical”
nature of absolute scope polarities, such as “infinite division equals
indivisibility,” and that the two poles (and the polarity itself) are illusory, or
representational and relative aspects (dotted circles) of the same
absolutized concept, e.g. divisibility. In example C, we have the relative
scope polarity (a real polarity, as opposed to an identity or tautology) of the
symbiogenesis of subject and object where the real duality is reconciled (and
symbiogenetically emergent) by the cultivating third of the sub-
representational (and immanent) “mnemonic primitives” at the “interface”
between subject and object.ii*
These two examples are both horizontal polarities in the Univocity
Framework, but we can also see the vertical polarity, or the holarchy of the
ontic and epistemic (or the sub-representational and representational,
respectively). As discussed, if a vertical polarity has one pole within the
i
* see Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
ii
* See Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
Page | 194
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
* See the section, Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind, p112.
ii
* see the sub-section above, “Vertical” Polarity: The Polarity of Polarity, p175.
Page | 195
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
arising,i e.g. the symbiogenesis of subject and object, the dependent arising
of mind and matter, or Fuller’s “unity is plural and at minimum two,” which
says that any mode (finite unity) necessitates, at least, an inside and an
outside.
i
Note that with univocity the relative and the absolute are fundamentally interdependent, or inter-
expressive. This means that Einstein’s absolutization of the relative scope in his relativity theories
violates the Univocity Framework, which actually explains why it is fundamentally incomprehensible
and irrational, as we will see.
ii
This, already, is an obvious violation of the principle of dependent arising.
Page | 196
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
i
Indra's Net: “Hinduism and Buddhism give life to the idea of Indra's Net. In the heaven of Indra, a
vast net or web of silken strands spans across space infinitely in every direction. Every intersection
of gossamer thread hosts a shining luminous pearl or multifaceted jewel. The surface of every jewel
completely reflects every other, and the net as a whole. Likewise, each reflected jewel in itself
reflects every other, that reflects every other, that reflects every other, without end, as mirrors to
infinity. Indra's Net may alternately be known as ‘Indra's Pearls,’ or the ‘Jewel Net of Indra.’” (from
answers.com)
Page | 197
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 198
THE UNIVOCITY FRAMEW ORK
way of seeing/saying the same identical “thing,” because this “thing” (the
absolute level) enfolds and unfolds all things, concepts, their opposites and
polarities and cannot be encapsulated by any of them.
The polarity of the ancient “All is One” is, and always was, horizontal and
absolute; an identity and ultimately a tautology, however useful it is as such.
With his monad as the boundary between “macrocosm and microcosm” (the
solidus in I/T and in the vision-logic equation ∞/∞), Leibniz has tacitly
shifted (equivocated) from the absolute scope of unbounded or Infinite
Unity,i to the relative scope of the monad, the mode or finite unity.ii It is
only, and exactly, half true that the monad contains within itself the All of
Infinite Difference. The other half of the All that the monadic interface
exactly bisects is the infinite without, or the transcendent pole of the
immanent/transcendent uni-axis which the monadic interface conceptually
spans.iii
The original “ALL is ONE” is, therefore, already and necessarily an
absolute identity (in mathematical terms, an “equality”) and thus “ONE is
ALL” is already the same statement as “ALL is ONE.” In other words, if ALL =
ONE then it follows necessarily, and indeed trivially, that ONE = ALL, just as
it follows from 2+2=4 that 4=2+2. But it doesn’t follow, necessarily (or at
all), that “one = ALL.” An identity necessarily goes both ways and none,
because, ultimately, they are the same “thing.” The line in the equation and
its arbitrary direction are an artifact of the linearity of symbolic thought, not
of the identity itself.
But given that Leibniz is talking about his monad, and hence the relative
scope of the “one,” not the “ONE,” this trivial identity and reversed tautology
of ALL=ONE is clearly not the sense in which he means “All is One” in his
principle of macrocosm and microcosm. The con-fusion is cleverly hidden in
the conflation of the undifferentiated, pre-fused and undisclosed scope
parameters of the term “ONE,” which provides for the undetected point of
ambiguity upon which this equivocation turns to the “one”. In Leibniz’s tacit
shift from absolute to relative scope in his principle of macrocosm and
microcosm—from the ONE to the one—the finite unity of the monad, the
“one” is taken as the illogical, or otherwise tautological, numerical (absolute)
distinction between the “one” and the “ALL,” forcing the independent
(tautological) attribute of the absolute on the monad rendering it necessarily
“windowless,” and merely self-identical. We will see, however, that indeed,
i
And the scope of the 1st order Absolute Infinity. See the section on The Triune Infinite: Interfacing
Emptiness (p268), and also the section on Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
ii
… the level of the 3rd order infinite, or bounded infinite
iii
Leibniz’s corollary in the “principle of macrocosm and microcosm” is true, however, in the sense
that the interface could not exist without the infinity within and the infinity without, the I/T axis of
the ONE is ALL. The within/without and the triuning/tuning-in interface (the I/T and its solidus
divider) are also polar opposites.
Page | 199
PART I: THE BASIC FRAMEWORK OF INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY
in the sense that the monadic interface (and real difference) is composed of
an infinite depth of detail, it does indeed rest in the absolute of the ONE, and
refract into the ONE-ALL through the Cycle of Unity (p257).
Leibniz equivocates either unknowingly and/or simply to justify the
principle of the macrocosm and microcosm with a twist on an ancient
truism. And all of this complex verbal wizardry—with its smoke-and-
mirrors sleight-of-hand scope-equivocation and con-fusion—in turn is to
justify the absolutized immanent mono-pole of the monad, eternal and
independent (absolute scope), yet whose beginning in time is dependent
(relative scope) on the choice of a providential transcendent God who could
not really have chosen other than this “best of all possible worlds.” And
thus, to conserve this univocity violation, God must create each eternal and
independent monad in a flash of transcendent-bias and a puff of scope con-
fusion, each with a magic mirror that can see Indra’s Net without causing a
change or a perception in the unobserving observer.
Page | 200
Page | 201
Page | 202
Despite the wild success of mathematics in its pragmatic roles in science and
technology, mankind has long been plagued with paradox and confusion
when it comes to infinity and number and the relation of mathematics to
physical and mental reality. Typical discussions about these mathematical
issues, in both specialist and vernacular tongues, hide a tangled mess of
oxymorons, equivocations and deeply rooted ideological conflicts. These
confusions (and indeed con-fusionsii*) hide behind seemingly innocuous
common phrases such as “infinitely small,” or “infinitely many,” as well as
more formal and rigorous philosophical/mathematical problems such as the
paradoxes of the infinite; the philosophical and commonsense problems
with the limit and the infinitesimal of the calculus; and the controversy and
confusion surrounding Cantor’s notion of the transfinite in modern set
theory.
The bulk of these problems, it will be shown, arise ultimately from
misunderstandings and con-fusions about the fundamentally polar, nondual
and univocal relationship between infinity and number (the finite)—which,
as we have seen and will see in much greater detail below, are the
quantitative aspects of the absolute and relative scopes, respectively.iii* This
con-fusion in turn arises from errors in the common meta-mathematical and
philosophical paradigm, an aborted, distorted and pre-mature rationalism,
i¥
From “To Believe and to Think”, qtd. in Escher on Escher p.150)
ii
* A con-fusion is a conflation of a prefused distinction. See Con-Fusions at the Interface, p122.
iii
* see Phase TWO: Polarity and the Opposable Thumb of the Mind, p112.
Page | 203
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 204
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
The problems with mathematical thinking, however, extend far beyond the
percept-impoverished common meta-mathematics and lead directly to
metaphysical or epistemological errors with the relation of number (an
epistemic or representational holon or “meme”) to reality (the ontic-level of
a sub-representational or real distinction, or unity, such as an atom or
apple). Since the whole of the philosophies and sciences is a transcend-and-
include holarchy, these deeper metaphysical and epistemological problems
(which extend beyond mathematics) have contributed to the unfortunate
abandonment of causation in modern physics and its 21st century trajectory
into highly abstract (blind-logic) and convoluted mathematics, such as the
“higher-dimensionality” (what I call black-box metaphysics) found in String
Theory, which lacks any causal and experiential method for understanding
its arcane and highly inelegant mathematics. We will explore this in great
depth in SpinbitZ: Volume II.
Modern meta-mathematics and hence mathematical physics are “non-
modelable” and in effect, pre-rational. They do not function in harmony with
the perceptual foundations of the human mind, and hence cannot be
modeled effectively in the imagination—and, as a subset of self-similar
reality, the mind should naturally be able to echo itself into a reflexive
understanding of its own unified or nondual substrate as dependently
arising in both external (objective) and internal (subjective) reality. The
limits and functions of standard mathematics are abstracted, simplified and
generalized far away from those of causation and physical reality, so if
mathematics is to replace causation in our models, then special care must be
taken to define and account for those differences, enabling us to retain a
i
minus its shadow element of academic misinterpretations and aborted rationality and the
performative contradictions forced therefrom.
ii
… such as Steven Rado’s Aethro-Kinematics and, most importantly, Gerald Lebau’s Sorce Theory
Page | 205
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
And in this designation, we are making no fundamental distinction between logic and mathematics.
Mathematics may be a form of logic or logic a form of mathematics, it is not clear, and perhaps, at
this level, meaningless.
Page | 206
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
Page | 207
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 208
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
a whole made of parts, and parts that make a whole; a whole-part or a part-
whole, or simply a holon.i A good example would be a collection of marbles,
taken at a higher level in a sack. At a still higher level we can take another
collection of many sacks of marbles in a still larger sack. And any sack of
sacks of marbles will still be part of a larger environment, such as the child’s
bedroom where the game of marbles is played. There is no set that is not a
subset of a larger set; no whole that is not a part of a larger whole. And in
the set-holarchy, it is naturally unthinkable that one of our marbles can be
equal in size to the whole sack of marbles which contains it, or that a sack at
the first level has the same number of marbles as a sack of sacks of marbles
at the second level surrounding it, or that a single marble is equivalent in
size to a room in which a game is played with them.
We naturally, implicitly and “unthinkingly” are programmed by evolution
to keep track of the immanent or transcendent (emergent) levels in the
holarchy of bounded-collections as we break them down into parts or build
them up into wholes. This natural, intuitive or implicit logic—founded upon
the human perception of sets as bounded collectionsii—is encoded, if
abstractly and incompletely, in the “part-whole axiom” of classical
mathematics which states simply that “every set is greater than its proper
subset.” Everything we experience in the relative world of form is bounded,
in some sense, and made of deeper collections. These “implicit sets” are, in
essence, boundaries around deeper collections, themselves boundaries
around still-deeper collections—potentially, logically, and very possibly, ad
infinitum. It is only when the self-identity of abstract categories comes into
play that these natural faculties have no ground or traction in difference and
begin to slip, leading to paradox.
In the implicit holonic logic of sets, for example, it makes little sense to
have a collection of nothings, or an “empty collection.” The more sensible
way to phrase it would be that we have no collection at all; a non-collection.
This brings us to a question, indeed an equivocation—a juicy semantic
ambiguity buried under a mountain of dry concepts and categories, hidden
at the very core of the controversies of modern (axiomatic) set theory. Is a
set a collection or a container? If it is a collection, or a “collection of
objects,”iii as it is commonly claimed, then the “empty set” (as I will show in
i
Note 1: The use of ‘holon’ in a theory of sets, is necessarily more abstract and general than a holon
in the typical use, such as that by Ken Wilber. Abstracted out of the typical equation is the necessity
of the notion of emergence, since we are dealing with holarchies of mere “classes” or abstract
categories. When using implicit holonic set theory to refer to real-world holarchies, emergence
must again be factored in. Note 2: We could also call this holon the “anatom” in that it is the
antithesis of the atom. The anatomic corpuscle in not indivisible, but infinitely divisible. It has an
anatomy.
ii
…and this, in turn is part of a holarchy, as we have seen in the section, Vision-logic Interfaces:
Vision-logic and Blind-logic, p124…
iii
From Wikipedia: Axiomatic set theory: The basic concepts of set theory are set and membership. A
set is thought of as any collection of objects, called the members (or elements) of the set.
Page | 209
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
What is the cost of this transition from the implicit, specific and empirically-
derived holonic notion of sets to the explicit general notion of sets as classes
with relations of membership? What is lost in the divorce of concept from
percept in the modern purely categorical notion of sets? As we have seen,
this abstraction of classes—now freed from the perceptual clues and
restrictions of implicit holonic set theory—allows a tacit equivocation of sets
as collections and as boundaries or containers, while blurring the
distinctions and relations of both. In effect, the axiomatic and categorical
modern notion of a set has been stripped of its immanent/transcendent
holarchical information and rendered purely in terms of a transitive-plane of
self-identity. All sets as categories are now conceived in freedom from
natural holarchy, causing a naïve disruption of the connections of percept
i¥
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Set Theory; < http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/set-theory/ >
Page | 210
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
taken for granted and forgotten in the movement into concept. These lost
connections in naïve set theory are the bonds symbolically or axiomatically
replaced in the newer axiomatic versions of set theory, and, as we will see, in
the study of mereology, literally the logic or study of parts.
In the naïve, abstracted freedom of the categorical set, breaking from the
holarchical, immanent/transcendent percept-aspect of sets as containers,
allows for the “infinite set,” such as the universal set—or the boundless
category of ALL categories (note the absolute scope). Unlike any holonic or
real-world set, the universal set appears to be a member of itself, i.e. it’s own
subset. The universal category of all categories, is itself a category, and so, it
would seem—according to these abstract rules of class and membership—it
is a sub-category of itself. (This, we can quickly see, leads to an infinite
regress of self-recursion, akin to the “grandfather paradox” in similarly
abstract musings on time-travel.)
Likewise, equivocating in abstraction in the other direction, away from
the explicit definition of a set as a “collection of objects,” or subsets, allows
the implicit holonic aspect of a set as a whole, a boundary or a container, to
re-emerge. This equivocation, in turn, allows the undisclosed set-as-
container to contain a collection of nothing, providing us with the useful, but
problematic, empty-set. Without this implicit equivocation from sets as
collections to sets as containers the empty-set would be meaningless—a
non-set—just as in the other direction we get the non-container of the
infinite set (boundless boundary). Yet at the same time, this equivocation to
sets-as-containers explicitly denies Cantor’s special use of the unbounded or
infinite set in his transfinite orders due to the absurdities of the “infinite
container.”
An empty collection is simply not a collection at all. It is a non-collection;
a non-set. Even in terms of the common definition of a set as a “collection of
objects,” the empty set is explicitly not a set. There is no “collection of
objects” in the empty set. And in the more abstract notion of sets as defined
by the “fundamental relation” of sets and membership—“a set is determined
by its elements”—there are no elements in an empty set, and there can be no
relation between a set and its non-existing elements. It clearly takes a tacit
equivocation in the definition of a set (as a collection, not a container) to
reach the empty container of the empty-set—the non-relation between a
class and its missing members—and this is easily achieved in axiomatic set
theory when concept (and reason) is freed from the causal/empirical
restraints of percept, our interface with reality, implicit in the holonic logic
of sets.
This equivocation can be seen clearly in attempts to make sense of the
empty-set. The article in Wikipedia on the “empty set” states (my
emphasis): “The empty set is not the same thing as nothing; it is a set with
nothing inside it, and a set is something. This often causes difficulty among
those who first encounter it. It may be helpful to think of a set as a bag
Page | 211
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
containing its elements; an empty bag may be empty, but the bag itself
certainly exists.”i¥ Recall the definition of a set as “a collection of objects.”
We now have a new definition of a set as a “bag” or container for, not of
objects, or even just an empty container. Both of these aspects of sets were
abstracted from the implicit holonic logic of sets, but when taken separately,
and indeed equivocated between, they allow sets that have lost their
immanent/transcendent aspects and “violate” the Univocity Framework,
reaching into the absolute scope. This, in turn, causes the well-known
problems with both the universal and the empty set.
The universal and the empty set each form two identical-opposite non-
holonic, and absolute-scope aspects of modern set theory. The universal set
is the aspect of absolute unbounded affirmation—allowing the “collection of
objects” to be conceived, non-holonically, as its own sub-collection. And the
empty-set is the non-holonic aspect of absolute unbounded negation,
allowing the tacit definition of sets as containers to be filled with the non-
collection of emptiness. The empty set, unlike the universal set, explicitly
cannot be a member of itself, because then it would no longer be empty. It
would be filled with an empty, abstract, infinite recursion of its self-negating
self, similar to the universal set.ii
Neither the universal set nor the null set, are “proper” sets, in the implicit
holonic logic of sets because they break from the implicit logic of sets as
bounded-collections, or part-wholes; they break from the relative world of
form into the absolute realm of the formless. They possess the absolute and
unbounded aspects of affirmation and negation, respectively. A set, in this
empirical/sensorial holonic logic, is necessarily a relativity; a part-whole,
collection-container, set/member relation. A holonic set is a relation with
other holonic sets, but critically within in an infinite, unbounded holarchy: a
critical univocal polarity of polarity, between the absolute and relative scope
of the infinite and finite; the boundless and bounded; the holarchy and the
holon. A set is the relative, bounded aspect of the univocal polarity. The
universal set breaks from the container aspect of the holonic set, which in
turn is needed to sustain the notion of the empty-set in its tacit breaking
from the explicit definition of the set as a collection. They each break in the
opposite direction from relative-scope, holonic percept-concept of the
bounded-collection—the whole made of parts, of the implicit holonic set
theory—to the absolute scope of the formless and unbounded.
So, what happens when we mix the two non-holonic, absolutized aspects
of the universal and null sets? Suppose that we can form a set of ALL sets, a
universal set of sets that, like the empty set, are not included in themselves.
i¥
Wikipedia: Empty-Set; <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Empty_set>
ii
The empty set is the set-theory equivalent of the “omni-non” which we will explore a bit later.
Page | 212
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
The paradoxes of logic and mathematics arise only when we “violate” the
Univocity Framework—breaking from the relative scope, unwittingly mono-
polizing the unbounded absolute with the relative concepts of sets, and
deviating through abstraction from the natural holonic set-logic with its
inherently delineated, perceived and conceived holarchical levels
(immanent/transcendent relations) of bounded-collections. Russell
discovered his paradox in the abstract set-theory of Frege (now called “naive
set-theory”), and it occurred precisely because of the naïve abandonment of
percept-restrictions leading to the ambiguity in the classical system of
classes. This conceptual abstraction—freed from its own holarchical
foundation of perception and imagination—failed to keep track of the
holonic levels in the implicit percept-logic of sets. This “violation” and
equivocation in turn, as we just noted, allowed both the universal and the
empty set to exist, coexist and interact, with “disastrous,” or perhaps
revealing, results.
Russell was deeply troubled by this paradox he found in Frege’s work, as
it impacted his own work, and interestingly, his own solution to the paradox
was based on applying a hierarchy or holarchy aspect in his theory of
“types,” in order to keep track of the different levels of set membership.
Even Frege himself had an implicit holarchical solution to the problem as it
occurred in his theory of properties; he avoided it by a distinction between
levels of concepts in which a concept can never take itself as argument. The
implicit holonic logic of sets naturally precludes this self-recursion, or self-
confusion, along with the problematic universal and empty sets, or
otherwise makes their “paradoxical” properties naturally explicit and
accountable, delineating these as special cases and not “proper” sets.
Indeed, as the study of mereology has found, the move from naïve
classical set theory to modern axiomatic and “Zermelo-Fraenkel” set theory
is essentially a move to reinstall—in abstract, explicit mechanisms—the
logic needed to keep track of the levels of sets and to restrict these violations
of the sensorial holonic logic already implicit, yet buried under abstraction,
in the stratified human mind. It is not generally recognized, however, that
the part-whole relation, itself derided as naïve, was the correct logic all
Page | 213
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
along, and the move into axiomatic set theory was a move to reinstall the
truths of this naiveté in the sense-barren abstraction of the set as category.
The incorrect naiveté , it is clear from an outsider’s retrospect, is the naiveté
of the categorical set conceived purely transitively, without its
immanent/transcendent holonic aspects.
The modern notion of the infinite, in axiomatic set theory, has its roots in the
paradox discovered by Galileo. In the Two New Sciences, Galileo laid bare an
apparent contradiction in the property of “infinite sets,” such as the whole
numbers (0, 1, 2, 3, …). Galileo noted that the whole numbers seemingly
contain the much smaller subset of the “perfect squares”i (0, 1, 4, 9, 36, 49,
64, 81, 100 …) with the spaces between the squares growing rapidly, filled
with non-square whole-numbers, such as the many non-square whole
numbers between 81 and 100, for example. Both the perfect squares and
the whole numbers are infinite in extent, yet the number of whole numbers,
seems to be vastly larger than the number of squares, with the gaps between
squares growing ever larger. Yet, given that the squares are derived by a
multiplication of each and every whole number with itself (a “one-to-one
correspondence”), there are then, of necessity, exactly as many perfect
squares as whole numbers.
The set of whole numbers and its subset of squares are then apparently
equal in size, and this is clearly a violation of the part-whole axiom, which
states that a subset must be smaller than its set. It is this paradox which
essentially led to the abandonment of the part-whole relation implicit in the
holonic logic of sets, and which, we will find, led to Cantor’s notion of the
transfinite orders of infinity as well as modern axiomatic set theory.
Or as Spinoza puts the problem, so much more simply, “If an infinite
quantity is measured by parts equal to a foot, it will consist of an infinitely
many such parts, as it will also if it is measured by parts equal to an inch.
i
… or we could just as accurately say the “perfect triangles,” as we will see…
Page | 214
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
And therefore one infinite number will be twelve times greater than
another.”i¥
i¥
Ethics, Part I, Prop XV, Note.
Page | 215
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
As we have seen in the implicit holonic logic of sets, the “infinite set”—such
as both the set of whole numbers and the set of perfect squares—though
perfectly adequate as abstract, general classes are not proper holonic sets
because they are boundless, not bounded, collections. They are merely the
abstracted “collection aspect” of implicit-holonic sets, conveniently
neglecting and equivocating from the container aspect of sets needed to
make sense of the empty set.
We will come to see “infinite sets” more clearly as “set aspects,” or
“aspect infinities,” rather than bounded-collections with definitive numbers
of elements, magnitudes or “cardinalities.” This new way of looking at things
will illuminate and resolve the truth behind this paradox in accord with
Galileo’s own reasoning that aspects of the finite, such as relative
magnitudes, do not really and fully apply to The Infinite. We will do so,
however, without nullifying Cantor’s great achievements in the
operationalization of the quantitative aspects of infinite sets, but only with
added clarification as to what is really taking place in these operations, thus
dissolving the controversies surrounding the Cantorian transfinite and the
modern axiomatic theory of sets.
For the time being, however, we have the tools in hand to see a simple
resolution of the Galilean paradox as a function of scope con-fusion in the
Univocity Framework. As we have seen, the quantitative aspect of the
relative scope is the finite. It deals with the bounded and with all relations,
such as the hierarchical or holarchical relations of one magnitude to another.
The absolute scope, on the other hand, has the quantitative aspect of the
Page | 216
MATHEMATICS: THE ART AND SCIENCE OF PURE RELATION
Page | 217
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
existing infinite, yet an infinite still exists. This is where Hilbert’s Hotel is
paradoxical.
In the Galilean paradox we saw that infinity, taken as a quantity, does not
function properly with respect to mathematical operations, such as squaring.
In this paradox we can see more clearly that infinity does not fit the function
of a quantity with respect to such properties as addition subtraction, or
division; for example, in division by two to get the evens and odds. In a
sense, we can actually see this paradox as a more vividly visual example of
the Galilean paradox. Imagine, for example, that we extend the paradox by
only filling the rooms with labels matching a perfect square. The “number”
of perfect squares are indeed infinite, yet the hotel would seem almost
entirely empty after this infinitely time-consuming procedure, this “super-
task,” of filling the perfect-square numbered rooms.
If we think of this in terms of the one-to-one correspondence used by
Galileo, we can see that by shifting the occupants down by one room, we are
effectively merely shifting the numbers on the rooms by one unit, and hence
shifting the one-to-one correspondence of the room-numbers and occupants
without really changing the nature of the hotel and its infinite, or unbounded
capacity at all. When we allow the occupants to fill up the odd numbered
rooms, we are merely acknowledging, as Galileo did, that the odd numbers
are by themselves infinite, in that they have a one-to-one correspondence
with the Natural numbers and the evens, just as do the perfect squares.
Page | 218
Page | 219
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
The absolute, recall, enfolds all aspects and attributes, including extension.
ii
In standard mathematics, the term “Operational Mathematics” refers to Laplacian and other
integral transforms.
Page | 220
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
This, however, is not to say that everything in the objectively-real world is tangible, such as energy,
and subtle forms beyond empirical reality, etc, but merely that it is embodiable in the imagination
and also that modelability can translate quantitative and objective (“IT” quadrant) aspects as such,
when the appropriate scales and empirical adjustments or hypotheses are taken into account.
ii
Note, 3V can also stand for the Vision-logic version of 3D: 3-vision-logic-dimensionality….but let us
avoid the natural tendency to call that 3VD. ;-)
iii
You may think of visualizations of infinite planes or points in a computer program, for instance, but
these representations are always measured in terms of pixels and truncated infinities, i.e. discrete
units. There is no possible representation of an infinitely thin anything and this is because the
concept amalgam is an oxymoron.
iv¥
Synergetics 216.03
v
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
Page | 221
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, Vision-logic Interfaces: Vision-logic and Blind-logic, p124.
Page | 222
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
We have already encountered the polarity of the finite and infinite in the
context of scope and univocity. It is also the more general aspect of the
polarity of infinity and number, which gives us the implicit identity of the
infinite number. The finite and infinite are the polar aspects of boundedness
and unboundedness for the relative and absolute scopes, respectively. And
in terms of pure-relation, they are the quantitative aspects of our polarity of
scope—the polarity and “contra-diction” at the very foundation of
quantitative reasoning itself, because our primitive notions of number
correspond precisely to boundary, as we will see.
The relative scope—and mathematics itself—necessarily deals
fundamentally in boundedness because in order for two event-objects to
inter-relate or even exist, they must have limits and boundaries (whether
gradients or not), excluding or including (or otherwise relating to) the other.i
By definition, however, the absolute scope cannot deal in boundaries, and
this is precisely because boundaries inter-relate—at the very least (and
fundamentally) between the inside and outside of that boundary. Indeed,
boundaries actually are, in a sense, this inter-relation or triune interface
between the within and without. It is in this sense that boundary
necessitates its own transcension in the boundless beyond and within itself.
The one cannot exist without the other.
The absolute scope, then, deals in the generally ineffable aspects of unity
and infinity, and the relative scope deals in the polarities and multiplicities
of the finite.
In esoteric wisdom we have the polarity of the infinite and the finite (or
bounded number) as a simple identity of opposites. The problem is that this
i
An interrelation involving an event/object with itself is an identity, and no real relation at all.
Hence an identity is, in some sense, a function of the absolute scope. The bounded identity
functions as an interface between the relative and absolute scopes because it identifies the infinite
in the finite or bounded individual. Such a bounded identity, as we have seen in the section on the
Univocity Framework, is a horizontal tautology, and if it is unbounded then it is vertical.
Page | 223
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
identity of opposites was not properly fleshed out, and through the LCD of
exoteric representational forces, the pre-modern esoteric polarity became
flattened into a mere duality of opposites: “infinity is not a number.” … but
why, and in what sense is infinity not a number? What about Cantor’s
“infinite numbers”? What about the immanent infinities of the “irrational
numbers”? Neither the exoteric classical duality, nor the esoteric ancient
polarity can satisfactorily explain these questions to the exacting standards
of modern, post-classical mathematics and philosophical logic and reason.
And Cantor’s transfinite arithmetic only touches them as they intersect the
field of mathematics, leaving in its wake a sprawling mess of philosophical
loose ends, as terms radically and unintuitively shift in meaning into their
seeming opposites. A mess for philosophers, to be sure, but it can be entirely
ignored by mathematicians uninterested in the controversies and meanings
of their machinations.
Against this classical duality of opposition between the finite and infinite,
the modern mathematical notions seemed to focus exclusively on the
missing identity, as it was parsed through the similarity of the abstracted set
as category. This is what Deleuze sees as the problem with a set-theory
based ontology. It sees everything in the terms of a similarity of the concept,
namely the abstract set. It reduces everything to a pure or abstract
“belonging” to the mathematical or pure-relational category. As Alain
Badiou writes, “[Deleuze] is challenging a set-theory ontology of elements
and belonging … which weaves out of the vacuum the greatest complexities,
and reduces to pure belonging the most entangled topologies.”
One of the problems with this set-theory ontology is that it generates “a
constant ambivalence between the ‘belonging’ (of an element) and the
‘inclusion’ (of a subset).” In other words, the abstracted categorical set had
lost the meaning and complexity implicit in our holonic logic of sets. And we
have seen these ambivalences and entangled topologies at the very onset of
this set-category, with its categorical blindness to the implicit holonic logic
as it manifested in Russell’s paradox, for example, but it also shows up in the
many paradoxes of set theory not discussed in this volume. And again, it
was only with the abstract, axiomatic re-encoding of the lost truths of the
part-whole (holonic) axiom that the paradoxes were brought into
mathematical reign. This is seen for example, in the fact that axiomatic set
theory has now come into line with mereology and its explicit part-whole
axiom, which set-theory explicitly or exoterically denies. There is, then, an
ambivalence of set-theory to this part-whole axiom, which on its face is
denied, but in its hidden and blind abstract inner-workings, it has
necessarily come to resemble.
Deleuze counters the mathematical notion of the set with the notion of
the “fold,” which he extracts from the Leibnizian monadology. We will find,
however, that the fold is essentially our Spinozan aspect infinite, as it
Page | 224
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
abstracts the immanent infinity of the aspect of locality from the infinite
ONE-ALL. Badiou says, quoting Deleuze’s The Fold:
Leibniz-Deleuze’s thesis is that the point, or element, cannot have the
value of a unit of matter: "The unit of matter, the smallest element of the
labyrinth, is the fold, not the point" (p9).
In this, Deleuze is directly in line with Spinoza and Leibniz, but also in line
with Whitehead’s “point-free geometry,” and our Interface Mathematics.i* It
is the point, conceived as Euclidean element, which generates the labyrinth
of the continuum, recall, and it was only with Leibniz’s abandonment of the
point for the Spinozan aspect infinite (Leibniz’s “termini”), as we will see,ii*
through which he found his Ariadne’s thread. Badiou continues [my
emphasis]:
Leibniz-Deleuze’s ontology apprehends the multiple as a point-subset, that
is, as an extension (an unfold) or a contraction (a fold), with neither atom
nor vacuum. …there have never been but two schemes, or paradigms,
of the Multiple: the mathematic and the organicist, Plato or Aristotle.
Opposing the fold to the set, or Leibniz to Descartes, reanimates the
organicist scheme. Deleuze-Leibniz does not omit remarking that it must
be separated from the mathematic scheme: "in Mathematics, it is
individuation which constitutes a specification; this is not so with physical
things or organic bodies" (p87).
The animal or the number? This is the cross of metaphysics, and the
greatness of Deleuze-Leibniz, metaphysician of the divergent world of
modernity, is to choose without hesitation for the animal. After all, "it is
not only animal psychology, but animal monadology which is essential to
Leibniz’s system" (p146).
The real question underlying this is that of singularity: where and
how does the singular meet up with the concept? What is the paradigm of
such an encounter?
We’ll see this encounter explicitly as it unfolds into the embryogenesis of
mathematics,iii* and as it traces its way through evolutionary unfolding into
the crossroads of the ontic/epistemic and subject/object, in Interface
Epistemology. iv * The encounter takes place through the interface of
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, as well as explicitly on our Vision-Logic Coordinate
System through the interface of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis, in
conjunction with the omni-axis through the Cycle of Unity. But again, this is
getting ahead of our story. Badiou continues [my comments].
i
* See, Boundary and Dimension: (p295), and The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation
(p306).
ii
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270, and Reconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical
Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and the Calculus, p400.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iv
*See, Interface Epistemology: A Preliminary Sketch, p541.
Page | 225
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
If Deleuze likes the Stoics, Leibniz, or Whitehead, and if he does not much
like Plato, Descartes, or Hegel, it is because, in the first series, the
principle of individuation [e.g. infinite difference beyond belonging to the
pure similarity or opposition of the concept] occupies a strategic place,
which it is denied in the second. The "Leibnizian revolution" is greeted
with rare stylistic enthusiasm in Deleuze’s supple narration, as the
"wedding of concept and singularity" (p91).
In the shock and integrating interface between the pre-modern
opposite and the post-modern identity, then, we will see emerging
again—but as a cultivated third and triune interface—the ancient
nondual identity of opposites of the finite and infinite. It is this identity
of opposites that finds its germination in the lost truths of modernity,
namely in esoteric rationalism as we find it in Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, also
reflected and refracted through Leibniz’s reactionary monadology. And in
this integration will likewise continue to unfold this “wedding of concept and
singularity.” We have already seen it with the immanent/transcendent
omni- and uni-axes, and we’ll soon see it more explicitly in the concept of
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite and, perhaps at its climax, in the Interface
resolution to Zeno’s paradoxes.
i¥
…from onelook.com
Page | 226
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Triune Infinite: Interfacing Emptiness, p268.
Page | 227
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
definition was wrong, per se, but rather because it was incomplete, or
prematurely aborted along with the project of rationalism itself. It was thus
still conceived as a simple duality or dichotomy—an opposition without the
identity in the triune interface which would be capable of unfolding the
complicated and inextricable relations between its two poles—the infinite
and finite. The nondual-rational or transrational concept of the Triune
Infinite—this triune interface between the finite and infinite—had yet to be
differentiated-and-integrated into modern meta-/mathematics, but this is
indeed a function of this work.
Page | 228
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Netz continues:
…the defining property of infinity today is that a set’s cardinality [its
number of elements] is equal to the cardinality of some real subset of that
set.
Netz simplifies this new set-theory definition of infinity as “Something which
is equal [or identical] to some of its parts.” As we should entirely expect, this
definition is naturally the inverse of the modern definition of the finite. But
recall that the conundrum of the Galilean part-whole paradox was exactly
this; that the parts of infinity—such as the set of all squares—are necessarily
infinite as well, and hence the parts are equal or identical to the whole.
Recall also, that this is the unique quality of the universal set, that it violates
the part-whole holonic relation and becomes a paradoxical subset of itself.
The new definition of the infinite, like that of the finite, is essentially a
codification, incorporation and encapsulation of the Galilean part-whole
paradox, rather than its resolution. We have rightly accepted the
paradoxical nature of the infinite, in its identity to the finite, but in
simultaneously discarding its opposition we have yet to understand its
nature. We have yet to tune and triune the paradox into a truly nondual
identity of opposites, and thus into a triune interface of inter-expression.i*
This part-whole violation is merely the result of representational forces,
of thinking of the Infinite in the identical terms of the finite, i.e. in terms of
parts and wholes, and more importantly, sets and subsets and their
abstracted categorical relations of class membership or belonging. The
modern definition of the finite and infinite—still a con-fused dichotomy, not
a polarity—is a result of looking through the representational prism of
axiomatic set-theory and its identical abstract categories. What do we get
when we conceive of the “infinite set” in terms of the identity of its subsets?
The “violation” of the part-whole axiom in the Galilean paradox where a part,
or subset, is identical to the whole infinite set. The main difference now, is
that we aren’t calling it a violation or a paradox. The paradox has not been
solved by this definition, but has now simply become the definition,
subsumed under the identity of the concept or category of the set.
i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
Page | 229
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Galileo himself when he said that magnitude did not apply. Indeed, Galileo
glimpsed this identity of opposites when he discovered that the infinite set
of the integers and its infinite subsets (such as the perfect squares) can be
put in a one-to-one correspondence with each other, thus further
demonstrating their equality. However, Cantor later found that this
correspondence with the Natural set of our counting numbers—a
correspondence which Cantor would naturally label “countability”i—was not
true for all types or sets of infinity, as we will see. And it is this feature with
which Cantor would later assign magnitude to what he discovered as an
infinite set of different “magnitudes” of mathematical infinity.
i
No pun intended…though allowed…
ii
* See, Paradoxical Postscript and Epitaph: Kan’t and the Antinomies of Pure Reason, p479.
Page | 230
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 231
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
It will indeed be shown that Zeno’s infinite division procedure was not stepwise, not of the order of
the rationals and thus not merely countable, but uncountable. See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning
and Triuning the Paradox, 432, and the subsection, Back to Zeno, p448.
ii
As we will see, however, Karin Verelst demonstrates in great detail that the fundamental structure
for all of Zeno’s paradoxes is an a priori uncountable continuum, thus taking the form of Cantor’s
Continuum Hypothesis itself in the form of a polarity which, as Interface Mathematics will
demonstrate, merely appears to us as a paradox given the implicit status of the fundamental binary
form of the VL-axes underlying conceptual relation itself. See Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 232
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
The question must be asked, “Does it ultimately solve, or make sense of the
paradoxes of the infinite to demonstrate a one-to-one correspondence
between an infinite set and its subsets and/or meta-sets, call them
‘denumerable’ and give them all a quantity or ‘cardinality’?” What about the
fact that an “infinite cardinality” or “infinite number” operates in radically
different ways from a finite one? What exactly is the nature of this
difference, and how can we make sense of it? For example, you can add or
subtract any amount whatsoever to an “infinite number” and you will get the
same infinite number. Just what is numerical about that kind of behavior?
This is clearly Hilbert’s Hotel paradox still in action. It hasn’t been explained
by a mere identity in countability, which is indeed still controversial for this
very reason. We still have the same counter-intuitive, oppositional and
paradoxical behavior of “infinite sets” with no real explanation of why. The
opposition of pre-modern naivety is simply obscured—transcended-and-
excluded—by this new mathematical definition under the identity of the set,
which merely incorporates the paradox right into its make-up.
Furthermore, to many it is somewhat confusing to call the infinite and
finite versions of cardinality by same name of “cardinality” or “number”
when they have such radically different properties and behaviors. And it
will be shown herein that the reason “infinite numbers” act so differently is
that they are not really quantities at all, in the traditional sense of numbers
as boundaries, but merely quantitative aspects or abstractions of The
Infinite. (We’ll get into this in much greater detail later in the section on
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite (p273), as well as in the section To Infinity and
Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox (p434).)
Page | 233
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
Page | 234
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
So now we can systematically say that the countably infinite set of Natural
numbers is numerically identical to its subsets, i.e. “self-nesting,” and we can
give them all a single number or cardinality, and use that number to perform
a kind of arithmetic between them. And through this transfinite arithmetic,
recursively unfolding above us we can “see” an infinite “paradise” of ever
larger and larger infinities. Indeed, not only can we see this (mathematically
speaking), but we can wander through it and perhaps use it for practical
purposes.
Beautiful and functional as this mathematical “vision” may indeed be,
however, it does not give us a vision-logic understanding of the crucial
opposition and interface between the finite and infinite which could explain
i
* See, Cantor’s Three Infinities, p268.
Page | 235
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
why an infinite set is equal to its subsets. This Cantorian liberation and
exodus of mathematics beyond the bondage of number and into the holy-
land of the infinite ultimately serves only the pragmatic needs of exoteric
mathematics to conceive of the infinite in the identical categorical terms of
sets and subsets, in order to move beyond the troubling mathematical
paradoxes in the evolution of their abstract, percept-less operations. The
liberation into the infinite is only partially complete, restricted as it is to
mathematics and its classes of number, and not yet open to the concepts and
identities of philosophy.
Recall that Galileo also demonstrated a paradoxical one-to-one
correspondence between the squares and Natural numbers. This is where
the paradox started, and almost where it is today, as far as human
understanding and philosophy is concerned. The crucial factor for
mathematics was in the Cantorian acceptance of the paradox as simply the
way it must be. Mathematics merely had to believe—to have faith in the
paradox itself, and then to act on this faith. And in the enfolding of this
paradox into its definitions and operations, mathematics itself has become
more systematic and unified in its abstracted rule-based interfaces with the
infinite—blindly encoding, as mereology shows, the previously cast-out
part-whole holonic relation itself. But there has been little progress in the
understanding of why infinite sets behave so paradoxically contrary to
common sense and intuition. Even though we know how to perform the
rituals, we still do not understand the ways and reasons of this new
mathematical God.
In short, only for mathematicians, and essentially only in the language of
mathematics, has the paradox been solved. For the bulk of us still wrestling
with the angel of understanding, we remain stuck in a head-lock with the
same old troubling paradoxes—still con-fused by “self-nesting” violations of
the implicit holonic logic of sets and the relations between the infinite and
finite—as between God and man.
Thus we seek further differentiations and integrations, transcensions and
inclusions. We seek new methods of sensing, intuiting, understanding and
digesting this newly swallowed paradox, leaving its golden Gordian knot to
churn out infinite vistas in the darkness of our bellies. We seek not merely
to swallow the paradox, but to incorporate its hidden truth into our being.
We seek to embody and explore the understanding with our imaginations,
and hence to rid ourselves of the indigestion of this real human controversy.
We seek vision-logic interfaces with which we can resolve and assimilate
this hidden, encapsulated contra-diction.
In order to get there, however, we must traverse a great deal of new
terrain. But when we do, we will indeed have all the functions in place to
truly understand the nature of the finite-infinite polarity underlying all the
paradoxes of the infinite, including the core paradox, which is properly
Zeno’s. We’ll be able to see this polarity between infinity and bounded-
Page | 236
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
Page | 237
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 238
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 239
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
the paradox itself as the definition. In so doing, Cantor appears (but only on
the surface) to have entirely abandoned the esoteric understanding of
infinity as boundless and innumerable, calling it denumerable and bounding
it with a cardinality and number for the sake of operationality.i*
For this encapsulation of ambiguity into axiom; enigma into equation; or
paradox into principle, we give these intensely creative individuals the
highest praise. But one can’t blame us, we seek direct expansion of
pragmatic power, often regardless of whether or not we understand that
power. And we can only bang our head against a wall for so long before we
seek a new direction in the labyrinth. So it is natural to praise the guy who
points us away from the operational dead-end and into a new, more
productive direction, even if, with respect to understanding (and in this case
meta-mathematics), the operational advance is often necessarily backward
and mostly lateral in other domains, causing, in these domains, more
confusion than resolution.
i
* Though, with his own Triune Infinite in mind—which it generally isn’t to mathematicians meta-
mathematicians alike—this provides Cantor with an ambiguous sort of escape route, which we’ll
discover soon in the sub-section on Cantor’s Three Infinities, p268.
Page | 240
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
* See, for example, What is Nondualism?, p56.
ii
* See, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156.
Page | 241
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
the Many. The absolute and Infinite form of Unity, however, sees the
identity of opposites of the ONE in the ALL; Unity as the identical opposite of
infinite Multiplicity; Emptiness as form, and vice versa; not two, but not
merely one.
As we have seen, duality and finite multiplicity (the Many) operate only
at the relative scope, since as soon as we have differentiation we necessarily
have relation. So when speaking of duality, or “two,” our scope is necessarily
at the relative level. In communicating the concept of the nondual, generally
when we shift to the absolute univocal scope of “ALL is ONE”—the one voice
that can only speak infinite difference—this necessary implicit shift in scope
is not communicated. Since “two” is already finite and bounded (relative
scope), then without the shift being communicated explicitly in the
“nonduality is not two,” the “ONE” would be taken as relative, finite and
bounded as well, the “one,” which is precisely the wrong meaning. This is
pointed to in the following quote from T’ai Chi Chih, “‘Advaita’ in Sanskrit
means ‘Non-Duality.’ This is a difficult concept for most people as we look
about us and see multiple objects.” The proper understanding of an Infinite
Unity is not bound to distinctions, but contains and exfoliates them all.
So, with the preliminary distinction between the absolute and relative
scopes, and the Infinite and finite aspects of unity, the leap of intuition from
bounded and relative notions of unity in the multiplicity of everyday objects,
to the Infinite and univocal “ONE is ALL” in the nondual, becomes more fully
explicated and much more easily replicated or communicated at the
cognitive and logical level.
As we have seen, Infinite Unity is absolute unity, and The Infinitei because
unboundedness, or Emptiness, is the definitional essence of the absolute
scope. This is necessarily the simplest, most fundamental and abstract of all
meta-mathematical unities. Infinite Unity can be readily summoned with the
univocal identity of opposites “ALL is ONE,” a defining feature of the
absolute scope. This is also Phase One in the embryogenesis of the concept.ii
The “ALL is ONE” was the original meaning for the term “Universe” as “one
song”; “a single voice raises the clamour of Being;” that which expresses ALL
of reality and, of necessity, as ONE inter-expressive unity. In the ALL-ONE,
there is nothing left to bound or surpass the totality of existence. ALL is
ONE, in pure principle and by definition. And in accordance with implicit
holonic logic of sets, nothing else can exist apart from the set which includes
i
* first order infinity, see Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270
ii
Note how, at the absolute scope, and in resonance with our principle of absolute reversal, the
identical opposite of ONE is automatically included in the absolute multiplicity of the ALL.
Page | 242
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
Note that, just as according to Spinoza there are infinite attributes of “God” so too there are
“aspects” of infinite unity abstracted as various infinities of a specific kind. These are the “aspect
infinities,” such as infinite space or infinite time (eternity), abstracting the spatial or temporal aspect
of The Infinite, respectively. We’ll discuss this in more depth in the section, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite,
p270.
ii
This is even true according to Cantor’s own triune categorization of kinds or degrees of infinity.
Page | 243
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
rules, which will be explained as they come up, and are used in a much
looser fashion than mathematical equations. They are used more as quick,
symbolic/visual metaphors, or maps, illustrating relations, rather than
quantitative derivations. This is largely because of their extensive use of
absolute and inquantate infinity,i and its inability to really partake in
quantitative operations—operating, as the VLE often do, between the
relative and absolute scopes.
As we discussed in The Univocity Framework (p155), The ONE-ALL
relation is the identity of opposites and univocity of the absolute and relative
scope, respectively. And as we will see, this is essentially the God/Substance
relation in Spinoza, as well.
The first conceptual operation upon the Infinite Unity of the absolute ONE is
the application of the identity of opposites and the principle of absolute
reversal to find its inverse-identical, in the absolute immanent multiplicity.
Thus we come to the quantitative aspect of Infinite Unity, the ALL. The
absolute ONE, seen relatively and quantitatively, then, is expressed as its
identical-opposite, the ALL, or The Infinite.ii* And in terms of Nondual
Rationalism, the quantitative ALL is expressed by the VLE ratio, ∞/∞.
So breaking it down using the vision-logic equations we have the
following: For our purposes the quantitative aspect of Infinite Unity (the
ALL) can be expressed loosely by the VLE:
The transcendent aspect of the ALL, the common notion of infinity within
absolute Unity, is expressed as:
i
This is not to exclude Cantor’s transfinite operations, because, as we will see (See, Cantor’s Three
Infinities, p268), Cantor as well, in his own Triune Infinite, excluded his first order “Absolute Infinite”
from his third order “mathematical infinite,” which he defined as “abstract.”
ii
* This is the first order of infinity in Spinoza’s Triune Infinite. See, Order 1: The Absolute Infinite,
p272.
iii
…or even inversely as 1/0 = ∞ , recalling our reciprocity across the solidus and our see-saw analogy
(see The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual Rationalism (p71), that pushing
up on one side of the see-saw gives the same result as a corresponding weight on the other.
iv
We will come to find this as also expressing Leibniz’s transcendent definition of God, as opposed to
Spinoza’s definition of God, not as the transcendent pole of the immanent-transcendent axis, but as
Page | 244
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
1
= immanent “zero” (VLE: Immanent Infinity)
Recall that immanent zero is really the boundless immanent pole of the
immanent-transcendent axis, or the infinite rational zero we encountered
already in The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism (p74). The boundless zero of infinite division is never reached
because it is “infinitely small.” This can also be represented by a single,
abstract and “infinitely precise” location, an ideal point or what we are
calling a Euclidean implicit singularity. In this same sense, with the
inversion occurring across the solidus/vinculum, placing a zero in the
denominator (the immanent position of the ratio) is identical to placing
infinity in the numerator (the transcendent position of the ratio).
the absolute view of the absolute scope, or simply a transcendent emphasis of the immanent-
transcendent omni-axis and polarity.
i
* See, Polarity and Univocity (p174).
Page | 245
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
As we have seen with the Hilbert and Galilean paradoxes, Infinite Unity, or
Infinity (as opposed to the common notion of infinity used, say, in the term
“infinite set,” which is merely an aspect of The Infinite), when operated
upon—divided, multiplied, added to, subtracted from, counted by odds,
evens or perfect squares into its multiple quantitative set-aspects—always
returns infinity. This is the nature of the absolute scope that, even when
conceived in its multiple aspect of the ALL, it cannot properly be operated
upon without leading to paradox or tautologyi*, such as “self-nesting” and
the ONE-is-ALL, respectively. And this is the core principle reconciling the
paradoxes of the infinite—an abstract generality which we will flesh out in
much more detail. We can see this principle as another resonating chord in
our Ariadne’s Cable, from our first chord, the Principle of Nondual
Rationalism; infinite division equals indivisibility.
i
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
Page | 246
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Explanation: Infinite Unity is the quantitative aspect of the absolute scope, therefore
it cannot participate in the art and science of pure relation (mathematics) except for
the role of the context and field of its other. It is “inquantate,” not quantitative or
measurable. In nondual terms, Infinite Unity is “not one,” in opposition to “Many.”
i
This principle can be stated with a “vision-logic equation” where is taken as a
general operator standing for any operation, or relation, whatsoever:
n or n
* … or zero, the omni-non, given the transitive function of zero as negation. Thus, to
hold, n, in transitive functions such as multiplication, cannot equal zero.
A prime example of the failure to grasp the principle of Infinite Unity and the
modelable nature of Interface Mathematics, is with the use of the “point-
particle” in particle physics. Because the foundation of modern
mathematical reasoning (meta-mathematics) is not fully rational—in that it
does not explicitly recognize the immanent-transcendent axis or its
immanent pole and its rational-zero as the immanent expression of
infinity—physicists do not explicitly conceive of a mathematical point as
itself representing an “infinite quantity.” Because this immanent infinity
(opened up through the function of the mathematical ratio) remains hidden
and “undefined” under the rational-holonic solidus (by the transcendent-
bias of pre-rational representational forces) the scientists were surprised to
find that operations thereupon—in the form of “infinitely-small” point-
particles—returned the answer of infinity when calculating its energy as a
function of distance squared. ii This failure led to the need for the
euphemistic, and now exceedingly necessary and useful, process of
i
* See the coming section: VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-logic Equations, p288.
ii
And as we will soon see, in the holarchical unfolding of the functionality of the higher numbers and
operations the rooting and powering functions come into play when the operations and their
number-functions finally return again to the immanent-transcendent axis. See, The Holarchical
Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
Page | 247
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Finite unity, is the identical-opposite of Infinite Unity and the absolute scope.
It is the unity of the relative scope. Mathematically, we will see, it is the unit-
number ‘one’ derived as the vinculum/solidus in the polarity and cycle of
Unity and the VLE ∞/∞. This is the unity of the one vs. the many, the 1 and
the n, as opposed to the univocal tautology or identity of the ONE is ALL.
Finite unity generally corresponds to Spinoza’s modifications and
Leibniz’s monads (and all emergents thereof). Indeed, Leibniz’s principle of
unity is essentially that the whole of any real unity (of which he dealt only
with the finite kind) is greater than the sum of its parts. This is essentially
the principle of emergence where real, unpredictable novelty is generated in
the synergy of the transcendence of immanent complexity into new forms.
Also, Spinoza’s notion of essence applies to finite unities in the sense that
any real finite unity will have a tendency to persist in its own being; an
emergent function of homeostasis or a “strange attractor” maintaining its
emergent form.
In Interface Mathematics, finite unity corresponds to the modelable,
volumetric root number 1, of which all others are relative aggregates,
relations, higher-functions or compounds (we’ll get into this in more depth
later).ii* Having volumetric extension and a boundary, finite unity can enter
into relations with other numbers; it can be added to and subtracted from,
divided and multiplied, odded, evened and squared to make endless and
indefinite operational sets, or definitions for infinite sets.
Finite unities, as relativities and primitive quantities, must have
boundary and magnitude, and in Fuller’s “Operational Mathematics”iii* as
i
From Answers.com: renormalization: In quantum field theory (QFT) and the statistical mechanics of
fields, renormalization refers to a collection of techniques used to construct mathematical
relationships or approximate relationships between observable quantities, when the standard
assumption that the parameters of the theory are finite breaks down (giving the result that many
observables are infinite). Renormalization arose in quantum electrodynamics as a means of making
sense of the infinite results of various calculations and extracting finite answers to properly posed
physical questions. … Some of the problems and phenomena eventually addressed by
renormalization actually appeared earlier in the classical electrodynamics of point particles in the
19th and early 20th century. When calculating the electromagnetic interactions of charged particles
…if the electron is assumed to be a point, the calculated value of this back-reaction diverges,
essentially because of the singularity at the origin in the inverse-square law.
ii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iii
* See, Empirical/Experiential Beginnings: Bucky’s “Operational Mathematics”, p217.
Page | 248
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
This also corresponds to Alfred North Whitehead’s “point-free geometry” where the implicit
singularity of the point (in our terms) is exchanged for the relativity of the finite “region,” as
Whitehead calls it..
ii
* For much more detail, see Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.
iii¥
Edmonson 25-8
Page | 249
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Explanation: This principle directly encodes the part -whole relation in the aspect of
holonic sets and invokes the symbiogenesis or emergent coupling of a finite set with its
parent- and sub-sets and vice versa, necessitating that any finite holonic set must be a
subset of a larger set and must also be composed of subsets; Any whole must be a part
of a larger whole and any part must be a whole for smaller parts. This within/without
relation is the holonic polarity implicit in finite, as opposed to infinite, unit y.
In accord with Fuller’s maxim, and indeed with his Synergetic Geometry—
and also for the same basic reasons that Whitehead generated his “point-free
geometry”—the smallest unit in Interface Mathematics is a vanishingly small
volumetric point and finite unity. This Operational, modelable and
empirically-observable spherical point is herein called a “real-point” to
contrast with the unimaginable, unobservable and unmodelable “ideal point”
in standard extensionless and non-volumetric mathematics. The real-point,
the volumetric finite unity (finity) existing at the limits of visibility, is too
small (or far away) for us to see its shape, size or magnitude, so we
approximate it with the simplest, most symmetrical shape we can imagine, a
sphere. This sphere has the intrinsic duality or polarity specified in Fuller’s
maxim and our principle of finite unity. The real point is the infinitely
divisible “anatom,” holon or corpuscle of Interface Mathematics.
The “real point” ideally correlates to the smallest currently observable,
empirically deducible, modelable object or arbitrarily selected scale of
measurement, and like all objects it necessarily has both volumetric
extension and a surface. Therefore all numbers derived from such a real
point (as is the case for the numbers in Interface Mathematics) are
boundaries or limitsi as well. And all higher-level numbers made from
compositions and relations of this finite unit are also necessarily limited in
magnitude because they are multiples or fractions of the unit-number.
The selection of the actual scale for the real-point is fundamentally
arbitrary as it is based in variable utility. Indeed, the impetus of this
volumetric stipulation is to enable a utilitarian correspondence and
resonance—an interface between mathematics and the basic elements of
nondual-rational ontology and empirical reality, such as volumetric
i
As we already discussed, it is the use of ideal non-extended points in physics, the study of physically
extended reality, that causes the problematic infinities euphemistically titled “renormalization.”
Page | 250
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
what we were also calling the rational-zero.
ii
Infinity as “boundless” is the form used throughout this work and to which this work presents a
return path without relinquishing the fruits of transfinite mathematics and set theory. It simply
redefines what a set is and how it relates to the categories of the infinite while resolving the
paradoxes that transfinite number theory was attempting to resolve by incorporating the problem
into its new and non-operational definition of “infinite”.
iii
* 2nd order Infinities, see Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270
iv
* See, Galileo, Cantor and the Transfinite, p442
Page | 251
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* “Immanence equals transcendence (and vice versa),” see Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of
Immanence in Transcendence (Yin in Yang), p95.
ii
* See, From Dependent- to Tetra- Arising: The Conceptual Embryogenesis of AQAL, p560.
iii
It must be noted at the outset that number itself is a fused concept that has already been
differentiated into at least three main branches, cardinal (magnitude or quantity), ordinal (order or
rank), and nominal (a mere label such as #83 on a football jersey). The numbers we will be dealing
with throughout this section are generally the cardinals because they deal with quantity and
therefore mathematics proper. If and when we discuss the others, they will be labeled accordingly.
Page | 252
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
… and with a strong transcendent-bias due to the plane of the paper image.
Page | 253
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
substance connects it. This polarity between The Infinite and number
means, however, that even the primitive bounded number one is
intrinsically infinite—an implicit and encapsulated infinite number. As we
will see in detail in the Cycle of Unity, boundary itself comes into being
conceptually from the boundless. A polarity, recall, is not just an opposition,
but also an identity.
This dual polarity and infinity essential to finity forms another tetrad,
which it seems Fuller was not aware of, as it necessitates a fundamental and
inseparable distinction (polarity) between The Infinite and number. This is
a variation and extension of the polarity of the infinite and the finite, as well
as the polarity of its unities, which we already explored.i* This is, rather, the
polarity of the ONE-ALL and the ‘1,’ as the interface of its ONE-one uni-axis.ii*
In Interface Mathematics, once that boundary is drawn (or perceived) a
number can be introduced into consciousness, or the imagination, to
represent, keep track of, and make use of, the bounded object. Numbers
(again as magnitudes) cannot come into being, either causally or
experientially, and have no function without at least tacitly representing, or
being capable of representing, some real, physically-conceived limit—be it
known or unknown.
i
* See, The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite (p221) and, Unity and Nonduality (p239).
ii
* See The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 254
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
This will be discussed in much greater depth in SpinbitZ: Vol. II
ii
This is in order to satisfy the Venturi pressure difference at the interface of motion or spin which
creates the bit of matter known as the matter unit. This real pressure difference is what causes the
nucleus to condense and differentiate substantially into the basic matter-unit. This is quite literally
and viscerally, the initial “contraction in the face of infinity,” and it represents the initial move from
immanence into the transitive dimensionality as one holon looking out and among many. The
contraction is the basic form of agency, while its chemical bonding harmonics and other
environmental interactions are the initial acts of communion.
iii
This is because it takes a nucleated substrate, with its transitive bias, to generate a Venturi effect
and a higher-level pressurized and differentiated nucleus … again to be explored more thoroughly in
SpinbitZ: Volume II
Page | 255
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
iii
* See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
iv
* Figure repeated from I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
v
* See, The Omni-Non: The Binary Logic of the Absolute/Relative Interface, p120.
Page | 256
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Figure 8: Repeated from I/T Interfaces, the Omni -Uni and the Omni-Non.
i
In mathematics these correspond roughly to coordinate, vector and scalar, respectively.
Page | 257
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
the uni-axis (the one singularity of the one axis) is finite and the uni-aspect of
the omni-axis (the ONE of ALL uni-axes) is infinite. The quantitative
difference between the uni-aspects of the uni- and omni-axes (i.e. the ‘one’
and the ‘ONE,’ respectively), therefore, presents us with the critical relative-
to-absolute polarity underlying the Cycle of Unity, as we will see. But recall
that this polarity is exactly that of the absolute or infinite aspects of
extension vs. position already embodied in the two poles of the uni-axis; the
ONE and the singularity (See Figure 8, above). Also, recall that we have only
two VL-axes in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System. The Cycle of Unity, then,
is the binary cycle by which the uncountable I/T axis breaks into the
fundamental unit by which to stepwise generate the countable transitive-
axis and to begin the agglomerative embryogenesis of mathematics itself.
Because of this, we can conceive of the uni-axis as the VL-axis (vision-
logic level axis) of the ONE-one, but ‘one’ in both the sense of the one
singularity, as well as being the VL-axis upon which we can define the one-
boundary and vinculum of finite unity. This gives us the distinction between
the VL-axes of the absolute ONE-ALL (omni) and the absolute-relative ONE-
one (uni), and it is critical to note the difference here in terms of scope. The
ONE-ALL, note, is fully contained in the absolute scope (as denoted by the
CAPS), even if viewed through the relative aspect of the multiple to give us
the infinite ALL. The ONE-one and uni-axis, on the other hand, actually gives
us a finite or quantitative aspect in the single position of the one singularity
hiding at its center. It is thus our first relative polarity (as opposed to an
absolute tautology) and conduit from the absolute to the relative scope.
While the omni- and uni- axes converge at the transcendent pole, the
interfaces of each are vastly different, recall. The interface of the omni-axis
is an unbounded volumetric expanse of a specific scale (a transitive plane),
whereas the interface of the uni-axis is the spherical boundary of our finite
unity. The polarity between the two I/T interfaces, therefore, swings us
from the Unity of the absolute, in the ALL-ONE to the unity of the relative in
the unit-interface of the uni-axis. This is the polarity underlying the Cycle of
Unity.
The Cycle of Unity begins with the transition, from the pre-differentiated,
uncountable omni-non of ALL-ONE positions (and thus infinite continuity)
shared by the transcendent poles of both I/T axes, to the infinitely
differentiated ‘one’ singularity of any particular ONE-one uni-axis. Due to
the Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity,i the VLE for Infinite Unity (∞/∞)
is at this point pre-differentiated, and can represent either the omni- or uni-
i
See, Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, p245. “Infinite Unity, or its
unbounded aspects of infinity, when operated upon, always returns infinity. Thus Infinite Unity is, to
coin a term, “inquantate,” not quantitative or immeasurable. In nondual terms, Infinite Unity is ‘not
one.’” Regardless of whether or not the infinity is the Euclidean implicit singularity of the uni-axis,
or the infinite multiple of the omni-axis, infinity is inoperable, quantitatively.
Page | 258
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
I/T axis. But to move from the mutual ALL-ONE in transcendence to our
transitive finite unity, with its one location and bounded magnitude, we
must transition from the omni-non of position (the omni-axis), to its
identical opposite in the omni-uni of position (the uni-axis, with its one
immanent singularity opposite the ONE.)
Figure 14: Univocity Framework for the I/T Axes and Interfaces:
This diagram illustrates the I/T axes and interfaces in the context of the Univocity
Framework.
i
* See, Exploring the Univocity Framework, 190.
Page | 259
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
From the transcendent Infinite Unity which both VL-axes share, this pre-
mathematical oscillation transitions us between them—from The Infinite
ONE to a single positional aspect of infinity—the implicit singularity of the
‘one’ of absolute position—but not yet to our finite unity of the first
mathematical boundary and number. On this I/T uni-axis, a “pre-
coordinate” is implicit or emergent as the unit-interface between the
immanent and transcendent aspects of the uni-axis. This boundary breaks
the infinite ALL of the absolute ONE into the relative scope “one of many.”i*
This boundary can be located or derived at any position on any arbitrarily
selected immanent/transcendent uni-axis. See Figure 15, above.
i
* See, Finite Unity: “Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two”, p246.
Page | 260
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
We can already see the Triune Infinite in this interface of The Infinite and finite.
iii
Mathematics in the common sense of operations on pre-existing numbers returning differentiated
answers.
Page | 261
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
To make this more visceral and tangible, and to provide us with useful tools
for the Triune Infinite, The Cycle of Unity can be visualized as an eccentric
orbit; a univocal cometary journey of representation from the dark, vast
i
* See, Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.
ii
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
Page | 262
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 263
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
this can be written as “ONE is ALL” (i.e. Unity = Multiplicity), and in its
relative and purely immanenti form as the multiple aspect, the ALL. From
the absolute ONE of Infinite Unity, we break from the stalled symmetry of
our orbital apoapsis, falling from the ONE-ALL of infinite complexity toward
the infinite focus and implicit singularity of the first polarity to touch the
relative-scope, the ONE-one and uni-axis. We pass swiftly through the
orbital clouds of higher-mathematics and arrive at the cultivated third of this
first relative polarity giving us the primary boundary needed for our
nondual-rational vision-logic interface understanding of the embryogenesis
of mathematical operations.
Nearing the point of closest approach, from this relative view—
embedded in the representational “orbital dynamics” of the infinite ALL and
its ONE-one uni-axis—the absolute scope of Infinite Unity can be further
abstracted (represented in either its omni- or uni-axis forms) and written by
the VLE statement; ∞/∞. For a brief moment, the periapsis of our orbit is
now distinctly in view. It is the division center of the vinculum/solidus; the
closest point in our orbit to the first meta-mathematical boundary of form
and duality, but the furthest from the nondual identity of immanence in
transcendence (yin in yang); the vastness of logical-Emptiness and Infinite
Unity, respectively. Accelerating us on in the fastest portion of our orbit the
equality of the representative VLE-ratio quickly returns us, in its pre-
mathematical unbounded function, to the ONE of Infinite Unity, flinging us
back into the vast Emptiness from which we came.
The observant reader will be struck by the inadequacy of the orbital analogy.
It is clearly imbued with a transcendent-bias … of all things. This can be
seen in the simple fact that the outer vastness of space represents both
transcendence and immanence whereas the inward direction moves us
toward its VLE division in the solidus/vinculum boundary. We can,
however, turn the unbalanced analogy inside-out, flipping the immanent-
transcendent polarity. Instead of approaching the boundary of the unit-
number from the outside, we can approach it from the infinite depth within
and return to this depth from whence we came on the outbound leg of the
journey.
Combining the two analogies into one, however, provides a more
integrated, balanced and complete view of the unity and distinction of this
most critical immanent-transcendent polarity. The goal in both cases is still
the approach towards the primitive boundary and origin point in Interface
i
…in the sense of “immanence in transcendence.”
Page | 264
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Figure 18: The Double Orbit of Unity (ant mobius image from M.C. Escher):
This diagram illustrates the mobius -aspect of the Orbit of Unity analogy, in that the
outer leads to the inner, and vice versa. This image is superior to the orbit of unity
because it transcends the transcendent -bias to show the immanence in transcendence
of the ONE-ALL. In this diagram, the 8 represents the ALL which is the relative view of
the ONE. The apoapses of both the immanent and transcendent loops represents the
limits of representation, and the self -crossing represents the location of the unit -
boundary and primitive number 1 of our finite unity between immanence and
transcendence.
To do this, instead of using a circular orbit, we use a figure eight. This figure
is the traditional symbol of infinity, the “lazy eight,” but turned upright;
perhaps to denote the awareness of the transcendent-bias in mathematics
and adopted in the ratio of our VLE. For the sake of convention, but now in
full awareness of the bias, the top loop of our figure-eight, represents
transcendence and the bottom, immanence—as in our VLE ∞/∞, and the
standard positions in the mathematical ratio. The return point of each—
both the top and bottom extremes of the eight—still represents our
apoapsis, the ONE-ALL, respectively, but this time we can see it more clearly
Page | 265
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Spinoza makes an important clarification to the polarity of the finite and The
Infinite, but he places his emphasis between the Infinite and the imagination
(i.e. representation), which he sees necessarily as finite, given its modal
nature and what we are calling its relative scope in the world of form. ii This
difference, he says in his famous Letter XII on the Infinite, is crucial to
untangling the confusions surrounding the infinite (as we will very soon
see). The Infinite is “that, which can be understood but not imagined” and
i
i.e. measurement.
ii
Technically, the imagination, or representation, is the epistemic level of the world of form, or what
the Hindus/Buddhists call Maya, the real world of real illusion.
Page | 266
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
the finite is “that which can [be understood and] also be imagined.”i¥ This is
the primary scope distinction between absolute and relative—the
fundamental polarity of the Univocity Framework—rendered in terms of the
multiple or quantitative aspects of the imagination, and the limitations of the
forces of representation.
In Spinoza’s view, all images or representations are part of the relative
and finite (or indefinite) imagination. This would then include perception
and conception, while the reality of this necessary representational illusion
of sensation and other forms of the imagination is our qualitative
connection, our interface with, and as, reality (and specifically a finite unity
thereof).ii*
Accordingly, the most primitive form we will explore in the
embryogenesis and holarchical unfolding of Interface Mathematics is the
very first Operational number, form, boundary and finite unity in
contradistinction to The Infinite and its ineffable and inoperable Unity, as
discussed above. This primitive unit-number is necessarily represented by
an image in the imagination or a real object of relative perception, already
designated herein by the appearance of the circular boundary on the white
paper in Figure 13, above (p254), but it is also the real object being counted
in the primitive forms of mathematics from whence we derived the natural
numbers. The Infinite, however, exists beyond, or prior to, any image or
boundary being introduced and thus beyond the imagination. Both the
infinite set of all possible real numbers and a space of infinite extent are
impossible to encapsulate in one’s imagination yet they are quite easy to
understand logically and procedurally. Just imagine endlessly counting by
ones, or multiplying by some recursive, set-generating algorithm, or imagine
an endless expanse of space, a horizon with no boundaries.
This imagination is the indefinite. The interfacing of The Infinite with
the finite forms of time. Through logic and intuition, we must then assume
that it simply goes on “forever” because we can’t get there in our
imaginations. Thus infinity is simple to understand through the rules of logic
and with the help of the imagination, but it is impossible to visualize, imagine
or encapsulate as a totality. The best we get with the imagination is the
indefinite, not the infinite.
Therefore, as the rationalists correctly noted, the abstract understanding,
reason or rationality, coupled with the intuition, can grasp things (at least
relatively so) of a general and symbolic nature extending beyond, or
transcending and including the capabilities of the detailed imagination,
including both objective and subjective forms such as perception. The
i¥
Letter XII (B. D. Spinoza)
ii
* See Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability” in this book and the
discussion on the Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object,
p528.
Page | 267
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
higher levels of concept, such as logic and reason, can (and should)
transcend and include percept. An understanding of infinity is therefore
always necessarily a conceptual abstraction based on the mnemonic
foundations at the interface of perception/conception, just as every
modification is an abstraction from the infinite itself. But without the
imagination and its foundational perceptions to aid in the process of
transcending itself, there is no understanding of the finite or the infinite.
i
Unless of course Bucky’s Universe was only dealing with the finite realm of observability, which
would fit with his notion of modelability, but it would necessitate his unrecognizing of the
fundamental distinction between the finite world of mathematics and the Infinite. It would mean
that Bucky did not recognize that the boundless, in principle, cannot be encapsulated in the realm of
the bounded, but vice versa. But then he likely didn’t study Spinoza or Leibniz.
Page | 268
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Universe. The finite unity (boundedness or finity) gives rise to duality and
only the Infinite Unity (boundless ALL and absolute scope) can be truly ONE
and non-dual because it contains and exfoliates all polarity.i
Bucky is correct, however, that infinity does not properly operate within
physics, observation or mathematics. He is right that The Infinite is not to be
found within any finite descriptive (subjective or objective) system, but he
neglects the inverse conclusion (necessitated by his own principle) that all
finite systems or wholes are to be found within, and necessitated upon, a
greater sub-meta-representational system or whole, and ultimately upon the
infinite division equals indivisibility or continuity of the fundamental
Principle of Nondual Rationalism. That nondual continuity as infinite
discontinuity (and vice versa) is the only thing capable of “giving rise” to a
boundless series of possible boundaries in the embryogenesis of the concept
of Universe.
i
This is another route for Spinoza’s “escape” from the mode to arrive at infinite and continuous
substance.
Page | 269
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
Wilkinson H. . Psychoanalysis as finite, psychoanalysis as infinite? Psychoanalysis’ religious
potential: International Journal of Psychotherapy, July 2003, vol. 8, no. 2, pp. 147-168(22)
Page | 270
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
occurs in the contingent, created world; third when the mind grasps it in
abstracto as a mathematical magnitude, number or order type.”
Given that, for Cantor, mathematical infinities only occur at the third
level, that of abstraction, or what we would call representation, it is
important to note that none of Cantor’s revolutionary transfinite
mathematics deals at all with our absolute scope, The Infinite or the ONE-
ALL of univocal Emptiness. All of Cantor’s work is strictly at his own third
order of infinity, in abstracto; the realm of the relative scope and the forces
and limitations of representation, with its inability to ultimately or
absolutely encapsulate the absolute scope and its abstracted quantitative
aspects. Recall that this is the critical feature of the Univocity Framework
and the nature of the nondual and Nagarjuna’s Emptiness. This feature
alone, of Cantor’s metaphysical context—if grasped by those mathematicians
and philosophers of mathematics who take issue with Cantor’s work—could
perhaps get us much of the way toward a resolution of the controversies at
the heart of modern “axiomatic” set theory. We’ll explore this in much more
depth later.i*
Spinoza’s Triune Infinite has a slightly different, less transcendental and
less theological mapping. In univocity there is no “fully independent
otherworldly being” because the ALL is the ONE in Substance and its infinite
modifications. But Cantor may be intuiting the absolute/relative scope
polarity as an independent duality, and generally from a transcendent-bias.
In this sense his 1st order can be seen as the absolute ineffable scope of The
Infinite, or the ONE, and his 2nd order can be seen as the relative scope view
of the absolute, or the ALL of infinite multiplicity as it appears in the
“contingent” reality of modification. His 3rd order, however, appears to be
merely a catch-all for all possible representational and quantitative infinities,
namely those of mathematics, which is then where we find the infinite levels
of infinities of his transfinite sets; all merely 3rd order mental abstractions of
“mathematical magnitude, number or order type(s).” So, essentially,
Cantor’s three infinities can be expressed as Absolute, Ontic, and
Mathematical (this last category of mathematical infinities is merely a subset
of the epistemic or representational forms of the infinite (aspects), i.e.
mathematics as the representation (art/science) of pure relation).
We will find a slightly different mapping in Spinoza, and one that is far
more useful for making sense of the polarity of The Infinite and finite, and
the paradoxes that they have inspired. We will find that Cantor’s loose set of
types leaves out several critical distinctions. Indeed, Cantor’s third
distinction is not a distinction in kind or degree of infinity, but merely based
on where it is found—in Cantor’s specialty, Mathematics—and, most
critically, it makes no room for non-mathematical forms of representational
i
* See, Galileo, Cantor and the Transfinite, p442.
Page | 271
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, Spinoza, the Infinite, the Indefinite and the Imagination, p264.
ii
likely out of fear of being associated with the “infamous Jew” and his heretical ideas
Page | 272
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
the infinite and other topics. Leibniz copied out the letter—which
extends for half a dozen pages—then added marginal notes of his own as
lengthy as the original text (p187).
According to Samuel Levy (in his Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually
Infinite Division of Matter), 1676 was the year of Leibniz’s Spinoza studies
and the year he solved his problem of the “labyrinth of the continuum” and
the infinitesimal of the calculus by recognizing “infinitely small” points not
as a priori composing the continuum but as a posteriori “termini” abstracted
from the a priori infinite depth of the continuum.i* These points as termini
are what we will come to see as Spinoza’s 2nd order infinities, and it is likely
that Leibniz drew this inspiration from reading Spinoza’s “thirteen year old”
Letter XII on the infinite, where he made this distinction (used throughout
his Ethics, I will argue) its most clear. And recall again that this is what
Deleuze extracts from Leibniz as the idea of the “fold,” converting his
infinitely divided monadology into an infinitely folded and unified one.ii*
Whether Leibniz invented the Triune Infinite independently thirteen
years later or customized and began to use Spinoza’s Triune Infinite as his
own without attribution—given Spinoza’s heretical and dangerous-to-know
status—is still an open question. Regardless, as with the bulk of Leibniz’s
reaction to his own secret Spinozism, there is much novelty and value that
Leibniz brings to the subject.iii
There is no doubt, however, that Leibniz and Spinoza shared the Triune
Infinite regardless of priority. In the transcript to a 1981 audio-taped
discussion, Deleuze states:
And Leibniz, who was himself a very great mathematician, who had
knowledge of the letter to Meyer, declared that he particularly admired
Spinoza for this geometrical example [which we will explore below]
which showed that Spinoza understood things that even his
contemporaries didn’t understand, said Leibniz.iv¥
And Jim Macdonald says in his paper Spinoza and Leibniz: A strong Affinity:
Leibniz liked Spinoza’s characterization of the three infinities, although he
said he was accustomed to call them by different names. Nevertheless, he
saw Spinoza’s division as pretty much the same as his.
i
* We’ll explore this connection further in the section on the calculus (see Reconnecting the Lost
Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and the Calculus, p400).
ii
* See, The Identity vs. the Opposite: Post-Modern Con-fusion and Pre-modern Naiveté, p221.
iii
Indeed, as we will see (see The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite, p407), Spinoza’s Triune
Infinite led Leibniz to his rejection of the idea that the continuum could be made up of mathematical
points, and hence to his (currently neglected) resolution to the problem of the infinitesimal and the
calculus.
iv ¥
Gilles Deleuze: Cours Vincennes - 20/01/1981 :
<http://www.webdeleuze.com/php/texte.php?cle=191&groupe=Spinoza&langue=2 >
Page | 273
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
And Macdonald continues, quoting Leibniz from his notes, and providing us
with a succinct introduction to the Triune Infinite:
‘I usually say that there are three degrees of infinity. The lowest is, for the
sake of an example, like that of the asymptote of a hyperbola; and this I
usually call the mere infinite. It is greater than any assignable, as can also
be said of all the other degrees. The second is that which is greatest in its
own kind, as for example the greatest of all extended things is the whole
of space, the greatest of all successives is eternity. The third degree of
infinity, and this is the highest degree, is everything, and this kind of
infinite is in God, since he is all one; for in him are contained the
requisites for existing of all the others.’i¥
Note that Leibniz says that all of the degrees of infinity share one thing in
common, they are “greater than any assignable.” This basically means that,
in their respective levels and domains, they are unbounded, as we have
established for the esoteric and nondual understanding of infinity, as the
quantitative aspect of the absolute scope. It is also worth noting that
Leibniz’s own language of “the greatest” seems to imply an actual magnitude
and thus a boundary, the greatest one, as opposed to the boundless. This is,
however, merely a consequence of rendering the infinite in relative terms
such as magnitude.
Leibniz categorized his degrees of infinity from lowest to highest, from
the first to the third degrees, respectively. In light of the embryogenesis of
the concept, however, we will work in the inverse direction, starting with
Infinite Unity as the first order and working into the lower orders in terms of
differentiation into larger numbers and working down into the relative view
of the absolute, from the ONE of Infinite Unity to the ALL of absolute
multiplicity and into the ONE-one of the uni-axis and its finite unity and
implicit, intrinsic singularity.
The 1st order Infinite is “The Absolute,” the ALL is ONE, the “Boundless ALL,”
our absolute scope, Emptiness and Infinite Unity which is not ‘one.’ Spinoza
describes it in his Letter XII as, “…that which must be infinite from its very
nature, or in virtue of its definition.” And Leibniz says, “…the highest degree,
is everything, and this kind of infinite is in God, since he is all one; for in him
are contained the requisites for existing of all the others.” This is the
ineffable absolute; enfolding and unfolding all other possible infinities,
polarities and forms of difference. This is also the “axis of Tao” denoted and
operationalized herein by the second order immanent/transcendent omni-
axis.
i¥
Leibniz; Notes; qtd in Macdonald
Page | 274
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Alexander R. Pruss in his paper Can Two Equal Infinity? The Attributes of
God in Spinoza, calls this 1st order Infinite the “Absolute Infinity.” He says,
echoing our principle of Infinite Unity,i “Something infinite in this sense
cannot be broken down into parts.” For the absolute scope to be broken
down into parts or divided, would first require a relation between divisor
and dividend, and barring that, it would require a division of infinite depth.
This “kind of infinite is indivisible,” as Spinoza mentioned, but it is indivisible
precisely because it is infinitely deep or infinitely divided, as Leibniz would
emphasize. The Absolute Infinite is the “infinite division equals
indivisibility” of the fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism. The
Infinite, being Absolute, cannot, by definition, possess internal relations. The
instant such relations exist, we are again at the relative scope.ii
And echoing Spinoza, Pruss continues, “This kind of infinity is only
conceived by the intellect, not the imagination.” The imagination is always
exhausted in a finite amount of time and therefore can only ever reach a
limited, indefinite depth of extension (transitive), division (immanence) or
time.
The Aspect Infinite is the second order infinity and it derives its infinite
nature directly from the first as unfolding aspects, perspectives, infinite
modes of being or mental abstractions from it. The Aspect Infinite mediates
as a cultivated third or a triune-interface between the first and last orders of
infinity, just as Spinoza’s attributes mediate the expression between
Substance and its modes,iii* just as Leibniz’s “pre-established harmony”
mediates between God and the subjective and objective monadsiv and just as
our relative-view ALL mediates between the ONE and the one.v See The
Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attributes and Modifications
(p288), below.
i
“Infinite Unity, or its unbounded aspects of infinity, when operated upon, always returns infinity.”
ii
But again, it is important to note that the absolute and relative scopes are not locations, or scales
of interaction in a relation of reduction, one to the other. They are, rather, the basic conceptual
contexts from which the mind attempts to make sense of the world and itself. Indeed, the absolute
scope only comes into the conceptual field of view when the relative scope attempts to relativize
itself in order to find its context in its identical-opposite. And thus the bounded relative scope must
find its basis and meaning in the boundless absolute scope and the concept comes full-circle to
grasp its genesis in the pre-conceptual, and the finite in the infinite. See “Vertical” Polarity: The
Polarity of Polarity, p175.
iii
* See The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attributes and Modifications, p285.
iv
God and monad together form the “supreme Gonad,” but that is beyond the credulity of this book.
v
And we can also see parallels here between the mediation of Jesus between the ONE God and the
one-many of humanity.
Page | 275
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Leibniz says in his notes, “The second is that which is greatest in its own
kind, as for example the greatest of all extended things is the whole of space,
the greatest of all successives is eternity.” These are the spatial and
temporal (extension and duration) aspects of The Infinite, respectively.
Spinoza distinguishes this type of infinity as, “that which has no limits, not in
virtue of its essence, but in virtue of its cause...” All abstracted aspects or
properties of The Infinite are in this sense also boundless because they apply
to, or are abstracted from, the Absolute Infinite. So each aspect of The
Infinite is infinite or boundless in extent and ultimate amount, not due to its
own “essence”—which is an Empty, finite and relative category or
abstraction—but because each draws its indwelling cause, or is abstracted
from, the Infinite, ineffable source, or true univocal and nondual essence of
the absolute. This very common type of infinity will be broken into sub-
levels for further clarification.
Perhaps because of the effectiveness of mathematical examples for this
type of infinity, Pruss calls it the “Mathematical Infinity.” However, this term
leaves out the whole class of aspects of The Infinite outside the realm of
mathematics. Furthermore it would seem to exclude the mathematical
aspects of the third order of infinity (introduced in a few pages below), and
this flies in the face of Spinoza’s own “geometrical example” of the third
order, as we will see.i Given this, we will loosely side with Cantor and choose
not to categorize the 2nd order as the Mathematical, but as the Aspect
Infinite.
i
This is likely due to the transcendent-bias in only recognizing transcendent forms of infinity in
modern mathematics, and seeing the immanent infinite as merely the undefined or the indefinite.
Page | 276
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Figure 15 and Figure 16 repeated from The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p257
In The Cycle of Unity, recall, we move from the outer-reaches of the orbit, the
apoapsisi of the pre-quantitative Infinite Unity of the ONE, through the
“quantitative aspect” in the infinite multiplicity of the ALL, to the recognition
of “immanence in transcendence”ii* in the pre-mathematical division or
interface of the immanent-transcendent uni-axis and its implicit singularity
into the first boundary and primitive number needed for mathematical
operations.
The second degree of infinity, the Aspect Infinite, arises with the first
(EOTC), pre-quantitative “multiplication through division” of The Infinite
ALL-is-ONE into the first polarity of the immanent and transcendent aspects
in the omni-axis. In this process we move from the sub-representational and
ineffable ONE to the quantitative, yet pre-mathematical aspect of multiplicity
and its inherent omni-non-directional, omni-non-local relativity in the ALL.
From there we move to the omni-directional/locational aspects of the ONE-
one uni-axis and then to the selection/derivation of our unit-scale interface
and finite unity for the beginning of primitive mathematical operations—
namely counting to create the first agglomerative and transitive “natural”
i
“(astronomy) The point in an orbit farthest from the center of attraction.” Answers.com
ii
* See Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of Immanence in Transcendence, p95.
Page | 277
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
Page | 278
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
In this way, as Spinoza notes, we can already see “what kind, of infinite may
… be conceived greater than another infinite, and what kind cannot be so
conceived.” The Absolute Infinite is inquantate,ii or “not one,” as the non-
dualists may put it, and thus (in accord with our Quantitative Principle of
Infinite Unity (p248)) it can’t be quantitatively operated upon to conceive of
any greater infinity. The aspects of infinity, however, spring from, and as,
the interface between The Infinite and the relative realm of representation
and its finite forms and frames of reference, as abstracted aspects of
“contingent” reality, as Cantor put it. Aspect infinities are thus “quantate”
and comparable insofar as their representational aspects and frames of
reference are concerned.
i
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
ii
Or non-quantitative…
Page | 279
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See The Pearl Principle, p235
ii
* We’ll explore this in much greater depth in, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation,
p306.
iii
* See, Spinoza, the Infinite, the Indefinite and the Imagination, p264.
iv
According to the definition of number as boundary, at least.
Page | 280
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
The Bounded Infinite is the third and lowest order of infinity as it deals with
the unbounded within the bounded. Leibniz says in his notes, “The lowest is,
for the sake of an example, like that of the asymptote of a hyperbola; and this
I usually call the mere infinite.” Spinoza describes it as, “…that, of which the
parts cannot be equaled or expressed by any number, though the greatest
and least magnitude of the whole may be known...” Spinoza provides for this
degree of the infinite, his famous geometrical example. Spinoza says [my
emphases]:
As, for instance, in the case of two circles, non-concentric, whereof one
encloses the other, no number can express the inequalities of distance
which exist between the two circles... This conclusion is not based on the
excessive size of the intervening space. However small a portion of it we
take, the inequalities of this small portion will surpass all numerical
expression. Nor, again, is the conclusion based on the fact, as in other
cases, that we do not know the maximum and the minimum of the said
space. It springs simply from the fact, that the nature of the space
between two non-concentric circles cannot be expressed in number.
Therefore, he who would assign a numerical equivalent for the
inequalities in question, would be bound, at the same time, to bring about
that a circle should not be a circle.
The modal infinity is a 2nd order derivative from the Absolute Infinite, and it
unfolds from the confluence of the two main aspect infinities: the I/T
(omnidirectional) and the transitive (uni-directional) derived from our finite
unity as a frame of reference. The modal infinity is the interface between the
immanent and transitive aspects or directionalities, and can thus be seen as
a subset of the 2nd order—as it reaches from the apoapsis of the ALL-ONE
and onto the ONE-one of the I/T uni-axis, passing the periapsis of the finite
unity, to the implicit singularity at its core. On the transitive axis which sees
a line segment or circle as explicitly bounded there is indeed a discernable
outside limit but this limit is not contained within the specified system of
immanent division, which has no conceivable end in sight, so no conceivable
ultimate number can be found for the inner limit. The limits themselves,
being “infinitely precise, are infinitely indefinable. This echoes our Principle
i
Wikipedia: Hume’s Principle: “…the number of Fs is equal to the number of Gs if there is a one-to-
one correspondence (a bijection) between the Fs and the Gs.”
Page | 281
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
It is certainly no coincidence that Spinoza used the example of the circle, the
cross-section of the sphere, in his explanation of the modal infinite. The
sphere itself is the simplest and root-level bounded infinite and infinite
number as the interface of the ONE-one uni-axis and the abstracted aspect of
infinite omni-symmetrical boundedness itself, from the boundlessness
within itself.
Fuller says in his Synergetics, “The Greeks defined the sphere as a surface
outwardly equidistant in all directions from a point. As defined, the Greek
sphere’s surface was an absolute continuum, subdividing all the Universe
outside it from all the Universe inside it; wherefore, the Universe outside
could be dispensed with and the interior eternally conserved” (224.07).
This is why he called the mathematical sphere a perpetual motion machine.
Energy can’t get out or in through an infinitely continuous boundary. And
this is of course exactly the boundary cannot exist, in the sense that stasis
cannot exist and persist without continual flux.
The sphere—in this absolute sense of bounded continuity—is the closest
possible EOTC representation of the omni-non-symmetry of the ONE, in the
omni-symmetry of the one. This is why the ancients intuitively held such a
vaunted place for the sphere, and rightly so. It is the interface of the ONE
Page | 283
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
and the one,i the abstracted essence of man himself in his relation to the
immanence and transcendence of God.
i
See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
Page | 284
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 285
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 286
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Recall Spinoza’s definition of the finite; “A thing is called finite after its kind,
when it can be limited by another thing of the same nature; for instance, a
body is called finite because we always conceive another greater body.” As
should be clear, we can also take Spinoza’s definition of The Infinite and
finite generally in terms of the polarity of Substance and its Modifications,
respectively, and its Cycle of Unityi*, within which Substance turns around
its modes and vice versa. That which is modified is, in some sense,
necessarily bounded and has magnitude (e.g. size, length width, duration)
relative to other modifications; modification is necessarily in the relative
realm of form in identical opposition to the absolute realm of Emptiness.
Spinoza also had infinite modes in his system, however, to which our
aspect infinities correspond, as aspects at the interface of the finite and The
Infinite. For example, the set of perfect-squares can be conceived as an
infinite or unbounded modification of the mathematical continuum, yet
Cantor discovered that this infinite has the exact same quantitative power
(aleph null) as that of the wholes and the rationals, and is first surpassed
only by the infinity of the irrationals. Thus the infinite modification is, in this
sense of the aspect of power, finite and bounded, and this is precisely due to
its being a modification, or participating in the world of form, identically-
opposed to the world of Emptiness or The Infinite, from which it draws its
boundless aspect in its power of set-generation.
Similarly, when we divide an infinite set or number-line into two parts,
both could still be infinite without paradox, as codified in our quantitative
principle of Infinite Unity.ii* The Aspect Infinite renders the paradox illusory
in the sense that taking directions at the line of division is to take a sub-
aspect of the infinite line. It is to take a sub-aspect of the polarity of the
aspect of linearity, abstracted from The Infinite. Neither of the sections on
either side of the division would be finite in their direction or “kind.”
Therefore, this division of the infinite does not produce limits in their own
kind but draws out polarities and aspects, all of which share in the
boundlessness of The Infinite from which they are abstracted.
i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity.
ii
* See, Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, p245.
Page | 287
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Figure 21: The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attribute and Mode :
In this diagram we can see the structural similarity between the mathematical
ontological and triads in Spinoza: the Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance,
Attribute and Mode.
This relation is key to the structure of Spinoza’s Ethics (See Figure 21,
above). This polar identity of opposites of the finite and infinite is helpful in
reconciling the relation between the mode and its infinite immanence
derived as the finite unity from the ONE-one uni-axis and its implicit
singularity. Take the following quote from Alain Badiou’s Spinoza’s Closed
Ontologyi¥ [[my comments emphases]]:
In the letter of March 1663 to Simon de Vries, Spinoza takes pains to
declare that the word ‘attribute’ does not by itself constitute a naming of
the ‘there is’ [[finite unity]] in any way essentially distinct from the
naming of the latter by substance. Having reiterated the definition of
substance he adds: ‘I understand the same by attribute, except that it is
called attribute in relation to (*respectu*) the intellect, which
attributes such and such a definite nature to substance. [[The attribute is
only finite in the sense that it is in respect to the intellect. It is abstracted
as a special kind of aspect of The Infinite.]] Thus the attribute, as well as
the multiplicity of attributes through which divine infinity is identified, is
a function of the intellect. In the general arrangement of the ‘there is’,
there exists—under the name ‘God’—a singular localization [[implicit
singularity, or aspect of locality, the ‘one’ of the ONE-one uni-axis]], that of
the intellect, upon whose point of view or operations depends thought’s
capacity for rational access to divine infinity, and hence to the ‘there is’ as
such.
It is thus necessary to recognize that the intellect occupies the
position of a fold—to take up the central concept in Deleuze’s philosophy.
Or, using my own terminology, that the intellect is an operation of torsion.
It is localizable of an immanent production of God, but is also required to
uphold the naming of the ‘there is’ as God [[abstracting the identifiable
i¥
(Donovan)
Page | 288
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
aspects of/from The Infinite]]. For only the singular operations of the
intellect give meaning to God’s existential singularization [[ALL-ONE]] as
infinite substance.
This infinite immanence and implicit singularity new to the rational—
explored deeply by Leibniz as well, in both metaphysical and mathematical
form (e.g. monads, the calculus and the labyrinth of the continuum)—is the
positive infinity which Deleuze called the secret of the rational. In univocity,
a mode unfolds from infinity, as infinity participates in its own bounded
aspects in the infinite depth of its interfaces (recall the infinite coastline,
above), and Substance turns around its modes, and its modes around
Substance, as Emptiness is Form and Form Emptiness.
It would indeed be a fruitful exercise to undertake an analysis of
Spinoza’s Ethics from this “organizing principle” of the Infinite as the triune-
interface of the “polarity of polarity” in the Univocity Framework.i* In this
sense one could continue to tease out many of the problems of traditional
Spinozist hermeneutics, such as the relation of modes to Substance, and both
to the varied forms of infinity, and The Infinite absolute. One could see that
indeed modes are not other than an interface of infinity, and so on. Some of
this will unfold herein, but much of it will remain beyond the scope of this
work.
i
* See, Polarity and Univocity, p174.
Page | 289
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270, above.
Page | 290
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
bias, as it is encoded also, only this time consciously, into the very structure
of the VCS meta-tags.
Since the scope for the uncountable I/T axis itself, the ab1 scope, includes
both poles, it will be considered “neutral” (intensive) and each of the two
poles taken separately will be considered “charged.” However, since this
isolation of one pole of the axis at the expense of the other can only occur
through an interface—i.e. the interaction between the ONE-one of the I/T
uni-axis, its implicit singularity and the finite unity of the transitive axes—
(as the discussion on the Bounded Infinitei* and The Cycle of Unityii*
suggests) this “charging” or “unbalancing” of the 1st level brings us down to
the 3rd level of the modal infinite and the finite unity, in a full-circle, linking
the top with the bottom through the interacting core aspects (see The Cycle
of the Infinite (p296) below and The Cycle of Unity (p257), above).
The scope of the isolated or emphasized immanent pole will therefore be
given the negativeiii suffix and the scope for the transcendent pole, the
positive. So we now have the ab3+ and ab3- scopes for the transcendent and
immanent scopes respectively, and we can introduce this “charge” into the
VLEs themselves to denote the imbalance between the immanent(-) and
transcendent(+) aspects of the Infinite.
Furthermore, each of the infinities and scopes also has an accompanying
vision-logic equation (VLE), which is a logical, or relational equation for
dealing with the quantitative aspects of the absolute/relative polarity (the
polarity of polarity)iv* from a vision-logic level in the meta-mathematical
framework. Since we are dealing with the absolute scope, and therefore
necessarily with the philosophical and pre-mathematical, rather than the
mathematical notions of infinity, and given that infinity in either case is not a
number, these VLEs are not rigorously mathematical, but rather meta-
mathematical, logical or relational, with their own peculiar logic.v They use
the relational operators of mathematics to quickly and intuitively invoke the
simple conceptual and logical relations between the levels and the VL-axes
of the VCS. They are used more as metaphors, or maps, than quantitative
derivations. This is largely because of their extensive use of infinity, and its
inability to really partake in quantitative operationsvi*—operating as the
VLE often do between the relative and absolute scopes.
i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270, above.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
iii
…due to the transcendent bias statistically emergent and empirically demonstrated in human
thought.
iv
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
v
The subject of operations on the infinite is already controversial for precisely this reason; Infinity is
not a number.
vi
* See, Principle 7: Chord 5: The Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity, p245.
Page | 291
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The root-level VLE, and the VLE upon which the others are based, is the
equation for the immanent/transcendent omni-axis, and thus for the
Absolute Infinite (ab1) to which it maps.i It is as follows:
ONE
ii
Equation 1: VLE: ab1 — The Infinite: The Root VLE
transcendent
ALL ONE
immanent
Equation 2: VLE: ab1 — Expanded Root Equation and VLE: Cycle of Unity
i
As would be expected; The lower levels of the infinite exfoliate from the first and this is echoed in
the relations among the VLEs.
ii
With the transcendent/transitive bias in modern thought this collapses to oo/0 where division by
zero is correctly recognized as undefined, but the denominator is incorrectly recognized as 0 as
opposed to the immanent pole of deep infinity (I/T) denoted as oo-.
iii
Note that division/multiplication is always the operator in these equations. This is because the
ratio is the core of Rationalism and multiplication and division are the two poles of the mediating
operator (cultivated third) between the I/T (powering/rooting) and transitive (arithmetical) axes in
the “Onion of Operations” in, Part Two: Interface Mathematics, p200.
iv
* See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
Page | 292
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
The 2nd order mathematical equations are many and varied, such as the “set-
aspects” or set generators of infinite sets and any other equation that
projects, or abstracts finite patterns or aspects from or onto The Absolute
Infinite. Aspect-level VLEs, however, are any VLE that involves the infinite
term with a finite operator. We’ll use as the universal operator to denote
any possible mathematical operation. The defining ab2: VLE is:
(n )=∞
Recall that prior to this point we were calling the root VLE the equation of
Infinite Unity,i* and that it denoted both the I/T omni- and uni- axes. Now
that we have delineated the a posteriori charge of the immanent and
transcendent operations as they transcend-and-include the transitive,ii we
can also differentiate the uni- from the omni-axis in terms of the VLE, placing
the uni-axis in the aspect level as touching the relative scope in its finite and
singular aspect of position or locality in its implicit singularity. The VLE for
the I/T uni-axis is as follows:
iii
Equation 4: VLE: ab2.1 — The Uni-Axis with Interface at Finite (Bounded) Unity
i
* See, Infinite Unity: ALL is ONE, p240.
ii
We’ll explore this in much greater depth in, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation,
p306, but very simply, the first numbers are the wholes and they form the first transitive
numberline. From there we move to the positive and negative transitive charge of the integers and
it is not till the Rationals that we break again into the intensive forces of immanence and
transcendence, transcending-and-including the transitive oppositional charge of the integers.
iii
The ONE-one of the uni-axis, recall, is the transition between the absolute scope of omni-non
locality and the one locality of its implicit singularity, or immanent position aspect. Therefore, we
place this VLE exactly half-way between the
Page | 293
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
And for balance, we’ll give the reciprocal VLE for the transcendent pole, the
Bounded Infinite with an internal limit at unity, the VLE for the charged ab3+
scope. Note that what is traditionally conceived as the unbounded is actually
bounded in the immanent direction. Thus the transcendent infinite, like the
immanent infinite is bounded and unbalanced, or charged, with a positive or
negative sign in the posterior position, denoting charge as intensity rather
than as transitive opposition.
1
Equation 6: VLE: ab3+ — Transcendent Infinite
For reference and summary, here is the list of the VLEs at their respective
levels of the Triune Infinite:
Page | 294
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
1: ONE
2: (n Ω ∞) = ∞
1
3: and
1
As the levels move down the triune hierarchy, from the absolute through the
relative scope aspects, they get progressively more and more relative (as
aspects) and finite (bounded), since this triunity represents the cultivated
third, or the interface, between the infinite and the finite. This also
corresponds to the move from the trans-trans-bias in the unrecognition of
the rational zero (undefined zero in the denominator) to the recognition, in
the 17th century rationalists, of immanence in the bounded infinite.
The I/T omni-axis is only relative in that, as a vision-logic interface, it
relates to, abstracts, and represents (or points outside itself to), the deeper
quantitative, or “pure-relational” aspect of the ineffable Infinite, with its
fundamental polarity in the ALL-ONE. The Aspect level, on the other hand, is
injected with a finite (relative) operator n (denoting a finite frame of
reference). As we have seen in the Cycle of Unity, however, the bounded
infinity is the interface between the transitive (relative) uni-directional axes
and the Immanent/Transcendent axis. The transcendent—ONE—of the final
bounded infinite then merges through the Cycle of Unity back into the ALL,
completing the Cycle of Infinity.
Though it contains an infinity within itself (and without itself), this
bounded infinite with its implicit singularity can act (and must act) as a
finite transitive root-unit and interact relative to other units. This nucleation
is indeed how the transitive axes exfoliate (emerge) from the immanence
and transcendence of the absolute, though we can clearly see here the
necessary cyclical nature of this non-dual and non-foundational framework
rooted in the rootlessness and implicit singularity represented by the
uncountable I/T axis.i* The Cycle of the Infinite is the move from a priori
I/T omni-non-local/-directional boundlessness, to the uni-axis, its implicit
singularity and finite unit-interface, and through the holarchical unfolding of
number and operation back to function on the I/T axis, making explicit its
i
* This cycle is explored in greater detail in a related aspect called the “Cycle of Identities,” (see The
Binary Cycle of Identities, Axes and Unities, p381) and it is seen in the physical aspect of the model
as well, called Sorce Theory.
Page | 295
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
…a specific form of holon, “corpuscle” or anatom whose harmonic maximization of its own implicit
singularity and infinite complexity culminates in extreme self-stabilization, self-focusing integrity and
inertia. See, Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.
Page | 296
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 297
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* Recall, The Omni-Non: The Binary Logic of the Absolute/Relative Interface, p120.
ii
… as demonstrated so beautifully by Buckminster Fuller’s radically different, exquisitely coherent
and consistent Synergetic Geometry, based on the 4 spatial dimensions inherent in the a priori
volumetric tetrahedron-octahedron isometric vector relation.
iii
Synergetic Geometry seems a good candidate ... eventually.
Page | 298
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
i
see Bode's Law and Sorce Theory.
ii
It must be noted that this is in full agreement with the embryogenesis of the concept, in the sense
that Universe is not the same thing as concept. Universe itself is eternal, but the concept-systems of
man indeed do evolve “from simplex to complex,” and this evolution of the concept, not the eternal
(absolute scope: temporal-Emptiness) Universe, is what we are tracing herein.
Page | 299
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 300
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 301
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
This radial dimension within each and every sphere of the IVM—and
determining, therefore, the a priori volumetric distance between every
point—recall, is essentially the function of the interface of our “I/T uni-
axis,”i* i.e. to determine the scale or first transitive “plane” or volumetric
field and scale of action, dimension or mensuration. As soon as a boundary
is introduced into the omni-non-dimensional continuum (involving exactly
“one tetrahedron” or 720 degrees of angular take-out), a first dimension, or
infinite polarity and VL-axis (aspect infinity), is already necessarily invoked
as the polarity which gives the triune interface of finite unity its context and
meaning (“(Finite) Unity is plural and at minimum two”). Without this initial
boundary in a priori boundless/formless Emptiness, there is no modelable or
Operational boundary, magnitude, extension, quantity or relation, with
which to dimensionally and modelably interrelate anything with anything
else.
i
* See I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146, and The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
ii
Fuller, Synergetics 963.00 … … and for those interested, I’ll give in this footnote a few quotes
outlining the rest of his dimensional model: (964.01) In conventional XYZ coordination, two-
dimensionality is identified with areal pointal frequency. (964.02) …In synergetics, second powering
represents the rate of system surface growth. (964.30) Shell Accounting: Second power has been
identified uniquely with surface area, and it is still the “surface,” or shell. But what physics shows is
very interesting: there are no continuous shells, there are only energy-event foci and quanta. They
can be considered as points or “little spheres.” The second-power numbers represent the number of
energy packages or points in the outer shell of the system. … (965.01) In a radiational or
gravitational wave system, third powering is synergetically identified with the total point population
involvement of all the successively propagated, successively outward bound in omniradial direction,
wave layers of the system. … (965.02) … as, for instance, total molecular population of a body of
water through which successive waves pass outwardly from a splash-propagated initial circle. As the
circle grows larger, the number of molecules being locally displaced grows exponentially. (965.04)
Perpendicularity (90-degreeness) uniquely characterizes the limit of three- dimensionality.
Equiangularity (60-degreeness) uniquely characterizes the limits of four- dimensional systems.
(966.01) In a radiational or gravitational wave system, fourth powering is identified with the
interpointal domain volumes. (966.02) It is not possible to demonstrate the fourth dimension with
90-degree models. The regular tetrahedron has four unique, omnisymmetrically interacting face
planes—ergo, four unique perpendiculars to the four planes.
Page | 302
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
These “external linear dimensions” are our familiar transitive axes, external
to the immanence within any unitary volumetric scale or frame of reference.
Fuller continues on in the same passage… (and please note that this is
included merely to give a taste of the complexity and beauty of his system,
and its understanding is not needed for the comprehension of Interface
Mathematics to follow)…
Synergetics starts system mensuration at the system center and,
employing omni-60-degree angular coordinates, expresses the omni-
equal, radial and chordal, modular linear subdivisions in “frequency” of
module subdivisioning of those radii and chords, which method of
mensuration exactly accommodates both gravitational (coherence) and
radiational (expansion) calculations. As the length of the vectors
represents given mass-times-velocity, the energy involvements are
inherent in the isotropic vector matrix (963.12).
Interestingly, in Synergetics Fuller also says, “It could be that the concept
conjured up by the mouthed-word sphere itself is scientifically invalid; ergo,
it could be that the word sphere is not only obsolete but to be shunned
because it is meaningless and possibly disastrously misleading to human
thought” (986.235). Fuller means here to distinguish the ideal, absolute
perfection of the platonic Form of the sphere from any real-world
(experiential/empirical) spherical emergent or form. He cautions, correctly,
and always from his experiential basis that we have found no absolute
continuity in nature whatsoever, and thus no perfect sphere. He also makes
the interesting note that such a perfect sphere would be a perpetual motion
machine, with neither input nor output of energy for either entropic (decay)
or syntropic (growth) functions.i
So with Fuller’s caveat on the Platonic sphere, we recognize its use here
as such a Platonic ideal category; an abstracted aspect of The Infinite, and
that a sphere in the real-world is never platonically ideal or infinitely
perfect. Even more, there is never any perfectly detailed frame of reference
from which to measure such a platonic perfection. We have already
“pulverized the categories” with Nondual Rationalism and the Univocity
Framework and need merely to recognize its function and differentiation
here. We fully realize that this ideal sphere belongs in the pure-relational,
abstract world of mathematics and its philosophy, and therefore also that
the sphere is merely the first step in the embryogenesis of the concept from
omni-non-symmetry of the ONE to the first omni-directional symmetry and
minimal modification of the interface of the ONE-one uni-axis…our first
boundary in this EOTC of mathematics as the art and science of pure relation.
i
A fact which would delight Plato, no doubt. And from a trans-foundational and Nondual Rational
frame of reference, this is to be expected as there can be no reduction to any form, including the
formless.
Page | 303
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The sphere is the basic modal infinity as the aspect of bounded omni-
symmetry and absolute bounded continuity.i*
ALL = = ONE
i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
iii
* See, VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-logic Equations, p288.
Page | 304
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 305
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
Of course we could take issue with Lebau’s adoption of the standard oxymoron “infinitely small,”
because taken to its infinite extreme “infinitely small” necessarily means “zero-size” (another
unavoidable oxymoron) and thus extensionless, but it is clear that Lebau is stipulating a point with
real extension, “circular” as a sphere represented in two dimensions on paper.
ii
* See, The Imaginary as Vestigial Transitive Axis at the I/T Interface, p348.
Page | 306
NONDUAL-RATIONAL AND EMPIRICAL EMBRYOGENESIS OF MATHEMATICS
Page | 307
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 308
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 309
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Before even number itself comes onto the scene in mathematics, the first
boundary in the boundless must itself become manifest in the closure of the
first implicit number 1; the object of the operation of counting … 1+1+1+1+
…. This first operation is Kant’s operator of existence itself, before the
predicate and category of quantity and quality can even arise. This first
operation of “unit-closure,” prior to even counting itself, represents the
formation in the mathematical mind of the primal mathematical identity or
rigid category (“numerically (or absolutely) identical” to any other of its
kind); the number 1, our finite unity as primitive encapsulated infinite
number and bounded or modal infinite. “This one, and that one, and this
other one… and this other-other one … ”—being composed of identical units
(unit-identities), the agglomerative or sequential numbers (cardinals and
ordinals, respectively) all begin to sound alike until we give them sequential
names in order to differentiate…and thus begins counting from a series of
“ones.”
As we recall, in The Cycle of Unity this unit-closure as a conceptual
breaking of the omni-non-symmetry of the formless, ineffable absolute into
the omni-symmetry of bounded relative form (and root Bounded Aspect of
The Infinite), takes place from our singular, relative-scope representation of
logical-Emptiness, the immanent-transcendent uni-axis. Recall from our
Cycle of Unity that this relative unit-identity (or finite unity) is our
interface—through the positional aspect in the uni-axis—with Infinite
Unity—the absolute, tautological identity of the ALL-ONE. So, even the very
first number, the finite unit-identity, is born from a coupling of an identity
and an operation in the differentiation-and-integration of the embryogenesis
of the concept.
This unit-closure is the separation of the absolute identity of the ALL-
ONE of Infinite Unity into its immanent and transcendent poles by the
selection of the first omni-symmetrical interface and boundary of our finite
unity and abstract, ideal sphere as the basic modal infinity. Thus the unit-
identity—our primal relative-identity in the art and science of pure-
relation—is born from the polarization of Infinite Unity, or absolute-identity,
the ALL is ONE, as we have seen in our Cycle of Unity. The sphere is, in this
sense, the closest possible relative representation of the omni-non-
symmetry of the ONE, in the omni-symmetry of the one. This is perhaps why
the ancients held such a high place for the sphere. It is the interface of the
Page | 310
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
ONE and the one, the abstracted essence of man himself in his relation to
God.
There is, then, a critical Heraclitean polarity of identity and operation;
noun and verb; stasis and flux, implicit from the very beginning of this
embryogenesis of the concept of mathematics and number, and we will find
it recurring throughout … and as we have already seen in the Univocity
Framework.i*
From the aspect of the boundless absolute, no number exists. Like Form
emerging from the concept of the formless, number emerges from the
numberless—the finite from the Infinite, and representation from sub-
representation. ii The sole purpose of number is the interrelation of
modifications or differentiations as abstract pure-relational categories in the
relative world of form—specifically between those found at the interface of
the observer and the observed. Thus without modifications and their
perceived boundaries numbers would never evolve, there would be no
distinct “objects” to count and numbers would serve no purpose.
Number is a tool for dimensioning. Operationally, this begins with the
simplest (most symmetric) volumetric geometry, the sphere, as abstractly
representing the first extended or modelable number or distinct physical
magnitude. The primary number ‘1,’ as we saw in The Cycle of Unity,
appears as a boundary between immanence and transcendence, and as the
basic modal infinite.iii From this first volumetric number we have an identity
and a scale to modelably replicate and interrelate all the other numbers, and
this interrelation of predefined unit numbers is the transitive axis (see
Figure 24, below). However, given that each unit-identity is composed itself
of a bounded infinite, then each composite number is a primitive infinite
number, whose infinity is simply encapsulated in the unit-identity itself. The
breaking of this encapsulation of infinity doesn’t occur operationally until
the invention of the ratio, in our holarchical EOTC of number and operation.
i
* See, Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID), p186.
ii
This is not a temporal priority, but a logical one. One cannot conceive of form without something
to be formed, nor the finite without the infinite (see Spinoza). But it must always be understood
that this is a polarity. The Numberless (infinite) turns around number, just as Emptiness turns
around Form, and Substance around its modes.
iii
As Shakespeare’s Hamlet says, “…I could be bounded in a nut-shell, and count myself a king of
infinite space…”
Page | 311
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 312
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
… or basic “matter-units” in physical reality (e.g. atoms)
ii
Plato’s descent from the “forms” to “matter” lies buried in this polarity between the elemental
monads and their compounds and emergent representations.
Page | 313
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 314
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
Relating to pleasure and pain
ii
* See, The “Labyrinth of the Continuum” and the Principle of Nondual Rationalism p71.
iii
This flatland is a tacit function of a proto-rational, trans-biased neo-Cartesianism generated as the
shadow-element of the aborted rationality of modernity. And so the proto-rational Descartes is
enfolded in the “History of Philosophy” as the “father of modernity” or rationalism rather than the
fully rational/modern Spinoza or the mostly rational/modern (and secretly Spinozist) Leibniz.
Page | 315
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Figure 26: The Image of the Trans-Bias in the Cartesian Graph and the Identity Line:
Note how the graph of immanence in the inverse-identity line crosses the unit
boundary in its outward mapping of the immanent/transcendent infinity.
Page | 316
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
And of course this is a function of pragmatism in that it would be extremely difficult to make such
an unbiased graph system, let alone make it the basis of mathematics. This is the real, physical basis
behind the trans-bias, and again the point is merely to acknowledge it and explore its implications
and affects on mathematics and philosophy as a whole.
Page | 317
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
The trans-bias, by the way, also shows up as a positive bias on the number line and in additive and
multiplicative operations, as we will see.
Page | 318
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
This is a spatial line, or a vector from the operation of set-generation, as opposed Fuller’s
essentially temporal vectors made from tracing a unit through its motion in space.
Page | 319
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
With the first coupling of unit-identity and operation (the 1 and the
operation of addition), the infinite set of our “numerical identities,” are
formed, as the set-aspect (or set-generator) of counting by ones. This
inherently indefinite operation gives us our first “infinite set,” the natural
numbers.
In mathematics, there is a relation between sets and operations known as
“the closure property.” It states that a set is closed, with respect to an
operation, if those operations, on any of its elements or subsets (our Natural
numbers so far), return only other elements within the set. If an operation
on a set, however, produces a value that does not exist within the set, then
the closure of that set is “violated” by that operation. Given that our set of
Natural numbers is infinite, or unbounded, and that if you add any Natural
number with any other, you merely get a larger natural number, therefore,
with respect to addition the Natural numbers are closed.
Counting is a function of unit-addition, or the addition of unit-identities:
1+1+1+1 … . It is the first stratum of a recursive layering of addition, which
is the first mathematical operation of agglomeration, and it generates its
own infinite set (the Natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, …) with its own closure
property with respect to the first operation of addition (and recursive
addition or multiplication). So we see here that the first number-set, the
naturals, is generated by the first operation, addition, a mathematical form
of unit-agglomeration. We can already see the trans-trans-bias at work with
the first mathematical operation and its generated number-set being a form
of stepwise agglomeration, infinitely increasing scale, mapped to a transitive
number-line. At this point in the EOTC of mathematics we have only this
symbolic agglomeration and the infinite set of Natural numbers it generates.
This simple operation, however, hides an important polarity and a
default directed bias; that of input and output and the trans-bias toward
increasing agglomeration entirely bypassing the immanence within the unit-
closure upon which this whole process is erected. This implicit uni-directed
polarity, as we will see, directly encodes agglomeration as the trans-bias
transcended-and-included in mathematics and the pre-rational Cartesian
graph system, as it maps, by default, the aspect of agglomerative growth in
evolutionary transcendence to the transitivity of the natural-through-
integer, or pre-rational numbers. If we break this primary unit-addition
process down to its visual/visceral real-world experiential elements from
which it evolved in the first place, we can begin to see the simple
input/output polarity in action. [To make it quicker to read, we will often
call the input/output polarity, simply the “iopol,” although we will transition
into it gently, to aid in quick memorization.]
Page | 320
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Figure 29: The Implicit Input/Output Polarity (Iopol) of Addition and Subtraction:
In this figure we can see that addition is a reversed subtraction, in the triune
movement of the unit-identities from the hidden implicit set int o the explicit natural
numbers.
Imagine that there exist two sets of units; one that consists of a single unit,
our selected unit-identity (1), and another which consists of a pile of
undifferentiated unit-identities (See Figure 29, above). The pile is sitting
hidden in the background, and it is our implicit input set from which we will
draw in order to out-put our agglomerating and differentiating number in
the process of unit-addition, or counting, creating, in the process, the set of
natural numbers.
So in order to add a number to our explicit unit in the first place—to
make our first step from the pre-numerical 1 and into the natural
numbers—we must first draw from our implicit set (hidden in the
background of mathematical thought), composed merely of undifferentiated
unit-identities. So we see this simple polarity in the processes of addition
that implies, and even necessitates a hidden subtraction from the
undisclosed, and uncounted set of unit-identities. This is the polarity of
addition and subtraction as a function of the implicit input/output polarity
(iopol). As any unit-identity is counted and added to the set of natural
numbers, it is simultaneously subtracted from the implicit input set. (see
Figure 29, above) This is another aspect of Kant’s operator of existence,
drawing the possible into the light of the actuality of existence before which
any predicates can be assigned.
Page | 321
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 322
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Note that the set of natural numbers, generated by the first operation of
unit-addition, was initially “closed” without zero, and the closure of the set of
Natural numbers is only “violated” with the inversion of the input/output
polarity (iopol) in the second operation, subtraction, which led to zero. Note
also that even though visually, physically and causally you can’t subtract any
more unit-identities from zero as nothingness, the operation of
subtraction—abstracted in the mind into symbolic relations (and on the
abacus rod)—can indeed continue, such as, for example, when we imagine it
as a sort of debt to be repaid when you do get a positive amount of unit-
identities in your explicit set. It can also be visualized on the abacus as
adding more unit-identities to the left-hand, negative set from some other
implicit set. Therefore, not only does the iopol inversion of subtraction open
up to us the important concept of nothingness, the cipher, but it opens up
the physically imaginary, but extremely (and fiscally) useful, realm of
negative numbers.
So, with the inversion of the iopol to reach the identical-opposite of
addition in subtraction, we get the set of whole numbers, with the addition
of zero, and then we get the integers as we bypass the immanence inside of
each unit-identity and move into the transitive operational polarity implicit
in the set-generating aspects of addition and subtraction.
Page | 323
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Just like the first finite unity or relative unit-identity was generated by the
noun-verb coupling of a pre-mathematical division or interface of the I/T
uni-axis and its absolute identity in the ONE-ALL (recall our Cycle of Unity),
so we have already seen that the first set of numbers, the naturals, was
generated by the noun-verb, identity-operation coupling of “unit-addition”;
i.e. 1+1+1+1… . This is the first level of addition, implicit in the Natural
numbers themselves as the “first dimension” of number. It is characterized
Page | 324
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 325
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
It is my current assumption and discovery that the unconscious accidental conflation between
these two unknown operational axes causes perhaps all of the known paradoxes in ancient and
modern Western meta-/mathematics, as we have already begun to see. We will address many more
of them as we continue to explore this holarchical unfolding of number and operation.
ii
* Recall The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 326
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 327
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
infinity of the transitive-axis, rather than to the uncountable infinity and full
continuity of the Immanent/Transcendent axis.
In this way, our recursive unit-addition in the set-generation of the
Naturals and digits, can also simply be called unit-multiplication, and we can
see that multiplication and iteration already exists implicitly with the set-
generation of the first numbers. This is why the number 1 is the
“multiplicative identity.” It is already implicit as the unit-identity in each of
our digits because, for example, the number 8 is already the unit-identity
iterated or multiplied 8 times. Multiplying by the unit-identity, then, simply
starts again at the beginning of the process that led to the generation of the
digits in the first place.
Multiplication is a pure-relational automated synthesis; one input
iterated according to the value of the second. In this sense, but very loosely,
multiplication can be seen as a doubled addition, acting in two dimensions,
instead of one. See Figure 32, below.
Page | 328
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
* See, Four-Dimensionality: Trans-Biased vs. Immanent/Transcendent, p352.
Page | 329
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Because the ratio opens up the implicit input of the enfolded unit-identical
1st level to the infinite variability of the numerical identities (digits), the
ratio begins operation on the VL-axis of scale, the uncountable I/T axis from
which the unit-scale was implicitly defined in the first place. In division, as
we can see in Figure 33 above, commutativity is absent because the order of
input determines the direction of a process of unit-scale remapping (our
expanding/contracting holonic solidus/vinculum, below). The divided
number, the numerator or dividend (thin blue lines), retains the implicit
default input scale and the active frame of reference of the value of the
number itself, and the divisor (thick red lines) then remaps itself as a
Page | 330
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
comparison to any two integers, that they “appear” identical in all practical
applications, but beneath appearances they have a singular difference. Thus
again we can see a direct correspondence between rationality in
mathematics and rational philosophy, metaphysics, epistemology and
ontology. The rational level in all of them operates on our I/T axis and its
category-pulverizing, re-mapping acategorical imperative, breaking beyond
the rigid distinctions of the numerical identities and opening up to the
infinite difference within.i*
We can see in this iopol reversal, then, a sort of ratcheting, back-and-
forth saw-tooth kind of cycle in our transcending-and-including holarchy
and embryogenesis of identity (number) and operation. Every time we
break the initial agglomerative bias of the transitive mapping of
transcendence,ii* and invert the implicit order of input and output, we move
to the next level of the holarchy.
This implicit polarity and trans-bias of input and output can be seen very
clearly in the asymmetry of the fact that it is easier to multiply than to
divide.iii The Babylonians, for example, compiled tables of division answers
in the form of 1/n for n integers, for the simple reason that division is much
more difficult to do on the fly than multiplication.iv¥ Multiplication/division
is asymmetric with respect to unit-closure. Multiplication recursively and
holarchically builds upon initial unit-closure, and division breaks it open in
the iopol reversal. This polar level of identity and operation exists between
the two ‘orthogonal’ axes—the transitivity of multiplication (with its
recursive expansion of the unit- and numerical-identities) and
immanent/transcendent (with its pulverization of numerical identity into
the intensive forces).
The division of the unit-number into the rational or fractional set,
reminds us that division of the immanent axis, from a unity into a polarity,
the within and without, is the first operation of mathematics in the setting of
the unit-magnitude. Just as in the Triune Infinite, the modal infinity is the
interface between the I/T and transitive axes, so too division and
multiplication function as a map (relational system of application) between
the transitive and I/T axes. Provided that the operational magnitudes are
greater than the unit number and the ratios result in clean integers, the
i
* See, Nondual Rational-Empiricism and the Acategorical Imperative, p62.
ii
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
iii
It may also be seen, in another way, in function offsets, with the asymmetry between the offsets of
input (x) and output (y). For example, take the function x + y = 6; offsets made to the input
parameter, x, such as plugging (x+3) into x, shift the graph in the negative direction—minus 3 units
on the x-axis—whereas those on the y (output) axis, shift it in the positive direction. This asymmetry
is a function of seeing one direction (trans-trans), from implicit input (recall our hidden realm of
input unit-identities used to subtract from in the process of addition) to explicit output, in the
implicit polarity of input and output.
iv¥
Bell, Development of Mathematics, p. 31
Page | 332
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
* See, Multiplication Through Division, p324.
Page | 333
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Trans-Rationality of the Irrational Numbers, p365.
Page | 334
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 335
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 336
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Figure 34: The Image of Absolute Value (or the absolutely valuable image):
The function of absolute value truncates the multiplicative plane into the intensive
forces transcended-and-included tacitly with the unit-identity, and explicitly with the
move into the Rational numbers and the new origin and identity of the multiplicative.
Zero, or the cipher, as we can already see, denotes at least two different
meanings in mathematics. It has an inherently binary nature due to the fact
that there are two fundamental or pre-operational VL-axes underlying
mathematics; the transitive and the immanent-transcendent. But each of the
Page | 337
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* Recall The (Binary) Cycle of Unity (p254), and the interface of the I/T uni-axis of the ONE-one.
Page | 338
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 339
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The initial orthogonal distinction between the transitive and I/T axes—and
their respective operations of addition/subtraction and
multiplication/division—perhaps finds its most lucid illustration in the
comparison and contrast between the additive and multiplicative inverses
and their respective identities. This clarity demonstrates the validity of the
assignments of addition/subtraction and multiplication/division to their
respective transitive and immanent/transcendent axes.
At this point there is some potential con-fusion that must be averted with
the different meanings of the term “identity”. Identities, used in conjunction
with the operations—e.g. additive and multiplicative identities—are
effectively nulls with respect to that operation. They are the numbers that
leave no effect on the operation itself, but return the identity of the other
input number; e.g. 3 + 0 = 3 or 3 x 1 = 3. So we have here a distinction
between categorical identities (e.g. the unit and numerical identities) and
operational identities (e.g. the multiplicative and additive identities). The
operational identities return the categorical identities in any operation.
The additive inverse of any number is its negative or inverse-identical
(e.g. x and –x). But the inversion of addition ultimately operates through the
subtraction, from zero (the additive operational-identity and implicit origin
of the transitive-axis), of its numerical-identical (i.e. 3 and 0 - 3). This
inversion process, for the transitive axis, operates symmetrically about
i
* See, Reconnecting the Lost Thread of Mathematical Rationalism: Spinoza, Leibniz, Immanence and
the Calculus, p400
ii
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
Page | 340
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 341
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
These terms and inverses of each level not only have different intrinsic
origin points, but they limitlessly “approach” different intrinsic “limits” on
either end of their respective number-line axes. For the additive, the limits
in the unlimited are the negative and positive transitive infinities
(“unboundaries”) of the integers, and for the rational it is immanent-zero
and the positive infinity of transcendence.i
The negative and positive (oppositional) signs that can occur in rational
and multiplicative numbers, as we have seen, get there by being
transcended-and-included from the additive and transitive layer. Because
the negative sign, and negativity, or opposition in general, is not native to the
I/T axis of the rational (again we see the correlation with Deleuze’s intensive
forces of univocity)—but even more critically because the I/T axis itself is
not fully operational in mathematics—the transcension-and-inclusion of the
transitive-axis at the higher level of powers and roots generates the non-
operational, non-modelable and non-conceptual transitive axis of the
imaginary numbers, in the pre-rational context of the Cartesian/Euclidean
rectilinear default geometrical model for numeration, as we will see in more
depth below.
Note that the addition of like signs always results in a number of that same
sign, leading further in the agglomerative direction of either the negative or
positive transitive infinity (e.g. -3 + -3 = -6 and 3 + 3 = 6 ), rather than
deglomeration toward the additive origin-identity at zero from either
oppositional direction. Note as well that with the addition of different signs
it is the number with the greater absolute value that determines the sign of
the result (e.g. 3 + -6 = -3 ).
With multiplication as a recursive addition/subtraction, however, there is
an apparent non-intuitive shift away from this straightforward
agglomerative operation. Unlike addition/subtraction, multiplication of like
signs (whether positive or negative) always leads to a positive number, while
multiplication of unlike signs always leads to a negative. This is not because
multiplication is fundamentally different from addition, but because
multiplication is actually a new emergent layer, operating at the higher
(transcended-and-included) level of recursion, as an automated, or doubled
form of addition/subtraction. For example, take the equation, -3 x -3. In
i
Note that here we again see the overlap of the positive transitive and transcendent infinities in the
default trans-trans bias as seen explicitly in the identity line. See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias,
p312.
Page | 342
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 343
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 344
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 345
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 346
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
The mult/div level is the interface between the transitive add/subtract level
and the immanent/transcendent power/root level. In a sense, while
mult/div held one agglomerative foot (mult) on the trans-trans identity axis
and the other foot (div) slipped into the hidden immanent uncountable
infinity of the I/T axis, not operationalized on the default pre-rational
Cartesian graph, roots and powers operate fully on the I/T axis. This is seen
in the fact that multiplication can modelably operate on the negative
transitive numbers while such operation at the levels of powers and roots
leads to the ambiguity of the square-root property and ultimately to the
unmodelable axis of the “imaginary numbers.” It takes the second-order
recursion of powers and roots to reveal the instability at the heart of the
mult/div level as seen in the numerical-identity and ambiguity between
multiplying numbers of like signs (either positive or negative).i*
Furthermore, this operation of the root/power level upon the I/T axis is
also seen in the graphs of powers and roots in that they can never line up
exactly with the trans-trans identity line (unless their power is strictly that
of the additive/multiplicative levels, i.e. 1), but can only approach it, being
fundamentally non- or trans-linear. In this sense as well, the first power of
the exponent is the representation of the implicit unit-closure transcended-
and-included at the power/root level. The unit-closure is also seen in the
fact that all numbers other than 0 taken to the power 0 are found to be 1.
There is a unique place for both zero and one at the power/root level. This
is the transcension-and-inclusion of the previous origin-identities seen in
the fact that all power and root functions of the form y = xn—which have not
transcended-and-included any transitive x or y off-sets—must pass through
both zero and one (for both x and y), our transitive and I/T origin-identities,
respectively. See Figure 38, below.
The instability between the oppositional forces of the default transitive
and the new intensive forces of the I/T is made manifest with the automated
recursion of multiplication in the power functions. And we can see the
oppositional transitive-axis itself and its integers, standing out in the context
of the rational and its intensive forces in the instability of the powers in
Figure 38, below.
i
* See, The Kernel of the Trans-Trans Asymmetry and Instability at the Crossroads of the Transitive
and I/T Axes, p340.
Page | 347
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 348
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Note that with the powers, and thus with multiplication itself, there is an
effectively infinite favoring of positive, or intensive forces, as opposed to the
negative and oppositional. This is seen in the fact that only with the exact
integer values of the odd powers do we see the recurrence of the transitive
identity line between the positive and negative infinity of the pre-rational.
In even-integer powers (ultimately meaning multiplication by like signs, or
multiples thereof), the trans-trans identity is truncated to the absolute value
of the multiplicative (y) axis and mapped in a mirror image, rather than in
the directionality of the identity axis. On the graph, the curves of the rational
values infinitely approaching the integer powers appear identical. For
example, the graph of x1.99999 appears nearly identical to that of x2.00001 and
since they aren’t integers, they map exclusively in the purely agglomerative
or intensive upper-right quadrant.i
In other words, in a purely random search through the deep infinity of
the space of graphs of powers with rational exponents, it is virtually
infinitely improbable that you will stumble upon one that maps to an integer
power and displays the trans-biased identity axis or directionality between
the upper-right and lower-left quadrants. In this way, curve B in the
diagram below is still infinitely misleading in that the horizontal lines are
infinitely thicker than the actual “infinitely thin” or “zero-dimensional” lines
that they represent.
The reason that non-integer powers of negative x do not show up on the
graph, however, is that they involve a mixture of powers and roots; or
transitive/agglomerative and immanent/transcendent functionality. The
forces of immanence, remember, are forces of intensity, rather than
opposition, and it was the first move onto the I/T axis in the ratio which
pulverized the unit-identity transcended-and-included in the integers,
bringing us intrinsically to the forces of intensity of the rational. So it is
ultimately because the rational number-line is operating on the intensive
axis of immanence and transcendence that rational roots only appear in the
upper-right intensive quadrant.
Take, for example, the value of 2.5 in the exponent. This is actually a
combination of 2 and ½. We have seen that in the exponent the rational
polarity of the solidus is mapped to the next higher operational polarity, the
roots and powers, for the base. And so the rational exponent of ½ is actually
the root 2 of x, or the square root of x. Given the positive-negative ambiguity
of multiplication by like signs (translated at the next higher level in the
onion of operations as “even powers”), and that it can never lead to negative
numbers, then –x is meaningless as a result of an even root … except on the
“imaginary axis,” as we will see below.
i
The Cartesian quadrants are obviously not to be confused with Wilber’s AQAL quadrants.
Page | 349
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Because the powers and roots have begun to operate fully on the I/T axis,
and because they have fully transcended-and-included the transitive-axis,
there is a necessary interface or transition that must be explored between
the initial oppositional forces and countable infinity of the transitive-axis,
and the intrinsically intensive forces of the I/T axis and its nondual-rational
positive and uncountable infinity.
The branching point of the imaginary axis is the square-root property,
and the deeper-level ambiguity of multiplication by like signs; our kernel of
trans-trans instability. Because it is impossible to derive an even-root of a
negative number—all like-sign multiplication leads to a positive number—
therefore the graphs of even-roots of negative values of x end up in the
undefined land spawned by this oppositional-ambiguity intrinsic to
multiplication itself. In this way, powers, operating exclusively on the
multiplication of like numbers with like signs, can only interface partly with
the transitive-axis and its forces and signs of opposition.
Page | 350
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
* See, Coordinates on the Immanent-Transcendent Axis, p142
Page | 351
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
ii¥
http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ImaginaryNumber.html
Page | 352
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 353
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
http://mathworld.wolfram.com/ImaginaryAxis.html
Page | 354
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 356
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 357
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
One of the advantages of this table is that you need only one row of digits by
which to multiply. Each number is multiplied by another number (or itself)
from the same set. Indeed, in this way, it becomes instantly recognizable
that powering is a numerical recursion or tautology of sorts, because you
don’t need two different versions of the same number by which to multiply,
i
Lauritzen’s main row went from 0-9, but I thought the zero row was a bit boring and useless:
0000000000
Page | 358
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
but only that number by itself. And further, this shows that even if
multiplication is a doubling that takes us into the domain of the plane (as
discussed in Multiplication Through Division), then by no means is this plane
inherently square, or rectilinear. Indeed, as we will see, there are very
strong structural reasons to consider that the triangle, not the square, is
inherently planar, mainly because three vertices is the minimum needed for
any plane, and also that the triangle is the only polygon with inherent
structural stability. Another clear and intuitive example of this distinction—
where triangling and tetrahedroning is more fundamental and accurate than
squaring as a geometrical instantiation of the self-multiplication of
numbers—can be seen in the fact that distortions of the squared grid always
produce sub-squares of different shape and unequal area, whereas those of
the triangle grid are always exactly the same shape and always the same size
in relation to the parent shape. See Figure 43, below, also adapted from
Fuller’s own diagram.
Page | 359
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 360
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 361
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 362
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
first constraints. Now add a third constraint, forming a triangle and the
sphere is only free to move in a line through the center of that triangle. Add
one more constraint, a fourth, forming the frame of a tetrahedron, and
suddenly the sphere can’t displace at all.
Figure 46: 4-D Restraints: “Four Vectors of Restraint Define Minimum System ”:
Adapted from Fig. 401.01, of Synergetics. “Investigation of the requirements for a
minimum system.”
Page | 363
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
Biblio-note.
ii¥
http://bfi.org/node/560
Page | 364
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Page | 365
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 366
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
i
Intuitionists, following Kronecker, see all numbers greater than the integers as functions.
Page | 367
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
Wikipedia: irrational number: <http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Irrational_numbers>
ii
Though it may indeed be the case, as Fuller seems to argue, that the frequency of our encounters
with mathematical irrationality (as well as probability) are a function of having “come in through the
attic window” of the transitive-axis and mapped all of number and reality to the perpendicular limits
thereof. The number pi, is a classic example, for Fuller.
iii
Open Question: What is the significance of the fact that the first two irrational numbers are the
square-roots of 2 and 10? Does it show the limits of a more rational, or immanent/transcendent,
base-nine system underlying the transitive base-ten, as Bucky intimated (e.g. “casting out nines”)?
What has this to do with the symmetrical Scheherazade numbers?
Page | 368
THE HOLARCHICAL UNFOLDING OF NUMBER AND OPERATION
Arthur continues:
Here Cantor alludes to the fact that just as irrationals can be conceived as
limits of infinite sequences of rational numbers, so transfinite numbers
can be conceived as limits of infinite sequences of natural numbers, in
each case added in immediately after the sequence they limit. If one
rejects transfinites, what right has one to allow the extension of the
number system to include irrationals? A reluctance to jettison the theory
of the real line thus explains the widespread acceptance among modern
mathematicians of the Cantorian theory of the infinite.
In Interface Mathematics there is no jettisoning necessary of any of these
operations, but merely a reinterpretation in a more coherent, more evolved,
integral, and rational context. Rational numbers are, more properly,
functions of recursive (non-stepwise) division (rooting) or relation between
integers which, while opening up fully the uncountable infinity of
immanence, still give the finite and final result of a number as boundary or
precise location in the mathematical continuum unreachable by rational or
stepwise operations. Irrational numbers, on the other hand, are the
consequence of higher level functions or relations (i.e. the square-root
function with its “2nd tier” level inversion of the input/output polarity), that
fall between the transcended-and-included transitive limits of the rational
numbers. They are the “Dedekind cuts” in terms of limits of transitive
representation on the real number-line into decimals or binaries, which give
actual infinities (unbounded answers), not final numbers as boundaries.
i¥
Cantor, 1887-8
Page | 369
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The fact that the irrational numbers give actual infinite (unbounded) results
demonstrates that the power/root level is operating fully (if not optimally,
coming from the aborted rationality of the default Cartesian system) on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, and has fully opened to the uncountable
immanent infinite neglected by the trans-bias of default agglomerative or
stepwise transcendent operation. Thus, like Cantor’s “transfinite numbers,”
irrational numbers are aspects of the infinite interfacing with the finite
function that generated the number; they are bounded aspect infinities, not
numbers as finite boundaries. As modal aspect infinities, they are bounded
only with respect to the transitive axis, and unbounded in the immanent
direction, identically opposite to Cantor’s transcendently unbounded infinite
numbers. As Deleuze says, in The Fold:
The irrational number implies the descent of a circular arc on the straight
line of rational points, and exposes the latter as a false infinity, a simple
undefinite that includes an infinity of lacunae: that is why the continuous
is a labyrinth that cannot be represented by a straight line.
Thus given that the “secret of the rational” is the positive infinite of the
immanent (as opposed to the regressive disaster of the medieval notion of
the infinite), the “irrational numbers” are “essentially” and deeply rational.
Perhaps undeniably, if we are allowing infinities to be numbers, as we are in
this post-Cantor world, then the “irrational numbers” are more correctly
“trans-rational” or “immanent infinite-numbers”—the mathematical
instances of the bounded or immanent aspects of The Infinite. And so, here
we find yet again a transcendent-bias in that immanent, boundless numbers
are considered non-rational, or “irrational” and transcendent infinite
numbers are naturally just infinite numbers. In other words, there is a ready
place for the transcendent forms of the infinite, but the immanent
manifestations, in this transcendent-biased pre-rational system, have no
place except in the negative (irrational) form. The positive infinity of the
secret of the rational has yet no home in the pre-rational, representational
system.
Page | 370
Page | 371
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 372
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Figure 47: The Holarchical Evolution of Number and Operation in the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System:
Following from the main VCS diagram —with transitive-planes visualized as orthogonal
to the I/T axis—addition and subtraction begin on such a transitive -plane.
Multiplication/division begin to transition onto the I/T axis, moving toward parallel
with it, and the power/root level operates fully on the I/T axis. Note the “vestigial”
transitive-axis of the imaginary. In the transitive, pre -rational space of the Cartesian
th
system, the 4 dimension—intrinsic to rational dimensioning itself (see Fuller ’s
Synergetics)—has no geometrical grounding. In Synergetic geometry, with its explicit
grounding in the rational I/T axis, there is no need for this vestigial transitive -
/perpendicular axis, so it drops off. Inset: The evolutionary path of number is outlined
as it moves from the default transitive mapping of transcendence in additive
agglomeration and the naturals, into the successive violations of closure in the
input/output polarity (iopol) inversions of the corresponding levels of agglomerative
recursion. From the naturals, the iopol is inverted (initially toward deglomeration) to
give us the integers and then the iopol of the operation of multiplication is inverted to
give us the rationals, following which the iopol of powering is inverted to give us the
irrational square-roots.
Page | 373
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
This same basic evolutionary movement and general form can also be
traced, and more accurately so, as a three-dimensional vector along with the
dimension of time (see Figure 48-A, below); 1) from the undifferentiated
ONE-ALL into the ONE-one I/T uni-axis and then 2) quickly shunting into the
orthogonal laws and rules of transitivity mapped to transcendence (the
trans-trans-bias), and then 3) only through the holarchical embryogenesis of
function and identity (operation and number) moving steadily (emerging
and transcending) toward operation again on the originary I/T axis.
In Nondual Rationalism, recall, there is a shift from the regressive pre-
rational notion of infinity (which sees immanence, yin or Emptiness as a
foundational disaster), to an affirmation of a “deep infinity” (as M.C. Escher
intuits it) or, as Deleuze calls it, a positive infinity as the “secret of the
rational.” The main axis in this core diagram (diagram A) represents this
“positive infinity,” operationalized in the VCS as the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. In the animated version on the SpinbitZ
website (http://www.spinbitz.net/) there are points of light moving in both
immanent and transcendent directions from the central transitive plane,
representing the directions of transcendence and immanence operating
simultaneously in transcendence or evolution. In the static version, this
polar, or bi-directional evolutionary motion is denoted by the spiraling
arrows.
Note that the shape of the spiral isn’t important for the evolution itself,
and is a drastic generalization (largely for aesthetic purposes) in an already
vastly over-simplified linearity. In mathematics, for example, the shape of
the emergent curve would have an underlying quantized saw-tooth wave
pattern, as the number set-closures are successively violated by the
corresponding iopol inversions of the new operations—and number and
operation ratchet themselves into higher and higher functions in tandem, as
we will see below.
In psychological or spiritual development, as well, the shape would have
all sorts of stops and starts, different velocities and directions and various
paths running simultaneously as the diverse lines of intelligence evolve at
different rates, from a range of starting places, through many levels and
plateaus of being.
Page | 374
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
A. B.
Page | 375
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
axis. These transitive planes unfold or emerge from the I/T axis as already
transcendent forms or levels of reality, but forms and operations thereupon
are oriented and configured by default—due to the trans-bias and the
transitive mapping of transcendence—to instantly move away from it,
conceptually, or representationally. The forms and operations are initially
(and very generally) blind to the I/T axis (and immanence in general)
because it is pre-representational and pre-operational and the “fitness
function” of evolution is initially invested in the mapping and
operationalization of transcendence via the transitive forms and forces of
categorical identity and opposition; rudimentary polarization into simplistic
terminals and opposites.
In philosophy, this initial transitivity corresponds to such things as
“essentialism,” dualism or foundationalism—basically superficial and
relative-bound absolutized, categorical thinking. Starting with the unit-
closure of the personal identity and the platonic forms and absolutized
categories, as well the transitive forms of the various foundationalisms and
dualisms, we then move onto the I/T axis with the pulverizing of the closure
of the self-identity of the forms—in the acategorical imperative of the key
rationalists (and the nondualists long before them)—opening up the
Emptiness of the positive infinity of the rational to the univocal unity of the
ONE-ALL and its Immanent/Transcendent axis.
In consciousness, the epistemic (representation) and spirituality, the
transitive corresponds first to egoism (and the Cartesian cogito-interface),
then, moving outward (transitively and transcendently) as the self-boundary
expands, we move simultaneously up the spiral (transcendence). But,
according to the principle of immanence in transcendence and the positive
infinity, as evolution progresses, or as transcendence moves forward, it
begins to turn from the transitive mapping of transcendence and move
closer and closer, full-circle, back to its origin (the integral capacity) on the
I/T axis and hence toward immanence, the “deep infinity,” at the same time.
In meditation itself, the goal is indeed to get closer and closer to this axis
whose temporal aspect, recall, is the “eternal NOW,” Spinoza’s sub specie
aeternitatis, participating in eternity in the instantaneous “intellectual love
of God.” (See Figure 10, repeated below from p191.) This goal is the “flat-
lining” of living in the moment, free from the turbulence of the categorical
forms of memory and anticipation, the illusions of the past and the future,
often absolutized with disastrous effect.
Page | 376
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Figure 10: Time Tree: Figure repeated from Univocity and the Eternal NOW (p191)
Page | 377
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
This path in the physical sphere moves from the unit-closure of atoms, into
the transitive laws of molecular agglomeration, into the higher complexities
of intelligent evolution, into primitive cultures with tool-making from vastly
agglomerated numbers of unit-atoms.
Note also, that only with trans-rationality, in its techno-evolutionary
form, does evolution begin to break the unit-closure of the atom and move
more fully into immanence and transcendence simultaneously in their
explorations and manipulations of the micro and macro cosmos. Beneath
the level of the atom, we have an explosion of more and more “particles,”
which are more like wave resonances, constantly changing form into other
particles and most with very short-lived existences. These particles as
resonances are more properly seen as functions of the forces of intensity,
having not coalesced into singular, nucleated form (finite unities) in
opposition to others. These resonances have no self-consistent, self-
maintaining form and identity of their own (no Leibnizian “principle of
unity” and no Spinozan homeostatic relative essence), but come into being
as fleeting resonances, dissonances and harmonics from very specific
interactions and environments often in the break-down of particles with
real, nucleated, unitary identity, such as the proton or neutron.
The forces of opposition begin only when there is unit-closure into the
emergent, self-stabilizing forms of finite unity. This is when the Spinozistic
homeostatic, strange-attractor notion of “essence” and the Leibnizian
emergent “principle of unity” come into play.
Page | 378
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
A. B.
Page | 379
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 380
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 381
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Recall, that there are only two VL-axes in the Vision-Logic Coordinate
System. And recall also, from the section The Orthogonality of Inverses and
the Offset Origin-Identities (p341) that the origins and operational-identities
of each of the VL-axes are identical, and thus we call them origin-identities;
i.e. the additive identity is zero precisely because it is the origin (or center)
of the transitive-axis, and similarly, the multiplicative identity is one
precisely because it is the origin (or center) of the I/T axis.
Notice as well that the power/root level has no new origin-identity or
axis of its own, but appears to have simply integrated its use of the previous
two origin-identities and VL-axes. This integration can be seen in the fact
that graphed curves of powers (which have no transitive offsets), always go
through both zero and one. At the power/root level, recall, only the odd
integer powers of x reveal the identity line—the image of the trans-bias in
the transitive mapping of transcendence—as their basis. Also, there is an
infinite favoring of the intensive forces seen in the purely
agglomerative/intensive quadrant of the rational, non-integer powers
(expressible as roots) as well as in the multiplicative/agglomerative
absolute value line (reflecting off the x-axis back into y-positivity) as the
basis of the even integer powers. (Recall Figure 38, above, The Trans-Trans
Instability: p349.)
What then is the relation between these two VL-axes, their countable and
uncountable infinities, their origin-identities and their unities? i The
transitive and immanent/transcendent origin-identities, ‘zero’ and ‘one’
respectively, can be seen as symbiotic or interdependent (polar) functions of
one another in the interplay between the two VL-axes in the continuation of
the Cycle of Unity in the unfolding of mathematics into higher and deeper
levels of operation and number.
The I/T uni-axis (the ONE-one axis),ii* recall, is the pole between
uncountable infinity in its transcendent vs. immanent directions with
i
We’ll explore in great detail the interface and relation between the uncountable and countable
infinities of the two VL-axes in the section on Zeno’s paradoxes. See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning
and Triuning the Paradox, p432, and the subsection, Back to Zeno, p448.
ii
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 382
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
respect to a unitary position. In the very “center”i of these two endless omni-
directions is the arbitrarily defined interface and unit-magnitude—the
number ‘one’—the periapsis in our Orbit of Unity,ii* and the origin-identity
of the I/T axis of multiplication and division. In the first phase of this
unfolding of the cycle of origin-identities, the immanent pole of this Infinite
Unity is the origin and operational identity of the countable and stepwise
(agglomerative) transitive-axis as it converts the I/T interface into the finite
unity and primitive number one. This is the interface between the I/T and
transitive VL-axes, as this first boundary from the boundless is then both the
unity (or unit) of the transitive (additive), and the origin and operational-
identity (origin-identity) of the immanent/transcendent (multiplicative).
On the transitive axis, however, once
the unit has been defined for additive
operations, it is the absence of any
unit—our transitive-zero as negation—
which is the identity, thus bringing us
back (even if from a transitive
viewpoint) to the immanent pole of the
I/T axis as origin in the creation (and
inversely as the negation) of the first
unit. The rational zero as immanent-
positional aspect of The Infinite—
through the Principle of Absolute
Reversal, the Principle of Immanence in
Transcendence (yin in yang) and the
identity of opposites—then reflects into
its identical opposite, the ONE, our
Infinite Unity. This returns us full-
circle, dissolving the initial boundary-
division of relative polarity, our finite
unity, back into absolute or Infinite
Unity—dissolving the one (as the
interface of the ONE-one in the Cycle of
Unity) back into the ONE-ALL—and Figure 52: The Binary Cycle of
Origin-Identity and Unity:
dissolving our primitive number-as-
The unity of each axis (I/T and
boundary and dimension back into transitive) is the identity of the
infinite omni-non-dimensional other, and vice versa.
continuity. See Figure 52, right.
i
…every boundary is in the exact center of an infinite axis, whether it be that of the number-line or
that of infinite divisibility and the absolutely indivisible continuum. In the infinite, the “center is
everywhere and *the+ circumference nowhere.”
ii
* See, The Orbit of Unity, p260.
Page | 383
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The multiplicative identity and finite unity, “one,” originates from the
primary VL-axis of dimension and Infinite Unity (the I/T axis) as the first act
of dimensioning, whereas the additive identity “zero” dissolves the
boundaries of the unit-number and fades back into the implicit singularity of
the rational zero, reflecting through the PAR into Infinite Unity, completing
the circle, and triuning (or tuning) the polarity from Unity to finite-unit-
identity to Unity. The Unity of one level is the identity of the next, leading us
one into the other, between the finite and infinite forms of unity and identity.
The cycle is from unity to identity to unity. The unity of one level
becomes transcended-and-included as the identity of the next. But given
that there are only two VL-axes, two origin-identities and two unities, it
cycles in and out, off and on, from the absolute to the relative to the absolute;
from zero, to one and to zero again; and from I/T to transitive to I/T. But,
recall, when it is at zero, through the Principle of Absolute Reversal and
identity of opposites, it is at ONE, so it also cycles from ONE to one to ONE.
Our Cycle of Unity is our cycle of origin-identities, refracting into the prism
of the artifice of pure relation called Mathematics.
The immanent/transcendent and absolute unity is ONE, whose
immanent and operational pole is the rational zero. The transitive identity,
however, is also zero. In this sense, the transitive axis and relative scope
sees the ALL is ONE (in its immanent aspect) as “all is none”: the omni-non.
Within the relative scope of transitivity, the absolute or Infinite Unity is
invisible and inoperable, the cipher, the absence, our common notion of
emptiness, providing the inert identity of the transitive operations of
addition/subtraction. The Unity of the initial Immanent/Transcendent axis
is therefore the operational identity (or null) of the transitive axis which
transcends-and-includes it.
The transitive unity, that is derived in this process of unity-to-identity
conversion, is 1, which will be written as (1) to remind us that it represents a
volumetric, or spheroidal, bounded and finite unity. The rational or
multiplicative identity is also this same (1), which is now transcended-and-
included from the transitive unity as the solidus between the I and T of the
I/T axis. We will represent the rational identity herein as /(1) to remind us
that the transitive-unity (1) is transcended-and-included under the hidden
solidus of all rational and pre-rational numbers. Any numerical imbalance,
balanced on the point of origin, is still that original imbalance.
The immanent/transcendent or rational unity is the I/T axis itself, the
absolute or Infinite Unity, the unreachable ONE-ALL (ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE)
reached by way of the Principle of Absolute Reversal and the identity of
opposites. This Unity, in its transcendent form (inverted across the solidus
in the immanent position), can be represented by the infinity of division by
zero, the rational zero, or /0, which is numerically equal to ∞/1. Transitive
operation begins in converting immanent/transcendent Infinite Unity, ONE-
ALL, ∞/∞, or /0, to the transitive and finite unity, (1). And this coincides
Page | 384
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
i
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 385
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 386
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 387
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, The Image of the Trans-Trans-Bias, p312.
Page | 388
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 389
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
expanded solidus that fits the recursive ratio. This is how it breaks the
closure of the unit-identity quantizing the integers.i*
In this way division (rationality) includes and vastly transcends the
hitherto transitive, agglomerative and pre-rational functions of addition and
its recursion layer of multiplication. By inverting the quantizing process
across the input/output polarity, and violating closure with the unit
selection in the output rather than a hidden input, division reveals the I/T
axis hidden in the invisible unit-divisor of the integers and upon which the
unit was initially (even if unconsciously or pre-operationally) selected.ii*
And, as we have seen, the asymmetry of the closure property, with the iopol
inversion always breaking closure toward immanence, directly
demonstrates the trans-trans-bias.
It is only natural that the transitive axes were initially mapped to the
transcendent operations encapsulating the trans-trans-bias in the
transcend-and-include holarchy of mathematics. This is, after-all, a natural
objective-bias inherent in sensorial and conceptual operation, and therefore
in mathematical evolution. This image of the trans-bias illuminates why the
trans-cendent and trans-itive collapse into the one-to-one identity of the
common mathematical notion of “the infinite”—mapped as the identity
line—and reveals precisely why the immanent pole of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, represented on the immanent side of the
solidus, gets thrown in the waste-bin of the “undefined” and identified with
the cipher. As we can see on the graph, even the unit-identity itself, the root
trans-unit that got the ball rolling, is invisible from the trans-trans identity
axis and from multiplicative functions, whereas in the inverse-identical
operations of division, and even in the power/root operations, the curves
frame the implicit unit-solidus clearly. From the default trans-trans view,
the immanent pole appears as but an infinitely insignificant spec on the
straight path from one side of (trans-)infinity to the other. The trans-trans
line crosses an infinity of them with every interval, without batting an eye.
However, this infinite insignificance of the immanent axis, marked by a
zero in the “undefined” divisor, is an infinite oversight. The physicists of the
20th century found this out the hard way, stumbling in the dark of pre-
rational meta-mathematics, tacitly assuming the inert nullity of their “point-
particle approximations.” Many still haven’t figured out how and why their
“cipher in the snow”—the implicit singularity of the immanent location-
aspect of The Infinite—manifested its infinite energy, but we have seen,
through the Principle of Absolute Reversal, just how this can happen.
i
* Recall, Phase FOUR: Transitive Interfacing with the I/T Axis, p324.
ii
* Recall, Phase TWO: Unit-closure and the Finite Unit-Identity, p308.
Page | 390
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 391
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 392
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 393
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 394
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 395
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Unfolding in accord with the EOTC, the level of powers has enfolded within it
several different input/output polarities. At least two of these polarities can
be inverted at this level to give us a new function or operation. Recall that
enfolded at the level of multiplication and division is the
immanent/transcendent polarity of the solidus/vinculum. This is the
polarity that—at the offset level of the exponent—is inverted from its
default agglomerative function to give us the function of rooting (See Figure
57, below). We have seen this already in the rules of exponents as
demonstrated in the Onion of Operations, above, where taking the reciprocal
of the exponent (flipping it across the solidus) inverts the operation into
taking the root of the base.
Another iopol open for use at the power/root level, however, unfolds
because the level of powers is the first level of operation explicitly
recognized and operationalized as a function. This explicit operationality is
provided with the role of the exponent, and is the reason that this level is
considered “second-tier,” because it exposes and operationalizes its own
transcended-and-included polarities.
At this level, then, we can differentiate between two types of function; the
power function and the exponential function. Both of these functions use the
same underlying operational form of layered recursion, which we have
already explored at length and which we visualized in the diagram of the
onion of operations (recall Figure 37 above, p347). The power function, we
have already seen, simply takes the input variable x (which we will call the
domain input, to emphasize that x is the input of an entire domain) as the
base, and raises it to the arbitrary single input number n; e.g. x3. The
exponential function, on the other hand, takes the arbitrary input number n
(a single number rather than a domain) as the base, and raises it to the
variable domain-input x; e.g. 3x.
Page | 396
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Figure 57: Powers, Roots, Exponential and Logarithmic Functions and the
Input/Output Polarity:
The trans-rational or power level has a singular, transcend -and-include, holarchical
structure of inputs and outputs. It is the differential mapping of these input and
output structures to the various aspects of functions, such as the domain -input of the
x, and the single-input n, that allows for the new operations of the logarithmic and
exponential functions. Notice how switching the position of the x and y (input/output
of the function, reversing the direction of the arrows), in the bottom section, converts
between exponential and logarithmic functions, whereas merely taking the reciprocal
of the exponent, in the top section, converts between power and root operations.
Page | 397
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The key difference at this point, then—at this very same level of holarchical
structure, which we can map out visually (see Figure 57, above)—is where
the x, y or n is placed, and this in turn determines the directions and flows of
the various inputs and outputs emerging at this level of the EOTC of number
and operation. Notice how switching the position of the x and y—the
input/output polarity of the function—in the bottom section, converts
between exponential and logarithmic functions (reversing the direction of
the arrows), whereas merely taking the reciprocal of the exponent, in the top
section, converts between power and root operations.
Page | 398
AFTER-MATH: INTEGRATING THE DIFFERENTIATIONS FROM THE 2ND-TIER
Page | 399
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 400
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
i
* See, Spinoza’s Triune Infinite, p270.
ii
Zeno was really the first to explore immanence rationally and logically, and in its uncountable form.
See, Back to Zeno, p448.
iii
…and via the Principle of Nondual Rationality, indivisible…
iv
* (e.g. folded, using Deleuze’s term to simply unite the two)
Page | 401
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Though its roots extend into both eastern and western antiquity (India and
Greece), the essential elements of the modern calculus emerged from the
exploding progress of algebra and geometry in the 17th century. With the
requisite mathematical pieces finally in place, the birth of the calculus was
imminent. This happened independently through the work of both Leibniz
and Newton, though it is Leibniz who provided the current notation and
terminology (the “science of fluxions” apparently wasn’t catchy enough).
And, as we will see, Leibniz, with the covert help of Spinoza, provided the
embryo of the nondual-rational meta-mathematics to match it and solve its
pre-rational philosophical problems, which naturally persist to this present
day of the aborted and unfinished project of mathematical rationalism.
The calculus was designed for increasing the depth and accuracy of
mathematics in the physical sciences and specifically for dealing with rates
of change between the interacting variables of a continuous curve. The
context of the calculus is this continuity and immanent infinity inherent in all
“points” of the rational number-line. Indeed, the calculus fails when it
encounters a discontinuous function, and the stipulation of continuity is
written into the Fundamental Theorem of Calculus itself, as we will see
below.
This rational continuity, or the “labyrinth of the continuum,” as Leibniz
famously addressed it, also spawned the problematic “infinitesimals,” which
are numbers approaching “infinite smallness”.i The calculus, of both Newton
and Leibniz, relied upon these infinitesimals as the key to mathematically
dealing with the immanent infinity of division by zero (the rational zero)
inherent in its processes.ii
i
…the rational zero and immanent pole of the Immanent/Transcendent axis as seen oxymoronically
through the trans-bias…
ii
Note that the numerical value of division by zero is transcendent not immanent infinity. However,
this is directly because of the immanent infinity of the rational zero. The breaking through of the
unit-closure as the denominator goes below 1 and toward the unreachable rational zero causes the
reciprocal increase to infinity in overall value due to the inherent transcendent-bias of the natural
numbers.
Page | 402
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
For reasons we will explore shortly, the critical role of the infinitesimal
has since been taken over by the less problematic concept of the “limit,” in
the 1800’s, and it is increasingly described more abstractly by functions
today. Behind the facade of these more abstract operations and symbols,
however, the problem of the infinitesimal itself remains.
Naturally, the processes at the core of the calculus form a polarity; the
“derivative” and the “integral,” which is roughly that of analysis vs. synthesis,
respectively. These can also be seen in terms of their motion with respect to
the Immanent/Transcendent axis. The derivative approaches the desired
infinitesimal itself, analytically, immanently, breaking it down through a
process of recursive division. Examples include finding an “instantaneous
velocity,” which is an attempt to “derive” the slope at a point on a velocity
curve to the most precise degree, or smallest scale possible on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. The integral, on the other hand, deals with
the infinitesimal in the opposite direction, synthetically, or transcendently, as
a summation (as Leibniz put it), or an accumulation and integration, of
infinitesimals. Examples here include taking the area under a graph of a
continuously varying function as a summation and integration of
infinitesimal slices. These two processes are indeed the inverse of each
other, as demonstrated explicitly and formally by the Fundamental Theorem
of Calculus which states essentially that if one function is defined as the
integral of another continuous function, then differentiating the new function
returns the function you started with.
It is fascinating to note that this polarity of “derivative and integral” also
goes by the name of “differentiation and integration,” respectively. And, as
we have seen, differentiation and integration are fundamental to the
embryogenesis of the concept. In this case, “differentiation and integration”
are not only implicit in the embryogenesis of the operational concept of the
calculus, but explicitly transcended-and-included in its genetic and
operational make-up, and hence included as well in the formal
operationalization of mathematical rationalism into the body of
mathematics proper. The raw utility of the calculus, with its polarity of core
operations, is therefore an example of the utility of the differentiate-and-
integrate polarity of the embryogenesis of the concept itself.
So far this all sounds well and good. Indeed it is very well and good, as far as
the mathematics of calculus is concerned. The calculus is an extremely
powerful mathematical tool, and it is used routinely and critically in virtually
all scientific and technological fields, from economics to rocket science. And
hence it is even perhaps justifiable (at least pragmatically so) that
Page | 403
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 404
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
i
This is the classic case of the transcendent-bias because it is much more common to make this
mistake of bounding the unbounded in the immanent than in the transcendent direction; a
mathematical instantiation of foundationalism from the lofty perch of transcendent operations.
ii
… note the constant refrain of this oxymoron…
iii¥
John Stillwell Yearning for the Impossible, The Surprising Truths of Mathematics A.K. Peter, Ltd.,
Wellesley, Massachusetts, 2006], pp.99-100, qtd. in Ross
Page | 405
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
like to get rid of. As Stillwell puts it, “To many this is a compromise solution
which fails to explain why infinitesimals work.”
The problems with the infinitesimal, then, are not just philosophical
anymore, but mathematical, because mathematicians are influenced, and
rightly so, by the clamoring voices of philosophers. In order to temporarily
quiet the mathematical philosophers, the cumbersome dual notation was
invented to distance the calculus from the problematic infinitesimal hidden
within its form and history.
But Stillwell goes on to ask, “Is it possible to define and use genuine
infinitesimals?” There have been mathematical attempts, he shows, such as
Abraham Robinson’s nonstandard analysis, but none of them are “as simple
as the old Leibniz calculus of infinitesimals, and there is a continuing search
for a really natural system that uses infinitesimals in a consistent way.”
Given that philosophy is where the problems of the calculus began, then the
solution to the problem must also be largely philosophical. Recall that the
problematic definition given by Newton and Leibniz, according to academia,
is that the infinitesimal is not really zero, but the quantity just before it
reaches zero. And recall that it is objected that “there is no quantity ‘just
before’ zero,” since we are dealing with an infinite axis. “Either there is a
finite number ... or there is zero, in which case dy/dx is either meaningless or
indeterminate.’” Again, this is the vague and fuzzy “ghost of departed
quantities” criticism by the philosopher George Berkeley, et al, and it indeed
changed the course of the calculus, and arguably (if temporarily) for the
worse.
So how can we use Interface Mathematics and Nondual Rationalism to
give a coherent operational context and definition of the infinitesimal so that
its use could be acknowledged and reinstated to make life easy again for the
mathematician? The essentials of the answer should already be apparent to
most, but we’ll dive in deep and flesh it out in detail.
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
Page | 406
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
As Kelley L. Ross states in his Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz, “Calculus in the 17th
century was thought to deal with infinitesimal, or almost infinitely small,
quantities. Leibniz, as it happens, has very conveniently provided a
metaphysics to match this. No matter how small the quantity, there is a
monad there.”i¥ Indeed, the infinitesimal (rationally understood) is merely a
monad beyond, or beneath, the immanent horizon of the indefinite
mathematical imagination. ii And further, Leibniz ultimately saw the
infinitesimal—an “infinitely small” point represented mathematically as
zero—as a necessary fiction to operationally bridge the infinite gap of the
series, only “convergent” from a transitive frame of reference on the infinity
of the immanent/rational zero.
In Leibniz on Mathematics and the Actually Infinite Division of Matter,iii¥
Samuel Levey explains (my emphases),
Though Leibniz is on occasion prepared to talk of the infinitesimal as “an
infinitely small fraction or one whose denominator is an infinite number”
(GM 4:93), this is not his most considered account of the concept. The
most considered account, rather, is expressed when he writes of the
infinitesimal as an “incomparable magnitude,” a phrase he clarifies thus:
“these incomparable magnitudes . . . are not at all fixed or determined but
i¥
( http://www.friesian.com/leibniz.htm)
ii
This intrinsically volumetric aspect is also key to the definition of a point in Buckminster Fuller’s
Synergetic Geometry and it corresponds to Gerald Lebau’s “needle sharp point,” as we have seen.
iii¥
The Philosophical Review, Vol. 107, No. 1 (Jan., 1998), 49-96.
Page | 407
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Levey says:
In his later analysis of the continuum, Leibniz contends that the labyrinth
arises from confusing the character of matter [namely infinite divisibility]
with that of mathematical or geometrical continua: either supposing
i¥
Letter to Varignon, 1702. GM 4:91
ii¥
“GM 3:524, 551”
Page | 408
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
i
This, of course, is a temporal version of Zeno’s paradox, who’s solution also follows from a solution
to the labyrinth of the continuum, and the infinitesimal, which Leibniz found through Spinoza's
Triune Infinite. See, Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 409
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
* See, I/T Omni- and Uni-axes, p145.
ii
* See, Back to Zeno, p448.
Page | 410
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
Levey explains:
I have argued that Leibniz’s actual mathematics for calculating the sums
of infinite series encodes a certain conception of the infinite convergent
series, what I call “the mathematical conception,” according to which
there is a terminal element bounding the series at its diminishing end.
That terminal element is supposed to be the infinitieth term in the series,
and is itself an infinitesimal magnitude. We knew already that Leibniz
denies the existence of infinitesimals. We now see also that he denies the
existence of an infinite number. But the mathematical conception
evidently implies the existence of both. Thus, we see more than just a
puzzle about how to make sense of his views of the composition of
matter: Leibniz’s philosophical views about mathematics—his denials of
infinite and infinitesimal numbers—appear to be in conflict with the
commitments of his own mathematical practices. Something has to give if
coherence is to be maintained. In “Infinite Numbers,” a cluster of notes
dated to 10 April 1676, Leibniz confronts these difficulties and submits
the concept of the infinite convergent series and its use in mathematics to
close scrutiny. From this renewed inquiry into mathematics emerges a
stable and subtle philosophy of mathematics and philosophy of the
infinite, and in the process the passage to the later period of his 1676
mathematics is transacted.
In De Quadratura Arithmetica (1676) Leibniz says expressly that we
engage in a certain “fiction” when, in order to find the value of an infinite
quantity, we suppose that it is bounded (133), as in the example of the
last passage “something must be added” to the infinite series in order to
calculate its sum. That “something” does not in fact occur in the series.
The mathematical conception of the infinite series smuggles in a fictional
terminus under its interpretation of the rider ‘etc.’ or ‘to infinity’ that is
inevitably affixed to the expression of the series as “measured” or as
having a sum. Since that series does not in fact contain a last term, the
proposition involving its measured form engages directly (if tacitly) in a
fiction, and so must be said not to be rigorously true. ... Talk of the sum of
Page | 411
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
A 6.3:503
ii
Note that this is not the same Bounded or Modal Infinite from Spinoza's Triune Infinite.
iii
This is not to be confused with Fuller’s Operational Mathematics.
Page | 412
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
Page | 413
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
As we have seen, the extensionless point—in the context of division and the
ratio—is the rational or immanent zero; the immanent pole of the
immanent/transcendent uni-axis. As such, it can’t be “reached” or bounded
by any number or division. The infinitesimal, in other words—conceived of
as “the number right before reaching zero,” or an “infinitely small”
number—cannot exist. It can only be a convenient fiction. In Spinoza’s
Triune Infinite, as we have seen, the “point” is seen simply as the immanent-
local aspect of The Infinite;i an immanent infinity.
The “limit” in calculus—replacing the problematic “ghost of departed
quantities” (the infinitesimal)—therefore must be seen purely in the
function of operationalizing—i.e. finitizing, bounding or reaching—the new
immanent uncountable infinity of the I/T axis, broken open through the
immanent operations of the ratio and the root functions (as we have seen).
It must be seen simply as a tool or trick for integrating the new I/T axis into
the trans-biased bounding or numerating operations of pre-rational
mathematics transcended-and-included at the trans-rational level of the
calculus.
The limit is the “finitizing” leap across the infinite immanent/regressive
abyss in order to bring the infinite and uncountable I/T sum to a finite and
countable transitive end. This operational leap is philosophically warranted
herein because the immanent/transcendent is a polarity, and, by the identity
of opposites, every regressive immanent value is also progressively
transcendent from deeper values and possible frames of reference, and vice
versa. Indeed, the aperspectival nature of the Vision-Logic Coordinate
System requires us to take on these immanent perspectives so that we can
see the transcendent value in any immanent infinitesimal, a non-zero value
only appearing from above as equivalent to the transitive zero of negation or
the implicit singularity of the immanent zero.
An essential thread of Nondual Rationalism is the overcoming of the
transcendent-bias by the integrating of the immanent, the positive and
progressive or emergent infinity as the secret of the rational. This is the
identity of opposites, of transcendence in immanence (yang in yin in yang
…), embodied and operationalized in the Immanent/Transcendent axis, and
i
And the immanent-omni-non-local aspect of The Infinite is, of course, the immanent pole of the
immanent/transcendent omni-axis.
Page | 414
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
The question then arises, “If the solution to the problem of the calculus was
ultimately so simple (rather obvious), and already implicit in the Leibnizian
metaphysics, then why was there ever a problem in the first place?”
We have already seen the Leibnizian, philosophical fix to the problem of
the calculus, but without a sociological fix as well, a philosophical solution is
isolated to the individual who invented it. Though Leibniz, in his more
mature reflections, had recognized the impossibility of the infinitesimal, he
failed not only to explicitly recognizei but to operationalize the new VL-axis
upon which mathematical rationalism was operating. To take hold, the
Leibnizian fix requires the explicit, esoteric, or common-place societal
acknowledgment and operationalization of the move, in rationalism and the
calculus, to this new Immanent/Transcendent axis. This explicit
operationalization would manifest in, among other things, putting the
obvious definition of infinity explicitly into the “undefined” rational zero.
Leibniz did not accomplish this step. He did not make explicit, for all to
explore, the existence of this implicit rational VL-axis and the nature of its
holarchical, embryological relation to the body of mathematics as a whole, so
his most considered metaphysical insights, about the rational way to
understand the calculus, did not take root and flourish in the mathematical
and meta-mathematical minds of his contemporaries.
The project of rationalism was still-born, aborted—its developmental
trajectory derailed—due largely to the incompleteness of its operational VL-
axis, but also because of the difficulty of accepting its more esoteric truths
caustic to the pre-rational and mythical-categorical level of development of
i
… along with its embryogenesis of the concept, holarchical structure, origin-identities and offsets,
etc.
Page | 415
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 416
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
In The Science of Logic,i¥ Hegel claims that this example demonstrates the
absence of the differential of the calculus in Spinoza’s thought. This
interpretation of Spinoza as having missed the essence of the calculus—as
opposed to Newton, for example, who “invented” the calculus and who,
according to Hegel, was the one progenitor who properly understood it—
presents Hegel with further opportunity to dismiss Spinoza (and in turn
Leibniz) and as a hapless historical victim of his dialectical progression
toward the apex of philosophical perfection and the completion of History in
Hegel’s own “absolute idealism.”
i¥
p251
Page | 417
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
Science of Logic § 565
Page | 418
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
Hegel continues:
It seems that he thought highly of this figure and of the concept which it
was used to illustrate, making it the motto of his Ethics.
Spinoza’s Ethics deals with the interface between The Infinite and finite, e.g.
between “God” and man, so this is a natural observation, and no doubt a
main reason Deleuze bases his own interpretation of the Ethics on this same
example.
‘Mathematicians conclude’, he says, ‘that the inequalities possible in such
a space are infinite, not from the infinite amount of parts, for its size is
fixed and limited and can assume larger and smaller such spaces, but
because the nature of the fact surpasses every determinateness.’ It is
evident that Spinoza rejects that conception of the infinite which
represents it as an amount or as a series which is not completed, and he
points out that here, in the space of his example, the infinite is not beyond,
but actually present and complete;
This complete infinity is the positive infinity of rationality; the uncountable
immanence opened up with the “violation” of the closure property of the
integers in the countable infinity of the Rational numbers, and the same
immanence explored and operationalized in the calculus. It is indeed “not
beyond,” not transcendent to, “but actually present and [a priori] complete,”
within, immanent to, the boundary of the finite, in which it shares a polar
relationship. That is precisely the point of this example of the bounded
infinite.
…this space is bounded, but it is infinite ‘because the nature of the fact
surpasses every determinateness’, because the determination of
magnitude contained in it cannot at the same time be represented as a
quantum [[a number or boundary]], or in Kant’s words already quoted,
the synthesis cannot be completed to form a (discrete) quantum.
i¥
Science of Logic § 566
Page | 419
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
In other words, “no number can express” it, as Spinoza so carefully states.
Hegel continues (my emphasis):
The incommensurability which lies in Spinoza’s example embraces in
general the functions of curved lines and more precisely, leads to the
infinite which mathematics has introduced with such functions, in
general, with the functions of variable magnitudes.i¥
Yes, the curved functions are embraced in this example, but the infinite
space illustrated here is that immanence opened up not merely by functions
of variable magnitude. These curves, as we have seen, can be either
transitive, transcendent or immanent, and they could also be based on
variable integers. But Spinoza’s example specifically illustrates the relation
between two 2nd degree continuous functions, emphasizing, even more
specifically, the immanence opened up in the pulverization of numerical
identity in the mathematical ratio (such as dy/dx), and operationalized by
the Immanent/Transcendent axis. It is this relation of powers in the
mathematical ratio, transcended, included, and fully operationalized in the
power/root functions, that allows for the variable continuity at the
foundations of the calculus, and critically encoded in its fundamental
theorem. The transitive axis of the variable integer, or dis-continuous
functions is included, but radically transcended in the operations of the
Rational numbers. So without recognizing the prefused distinction between
the immanent/transcendent and transitive, this conflation and con-fusion is
understandable.
This infinite is the genuine mathematical qualitative infinite which
Spinoza also had in mind...
This infinite is the bounded 3rd order infinite; merely one type of
“qualitative infinite which Spinoza also had in mind,” but it is centered on
the new axis of immanence opened up to operationality by the ratio, and
represents the full-circle return of the finite to its source, in The Cycle of
Unity and origin-identities (as we have seen).
i¥
§ 567
ii¥
§ 568
Page | 420
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
from ... mere variability” and mere curved functions, in Spinoza’s example.
Maybe what follows can explain it.
...It is, too, only because of a lack of awareness of what constitutes the
peculiar interest of higher analysis and of what has led to the need for and
invention of the differential calculus, that functions of the first degree and
the equation of the straight line are themselves included in the treatment
of this calculus; i¥
These lower degree transitive functions are, of course, transcended-and-
included in the functions of the calculus. However, Spinoza’s example does
not explicitly use the straight line, but points to the difference between two
circles, each of which is a 2nd degree function, and the infinity in question
depends critically on this factor. In other words, there are several
transcended-and-included layers of “relations of power” in Spinoza’s
example; the relation of transitive magnitudes transcended-and-included in
the ratios making possible the continuity of the curves, the relations of ratios
in the 2nd degree functions of the circles, and the relation of offset between
the infinitely continuous circles themselves, illustrating an infinite and
uncountable depth of difference in the distance between them.
...such formalism originates partly, too, in the mistake of imagining that
the intrinsically correct demand for the generalisation of a method has
been fulfilled when the specific determinateness on which the need for the
calculus is based is omitted, as if in this domain we were concerned only
with variable magnitudes. A great deal of formalism would, indeed, have
been avoided if it had been perceived that the calculus is concerned not
with variable magnitudes as such but with relations of powers.
Hegel rightly claims (conveniently opposing his personal Spinoza) that “the
calculus is concerned not with variable magnitudes...but with relations of
powers.” This leaves the erroneous interpretation of calculus—as leading
merely to (or from) the infinite of “variable magnitudes”—falsely projected
onto Spinoza’s example, and it leaves unacknowledged the uncountable
immanence in this example, in the Triune Infinite in general, in Spinoza’s
Letter XII, and indeed pervading his Ethics.
This is where Hegel’s interpretive error lies. He erroneously claims that
Spinoza’s example is not concerned with “relations of powers,” but leads
merely to or from the infinite of the variable function. Indeed, what is the
mathematical ratio if not a relation of powers? And, as we have seen, it is
this relation that breaks open the immanence in Spinoza’s geometrical
example, regardless of the degree of those powers. Without the relations of
magnitudes in the mathematical ratio, there could be no continuously
varying functions, no continuous higher power functions, no infinitesimal,
no limit and no calculus.
i¥
§ 569
Page | 421
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Hegel continues:
Although the mathematics of the infinite maintained that these
quantitative determinations are vanishing magnitudes, i.e. magnitudes
which are no longer any particular quantum and yet are not nothing but
are still a determinateness relatively to an other, it seemed perfectly clear
that such an intermediate state, as it was called, between being and
nothing does not exist.i¥
We have already seen that Leibniz—in his more mature, Spinoza-catalyzed
thought—considered this “intermediate state” of the infinitesimal as a
“necessary fiction”—in our terms, an operational bridge between the
immanent and transitive-axes—and he got his key insight from Spinoza’s
Letter XII. Hegel is here reacting to, proliferating, or indeed partially
generating, the exoteric/academic mis-reading of Leibniz discussed above,
where Leibniz says that the infinitesimal is the number “just before
reaching” zero.
What we are to think of this objection and the so-called intermediate
state, has already been indicated above in Remark 4 to the category of
becoming. The unity of being and nothing is, of course, not a state; a state
would be a determination of being and nothing into which these moments
might be supposed to have lapsed only by accident, as it were, into a
diseased condition externally induced through erroneous thinking; on the
contrary, this mean and unity, the vanishing or equally the becoming is
alone their truth.
Indeed, the “unity of being and nothing” is “not a state;” it’s a fiction. The
vanishing act, and the limbo-state itself, is a function of perspective from the
relations between the powers of the transitive and Immanent/Transcendent
axis—or number, and the positive infinity of the rational, respectively. The
truth, as Hegel says—and as the aperspectival Vision-Logic Coordinate
System demands and allows us to see—lies in the limitless becoming of the
i¥
§ 573
Page | 422
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
Page | 423
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
the simpler case: the sum of unequal distances. Why does he want to sum
up the differences?
Duffy writes:
The derivative, from the differential point of view of the infinitesimal
calculus, is the quotient of two differentials, that is, a differential relation,
of the type dy/dx. The differential, dy, is an infinitely small quantity, or
what Deleuze describes as ‘a vanishing quantity’; a quantity smaller than
any given or giveable quantity. Therefore, as a vanishing quantity, dy, in
relation to y, is, strictly speaking, equal to zero. In the same way dx, in
relation to x, is, strictly speaking, equal to zero, that is, dx is the vanishing
quantity of x.
The differential relation can be written as dy/dx = 0/0. “However,” says
Duffy, “although dy is nothing in relation to y, and dx is nothing in relation to
x, dy over dx does not cancel out, that is, dy/dx is not equal to zero.” True,
“there is no relation between two things which do not exist.” However,
Deleuze, like Leibniz, sees the differentials continuing to exist “as vanishing
quantities insofar as they continue to vanish as quantities rather than having
already vanished as quantities.” They aren’t truly zero, but merely vanishing
beyond the horizon of the transitive mathematical imagination.
This is essentially the point of view already expressed by Leibniz, recall,
which he honed through his 1676 encounter with Spinoza’s Letter XII on the
Triune Infinite, and it invokes Hegel’s notion of a relation of powers in action
or Becoming—the difference being that Deleuze sees this becoming in
Spinoza’s geometrical example, in that the numeration or numerical
expression never comes to an ultimate end. The infinitesimal as zero (the
nonexistence of power), is a necessary fiction. Rather, it continues to exist,
i¥
Gilles Deleuze, translated transcript from a lecture at the Cours Vincennes dated 20/01/1981.
http://www.webdeleuze.com/php/texte.php?cle=191&groupe=Spinoza&langue=2
Page | 424
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
Duffy writes:
Instead [of vanishing out of existence], the differential relation itself,
dy/dx, subsists as a relation. ‘What subsists when dy and dx cancel out
under the form of vanishing quantities is the relation dy/dx itself’ …
Despite the fact that its terms vanish, the relation itself is real.
The relation between the powers is still real because this vanishing act is
merely a perspectival illusion; a function of a default, static, numerical frame
of reference; the transitive axis, interfacing with motion beyond the
immanent horizon on the Immanent/Transcendent axis.
It is here [with this subsisting relation in the “differential point of view of
the infinitesimal calculus”] that Deleuze considers seventeenth-century
logic to have made ‘a fundamental leap’, by determining ‘a logic of
relations’.30 He argues that ‘under this form of infinitesimal calculus is
discovered a domain where the relations no longer depend on their
terms’.31
This domain is immanence, the sub-representational, the dark and
mysterious yin. It has been encountered and explored since antiquity
(perhaps most notably with Zeno), but not operationalized and legitimated,
mathematically and metaphysically, until the seventeenth-century, and
perhaps not “fully” until now with the deployment of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System of
Nondual Rationalism and Interface Philosophy.
It is not quite accurate, or complete, however, that “the relations no
longer depend on their terms,” but rather that we no longer need to
represent them as such, because the terms have receded beneath the
mathematical detail of our limited (finite) and transcendent-biased view.
They appear now as zero and we can no longer keep track of the still existing
relation. Yet beyond this immanent horizon, we are forced to take seriously
the immanent forces and the sub-representational field into which the terms
have vanished and in which they must continue to exist, because we know,
intuitively, logically and rationally, that the process of division in dy/dx
cannot finally yield the “infinitely small” and the immanent rational zero—
and this is the core intuition of the “differential point of view of the
infinitesimal calculus.” The space here is one of intensive forces, those
between immanent zero and transcendent infinity, and no longer those
oppositional forces between positive and negative trans-trans infinity.
According to the fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism and the
Law of Absolute Reversal, infinite division [i.e. boundless division] does not
“end” [bound] in the absolutely divided immanent zero, but reverses, at the
Page | 425
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Duffy continues:
The concept of the infinitely small as vanishing quantities allows the
determination of relations independently of their terms. ‘The differential
relation presents itself as the subsistence of the relation when the terms
vanish’.32 According to Deleuze, ‘the terms between which the relation
establishes itself are neither determined, nor determinable. Only the
relation between its terms is determined’.33 This is the logic of relations
that Deleuze locates in the infinitesimal calculus of the seventeenth
century, which he then mobilizes in his reading of Spinoza’s Letter XII, and
in his reading of Spinoza’s work as a whole, particularly in relation to the
physics of bodies in the second part of the Ethics.34
This point of view is what allows us to finally “perceive,” legitimate and
operationalize rational immanence and the intensive (non-oppositional and
nondual) forces of the sub-representational. But it is the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and its uncountable infinity that operationally
represents the positive infinity of the rational and the subtle identity of
opposites in Spinoza’s Substance/God (respectively), rendering it the
mathematical representation of the foundationless-foundation, the
boundless Emptiness of Nondual Rationalism.
Page | 426
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
quality of the original function; its rate of change at that point. The
differential relation therefore indicates the specific qualitative nature of
the original function at the different points of the curve.
This was basic to Spinoza’s point (no pun intended), that there are
numberless (infinite) different “rates of change” in any interval along the
space between the non-concentric circles, but he could have used any
number of different examples of various curves and/or their relations to
illustrate it. He chose circles, in my view, because he wanted to emphasize
the boundedness and uncountable immanence of the 3rd order infinity. The
point is that there are an “infinite number” of immanent differences in
“specific qualitative nature” (in this case expressed as “inequalities of
distance”) to be found in any segment of any continuous, bounded curve.
The image of the two circles just draws out this uncountable immanence of
the Bounded infinite very clearly.
Duffy continues:
... To put it simply, to determine the tangent of a curve at a specified point,
a second point that satisfies the function of the curve is selected, and the
gradient of the line that runs through both of these points is calculated. As
the second point approaches the point of tangency, the gradient of the line
between the two points approaches the gradient of the tangent. The
gradient of the tangent is, therefore, the limit of the gradient of the line
between the two points. Deleuze contends that the maximum and
minimum illustrated in Spinoza’s geometrical example are suggestive of
such limits.
In other words, using points to recursively divide the half-circle arc between
the minimum and maximum distance between the circles (See Figure 60,
below), we can draw a line between them to give us the tangent. As we
move from the outer limit to the inner one, progressively dividing the arc
segment, we endlessly approach the tangency of the minimum point (or we
could work from min to max). At some point, due to the set scale of our
drawing, we can no longer tell the difference between these two angles, or
their respective differences in distance between the two circles, and the
value effectively drops to zero, even though we know that with a true
mathematical curve the division of powers will never end and the tangents
and distances will never be fully equal.
Deleuze is certainly correct that the maximum and minimum in Spinoza’s
example are suggestive of these tangents-as-limits. It seems to me, however,
beside the point to attempt to locate definitively the specific mechanism of
the differential in Spinoza’s example. As we have seen, Leibniz’s solution to
the problem of the calculus, and his mature understanding of the infinite
came to him through his study of Spinoza’s Letter XII, and all we need do, to
further establish the alternate lineage from Spinoza to Leibniz—anticipating,
transcending and including Cantor—is locate the “differential point of view
Page | 427
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 429
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 430
RECONNECTING TO THE LOST THREAD: SPINOZA, LEIBNIZ, THE CALCULUS
Page | 431
Page | 432
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 433
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
In his book A Brief History of the Paradox, Roy Sorenson writes that
paradoxes are “questions (or in some cases, pseudoquestions) that suspend
us between too many good answers.” A paradox, Sorenson points out, finds
its strange stability in the dynamic equilibrium between two necessary
conclusions from a single question, premise or point of view. “From
engineering, we know that this kind of dynamic equilibrium is most simply
achieved by symmetry. When two boards are propped up against each other
(like this: /\), their equal but opposed forces keep the pair standing.”
To whet our appetite with a simple example, Sorenson asks, “When an
amoeba divides in two, does it go out of existence?” The amoeba has not
perished but merely transformed, so “no” she hasn’t gone out of existence.
Yet she is no longer one individual but two—she has transformed too
much—so “yes” she has gone out of existence. The swinging pendulum of
the answer, of course, depends on the implicit fuzziness or imprecision of
our general category of individual identity—the “it” of which the amoeba
implicitly is … or was … a special case. On the one hand the amoeba has
successfully multiplied its identity by two. So, not only does “it” still exist,
but in twice the quantity. On the other hand, the identity of the amoeba has
been negated in this very act because “to say that the mother amoeba
continues as the pair of daughters conflicts with the idea that organisms are
unified individuals.”i¥ And to satisfy our singular or “unified” idea of
individual identity it is an arbitrary matter to trace the single trajectory of
the mother amoeba’s identity through only one of the daughters she has
become. The mother amoeba was an individual organism, yet, without
perishing, suddenly she is no longer an individual. She has actually divided,
and now each daughter would seem to be merely one half of the “dividual”
that was once the individual mother amoeba. The individual has died to
become the dividual.ii
But what has actually been divided out of existence other than rigidity of
our implicit category of organismic individuality itself? What has been lost
but the applicability of a category generated in the anthropocentric frame of
reference of sexually reproducing beings and then implicitly applied to the
asexually reproducing amoeba? It is the category of organism as indivisible
i¥
(Sorenson)
ii
This is close to the inverse-identical to the Borg crisis of identity in assimilation. Instead of a simple
agglomeration, this is a multiplication through division. And for another inverse-identical in the
Leibnizian “problem of sex,” see Monadic Immaculate Conception and the “Problem of Sex”, p683).
Page | 434
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
then, which when implicitly misapplied causes this dichotomy of not quite
right conclusions we perceive as a paradox. The intrinsic precision of the
actuality cannot be reached by the imprecision of the extrinsic boundaries of
the category, and so we oscillate between the two closest approximations:
the mother amoeba has not died so she still exists, yet, in a real sense, she
has gone out of existence.
Paradoxes, then, are errors of intrinsic incompatibility in a
compartmentalized, categorical and dualistic logically descriptive system.
Paradoxes are dualisms. It is not in Nature herself that the dualistic
compartmental incompatibilities of the paradox reside, but only in the
oppositional categories cast upon her from above. From a different vantage
point, then—e.g. from a more detailed system of categories—we will see that
the paradoxes can, and often do indeed disappear. This disappearance can
come not simply by avoidance or turning away, and not necessarily by
“refutation,” but by the very opposite, by explicitly modeling the pivotal
detail inaccessible by the categorical framework rendering and generating
the paradox. Indeed the acategorical perspective of Nondual Rationalism
and Interface Philosophy provides a vantage point from which a new system
or level of categories can be constructed, with the resolution of the paradox
in mind. This is a large function of Interface Philosophy and the Vision-Logic
Coordinate System: to provide the acategorical and aperspectival framework
for such transformations to take shape. But this nondual system was already
built largely to resolve the dualistic paradoxes in a nondual fashion—such as
those of the infinite—as we will continue to see.
i
… and often times for the very purpose of conquering a region through this division of the collective
power of its people.
Page | 435
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
emergent from syntax, but the fact is that once syntax emerges, they are
symbiotic and co-dependent. They each engender the development of the
other. And it is the attempt of syntax or language and its rigid categories to
represent and modify the fluid contours of deeper semantics and sub-
representation (sub-semantics) that can often lead to the symmetric
opposition between two such rigid categorical conclusions.
In the EOTC, categories and concepts multiply through division, forming
an ever expanding and deepening meshwork of internal categorical
opposition—a sprawling system of polarities operating as opposable
conceptual appendages for grasping various differences in the mind. In the
paradox, however, we have reached the immanent limits of the categories as
they currently exist. We have reached the “limits of minimum (semantic)
ambiguity”—the LOMA, as Gerald Lebau calls it—afforded by the particular
evolutionary state of our system of categories. And if there is no implicit
understanding of the oppositional nature of categories and representation—
in the context of the intensive forces of sub-representation—then a
contradiction is conceived as something to be refuted and rejected from
above, rather than as possibly evoking a deeper truth beyond the
oppositional categories of the particular representational system.
The category representing the organismic individuality of the amoeba,
for example, is like the rigid board in the above image ( /\ ), in contrast to
the underlying continuity, possibility and fluidity of the semantic and sub-
semantic territory which it divides. When mapped to a set of facts which it
doesn’t intrinsically fit—namely the dividual nature of the amoeboid
identity—the category-system equivocates back and forth (yes and no, / and
\), trying to reach the intrinsic detail which its boundaries obscure (/.\).
Thus the category, expressed through the linearity of language and
conceptual thought, takes turns siding against itself, attempting to
triangulate on a detail, made inaccessible by the rigidity of its boundaries.
Like trying to pick up a toothpick while wearing boxing gloves, the system of
categories is too unrefined for the task. In this simplistic case, the
inaccessible detail is the fact that individual identity is not applicable to all
organisms, such as the amoeba, and a new category or distinction of
organismic existence as a divisible identity (“dividual”) is thus needed.
Page | 436
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
because there must be something for the system to represent. The other half
is a sub-representational foundation which autonomously and
unconsciously generates problems and then feeds the unfolding
consequences and solutions in real time to the representational layer to be
displayed in the form of lines, or collections of lines, such as polygons. As
such, the system is unaware of any of its processes (analogous to thoughts)
as anything other than polygonal. It knows only its polygonal
representations and not the problems and solutions represented from the
deeper sub-representational and subconscious level. This is a polygonal
consciousness which sees the world through a purely polygonal lens.
One day a curious image spontaneously emerges into the display. A
shrinking series of polygons appears—smaller and smaller until finally:
hexagon, pentagon, square, triangle … but then suddenly the display jumps
back to the square, then again to the triangle … square, triangle, square,
triangle… The sub-representational system has converged into a rapid
oscillatory state, flipping the representational layer back and forth between
the triangle and the square. The form appearing in the consciousness of the
system—as the representational answer to the particular sub-
representational problem—seems to be both and neither a square and a
triangle. The shape in consciousness is a duality—a contradiction, a
controversy, a paradox.
But what the representational layer (and the consciousness of the system
itself) doesn’t know is that the sub-representational form being converged
upon is a circle whose diameter is smaller than the line segment. The
system is simply trying to represent the area of this circle. However, this
quantity just happens to be a number exactly between the quantities
representable by the areas of the two smallest possible polygons: the square
and the triangle (See Figure 61, below). The square is too large a polygon to
accurately render the radius and area of the circle, and the triangle is too
small. But the real problem is that the area of the circle happens to lie
exactly in the center between the two, and the system’s only possibility for
coming to rest on the nearest representational state is a sub-
representational rounding function that jumps to the nearest numerical
value. In the extremely rare case of convergence upon a perfect balance
where the sub-representational system ends up in the actual absence of a
nearest representational state—i.e. in perfect dynamic equilibrium or
symmetry between two states where there actually is not any one such
nearest state—the system enters an oscillation between the two nearest
states, in effect averaging its area over time between them.
Page | 437
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 438
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 439
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 440
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Sorenson states:
Common sense may seem like a seamless, timeless whole. But it really
resembles the earth’s surface; a jigsaw puzzle of giant plates that slowly
collide and rub against each other. The stability of terra firma is the result
of great forces and counterforces. The equilibrium is imperfect; there is
constant underlying tension and, occasionally, sudden slippage.
Paradoxes mark fault lines in our common-sense world. Do these fissures
reach into reason itself?
This final question can simply and effectively be inverted. Can reason itself,
through the acategorical imperative, reach into the categorical fissures of
common-sense—the paradoxes—and find their common-ground in some
kind of deeper level of fluidity and emergence—some nondual form of
rationality that resolves paradoxes naturally?
To a great degree, we will find that paradox traces the very “backbone” of
nondual philosophy. It follows the curves of the “axis of Univocity”—where
the absolute meets the relative scope of logic and rationality—as it winds its
way through the transitive and agglomerative categories of thought itself.
This is why the paradoxes cluster around the interface between the
quantitative aspects of scope—the finite and infinite—as seen so clearly
with the paradoxes of Galileo and Zeno.
We will find, then, that what is central to the resolution of the paradox is
the relation between the transitive-axis—with its forces of representation
and opposition—and the Immanent/Transcendent axis—with its forces of
univocity and intensity. Recall that it is the transitive-axis that is the root of
the identity of the category and thus of singular perspective and its logical
operations. The dissolution of the illusions of perspective—the
pulverization of the categories—then, through the aperspectival Vision-
Logic Coordinate System, itself centered on the Immanent/Transcendent
axis, will be key to the resolutions of the paradoxes of the infinite herein.
Page | 441
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 442
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 443
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
See, The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite, p221.
ii¥
Dr. Reviel Netz, NOVA interview
Page | 444
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
i
* See, Implicit Holonic Set-Theory and the Part-Whole Axiom, p207.
ii
* See, Cantor’s Three Infinities, p268.
iii
* See, The Polarity of the Finite and Infinite, p221.
Page | 445
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Recall the binary logic of the VL-axes. In Cantor’s transfinite we can see yet
another manifestation of this dual or polar nature fundamental to
mathematics. The countable infinite is the first level of infinity and all the
higher levels are uncountable. But the countable and the uncountable
correspond directly to operation on the transitive and
immanent/transcendent axes, respectively, in their interfacing throughout
the holarchical embryogenesis of mathematics. Where the function of
number escapes the quantized limits of the transitive, we break into the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and from the oppositional into the purely
intensive forces of infinite depth. And recall this happened explicitly, for
example, with the iopol-inversion of powering, to the function of rooting and
its breaking open to “irrational” or transrational (e.g. transcendental)
numbers. This division between the Rationals and the Reals is precisely the
breaking point between Cantor’s countable and uncountable infinities, and it
is precisely the point where the function of number and operation moves
fully onto the Immanent/Transcendent axis, at the “second tier” level of
powers and roots.ii*
i
* See, The Trans-Rationality of the Irrational Numbers, p365.
ii
* See Phase FIVE: The Trans-Rational as Second Tier, p342.
Page | 446
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
i¥
Notes from Spinoza’s Finite Modes: Explained or Explained Away?: 1997 Carl Brock Sides
ii
* See, A Foot in the Door to Paradise: Cantor’s Quick Fix, p228.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iv
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
Page | 447
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 448
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Zeno is reputed to have invented some forty paradoxes. But the myriad
proposed solutions are almost as old as the paradoxes themselves. For
example (and as we shall see in more detail), Aristotle employed the
distinction between actual infinity and potential infinity to attempt a quick
and easy refutation of Zeno’s paradoxes of motion. And, as discussed
previously,i* it is generally assumed that Zeno’s paradoxes were finally and
definitively solved by Cantor’s transfinite arithmetic and the modern
mathematics of the continuum. As explained by Sorenson:
Alfred North Whitehead remarked, “To be refuted in every century after
you have written is the acme of triumph … No one ever touched Zeno
without refuting him, and every century thinks it worth while to refute
him.” (1947, 114) I think this compliment will not be paid by future
centuries. There are still paradoxes involving hypertasks. None of them
overturns the verdict that all of Zeno’s paradoxes were solved by Cantor a
hundred years ago. Cantor’s triumph shows that some important
paradoxes can be solved. We now have answers to Zeno’s riddles that
satisfy the exacting standard set by modern mathematics. Twenty-four
hundred years is a long wait. But remember that the comparison was with
Sisyphus, who labors for eternity.
i
* See, A Foot in the Door to Paradise: Cantor’s Quick Fix, p228.
Page | 449
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Our purpose here is likewise not Sisyphean. We aim not merely to give yet
another purported resolution to the general Zenonian paradox, but to render
the problem and its proposed solutions in the clear light of Interface
Philosophy and the Vision-Logic Coordinate System. Indeed, we will come to
see explicitly why Zeno’s paradoxes hold such an enduring fascination for us,
and why Cantor’s abstract solution works. What we will find, however, is
that far from being an error in itself to be refuted, resolved and corrected,
the duality at the heart of Zeno’s paradoxes is a transitive, categorical
symptom of the fundamental polarity of conceptual relation itself which
Zeno’s pioneering thought experiment deftly tapped into. In the end, Zeno
gives a tantalizing glimpse of the fundamentally polar or nondual nature of
conceptual relation which won’t be operationalized mathematically into the
modern infinitely divisible and indivisible continuum until Cantor and
others in the nineteenth century, and which won’t be fully assimilated into
the social sphere until a truly rational and nondual framework of thought
(e.g. Interface Philosophy and Nondual Rationalism) works its way through
the collective consciousness of mankind. Until then, humanity may continue
to “refute,” rather than to understand the seemingly paradoxical polarity at
the heart of Zeno’s thought experiments, as they inch their way closer and
closer to functionality with Zeno’s “paradoxical,” and ultimately
Parmenidean truth. To understand this truth, then, we must come to
understand Parmenides and the Pre-Socratic context in which it arises.
Page | 450
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
elemental gods begin in direct opposition and duality, polarized against one
another in countless battles which through subsequent generations
ultimately civilized the dark of Chaos into the dawn of an uneasy and
capricious order of operations.
The first recorded attempt to abstract this originary “muck” into rational
thought as a “first principle” came with Thales and his principle of water,
from which all the other “elements” would arise. Like the battles of the
elemental gods themselves, this water principle was then objected to by
subsequent philosophers, not on the grounds of empirical observation, but
as a matter of self-derived authority and logic. Anaximander, for example,
recognized that in order for a first principle to spawn all the elements it
cannot itself be an element. Thus he chose the boundless itself—the
apeiron—as his first principle. Anaximander reasoned that this apeiron
contained within itself the potential of all the elements, while possessing
none of their individual limits. Mirroring or echoing the implicit EOTC itself,
the Anaximandrian elements are simply separated out of or abstracted from
the unbounded unity of the apeiron. “In effect, by naming a stuff which is not
one of the everyday stuffs we know, Anaximander removed the paradox
involved in describing the whole class of stuffs in terms of one of its
members” (p42).
But history ebbs and flows, from progress to a seeming regress, all the
while gaining new (if hidden) traction in its endless explorations.
Anaximenes, for example, dissatisfied with the ineffability and abstractness
of Anaximander’s apeiron, selected air as his first principle, with the
advantage that he could describe how air could be condensed into fluids and
further into solids, and then liquefied and rarified back into fundamental air.
But at the same time he stepped back into the paradoxes of describing the
class of elements with another member of the same class. Subtle is the way
of nonlinear and massively parallel progress.
Heraclitus was the first philosopher to break from early Ionian first
principles as some kind of muck. In a subtle echo of Anaximander’s apeiron,
Heraclitus exchanged the problem of how stuff can change into other stuff,
with the more abstract idea that change itself was the primordial “stuff.” For
this reason he poetically described his first principle in terms of fire because
it is more of a process of transformation—e.g. from twigs and branches into
smoke and ashes—than a stuff or an element. Through this ceaseless
transformation, however, the ever-changing form of the fire remains. In this
sense, Stewart reasons, Heraclitus, like Pythagoras, successfully and fully
transitions from stuff to form or abstraction as the first principle.
Essentially, Heraclitus selected the nondual and triune interface between
the dual states of any transformation as his primal “stuff.” In this same way,
Page | 451
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
goes the common Heraclitean maxim, “you can’t step into the same river
twice,” because the water in the river is always influxing anew, and the river
itself is constantly in a process of change. It is change. This cultivating third
of change in Heraclitus was formalized into the principle of “logos,” which
can mean anything “from ‘word’ to ‘story’ to ‘account’ to ‘proportion’ or
‘measure.’”
Implicit to Heraclitean logos, we can see, is the essence of the nondual, in
that through it, Heraclitus reasoned, opposites ceaselessly transform into
one another, because in the deepest sense they are one another. This, we
can see, is a pre-echo Parmenides’ Being-now and an echo Anaximander’s
apeiron and it expresses an uncanny resemblance to Nagarjuna’s
pulverization of the categories and Buddhist dependent arising. “In this
synthesis of opposites, by the way, Heraclitus foreshadows for us a feature of
philosophy that will remain with us for the course of this history. The drive
for unity is perhaps the primordial urge of philosophy, and in the end it must
run over all the (merely apparent) oppositions which populate the world”
(p44). The “Heraclitean paradox,” or what we can call a nonduality, Stewart
reasons, “takes us to the bottom [our absolute scope] of the very idea of a
first principle,” which, as we have seen along with Heraclitus, reflects into its
opposite.
A first principle presumably is the form of everything. So what is the form
of everything? Well, it cannot be a particular form, like water or
squareness, for any such particular form would be dissolved into its
opposite through the form of—form. The form of everything, in other
words, is form itself. Everything, Heraclitus tells us, is part of the form of
the world. But to say that form itself is the first principle is to present an
argument in the form of a circle. The very idea that there is such a thing
as a first principle supposes that there is a form of the world. The
premise of the search is its conclusion.
We could end the history of philosophy at this point. In Heraclitus’
inspired hands, philosophy dissolves itself. It falls silent. But in this
Heraclitean world, alas, nothing ever comes to rest. Philosophy will
crystallize again and again, in countless new shapes, throughout the
course of our history.
Page | 452
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
We have already witnessed a bit of a crude echo into the very beginnings of
philosophy. This came with the recapitulation of the ancient theological
transition from muck into elemental gods, in the early philosophies of the
Presocratics, with their muck-like first principles spawning the elements of
the world. Stewart demonstrates quite effectively, however, that this kind of
repetition is ubiquitous throughout the history of philosophy, as the truths
of the previous generations are reduced to the LCD of the next, or simply just
forgotten to be rediscovered anew. To conclude an earlier brief account of
this self-similarity, we take up where we left off with our previous quote
from Stewart [my comments]:
Page | 453
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 454
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Naturally our story must peal off from this self-similar historical trajectory
with Zeno of Elea, as the intellectual heir to the “original” second-order
philosophy of Parmenides. As Stewart said, “Zeno’s hair-splitting paradoxes
would first drive the Socratic dialectic, and then become the conceptual
clarifications of mid-twentieth century philosophy of language.” And, we can
add, Zeno’s paradoxes also forced into the open, critical distinctions in logic
and mathematics, and continue to do so to this day, culminating with the
validation and instantiation of Zeno’s Parmenidean conclusions into the
truths of modern mathematics, as we will indeed see.
As Karin Verelst and Bob Coecke argue—in their paper Early Greek
Thought and Perspectives for the Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics:
Preliminaries to an Ontological Approach [my emphasis}:
[Zeno’s paradoxes] stem from what was perceived by classical philosophy
to be the fundamental enigma for thinking about the world: the seemingly
contradictory results that followed from the co-incidence of being and
non-being in the world of change and motion as we experience it, and the
experience of absolute existence here and now. The most clear expression
of both stances can be found, again following classical thought, in the
thinking of Heraclitus of Ephesus and Parmenides of Elea. The problem
put forward by these paradoxes reduces for both Plato and Aristotle to
the possibility of the existence of stable objects as a necessary
condition for knowledge. Hence the primarily ontological nature of the
solutions they proposed: Plato’s Theory of Forms and Aristotle’s
metaphysics and logic. Plato’s and Aristotle’s systems are argued here to
do on the ontological level essentially the same: to introduce stability in
the world by introducing the notion of a separable, stable object, for
which a ‘principle of contradiction’ is valid: an object cannot be and not-
be at the same place at the same time. So it becomes possible to forbid
contradiction on an epistemological level, and thus to guarantee the
certainty of knowledge that seemed to be threatened before.
In the exoteric history of philosophy, then, the paradox and univocal polarity
(the “co-incidence” or interface) between the absolute (the omni-non of
Being and non-Being) and relative scopes (“the world of change and motion
as we experience it”) was naturally prior to the closure and absolute identity
of the concept, as we see in Plato’s Forms and Aristotle’s principle of
contradiction, his metaphysics and his logic. This originary absolute-relative
polarity in the axis mundi of ancient thought, we will see, manifests into the
opposition of the concept through Zeno’s derivative “paradoxes,” and finally,
now, into the unity, polarity and triune interface of the
Immanent/Transcendent axis and the Cycle of Unity.
In order for the certainty and rigidity of subsequent philosophical and
“Rational” thought to progress, then, it had to move again from this originary
intensive “muck” of fuzzy nonduality and polarity, into the numerical
identity of the category and the transitive and transcendent (trans-biased
Page | 455
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i
But this is not to say that they each don’t have their nondual elements, just that their emphasis
pushed philosophy, and necessarily so, into the forces of opposition and conceptual, trans-biased
agglomeration.
Page | 456
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
“Whatever it was that was refuted,” says Verelst, “it was certainly not Zeno.”
Generally what has been “refuted”—along with the exoteric caricatures of
Zeno and Parmenides—are the purely unsubstantiated and absurd views
they never held, such as the simple nonexistence of things and change. In
the common versions of history—what Verelst calls the Received View—it is
said that both Zeno and Parmenides rejected their sense data that
everywhere showed evidence of the plurality of things and change. Yet
every child knows that these comic characters are dead wrong. It is further
claimed that these patently absurd ideas—e.g. no things nor change—were
supported merely through Zeno’s purely logical paradoxes, taken
collectively as reductio ad absurdum (more like a reductio into absurdum, for
the sake of convenient “refutation”) .
From the start, for example, Plato fictionalizes an interaction between
Zeno and Socrates for this very purpose, however consciously or
unconsciously: to make Zeno’s stance appear absurd and make tractable and
possible its subsequent refutation. Plato writes in his Parmenides
Page | 457
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
i¥
Qtd in (Sorenson).
Page | 458
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Plato with his fictionalized Zeno, Parmenides and Socrates. The Received
View, then, is a scope con-fusion. At the relative scope of the everyday ontic
and epistemic interface there is no such denial of plurality and motion
whatsoever. But Parmenides and Zeno were primarily concerned with first
principles, and hence with the absolute. And by taking it to the absolute
scope Zeno merely demonstrates that the infinite division of plurality is
logically equivalent to the indivisibility of Unity, and subsequently that logic
and rationality, at its core, is fundamentally polar and nondual—“contra-
dictory” in the face of absolute Unity.
But this is a given, since polarity is the most general function of the world
of conceptual relation, which of necessity includes the world of logic. In his
paradoxes of motion, we will see plurality expressed through the infinite
divisibility of change, and through the same underlying form the
simultaneously infinite division of time is demonstrated to be the equivalent
of the indivisibility of eternity manifesting in the Zenonian instant. Motion,
then, is not so much denied, as demonstrated to be indivisible, continuous
and ultimately ONE eternal and instantaneous Unity—the Parmenidean
Being-now. And this is naturally in conjunction with our PNDR, “infinite
division equals indivisibility,” and its Ariadnean resonance into the chord of
“infinite determinism equals indeterminism” and its eternal-NOW.
It indeed seems to be the case, then, that the Parmenidean legacy (echoing
Anaximander’s apeiron) consists generally of an emphasis on the Unity,
rational harmony or indivisibility aspect of the fundamental identity and
univocal tautology of the ONE-ALL, whereas the Heraclitean (and
Anaxagorean) legacy would emphasize its multiplicity, diversity and
conflicting aspects in the infinite division, difference and change of the ALL.
(Indeed, as we will see, this is the same polarity and triunity of emphasis
underlying the perceived and received view of the dichotomy between
Spinoza and Leibniz, respectively.) In the interface and “shock” between
these two, however, we find the unity in triunity—the nonduality and
resolution to all the resonant dichotomies, dualities, conflicts and
paradoxes—but most importantly, this resolution comes not at the price of a
negating refutation, but with the integrating shift in perspective into a
vision-logic framework whereby the polarity underlying the fundamental
“paradox” of Being itself becomes visible—tuned and triuned—as a singular
omni-axis of thought and conceptual/ontological unfolding—namely the
axis-mundi or I/T axis.
This “atonement” in triunity can perhaps be seen most clearly with our
Cycle of Unity between the Infinite and finite forms of unity—the ALL-ONE
and the “one,” respectively. This, recall, can be seen as an orbit, where the
axis-mundi of the immanent/transcendent ALL-ONE, cycles back through its
Page | 460
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
tautological identity with the ONE-ALL. To enter the orbit and approach the
finite unity of the “one,” however, from the identity in transcendence
between the ONE-ALL omni-axis and the ONE-one uni-axis, recall, the cycle
moves (simultaneously from immanence and transcendence) onto the uni-
axis and toward its bounded interface in the closure of the categorical unit-
identity—the unit of the transitive-axis. Then—through the equality of
immanence and transcendence in the ratio of the ALL (∞/∞)—the
conceptual cycle moves back to the ONE. This, recall, is represented in our
VLE — ONE = ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE — which itself represents the tuning and
triuning binary cycle of emphasis between the Parmenidean unity in the
ONE, and the Heraclitean conflict in the ALL.i* The solidus/vinculum
between the immanent and transcendent infinite in our VLE (∞/∞), recall, is
the very interface of our finite unity, implicit in the ONE-ALL from the
beginning. See Figure 15, repeated below.
Figure 15, Repeated from The (Binary) Cycle of Unity (p257): Polarity of the Forms in
the Cycle of Unity.
Most importantly, however, this Cycle, recall, also reflects through the pure-
relational categories of mathematics into The Binary Cycle of Identities, Axes
i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
Page | 461
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
and Unities (p383), which acts as the triuning interface between the two
fundamental VL-axes of conceptual relation: the I/T and the transitive.
These binary VL-axes, recall, also represent operational aspects of the
uncountable and countable Cantorian infinities, as we have just seen in the
recent section on Cantor.i* Indeed, we will soon see the interface between
these two VL-axes and their Cantorian infinite aspects as essential to the
understanding—the tuning and triuning—of Zeno’s paradox.
i
* See, The Two-Floors of the Transfinite (p445).
ii¥
(Verelst, Zeno's Paradoxes. A Cardinal Problem: I. On Zenonian Plurality)
Page | 462
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
(PP). And this model underlying even the paradoxes of motion (PM)
(stadium included) consists of a simultaneous “through and through” infinite
division. This is essentially our immanent/transcendent omni-axis of
infinite omni-local division. Indeed, Verelst demonstrates through linguistic
analyses from the original Zenonian Greek that Zeno nowhere invokes time
for this divisional procedure. Just as our immanent/transcendent omni-axis
exists in the second-order eternal NOW of conceptual pure relation, so too
does Zeno’s infinite “through and through” division also exist sub specie
aeternitatis. And in the paradoxes of motion, the underlying simultaneous
“through and through” division is simply encountered and made manifest,
demonstrating the “infinite division equals indivisibility” of motion through
infinitely divided and thus indivisible extension. It is for this reason, argues
Verelst, that Aristotle’s distinction between potential and actual infinity is
untrue to Zeno’s premises and thus fails to refute him, as modern
mathemagicians, stage-hands and participating audience members all seem
to agree.
The basic Zenonian PP argument can be found in many forms. For example,
Sorenson gives a common exoteric account, following along with the
problematic and con-fused received view of the Parmenidean legacy [my
comments and emphases]:
Some of Zeno’s arguments bolster Parmenides’ [purported] rejection of
anything having size. If an object has a size, then it has parts [e.g. left and
right sides]. This collective is actually a conglomeration of things rather
than a single thing. Therefore, the only genuine individuals must have
no size. But if an object has no size, then it is nothing at all. Go ahead, add
a sizeless object to another object. There is no increase in size. If
thousands of sizeless objects were put together, they would still not add
up to anything. Since sizeless things do not differ from nothing, they are
nothing.
Notice here the implicit assumption that thingness necessarily equates to
individuality. The argument here—presented in exoteric form—is not
ultimately against things having size, but only against “genuine individuals”
or indivisibles (i.e. a-tomoi and absolutized finite unities) having size—and
therefore, ultimately merely for the idea of the infinite ALL-ONE. The
category of “thing” employed by the exoteric caricature of Sorenson’s Zeno
implicitly includes and hides the category of absolute individuality. Zeno is
not merely arguing against the existence of things, but against absolute
things, like a-tomoi. If we “pulverize” the category of “thing” upon the
exoteric ambiguity hidden within it, we can divide it into two categories:
individuals and dividuals (e.g. a-tomoi and holons). Zeno’s argument merely
demonstrates, and purposefully so, the impossibility of the absolute
individual (a-tom), with respect to the concept of size, and thus indirectly for
the implicit holonic logic of sets, with its implicit unity in the ONE-ALL.
Page | 463
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Zeno, recall, was arguing for the infinite and eternal Parmenidean Being-
now, but only at the absolute scope. At the relative scope, things can come
and go. Zeno and Parmenides merely state that ultimately they are ONE.
This hidden argument is very similar to the much more transparent
Buddhist argument against the Eastern equivalent of the a-tomoi. If atoms
have any size whatsoever they will have a boundary and thus they can be
placed next to each other. When placed together there will be one part of
each a-tom that is closer to, or even touching the other. Therefore atoms—
and things of any size whatsoever—are necessarily composed of parts (as
indeed science has shown, where it can). Only infinitely small points can be
free from a boundary and thus free from proximally relational parts. But in
this freedom they are also free from existence. They are mere abstractions
of location—aspect infinities and implicit singularities—with no extension
and no “substance.” Recall again our encounter with these points through
the Principle of Absolute Reversal. This occurred, recall, in the
absolutization of thingness and individuality in modern physics. And this
ended with the reduction of “ultimate particles” to mere points, resulting in
the “Inverse Unified Field”—the ONE-ALL of negation with its nonexistent
“infinitely small” points nonexistently flitting about the nonexistence-
incarnate contradiction of the boundless void.i*
Without the recognition and admission of the category of Parmenidean
“thingness” itself as implicitly enfolding the category of indivisibility (i.e. that
they are talking about first principles and thus the absolute scope),
Parmenides and Zeno can appear to be arguing against mere “thingness”
itself, and thus against the natural and common-sense correlative of the
infinite Heraclitean multiplicity of the ALL. Through their correct arguments
against bounded indivisibles—absolute finite unities—they would seem to
be arguing against relative difference itself—exoterically couched as their
arguments commonly are against mere “things,” such as we find in
Sorenson’s rendition. This is why their paradoxes seem on the surface to
contradict everyday experience, yet ultimately, in the proper nondual
context, they merely reach the founding principle of esoteric and originary
rationalism—not a problematic paradox, but a necessary identity of
opposites; a Heraclitean and Parmenidean polarity where infinite division
equals indivisibility, and vice versa.
i
* See, Chord 3 Example: The Inverse Unified Field, p117.
Page | 464
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 465
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Verelst demonstrates this even more effectively through the “first Paradox of
plurality.” She summarizes the argument thus:
Zeno says that a) infinite division leads to an infinite number of final,
indivisible parts which still do have a magnitude, because, b) if they
would not have magnitude, they would not be at all, and so the object of
which they are part would not be at all. And an infinite number of parts
possessing, however small, finite magnitude, would give us an object
infinitely big. But c) given that the division is complete ('throughout'), no
parts with finite magnitude can remain, therefore d) the object
constituted by them will be infinitely small. Thus, upon Zeno’s argument,
a finite thing consisting of a plurality would be either infinitely large or
infinitely small. The subtle variant of the standard interpretation thus
offers us Zeno’s argument as a dilemma.
In other words, by taking finite division to the absolute scope it reflects (via
dilemma) into the two poles of the Immanent/Transcendent axis; the
“infinitely small” and the “infinitely large.” Verelst continues [my
emphases]:
The central point thus is that by being simultaneous (i.e., by occurring in
no lapse of time) the completion by division is at once, cardinal, not
Page | 466
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 467
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
For in two ways it can be said that a distance or a period or any other
continuum is infinite [apeiron], viz., with respect to the partitions or with
respect to the projecting parts [Aristotle, Phys. Z, 2, 263a (24-26)].
For whoever divides the continuum into two halves thereby confers a double
function on the point of division, for he makes it both a beginning and an end
[Phys. Θ 8, 263a (23-25)].
Page | 468
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
We have no first hand account of Zeno’s paradoxes of motion, rather they are
rendered for us by Aristotle, who was simultaneously attempting to refute
them. (For some reason Aristotle did not attempt a refutation of the
underlying and critical PP. Perhaps the PM were easier, given that through
them Aristotle could inject non-Zenonian time, to make his distinction
between potential and actual infinity.) Verelst writes:
Zeno’s famous Paradoxes of Motion are transmitted to us by Aristotle
[Phys., Z 9, 239b], with the comment that they are notoriously difficult to
refute. And indeed attempts to either refute, [or] resolve them have been
at the order of the day up to the present: no one has ever touched Zeno
without refuting him, and every century thinks it worthwhile to refute him.
Let it suffice to say that, however relevant in themselves for future
developments in, say, mathematics, all presumed refutations hinge on
non-Zenonian premises, so that, whatever it was that was refuted, it
was certainly not Zeno.
As stated previously, Verelst demonstrates that all of Zeno’s paradoxes of
motion (PM)—including even the stadium paradox—can be subsumed
under the timeless and instantaneous form of the general paradox of
plurality (PP), rendered into mathematical rigor, above, and explained in her
paper in the formal language of domain theory. Verelst writes [my
emphasis]:
It would moreover be quite strange that Zeno, in order to defend
Parmenides’ stance with respect to the deictical unreality of time [i.e. time
as illusory with respect to the absolute of the Being-now], would
introduce it to make his point. …
… Our analysis of PP thus should be applicable to PM as well. The
reason invariably is that “to move” implies “to count the uncountable”
…
In other words, the tables have turned on Aristotle. It is the uncountable
infinite of the ignored PP which already exists as the actual infinite
underlying all of the PM. And further, it is divisible movement that takes on
the time-ordered, stepwise function of the potentially infinite, never able to
reach the immanent pole of the actually existing omni-axis within which
motion acts.
Bell puts it like this: Continuity and discreteness are united in the process of
measurement in which the continuous is expressed in terms of separate
units, that is numbers. …
Page | 469
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 470
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 471
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
The second [argument] is the so-called Achilles. This is that the slowest
runner will never be overtaken by the swiftest, since the pursuer must
first reach the point from which the pursued started, and so the slower
must always be ahead. This argument is essentially the same as that
depending on dichotomy, but differs from it in that the added lengths are
not divided into halves.
Aristotle precisely notes that this argument is essentially the same as the
Dichotomy. However, “The case is slightly more complicated,” Verelst notes,
“by the fact that both the moving body and the goal to attain are themselves
in motion, but the complication is not substantial, as Aristotle points out
himself: it merely implies that the distances to cross will not decrease
symmetrically.” Verelst continues:
The received view presents us Zeno’s argumentation as flawed by an
elementary mathematical error, due to a lack of mathematical
sophistication. In accordance with Aristotle’s distorted rendering of
Zeno’s argument, it is presented as a potentially infinite sequence
decreasing geometrically… the sum of which can very well have a finite
total, because the underlying sequence converges to its finite Cauchy-
limit.
Verelst continues to show that this view has already been challenged by
Vlastos, who, “given his direct acquaintance with the sources of ancient
Greek thought” was “at unease” with this modern interpretation. He then
finds another interpretation that requires a countably infinite number of
steps, a “supertask,” which is generally considered possible in certain
circumstances. Because a supertask is a time-ordered procedure, however,
it is essentially Aristotle’s potential infinite argument in another guise and
with a possible refutation. The false assumption on both of these accounts is
that Zeno’s infinite division is stepwise and thus countable, and thus the
purported resolution via supertask is also a non-starter. Verelst continues:
But although we ever only make finitely many steps, even if we could
make countably many, the stretches to cross would be uncountable in
number. Thus a Zenonian supertask properly speaking would require an
infinity of acts in no time!
Page | 472
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
BEFORE AFTER
A A A A A A A A
B B B B B B B B
C C C C C C C C
Let AAAA represent the fans. Let BBBB and CCCC Represent two complex
bodies that move in opposite directions at equal speed until they are
aligned with the fans. Is this convergence possible? After moving, the first
B has moved past two As. Yet the first C has passed four Bs. Therefore, the
first C has moved twice as fast as the first B. This contradicts the opening
assumption that the blocks were moving at equal speeds.
ARISTOTLE’S SOLUTION
I remember having trouble understanding the stadium paradox. Doesn’t
Zeno realize that velocity is relative? BBBB and CCCC are moving equally
fast with respect to AAAA but are moving twice as fast with respect to
each other. Aristotle’s solution to the “paradox” simply draws the
distinction we find so obvious. I thought this was uncharitable to Zeno;
could such a brilliant philosopher be guilty of so obvious an equivocation?
Given that ultimately the same paradox of plurality underlies this paradox as
well, as usual, things are not as simple as they might seem. First of all, the
exoteric Received View doesn’t mention at all the infinite division “through
and through” of the PP underlying this paradox. It simply mentions a
doubling of speed, which is time/distance. Sorenson’s rendition is then
another example of Zeno’s simultaneous through and through division not
only ignored, but also injected with the non-Zenonian premise of time.
Secondly, repeating Verelst from before, “Time, being related to distance, is
irrelevant in exactly the same way as the length of our measuring rod was
irrelevant.” The uncountable infinite Zenonian plurality of each passing
body exists prior to the stepwise and merely countable act of mutual
measurement. “‘To count the uncountable’ is thus the motion-face of the
plurality-coin,” says Verelst. She continues [my emphases]:
The Received View here is that Zeno did not understand the (Galilean)
relativity governing the motions of bodies in inertially moving frames of
Page | 473
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
reference, as in the case of two cars crossing each other with equal speed
on a high way: The unanimous verdict on Zeno is that he was hopelessly
confused about relative velocity in this paradox. But in Zeno’s description,
every part at every moment faces its doubling by division, whether it be
in comparison to a stable measuring rod, or a rod passing by. The
problem arises from the fact that, because of simultaneous through-
and-through division, “to double” here involves a transition from
ordinal to cardinal, from countable to uncountable, from potential to
actual infinity. The infamous “doubling of the times” only takes into
account the potential, stepwise part of the argument. For of course, every
body, while being a continuum, “touches” (counts) the other one
everywhere when it passes (measures). It remains just the same
cardinal problem. Their speed proportional to each other does not
change anything to this fact, analogous to what we saw with the Achilles:
they are at every moment passing each other at infinitely many parts,
which, by facing each other’s unlimited division, count each other’s
uncountability.
Thus, Verelst demonstrates, even Zeno’s Stadium paradox has not been
refuted, given the same paradox of plurality underlying it which even
Aristotle did not attempt to refute. Verelst reminds us, however, “Let us
stress once more that Zeno does not imply that motion does not exist,
only that it is paradoxical.”
The Arrow paradox is traditionally known as the most perplexing of them all
because, writes Verelst, “the only thing that remains is the naked paradox.”
Verelst gives Aristotle’s account of the paradox as follows [my emphases]:
The Third is that just given above, that the flying arrow is at rest. This
conclusion follows from the assumption that time is composed of
instants; for if this is not granted the conclusion cannot be inferred.
We find a more detailed account in Sorenson, however:
The third paradox asks whether a moving arrow is at rest. An arrow is at
rest if it is in a place equal to itself. At any given moment, even a very
speedy arrow cannot be where it is not. Therefore, it must be where it is,
and so in a place equal to itself. So a flying arrow cannot move.
This paradox, says Verelst, “radicalizes the reasoning by combining the first
two arguments pointwise, so that the contradiction plainly arises.” In
“refuting” this “naked paradox,” and because “it does not leave any room for
anything timelike to be smuggled in,” says Verelst, Aristotle has to resort to
the premise of the “parallelism of divisibility of space and time.” This
parallelism states essentially that Zeno forgot to take into account the
division of the time it would take to make the transit, and thus each division
Page | 474
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
The last two arguments show that, whether we consider the megala or
the mikra, the paradox remains the same. This is where the reading of the
last two arguments as a dilemma stems from.
Thus we see that the perception of “paradox” itself is a con-fusing function—
a conflation of the prefused distinction—of the hidden polar and triune
interface between these two VL-axes and thus between the countable
stepwise transitive infinity and the uncountable infinity of instantaneous
immanence and transcendence, not merely a result of one or the other.
Verelst continues:
But once the true nature of Zeno’s paradoxes is assimilated, this last
argument reveals itself as the contrary of how it is generally perceived: a
clear an incontestable exposure of the paradoxical nature of motion and
change, and not an incomprehensible enigma.
In other words, Zeno’s thought experiment does not show that motion does
not exist, but merely (exactly as Simplicius indicates) that motion is contra-
dictory, or that it contains a con-fusing polarity which emerges when one
tries to speak and reason about it.
If you let motion, conceived of as covering all systematically smaller
extended parts of a line by counting the uncountable in every single part,
come to an end by mentally letting the extension of the parts decrease to
nought, then division ‘comes to an end’ too, and the only thing that
remains is the naked paradox. This explains why this paradox in the
literature has been considered as the most enigmatic one, while it actually
only sums up Zeno’s conclusion in a concise way.
Page | 476
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
i
* See, The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite, p407.
ii
* See, Paradox and the LOMA: A Geometrical Example, p435.
iii
“limits of minimum (semantic) ambiguity” — Lebau
Page | 477
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 478
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
i¥
(G. Lebau)
Page | 479
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Given that both Zeno’s and Galileo’s paradoxes have been tuned and triuned
by the modern mathematical continuum and Cantorian transfinite
arithmetic, and into philosophy and common-sense with the understanding
of Interface Philosophy and Nondual Rationalism, it is more than obvious
that, contrary to Kan’t, the human mind can indeed reason about the infinite,
in whatever form it happens to take. Kant’s claim was that human reason
had reached its limits with the concept of infinity as applied cosmologically
or cosmogonically to spatial or temporal aspects. For example, when
attempting to reason about the “beginnings” or extent of the universe. With
the culmination of Interface mathematics in our section on Zeno, however,
with his vindication and codification into the truths of the mathematical
Page | 480
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Up until the rise of Christianity in the Dark Ages the universe was
incontrovertibly considered without a beginning or end in space or time.
Exoteric Christianity, with its representational and transcendent forces of
anthropocentrism, however, seized the absolute, called it God, gave it human
powers and limitations, and said “Let there be light.” Thus began the world
of man, but only out of the a priori eternity and infinity of God.
With the operationalization and vindication of Zeno and the binary truths
and axes of the infinite in the modern mathematical continuum, however,
Rationality and Reason have overturned the recent confusion about origins
and put the infinite of eternity back into its originary place. Kant’s
antinomies merely show the limits of the imagination, not of reason, as
Spinoza had already shown in his Letter XII on the infinite. Indeed, given
that mathematics itself operates on Kant’s sanctified “categories of reason,” a
Kantian response must follow and accept the truths of mathematics and its
successes with the infinite and continuous. And to cosmological concerns,
those truths can indeed be applied.
For example, reasoning about the spatio-temporal infinite only becomes
a real problem when we break from the implicit holonic logic of sets—and
from the polarity of the infinite and finite as well as the Univocity
Framework—and impose limits to the absolute, such as an absolute
beginning in Time. Below, Sorenson gives us an account of Kant’s first
antinomy, and note that the proofs in these arguments take the form of
reductios. Kant assumed that each opposing thesis—e.g. that the world had
a beginning, and that it did not—could be proven by the absurdity of the
other. But as we’ll see, the only thesis that is absurd is the thesis that
imposes these absolute limits—or absolute relativities. The infinite itself—
though it can’t fit into the imagination, but can nonetheless be understood in
its percept-based terms—is the only option of the two that makes sense.
Sorenson gives the first half of the antimony as follows:
THESIS
The world has a beginning in time, and is also limited as regards space.
PROOF
If we assume that the world has no beginning in time, then up to every
given moment an eternity has elapsed, and there has passed away an
infinite series of successive states of things. . . .
Kant assumes that this is a logical reductio, but plainly it is no such thing. As
Zeno, Spinoza and Cantor have shown, there is simply nothing illogical about
an infinite number or series of successive states—previous or not. This is
merely the countably infinite, not the Zenonian Being-now. And together,
we have seen, they are merely the interface of the transitive and
Page | 481
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
PROOF
For let us assume that it has a beginning. Since the beginning is an
existence which is preceded by a time in which the thing is not, there
must have been a preceding time in which the world was not, i.e. an
empty time. . . .
The logical absurdity is obvious, and thus the reductio vindicates the infinite
antithesis over the failed reductio of the thesis. A spatio-temporal beginning
presupposes the concepts of both space and time. A “beginning to Time” is a
circular concept. A tautology, and a logical, conceptual and imaginative
absurdity. Likewise, a beginning in space presupposes a space in which this
boundary and beginning exists. Thus again, the infinite is merely impossible
to imagine and fully encapsulate (by definition, naturally) as ONE-ALL, while
the notion of ultimate boundary is not only impossible to imagine, but also
illogical, i.e. circular.
To be fair, Kant’s antinomies were discovered in a time prior to the
mathematical resolution of the paradoxes of the infinite, and in the
ignorance of the esoteric rationality of Spinoza’s Triune Infinite. Thus Kant
had very good reasons to side against the powers of reason and with the
paradoxes and con-fusions as being inherently irresolvable.
We have seen otherwise, however, and so we can side with the
capabilities and faculties of man. We have seen that the paradoxes
themselves put a pressure on reason to work themselves out into nondual
recognitions of the fundamental polarity of conceptualization itself. With
Galileo’s paradox, for example, we saw that the polarity of infinity and
number worked itself out through the Cantorian transfinite orders and
arithmetic of the infinite, and into the nondual-rational Triune Infinite. And
through Zeno’s paradoxes the mathematics of the continuum worked itself
into its own ordering of the immanent infinities or singularities of the
irrational and transcendental numbers, and now into philosophical
understanding with the triune interface between the two fundamental VL-
axes of conceptual thought itself.
Page | 482
TO INFINITY AND BEYOND: TUNING AND TRIUNING THE PARADOX
Page | 483
PART II: INTERFACE MATHEMATICS
Page | 484
Page | 485
If mathematics is the art and science of pure relation, then philosophy is the
art and science of the pure concept, which often—and perhaps best—serves
the transcendent or “higher level” purpose of the inter-relation and
integration of the arts and sciences (or knowledge in general). Otherwise
knowledge itself remains fragmented, divided and conquered. This
integration is the function that philosophy has already served throughout
this text, but at the more general level (deeper in the EOTC) of meta-
mathematics, as well as the meta-philosophy and meta-paradigm of the
Vision-Logic Coordinate System and the Univocity Framework.
In this section, however, we delve into the traditional details of
philosophy itself, instead of the areas “outside”, or in the external direction
away from philosophy (such as mathematics) into which philosophy often
strays—offering its integrating perspective by weaving a tapestry of
concepts. The problems we will encounter—with our nondual-rational
integrating perspective and meta-philosophy now intact—are the common
ones which, solved long ago in essence (by the nondual philosophies in
general, for example), seem to persist in philosophy classes, their dualisms
grotesquely exaggerated and caricatured so as to offer eternal resistance and
practice for the budding philosophy student—and perhaps to keep the
professors and philosophy itself employed in the modern academy. These
problems include—the “mind-body problem”; the problem of free-will and
determinism; the nature of knowledge (i.e. epistemology); as well as the
problem of nondually integrating and inter-relating the philosophies of
Spinoza and Leibniz, the two main nondual rationalists.
Page | 486
i
The core analysis in this section was discovered and written long before my encounter with Deleuze
or Wilber. For the original publication of this sub-thesis see
http://home.comcast.net/~anpheon/misc/Spinozas_Attribute_Polarity.pdf. The quote, “the
nucleation of observability” comes from Bucky Fuller’s Synergetics.
Page | 487
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 488
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 489
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, I/T Omni- and Uni-axes, p145.
ii
It is this platonic inheritance in the medieval system that the last renaissance man, Leibniz (in line
with Descartes), wishes to protect from the onslaught of inevitable modernity initiated by the first
modern philosopher, Spinoza. Descartes may have been the first philosopher employing a modern
method, but his philosophy, like Leibniz's, is an attempt to protect the medieval Theocratic system.
Spinoza, however, is the first of the modern's in both method and message.
iii
Essentially, the project of rationalism failed in part due to the political/theoretical reactions against
the necessary implications of the project in its dethronement and pulverization of the platonic
category of the immortal human soul. Surprisingly, one of the main facilitators of the abortion of
the project of rationality was also one of the progenitors of its key insights, Gottfried Leibniz himself.
In his attempt to subvert his own covert Spinozism in the creation of a “popular religion” which
would unite the catholic and protestant churches, he fostered a transcendent-biased line of
thinking, Idealism, which was itself pre-rational (and indeed pre-postmetaphysical) in many of its key
aspects. This is explicated in great historical detail in Mathew Stewart’s The Courtier and the
Heretic, and is further expanded upon in the section, Leibnoza Von Spinbitz: An Identity of
Opposites, p659.
Page | 490
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
bring his project far enough to explain the percept-based source of its
resultant conceptual form. For this reason we will take Spinoza’s model as
given—however revealed and/or distorted by the geometric methodology
and the archaic medieval terminology he inherited—and we will shed light
on its epistemological and ontological form through the subsequent
discoveries and inventions in modern and post-modern philosophy and
mathematics, both academic and on the outskirts of orthodoxy, such as the
ideas of Buckminster Fuller and Gilles Deleuze.
Modern Spinozistic exegesis is divided into two main camps, the Objectivists
and the Subjectivists, centered on the problematic, and supposedly
ambiguous, definition of an attribute. As we will see, this division is in turn
generated by a false dichotomy surrounding the interpretation of a central
term in Spinoza’s ultimately inadequate definition of an attribute.
The central definition of an attribute in its original Latin form is “Per
attributum intelligo id, quod intellectus de substantia percipit, tanquam
ejusdem essentiam constituens.”i¥ The most common and natural English
translation of this definition is as follows (my emphases); “the attributes are
that which the intellect perceives of Substance as constituting (tanquam
constituens) its essence.” The term tanquam plays a pivotal role in this
exegetic rift in that it both separates and connects two crucial aspects of the
definition, the epistemic and the ontic. The phrase, “intellect perceives”
represents the epistemic level (perception as a function of knowledge and
representation) and “essence” represents the ontic level, and as we have
seen, ultimately and necessarily Emptiness and Substance.
Perhaps due in part to the pre-rational and transcendent-biasedii*
reactionary restrictions of the historically distorted hermeneutic space
forced upon modern academia by its post-modern Empiricist and Idealist
reaction against metaphysics (or creative ontological conceptualization),
neither side can see, nor invent, a possible way to include both the ontic and
the epistemic aspects of this definition in the final historical interpretation.
Accordingly, the two camps have split precisely at this symbolic conjunction
between the ontic and epistemic aspects, both of which are crucial to
Spinoza’s definition of an attribute. To make matters worse for our modern
academics, Spinoza, being the neutral party that he naturally is—with his
nondual ontic-epistemic polarity implicit in his univocal view of
Substanceiii*—unwittingly armed both sides of the debate by his purposeful
repeated use of both aspects of the definition.
i¥
Ethics I, Def. IV. quoted in Francis S. Haserot, Spinoza's Definition of Attribute, (The Philosophical
Review, Vol. 62, No. 4 (Oct., 1953), 499-513.)
ii
* See, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias, p91 and, The Image of the
Trans-Trans-Bias, 312.
iii
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153.
Page | 491
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Since the Objectivists take the ontic view that the attributes represent the
essence of Substance, they have the luxury of taking the most common and
natural translation of an attribute, as discussed above, because the “as
constituting” puts a clear link from the attributes to the essence of
Substance—the attributes then become linked to the ontic or sub-
representational level, as constituting the essence of Substance. For the
Objectivists then, the epistemic aspect in Spinoza’s definition, represented
by “the intellect perceives,” becomes a secondary and superfluous (yet
curiously ever-present and bothersome) feature of the definition. The
attributes of both Thought and Extension, according to the Objectivist
interpretation, therefore somehow exist (though they never say how, or in
what form) as part of the essence of Substance, and then merely by
ontological default they extend to the epistemic level providing the support
for the arguments of their epistemically-bound opponents.
The Subjectivists, on the other hand, are at a slight disadvantage, since
they take the less common linguistic interpretation, the view from the
epistemic pole, that the attributes represent merely the ways in which the
essence of Substance can be known. But this linguistic disadvantage is
countered or supplemented by the ubiquity of the scientific/materialist
framework that tends to support this interpretation. The Subjectivist’s
preferred interpretation of this critical passage assigns to the Latin tanquam
the less common meaning of as ifi and the interpretation then becomes “the
attributes are that which the intellect perceives of Substance as if
constituting its essence.”
This emphasis on the illusory “as if” enables the Subjectivists to connect
the attributes to the higher-level intellect and its necessary perceptions (and
perspectival illusions) in direct opposition to connecting the attributes to the
very essence of Substance, the ontic level. The attributes are raised up from
the problematic ontic-level univocity of essence as existence, and into the
abstract, anthropocentric realm of the epistemic, as merely the key ways in
which the essence of Substance (existence) can be known. To the
Subjectivists then, the intellect ascribes attributes to Substance which “in
reality” (ontic) is without them. In the forward to Reflections and Maxims
(edited by Dagobert D. Rune), Albert Einstein—who famously spoke of
himself as a “disciple” of Spinoza—gives a succinct example of a Subjectivist
(scientific/materialist) reading; “Here one finds the majestic concept that
thinking (soul) and extension (naturally conceived world) are only different
i
Think here of the inflection put on this by a modern teenage girl, “as if”, to get my point that this
puts the attributes in the position of being illusory functions, if however necessary, of the limits of
knowledge.
Page | 492
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
Quoted from Dagobert D. Runes editor with a forward by Albert Einstein, Reflections and Maxims,
(New York, Philosophical Library Inc, 1965). Note that this is essentially an “integral,” or “AQAL” way
of thinking in terms of perspectives as fundamental. Ken Wilber’s AQAL (all quadrants all levels,
lines, etc), however, has two more “quadrants”, which represent the plural aspects of the internal
(mind) and the external (matter) perspectives.
ii¥
Ethics II, Prop VII, note:
iii¥
Ethics I, Prop. 19 Proof.
Page | 493
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
such a way as to perceive the essence of Substance through these two ways,
aspects or attributes.
Given the complexity of the subject matter of the mind, the explanation
will, however, necessarily still be at a general level, and we will see that it is
not necessary for our purposes to dig into the neurobiology of cognitive
functions in order to give an adequate explanation that appears to reach the
plane of consistency in Spinoza’s thought. It is true, however, that those
empirically derived neurobiological explanations have indeed influenced,
are supported by, and are interfaced in this work.
Page | 494
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
As the discussion above suggests, there are two critical aspects of the
definition of an attribute which must be reconciled in the new
interpretation: they are the ontic and the epistemic. The attributes, in
Spinoza’s definition, express the sub-representational essence of Substance
and pre-exist (ontic) the representational intellect which necessarily
perceives this essence through them (epistemic).
Recall that the exegetic division in Spinozistic scholarship is centered on
the subject/object distinction. If we find, however, that in Spinoza’s system
the distinction between the subjective and the objective is a difference in the
fundamental ways in which we can obtain knowledge about the world (as we
will see below)—and as such, this subject/object duality maps squarely onto
the representational domain of epistemology as only an epistemic-level
expression of the much deeper polarity of the attributesi—what then does
this do to the validity of the “Subjectivist” and “Objectivist” labels given to
our exegetic division between the warring camps?
Furthermore, as we will see, this nominal problem is due to the hidden
nature of these dual polarities and the subsequent modern tendency (“flat-
land materialism”) to collapse the objective into the ontic as foundational
and to raise the subjective to the secondary, and at best emergent epistemic.
The other modern tendency (“idealism”) is to react and counteract this
object-reductionism with its opposite replacement in a flat-land subject-
reductionism. This gives us the opposing equations, object = ontic vs. subject
= ontic, which gives us the relational nuclei of the twin poles of this exegetic
rift.
The nondual-rational solution to this problem of foundational imbalance
and tacit-dualismii* will be facilitated, naturally, through use of the VCSiii*
and the Univocity Frameworkiv* as a conceptual reference system for
i
…or as the two upper quadrants in Ken Wilber’s epistemic “AQAL matrix” in his Integral
Methodological Pluralism.
ii
* See, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156).
iii
* See, The Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS), p123.
iv
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF),, p153.
Page | 495
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
Ken Wilber’s AQAL matrix, useful as it is at the epistemic level, is not quite adequate here because
it does not explicitly address the ontic/epistemic polarity. This is because it takes as given, at least
on the surface, the modern academic (exoteric) post-modern rejection of any ontic-level claims. For
our purposes, suffice it to say that Wilber’s post-metaphysics relies on a peculiarly medieval notion
of metaphysics as reliant on the “Great chain of Being” (GCB). (This is explained in more detail in the
section Clearing Away the Dust of the Great Chain of Being, p37) Although a common academic
interpretation of Spinoza (fostered by Leibniz and Hegel, for example) is that he offers an essentially
materialistic system. A more informed and perhaps more common view, taken by Bertrand Russell
for example, is that Spinoza’s system is neither a materialism nor an idealism, but rather a neutral
monism. One of the critical criteria for a post-metaphysical model, according to Wilber, is that the
GCB become subverted from its matter-to-mind hierarchy (though it is odd that Wilber doesn’t
address the inversion of this hierarchy in idealism) and these essential distinctions become
epistemic and perspectival, such as the inside vs. the outside points of view. This is precisely the
interpretation of Spinoza herein, and at the general level, it is not an uncommon interpretation.
Note also that this interpretation herein was arrived at long in advance of this author ever
discovering the work of Ken Wilber, and was explicated in the original publication of this article on 7-
31-04
Page | 496
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Figure 8: Omni- Uni- Interfaces: Repeated from I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the
Omni-Non.
Page | 497
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
one could reduce thought to a few laws and principles, or indeed (and
perhaps the height of absurdity) to “an equation that could fit on a T-shirt.”i
In Spinoza’s time in general, and in his writings, however, the term
‘objective’ referred to the observations of external reality rather than to that
reality itself. Therefore, ‘objectivity’ referred to our knowledge of the
external world and ‘subjectivity’ referred to our knowledge of the internal
world. This distinction between the ontic and the objective (and by
corollary to the subjective) is encoded in the Aristotelian distinction
between actual or formal reality and objective reality, which Spinoza
incorporated wholesale into his terminology via his study of earlier
philosophers, such as Descartes. Indeed, this is made explicit with an
editor’s note from Spinoza’s Ethicsii¥ (265):
Spinoza is here using a scholastic distinction which is also used by
Descartes, (…where Descartes distinguishes between ‘actual’ or ‘formal’
reality and ‘objective reality’). When Spinoza speaks of the ‘formal
essence’ of something, he means the essence of that thing as it is in itself.
On the other hand, to say that something exists ‘objectively in God’s
intellect’ is to say (a) that its existence is mental and (b) that it is
representative of something.
With the Newtonian scientific revolution of the 17th century, however, and
the wild success and ascendancy of pragmatic mathematics, physical
principles and Laws of physics—at the expense of causal or ontological
speculation and explanation, and its roots in scholastic terminology—the
meaning of ‘objective’ slowly became synonymous with the ontic, and came
to refer to the reality itself whose Laws we felt we were uncovering, e.g.
Galileo’s book of Nature written in the language of mathematics.iii
With the “Scientific Revolution”—in which Spinoza’s system was spurned
for Descartes’ and Newton’s respective “mechanistic” dualities—a
corresponding shift in the meanings of these polarizing terms (objective and
subjective) has followed suit. With this ontic shift toward objectivity, the
i
Matthew Stewart, in his book The Truth About Everything notes quite presciently that such a
reduction to man-made and arguably ideal laws discloses a polarity reversal (See, Principle 4: Chord
3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR), p117), in that materialism becomes an idealism when
matter reduces to merely the ideal laws of physics. Indeed we can see this quite clearly in the
operations at the empirical edges of physics where the function of the conscious observer in the
collapse of the wave-function is taken to be the reality itself. Stewart comically calls this problem
“The Schmiderialism Principle” (p. 309) and indeed it is a problem of mistaking descriptive
(epistemic) protocols, subjectivity or objectivity for the formative, ontic or sub-representational
level.
ii¥
Translated by Andrew Boyle with notes by G.H.R. Parkinson (Orion House; USA, 1993)
iii
This shift was also catalyzed by the operationalization of the intrinsic solid bias, the attempt to
search only for the ultimate in terms of particles. This solid-bias, in turn, debilitated the causal
th
reasoning of the physicists of the 20 century when they encountered the vast fluid complexity of
the quantum world with its “zoo” or particles which appear far more like fleeting wave resonances
and vortices than anything solid.
Page | 498
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
Idealism quickly emerged and constantly re-emerges as a healthy countermeasure to the ontic-
objective reduction thus attempting to balance the imbalance, but it is still a minor reactionary sub-
paradigm on the margins of the default materialism.
ii
It is ironic that the two camps spontaneously divided upon a line which is emergent from the
fundamental division of the attributes themselves. The subjective and the objective are the names
of the two attributes at the level of “excellence” (in complexity) corresponding to that of a cognitive
mode, such as an animal brain/mind. So if the exegetic division occurs between the actual
attributes—at the epistemic level of object and subject—then clearly it is an erroneous mapping
unless one wishes to deny the existence of one or the other attribute. But this may indeed be the
underlying driving factor due to the natural tendency of the human mind for absolutizing inherently
relative knowledge systems or interpretations. This spontaneous division only goes to show the
actual pervasiveness of the fundamental polarity. It exists at all levels of modification, from a-tom
to episteme.
iii
Hegelians may jump at this chance to reaffirm to themselves their favorite interpretive error,
namely that Spinoza’s substance is inert, passive and rigid because, as they suppose, it excludes the
concept of Becoming. This is a common misconception about Spinoza’s substance, but Spinoza
claimed in his Short Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being, that “since substance is [the cause]
and the origin of all its modes, it may with far greater right be called acting than passive.” Spinoza’s
substance does not equate to the modern physics notion of inert, dead, blind and stupid matter and
it cannot in any sense be passive because it is the root of existence itself.
Page | 499
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 500
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
* See section 2.5 “Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object”
ii
“For the excellence of ideas, and the actual power of thinking are measured by the excellence of
the object.” Ethics III, General Definition of the Emotions
iii ¥
Darren Staloff, Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition: Lecture 33: Spinoza—
Rationalism and the Reverence for Being, audio CD of a lecture for The Teaching Company
(http://www.teach12.com ). In this lecture Staloff defined Spinoza’s attributes as “descriptive
protocols.”
Page | 501
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
or even a binary description of a digital photograph, but this seems to be in a specialized category,
that of the constructive protocols, such as DNA. In Golem XIV, Stanislaw Lem calls them “causative
languages.”
ii
And Ken Wilber would argue, quite effectively perhaps, that there are ultimately four; his AQAL
quadrants.
iii
Ken Wilber has mapped out these two “quadrants” sufficiently for our purposes, and we need not
belabor this point. For further demonstration of this distinction, see virtually any of Ken’s books on
his integral model.
iv
A causal explanation of how the formative protocols might function is beyond the scope of this
paper. At the foundation, this Spinozistic interpretation ties into and draws from a new unified
model of physics called “Sorce Theory.” For more information see http://www.anpheon.org .
Page | 502
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 503
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
For those informed of Ken Wilber’s Integral Methodological Pluralism, this quadrant map is entirely
orthogonal (a side view) to Ken’s AQAL matrix which would be seen edge on as the line between the
ontic and epistemic quadrants. This is because Ken’s map deals exclusively with epistemic functions
as they fade down into the ontic level. Accordingly, when visualized as extended into 3d space
Page | 504
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
informed by the categories of the AQAL matrix not shown in this map, a new set of four cubes is
formed for the two “objective and subjective plural” quadrants as they extend from the epistemic
AQAL modalities into the ontic nondual-rational modalities forming a total of eight cubes when
combined. In this extended map of the orthogonal intersection between the nondual-rational ontic-
epistemic polarity and the AQAL singular-plural polarity, only the singular quadrants are visible in
the diagram here, and under consideration in this immediate discussion, except as necessarily
implied in the plurality inherent in the sub-unit architecture and the transitive-plane of the omni-
axis, etc..
i
The omni-local is the identical inverted pole of the non-local. Neither of which are local because a
location requires a field of otherness to give it reference; the omni is negating the local because it is
all-encompassing and thus not located and the non-local is quite obvious as a negation of the local.
ii
* See, Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID), p186.
iii
Consciousness herein is based on the human as exemplar and generally connotes a
representational level of awareness as opposed to a general universal reactivity or within-ness
/immanence.
iv¥
Ethics III, general definition of the emotions.
v
See “The Antipodes of Organization” in the article, Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement.
Page | 505
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
This concept of holonic emergence corresponds to Leibniz’s “principle of unity” which serves to
define his conception of substance.
Page | 506
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
This surface is an abstraction for the emergent nature of consciousness and must not be taken for a
visually distinguishable barrier. It is likely that the actual subject/object interface is indeed quite
distributed in the brain as the “mnemonic primitives” discussed in section 2.5.
Page | 507
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 508
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
See Michel Serres for discussion on his concept of the “cultivated third”. I have merely emphasized
the ontic, or a priori and active/formative aspect of this polarity-triuning interface, or third.
ii
Thus the modern physics concept of the “zero-dimensional point particle” is a mathematical
abstraction—albeit a perhaps necessary simplification—which has been substituted and confused
for the reality it represents.
iii
See my article, Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement.
iv¥
From http://www.dictionary.com
Page | 509
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
than to other individual things, all of which, though in different degrees, are
animated [animata].”i¥ This “anima” is the immanent active causation within
all things (corresponding to the existential idea that existence, an active
property, precedes individual essenceii*), and as Spinoza says in his Short
Treatise on God, Man and His Well-Being, “since substance is [the cause] and
the origin of all its modes, it may with far greater right be called acting than
passive.”iii
Spinoza makes it clear that the attribute of thought is an interior
existence, experience, or point of view whose degree of “excellence” is
dependent upon the degree of “excellence” of the mode doing the existing
perceiving or conceiving. As Spinoza says, “For the excellence of ideas, and
the actual power of thinking are measured by the excellence of the object.”iv¥
This collective degree of excellence is the morphological gradient and
interface between the ontic and epistemic where the modes at the epistemic
level (a somewhat arbitrarily defined level of cognitive complexity
somewhere between the level of the human brain/mind and, say, an
amoeba) would be considered “cognitive modes,” or cognitive holons.v
In Spinoza’s system then, the term for the attribute of “Thought” is
misleading in many respects because it generally connotes to us our own
human intrinsic/subjective and epistemic experience and then seems to
project this connotation onto the fundamental nature of reality. This is
clearly an erroneous reading, however, and this is qualified by Spinoza’s
stipulation of the gradient of “excellence” as interpreted herein.
It is possible that Spinoza used this now problematic term because he
recognized the continuity of the morphological gradient of representational
intelligence (what we might indeed call “thought”) and wished to forestall
the reduction of either mind or matter to the other. And accordingly,
Spinoza extended the attribute of Thought all the way down the infinite,
immanent gradient of excellence (or “depth” as integral theorists would call
it) to objects which we would not ordinarily consider to be thinking at all,
but which nonetheless do indeed have an inner aspect of existence
conceivable only through the attribute of Thought (i.e. from within) in
contradistinction to the outer interrelational aspect perceivable and
conceivable only through the attribute of Extension.
i¥
Ethics II, PROP. XIII
ii
* See, Univocity and Essence, p170.
iii
This, recall, directly contradicts Hegel’s main criticism of Spinoza's Substance as rigid. Again,
Substance is Emptiness, the absolute scope. It can no more be called rigid than floppy. Polarities do
not apply.
iv¥
Ethics III, General Definition of the Emotions
v
Note that only certain types of modes would be considered holons. These holons are modes with a
bounded synergetic unity and a homeostasis, where the
Page | 510
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
This is yet another case in which Spinoza seems to have intuited critical
aspects of modern science; this time it is the property that complexity
scientists call “emergence.” With this understanding, Spinoza recognized the
impossibility of ascribing an exact line of demarcation on the gradient
between the morphological instances of the ‘thinking’ and the ‘unthinking’,
the ‘conscious’ and the ‘unconscious’, the ‘intelligent’ and the ‘pre-
intelligent’, or more generally the ‘cognitive’ and the ‘pre-cognitive.’ This is
essentially the view that modern cognitive science has arrived at with its
ideas of the functional nesting of simple mechanisms leading to the gradual
irreducible emergence of higher representational functionality through
synergistic non-linear feedback mechanisms at the boundary between chaos
and order.
Spinoza also makes it clear that the epistemic aspect of the attribute of
Extension is an external point of view from which one conceives or perceives
of the world entirely as if the indwelling essence of reality were exclusively
extended in matter and its inter-relations. This is because outsides and
inter-relations are all we can see when we take things apart and view them
from outside their own immanent causal existence (see Figure 67, below).
The interpretation herein makes it clear how every mode of Substance can
and must be independently conceived under one or the other attribute as
each mode necessarily has an internal and external experience or point of
view from which it can be conceived of and perceived, and—corresponding
to its degree of excellence—from which it can itself, conceive and perceive.
As Matthew Stewart says in The Courtier and Heretic [[my comments]] “The
place to look for the unconscious part of the mind, then, is not in a fictional,
hidden mind, but in the gap between the idea of the body that constitutes the
mind and the body itself” [[i.e. the “explanatory gap”]] (p172). In other
words, the human mind (the “idea of the body” or the idea that the body
has), as epistemic and representational, emerges from the body itself as
ontic, but both stratified ontic and epistemic aspects of attribute-neutral
modality of the body are subject to the vertical bisection of the twin
attributes, Thought and Extension, since holonic nucleation, and the polarity
of the within and without, occurs at all levels of the body, ontic and
epistemic (recall Figure 65, p505).
The dual (within/without) aspect necessarily inherent in the formative
and descriptive (ontic and epistemic) essence of all modification quite
simply accounts for the exact “order and connection” that both the “modes of
thought” and the “modes of extension” adhere to (see Figure 67, below).
Page | 511
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
“The order and connection of ideas is the same as the order and connection
of things”i¥ and simultaneously it explains why the two attributes must
function in parallel isolation from one another; this is because as a
localization you can’t simultaneously be outside the mode, viewing it under
the aspect of Extension, and inside the mode as the intrinsic experience
itself.ii Or more simply put, you can’t be both outside and inside yourself at
the same time.iii However, Spinoza also says, “thinking substance and
extended substance are one and the same substance, comprehended now
under this attribute, now under that. So, too, a mode of extension and the
idea of that mode [[a “mode of thought”]] are one and the same thing,
expressed in two ways.”iv¥ The “idea” of the mode, as a modification of the
attribute of Thought, is this intrinsic existence or the experience of being the
mode itself.
The gap of attribute parallelism at the epistemic level exists because of
the necessary distinction between the two basic modes of
conception/perception—the within and the without—manifesting at the
epistemic level as the fundamental descriptive protocols
(subjective/objective) with their intrinsic limits as an emergent or
transcendent interface. To cross this gap the best one can do is to view both
attributes separately and pseudo-simultaneously (i.e. intermittently shifting
ones attention between the two, time-slices), for example watching a TV
monitor of an active brain scan of the mental states one is in while he
watches his own brain scan. However, the two views—now feeding back
into each other limiting both states simultaneously to an interlocked
existence—are still essentially separate and must be correlated through the
knowledge of what one is watching from the outside vs. how it feels on the
inside.
Ultimately, Spinoza says, “…in the universe nothing is granted, save
substances and their modifications,”v¥ therefore, with only one Substance
(the ONE-ALL of The Infinite or simply Emptiness) in existence, every
modification of an attribute is essentially a modification of Substance,
comprehended and expressed now through one attribute and now through
the other (from within or without), but as we have seen, never both
i¥
Ethics I, Prop. VII.
ii
A key is presented here to disabling the homuncular regress by abandoning the notion that the
experience of consciousness necessitates an experiencer. They are one and the same thing but
occasionally the experience includes a feedback function we call “self-consciousness.”
iii
Of course this further depends on the aperture or scope of your definition of self which can be as
flexible as one wants, and can extend beyond Extension to Substance itself thus revealing the
polarity and unity of this duality. It is the control of this aperture that opens the communication
lines between free-will and determinism.
iv¥
Ethics II, Prop. 7
v¥
Ethics I, Prop. 6, Proof.
Page | 512
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
…unless perhaps one realizes the fundamental symbiotic unity beneath the perceived/conceived
duality of subject and object in the emergence of the sensory/mnemonic interface (see the coming
section, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528).
Page | 513
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
polarities,, recall, are ultimately found on the I/T omni- and uni-axes,
respectively, with their respective interfaces in the transitive-plane and the
spheroidal boundary. There is an ontic aspect to the attributes in the
“formative protocols,” and the attributes exist whether perceived through or
not. As the fundamental polarity of boundary—the duality of finite unity—
the two attributes, existing in the nucleated holonic ontic substrate from
which the epistemic emerges, are naturally prior to emergent and nucleated
perception and conception. And naturally the ontic aspect (the formative
protocols) of this fundamental polarity of bounded form is necessarily
perceived through the a priori “descriptive protocols” of the epistemic.
The mistaken reading of the attributes is the assumption that objectivity
and subjectivity—the twin aspects of cognition, representation and the
epistemic—are both subsumed under the attribute of Thought. The
attribute of Thought, it must be clear, is not the common notion
‘thought.’ Objectivity is the epistemic level of the attribute of Extension
and subjectivity is the epistemic level of the attribute of Thought. The
“crossroads” of the two polarities—the attributes and the ontic/epistemic—
arises at the emergent monadic interface of every
cognitive/representational holon or mode, but the distinction must be kept
from collapsing into a con-fusion between the omni- and uni-axes of the
ontic-epistemic and the subject-object polarities, respectively.
the absolute scope takes us not into the certainty of any of the truths of form
outside the self, but to an absolute certainty of only oneself—the solipsistic
self-absolute because the only thing the self can know absolutely is the
representational interface itself. All else is projection.
Through the principle of absolute reversal, however, of taking the self-
boundary to the absolute, it dissolves its other and fades into the omni-non
of nihilipsism (self-annihilation). If there is no other, there is no self—just as
in the omni-local if there is no distinction between one location and all
others, there is no location referenced at all. Ultimately we come to the
annihilation of the self-distinction and boundary itself with the elimination
of polarity. This is the “cogito of the dissolved self,” roughly.
Page | 515
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Spinoza’s use of the term ‘extension’ comes from a long line of tradition
ending with Descartes who conceived of it as synonymous with volume; a
combination of the measurements of width, height and depth. How does one
measure or perceive volume? As we have seen in the EOTC of number and
operation,i* one begins by identifying a unit of reference for setting the
relative scale of measurement—ideally a highly stable and uniformly
replicable physical object, like a meter-stick—and then one uses this unit to
measure relative distances in terms of multiples or divisions of the unit. The
key point to understand is that these distances are always relative to the
scale of choice, and in turn, this scale must be relative to the organism doing
the measuring. Consequently it is the finite cognitive holon—a form already
transcendent from the Emptiness of immanence—and the limits and range
of its perceptual modifications (sensory systems), which are the ultimate
transcendent referent by which all scales must be set for the purposes of
perceiving and measuring transcendent extension. And it should be clear
that no such finite or indefinite objective process can ever reach the infinite
either in terms of extent or resolution (transitive or immanent,
respectively).ii
Even though Spinoza’s extended Substance is fundamentally continuous
(recall our principle of Nondual Rationalism; infinite division equals
indivisibility), extension—as a relative conceptual, perceptual and metrical
concept—does not descend into the immanent causation or infinite-
divisibility/indivisibilityiii within the continuity. Rather it must remain a
strictly transitive or transcendent (trans-biased) concept based on the set
limit or range of scale centered on the basic unit itself; otherwise every
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
This is why, as Leibniz discovered, neither the multiplicative infinite nor the divisive zero are true
numbers.
iii
At the absolute level these two (infinitely-divided and indivisible) are identical.
Page | 516
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
A term borrowed from Gerald Lebau which fits with Bucky Fuller’s “Operational Mathematics” by
adding extension and boundary (and the corresponding nuclear polarity) to every conceivable point,
rendering “infinitely small” ultimately an oxymoron (see SpinbitZ).
Page | 517
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 518
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
This universal self-similar or fractal patterning can be seen on all scales, from the electron shells of
the atom (mapped with Schrödinger’s equation) to the structuring of the stellar systems (mapped
with Bode’s Law). The possible mechanisms for this patterning are explained in Sorce Theory
(www.anpheon.org )
ii
We are constantly expanding our range of perception through technological augmentation. A great
example is the “Terahertz gap” in the spectrum of detectable em-waves between infrared and
microwaves which is just beginning to be opened by technological means offering whole new realms
of observational capabilities such as seeing through walls and enhanced medical imaging. There is
simply no end in sight to the expansion of our perceptual range and no reason (except for current
limitations of “Standard” theory) to suspect an absolute barrier.
Page | 519
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Figure 69: The Cognitive Holon and the Subject/Object Interface with Immanence and
Transcendence:
Perception is a subject/object resonance within a limited domain of frequencies
(transitive plane) on the infinite VL-axis of scale (I/T axis). The white background
without and within each mode corresponds to those frequencies of resonance which
are beyond and below (respectively) the perceptual reach of the cognitive holon, i.e.
beyond the sensorial realm. The black rings denote the self -stabilized homeostatic
integrated emergence of intrinsic, self-focused ‘experience’ (“qualia”) from within the
mode. The larger spheres are the modes of cognition such as a human brain/mind with
its corresponding epistemic duality of objectivity and subjectivity. Note that when the
arrow of extension tries to touch the inner ‘experience’—the inner black rings—of an
outer mode, the best it can do is convert the insides into outsides in exposing the
inside components to an outside view. One may object that we can receive sens ory
data, such as active brain scans, directly from the insides of living brains, but this is
still a view of the inside from outside the mode in question. One cannot ever
experience the within of anything through sensations from without, without
transforming that without into that within. One must be the focal point of the
energies to be the experience of the subjectivity in question.
Page | 520
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
Keep in mind that the plane itself is a spatial abstraction from the continuity of the spectrum of
frequencies and thus it really represents a continuous range in a volume of frequencies set by the
cognitive mode itself which in turn is based at the deeper ontic level of the “matter-unit substrate”
or “islands of resonance.”
ii¥
Ethics I, Prop. 1.
iii
Possible mechanisms for this quantization can be found in Sorce Theory, and covered at a general
level in my article Sorce Theory: Unlocking the Basement. The galactic-scale quantization is seen in
the recent conclusions of the “quantization of redshift” based on observations initially conducted in
the early 1970’s by William G. Tifft, of the University of Arizona. See for example
http://www.ldolphin.org/tifftshift.html This also may cast a deep problem onto the Big Bang
cosmogony which is based on the Doppler interpretation of the Hubble redshift as its sole
mechanism. If—as has been shown in other studies such as the “fingers of God” anomaly—there
are serious problems with the Doppler interpretation of redshift, then there must be another
mechanism other than the fantastical idea of the expansion of the entire Universe, whose extent, for
all we know, may be infinite.
iv
This is the field of “simplest bodies” denoted by Spinoza which evolves into “composite bodies”
along the gradient of “excellence.” Depending on the meta-unit homogeneity (density/pressure
gradients/patterns) of the next substrate level from which they form.
v
* See, Trip-Reset: “Simplest Bodies” and the Self-Similar Kosmos, p586.
Page | 521
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
“physical monads”), our atoms and their quantized variants i (the ~92
naturally occurring chemical elements), generate resonant levels or planes
of morphological complexity, stability and agglomerative possibility
enabling the architectural complexification necessary for the “spontaneous”
evolution of the cognitive holons. These transitive planes of
stability/possibility (“islands of resonance”) on the I/T omni-axis are then
the “ground” of the morphological gradient of cognitive complexification
towards Spinoza’s cognitive “excellence.”
From the relative simplicity at the level of the homogenized/granulated
matter-unit substrate, to the monstrous architectural complexity of the
cognitive holons—this gradient forms the essence of the ontic/epistemic
polarity; the distinction from which the conceptual/perceptual
(mental/metrical or epistemic) aspect of extension (the fundamental
descriptive protocol) can expand its range of inter-relating, representational
action upon the ontic level in order to create what we call “physical science.”
The immanent scales of these transitive planes are set by the uniformity
of the interrelating and interacting matter-units and their resonant
frequencies. Of necessity—as immanent causal aspects of univocal
Substance—they are perfectly, causally and harmoniously integrated in all
directions on all imaginable and unimaginable omni-relational transitive,
immanent and transcendent axes. It is an infinite causal self-similar
holarchy in which each immanent level enables the quantized existence of
the next transcendent level and vice versa. At the descriptive or perceptual
level, however, these orthogonal ‘planes’ function quite independently as
individual cognitive holons come into or out of sensorial resonance with
them, expanding, contracting or shifting their miniscule range of perception,
through birth, death, technology or evolution.
At our scale of sensory resonance, we observe this homogenized,
interrelational, extensional orthogonality most clearly in the ubiquitous
molecular/atomic matrix of hydrogen (the root atom) that is known to fill
interstellar and intergalactic space.
As highly complex compounded modifications, we are born from and into
this self-similarly modified extensional orthogonality on the chemically and
biologically active surface of a terrestrial nucleus—a planetary biosphere.
This emergent I/T-orthogonality or transitivity inherent in the immanent,
continuous active essence of Substance—in its formative aspect to nucleate
into transitively inter-relating self-similar islands of resonance—is
extension at the ontic level as it causally interrelates the nature of
i
Sorce Theory and quantum physics demonstrates the likelihood that the subatomic particles are
either variants of the simplest atomic nucleus, such as protons and neutrons, or they are relatively
short-lived wave-forms and resonances such as solitons, breathers or other complex and dynamic
morphologies that do not ‘own’ their own material, and thus collectively they form charged fields
rather than composite bodies proper.
Page | 522
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 523
Page | 524
Figure 70: Duality Chasm: The Vista of the Expanded
Crossroads:
This chart is a logical extension of Figure 65 (p505), but
renders a more comprehensive view of the ideas given so
far. Note that it includes c onceptual links to the physical
theory upon which this model is based, such as the inclusion
of the single force (“sorce”) and its bifurcation into the
duality of force (all attraction and repulsion) in the
distinction between reflection and refraction. Note also that
there are many open spaces in the tentative listing of
categories and descriptive and formative protocols. Because
of the pervasiveness of these fundamental orthogonal
polarities which are found in almost all known metaphysical
systems, this chart is useful for the organization of many
systems of thought
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 525
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 526
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 527
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
view, then, is the common-sense notion that no finite system can encompass
the infinite. In the Univocity Framework, recall, the infinite and the finite
form a fundamental polarity—the polarity of polarity itself, where the
relative scope projects its other, the absolute scope, to give it defining
context.i* The infinite and finite are the quantitative aspects of the absolute
and relative scopes; the core polarity of Substance and its modes.
According to this nondual-rational point of view, then, both the
materialists and the idealists (or the Subjectivists and Objectivists) make a
common mistake. They each fail to understand the proper role of the
subjective and the objective as fundamental descriptive protocols in the
epistemic and relative realm of inherently limited and fallible
representational abstraction. They therefore each take one epistemic
protocol or the other and erroneously project it down to the ontic level,
toward the foundational absolute scope, in exclusion of the other (see Figure
71, above). This unbalanced view is akin to claiming that outsides can exist
without (or prior to) insides or vice versa and that the entire universe is
ultimately composed only of either the outsides or the insides of things.
When understood in this way, these two common views, in their various
forms, become quite nonsensical because they each neglect the fundamental
nondual principle of polarity, violating the Univocity Framework, as we have
seen.
Materialism (or physicalism) is the view that objectivity (modified
Substance as viewed externally through the attribute of Extension) is the
fundamental point of view into which all others must reduce. Even further,
it is the failure to recognize that objectivity is a point of view at all.ii This
failure enables the ontic=objective absolutization of this relative view and
the reduction of its symbiotic opposite. In the minds of the materialists, this
view then becomes inherently infallible in principle (i.e. the finite is
considered infinite or unlimited and the relative is considered absolute) and
the materialist then claims that subjectivity is fundamentally unreal and
therefore encompassable and replaceable by objectivity.
This is the view taken, in one form or another, by many scientists and
philosophers such as Daniel Dennett, for instance, who has gone so far as to
reject the notion (or maybe just an absolute distortion of the term) of ‘qualia’
(the ‘what it’s like’ quality of mental states) entirely as inherently
meaningless and replaceable by mechanical descriptions.iii
i
* See, “Vertical” Polarity: The Polarity of Polarity, p175.
ii
As stated previously, this is because the meaning of “objectivity” has changed from the
representation of external reality to the reality itself, the ontic. Now there is no corresponding word
to denote its prior meaning and to balance the meaning of subjectivity.
iii
Dennett’s view on qualia, however, is quite justified from within the materialist’s paradigm, and
indeed it is useful to break the Cartesian dualistic spell. Dennett places great emphasis on
demonstrating that the common, absolutized and mystified usage of the term qualia renders the
Page | 528
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
In his book The Truth About Everything, Matthew Stewart notes quite
presciently that in materialism, such a reduction to man-made and arguably
ideal laws discloses a polarity reversali* in that materialism becomes an
idealism when matter reduces to merely the ideal laws of physics. Indeed
we can see this quite clearly in the operations at the empirical edges of
physics where the function of the conscious observer and his descriptive
protocols in the collapse of the wave-function is taken to be the reality itself.
Stewart comically calls this problem “The Schmiderialism Principle”ii¥ and
indeed it is a problem of mistaking descriptive (epistemic) protocols,
subjectivity or objectivity for the formative, ontic or sub-representational
level itself.
Similarly, idealism intuitively recognizes that objectivity has forced
something critical out of the picture and so the idealists swing the other
direction and project the intrinsic emergent aspect of modal existence, down
to the absolute level, often rejecting any and all objective external
descriptions, and even science itself in many cases. The idealists too fail to
realize the emergent/transcendental nature of the epistemic mode
(fundamental descriptive protocol) of subjectivity as inherently abstract and
limited—as well as failing to understand the fundamental polarity and
symbiosis of the two fundamental descriptive/representational points of
view.
Both of these views, we can see, ultimately (when taken to their
extremes) collapse into the “cogito of the dissolved self,” the solipsistic
reduction to the ontic-epistemic boundary of individual experience and the
problem in Cartesian dualistic terms, his ‘Cartesian Theatre.’ Essentially Dennett is only denying that
we have subjective experience in order to say that we are the subjective experience which is
ultimately reduced to a “benign user illusion.” The illusion of course, includes the self-diagnostic
feedback function of self-reflexion.
Notice how the rephrasing from “we have subjective experience” to “we are subjective experience”
disables the dualistic, subject/object, internal homuncular projection. His point is that we have let
the common meanings of this problematic word ‘qualia’ disable the functioning of the “intuition
pumps” or “heuristic bridges,” used by the cognitive scientists, thus disabling the relative truths of
cognitive science to work their way through the philosophy of mind. Since the explanatory gap is
fundamentally unbridgeable, intuition or heuristics are then the only means of correlating the
physicalist descriptions with the actual experience we know as ‘qualia.’ This means that if the word
‘qualia’ causes us to misunderstand the nature of the problem, and therefore causes us to fail to
properly use the quite adequate heuristic bridges provided by cognitive science, then the term must
be disabled in favor of a more correctly functioning word in order to render the problem workable.
Perhaps Dennett could have gone the route of saying that we are qualia rather rejecting the word
itself, but this would still not disable the collective connotative basins of attraction into typical and
simplistic Cartesian dualistic notions that the word engenders. It is perhaps indeed more useful to
just abandon a word and start fresh rather than insist that people use it in a new way.
i
* See, Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR), p117.
ii
Matthew Stewart, The Truth About Everything, p. 309
Page | 529
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, Principle 4: Chord 3: The Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR), p117.
ii
In Spinoza’s view, “substance is prior to its modifications,” therefore no particle can be
fundamental in any absolute sense. The absolute fundamental is the ONE, infinite and continuous
substance, i.e. the universe itself—and all else is but multiplication through division—a modification.
However, in a forthcoming integration and interpretation of Leibniz’s concept of the ‘monad’, there
is a sense in which a pattern, in this case nucleation (for instance at the ontic level of “simplest
bodies” or atoms) and its distinctive pattern of quantization (seen in the intra-atomic-electron orbits
and in the structure of the solar system etc,) can be fundamental as the self-similar infinitely
recurring pattern in the cosmos, the “matter-unit (see Sorce Theory). The absolute fundamental
element of nature, however, is the One, infinite substance, i.e. the universe itself or the absolute
scope. All else is but multiplication through division—a modification.
iii
Spinoza calls the tendency or “endeavor” for each composite body towards self-preservation, its
“essence.”
Page | 530
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
important to note that what is coupled is not the environment and the
interior of the organism, but the interior and the exterior of the abstract
interface of perception itself. Objectivity, recall, is not the outside itself (i.e.
the ontic), but the outside view of the epistemic. At the higher levels of
morphological complexity—yet at the very rudiments of the emerging
cognitive mode—this templating or subject/object calibration process
(enfolding) generates what can be called the “mnemonic primitives,” which
are the defining feature of ‘qualia’ as the emergent, primitive-level
subject/object interface (vinculum) itself; the raw percepts transcended-
and-included in the higher forms of concept.
When a child is born into sensorial resonance with the world, it begins an
intensive calibration process between its inherent pattern recognition,
mnemonic and sensory structures and its resonant environment. This
calibration process is the essence of memory, qualia and sensation in one
enfolding interface between the within and the without. This is why the
newborn infant, as it learns to see and interact with the world, generally
forms and retains no memories that make sense as such to the adult, though
they are ‘remembered’ in dismembered or distributive form as the
primitives of the experience of qualia itself throughout conscious life.i The
infant’s root-level mnemonic pattern-recognition medium is still being
formed and it is from this medium (or context) that all subsequent memories
arise as further complexifications. The child’s memories come into focus as
s/he matures because part of that maturing involves the gradual
development of the mnemonic sensory system itself, from the ground up.
At a basic neurological level the senses begin to ‘memorize’ or ‘learn’
(enfold) the abstracted relevant details and differentiations of reality (e.g.
colors) as it resonates and interacts at the sensory-motor interface. It does
this in order to generate distinct and differentiated responses to different
stimuli as the basis for further higher-level, more abstract homeostatic
cognition and interaction. Some of these responses—the mnemonic
primitives—are the learned neuro-sensory patterns and differentiations
(memories) that are reactivated every time the same basic stimulus is
presented, such as the various frequencies of light impinging on the retina.
Subjectivity itself (e.g. qualia), in this primitive form, thus emerges as the
very experience of the cognitive mode, in active/reactive sensory/mnemonic
resonance with its objective environment.
i
Every once in a while, these primitive memories can crop up in strange places, however, such as a
memory I have which I can only attribute to the moment of birth. This memory of a thick squeeze
and release, seems to emerge into my awareness very strongly and only at the still moments of
crisis. In the embryogenesis of the concept, as one would expect, this primitive memory is very
simple and undifferentiated. It is not even localized in space or time, but feels as if it were occurring
throughout my entire body simultaneously, as if it weren’t composed of subcomponents at all. It
squeezes tight my entire, undifferentiated primitive body-“image” and suddenly releases. Perhaps,
indeed, a primitive memory of the contractions or the moment of birth.
Page | 531
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
Alan Watts calls this “spotlight consciousness” as opposed to the “floodlight sub-consciousness.”
Page | 532
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i¥
George B. Dyson, Darwin Among the Machines (USA: Addison Wesley, 1997)
Page | 533
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 534
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 535
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Does this mean that Identity Theory and Spinoza’s “neutral monism” or
univocal Nondual Rationalism, share no relation? Spinoza says [my
emphasis], “Thinking substance and extended substance are one and the
same thing, comprehended now through this, now through that, attribute.”
This certainly seems to entail an identity of some kind, especially with the
phrase “one and the same thing,” which is actually used in the definition of
Reductive Materialism given above. If the subjective mind and the objective
brain are not numerically identical, then in what sense are they identical and
in what sense can they be reduced, one to the other?
The key here is found in Spinoza’s use of the term “substance.” In
Spinoza’s neutral monism both subjectivity and objectivity are
representative or epistemic aspects of reality, which is neither mind nor
matter exclusively, but it has balanced aspects of both Thought and
Extension (the within and the without as specifically defined herein). Recall
that all modes conceived under each attribute, e.g. the “modes of extension”
and the “modes of thought,” are fundamentally modes of Substance.
Since the mind and the brain are modes of Substance conceived
(episteme) and only differentiated under the attributes of Thought and
Extension respectively, they are then considered and categorized as modes
of the attributes under which they are currently conceived. Thus—due to
the fundamental non-identity between the attributes—“mind” and “brain”
cannot be numerically identical. An identity must therefore be drawn down
through an attribute-neutral ontic channel to the modification of Substance
itself, inclusive of both of its attributes, i.e. before the epistemic distinction
between the within and the without of the singular mode itself is made (See
Figure 74, below). It is this connection between the epistemic and ontic
symbiogenetic polarities of the singular bounded or nucleated modes of
substance, which provides the parallelism and the “exact order and
connection” between the attributes as both descriptive and formative
protocols.
Neutral Monism—as herein described in the context of Nondual
Rationalism—inherits all of the positive aspects of Identity Theory and yet
seems to escape all of its problems. It is said that one of the benefits of
Identity Theory is its accordance with scientific accounts of the functioning
of the brain. Neutral monism, however, is directly in line with, and accepts
both fundamental descriptive protocols; the objective (cognitive science)
and subjective (folk psychology), and it unifies them at a deeper, univocal
ontological level, through the polarity of bounded form. Thus neutral
monism naturally inherits this same positive scientific aspect because
objectivity is a real perception of real modified Substance.
Page | 536
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
i
* See, Univocity: Monism, Polarity and the Nondual, p156.
Page | 537
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
absolute nature of the concept of the numerical identity, because if the same
mental state can be achieved in different physical/material instantiations
and functional platforms, then there can be no one-to-one identity. The
problem is that identity theory unwittingly claims an identity between
physical states and mental states at the epistemic level of the objective and
the subjective, rather than at the ontic level of the single mode of substance.
In order for Identity Theory to hold, a weaker, or relative version of the
identity must be maintained, and this weakens the reductive force and
scientific feel of the model, already lacking any morphological or percept-
based description of the identity, and also lacking the reason that its identity
is now merely relative.
Since, however, the attribute-neutrality of neutral monism and Nondual
Rationalism does not place a numerical identity between subjective mental
states and their objective (externally observed) brain-state counterparts, no
such definitional identity problems arise. The mental-states and the brain-
states are fundamentally different states of description at the epistemic level
and they are the relative and limited means to identify or observe states in
the cognitive mode, arising as they do in dependent symbiogenesis of subject
and object at (and as) the mnemonic interface of the cognitive mode. In
Nondual Rationalism, such an absolute attribution of identity between these
relative, limited, and fundamentally (indeed symbiogenetically) opposed
descriptive protocols, is a violation of the Univocity Framework and the
principles of nonduality.
As we will see, however, the main problem with Identity
Theory/Reductive Materialism—and indeed a common problem with
virtually every materialistic, physicalist or Objectivist theory of mind—
stems from its foundationalist nature. The problem is that no strictly
materialist theory can fully (i.e. absolutely) and explicitlyi account for qualia.
This is naturally because the relative world of description can’t encompass
the absolute scope of the infinite difference of the embodied experience of
subjectivity itself. In other words, given the polarity of the attributes, and
the fallibility of the fundamental descriptive protocols occurring at the
relative and emergent level of awareness, qualia are naturally irreducible to
an objective, physicalist description. The explanatory gap simply cannot
ultimately be bridged. Instead, what we get in all of these theories is a
promissory note that eventually science will evolve to the point that such an
explicit account will indeed bridge this gap.ii While certainly such an
i
Note that the ‘explicit’ is the essence of materialism and objectivity.
ii
It is quite unclear how the explanatory gap ever could be bridged, however, except by relying at
some level on an intuition pump or a causative means rather than an explicit objective explanation.
Of course intuition pumps can already bridge the gap, provided one can properly operate the pump,
but this is not at all satisfactory to the absolute aims of the physicalist or idealist programs which
assumes one or the other descriptive protocols as absolute reality itself and thus needs perfectly
Page | 538
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
account will continue to evolve to the point that it feels adequate, it can
never be complete and absolute in any nondual account.
Nondual Rationalism, however, makes no such absolutist claims about
any necessarily finite and relative knowledge system, or about any of the
relative concepts in its own system. The absolute scope, in Nondual
Rationalism, is explicitly open and ineffable. No concept can land there and
retain its own identity. Through the Univocity Framework, Nondual
Rationalism systematically and categorically recognizes that no finite
representational system can encompass the infinite and continuous
immanent causation of Substance and it is therefore a categorical error to
claim that any description ever could or even should be absolute. There can
and need be no numerical identity between any descriptive protocols. The
problem—which is indeed a problem pervasive to philosophy in general—is
one of assigning absolute characteristics to the relative, and it is explicitly
reconciled in the Univocity Framework.
explicit, logical and thus linear accounts of what, as is often the case, is inherently non-linear and
irreducible.
i
Unless of course the menu or the sheet-music can trigger complexly patterned neural responses in
the brain itself and thus the explanatory gap is crossed not by explanation at the epistemic level, but
by causation at the ontic level. This, of course, is not at all the problem in question, but rather a
subversion to the level at which the problem must be addressed.
Page | 539
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The Spinozistic exegetic rift has been resolved by the recognition that both
the epistemic (Subjectivist) and ontic (Objectivist) readings contain essential
aspects of a deeper morphological gradient. These two warring hermeneutic
camps were also shown to be con-fusing (conflating the pre-fused
distinction between) the two polarities and VL-axes of the ontic-epistemic
and Thought/Extension. These two polarities, recall—the I/T omni-axis of
the ontic-epistemic and the I/T uni-axis of the within and without,
respectively—converge at the cross-roads of the mnemonic interface of the
nucleated observer itself, and this undifferentiated distinction itself is a main
cause of confusion in the literature.
Indeed once the enigmas, ambiguities and nominal confusions of the
traditional exegesis have been explained through the deeper morphological
analysis, Spinoza’s crystalline metaphysical and epistemological structure is
found to be quite robust and indeed resonant with our modern age of
science.i This explanation has been used to elucidate the solution to a few
problems in the philosophy of mind, but we have only scratched the surface
of the possibilities inherent herein.
Nondual Rationalism—with its Vision-Logic Coordinate System,
Univocity Framework, Fullerian “nucleation of observability,” and Deleuzian
“transcendental empiricism”—has been demonstrated as a simple and
powerful resolution to the mind/body problem, and indeed this was a large
part of Spinoza’s original purpose once Descartes burst onto the scene with
his problematic Substance dualism. In this interpretation of Spinoza, the
mind/body problem is solved by logically placing it (the “explanatory gap”)
in the explanatory realm of the epistemic itself where it can naturally be
seen as an incommensurability or non-identity between two symbiogenetic
and fundamentally incomplete polar opposites—the fundamental
“descriptive protocols” of subjectivity and objectivity—morphologically
emergent from the deeper formative protocols of modal nucleation.
Through the topological analogy of “the nucleation of observability” and
the concept of consciousness (the realm of the epistemic) as a finite
emergent interface phenomena (the mnemonic primitives) between the
infinities and perceptual irrelevancies of the within and the without, this
subject/object descriptive discrepancy has been shown as a consequence of
the fallibility of all finite representational systems. The fallibilism,
knowledge-relativity, and Substance neutrality of the nondual-rational
approach are therefore the keys to de-absolutizing and integrating the
skewed materialist and idealist agendas, but this can only be understood and
accepted through the realization of the epistemic and symbiogenetic nature
i
For another excellent example of Spinoza’s surprisingly modern and scientific views, see Looking
For Spinoza, by Antonio Damasio.
Page | 540
SPINOZA’S ATTRIBUTE POLARITY
Page | 541
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 542
Page | 543
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, Embryogenesis of the Concept (EOTC), p106.
ii
* See, I/T Interfaces, the Omni-Uni and the Omni-Non, p146.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
iv
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
v
* See, Polarity and Univocity, p174.
Page | 544
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
* See, Polarity and Univocity, p174.
ii
Recall that a “transitive-plane" is only a plane with respect to the representational linearity of the
omni-directional I/T axis on the main diagram of the VCS. (See Figure 6, p141.) In reality, the
transitive-plane is a scale, or a region between scales, in the unlimited possibilities of scale itself.
Page | 545
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
See, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
Page | 546
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
* See, Post-Post-ism-ism: Condition-Critical in the Ontic-Shadow of Post-Kantian Dualism, p40.
Page | 547
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
world. While the phenomenal world (literally “appearances”) deals with the
relative properties seen in the forms of “sensibility,” logic and
representation. And never the twain shall meet.
In his book Foundations: A Manual for the Beginning Student of
Epistemology, academic epistemologist and Kantian, Claude L. Fox writes,
“Distinct from the idea of a thing in itself is the idea of a thing in relation to
other things” (p18). The example Fox gives is of the relation of a father
(himself) to his son, which, he says, is a property predicated to him “not
because of what I am in myself but because of a relationship I bear, to some
other thing.” Kant’s “thing in itself” must then go far beneath the real
relations and effects caused by the real relations a father has with his sons,
such as the memories of the birth, growth, development and all the good and
bad times.
Kant’s “thing in itself,” then, jumps directly from representational
relation, entirely bypasses the real world of sub-representational relation
and reaches into the absolute scope of infinite immanence. Das ding en sich,
then is an independent arising, opposing the relative world of form in
dependence on—interfacing, coupling and changing in accordance with—
other form.i This is in direct opposition to the truths of the nondual
traditions and Spinoza’s real difference, in which the entirety of the world of
form arises in strict inter-dependence in its relations with other form. Kant’s
ding en sich was (or has become) a numerical identity and difference, an
absolutized category free from relation itself, but in absolute opposition to
other categories. And so Kant—or the post-Kantians in his nameii—
bypassed all of ontic sub-representational relation—jumping directly from
the relative world of representation to the absolute of non-relation—and by
default relegating the ontic to the untouchable absolute category of the
“noumenon” while freeing up “phenomenon” for further games with suture
and scalpel.
And so the real world of sub-representational relation—Brahma—was
sunk into the ineffable absolute scope, a lost continent of Philosophy, while
the transcendent world of real illusion—Maya—was elevated and venerated
as a worthy patient. This veneration itself is indeed deserved (though the
operations performed by the doctors of Philosophy may not be). Maya is not
i
When asked in person, Fox stated that Kant’s noumenon is not free from relation, but the thing in
itself is related to all things. This would then be equivalent to the original Aristotelian notion of the
ontos, the One. I then asked him whether Kant made this explicit and the answer was, “No.” It is
well known that Kant himself was unclear about his noumenon/phenomenon distinction, and it is
the post-Kantian reaction which was likely most responsible for the radical ontotomy discussed
herein.
ii
There are indeed Kantians who don’t believe this was Kant’s original intent and that it is the result
of subsequent misinterpretations. Mr. Fox is one of them. This author has not studied Kant’s
original surgical procedure in enough depth to make such a call, but the aftermath is ubiquitous
enough in my contact with run-of-the-mill Kantians and quite readily apparent.
Page | 548
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
only real, but also a real illusion and a real representation. She is more real
than Brahma…but only because she is Brahma, in her roots and in her very
soul. See Figure 75, below.
The task of post-Kantian, post-ontotomy Interface Philosophy, then, has
been to bring the ontic back out of the absolute scope, and to provide an
epistemic interface for exploring this lost continent. And in this process we
will continue to demonstrate that the ontic is not the ineffable, untouchable
Absolute, but fully within the relative and effable world of form embraced in
the very interface of Maya and Brahma. And indeed, this interface of Maya
coming to know Brahma grows ever larger as more and more unknown
territory is uncovered daily and become known. But more to the point, in
our relative freedom to explore the lost ontic continent of Brahma in
epistemic union with Maya, we will then be equipped to explore the lofty
heights to which only Maya can lift us.
Page | 549
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 550
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
In Aristotle’s works, ontology was the study of “Being,” the “ontos,” the One
whereas “epistemology” was the study of “knowing,” “episteme.” This sets
up a polarity from the outset between the One and the Many. The ontic is
the One whereas the epistemic starts in the division of the One into the
various ways and means by which it can be broken down and analyzed. We
have already seen this indefinite analytical epistemic process of
differentiate-and-integrate in the EOTC, and in the fact that representation
itself first breaks into structure and form with the nucleation of
observability, and the opposition of self and other—subject vs. object—that
this brings.
When pointing to the ontic from its identical opposite in the epistemic,
then, we must be aware that we are recognizing the unity in diversity, and
ultimately, at the absolute scope, the ONE-ALL tautology and
Unity=Multiplicity of Univocity. It is in the ontic where the symbiogenesis of
subject and object occurs, recall, and it is in the ontic where we recognize the
nature of the epistemic as real in itself—i.e. as transcended-and-included
from the real, or from the ontic.
Recall from our section Univocity and the Vertical Ontic/Epistemic Polarity
(p178) the intrinsic polarity between the ontic/epistemic and between
ontology/epistemology (see Figure 76, below). Ontology is inherently
epistemic (a form of knowledge), and epistemology is inherently ontic (a
form of the real). At the risk of further confusion, the first polarity of terms,
the “ontic/epistemic” can be applied to itself and to the second polarity of
terms, “ontology/epistemology,” to gain a bit of verbal clarity in our
discussion (if this tricky self-referential analysis provides more confusion
than clarity, then by all means skip it).
Page | 551
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The ontic/epistemic pair can be seen as the ontic aspect of the general
polarity of representation/sub-representation, and the
ontology/epistemology pair can be seen as the epistemic aspect. The words
point out the real vs. representational aspects of their general referents
respectively.
This is easy to spot and to remember in the fact that “ology” itself refers
to a field of study, or knowledge, the real world of the epistemic, and that the
“ic” points out a real aspect or feature of reality. So when discussing the
knowledge or epistemic fields themselves we say ont-ology or epistem-ology,
and when discussing their real-world (or ontic aspects) we say ont-ic and
epistem-ic. In this sense, ontology studies the real ontic, and epistemology
studies the real epistemic as transcended-and-included from the ontic. This
will make much more sense shortly when we explore in more detail the
holarchical nature of the epistemic, transcending-and-including the ontic.
Page | 552
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
Another interesting historical side-note on Mr. Fox: In an inconceivably fortunate set of events, as I
was given two days to vacate my apartment in Superior Colorado, I decided I needed a move into
the mountains, and the very first and only place I looked at was a basement studio apartment above
Boulder, Colorado. After I moved in I finally met the owner and tenant of the house and we had a
little discussion over tea about the rental situation. It just so happened that my new landlord was a
retired philosophy professor specializing in epistemology. Indeed, Mr. Fox’s views were unorthodox
in exactly the same way as my own, stressing the ontic-epistemic polarity and the ontic foundations
of the epistemic in the precise way I just happened to need for the very section of this work that I
happened to be writing at that very moment in time—this one. The odds of the first and only
apartment I looked at just happening to be co-occupied by with a retired philosophy professor are
themselves very low, but the odds shrink dramatically with the fact that he happened to be
unorthodox in exactly the same way that I just happened to need at that very precise moment in the
progress of this work. As Gerald Lebau says, “God said look for me in coincidences.”
Page | 553
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
ontic (recall the mnemonic interface as the crossroads between these two
polarities).i
Fox continues, “These distinctions are indispensable for avoiding
confusion, especially, for example, when we consider the object of
knowledge to be the knowing subject itself; that is to say, when the knower
is considered as the known.” In other words, when we consider the real and
relative formal or ontic nature of the epistemic subject (i.e. as an “object”) in
order to ascertain the limitations and powers with respect to the knowledge
which that subject-as-object can attain, then we must be clear that we are
addressing the ontic (relative not absolute) nature of the epistemic in the
real and relative formal properties and limitations of the knower itself.
And again, it must also remain clear that ontic does not equate to
objective, though ontic objects (e.g. rocks), as opposed to epistemic objects
(e.g. thinking beings) are easiest to identify and understand. As discussed in
Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and the Nucleation of Observability, objectivity is
merely the outside view of the epistemic; i.e. knowledge gained about the
external world, and there is a natural tendency to collapse the objective into
the ontic which must be avoided—e.g. when subjects become seen as
objects.
Often in epistemology it is the ontic nature of the epistemic subject that is
the object in question, so there is always a danger of an unrecognized
feedback loop and circularity. And if the ontic, epistemic, subject and object
polarities and their respective VL-axes, interfaces and distinctions are not
maintained in clarity, this can easily trip up and con-fuse the user.
Fox continues, “In the most general terms then, according to the three
basic dimensions of the phenomenon of knowledge as mentioned above, the
basic questions of epistemology will always be derivatives of the three
questions: What is the nature of the knower?, What is the nature of the
means of knowing?, and What is the nature of the known?” Questions
probing “the nature” of these three “dimensions,” as should be clear, are
ontological questions, as they attempt to address (relatively) the formal
reality of the three basic dimensions of the epistemic, and the powers and
limitations thereof (see Figure 77, below).
i
There is, of course, a clear conflation at this point between the object/subject and ontic/epistemic
polarities and their respective uni- and omni-axes which will be cleared up as we proceed.
Page | 554
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Figure 77: The EOTC of the Triune Dimensions of the Epistemic /Subject at the
Crossroads of the Ontic/Object:
Notice here that the crossroads between subject/object and ontic/epistemic is clearly
defined in the space where the “means of knowing” between subject and object is
inquired of as to its ontic nature.
Page | 555
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Fox continues [my emphasis], “As should be clear from the preceding, those
ontological concepts which are instrumental in describing the nature of the
known are in that regard epistemological concepts. In this overlap can be
seen the reason for saying that ontology and epistemology may be said to be
distinct but not separate.” Recall at this point our basic definition of
conceptual nonduality and polarity as “distinct but not separate.” Fox is
here pointing simply and clearly—if unconsciously—to the fundamental
polarity and holarchy between the ontic and its real meta-set, the epistemic
(the territory and the map), as they unfold into the triune nature of the
knower, the known and the interface and means of knowing.
In this overlapping sense, because the epistemic is not only real, but also
(meta) an emergent representation, it is a higher or transcendent level of
reality, or as Ken Wilber would say, it is “deeper” or has more depth of form,
complexity or reality to it. Yet the epistemic is a sub-set in the sense that it
has a smaller domain, because only a small percentage of ontic modes or
holons will deepen into the epistemic or into representational capabilities.
This is what we see, in integral theory, in the maxim that with increasing
depth comes a decreasing span. The higher and deeper (the more layers of
depth) the form of transcendence the more rare it becomes.ii* In this same
sense, Maya or the illusion is a deeper reality than mere Brahma, the plain
old reality—it goes beyond, or meta, but only in the transcension-and-
inclusion of the ontic in those most rare holons capable of representation.
i
… until that process is turned on itself, for example, in transformative practices like meditation and
shadow-work in psychotherapy, and then only very slowly. This is how transitivity is mapped to
transcendence.
ii
* We’ll discuss this in much more “depth” in the section, Depth vs. Span: Further Untangling the
Trans-Trans-Bias, p573.
Page | 556
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
So, at this point we have the triunity of the knower, the interface of knowing,
and the known; roughly the epistemic subject, the subject/object interface
and the epistemic object—and this triune structure, recall from Figure 77
above (p556), is emergent across the polarity and triunity of the
ontic/epistemic and its interface in the probing of the “nature of” the
elements of this fundamental epistemic triunity. But there is another
“indispensable” triune (holarchical and emergent) set of relations which Fox
wants the beginning student of epistemology to be aware of, and which, Fox
says, “Aristotle reminds us to employ whenever we are doing philosophy…”
(p5). Aristotle calls this triune structure the “three levels of being” and they
are, as Fox states: “reality, meaning and language, or respectively reality
itself, our mental representation of reality and our linguistic symbolization
of those representations.”
This triune Aristotelian distinction, in a sense, collapses or ignores the
interface and polarity between the ontic and epistemic, but it expands or
differentiates the epistemic into a distinction between semantics (meaning)
and language (roughly syntax in addition to meaning). As we have stressed
previously,i* and will explain more fully below, semantics, meaning or
“intentionality” is emergent in the symbiogenesis of subject and object. In
the very process of emergent, representational embodiment itself,
meaning unfolds in layers of accretion, transcension-and-inclusion.
Syntax or language, then, is a later invention of creatures whose
foundational semantics is already emergently embodied in its mnemonic
primitives and higher-level representational and mimetic structures—such
as hunting strategies or avoidance routines. This later invention of language
then serves to rigorously tease out, complexify and communicate higher and
higher forms of meaning, transcended-and-included from embodiment itself
and expanded through the subsequent embodiment of invented language.
As the attentive reader can see, in our EOTC of the epistemic categories, we
now have a fourth and even a fifth level differentiated-and-integrated into
our original triune holarchy; the epistemic subject, the subject/object
interface and the epistemic object. So now we have the fivefold delineation
of epistemology; (1) the ontic, (2) the ontic/epistemic interface gradient, (3)
meaning, (4) the meaning/language interface gradient, and (5) language.
See Figure 78, below.
i
* See, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
Page | 557
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The Absolute scope breaks into the relative scope and then into the
ontic/epistemic (Brahma/Maya) holarchy/polarity. From there we expand
the category of the ontic/epistemic interface gradient and break it into the
intra-objective/intra-subjective sensory-mnemonic primitives, and
complexes. Via Aristotle, we have also expanded the category of the
epistemic first into meaning and then into higher level language and into the
inter-objective/inter-subjective meme-complexes, such as schools of
thought, where language and meaning unfold each other into ever higher
and higher levels of complexity.
Page | 558
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i¥
This was disclosed in a recent public ISC call—May 12, 2007—in which I participated with Wilber.
Page | 559
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 560
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 561
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, for example, The Tao of Rationalism: Pulverizing the Categories (p56), Spinoza’s Univocity
(p158) and Spinoza: A Nondual Sketch (p664)
ii
* See, The Univocity Framework (UF), p153, for more detailed information.
iii
* See, Spinoza’s Attribute Polarity and “The Nucleation of Observability”, p486.
iv
To this integrative purpose, then, we flesh out the alternative lineage of Western Nondual
iv
Rationalism, from Heraclitus to Parmenides and Zeno —going underground with the exoteric
rationality of Socrates, Plato and Aristotle (for example in the principle of contradiction and platonic
absolutized categories)—emerging with the stoics perhaps and the Neo-Platonists—and meeting up
with Deleuze at Spinoza.
Page | 562
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
… and now the eight primordial perspectives and their respective methodologies.
Page | 563
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 564
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 565
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 566
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
itself exists to make this transitive opposition explicit for the sake of
integration, and thus transcension-and-inclusion up the
Immanent/Transcendent axis. So, in AQAL metatheory there exists the very
same polarity between the I/T axis and the transitive-planes—as there
indeed does in any model dealing with the truths of evolution—though this
distinction remains, to a large degree, implicit.
The AQAL map, therefore,
consists of a transitive-plane,
projected from the transcendent
level of the epistemic, “down” into
“lower and lower” immanent
transitive-planes, as well as “up”
into “higher and higher”
transcendent ones (see Figure 80,
p562, above). The AQAL map
projects from the epistemic simply
because, in relational reality (in the
ontic) there is no such distinction
between these relations—in reality
they are already integrated and in
need of none of our maps. They
tetra-arise together, not apart. It is Figure 82: The I/T AQAL Grid: The
only because finite unity begins in Quadrants as a Transitive-Plane on the
representational or operational I/T axis:
opposition and relation to other Because the AQAL quadrants deal with
finite or bounded unities that it oppositional relations, rather than with
unfolds initially onto the relations of transcension and immanence
(included in other aspects of the model,
oppositional transitive-axis, and this such as the laws of holons) the quadrants
is the very reason that opposition, at (at whatever level they are projected to)
the higher (e.g. “second-tier”) levels can be placed on a transitive-plane, with
of consciousness must make maps respect to the Immanent/Transcendent
to integrate at the epistemic level axis.
that which was never disintegrated
at the ontic.
Indeed, this is an explicit feature of the AQAL model in the dictum that
the quadrants “tetra-arise” and that ultimately there is never one without
the other three. The AQAL quadrants explicitly form merely a map of
important distinctions to be made at the epistemic level, of intrinsically
integrated or inseparable features of relational reality—the ontic level (See
Figure 82, above).
Page | 567
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, Quadrant Interfaces and PAR-Tunnels: Cogitism, Formalism and Other Theories of Knowledge,
p631.
Page | 568
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
detail they deserve, I include Figure 83 (see below) merely for interest, and
to show perhaps a glimpse of the power of Wilber’s model.
“The idea is simple enough,” says Wilber:
Start with any phenomenon (or holon) in any of the quadrants—for
example, the experience of an ‘I’ in the UL [upper left] quadrant. That ‘I’
can be looked at from the inside or the outside. I can experience my own
‘I’ from the inside, in this moment… But I can also approach this ‘I’ from the
outside, in a stance of an ‘objective’ or ‘scientific’ observer. I can do so in
my own awareness (when I try to be ‘objective’ about myself or try to ‘see
myself as others see me’), and I can also attempt to do this with other ‘I’s’
as well, attempting to be scientific in my study of how other people
experience their ‘I.’ The most famous of these scientific approaches to I-
consciousness have included systems theory and structuralism (p35-6).
Wilber goes on to outline this new within/without perspectival polarity with
respect to each of his quadrants.
This additional polarity and distinction to the quadrant map as a whole
may indeed be indicative of the importance of the implicit
immanent/transcendent uni-axis with its finite unity (e.g. the holon) and its
within/without polarity (recall our Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity
(p251)). Though it still seems to be the case that Wilber’s distinction is of a
more linear, oppositional, and therefore transitive nature. Regardless, we
can notice a very clear difference here, between the two axes in Wilber’s
model, given that the quantitative or plural axis has not been reiterated, self-
reflexively, in this fashion.
Because the “primordial perspectives” themselves are generated in a
recursive “fissioning” across the holonic polarity of finite unity, there
appears, then, to be—shall we say—an “integral” aspect of finite unity and
boundedness to perspective itself in IMP. In other words, in integral terms,
there is, necessarily, a fundamentally holonic nature to perspective.
Perspectives, we can say, at minimum come in twos. This obviously is a
corollary to our Fullerian Quantitative Principle of Finite Unity. So it is
interesting to note that the very core of Wilber’s move into “post-
metaphysics” is the replacement of “perceptions” with “perspectives,” which
conveniently and simplistically gets rid of the problem of correspondence in
epistemology, and its metaphysics of the “myth of the given.” Wilber makes
the very accurate claim that we cannot have perceptions without first having
a perspective. Indeed, however, he often makes the seemingly absolutist
conclusion that “All is perspective.”
This claim, in Integral Post-metaphysics, that perspectives replace
perceptions, and especially the claim that “All is perspective” must be
tempered with the recognition of the ontically-timid nature of the academic
climate into which Wilber is projecting his new model. Given this, it is
natural for Wilber to often conveniently drop the corollary that “All is
holonic,” because it is the holons that ontically embody the perspectives.
Page | 569
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i¥
(Wilber, Integral Spirituality) p. 43
Page | 570
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
As truly odd and senseless as an extensionless building block may sound, given that it breaks down
into the labyrinth of the continuum.
Page | 571
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The popular symbol of the Atom is stark: a black dot encircled by the
hairline orbits of several other dots. The Atom whirls alone, the epitome
of singleness. It is the metaphor for individuality: atomic. It is the
Page | 572
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
irreducible seat of strength. The Atom stands for power and knowledge
and certainty. It is as dependable as a circle, as regular as round.
…
The internal circles of the Atom mirror the cosmos, at once a law-abiding
nucleus of energy, and at the same time the concentric heavenly spheres
spinning in the galaxy. In the center is the animus, the It, the life force,
holding all to their appropriate whirling stations. The symbolic Atoms’
sure orbits and definite interstices represent the understanding of the
universe made known. The Atom conveys the naked power of simplicity.
The original ancient Greek Atom was foundationalist and absolutized
bounded form. The Atom (a-tomos) was the “uncuttable,” indivisible rival
and antithesis of the infinitely divisible “corpuscle” of eighteenth-century
“Natural Philosophy.” The Atom, and Newton won out over the corpuscular
folks like Leibniz and Boyle. Atomic simplicity was far easier to deal with for
the exoteric LCD of humanity. But the victory of the Atom was short-lived.
Indeed, the Atom of the 20th century is no longer the indivisible entity of
Leucippus, Democritus, Gassendi and Newton. Without anyone noticing it,
the Atom was transformed into its rival, the corpuscle—the an-atom.
The corpuscle, or the anatom, is infinitely divisible. It has anatomy. It
ontologically embodies the modal half of the fundamental principle of
Nondual Rationalism.
The Holon, on the other hand, is the conceptual and abstract form of the
infinite divisibility of the corpuscular anatom—and it is directly opposed to
the Atomic concept of the absolutized and foundational Planck scale in
modern physics. This infinite divisibility is encoded into its very definition
as a part-whole, or equally as a whole-part—i.e. a whole that is always part
of a larger holon, and a whole whose parts are always made from smaller
holons. The very definition of a holon, then, necessitates that there can be
no end to the holarchy, because (in the immanent direction) this would
entail that a holon is either made of foundational non-holons (the ancient
Greek A-tomoi) or (in the transcendent direction) that the last holon is not a
part of a larger holon, and thus not a holon either, but some kind of inside-
out Atom, e.g. a transcendent God. These two forms absolutize our two
vision-logic equations: ∞/1 and 1/∞, respectively, corresponding to
immanent and transcendent bounded form.
Kelly continues:
Another Zen thought: The Atom is the past. The symbol of science for the
next century is the dynamical Net.
The Net icon has no center — it is a bunch of dots connected to other dots
— a cobweb of arrows pouring into each other, squirming together like a
nest of snakes, the restless image fading at indeterminate edges. The Net
is the archetype — always the same picture — displayed to represent all
circuits, all intelligence, all interdependence, all things economic and
Page | 573
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
social and ecological, all communications, all democracy, all groups, all
large systems. The icon is slippery, ensnaring the unwary in its paradox of
no beginning, no end, no center. Or, all beginning, all end, pure center. It is
related to the Knot. Buried in its apparent disorder is a winding truth.
Unraveling it requires heroism.
This use of the dynamical Network as “the symbol of science for the next
century” is similar to Deleuze and Guattari’s championing of the concept of
the rhizome. In The Deleuze Dictionary we find:
…the rhizome is a concept that ‘maps’ a process of networked, relational
and transversal thought, and a way of being without ‘tracing’ the
construction of that map as a fixed entity. Ordered lineages of bodies and
ideas that trace their originary and individual bases are considered as
forms of ‘arborescent thought’, and this metaphor of a tree-like structure
that orders epistemologies and forms historical frames and homogenous
schemata, is invoked by Deleuze as everything that rhizomatic thought is
not.
Where Deleuze and Guattari conceive of the tree (“arborescent thought”) as
opposite to the rhizome, we can see the simple difference between these two
forms in the idea of lineage. The tree traces everything back to the
individual unit, the trunk from which the roots and the branches diverge.
This, they say, is the focal point of power. By forcing everything into
patterns of “arborescent thought” power becomes centralized and controlled
through the trunk. The roots of the tree can be seen as the past or the
immanent line of emergent descent (if looking regressively from the
transcendent trunk) or ascent into the trunk, while the branches can be seen
as the future or the transcendent line of emergent ascent away from the
trunk.
The trunk of the tree, then, is roughly analogous to the holon—analyzed
into its own spatial and/or temporal networks. What we can see in the
infinite holarchy, however, is the combination of the rhizome and the tree.
In the holarchy we can find both. Trees are found by tracing both immanent
and transcendent lineages (lines of flight) to a single holon, and rhizomes are
found by tracing them through large groups or collections of holons.
A holon, however, is always composed of an infinite number of deeper
holons—indeed an infinite holarchy or a rhizomatic network of holons—
whereas the trunk of a tree is not composed of an infinite number of trunks
of trees. The trunk and strictly “arborescent thought”, therefore, is much
more akin to the Greek Atom and/or “Atomic thought”—which is a variant of
our friend “categorical absolutism”—whereas both the holon and the
holarchy contain and remain free from the restraints of both and embrace
the fundamental principle of Nondual Rationalism.
The holon/corpuscle/anatom and the holarchy/network/rhizome, then,
correspond in the pure-relational terms of immanence and transcendence to
the I/T uni-axis and the omni-axis, respectively. The holon embodies
Page | 574
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 575
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* Recall the Principle 3: Chord 2: The Principle of Immanence in Transcendence (Yin in Yang), p95.
ii
This is an expanding corollary to our Principle of Immanence in Transcendence.
iii
* Please refer to, The Vision-Logic Coordinate System (VCS), p123, for any confusion that will
inevitably crop up for those who haven’t read the sections basic to these concepts.
Page | 577
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 578
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 579
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
This is not the same dependency, however, as the human on its social structure or environment,
simply because while the social sphere or the environment can exist without a particular human, the
human can’t exist without its brain. Furthermore, a brain does not possess the properties of holons,
such as agency and communion. Without the body, the brain has no function of homeostasis and it
quickly dies.
Page | 580
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 581
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 582
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
This process is explained in explicit and exquisite causal detail in Sorce Theory.
Page | 583
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 584
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
The preceding section perhaps explains our popular fascination with the
idea of the “black hole.” Indeed, the simplest holon is the point where the
maximal energies enfold and self-reinforce in such a way as to “encapsulate”
or hold them within its body—a holding pattern limiting its outward
complexity to an apparent inter-unit self-similarity and homogeneity. But
the simplest bodies are not black holes. They don’t suck in everything
around them based on a runaway concept of abstracted gravity.i They
merely have the power to harness their own intrinsic energies and those
around them, with a minimum of loss to outward complexity. There is
indeed a degree of outward complexity displayed. It’s just the minimum
level.
Perhaps also, it is this innate idea of the focal point of complexity
emerging into maximal simplicity that forms the locus of our attractor for
meditative transformational practices. This move is accomplished, however,
only through an analogous sort of inter-harmonizing of internal energies to
attain a self-reinforcing and self-stabilizing form of “psychic inertia” that
only the focal point of maximal and maximized energies can provide.
In meditation, for example, the generally trans-biased (transitive and
transcendent) focus is instead centered within. But representation can’t
simply enter the implicit singularity of the immanent/transcendent uni-axis
of its bounded form. Rather—through a relaxation simultaneously into
transcendence—it enters the immanent multiplicity of the boundary itself
(e.g. from mnemonic complexes to primitives in the sensory-mnemonic
interface) until the limits of this process are reached and the
representational and experiential detail is so fine (and simultaneously vast)
as to appear continuous and empty, due to the perspectival limits of
representation itself.
Indeed, relative to everyday experience this experience is Emptiness, but
it is not the Emptiness we conceive of logically and rationally at the absolute
scope as infinite or limitless depth in itself. Experience itself is bounded and
i
Indeed, we can recognize that Einstein himself felt that his concept of gravity was only one half of
an abstract polarity, which, by itself leads the universe to implosion. Thus he invented his opposing
concept of the cosmological constant. This concept was disparaged with the arising of the
popularity of the Big Bang Theory, but oddly enough, the constant was revived under a the guise of
“inflation” in order to save the Big Bang model itself from collapse.
Page | 585
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
enabled by its form; indeed Emptiness is Form and Form Emptiness. The I
cannot escape the IT, in AQAL parlance. So, even though the holarchy itself
is infinitely deep, it is the brain that is doing the representation, and
representation is possessed of a relative and finite depth, as it merges into
the infinite depth of sub-representation. What is meant, then, by
experiential Emptiness, must simply be “the experience of non-experience,”
or the non-experience within experience. This is sometimes called the
“witness” or the fundamental perspective or ground of being necessary for
experience itself. It is the approach and realization thereof to the identical
opposite and sub-representational context of experience itself. In this sense,
if the approach is successful, Emptiness can’t “feel like” anything at all.
This immanent process of approaching representational continuity,
immanence or Emptiness, provides the practitioner with the chance to
decouple his higher-level internal-external (subject-object) mappings and
differences and move closer and closer to a ground of maximal simplicity
and unity. And—as analogous to the role of immanence in the
transcendence of operation and numberi where it was always through
immanence that the breaking of closure was accomplished and the
transcendence into the next set of numbers was reached—it is through this
immanence that transcendence is accomplished, and perhaps vice versa.
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
Page | 586
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
through the forms of time. Indeed, the one without the other is a duality, not
a nonduality or polarity. In this way, it is only through logic, rationality or
trans-rational and trans-logical intuition that we can recognize what these
relative experiences point to in their own identical opposite of the
unreachable Absolute Infinite and Emptiness, or even vastly beyond the sub-
and meta-representational reaches of experience. And this is indeed why
the cognitive line is so important to development. We may experience
emptiness all the time, but without cognitive models for what is being
experienced and how to recognize its signs, we have no tools for maximizing
or controlling its unfolding.
The basic relation in experience is that between subject and object.
Through meditation one may indeed break down to the cogito of the
dissolved self, but to retain experience through it one must relate the
experience to memory and indeed pull it back through the mnemonic
primitives themselves. In these states one breaks down the mnemonic
complexes to their primitives and approaches the nondual state of the
symbiogenesis of subject and object. This is a state of pre-differentiation
between self and other and a state prior to the learning and functioning of
the senses, so it approaches ineffability, in itself. But all states are relative
whether nondual or not, because form is emptiness and emptiness form.
This will make much more sense when we revisit the concept of scope,
below and see that ultimately, or merely ontically, they are inseparable.i*
With this loose speculation, however, it is important to note that the self-
similarity between the ground-level of simplest bodies and the interstitial
level of the human being is clearly and observationally inexact—a loose
analogy and real-world echo distorted through the chambers and
stratifications of complexity itself between its recursive isomorphisms.
Indeed, as we’ll see below, man sits virtually halfway between his upper and
lower simplest levels in a state meso-complexity. His form, then, cannot be
identical to that of the simplest body (e.g. the atom), but it can be a self-
similar echo of many of its patterns and relations. We see this effect in the
self-similar forms of both mathematical and real-world fractals, where
between specific levels of self-similarity we see only “distorted” similarities
to the main pattern. And it is this self-similarity in nature that reinforces the
notion that man, as a self-similar echo of nature, can understand and
experience that nature itself. In other words, if nature is wholly self-similar,
as it indeed appears to be, then the epistemic is a self-similar echo of the
ontic, and thus, in this sense, “corresponds” to it.
i
* See, Defining the Scope of Scope, p592.
Page | 587
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See Principle 1: Chord 1: The Fundamental Principle of Nondual Rationalism (PNDR) (p84), which
states that “infinite division equals indivisibility.”
Page | 588
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
See Oldershaw < http://www.amherst.edu/~rloldershaw/menu.html>.
ii¥
(Oldershaw)
Page | 589
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
of magnitude (in meters), from the Planck level, to the atom, to the M-dwarf
stars, to galaxies or voids and very likely beyond.
We’ll get into the physics and causation of this empirical relation in
Volume II (and I explore it in depth in my article Sorce Theory: Unlocking the
Basement), but suffice it to say that the effective continuity of the emergent
levels imparts a critical set of emergent qualities or quantifiable properties
(e.g. superfluidity, with an effectively zero friction and viscosity) which
allows the next ground-level of units or “simplest bodies” to enfold the
infinite complexity beneath it into self-stabilizing, self-harmonizing and self-
centering inertial integrity, emerging into what appear on the surface as a
level of homogenized and simplest bodies (see this note for more details).i
i
Sorce Theory, gives us a simple way to causally understand one of the properties that can lead to
such a real, emergent, self-similar relation. Beneath the unit-level or “ground-level” of the atomic
nucleus (the proton) we have an effective subatomic continuity (a quasi-continuity) that doesn’t see
its deeper unit-level until another whopping twenty orders of magnitude in meters—the Planck level
(the same distance on the Immanent/Transcendent axis between an atom and a star). Accordingly,
the actual properties of matter shift dramatically between the atomic (unit) and subatomic (sub-
unit) levels, and this is precisely why the physicists of the early twentieth century were so utterly
befuddled when their “classical” meso-scale and particle-based expectations were shattered by the
entirely new properties of the sub-atomic quasi-continuous level—themselves emergent from a
much deeper level.
The intermediate holons between the Planck and atomic scales are highly unstable, as physics
has discovered, whereas the proton (atomic nucleus) is extremely stable (the neutron is also
unstable and decays into the proton). It is this aspect of extreme or maximal stability—among other
things such as maximal unit simplicity (minimal complexity)—which qualifies a level as a ground-
level of “simplest bodies.” We find such levels at the scale of the Planck unit (the Planck scale), the
proton, the M-dwarf stars and likely at the level of galaxies or voids. The larger and larger we get,
however, the more sparse and indirect the data, so it is difficult to determine the precise unit-levels
at those scales. This is mainly because of temporal dilation at larger scales in that we see fewer and
fewer complete events and thus we have far fewer points of data to correlate into an empirical
relation. … This shift between levels and their qualities can be seen most clearly in the emergent or
transcendent direction, as opposed to the regressive or immanent. As we zoom out in scale from
the size of the atomic nucleus, for example, the discreteness of the atomic level recedes from view
and rather quickly begins to appear continuous. Even by the time we get to the human level (the
meter), exactly half-way between the upper and lower levels (atomic and stellar), we have what
appears as an effective continuity. Water, for example, appears quite continuously fluid. Despite
this apparent continuity at this mid-level, however, water has a specific and tangible discrete aspect
in its quality of viscosity. As you get to smaller and smaller scales, for example, there is a rise in
surface tension and viscosity such that water at those levels tends to quantize into droplets of a
similar size. This is called “atomization,” naturally.
These are thermo-inertial and chemical properties directly emergent from the inertial properties
of the unit-level of the atom, but properties which effectively disappear at the subatomic level. And
again in the transcendent direction, by the time we get to another twenty orders of magnitude
larger, according to this model, at the level of the M-dwarf stars this apparent continuity has
drastically changed, transcending its atomic discreteness through this shear quantity of its intrinsic
qualities and its emergent effects. At this point a new set of continuous and superfluid properties
has emerged. This shift to superfluidity at the stellar level (as also seen at the sub-atomic or sub-
inertial level) can be seen in the shift in astrophysics to modeling cosmic scale objects, such as black-
holes, for example, on superfluid dynamics (see the work of Volovik, for example).
Indeed, as seen in studies of superfluidity, this zero friction/viscosity aspect allows superfluids to
achieve remarkable things, such as forming metastable vortices that interact as discrete units,
Page | 590
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
similar to atoms. In Sorce Theory, it is shown how the subatomic Planck-level superfluid can indeed
form the atoms as metastable vortices with their harmonically quantized interior energy shells.
Page | 591
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 592
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
“Infinite determinism equals indeterminism.”
Page | 593
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The absolute and relative scopes, recall, are purely epistemic functions. They
are the two nodes of conceptual context in the fundamental distinction and
polarity in the Interface model of Epistemology, as already used extensively
throughout this work. This is not to say that there is no absolute and
relative world, however, but to say that it is only in the oppositional realm of
the epistemic, the realm of scope itself with its embryogenesis of the
concept, that such an oppositional distinction necessarily exists.
Recall again how the absolute scope was generated in the attempt by the
relative scope to find its ultimate context-defining other. The absolute scope
then is reserved in opposition to relation, but with the understanding that
this opposition is merely a way of looking at things—a scope. And in a true
polarity, the absolute and relative scopes are distinct but not ultimately
separate. The absolute scope is The Absolute conceived initially apart from
the relative—Emptiness conceived apart from Form—for the sake of making
the initial distinction apparent and breaking the bonds of absolutism in
order to effect their consistent integration. This is in the same way that
Spinoza’s attributes are conceived as apart and parallel, with the
understanding that there is ultimately only Substance and its modes as
Page | 594
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
conceived through one or the other attribute. And this is also in the same
sense that the AQAL quadrants are seen as apart (e.g. scopes) but understood
as fundamentally integral (tetra-arising) and ultimately never separated in
the first place (ontic). The initial differentiation ensures the proper
integration. This, recall, is a fundamental function of the EOTC.
Recall again how the absolute scope reserves the space for The Absolute
itself free from conceptualization. This is because the quantitative aspect of
The Absolute is The Infinite and the concept itself is always a bound. When
The Absolute is conceived in terms of a concept, the unlimited is conceived
as a limit. In the EOTC, however, such a differentiation must eventually be
resolved to an integration—an organization must always resolve to an
organism. And so in the ontic—the sub-representational—the absolute is
understood as infinite difference and relation in itself—the ALL-ONE. So
ultimately The Absolute is not other than the relative, but merely the infinite
or Emptiness aspect of the relative world of Form (Spinoza’s Absolute
Infinity)—or vice versa, the relative is merely the finite or bounded and
differentiated aspect (the Form) of The Infinite Absolute, or Emptiness.
Taking these linear logical limitations in parallel, together, we can perhaps
approach the true polarity beyond the limitations of our language. The
absolute is the relative is the absolute. Unity is Multiplicity.
Page | 595
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i¥
(Fox, Foundations: A Manual for the Beginning Student of Epistemology)
ii
And moreover, confusion itself is a fully relative phenomenon. If confusion thinks it is dealing with
the absolute scope it is fundamentally mistaken. The absolute scope cannot, by oppositional
definition, partake in the relation of any contrariwise fusion.
Page | 596
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
But further, and very importantly, to say that “reality is relative” is no longer
to say that it is dependent only on the observer, but precisely the opposite.
The real is simply relational, and infinitely so. It is not fundamentally
representational or purely subjective: Truth is not relative in this purely
subjective sense. The subjective, recall, is the epistemic level of the within—
the representational level of the “I” quadrant, in AQAL theory. An atom, for
example, does not make a “purely aesthetic” judgment call (as if aesthetics
were purely subjective either) as to which atom it will conjugate a chemical
bond with. It does so based on its own intrinsic relations in its active
interfacing with the intrinsic relations of the other atoms it is “courting.” If
there is a harmonic fit it snaps into place and the bond tightens into a
greater, synergistic harmonic interface, the two now greater than the sum of
their parts.
Often times the relation of the real is between the real observer and the
real observed, in which case the triune interface between them is indeed
dependent on its polar terms, but in all cases the relative is fully real. In
Interface Epistemology, knowledge is no longer cut off from the reality
which, through its various relations and interfaces, brings it into being;
representation is no longer cut off from the field of sub-representation; and
transcendence and transitivity are no longer cut off (through the trans-bias)
from immanence. The interface which differentiates and unites them in
“real difference” is key to Interface Epistemology. This infinite difference of
immanence in the triune interface itself, as Deleuze says, affirms “the truth
of relativity”—the truth of the relation of “real difference” itself—as opposed
to “the relativity of truth.”
As Deleuze says in Expressionism in Philosophy: Spinoza, “In short, what is
expressed everywhere intervenes as a third term that transforms dualities.
Beyond real causality, beyond ideal representation, what is expressed is
discovered as a third term that makes distinctions infinitely more real and
identity infinitely better thought. What is expressed is sense: deeper than
the relation of causality, deeper than the relation of representation.” This
“sense,” as we will shortly see, is the enfolding of meaning in the immanence
and embodiment in the evolution, embryogenesis and development of every
individual—each of which is a confluence of singularities of infinite
difference, interfacing within the unbounded confluence of external
singularities; Bounded Infinities boundlessly interfacing Bounded Infinities.
Page | 597
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Interface Epistemology, on the other hand, recognizes and affirms the reality
of relation. This “truth of relativity” extends, therefore, to the forms of
knowledge—both objective and subjective, both mediated and immediate.
And critically, Interface Epistemology recognizes and affirms the relative
subject/object polarity and bounded sensory-mnemonic interface of the
individual itself as the very root of knowledge at the crossroads of the
orthogonal polarity of the ontic/epistemic (sub-
representation/representation). It is this cogito-root into which both
models collapse into a common epistemic-bound Cogitism.
As the Bodhidharma says, “The mind and the world are opposites, and
vision arises where they meet.” If we contract the representational world
down to the absolute knowledge of the raw sensory-mnemonic interface—
but before even the projective, pattern-recognition properties of the
mnemonic primitives and “qualia” arise—the world and the mind disappear
into the solipsistic and nihilipsistic cogito of the dissolved self.
Page | 598
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
This, recall, is the return journey in The Cycle of Unity, where the
recognition of the interface represented by the vinculum of the vision-logic
equation for the ALL — ∞/∞ — the ‘one’ boundary of finite unity on the I/T
uni-axis, along with the recognition of the unity of the ratio of immanent and
transcendent infinity (∞/∞ = ONE), returns us to the boundless ONE of
Infinite Unity, the ineffable absolute scope. This Cycle of Unity is expressed
in the vision-logic equation: ALL = ∞/∞ = ONE — as the swerving deviation
from the univocal tautology of the ONE-ALL, into the relative realm of the
bounded individual—the one and its vinculum interface—simultaneously
from both omni-directions, the infinite within of the implicit singularity and
the explicit infinity of the transcendent ONE.i* The individual cogito of the
evolved- and involved-; the unfolded- and enfolded-self is the
vinculum/interface between this infinite immanence and transcendence—
between the dark and mysterious subjectivity of yin, and the bright and
obvious objective-power of yang.
i
* See, The (Binary) Cycle of Unity, p254.
ii¥
Quoted from Kelly’s Out of Control.
iii
The phrase was invented by Herbert Spencer for his spin-off of evolution called “Social
Darwinism”.
Page | 599
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 600
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
As P. D. Ouspensky wrote:
But we do not realize, do not see the presence of intelligence in the
phenomena and laws of nature. This happens because we always study
not the whole but a part, and we do not see the whole we wish to study.
But studying the little finger of a man we cannot see the intelligence of the
man. The same refers to nature. We always study the little finger of
nature. If we realize this and understand that EVERY LIFE IS THE
MANIFESTATION OF A PART OF SOME WHOLE, Only then a possibility
opens of knowing that whole. In order to know the intelligence of a given
whole, one should understand the character of that whole, and its
functions.
This core idea of evolution as a form of intelligence can be found in a long
line of eminent thinkers, from Erasmus Darwin to Samuel Butler to P. D.
Ouspensky to Alan Watts to Kevin Kelly to George Dyson—not to mention
the eastern thinkers and the countless engineers working in the trenches
with the alien distributed-intelligence of evolution first-hand to help evolve
solutions to problems unthinkable by single-track human intelligence.
Unfortunately we’ll only have time to skim a small portion of these
fascinating details.
Page | 601
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
conscious or how wise you are—indeed determines the power (or quotient)
of your intelligence. But it can be seen that intelligence is a form of
consciousness or wisdom, or that wisdom or consciousness is a form of
intelligence, depending only on your preference and the way your intrinsic
system of categories is already set up.
If we de-couple the ‘problem’ from its anthropocentric roots, however,
the flexibility of its definition can be extended to the more general field of
biology, and even to evolution. “Living organisms” says computer-scientist
John Holland, “are consummate problem solvers. They exhibit a versatility
that puts the best computer programs to shame.”i¥
Naturally, problem and solution form a polarity, and a problem-solver is
a solution in its own right. Indeed, sometimes problems, in another sphere,
can only be seen in light of their solutions. But where there is a solution,
there was a problem … and where there is a problem-solver there is a form
and power of intelligence—some kind of an “intelligent designer,” or
“composer,” if you will.
The question, of course, is whether this prodigious composer of profound
and preposterous proteinaceous fugues is humanoid, reptilian, vegetative,
mineral or an entirely different form altogether: perhaps an amalgam or
even an abstract principle… What kind of intelligence must it be? … and just
how intelligent, given the vast, “geological” resources of time, energy and
matter at its disposal?
The solutions to the problems hidden in the depths of evolution are the
myriad “life-forms” scattered throughout the history of life on this planet—
perhaps %99 of which are already extinct (which tells us that the death of
organisms hasn’t yet been on the list of problems for evolution to solve). We
organisms—intelligent solutions in our own right, if sometimes a bit
quirky—are the problem-children of evolution.
Evolution, the mother of invention, has the general problem of getting its
children to replicate its code. But it has another problem. Every time it
thinks it has solved a problem—firing off an organism capable of replicating
its newly invented code—the environment into which the problem-children
are injected has changed and they often can’t seem to adjust. And so the
code they would replicate dies out. Evolution, then, must continually find
new solutions to its new problems which are, by now, vastly multiplying out
of hand.
i¥
Quoted in Kelly, Out of Control
Page | 602
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
this is what gives evolution its inhuman power of creation. It multiplies its
code in billions of billions of variations at once, and those that survive to
reproduce are already successful while the rest, unneeded, are forgotten.
Evolution is a “differential reproductive success”—a shotgun creationism;
the madness of a method exploding into a billion-billion sub-processes, each
one a new trajectory tunneling into the dark space of biological possibility.
Kelly writes:
Parallelism is one of the ways around the inherent stupidity and
blindness of random mutations. It is the great irony of life that a mindless
act repeated in sequence can only lead to greater depths of absurdity,
while a mindless act performed in parallel by a swarm of individuals can,
under the proper conditions, lead to all that we find interesting.
This is indeed why engineering is increasingly turning to “evolutionary
algorithms” as an interface between the limits of single-minded human
engineers and the alien, distributed, vastly-parallel intelligence of deep
evolution. The novel solutions emerging from this computational interface
of simulated evolution tend to be far beyond the capabilities of humans to
engineer, let alone even to understand. Kelly writes:
What humans can’t engineer, evolution can. [Tom] Ray puts it nicely as he
shows off a monitor with traces of the 22s propagating in his soup: “It
seems utterly preposterous to think that you could randomly alter a
computer program and get something better than what you carefully
crafted by hand, but here’s living proof.” It suddenly dawns on the
observer that there is no end to the creativity that these mindless hackers
can come up with.
Evolution is indeed a form of distributed intelligence and creativity quite
alien to the single-minded approach of human consciousness.i At best, we
can sit atop and harness the vast parallelism of our brain-cells in an intuited
spark which seems to come from nowhere, but it is difficult for us to grasp
the raw power—and the products—of this alien intelligence which brought
us into being, and whose unconscious goals and desires still course through
our own veins.
i
For a brilliant and fun exploration of the intelligence of evolution see George Dyson’s book Darwin
Among the Machines.
Page | 603
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
turned the mutation function off, Ray let the soup run without deliberate
error. He was flabbergasted to discover that even without programmed
mutation, evolution pushed forward.
The fact that evolution—after inventing its own sex games—pushes forward
even in the absence of random mutations, empirically informs evolutionary
biologists that sex is a powerful addition to the arsenal of deep evolution.
To scientists, the most exhilarating news to come out of Ray’s artificial
evolution machine is that his small worlds display what seems to be
punctuated equilibrium. For relatively long periods of time, the ratio of
populations remain in a steady tango of give and take with only the
occasional extinction or birth of a new species. Then, in a relative blink,
this equilibrium is punctuated by a rapid burst of roiling change with
many newcomers and eclipsing of the old. For a short period change is
rampant. Then things sort out and stasis and equilibrium reigns again.
Page | 604
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
In the evolution of life on this planet there is a tell-tale sign of the power of
an evolutionary function: The faster the pace of change the greater the
power (or intelligence) of the function behind it. For the first few billion
years of evolution—based perhaps mainly on the function of cellular
division and random mutation—the history of change moved at a snail’s
pace. It hardly budged from one point in time to the next…and it left a slimy
trail.
Then, at only around 500 million years ago—perhaps already 4 billion
years into this languishing, monotonous, barely-intelligent cycle—occurred
a biological “Big-Bang” (pardon the pun). This is the “Cambrian explosion”
where, in the geological blip of perhaps merely 10 million years, all the body
plans of the subsequent biological eras were evolved. So, after four billion
years, evolution suddenly picked up its pace, exploding from single-cells into
the sprawling possibilities of multi-celled organisms and body-plans.
Page | 605
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
What changed? Kelly, tells us that the Cambrian explosion occurred just
after the invention of sexual reproduction, perhaps about the time it takes
for real-world eukaryotic sex to work its hill-climbing magic on dull
mutation. It took about 500 million years to reach the knee of the
exponential curve, but when it did — POW! — this magic finally exploded
from single-celled organisms into myriad modes of multicellular monsters,
injecting their own exponentially increasing intelligence into the exploration
of this vastly unfolding space of multi-cellular possibilities.i A fantastic
menagerie of forms of intelligence was now at the disposal of natural
selection and deep evolution.
In sex, recall (if your lucky), rather than merely going off in a corner and
replicating by yourself—actually dividing yourself in half—there is an
interfacing or union of two organisms to create a third. But recall from your
fortunate and romantic courtship all the energy of intelligence (both
conscious and unconscious) that went into the endless quest, the
intermittent battles and the final decision of with whom to mate—you
weren’t prepared to mate with just anybody, right? The same is true, but at a
smaller scale with the early organisms who first began to experiment with
sex.
Sexual reproduction opens a space for sexual selection, and sexual
selection harnesses the intrinsic intelligence of the organism in solving the
problem of with whom to interface. Sex itself is a medium for intelligent
design, much more powerful than mere random mutation, and we can see its
effects directly in the often bizarre sexual dimorphisms of its unwitting
participants…which includes us. Every time we have sex, we are
participating in the higher-level intelligence of evolution, because we have
injected our own intelligence into this program and passion for selective
bonding and breeding. Sexual selection, then, is a feedback “mechanism”
magnifying the intelligence of natural selection and the other mechanisms of
pre-sexual evolution.
If natural selection is the “additive function” in the mathematics of life,
then sexual selection is its “recursive function.”
i
The Cambrian explosion occurred around 500 million years after the invention of sex. Because the
intelligence power of sexual selection is indeed dependent on the intelligence power of its
participants, then one would expect that its power would increase exponentially as it starts feeding
back into itself its new powers. It then perhaps took around 500 million years to reach the bend of
the knee of this curve.
Page | 606
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
Indeed, as we’d expect from a true polarity, though Lem’s meaning is clearly intended as “The
meaning of the organism is the code,” it’s hard to really or ultimately pin down which is the
transmitter and which the transmission; the organism or the code. Does evolution transmit its
meaning into its organisms as code, or does the organism transmit its deepest meaning through
reproduction of the code? Of course this breaks down into “mere” semantics…
Page | 607
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Stepping back to look at the whole of life on Earth, we see it evolving within
the thin interface and atmosphere of the planet. We know that life
penetrates or emerges from this interface at depths and heights which to us
are difficult to imagine, but in relation to the earth, life is concentrated
within a thin film of atmosphere, hydrosphere and lithosphere, whose depth
may be rightly compared to the thickness of the skin of an apple.i Indeed, we
can again see the interface as key when we reflect that this living cosmic
membrane occurs precisely at the boundary between the “order” of the
i
… or with the “deep hot biosphere” perhaps the depth of an orange peel. (see Thomas Gold)
Page | 608
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
frigid reaches of interstellar space and the “chaos” of the molten core of the
earth, both of which are hostile to life, yet at their enfolding and unfolding
interface, life flourishes. Life itself is a cultivated/cultivating third, on this
“third rock from the sun.” i
Stepping back yet again, we see life emerging at another interface, the
“sweet spot” or “habitable zone” of the temperature gradient of the
planetary orbit of the earth, just close enough to the sun for life to evolve
through the benefit of photosynthesis, and just far enough away for those
life-forms to avoid burning up.
And naturally, we can see this purely positive reinforcement of the living
story of evolution—told only by its victors—as a form of the familiar
Deleuzian intensive forces, arising from the immanent, sub-representational
level of the causative language of evolution. The intelligence of evolution
i
It is, of course, just a coincidence that the earth is the “third rock” or node from the sun. Indeed, it
is very likely only the third visible node from the sun. Let us not break down into numerology, but
remain in the power and embrace of logic and causation.
Page | 609
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
itself functions on the intensive forces of this purely positive feedback. The
intensive forces of the “additive” and recursive functions of natural and
sexual selection—informing and re-injecting evolution only with its
successes—is the very rudiments of evolutionary sensation, and it is
naturally coupled with the rudiments of memory in the genetic code. As this
ever renewing tale is directly “memorized” (encoded) and expressed in the
causative language of DNA, it echoes, recapitulates and unfolds into the very
embryogenesis of its creations.
Strangely, but as we may by now expect, the new direction in cellular biology
directly supports an Interface Philosophy or Epistemology of emergent
intelligence, creativity and knowledge. Cellular biology is indeed moving
away from the idea that the cellular nucleus is the driving intelligence or
“brain” of the cell, and toward the notion that the intelligence is actually
found in the outer cellular membrane itself; the interface where primitive
sensation and its encoded reactions (rudimentary genetic-mnemonic
primitives) takes place.
This new idea is reinforced by numerous experiments that show that a
cell can live a virtually normal, active and reactive existence long after its
nucleus has been removed. In this new direction in biological science, the
nucleus of the cell now mainly serves the function of reproduction—doing
the “dirty work” of the slower and distributed intelligence of evolution. The
nucleus, in short, is not the brain of the cell, but its gonad—its genetic or
long-term memory—and these experiments have basically created a bunch
of cellular eunuchs.i
So there a shift in biology to the idea of the interface as the driving
intelligence of primitive life-forms; the code or genetic memory remains
safely tucked away in the core—in the gonads—while the cutting edge of
intelligence and active memory unfolds, enfolds, acts and reacts largely at
the interface between the within and without of the cell. As Bruce Lipton
states, in his article Fractal Evolution, ii ¥ “The membrane boundary
enveloping each biological cell comprises the structural basis of a biological
processor system…. As a processor, the cell’s membrane receptors scan the
environment for signals. … the specificity of reception that is characteristic
for each receptor … enables it to distinguish its complementary signal out of
all the jumbled ambient noise.”
i
… or else—if we have unintentionally reversed this polarity—perhaps our own gonads are the
proper brains of us “higher” forms of life. Gonads are “deep brains” or the brains (or perhaps
merely the nerve cells) transcended-and-included in the vast, slow and alien distributed intelligence
of evolution.
ii¥
(Lipton PhD.)
Page | 610
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 611
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
…i.e. the entire evolutionary chain of development leading to the specific individual is echoed in its
very own embryogenesis…
Page | 612
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
It takes a mere chemical gradient in the embryonic medium to differentiate the zygote into a front
and back, given the expressivity of the genetic code in response to the environment, though there is
much more complexity involved in this interaction.
Page | 613
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
As we move into more and more complex life-forms with ever more
complex sensory-effector appendages, it is a straight-forward matter to
differentiate the sense of touch into its higher forms, such as the refinements
and distinctions between smell and taste. These newly evolved and
specialized appendages allow the further evolution of the active (sensor-
effector) participation of the organism in sensory-mnemonic interaction
with its environment, such as the function of the highly-sensate hand in the
evolution of man, the tool-maker. In the higher organisms, these
rudimentary functions become more and more localized into highly evolved
appendages; differentiating islands of skin and muscle enfolding and
unfolding the sensory-mnemonic, sensor-effector active intelligence of
evolution.i
In this way, the sense of taste is differentiated from the global ambient
chemo-sensation of smell. Smell, and the appendage of the nose, seems to be
the islanded and evolved variant of this basic sensation of ambient chemical
signatures, while the tongue becomes a more active and controlled
appendage for direct chemo-sensation and tactile manipulation, not of the
ambient fluid or air, but actively directed toward differentiating, interfacing
and sometimes manipulating the chemical and mechanical properties of
various surfaces.
Hearing, as well, is a direct differentiation of the mechano-sensation
found at the most rudimentary cellular levels. At the advanced levels of the
pattern recognition in higher organisms, the detection of types of
repetitions, or frequencies become encoded and memorized in the genes and
expressed in the intricacies of the organs of sound. These organs transcend-
and-include cells that—like the single-celled organism—react to direct
mechanical stimulation. These cells, however, are now highly specialized,
reacting in a highly specific electro-chemical fashion, and the mechanical
stimulus is now highly amplified by the surrounding structure of the
i
On a side note, this active intelligence of evolution, which requires no forethought, but acts in such
a way as to solve problems difficult, if not impossible, in any other fashion, is the rudimentary
embodiment of the principle of non-action found in ancient Taoism. The indwelling intelligence of
evolution, of the body, is the Tao, “the way,” in its yin, feminine or immanent aspect, transcended-
and-included in the higher, more transcendent forms of life, intelligence, knowledge and
consciousness. An explicit goal of Taoism, as we have seen, is to get beyond the intrinsic
transcendent- or yang-bias (“all things have their back to the yin…”) and tap into the immanence
and wisdom of yin.
We can transpose this goal directly into the operationalization of yin as it is expressed in the
immanent biological intelligence of evolution itself in everyday action, and to let thoughts arise in
the context of this deeper and wider intelligent function; the “wisdom” of evolution, spanning
geological ages and the globe itself. The Tao is in opposition, in a representational sense, to the
transcend-and-negate attitude that excludes bodily intelligence and intuitive action; and in parallel,
it is in opposition to the use of concept in such a way that excludes or negates the percepts and
intuitions which brought it, often unconsciously and symbiogenetically (rather than foundationally
or reductionistically), into being.
Page | 614
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
acoustic organs. But the basic sense of touch clearly still exists at the very
root of the specialized sensation of hearing in higher organisms.
Sight too can be seen as a modification of touch, with specific pigments in
specialized cells absorbing and reacting to the effects of being touched or
impacted by certain frequencies of light waves (or “photons”) emitted or
reflected by other surfaces. These cells are now highly specialized and
arranged in organized arrays, with long specialized appendages called axons,
collectively transmitting their massively parallel messages into optic nerves
winding directly into the specialized optic regions of the brain.
But, once again, touch is at the very root of the sensation. Indeed, the
sense of sight can be seen as the extended interface of touch, whose critical
distance and simultaneous detail (to near quantum levels) is afforded and
mediated by the great speed and fidelity of light waves, emitted, reflected or
refracted through the surfaces and membranes of other creatures or
structures in the environment. Without that touch of the “photon” with the
pigment—and the intelligent sensory-mnemonic interface it affords—there
would be no sight.
To further plumb the depths of the nature of the “knower” or the self, we can
tease apart the evolution of self-hood in terms of a critical polarity at the
very heart of embodiment and active intelligence itself: that between sensor
and effector (e.g. sensory and motor neurons). The self, as a homeostatic
function of active evolutionary intelligence, can naturally be seen to evolve
from the cellular interface as well, and we’ll see that as the self interface
emerges, complexifies and “thickens up,” this sensor-effector polarity
spreads, differentiates, integrates and complexifies as well, indeed, as two
aspects in the very same process.
The evolutionary self expands as an “aperture,” in a sense, actively taking
in, processing and reacting to larger and larger amounts of information. But
even as this bounded interface gets larger in scale—from the radius of a
cellular membrane to the extended radius of the limits of the human senses,
skin and brain—much more to the point it expands in thickness and
complexity. It’s not so much like an expanding balloon, but an expanding
spongy and convoluted surface getting thicker and thicker as it unfolds into
more and more complexity needed to process and integrate ever more
information—much more information than can be accommodated by the
merely mechanical reflexes seen with the thin cellular membrane.
It is critical, however, to understand this sensor-effector polarity not
simply in terms of the I/T uni-axis and its spheroidal/bounded interface,
because neither sensor nor effector exists solely on one or the other side of
the interface-boundary of the organism. It’s a much more complex and
abstract polarity. Rather than a simple spatial polarity, sensor/effector is a
Page | 615
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
…and so we might have called this sensor-effector polarity the “sepol,” had this polarity played a
more ubiquitous role in this section. Indeed, that’s the shorthand used in writing this work, but the
word-processor automatically replaces “sepol" with “sensor-effector polarity” so it not encumber
the user with infrequently used new vocabulary.
ii
…insofar as we can stretch our definition of sensation to this rudimentary level…
Page | 616
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 617
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 618
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
According to Ken Wilber, in the original Khunian sense, the term “paradigm” referred to any
scientific instrument that allowed the observation of new realms of empirical fact. In this sense,
perception itself—in each of its various modes—is a paradigm.
Page | 619
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
We have already seen the symbiogenesis of the rational and the empirical in
the pure-relational and categorical context of the holarchical unfolding and
embryogenesis of mathematics. i * This symbiogenesis unfolds in the
coupling between the empirically-derived geometry of the numerical
identities as boundaries, with their unfolding into the logic and rationality of
the noun-verb, identity-operations of arithmetic. We also saw a glimpse of
how this coupling between empirically-derived geometry and abstractly
rational arithmetic can be maintained even up to the fourth dimension, in a
direct correlation, without any compromise of the foundational axioms of
dimension. This is because with a move to an a priori operationalization of
the Immanent/Transcendent axis, for example in Fuller’s Synergetic
Geometry, we move away from rectilinearity and into radial and convergent
equiangularity with its dimensional limits not at three, but at four,
corresponding to the four perpendiculars (normals) from the faces of the
tetrahedron. And therefore the fourth dimension of the axis of the
imaginary numbers can be mapped in a purely modelable and consistent
manner.ii*
But with these various symbiogeneses or structural couplings in
evolutionary and organismic embodiment—subject and object, intelligence
(rationality) and experience (mnemonics), percept and concept, sensor and
effector, etc and etc—we can see the simple resolution to the nature vs.
nurture debate rattling at the very core of the distinction and duality
between the so-called “Rationalists” and “Empiricists.” Is the mind by nature
possessed of “innate knowledge” and rationality or does all knowledge come
from experience, or from nurture?
The answer, we can see, is yes, and yes. We have seen the innate
knowledge, intelligence and rationality of the organism in the knowledge
contained in its very own DNA, and we have seen how this knowledge itself
gets encoded into the causative language of proteins by the very experience
of the organism itself, interacting with its environment and injecting its
i
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
ii
* See, The Imaginary as Vestigial Transitive Axis at the I/T Interface, p348.
Page | 620
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
intelligence back into the stream of deep evolution itself through sexual and
natural selection. This coupling of experience and intelligence in evolution
itself is ultimately expressed in the highly rational and intelligent instincts of
its organisms even before birth and before the coupling of experience and
intelligence in the construction of the sensory-mnemonic interface in the
symbiogenesis of subject and object. The experiences and interactions of
evolutionary trials (genotypes) that prove fruitful get passed on—the story
told by the victors—and this feeds back into the code—as a rudimentary
“sensation”—reinforcing the positive effects and successes of the various
forms of directed and undirected mutation while ignoring the negative
effects.
There is no evolution of problem-solving intelligence and solution-
encoded rationality without experience to drive it into higher levels of
solutions encoded ultimately into the generalized principles at the corner-
stone of human levels of rationality. From the very beginning, rationality
and experience go hand in hand; they are symbiogenetic.
Leaving the cumulatively successful evolutionary sequence (phylogeny)
and taking residence in the development of a single human individual
(ontogeny), the symbiogenetic rudiments of both empiricism and
rationalism can be seen in the functions of sensation as it gets encoded into
memory (experience, empiricism) and intelligence (rationality) in the
cognitive and intelligent pattern-recognition and differentiating functions of
the mnemonic primitives, and primitive sensation. Indeed, the
symbiogenesis of Rationalism and Empiricism is a direct corollary of the
symbiogenesis of subject and object, in that the intelligent functions of
sensation necessitate the experience of the objective world in order to
encode the differentiations of sensation into the increasing rationality of its
cognitive functions.
These newer functions, in turn, allow the developing organism to
experience higher and higher forms of sensation, enfolded into higher and
higher forms of intelligence and rationality, and enfolded into higher and
more complex memories, until these memories begin to reach the level of
the percept-concept and into abstract concepts and can be encoded and
retrieved in language by the highly developed adult. Prior to this point, the
memories are of such a primitive nature that they only appear as the very
background of embodied meaning itself, such as qualia or the what-it-is-like
quality of sensation, encoded and transmitted abstractly via our mimetic and
representational language.
As we can see, there is no ultimate defining line before which experience and
sensation did not exist. On closer inspection, that line—the ontic-epistemic
Page | 621
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
…so much for the “Copernican revolution”…
ii¥
(Stewart, The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy with Illustrations)
Page | 622
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
And Kant seems at first to agree, in the Introduction to The Critique of Pure
Reason:
It is beyond a doubt that all our knowledge begins with experience, for by
what should our faculties be roused to act if not by objects that affect our
senses, and thus partly of themselves produce impressions, partly again
bring the understanding itself into movement in order to compare these,
to join or disjoin them, and in this manner work up such crude material of
the intimations of sense into a cognition or recognition of objects, which is
named experience. So far as time is concerned then, no cognition of ours
precedes experience, and with experience all our knowledge begins. …
But, Kant draws the line of this dualistic chicken-and-egg problem at the
categorical and “transcendental” ontic eggs buried in the human
understanding. He continues…
Though all our knowledge begins with experience, it does not follow that
therefore it all derives from experience. For it is just possible that
experience is itself a compound. It is just possible, that is, that there is
experience besides what is due to the impression of sense, something in
addition that comes from our faculties themselves, when merely acting
because of impression, and in that case it would take long practice, it may
be, to enable us to distinguish the latter and separate it from the former.
The gradation of “sense,” for Kant, clearly ends at the level of human
complexity in the holarchy which makes up the human form itself. But
indeed “there is experience besides what is due to the impression of
[anthropocentric] sense, something in addition that comes from our faculties
themselves,” for in these a priori eggs of sensibility, we have seen, incubates
a deep evolutionary gradient of interaction between more primitive forms of
sensation and sensations of form, i.e. between experience and rationality.
He continues…
Can there really be such component part of knowledge as is independent
of experience, and indeed of any impression of sense whatever? Such
component part of knowledge, did it exist, was alone to be truly a priori,
and it would evidently stand in contradistinction to what other
component part of knowledge is called empirical, the latter, namely
having its source only a posteriori, or in experience. … The expression a
priori, at the same time is not precise enough to designate the entire sense
of the preceding question, for of many a mere empirical fact we say that
we know it a priori simply because we do not derive it directly from
experience, but from a general rule, and this even notwithstanding that
the rule itself may be so derived. For example, we say of a man that shall
have undermined his house, he might have known a priori that it would
fall in. He had no occasion to wait for the experience of the actual event.
Nevertheless he could not have known this absolutely a priori, for that
bodies are heavy and consequently fall when their supports are
withdrawn, this at least he must have known by experience.
Page | 623
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Kant supposed that the categories of the understanding were absolute. They
were free from relation, in the sense that, whatever the circumstances, they
were absolutely universal and fundamental to any human perception and
conception whatsoever. We can indeed see why, and in what sense they are
“absolute” and universal. They are interfacing, from the ground up with the
reality that they are and with that which surrounds them. It is the reality of
relation itself which forms and informs the forms of sensibility, and which
grounds them in an inevitable universality…in this neck of the universe, that
is.
Of the forms of sensibility Kant identifies only two: space and time. As
Matthew Stewart explains [my emphasis], “…they are features of our mode
of knowing, rather than, as common sense would have it, features of the
world.”i¥ This separation between the forms of sensibility (representation),
such as space and time, from the forms of sub-representation, is part of the
radical ontotomy performed by Dr. Kant in order to sanction science and
religion from the extreme versions of each other. This is not a transcend-
and-include differentiation, from reality into its real illusions. If it were, the
noumenal and the phenomenal would have space and time in common, at
least in some form. As Kant says, “Time has no objective reality. It is not an
accident, not a substance and not a relation. It is a purely subjective
condition, necessary because of the nature of the human mind which
coordinates all our sensibilities by a certain law, and is a pure intuition. We
coordinate substances and accidents alike according to simultaneity and
succession only through the concept of time.”ii¥ In other words, though Kant
is not stating it explicitly, the faculty of time coordinates the real “temporal”
relations it receives at its active sensory interfaces, such as real simultaneity
and real succession. Kant simply chooses not to call this real temporal
relation, in both the senses and the objects and relations which it senses, by
the distinct name of time. We can see this radical transcend-and-negate
division as well in Kant’s Transcendental Logic with the sequestering of
causation itself into the phenomenal world alone.
With our ontic/epistemic polarity there is a clear sense into which this
kind of differentiation resonates into a reconstructive bit of surgery. Time
and Space (and causation) are aspects of relation abstracted out of the One—
the ontos—into the forms of representation or sensibility, through the
interface between the ontic and epistemic in the evolutionary symbiogenesis
between the forms of sensibility and the sensation of form.iii* In other
words, it’s not as if there were nothing “resembling” time and space in real
i¥
(Stewart, The Truth About Everything: An Irreverent History of Philosophy with Illustrations)
ii¥
Collected Works, Volume II
iii
* See, The Gyth of the Miven, p42.
Page | 624
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
relation, but rather that in the ontos there is no real distinction between
them. In acategorical reality time and space are One. The resemblance itself
emerges and differentiates into the epistemic in the interface-gradient with
the ontic. time and space, as separate faculties of knowledge, are abstracted
out of the One of real relation and its infinity of multiplicity and activity.
As we have discussed at length, mathematics (including geometry) is the
art and science of pure-relation.i And this is why geometry and arithmetic
are composed of “synthetic a priori judgments.”ii Relation itself—in its
various inter-relational interfaces and couplings of increasing sensation,
experience and intelligence—informs the forms of sensibility, which
themselves inform the intuitive-substance manifesting into the whole of
generalized categorical and conceptual mathematics. Geometry is simply its
most sensate and explicit form, but all of mathematics draws from this deep
evolutionary reservoir of sensation and experience with the most primitive
forms of relation.
Interestingly, Kant claims that Arithmetic is a function of the category of
time and Geometry is a function (naturally) of the category of space. With
the Einsteinian revolution, however, even this absolute categorical
distinction is rendered moot. And as we have seen, there is no operation
without identity and no identity without operation. Thus there is no spatial
noun without a temporal verb and vice versa. In Interface Philosophy and
Mathematics, they are structurally coupled or symbiogenetic polar
relations.iii*
i
In other words, the mathematics approaches the most primitive and general forms of relation at its
very foundations and forms this generalized artifice into a creative science.
ii
A “synthetic a priori judgment” is a judgment that reveals new facts (synthetic) about the world
prior to having experienced them (a priori). The boundary of experience here is the boundary of
human representation. As we have seen, however, this boundary is a gradient, and pre-human
experience, in a structural coupling, actually informs the forms of sensibility that lead to the human
level of representation.
iii
* See, The Holarchical Unfolding of Number and Operation, p306.
Page | 625
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The unity stage in this development is the primitive state of raw sensation.
This is the state to which the absolute demands of the cogito breaks down,
because all higher forms, which include a self-other distinction and
recognition, necessarily reach into the higher and higher complexities where
percept graduates—through simple projective pattern-recognition into
abstract concept. It is this projection itself—of the various depths of
pattern-recognition and sensor-effector couplings in the mnemonic
simplexes and complexes—that the cogito breaks down to the absolute
knowledge of no projection and no cognate self-other distinction at all.
This first or unity stage of representation then is an undifferentiated raw
awareness. This is the stage of the simple innate consciousness of an infant,
undifferentiated in his/her understanding from his environment. The world
revolves around this infant, and he can’t even make the distinction between
his own self and his surroundings.
Page | 626
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
perception between subject and object is really taking place. This is a simple
and tacit acknowledgement of the subject/object interface itself, prior to
triuning and making any further conceptual and conscious refinements to
the polarity, and prior to its breakdowns and con-fusions.
This tacit belief underlying naïve realism—naïve as it may indeed be—is
empirically justified, in the relative world of form, by the billions of years of
evolution which brought it about, making it worthy of its own cliché; “seeing
is believing.” The evolutionarily-informed effectiveness of this largely
subconscious and autonomous model, operating throughout the less-than-
humanly-conscious animal kingdom, is the relative truth underlying
correspondence theories of knowledge. There is a correspondence, in a
sense, but rather than dualistically absolutizing the terms of the
correspondence itself, the interface model recognizes the relativity in the
triune interface of perception itself in the symbiogenesis of subject and
object.
Naïve realism has been generally derided in philosophy, but the one main
criticism seems to hold no water. This criticism, “the argument from
conflicting appearances,” states that because the same object may appear
differently to different people, or even to the same person at different times,
therefore the properties in question cannot be contained or expressed in the
object itself, but only in the perceiver of those properties. For example, an
apple may appear red in the daytime, but at dusk a shade of grey. Thus, the
apple cannot really (or intrinsically) possess the property of redness, but
that property must hold only in the perceptual apparatus of the observer.
This problem of conflicting appearances is easily dismissed,i however, as
no problem at all, because to say that something cannot intrinsically possess
a property if it appears different under different conditions is logically
equivalent to the claim that something cannot really possess a property
unless it always appears to possess that property. If this were true, we
would have to conclude that a stick placed halfway in water was no longer
straight, but actually was bent, as it appears to be.
In such a case, the real polarity and distinction between reality and
illusion (between the territory and the map and between the ontic and the
epistemic) breaks down. It is this critical and indispensable polarity of the
real illusion and the illusory reality, that the interface model affirms. In this
model, the illusion itself is a function of the perspectival interface between
subject and object. Color itself is a function of this symbiogenetic interface,
as it has taken place billions of years of evolution to unfold. The triune
neural-model of color in the primate retina itself is a function of the coupling
i
…for example, see Myles Burnyeat’s article Conflicting Appearances
Page | 627
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The truth of naïve realism is in its implicit coupling of subject and object,
directly intuiting the symbiogenesis of subject and object itself. The falsity
of naïve realism is merely in its naiveté . It is simply incomplete.
This triune interface implicit in the polarity of naïve realism was explored a
bit further by Thomas Reid, in his refinement of this model, now called
“direct realism.” This idea acknowledges the inadequacy of naïve realism
and directly recognizes the interface or “veil of perception” as being
somehow, and in some sense, transparent to the objects in question. In this
sense, direct realism acknowledges the fact of representation or the “benign
user-illusion, as Daniel Dennett calls it, but claims that through a “set of data
transfers” the illusion is part of the mediation of direct sensation itself. This
sense of transparency, can perhaps be likened to the transparency one
senses in the use of the screen of a video camera. In this analogy, however,
the sensory apparatus is conveniently brought into the exterior and we can
see both the illusion and the reality as well as their actual or causal
correspondence.
Reacting to this simple polar naiveté, however, and further refining and
focusing on the reality of the veil of perception, to the point of its blinding
opacity, we come to the next stage: “indirect realism.” At this phase we come
to recognize and emphasize the role of imagination, representation and
illusion in the construction of sensation. At this point, we are so focused on
the interface of perception itself, that we cannot see it as the medium of
relation through which perception necessarily takes place. There is no
possible perception without mediation. Indeed, this is what perception
inherently is; the mediation and interface between subject and object.
Indirect realism, however, looks for unmediated and absolutely direct
sensation. The idea of indirect realism is that we can directly and
immediately sense only the interface of perception itself, occurring
i
* See, Emergence, Mnemonic Primitives, and the Symbiogenesis of Subject and Object, p528.
Page | 628
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
somewhere in the brain, and therefore not the object at all…at least as far as
we know absolutely. The interface then becomes not just a veil, but a final
curtain… but we can see this problem very simply as a function of
absolutizing the relative world of reality and its mappings. It’s a simple con-
fusion of the relative and absolute scopes.
This con-fusion presents another obvious problem. If we can sense only
the sense-data themselves, and this is occurring somewhere in the brain,
then in what way do we sense this sense-data? Is there yet another observer
inside the brain blinded by another final curtain of sensation ad infinitum?
Clearly, pushing the zone of sensation into the brain does not solve the
problem. It merely changes its location, breaking it into the infinite chain of
cause-and-effect relation that it is, in its con-fused search for absolute
relation and unmediated mediation between subject and object.
In both of these models, direct and indirect realism, we now have the
problematic triune interface of the self, the representation and the reality
(corollaries of our fundamental epistemic triunity of the knower, the means
of knowing and the known) and where and how in this continuum of
infinitely divisible multiplicity and relation to draw the dividing line. Direct
realism chooses to draw the line between the subject and object themselves,
and at the interface of the senses, but it draws this line loosely, maintaining
the connection of the interface of perception itself. Indirect realism, on the
other hand, correctly transcends the naiveté of direct realism in identifying
that there is a deeper level of sensation and representation occurring in the
brain, and in making this distinction clear it locates a more solid and
dividing line somewhere in the “Cartesian theater” of gray matter. The
interface model, on the other hand, sees both models as illuminating and
emphasizing different zones in a single, continuous, yet differentiated
interface.
The above models are considered “realist” models because they assume the
real existence of a world outside of our senses. There are, odd as it might
seem, “anti-realist” models of perception. In fact we have already
encountered both of them in the break-down of our cogito. These are Bishop
Berkeley’s Subjective Idealism, and the deep Skepticism seen in Descartes’
cogito. Indeed, they both begin with an absolute criterion for truth, the
contracted cogito, which is the Skeptic’s prime directive. Only after shucking
off the real world through the initial criterion of absolute knowledge, do
both of these models fudge their criterion and bring in the faith-factor of God
through various bad arguments. If we hold both of these models self-
Page | 629
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
consistent, however, as we have seen they both break down into the cogito
of the dissolved self.
Page | 630
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
* See, The Tao of Rationalism: Pulverizing the Categories, p56.
Page | 631
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 632
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
… and indeed there is a subjective form of scientific empiricism as well, such as in psychology.
Page | 633
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i¥
Matthew Stewart, The Truth About Everything, p. 309.
Page | 634
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 635
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 636
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 637
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The “infinitists,” like the nondualists, are not bothered by an infinite regress
of truth and justification. In this regard, like the esoteric “Grand rationalists”
they see a positive aspect to infinity. Infinitists, however, argue that it is
indeed possible for an infinite chain of justified true belief to exist, at least in
potential. This would mean that it is possible, given the resources, that a
justification could be found for each belief in an infinite chain. But,
ultimately this would be to say that the finite could reach the infinite, which
on its face, and by definition, is absurd. In other words, while each single
link in the chain could, in principle, be justified, it is a logical contradiction to
suppose that one could ever get the resources—even in principle, in an
infinite universe—for the justification of the entire infinite chain. The finite,
in any form, simply cannot overtake the infinite. The act of overtaking,
increasing in magnitude, lies squarely in the finite and indefinite realm of
magnitude and boundary itself. The infinite, as we have seen, is not a
boundary or magnitude. It can’t be reached. There is no ∞ - 1. The very
premise of the infinitist argument is contradictory; a hopeless scope-
confusion. In an infinite chain of belief, there will be no final justification.
The truth of the infinitist’s position, however, is in the acceptance of the
open-ended or boundless aspect of justification in the face of absolute
Truth—the relative scope interfacing with the absolute scope. Where it
went wrong is in the assumption that the potential of a finite process could
equal the actuality of an infinite reality. This is a clear con-fusion between
the quantitative aspects of scope.
Page | 638
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 639
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Figure 91: Correspondence on the I/T-AQAL Grid and its Missing Interfaces:
With the help of the I/T axis, we can see that the correspondence relation between
idea and object is not merely horizontal (or transitive) but also vertical
(immanent/transcendent), which together gives a diagonal relation. It is this diagonal
relation in the tacit correspondences of science that gives rise to the con -fusion
between the ontic and objective. But we can also see that the correspondence view
has no interfaces between subject/idea, subject/object, idea/ideate an d ideate/object.
Page | 641
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Alain Badiou writes, “One of Deleuze’s strong points is to have thought with
Leibniz an objectless knowledge. The ruin of the category of the object is a
major success of philosophic modernity…” (p67). The object is “ruined” by a
transcension-and-inclusion, or an enfoldment into the subject/object
interface and polarity itself. In The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze
takes Leibniz’s seemingly discontinuous stipulation of an infinitely divided
universe and translates it across the implicit Principle of Absolute Reversal
and into the interpretation of infinite division as an infinite continuity of
folds within folds within folds ad infinitum. In Leibniz’s universe, according
to Deleuze, reality is infinitely folded, infinitely modified, and through the
Principle of Nondual Rationalism, we can see the identity here with
Spinoza’s universe.
The subject/object interface, what Deleuze calls the vinculum, is likewise
composed of infinite folds. And this vinculum, composed of folds of folds
within folds and folds..., offers a perfect symbol for the mnemonic interface,
and is actually seen in the folds of the neocortex. From single- to multi-
cellular organisms, the interface of awareness itself, as we saw in Interface
Biology (p612), maximizes its power of intelligence and perception by
maximizing its surface area. At the higher levels of this transition it begins
to maximize its surface area by convoluting into pleats called sulci and gyri,
in order to give maximum space for mapping and expanding the collective
and vastly parallel sensory/mnemonic interface.
The outer pleats of the interface fold inward and the inner outward,
involution becomes evolution and vice becomes versa. Thus subjectivity and
objectivity become intrinsically enmeshed in the labyrinthine folds and
internal sensor-effector lattice-works, remappings and holarchies—the
cultivating third and symbiogenesis of subject and object in the
sensory/mnemonic interface and the higher levels of representation. No
longer can the object of perception exist without this deep interface and
identity in the subject, because both exist also within the interface of
representation itself, as the inner cleaves from the outer at all levels in the
infinite holarchy. As Deleuze says, “[the fold] also passes between mind and
body, but after having already passed between the inorganic and the organic
Page | 642
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
for the bodies…” The fold, then is also the metaphor for the cultivating third
between the inorganic and the organic, or between life and death. Deleuze
makes a point of Leibniz’s idea that the “machine” is not mechanical enough
to be alive. Living organisms are composed of infinite holarchies of deep
complexity—machines made of machines made of machines—whereas
“artificial” machines are made of bulk materials, vast crystals roughly hewn
into behemoth gear-works, clanking and grinding around in the comparative
inter-galactic space between. We’ve just begun to tap the depths of this
Leibnizian complexity with the electron and molecular bio-machines.
Through infinite multiplicity the categories of both life/death and
subject/object become pulverized as well and the truth of the relativity
between them is revealed. Deleuze continues, “It is an extremely sinuous
fold, a zigzag, a primitive unlocalizable link” (p162). We saw it already zig-
zaging its way through the complexities of evolution in the symbiogenesis of
rationality and experience in the sensory feedback functions and intelligence
of deep evolution as it encoded experience and intelligence (“innate ideas”
and rationality) into the convoluted folds of its creations. The category of
the object in opposition to the subject has become pulverized and
reassembled at all levels along with the subject into the interface, the
cultivating third in the truth of relativity, free from the singular and linear
correspondence with an implicitly absolute Truth.
It is only when correspondence and analogy are used without a univocal
grounding in the Two Truths and real difference (dependent and relative
arising) that the one-to-one mapping between relative knowledge and
absolute Truth takes place, negating the truth of relativity and its infinite
reality of truths. As Deleuze says in The Fold, “This is not a variation of the
truth from subject to subject, but the condition under which the truth of a
variation appears to the subject” (p27). Truth itself unfolds into variation in
the reality and infinite multiplicity of relation. Badiou says, echoing Deleuze
and pre-echoing Wilber’s IMP, the subject becomes “the point (of view) from
which there is a truth, a function of truth. Not the source, or the constituent,
or the guarantee of truth, but the point of view from which the truth is.
Interiority is above all the occupation of such a point (of view)” (p62).
As we have seen throughout this text, Foundationalists, like many others, see
the necessary infinite depth of justificatory relation as a regressive disaster.
Despite the fact that Foundationalism is most commonly associated with the
traditional exoteric view of Rationalism, this negative, regressive view of the
infinite, we have seen, is the very antithesis of the positive infinity of the
“secret of Grand Rationalism,” as Merleau-Ponty put it. Indeed, as we have
also seen, in opposition to the positive infinity, it is the pre-rational and
medieval transcendent-bias that leads to the view of the infinite as
Page | 643
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, Foundationalism, the Infinite Regress and the Transcendent-bias p91.
Page | 644
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 645
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, Principle 5: Chord 4: The Principle of Infinite Determinism (PID), p186.
Page | 646
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
i
* See, Univocity and the Eternal NOW, p187.
ii
Stewart, Courtier, p161
Page | 647
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 648
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
particular advantage which has yet to be fully explicated and exploited. This
may be the province of parallel functions in computational simulations,
however, rather than logic. A logical circuitry as opposed to a circular logic.
Furthermore, this circularity in coherence models and in reality itself tends
to be in a transitive-plane, while supported by webs of immanent complexity
(cultivating thirds) giving rise to an emergence of properties. It may simply
be that linear forms of logical circularity are invalid, while parallel, trans-
logical and non-linear forms of circularity and circuitry have yet to be
discovered and utilized.
But aside from this generally repudiated and vacuous logical circularity,
most coherentists now hold that an individual belief is justified mainly by
the way it fits or coheres with the rest of the belief system of which it is a
part. Coherentism, then, generally takes place in transitive interrelations of
justification between its component beliefs. None of the beliefs are
foundational and each belief helps to justify the rest in the synergetic
consistency and coherence of the whole. This theory, consisting mainly of
transitive relations of beliefs, naturally has the advantage of avoiding the
problem of the infinite regress, without the need to claim special, arbitrary
foundational status for some particular types of beliefs. See Figure 93,
below.
Page | 649
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Indeed, coherentist models function largely as a transitive -plane, floating above the
abyss of immanence and transcendence. This is why they are generally conceived with
the metaphor of the raft.
Metcalf continues…
On the other hand, perhaps we may try to reach truth as an internal
relation of the concept by using a definition of internal coherence. But this
gives us only representative content, and its form is that of psychological
consciousness.
So, while Correspondence models possessed merely extrinsic or external
relations, Coherentist models possess merely internal relations. Coherence
is essentially a dualistic reaction against correspondence, so naturally it flips
across the quadrant interface from the external to the internal. Coherence
models, however, intrinsically allow the pluralism of multiple perspectives
and truths, and as such fit on the AQAL grid in the “WE” quadrant, as
systems of relations forming a collective whose internal quality is greater
than the sum of its parts.
The usefulness or truth of Coherentist models which must be retained in
an integral model is in their use of coherence, internal consistency and
rigorous interconnectivity as a marker for success. This same kind of truth
characterizes the nature of the objects of consciousness themselves.
Faced with these two opposing models and their intrinsic relative truths,
Susan Haack, in the integral spirit, mashed them together to create
“Foundherentism.” With the “analogy of the crossword puzzle,” and in light
of the Vision-Logic Coordinate System, we can see that Foundherentism
combines the immanent/transcendent justificatory chains and networks of
Foundationalism with the transitive chains and networks of Coherentism.
See Figure 94, below.
Perhaps a better analogy for Foundherentism, however, would be the
idea of a pyramid, each layer of which would be composed of coherent rafts,
and extending the criterion and function of coherence on the
Immanent/Transcendent axis, each component belief in each raft would
interlink, in both immanent and transcendent directions, and cohere with
those beliefs in its surroundings. Inherent in this metaphor, then, would
Page | 650
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 651
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
There are two other, simpler related examples which preceded Gettier’s
accounts, however. The first case, by Meinong, posits a situation in which S
has an auditory hallucination of the sound of a harp. This, supposedly,
justifies S’s belief that a harp is playing. And, lo and behold, a harp just
happens to be playing … but it is the one not heard by S. Only the
hallucinatory harp is heard by S. So S has a justified true belief that a harp is
playing. But does she have knowledge?
The second case, by Russell, imagines that a clock has stopped, say at
12:00. S looks at the clock and forms a belief that it is now 12:00. We will
suppose, for the sake of the story, that this belief is justified by the face of the
Page | 652
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
clock. And indeed, at that very moment it just happens to be 12:00. But does
S actually know that it is now 12:00?
The first case seems rather straightforwardly the case of a belief
randomly connected to an actuality. It is truly a mere coincidence that there
happens to be a harp playing at the very moment that S hears a harp, and she
has no other reason than her hallucination to believe in the harp. And so it
seems clear that S wouldn’t be justified in her belief. In the second account,
however, there would be many reasons to take the word of the clock at face
value. The sun, for example, should be just overhead, as would be expected
of 12:00 noon. And S’s internal clock may be adding to S’s justification as a
visceral and emergent reason for her belief that it is twelve o’clock.
Regardless, from cases like these we can conclude that perhaps all
accounts of justification share a common fallibilism, given that knowledge is
always taken at the absolute scope. What one is justified in believing does
not necessarily determine the absolute truth-value of what is believed, and
thus there can be no such thing as absolute knowledge. Because of this, one
can have a justified belief that is false, and fails to be knowledge. Yet one can
also have a justified belief that is true, but in a way that is disconnected from
the justification itself. What each of these cases demonstrate is that
justification is always mediated by a series of relations—between words,
referents, statements and facts—and there are many cases in which cross-
talk and confusion between these levels can occur, making it appear that one
has knowledge, or that one does not, when the reverse is true. Such is the
way of the true relations of real knowledge.
Page | 653
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
cannot know all factors in any case, we must deal with what we can know,
i.e., with what is “internal” to consciousness.
On the other side of the token, when we seek to asymptotically approach
absolute Truth—as we do in science—it is clear that there will always be
facts outside of awareness that may eventually change the status of the
belief. As a rational observer, it is indeed necessary that we recognize this
fact and seek to transform those external facts into internal ones. This, then
seems to point directly to an interface with Externalism.
Externalism, as should already be clear, is the view that there are facts
outside the immediate consciousness that affect, should affect or that will
affect the status of the belief as knowledge. Externalists deny that one can
always have this internal sort of access to the factors that can justify one’s
beliefs.
Clearly this entire debate hinges on ones personal tastes and definitions
for justification. What is of value for the Externalist position is that it is
analogous to Gödel’s Incompleteness Theorem. The “pure-relational”
acategorical imperative of Gödel’s Theorem naturally should open our
limited categories, sets and contexts of truth and justification to what is
external to them. This recognition, then, opens the way to an
acknowledgement of the Interface itself, always expanding in the conversion
of external justifications into internal truths.
Page | 654
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 655
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
This brings us to the task at hand of briefly sketching out the integration of
the epistemological models so far in light of the preceding context. Given the
holarchic emergence of the epistemic from the ontic, and the reduction of
span with increased holarchic depth, the epistemic is therefore necessarily
Page | 656
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 657
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
All of these crucial terms that we associate with epistemic models are to be
given a relative scope (i.e. limited in certainty as opposed to fundamentally
or absolutely ungrounded), but always in polar relation to the absolute
scope in the Univocity Framework. They will be defined here.
Ontic: The ontic is the relative world of form underlying
representation, and from which it emerges through an interface
into the epistemic. It is therefore also called sub-representation.
The ontic, as the real world of real relation, is the equivalent of
Brahma, in Hinduism.
Epistemic: The Epistemic is the relative world of real representation,
or the real world of representational relation, i.e. knowledge.
Maya, the real illusion. It is emergent as an interface or
transitive-plane and its units are the individual cogito-, sensory-
mnemonic or subject/object interfaces emergent in the
symbiogenesis of subject and object.
Page | 658
INTERFACE EPISTEMOLOGY: A PRELIMINARY SKETCH
Page | 659
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 660
Figure 95: Leibnoza Von Spinbitz—The Only Surviving Portrait
Page | 661
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Despite their tantalizing similarities, it has long been thought that the
philosophies of Spinoza and Leibniz are fundamentally incompatible and
even purely and irreconcilably opposed. Spinoza—a self-sufficient heretic,
branded atheist, and Nietzsche’s “predecessor”i—conceived of the absolute
as a single “Substance,” continuous and indivisible; whereas Leibniz—a
foppish courtier and tireless champion of the Christian pre-rational,
anthropomorphic religion and its Theocracy—put forth a notion of the
absolute as infinitely divided into innumerable simplest substances called
“monads.” But most importantly, Leibniz’s system possesses a profound
inner tension between an absolute exteriority, the pre-rational
transcendent-biased God, and the ultimate interiority, the “monad,” whereas
Spinoza’s system is a harmonious whole where God, Nature and ALL its
modifications are essentially ONE, but seen in different ways, as we have
seen, in Spinoza’s polarity of attributes.
Despite these seemingly opposite foundations, conceptions and
personalities, however, Spinoza and Leibniz agree on many important
points, such as an overriding unity that pervades both systems, and beyond
their differences, they stand together in direct opposition to the proto-
rationality of the Cartesian dualism, the ghost and the machine, popular in
their own time, and now ubiquitous and unseen in ours.
While great disparities appear to exist between their systems, especially
at the absolute level, it will be demonstrated herein that these differences
are largely nominal and superficial, subsisting mainly at the level of words
and their different syntactic mappings through opposite conceptual
emphases. Unfortunately, these superficial differences have been
exaggerated through the years from surface-level readings, over-
simplifications and procrustean historical categorizations. Great strides
have been made toward reconciliation, for example, with the work of Gilles
Deleuze and Matthew Stewart, in tracing out the roots of the traditional
misconceptions surrounding these two philosophers.
As Stewart writes in The Courtier and the Heretic:
… even in the days of their first exchange, there was already at least a hint
of the possibility that, far from being pure contraries, Leibniz and Spinoza
were two very different faces of the same philosophical coin, always
looking in opposite directions as they spin through the air, yet always
landing in the same place (p116).
While representing the two faces of the coin of modernity—the active and
the reactive—Spinoza and Leibniz, respectively, have never been properly
reconciled within the single underlying anti-Cartesian,ii and nascent trans-
i
As proclaimed by Nietzsche himself in his notes on Spinoza.
ii
…though indeed this anti-Cartesianism is not absolute. There are a few things from Descartes that
get included in the trans-rational system that traces its Deleuzian lineage through Leibniz and
Spinoza.
Page | 662
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
rational system that they both explored and inhabited from their different
vantage points.
In accord with the Taoist principle of the “identity of opposites,” and
through the use of our Vision-Logic Coordinate System and Univocity
Framework, a reconciliation will be presented which will avoid the complete
“collapse” of the Leibnizian tension into Spinozistic release, as so many
commentators have predicted. Instead, while some purely reactionary, and
correspondingly absurd layers of the Leibnizian system will be expelled as
the differences shrink, we will find that the metaphysical foundations of the
philosophies of Spinoza and Leibniz are fundamentally compatible, and even
represent a symbiotic, and perhaps symbiogenetic, polarity of opposite
tensions, methods and perspectives for addressing a common intuitive
unfolding essence of rationality, a similar “plane of immanence,” as Deleuze
might say. As Leibniz sheds layers of unnecessary assumptions built to
serve his theocratic/exoteric patrons and his own intrinsic reaction against
modernity, Spinoza gains new layers of detail gleaned by Leibniz through his
effort to overcome his own Spinozistic attraction and collapse. In other
words, we will find that as Leibniz loses his own pre-rational layers of
complexity, Spinoza loses his inherent ambiguity as he gains in Leibniz’s
additional transrational complexity, in perhaps a balanced and reciprocal
fashion.
For this integration, we will finally make heavy use of the full set of our VCS-
meta-tags (scope parameters and vision-logic equations or VLE) outlined in
Interface Mathematics. See VCS Meta-tags: Scope Parameters and Vision-
logic Equations (p291) for the full explanation, but for our purposes we will
summarize them quickly below. Recall that the VLE essentially trace out the
Triune Infinite as it abstracts the absolute scope through the three degrees
of infinity, with the scope-parameters from “ab1,” to “ab2,” to “ab3.” The last
degree (ab3, the Bounded Infinite), recall, completes the Cycle of Infinity,
reconciling the trans-bias with the immanence of the Bounded Infinite.
Recall also the use of “charge,” or the positive and negative signs. Because
the forces of opposition are intrinsic to the transitive-axis, the sign is used as
a prefix, to denote positive or negative forms of transitive infinity (e.g. -∞ or
+∞). The I/T axis, however, operates on the intensive forces, transcending-
and-including the transitive oppositional charge as secondary, not intrinsic
to its own polarity. Thus the charge of the I/T axis is found as a suffix, rather
than a prefix, denoting the two intensive poles of the bounded infinite:
immanent vs. transcendent (e.g. ∞- or ∞+). With this again in mind, the VLE
can be summarized and recapped below. Recall also our use of as the
universal operator, denoting any operation whatsoever. This is used, recall,
Page | 663
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
ONE
i
VLE: ab1 — The Infinite: The Root VLE
transcendent
ALL ONE
immanent
(n )=∞
ii
VLE: ab2.1 — The Uni-Axis with Interface at Finite (Bounded) Unity
i
With the transcendent/transitive bias in modern thought this collapses to oo/0 where division by
zero is correctly recognized as undefined, but the denominator is incorrectly recognized as 0 as
opposed to the immanent pole of deep infinity (I/T) denoted as oo-.
ii
The ONE-one of the uni-axis, recall, is the transition between the absolute scope of omni-non
locality and the one locality of its implicit singularity, or immanent position aspect. Therefore, we
place this VLE exactly half-way between the
Page | 664
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
1
VLE: ab3+ — Transcendent Infinite
Page | 665
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 666
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Page | 667
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Though both Spinoza and Leibniz employ the word “substance,” as we will
see much more clearly, its meaning in their respective systems is far from
coinciding with each other and with the more common (e.g. Lockean)
connotations of the term as an underlying “substrate” of material. Spinoza’s
Substance, we have seen in the Univocity Framework and the nondual
sketch above, is essentially a Nagarjunan Emptiness, rather than a plane of
immanence or self-existing substrate. As we have seen, all immanent planes
are transitive, and relational, and hence modified. Spinoza’s Substance, we
have seen, is derived in a univocal polarity between the absolute and relative
scopes. Substance reaches into the absolute scope as ultimately an
immanent emphasis—unfolding an infinity of attributes—on our
Immanent/Transcendent axis, in identical opposition with the transcendent
emphasis of God—enfolding all infinite attributes. With the interface of the
attributes, we can then see Spinoza’s polarity between Substance and God as
a function of involution and evolution. Substance unfolds the attributes in
its immanent Becoming, and God enfolds them into transcendent Being.
Spinoza’s Substance, inversely identical to his notion of God, is thus
infinitely immanent and infinitely transcendent since it is merely an
emphasis on the axis itself (“there is only substance” = ALL is ONE) and we
can adopt for it the Root VLE and scope for the I/T axis, with its neutral or
uncharged scope ab1:
Page | 668
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
ONE
Page | 669
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
In The Fold: Leibniz and the Baroque, Deleuze sees in Leibniz a fundamental
“chiaroscuro” (a term borrowed from the visual arts in which there is a
dramatic swing between positive and negative, light and dark, such as we
find in Rembrandt). Deleuze states, “in the same way the clear plunges into
the obscure and never ceases plunging into it; it is chiaroscuro by nature,
development of the obscure, it is more or less clear as revealed by the
sensible.”i¥ In The Courtier and the Heretic, on the other hand, Matthew
Stewart demonstrates Leibniz's philosophy as a “reactionary” form of
modernism, and the powerful precursor to reactionary modernism to this
day. Stewart writes:
We live in an age defined by its reaction to Spinoza and to all that he
recorded in his philosophy. And there is no more compelling expression
of this reaction than the philosophy Leibniz developed in the long years
after his return from Holland (p16).
In this first section we will bring to light those many aspects of this
reactionary chiaroscuro that result from a philosophy of pure reaction, with
Leibniz’s attempt to forge a “popular religion” by pulling the critical features
of pre-rational religion through the labyrinthine Zenonian interiors of
rationality itself. The result of this bizarre attempt is this vastly beautiful
and fantastically baroque cathedral of philosophical curiosities that
characterizes Leibniz's philosophy to this day—this infinite origami and
Indra’s net of endless monads within monads, “windowless,” “pregnant with
the future, and each with a magic mirror on its interior wall—this
transcendent God as “prime chooser” among a bottomless pyramid of
suspended worlds from which ours is the apex and “best of all possible.”
Much of this, we will find problematic—obsolete curiosities and museum
pieces in the halls of philosophy. This is due to Leibniz's indiscriminate
mixture of pre-rational (mythic) and rational elements into a pseudo-
rational whole. Much of this popular caricature of the mythic elements of
Leibniz, therefore, will be jettisoned, as we reach the core elements of
rationality which both Leibniz and Spinoza explored. But what remains in
i¥
Quoted from The Fold, in Badiou.
Page | 670
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
As we have seen, rationality itself has a certain intrinsic structure, with its
own fundamental conceptual axis, implicit nondual principles and distinct
tendencies. And it has been demonstrated herein that the Rational, when
taken to its ends, unfolds the intensive truths of the nondual, not the
oppositional truths of duality. We’ve seen this explicitly and unequivocally
with the truths and intensive forces of Rational mathematics, and also with
the rational acategorical imperative found in both Spinozai and Nagarjuna.
And we’ve also seen it with the inevitable unfolding of the fundamental
Principle of Nondual Rationalism in Zeno and Parmenides. However, as we
have also seen, for the most part Descartes merely honed the expository
style, and its nascent Principle of Sufficient Reason, appropriate to this age of
reason. He did not fully explicate the truths of the Rational, nor should he be
considered its exemplar or father, but as a transitionary and largely proto-
rational figure.
It was Spinoza, in his early study of Descartes, who rendered the
Cartesian philosophy in the “geometric style” of early mathematical forms of
rationality, namely from the 4th century B.C.E. and Euclid’s geometry. This,
then, can be seen as the culmination of the rational style of philosophy, as it
expresses the largely proto-rational Cartesian philosophy in the rationality
and syntax of mathematical formal systems. Rationality itself, then, must not
be confused with its style of exposition, which is merely the perfection of the
use of reason itself. With Spinoza's Ethics, the rational style and its use of
reason becomes married with a truly rational—and thus nondual—
philosophy. An apex which rational philosophy has yet to surpass, perhaps.
So “Rationalism,” in the Cartesian and common sense, is largely
synonymous with the intellectual rigor of a geometrical style and its
emphasis on reason. But the tool of Cartesian rationality, again, did not
reach the truths and understanding ultimately accessible through its
properly self-consistent use, to reach its full potential.
Spinoza, on the other hand, was the first to take this tool into its depths,
and really map out the philosophical territory and paradigm of the Rational
in detail, and in the modern, rational style so finely polished by Descartes.
And as we shall see, Leibniz then came along afterword, explored this same
rational territory, and expanded it greatly into its mathematical sphere with
the help of Spinoza's map. Leibniz, however, employed a radically different
i
This is seen in Spinoza's fundamental anti-Platonism, recall.
Page | 671
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
…but then again he considered himself profoundly anti-Spinozan as well…
Page | 672
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Page | 673
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
influential at a deep and hidden level. As Philip Clayton writes in his The
Problem of God in Modern Thought:
…one has to recall that the term Spinozism represented to the late
seventeenth century—and especially to a thinker who was by nature a
mediator and who thus worried about the orthodox appearance of his
thought—a dangerous and pernicious heresy. Like the term murder, its
use implied immediately that one had done something wrong. Yet like
other heresies in the history of thought, it also exercised a seductive
attraction on metaphysicians of the period (and not just then!). One must
finally agree with Catherine Wilson: “Spinoza was, in a sense, Leibniz’s
ghost. He was what Leibniz was afraid of being and saw himself as
dangerously capable of becoming; the [Spinozan] doctrine that God was in
some way related to creatures as a whole to its parts, not as an extra item,
was one which obsessed him.
And as Matthew Stewart writes in The Courtier and the Heretic:
Justice is no more assured in the history of thought than it is in the rest of
human experience. In the crucial half century after his death—the
crucible of modernity—Spinoza was arguably the most important
philosopher in the world. Yet his influence was mostly negative and
almost always unacknowledged. The incalculable impact he had on
Leibniz is only one example, albeit the finest, of the immense but nearly
invisible power Spinoza wielded over his contemporaries (p307).
Spinoza’s philosophy deeply unfolded the hidden nondual truths of the
Rational, as we have seen. It was thus the very antithesis of the pre-rational,
exoteric, transcendent-biased and oppositional forces of representation,
entrenched in the power structures of his day. Like a hot cinder on a cold
block of butter, this radically new philosophy—at once both repugnant and
irresistible—passed into the representational power structures and
ideologies which it opposed, and from generation to generation left its
cryptic trail only in the distortions surrounding it; i.e. the obscuring defenses
built up against it. Precisely because Spinoza was so vehemently vilified, the
cultural lens surrounding his philosophy became radically distorted, with
numerous defects persisting to this day.
Leibniz’s obsessed and repulsed reaction from the pre-rational “City of God”
was simply one of the first, strongest and most compelling of these many
distorting interpretations. But Leibniz wasn’t just reacting externally or
transitively to Spinoza. As is shown in various accounts, Leibniz possessed a
profound inner tension secretly both towards, and publically against what
many scholars see as his own intrinsic “heretical” Spinozism. Indeed, in
seeming accordance with his own principle of activity—which states that a
body cannot react to a force without an interior active resonance of
Page | 674
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
“perception” within that body and to that force—in the vastly complicated
interior folds of the vinculum of the monad of Leibniz himself, a Spinozan
logic unfolded in secret as a function of his own intrinsically rational
principles. It was this inner Spinozan resonance that allowed Leibniz his
outward Spinozan dissonance.
Bertrand Russell writes, “… Leibniz fell into Spinozism whenever he
allowed himself to be logical; in his published works, accordingly, he took
care to be illogical.” Indeed, Russell felt that Leibniz had two distinct
philosophies. The inner one, akin to the brazen heresies of Spinoza, and the
outer one, cowed and contorted in accord with the orthodoxy of his times.
For this reason, Russell considered Leibniz a great logician, but a scoundrel
of sorts who lacked the conviction or courage of his own true philosophy.
It is difficult, however, for us to comprehend the danger of the times for a
free thinker challenging the status-quo and its political power structures.
Spinoza had put his life on the line with the publication of works such as the
Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, and nearly paid for it with an attempted
assassination—the knife in the dark leaving its open wound only in the
threads of Spinoza’s overcoat. After this, Spinoza adopted the thorny signet
ring of Caute, or “Caution,” as the seal for all his correspondences.
Given these dangerous conditions for thought, and given Leibniz’s
profession as a court barrister within the very bowels of the pre-rational
power structure itself, one can quickly see what devastating consequences
would follow such a courage for a man such as Leibniz. It’s impossible to
understand the effects this had on the inner Leibniz. And perhaps we can be
grateful for Leibniz’s shrewdness in hiding his inner conflicts from those
who would never understand them. Without this subterfuge, perhaps, we’d
have none of the profound truths and tools Leibniz invented along with his
fascinating and fantastically Baroque philosophical reaction.
Matthew Stewart notes that along with this inner Leibnizian Spinozism
coincided a profound inner reaction against Spinoza as well. Stewart writes:
It is too simple by an order of magnitude to say either that Leibniz was a
Spinozist, with Stein, or that he was never a Spinozist, with Freidman.
The truth is that before he knew anything about Spinoza, Leibniz was
against Spinoza; and yet, at the same time, he also had a Spinozistic side.
The encounter with Spinoza was crucial to his philosophical development
because it forced him to confront this division within his own thought.
Spinoza presented him with a problem he devoted his philosophical
labors to solving, namely, how to suppress the dangerous Spinozist within
himself. Absent the dalliance with Spinoza, Leibniz would have remained
a conservative thinker; but he would not have been an essentially modern
one, and his philosophy would not have originated the reactive form of
modernity. To make a long story even more complicated: It is quite
plausible to say that, before, after, and during their encounter, Leibniz
was deeply anti-Spinozistic, superficially anti-Spinozistic, and deeply
Page | 675
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Spinozistic, all at the same time. The only thing that cannot be said, in my
view, is that for Leibniz Spinoza did not matter (p331).
As we will see, and as Stewart aptly demonstrates, at nearly every turn,
Leibniz’s privately expressed Spinozistic logic impelled him toward this
radical rationality already embodied in heretical Spinozism. And in every
instance, his inner and outer anti-Spinozist and anti-modernist compelled
him to invent a fantastic metaphysical contrivance to counteract this
dangerous and heretical Spinozism. It is indeed because his inner rational
truths are so strong and deep, that his reaction against them is so fabulous
and informative.
Through detailed studies of Leibniz’s private correspondence, Stewart
shows that this Spinozism was implicit in Leibniz from his secret readings of
Spinoza’s work long before their meeting in the Hague. During this time, for
example, while Leibniz was reading Spinoza’s Tractatus, he would write of
the book to his contemporaries and patrons that it was “terrifying,”
“monstrous,” and “intolerably impudent,” even feigning ignorance of the
name of its author, while simultaneously writing favorably of it in his notes
and penning a clandestine letter to Spinoza in praise of his work, in order
eventually to secure a secret meeting with him.
In the year 1676, recall, Leibniz began his Spinoza studies. Indeed,
Stewart writes, “Leibniz’s interest in Spinoza began to take on the character
of an obsession,” where he would attempt to secure any and all of Spinoza’s
writings he could possibly get his hands on (p187). And it was this
obsession, recall, through which Leibniz found his Ariadne’s thread out of
the labyrinth of the continuum, as well as his solution to the problem of the
calculus, after locating and copying out Spinoza’s Letter XII on the infinite.i*
During this year as well, Leibniz had a lengthy discussion with his friend
Tschirnhaus in which the contents of Spinoza’s “secret philosophy”—the
Ethics—were spelled out. The influence of this discussion is seen in blatant
Spinozisms in Leibniz’s notes of the time. At this point for Leibniz, as for
Spinoza, God and Nature are ONE. But later on, near the point of their
meeting, Leibniz “suddenly recants” his unwitting “collapse” (or advance)
into Spinozism saying:
“God is not something metaphysical…so that it would be the same if you
were to say that God is nature…. Rather, God is a certain substance, a
person, a mind.” (p184)
Leibniz then sets himself the task: “It must be shown that God is a person,
i.e., an intelligent substance.”ii¥ As we have seen,iii* on a ferry boat just prior
i
* See, The Spinozan Catalyst in the Triune Infinite, p407.
ii¥
VI.iii.518; DSR, p. 26
iii
* See, The Exoteric Face of Esoteric Rationalism, p67.
Page | 676
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
to his meeting with Spinoza, Leibniz reveals the original difference between
he and Spinoza, saying [my emphasis]:
“A metaphysics should be written with accurate definitions and
demonstrations. But nothing should be demonstrated in it apart from
that which does not clash too much with received opinions. For in
that way this metaphysics can be accepted; and once it has been
approved then, if people examine it more deeply later, they themselves
will draw the necessary consequences. …” (p187)
“At this point,” writes Stewart, “Leibniz was a Spinozist and he knew it.”
His strategy would be to conceal his true views wherever they offended
the orthodox, to cite great men such as Plato and Parmenides as a
diversion, and, in general, to work for the day when Spinozism might
emerge out from under the false accusations of heresy and claim its
rightful place in the sun. In the meantime…Leibniz would censor
himself…of…thoughts that the world was not ready to receive (p187).
We can see here that Leibniz and Spinoza had drastically different strategies
for interfacing their esoteric philosophies with the exoteric public. Leibniz’s
public interest was, as he himself admitted, in establishing a “popular
religion” and theocracy, a “City of God.” And after this fateful meeting in the
Hague, as Stewart shows, and as we will see, Leibniz willfully converts his
esoteric Spinozism into exoteric contortions largely because the truths of
Spinoza’s radical modernism are incompatible with, and intolerable to the
masses, let alone even to himself.
This is the original function of his monadology; to explode the truths of
esoteric modernity and rationality into the exoteric trappings of a
transcendent, anthropomorphic and pre-rational God, in a tensile and polar
arrangement to the immortality of the individual soul. In this reaction,
Leibniz fractured Spinoza’s ONE=ALL of God/Substance into an ALL of
infinitely many monads (ones), but only in order to separate the ONE of God
out of the identity of the equation and into a transitive and causal relation of
dependency with it, as we will see. Indeed, as we have already glimpsed, in
doing so he placed the omni of the ONE outside of the reach of logic and
rationality, where we will see it collapses into the non of a mythic vacuum of
logic.
On the surface, Leibniz essentially reverted the Parmenidean and
esoteric rational ONE to the pre-rational, mythic and exoteric Christian God
of pure transcendence. All of Leibniz’s reactions against his own Spinozism,
then, can be traced to the single idea that God is not immanent, but only and
purely transcendent … and we’ll see what happens when transcendence is
absolutized or “purified” without its identity with immanence.
Page | 677
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The rejection of Spinoza’s God as Nature—the ONE as the ALL, and the
anima mundi of the omni-axis—becomes the first principle of Leibniz’s
mature philosophy. Leibniz rejected Spinoza’s God essentially because it has
no will nor intellect in order to be “good” and deserving of the name of
“God.” And with this Spinozan identification of the ONE and the ALL, exoteric
and top-down morality can have no basis. This first principle of Leibniz’s
philosophy, we can see, is essentially that God is not immanent, and we’ll see
this echo throughout the rest of the Leibnizian reaction, building a profound
tension between the immanence of man and the transcendence of God, or
1/∞ vs. ∞/1, respectively.
Leibniz asks the critical question that can be asked of Spinozism. Can
Spinoza’s God be properly considered “God” at all if it is merely Nature?
Stewart writes:
According to Spinoza, God or Nature causes the things of the world in the
same way that the nature of coffee causes it to be black. But we do not
usually say that the nature of coffee is divine, so why should we say that
Nature is divine? Leibniz’s position here might be stated this way: what is
divine must be in some way beyond or before what is natural, or else it is
not divine at all (p236).
This implies a false analogy, however, because the nature of coffee, as
opposed to the nature of anything else, say tea, is just a deeper level of
modification (an immanent plane of transitive causation), rather than
corresponding to Spinoza’s implicit definition of Substance as an immanent
emphasis on the I/T axis. In other words, what we would call nature, even
as in “the nature of the physical world,” is not what Spinoza would call
Nature as Substance at all. Rather it would generally pass for nothing more
than the modifications known as the biosphere—or perhaps the
“physiosphere,” objectivity, or a plane of immanent transitivity. All of these,
as we have seen, are merely subsets of modification or form.
Spinoza’s Substance—like Nagarjuna’s Emptiness—is the identical
opposite of “form” and of modification. God as Nature, then, would simply
denote the ONE as enfolding the ALL, and hence God, in Spinoza, is seen as
intrinsically animate, as it enfolds and unfolds nature herself. This is,
however, one of the main distorted criticisms of Spinoza we see in Leibniz,
and echoed into Hegel: that Spinoza’s Substance is “rigid” or inanimate. And
this animate immanence and ALL in his own infinitely divided or folded
Page | 678
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
i
Recall also that Spinoza mentions explicitly in his Short Treatise that God is anything but passive
and therefore can only be seen as active.
Page | 679
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
In other words, if Spinoza is correct then the orthodox God of “the pious” is
impossible because he doesn’t choose to create the world, or to interact with
it, but rather it merely ‘emanates’ from his nature. Leibniz continues, “If all
things emanate of necessity from the divine nature, then all possible things
exist, with equal ease unfortunately for the good and the bad. Therefore
moral philosophy is destroyed.” According to Leibniz, this Spinozan idea
that “matter assumes all forms possible successively” is “the proton pseudos
[first lie] and foundation of the atheistic philosophy”(p224).
However, it would seem impossible to argue that the possible has not
been, and is not now equal to the actual, in some sphere in this inconceivably
infinite and eternal universe. For if a thing is possible, and there are infinite
chances (times and places) for this possibility to become actual, then the
likelihood of its not actualizing reduces to zero. Stated another way, an
event with any possibility whatsoever will have a finite probability greater
than zero, and this number—even the smallest conceivable number—
multiplied by infinity is … infinity. We’ve seen this in the paradoxes of the
infinite, as well as encoded in our Quantitative Principle of Infinite Unity,
represented in our VLE: ab2.
Assuming Leibniz is right, however, if an event is possible, yet never has
been nor will be actual, what can this possibility mean? Leibniz has a ready
answer for just that question, as we will see.
Leibniz offers a rare confession about his precarious position with respect to
the Spinozan actual-possible. He says:
“When I considered that nothing occurs by chance ... and that nothing
exists unless certain conditions are fulfilled from all of which together its
existence at once follows, I found myself very close to the opinions of
those who hold everything to be absolutely necessary [i.e. Spinoza]... But I
was pulled back from this precipice by considering those possible things
which neither are nor will be nor have been” (p220-1).
Twenty-five years later Leibniz would admit that he had once “leaned to the
side of the Spinozists” and that “these new lights have healed me, and since
that time I have sometimes taken the name of Theophile.”
Leibniz’s Theophilic answer to Spinoza’s God of “immanence in
transcendence” is what would appear to be a purely transcendent God,
outside of all space and time. Stewart writes:
...Leibniz provides a more vivid representation of this idea of God. In the
final pages of his Theodicy, a character named Theodorus (Leibniz’s alter
ego in this instance) falls asleep in a temple and begins to dream. In his
reverie he visits “a palace of unimaginable splendor and prodigious
size”—an edifice that, as it happens, belongs to God. The halls in the
palace represent possible worlds. As Theodorus wanders through this
Page | 680
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
“The halls rose in a pyramid, becoming even more beautiful as one mounted
toward the apex, and representing more beautiful worlds. Finally they
reached the highest one which completed the pyramid, and which was the
most beautiful of all: ... for the pyramid had an apex, but no base; it went on
increasing to infinity. That is ... because amongst an endless number of
possible worlds there is the best of all, else God would not have determined
to create any” (p237).
The central feature of Leibniz’s mature philosophy, Stewart notes, is “his
representation of God’s choice in terms of possible worlds—as opposed to
possible things.” This, then, is Leibniz's infamous “principle of the best.”
This marks what Leibniz believed was one of his decisive breakthroughs
in the ten years after his journey to The Hague. (p238).
Prior to this time, however, Leibniz found it difficult to conceive of merely
possible things. This is because his Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR)—
essentially that all things must have a logical reason for existing—demands
that no-thing be ultimately accidental or random. All things in Leibniz’s
infinitely interconnected and rationalistic world are ultimately pre-
determined, and actual, not merely possible [my comments].
“Because of the interconnection of things,” he acknowledges at the time of
his Discourse, “the universe with all its parts would be wholly different
from the commencement if the least thing in it happened otherwise than
it had.” [Note that this is an anticipation of the “butterfly effect” in
modern complexity science.] By raising God’s choice to the level of
possible worlds, however, Leibniz can have his Principle of Sufficient
Reason and eat it, too, in a sense: that is, he can grant that all things within
our world are linked together in a necessary way while still maintaining
that the world as a whole does not necessarily have to be the way that it
is. “The reasons for the world,” he says, “lie in something extramundane”
(p238).
Leibniz then, in accord with his PSR, maintains the Spinozan equation
between the possible and actual, but isolates and encapsulates this
problematic equation into his bounded conception of worlds, leaving God’s
“extramundane” world of worlds free from logic and free from the Spinozist
and rationalist constraints implicit in the fundamental Leibnizian PSR. One
then wonders how indeed this world of worlds has spontaneously self-
ordered into this bottomless pyramid of ever more perfect worlds, without
an infinitely perfect and interconnected logic of its own to accomplish such a
supertask, leaving this good God the no-brainer of merely plucking the top-
most ripe, yet merely possible world for “actualization” into this “best of all
possible worlds.”
Page | 681
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
* See, Depth vs. Span: Further Untangling the Trans-Trans-Bias, p573.
Page | 682
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Page | 683
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Monads are eternal ... with the exception that, in order to cleave a
transcendent, and indeed transitive, space for God with a bit of smoke and
mirrors, they can be created or destroyed with an attendant flash, all
supposedly outside of time, and outside of the core Leibnizian principles,
such as the principle of activity, and sufficient reason. Instead of windows,
eternal monads flash into existence complete with “mirrors,” which can
miraculously show their monads the entire universe and their place within
it, all somehow without any real conduit or interface to the outside. This is
because, recall, being substances, monads can’t arise with any external
dependencies whatsoever. Indeed, one must ask why a mirror is any less a
function of causal interaction than a lens, except merely that it breaks the
line of the light into reflected and redirected segments, rather than merely
bending it, thus interrupting our simple linear correlation with the
perception to its object. I suppose this is like questioning the logic of a good
fantasy or science fiction book, however, which, of course, spoils the effect.
Page | 684
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
So we allow Leibniz his “magic mirror on the wall,” and in the interior folds
and vinculum of his infinite eternal monads.
By means of these 'mirrors' of consciousness, each monad replicates the
entire universe of monads within itself; and so each monad is a “universe
in prototype.” Leibniz refers to this strange vision of worlds within
worlds as “the principle of macrocosm and microcosm”—meaning that
the microcosm contains or replicates the macrocosm all the way down to
the infinitely small. He expresses the same notion in his claim that the
ancient doctrine that “All is One” must now be supplemented with the
equally important corollary that “One is All” (p245).
We have already discussed the con-fusion here in the context of the
univocity framework.i* Essentially, recall, Leibniz has tacitly equivocated
from the absolute scope of the 1st order Absolute Infinity—taken in the
ancient “All is One,” (our balanced VLE ∞/∞)—to the relative scope of the
monad at the level of the 3rd order infinite, or bounded infinite (our charged
VLE 1/∞). The ALL-ONE was already the ONE-ALL, but the Leibnizian “One
is All” shifts through the Cycle of unity to the interface of the uni-axis, and to
the one of many. The “principle of macrocosm and microcosm” is thus not
quite the logical corollary, of the ONE-ALL, which is why the mirrors
themselves are “tarnished” by the finite variable, n. Stewart says the mirrors
are “splotchy,” and Badiou says, “Deleuze’s subject, the subject-as-fold, has
its numeric formula 1/oo, which is the formula for the monad, even if its
clear part is 1/n (Fold p. 178).” Thus the “All”—reflected in the clear part of
the splotchy mirror of the monad—in Leibniz’s “principle of macrocosm and
microcosm”—is not the ALL of the ancient ONE-ALL, but merely the Many of
the One and the Many.
These splotchy magic mirrors (or pre-established virtual reality
simulators), give an imprecise view of reality, and it is this imperfection of
window-less “perception” (in a prescripted harmony) that gives distinction
and individuality to each monad. Furthermore, according to Leibniz, it is
this same lack of perfect knowledge or virtual-perception which imparts the
gift of free-will on the monad. A strange freedom indeed being the “gift” of
absolute perceptual isolation and relative imperfections in the magic mirror
of each monad, a bunch of splotches merely obscuring the fact of a purely
pre-scripted and pre-determined existence.
i
* See, The Univocity Framework In Action: Leibniz and the “Principle of Macrocosm and
Microcosm”, p195.
Page | 685
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
it a “freedom” of the will. As Leibniz says, monads are “pregnant with the
future.” Individual monads, such as the Leibniz monad, “begin” as seeds,
floating around for eternity like particles of dust or atoms, agglomerating
into a larger entity here, dissolving again there. Thus, according to Leibniz,
monads can grow and develop, and they can also disintegrate and devolve.
This conception—as pleasing as it may sound to float around for a near
eternity as a speck of dusti—posed a vexing problem for Leibniz’s followers.
Which one of your parents, mom or dad, contained your monad—you—as a
seed? This was known as the “problem of sex,” and we can see it as
essentially the inversion of the paradox of the amoeba.ii*
Ultimately, again the problem comes down to the indivisibility of the
category of the individual, except this time the division occurs in reverse,
with the process of sex merging, in a sense, the identity of two “individuals.”
If an indivisible monad is the essence of your individual identity, and you are
created in the merger of two individuals, then indeed it must be asked which
parent’s gonad housed your monad—your mom’s or your dad’s? “…And
why do you look like a mixture of them both?”
i
* See, Immortality…as a “Speck of Dust”?, p694).
ii
* See, To Infinity and Beyond: Tuning and Triuning the Paradox, p432.
Page | 686
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
round: and they, who assert that everything is right, do not express
themselves correctly; they should say that everything is best.
According to Leibniz, bear in mind, the Spinozan equation of the possible
with the actual is “the proton pseudos” or first lie of “the atheistic
philosophy.” Recall also our mathematical demonstration that, in an infinite
universe any finite possibility whatsoever would have an infinite chance of
being actualized, putting its probability of occurrence exactly at one—
somewhere and somewhen in this infinitely infinite universe of universes.
We then gave Leibniz the benefit of the mathematical doubt, granting the
good doctor the claim that “OK, all possibles are not all actuals.” The Von of
all possible Leibniz’s then exclaims, “Oh contraire! In this best of all worlds,
governed by this best of all principles, and hence with amply sufficient
reason, all possibles are indeeeeed actual!!” “But!,” proclaims the doctor,
“This best of all worlds is not the only one possible!!!”
Dr. Von Leibniz then reveals that an infinite number of possible worlds
actually exist and yet will never exist actually. And in each of these possible
worlds there actually exist an infinite number of possibles which also will
never exist … actually. “This is because,” beams the good doctor, “there is
actually a world of all possible worlds, within which, self-assembled into a
bottomless pyramid of worlds of lesser and lesser possible perfection, there
actually sits atop, for all eternity, an apex!” This actual possible, it turns out,
is actually the best of all possible worlds, and possibly the best of all actual
worlds.
“God!,” explodes the doctor, “Being ‘good,’ as he is by nature, need select
only this ‘best of the best,’ in order to retain his title as… God.” And thus he
does . . . effectively consigning the rest of all possible worlds, and the rest of
all unfortunately impossibly-possible inhabitants, to the actual dustbin of
the incompossible, in this pyramid and world of infinitely actual possibles,
yet only one possibly actual world.
We then ask again, “Pray tell, Dr. Von, what possibly can be the meaning
of ‘possibility’ in this actual world of infinite possibly impossible worlds, and
their actually possibly impossible inhabitants in this best—and indeed in the
rest—of all possibly impossible worlds?!”
The problem rising to the surface in this infinite Leibnizian game seems to
be a contradiction of Leibniz's own Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR). In
constructing his world of all worlds, in which Leibniz can have his PSR and
eat it too, Leibniz has cleaved the world of causal and logical integrity off
into a purely arbitrary “fantasy world of all worlds.” In this fantasy land,
outside of space and time, apparently anything can happen. It thus fulfills
Leibniz's need of displacing the PSR and once again offering God a “moral”
choice in order to demonstrate to us his “goodness.” And so, by fiat and
royal decree, it becomes an actual world of mere possibles, already
actualized into a pyramid of mere possibles, timelessly awaiting an eternity
Page | 687
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
for a “good God” to choose to actualize the only one of these actually existing
mere possibles which is the best. In this world of all possible worlds Leibniz
is God. It is by his fiat that the PSR is suspended, and by his decree that this
world has actualized into its pyramid of worlds etc, etc, etc….
Perhaps the only appropriate question to ask is one of aesthetics. Does
this Baroque fantasy appeal to us enough that we can will ourselves into a
belief and faith in it? I am not sure, actually, if any of the infinitely possible
possibles (or merely any of the actuals) has ever really believed in it, or
thought it really even possible, including Leibniz himself—one of the most
eminently logical of all actual thinkers in this actual world of pure actuals.
Perhaps just for fun, we’ll outline these problems more detail, below:
Page | 688
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
i
Compossible means “compatibly possible,” essentially, such that a compossibility takes into
account the inter-expressive compatibility of its intrinsic terms.
Page | 689
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
that only God has. It must therefore be because the choice of the best of
all possible worlds follows from God’s nature. In other words, God
chooses the best of all possible worlds because it is in his nature to be
good. God could not do otherwise because if he did so he would not be
good, and therefore he would not be God (p281).
To deal with this problem, Leibniz labors to divide necessity into moral and
metaphysical (causal) varieties. Since God exists in an extramundane and
indeed a “meta-metaphysical” space, Leibniz can then decree that the laws of
this divine world of worlds are purely moral. God is thus exempt from
metaphysical necessity and rather “chooses” the best world out of purely
moral necessity.
However, since Leibniz declares God “good” merely because he decides
to actualize our world, which just happens to be the best and only world in
which we are compossible, then what about the disservice God does to those
inhabitants of the rest of all possible worlds by choosing our world to
actualize and not theirs? Is not God evil in their eyes, and rightly so, since he
effectively condemns the inhabitants of these slightly and ever lesser worlds
to an existence of nonexistence in this extramundane pyramidal necropolis
of worlds?!? Does not this “moral necessity” of choosing only one world thus
generate a moral “evil” along with its moral “good”? And is not this moral
evil infinitely worse, given that there are infinitely many more less-perfect
worlds which will go unactualized by this choice?
This cleaving of moral from metaphysical necessity, like Leibniz's
cleaving of the “world of worlds” from our world governed by logic and
sufficient reason, is purely arbitrary and leads to patently absurd
consequences. In the end it serves only to justify Leibniz's fantasy wherein
the rational and the pre-rational can mingle together on equal, and
ultimately transitive ground. The distinction, naturally, by no means
convinced everybody. Samuel Clarke, in his exchange with Leibniz, argues
that “necessity, in philosophical questions, always signifies absolute
necessity.” Necessity, after-all, is necessity, be it moral or metaphysical.
Arthur Lovejoy wrote, “The distinction Leibniz here attempts to setup is
manifestly without logical substance; the fact is so apparent that it is
impossible to believe that a thinker of his powers can have been altogether
unaware of it himself.”
Indeed, it is increasingly difficult to imagine that even Leibniz himself
could take much of this seriously, and there is ample reason to suggest he
didn’t, as shown by Stewart. Leibniz was a court barrister, in the end, and he
made a living of convincing others of beliefs that he never held. And in
accord with his admitted purpose on that ferry boat to his meeting with
Spinoza, Leibniz's universe seems to have been merely a toy world, a
fantastic metaphysical contrivance meant not ultimately for him, but for the
masses. It was conceived as a popular religion, and Leibniz was not to be
one of its followers, but its founder.
Page | 690
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
We can see here yet another resonant chord in our Ariadne’s cable.
Page | 692
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Explanation: This principle is a direct function of the transcendent bias and the
Univocity Framework. As the pre-rational forces of representation seek to mono -polize
the absolute scope with its transcendent pole, pure transcendence reflects through the
Principle of Absolute Reversal (PAR) into its implicit other, pure transitivity, because in
order to escape immanence, transcendence must conceive of itself outside of Being, as
we see with Leibniz’s inconsistent attempt to escape his own principle of Sufficient
Reason and causality. Thus pure transcendence implicitly cleaves for itself an absolute
and absurd dualism between itself and the ONE -ALL of the PSR. And (this absurdity
aside) in order for pure transcendence to effect anything from its “outside” position, it
must do so transitively, because immanence is not an option, and simply because it is
on the outside. The world then becomes the absolute object of the absolute subject,
and as we have seen, the subject -object polarity and causation is a transitive function.
Given the duality, however, Leibniz unwittingly falls yet again into the Cartesian
dilemma. Without an “immanent plane” there is no univocity and no real difference or
inter-expressivity between God and the worlds. A transitive-plane is always immanent
to higher levels of transcendence, as we see with Leibniz's God embedded within a
world of worlds which he did not create and which he cannot control, but merely
selects transitively from the static, p re-determined apex of its pyramidal necropolis.
And to conclude these arguments on the possible vs. the actual, we can sum
it up with yet another principle, echoing the anima-mundi itself as it reflects
into Spinoza’s principle that the totality of possibility in an infinite world
equals the totality of actuality, or that all possibles, given infinite space and
time, will be actual. This is also a reinstatement of the PSR and a limitation
or identification of the world of all possible worlds to an affirmation of this
world of immanence in transcendence and the ONE-ALL.
Page | 693
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Explanation: In an absolutely infinite and eternal universe any finite, non-zero true
possibility whatsoever would have an infinite chance of being actualized, putting its
probability of occurrence exactly at one —somewhere and somewhen in this infinitely
infinite universe of universes.
i¥
qtd. in Courtier p245
ii
* See, Transcendental Determinism and the Captive Will, p643.
Page | 694
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Page | 695
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
combine, all things achieve harmony.” For Spinoza, as for the Tao, a goal is
the overcoming of the transcendent or yang bias and its mapping to the
oppositional forces of transitivity, and this goal is distinctly a function of the
Rational, as we have seen in both its mathematical and philosophical
aspects.
For Spinoza, immanent causation (yin) is not a restriction of human or
relative freedom, but its implicit and invisible emergent foundation. The
immanent causation of the individual is included in the maximizing
definition of his own freedom. For this reason Spinoza’s determinism of
mind can be mapped into the “infinite determinism equals indeterminism”
of the body, but critically not reduced to it. Leibniz’s determinism, on the
other hand, is logically contained in the moment of creation of each monad
and in its pre-scripted transitive list of actions. Stewart writes [my
emphasis]:
According to the doctrine of pre-established harmony, mind and body
move in parallel only because God has seen fit to harmonize the pre-
determined activities of independent mind- and body-substances...
(p286).
Bear in mind that Spinoza’s philosophy of mind and body—his theory of the
attributes—is generally also conceived as a parallelism. But just as Spinoza’s
parallelism is an illusion of transitive perspective—as we have seen with the
immanent interface in the symbiogenesis of subject and object—so his pre-
determinism is an illusion. There is no time-line in univocal existence, but
only the eternal-NOW, the Parmenidean Being-now of Spinoza’s sub specie
aeternitatis. And as in Heraclitus, there is nothing but change itself,
changing, Being, Becoming for all eternity. And in the understanding of this
in the now itself we can thus participate in the eternal. This is Spinoza’s
notion of immortality as it transcends the limits of personal identity and
recognizes that eternity is not a function of life. Thus immortality has
nothing to do with duration but is a scope con-fusion projected onto the
aspects of mortality.
As we have seen, Spinoza and Leibniz have very different ideas about
immortality. But through their respective accounts of virtue, these
differences and their consequences begin to come into the light. For Leibniz,
virtue is correspondingly pre-rational, transitive, and transcendent; a virtue
which lies ultimately outside and beyond oneself. Leibniz thus seeks virtue
in the acknowledgement or praise of others. It is thus because virtue goes
unrewarded in this lifetime that Leibniz seeks salvation in the immortality of
the individual. Spinoza, as advocate of existential honesty and humility, on
the other hand, accepts individual mortality and seeks virtue as its own
reward. He thus does not require personal immortality. Stewart writes:
Page | 696
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Recall how Leibniz's drive for individual immortality is the sole impetus of
his ascription of the absolute properties of substance to the relativity of the
monad. And how this con-fusion generates the tension between the monads
and God their creator, and recall how this God of pure transcendence thus
collapses with his possible worlds into a pure fatalistic transitivity,
immanent to a higher transcendence which is equivalent to Spinoza’s God.
We’ve also seen how this forced individual immortality imposes upon the
monad an absolute dependence on God, as their free will becomes solely a
function of the obscurance of their splotchy mirrors, limiting their ability to
see their own fatalistic, infinitely detailed and pre-determined life-scripts.
There is another problem that comes with this pre-rational wish for
personal immortality, however. Given that Leibniz is committed to a
dualistic form of parallelism, “…Leibniz is forced to acknowledge that even in
its before- and after-lives, the mind-monad remains tied to some parallel
manifestation of body-monads” (p287). When a body dies, then, it begins to
disintegrate back down the levels of the Great Chain of Being, from human,
to animal and ultimately to mineral forms of awareness. The mind-monad
then wafts around the universe as a speck of dust, for what easily could seem
a near eternity before it finally might get incorporated into a more
transcendent monad, such as another human. The question then arises, why
would this one of billions of specks of dust have any more claim to the
singular mind-monad position of its human host than any of the others that
are likely caught in the mix?
Another related question is posed by Stewart:
Page | 697
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
… why not ascribe to this outside infinity of [physical] monads all of the
attributes we use to define our identities... ? (p287)
In other words, if the mind monad gets its properties and levels of
awareness from its aggregation with the physical monads, then why do we
need the mind monads at all. Why not say, as does Spinoza, that matter
itself, as modifications of Substance, possesses the power or attribute of
thought as a simple function of interiority, and this power is simply
magnified or unfolded in emergence into higher forms of complexity or
“excellence,” which is the individual identity itself in its interior aspect?
What does the speck of dust mind-monad really add to the picture of the full-
scale complexity of the body monad except for merely something to attach
the immortality category itself to? And is this immortality as a speck of dust
really worth the trouble of this Cartesian-esque parallelism? Stewart notes
[my comments]
Instead of preserving the sanctity of the [absolute] individual, Leibniz
may be inadvertently engaged in a deconstruction of individuality itself—
which, of course, is exactly what Spinoza accomplishes in his system
(p287).
Of course in this deconstruction of individual immortality one recognizes
oneself in reverse as a divine construction from God or Substance itself, in
sub specie aeternitatis.
i
This linear and even algorithmically coordinated unfolding of infinite parallel histories is in direct
contradiction, however, with the modern empirical concept of nonlinearity and emergence which
otherwise would justify Leibniz's prescient principle of unity.
Page | 698
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
i¥
Courtier, p251-2
ii¥
Courtier, p252
iii
By Hegel’s time, and largely due to the Leibnizian reaction itself, the historical reading of Spinoza’s
philosophy had thoroughly collapsed into the objective-ontic flat-land of materialism (or slightly
better, the “eco-philosophy” of the romantics) the “rigidity” and lifelessness of which both Leibniz
and Hegel falsely projected onto an already distorted Spinozism.
Page | 699
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
created by God, like the blocks of a pyramid. At the end of that road lies
Spinozism. If we say that this higher world has always been there and has
always been the way it is, on the other hand, then we make God one of its
creatures and we subject God to its rules, and he acts unfreely—i.e.,
according to its nature and not his own. In a sense, God is no longer God,
but just a logical operator within the scheme of some pre-existing nature.
At the end of that road lies atheism—or, one could say, a form of
Spinozism without Spinoza’s belief in the divinity of nature (p 283-4).
One problem, as we have seen, is the presumption that monads can be
absolutized into substances, as absolutely independent entities. We’ve seen
how this reverts into its opposite, forcing monads into an absolute
dependence on God in a fatalistic master and servant, or perhaps
programmer and program, relationship. The inverse problem is that Leibniz
has erected his God purely transitively, as an injection of the transcendent
bias of pre-rationality into the logical rigor and immanence of an unfolding
Spinozist rationality. In this rational light, recall, this pure transcendence
collapses into pure transitivity and thus Leibniz’s world is left Godless,
bereft of the divinity that Spinoza ascribes to the ONE-ALL of
God/Substance. Stewart notes [my emphases]:
All of the suggestions that Leibniz is some sort of Spinozist can be mapped
into the claim that monads are not true substances, as Leibniz maintains,
but rather something more like modes of a single Substance. Leibniz
himself acknowledges the centrality of the matter when he says that
Spinoza would be right, if there were no monads. All of the challenges to
the substantiality of the monads in turn come down to a question about
the relation between monads and God.
In his metaphysical system, Leibniz strives to maintain a delicate
balance between God and the monads. For example, he avers that
monads are eternal and indestructible—as indeed substances must be—
but then turns around and allows that God can create them and annihilate
them all in a flash. He grants monads freedom in their own eyes—which
is as it should be for all substances—but then seems to take away their
freedom in God’s eyes. These and other tensions in the City of God come
to a head in the simple question: is God a monad?
It would seem a straightforward question, the sort to which the great
monadologist would have a ready answer. Yet Leibniz is surprisingly
cagey on the subject. His best hint comes in the phrase that God is the
“Monad of monads.” One would have thought that, after three centuries of
effort, the Leibniz scholars would have come to a consensus on just what
Leibniz means by “the monad of monads.” But such is not the case. Some
argue that God must be a monad, others that he cannot be. In fact
there is no answer that works within the Leibnizian System (p288-9).
So let’s look at these two options.
Page | 700
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
If we say that God is not a monad we can understand the postulate that God
flashes the monads into existence and then must exist before them. The
monads, however, then get their properties from God, including an infinite
pre-determined script controlling (or “harmonizing”) their entire lives.
Hegel says, “There is a contradiction present. If the monad of monads, God,
is the absolute substance, and individual monads are created through his
will, their substantiality comes to an end.” i ¥ Monads, then, are not
independent. However, they are not merely dependent either, but infinitely
dependent on God to mediate their interactions with other monads. In this
sense, monads seem merely to be extensions, appendages or unwitting
agents of God, at best. And Since God alone is independent—barring of
course his collapse into transitivity and thus dependence on the world of
worlds which auto-arranges into his pre-defined choice—“he” alone can be
Substance, and we are again at Spinozism. As Stewart notes, “If God is not a
monad, in short, then Leibniz is a Spinozist” (p289).
i¥
Courtier, p289
Page | 701
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
The problem, Stewart notes, is that there is no way an observer could tell the
difference between a Leibnizian and a Spinozan world. Indeed Leibniz’s
critics accuse him of plagiarism over and over on this point. But Leibniz
insists that his form of parallelism is different in that it occurs by the will of
God. This is a moral, rather than a metaphysical necessity, he insists. God
could have chosen to make a “disharmonious” universe, claims Leibniz, but
he didn’t, because he is good. And thus “the pious” have something in which
to believe—which incidentally never seemed to have included Leibniz given
that he loathed church and never appeared to have worshiped on his own.
But, Stewart asks, is a “disharmonious” universe even metaphysically
possible, as Leibniz indeed implies?
According to Leibniz’s principle that One is All, each individual monad
entails the entire existing universe of monads, in the sense that its
internal “mirror” replicates the activities of all other monads, no matter
how many or how far.
A monad is intrinsically tied to the universe of all other monads. Choose one
monad, says Stewart, and you choose the entire universe.
In a disharmonious universe, however, the “universe” within each monad
would have nothing to do with the “universe” outside. … Choose two or
more monads, in other words, and you choose two or more universes that
have nothing to do with one another. ... But if disharmonious monads do
not belong to the same universe, then a disharmonious universe is not
possible. And if a disharmonious universe is not possible, then Leibniz’s
God has only harmonious possible universes to choose from, which is to
say that in all possible universes mind and body are harmonious, which is
to say that the parallelism of mind and body exhibits just as much logical
necessity in Leibniz’s world as it does in Spinoza’s (p 287).
Page | 703
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 704
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
i¥
Stewart, Courtier
Page | 705
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
about the relativity of space and time, not only prefigure developments in
twentieth-century physics, but his view that they’re mentally constructed,
prefigures the Kantian distinction between the noumenal and
phenomenal. And finally his critique of extension, and with it an implied
critique of the notion of matter, and his role of God as a sort of universal
switchboard between monads, certainly prefigures and presupposes the
development of classic Idealism, both in Berkeley and the English
tradition, and in classic German Idealism of the late eighteenth and early
nineteenth century. i¥
As we have seen, however, many of the specific mythic ideas in his
monadology collapse in the light of logic and reason. They are simply
revealed as by-products of his attempt to forge a popular religion by pulling
critical mythic ideas through the labyrinthine cusp of Rationalism, as it was
emerging in Spinoza. Together they end up being merely one of many
bizarre and obsolete projects of Leibniz's omnimaniacal mind—a brilliant
but futile attempt to inject critical pre-rational elements into an essentially
Spinozist rationality in order to found a religion. These incompatible
notions, then simply get shucked off with our emphasis on rational-level
philosophy rather than pre-rational and mythic-level religion. What remains
is largely the bare and tensile differences of emphases on an underlying
rationality—the same emergent territory explored by Spinoza, but seen in a
new critical light and with a new emphasis in Leibniz.
These obsolete mythic notions include; (1) the anthropomorphic God of
pure transcendence, (2) the tyranny of monadic existence under the
absolutism of substantial stasis, e.g. (2a) windowlessness, (2b)
independence=fatalistic dependence, (2c) the need for a monadic “magic
mirror,” as well as (3) the world of all possible worlds and (3a) its fiat
suspension of the PSR and the principle of activity, (4) the “creation” event,
and (5) the principle of the best.
With all of this reactionary con-fusion swept aside, we can now focus on
the core positive elements and results of this reactive philosophy, as it
carves new grooves and makes new folds in the body of Rationalism first
represented by Spinoza. As we have seen, in order to inject his pre-rational
elements, Leibniz created a profound tension ultimately between our two
forms of unity: the finite unity of his monads and the Infinite Unity of his
transcendent God—the one and the ONE, respectively. We have already seen
how to tune and triune this tensile polarity in the Cycle of Unity, and as it
manifests in the triune interface between the binary VL-axes of conceptual
relation, as well as in the resolution to the paradoxes of the infinite.
In Leibniz, however, the tensile relation remains, and this relation is
critical to the chiaroscuro and mannerist style of his system, with its truths
i¥
(Staloff, Great Minds of the Western Intellectual Tradition: Lecture 12: The Philosophy of G.W.
Leibniz: Audio CD Lecture: The Teaching Company.)
Page | 706
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
of emphasis. Along with this tension, then, the monad itself must remain,
freed from the tyranny of the absolute stasis and independence of
substantial aspects. This then marks a shift in emphasis from the Spinozan
Infinite Unity of Substance as God, or ALL as ONE, to the almost Zenonian
inversion of ONE as ALL. Leibniz, recall, demonstrated mathematically that
substance taken as plurality shifts from infinite Unity to the infinity of the
ALL and the Zenonian labyrinth of the continuum. With the substantial
tyranny of absolute independence removed from the monad, what we find is
a fleshed-out holarchy of monads within monads—an inverted “indivisibility
equals infinite divisibility” of folds within folds—each with a principle of
“unity as emergence,” now freed from eternity and numerical identity to
really emerge in an infinitely inter-expressive arising.
This, then, is the core value of the Leibnizian addition to Nondual
Rationality: the integration of the Spinozan principle of Infinite Unity with
the Leibnizian emergent principle of finite unity—the ONE with the one.
Deleuze sees this critical Leibnizian move as a “new relation between the
one and the multiple,”i¥ and in Interface Philosophy, we can pull this through
the triune interface and cultivated third of Spinoza’s three infinities and into
the Cycle of Unity, from ONE to ALL and into the ONE-one uni-axis and its
monadic interface, and then back through the equality into the ALL-ONE—
the cycle recall is—ONE = ALL = ∞/∞ = ALL = ONE.
The Leibnizian injection of the monadology can be seen as explicating the
Spinozan system in the positive, because it begins to flesh out the
holonic/monadic interface, the infinitely folded vinculum and the emergent
source of finite unity, and with it the uni-axial triune interface—the
cognitive holon—in the polarity of the two attributes. It begins to integrate
and interface our finite (relative) unity with Infinite (absolute) Unity, and
thus places the emphasis on the Zenonian/Heraclitean instantaneously
active ALL, pulling away from the eternally timeless Parmenidean/Spinozan
emphasis on the ONE. This is the move from the calm serenity of the ONE
into the wild, labyrinthine, immanent, organic, Baroque folds of the
monadology. And this is how “the clear plunges into the obscure and never
ceases plunging into it.”ii¥
From this new emphasis on the one, and with the monadic equation of
the bounded infinite with an external limit at 1, i.e. 1/∞ , we find that “The
human being is the new God,”iii ¥ and that each of us is “a small divinity and
eminently a universe: God in ectype and the universe in prototype.”iv¥ As
Stewart explains, “This is the idea that defines Leibniz’s philosophy, and that
i¥
(Badiou p. 173)
ii¥
Quoted from The Fold, in Badiou.
iii¥
Stewart, Courtier, p241
iv¥
Leibniz, qtd. in Courtier, p241
Page | 707
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Page | 708
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
opposition, as we see in the move from the unit-identity (1) into the
oppositional transitive forces of addition and subtraction.i And thus it is
with the Hegelian dialectic. Univocity breaks the absolute dominance of the
dualistic forces of the dialectic—it pulverizes the categories and opens up
the triune interfaces in the inter-expressive forces of intensity closed off and
forgotten in the origination of duality.
And in the sphere of set theory, as we have seen, the “animality” or
“organicity” of the fold is opposed to the “mathematicity” of the set, and its
identity and similarity of “pure belonging.”ii It was this “pure” or abstracted
aspect of “elements” and “belonging,” recall, that generated the naïve
paradoxes of set theory to begin with. An abstraction from the percept-logic
of the implicit holonic theory of sets, which, recall, was blindly reinstated
through “axiomatic set theory,” as reflected in its congruence with
mereology. Badiou continues:
The fold is finally an anti-Cartesian (or anti-Lacanian) concept of the
subject, a “communicating” figure of absolute interiority, equivalent to the
world, of which it is a point of view. Or again: the fold allows us to
conceive of an enunciation without “enouncement,” or of knowledge
without an object. The world as such will no longer be the fantasy of the
All, but the pertinent hallucination of the inside as pure outside.
Thus we see the fold as the vinculum of the monad, as we have seen it in the
symbiogenesis of subject and object, and the “ruin of the object.”iii With the
fold, then, as with the symbiogenesis of subject and object, the inside is
folded into the outside and the outside inside. The fold is thus the thick
mobius texturology of subjectivity as objectivity, the recognition of the
“hallucination of the inside as pure outside” as a triune interface between
subject and object, ruining the duality and opposition of the twain, and
elevating the hallucinating interface to the status of direct knowledge.
Badiou continues:
This vision of the world as an intricate, folded, and inseparable totality
such that any distinction is simply a local operation, this “modern” convic-
tion that the multiple cannot even be discerned as multiple, but only “acti-
vated” as fold, this culture of the divergence (in the serial sense), which
compossibilizes the most radical heterogeneities, this “opening” without
counterpart (“a world of captures rather than enclosures” [p. 111]): all
this is what founds Deleuze's fraternal and profound relationship to
Leibniz. The multiple as a large animal made up of animals, the organic
respiration inherent to one’s own organicity, the multiple as living tissue,
which folds as if under the effect of its organic expandings and
i
See, Phase TWO: Unit-closure and the Finite Unit-Identity (p308) and, Phase THREE: The Transitive-
axis and Agglomeration (p311).
ii
See, The Identity vs. the Opposite: Post-Modern Con-fusion and Pre-modern Naiveté (p221).
iii
See, The Fold and “Ruin” of the Object (p640).
Page | 709
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
Thus we can see that Leibniz’s notion of “substance” is quite different from
that of Spinoza, and effectively illegitimate except insofar as his principle of
unity is concerned. Both in his absolute substantiation of the monad, and in
his inclusion of God as pure transcendence, Leibniz employed a pre-rational
methodology, an operation on the transitive axis, rather than the rational
methodology of the I/T axis intersected into mathematical/philosophical
thought with the continuity of the rational numberline. This transitive and
pre-rational operation resulted in the split and tension between God and the
monad, which drives the dazzling baroque machine of his entire system into
such exquisite and often absurd heights. It is this “tension in the City of
God”ii that Leibniz was in danger of collapsing had he taken up the intrinsic
heretical Spinozism and brute modernity and rationalism that he was drawn
to. But we are demonstrating how indeed Leibniz and Spinoza can coalesce
in opposition from the same underlying elements of rationality—and thus
how they can both coexist in harmony on the same “plane of immanence,” or
more properly, in the Vision-Logic Coordinate System.
i
(Fold, p189)
ii
Stewart, Courtier
Page | 710
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Page | 711
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
i
See, The Problem of the Infinite Holarchy (p578).
Page | 712
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
This then brings Leibniz squarely in accord with Spinoza at the absolute
level, but with the benefit of integrating, rather than negating the differences
that make these systems unique. Through the use of the scope parameter,
we can see that Leibniz is taking the pluralistic, or ab3 view of the absolute
I/T axis and polarizing, charging, and unbalancing its binary components
into his crucial tension between the pre-rational transcendent/transitive
God and the rational/immanent/intensive monad, and hence between God
and man. This I/T polarizing view is the inverse identical to the I/T unifying
view adopted by Spinoza, and the symbiotic and harmonic tension—the
“shock” between the two methodologies as explicated in SpinbitZ—brings a
“New Harmony” a cultivated third, transcending and including, retaining, not
draining, the elements and details spawned from each.
So, in dramatic conclusion, to reach Leibniz = Spinoza, we end with a
measly formula. We simply (and anticlimactically) multiply,i reintegrateii
and re-equilibrate, the two charged (bounded) poles of the Leibnizian
system (see below):
i
…since multiplication is the inverse operation of division and since it is the cultivated third
(interface) in the onion of operations between the I/T infinite and the transitive infinite…
ii
many have used the term “collapse” here, in reference to impending resolution of Leibniz’s
harmonically self-contradictory system, into the non-contradictory harmony of the Spinozan system.
Page | 713
PART III: INTERFACE PHILOSOPHY AND NONDUAL-RATIONAL EMPIRICISM
(Leibniz = Spinoza)
or
or
or
1
ALL ONE
1
or
and finally…
Page | 714
LEIBOZA VON SPINBITZ: AN IDENTITY OF OPPOSITES
Page | 715
I would like to give a special thanks to Juan Calsiano for helping me to find
my way out of this dark labyrinth. Without his constant help and feedback
this book would not have been possible. And Robert Kernodle’s deeply
embodied dance with the human language, as well, was a constant source of
feedback and inspiration. And also Gerald Lebau, for his brilliant
demonstration of the raw power of the imagination to effect an exquisitely
beautiful causal understanding of the fundamentals of nature—and through
his patience in leading me up the treacherous paths to the other side of the
mountain—I cannot begin to thank him enough. But it was through my
mother’s wisdom and her understanding of the value of the arts for the
development of a young child—and in her own patience and constant
support, that the very foundations of my being were constructed. She was,
and is, a true renaissance woman. And I’d like to also thank my wife Liz, and
my son Grey for patiently and lovingly enduring this difficulty of an absent-
minded and absent-bodied father… I’m finally coming home …
Page | 716
Figure 1: The Holonic Solidus: .................................................................................................84
Figure 2: Space in the Process of Infinite Division by Spheres: .................................................89
Figure 3: Embryogenesis of the Concept: .............................................................................. 109
Figure 4: The Yin-Yang of Emptiness and Form: ..................................................................... 117
Figure 5: Polarity: ................................................................................................................. 118
Figure 6: The Main VCS Diagram: .......................................................................................... 143
Figure 7: The Nuclear VCS Diagram With Coordinates: .......................................................... 145
Figure 8: The Omni and Uni Axes and Interfaces: .................................................................. 151
Figure 9: Ontic-Epistemic Polarity: ........................................................................................ 179
Figure 10: The Tree of Singular Time: .................................................................................... 191
Figure 11: The Univocity Framework Template: .................................................................... 194
Figure 12: “Finite Unity is Plural and at Minimum Two”: ....................................................... 250
Figure 13: Orthogonality at the Boundary: ............................................................................ 254
Figure 14: Univocity Framework for the I/T Axes and Interfaces: ........................................... 260
Figure 15: Polarity of the Forms in the Cycle of Unity: ........................................................... 261
Figure 16: VLE of the Cycle of Unity: ...................................................................................... 263
Figure 17: The Orbit of Unity: ............................................................................................... 264
Figure 18: The Double Orbit of Unity (ant mobius image from M.C. Escher): .......................... 266
Figure 19: Mandelbrot Fractals: ............................................................................................ 286
Figure 20: The Infinite Coastline:........................................................................................... 287
Figure 21: The Triune Infinite and the Triad of Substance, Attribute and Mode: .................... 289
Figure 22: Fuller’s Isotropic Vector Matrix (IVM): .................................................................. 302
Figure 23: Boundary as the First Dimension: ......................................................................... 306
Figure 24: Transitive and I/T Relations: ................................................................................. 313
Figure 25: Agglomeration and Transitivity: ............................................................................ 314
Figure 26: The Image of the Trans-Bias in the Cartesian Graph and the Identity Line:............. 317
Figure 27: Numbering the Infinite: ........................................................................................ 319
Figure 28: The Primitive Numerical Identities: ....................................................................... 320
Figure 29: The Implicit Input/Output Polarity (Iopol) of Addition and Subtraction: ................ 322
Figure 30: The Abacus and the Iopol: .................................................................................... 324
Figure 31: The Iopol of Multiplication/Division: .................................................................... 328
Figure 32: Doubled Addition: ................................................................................................ 329
Figure 33: Multiplication/Division Commutativity and the Breaking of Unit Closure: ............. 331
Figure 34: The Image of Absolute Value (or the absolutely valuable image): .......................... 338
Page | 717
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 718
TABLES AND LISTS
Equation 1: VLE: ab1 — The Infinite: The Root VLE ................................................................ 293
Equation 2: VLE: ab1 — Expanded Root Equation and VLE: Cycle of Unity .............................. 293
Equation 3: VLE: ab2 — The Aspect Infinite ........................................................................... 294
Equation 4: VLE: ab2.1 — The Uni-Axis with Interface at Finite (Bounded) Unity ................... 294
Equation 5: VLE: ab3- — The Bounded-Immanent Infinite ..................................................... 295
Equation 6: VLE: ab3+ — Transcendent Infinite ..................................................................... 295
Page | 719
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 720
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Page | 721
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 722
BIBLIOGRAPHY
Page | 723
Absolute Infinite, 39, 243, 269, 273, Aristotle, 28, 171, 174, 224, 440, 449,
274, 275, 277, 278, 280, 291, 292, 455, 456, 457, 463, 464, 468, 469,
443, 445, 447, 584, 713 470, 471, 472, 473, 474, 475, 479,
acategorical imperative, 45, 49, 52, 66, 480, 550, 556, 557, 561, 672, 709
67, 188, 331, 375, 422, 440, 441, Arnheim, Rudolph, 22, 25, 125, 126,
638, 643, 653, 670, 672 127, 128, 129, 131, 220
advaita, 57 Aspect Infinite, 137, 191, 274, 275, 276,
aleph null, 87, 230, 231, 286, 446 277, 286, 292, 447, 663, 707
anatom, 209, 249, 295, 572, 573, 590 asymptote, 273, 280, 293, 391, 392,
Anaxagoras, 29 393, 394, 395
Anaximander, 451, 452, 460 a-tomos, 572
Anaximenes, 451 axis of univocity, 195
animality, 708 Badiou, Alain, 223, 224, 287, 641, 642,
apeiron, 72, 74, 76, 78, 79, 111, 162, 669, 684, 706, 707, 708
221, 226, 227, 448, 451, 452, 460, baroque, 669, 709
465, 467, 468 Berkeley, George, 47, 404, 405, 406,
apoapsis, 262, 264, 276, 280, 505 597, 628, 632, 705
Applewhite, Ed, 363 bijection, 225, 226, 232, 280
AQAL, 107, 163, 236, 251, 348, 493, biology, 601, 609, 704
495, 496, 502, 504, 558, 559, 560, blind-logic, 128, 205
561, 562, 563, 564, 565, 566, 567, Bodhidharma, 46, 542, 597
569, 574, 576, 584, 591, 594, 596, breaking of closure, 381, 385, 439, 584,
631, 632, 634, 635, 639, 640, 649, 696
654 Bucephalus, 174
AQAL metatheory, 560, 562, 563, 564, calculus, 30, 37, 72, 73, 78, 79, 89, 99,
566, 567, 574, 591, 631, 639 140, 203, 233, 272, 288, 339, 401,
arborescent, 573, 577, 578 402, 403, 404, 405, 406, 408, 410,
Ariadne, 73, 84, 95, 118, 121, 224, 245, 413, 414, 415, 417, 419, 420, 421,
332, 415, 477, 640, 675, 691, 707 422, 423, 424, 425, 426, 427, 428,
429, 430, 431, 478, 675, 704, 710
Page | 724
INDEX
Page | 725
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
organicity, 529, 707 Einstein, Albert, 40, 44, 64, 119, 124,
philosophy, definition of, 134 127, 189, 196, 208, 236, 238, 440,
plane of immanence, 131 492, 493, 584, 693
rationalism, secret of, 27 embryogenesis of the concept, 25, 27,
rhizome, 573 28, 50, 58, 94, 108, 109, 110, 111,
set-theory, 223 114, 136, 163, 206, 241, 255, 260,
Spinoza, 416 261, 268, 269, 273, 277, 278, 296,
Spinoza and Leibniz, 661 298, 302, 303, 309, 310, 317, 325,
Spinoza as anti-Descartes, 52 374, 387, 403, 415, 530, 543, 544,
Spinoza, Ethics and univocity, 419 557, 561, 593, 611, 625, 656, 665,
transcendental empiricism, 514 666
truth of relativity, 596 entheogen, 130
univocity, 155 erewhon, 152, 158, 321
univocity as organizing principle of ergodic, 152
Spinoza's Ethics, 39 Escher, M.C., 25, 72, 98, 113, 116, 117,
denumerability, 229 143, 203, 264, 373, 449
dependent arising, 33, 40, 50, 52, 59, eternalism, 58, 59
69, 86, 93, 98, 101, 102, 107, 157, Euclidean, 44, 146, 147, 148, 150, 218,
163, 168, 169, 191, 196, 197, 198, 224, 244, 257, 267, 277, 278, 281,
251, 418, 452, 489, 561, 562, 563, 297, 306, 327, 335, 341, 350, 353,
576, 645, 666, 682, 683, 688 409, 570, 707
Descartes, Rene Eudoxus, 367
as pre-rationalist, 61 extensionless, 74, 85, 120, 147, 218,
as proto-rationalist, 670 219, 220, 249, 251, 305, 333, 338,
as proto-rationalistist, 61, 89 409, 413, 414, 428, 570
cogito, 597 externalism, 543, 656
dualism, 539 fallibilism, 539, 652, 654
imaginary numbers, 349 fatalism, 90, 646, 693, 694, 701
pre-Socratics, 454 fissurotomy, 41, 546
reconciler of science and religion, 41 force, 39, 170, 187, 416, 462, 523, 537,
Spinoza, anti, 40, 52 564, 572, 599, 673, 703
descriptive protocols, 40, 174, 501, formative protocols, 174, 502, 504,
502, 504, 507, 508, 512, 514, 525, 508, 509, 513, 514, 523, 525, 535,
527, 528, 534, 535, 537, 538, 539, 539
540 foundationalism, 92, 96, 97, 98, 100,
deterritorialize, 34 103, 120, 156, 157, 160, 162, 179,
diagonalization, 230, 445 237, 313, 375, 405, 534, 536, 543,
dimethyltryptamine, 130 656, 657, 659
dividual, 434, 436, 440 foundationlessness, 103
dogma, 43, 45, 49, 50, 237, 638 four-dimensionality, 221, 305, 354,
Duffy, Simon, 34, 35, 36, 37, 38, 424, 359, 360, 361, 362
425, 426, 427, 430, 431 Fox, Claude L., 547, 552, 553, 555, 556,
effector, 612, 613, 614, 615, 616, 617, 632
619, 625, 641, 647 freedom, 684
free-will, 7, 65, 152, 164, 442, 486, 512,
645, 684, 687, 688
Page | 726
INDEX
Page | 727
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
infinite regress, 39, 92, 98, 99, 100, anti-Cartesian, 60, 86, 89
103, 211, 313, 338, 408, 637, 648, anti-Spinozism, 69, 196
665 as anti-Spinozist, 672
infinitieth term, 230, 231, 411 as atheist, 699
input/output polarity as exoteric rationalist, 68
definition of, 319 as pre-rationalist, 669
Integralism, 36 as rationalist, 47
intelligent design, 601, 605, 612 as reactionary modernist, 669, 675,
intensive forces, 170 677
intepretation, 156 as Spinoza plagiarist, 68
interaccommodative, 298 as Spinozist, 69, 673, 699
interparadigm, 563 binary logic, 122
intertheoretical reduction, 160 calculus, 401, 403
involution, 117, 141, 581, 582, 583, Candide, 685
641, 667 Cantor, 410, 446
iopol. See input/output polarity chiaroscuro, 29, 669, 699
irrational number, 137, 220, 223, 231, complexity, 642, 704
333, 338, 351, 353, 365, 366, 367, compossibility, 688
368, 369, 371, 379, 388, 446 continuum, 148
Kant, Immanuel contra Spinoza, 676
antinomies, 480 corpuscularianism, 572
contra Cantor, 229 creation event, 197
dualism, 41, 546 Deleuzian alternative lineage, 38,
epistemic reductionism, 180 156
forms of sensibility, 621 determinism, 693
Great Chain of Being, 40 disharmonious universe, 701
misinterpretations by, 34, 38 emergence, 377
ontic-shadow, 41, 546 emotion, 63
radical ontotomy, 41, 546 eternal now, 195, 377
Khun, Thomas, 618 exoteric agenda, 675
koan, 86 extension, critique, 693
kosmos, 24 fatalism, 646, 693
Kronecker, Leopold, 312, 366 fold, the, 223, 641, 707
Laplacian, 219 freedom, 646
Lauritzen, William, 356, 357 God, 677, 699
Lebau, Gerald I., 5, 6, 30, 32, 86, 103, God, "presumptive will of", 701
109, 132, 205, 304, 305, 332, 407, Hegel, 417
436, 477, 478, 479, 517, 552, 715 Heraclitus, 29
Leibniz, Gottfried, 518 honesty, 70
"active space" and the arrow of human as divine, 681
time, 183 hyper-essentialism, 172
"City of God", 675 immanent determinism, 186
"magic mirrors", 684 immortality, 681, 695
alternative interpretation, 47 Indra's net, 197
Anaxagoras, 29 infinite, 99
animality, 707 infinite baroque machine, 642
Page | 728
INDEX
Page | 729
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
mensuration, 265, 301, 302, 303, 365, naïve realism, 625, 626, 627
371 natural number, 87, 169, 266, 295, 312,
mereology, 211, 213, 223, 234, 235, 314, 317, 319, 320, 321, 322, 326,
445, 708 368, 402, 443
Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 39, 642 Negri, Antoni, 36
metaphysical necessity, 689, 690, 701 neocortex, 641
metaphysico-theologo- Netz, Reviel, 227, 228, 232, 233, 444
cosmolonigology, 685 neutral monism, 534
metastable, 589 Nietzsche, Freidrich, 37, 156, 160, 169,
mind-body problem, 62, 486, 488, 489, 173, 179, 187, 454, 661, 678
499, 500, 688 nihilipsism, 515, 529, 597
Minkowski, Herman, 238 nomothetic, 187, 188
mnemonic interface, 189, 513, 518, nondualism, 37, 57, 58, 61, 66, 158,
531, 537, 539, 544, 553, 584, 595, 171, 183, 186, 191, 240, 317, 666
596, 597, 614, 617, 620, 630, 631, nonduality, 27, 33, 50, 52, 57, 58, 65,
641, 656, 667 77, 90, 112, 155, 165, 169, 171, 173,
mnemonic primitives 176, 180, 191, 192, 237, 240, 241,
definition of, 529 374, 378, 426, 452, 455, 460, 537,
mobius, 116, 264, 265, 595, 708 544, 555, 584, 646, 691
Modal Infinite, 282, 283, 412, 442 noumena, 42
monad, 29, 196, 197, 198, 199, 200, numerical distinction, 52, 167, 168, 180
274, 295, 407, 413, 428, 529, 646, numerical identity, 74, 80, 171, 173,
660, 661, 671, 674, 681, 684, 685, 325, 328, 331, 333, 420, 430, 455,
693, 694, 695, 696, 697, 699, 700, 537, 538, 547, 706
701, 702, 706, 707, 708, 709, 710, objective-ontic shift, 160, 509, 534
711, 712, 713 observability, 267, 487, 505, 506, 517,
monadology, 69, 71, 72, 89, 158, 196, 518, 525, 539, 543, 550
223, 224, 225, 272, 407, 672, 676, occasionalism, 90
698, 705, 706, 709 Oldershaw, Rob, 99, 205, 587, 588, 591
monism, 36, 158, 159, 165, 167, 171, omni-axis
173, 488, 496, 534, 535, 537 definition of, 146
monological, 133, 599 omnidimensional, 139
Montag, 34 omnidirectional, 139, 141, 145, 146,
moral necessity, 689, 690 280, 291
multiplicity, 7, 29, 59, 96, 107, 108, omnilocal, 147
109, 111, 149, 156, 160, 165, 166, omnimaniacal, 705
189, 196, 241, 243, 250, 255, 260, omni-non, 122, 123, 148, 149, 151, 188,
270, 273, 275, 276, 287, 410, 447, 212, 227, 242, 246, 255, 257, 276,
460, 464, 477, 569, 574, 578, 584, 277, 282, 292, 294, 297, 299, 301,
590, 601, 604, 606, 621, 624, 628, 302, 303, 304, 305, 309, 328, 350,
639, 642 383, 384, 387, 410, 414, 455, 515,
myth of the given, 43, 45, 568 529, 663, 698
Nagarjuna, 33, 36, 37, 39, 50, 58, 59, omniradial, 301
66, 67, 80, 98, 169, 270, 401, 407, omnisimilar, 359
440, 452, 561, 665, 666, 670, 677, omni-uni, 151, 255, 258
681 oneironaut, 139
Page | 730
INDEX
onion of operations, 348, 385, 387, 460, 561, 632, 635, 672, 676, 682,
391, 396, 398, 399, 400, 712 709
ontic-epistemic polarity, 178, 491, 505, Poincaré, Henri, 206, 238
552, 570 positive infinity, 27, 39, 46, 50, 80, 82,
ontogeny, 125, 344, 400, 562, 611, 617, 83, 89, 93, 99, 103, 122, 156, 162,
620 182, 184, 288, 289, 335, 341, 369,
ontologies, 30, 99, 100 373, 374, 375, 378, 389, 407, 410,
ontos, 547, 550, 623 419, 422, 426, 428, 642
ontotomy, 41, 42, 49, 546, 547, 548, postdarwinian, 598
623 postformal, 133
Opdenberg, H.R., 660 post-ontology, 48, 49, 558, 559, 570
ordinality, 467 pragmatism, 316
organicism, 709 pre-established harmony, 90, 274, 646,
organicity, 708, 711 695, 697, 698, 700, 701, 703
origin-identity, 122, 341, 343, 382, 383, Presocratic, 450, 453, 454
388, 395 Prigogine, Ilya, 184, 186
orthogonality, 136, 142, 252, 351, 352, Procrustes, 39
353, 354, 522 propria, 667
Ouspensky, P.D., 125, 433, 600 protolife, 599
Pangloss, 685 proto-rational, 89, 140, 314, 661, 670,
Parmenides, 28, 29, 69, 70, 88, 450, 671
452, 453, 454, 455, 456, 457, 458, Pruss, Alexander, 274, 275, 282
459, 463, 464, 469, 471, 477, 478, Pythagoreanism, 633
561, 668, 670, 676 quadrant interface, 649
misrepresentations, 457 qualia, 503, 520, 527, 528, 530, 537,
PAR-Tunnel, 632, 633, 634, 635 597, 618, 620, 627, 630
Pearl Principle, 238, 279, 444 Rado, Steven, 205
percipi, 597 Rational number, 73, 74, 75, 76, 79, 80,
performative contradiction, 181, 205, 82, 83, 84, 87, 88, 89, 122, 152, 277,
267, 558, 638 295, 330, 332, 333, 335, 336, 354,
periapsis, 262, 263, 280, 383, 505 367, 368, 406, 418, 419, 420, 576
perspectival, 45, 289, 339, 408, 415, Rationals, 74, 79, 80, 83, 278, 292, 316,
423, 425, 488, 489, 492, 496, 565, 324, 330, 366, 379, 381, 401, 445,
568, 584, 626, 666 446
perspectivism, 569, 639 Real number, 446
phenomenae, 57 realism, 459, 625, 626, 627, 628, 634
phylogeny, 125, 344, 400, 611, 617, 620 rectilinearity, 351, 353, 619
physicalism, 527 redshift, 521
physiosphere, 677 rhizome, 573
Pickover, Clifford, 87, 285 Sagredo, 216
plane of immanence, 128, 131, 132, salvation, 695
134, 156, 160, 162, 167, 169, 170, Salviati, 215, 216
172, 182, 184, 191, 525, 662, 667, scalactic, 140
709 scalaxis, 140
Plato, 28, 59, 69, 70, 174, 224, 225, schmiderialism, 633
302, 312, 455, 456, 457, 458, 459, Scotus, Duns, 38, 156
Page | 731
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Page | 732
INDEX
Page | 733
SPINBITZ: VOLUME I
Tao, 3, 56, 58, 60, 72, 76, 92, 95, 107, uncountability, 138, 474
136, 137, 161, 162, 176, 182, 273, uncountable, 87, 88, 136, 146, 152,
317, 613, 694 158, 172, 230, 231, 236, 254, 255,
Tao Te Ching, 3, 56, 58, 60, 76, 92, 107 256, 257, 290, 294, 308, 311, 313,
technolinguistic, 606 327, 329, 333, 343, 346, 349, 353,
telos, 254 367, 368, 369, 374, 379, 382, 385,
teraform, 24 387, 401, 405, 410, 414, 415, 419,
tetrahedron, 297, 298, 299, 300, 301, 421, 422, 426, 427, 428, 429, 445,
305, 354, 355, 359, 360, 361, 362, 446, 457, 462, 465, 466, 467, 469,
363, 364, 365, 619 470, 471, 472, 473, 474, 476, 477,
texturology, 708, 709 478, 479, 480
Theaetetus, 367 uncuttable, 119, 572
Theodorus, 679 uni-axis
Theophile, 679 definition of, 146
Theosophy, 28 unit-closure, 123, 170, 248, 309, 314,
thinkability, 141 315, 317, 318, 319, 324, 326, 328,
trans-bias 330, 331, 332, 335, 346, 371, 374,
definition of, 93 375, 377, 387, 402, 429
transcendental determinism, 646, 693, unit-identity, 170, 309, 310, 311, 316,
694, 700 317, 318, 319, 320, 321, 322, 323,
transcendental number, 74, 75, 140, 324, 325, 327, 328, 330, 332, 333,
482 336, 340, 348, 350, 351, 366, 384,
transfinite, 88, 203, 211, 214, 216, 223, 385, 387, 388, 390, 395, 400, 429,
225, 227, 230, 234, 243, 250, 270, 461, 543, 554, 708
277, 278, 279, 367, 368, 369, 411, univocity, 27, 36, 39, 60, 72, 89, 97,
442, 443, 444, 446, 447, 448, 449, 155, 156, 157, 159, 163, 165, 166,
477, 480, 482 172, 175, 176, 177, 178, 180, 182,
transitive axis 183, 184, 186, 188, 191, 192, 193,
definition of, 138 194, 195, 196, 198, 200, 222, 243,
trans-rational, 27, 30, 31, 46, 51, 66, 270, 288, 341, 408, 441, 492, 684,
67, 73, 74, 93, 98, 106, 140, 147, 692
204, 218, 220, 245, 278, 343, 369, Univocity
377, 397, 398, 399, 414, 446, 488, as organizing principle of Spinoza's
543, 559, 584, 661, 662, 711 Ethics, 39
triangle, 299, 328, 355, 357, 358, 359, Urner, Kirby, 363
361, 362, 437, 438, 439 vector, 151, 256, 297, 298, 299, 300,
Triune Infinite, 30, 72, 98, 137, 148, 302, 318, 359, 362, 373
149, 163, 166, 189, 224, 225, 227, Vedantic, 42, 546
232, 239, 241, 242, 243, 250, 260, Venturi, 254
261, 269, 270, 271, 272, 273, 286, Verelst, Karin, 88, 141, 146, 231, 455,
287, 289, 290, 293, 303, 318, 331, 457, 459, 462, 465, 466, 467, 469,
401, 407, 408, 409, 410, 412, 414, 470, 471, 472, 473, 474, 475, 476
421, 423, 424, 430, 442, 444, 445, virtuality, 169
446, 470, 476, 477, 482, 525, 662, vision-logic equation, 199, 204, 242,
666, 675, 707 243, 246, 290, 303, 572, 598, 662
Tschirnhaus, 68, 69, 489, 675 definition of, 289
Page | 734
INDEX
Page | 735