0% found this document useful (0 votes)
305 views16 pages

Rob Lucas - Feeding The Infant

This document discusses different perspectives on the concept of "totality" in Marxism. It addresses how totality has been used and interpreted by various Marxist theorists from Lukács to Althusser. While totality can refer to many things, it often implies some unified whole or structured complexity of a society. However, the document questions whether any actual society can truly be viewed as a coherent, self-standing totality given the transnational nature of markets, ideologies, and other social relations.

Uploaded by

Ege Çoban
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
0% found this document useful (0 votes)
305 views16 pages

Rob Lucas - Feeding The Infant

This document discusses different perspectives on the concept of "totality" in Marxism. It addresses how totality has been used and interpreted by various Marxist theorists from Lukács to Althusser. While totality can refer to many things, it often implies some unified whole or structured complexity of a society. However, the document questions whether any actual society can truly be viewed as a coherent, self-standing totality given the transnational nature of markets, ideologies, and other social relations.

Uploaded by

Ege Çoban
Copyright
© © All Rights Reserved
We take content rights seriously. If you suspect this is your content, claim it here.
Available Formats
Download as DOCX, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 16

Feeding the Infant

Rob Lucas

Marxists have long been fond of rambling about ‘totality’, from the precedent of Hegel’s
‘Das Wahre ist das Ganze’1, through Luká cs, Korsch, Adorno, Althusser. But if the truth is
the whole, or the whole is the false, what actually is the whole, aside from its truth value? Is
there only one whole, and if not, which one are we talking about? Though Marx was apt to
make certain gestures towards a kind of holism, the elevation of totality within Marxism
was a Luká csian innovation. In Capital, Marx’s use of the term tends to be either
contextually specific and non-technical—‘since the existence of commodities as values is
purely social, this social existence can be expressed by the totality of their social relations
alone’; ‘the capitalist class in department I comprises the totality of capitalists who produce
means of production’—or implicitly defined in a technical sense as the unity of a particular
set of mutually-related moments: ‘industrial capital, considered as a self-moving totality’. 2
In neither case do we have the sort of ‘saturated’ or all-encompassing totality that
necessarily raises the ontological question of the nature of our inclusion within that whole,
or of how to get ‘out’ of it, as in certain uses of the concept of ‘real subsumption’. Yet
revolutionary theory seems constantly to pivot upon this problematic of inclusion and exit,
and it displays a recurrent—and perhaps rather morbid—fixation on the idea that some
encapsulation has, in some sense, now been completed: Adorno, Debord, Camatte, Théorie
Communiste, Negri, Jameson etc. And when we think in such terms, the question of
revolution easily shades into a somewhat ‘theological’ problematic of immanence and
transcendence, laden with paradoxes: how does something immanent to the mode of
production overcome that mode without perpetuating it?

Totality means many things in the history of Marxism. As a work of intellectual history
rather than first-order theory, Martin Jay’s study of its uses in Western Marxism holds back
from addressing directly what it most strikingly demonstrates: the comedy of more than
half a century of intellectual exertions around a concept that in the last analysis seems to
mean everything and nothing. Even in this relatively tight cluster of theorists and texts
alone, totality identifies the unity of subject and object; of a lost Golden Age; of theory and
practice; of a post-capitalist plenitude to come; of the working class; of history; of capitalist
society; of theoretical problematics; of the state; of man with nature, and so on. 3 Within a
broader history of holism in Western thought, we find it also referring to artworks, the
1
‘The True is the whole’: Phenomenology of Spirit (translated by A. V. Miller), Oxford 1977,
p. 11. In the next sentence, Hegel specifies what he means by a whole: ‘the whole is nothing
other than the essence consummating itself through its development’—which is to say, it is
not just everything, but the specifically Hegelian notion of the Absolute as something
constituted through the determinate mediations of the self-unfolding of Geist.
2
Marx, Capital, vol. 1, in MECW, vol. 35, pp. 77; Capital, vol. 2 (translated by David
Fernbach), London 1978, pp. 498; ibid. p. 182.
3
Jay, Marxism & Totality: The Adventures of a Concept from Lukács to Habermas, Berkeley
1984.
Greek polis, mankind, ‘the Spirit of the times’, community, the Parmenidean One, the
cosmos, life and so on. If it was the perennial will-o’-the-wisp of post-Luká csian Marxism—
whether to be chased or fled from—in the post-Marxist epoch it still persisted through its
endless exorcism, whether or not linked in ideological fashion to ‘totalitarianism’. Here we
will try neither to enshrine nor vilify what is surely so basic a category as to be unavoidable
(are we to avoid conceptualising the whole of anything?), but to become reflectively aware
of the conceptual artefacts and effects that can come with it. What are we invoking when
we invoke some ‘totality’?

The structured unity of everything


For those less philosophically inclined and more influenced by Gramscian and Leninist
lines of thought—perhaps with an Althusserian admixture—totality is typically a matter of
an injunction to think through all the organic complexities of a given society (state, classes,
culture, institutions and so on), implicitly with a certain strategic orientation perceived as
lacking in the narrow focus of ‘economistic’ Marxisms. Appealingly for intellectuals, this
leaves room for such things as ‘culture’ on the battlefield of the struggle for socialism or
communism. A holistic attitude to the complexities of social formations may be a more
useful orientation in concrete thinking than any idea that everything must be traced back
somehow to the ‘class struggle’ or some other privileged moment. But does this amount to
anything more than a generic injunction to contextualise? What is the implied theory of the
whole itself in such cases? What constitutes its unity? Is it something determinate, or just
everything?

The polemical impetus of the Althusserian project finds its justification in modes of
thinking that one still encounters fairly frequently. Althusser had a point in insisting, within
the context of Western Marxism, on complexity and an opposition to mystical reductions;
in pitting the ‘determinate unitary structure’ or the ‘structured unity of the complex whole’
against ‘empty unity’ and the ‘spiritual’ or ‘expressive’ totality. 4 His enduring merit is
probably to have signposted a way beyond the circumvolutions of philosophical Western
Marxism, towards a theoretically self-conscious appreciation of historical and political
complexity. But the positive accomplishments of his project, and the conclusions drawn
from it, have always seemed more questionable.

No matter how many times one arrays words like ‘complex’ and ‘structured’ against others
like ‘empty’, this does not in itself get one closer to anything determinate. Hegel too
polemicised against invocations of a vacuous unity, in such forms as the infamous ‘night in
which all cows are black’ of the Schellingian Absolute. And Althusser’s characterisation of a
specifically Marxian kind of abstraction—in contradistinction to the Hegelian—as never
primordial but always the outcome of prior determinations, seems unwittingly to identify
precisely the aspect of Hegel that the mature Marx most self-consciously drew inspiration
from.5 As both Hegel and Marx were well aware, concreteness is something that must be

4
Inter alia, Louis Althusser, For Marx, London and New York 2005, pp. 67, 202 and Reading
Capital, London and New York 1997, p. 17.
5
For example, Althusser, For Marx, p. 67; Marx, Grundrisse, Harmondsworth 1973, pp. 100–
108; Hegel, Science of Logic, London 1969, pp. 70–72.
achieved laboriously, through the systematic elaboration of determinations; if it is conjured
in advance of this then it can be no more than an image of determinacy—at most a
‘description’ rather than a ‘theory’, to put it in Althusser’s terms: Hegel, Marx and Althusser
are all in essential agreement on this.6 The main question is how to proceed in that
elaboration: is this an inductive or deductive process? A matter of analysis or of simple
discovery? What is it that drives one forward? The questions of a socially and historically-
conditioned ‘problematic’? The carrot of some positive ‘dialectic’, or the stick of simple
conceptual inadequacy?

Althusser’s project of differentiating and theorising the different ‘levels’ and ‘relatively
autonomous’ moments of the ‘complex structure’ of capitalist society assumes implicitly
that this society can itself be identified unproblematically prior to its analysis into ideology,
economy, state etc. As with most theorisations of ‘society’, that is to say, it seems to be
premised on the idea of a coherent, fundamentally self-standing whole, which is surely
nothing other than the image of the modern nation-state, with its unifications of internal
market, territory, governing institutions, language, ideology and so on. No matter how
complex, if the word ‘totality’ is to mean anything in this usage, there must at minimum be
some such ultimate coextensivity to the various levels of this society. But one need not
agree with Michael Mann’s whole approach to think he had a point in declaring that:

Societies are not unitary. They are not social systems (closed or open); they are not
totalities. We can never find a single bounded society in geographical or social
space. Because there is no system, no totality, there cannot be ‘sub-systems’,
‘dimensions’, or ‘levels’ of such a totality. Because there is no whole, social relations
cannot be reduced ‘ultimately’, ‘in the last instance’, to some systemic property of
it...7

Can one identify a single concrete society where each level or dimension—ideology,
economy, state and so on—is coextensive with the others? Markets and firms straddle
borders; states manage economies partially and imperfectly, through whatever limited
tools are at their disposal—currency, taxation, legal regulation; ideologies and cultures
both condense in specific, sub-state localities and spread trans-nationally; economic
structure too is differentiated at sub-state levels. In the period of high Keynesianism and
institutionalised collective bargaining, before the Nixon shock and European economic
integration, it was easier to think in such terms; there really was a certain regulative unity
of capital and state within individual nation-states. But even then, the globe was not
divided into essentially autarkic worlds: any analysis of individual societies in abstraction
from global markets and imperial structures, decaying or triumphant, was a distorted one.

6
Those schooled in Western Marxism or 20th Century French philosophy may be surprised
that the category of totality strictly speaking was of little more importance for Hegel than
for the mature Marx: as we might expect for a term that can be deployed as a synonym for
‘all’ or ‘whole’, it peppers the Logic, yet unlike categories such as Being, Quantity, Measure,
it doesn’t even get its own section.
7
Michael Mann, Sources of Social Power, volume 1: A History of Power from the Beginning to
AD 1760, Cambridge 2012, p. 1.
What, then, was the whole, and what was its theory? Was Althusser’s ‘structured unity’
ultimately that of the entire planet? What is the theory of the entire planet? Can there even
be one? While we may analyse, contextualise and describe particular societies, doing so
does not seem to get us closer to specifying the unity of the ‘determinate unitary structure’.
This totality is not yet an object of theory.

Mann was reacting to the Althusserianism of the 1970s, and in some ways his polemical
impetus aligned him with contemporaneous poststructuralist assaults on totality. But like
any unsystematised series, the neo-Weberian enumeration of ‘sources’ that he offers as an
alternative (politics, ideology, military, economy) invites indefinite expansion. Where, for
example, does the power of the controllers of technical infrastructure or of standards-
setting bodies come from? None of Mann’s categories seem right; perhaps there are five
sources—perhaps more are possible. Or, if there really are only four, why this number and
not some other? How do we account specifically for the four? That such impertinent
questions continue to niggle suggests perhaps that the unsystematised series is not
ultimately an alternative to totality-thinking, but the product of an incompletely theorised
analysis. As Hegel recognised, conceptual thought drives to unite the separate. Every
enumeration bears implicitly the question of the unity of the list itself.

Grooming as totalisation
For Durkheim, ‘the concept of totality is but the concept of society in abstract form. It is the
whole that contains all things, the supreme class that contains all classes’. 8 But what if there
is no concrete concept of society? What if, on the contrary, the concept of society itself is an
abstract, indeterminate totality? After all, it is hard to see how one would go about
elaborating theoretically the whole of ‘society’. What level of abstraction would be the right
one? Should the theory map all the concrete institutions, customs, cultures, groups,
individuals, buildings, classes, territories, kinship structures, transactions, laws and so on
that would typically be seen as constituting a society? What sort of theory would that be?
Where should it stop? Or, if it is to involve something more abstract, what specifies that
abstraction? In itself, the concept of society is distinctly lacking in determinate content.
While sociological analyses might imbue it with some, to what extent will those analyses be
generalizable as a matter of the actual concept of society? Durkheim’s pronouncement on
totality, that is to say, seems to have things precisely inverted: concepts like ‘society’ are
examples of the most abstract, indeterminate kind of totality, for how could a whole that
contains all things be concrete at the level of theory? In our imaginations we may conjure
up a picture of concreteness—some mass of details, like a ‘Where’s Wally?’ picture perhaps
—but that is a long way from actual determinacy.

Social wholes in general—at least those beyond a certain scale—seem to be characterised


by such elusiveness. What does a nation or civilisation contain, concretely? What about ‘the
people’? Perhaps this has something to do with the famous ‘Dunbar number’: an apparent
limit to our cognitive capacities in terms of thinking about groups larger than roughly 150
members. For Robin Dunbar, the social bonds of other apes are maintained by direct
grooming processes, which set determinate limits on group size, since the number of social

8
Emile Durkheim, The Elementary forms of Religious Life [1912], New York 1995, p. 443.
connections grows exponentially as members are added, and there is only enough time in
the day—and neocortices are only ever big enough—to cultivate and map immediate
relations with so many individuals.9 Radical imaginings of a purely immediate kind of
‘society’ reduced to direct inter-individual relations—or perhaps of the mythically integral
Homeric Greece in the visions of a Winckelmann or the young Luká cs—might be said to
conceive sociality on the model of the non-linguistic primate group, where it is always in
principle within the capacity of the individual to track the concrete relations between all
others. This renders a very distinct kind of social totality, where the social group is always
potentially graspable in all its determinations, without abstraction.

Dunbar speculates that the origins of human language, with its capacity for abstraction,
may lie in the evolutionary pressure towards the formation of larger groups. He sees
evidence for this in all sorts of places: the typical organisational structures of differently
sized firms; human neocortex scale relative to other apes; the social-regulative practices of
Hutterite communes, and so on. Once group size surpasses this level, new phenomena
come into play, such as increasingly hierarchical structures, and a displacement of direct
personal loyalties by ‘more nebulous and less inspiring concepts such as “the regiment” or
“the Queen”’.10 It is, we might say, as if the totality at play in non-human social groupings
were constantly in the active process of totalisation—always deliberately cultivating and
remaking itself in each of its links, and thus always potentially present to itself in all its
determinations—but that what some archaeologists and anthropologists term the ‘human
revolution’ introduced an abstractive rupture into the continuity of animal social forms,
after which the social totality would need to be thought through abstract concepts such as
the king’s second body, the nation-state, God’s chosen people, the corporation or
cosmopolitan world society.

The indeterminate totalisation of the social whole would then be not simply a failure of
thought, but an abstractive function that enables that whole to exist in the first place. Social
groups unify themselves under the sign of one or another concept that can stand in for the
whole, yet without specifying it concretely. The nation comes into being in referring to
itself as such; it performatively establishes a social actuality for itself, embodying itself in
institutions, cultures and so on; yet it remains in the nature of such concepts to resist
pinning down definitively.11 This projected unity of the indeterminate is thus perhaps a
structural facet of social thinking, and indeed of ‘society’ itself, beyond the smallest scales—
a sort of placeholder, a zero or an ∞, always in lieu of substantiation, but always essential
to the very possibility of the large-scale social entity. If this is the case, then we perhaps

9
Robin Dunbar, Grooming, Gossip and the Evolution of Language, Harvard 1996.
10
Dunbar, Grooming, Gossip and the Evolution of Language.
11
Note here the possibility of parallelisms with money as universal equivalent. This is the
sort of thing Marx had fun with, drawing analogies with such things as the Hegelian
sovereign. A certain kind of value-critical maximalism may be inclined to use this as a
justification for treating the value-form as a kind of Godhead, in relation to which all other
social forms are mere emanations. But it is hard to reconcile such thinking with historical
realities such as, for example, the imperial structure of Inca civilization, which was
essentially moneyless but was anything but immediately self-present or abstraction-free.
have some explanation for the elusiveness of the totality. Real, but indeterminately so, the
social whole gives to our thought a basic compulsion to totalise with similar indeterminacy.
But such totalisations necessarily remain pre-theoretical: if the work of theory is to
illuminate and specify something previously implicit or unclear, we might reasonably
doubt that any amount of theorising will ever elaborate the concept of something like
‘society’. What we might shed light on instead, is the problem of this indeterminacy itself.

Revolution against everything


This matters for revolutionary thinking because it has a bearing on the question of what is
actually to be overcome. What is the scope of revolution? If it is a whole that contains all
things then we must wonder where to begin; anywhere might be as good as anywhere else.
If the object of revolution is to be a hazily defined ‘society’, this is liable to leave the notion
of revolution itself hopelessly indeterminate. As long as we are operating at this level,
revolution seems to remain a matter of what Hegel termed ‘picture thinking’ (Vorstellung).
It may be brought to mind as a fantasized event, such as a global riot, insurrection or the
formation of an organisation—depending on your identity and affiliations. Such speculative
imaginings may at least perform a certain role in making present to consciousness the
question of radical social change, but they betray a poverty of actual content, as
indeterminate as the world that they are arrayed against. In order to move from picture to
theory, it is necessary to address this problem of scope, and to question the compulsion to
totalise indeterminately.

Not all totalities are indeterminate. The capitalist mode of production is what we term a
determinate totality, and it is such a totality that Marx strove to elaborate in the volumes of
Capital. It is determinate because it is possible to specify in detail the mediations that
constitute it—labour, capital, money, means of production and so on—and to show how
these relate to each other in such a way as to constitute an integral whole. Capitalist society
by contrast, with all its people, cultures, institutions, practices, beliefs and so on, is an
indeterminate totality: no theoretical analysis could ever enumerate its mediations as an
internally self-related system. In Marxist theory, things like ‘society’ tend to be closely
identified with concepts derived from the critique of political economy such as ‘the
capitalist mode of production’, or more loosely, ‘capitalism’. There is often an implicit
telescoping of terms, such that ‘society’—with all its indeterminacy—is identified with
‘capitalism’, which is in turn identified with ‘the capitalist mode of production’, or simply
‘capital’.

This telescoping identification of concepts can lead to certain illusions of explanation, such
that one seems to promise to account for the other—as if all the moments of capital’s
systematic self-positing could be enough to explain whatever ‘society’ is. Marx constructed
lucid explanations of what capital is, how individual capitals relate to each other, how they
form something more general, how capital relates to workers, why the classical political
economists were systematically blind to certain things about all this, and so on. This does
not however mean that he had a general theory of whatever it might be that ‘society’
denotes, or even ‘capitalism’ (if we take this to be anything more than a contraction of ‘the
capitalist mode of production’). The theory of capital does not in itself account for the
projected unity of the social world; although no doubt in many ways related, these are
quite distinct. If we cannot construct a theory of ‘society’, or even of ‘capitalism’, in the way
that we can construct a theory of capital, nor can a theory of the one stand in as a theory of
the other.

Capital as society
There are, however, some concepts that seem to provide justification for the identification
of the mode of production in a strict sense with other aspects of the social world.
Subsumption and reproduction are key examples: the first, in summary, because it seems
to identify a way in which capital incorporates within itself a world beyond it; the second
because if society reproduces itself through the mode of production, it might seem to follow
that everything that occurs within ‘society’, and which can be characterised as reproductive
in some sense, is part of the mode of production.12 Let’s consider these concepts in more
detail.

In a fairly loose sense, ‘subsumption’ has entered the lexicon of critical social theory: this or
that aspect of society, reason, culture, nature may be said to have been at some point
‘subsumed’ by ‘capitalist logic’ or suchlike.13 This non-technical usage names a certain basic
intuition about how capital profoundly shapes the world in general, and there is of course
much truth in this. But there is also a stronger, more ostensibly technical sense in which it
has entered some conceptual toolkits. As we noted back in Endnotes 2, since the 1970s or
so, when many people first discovered the ‘missing sixth chapter’ of Capital, some—
particularly on the French ultra-left—have perceived in Marx’s distinction of formal and
real subsumption a periodisation of the history of capitalist society. 14 Crucial to this is the
way in which subsumption seems to provide a bridge between the capitalist production
process in the narrow sense and more expansive notions such as society or humanity. It
can thus seem to perform a theoretical role reminiscent of ‘reification’ in the Luká cs of
History and Class Consciousness.

For Jacques Camatte, an ‘anthropomorphosis of capital’ had occurred, such that capital
became directly identified with human community as such:

The fact that capital is erected as a material community allows capital to avoid
losing itself in all the various processes. This community flourishes on the dead and
the reified. But, with the movement of anthropomorphosis, capital becoming man,
its community poses as Gemeinwesen. Thus men are snared by the being they
themselves produced.

12
One might anticipate this problem extending to ‘social reproduction theory’, but serious
analysis of works in that area will have to wait for another day. Here we will concern
ourselves only with reproduction as it is conceptualized in the example of Théorie
Communiste’s work, where it is closely related to real subsumption.
13
See for example, Wolfgang Streeck, How Will Capitalism End? Essays on a Failing System,
London and New York 2016, p. 202: ‘a progressive subsumption of social life under the
organizing principles of a capitalist economy is an inherent, ever-present danger of life
under capitalism that needs to be politically counteracted.’
14
‘The History of Subsumption’, Endnotes 2: Misery and the Value Form, April 2010.
In the process, for Camatte, capital had integrated the proletariat by ‘capitalizing’ it, and
‘everything’ had ‘become capital’ in a kind of total subsumption. 15 This had practical
implications: the Bordigist ‘theory of the proletariat’; the problematic of class
consciousness; the revolutionary organisation; the orthodox faith in the progressive
development of the productive forces—all were to be abandoned in favour of an
orientation to a human species viewed as domesticated and decadent, and hope could only
lie in something external to this monolithic totality. Yet since capital was identified with
human community as such, ‘having absorbed all the old contradictions’, it became hard to
see what the positive content of such an outside could be; were we to be left merely
positing an empty transcendence?16

There are echoes of these formulations in Théorie Communiste’s work, albeit shorn of the
humanist mysticism. Rather than humanity, here we find, in a particular historical moment,
capital ‘becoming’ capitalist society through a process of subsumption:

It is not possible to understand the real subsumption of labour under capital


without considering that what occurs in the labour process only resolves itself
outside of it. Capital, as society […], is a perpetual work of the formation of its
inherent contradictions at the level of its reproduction which undergoes phases of
profound mutations. It is possible to go so far as to say that the real subsumption of
labour under capital is defined as capital becoming capitalist society, i.e.
presupposing itself in its evolution and in the creation of its organs. 17

The justification for this identification seems to be that the main prerequisite of the
capitalist production process—the separation of capital and labour—is also its major
outcome. At a general social level, this means the reproduction of the fundamental classes
of capitalist society, and the perpetuation of capitalist relations of production. And once we
are talking at this level of social reproduction it becomes tempting to slide from the narrow
gyrations of capital’s own circuit to the reproductive functions of all sorts of aspects of
‘society’:

As far as real subsumption is concerned, the criterion for its dominance has to be
sought out in the modalities of reproduction of labour-power (social and political
modalities): social welfare systems, the invention of the category of the
unemployed, the importance of trade unionism, etc. All this naturally accompanies
the transformations in the labour process: the decline of handicrafts and domestic
industry caused by the first phase of large-scale industry. In order for there to be

15
Jacques Camatte, ‘Preface to the French edition’ and ‘Remarks’, in Capital and Community:
the Results of the Immediate Process of Production and the Economic Work of Marx, London
1988, available online.
16
Camatte, The Wandering of Humanity, (translated by Fredy Perlman), Detroit 1975;
available online.
17
‘Théorie Communiste responds’, in Aufheben #13, 2005.
real subsumption, […] modalities of reproduction of labour-power must be created
which are adequate to the transformations accomplished in the labour process. 18

Since the reproduction of capitalist relations of production can be conceived as the


reproduction of capitalist society, an elision can be performed whereby the whole of
society becomes little more than the capitalist production process writ large. And since that
process has a peculiar developmental dynamic, it becomes tempting to read this into the
history of capitalism in general. Thus Marx’s logical schematisation of the phases in
capital’s relationship to its production process—moving from formal to real subsumption
—becomes a historical periodisation of capitalist society as a whole.

The theoretico-historical apparatus that Théorie Communiste have constructed on this


basis is in many ways a sophisticated and compelling one. And the language of
subsumption seems to chime with a general intuition that some fundamental incorporation
has taken place. But this is a striking case of that telescoping pattern of identification that
we encountered earlier, where the logical totality of the moments of capital’s circuit comes
to account somehow for the indeterminate totality of society, for the imagined unity of the
social world. The telescoping movement provides an illusion of systematicity as well as of
explanation: if we can elaborate in some theoretical detail what it is for capital to subsume
the moments of the production process, and if this subsumption gives us a ticket to the
level of ‘society’ as such, then volume 1 of Capital (read through its ‘missing’ sixth chapter)
becomes a total theory of society and everything in it, and the problem of revolution
becomes the ontological one of inclusion within a capital-saturated totality, a problem of
immanence and transcendence, while we circle infinitely around a seductively enigmatic
paradox: ‘How can the proletariat, acting strictly as a class of this mode of production, in its
contradiction with capital within the capitalist mode of production, abolish classes, and
therefore itself, that is to say: produce communism?’.

How we become capital


Let’s revisit this question of subsumption once more, to clarify what it actually involves. If,
through ‘subsumption’, capital does not merely shape the world but actually seems in some
sense to incorporate it within itself, what is the nature of this incorporation?

Means of production are subsumed by capital in an ontological sense when it takes hold of
them and makes them serve the ends of its self-valorisation. The employment of workers is
part of this process, and in this case the wage is the key mediation. As part of capital’s
circuit that wage posits the worker’s labour as its content. Here our labour appears as ‘part
of’ the capitalist mode of production not just in the manner of this or that incidental aspect
of the forces and relations of production of a given capitalist society, but as a systemic
aspect of capital’s own production process—indeed, as part of capital itself. In the wage, an
abstract monetary magnitude ranges our labouring capacity under itself, such that certain
of our concrete exertions appear as a mere facet of capital’s own self-aggrandising project.
The peculiarity of such arrangements led Marx to conceptualise them with a word

18
Ibid.
borrowed from logic and ontology: the technical term for some ranging of particulars
under a universal—such as that of animals under their species—is subsumption. 19

This is different from mere ‘domination’, which is a matter of being ruled over by the
master of the house—the domus. In a relation of domination the two poles remain
relatively external to each other, unimplicated in one another’s being. But when some
particular is subsumed under a universal, the relation is between two inextricable logical
facets of some self-same being: a whale is both this whale, and a whale. The universal
presents itself as the essential truth of the particular, the particular as a mere instance of
the universal. Monetary exchange is peculiar in realising something like this not just as a
mental operation, but as something practically real and socially objective. In every act of
exchange, a monetary quantity presents itself as the true measure of some thing, in all its
qualitative irreducibility; a mass of particulars is subsumed.

If the claims of money over what it buys have always had a certain ontological character,
however, as long as we are focused only on the moment of exchange this inclusion appears
as strictly momentary. If the monetary measure seems to subsume the qualities of the
commodity, it does so only fleetingly and from a specific standpoint: once bought, this book
ceases to perform as a commodity, subsisting simply as your book, until you decide to sell it
on to someone else. Likewise labour power, once bought with a wage, ceases to present
itself as a commodity, dissolving itself into the flows of daily activity; the wage presents
itself as the truth of the worker’s labour only when they go to market—which is to say, only
as long as we are considering their labour-power itself as one side of a market-mediated
transaction. Thus this ontological mode of inclusion so far signalled by the term
‘subsumption’ appears, by the same token, extremely weak. Insofar as labour is only ever
posited passingly and contingently as the content of the wage, in instants of mere exchange,
it barely raises the ontological question of inclusion and exit.

A greater necessity comes into play when we consider not simply monetary exchange in
general, but exchange as a moment of capital’s circuit. The various transactions which
make up capital’s valorisation process constitute a certain unity, which folds back upon
itself to reproduce some of its own conditions: profits are reinvested in subsequent
iterations of the process. These exchanges can be understood as the moments of a single
process, and thus so can the accompanying dynamic of subsumption. Where we are dealing
not just with financial or merchant’s capital, but with a capital that has taken hold of some
production process, its various exchanges can be seen as enacting the subsumption of
another unified process. It is insofar as my labour participates in this process that it is
identified specifically with capital and not just with the wage that I am paid. Insofar as it
inherits a kind of necessity from capital’s circuit, subsumption may seem to have deepened
here, but it has also inherited the contingency of the mere moment of exchange, and is still
distinctly weak. For though my labour feeds the capitalist glutton during the day, my
capacity to work comes home with me in the evening, itself unsubsumed by this particular

19
For a fuller elaboration of these points see ‘The History of Subsumption’.
capital, and free in principle to go elsewhere: this is part of the definition of wage labour as
opposed to dependent labour or slavery.

If I am in a sense ‘included’ in a particular capital during the working day, this always
remains a particular capital, for the drive to accumulate has the individual firm as its
irreducible nexus. No worker is employed by—and no means of production are set in
motion by—‘capital in general’: it is always a particular firm that offers a wage in order to
keep in motion its own production process, that aims to sell the result at a profit, and that
returns again to the labour market with the resulting revenues. Strictly speaking—that is to
say, understood rigorously not simply as domination, but as a logical or ontological matter
—‘subsumption under capital’ occurs only within this basic circuit. Whether merely formal
or fully real, subsumption under capital by definition occurs only within individual
production processes, for it is only there that anything is directly identified with, or
included within, capital itself. And thus, insofar as the wage permits no capital to claim me
in my entirety, this ontological inclusion identified by the concept of subsumption still
remains weak. There is always a world outside, and we are always part of it. In this sense
subsumption under capital does not in itself even raise the ontological question of inclusion
within—and exit from—the mode of production.

Infancy to dotage
Of course, capitalist production processes have major implications beyond their own
narrow circuits, encompassing such things as the carbonisation of the atmosphere and the
melting of the ice caps. But implications are not identifications: things do not have to
become capital to be affected by it, even profoundly. Whatever its outcomes, if
subsumption under capital, strictly speaking, occurs only at the level of individual capitals,
it cannot directly characterise society in general, or its history, especially not at a global
level.

That subsumption occurs strictly at this level also has implications for any attempt to
periodise capital itself in these terms. Each capital will negotiate its relationship to each of
the things that compose its production process in a particular way, accepting them as is,
reorganising or transforming them. With time, these reorganisations and transformations
will of course accumulate and deepen. Thus these subsumptive relationships will tend to
chart a trajectory from a ‘formal’ to a ‘real’ character, and such developments will spread
from one capital to another, tendentially generalising throughout the global economy. Thus
the aggregate too will tend to chart a trajectory from ‘formal’ to ‘real’. But if everything
tends to run in one direction, that ‘everything’ is a vast chaotic manifold that cannot itself
be reduced to single stages at given points in history, as if last year the wider world was
only formally subsumed while this year it really is.20 This is because the distinction between

20
For Théorie Communiste, as for the regulation school, the key shift here occurred around
the First World War, when increasing productivity of labour supposedly first began to
cheapen goods consumed by the working class. Under the influence of the French ultra-left,
Loren Goldner has made essentially the same claim, seemingly contradicting his own
Bordiga-inspired recognition that ‘capitalism is first of all the agrarian revolution; before it
is possible to have industry and cities and urban workers, it is necessary to revolutionise
formal and real subsumption schematises, in the abstract, the generic temporality of the
capitalist production process, not its social history. The human ageing process too is
generally unilinear—one must be young first before one can be old—and we may say that
the human race in aggregate is now demographically older than it was a few decades ago,
but any claim that human history as a whole could be divided into such things as an
‘adolescence’ and a ‘maturity’ could only ever be a dubious metaphor; here too, there is a
key distinction to be made between temporality and history.

Historical attempts to distinguish between eras of formal and real subsumption do have
some formal resemblance to another, more legitimate, distinction between phases. At the
level of the most abstract form it makes obvious sense that an ‘extensive’ moment would
have to precede any ‘intensive’ one. And it is empirically true that pre-capitalist
exploitation was typically extensive, while the coming into being of capitalism involved a
shift to a kind of intensive growth. Prior to the emergence of agrarian capitalism—and
continuing until relatively late in contexts such as the European absolutist state—
exploiting classes have tended to gain greater surpluses just by squeezing more out of their
inferiors through extra-economic power. The peculiarity of the English state and agrarian
economy immediately prior to the formation of capitalist relations of production was the
way in which the configuration of these two removed that option, compelling landowners
to extract a surplus from their tenants by means of the market in rents, while driving
producers to increase their productivity and ‘improve’ the land. 21 It is in such intensive
development that we find the origins of capitalism, for it set in train an ever-expanding
process of accumulation and dispossession of which both proletariat and capital were
products. If capitalism finds its origins in intensive development, it then drives that
development further as market competition ceaselessly compels producers to make
transformations in the production process: in this sense, capitalism is real subsumption.

agricultural productivity to have the surplus to free labour power from the land’: Loren
Goldner, ‘Amadeo Bordiga, the Agrarian Question and the International Revolutionary
Movement’, in Critique: Journal of Socialist Theory, vol. 23, no. 1, 1995. In Endnotes we have
already pointed out the empirical implausibility of this idea, referring readers to Robert
Brenner and Mark Glick’s critique of regulationism; I do so again: ‘The Regulation
Approach: Theory and History,’ New Left Review I/188, July–August 1991. The key
problem, as we argued there, is that ‘capitalist production tends to commoditise and
cheapen consumer goods from the outset, and agriculture is not something that is
capitalised late, except perhaps in particular cases such as that of France, whose rural
landscape remained dominated throughout the 19th century by small peasant owner-
producers.’ Indeed, simple logic suggests that the development of large proletarianised
populations living in cities could not take place without productivity growth in agriculture,
though it of course says nothing about the sources of that growth. For these, we need to
look to the vagaries and outcomes of agrarian class struggle in pre-industrial England; see
Brenner, ‘The Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism’, in The Brenner Debate: Agrarian
Class Structure and Economic Development in Pre-Industrial Europe, Cambridge 1985.
21
Ellen Meiksins Wood, The Origin of Capitalism: A Longer View, London and New York
2017; Brenner, ‘Agrarian Roots of European Capitalism’.
Any attempt to tell this history on the basis of shifts to formal then real subsumption would
seem implicitly to assume both a pre-existing capital, always already capable in principle of
grabbing hold of its share of the world, and a pre-existing proletariat always already lining
up at the factory gates. Accounts of so-called primitive accumulation, which imagine the
origin of capitalism as something constituted more or less ‘politically’—through simple
violence and a sort of extensive development which had the effect of heaping up capital on
the one side and labour on the other—seem to make a similar assumption. 22 For how do we
account for the separation of the political and the economic, which itself is something
peculiar to capitalist society? In ancient empires rapacious violence and expropriation
tended to increase such things as tax revenues and supplies of slave labour rather than
laying the bases of capital accumulation.

Policing the exit


If capitalism is real subsumption, and has always had this intensive character, then it does
not make sense to think of real subsumption as posing the sort of problem of inclusion and
exit that we have been interrogating here—at least, no more so than the capitalist mode of
production always has. Real subsumption in itself cannot characterize either an epoch or a
society, and it has not, in itself, enchained every reproductive aspect of the entirety of
society to the production process. But if—as we found in our look at the ontology of
subsumption under capital—we always inhabit a world beyond the capitalist production
process strictly speaking, then why can we not simply abandon this mode of production
and do something else? What is the real nature of the problem? There are surely reasons
for the popularity of such ideas; they seem to correspond to a certain intuition.

There are several possible answers to this question. Firstly, given their historical
concurrence, it is easy to identify the capitalist mode of production with the modern nation
state. As the latter encompasses us within its borders, manages us through its bureaucratic
institutions, regulates us through its laws, inculcates in us a specific culture and language,

22
This is presumably a side-effect of Marx’s polemical purpose in part 8 of Capital volume
1: debunking Smith’s dreamily peaceable ‘previous’ accumulation by pointing out the
brutal realities that the beginnings of capitalism actually entailed. (The specific
connotations of barbarism in the rendering of Marx’s ursprüngliche Akkumulation as
‘primitive accumulation’ are an artefact of the retranslation into English of Marx’s German
translation of Smith’s term.) But this polemic does not amount to a positive theory of
origins; Marx left useful leads, gesturing towards many possible factors in the origin of
capitalism, but worked none up to the status of what can reasonably be called a theory. He
identified the capitalisation of English agriculture as a key moment, but went on to claim
every other violent act of European colonisation—even Spanish and Portuguese, which
specifically did not lead directly to capitalism—as an example of ‘primitive accumulation’,
while appealing to an abstract ‘force’ as an ‘economic’ factor driving this process. A
teleological bias contributes to the confusion, various things that preceded capitalism being
identified with its origins seemingly because of what came after them. Subsequent attempts
to identify one or another violent accumulation process with ‘Marx’s concept of primitive
accumulation’ gain little theoretical insight from this appellation, whatever the other
merits of the analyses in which they are deployed.
its relation to us can seem in a sense deeply ontological. And in its own way—though the
logics are fundamentally distinct—the state may be just as subsumptive as capital: political
sovereignty involves an identification of citizens and subjects with a greater whole. 23
Rather than the capitalist mode of production, it may be that it is the programme of
national state-consolidation that helps explain the holisms of Hegel, Croce or Gramsci—
intellectuals self-consciously struggling to do their universalistic, integrative bit—and thus
a significant aspect of the Marxist discourse of totality.24

In themselves, the fearsome encaging effects of political power are of course not something
particular to the capitalist epoch. Consider Gibbon’s terrifyingly totalistic description of the
imperial Roman state:

The empire of the Romans filled the world, and when the empire fell into the hands
of a single person, the world became a safe and dreary prison for his enemies. The
slave of Imperial despotism […] expected his fate in silent despair. To resist was
fatal, and it was impossible to fly. On every side he was encompassed with a vast
extent of sea and land, which he could never hope to traverse without being
discovered, seized, and restored to his irritated master. Beyond the frontiers, his
anxious view could discover nothing, except the ocean, inhospitable deserts, hostile
tribes of barbarians, of fierce manners and unknown language, or dependent kings,
who would gladly purchase the emperor’s protection by the sacrifice of an
obnoxious fugitive.25

Given the relative constraints on their communicative capacities, it is hard to believe that
earlier forms of political power could ever have felt quite as total as those of the present,
yet Gibbon’s fugitive of Rome is not all that far from the despairing Foucauldian, fixated on
the repressive powers of the modern state. That is, in short, because the encompassment
and repressive regulation of a population is just what states do, and have done since their
Neolithic origins.

Nonetheless, states must have seemed more porous and provisional prior to the
consolidation of the bureaucracies and infrastructures of the modern world: feudal
boundaries were constantly shifting due to the vagaries of aristocratic succession; the
physical walls of the polis gave way to relatively unprotected countryside which might
readily change hands with some shift of fortune; the inhabitants might be moved en masse
to some other location or colony; the ebbs and flows of imperial conquest could displace
large populations; and throughout much of human history, nomadism was still a relatively

23
Indeed, Marx’s concept of subsumption under capital stems from Hegel’s description of
the subsumption of the particularity of civil society under the universality of the
sovereign’s decision—a characterisation that the young Marx thought outrageously
idealist: Hegel, Elements of the Philosophy of Right, Cambridge 1991, p. 328; Marx,
Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right (MECW 3) p. 48.
24
Jay, Marxism & Totality, pp. 72–6.
25
Edward Gibbon, Decline and Fall of the Roman Empire (1776), vol. 1, New York 1879; pp.
99–100; available online.
familiar phenomenon from beyond the bounds of the agrarian state. Such things must have
had a bearing on the character of the social imaginary; active membership of the citizen
body, and its absence or withdrawal, could be central in policing the bounds of the polis
(thus the importance of exile and ostracism in the Greek world), but could the individual
ever have imagined themselves as included within some saturated, all-encompassing
totality as we are prone to now?

Is, then, the real problem of inclusion and exit that of the state, rather than the mode of
production? Though its precise definition may remain somewhat blurry, with all its
identifiable institutional articulations this state is a more determinate totality than is
society as such. And in an important sense the state also helps tether us within specific
relations of production: its repressive apparatuses prevent us from simply walking out of
the workplace and finding another way to feed ourselves. But this is not simply a matter of
policing the exit—after all, the land that we might use for such ends is already possessed by
someone else, and it is specifically the maintenance of that possession that matters. And
thus we quickly find our way back to capitalism and its fundamentally agrarian basis. 26
Though it is hard to come by reliable statistical data (since many landowners like to hide
behind layers of legal obscurity), holders of land amount to a tiny and dwindling portion of
the population, and some of them are extremely powerful. Such people have of course
ensured their protection, and any genuine attempt at some proletarian reappropriation of
agricultural land would immediately run up against the full force of a heavily militarised
surveillance state which has us hemmed into its borders. This is the real bind that we will
one day need somehow to find our way out of.

Capital’s infant
The crux here is not an ontological matter of incorporation or identification. It is a problem
of dependence and its modalities. Market dependence is the principle prerequisite for the
establishment and maintenance of the capitalist mode of production; it is firstly market
dependence that will need to be overcome if we are ever to move beyond it; and market
dependence is premised upon a separation from means of subsistence. There is at least
some scope for a nominal reciprocity within this basic dependence: though workers need
commodities, capital too has a need for labour. But the tendency of this relationship to
issue in a surplus population amounts to a shift from mutual dependency—albeit within an
asymmetry of power—towards an increasingly lopsided situation, in which a large part of
the human population clings on for dear life to its dysfunctional supplier of subsistence
goods. Bound to the extraction of fossil fuels and a broader despoliation of nature, this
supplier threatens ultimately to kill its dependents. Such profound dependence on
something that threatens ultimately to kill us might be compared to a narcotic addiction,
but the reproductive, nutritive nature of the bond here invokes something even more
thoroughly existential: the fragility of the infant. The proletariat is the dependent child of
capital, infantilised by capitalist society and insecurely attached to a parent constantly
threatening to withhold their affections.

26
On this, and for a discussion closely related to the present text, as well as ‘Error’, see John
Clegg and Rob Lucas, ‘Three Agricultural Revolutions’, South Atlantic Quarterly, vol. 119, no.
1, 1 January 2020.
It is easy to mistake thoroughgoing dependency for perfect identification, as if the capital
relation permitted some womb-like ‘oceanic feeling’. But we are not enclosed within this
mode of production as in a uterus. Though the dependency may be complete, it does not
engulf us. And even a baby does a great deal more than eat and shit: it is a self-developing
neural system which learns spontaneously to integrate and regulate its sensory organs,
limbs, interior; to locate itself in space; to form a posture oriented to the world of things
and people stretching beyond its parents; to extend the neural maps of its limbs into tools,
and to begin to make that world act upon itself—all alongside a complete alimentary
dependency. Capital’s dependents too will have to develop a posture, an orientation, tools,
if they are to stand a chance of eating after their parent’s demise, and they cannot and do
not merely wait for that moment. Everywhere people strive to stand and become mobile; to
set and follow their own rules, if given half a chance. They find ways with the stuff of the
world to construct themselves and to reconstruct that stuff. Insofar as capitalist society
inhibits or prohibits that development of autonomy, it infantilises us. But the infant must
learn to feed itself.

You might also like