Chapter 3 Report - Philo Social
Chapter 3 Report - Philo Social
& Philosophical
Foundations of
Humanity, Philosophy,
Religion & God
Philosophy of Philosophy of
Reasoning Politics and
Society
Philosophy of Philosophy of
Morality Education
PHILOSOPHY OF
REASONING
Reporter:
Meliza N. Abucay
Reasoning is the set of processes that
enables us to go beyond the
information given, especially when the
world around us does not always give
us complete information.
Reasoning is the process of thinking
about something in a rational way in
order to form a conclusion or
judgment.
Look at the three images in sequence as
presented above.
1. What do you think is the scenario in each
image?
2. What assumptions did you make, based on the
information given?
3. Explain your reasoning. In other words, explain
how you arrived at your answer to these
discussion prompts.
Reasoning is generally seen as a means to improve knowledge
and make better decisions. For example, you may have
overheard someone engaged in a discussion say, “Look, be
reasonable.” When people make this comment, they are usually
asking others to:
• be open to changing their minds;
• avoid bias;
• think logically;
• dig deeper for the truth, whether they like that truth or not;
and/or
• set aside narrow-mindedness, superstitions, magical thinking,
and impulsiveness.
Philosophical reasoning then, at its root, is
about engaging in discourse - one that asks
the participants to argue a point, a thought,
an issue, with logic. You will need to learn
how to discuss philosophical questions the
way philosophers do, as presented in, “How
to Argue,” a video created by Crash Course.
Parts of an Argument
What constitutes an argument?
Well, as simple and yet as odd as this may sound, arguments are
composed of sentences. In fact, they are made up of a particular
type of sentence, known as a proposition. A proposition is a
declarative sentence - or statement - that has a truth value. To be
more precise, a proposition is a sentence that expresses facts
that can be either true or false. For example, “Today is Tuesday”
or, “It is very hot today.” Now, it could be Tuesday, so this
statement would therefore be perfectly true. No one would argue
with it. This statement, then, is NOT a proposition.
Typically, most of the propositions in an argument state
facts or provide information which supports
the claim being made. These propositions are known as
premises - a proposition serving as a reason for a
conclusion. The following statement is an example of
this: "Since the housing market is depressed and interest
rates are low, it's a good time to buy a home."
The claim being made is known as the conclusion of the
argument - a proposition that is supported or entailed by
a set of premises.
Arguments always have one conclusion, but the number
of premises can vary quite a bit.
Types of Arguments
Philosophers distinguish between two broad
methods of arguing: deductive and inductive.
The deductive method moves from the more
general to the specific, whereas the inductive
method moves from a specific case to a more
general conclusion.
Deductive Arguments Inductive Arguments
Deductive arguments are supposed to be Inductive arguments needn’t be as
watertight. For a deductive argument to be rigorous as deductive arguments in order to
a good one (to be valid) it must be be good arguments.
absolutely impossible for both its premises An example of a strong inductive argument
to be true and its conclusion to be false. would be:
With a good deductive argument, that 1.The sun has not exploded for all its
simply cannot happen; the truth of the existence. therefore...
premises entails the truth of the conclusion. 2.The sun will not explode tomorrow.
The classical example of a deductively We are not 100% certain that the
valid argument is: conclusion is true, but it is more than likely,
1.All men are mortal. based on past outcomes, that the
2.Socrates is a man, therefore... conclusion is true.
3.Socrates is mortal.
It is simply not possible that both 1 and 2
are true and 3 is false, so this argument is
deductively valid.
The Prisoner’s Dilemma
Let’s imagine the following scenario:
Tanya and Cinque have been arrested for robbing the Hibernia Savings
Bank and placed in separate isolation cells. Each of them cares more about
their personal freedom than about the welfare of their accomplice. A clever
prosecutor makes the following offer to each. “You may choose to confess or
remain silent. If you confess and your accomplice remains silent, I will drop
all charges against you and use your testimony to ensure that your
accomplice does serious time. Likewise, if your accomplice confesses while
you remain silent, she (or he) will go free while you do the time. If you both
confess I get two convictions, but I'll see to it that you both get early parole.
If you both remain silent, I'll have to settle for token sentences on firearms
possession charges. If you wish to confess, you must leave a note with the
jailer before my return tomorrow morning.
You are Tanya - what do you do?
Steps:
1.Explain what you chose to do - and your reasons
for this decision.
a) How did you validate your reasoning?
b) What premises did you put forth?
c) What claims were made?
d) Were your arguments deductive or inductive?
Logical Fallacies - What They Are, and How to Avoid Them
Simply put, a logical fallacy is an error in reasoning.
For example, say people try to argue with you and base their positions on a
bad piece of reasoning - not information, but reasoning - in other
words, how they assert their position, or try to persuade you to come around
to their way of thinking.
For example: There is a huge Math midterm exam in two days. You are
concerned that you are going to fail and mess up your overall average - an
average that you need to maintain to get into the college you want. While
you are walking through the cafeteria, wondering how to rearrange your
schedule so you can get maximum prep time, someone from class whom
you barely know calls you over to a table. Turns out that particular someone
got a copy of the mid-term and offers you a copy.
Now, leave alone the ethical issue here. You decline, saying that
you don’t think it is right. This person then argues with you and
wants to know what the big deal is - says to you, “Look, everyone
else is doing it, so it's not like it’s really cheating if we all have the
same edge.”
That is an example of bad reasoning. That classmate is using
what is known as “the bandwagon fallacy” or “authority of the
many.” She or he is trying to persuade you that if an idea is
popular, or if many people believe it is right, then it must be right.
So logical fallacies are not about the content of the argument -
we will cover that later - they are about the reasoning that
individuals use to justify why they think that they are right.
Formal and Informal Fallacies
Fallacies can be categorized as either formal or informal.
1. Religion. Morality is
2. Nature. By the relation
determined by the
between human being
relation between human
and nature.
being and supernatural
being.
Morality is determined by
four areas:
3. Individuality. By the 4. Society. By the relation
relation the individuals between human being
has to him or herself. and society.
Where does morality came from
Empathy
Guilt and conscience
Shame (and concern for reputation)
Disgust
Outrage and inequity aversion
Where does morality came from
Cognitive Capacities
Self-control
Reasoning/rational intelligence
Where does morality came from
Empathy
Guilt and conscience
Shame (and concern for reputation)
Disgust
Outrage and inequity aversion
Where does morality came from
Enlightened self-interest and
reciprocity
● For consequentialism,
the moral rightness or
wrongness of an act
depends on the
consequences it
produces.
1. Consequentialism
(Classic Utilitarianism)
● For consequentialism,
the moral rightness or
wrongness of an act ● Benefit and harm can be
depends on the characterized in more than
consequences it one way; they are defined in
produces. terms of
happiness/unhappiness and
pleasure/pain.
1. Consequentialism
(Classic Utilitarianism)
● Utilitarians’ concern
is how to increase net
utility. Their moral
“the morally right action is
theory is based on the
the action that produces
principle of utility the most good” (Driver
which states that 2014).
2. Deontology
(Deontological Theory)
● He models his
morality on science, Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
● Kant distinguishes
two types of Immanuel Kant (1724-1804)
imperatives: ● A hypothetical
hypothetical and imperative is a
categorical contingent
imperatives. command.
2. Deontology
(Deontological Theory)
Immanuel Kant
(1724-1804)
● It’s conditional on a
person’s wants, needs,
● For example, the
or desires and normally
advice, “If you want to
comes in the following
do well on a test, then
form: “If you want/need
you should study a lot”
A, then you ought to do
would be a hypothetical
B.
imperative.
2. Deontology
(Deontological Theory)
Immanuel Kant
(1724-1804)
● A categorical
imperative, instead of
● Examples of categorical
taking an if-then form,
imperatives would be
is an absolute
“You shouldn’t kill,”
command, such as,
“You ought to help
“Do A,” or “You ought
those in need,” or
to do A. “Don’t steal.”
3. Virtue-based Theory
• Modern virtue ethics takes
its inspiration from the
Aristotelian understanding
of character and virtue.
Aristotelian character is,
importantly, about a state of
being. It’s about having the
appropriate inner states. Gertrude Elizabeth
Margaret Anscombe (1919-
2001)
3. Virtue-based Theory Gertrude Elizabeth
Margaret Anscombe
(1919-2001)
• Another distinguishing
feature of virtue
ethics is that
• The character trait of
character traits are
kindness, would be
stable, fixed, and expected to be
reliable dispositions. possessed
consistently.
3. Virtue-based Theory Gertrude Elizabeth
Margaret Anscombe
(1919-2001)
Arthur Schopenhauer
on Morality
• The assumption that animals are without
rights and the illusion that our treatment of
them has no moral significance is a
positively outrageous example of Western
crudity and barbarity.
• Universal compassion is the only guarantee
of morality.
Philosopher’s for Morality
Friedrich Nietzsche on
Morality
• Nietzsche argued that there were two
fundamental types of morality:
• Master morality values pride and
power.
• Slave morality values kindness,
empathy, and sympathy.
Philosopher’s for Morality
‘ Man in Nature is a
political Animal’
Aristotle
Defining Politics
• The word ‘politics ‘ is derived from polis, meaning
literally ‘city state ‘.
04 02
MORAL STATE
FOUNDATIONS OF 03 ITS NATURE,
LEGITIMACY,LIBERTY,EQ PURPOSE,AND LIMITS
UALITY ,JUSTICE AND
HUMAN RIGHTS
DIMENSION OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
Perspective or normative Dimension
The aspect of philosophy that prescribes
how things ought to be
The need of knowledge concerning
principles of evaluation that enable us to
construct and apply a standard to judge
politics.
DIMENSION OF POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
Descriptive Dimension
The aspect of philosophy that describe
how things are
The six issues require a comprehensive
knowledge of the facts about human
nature and human social relationship
POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY
• It begins with the assumption that such public
questions as obedience to the law, the best possible
government, or the justice of public policies are in
need of justification
• It is possible only in word where ends collide –Sir
Isiah Berlin
• It is an attempt to truly know both the nature of
political things and the right to the good political
order-Leo Strauss
The problem: Its Diagnosis and Prescription
Sources of Political Conflict: Differences
ECONOMIC INTEREST
RELIGION
CONFLICT
Many of the great or epic political philosophers have pursued their
Inquiries as a result of profound social conflict and decay
• Globalization
• Gender inequality
• Terrorism
Conflict
• Conflict
• Disorder
• Corruption
• Violence
• Terrorism
• Exploitation
Philosophy and
Diagnosis
Hobbes examine human passion
Plato on differences as the basis
for justice
Machiavelli focuses on human deception
and its relevance to successful political
leadership
Marx addresses the role that economic
inequality and class conflict play in
forming political system
Philosphy and Diagnosis
Political Philosophers are not satisfied in simply describing public disorder
or discontent ;
To Leo Strauss :
Human beings will never create a society free of contradictions –perhaps even
including contradictory norms
In Summary
-Jamie Chase
What we think: Society
I feel no matter what kind of government you have,there will
always be someone dictating your mannerisms /life .Don’t do this,
don’t do that .Its never going to end.Society is and will always be
oppressive in that way.But if that is the noun,we can really call it
oppression?
-Manuel Alonzo
What we think: Society
I feel no matter what kind of government you have,there will
always be someone dictating your mannerisms /life .Don’t do this,
don’t do that .Its never going to end.Society is and will always be
oppressive in that way.But if that is the noun,we can really call it
oppression?
-Manuel Alonzo
What others think: Society
-’The most unpardonable sin in society is independence of thought’-
Emma Goldman
‘To cut himself off thought from all of is relationship of race,and country
And citizenship get rid of all of those interest
prejudices,likings,superstitions,generated
What others think: Society
‘To cut himself off thought from all of his relationship of race,and country
And citizenship- get rid of all of those interest, prejudices, likings,
superstitions, generated in him by the life of his own society and his own
time –to look on all of the changes societies have undergone and are
undergoing, without reference to nationality, or creed or personal welfare;
Is what average man cannot do at all, and what the exceptional man can
do very imperfectly ‘
Herbert Spencer
Thank
you!